ALVMHVS BOOK FYND 
 
Digitized by the Internet Archive 
 
 in 2007 with funding from 
 
 Microsoft Corporation 
 
 http://www.archive.org/details/ethicsgeneralspeOOhillrich 
 
ETHICS 
 GENERAL AND SPECIAL 
 
THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 HKW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO • DAUAS 
 ATLAKTA • SAN FKANCISCO 
 
 MACMILLAN & CO., Limited 
 
 LONDON • BOMBAY • CALCUTTA 
 MELBOURNK 
 
 THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ln>. 
 
 TORONTO 
 
ETHICS 
 
 GENERAL AND SPECIAL 
 
 BY 
 
 OWEN A. HILL, S.J., Ph.D. 
 
 Lecturer on Psychology, Natural Theology, Ethics 
 and Religion, at Fordham University, 
 New York City, N. Y. 
 
 iiaeto gotfe 
 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 1920 
 
 AU rights reserved 
 

 OOPTEIGHT, 1920, 
 
 By the MACMILLAN COMPANY 
 
 Set up and electrotyped. PubUshed, July, 1920 
 
 !'• 
 
 1 
 
 r 
 
 i^iy:\.l "^f . 'V. 
 
Jtsqtrimi patteL 
 
 JOSEPHUS H. ROCKWELL, S.J., 
 
 Praepositus Prov. Marylandiae Neo-Ehoracensis. 
 
 N!1|U obBtat 
 
 ARTHURUS J. SCANLAN, S.T.D., 
 
 Censor Librorum. 
 
 Imiiriinatnr. 
 
 PATRITIUS J. HAYES, D.D., 
 
 Archiepiscopus Neo-Ehoracensis. 
 
 Neo-Ebobaci, die 15 Aprilis, 1920. 
 
 435851 
 
FREFACB 
 
 The whole trouble with all Modern Philosophy is rank sub- 
 jectivism, and subjectivism is, perhaps, most destructive in 
 the domain of Ethics. Protestantism and Modern Philosophy 
 grow on the same tree, and the root of the tree is subjectivism. 
 This fact accounts for all the atheism, all the materialism, all 
 the socialism in the world. It is to blame for all the irreli- 
 gion, all the injustice, all the tyranny now afflicting large and 
 small nations; and the World War did not settle matters, 
 the Peace Conference, in spite of all its good intentions, prac- 
 tically left things where it found them. Evils persevere as 
 long as their causes; and till men think right, till Modern 
 Philosophy js killed from men's minds, till Scholastic Phi- 
 losophy gets everywhere the hearing it deserves, these evils, 
 far from being eliminated, will prosper, grow and multiply. 
 No body of men can regulate mankind, unless mankind itself 
 is amenable to direction, unless mankind entertains correct 
 notions regarding God, the Soul, and the nature of author- 
 ity. I^aws are no better than the men who make them, and 
 laws are little worth, unless subjects are minded to see and 
 obey divinity in them. It is awfully hard, in fact it is im- 
 possible, to persuade anybody to think that any single man 
 or any collection of men, whether a majority or a minority, 
 possess independent right over the free wills of other men, 
 and are empowered to make and execute laws on their own 
 initiative. God alone holds that supreme prerogative; and 
 this fact is clear proof not only that all authority is imme- 
 diately from God, but also that all authority passes imme- 
 diately from God to ruler, without effective interference with 
 authority itself on the part of the people. God is immediate 
 maker of the Natural Law, He is mediate maker of all civil 
 law; and the presence of God in civil law makes civil law a 
 sacred obligation. Unjust law is no law at all, because God 
 has no part in its making. Unjust law has all the force men 
 
VIU 
 
 PREFACE 
 
 can give it. It has physical force in its favor, because men 
 can contribute that; and physical force never binds men's 
 free wills. Unjust law has no moral force, the kind that God 
 gives; and free wills are servants to moral force alone. All 
 the moral force in civil law comes from God, men are able 
 to back it up with physical force; but moral force, because 
 it touches free wills, is beyond the jurisdiction of mere men, 
 and necessarily leans for its validity on God alone. 
 
 Consent of the governed is one thing before the establish- 
 ment of government, it is an entirely different thing after 
 government is once established. Physical freedom is man's 
 birthright, and remains intact before and after the establish- 
 ment of government. Civil law is made by the state, and 
 before government is constituted there is no state, and there- 
 fore no adequate human lawmaker. Before government be- 
 comes a fact, natural law is the one restraint on moral free- 
 dom ; and natural law wants a multitude without government 
 to form a government at its earliest convenience. A people, 
 therefore, is not morally free to live with or without govern- 
 ment. Nature wants men to live in a state, under law and 
 authority; and nature's wishes are what God wants, nature's 
 wishes are the Natural Law. 
 
 A government de jure and de facto is, of course, better 
 than a government merely de facto; but when a government 
 de jure is impossible without continuous strife and universal 
 bloodshed, a government de facto is better than no govern- 
 ment at all. Even rights must be prosecuted with prudence, 
 and in case of such a government de facto, right must await 
 a more favorable opportunity to assert itself, it must not work 
 with headlong rashness to its own harm and the destruction 
 of order. 
 
 In common sense and the natural law legitimate conquest 
 is as just and secure a title to authority as inheritance or 
 suffrage or purchase ; and in the words of Suarez nearly every 
 government in modern times traces its origin to right of con- 
 quest. This is far from meaning that modem states are built 
 on physical force for single title. They are built immediately 
 on physical force, mediately on moral right. Physical force 
 when employed to pursue a right has all the sacredness of 
 
PEEFACE ix 
 
 moral right itself. To take a familiar and up-to-date instance, 
 the Allies had a perfect moral right to impose on Germany 
 and Austria all the terms of the armistice. Whatever terms 
 the Allies exacted from the defeated Germans they exacted 
 by force; but this force was backed up by clear moral right, 
 the indisputable right nations have to defend themselves 
 against an open, bold and aggressive oppressor, to punish his 
 crime with becoming penalties, and to make it effectively and 
 forever impossible for him to repeat his dastardly act. When 
 criminals are captured and convicted, they are not straight- 
 way liberated. They are fined light or heavy sums, they are 
 imprisoned for short or long terms; and if the criminal hap- 
 pens to be a murderer, reason quite approves of his utter de- 
 struction. Conquest, of course, can be illegitimate or legiti- 
 mate. Illegitimate conquest is no valid title. Illegitimate 
 conquest, like everything else illegitimate, is of no value in 
 the court of morality. 
 
 A government or State always implies a body of laws, or 
 a constitution; and, prior to the establishment of a govern- 
 ment, the people enjoy full moral freedom to select some set 
 form of government and appoint a ruler. Moral freedom is 
 removed by law, law is the denial of moral freedom, because 
 law means obligation, and obligation means moral necessity, 
 the diametrical opposite of moral freedom. 
 
