UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. ( )K m m A SKETCH OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY FROM THALES TO CICERO. Camtrfoge : PRINTED BY C. J. CLAY, M.A. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. Smcs. A SKETCH OF ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY FROM THALES TO CICERO SITY) vv &A *>^Jj JOSEPH B. MAYOR, M.A. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY AT KING'S COLLEGE, FORMERLY FELLOW AND TUTOR OK ST JOHN'S COLLEGE, CAMURIDGK. EDITED FOR THE SYNDICS OF THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. ionium: CAMBRIDGE WAREHOUSE, 17, PATERNOSTER ROW. e: BRIGHTON, BELL AND CO. tpjtfl: F. A. BROCKHAUS. 1881 [All Rights reserved^ TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. PRE-SOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. IONIC SCHOOL. One ever-changing self-developed universe. (Dynamical Physicism J . ) B.C. 600 fi. Thales, p. -2. 580 Anaximander, p. 3. 520 Anaximenes, p. 4. 510 Heraclitus, p. 4. ITALIC SCHOOL. One unchanging self-existent ^lniverse ( Transcendental Physicism . ) B.C. 530 fl. Pythagoras, p. 7. 530 Xenophanes \ 480 Parmenides > Eleatic school, pp. 1416. 460 Zeno of Elea ) 1 Ritter in his History of Ancient Philosophy employs the terms Dynamical and Mechanical to distinguish the view which regards the universe as one great organism with an inherent power of move- ment and change, from that which regards it as a result of forces acting upon a number of independent elements. vi CONTENTS. I ON I CO-I T AT.I c S CHOOL \ Changing Universe formed out of a plurality of unchanging elements. (Mechanical Physicism.) B.C. 470 fl. Empedocles, p. 17. 470 Anaxagoras, p. 19. [460 Diogenes of Apollonia, p. 19 2 .] 430 Democritus, p. 20. B. SOCRATES TO ARISTOTLE. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE AND MAX. SOPHISTS, pp. 25, 26. ^B. C. 450 fl. Protagoras. 440 Gorgias. 430 Hippias. 430 Prodicus. B.C. 470 399, SOCRATES, p. 27. B.C. 440 355 Xenophon, p. 32. 399 fl. Euclides of Mcgara, p. 35. CYNICS, pp. 3539- B.C. 380 fl. Antisthenes. 360 Diogenes. CYRENATCS, pp. 3941. B. c. 380 fl. Aristippus. -VfTheodorus. O JQ \ J [Hegesias. B.C. 428 347, PLATO (Academy), pp. 41 83. Abstract of the Republic, pp. 47 59. Remarks on Republic, pp. 59 67. Example of dialectic, pp. 67 73. Examples of exposition, pp. 74 80. Example of allegory, pp. So 83. 1 This is not a recognized title, but merely used here for the sake of convenience. 2 Diogenes, as explained in the body of the work, is re-actionary, approaching more nearly to the earlier Ionic philosophers. CONTENTS. vil B.C. 385322, ARISTOTLE (Lyceum), pp. 83142. His writings, pp. 91 100. Abstract of Nicomachean Ethics, pp. 100 126. Remarks on same, pp. 126 130. Abstract of Politics, pp. 130 138. Contrast between moral and physical treatises, pp. 138140. History of his writings, pp. 140 142. Lost Dialogues, p. 142. C. POST-ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY OF MAN. CHARACTERISTICS OF THE LATER PHILOSOPHY, pp. 143145. PERIPATETICS, p. 145. B.C. 310 fl. Theophrastus. 290 Strato. SCEPTICS, p. 146. B.C. 320 fl. Pyrrho. 270 Timon. ACADEMY OLD, p. 147. B.C. 350 fl. Speusippus. 340 Xenocrates. ACADEMY SCEPTICAL (by Cicero called 'New'). B - c - 3i5 241 ArcesilausJ 214 129 CarneadesV pp. 147 150. 130 fl. Clitomachus ) STOICISM, pp. 150 178. B. C. 280 fl. Zeno of Citium. 260 Cleanthes. 240 Chrysippus. Stoic Logic, p. 152. Physics, pp. 153 J 55 Ethics, pp. 155 162. Theology, pp. 162 164. Comparison with Christianity, pp. 164 177. Hymn of Cleanthes, p. 177. Vlil CONTENTS. EPICUREANISM, pp. 178205. B.C. 341270 Epicurus, pp. 181183. His aversion to science, pp. 183 186. Epicurean Logic, pp. 186 188. Physics, pp. 188 191. Atomic System, pp. 191 193. Theology, pp. 193 199. Ethics, pp. 199203. Lucretius quoted, pp. 203 205. ECLECTICISM, pp. 205 to end. Philosophy in Rome, pp. 206 218. Eclectic Stoics, pp. 218, 219. B.C. 140 fl. Panaetius. 100 Posidonius. Eclectic Academics (Reformed or ' Old' Academy], pp. 220 223. B.C. TOO fl. Philo. 80 Antiochus. Eclectic Epicureans and Peripatetics, p. 223. B.C. 10643, CICERO, pp. 224244. His character, pp. 224 226. Professedly a 'New' (i.e. Sceptical) Academic, p. 226. In reality a moderate Stoic, p. 227. in regard to Theology, p. 227. in regard to Ethics, p. 230. Survey of his philosophical writings, pp. 231 237. Their value for the history of philosophy, pp. 238243. Their value as philosophy, pp. 243, 244. B.C. 60 fl. Varro, p. 245. 60 Nigidius Figulus, p. 245. 30 Sextius, p. 246. CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS, pp. 246253. PREFACE. THE readers whom I have chiefly had in my mind, in writing the following sketch of Ancient Philosophy, are Undergraduates at the University or others who are commencing the study of the philosophical works of Cicero or Plato or Aristotle in the original language. It has been my wish to supply to them, what I remember vainly seeking when I was in their position, something which may help them to find their bearings in the new world into which they are plunged on first making acquaintance with such books as Cicero's JDe Finibus or the Republic of Plato. The only helps which I had in similar circumstances some thirty years ago were a trans- lation of Schleiermacher's Introduction to the Dialogues of Plato, of which I could make nothing, and Lewes' small Biographical History of Philosophy, of which the aim, as far as I could judge, was to show that, as philosophy was moonshine, it was mere waste of time to read what the philosophers had written. Things have changed since then. The noblest defence of ancient philosophy which has ever appeared, is contained in the chapters on the x PREFACE. Sophists and Socrates written by one, who might have been supposed to be himself more or less a sympathizer with Lewes, and in the elaborate examination of the spe- culations of the Ancients contained in the same Author's Plato and Aristotle. During the same interval the charm and the wit and the irony of Plato have for the first time been made intelligible to English readers by Mr Jowett's admirable translations; and the excellent German his- tories of philosophy by Zeller, Ueberweg and Schwegler have been translated into English. None of these however, nor any others which might be named, seem to me exactly to meet the wants of the case. They are too long, too full, too hard, too abstract, or too vague, for a first sketch. What is wanted is something to combine conciseness with accuracy and clearness, something which will be easy and interesting to readers of ordinary intelligence, and will leave no doubt in their minds as to the author's meaning. It is for others to judge how far this object has been accomplished in the present book, which is the outcome of various courses of lectures delivered on the same subject during the last quarter of a century. ^ But, though I write in the first instance for Classical scholars, and have therefore thought myself at liberty to quote the original Greek and Latin, wherever it seemed expedient to do so ; I am not without hopes that what I have written may be found interesting and useful by educated readers generally, not merely as an introduction to the formal history of philosophy, but as supplying a PREFACE. xi key to our present ways of thinking and judging in regard to matters of the highest importance. For Greece is in everything the starting-point of modern civilization. Homer is not more the fountain-head of Western poetry, than Socrates of Western philosophy. Allowing as much as we will to Semitic and Teutonic influences, it remains true that for Art and Science and Law, for the Philosophy of thought and of action, nay even for Theology itself, as far as the form is concerned, we are mainly indebted to Greece, and to Rome as the interpreter of Greece. Even that which we call 'common sense' consists of little more than the worn fragments of older systems of thought, just as the common soil of our gardens is com- posed, in great part, of the detritus of primeval rocks. As we trace backwards the march of civilization, we find extraordinary contrasts in the degrees of progress made in its different departments. In some departments, as for instance in the inductive sciences and in mechani- cal inventions, the early stages have only a historical value : in others, as in geometry, we still use text-books written two thousand years ago. So in the arts : while in sculpture we despair of approaching Greece, in music \ve have far surpassed her, and in poetry we may claim equality at least, if not superiority. How stands it with regard to philosophy? Here too we find the same variety. While the fanciful speculations of the ancients as to the constitution and laws of the external universe, have for the most part vanished away before the touch of reality, and given place to the solid edifice of modern xil PREFACE. physical science ; while the loose induction of Socrates and of Aristotle has been reduced in our own day into a definite system of Inductive Logic; while immense additions have thus been made to our knowledge of the external universe and of man as a part of the universe, that is, of the anatomy, the physiology and the habits of the human animal, there has been far less advance in the knowledge of man as a moral and intellectual being. Thus, Deductive Logic remains in its essentials the same as when it was first given to the world by Aristotle, and neither in Psychology nor in Ethics can it be said that the ancient systems have been finally superseded by any generally accepted system of modern times. No doubt many new facts have been observed and new explana- tions have been offered in reference to such subjects as comparative psychology, the association of ideas, the influence of heredity, the influence of nature on man, the laws of human progress, and so on. Above all, Chris- tianity has imparted a far deeper feeling of the complexity of life, a sense of moral responsibility, of man's weakness and sinfulness, and of the regenerating powers of faith and love, such as was never dreamt of by the ancients. And yet, in spite of all this, is there any modern work of systematic morality which could be compared with Aristotle's Ethics for its power of stimulating moral thought? Most moderns appear to write under the consciousness that they are uttering truisms ; or, if they escape from this, it is by running off from the main high- way of morality into by-paths of psychology or physiology PREFACE. Xlll or sociology. Again, they are hampered by the suspicion that whatever concerns moral practice is more impres- sively and effectively treated of by religion ; or else they consign, what, supposing it to be true, is the most im- portant part of morality, to the region of the unknown . and unknowable. The ancient moralists knew no such restrictions. Aristotle's, and still more Plato's, theory of conduct was no stale repetition of other men's thoughts ; it was the full expression of their own highest aspirations and discoveries in regard to the duty, the hopes, and the destiny of man. And thus there is a freshness and a completeness about the ethics of the Ancients which we seek in vain in the Moderns. Even if it were otherwise, the comparison between pre-Christian and post-Christian systems of morality must always be full of interest and importance in reference to our view of Christianity itself. One word more as to the general use of the history ot philosophy. It was a saying of Democritus that a fool has to be taught everything by his own personal ex- perience, while a wise man draws lessons from the experience of others. History of whatever kind supplies us with the means of thus gaining experience by proxy, and in the history of philosophy above all we have the concentrated essence of all human experience. For the philosopher is, no more than the poet, an isolated pheno- menon. As the latter expresses the feeling, so the former expresses in its purest form the thought of his time, sum- ming up the past, interpreting the present, and fore- xiv PREFACE. shadowing tli2 future. We might be spared much of crudeness and violence and one-sidedness, if people were aware that what they hold to be the last result of modern enlightenment was perhaps the common-place of 2000 years ago ; or, on the other hand, that doctrines or prac- tices which they regard as too sacred for examination are to be traced back, it may be, to a Pagan origin. It is possible to be provincial in regard to time as well as in regard to space ; and there is no more mischievous pro- vincialism than that of the man who accepts blindly the fashionable belief, or no-belief, of his particular time, with- out caring to inquire what were the ideas of the countless generations which preceded, or what are likely to be the ideas of the generations which will follow. However firm may be our persuasion of the Divinely guided progress of our race, the fact of a general forward movement in the stream of history is not inconsistent with all sorts of eddies and retardations at particular points ; and before we can be sure that such points are not to be found in our own age, we must have some knowledge of the past develop- ment of thought, and have taken the trouble to compare our own ways of thinking and acting with those that have prevailed in other epochs of humanity. Had space permitted, I should have been glad to have followed the example set by Sir Alexander Grant in his Essays on Aristotle, and shown how the half-conscious morality of the Epic and Gnomic and Lyric poets, and of the early historians, provided the raw material which was afterwards worked up by the philosophers; and PREFACE. XV again how the results of philosophic thought became in their turn the common property of the educated class, and were transformed into household words by Euripides and the writers of the New Comedy, and still more by the Roman Satirists. But to do this would have swollen the volume to twice its present size, and perhaps it may suffice here to throw out a hint which any Classical scholar may put into practice for himself. In conclusion I have to return my best thanks to the friends who have helped me by looking over portions of my proof-sheets, especially to my colleague Prof. Warr, to whose suggestion indeed it is mainly owing that a part of the Introduction to my edition of Cicero's De Natura Deorum has thus been expanded into a separate work on the History of Ancient Philosophy. N.B. The references to Zeller are, except when otherwise stated, to the latest German edition, which is denoted by the small numeral following the number of the page. To the books recom- mended under Aristotle's Ethics, p. 100, add a new translation by Mr F. H. Peters, and the Essays V. and VI. contained in Grote's Fragments on Ethical Subjects. May 20, 1 88 1. "OTAN r^p e0NH TA MH NO'MON exoNTA c^ycei TA Toy NOMOY TTOIOJCIN, ofroi NO'MON MH exoNrec eAYroTc eiciN NOMOC, orriNec GNAEIKNYNTAI TO eproN TOY NOMOY TpATTTON 6N TA?C KApAlAIC AYTOON, CYMMApTYpOYCHC <\YT(x)N THC CYN6lAHC6(jOC KAI META^Y AAAhAOON TOON AOflCMCON KATHfOpOYNTCON H KA^I AnoAOfOYMeNCON. S. PAUL, ad Rom. n. 14, 15. AlOTI TO fNCOCTON TO? 6GOY 4>ANepON 6CTIN N AYToTc' 6 Gedc r^p AYTO?C 6c[)ANepoaceN. TA r^p AOpATA AYTOY And KTi'cecoc KOCMOY TO?C HOIH'MACIN NOOYMENA KAGOpATAI, H T6 AlAlOC A^TOY AYNAMIC KA! GeiOTHC. Ibid. I. 19, 20. it 'HN MEN OYN npd THC TOY KYP/OY HApOYciAC eic AIKAIOCYNHN^EAAHCIN ANAPKAI'A (J)iAoco(f)i'A ; NYNI Ae XPHCI'MH npoc GeoceBeiAN PNGTAI, nponAiAeiA TIC OYCA TO?C TKJN TTICTIN Al' AHOAeileCOC KApnOYM6NOIC. CLEM. AL. Strom. I. c. 5 a8. ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY FROM THALES TO CICERO 1 . GREEK philosophy had its origin not in the mother country, but in the colonies of Asia Minor and Magna Graecia. This is owing partly to the reflectiveness be- longing to a more advanced civilization, and partly to the fact that the colonists were brought in contact with the customs and ideas of foreign nations. The philoso- 1 The following works will be found useful by the student. They are arranged in what I consider to be their order of import- ance. Full references will be found in the two which stand at the head of the list and also in Ueberweg. Ritter and Preller, Historia Philosophic* Graccae ct Romanae ex fontium locis co&texta (referred to as R. and P. below). Zeller, History of Greek Philosophy (in German. Translations of portions have been published by Longmans). Grote, History of Greece, together with his Plato and Aristotle- Grant, Ethics of Aristotle, Vol. I. ed. 3. Ueberweg, History of Philosophy, Vol. I. tr. by Morris. Schwegler, Hist, of Philccophy, tr. by Sterling. Dollinger, The Gentile and the JKV, translated by Darnell. A. Butler, Lectures on Ancient Philosophy. Mullach's Fragmenta Philosopher urn in Didot's series ought to have been more useful than any of these, but its value is much lessened by the want of discrimination shown in the selection and arrangement of the writers quoted. M. P. I 2 TIIALES. phers of the earliest, or Pre-Socratic period, are broadly divided into the Ionic and the Italic Schools. Both had the same object of interest, to ascertain the nature, the origin, the laws, the destiny of the visible world. But while the former, with the Ionic sensitiveness to all out- ward influences, dwelt more upon the material element it- self, and the life which manifested itself in its ever-chang- ing developments, the latter (who, if not themselves Dorian, were yet surrounded by Dorian settlers, with their Doric ideal of discipline, order, stability, superiority to sense, as opposed to the Ionic ideal of free growth, of ease, beauty and nature,) turned their thoughts more to the laws by which the world was governed, or the one unchanging substance which they believed to underlie its shifting phenomena. The first name in Greek philosophy is the so-called founder of the Ionic or physical school, Thales of Mile- tus, a contemporary of Solon (B.C. 640 550), said to be of Phenician descent. With him begins the transition from the mythological to the scientific interpretation of nature, the transition, as Grote puts it, from the question Who sends rain, or thunder, or earthquakes, and why does he send it ? to the question What are the antece- dent conditions of rain, thunder, or earthquakes? The old cosmogonies and theogonies suggested the idea of development under the form of a personal history of a number of supernatural beings variously related to each other. The first parent of all, according to Homer, was Oceanus (//. xiv. 201, 240), perhaps a nature-myth to be interpreted of the sun rising and setting in the sea. Thales stripped him of his personality, and laid down the proposition that water is the one original substance ANAXIMANDER. o out of which all things are produced. Aristotle conjec- tures that he was led to this belief by observing that moisture is essential to animal and vegetable life : pro- bably it was also from the fact that water supplies the most obvious example of the transmutation of matter under its three forms, solid, fluid and gaseous. Thales further held that the universe is a living creature ; which he expressed by saying that 'all things are full of God/ and in agreement with this he is reported to have said that 'the magnet had a soul.' The second of the Ionic philosophers was Anaxi- rnander, also an inhabitant of Miletus (B.C. 610 540). He followed Thales in seeking for an original substance to which he gave the name of apX r /> but he found this not in Water, but in the drm/Doy, matter indeterminate (/. e.- not yet developed into any one of the forms familiar to us) and infinite, which we may regard as bearing the same relation to Hesiod's primaeval Chaos, as Water did to the Homeric Oceanus. The elementary contraries, hot, cold, moist, dry, are separated from this first matter by virtue of the eternal movement belonging to it ; thus are produced the four elements ; the earth was in the form of a cylinder, self-poised, in the centre of the uni- verse; round it was air, and round that again a fiery sphere which was broken up so as to form the heavenly bodies. As all substances are produced out of the In- finite so they are resolved into it, thus ' atoning for their injustice 1 ' in arrogating to themselves a separate indi- vidual existence. The Infinite is divine, containing and directing all things : divine too are the innumerable 1 AiSoycu yap aura rlffiv /cat 5iicr)v TTJS dfo/a'as. R. and P. 18. I 2 4 ANAXIMENES. worlds which it is ever generating and re-absorbing into its own bosom. After Anaximander comes Anaximenes, also of Miletus, who is supposed to have flourished about 520 B. c. While his doctrine approaches in many respects to that of Anaximander, he nevertheless returned to the principle of Thales in so far that he assumed, as the apxtfi a definite substance, Air, in contradistinction to the indefinite aTretpov of his immediate predecessor. Air is infinite in extent and eternal in duration. It is in con- tinual motion, and produces all things out of itself by condensation and rarefaction, passing through successive stages from fire downwards to wind, cloud, water, earth and stone. As man's life is supported by breathing, so the universe subsists by the air which encompasses it. We are told that Anaximenes gave the name of God both to his first principle Air, and to certain of its products, probably the stars. The greatest of the Pre-Socratic philosophers, Hera- clitus of Ephesus, known among the ancients as the obscure and the weeping philosopher, was a little junior to Anaximenes. Following in the steps of his predecessor, he held that it was one and the self-same substance which by processes of condensation and rarefaction changed it- self into all the elements known by us, but he preferred to name this from its highest potency fire, rather than to stop at the intermediate stage of air. But the point of main interest with him was not the original substance, but the process, the everlasting movement upwards and downwards, fire (including air), water, earth; earth, water, fire. All death is birth into a new form, all birth the death of the previous form. There is properly no ex- HERACL1TUS. 5 istence but only ' becoming/ i.e. a continual passing from one existence into another. Each moment is the union of opposites, being and not-being: the life of the world is maintained by conflict, TroAe/xos Trarrjp iravruv. Every particle of matter is in continual movement. All things are in flux like the waters of a river. One thing alone is permanent, the universal law which reveals itself in this movement. This is Zeus, the all-pervading reason of the world. It is only the- illusion of the senses which makes us fancy that there are such things as permanent substances. Fire exhibits most clearly the incessant movement and activity of the world: confined in the body it constitutes the human soul, in the universe at large it is God (the substance and the process being thus identified). The fragmentary remains of Heraclitus abound in those pregnant oracular sayings for which he was so famous among the ancients. Such are the following, in which the law of man and the law of nature are connected with the Will and Word of God. Fr. 91 ! , 'Understand- ing is common to all. When we speak with reason we must hold fast to that which is common, even as a city holds fast to the law, yea, and far more strongly: for all human laws are fed by one law, that of God, which pre- vails wherever it will, and suffices for all and surpasses 2 .' Fr. 100, 'The law is the rampart of the city 3 .' Fr. 92, 1 I give the numbering of Mr Bywater's edition. 2 tZvi/6v eon Tracrt TO (frpcv^eLV %vv vob) \eyovras tV ry ^vvu iravTUv, OKUffirep vb/Jiu) iro\Ls KCLL iro\v iV%u/)OT^pcos. yap Trdvres ol avUp'JjTTfioi. vopioi virb evbs rov deiov Kpartei. yap roffou- rev CKOffov 0\i Kal ^apt^eet Trdat /cat irepiyiveraL. 3 Maxe0-#cu %/>?} rbv 5i),uoi> virep rod VO/JLQV o/cws virtp ret'xeos. 6 HERACLITUS. 'Reason is common to all, but most live as though under- standing were their own 1 .' Fr. 29, 'The sun shall not overpass his measure, else the Erinyes, the ministers of justice, will find him out 2 .' Fr. 19, * Wisdom consists in one thing, to know the mind by which all through all is guided 3 .' Fr. 65, 'One thing alone wisdom willeth and willeth not to be spoken, the name of Zeus 4 .' I add a few apophthegms of a more miscellaneous character. Fr. 46, 'Out of discord proceeds the fairest harmony 5 .' Fr. 47, 'The hidden harmony is better than that which is mani- fest 6 / Fr. n, 'The king to whom belongs the shrine at Delphi neither publishes nor conceals but shadows forth the truth 7 .' Fr. 12, 'The Sibyl, uttering with frenzied mouth words unmirthful, unadorned, untricked, reaches with her voice through a thousand years by the help of God 8 .' Fr. 122, 'After death there await men such things 1 ToO \6yov 5' 6vros ui>ou, faovvi ol TroXXoi ws Idirjv ^o^res pbvrjcriv. 2 'HXos oi>x virepprjcreTai. ^rpa" el dt /XT;, 'Epu/ues /JLIV St/c?;? tirl- Kovpoi e^evprjeovvL. 3 *E^ TO ]mr)v rj KvfiepvoLTai Travra Sia. Trdvrwv. 4 *Ef r6 aoa^ ou rb jjiavTeiov CGTI rb ev AA00iS, cure \yei cure Kpvirrei, aXXa (7T]/j.aivt. 8 2/^uXXa 5 /JLaLvofJL^vit} ffTo/J.ari dy\affra Kal aKaXXwTrtcrra /cat dfMvpHrra (j)6cyyoiu,{vT] xtXtwv erfuv e^iKveerat rrj rj did rov 6e6v> which Coleridge has thus translated (Lit. Ron. ill. p. 419) not hers To win the sense by words of rhetoric, Lip-blossoms breathing perishable sweets; But by the power of the informing Word Roll sounding onward through a thousand years Her deep prophetic bodements. PYTHAGORAS. 7 as they think not nor expect 1 / Fr. 4, 'Eyes and eais are bad witnesses when the soul is barbarous 2 .' Fr. 7, 'To him that hopes not, the unhoped will never come 3 .' Fr. 8, 'They that search for gold, dig much ground and find little 4 .' Fr. 16, 'Great learning does not teach wis- dom 5 .' Fr. 75, 'The dry light is the wisest soul 6 .' Heraclitus is the first philosopher of whom we read that he referred to the doctrines of other philosophers. He is said to have spoken highly of some of the seven Wise Men, but condemned severely Pythagoras and Xenophanes as well as the poets Hesiod, Homer and Archilochus. Though I agree with Ueberweg in classing him with the older Ionics, yet his philosophy was no doubt largely developed with a reference to the rival schools of Italy. Thus there is something of a Pythago- rean colour in fragments 46 and 47 quoted above. We must now cross the water Vith Pythagoras of fjt,vi re\VTrj(TavTas dWa OVK \Tror>Tai oJ5 do 2 Ka/cot jjidprvpes avdpuiroLffL 6(p6a\]JLoi /cat wra, fiapfidpovs 3 'Eai> ny ?X7n?cu, avt\TriWTdnj /cat dpLi\.a,uej>os 3' airo trp&Tov irtt;i6i, teal /xer^ Plato (AV/. x. 600) bears witness to the marked character of the Pythagorean life (UvdayopeiosrpoTrosTov piov) ; and Herodotus (ll. 81) connects the religious rites practised by them with those of the Orphic sect and of the Egyptians, ofj.o\oytov Zyvuv (pdey^afJLfrrjs a'Cuv. It was believed that he retained the memory of his own former transmigrations, and that he had once recognized a shield hanging up in a temple, as one which he had himself carried at Troy under the name of Euphorbus, (see Hor. Od. I. xxvm. 1. 10). 