 Self-determination implies full moral freedom to choose a 
 form of government and select a ruler. Where no government 
 exists, no civil law exists, no constitution exists, and this right 
 to self-determination is sacred; where government is already 
 established, civil law exists, a constitution or fixed body of 
 civil laws, exists; and the principle of self-determination is 
 all wrong. Correct Ethics recognizes no such independent 
 right in ruler or subjects. Law restricts moral freedom, and 
 the constitution is law. The constitution stands for the Royal 
 Compact championed by Suarez. Neither ruler nor people 
 must override the constitution. This constitution embodies 
 the respective rights and privileges of ruler and subjects, and 
 defines the method of procedure to be followed in case of a 
 dispute between ruler and subjects. As long as the ruler 
 keeps within the terms of the constitution, his right to author- 
 
PREFACE 
 
 ity is beyond question, and subjects by themselves are not at 
 liberty to change the form of government or curtail the ruler's 
 prerogatives. The ruler can at intervals make concessions to 
 his subjects, subjects can at intervals do the same favor to 
 their ruler; but every such transaction must be mutual and 
 agreeable to both parties. The ruler can voluntarily abdicate 
 or forfeit his authority by abuse of his prerogative; and in 
 either case, unless succession is otherwise settled by the con- 
 stitution, the multitude reverts to its original condition of 
 no government, and the people have full moral freedom to 
 select a form of government and choose a ruler. In the prose- 
 cution of an unjust war the ruler can lose his authority by 
 legitimate conquest ; and in this case ruler and subjects pass 
 under the authority of the conqueror. In pursuance of this 
 truth the Allies at the Peace Conference imposed a form of 
 government on Germany and Austria, allowing them a small 
 measure of liberty in their selection of rulers, disarmed them, 
 taxed them, and in every way treated them as subject peoples. 
 The small states previously belonging to Germany and Aus- 
 tria got from the Allies, for purposes of peace, the right to 
 self-determination, and in granting this favor the Allies as 
 victors were clearly within their rights. 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 PART I 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 Introduction- Pages 1-7 
 
 Thesis I. Every agent worka unto an end. This end is truly a 
 cause. The will in all its deliberate movements has some 
 definite last end, whether strictly or relatively such Pages 7-18 
 
 Thesis II. Man of his very nature desires complete happiness. 
 Complete happiness is man's absolutely last end subjectively 
 taken. This natural desire must be possible of fulfilment. 
 No created good can secure to man complete happiness. 
 The possession of God is alone complete happiness, and God 
 is man's absolutely last end objectively taken . . Pages 18--28 
 
 Thesis III. Man's destiny in this life, his supremest happiness 
 on earth, consists in drawing closer and closer to his last 
 end by the establishment of moral rectitude in his actions. 
 Between good and bad in the moral order, between right 
 and wrong, an essential, intrinsic difference exists. The 
 immediate measure of moral rectitude is the objective order 
 of things as understood by the intellect ; the mediate measure 
 is God's wisdom and goodness Pages 28-41 
 
 Thesis IV. A Natural Law, unchangeable, universal, eternal, 
 has place in man ; its complete and full sanction is reserved 
 for the next life; and eternal punishment is not opposed to 
 God's goodness. This Natural Law is the foundation and 
 corner-stone of all Positive Law Pages 41-70 
 
 Thesis V. The five causes of morality, final, material, formal, . 
 model and efficient. Generic and specific morality. Ob- 
 jective and subjective morality. Good, bad and indifferent 
 acts. Morality's subjective measure is synderesis and con- 
 science. Morality's efficient case is intellect and will. Appe- 
 
xii * CONTENTS 
 
 tite, the passions, and will. Morality's root is freedom of 
 will. Voluntary and involuntary acts. End and intention. 
 Morality's obstacles, ignorance and error affect the intellect ; 
 the passions, notably fear, affect the will; violence affects 
 executive not appetitive faculties, ordered not elicited 
 acts Pages 70-92 
 
 Thesis VI. A human act gets its specific morality from the ob- 
 ject of the act, from the agent's end or purpose, and from 
 circumstances affecting both ....... Pages 92-101 
 
 Thesis VII. Probabilism is a safe and correct system in mat- 
 ters of conscience Pages 101-110 
 
 Thesis VIII. Virtues and Vices Pages 110-122 
 
 Thesis IX. Character and Habits Pages 122-127 
 
 Thesis X. Rights and Duties Pages 127-137 
 
 Thesis XI. Contracts Pages 137-144 
 
 Thesis XII. Interest Pages 144-149 
 
 Thesis XIII. Merit and Demerit Pages 149-152 
 
 Thesis XIV. Utilitarianism is wrong, dangerous and ab- 
 surd Pages 152-170 
 
 Thesis XV. Kant's autonomy of reason is wrong . Pages 170-175 
 
 PART II 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Introduction Pages 175-177 
 
 Thesis I. Religion is man's first duty, a matter of essential 
 necessity to the individual and to the state. Worship, in- 
 terior and exterior, public and private, is God's due. Man's 
 duty towards revelation is to accept it, when known as such ; 
 to diligently seek and find it, when hidden, and when he has 
 reason to suppose that it exists. Toleration in matter of 
 dogma is absurd Pages 177-201 
 
CONTENTS xiii 
 
 Thesis II. Suicide is a sin against nature. Death inflicted in 
 self-defense is under certain conditions justifiable. Private 
 duels are highly absurd and contrary to the Law of 
 Nature Pages 201-225 
 
 Thesis III. A lie is always and of its very nature wrong. To 
 safeguard a proportionate right the use of a broad mental 
 reservation is allowed Pages 225-241 
 
 Thesis IV. Man's right to ownership, whether temporary or 
 lasting, is derived to him not from any formal compact 
 nor from any civil law, but from nature . . Pages 241-260 
 
 Thesis V. Socialism is false in its principles, morally impos- 
 sible in itself, and quite absurd Pages 260-280 
 
 Thesis VI. The right remedy for labor troubles is union be- 
 tween employers and workmen, based on inequality; con- 
 sulting the interests of both in such a way, that they 
 enjoy life and its comforts along with freedom and 
 peace Pages 280-289 
 
 Thesis VII. Marriage is honorable and in harmony with man's 
 
 dignity Pages 289-300 
 
 Thesis VIII. Celibacy, when love of virtue is its motive, is 
 more excellent than marriage . . . . . Pages 300-311 
 
 Thesis IX. Polygamy, though not against strict Natural Law, 
 
 little accords with it ....... . Pages 311-318 
 
 Thesis X. Incomplete divorce, or separation without any at- 
 tempt to contract a new marriage, is sometimes allowable. 
 Complete divorce, or separation affecting the marriage tie, 
 though not evidently opposed to strict Natural Law in 
 every conceivable case, is nevertheless out of harmony with 
 that secondary Law of Nature, which counsels the 
 proper Pages 318-342 
 
 Thesis XL Education of children belongs to parents first; 
 
 to State, last Pages 342-358 
 
 Thesis XII. Man is by very nature a social being Pages 358-366 
 
 Thesis XIII. A multitude and authority, or subjects and a 
 ruler, are elements essential to civil society or the 
 state Pages 366-371 
 
3UV 
 
 CONTENTS 
 
 :)-V/j! ■ t^- i^/v* 
 
 Thesis XIV. Authority proceeds immediately from God. In 
 the nature of things and ordinarily authority is not cou' 
 ferred on the people. Ordinarily and in the nature of 
 things the consent of the people fixes or determines the 
 person in whom authority resides. It may be implied or 
 expressed; immediate or gradual; and cannot always b© 
 withheld Pages 371-388 
 
 Thesis XV. Woman suffrage, though legitimate in exceptional 
 
 eases, is fraught with dangers Pages 388-398 
 
 Thesis XVI. The State enjoys full Legislative Executive and 
 Judicial rights, the prerogative of Eminent Domain, and the 
 War-Power Pages 39ft-404 
 
ETHICS, GENERAL AND SPECIAL 
 
 PART I 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 INTEODUCTION 
 
 A WORD about the importance of our subject. This work 
 is intended to throw some additional light on the topic of 
 morality. For Ethics is our theme, and Ethics is the science 
 of morality. And if any detail of thought has a vital bear- 
 ing on man's destiny, if any branch of study helps shape his 
 life, that detail of thought is suggested by Ethics, morality 
 is that study. Ethics is the science of putting order in man's 
 free acts; and, when you reflect that all sin, and much trouble, 
 and hell itself are only varying phases of disorder, it must 
 be evident that this science, theoretically mastered and sys- 
 tematically reduced to practice, could effect a revolution in 
 the world. And the revelutionists would be hailed as the 
 Emancipators of mankind. They would go down in history, 
 and they do go down in history as the supremest benefactors 
 of our race. 
 