10 PYTHAGORAS. Pythagoras; (3) the unquestioning submission with which the dicta of the master were received by his disciples, as shown by the famous avros ca, ipse dixit^ which was to them an end of all controversy. The brotherhood, first established at Crotona, soon gained great influence with the wealthier class in that and the neighbouring cities; but after some twenty years of prosperity they seem to have provoked the opposition of the democratic party by their arrogance and exclusiveness. Pythagoras himself is said to have been banished from Crotona and taken refuge at Metapontum. A worse fate overtook his follow- ers about a hundred years later, when their church at Crotona was burnt down, and they themselves massacred with the exception of two. The school appears to have died out altogether about the middle of the 4th century B.C., but revived in the time of Cicero. The new and startling feature in the Pythagorean philosophy, as opposed to the Ionic systems, was that it found its apx^ its key of the universe, not in any known substance, but in number and proportion. This might naturally have occurred to one who had listened to the teaching of Thales and Anaximander. After all it makes no difference, he might say, what we take as our original matter, it is the law of development, the measure of con- densation, which determines the nature of each thing. Number rules the harmonies of music, the proportions of sculpture and architecture, the movements of the heavenly bodies 1 . It is Number which makes the universe into a 1 He believed that the intervals between the heavenly bodies corresponded exactly to those of the octave, and that hence arose the Harmony of the Spheres, which mortals were unable to hear, either because it was too powerful for their organs of hearing or be- PYTHAGORAS. Ir s 1 , and is the secret of a virtuous and orderly life. Then, by a confusion similar to that which led Heraclitus to identify the law of movement with Fire, the Pythago- reans went on to identify number with form, substance and quality. One, the Monad, evolved out of itself Limit (order), exhibited in the series of odd numbers, and the Unlimited (freedom., expansiveness), the Dyad, ex- hibited in the series of even numbers, especially of the powers of Two; out of the harmonious mixture of these contraries all particular substances were produced. Again, One was the point, Two the line, Three the plane, Four the concrete solid (but from another point of view, as being the first .square number, equal into equal, it was conceived to be Justice). Yet once more, One was the central fire, the hearth of the universe, the throne of Zeus. Around this revolved in regular dance ten spheres ; on the outside that of the fixed stars, within this the five planets in their order, then the Sun, the Moon, the Earth, between which and the central fire was interposed the imaginary Anti-Chthon or Counter- Earth, cutting off our view of the central fire and leaving us dependent on the reflection of its light by the Sun, which was not in itself luminous. The separation of the Earth into its two hemispheres was for the purpose of making up the Decad, the symbol of totality. As the Decad was the sum of the first four numbers (1 + 2 + 3 + 4=10), special sacredness attached to this group, known under the name Tetractys 2 . cause they had never experienced absolute silence. Arist. Gael. II. 9, Plin. N. If. II. -22. 1 Pythagoras is said to have been the first who called the universe by this name. 8 Compare the Pythagorean oath contained in the Golden Verses, 12 PYTHAGORAS. The number Ten was also the number of the Pythagorean categories, or list of contraries, thus given by Aristotle (Met. I. v. 986), Limit and Unlimited, Odd and Even, One and Many, Right and Left, Male and Female, Rest and Motion, Straight and Curved, Light and Darkness, Good and Bad, Square and Oblong. These mystical extravagances appear to have been the necessary introduction to the sciences of Arithmetic and Geometry, just as Astrology and Alchemy were the intro- duction to Astronomy and Chemistry. Indeed we find that men like Copernicus and Kepler were to some extent influenced and guided in their investigations by the ideas of Pythagoras. Nor was he himself deficient in knowledge of a more exact kind, if it is true that he was the discoverer of the theorem which we know as the 47th in the first book of Euclid, and was also acquainted with such pro- perties of numbers as are mentioned byZeller (i. p. 32 2 4 ). ^x^The Pythagorean doctrine of the soul and of God is variously reported. If we may trust the oldest accounts, there does not seem to have been any close connexion between the religious and philosophical opinions of ou /xa rbv a/urfyp yevey irapadovTa rerpaKrvv, Traydv devdov (pvaios pifujjLCLT txovaav. There \vas of course no end to the fancies which might be connected with numbers. Thus, One was reason, as being unchangeable; Two was opinion, and the earth as the region of opinion ; Three was perfection, as comprising in itself beginning, middle, and end ; Five was marriage, the union of odd and even. Later Pythagoreans made the Monad God, the Dyad Matter, the Triad the World. For other interpretations, see Zeller I. p. 359-* foil. The five regular solids were supposed to be the ultimate forms of the five elements, the cube of earth, pyramid of fire, octahedron of air, icosahedron of water, dodecahedron of the etherial element which encompassed the universe on the outside. PYTHAGORAS. ! 3 Pythagoras. We are told that he believed in One God eternal, unchangeable, ruling and upholding all things, that the soul was a 'harmony 1 ,' that the body was its prison 2 , in which it was punished for past sin and dis- ciplined for a divine life after death, that those who failed to profit by this discipline would pass into lower forms of life, or suffer severer penalties in Hades. Heraclides Ponticus reports (Diog. L. Proem. 12, Cic. Tusc. v. 3) that Pythagoras was the first to call himself , Plut. Def. Or. 183, see Cic. Leg. II. n. 1 4 XENOPHANES. spirit; for sleep in them is akin to death,' (Stob. Flor. i. 19). 'It is hard to take many paths in life at the same time,' (Stob. Flor. i. 27). 'It is the part of a fool to attend to every opinion of every man, above all to that of the mob, ' (Iambi. V. P. 31). The second of the Italic schools was the Eleatic, founded by Xenophanes of Colophon in Asia Minor (b. 569 B.C.), who migrated to Elea in Italy about 540 B.C. While the Pythagoreans strove to explain nature mathe- matically and symbolically, the Eleatics in their later developments did the same by their metaphysical ab- stractions. Xenophanes himself seems to have received his first philosophical impulse in the revulsion from the popular mythology. In his philosophical poem he con- demns anthropomorphism and polytheism altogether, and charges Homer and Hesiod with attributing to the Gods conduct which would have been disgraceful in men. 'If animals had had hands they would have depicted Gods each in their own form, just as men have done 1 . God is one, all eye, all ear, all understanding; he is for ever unmoved, unchangeable, a vast all-embracing sphere. 1 1 Hdvra 6eols dvedr^nav "O^Tjpos 0' 'Hcrtodos re oucra Trap dvOpuTroiaw oveidea /ecu 1^6705 eariv, ot TrXeZor' eTrareveiv. EFs Oeos ev re &eoi, and can never be 1 Kal rb ptv ovv trends oims dvfjp ytver ov54 rts larai eldus a.^s. Zeno of Elea (b. 490 B.C.) is chiefly known from his arguments showing the absurd consequences of the ordi- nary belief in the phenomenal world. Parmenides must be right in denying motion and multiplicity, for their as- sertion leads to self-contradiction. Zeno was in conse- quence called the inventor of Dialectic. His arguments, especially the famous 'Achilles, 1 still find a place in treatises on Logic 1 . 1 It is thus given by Mill (System of Logic n. 385 2 ), 'The argu- ment is, let Achilles run ten times as fast as the tortoise, yet if the tortoise has the start, Achilles will never overtake him. For sup- pose them to be at first separated by an interval of a thousand feet : when Achilles has run those thousand feet, the tortoise will have got on a hundred : when Achilles has run those hundred, the tor- toise will have run ten, and so on for ever: therefore Achilles may run for ever without overtaking the tortoise.' EMPEDOCLES. I 7 The clearly marked opposition between the Ionic and the Eleatic views of nature, as shown in Heraclitus and Parmenides, had a powerful influence on the subsequent course of philosophy. Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and the Atomists agreed in accepting the Eleatic principle of the immutability of substance, while denying its absolute Oneness; and they explained the Ionic 'becoming' as the result of the mixture of a number of unchangeable substances. Empedocles of Agrigentum (b. 500 B.C.) 'than whom/ says Lucretius, 'Sicily has produced nothing holier, more marvellous or more dear/ held that there were four eternal, self-subsistent elements or 'roots of things/ which were being continually separated and com- bined under the influence of Love and Hatred. At times Love has the upper hand, at times Hate. When Love has the complete supremacy the elements are at rest, united in one all-including sphere (3atpos) : when Hate prevails, the elements are entirely separate. The soul,/"" like all other things, is formed by the mixture of the elements, and is thus capable of perception, for like can only be perceived by like 1 . In regard to the origin of living things, Empedocles imagined that the several parts or limbs were in the first instance produced separately in the bosom of the earth, eyes apart from brows, arms from shoulders, etc. ; and that these were afterwards joined at haphazard, giving rise to all sorts of monsters, ox- headed men, men-headed oxen; and that it was only after successive trials that nature gave birth to perfect animals, fitted to survive and to propagate their 1 yatrj [JLV yap yaiav OTrwTra/Jiev, vdari 5' i/3u>/), aldtpi 5' alOtpa dlav, drap Trvpl Trvp d'i'5T]\ov aTOpyy 8 2rop7^j', Net/cos 5^ re vettce'i \vyp. M P. 2 1 8 ANAXAGORAS. I race l . In his opinions on the Gods and on religion, Empe- docles was chiefly influenced by Pythagoras. He believed in the existence of Daemons intermediate between Gods and men, some of which had passed into mortal bodies as an atonement for former sins, and could only be restored to their original state after long ages of disci- pline. While at one time he speaks of God as one spirit pervading the world in swift thought, in other places he speaks of Gods produced like men from the mixture of the elements, but possessed of a longer existence, and then again we find divinity attributed to Sphaerus and the four elements and two moving powers. Empedocles closes the series of those philosophers who used the medium of verse for their speculations. We have still nearly 500 verses remaining of his two great philosophical poems (the IIcpl vo-W9, in which he main- tained ist 'that nothing exists' (i.e. doubtless 'in the absolute Eleatic sense'); 2nd that, if anything did exist, still it could not be known ; 3rd that, even if it could be known, the knowledge of it could not be communicated to others. Hippias of Elis and Prodicus of Ceos 1 Trfpl JJLV 6euv OVK ?x w cidtvat, ovd' ws elcriv ou0' ws ou/c eurtV TToXXo, yap ra nuXvovra eidevcu, 97 TC ddrjXorTjs /ecu paxi>s uv 6 /St'os TOV drOpwrov. Diog. L. ix. 51. HIPPIAS AND PRODI EUS. 2 f were some twenty years younger than Protagoras. The former was best known for his scientific attainments : he is said to have given utterance to the revolutionary senti- ment of the age in the phrase, * Law is a tyrant over men, forcing them to do many things contrary to nature. 1 Prodicus is famed for his moral apologue on the Choice of Hercules narrated by Xenophon. He is reported to have considered the Gods of the popular religion to be merely deified utilities, Bacchus wine, Ceres corn, &c. But the extreme effects of the disintegration of es- tablished beliefs were not seen in the teachers, but in some of their pupils who were less dependent on public opinion, young aristocrats who fretted under democratic rule, and were eager to take advantage of the disorga- nized state of society in order to grasp at power for them- selves. Such was the Callicles of the Gorgias, such Critias and Alcibiades, both disciples of Socrates, of whom we have now to speak. Socrates was bom at Athens 4706.0.; he was the son of Sophroniscus a sculptor, and Phaenarete a mid- wife. While sharing the general scepticism as to the possibility of arriving at certainty in regard to the Natural Philosophy which had formed the almost exclusive sub- ject of earlier speculation, he maintained, in opposition to most of the popular teachers of his time, the certainty of moral distinctions, and laid down a method for the discovery of error on the one side, and the establishment of objective truth on the other. The main lines of his philosophy are given in three famous sentences: (i) that of Cicero, that he brought down philosophy from heaven 28 SOCRATES. to earth 1 ; (2) his own assertion that he practised in re- gard to the soul the art of midwifery (/xcueuri/o?) which his mother had practised in regard to the body, bringing to birth and consciousness truths before held unconsciously 2 ; (3) Aristotle's statement that Socrates was the first to introduce inductive reasoning and general definitions 3 . But more important than any innovation in regard to method was the immense personal influence of Socrates. His force of will, his indifference to conventionalities, his intense earnestness, both moral and intellectual, con- trasting so strongly with the dilettanteism of ordinary teachers, and yet combined with such universal interest and sympathy in all varieties of life and character, his warm and genial nature, his humour, his irony, his ex- traordinary conversational powers, these formed a whole unique in the history of the world; and we can well be- lieve that they acted like an electric shock on the more susceptible minds of his time. For we must remember that Socrates did not, like earlier philosophers, content himself with imparting the results of solitary meditation to a few favoured disciples: nor did he, like the Sophists, lecture to a paying audience on a set subject; but obey- ing, as he believed, a divine call, he mixed with men of every class wherever they were to be found, cross- questioning them as to the grounds of their beliefs, and endeavouring to awaken in them a consciousness of their ignorance and a desire for real knowledge. His own account of his call is as follows : one of his disciples was 1 Cic. Tusc. v. 10. 2 Plat. T/ieaet.\\ 1 49 foil.. 8 Ai'o yap es \6yovs Kal rb oplfcadai Ka66\ov. Arist. Met. M. 4. SOCRATES. 29 told by the Oracle at Delphi that Socrates was the wisest of men. Socrates could not conceive how this should be, as he was conscious only of ignorance; but he de- termined to question some of those who had the highest repute for wisdom; accordingly he went to statesmen and poets and orators, and last of all to craftsmen, but every- where met with the same response: none really knew what were the true ends of life, but each one fancied that he knew, and most were angry when Socrates attempted to disturb their illusion of knowledge. Thus he arrived at the conclusion that what the oracle meant was that the first step to knowledge was the consciousness of ignorance, and he believed, in consequence of other divine warnings, that it was his special mission to bring men to this consciousness. The next step on the way to knowledge was to get clear general notions, by comparing a number of specific cases in which the same general term was employed;! or, according to the phraseology of ancient philosophy, to see the One (the kind or genus, the general principle, the law, the idea,) in the Many (the subordinate species or individuals, the particulars, the phenomena, the facts) and conversely to rise from the Many to the One. The process of doing this he called Dialectic, i.e. discourse, since it was by question and answer that he believed the proposed definition could be best tested, and the uni- versal idea which was latent in each individual could be brought to light. Truth and right were the same for all : it was only ignorance, mistake, confusion which made them seem different to different men. And similarly it is ignorance which leads men to commit vicious actions : no one willingly does wrong, since to do right is the 3 SOCRATES. only way to happiness, and every man desires happi- ness 1 . Thus virtue is a knowledge of the way to happiness, and more generally, right action is reasonable action ; in other words, virtue is wisdom, and each particular virtue wisdom in reference to particular circumstances or a par- ticular class of objects. Thus he is brave who dis- tinguishes between what is really dangerous and what is not so, and knows how to guard against danger, as the sailor in a storm at sea; he is just who knows what is right towards men; he is pious who knows what is right towards God; he is temperate who can always distinguish between real and apparent good. Training therefore and teaching are essential to virtue, and above all the training in self-knowledge, to know what are man's needs and capacities, and what are one's own weak points. No action can be really virtuous which is not based on this self-knowledge. In regard to religion, Socrates, while often employing language suited to the popular polytheism, held that there was one supreme God who was to the universe what the soul of man was to his body, that all things were arranged and ordered by Him for good, and that man was the object of His special providence and might look for guidance from Him in oracles and otherwise. The soul was immortal, and had in it a divine element. Socrates believed that he was himself favoured beyond others in the warning sign (TO 3vioy) which checked 1 Compare Xen. Mem* iv. 8. 6, 'He lives the best life who is always studying to improve himself, and he the pleasantest, who feels that he is really improving,' (aptora fiv rous dpiffra ^7Ti;ueXo- /Lt^i/ous rov ws / fjitvovs ori /SeXn'oi/s SOCRATES. 31 him whenever he was about to take an ill-judged- step l . The personal enmity provoked by the use of the Socratic elenchus^ and the more general dislike to the Socratic method as unsettling the grounds of belief and undermining authority, a dislike which showed itself in the Clouds of Aristophanes as early as 423 B.C., com- bined with the democratic reaction, after the overthrow of the Thirty, to bring about the execution of Socrates in the year 399 B.C. The charges on which he was con- demned were that he did not believe in the Gods of the established religion, that he introduced new Gods, and that he corrupted the young: the last charge probably referring to the fact that Socrates freely pointed out the faults of the Athenian constitution, and that many of his disciples took the anti-popular side. Our authorities for the life of Socrates are the writings of his two disciples, Xenophon and Plato, which are 1 Much has been written on the exact nature of the I take nearly the same view as Zeller (Socrates tr. p. 94), that it was a quick instinctive movement, analogous in its action to what we know as conscience and presentiment, but not identical with either, combining with a natural sensitiveness for whatever was right and fitting the practised tact acquired by large experience of life. To this sudden decisive mandate of the inward monitor, Socrates ascribed a supernatural origin, because he was unable to analyse the grounds on which it rested, attributing it, as he did all other good things, to the favour and goodness of God. We note here an element of mysticism, which showed itself also in the sort of brooding trance to which he was occasionally liable (cf. Plat. Symp. 220). It belonged to his wonderful personality to unite in himself, as perhaps none other but Luther has ever done, robust common- sense with deep religious mysticism, keen speculative interest with the widest human sympathies. 3 2 XENOPIION. related to one another much as the Gospel of St Mark to that of St John. Xenophon (440 355 B.C.) was a soldier and country gentleman with a taste for literature, who endeavoured to clear his master's memory from the imputation of impiety and immorality by publishing the Memorabilia, a collection of his noteworthy sayings and discourses. Other discourses of Socrates are given in his Apologia^ Convivium y and CEco?iomicus. What has been said above as to the method and the belief of Socrates may be illustrated by the following passages from the Memorabilia. In a conversation with Euthy- demus * the question arises as to the nature of jus- tice. To discover what injustice is, it is necessary to consider what kind of actions are unjust. 'It is unjust/ says Euthydemus, 'to lie, deceive, rob, c.' On Socrates reminding him that such actions are not thought unjust in the case of enemies, Euthydemus amended his definition by adding 'if practised on a friend/ 'But,' says Socrates, ' it is not unjust in a general to encourage his soldiers by a lie, or in a father to im- pose upon his child by giving medicine in his food, or in a friend to rob his friend of the weapon with which he is about to kill himself/ Euthydemus has no answer to make, so Socrates turns to^nother point, and asks which is the more unjust, to tell a lie intentionally or unin- tentionally. The answer naturally is that it is worse to lie with intention to deceive. Socrates, arguing on his principle that all virtue is knowledge, asks whether a man must not be taught to be just, as he is taught to read and write, and whether the man who misspells in- 1 Mem. iv. 2. XENOPHON AND PLATO. 33 tentionally does not know his letters better than one who misspells without intending it; whether therefore he who intentionally commits an unjust action must not have a better knowledge of what is just than he who commits it unintentionally, and consequently be a juster man, since justice consists in the knowledge of what is just. Socrates then proceeds to show that Euthydemus' ideas of what is really good are no less confused and self-contradictory than his ideas about justice, and Euthydemus goes away convinced that he knows nothing, and thinking himself no better than a slave. 'Such/ adds Xenophon, 'was a frequent result of conversing with Socrates; in many cases those who had been thus humiliated kept out of his way for the future; these he called cowards; but Euthydemus on the contrary thought his only hope of improving himself was to be continually in the society of Socrates, and Socrates, finding him thus docile and eager to improve, taught him simply and plainly what he thought it most useful for him to know/ I have selected this conversation for the sake of comparison with a conversation on the same subject which I have quoted below from Plato's Republic. It is interesting to note that it ends with a negative conclusion, as so many of the Platonic dialogues do, its object being to destroy a false belief of know- ledge and awaken interest, not to communicate any definite doctrines. The paradox as to the superior morality of intentional wrong-doing reappears in Plato. And no doubt, if we are comparing the moral condition of two persons guilty of the same act of treachery or ingratitude, one of whom did wrong knowing it to be wrong, while the other had no feeling of wrong in M. P. 7 34 XENOPIION AND PLATO. the matter, we should agree with Socrates in considering the latter more hopelessly immoral than the former 1 : but it is plain, from many passages both in Xenophon and Plato, that Socrates was really carried away by his analogy between the art or science of life (which was his view of virtue) and the particular arts and sciences; and that he never gave due attention to the phenomena of human weakness (cx/cparcta) and moral choice (Trpocupco-i?) which were afterwards so carefully analyzed by Aristotle. One other passage from Xenophon may be cited here, as the first appearance of the argument from Final Causes*. Socrates is endeavouring to prove to Aristodemus that the world is the work of a benevolent Creator, not the result of chance. After laying down the principle that the adaptation of means to ends is an evidence of in- telligent activity, he proceeds to point out the adaptations existing between the several parts of man's nature and also between his nature and his environment. Man is endowed with instincts which lead him, independently of reason, to perform those actions which are essential for self-preservation and for the continuance of the species; he has senses capable of receiving pleasure, and he finds objects around him of such a nature as to give him pleasure; he is favoured above all other animals in the possession of hands and in the faculty of speech and the power of thought, through which he is made capable of higher pleasures and brought into communication with higher objects. His consciousness of his own reason is a proof to him of a Reason outside of him, from which that reason was derived. 1 See Arist. Eth. in. i. 14. 3 MM. i. 4, cf. iv. 3. EUCLIDES, ANTISTHENES. 35 Plato is distinguished from the other disciples of Socrates as the one who represents most truly the many-sidedness of his master, completing indeed and developing what was defective in him and incorporating all that was valuable in the earlier philosophers. Before treating of him it will be convenient to speak shortly of the l imperfect' or one-sided Socraticists. Euclides of Megara, the founder of the Megaric and so ultimately of the Sceptic school, was chiefly attracted by the negative teaching of Socrates, and his followers are noted as the inventors of various sophisms which served them as offensive weapons against their oppo- nents. The main positive doctrine attributed to them is that they identified the Good, which Socrates called the highest object of knowledge, with the Absolute One of Parmenides, denying the existence of Evil. Antisthenes, the founder of the Cynic and in- directly of the Stoic school, was the caricature of the ascetic and unconventional side of Socrates. Nothing is good but virtue, nothing evil but vice. Virtue is wisdom and the wise man is clways perfectly happy because he is self-sufficient and has no wants, no ties and no weak- nesses. The mass of men are fools and slaves, and the wise man is their appointed guide and physician. Acting on these principles the Cynics were the mendicant Friars of their lime, abstaining from marriage and repudiating all civil claims, while they professed themselves to be citizens of a world-wide community. On the subject of religion Antisthenes stated explicitly, what was doubtless implied in the teaching of Socrates, that there was only one God, who is invisible and whose worship consists in a virtuous life. 36 ANTISTHENES. The name 'Cynic' may have had a reference in the first instance to Cynosarges, the gymnasium in which Antisthenes taught; but it speedily received the conno- tation of dog-like, brutal, which seems to have been justified by the manners of some members of the school. Diogenes, the more famous disciple of Antisthenes, was fond of speaking of himself as o Ku<;) with all.' Fr. 8 and 15, asked why philosophers seek the rich and not the rich philosophers, he replied, 'because the former know what they need, the latter do not. The physician visits his patient, but no one would prefer to be the sick patient rather than the healthy physician.' Fr. 30, when reproached for his intimacy with Lais, he defended himself in the words l^o) Acu8a a/\\' OVK Ixo/xat. Fr. 53, 'He is the true conqueror of pleasure, who can make use of it without being carried away by it, not he who abstciins from it altogether.' Fr. 50, Dionysius reminded him, on his begging for money, how he had once said that a philosopher could never be in want. 