 Witness the instance of our Lord and Saviour Jesus Christ. 
 Even His bitterest enemies, even men who deny Him every 
 other vestige of divinity, acknowledge that the world was 
 made better by His presence among men, and attribute to 
 His maxims and example an abiding influence for good. He 
 was a teacher of Ethics for whom the world waited with long- 
 ing for full four thousand years. He was a teacher of Ethics, 
 whose like the world of to-day misses exceedingly. The wis- 
 dom of His utterances even from a purely human standpoint, 
 without regard at all to the spirit of faith and grace's en- 
 vironment, in which they ought to be accepted, is as much 
 a subject of concern to the learned of to-day as it was in His 
 
^lyUym \ S\ 'GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 own lifetime to the doctors in the temple, to the Scribes and 
 the Pharisees deeply read in the Law. The wisdom of His 
 utterances extorts praise from unbelievers, and compels the 
 attention of the universe. Men who will not worship Him 
 as God are unable, when face to face with His heavenly doc- 
 trine and precepts, to withhold the homage due superhuman 
 intelligence. I insist upon this point as a conclusive proof 
 of the deep importance attaching to Ethics, because Christ's 
 ethical teaching is the only claim Christ has on the reverence 
 and respect of men completely abandoned by faith, and not 
 wholly bereft of reason. He has other and far more cogent 
 claims on our homage; but we, as well as strangers to faith, 
 can learn with profit to appreciate the human side of the 
 God-man's character. And Christ, apart from His tran- 
 scending dignity as God, ranks first among the most consum- 
 mate legislators the world ever entertained, and merits as 
 such unstinted praise from all mankind, from believer and 
 unbeliever alike. He owes the homage wrung from unwilling 
 unbelievers not to the influence of grace, nor yet to the 
 miracles of wonder He wrought in favor of suffering and 
 sickness, but mainly to the fact that His discourses breathe 
 an unerring love for rectitude; and half His lifework was 
 the ethical instruction of humanity. 
 
 Teachers, who appeal to the curious in human nature, will 
 hold the ears of men until supplanted by other teachers with 
 more startling novelties for wares; but teachers of morality 
 will never be without an audience, though they deal out 
 truths as old as time. Such is the passion of mankind for 
 what tends to put men in improved relations with themselves, 
 with one another, and with God, that, as long as a human 
 heart beats, due importance will be attached to problems of 
 morality, and propounders of morality will have their uses 
 in the universe. We men are eminently practical beings, and 
 the almost total absence of pure theory, and of the strictly 
 academic discussions common in Logic and Metaphysics from 
 Moral Philosophy, makes this branch of the science more in- 
 teresting and absorbing. After all, we were equipped with 
 minds only to borrow light from them for the operations of 
 the will, the head is servant to the heart, and life takes all its 
 true color from action, not from knowledge. To this simple 
 
 I 
 
INTRODUCTION 3 
 
 fact must be ascribed the undoubted superiority of Ethics in 
 the kingdom of study. Then, too, we are born with an in- 
 alienable and harassing love of happiness. We want to be 
 happy here, we want to be happy hereafter, and the wish 
 lives of our very life. Every glance of the eye aims at the 
 discovery of happiness' hiding place, every throb of the heart 
 is an invitation to happiness' pity, and every single thought 
 of saint and sinner alike has happiness for mainspring and 
 motive. There is no help for it ; we were made that way ; and, 
 to lose the inclination, we should have to get outside of our- 
 selves. Moral Philosophy professes to mark out the lines 
 along which we can without loss pursue this fleeting phantom 
 of happiness, and at the same time makes distinct record 
 of blunders to which the history of our race bears witness. 
 It puts on a solid basis principles, that, if practically ful- 
 filled, can have but one result, the inward approbation of a 
 conscience, working on and up to the right. And when con- 
 science approves, remorse is still, this life knows no truer 
 happiness than peace, and thorough blamelessness is bonded 
 promise of eternal blessedness. 
 
 Moral Philosophy puts us right with the world of being in 
 which we move, and does the thing in the neatest way con- 
 ceivable. It first discusses general notions of morality; mo- 
 tives for action, standards of measure, methods and means of 
 discovery, palliative circumstances, characteristics, responsi- 
 bility, merit and blame, helps and hindrances, law. These 
 abstract questions pave the way for more tangible and posi- 
 tive considerations. They partake of the nature of principles, 
 that run through the second or practical part of Moral Phil- 
 osophy. A man's duties and a man's rights are definitely 
 settled in this second part, by applying to the different emer- 
 gencies, in which a man may find himself, all the truths ac- 
 cumulated and made good in the first part. Thus, the first 
 condition that confronts us, when brought into being, is that of 
 dependence on God. Moral Philosophy takes hold of this con- 
 dition, examines it in every detail, and sternly decrees the 
 rigid demands of reason with regard to religion, worship and 
 revelation. It then lays down rules for man's behavior to- 
 wards himself and towards his fellow-men, taken as indi- 
 viduals. These rules are far reaching, and define exactly his 
 
4 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 obligations with respect to his body, his soul, his life, and his 
 neighbor's body, soul and life. They determine the nature 
 and fairness of private property, and establish the sanctity of 
 contracts. Society in all its ramifications is the next study. 
 The family and the State are the topics ; and each meets with 
 the fullest treatment. The family presents such vital ques- 
 tions as marriage, its oneness, its perpetuity, its obligations, its 
 relations with the civil power, parents and children. The 
 State leads to an analysis of men's inclination to band them- 
 selves together, of the purpose that actuates the inclination, of 
 the elements entering into society 's structure ; of authority, its 
 origin, its phases, its constituents, and of the mutual relations 
 between ruler and subjects. Tongiorgi offers this other di- 
 vision of Ethics from its causes: 1, Final cause, or man's 
 last end; 2, Material cause, or man's moral acts; 3, Formal 
 cause, or good and evil; 4, Model cause, or Natural Law; 5, 
 Efficient cause, mind, will and habits, behavior. 
 
 These, therefore, are some of the topics destined to occupy 
 our attention. The field is so vast that we can hope to do any- 
 thing like justice to only the leading points; and it shall be 
 my endeavor, while making my treatment of the matter as 
 thorough as possible, to omit nothing of primary importance. 
 While devoting no little time to the forward part of Moral, 
 or General Ethics, we intend to pay more special attention 
 to the after-part, designated by some authors as Natural Right. 
 The spirit of Catholicity will of course pervade our whole 
 work. We shall never forget that we are men of faith, with 
 the light of the Scriptures as interpreted by the Church for 
 guide, with the traditions of two thousand years at our serv- 
 ice, and the example of an army of saints before our eyes. 
 We enter not into this enquiry in the disposition of Rational- 
 ists, who exercise to-day so wide an influence in the world 
 of thought, outside the one true Church. We hesitate to re- 
 move God's messages to men from the field of morality. We 
 refuse to regard man as an absolute, self-sufficient being, in- 
 dependent of his surroundings, accountable to no superior for 
 his conduct, his own guide, his own reward, his own punish- 
 ment. We maintain, on the contrary, that every instant of 
 his life is beset with well defined relations; that he is poor, 
 and weak, and erring ; that he is affected by his environment, 
 
INTRODUCTION 5 
 
 strictly responsible before an all-wise, an all-holy, and an all- 
 powerful God for his thoughts, his words and his acts; and 
 a candidate for the Heaven or hell of Scripture, for the place 
 of delight with golden streets, or the prison house of fire 
 that knows no surcease of pain. Reason with us is quite as 
 important a factor in morality as it is with the Rationalists. 
 "We hold it in even higher esteem than they. We follow as 
 far as it leads, accept all its legitimate conclusions, and allow 
 neither prejudice nor passion to meddle with our loyalty to 
 its counsels. We take no half -measures, we journey not to 
 a certain point and then stop short. But, when reason makes 
 clear the undoubted existence of a teaching Church, the real- 
 ity of a code of law harassing in the extreme to human na- 
 ture, we adopt its teaching with all the responsibilities and 
 all the sacrifices implied. When reason proclaims in a loud 
 voice its own proneness to confound the false with the true, 
 its inability to cope with problems, capable of taxing even 
 angelic minds, we take reason's word for the statement, and 
 accept on God's authority what reason cannot even under- 
 stand. Reason without a guide is not sufficient in the deli- 
 cate task of arranging the moral details of a man 's life. Rea- 
 son was made to adopt the truth, not to fathom all truth ; and 
 reason is then exerting its proper activity, when in matters 
 beyond its grasp it humbly submits to instructions from a 
 superior. Reason is of its nature infallible, but it is by acci- 
 dent capable of mistake, and accidents are nowhere so likely 
 to occur as in the domain of moral teaching. IntellectuaJ 
 pride is the forerunner of unbelief, unbelief gives loose rein 
 to license, license kills conscience; and, when conscience is 
 once dead, man sinks lower than the level of a beast, and 
 becomes a veritable monster of iniquity. 
 
 There are certain basic truths we take for granted in all 
 these discussions, not because they cannot be proved, but be- 
 cause they belong to other departments of philosophy. They 
 are all abundantly proved elsewhere, and we are justified in 
 carrying over truths made good in other portions of the study. 
 Chief among these truths I should reckon the existence of 
 God; His supreme ownership of all else, man not excepted; 
 the immortality of the soul; free will; and man's ability to 
 compass certainty in the domain of knowledge. Atheism, Ma- 
 
6 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 terialism, Determinism, and Scepticism are theories opposed 
 to these several points of doctrine, and are overwhelmingly 
 refuted in Natural Theology, Psychology, and Logic. We 
 prove God a living reality from the need of one unproduced 
 actual being, to explain the produced beings that fall under 
 our experience. Deny God, and the universe of creatures is 
 without explanation, an effect with no cause. We prove God 
 a living reality from the wonderful order apparent in the 
 physical universe, written large across the sky, the earth, and 
 the sea. We prove God a living reality from a moral order 
 embodied in the voice of conscience, proclaiming aloud the 
 wishes of a superior compelling us with threats and promises 
 to cherish right and despise wrong, to do good and avoid 
 evil. We prove God a living reality from the common con- 
 sent of mankind, dating back to the earliest ages of history, 
 and enduring with undiminished vigor down to our own times. 
 God is supreme owner of all else in virtue of the principle 
 that to the maker belongs the thing he makes; and God cre- 
 ated, made from nothing, the world and all the minerals, 
 plants, brutes and men the world contains. Apart from other 
 compelling arguments, the soul's immortality is settled by its 
 simplicity and spirituality. It has no parts, and is, therefore, 
 in itself incorruptible or indestructible. It is intrinsically 
 independent of matter, and is, therefore, safe from accidental 
 corruption or destruction. The omnipotence of God cannot 
 annihilate a human soul without doing violence to God's other 
 attributes; and no one attribute in God runs counter to an- 
 other. Every individual man is a living witness to his pos- 
 session of free will. All human intercourse is based on this 
 quality of men; and in any other hypothesis law and social 
 order would have no meaning; honesty and virtue would 
 perish from the earth ; reward and punishment would be idle 
 terms without a show of significance. Scepticism is a huge 
 joke in philosophy; a direct insult to the goodness and wis- 
 dom of God; and its own completest refutation. Therefore, 
 with perfect right we suppose everywhere in these discussions 
 that God exists, that man is His property to dispose of as He 
 pleases, that man's soul will live forever, that man is free, 
 and that all doubt is a diseased condition of the mind that 
 study and observation can cure. 
 
THESIS I 
 
 Every agent works unto an end. This end is truly a cause. 
 The will in all its deliberate movements has some definite last 
 end, whether absolutely or relatively such. Jomn, 5-19; 
 Rickaby, 3-6. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 By a sort of paradox we begin our Ethics with the end. 
 Ethics is a set of rules for conduct, man's conduct is a series 
 of his deliberate acts, and the beginning of every deliberate 
 act is some end or purpose the man proposes to himself to 
 accomplish or effect. And so the paradox ceases. While 
 true to its name in one order, the end is false to its name in 
 another. It is last in the order of execution, first in the order 
 of intention. The house as a finished product is the last thing 
 to reward the builder's eyes, after weeks and months of work; 
 the same house, as it existed in his mind and will, was the first 
 thing to suggest plans and operations, running all the way 
 from cellar to roof. We are therefore justified in beginning 
 with the end, because intention precedes execution, and no- 
 body builds a house without prior thought of plans, without 
 prior wish of a habitation. People never build a house with- 
 out caring what will be the result of their endeavors; they 
 never build a house, when they want an automobile. Inten- 
 tion is end energizing the will, and on this account intentional 
 and deliberate are practically synonymous. To energize the 
 will, the end must first fall under the notice of the intellect ; 
 and a deliberate act is an act done with full knowledge and 
 consent. Unintentional for the same reason is in our language 
 an equivalent for indeliberate. The philosophy of the thing 
 is plain in our expression, ''Where no offense is intended, no 
 offense can be taken." Wise men pay no attention to a hurt, 
 when the wrong-doer has no desire to hurt, or hardly knows 
 that his conduct causes pain. Intention, therefore, presup- 
 poses an intellect and a will working together in mutual har- 
 
 7 
 
8 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 mony, and the use of the word is regularly restricted to man. 
 
 In brutes, plants and minerals the same phenomenon of 
 finality, or seeking an end, is verified in every exertion of 
 their energy, and is best named appetency, tendency, nature. 
 A brute has instinct for guide and appetite for root of de- 
 sire, both are constrained faculties without a vestige of free- 
 dom ; and they base a certain imperfect deliberation, a certain 
 show of intention, attributed in philosophy to brutes. Brutes 
 never in reality choose, when of two or more alternatives they 
 adopt or embrace one ; the transaction is due not to choice or 
 selection, but to an inexorable law imposed on them by their 
 Maker, and instinct is with us a handy term for that law. 
 The whole process in brutes is not intention, but appetency; 
 and the perfect deliberation present in man's acts is always 
 absent from the acts of brutes. Plants enjoy neither sense nor 
 appetite; and they grow, nourish and reproduce themselves 
 without any knowledge whatever on their part, without any 
 desire whatever, but wholly in virtue of a tendency or bent 
 communicated to them by their Maker. In their case, all 
 knowledge of end and all desire of its accomplishment are 
 in God. And what is true of plants is true of minerals, with 
 this single difference that capacity for self-motion attaches 
 to plants, while it is absent from minerals. Minerals, there- 
 fore, prosecute their end by very nature, in virtue of obedi- 
 ence to the law of gravity, and to whatever other physical 
 and chemical laws obtain in creation, God imposing this duty 
 of obedience. 
 
 Every agent works unto an end; and the saying, when re- 
 stricted to minerals, plants and brutes, is of small or no im- 
 portance in Ethics, because every such agent is outside the 
 sphere of morality. In common with other creatures, man 
 works towards an end ; and, what is more important in Ethics, 
 man in all his deliberate movements works towards a definite 
 last end, whether absolutely and unreservedly or only rela- 
 tively such. God Himself is no exception to this rule of 
 finality; and in creation He must have purposed His own 
 glory, as nothing short of God is worthy of God, and God 
 can slave to no unworthy end. God's glory is, therefore, 
 the absolutely last end of all creatures; and, in the words 
 of our catechism, we are all here to praise, worship and serve 
 
END AND DESTINY 9 
 
 God, and to save our souls. God's glory is creatures' ex- 
 ternal last end, because it is primarily for God, not for crea- 
 tures. Besides this external last end, we must recognize an 
 internal last end ; and in the course of our work we shall see 
 that it is for man complete happiness, the vision of God, 
 salvation. In the event of wishing to create, God simply 
 had to intend creatures for His glory, and we know from 
 man's natural craving for complete happiness that God 
 meant man to compass this surpassing good. 
 