'Give the money.' said he, 'and we will discuss that point afterwards.' 1 See Horace Efp. I. 17. 13 3 2 - PLATO. 4I The money being given, he said, 'You see it is true, I am not in want.' (Compare with this the manner in which he got his wants supplied in shipwreck, Fr. 61.) Among the more prominent members of this school was Theodorus, surnamed the Atheist, who lived towards the close of the 4th century, B.C. Objecting to the doctrine of his predecessor on the ground that it did not leave sufficient scope to wisdom, since pleasure and pain are so much dependent on outward circumstances, he put forward as the chief good, not the enjoyment of passing pleasure, but the maintaining of a calm and cheer- ful frame of mind. The anecdotes related of him have quite a Stoic ring. Thus, when Lysimachus threatened to crucify him, he answers 'keep your threats for your courtiers : it matters not to Theodorus whether his body decays in the earth or above the earth.' Euhemerus, the rationalizing mythologist so much quoted by the Fathers, is said to have been a pupil of his. His contem- porary, Hegesias, called Trcio-itfaKzros from his gloomy doc- trine, considered that, as life has more of pain than pleasure, the aim of the wise man should be not to obtain pleasure, but to steel himself against pain. Thus in the end the Cyrenaic doctrine blends with the Cynic. Plato 1 , the 'dais philosopher urn 1 (Cic. N. D. n 32), was born of a noble family at Athens 428 B.C. and, like his brothers, Glaucon and Adimantus, and his relations Critias and Charmides, became a disciple of Socrates in 408 B.C. After the death of his master he left Athens and lived at Megara with Euclides. From thence he 1 The best complete edition is Stallbaum's with Latin notes, the best English translation Jowett's in 5 vols. Oxford, 1875. 42 PLATO. visited Cyrene, Egypt, Magna Graecia.and Sicily. After nearly ten years of t travelling he took up his residence again at Athens in 389.6.0. and began to lecture in the gymnasium of the Academia. At the request of Dion he revisited Sicily in 367 with a view of winning over Dionysiu's the Younger to the study of philosophy, and again in 361 in the hope of reconciling him to Dion; but he was unsuccessful in Jjoth attempts, and indeed seems to have been himself in considerable danger from the mercenaries of the tyrant. He died in his eightieth year, B.C. 347. Building on the foundation of Socrates, he insists, no less than his master, on the importance of negative Dialectic, as a means of testing commonly received opinions ; indeed most of his Dialogues come to no positive result, but merely serve to show the difficulties of the subject discussed and the unsatisfactory nature of the solutions hitherto proposed l . As he makes Socrates the spokesman in almost all the Dialogues, it is not always easy to determine precisely where the line is to be drawn between the purely Socratic and the Platonic doctrine, but the general relation of the one to the other may be stated as follows. In his theory of knowledge Plato unites the Socratic definition with the Heraclitean Becoming and the Eleatic Being 8 . Agreeing with Heraclitus that all the objects of the senses are fleeting and unreal in themselves, he held 1 These are classified by Thrasyllus as \6yot ^TTJTU-CH, dialogues of search, in opposition to the \67ot v(prjyr}Ti.Koi, dialogues of exposition. Among the sub-classes of the former are the ^ateurt/cot (obstetric), and TretpaariKoi (testing). 2 See Aristotle Met. A 6. 987, M 4. 1078. PL A TO. 43 that they are nevertheless participant of Being in so far as they represent to us the general terms after which they are named. Thus we can make no general assertion with regard to this or that concrete triangular thing : it is merely a passing sensation : but by abstraction we may rise from the concrete to the contemplation of the Ideal triangle, which is the object of science, and concerning which we may make universal and absolutely true predications. If we approach the Ideal from below, from the concrete particulars, it takes the form of the ' class, the common name, the definition, the concept, the Idea; but this is an incomplete view of it. The Ideal exists apart from, and prior to, all concrete embodiment. It is the eternal archetype of which the sensible objects are the copies. It is because the soul in its pre- existent state is already familiar with this archetype, that it is capable of being reminded of it when it sees its shadow in the phenomenal existences which make up the world of sense 1 . All learning is reminiscence 3 . What 1 The reader will remember the magnificent ode in which Wordsworth has embodied Plato's sublime conception. The fact which underlies it was well illustrated by the late Prof. Sedgwick, commenting on Locke's saying that "the mind previous to ex- perience is a sheet of white paper" (the old rasa tabula], "Naked he comes from his mother's womb, endowed with limbs and senses indeed, well fitted to the material world, yet powerless from want of use: and as for knowledge, his soul is one unvaried blank; yet has fhis blank been already touched by a celestial hand, and when plunged in the colours which surround it, it takes not its tinge from accident, but design, and comes forth covered with a glorious pattern." Discourse, p. 53. The Common-sense Philosophy of the Scotch and the d priori judgments of Kant are other forms of the Same doctrine. 2 Cf. Aleno, p.8i, and Grote's Plato n. p. 7, 'Socrates illustrates 44 PLATO. can.not be traced back to this intuitive consciousness in the soul itself is not knowledge, but mere opinion. Dialectic is the means by which the soul is enabled to recover the lost consciousness of the Ideal. The highest Ideal, which is the foundation of all existence and all knowledge, is the Ideal Good or Goodness (77 iSc'a TOV ayaflov), personified in God. He, as the Creator or Demiurgus, formed the universe by imprinting the ideas on formless chaotic Matter. The process of creation is described in the Timaeus under the form of a myth, Plato holding, like Parmenides, that it was not possible to arrive at more than a symbolical adum- bration of physical truth. The cause and ground of creation is the goodness of God, who seeks to extend his own blessedness as widely as possible. He begins his work by constructing the soul of the world out of the two elements before him, the immutable harmo- nious Ideals and changing discordant Matter. This soul he infuses into the mass of matter, which thereupon crystallizes into the geometrical forms of the four elements, and assumes the shape of a perfect sphere rotating on its axis. The Kosmos thus created is divine, imperishable and infinitely beautiful. Further, each the position, that in all our researches we are looking for what we have once known hut have forgotten, by cross-examining Meno's slave; who, though wholly untaught, and never having heard any mention of geometry, is brought by a proper series of questions to give answers out of his own mind furnishing the solution of a geo- metrical problem. From the fact that the mind thus possesses the truth of things which it has not acquired in this life, Socrates infers ^ that it must have gone through a pre-existence of indefinite dura- tion.' The same argument is used in the Phaedo to prove the immortality of the soul. PLATO. 43 element is to have living creatures belonging to it Those belonging to the element of fire are the Gods, both the heavenly bodies and those of whom tradition tells us. All these were fashioned by the Demiurgus himself, but the creatures belonging to the other elements, including the mortal part of man, were the work of the created gods. The immortal part of man, the reason, is of like substance with the soul of the world, and was distributed by the Demiurgus amongst .the stars till the time came for each several particle to enter the body prepared for it by the created gods, when it combined with two other ingredients, the appetitive (TO iiriOv^riKov} and the spirited (TO flu/xoetScs) which it had to bring into subjection. If it succeeded, it returned to its star on the death of the body ; if it failed, it was destined to undergo various transmigrations until its victory was complete. In all these physical speculations Plato was much influenced by the Pvthagoreans. We have now to speak of his ethical doctrines, which were based upon the psychological views mentioned above. The soul is on a small scale what the State, or city, is on a large scale : it is a constitution which is in its right condition when its parts work harmoniously together, when the governing reason is warmly supported by its auxiliary the heart, and promptly and loyally obeyed by the appetites. Thus perfect virtue arises when wisdom, courage and temperance are bound together by justice. The highest good is the being made like to God ; and this is effected by that yearning after the Ideal which we know by the name of Love. Thirty-five Dialogues have come down to us under the name of Plato, the greater number of which are 4 6 PLATO. all but universally acknowledged to be genuine. Five c f these are classified as 'logical' in the catalogue of Thra- syllus; one, the Timaeus, as 'physical;' in the remainder the ostensible purpose commonly is to define the meaning of some ethical term, as the Laches turns on the definition of Courage, the Charmides on the definition of Tem- perance, the Republic on that of Justice. But, in a writer so discursive, and so little systematic as Plato, it is impossible to carry out any strict system of classification: all that can be done is to group different dialogues together from one or another point of view; as we may call the Apology, Crito, Euthyphro and Phaedo Socratic in a special sense, because they give the substance of discourses really held by the historic Socrates. Or again we may trace a gradual progress from the simpler and narrower doctrines of the Protagoras, the Lysis, the Charmides, the Laches, which hardly pass beyond the Socratic point of view, to the Phaedrus, the Gorgtas, the Phaedo, the Symposium, in which the Ideal theory is developed along with the doctrines of pre-existence and immortality; until at length we arrive at the culminating point of the Platonic philosophy in the Republic, that un- surpassable monument of genius, which stands on the same level in the world of speculation, as the Agamem- non or the Parthenon in the world of Art. We may observe the growth of Pythagorean mysticism in the Timaeus; and finally, in the deeply-interesting dialogue of the Laws, we may listen to the sadder and sterner tones in which the aged Plato, summing up his life's experience, confesses that he had been too sanguine in his hopes as to what could be effected by philosophy, and avows his belief that the deep-rooted evil in nature and in PLATO. 4/ man must be traced back to an evil spirit counterworking the action of the divine spirit in the universe 1 ; and that the lessons of philosophy must be supplemented and en- forced by religion, if they are to have a real practical power over the mass of men. In addition to the extant Dialogues, we find references to lectures of a more esoteric character upon the Chief Good, in which the theory of Ideas seems to have been mixed up with quasi- Pythago- rean speculations on the symbolism of Number. Perhaps the best way in which I can employ the brief space at my disposal, in order to give some notion of Plato's manner of treating a subject, will be to append here an abstract of the Republic* ', and then to illustrate, from that and from other dialogues, his three styles, dialec- tical, expository, and allegorical. In the ist Book of the Republic we have an excellent example of a dialectical discussion, which will be given more in detail below; upon the nature of Justice or Righteousness. The conclusion arrived at is that Justice is in all respects superior to injustice, the opposite thesis having been maintained by Thrasymachus, and that the just man is happier than the unjust, not only because he is loved by the Gods and by all good men, but because Justice is that quality of the soul by which it is enabled to perform well its proper functions. Socrates however allows that the discussion had been too rapid, and that they ought to have determined the exact nature of justice before arguing as to its effects. Accordingly in the 2nd Book two of his disciples put forward the difficulties they 1 Cf. x. 896. * On the Republic see the interesting paper by Mr Nettlesliip in 4 llellenica,' and the translation by Davies and Vaughan. 48 PLATO. feel on the subject, and beg of Socrates to prove, if he can, that justice is not only good in its results, but good and desirable in itself. Though men agree to commend justice, yet they generally do this in such a way as to imply that, if a man could practise injustice without fear of detection and retaliation or punishment, he would be happier than a just man who suffered under a false imputation of injustice, particularly if it be true that the favour of the Gods may be won by sacrifices and offerings, irrespectively of the moral character of the worshipper. Socrates commences the expository portion of the dialogue by proposing to examine the nature of justice and injustice on a larger scale in the State. Tracing the rise of the State we shall be able to see how justice and injustice spring up within it. Society is founded in the wants of the individual : men enter into partnership because no one is sufficient to himself. Experience soon teaches the advantages of division of labour: thus one is a husbandman, another a builder, another a clothier; and with the growth of the community a whole class of dis- tributors are needed in addition to the producers. If the State becomes wealthy and luxurious it will speedily be involved in war, and we shall need a standing army of thoroughly trained soldiers. Like good watch-dogs, they must be brave to resist the enemy, while at the same time they are gentle towards the citizens whom they guard. They must be carefully selected and trained up from their earliest years to be true Guardians of the State, trained in mind by music (including under this term literature), trained in body by gymnastics. The earliest training will be that by means of tales partly fictitious and partly true. Tales, such as those of Homer PLATO. 49 and Hesiod, whi^h attribute wicked actions to the Gods, or represent the- heroes as mastered by passion or be- moaning the approach of death, must be altogether excluded, and only such admitted as inculcate truth, courage, self-control, and trust in the unchanging good- ness of God. God, being perfectly good, can never deceive, never be the cause of evil : when he sends what is apparently evil, it is really good in the form of chastisement. But not only the substance of these tales, but the form also must be under strict regulation. The style, the rhythm and the music must all be simple, grave and dignified, expressive of the feelings of a noble and virtuous man, never stooping to imitate folly or vice. Similarly in every branch of art, our youthful Guardians must be familiarized with all that is beautiful, graceful and harmonious, in order that they may learn instinctively to hate what is ugly, and thus may be fitted to receive the fuller teaching of reason, as they advance in years. The use of gymnastic is not only to train the body, but to develop the spirited element in the mind, and so supplement the use of music, which develops especially the philosophic element and by itself might induce too great softness and sensitiveness. For this second branch of education we need the same rules as for the first; it must be simple, sober, moderate. When our Guards have been thus trained, we shall select the ablest, the most prudent, the most public-spirited, to be governors or chief Guardians ; the rest we shall call the ' Auxiliaries.' To prevent jealousies we must instil into all the citizens the belief that the Guardians are born with a certain mixture of gold in their composition, the Auxiliaries with a like mixture of silver, and the inferior classes with M. P. 4 50 PLATO. brass and iron ; that it is the duty therefore of the rulers carefully to test the nature of each citizen, and not allow one of golden nature to remain in a lower class, or one of iron in the higher, since the city is fated to perish if ever brazen or iron men become its Guardians. Finally the Guardians and Auxiliaries are to live together in a camp, having no private property or home, but maintained by the contributions of the other citizens. Otherwise they will become tyrants rather than Guardians, wolves instead of watch-clogs. Adeimantus here objects that the Guardians will be worse off than the other citizens. To which Socrates replies that the end of the true legislator is not to make any particular class happy, but to provide that each class and each citizen shall perform aright their proper function, and thus contribute to the general welfare of the city as a whole. One of the duties of the Guardians will be to take care that the citizens are not unfitted for their work or estranged from each other by the entering in either of poverty or riches. Another will be to prevent the city outgrowing its proper limits and losing its unity in that way: a third to guard against any innovation in the constitution, especially as regards the training of the Guardians themselves. The State being thus fully organized, we have now to look for justice in it. If it is a perfect State, it must possess all virtue, i.e. it must be wise, brave, temperate and just. If we can discover the three former charac- teristics in our State, then the virtue which remains unaccounted for will be justice. Now the State is wise in the wisdom of its Guardians; it is brave in the bravery of its Auxiliaries, who have learnt in the PL A TO. 5 ! course of their training to form a true estimate of what is, or is not, really formidable, and have acquired, through the same training, sufficient strength of mind to hold fast to these convictions in spite of all temptation. Temperance is another name for self-mastery, by which we understand the subordination of a lower self to a higher self in the individual : in our State it will mean the willing obedience of all the citizens to the Guardians who form the smallest class. Finally justice is that principle of conduct which lies at the root of all these, and which we assumed in the very foundation of our State, the principle, namely, that each citizen should do his own work without meddling with others. Our city will be just, as long as each class in it confines itself to its own proper work; it will become unjust, when one class usurps the position of another, especially if a lower class usurps that of a higher. We have now to apply this analogy to the individual. As there are three classes in the State, so there are three parts or elements existing in the individual mind. One is Appetite (TO eTriflv/x^TtKoV), such as we are conscious of when we thirst; another Reason (TO Aoyto-Tt/coV), which at times forbids us to drink, though thirsty; the third Spirit or the sense of honour, (TO flu/xoctSe's), which at times assists the reason to keep under the appetites, at times itself chafes and frets, like a wild horse, under the control of reason. The virtues then of the individual will be analogous to those of the State. He will be wise through the wisdom of the rational element within him ; brave, through the courage of the spirited or irascible element; temperate, through the willing obedience of the two inferior elements to the superior; just, when each 42 5 2 PL A TO. part of the soul performs its own proper function without encroaching upon the others. And this inward harmony will show itself outwardly in just deeds, while injustice is an unnatural discord and disease in the soul, and mani- fests its presence outwardly in all unjust and criminal actions. From this it must follow that justice in itself, apart from its consequences, must be always the greatest good, and injustice the greatest evil of the soul, as health is the greatest good and disease the greatest evil of the body. In the 5th Book Socrates explains at length the community of women and children to which he had before alluded. The greatest evil to a State being separation of interests, and the greatest good being unity of interests and harmony of feeling, it must be our object to weld the whole city into one body, in which every part sympathizes with every other part, and the separate parts cease to talk of 'mine' and 'not mine, ' but all together speak of ' ours/ But, as long as we have separate homes and separate families, we cannot hope for this complete blending of interests. It will be otherwise in our model State. Our women will go through the same training as the men; for the common opinion which restricts all women to a narrow circle of family duties is altogether contrary to nature : women have the same variety of aptitudes and ability as men; they only differ from men in being weaker. As we do not refuse to make use of female watch-dogs because they are weaker than the male, so we shall not forbid a woman to be a Guardian if she shows the requisite qualifications for the office. In regard to the rearing of children, it will be the duty of trie rulers to follow the example of skilful breeders, and PLATO. 53 secure the best offspring by selecting the best parents. No union of Guardians or Auxiliaries will be allowed without the sanction of the rulers, and the children will be removed at once to a state-establishment, where they will be brought up under the charge of nurses, unknown to their parents; but every child will regard every man of mature age as a father; and all of the same age will be to each other brothers and sisters. It is a question how far this ideal is capable of being put into practice. The only chance of it would be by the union of political power and philosophy in the same person. And here it becomes necessary to distinguish between the true philosopher and the pretender. The true philosopher, while he eagerly pursues every kind of wisdom and is enamoured of every kind of beauty, is never satisfied with the contemplation of isolated truths or of individual beautiful objects, but presses onwards till he sees the Ideal itself, which alone is always true, always beautiful, and is the cause of beauty and truth in other things by entering into them and irradiating them with some faint gleams of its own perfection. One who is thus familiar with the Ideal will be most likely to keep continually before his eyes the type of the perfect State, and to make laws in accordance with it. Having his mind occupied by such high thoughts, he will be in no danger from those temptations to voluptuousness, avarice and other weaknesses, which beset ordinary rulers. He will possess in fact those four characteristics which make up perfect virtue. Adeimantus here objects that Socrates' picture of the philosopher is not in accordance with experience. Those who devote themselves to philosophy are generally thought 54 PLATO. useless, if not unprincipled. Socrates replies that this is owing to the corrupt state of public opinion, through which the qualities of mind which go to make a philosopher are perverted by adverse influences, while philosophy is left in the hands of pretenders who bring discredit upon it;- or, if here and there a genuine philosopher is to be found, he is powerless to resist the stream, and is content if he can keep himself pure from the world, and retain the hope of a better life to come. In such a State as we are describ- ing, the philosopher would not only reach a higher stage of growth himself, but he would secure his country's welfare as well as his own. The next point then is to show by what kind of education the Guardians may be raised into philosophers. Besides the tests previously mentioned, they must now be exercised in a variety of studies, terminating in the highest of all studies, that of the Ideal Good, the knowledge of which is needed, if they are to be perfect Guardians. What then is the Ideal Good? Socrates answers by an analogy. The Ideal Good is, in the invisible world, which is apprehended by the intellect and not by the senses, that which its offspring, the Sun, is in the visible world. . As the Sun is the source of life and light to visible things, so the Ideal Good is the source of being and of knowledge in the intelligible world 1 . The use of education is to turn 1 The analogy may be presented in a parallelism, as follows : Sphere. TO oparov the visible. TO vorjrov the intelligible. Supreme Cause. ij\tos. Idea TOV aya6ou. Effect (1) Objective. >^e<7is, 'becoming.' oucrfa, 'being.' ( 2 ) Subjectivo- objcdivc. 0u5s, light. ciX^eta, truth. PLATO. 55 the mind from that which is visible and temporal, and to fix it upon the invisible and eternal. The preparatory studies are Arithmetic, Plain and Solid Geometry, Astro- nomy, Harmonics ; he who has been duly trained in these will be fitted to enter on the crowning study of Dialectic, which does not start with assumed premisses, like the others, but examines and tests the premisses themselves, and will not rest till it has traced back each portion of knowledge to its fundamental idea, and further has seen how all ideas are connected with the Ideal Good. The subject of education being thus completed, the argument proceeds to the consideration of the different kinds of constitution, and the corresponding varieties of character. Since all that has had a beginning is liable to decay, the time will come when the breed of Guardians will degenerate. The spirited or irascible element will (3) Subjective. ci/as, sight. tiriaT-riW, knowledge. Human Organ. o/x/*a, the eye. vovs, the reason. A further parallelism will represent the action of the mind within the two spheres. Thus regarded, the visible world is the sphere of opinion (do^ao-rop), the other of knowledge (yvuvrbv), and both are capable of subdivision, thus : Sofaa-rop, world of opinion. yvwo-Tov, world of knowledge. Object images things mathematical abstractions ideas 1/6770-15, intui- Sidvoia, discur- tion, which Mental e/Katr/a, irforis, sive reasoning, tests hypo- operation. conjecture. faith. starting from hypotheses. theses by the aid of dia- lectic. 