 And all morality dates back to this single fact. Man must 
 respect his Maker's wishes, because it rests with the maker to 
 dispose of his work as an owner ; and God 's wishes are plain ; 
 man must glorify God by a life of virtue here, and by com- 
 plete happiness hereafter. Good and evil must, therefore, be 
 differentiated, law must be kept under penalty of punish- 
 ment, and duties must be fulfilled with scrupulous exactness. 
 Hence, we begin with end, show that while God's glory is 
 man's absolutely last extrinsic end, the possession of God is 
 man's absolutely last intrinsic end; that virtue is his rela- 
 tively last intrinsic end; that virtue can be differentiated 
 from vice; that the objective order of things is the standard 
 or measure enabling men to distinguish virtue from vice ; 
 that man is under strict law to avoid evil and do good, and 
 satisfy every relation in force between himself on the one 
 hand, and God, self and the neighbor on the other. Destiny 
 is end viewed as an obligation imposed by a superior; and 
 man's destiny, taking into account his present and future 
 life, is complete happiness or the intellectual possession of 
 God; man's destiny, restricting the question to this present 
 life alone, is virtue, or a closer and closer approach to God 
 by the introduction of moral rectitude into his conduct. And 
 the enemies of finality want to feel free from all restraint, 
 and escape responsibility for their misdeeds, on the plea of 
 total and complete independence. 
 
 Finality is the most obvious phenomenon in nature; and 
 yet, to escape the manifest responsibility resulting from final- 
 ity, some philosophers have denied its existence. Epicurus 
 and men of his stamp felt themselves hampered in their dreams 
 of pleasure by the unwelcome notion of a final cause, and in 
 their intellectual impotence strove to shake it off, by agreeing 
 
10 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 to regard it an empty fancy. They maintained that every- 
 thing happened by a sort of unavoidable chance, and claimed 
 that man trifled with himself in supposing that he had any 
 destiny to fulfil. Of course the doctrine would prove con- 
 venient to men set on living at haphazard, unwilling to bor- 
 row any worry from possible consequences of their rash con- 
 duct. Whatever obscurity may cloak the truth in the case 
 of inanimate and irrational agents, the thing is too plain in 
 the case of man to admit of the slightest doubt. Man knows 
 that he has a destiny to fulfil, and because of his power of 
 choice, coupled with the inevitable conviction, that in his 
 every act he is pursuing some definite purpose, he knows 
 that he will be rewarded or punished according to his deserts. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Every Agent. Agents can be separated into three classes, 
 beings without any knowledge whatever, beings with sensible 
 knowledge or instinct, and beings with intellects and wills. 
 Agents of the first class work unto an end under direction; 
 minerals without any motion of their own, plants with self- 
 motion. Agents of the second class work unto an end appre- 
 hensively or with knowledge, and with motion of their own, 
 but by instinct which is a necessary cause. Agents of the 
 third class work apprehensively, with motion of their own, 
 and with the power to select and reject means. Examples of 
 all three are an arrow on its way to the target, a dog walk- 
 ing home, a man making money. 
 
 End. Finis est id propter quod aliquid fit, id cujus gratia 
 aliquid fit. The end is that on account of which, for the sake 
 of which something is done. It is what induces the agent to 
 work; that towards which the agent strives, to rest in it, to 
 quit the activity of seeking, not the activity of enjoyment. 
 Ends are classified thuswise: Last or farthest away; proxi- 
 mate or closest; and intermediate, between last and proxi- 
 mate. Last is sometimes absolutely and unreservedly last, 
 sometimes relatively last. An end is absolutely last, when it 
 cannot in reason be referred to any higher end, any end be- 
 yond or farther away; when the agent can in reason devote 
 himself and all his endeavors to its accomplishment; when 
 
DIVISION OF ENDS 11 
 
 it is the possession of God, and only then. It is relatively 
 last, when it is in reality referred to no end heyond, like money 
 in the case of a miser, though it can he in reason, and in 
 conscience ought to he referred to some higher end, like 
 money in the case of a saint; when it cannot in reason claim 
 all a man's endeavors, hut only a certain corner of his ener- 
 gies and attention. A proximate end is virtually a means 
 to some last or intermediate end. An intermediate end is a 
 means lying between a proximate and last, the first interme- 
 diate being a means to the second, and so on to the finish. 
 In the present classification we distinguish two orders, that 
 of execution and that of intention ; and our division is in the 
 order of execution. The possession of God, or complete hap- 
 piness, is first thing in the order of intention, last in the 
 order of execution. Thought of reward starts effort, reward 
 stands to the winner after effort is over. Ends are likewise 
 divided into end which, end for which, and end in which. 
 They are, respectively, the good sought, the person advan- 
 taged, and possession. Examples are, learning, student and 
 education, in the matter of study. An end to he produced 
 is a good without physical existence prior to the agent 's activ- 
 ity; an end to he ohtained is a physical reality prior to the 
 agent's effort. Health in the case of a sick man, and gold 
 in the ease of a miser are instances. End of deed and end 
 of doer, in Latin, operis and operantis, are important. The 
 first is that to which the agent's work is by its very nature 
 suited and fitted ; the other is whatever good the agent selects 
 for purpose of his work. Ends of deed are, a house with a 
 builder, a song with a singer, time with a watchmaker. Ends 
 of doer are, worship, fame, money with all three. 
 
 Cause. Whatever produces another with influence on its 
 very heing, the influence issuing in dependence, is a cause. 
 There are four leading causes, two of them internal, material 
 and formal; two of them external, efficient and final. Each 
 of the four has its own proper and peculiar activity, each 
 producing the effect, each contributing in its own special 
 way to the production of the effect or new existence. An 
 efficient cause has direct bearing on the effect, without enter- 
 ing its intrinsic constitution, and contributes of its own to 
 the effect, whether its activity be physical or moral. A final 
 
12 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 cause directly affects the efficient cause, and through it in- 
 fluences the effect, contributing of its own to the effect by 
 moral activity alone. The influence of an efficient cause is 
 exerted first and foremost on the effect; the influence of a 
 final cause is exercised first and foremost on the mind and 
 will of the agent, and through them on the effect. The 
 difference between a physical efficient cause and a final cause 
 is too plain to be missed, but the same is not true of a moral 
 efficient cause and a final. Moral efficients are close images 
 of finals, and yet the two must not be confounded together. 
 A moral efficient has a more direct bearing on the effect than 
 a final. One man bribes another with money to commit 
 murder. The briber is moral efficient cause of the murder, 
 the money offered is final cause of the murder. The activity 
 of the briber bears on the murder, he uses the murderer as 
 an instrument, and the moral phase of the affair passes to 
 physical. The money bears on the mind and will of the mur- 
 derer, and all its activity remains moral. Neither is a final 
 cause a mere condition. Like all causes, it is a condition too ; 
 but to the notion of condition it adds the quality of a thing 
 more intimately connected with the work or effect. A condi- 
 tion as such enters into no part of the effect proper. All 
 its ultility ceases, when the effect proper begins. It makes 
 things ready, and then disappears. The final cause, on the 
 contrary, really sets the agent in motion by the influence it 
 exerts on his will, if the agent is rational, or by the influence 
 it exerts on the will of the First Cause, God, if the agent is 
 irrational. Besides, a condition is no sufficient reason for the 
 effect. In the process of burning compare the dryness of the 
 waste burnt, and its juxtaposition, with a fire that consumes 
 it. Some final cause must urge the builder to begin opera- 
 tions, and this final cause influences him all the way from 
 beginning to finish, from cellar to roof. The end is a cause 
 only in the order of intention ; in the order of execution it is 
 in proper language an effect. 
 
 The Will. A spiritual faculty^ proper and peculiar to 
 man, capable of seeking good hy acts elicited under the di- 
 rection of the intellect. Appetite is of three kinds; natural, 
 proper to minerals and plants; sensible, proper to brutes; and 
 intellectual or rational, proper to man. All three are in man, 
 
HUMAN ACTS 13 
 
 natural and sensible alone are in brutes, natural alone is in 
 minerals and plants. The will is rational appetite, and meets 
 with full and complete treatment in Psychology. 
 
 Deliberate. Man is capable of two kinds of acts, deliberate 
 and indeliherate. Toying with the beard or aimlessly rub- 
 bing the chin, is the classical instance of an indeliberate act. 
 Deliberate acts are so familiar that an example would be 
 superfluous. The will aside, intellectual knowledge and a 
 degree of attention are really the distinguishing characteris- 
 tics of a deliberate act, as compared with an indeliberate act. 
 Will separates it not from indeliberate, but from spontaneous 
 acts. Perfect deliberation is itself defined to be an act of the 
 reason, by which, at the instigation of the will, the mind 
 compares together different ends, different means, with a view 
 to making a choice. In deliberation it will be noted that the 
 third operation of the mind, not merely the first or second, 
 has play. In other words, a comparison is instituted, and this 
 process necessitates the employment of argumentation. Phi- 
 losophers recognize a kind of imperfect deliberation, which 
 they attribute to brute animals. The knowledge requisite 
 is limited to sole perception of the end by means of the ex- 
 ternal senses, aided principally by sensile discrimination. 
 And men are as capable as brutes of this imperfect delibera- 
 tion, or real indeliberateness. It nowise reaches, like the 
 knowledge of perfect deliberation, to the nature of the end, 
 or to the connection between a certain act and a certain pur- 
 pose. In imperfect deliberation the motion of the agent is 
 ordinarily quick and sudden; in perfect deliberation it is 
 ordinarily slow and measured. Human acts, distinctively 
 such, have three elements, intellectual knowledge, desire and 
 freedom., activities of intellect and will, man's two specific 
 functions. Desire and freedom can be expressed together by 
 the one word, selection. Selection always presupposes knowl- 
 edge, in much the same way as operations of the mind have 
 operations of the senses for foundation. Hence the adage, 
 ''Nil volitum, nisi praecognitum, " "Things unknown are not 
 matter for wishes." Freedom in the same way has for sup- 
 port the two faculties of intellect and will; and, in the ab- 
 sence of either, freedom is impossible. A voluntary or delib- 
 erate act is an act proceeding from the will accompanied by 
 
14 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 intellectual knowledge of the end sought. Deliberate, or vol- 
 untary acts in strict sense, are arranged in different classes. 
 
 Perfectly voluntary acts are accomplished with full knowl- 
 edge, and with fall consent of the will. 
 
 Imperfectly voluntary acts imply that either knowledge, or 
 consent, or both are imperfect. 
 
 Absolutely voluntary acts are accomplished with full delib- 
 eration, attention and bias. 
 
 Acts are relatively or after a manner voluntary, when con- 
 sent is present, but mingled with a certain aversion and lean- 
 ing of the will towards the opposite act. E.g., sailors throw- 
 ing cargo overboard in storm. 
 
 A directly voluntary act turns on some immediate object of 
 the will, intended in itself and for its own sake. E.g., theft, 
 murder. 
 
 Indirectly voluntary acts turn on some object necessarily 
 connected with immediate object. E.g., effect in cause, drunk- 
 enness in excessive drinking, death and a thrown stone. 
 
 In a positively voluntary act the will acts, as in a sin of 
 commission. 
 
 In a negatively voluntary act the will refuses to act, as in 
 a sin of omission. 
 
 Expressly voluntary acts are clear from words or signs. 
 
 Tacitly voluntary acts are gathered from facts. 
 
 An act is actually voluntary, when willed here and now, 
 without question of break or interruption. 
 
 An act is virtually voluntary, when voluntary by force of 
 an original actual voluntary, the actual wish being broken or 
 interrupted, without detriment to its moral continuity and 
 influence. 
 
 An act is habitually voluntary, when its original was actu- 
 ally willed once, and was never taken back; but the actual 
 wish was broken or interrupted to such an extent by sleep, 
 or delay, or something such that it no longer lasts or influ- 
 ences by way of an act, but only by way of a habit. 
 
 An act is interpret atively voluntary, when never actually 
 willed, but would be willed if thought were had of the thing, 
 e. g., desire of salvation combined with opposition to baptism. 
 
PROOFS 15 
 
 Division 
 
 Three parts. I. End. II. Cause. III. Last end. 
 Proofs I, II, III 
 
 I. Every agent works unto some determined and well de- 
 fined effect. Otherwise all effects would be indifferent, or of 
 the same attractiveness; and there would be no reason why 
 one effect should be produced rather than another. Very pro- 
 duction is a sign that the effect produced was more attractive 
 to the agent than other effects. But such an effect has all the 
 constituents of an end, which is that on account of which the 
 agent works. Ergo, every agent works unto an end. 
 
 II. Whatever produces another with influence on its very 
 being, the influence issuing in dependence, is truly a cause. 
 But such is the end. Ergo, the end is truly a cause. With 
 regard to the Minor. The builder's purpose contributes even 
 more to the building of the house than his saw or hammer, be- 
 cause it starts things and stays with him to the finish. The 
 saw does its own work, the hammer its own; and that is all. 
 The end is responsible for their work and for the work of 
 everything else employed in the construction of the building. 
 In rational agents the end's influence is immediate; in min- 
 erals, plants and brutes it is mediate, directly influencing 
 God, their Maker and First Cause, to furnish them with such 
 and such natures, tendencies and faculties, or instincts, in 
 preference to others, because best suited and adapted to the 
 works He intends them to accomplish. 
 
 III. 1°. In every series of causes there ought to be a flrst 
 cause. But if the will had no definite last end, there would 
 be no first cause. Ergo. 
 
 With regard to the Major. The second cause, to be second, 
 would be an effect. But an effect without a cause is impos- 
 sible. Ergo. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. The last end is the first cause. 
 Ergo. 
 
 With regard to this Antecedent. The first cause is what 
 first excites the agent to activity. But this is the office of the 
 last end. Ergo. 
 
 With regard to this Minor. Axiom — The end is first thing 
 in a man's intention, last thing in the order of execution. 
 
16 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 2°. The last end, with regard to an act of the will, fills 
 the place of motion's first principle. But remove the first 
 principle of motion, and no motion exists. Ergo, in the 
 event of no definite last end, no act of the will ensues. 
 
 3°. When one thing in nature is the reason why another 
 thing receives such or such a denomination, the first of the 
 two is more deserving of the denomination than the second, 
 which actually receives it. But all intermediate ends owe 
 their whole being, and consequently their every denomination, 
 to some last end; and these intermediate ends, at least, are 
 purposes worked unto by every agent. An intermediate is 
 sought only with a view to some corresponding last end. 
 Otherwise it is not an intermediate end. Ergo, the last end 
 is all the more so such a purpose; that is, the will in all its 
 deliberate movements has some definite last end, whether 
 strictly or relatively such. 
 
 4°. Every particular or individual good tends of its nature 
 to some common or universal good, as to its proper end. But 
 God, the absolute good, is common or universal good, and 
 every created good is particular or individual good. Ergo, 
 every created good, or things in general tend of their nature 
 to one good, God, as to their last end. 
 
 With regard to the Major. Parts exist for the sake of the 
 whole. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. All good comes from, and de- 
 pends for its being on God. 
 
 N.B. This last argument proves that nature wants man in 
 all his deliberate movements to have God for definite last 
 end. Man's every wish is implicitly, if not explicitly, an ef- 
 fort towards complete happiness, and complete happiness is 
 the possession of God. Implicitly, therefore, this definite last 
 end is always the absolutely last or God ; and implicitly speak- 
 ing God is necessarily the last end of every deliberate act or 
 series of actions. What nature wants, God wants. We can- 
 not improve on God, and when we try to do so we fail. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. The single difference between a means and an end is 
 this, that the former is striven after merely for the sake of 
 
PRIiNCIPLES 17 
 
 the end, while the latter is striven after for itself. In fact, 
 a means is an end before it is compassed ; it becomes a means 
 only after it ceases to be an end only after it is compassed. 
 Means in process of making, means in fieri, is an end; means 
 formally taken, means in facto esse is not an end. Before it 
 can be used, it has to be compassed or sought ; and what the 
 will seeks, is the man's end. Hence the absurdity of writers, 
 who claim that Jesuit philosophers and moralists advocate 
 the wicked theory, that a laudable end justifies any means 
 whatever, no matter how immoral and wrong. Jesuits would 
 be blind, indeed, if they failed to see at a glance that such a 
 theory, because of the unimportant difference between means 
 and end, would be a virtual advocacy of this evidently iniqui- 
 tous principle, that all ends, good, bad and indefferent, are 
 justified ; and that murder and forgiving charity, robbery and 
 alms-deeds are equally worthy of our aspirations and en- 
 deavors. 
 