56 PLATO. overpower the rational element; and the two upper classes will enslave the third, and devote themselves to wars of conquest. Thus the aristocracy, or govern- ment of the best, will be changed into a 'timocracy' or government of honour, resembling that of Sparta; and corresponding to this we shall have the timocratical or ambitious man. The next stage in the downward progress will be the change from the love of honour and power to the love of wealth, giving rise to an oligarchical government or plutocracy, under which the old harmony will entirely disappear, and the city will be divided into two hostile communities, the few rich opposed to the many poor. Correspondingly to this, when the son of an ambitious father is taught by his father's calamities the danger of ambition, he becomes industrious, prudent and parsimonious, providing the means of enjoyment without the skill or the courage to use them. Democracy is the constitution which succeeds plutocracy, when those who have wasted their property by extravagance offer themselves as leaders to the discontented poor, and with their aid expel the rich and establish equality of rights. The democratical man is one who uses the money left by his father to gratify every impulse and indulge in every amusement, keeping himself however within certain limits of moderation. Lastly we have the passage from demo- cracy to tyranny, when some popular leader has succeeded in putting down an insurrection of the rich, and having surrounded himself with a body-guard proceeds to estab- lish his power by putting to death the bolder and more able citizens, and grinds down the rest by every kind of extortion and oppression. The tyrannical man is the son of the democratical man, but in him the father's various PLATO. cy and comparatively innocent impulses are swallowed up by one over-mastering and lawless passion, which he gratifies at the expense of whatever violence or crime. If the tyrannical man is able to find a sufficient number of followers like himself, he makes himself an actual tyrant in his city and thus attains the summit of wickedness and injustice. And now we have to answer the question which of these conditions is the happiest, which the most miserable. There can be no doubt as to which is the happiest, and which the unhappiest city, but some have maintained that, however unhappy may be the city which is under tyrannical rule, the tyrant himself is happy. But the facts are the same in both cases. As in the State, so in the tyrant, the better part is enslaved to the worse, the soul is for ever agitated by fierce and violent impulses; it is conscious that it is sinking deeper and deeper into wretchedness and crime, and is terror-stricken at the pros- pect of coming vengeance. The same conclusion follows from a consideration of the different kinds of pleasure. Each element of the soul has its appropriate pleasure. Thus he who is governed by reason enjoys the pleasures of wisdom, and extols these above the pleasures derived from honour or from wealth, while those in whom the irascible, or the appetitive element is strongest, magnify these latter pleasures above the former. Whose judgment are we to take? Manifestly that of him who both pos- sesses the faculty of judgment and has had experience of all pleasures, that is, the philosopher; for he alone has the necessary mental qualifications, and has tasted both the pleasures of appetite and of honour; while the other two have never tasted the pleasures of knowledge. Again 58 PLATO. the pleasures which spring from philosophy are the only pure pleasures: other pleasures are for the most part merely negative, consisting in a momentary release from pain. He that drinks only escapes the pain of thirst for the moment, but he who has become conscious of mental emptiness and feels himself replenished by instruction, is nourished by a food more real and true. Further even the inferior pleasures cannot be fully enjoyed except by one in whose soul reason is supreme. Thus we conclude that it is best for every one to be governed by the divine principle of reason residing in his own soul; but if not, that this government must be imposed upon him from without; that the worst of all conditions is to be unjust, and then to evade the penalties by which injustice might be cured and the soul restored to health. In the Tenth book Plato reverts to the subject of poetry and imitation, and lays down the rule that the only poetry allowed in the model State will be hymns in honour of the Gods and of virtuous men. He then introduces a consideration which, he says, adds tenfold force to all that has been urged in favour of justice, viz. the immortality of the soul, for which he gives the following as a new and additional proof. Whatever perishes, perishes in consequence of some particular vice or disease which belongs to it. If there be any thing which can withstand the corroding effect of its own special vice, that thing would be indissoluble and imperishable. The soul is liable to the disease of injustice, but we do not find that it ever dies of this disease. We must conclude therefore that it is imperishable. Thus, in considering the natural consequences of justice, we must not limit ourselves to this life, but must raise our eyes to the eternity beyond. PLATO. 59 As we have proved that justice is in itself best, we need no longer fear that we shall be thought to base its claim on mere accessories, if we view the facts as they really are, and confess that the just man will always be seen in his true character by the Gods, and will be loved and favoured by them, however he may seem to be neglected with a view to his better training in virtue in this life. For it is impossible, we shall say, that he whose chief object it is to grow like to God, should ever be really neglected by him whom he resembles. And as for man, we shall say that, in the end at any rate, justice and injustice will be detected and will receive their due deserts of honour and dishonour. And yet these rewards are nothing in comparison with those which await the just in Hades, as we gather from the story of Er, who was permitted to return to earth after visiting the unseen world, and brought back with him the report of all that he had witnessed there. In dealing with a book so pregnant and suggestive as the Republic, it is difficult to know where comment is likely to be most useful. The few remarks which I am able to make will have reference (i) to Plato's intention in writing the book ; (2) to the circumstances which may have contributed to give it its special form and colouring; (3) to the anticipations of later thought and especially of Christian thought which may be found in it; (4) to the more striking examples of divergence between Plato and the prevalent views of his own or of later times. (i) ' Some have held that the object of the writer is fully given in the name by which the book is commonly known, and that whatever travels beyond political philo- 6o PLATO. sophy is to be regarded as a part of the scaffolding of the dialogue, or put to the account of Plato's incurable love of rambling. Others have been equally sure that the model State is a mere piece of machinery for the exhi- bition of Justice. Others have considered that its main object was to put forward a new theory of Education. The true view is given in a sentence of the Laws, 'our whole State is an imitation of the best and noblest life 1 .' The root or foundation of this perfect life is righteousness, which is no spontaneous product of human nature, but must be fostered by careful training ; and that life cannot be fully manifested except in a community. Next follows the subordinate question, 'Did Plato mean his State to be a practical model, or did he mean it for an ideal, which might guide or suggest legislation, but could not be actually reali/ed in practice?' His own language seems to waver ; thus, while in vi. 502 it is stated that it is indeed difficult to carry out this ideal, but certainly not impossible, if the government were in the hands of philosophers; in ix. 592 Socrates, in reply to Glaucon's remark, that such a city is not to be found on earth, claims no more for it than that perhaps a pattern of it may exist in heaven for him who wishes to behold it, and beholding to organize himself accordingly ; adding that it is of no importance whether it does no\v, or ever will, exist on earth. This double aspect of the State, in which it appears at one time as an improved Greek city, at another as the ideal society, the /foo-tXeia tfeou or rivitas dei, reminds one of the double meaning of Jewish prophecy, by which the changing fortunes of the little 1 Lc%. vil. 817 7rcia*'T/a, ciXXd rd v"ytivd. povov. 7 o PLATO. what is to be understood by 'friends'. Does it mean 'those whom a man thinks honest and good'? Then, since we do not always think aright, it may be just to help the bad and injure the good. Does it mean 'those who are really just, whether we think so or not'? Then it may be just to injure those whom we call our friends and to benefit those whom we call our enemies, reversing the original definition. Thus we arrive at the amended definition ; 'Justice is to help friends, if good, injure enemies, if bad.' Here Socrates lays hold of another point. Is it consistent with justice to injure, to do harm? Harm, in its true sense, means degrading a man in a moral point of view, making him less just, less righteous. Can it be the part of righteousness to make a man less right- eous? [This high view of what is beneficial and what is harmful recurs in p. 379, where it is shown that God harms none. He may punish and indict pain, but it is only to bring out good in the end. Man has no right to harm for the sake of harming. This is the opposite of the old Greek view that the true manly character was shown in the power and will to favour friends and injure enemies.] Polemarchus being silenced, Thrasymachus brings forward a new definition, 'Justice is the interest of the stronger; i. e. of the sovereign power in the state.' 'It is just for the subject to obey his ruler and to act for his ruler's interest.' How then, if the ruler enjoins what is not for his own interest? Then the act will be just by one part of the definition, unjust by the other. PLATO. 7! Amended definition (i) 'What the stronger imagines to be for his interest is just/ Amended definition (2) 'Justice is obedience to the true governor who always enjoins what is for his interest.' But the true governor is one who practises the art of government unmixed with other arts, who is in fact an impersonation of the art. Now, is the notion of self- interest involved in the art? Compare the pilot's art, the physician's art; they may be combined with other arts, but nothing is essential to them beyond the healing of the sick and the management of the vessel. The art simply exercises an oversight over that to which as an art it belongs; but the art is stronger than that which it oversees; therefore the art provides for the interest of the weaker, and the true governor, who personifies the art, will accordingly act not for his own interest, but for the interest of his subjects, who are the weaker 1 . Thrasymachus brings forward an instance on his side; 'why should the ruler, the Troi^rjv Aa Plato means the supposed power, on the part of an unrepentant sinner, to avert the Divine wrath by votive offerings. 80 PLATO. words: *I do not doubt, Socrates, that you are as fully convinced as we are of the impossibility, or at least the extreme difficulty, of arriving at actual certainty in regard to these matters, whilst we are on earth. Still you would justly blame our faint-hearted ness, if we desisted from the search for truth, before we had tried every possible means of attaining it. You would tell us that, if a man has failed to learn the truth from another, or to discover it for himself, it is his duty at any rate to find the best and most irrefragable of human words, and trusting himself to this, as to a raft, to set forth on the hazardous voyage of life, unless it were possible to find a surer and less dangerous way on board a stronger vessel, some word of God 1 . 1 I conclude with one example of Plato's allegorical style, the famous simile of the Cave from the Seventh book of the Republic. ' Imagine human beings living in a sort of under- ground den which has a mouth wide open towards the light : they have been there from childhood and, having their necks and legs chained, can only see before them. At a distance there is a fire, and between the fire and the prisoners a raised way, and a low wall built along the way, like that over which marionette players show their puppets. Above the wall are seen moving figures, who hold in their hands various works of art, and among them figures of men and animals, wood and stone, and some of the passers-by are talking and 1 rbv yovv (BtXriffTov ruv avdpuirlvuv \6yuv \aj3&vTa Kal dvcrc^- \yKT6raTov, tiri TOVTOV 6xovfjt.voi>, uxrirep irl (rxeStas, Kivdvvevovra rbv (3tov, el fJLrj TIS dvvairo aff(f>a\ T ^ & o-\7)6^ tv rois vpaicrois CK TUJV tpyuv /ecu rou /3iou Kpivercu' v rourots yap rb Kvpiov. d-rj rd irpoctpt^va XPV ^ Ta fy7 a Ka ' r v &' LOV <^^/>oi>Tas, Kal ffvvadovTuv ptv rots fyyois diroSeKT^ov, dtaQuvovvTW 5t Xoyous ARISTOTLE. 87 posed to think, as we study his writings more carefully, that no other style could have given so strong an impres- sion of the earnest truthfulness and the philosophic calm of the author 1 . For a further account of the relation between them, I borrow again from Sir Alexander Grant. 1 While Aristotle is far more scientific, he is wanting in the moral earnestness, the tenderness, and the enthusi- asm of Plato... On the other hand he is more safe than Plato. He is quite opposed to anything unnatural (such as communism) in life or institutions... And on all ques- tions he endeavours to put himself in harmony with the opinions of the multitude, to which he thinks a certain validity must be ascribed' (p. 215). l Plato's rich and manifold contributions to logic, psychology, metaphysics, ethics, and natural religion, were too much scattered up and down in his works, too much overlaid by conversa- tional prolixity, too much coloured by poetry or wit, sometimes too subtly or slightly indicated, to be readily available for the world in general, and they thus required a process of codification. Aristotle with the greatest gifts for the analytic systematizing of philosophy that have ever been seen, unconsciously applied himself to the required task' (p. 181.) Thus Plato's Dialectic method was developed by Aristotle into the strict technical science of Logic: Plato's Ideas, though shorn of their separate supra-mundane existence, still survived in the Aristotelian Form, as opposed to Matter. Aristotle distinguished three move- ments or aspects of the former, and, by adding to these the antagonistic principle of Matter, he arrived at his 1 For a more unfavourable view of Aristotle's style, see Cope, Introduction to Aristotle's Rhetoric , p. 132. 88 ARISTOTLE. famous classification of the four Causes, the strictly formal (cl^os, TO TL ?jv ctvat 1 , TJ TrpuTrj ovcrta), the material (v\rj, TO VTTOKtifJLWOV, TO c Ou), the efficient (TO KIVOLT, TO v* ov), the final (TC'/VOS, TO ov eyc/ca), which are really four kinds of antecedent conditions required for the existence of each thing. For instance, in order to the production of a marble statue by Phidias there is needed (i) the pre-existence in his own mind of the ideal form which is subsequently impressed upon the stone ; (2) the existence of the stone; (3) the act of carving; (4) the motive which induced the sculptor to make the statue, as for instance the desire to do honour to the God whose statue it is. Or again, we may illustrate Aristotle's doctrine on this point, and shew how the three aspects of 1 This curious phrase, applying most properly to the creative idea in the mind of the artist, is thoroughly characteristic of the plastic genius of Greece. We may ask, in regard to any work, rl cart ; \vhat is its actual nature ? or we may ask rL TJV ; what is the idea it was intended to embody? And by putting this in a substantival form, ' the being what it was intended to be,' we get an expression for its essential nature or true definition ; see Trendelen- burg's note on the De Anima I. i, 2, Waitz on Anal. Post. I. n. Every concrete object is a combination of pre-existing matter and form : matter being regarded as indefinite, without character or quality, (cf. Met. VII. 10, p. 1036 a. TJ 5' v\r) ciyvwffTOs Ka.6' avTr]i>), all that is characteristic in the object must come from the other element, viz. form, which may therefore be described as that which the thing was, previous to its state of concrete existence. Thus a house consists of bricks or other materials adapted to a certain end, but the thought of this adaptation preceded the actual existence of the house : so, in nature, the tree is a combination of materials grouped according to a certain law or form, but this law was pre-existent in the seed before it was made manifest in the tree, and again it pre-existed in the parent tree before it received a latent embodiment in the seed. ARISTOTLE. 89 Form tend to run into one another, by considering what was the cause of the virtue of Socrates. The material cause here is the existing Socrates with a yet unrealized potentiality of virtue; the formal cause is the virtuous ideal presented to his mind; and this formal cause will also be the efficient cause, in so far as it tends to actualize itself in the concrete Socrates, and the final cause, in so far as the virtuous character is its own end. But the opposition of Form and Matter is not confined to such simple cases; it covers the whole range of existence from the First Matter, which is mere potentiality of being (Swa/us) at the one extreme, to the First Form which is pure immaterial actuality (ci/cpycta), the Divine Being, at the other extreme. The intermediate links in the chain are matter or form according as they are viewed from above or below, as marble for instance is form in reference to stone generally, matter in reference to statue ; vitality is form in reference to the living body, matter in reference to rationality. In this way Matter becomes identified with the logical Genus, Form with the Differentia : as Matter can only attain to actual existence in some concrete shape by the addition of Form, so the Genus is by itself only potential, but attains actual existence in its Species through the addition of the Differentia 1 . The First Form of Aristotle, like the tSe'a TOV dyaOov of Plato, is also the First Mover, the cause of the upward striving of the universe, of the development of each thing from the potential into the actual; and this not by any act of creation, for He remains ever unmoved in His own eternity, but by the natural 1 See Zeller ill. p. 210, Bonitz on Arist. Met. IV. p. 1024 , Grote Arist. II. 341. 9 o ARISTOTLE. tendency which all things have towards Him as the absolutely Good, the object and end of all effort, of all desire 1 . The universe itself is eternal, a perfect sphere the circumference of which is composed of the purest element, ether, and is carried round in circular motion by the immediate influence of the Deity. In it are the fixed stars, themselves divide. All above this Primum Mobile is the abode of divinity, in which there is no body, no movement, no void, and therefore no space and no time. The lower planetary spheres have a less perfect movement and are under the guidance of subordinate divinities. Still, throughout the whole space, from the outermost sidereal sphere down to the lunar sphere, all is ordered with perfect regularity according to Nature. It is only in the sublunary region extending from the moon to the earth, which is fixed in the centre, furthest removed from the First Mover and composed of the four inferior elements with their recti- linear movements, centripetal or downwards in the case of earth and water, centrifugal or upwards in the case of air and fire, that the irregular forces of Spontaneity and Chance make their appearance, and impede or modify the working of Nature. Yet even here we find a constant progressive movement from inorganic into organic, from plant into animal, from life which is nutritive and sensitive only into life which is locomotive and finally rational in man. The human soul is a microcosm, uniting in itself all the faculties of the lower orders of animated existence, and possessing, 1 Aristotle's words KIVC? ws tpupcvov (Met. XII, 7), remind us of the yearning after the First Fair, treated of in the Symposium and other dialogues of Plato. ARISTOTLE. 9 ! besides, the divine and immortal faculty of reason. As each thing attains its end by fulfilling the work for which it is designed by nature, so man achieves happiness by . the unobstructed exercise of his special endowment, a rational and virtuous activity. Pleasure is the natural accompaniment of such an activity. Virtue, which may be described as perfected nature, belongs potentially to man's nature, but it becomes actual by the repetition of acts in accordance with reason. It is subdivided into intellectual and moral, according as it is a habit of the purely rational part of the soul, or as it is a habit of the emotional part, which is capable of being influenced by reason, but not itself rational. Every natural impulse is the potential basis of a particular virtue which may be developed by repeated actions freely performed in accordance with the law of reason so as to avoid either excess or defect. Since man is by nature gregarious, his perfection is only attainable in society, and ethical science is thus subordinate to political science. I have here given the briefest possible summary of Aristotle's general system, as it is contained in the Physica, the Mctaphysica (so called as following the Physica) and the Nicomachean Ethics. Of the latter and of the Politics I have added a fuller analysis below, in order to enable the reader to compare them with Plato's Republic. In the remaining works we have a sort of encyclopaedia of science. The Organon 1 contains the theory of deduc- tive reasoning. It includes (i) the Categories in which 1 There is an excellent edition by Waitz with Latin notes : Mr Poste has brought out an English translation of the Posterior Analytics and Fallacies, with introduction and notes. See also Trendelen- burg's Element a Logic es Aristoleae* 92 ARISTOTLE. all predications are classified under ten heads, Sub- stance (ovo-i'a), Quantity (TTOOTOI/), Quality (THHOV), Relation (Trpos rt), Place (TTOV), Time (TTOTC), Situation (/ccto-^at), Possession (^ctv), Action (Troteu/), Passion (jrda-^iv). Their use may be thus illustrated, * Socrates is a man, seventy years old, wise, the teacher of Plato, now sitting on his couch, in prison, having fetters on his legs, in- structing his disciples, and questioned by them'. It has been often pointed out that the classification here given errs both in excess and in defect, but it has the merit of being the first attempt of the kind. Trendelenburg sug- gests that it was borrowed from the grammatical division of the Parts of Speech. The 2nd of the Logical treatises is the De Interprttatione, dealing with the Proposition, in which the distinction between Contrary and Contradictory, and between Possible and Necessary (' Modal') Proposi- tions, is for the first time clearly explained. In the 3rd, the Analytica, we have the doctrine of the Syllogism set forth with as much completeness as in Whately or Aldrich, together with an account of applied reasoning under the two heads of Demonstration (aTrdScifis) and Dialectic (StaXe/cn/o?'). It further distinguishes between Induction (eVay coy??'),. arguing upwards to Universals from Particulars, which are yvw/H/xorrcpa r\\jlv, more familiar and intelligible to the learner or investigator, and Deduction (cnAAoytoyxds), arguing downwards to Particulars from Universals, which are c^ixrci yvcupijuorrepa, naturally and in themselves clearer and more intelligible. But though Aristotle thus derives the major premiss of the Syllogism from previous Induction, he has nowhere attempted to state the laws of the Inductive process, as he has done those of the Syllogism. He only tells us that the general idea, which ARISTOTLE. 93 Plato thought to be a separate existence known to the soul in a previous state of being, was simply a truth attained by gradual process of Induction, and certified by the un- erring principle of reason (vovs). The steps were percep- tion (reX^xa 77 irputrr) 3 himself knows; and only to that extent is he a good critic. Special points will be judged best by him who has received a special education, and general questions by him who has been generally educated. It follows that a young man is no fit student of our science, having no experience in the affairs of real life, from which our reasonings must be drawn and with which they are concerned. Moreover, as he is prone to follow hi c , passions, it will be idle and profitless for him to listen to moral truths, of which the end is not intellectual* but practical. Whether such a student be young in age or only childish in character, is immaterial, as his incompe- tence is not measured by length of time, but is due to his living, and pursuing his several objects, under the rule of the passions. To such persons knowledge is useless, as it is to those who have no self control; on the other hand to those who shape their desires and regulate their conduct in accordance with reason, it will be highly profitable to be informed on these points. * These remarks may serve as an introduction to indicate who are the proper students of morals, what is the spirit and method with which the subject must be treated, and what is the precise scope of the present treatise.' Aristotle then proceeds, in his usual manner, to ex- amine the opinions current on the subject of the chief good, first premising that, as our reasoning must be drawn from experience, he who is to appreciate its force must have been so brought up as to have this experience at com- mand, i.e. to have the feeling of honour and right, in his own mind. He points out that, while all agree in calling the Chief Good by such names as Happiness, 104 ARISTOTLE. Living-well, Doing-well, there is great dispute as to what these consist in. Judging from people's lives, we may distinguish three main views : the mass hold that v happiness consists in bodily pleasure ; those of a higher class, who are engaged in active life, make it consist in honour; the philosopher makes it consist in thought. The ist is an animal view, the 2nd assumes an end which is precarious, and is sought rather as a means to assure ourselves of our own excellence than as being in itself an end: the consideration of the 3rd is postponed. Then, though reluctantly, he criticizes Plato's ideal good, for * friends and truth being equally dear, we are bound to prefer the truth 1 / The arguments are not very clear 2 , but their general purport is to prove that the * Ideal Good' is something unintelligible, and in any case of no use for practice. Having thus cleared the ground, Aristotle developes his own conception of happiness. It is final, it is self-sufficing (aurapKc?), it must be found in the proper work or function (epyov) of man. The reasoning by which man's happiness is inferred from his Ipyov appears to be as follows. Everything which exists is specially adapted to some special good end (reXos). This adaptation is called the nature (Averts) of the thing. The process by which it arrives at its end is its epyov. Its special excellence (dptT-rj) consists in the per- fection of its 5 actively rational, and such as is found in the best speci- men of man. Thus we obtain the definition: 'the good of man is a putting forth of the faculties of the soul in accordance with his highest excellence, (TO dvOpuinvov dyaOov i/a^T/s Ivepycia yiverai Kara rrjv dpLcnrjv apT^i/). And further we must add Iv ftiu rcXctu) 'in a complete life,' so that nothing may hinder the full development of the eVepyeta. It is shown that this definition embraces all the various characteristics of happiness distinguished by previous philosophers, not excluding pleasure, because virtue is essentially productive of pleasure, and that the highest pleasure. Hence we learn that man is himself the chief source of his own happiness, and that Solon was wrong in saying that no man is to be called happy during his life. Aristotle then proceeds to give a further account of human excellence. Man is a compound of a rational and an irrational nature. Of the irrational nature part is merely nutritive and entirely unparticipant of reason, part is appetitive and impulsive (l7n6vfj.r]Tt,Kov KCU opeKTi/coY) and is capable of being brought into subjection to reason. Human excellence therefore will be twofold, according as it is seen in the purely rational or the semi-rational part. The excellence of the former is intellectual, 6W vorjruaj, the excellence of the latter moral, I^IKT}. (In speaking of the latter the word dpcnj will be translated by ' virtue.') Moral virtue is acquired by practice, just as manual skill is acquired. According to the practice will be the resulting character; by a repetition of brave acts we become brave, &c. ! We start with a capacity (SiW/xis) which may be developed in either direction by 1 K rdv OftotW tvepye&v ai |ets yivovTU* II. I. 7. io6 ARISTOTLE. a series of acts of a definite quality, and thus become fixed in a corresponding habit or tone of mind (If is). In order to become virtuous then, we must first know how to do virtuous actions, to act, that is, in accordance with right reason or the right standard ; and this we shall do by avoiding excess or defect. When a man does such actions wittingly, intentionally, choosing them for their own sakes and taking pleasure in them, and when he is also firmly set in this course, he exhibits all the marks of a formed habit of virtue; of which let this be our definition, *a fixed habit of mind, resulting from effort and principle, which, with reference to our own particu- lar nature, is equidistant from excess or defect ;' to which we must add, that the mean must be determined by reason and as a sensible man would determine it 1 . It must be confessed however that there are exceptions to the definition. We sometimes find a virtue which has nothing to do with a mean, and it frequently happens that a virtue is more opposed to one extreme than to another. A good practical rule is to shun the worse extreme or that to which we are most prone. The Third Book commences with an inquiry into moral responsibility. It is only voluntary acts, that are praised or blamed. An act is involuntary when done ignorantly or under constraint. Of constraint there are two kinds, physical or moral ; it is only the former which is, strictly speaking, involuntary. So of ignorance there are two kinds, ignorance of principles, which is a mark of utter depravity, and ignorance of particular facts, which is excusable if the agent, when better informed, repents 1 ets TTpoatpeTiKri, kv /meajTiiTi o&ra ry vpos ^uas, KCU ws ao 6 ' Tj/xu/). A question has been raised as to the nature of the End which is the object of our wish. The true account seems to be that abstractedly, and to the virtuous man, good itself is the end wished for, but to others the I apparent good. And then arises the question whether vice is really voluntary, if we of necessity wish for the apparent good, which may not after all be the real good. To this it may be answered that it is in our power to be virtuous (and so, to wish rightly), because it is in our power to do the acts which lead to the formation of virtuous habits, and avoid the opposite acts: and that we are thus free, is witnessed to by the whole constitution of society. If it is further argued that we are born dif- ferent, one with an eye for what is good and right, and another without it, we may at least reply that in any case virtue and vice must stand on the same footing as regards freedom, and that our own actions do at any rate contri- bute to intensify this difference. Aristotle then proceeds to the discussion of the io8 ARISTOTLE. several virtues which may as follows with their correspc SPHERE. DEFECT. be presented in a scheme mding extremes. VIRTUE. EXCESS. anticipated deiXia, dvSpeia, Opcurtnp, evils. timidity. courage. foolhardi- ness. bodily plea- avatar 6 rji\orijULiaj 0tXori^c'a, want of spirit. right ambi- wrong am- tion. bition. provocation. aopyijo-la,, Trpaorrjs, <5/rytX6T?7y, dullness. gentleness. irascibility. companion- a.Tr^x^ ia j 0tXia, KO\aKia, ship. rudeness. sociableness. flattery. conversation. elpuvtia, dX77^eia, d\a6veia, self-dispa- sincerity. boastfulness. ragement. recreation. dypoiida, VTpaTT\ia t /3co/xoXox^et, sullenness. urbanity. buffoonery. facing of men. dvatffXvvTta, a/5tos, Kardir\T]i.s, impudence. modesty. bashfulness. the fortunes of eTTLxa-iptKCLKia, Vincent 1 006 i/os, others. malignant indignation. envy. pleasure. is a ' mean,' because the indignant man is pained only at undeserved prosperity, while the envious, exceeding him, is pained at all prosperity, and the malicious is so far defective in feeling pain that heeven rejoices at not prosperity, but adversity, Eth. II. 7. By the time he wrote the Rhetoric , Aristotle had come to see the absurdity of this opposition, and identifies ^irixo-ipcKaKia with envy, Rhet. II. 9. ARISTOTLE. 109 As a specimen of Aristotle's analysis of character, I give an abstract of his remarks on the Brave Man and the Magnanimous or high-minded man. He begins by limiting the sphere of Bravery. Bra- very is not concerned with all objects of fear; e.g. a man is not called brave for being fearless as to disgrace, or to injury which may threaten his family ; but we call him brave who does not shrink from death. He is truly brave who in presence of danger behaves as reason directs and under a sentiment of honour. Suicide is a mark of cowardice rather than of courage. There are five imper- fect forms of courage, (i) that which is produced by a regard to the opinion of others, (2) that which comes from experience, as the sailor's in a storm, (3) that which comes from passion or spirit ; when joined to reason this becomes true courage, (4) that which comes from a hopeful temperament, (5) that which comes from ig- norance of danger. High-mindedness or loftiness of spirit is an accom- paniment and ornament of the other virtues combined. The high-minded man is one who is worthy of the highest honour and rates himself at his true worth. If a man has small worth and rates himself accordingly, we should call him modest. The vicious excess is where a man rates himself above his worth, the vicious defect where he is too humble and rates himself below his worth. The high-minded man will always bear himself with calmness and moderation. He will despise dis- honour, knowing it to be undeserved, and honour too, for this can never be an adequate reward of virtue, though he will accept it as his due from the good. He is ready to bestow favours on others, but scorns to receive them ; no ARISTOTLE. is proud to the great, but affable to the lowly ; will not compete for common objects of ambition ; is open in friendship and hatred ; cares for reality more than for appearance, dislikes personal talk, wonders at nothing, bears no malice, disregards utility in comparison with beauty, is dignified in all his actions and movements. The Fifth, Sixth and Seventh books are taken bodily from the Eudemian Ethics, a sort of paraphrase of the Ni- comachean Ethics, written by a pupil of Aristotle. Some suppose that the Nicomachean Ethics were never com- pleted; perhaps it is a more probable view that these three books were accidentally lost, and that their place was supplied from the paraphrase. Sir A. Grant and others have pointed out slight divergences between the genuine Aristotelian doctrine and that put forward in these books; but, though inferior in force and perspicuity, they may be accepted as supplying a generally faithful representation of the ideas of Aristotle. Justice is the subject of the Fifth Book. The writer begins by distin- guishing two meanings of the term: it either means 'the fixed habit of fulfilling the law,' which is equivalent to virtue in general as displayed towards our neighbour; or it is used in a narrower sense and means 'fair dealing with regard to property/ It is the latter or Civil Justice which is our subject. It is divided into two kinds, Distributive (Scave/^Tt/c?;) and Corrective (SLopOuTLKij). The former assigns to each citizen his due in regard to the honours and burdens of civil life: and that which is due or equal will be discovered here by a 'geometrical propor- tion;' as man is related to man, so must the honour done to the one be related to the honour done to the other. Corrective Justice takes no account of persons, but, when ARISTOTLE. in inequality has been occasioned by injustice, it endeavours to restore equality by an 'arithmetical proportion,' simply subtracting so much from one side and adding it to the other. This latter Justice is the principle of commerce. The simple 'retaliation' of Pythagoras is too rude for either Distributive or Corrective Justice. Just dealing is a mean between injuring and being injured, so that Injustice is both an excess and a defect. Justice in the strict sense exists only between equals who are subject to the same law. It is partly natural, partly conventional. One form of justice is Equity, cTrieiWa. This is a rectification of law in the spirit of the Law- giver, where the law fails to prescribe what is just in the particular case, owing to its generality. The Sixth Book returns to the definition of virtue, and explains the phrase 'right reason' there employed. The soul has been already analyzed into Irrational and Ra- tional; and we have shown that the Moral Excellences, though having their foundation in the former, must be reg- ulated by the latter. It remains to explain how this is done. We begin by sub-dividing the rational soul into the Scientific part (eTncn-^oi/tKoV) which is concerned with necessary truth, and the Calculative or Deliberative (XOJLO-TIKOV, /3ov\evTiKov) , answering to the So'a of Plato, which is concerned with contingent matter. It is this latter kind of Reason which, when combined with Im- pulse (opeis), becomes Trpocu/Dco-is and leads to action. Action itself is of two kinds, Making (77-01770-19) and Doing (7rpais). The rational excellence which is concerned in making is rix v ^ Art, that which is concerned with doing is ^/DoV-qo-is, Practical Wisdom or Prudence. Returning to the eTrto-TTy/xovtKcV, we find two forms of excellence which 112 ARISTOTLE. belong to this head, Intuitive Reason, vovs, the faculty which supplies first principles (ap^ai), and Discursive Reason, CTTICTTT^T;, which arrives at truth by reasoning from the principles supplied by vov?; the combination of the two is called pocrvi>rj, the guard of Prudence), and is strengthened by experience. Without moral virtue, Prudence would be mere cleverness, and without Prudence moral virtue would be only a generous instinct liable to perversion. For complete virtue we need both the impulsive and the rational element. This explains the mistake of Socrates in confounding Virtue with Knowledge. In the Seventh Book we have a fuller account of Temperance and the allied and contrasted qualities, which bears no relation to the previous discussion on the subject. It contains a graduated scale of good and evil states in reference to our power of resisting pleasures and pains. Thus, between divine or heroic goodness on the one side and bestial depravity on the other, we have po(rvinrj, where passion is entirely subject to reason; eyKpareia Continence or Self-control, where reason prevails over resisting passion; dnpaa-ia Incontinence, where passion prevails in spite of the resistance of reason; cxxoXao-ta Intemperance, where reason is entirely subject to passion. ARISTOTLE. 113 Corresponding to cy/cparcta and a/cpa<7ia in reference to pleasure, we have two states distinguished in reference to pain, Kaprcpia endurance, and /txaXaxta effeminacy. The account above given of ctKpao-t'a seems at variance with Socrates' principle that men never do wrong except through ignorance. In what sense is it true that the incontinent man sins against knowledge? Before he is under the influence of passion, he certainly knows that the act is unlawful. But a man may have knowledge without using it, as in slumber; and a man may un- consciously practise sophistry towards himself, allowing the general principle * excess is wrong/ but shutting his eyes to the particular premiss ' to drink this would be excess,' and attending to another principle suggested by passion, ' drinking is pleasant.' Incontinence in Anger is not so bad as incontinence in respect to Lust, because Anger, which kindles on suspicion of wrong, does in a way listen to Reason, though it listens amiss ; also Anger is less deliberate than Lust, and it is accompanied with pain and is less wanton. There are two kinds of incontinence, the one proceeding from hastiness of temper, where a man acts without deliberation ; the other from weakness of will, where he deliberates but cannot hold to his resolve ; the latter is less easily cured. Holding to one's resolve is not always a mark of continence ; it may even be a kind of incontinence, as when a man sticks to a wrong opinion merely from self-will. In Book VIII. we return to the genuine Aristotle. I have thought it worth while to give a somewhat full analysis of the beautiful treatise on x &* TJ ^s l TI rt'Aos, olov rocs a/tytcUots 17 ay>a, X. 4. ARISTOTLE. 123 him \ But it is no wonder that these pleasures are not agreeable to corrupt and degraded natures, nor on the other hand that what they think pleasures are abhorrent to the virtuous man. Aristotle here reverts to his definition of happiness, 'an activity in accordance with excellence,' and preemi- nently with the highest excellence, which is that of the highest part of the soul, the reason (vovt). The highest happiness therefore consists in activity of the reason, i. e. in philosophy (eVe'pyeia OtuprjTLKij). This activity is capable of being sustained longer than any other. It is also the pleasantest, the least dependent on circumstances, and the freest from care ; and it is sought for its own sake without reference to any further result to be gained by it. Such a life of calm contemplation (0ewpia) continued through an adequate period is the highest human happi- ness 2 . Nay, it is more than human, for it is only by virtue of the divine element within him that man is capable of living such a life. And in whatever proportion that 1 ^ffTtv KS TrapatvovvTas dvQpuTTtva " oaov eV5ex erat aOavari^tv KCU TraVra troietv Trpds r6 $rjv Kara rb KpaTiffrov r&v kv oury, X. 7. ARISTOTLE. 125 what have they to do with contracts and deposits? nor brave acts; for what danger can threaten them? nor temperate acts; for what passions have they to need restraint ? And yet the Gods are in the full enjoyment of conscious life. If then this life is not one of action, still less one of production, nothing remains but that it should be a life of contemplation. And thus it is in the contemplative life that man approaches most nearly the eternal blessedness of the Gods. The other ' animals have no share in happiness because they are incapable of contemplation. Something of external prosperity is needed for the putting forth of that activity which constitutes happiness, but the wisest of men are agreed that what is needful is very small. And if there is any providential care of mankind, surely it is reasonable to suppose that he who cherishes reason above all things, and passes his life in harmony with reason, will be dear to those to whom reason is dear, and consequently under the special charge of the Gods and receive from them all he needs. Our theory is now complete, but theory has little influence except with the small minority who are pre- disposed to virtue. The mass of mankind are insensible 4 to appeals to reason or honour. Living by the rule of their passions they know of no higher pleasures than can be obtained through these. What is to be done, if such as these are to be reformed ? Some hold that goodness is a gift of nature, some that it comes from teaching, others that it comes from habituation. If the first is a true account, we can ascribe it only to a special divine blessing ; the second, as we have said, is only efficacious where the soul of the learner has been duly prepared, 126 ARISTOTLE. as soil to receive good seed, by being accustomed to like and dislike as he ought ; when a man is once enslaved to his passions, there is no reasoning with him. We must therefore begin a course of habituation early in life. It is a part of the duty of the State to provide a system of public education and to enforce discipline by punish- ments, and this authoritative control should be con- tinued through the whole of life, as at Sparta. Where such a system does not exist, private individuals should do their best to train and influence for good those who come within their reach. For this purpose it is necessary that they should endeavour to acquaint themselves with the principles of legislation and gain something of the spirit of a legislator. But where and how is this to be learnt? Up to the present time we have nothing but the empirical politics of the statesman, or the doctrinaire politics of the sophist. Aristotle proposes to construct a science of Politics from which to determine the nature of the best State and the laws by which it will train its citizens to virtue. The sequel to the Ethics, as we might infer from the last sentence, is to be found in the Politics. Before proceeding to the analysis of the latter, I will make one or two brief remarks upon the former. First, as to Aristotle's general conception of Ethics, is he to be called a Eudaemonist? So it has often been said, because he makes c^Sat/xoi/ta the end to which man's life and actions should be referred. But the well-being and well-doing, the cru>i'a and cv7rpaia, which constitute the cvSat/xovta of Aristotle, are carefully distinguished from any form of pleasurable sensation. EvScu/juwa with him is a particular ARISTOTLE. 127 kind of putting forth of the powers of the soul, which is intrinsically good by itself, quite apart from the pleasure which, as a matter of fact, attends it like its shadow. Virtuous activity does not become good because it is a < means to pleasure; it is good as being itself the end we should aim at. We admire it in and for itself, as we admire a beautiful statue. This view is of course very far removed from the Epicurean and also from the modern Utilitarian. It agrees with these in so far as it determines the quality of our actions by referring them immediately to an end, instead of to an absolute law, or intuitive conception ot right; but the end is neither pleasure to self nor pleasure to others, but the perfect fulfilment of the tpyov of man. And to know what this perfect fulfilment is, we must fall back on reason em- bodied in the judgment of the wise man. It is no doubt a grave defect in Aristotle's system, as compared with Utilitarianism or with Christianity, that in determining the quality of actions, he only incidentally, as in the dis- cussion on friendship, notices their influence on the well- being of others; in fact, he nowhere gives any clear statement of the grounds of reason on which the wise man founds his judgment as to the virtuous mean. Secondly, as to the doctrine of the 'Mean' itself, I think every one must feel that, while it is highly important to insist on balance, proportion, moderation, as an element of a perfect character, yet to make this the differentia of virtue, is both superficial and misleading. Aristotle himself confesses that the definition is not always strictly applicable; and, if we try to apply it to the higher Christian conception of virtue, as love towards God and Man, it of course fails utterly: there can be no excess of I 2 8 ARISTOTLE. such love. But confining ourselves to cases which Aristotle gives, and where the doctrine of the mean might seem least unsatisfactory, as in the definition of courage, this would seem to imply that there is a certain quality or instinct, which is found existing in three different degrees; a small degree constituting cowardice, a somewhat larger amount courage, a larger still rashness. Whereas the truth is that, while courage and rashness do differ in degree, and spring from the same instinctive root, cowardice differs from them both in kind, and springs from an entirely different instinct. There cannot be less of the natural impulse which, moralized and rationalized, becomes courage, than none at all; yet such a negative state would never give rise to the impulse to run away, which springs from another positive principle, the desire of self-preservation. Aristotle's 'Mean' is in fact an attempt to express two distinct circumstances in regard to the moral constitution of man, one that the several instincts are indeed the raw material of as many virtues, but that, if untrained and unchecked, they run to excess and become vices; and, secondly, that the perfect character is one in which all the various instincts are harmoniously developed, so that the adventurous instinct, for instance, is balanced by the cautious instinct; one giving rise to the virtue of courage, the other to the virtue of prudence. The last point on which I shall touch is the divergence between the Aristotelian and Christian ethics. I have mentioned the absence of benevolence from Aristotle's list of virtues. In this he fails to give a right idea of our relation towards our fellow-men; but the main defects of his system arise from his defective * idea of our relation to God. In regard to theology, as in ARISTOTLE. 129 regard to every thing else, Aristotle seeks to find some confirmation for his own view in the ordinary belief of men. He thinks that the human race is for ever passing through alternate cycles of barbarism and civilization, and that in the traditional beliefs of men we may see, as it were, a ray of earlier light which has not been entirely extinguished in its passage through succeeding dark- ness 1 . [Such is Aristotle's matter-of-fact rendering of the ' Reminiscence ' (dvdfjivrja-is) of Plato *.] It is this primaeval tradition which teaches us that all nature is encompassed by Deity, and that the heaven itself and the heavenly bodies are divine. But this original belief has got incrusted with mythological additions, partly owing to man's natural tendency to generalize his own experience 3 , and attribute to the Gods whatever belongs to himself; and partly to design on the part of legislators with a view to moral or political expediency. While Aristotle considers these fables unworthy of serious atten- tion 4 he is not roused like Plato, to protest against their immoral tendency. Nor, again, will he accept Plato's idea of God as the Creator and Governor of the world. Such an idea appears to him unworthy of the Deity and incon- sistent with the blessedness which we ascribe to Him. The supreme God of Aristotle is the perfection of wisdom, % the never-ceasing cause of all the beauty and order of the universe; but we cannot speak of Him as acting, or, as 1 Cf. Zeller, u. 2. p. 792 with the references, especially Met. xn. 8. 3 See above p. 43. 3 Cf. Pol. I. 2, (jjuwep TO. e'idr) CCLVTOIS d.ofJLOLOu 0(j}V. 4 Met. II. 4, irepl TUV pvOiKus ffO(pi^o^vwv (such as Ilesiod) OVK O^LOV (j.Ta airovS^s VKOTrelv. M.P. 9 130 ARISTOTLE. displaying moral virtue; He is not in any sense a moral Governor ; no idea of Duty or of Sin arises in us at the thought of the relation in which we stand to Him. The same reason may probably explain why humility is treated as a failing; why nothing is said of purity, as distinct from self-mastery; and why the descrip- tion of the crowning virtue of magnanimity, presents so much that is offensive to our present feeling. There is a further difference between the Aristotelian and the Christian views as to the immortality of the soul. Aris- totle, it is true, allows immortality to vovs, the rational element in man, but his statements in regard to the continuance of a separate individual existence after death are extremely vague 1 . The thought of immortality is far from having the same practical influence with him, as it had with Plato. I proceed now to the analysis of the Politics*, which commences, as is usual in Aristotle's writings, with a broad generalization 3 . Every association aims at some good, and the State, as the highest and most comprehensive association, at the highest and most comprehensive good. The elements of 1 See Grant, Ethics of Aristotle I. p. 294 foil. 2 English editions by Eaton, 1855, and Congreve, ed. -2, 1874; a better one of books i, 3, 4 with translation by Bolland and Lang, 1878. See Oncken Staatslehre des Aristoteles, 1877, and an essay on 'Aristotle's conception of the State' by A. C. Bradley in Hellenica. 3 It is a great drawback to this interesting and admirable book that it has come down to us in such a confused and fragmentary state. In my analysis I have arranged the topics in the order which seemed to me most natural, disregarding altogether the order of the books after the first two. ARISTOTLE. ! 3I the State, in the ultimate analysis, are male and female, ruler and ruled. Society originates in the instinctive and necessary combination of these elements, for the sake of the preservation and perpetuation of the race. The simplest form of society is the family, consisting of husband, wife, children, slave. Out of a combination of families is produced the village (KW/ZT;), governed by the eldest progenitor ; out of a combination of villages is produced the complete and self-sufficing organization of the State (TTO'AIS) still under the government of One. Though later in time, this is essentially prior (-Trporepov x y aur?) ffwfypoGvvT) yvvaiKos KCLI di>5p&s, ou5' dvdpla /cat diKaioavvr], KO.6a.Trep (f}ro 2wAc/3a'r?7S, aXX' rj iJ.v apxt-K^, 77 8' i'TrrjpertKT;. Compare, on the difference of the male and female character, (Econ. I. 3, and the very elaborate comparison in the I/Ut. An. IX. i, quoted by Zeller n. i. p. 688. ARISTOTLE. 133 right, without granting to each the enjoyment of that right), this would have no tendency to produce harmony. (2) Such policy would lead to an absence of interest : every man's duty being no man's duty. The sonship pro- posed would be a weaker tie than the most distant relation- ship now recognized. (3) It is impracticable : resemblance would betray the closer relationship. (4) Concealment of relationship would open the door to offences against nature. (5) As regards property, Communism destroys the charm of property and the virtue of liberality 1 . (6) The State is split up into two nations differing altogether in manners and institutions. (7) The argument from the customs of animals (ots oiKovo/zias ovSev pcrcvcrii/, when he sanctions abortion and exposure of infants. The contrast between Aristotle's philosophy of Man and his philosophy of Nature, between the richness of ideas, the exhaustive analysis, the firm grasp of fact, the sound judgment, which characterize the former, and the barren notionalism which is too prevalent in the latter, is a striking justification of Socrates' resolve to keep clear of physics. Aristotle indeed is unfortunate even as com- pared with other ancient writers on the same subject. While Parmenides and Plato, as we have seen, profess to give nothing more than guesses as to the nature of the Universe, Aristotle puts forward his views with an air of scientific precision which makes his mistakes seem all the more absurd; and he often deliberately rejects anticipa- tions of later science which may be found in the writings of his predecessors. Thus Pythagoras having guessed that the earth was a planet moving round the central fire of the Universe, Aristotle rebukes him for not squaring his causes and theories with the apparent facts, but en- ARISTOTLE. ! 