 B. An intention is an a-ot by which the will embraces the 
 end as its peculiar good. Any reason urging the will to this 
 act is called a motive. Whatever helps to the possession of 
 the end is a means ; and such means as simply remove impedi- 
 ments from the path are remedies. 
 
 C. The motion the end communicates to the agent is not 
 physical, but of equivalent efficacy in another order, namely, 
 in the logical order, the order of thought. Its whole effi- 
 ciency lies in the love it stirs in the agent's will, after its 
 presentation by the intellect of the agent; and this love con- 
 tributes as much to the production of the effect as the physical 
 efficient cause. 
 
 D. Man in his indeliberate actions, works unto an end much 
 as brutes, apprehensively, with motion of his own, but by in- 
 stinct. Such acts are called acts of the man, not acts of man 
 or human acts. 
 
 E. The end, or final cause, considered in the order of exe- 
 cution, is no cause of the effect, since its place is behind that 
 of the effect, and causes precede their ffects. We maintain 
 only this, that the end is a true and real cause, when con- 
 sidered in the order of intention. Objectively speaking, end 
 in the order of execution is a built house, end in the order of 
 intention is a thought house. 
 
THESIS II 
 
 Man of his very nature desires complete happiness. Com- 
 plete happiness is man's ah&olutely last end subjectively 
 taken. This natural desire must he possible of fulfilment. 
 No created good can secure to man complete happiness. The 
 possession of God is alone complete happiness, and God is 
 alone complete happiness, and God is man's absolutely last 
 end objectively taken. Jouin, 5-19 ; Rickaby, 6-26. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Here on the threshold of morality a multitude of questions 
 besets us. We know from Metaphysics that every agent, man 
 included, works unto some end. We know, further, that man 
 excels all other creatures in this, that he chooses his end and 
 selects means to its accomplishment. He is not an accumu- 
 lation of blind forces, working along lines mapped out for him 
 by another. He thinks for himself, he decides for himself, 
 he weighs, examines, approves, condemns. We have from 
 our previous acquaintance with philosophy a fair insight into 
 his faculties. From experience we have a fair knowledge of 
 the motives, that clamor for his attention in the routine of 
 everyday affairs. Some are money-makers, some are chiselling 
 for themselves a niche in the temple of fame, some are in 
 continual search for health or the means to preserve it, some 
 keep busy nursing an appetite for palatable dishes, and others 
 travel in pursuit of a good they can expect to come up with 
 only after death. We have to range ourselves in some class. 
 Nay, we are placed already. For the present we want to 
 look at things with the cold, calculating eyes of reason, to 
 profit by our own mistakes and the mistakes of others, and 
 stand just where common sense would have us stand in life's 
 struggles. We want to find out what craving is in reality at 
 the bottom of human d-esires, and what one object in the uni- 
 verse can sate the craving. Our thesis is the answer. Hap- 
 
 18 
 
COMPLETE HAPPINESS 19 
 
 piness is last in the series of wish-factt)rs, and God is alone 
 large enough, when possessed, to leave no room for further 
 desire. We mean by wish-factors the reasons prompting our 
 wishes; and money, pleasure, honor are wished in last analy- 
 sis because they hold out promise of happiness. Man cannot 
 in reason want anything beyond God, man cannot in reason 
 rest in the enjoyment of anything this side of God. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Happiness. This is the theme with which the Lord Christ 
 opened His sublime discourse on the Mount. The beatitudes 
 are eight steps in the ladder to God ; and, when the wisest of 
 men communicated the secret of success in life to the listen- 
 ing multitude. He knew best with what word to preface His 
 remarks. Beati, He said, blessed, happy are the poor in 
 spirit, and so on through the catalogue. His mission was in 
 part the instruction of mankind and the conquest of souls. 
 Redemption and merit aside, He aimed in all His movements 
 at spreading the kingdom of virtue in the hearts of men. 
 And the happiness born of virtue was the most tremendous 
 motive at His command. He thought no reward a more ap- 
 pealing incentive to virtue than happiness, and God's ideas 
 are right. He knew in His infinite wisdom that other re- 
 wards, while possibly exerting a temporary influence over 
 men's minds, would in the last resort fail of effect. He knew 
 that other rewards, from their very nature and the constitu- 
 tion of man, would prove only partial incentives, subject to 
 all the varying phases of human conduct. He knew that 
 wealth, for instance, with all its attractiveness for some, would 
 act as a deterrent on others ; that fame would appeal to the 
 instincts of a circle limited indeed in numbers. But happi- 
 ness is a universal good, it is at the root of all the world's 
 wishes, it holds its own against the ravages of time, against 
 all the vicissitudes with which humanity is acquainted. 
 Boethius thus defines complete happiness, ''A lasting condi- 
 tion blessed with everything good." ''The enduring posses- 
 sion of every good." These are no idle words, and their right 
 understanding will remove many difficulties. They vindi- 
 cate to complete happiness at least two characteristic ele- 
 
20 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 ments, a Jieaped-iip measure of good, and imending diiration. 
 These elements are thoroughly wanting in all the varied joys 
 this earth affords. Mundane or incomplete happiness has 
 inseparably linked with itself a twofold curse. While it fills 
 one comer of a man 's heart with pleasure, it fills another with 
 pain. Its near departure haunts its possessor like a spectre. 
 Partial pain and possible loss are ingredients of all the happi- 
 ness with which this earth is acquainted; and no amount of 
 reasoning, no amount of care can quite eradicate them. St. 
 Augustine, insisting on its fulness, thus describes complete 
 happiness, ^'That man is happy who has all that he wants, 
 and wants only what he can hav^ without sin." Complete 
 happiness is, therefore, an unending round of delights, in 
 which no legitimate craving goes unfulfilled, in which no ille- 
 gitimate craving has existence. This is perfect hliss. Philos- 
 ophers besides recognize an inferior sort of blessedness, which 
 for clearness' sake they call imperfect hliss. It is the only 
 sort of incomplete happiness, truly deserving the name, this 
 present life affords ; and it consists in a close union with our 
 last end by the establishment of moral rectitude in our ac- 
 tioTis. It is peace of conscience, it is holiness, it is the inher- 
 itance of the saints. It is the initial step in our progress to- 
 wards complete happiness, or perfect bliss ; and, while haunted 
 with the fear of loss and mingled with misery, wretchedness 
 and pain, it procures in the grand total of blessings and ills 
 a preponderance of blessings. Philosophers likewise distin- 
 guish between objective or material happiness, and subjective 
 or formal happiness. The first, or objective, is the object or 
 thing, whose presence fills out man's every desire, God. The 
 second, or subjective, is the actual possession of that object 
 or thing. The first is called the end which; the second, the 
 end in which. The definition quoted from Boethius tallies 
 exactly with subjective complete happiness. 
 
 Of His Very Nature. This longing for happiness is there- 
 fore a natural craving, and things may be natural to man in 
 either one of two ways. They may be born and live with him 
 in a manner entirely independent of his free will, or they 
 may be in strict accord with his nature, and yet entirely de- 
 pendent on his free choice for their existence within him. 
 The desire of which we at present speak is natural to man in 
 
CREATED GOODS 21 
 
 the first way. It is a necessity of his nature, it cannot be 
 schooled out of his thoughts, it cannot be shaken off or gotten 
 rid of. It is as much a part of the man as upward motion is 
 part of fire 's essence. It is different from an acquired desire, 
 which may of course be natural to man in the second way. 
 Marriage is usually alleged by writers on the subject as an 
 instance of something natural to man, with full dependence 
 on his own free choice. 
 
 Desires. Many in their folly miss the proper means to 
 make good this desire. Many seek its accomplishment in very 
 dubious occupations, in pleasures decidedly illegitimate, and 
 are sadly disappointed in their expectations. But, as it is 
 possible of fulfilment, it must be within man's reach. There 
 must be a line of conduct unfailingly able to lead to its con- 
 summation. It can never happen that complete happiness 
 will fail him, who honestly does his utmost to win it, and 
 steadily keeps his record clean of fault and defect. 
 