39 deavouring to force facts to suit his fancies (De Caclo, n. I3) 1 . So Democritus had already exploded the doctrine of the four elements, substituting for it the more scientific conception of atoms; similarly he had explained circular movement as a resultant of various rectilinear move- ments ; and Epicurus afterwards distinctly controverted the attribution of a natural upward movement to air and fire 2 , as well as the Aristotelian limitation of Space 3 . And yet, if we hold Plato right in describing the philosopher as one who is enamoured of all truth and all knowledge 4 , we can hardly blame Aristotle either for his boundless curiosity in seeking to ascertain facts and causes, or for his endeavour to harmonize all facts, whether of inner or outer experience, and so to build up one all-embracing body of science. No doubt he, like his predecessors, thought the human microcosm to be a truer mirror of the macrocosm than it really is, and was disposed to assume as a law of the objective universe whatever appeared to satisfy our subjective needs and tastes; and yet he made a decided advance by insisting on the importance of observation, and on the necessity of testing theory by comparison with the actual phenomena 5 . Again it is no doubt true that when he 1 It is probable, however, that, in this criticism, Aristotle is thinking chiefly of the Anti-Chthon, invented for the purpose of making up the sacred number Ten. 2 See Lucr. II 185. 3 Lucr. I 958. 4 Rep. v. 475. 5 See Gen. An. ill. 10. 25. * From our reasoning and from the apparent facts, such would seem to be the truth about the bees ; but the facts have not yet been fully ascertained : when they have been, 1 40 ARISTOTLE. ventured into the province of Physical Science, Aristotle was endeavouring to map out a terra incognita which he had no means for exploring. He had neither the methods nor the instruments which were needed: but were men to wait for the microscope and telescope, or for the full development of the various branches of mathematical and physical science, before formulating any ideas on the general character of the universe in which they were placed ? Now, that we know that Aristotle was following a blind path in his endless refine- ments on the meaning of ' motion 1 and similar terms, we may find his physical treatises 'inexpressibly fatiguing and unfruitful 1 ;' but the question is, whether it was not worth while to make some attempt at a working hypo- thesis which might supply men with a framework in which to arrange their thoughts and feelings with regard to the nature of the world around them. There is a value in the prophet's vision as well as in the historian's narrative; and men may be thankful to the philosopher who gives wings to their imagination and extends the limit of their mental horizon, however much he may have failed to anticipate the revelations of modern science. To turn now to the history of Aristotle's writings. All readers of Aristotle have had to complain of the defective arrangement and the general abstruseness of then we must trust observation more than theory, and only trust our theory if it gives results corresponding to the phenomena/ roTs \6yois iriffrevT^ov hv 6iJ.o\oyovfj.et>a kuOffoMFt rots (fxuvofJifroLS. Com- pare a multitude of similar passages in Bonitz's Index under (f>aiv6/j.eva. 1 Lewes Aristotle, p. 127. ARISTOTLE. 141 his works. This has been accounted for, partly, by the supposition that the treatises which have come down to us under his name, consist of notes for lectures hastily revised by himself, or edited after his death by his disciples, and partly by the story, reported by Strabo and others, of their concealment for nearly 150 years in the cellar of Neleus. According to this story, the Library and MSS. of Aristotle passed, at the death of his successor Theophrastus, into the hands of Neleus, a pupil of the latter, and were taken by him to Scepsis, a city which was then under the rule of the kings of Pergamus. These kings appear to have paid little regard to the rights of property in their desire to augment the royal library, which was almost as renown- ed as that of the Ptolemies; and the descendants of Neleus could only preserve their treasures by hiding them in a cellar where they suffered much from worms and damp. When the last Attalus left his kingdom to the Romans in 133 B.C., the then owner of the MSS. brought them out from their concealment and sold them to Apellicon, a Peripatetic residing at Athens, who at once had copies made, and endeavoured, not very succes- fully, to restore the text where it was defective. The library of Apellicon was seized by Sulla on his conquest of Athens in 86 B.C., and transported to Rome, where the Aristotelian MSS. once more fell into the hands of a competent reader in the person of the Rhodian Androni- cus, who brought out a new edition in which the treatises were rearranged and the text much improved. This edition is considered to be the foundation of our existing text of Aristotle. There seems no doubt that somehow or other the abstruser works of Aristotle had been lost to common use not many years afcer his death. Strabo I 4 2 ARISTOTLE. tells us that only a few of the more popular treatises were in the possession of the Peripatetic school at Athens, and this is what we might infer from the manner in which Cicero speaks of the style of Aristotle, 1 using expressions which are certainly anything but appropriate to the books which have come down to us, as well as from the comparative frequency of his references to the lost Dialogues. Again we find in Diogenes Laertius a list taken probably from the catalogue of the Alexandrine Library, containing the names of 146 separate Aristotelian treatises, of which more than twenty are dialogues. This would represent Aristotle as he was known at the beginning of the 2nd century B. c. Our existing Aristotle consists of 46 treatises, very few of which appear in the list of Diogenes. As a specimen of the more popular style by which Aristotle was best known during the interval from Theo- phrastus to Andronicus I insert here a translation of a passage from his dialogue De Philosophia preserved by Cicero (N. D. n. 95). 4 Imagine a race of men who had always lived under ground in beautiful houses adorned with pictures and statues and every luxury of wealth. Suppose that some dim rumour of a divine being had reached them in their subterranean world. Then suppose that the earth were to open and they ascended up from their dark abodes and saw before them all the wonders of this world. Could they doubt, when they beheld the earth and the sea and the sky with its gathering clouds and its mighty winds, and the glory and majesty of the sun as he floods the heaven with the light of day, and then the starry 1 See Acad. II. 119, veniel flumen orationis aureum fun Jens Aristoteles, and the other passages cited in Crete's Aristotle^ I. 43. ARISTOTLE. 143 heaven of night, and the varying brightness of the waxing and the waning moon, and the regular movements of all the heavenly bodies and their risings and settings governed by an everlasting and unchanging law, could they doubt that the Gods really existed, and that these mighty works were theirs ?' With the death of Aristotle a new age begins. The fearless spirit of Greek thought which had soared up- wards as on eagle wings to the empyrean, gazing with Plato on the Ideas clustered around the one supreme Idea of Good, contemplating with Aristotle the Thought of Thought, the Form and End and Cause of all existence, sank back to earth in weariness when once the spell of the mighty masters was removed. A feebler generation followed whose lot was cast in a more ungenial time. As the great prae-Socratic movement had terminated in the scepticism of the Sophists, so this greater movement produced its natural reaction in the scepticism of Pyrrho and the later Academy. Even the dogmatic systems which sprang up along with them, while asserting man's claim to know, yet changed the object and limited the range of knowledge, as it was understood by the preceding age. Lofty idealist systems require strenuous effort of thought and imagination on the part of their adherents, if they are not to wither into mere empty phrases and barren formalism. While the founders live, enthusiastic faith gives a motive for effort, and supplies any deficiency in the evidence demanded by reason: when that first enthusiasm has died away, slumbering doubts awake in the minds of the more independent disciples, and the ruder and coarser among them are likely to seize on some one I 4 4 ARISTOTLE. portion or aspect of the master's teaching, losing sight of its more subtle and refined elements, and to make that stand for the whole ; or perhaps they break away altogether and fall back on some earlier and simpler philosophy. So here, men were not only repelled by the difficulty of understanding what Plato and Aristotle really meant; they had further positive grounds for departing from them when they found them opposed to each other on essential points, such as the nature and import of ideas, when they saw the weaknesses of the former laid bare in the criticisms of the latter, and became aware of the vagueness and uncertainty which characterized the the critic's own utterances in regard to questions of deep practical interest such as the nature of God and the provi- dential government of the world. Under these circum- stances those who still believed that it was possible for men to attain to knowledge, practically limited the range of knowledge to what had reference to man's own immediate use ; all that they asked for was knowledge so far as it is needed to direct the life of man ; and by man they meant the individual standing alone, not man as the citizen of a Greek TTO'AIS. We shall see, when we come to speak of the Stoics, in what way the political circum- stances of the time contributed to this change of view. Again, the abstruseness and indefmiteness, which offended them in preceding philosophers, were especially connected with Ideas and Forms, with the depreciation of the senses and the glorification of incorporeal spirit. All this might be avoided by the assumption that the sole ground of knowledge is sensation, and that body is the only thing which can either act or be acted upon. The post PERIPATETICS. I4 - Aristotelian schools therefore were predominantly ethical, sensationalist, and materialist, as opposed to the idealistic metaphysics of the preceding age. Of these schools the least original and the least important is the Peripatetic. The immediate successor of Aristotle was Theophrastus, whose Characters and treatises on Botany we still possess, together with fragments of other works. He appears to have carried further his master's investigations upon particular points, without diverging from his general principles. Cicero charges him with assigning too much weight to fortune as an element of happiness. Strato, who succeeded him as head of the Lyceum in 287 B.C., dethroned the Nous of Aristotle, and explained the ordered movement of the universe by ascribing * to the several parts of matter an inward plastic life, whereby they could artificially frame themselves to the best advantage according to their several capabilities without any conscious or reflexive knowledge 1 .' Cicero says that he is omnino semovendus from the true Peripatetics, as he abandoned ethics and departed very widely from his predecessors in physics, to which he confined himself. Aristoxenus and Dicaearchus were contemporaries of Theophrastus; the former is chiefly known as the writer of the first scientific treatise on Music, the latter was a voluminous popular writer much esteemed by Cicero. He denied the immortality of the soul. After the time of Andronicus, mentioned above, the Peripatetics were chiefly known as laborious commentators. Cratippus presided over the school during the lifetime of Cicero, who sent young Marcus to Athens to attend his lectures. 1 Cud worth i. p. 149. M. P. 10 146 SCEPTICS. The first name among the Sceptics is Pyrrho of Elis (fl. about 3 20 B.C.), who is said to have had some connexion with the Megarian and the Atomic schools, and to have accompanied Alexander on his expedition into India, and thus learnt something of the doctrines of the Magi and the Indian Gymnosophists. Perhaps the influence of the latter may be traced in the three posi- tions attributed to him, (i) that the wise man should practise CTTOX^, suspension of judgment, (2) that all external things are a'Sia' who endeavoured to strengthen the Academy by uniting Stoic and Peripatetic doctrines with the original Platonism. Further details will be given when we come to speak of the influence of the Roman spirit on the development of philosophy. We turn now to the two most important developments of post- Aristotelian philosophy, Stoicism and Epicurean- ism. To understand them it is necessary to look for a 1 See Zeller in. i. p. 53 1 3 . 2 Cic. Acad. n. 130. STOICISM. 151 moment at the changes which had been brought about by the conquests of Alexander. While Greece proper lost its national life, the Greek language and Greek civilization spread throughout the world, and the Greeks in their turn became familiarized with Oriental thought and religion. Thus the two main supports of the authoritative tradition by which practical life had hitherto been regulated, the law of the State and the old religion of Greece, were shaken from their foundations. The need which was most strongly felt by the best minds was to find some substitute for these, some principle of conduct which should enable a man to retain his self-respect under the rule of brute force to which all were subject. It must be something which would enable him to stand alone, to defy the oppressor, to rise superior to circumstances. Such a principle the Stoics boasted to have found 1 . Zeno, the founder of the school, was a native of Citium in Cyprus. He came to Athens about 320 B.C. and attended the lectures of Crates the Cynic and afterwards of Stilpo the Megarian and of some of the Academics, and began to teach in the oroa Trot/a'Ar; about 308 B.C. He was succeeded by Cleanthes of Assos in Asia Minor about 26oB.c. Among his other pupils were Aristo of Chius, Herillus of Carthage, Persaeus, who like his master was a native of Citium, and Aratus of Soli in Cilicia, the author of two astronomical poems translated by Cicero (N. JD. ii. 104 115). Cleanthes was succeeded by Chrysippus of Soli (b. 280, d. 206), who did so much to develop and systematize the Stoic philosophy that he was called the Second Founder of the 1 See the interesting treatise on Stoicism by W. W. Capes in the S. P.C.K. series, and Essay VI of the Introduction to Grant's Ethics. 152 STOICISM. school 1 . Next came Zeno of Tarsus and Diogenes of Babylon, one of the three ambassadors to Rome in 155 B.C. From this time forward Stoicism begins to show a softened and eclectic tendency, as we may see in Panaetius of Rhodes (180 in B.C.), and also in his pupil Posi- donius of Apamea in Syria, of whom we shall have more to say hereafter. The end of philosophy with the Stoics was purely practical. Philosophy is identical with virtue. But since virtue consists in bringing the actions into harmony with the general order of the world, it is essential to know what this order is, and thus we arrive at the famous triple division of philosophy into physics, including cosmology and theology, which explains the nature and laws of the universe ; logic, which ensures us against deception and supplies the method for attaining to true knowledge; ethics, which draws the conclusion for practical life. The Stoics were famed for their logical subtilties, and are often referred to under the name Diakctici. They in- cluded in Logic both Rhetoric and Grammar, and made great improvements in the theory of the latter subject. The chief point of interest however in their Logic is their theory as to the criterion. They considered the soul to resemble a sheet of blank paper 2 on which impressions (^avrao-tat) were made through the senses 3 . 1 Cf. the line d M ydp fy XpuViTTTros OUAC &v r\v orod. 2 Plut. Plac. Phil. IV. u. 3 Cleanthes held that each impression was literally a material impression on the soul, like that of a signet-ring on wax: Chrysippus thought this inconsistent with the infinite variety of impressions which we are continually receiving, and preferred to speak of them as modifications (^re/>oiwavTaaia a perception that hs a firm grasp of reality 1 . The same irresistible evidence attaches to a TrpoX^ts 2 , but artificial concepts required to have their truth proved by being connected with one or other of these criteria. The ten Categories of Aristotle were reduced by the Stoics to four, (i) the substratum, TO vTroKetjucvov, (2) the essential quality, TO TTOIO'V, (3) the condition, TO TTOJS ex ov > (4) tne relation, TO Trpos TI TTGJS ^x ov - The physical theory of the Stoics is a pantheistic materialism. The only real existences are such as can act and be acted upon, and these are bodies, for like can 1 Zeno compared the simple impression or sensation (0a*>raavTavffi ftp, oirep Ivrl Kara re rrjv aurou KO! Kara rr\v ruv 8\ut>, and Cic. De Off. I. 107. 2 This was called fotprimaconcilidtio naturae, T) irpuT-rj ou-eiWu, sec Cic. Fin. in 16 with Madvig's note. STOICISM. I57 and we come to hate whatever produces that effect. But these prirna naturae^ are not good in themselves, and there is nothing virtuous in the effort to attain them. It is only as the dawning reason of the youth becomes conscious of a wider nature of which his own nature is a part, and of a higher Reason revealing itself in the order and harmony of nature and of human society, that the true Good becomes possible for him, not in the attainment of those primary ends, but in the right choice of the means by which to attain them. . And the right choice is one which is always in accordance with reason and with nature. If he takes the right course, whether he attains those lower ends or not, he has attained the highest end of man, the true Bonum or Honestum. Just as the archer's excellence is shown in aiming rightly, and there is no independent value in the mere act of hitting the target ; so there is no independent value in those prima naturae ; the acting in accordance with nature is all in all 2 . One who has thus learnt to live in accordance with nature is avrap/oys, in need of nothing. He alone is free, for he has all he wishes : his will is one with the universal Will. External good, external evil are matters of indifference (aSia' rjfv.v, the sphere of Trpoalpew according to Aristotle Eth. STOICISM. 159 fixed habit and character, which would control by counter-suggestions the impulse arising at each special moment, particularly all disturbing terrors or allurements, by the reflection that the objects which appear to be desirable, or the contrary, are not really such, but are only made to appear so by false and curable associations. Nothing can really harm us unless we choose to make it do so by allowing it to conquer our reason and will 1 . Pleasure is a natural concomitant (eVtycW^a) of activity, but is not a natural end : not even if we count as pleasure that high delight (x a P<* as opposed to TjSov?;), which belongs to virtuous activity, for pleasure regarded in itself has a tendency to lead man away from the true end, viz. acting not for self, but for the whole. On this ground Chrysippus condemned Plato and Aristotle for preferring the contemplative to the practical life, alleging that the forjner was merely a higher kind of self-indulgence. Man is born for society, he is a member of the great body 2 which includes all rational creatures within it : if he forgets his relation to other men, and only cares to gratify his intellectual tastes, he abnegates his proper place in the world. The feeling of common membership in one body binds each not to justice only but to bene- ficence and to mutual help 3 : above all it constitutes the firmest bond of friendship between those who act up to that membership, so that every wise man is dear to all who are wise, even though he may be personally unknown to them 4 . 1 See Crete's Aristotle, II. p. 446. 2 Seneca Ep. xcv. 52 membra sumus corporis magni. Natura nos cognatos edidit\ Cic. Off. in. 32. 3 Cic. Off. i. 20. 4 Cic. N. D. i. 121. i Co STOICISM. But while on the one hand the consciousness of our being thus bound up with others, as parts of a common whole, supplies a motive for action and forbids all exclusive self-regard, as far as feeling is concerned ; on the other hand the consciousness that the indi- vidual reason (TO AoyiortKoV, TO ifye/Aomcoi/) in each man is a portion of the Universal Reason, a revelation to him personally of the Divine Will 1 , this preserves intact the individuality of each, and enables and requires him to act and think for himself, and to stand alone, regardless of the opinions and wishes of the world outside. It is this sense of independence towards man and of responsibility towards God which especially distinguishes the Stoic morality from that which preceded it. The Stoics may be said to have introduced into philosophical ethics the con- ception of Duty, involving obligation 2 , as distinguished from that of Good, regarded as the desirable or the useful or the beautiful, and of Virtue as the way to this. Not that Duty is with them mere obedience to an external law ; 1 See Chrysippus in Diogenes vn. 88, 'We call by the name of Zeus the Right Reason which pervades the universe ; ' Zeno in Cic. N. D. I. 36 l God is the divine law of nature, commanding what is right, forbidding what is wrong,' Cic. Leg. II. 10, and I. 18, 'Law is first the mind and reason of Jupiter, and then reason in the mind of man;' Leg. I. 33, 'To whom nature has given reason, to them she has given law;' Chrysippus in Plut. Comm. Not. p. 1076 'not even the smallest particle can exist otherwise than as God wills' (aXXws x eiJ/ ^XX* ?/ KaraT^v rou Atos pov\r)(riv) ; also passages from Seneca referred to in a previous note. 2 Compare the Stoic definition of right and wrong as that which is commanded or forbidden by law, TO Karopdw/j-a v6fj.ov Trpoffray/aa efrcu, TO 5' ofjidpr-rj^a v6fj.ov aTrcryopei^a Plut. Sto. Rep. II. I, and other passages quoted by Zeller p. 245. STOICISM. 161 it is also the following of the highest natural impulse (opjjiij) 1 . But impulse by itself is no trustworthy guide. On the contrary it is one chief work of reason in man to subdue and eradicate his irrational impulses. These passions (THX^), as they are called, originate in a perver- sion of the reason itself. The four principal are pleasure and pain, which may be defined as false beliefs of present good or evil ; hope and fear, which are similar beliefs in reference to the future. No man can be called virtuous who has not got rid of all such beliefs and arrived at the state of pure aTrafleta. We may distinguish different virtues in thought, as the Stoics themselves summed up their teaching on this subject under the four Cardinal Virtues, which represent four principal aspects of the one Honestum or Decorum; but in fact no virtue can exist apart from the rest 2 . He who has a right judgment and right intention is perfectly virtuous, he who is without right judgment and intention is perfectly vicious. There is no mean. The wise man is perfectly happy, the fool perfectly miserable : all the actions of the former are wise and good ; all the actions of the latter foolish and bad. There may be a progress towards wisdom, but, until the actual mo- ment of conversion, even those who are advancing (ot TrpoKOTTTovTcs) must still be classed among the fools 3 . Thus in the original Stoicism we have the strange 1 See Zeller ill. i, p. 2?3 3 . 2 So Aristotle had said that all other virtue is involved in 2 STOICISM. union of a highly ideal ethics with a materialistic philo- sophy. But it was impossible to maintain this un- compromising idealism in practice. The later Stoics found themselves compelled to admit that, apart from virtue and vice, the absolute Good and Evil, there were preferences to be made among things indifferent. Some of these, such as bodily health, mental endowments, even wealth and position, were allowed to have comparative value, and, as such, were called TrpoTjy/xcVa, producta or praeposita, ' preferable,' while their opposites were termed aTroTrpo^y/xeVa, rejccta, * undesirable'; and the name aSia'os OVK avayKa^eraLy Kal os ou ^aaavl^eraL, Kal irypov- /xei/os ou ^XaTrrercu, Kal irliTTUV v TO; Tra\aleiv arjTTrjTos CUTI?, Kal TrpiTix<-$(JLvos airo\t6pKr)Tos, Kal irw\ovfJLi'os UTTO ruv iro\fj.l(av ai'dXwTos, and just above, ctav jj. ov 0Aet 6 0e6s, 77/6- Old Faith and the Nw t Eng. tr. p. i6r. STOICISM. I77 to oppose himself with such audacious levity [as the Pessimists do] to the Cosmos, whence he springs, from which also he derives that spark of reason [compare the diroppoLa. and a7rocr7rao-/xa of the Stoics] which he misuses. ...We demand the same piety for our Cosmos that the devout of old demanded for his God 1 . 7 The hymn of Cleanthes may fitly conclude our account of the Stoics. *O Thou of many names, most glorious of immortals, Almighty Zeus, sovereign ruler of Nature, directing all things in accordance with law; Thee it is right that all mortals should address, for Thine offspring we are, and, alone of all creatures that live and move on earth, have received from Thee the gift of imitative sound 2 . Where- fore I will hymn thy praise and sing thy might for ever. The universe, as it rolls around this earth, obeys Thy guidance and willingly submits to Thy control. Such a minister Thou holdest in thine invincible hands, the two- edged thunderbolt of ever-living fire, at whose strokes all nature trembles... No work is done without Thee, O Lord, neither on earth, nor in the heaven, nor in the sea, except what the wicked do in their foolishness. Thou knowest how to make the rough smooth 3 , and bringest order out of disorder, and things not friendly are friendly in Thy sight : for so hast Thou fitted all things together, good and evil alike, that there might be one eternal law and reason for all things. The wicked heed it not, 1 It is worthy of note that Strauss also accepts the Stoic confla- gration, see p. 1 80. 2 The Stoics thought that names were given vv TO, irpayfjiara, see Orig. c. Ceh. I. 24. 8 Literally ' to make what is odd even.' M. P. 12 1 7 8 EPICUREANISM. unhappy ones, who, though ever craving for good, have neither eyes nor ears for the universal law of God, by wise obedience to which they might attain a noble life. But now they think not of right ; but hasten each after their own way, some painfully striving for honour, others bent on shameful gains, others on luxury and the plea- sures of the body. But do Thou, all-bounteous Zeus, who sittest in the clouds and rulest the thunder, save men, from their grievous ignorance : scatter it from their souls, and grant them to obtain wisdom, whereon relying Thou dost govern all things in righteousness; that so, being honoured, we may requite Thee with honour, as it is fitting for man to do, since there is no nobler office for mortals or for gods, than duly to praise for evermore the universal law.' The broad distinction which we noticed at the be- ginning of our history between the Italic or Doric and the Ionic Schools, reappears in the marked contrast between the two materialistic schools of later times. As the Stoics are preeminently Doric and Roman in charac- ter, so the Epicureans are Ionic and Greek. The one might be said to represent the Law, the other the Gospel of Paganism. The former not unfrequently made them- selves odious and ridiculous among the more educated class by their obstinacy, pride and intolerance, their exaggeration, pedantry and narrow-mindedness; while the latter won general favour in society by their freedom from prejudice, their good sense and amiability. But, in spite of this, it was the Porch which was the nurse and school of all that was noblest in the Graeco-Roman world; from it came the patriot, the martyr, the missionary, the hero : EPICUREANISM. 179 it set the example of that renunciation which was followed by the ascetic orders of Christendom ; it supplied to the technicalities of Roman law that ideal element which fitted it to become so important a factor in our modern civilization. On the other hand, if we ask what results proceeded from the Garden of Epicurus, we may point to such a life as that of Atticus, who passed unscathed through the Civil Wars of Rome, retaining the esteem of all parties, and using his influence to alleviate the sufferings of all ; we may see in Epicureanism a needful protest in behalf of the rights of human nature and the freedom of individual thought and feeling, against the oppression of a superstitious religion and an over-strained morality. But it is only as protest and correction that it is of value; its own view of human nature is poorer and narrower than that put forward by any of the systems which it sought to supersede ; it cares not for science in itself, it has no serious regard for truth as such, it offers no spirit-stirring ideal for action ; there is nothing great, generous or self-sacrificing in the temper of mind which it tends to foster and encourage. And popular opinion, which only recognizes broad contrasts, fastened upon the essential differences in the two schools ; it regarded with admiration the lofty character of a Zeno or a Cato, and looked with suspicion upon their Epicurean rivals, as undermining the foundations of religion and morality, and advocating a life of selfish enjoyment. We have comparatively few remains of Epicurean writers, none in fact but the poem of Lucretius, together with some letters of Epicurus and the scarcely legible fragments of Philodemus and others discovered at Her- culaneum; while we have several complete treatises on 12 2 i8o EPICUREANISM. the other side, such as those of Seneca, Epictetus, M. Aurelius, and Cicero's philosophical dialogues. The Christian Fathers also sided strongly with the Stoics against the Epicureans, even going so far as to count Seneca one of themselves, so that the traditional literary view had till lately followed the old popular view. But of late years the pendulum has swung in the other direction, partly owing to more accurate research, which has brought to light the exaggerations of the old view, partly to the present rage for rehabilitating whatever has been condemned by former ages, but more particularly because Epicureanism was identified with the cause of freedom, intellectual, social, moral and religious ; because it was regarded as the forerunner of positive science and of utilitarian morality ; and in a lesser degree because, the great poem of Lucretius having been better edited and more widely studied, admiration for the poet has led to an increased sympathy with the philosophy which he advocates 1 . To what extent these advantages may fairly be claimed on behalf of Epicureanism will perhaps be made clear as we proceed. For my own part I am in- clined to think Cicero was not very wide of the mark when he spoke of it as a ' 'bourgeois philosophy 2 . 7 Whether we have regard to his expressed opinions on science and literature and ethics; or to the naivete of his assumptions, the narrow scope of his imagination, the arbitrariness and one-sidedness shown in his appeals to experience, and the want of subtlety and thoroughness in his reasonings, 1 An example of this change of view, in quarters where it would hardly have been expected, is to be found in Dean Alford's Note on Acts xvii. 1 8. 2 Plebeii philosophi, Tusc. I. 55. EPICUREANISM. 181 Epicurus seems to me to stand out among philosophers as the representative of good-natured, self-satisfied, un- impassioned, strong-willed and clear-headed Philistinism. No doubt it was doing a service to mankind to give any- thing like philosophical expression to such a very im- portant body of sentiment as that with which we are familiar under this name ; but I think Epicurus himself would be not a little surprised, if he could return to life and see the kind bf supporters, aesthetic and other, who have lately flocked to his standard. Historically speaking, Epicureanism may be roughly described as a combination of the physics of Democritus with the ethics of Aristippus 1 . Epicurus (341 270 B.C.) was an Athenian, born in Samos, where he is said to have received instruction in the doctrines of Plato and Demo- critus, though, like Hobbes and Bentham and Comte in later times, he himself always denied his indebtedness to previous thinkers, and stoutly maintained his entire independence and originality of thought. He founded his school at Athens about 306 B.C., teaching in his own 1 Garden/ which became not less famous than the Stoic 'Porch.' Here he gathered around him a sort of Pytha- gorean brotherhood, consisting both of men and women, united in a common veneration for their master 2 , and in a mutual friendship which became proverbial in after 1 See the excellent, though somewhat apologetic, account of Epicureanism by W. Wallace, in the S. P. C. K. series. 2 For the extravagant terms in which the Epicureans were accustomed to speak of their founder, see Lucretius V. 8, deus ille fuit, deus, inclute Memmi, qui princeps vitae rationem invenit earn quae nunc appellatur sapientia, and other passages quoted in my note on Cic. N. D. I. 43. His disciples kept sacred to his memory not only his birthday, but the 2oth day of every month, in ac- ! 8 2 EPICUREANISM. years. All Epicureans were expected to learn by heart short abstracts of their master's teaching, especially the Articles of Belief, Kvpiat So&u 1 , still preserved to us by Diogenes Laertius; and it is said that the last words addressed by Epicurus to his disciples, were to bid them 'remember the doctrines/ /xc/AvvJcrflcu TO>I/ Soy//,aTo>v. The scandalous tongue of antiquity was never more virulent than it was in the case of Epicurus, but, as far as we can judge, the life of the Garden joined to urbanity and refinement, a simplicity which would have done no discredit to a Stoic; indeed the Stoic Seneca continually refers to Epicurus not less as a model for conduct, than as a master of sententious wisdom. It is recorded that, though partly supported by the contribu- tions of his disciples, Epicurus condemned the literal application of the Pythagorean maxim KOIVO, ra <^tAwi>, much as Aristotle had done before, because it implied a want of trust in the generosity of friendship. Among the most distinguished members of the school were Metrodorus, (paene alter Epicurus, as Cicero calls him) Hermarchus the successor of Epicurus, Colotes, Leonteus and his wife Themista, to whom Cicero jestingly alludes in his speech against Piso, as a sort of female Solon, and Leontium the hetaera, who ventured to attack Theophrastus in an essay characterised, as we are told, by much elegance of style 2 . Cicero mentions among his own contemporaries Phaedrus, Zeno of Sidon, called the Coryphaeus Epicureorum cordance with the instructions in his will. Hence they were called in derision efca&oral, see Diog. L. X. 15, Cic. Fin. n. 101. 1 Cf. Diog. x. 12, 1 6, and Cic. Fin. II. 20, quis mini vcstrum non edidicit Epicuri Kvplas 6as? 3 Cic. N. />.!. 93. EPICUREANISM. ^3 (N. D. I 59,) and Philodemus of Gadara 1 : and his ac- count of the Epicurean doctrines is probably borrowed from these. Epicureanism had great success among the Romans 2 ; but, with the exception of the poet Lucretius, none of the Latin expounders of the system seem to have been of any importance 3 . The end of the Epicurean philosophy was even more exclusively practical than that of the Stoics. Logic (called by Epicurus 'Canonic/ as giving the 'canon' or - test of truth) and physics were merely subordinate to ethics, the art of attaining happiness. Knowledge, as generally understood, is in itself of no value or interest, but tends rather to corrupt and distort our natural judg- ment and feeling. Hence we are told that Epicurus preferred that his disciples should have advanced no further in the elements of ordinary education than just so far as to be able to read and write 4 . In particular we are informed that he condemned not only the study of Poetry, Rhetoric and Music, but also those sciences which Plato had declared to be the necessary Propaedeu- tic of the philosopher, Arithmetic, Geometry, Astronomy and Dialectic or Logic, as being at best a frivolous waste of time, dealing with words and not with things, if not 1 Several treatises of Philodemus have been found among the Herculanean papyri. On the relation between his Uepl Evdefielas and Cicero's De Natura Deorum see my edition of the latter, pp. XLII LV. 2 Cic. Tusc. iv 7, Fin. I 25. 3 Cf. Cic. Tusc. II 7, and Zeller ill i. p. 372. 4 Compare his words reported by Diogenes X 6, Tratdctav 5 iraevye ; Quintil. Inst. XII 24, Epicurus fugere omnem disciplinam navigatione quam vdocissima jubet ; and Sext. Emp. Math. 1 1 and 49. 1 84 EPICUREANISM. actually erroneous and misleading 1 . It is possible that these strictures may have had reference not so much to Art and Literature and Science in themselves, as to the manner in which they were then prosecuted, to the 'learned' poetry of Alexandria with its recondite mytho- logical allusions 2 , to the hair-splitting logic of the Me- garic and Stoic schools, and the unreal interpretations of Nature propounded by the great idealistic philosophies; but there is not the least appearance of any real specula- tive interest among the early Epicureans*. If there had been, we can hardly suppose, that they would have spoken of geometry as 'utterly false/ just at the time when the Elements of Euclid, the elder contemporary of Epicurus, had made their appearance amid the general applause of the scientific world 4 . Even their supposed strong point 5 , Physical Science, was not studied by them for its own sake. Epicurus himself distinctly says that 1 See Cic. Fin. I 72, n 12, Acad. n 106, and 97. 8 Metrodorus, however, told his disciples they need feel no shame in confessing that they could not quote a line of the Iliad, and did not know which side Hector took in the Trojan war. 3 Hirzel has shown in his U-utersuchungcn zu Ciceros phifasoph- ischcn Schriftcn,^. 177 foil, that there was an important section among the later Epicureans (probably alluded to in Diog. X 25, as those ous ol yvt](Tioi 'ETrt/coupetot quae caput a caeli regionibus ostendebat horribili super aspectu mortalibus instans, &>c. IQO EPICUREANISM. mention magic and baser forms of superstition, flourished alongside of Epicureanism all through its career, and probably reached their maximum in the first and second centuries of the Christian era 1 .' The fault of Epicurus was that he only saw the bad side of this state of things. He saw, as Plato had done, that ' a corrupt religion gives birth to impious and unholy deeds;' he saw the paralyzing influence of a real belief in the never-ending punishment of sin 2 . Plato's remedy was to train the young in the be- lief of the perfect goodness and justice of God, that so they might learn to trust in His Providence, and receive with meekness His chastisements, knowing that He harms none and punishes only to reform. Epicurus thought there could be no security from superstitious terror unless men could be persuaded that death ended all, and that the Gods took no heed of our actions. Plutarch has well pointed out how little this accords with the experience of life 3 . 'It is far better,' says he, 'that there should be a blended fear and reverence in our feelings towards the Deity, than that, to avoid this, we should leave ourselves neither hope nor gratitude in the enjoyment of our good things, nor any recourse to the Divine aid in our adversity. Epicurus takes credit to himself for delivering us from the misery of fear, but in the case of the bad this fear is the 1 Wallace Epicureanism^ p. 123, Theophrastus Characters xvi. Plutarch De Supcrstitione. 2 See Lucr. I ior, tantum religio potnit suadere malorum, and 107, nam si certam Jinem esse viderent aerumnarum homines, aliqua rations valerent religionibus atque minis obsistere vatum: nunc ratio nulla est restandi, nulla facultas, aeternas quoniam poenas in morte timendumst. 8 The quotation which follows is a paraphrase from the treatise Non posse suaviter vim secundum Epiairum, p. 1 101 foil. EPICUREANISM. 191 one thing which enables them to resist temptation to vice, and in all other cases the thought of God and of a future life is a source of joy and consolation, in proportion as a man has come to know God as the Friend of man and the Father of all beautiful things.' We will now see what was the talisman by which Epicurus endeavoured to arm the soul against the religion which he so much dreaded. The two main principles on which he built his physical system were that nothing could be produced out of nothing, and that what exists cannot become non-existent. From these principles he deduced the truth of the atomic doctrine, differing however from Democritus in one im- portant point, viz. in his explanation of the manner in which the atoms were brought together. Democritus had asserted that the heavier atoms overtook the lighter in their downward course, and thus initiated the collision which finally resulted in a general vortical movement. Epicurus retaining the same crude view of 'up' and 'down' held that each atom moved with equal speed, and that they could only meet by an inherent power of self-movement which enabled them to swerve to the slightest possible extent from the rigid vertical line; and he found a confirmation of this indeterminate movement of the atoms in the free will of man 1 . In other respects there is little difference between the physical views of De- mocritus and Epicurus. Both held that there were innumerable worlds 2 continually coming into being and 1 On the deviation of atoms (Trap^/cXto-is, clinamen), see Cic. N". D. I 69 with my note. 2 Epicurus defined a world as 'a section of the infinite, embracing in itself an earth and stars and all the phenomena of the heavens,' 192 EPICUREANISM. passing out of being in the infinitude of space. Our own world is already showing signs of decay, and is no longer prolific of fresh life as in its beginning. As to subordinate arrangements Epicurus thought it unnecessary and indeed impossible to assign any one theory as certain. It was enough if we could imagine theories which were not palpably inadmissible, and which enabled us to dispense with any supernatural cause. The ex- istence of the present race of animals was explained, as it had been by Empedocles, on a rude Darwinian hypothesis 1 . Out of the innumerable combinations of atoms which had been tried throughout the infinite ages of the past, those only survived which were found to be suited to their environment. The eye was not made to see with, but being made by the fortuitous concourse of atoms it was found on trial to have the property of seeing*. On the nature of the soul and the manner in which it receives its impressions by images from without, Epicurus, in the main, follows Democritus, adding a few unimpor- tant modifications suggested by the subsequent course of speculation. Thus the soul is still made to consist of smooth round atoms, but it is no longer a simple substance : it is partly the irrational principle of life (anima) dispersed throughout the body, partly the rational principle (mens, animus}) concentered in the heart : and the atoms of which both of these are made up, though we must suppose not in the same proportions, have (wpLOXn TtS OVpCLVOV CLffTpCL T KO.I yT]V Kdl TTaVTO. TO, (pCLLVOfJieva TTf/H- <-Xowa) ; such worlds are of every variety of form, Diog. L. x SS. (Hiibner and other editors omit yyv without reason.) 1 Lucr. v 783 foil. 3 Lucr. iv 823 foil. EPICUREANISM. 193 already coalesced into four distinct elements, one resem- bling wind (Trvev/xa, ventus or aura), which predominates in the timid soul of the swift deer, one fire, which shows itself in the fury of the lion, the third air, which gives to the oxen their character of calm repose, midway between burning passion and chill fear; the last element (evidently suggested by the Qidnta Essentia of Aristotle) is name- less, composed of the very finest atoms ; sensation, thought and will, are transmitted from it to the other elements. Death ensues on the severing of the link which binds the soul to the body: the etherial atoms of soul are immediately dispersed into the outer air, the earthy atoms of body gradually fall apart and rejoin their parent earth. Every mental impression is a modification of touch. The images thrown off from the surface of solid objects (crepe/ma) are perceptible by the soul- atoms located in the bodily organs ; but there are more delicate images which are only perceptible by the mind itself: such are the images presented to the mind in slumber, or in thinking of the absent or the unreal. These images are sometimes produced by the coalescence of two or more images as in the case of the centaur, sometimes by a chance concatenation of fine atoms. Often, as in recollection, it requires an effort of mind (eVt/So/Xr/, injectus animi,) to bring the fleeting image steadily before us. It is for the wise man to determine in the case of each image, whether it has a real object corresponding to it. One class of images deserves especial attention. They are those which have led men to believe in the Gods. Shapes of superhuman size and beauty and strength appear to us both in our waking moments and M. P. X 3 194 EPICUREANISM. still more in sleep 1 . These recurring appearances have given rise to an anticipation, TrpoX^t?, of Divinity, of which the essential characteristics are immortality and blessed- ness. The truth of this 7rp6\rj\l/is is testified to by the universal consent of mankind. Taking it as our starting point we may go on to assign to the Gods such qualities as are agreeable to these essential attributes. If, in doing so, we run counter to the vulgar opinion and the many idle imaginations (vrroAa^w) which have been added to the 7rp6Xr]\l/t<;, it is not we who are guilty of impiety, but those who impute to the Gods what is inconsistent with their true character. The idea of blessedness involves not only happiness but absolute perfection. It forbids us to suppose that the Gods can be troubled with the creation or government of a world ; and this conclusion is confirmed by our experience of what our own world is, the greatest portion of it uninhabitable from excess of cold or heat, much of the remainder barren and unfruit- ful, even the best land requiring constant toil to make it produce what is of use to man. Then think of the various miseries of life, to which the good are exposed no less than the bad, all this shows nequaqiiam nobis dhnnitus esse paratam nat ur am rerum ; tanta stat pracdita culpa*. 1 The fact of these 'epiphanies' was generally accepted. For recorded instances see my note on Cic. N. D. I 46. It is not very clear why the appearances of Gods were considered to stand on a different footing from those of departed spirits, which were equally vouched for by experience. See Lucr. IV 32 foil, of the shapes of the dead, which 'frighten our minds when they present themselves to us awake as well as in sleep;' and compare 722 foil, and I 132. Aristotle also referred to dreams as one cause of our belief in Divine beings. 8 Lucr. v 198. EPICUREANISM. 195 There are other more general considerations which point to the same conclusion : for what sudden motive can we conceive which should make the Gods abandon their state of eternal repose, and set to the work of creation, and how, with no model before them, could they know what to make or how to make it; again, how can we possibly believe that any being should be powerful enough to administer, not to say to create, the infinity of nature ? It is equally impossible to ascribe to the Gods such weakness and pettiness of mind as to feel anger or be propitiated with gifts, or to take a fussy interest in the affairs of men. They enjoy undisturbed tran- quillity in some region far removed from our troubled world. This tranquil region Epicurus found in the inter- mundia, the spaces between his countless worlds. He seems to have borrowed the suggestion from Aristotle, who transformed the heaven of the poets into the supra-celestial region where space and time are not, but ' where the things outside enjoy through all eternity a perfect life of absolute joy and peace 1 . 1 But the unchangeableness which belongs naturally to Aristotle's solitary world is altogether out of place in the countless perishable worlds of Epicurus. For successive worlds need not occupy the same point in space nor be made up of the same materials ; new worlds are formed KOL lv KOO-JUO) KOL ev jaTa/cocr/uct>, and their materials may have been either already made use of for the formation of a world or they may be floating loose in an intermundium*. Moreover, during the existence of each world, it is constantly either 1 Arist. De Caclo I 9. 3 Diog. X 89. 132 196 EPICUREANISM. receiving an accession of atoms from the intermundia or, in its later stages, giving them back again. It is plain therefore that Epicurus has failed to find a safe retreat for his Gods in the intermundia and that they are quite as much exposed to the metus ruinarum there as they would have been within the world '. Again, the Gods, like every other existing thing, are made up of atoms and void; but every compound is liable to dissolution ; how is this compatible with immortality ? One answer given was that the destructive and conservative forces in the universe balance one another, but in this world the destructive forces have the upper hand, therefore elsewhere, probably in the intermundia, the conservative forces must prevail*. Another reason was that the atoms of which the Gods are composed, were so fine and delicate as to evade the blows of the coarser atoms n . This idea of the extreme tenuity of the divine corporeity was doubtless suggested partly by the Homeric descrip- tion of the Gods 'who are bloodless and immortal' (//. v 340) and partly by the shadowy idola of the dead, which escape the grasp of their living friends. We find yet another reason assigned, not so much perhaps for the actual immortality of the Gods, as for our belief in it, in the alleged fact of an incessant stream of divine images ), too subtle to impinge on the bodily senses, but 1 Compare Cic. Divin. II 40, N. D.I 18, 53, 114, Diog. x 89, Lucr. II 1105 1174. 3 Cic. N. D. I 50, with my note. 8 See Cic. N. D. I 68 71, and the passage from Herculancnsia, Vol. VI. pt. 2 p. 35, quoted in my note on 71 'no object which is perceptible to the senses is immortal, for its density makes it liable to severe shocks. ' EPICUREANISM. 1 9 7 perceptible by the kindred atoms of mind 1 . Evidently this incessant never-ending influx of divine images is not a thing which can be directly vouched for by any human experience. We are not directly conscious even of the stream of images. All that an Epicurean could say is that we seem from time to time to behold the same glorified form, and that there is some ground for suppos- ing similar appearances during past ages ; that we can only account for such appearances by the supposition of an uninterrupted succession of images continued from a very remote period. But this of course is no proof of immortality : if it were so, we must a fortiori believe the immortality of the sun, or indeed, as the Ciceronian Cotta remarks (N. D. i 109), of any common object, since our ordinary perceptions are due to such an uninterrupted stream of images*. If it is said that we cannot help attri- buting in our thought a permanent unchanging existence to the divine nature, and that this law of thought is only explicable, on the Epicurean hypothesis, by the supposi- tion of an endless stream of images actuating our mind, then the belief in the divine immortality is made the 1 Lucretius (v 1161 foil.) describing how the belief in the gods originated in visions, tells us that they were thought to be immortal, partly because they seemed to be too mighty to be overcome by any force, and partly quia semper eorum subpeditabatur fades rf forma manebat, one image constantly succeeded another giving the impres- sion of a permanent form. There is a similar use of the verb suppedito in iv 776, (where he explains the apparent movements in dreams by the rapid succession of particles, tanta est copia par ticu la- rum ut possit suppeditare] and in Cic. N. D. I 109 (referring to the divine images) innumerabilitas suppeditat atomorum. See for a general discussion on the subject my notes on N. D. I 49. 2 See Lucr. IV 26 foil, Diog. x 48. X 9 8 EPICUREANISM. ground of our belief in the interminableness of images, not vice versa. When we further remember that these countless images are supposed to travel intact all the way from the intermundia, (see Cic. N. D. i 114 ex ipso (dco) imagines semper affluant, and Lucr. vi 76 de corpore quac sancto simulacra feruntur in mentes hominum divitiae nuntia formaej) and to be incessantly thrown off from bodies which were themselves scarcely more than images, we shall not wonder that some of the Epicureans failed to rise to the height of the credo quia impossibile which their system demanded, and fell back on the easier doctrine of Democritus, asserting the divinity of the images them- selves, and deriving them not from the deities of the intermundia, but from the combinations of etherial atoms floating in the surrounding air 1 . 1 This seems to me to be the easiest explanation of the much disputed words of Diogenes X 139, v oXXots 6 rj(ri rous Stout Xcryy ous p^v year apiO/Jiov u^eo-rarraj, ou$ KaO' 6/JLoeidLcu' K TTJS tirippvcrcus rdv 6(j.olw e&cJXttP tirl TO auro aTrorereXecr^va;*' Suis. Hirzelinhis Untcrsitchnngc n zu Cicero* s philosophischen schriften, pp. 46 90, whom Zeller follows in his last edition, p. 431, lias shown, in opposition to Schomann (De Epicuri Thcologia, con- tained in the 4th vol. of his Opuscula\ that there is no reason for altering the text, and that we must accept it as a fact that there were two classes of gods recognized in the Epicurean school, one possessed of a separate individuality and having their abode in the intermundia, the other existing only in virtue of a continuous stream of un- distinguishable images which in their combination produce on our minds the impression of a human form. Zeller thinks that the latter are meant for the unreal gods of the popular mythology, which, like the centaur and every other human imagination, must have their origin in some corresponding image; but the words of Diogenes seem to me to be less appropriate to the very concrete deities of the Greek pantheon than to some vague feeling of a divine presence such EPICUREANISM. 199 Leaving the question of immortality, we pass on to speak of the Epicurean belief as to the shape of the Gods. They derided the spherical mundane God of the Stoics, and held that the direct evidence of visions, no less than the general belief of mankind, testified that the Gods were in the likeness of men. But this might also be proved by reasoning, for experience showed that rationality was only found in human form ; and besides, the human, being the most perfect form, must be that of the most perfect being. Some of the later Epicureans went on to describe in detail the manner of life of their Intermundian Gods. They lived in houses, ate and drank celestial food, needed no sleep, for they were never weary; their chief enjoyment was conversation, which probably went on in Greek or something very like it: in fact they were in heaven what the Epicurean brotherhood was, or strove to be, on earth 1 . Such Gods were worthy of our reverence and imitation, but they were not objects of fear, as they neither could nor would do us harm 2 . While Epicurus agrees with Aristippus in making pleasure the sole natural end of life, the standard of good, as sensation is of truth, he differs from him in attaching more value to permanent tranquillity than to as might be caused by the idola of Democritus. Compare also the parallel passage in Cic. N. D. I 49. 1 See Philodemus, quoted by Zeller, p. 434 foil. 2 Some of the Epicureans seem to have allowed to their Gods a certain influence over the happiness of men ; see the passages quoted from Philodemus irepl eul\ov TTOT Tedvrj&cdai. Diog. 121. 2 Diog. X 121. 8 Diog. x 119. The last clause is added by Seneca, see Zeller, p. 459, n. 204 EPICUREANISM. during grief ."...Once more, if Nature could suddenly utter a voice and rally any one of us in such words as these, " what reason hast thou, O mortal, for all this ex- ceeding sorrow? why bemoan and bewail death? For, if thy life past and gone has been welcome to thee, why not take thy departure like a guest filled with life, and enter with resignation on untroubled rest? But if all thou hast enjoyed has been squandered and lost and life is a grievance, why seek to add more, to be wasted in its turn and utterly lost without avail ? Why not rather make an end of life and travail ? for there is nothing more which I can contrive to give thee pleasure : all things are ever the same."... With good reason, methinks, Nature would bring her charge ; for old things give way and are supplanted by new,... one thing never ceases to rise out of another, and life is granted to none in fee- simple, to all in usufruct... And those things sure enough, which are fabled to be in the deep of Acheron, do all exist for us in this life... Cerberus and the Furies and Tartarus belching forth hideous fires from his throat, these are things which nowhere are, nor sooth to say can be. But there is in life a dread of punishment for evil deeds, signal as the deeds are signal ; there is the prison and the hurling from the rock, the scourging and the executioner, the dungeon of the doomed ; or should these be wanting, yet the conscience-stricken mind through boding fears applies to itself whips and goads, and sees not what end there can be of evils or what limit at last is set to punishments, and fears lest these very evils be aggravated after death, so that the life of fools becomes at length a hell on earth. Remember too that even worthy Ancus has closed his eyes in darkness, who was EPICUREANISM. 205 far, far better than thou, unconscionable man. And since then, many kings and potentates have been laid low, who lorded it over mighty nations. He too, even he who erst made a path for his legions to march over the deep, and set at naught the roarings of the seas, trampling on them with his horses, had the light taken from him and shed forth his soul from his dying body. The son of the Scipios, thunderbolt of war, terror of Carthage, yielded his bones to earth, just as if he were the lowest menial. Think too of the inventors of all sciences and graceful arts, think of the companions of the Heliconian maids ; among whom Homer bore the sceptre without a peer, and he now sleeps the same sleep as others. ..Even Epicurus passed away, when his light of life had run its course, he who surpassed in intellect the race of man and quenched the light of all, as the etherial sun arisen quenches the stars. Wilt thou then hesitate and think it a hardship to die? thou for whom life is well nigh dead whilst yet thou livest and seest the light, who wastest the greater part of thy time in sleep and snorest wide awake and ceasest not to see visions and hast a mind troubled with groundless terror and canst not discover often what it is that ails thee, when, besotted man, thou art sore pressed on all sides with a multitude of cares and goest astray still floundering in the maze of error 1 .' In tracing the history of the post- Aristotelian philo- sophy we have seen that, underneath the antagonisms of the different schools of this period, there was, in the first place, much which they held in common, in opposition 1 Lucr. in 894 1052. The translation is Munro's, slightly altered and abbreviated. 206 ECLECTICISM. to the earlier schools ; and secondly that there was a constant tendency, especially noticeable in the Acade- mic and Stoic schools, to approximate to each other and to modify or suppress their own distinctive characteristics. Partly owing to better acquaintance and improved under- standing of each other's doctrines, and partly as a result of criticism bringing to light the weak points of each, there was a double movement going on, towards eclecti- cism on the one side, as it began to be surmised that the different schools presented different aspects of truth, and towards scepticism on the other side, as it was felt that no school could boast to have attained to absolute truth. This natural tendency of speculative thought was further assisted by the circumstances of the time, especially by the rise of the Roman power and the growing intercourse between Greece and Rome. To estimate the nature and extent of this influence on the ulterior development of philosophy, there are four points to be considered; (i) what new factors were supplied by Rome? or, to express it differently, what were the distinguishing features of the Roman intellect and character before it underwent the process of Hellenizing? (2) through what channels was this process carried on ? (3) what was the result as re- gards the Romans ? (4) how did Rome react on Greece ? As regards (i), if we compare a Roman or a Sabine at the beginning of the 3rd century B.C. with an Athenian, we shall probably find the latter to be a townsman, vain, flighty, impressible, excitable; tolerant and liberal in opinion, and lax, not to say loose, in morality ; of ready and versatile talent, with a taste for literature and art, and a natural fondness for dis- cussion, ever seeking for novelty and amusement; demo- ECLECTICISM. 207 cratic in politics, so far as, under the altered circum- stances of Athens, he still retains any interest in politics ; half sceptical, half superstitious and wholly inquisitive in matters of religion. The former is the contrary of all this, a dweller in the country, fond of home, proud, stubborn, earnest, narrowly conservative, a stern moralist and strict disciplinarian, scorning luxury and refinement, and content to be guided in all things by the wisdom of his ancestors, suspicious of ideas and rhetoric, indifferent to all but practical considerations, aristocratic in politics, with a deep-rooted belief in his traditional religion, as the only foundation and safeguard of the fortune and the great- ness of the city, for which he is at all times ready to sacrifice his life 1 . The contrast was often commented on both by Greeks and Romans. Thus Polybius in the middle of the 2nd century B.C. writes as follows, ' the great superiority of the Romans lies in their religious belief: what is blamed among other men is the foundation of their power, I mean, superstition. They endeavour in every way to heighten the imposing aspect of their religion (eri TOVOVTOV eKTcrpaywS^Tat) and to extend its influence over the whole of life, both public and private. And this seems to be done especially with a view to the common people, for in a state consisting of wise men alone, perhaps such a course would be less necessary. But as the multitude is always frivolous, full of lawless passions and senseless anger, nothing remains but to restrain them by giving form and shape to the terrors of an unseen world (rots aS^Aots irtutis ; ib. v. 61 indicant pueri, in quibus, ut in speculisj natnra cernitur ; Leg. I. 24 animum essc ingcneratum a deo...ex quo efficitur illnd, ut is agnoscat deum, qui undc ortus sit quasi rccordetur ac noscat ; Tusc. I. 35 omnium consensus naturae vox est; ib. I. 65, 70, v. 70, Consol. fr. 6, De Fato 23 foil., Tusc. iv. 65, 79. 1 Tusc. i. 27, 30, 66, Rep. VI. 13, Leg. I. 59 qui se ipse norit, primum aliquid se habere sentiet divinum, ingeniumquc in se sunm sicut simulacrum aliquod dicatum putabit, tantoque miincre deornm semper dignum aliquid ctfaciet ct sentiet ci intelliget qnem ad modum a natura subornatus in vitani vcnerit, qnantaquc instnunenta habeat ad obtincndam adipiscendamquesapientiam, quoniam principio rerum omnium quasi adumbratas intellegentias animo ac mentc conccperit, quibus illustratis sapicntia ducc bonum virum ct ob cam ipsam causam ccrttat se beat um fore. 2 Tusc. I. 70, N. D.I. 60. 3 Tusc. I. 66 nee vero dcus ipse qui intcllegitur a nobis alio modo intellegi potest, nisi mcns soluta quaedam et libcra, segregata ab omni concrctione mortali, omnia sentiens et movcns ipsaquc prafdita motu CICERO. 229 the same is true also of the soul, which is an emanation from Him and which, 'as we have been taught by our ancestors, and as Plato and Xenophon have shown by many excellent arguments/ is destined to enjoy a blissful immortality in the case of the wise and good 1 . Perhaps that which has most weight with Cicero is the practical consideration, 'if we give up our faith in an over-ruling Providence, we cannot hope to retain any genuine piety or religion ; and if these go, justice and faith and all that binds together human society, must go too 2 / He is also fully convinced that reverence is due to what is old and long established, and that it is the duty of a good citizen to conform to the established church, to accept the tenets of the national religion and observe its customs, except so far as they might be incon- sistent with the plain rules of morality, or so flagrantly opposed to reason as to come under the head of supersti- tion. Thus, while he is himself a disbeliever in divina- tion, and argues convincingly against it in his book on the subject, yet, as a statesman, he approves the punishment of certain consuls who had disregarded the auspices. 'They ought/ he says, 'to have submitted to the rule of the established religion.' 3 He cannot approve of the in-. sempitemo ; Rep. vi. 26 foil. Yet he does not altogether deny the possibility of the Stoic view, that God is of a fiery or ethereal nature, Tusc. I. 65. 1 Tusc. I. 70, Lael. 13, Cato 77 foil. 2 See N. D. I. 4 with the passages cited in my note, II. 153, Leg. II. 16. 3 Divin. ii. 71 parendum fuit religioni, nee patrius mos tarn contumaciter repudianduS) and just before, retinetur et ad opinionem vulgi et ad magnas utilitates reipublicae mos t religio^ disciplina, jus, augurium, collegii auctoritas. 230 CICERO. genious defence of divination by the Stoics, any more than he does of their elastic allegorical method, which might be stretched to cover the worst absurdities of mythology. Religion is to be upheld, in so far as it is in accordance with the teaching of nature ; but superstition is to be torn up by the root. Unfortunately Cicero gives no precise definition of the latter opprobrious word, nor does he distinctly say how the existing religion is to be cleared of its superstitious elements. In regard to ethics Cicero openly disclaims the nega- tive view of Carneades 1 , and only wavers between a more or less thorough acceptance of the Stoic doctrine. In general, it may be said that he has a higher admiration for the Stoic system of ethics and theology than he has for any other. Thus he calls it the most generous and masculine of systems, and is even inclined to deny the name of philosopher to all but the Stoics 2 . He defends their famous paradoxes as being absolutely true and genuinely Socratic 3 , and finds fault with Antiochus and the Peripatetics for hesitating to admit that the wise man will retain his happiness in the bull of Phalaris*. Similarly he blames the latter for justifying a moderate indulgence of the various emotions instead of eradicating 1 Leg. I. 39 pcrturbatricem harum omnium rerttm Acadcmiam, hanc ab Arccsila et Carneade recentem exoremus, ut sileat ; nam si invaserit in haec quae satis scitc nobis instntcta ct composite vidcntur, ni it lias edct mi nets. 2 TtiSC. III. 22, IV. 53. 8 Paradoxa 4 mihi ista irapaSo^a maxime videntur essc Socratica longcque verissima, Acad. n. 135. Arguing as a Peri- patetic in the DC Finibus iv. 74, Cicero takes the opposite side. 4 Tusc. v. 75. CICERO. 231 them altogether 1 . At the same time he confesses that Stoicism is hardly adapted for this work-a-day world ; it would be more in place in Plato's Utopia 2 ; when it is attempted to apply it to practice, common sense speedily reduces it to something not very different from the Academy or the Lyceum. Indeed we often find Cicero arguing that the difference is merely nominal, and that Zeno changed the terms, but not the doctrines of the original Socratic school of which these were offshoots 3 . I proceed to give a very brief survey of Cicero's philo- sophical works, all composed, with the exception of the De Oratore, the De Republica and De Legibus, within the last two years of his life. His object in writing them was to give his countrymen a general view of Greek philo- sophy, particularly of its practical side ; and he claimed that in doing this he was labouring for the good of his country no less than, when he had been most active as a speaker in the Senate-House and the Forum 4 . 1 Tusc. IV. $%,mollis et enervata putanda est Peripateticorum ratio et oratio, qui perttirbari animos necesse dicunt csse, sed adhibent modum quendam, quern ultra progredi non oporteat. Modum tu adhibes vitio? and 42 nihil interest utrum moderatas per turbationes approbent an moderatam injustitiam &c ; compare III. 22 and Off. I. 89. On the other hand in the Academica II. 135, where Cicero represents the New Academy, he defends, though in a somewhat perfunctory way, the moderate use of the emotions. 2 Fin. iv. 21, Tusc. v. 3, ad Att. II. i. 3 Fin. v. 22, restantStoici, qui cum a Peripateticis et Academicis omnia transtzilissent, no minibus aliis easdem res secuti sunt. Leg. I. 54, 55- 4 N. D. I. 7 foil, with my notes, Divin. n. i, quaerenti mihi mul- tumque et diu cogitanti quanam re possem prodesse quam plurimts, ne quando intermitter em consider e rei publicae, nulla major occur re- bat quam si optimarum artium vias tradercm meis civibus. 232 CICERO. The earliest of this later group was the Hortensius, written in 46 B.C., but now lost. This was followed by several oratorical treatises. The De Consolatione, also lost, was written on the death of his daughter in 45. Then came the Academica, of which only a portion has come down to us. In this, as has been already mentioned, Cicero defends the doctrine of Probability, as enunciated by Philo, which may be regarded as a softened form of the scepticism of Carneades, against the 'Certitude' of Anti- ochus, the champion of the Eclectics. The Academica would be reckoned with the Topica and the rhetorical treatises, as coming under the head of Logic 1 . Under the head of Ethics we have (i) the De Finibus*, a treatise on the Summum Bomim. In the ist book the Epicurean doctrine is expounded by Torquatus ; in the 2nd it is controverted with Stoic arguments by Cicero; the 3rd book contains an account of the Stoic doctrine by Cato, to whom Cicero replies with an argument taken from Antiochus in the 4th book, in which he endeavours to show, first, that all that is of value in Zeno's teaching is really Socratic, being derived from his master Polemo, and secondly, that the innovations of Zeno, where they are not confined to the use of an unnatural and paradoxical terminology, involve a contradiction between the prima naturae with which he starts, and his final conclusion that virtue is the only good; in the 5th book the doctrine of Antiochus himself it will be remembered that this is an amalgam of the three anti-Epicurean systems is expounded by the Peripatetic Piso. 1 Divin. II. 4, Acad. I. 32. 2 On the plural, see Madvig's ed. Praef. p. Ixi n. It is uncer- tain who introduced the idea of a Summum Malum to correspond with the Summum Bonnm. CICERO. 233 After dealing with the theory of morals in the De Finibus, Cicero goes on to treat of practical morality in the De Offidis (2) addressed to his son, then studying under Cratippus at Athens. In a work intended for direct instruction, Cicero abandons the form of dialogue, which he was accustomed to employ in order to exhibit the views of others without necessarily indicating his own; and lays down in plain terms the principles and rules which he held to be of most importance for the guidance of conduct. It is therefore significant that here, where he is speaking in his own person and not acting a character in a dialogue, he shows himself most distinctively Stoic in doctrine l , though he still only claims to be giving utterance to probabilities not to certainties 2 . The treatise is further of special interest as being the earliest we possess on Duty, and on that conflict between different kinds of Duty or between Duty and Expediency, which forms the subject of Casuistry. In the ist book Cicero treats of the honestum (TO KaXov) subdividing it into the four cardinal virtues, and gives directions for action in cases where one duty seems to conflict with another. In the 2nd he does the same for the utile (TO G) 250 CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS. will to the Divine will, of acting not for private interest but for the good of all. And just as deeper thoughts about the nature of knowledge forced on men the conviction of their own ignorance, so deeper thoughts about virtue made men conscious of their own deficiency in virtue, and produced in them the new conviction of sin. The one conviction taught them their need of a revelation, the other convic- tion taught them their need of a purifying and sanctifying power 1 . And one step more philosophy could take : it chose out for its ideal of humanity, the Zeus-sprung son of Alcmena, whose life was spent in labours for the good of others, and who, after a death of agony on the burning pyre, was received up into heaven, thenceforth to be worshipped with divine honours by the gratitude of man- kind". 1 See above, p. 160 foil. The prevalence of this feeling of guilt and need of atonement is shown by the rapid growth of Jewish proselytism about the time of Augustus, by the new forms of ablution and sacrifice introduced in connexion with the worship of strange deities such as Isis, Serapis, Cybele, Bellona, especially the blood- bath, fauroboliumj which came into vogue in the 2nd century A. D. Virgil in his Messianic eclogue makes the power of cleansing from sin one of the attributes of the new-born King. 2 Cicero and the Stoics continually appeal to the example of Hercules, see Off. HI. 25 'It is more in accordance with nature to undergo the greatest labours and pains in order to save or help mankind, as Hercules did, whom the gratitude of men has placed among the company of the immortals, than to live alone in the highest enjoyment, 'also Fin. II. 118, ill. 66, Tusc. I, 32 'That man is of the noblest character who believes himself born for the assis- tance, the preservation, the salvation, of his fellows. Hercules would never have ranked among the Gods, if he had not paved his own way to heaven, while still on earth,' Hor. Od. ill. 3, 9, IV. 5, 35, 8, 29, Epist. n. i, TO. CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS. 251 Thus far the light of nature had carried men. Here, when it had reached its climax, in the fulness of time, as we believe, the light of revelation was vouchsafed, to confirm its hesitating utterances, to answer its questions, to supply its deficiencies, to manifest before the eyes of men the power of a new life in the Word made flesh. In Christianity we reach the true goal of the ethical and religious philosophy of the Ancients. Christ fulfilled the hopes and longings of the Stoic and the Platonist, as He fulfilled the law of Moses and the prophecies of Isaiah. Here therefore, it seems to me, is the natural place to pause in our sketch of the development of ancient thought and see what was the highest attainment of the human mind, uninfluenced by Christianity. It is true there is one phase of that development, the mysticism of the Neo-Pythagorean and the Neo-Platonist schools, which we shall have to exclude, as it lies still in the future which we forbid ourselves to enter. But Neo- Platonism can, no more than Christianity, be regarded as a simple development of Hellenic or Western thought ; it is a hybrid between East and West. Among its chief precursors we find the Alexandrian Jew Philo, born shortly after the death of Cicero, the object of whose teaching was to harmonize Judaism and Platonism, and Plutarch of Chaeronea, born about 50 A.D., who believed that a divine revelation was contained in the mysterious rites of Egypt no less than in the oracles of Delphi. The mixture of Orientalism is even more marked in the marvellous history of the Neo-Pythagorean Apollonius of Tyana, born about the time of the Christian era, which was afterwards utilized by the opponents of Christianity as a rival to the Gospel history. If then we are to 252 CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS. admit these into a history of Western philosophy, on what principle are we to exclude genuine Greeks and Romans who added to a training in the old systems of philosophy, ideas borrowed, not from Judaism or Zoroastrianism or the religion of Egypt, but from Chris- tianity? For instance, on what grounds are we to exclude Justin Martyr, himself a philosopher by pro- fession, who tells us that he had tried every sect, and at last found in Christianity what he had been vainly seeking in them? or Pantaenus the Stoic, or his pupil Clement of Alexandria, who saw in Christianity the perfect wisdom which united all the broken lights which had been divided in the several schools of the earlier philosophy? Why admit Apuleius, and exclude his fellow-countrymen Tertullian and Augustine, men not only of far greater natural ability, but of keener philo- sophical interest, and probably even better acquainted with the past history of philosophy? Why admit Plotinus and exclude his fellow-disciple Origen ? The difficulty is increased when we remember the mutual influence of the Pagan and Christian philosophy. While some of the Pagan philosophers, such as Julian and Porphyry, owe their significance mainly to the fact that they endeavoured to remodel the old paganism into something which might hold its own against the rising religion; on the other hand many of the heresies were attempts to perpetuate some special doctrine of pagan philosophy' within the pale of the Christian Church. Or we may state the question in another way, as follows : up to the date of the Christian era the history of philosophy has been the history of thought in its most general sense, whether materialistic or CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS. 253 idealistic, whether sceptical or religious. It includes the allegorical mythology of the Stoics and the mysticism of Pythagoras, no less than the logic of Aristotle and the physics of Epicurus. Why then, after this era, are we to confine our attention to a portion, and that the less important portion, of the mental activity of the time? Why are we to turn our eyes exclusively to the philosophy of the Decline, and refuse to see the new life which is springing up by its side ? By so doing, we lose, as it seems to me, one of the most interesting and instructive of spectacles; we spoil our view of history, and do injustice to both sides, while we insist on keeping them separate from each other, It is a partial but, so far as it goes, a true account of Christianity that it is the meeting-point of Judaism and Hellenism. We get a very wrong impression of the early Christian writers, if we disregard the Hellenic element in them. We should be able to judge more fairly of many of the Fathers, if we regarded them as successors of the philo- sophers, especially of practical teachers such as Epictetus and Dio Chrysostom, instead of treating them as channels of a sort of supernatural tradition. Superstitious reverence for their supposed authority makes it impossible to appreciate their real greatness as men. I think therefore that, after the rise of Christianity, Christian and Pagan philosophy should be treated of together, until the time when the West was again separated from the East, and Western thought was crushed under the invasion of the barbarians. To give an accurate picture of the religious thought of the first four centuries after Christ, (and all thought was then more or less religious), to exhibit it in its relation 254 CONCLUDING REFLEXIONS. not only to the earlier philosophical ideas, but to* the con- temporary religious systems of Egypt and the East, is a work which still remains to be done, and one which would require a variety of the highest qualities for its adequate performance. I have been merely occupied here with the preliminary inquiry as to the manner in which the philosophy of Greece prepared the way for that great central epoch of all human history ; to show how, in the words of Clement of Alexandria, 'philosophy was to the Greek, what the Law was to the Jew, the schoolmaster to bring him to Christ 1 / It has therefore been my endeavour, while tracing the general development of philosophy in accordance with the lines laid down by Zeller, to note particularly the interaction of religion and philosophy, and show how the early hostility gave place to sympathy, as out of the old corrupt religion the form of a purer religion gradually disclosed itself to the mind of the philosopher, and philosophy itself learnt from fuller experience to distrust its own power whether of attaining to absolute truth or of moulding the character to virtue. 1 Clem. Al, Strom, I. 5 p. 122. CAMBRIDGE: PRINTED nv c. j CLAY, M.A. AT THE UNIVERSITY THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL PINE OF 25 CENTS WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $I.OO ON THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE. SEP 1937 8 im MAY 6 JUN ZV 1944 YB :