 No Created Good. The assertion is sweeping, and excludes 
 from the dignity of man's last end everything but God. In 
 the history of philosophy not a few ancients went astray on 
 this point. Epicurus contended that pleasure was man's su- 
 premest desire, his highest good. He sometimes bestowed a 
 scant praise On virtue, only because opposite vices interfered 
 with the full enjoyment of physical pleasure. Zeno, a leader 
 among the stoics, reckoned wisdom combined with virtue the 
 summit of man's aspirations. Aristotle, the founder of the 
 Peripatetic school, contended for a union of virtue and pleas- 
 ure. It may be noticed that the dignity of last end, or high- 
 est good, is ascribed by no one to wealth. Misers alone love 
 wealth for wealth's sake, and misers are not numerous. Prac- 
 tical men of sense regard wealth as only a useful commodity, 
 a means to the acquirement of other blessings more eagerly 
 coveted. As a merely useful good, wealth must of course 
 yield precedence to virtue, pleasure, wisdom, and every good 
 catalogued as either becoming or pleasurable. 
 
 Possession of God. In purely ethical discussions theology 
 of course has no place, and statements advanced must be made 
 good without any reference to Holy Scripture, as a source of 
 argument. We Catholics know from our catechism that 
 Heaven is our last end, and we know that Heaven is the ac- 
 
22 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 cumulation of all good centered in the beatific vision, or 
 closest kind of union with God. Bliss in Heaven consists 
 entirely in seeing God face to face, and this intellectual pos- 
 session of God, supernaturally accomplished, constitutes man's 
 supremest happiness. Strip the beatific vision of its super- 
 natural qualities, and you have at once the doctrine of phi- 
 losophy concerning man's last end. Though able to make 
 surmises, philosophy teaches nothing positive regarding the 
 resurrection of the body; but in Psychology we saw how 
 clearly it makes good the immortality of the soul. There- 
 fore, the only possession of God, possible of conception to 
 unaided human thought, is intellectual possession, based on 
 an intimate union of intellect and will with Him. 
 
 Last End. This complete happiness, or possession of God, 
 is therefore the ultimate purpose of man's every movement. 
 His proximate and explicit purpose may be limited happi- 
 ness, but his ultimate and implicit purpose is always complete 
 happiness. Its influence is not always evident, because some- 
 what below the surface of things; but its influence is none 
 the less present. It has a twofold value, implicit and explicit. 
 Thus, when, for instance, knowledge because of its manifold 
 advantages urges the student to labor, the hiding principle is 
 that all-pervading desire of perfect happiness. Love of 
 knowledge merely seems to be the sole motive. Complete hap- 
 piness has in this case an implicit value, and its efficacy is 
 none the less real than when it explicitly asserts itself. 
 
 Proofs I, II, III, IV, V 
 
 I. 1st. Complete happiness is the satisfaction of man 's every 
 legitimate wish. But man of his very nature desires the sat- 
 isfaction of his every legitimate wish. Ergo, man of his very 
 nature desires complete happiness. 
 
 With regard to the Major. Perfect or finished good is the 
 all important and characteristic element of complete happi- 
 ness; and since good is subject-matter of the will's legitimate 
 wishes, complete happiness is the satisfaction of man's every 
 legitimate wish. N.B. Nature prompts no illegitimate wish. 
 Perverted passion, wrong prejudices, faulty education are 
 responsible for such wishes. 
 
PROOFS 23 
 
 With regard to the Minor. Man's will would be otherwise 
 doomed to perpetual unrest, and would become an instrument 
 of unending torture. 
 
 2nd. Nature, impediments aside, exerts its utmost activity. 
 But human nature or man is capable of desiring complete 
 happiness, and no impediment is conceivable. Ergo, man of 
 his very nature desires complete happiness. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. Man's mind is able to grasp 
 the highest truth. His will, to keep equal pace with his mind, 
 must be able to desire the highest good, or complete happi- 
 ness. 
 
 II. Man 's last end must have these three qualities : It must 
 be the supremest good, fully equal to all the wants of all his 
 faculties, even vegetative and sensitive. Needless to say, it 
 must satisfy vegetative and sensitive wants eminently, not 
 formally. It must so contain within itself all the good resi- 
 dent in other conceivable ends, that these other ends be only 
 stages in man's progress toward its acquisition. In other 
 words, it must be of such sort, as to attract man's heart of 
 its own single self, and be at the same time the thing of in- 
 terest in every object of man's desires. It must be the de- 
 sire of every man's heart, whether formally and explicitly, or 
 materially and implicitly. But complete happiness is the 
 only good answering this description. Ergo, complete happi- 
 ness is man's last end. 
 
 III. A desire with nature for origin and author, cannot be 
 impossible of fulfilment. But man's desire for complete hap- 
 piness is a desire of this sort. Ergo, it is possible of fulfil- 
 ment. 
 
 With regard to the Major. Denial of this Major would be 
 an open denial of the axiom, that every effect demands a cor- 
 responding cause. For the effect, or natural desire, is admit- 
 tedly alive in every man's bosom, and its cause is assuredly 
 nothing short of at least possibility of fulfilment. Besides, 
 God, the Author of our nature and all its inborn longings, 
 would be, were complete happiness an empty dream, a most 
 consummate torturer and executioner, not the beneficent cre- 
 ator reason requires Him to be. 
 
 IV. The good things, proposed by adversaries for man's 
 last end, are signal failures. Thus, 
 
24 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 a, physical pleasure ministers to only senses of the body, 
 and neglects the soul 's interests ; 
 
 b, physical pleasure likewise involves pain for some member 
 or organ not actually participating in it, and nearly always 
 threatens harm to the soul; 
 
 c, physical pleasure is an utter stranger to that endless 
 duration, which is happiness' first requisite; 
 
 d, spiritual delight is at most an effect of the good we seek, 
 and as such inferior to the good productive of this delight; 
 and, therefore, an impossible last end; 
 
 e, spiritual delight would then be the motive for search 
 after becoming good; and the becoming and the agreeable 
 would be without distinctive characteristics ; 
 
 f, pleasure, whether physical or spiritual, is change or mo- 
 tion ; and man 's last end is complete rest ; 
 
 g, the wisdom and virtue of this life leave manj things yet 
 to be desired, health, wealth, beauty, strength, long years. 
 Certainly wisdom and virtue, accompanied by these several 
 blessings, are more an incentive to desire than wisdom and 
 virtue, considered apart from them; 
 
 h, pleasure, wisdom and virtue combined, or the joint pos- 
 session of all the blessings this earth affords, is so full of con- 
 flicting elements, as to be quite out of the question, and im- 
 possible of fulfilment ; 
 
 i, danger of change, fear of loss, actual loss, gnawing anx- 
 iety, toil and a thousand other evils poison all the good things 
 of this exile, and emphatically forbid man to look for satis- 
 faction or rest in their acquisition; 
 
 j, virtue alone excepted, every other good with which earth 
 is acquainted, even life itself, may without discredit he sacri- 
 ficed on the altar of patriotism. 
 
 V. 1st. Some good, created or uncreated, is man's last end, 
 or complete happiness. But no created good is equal to the 
 task, and God alone is uncreated good. Ergo, God is man's 
 complete happiness, his last end. 
 
 2nd. God, when creating man, necessarily appointed him 
 an end wholly worthy of Himself. But God alone is wholly 
 worthy of God. Ergo, God is the end appointed man, the 
 end established in man's creation. But the end assigned by 
 God to man is man's last end. Ergo, God is man's last end. 
 
PRINCIPLES 25 
 
 3rd. Nothing short of the universal and supreme good can 
 be man's last end. But God alone is the universal and su- 
 preme good. Ergo, God, and nothing short of God, is man's 
 last end. 
 
 With regard to the Major. Man's last end, from the very- 
 nature of things, must be a good, whose possession leaves 
 nothing further to be desired ; and universal or supreme good 
 alone enjoys this prerogative. 
 
 With regard to the Miliar. Were there another universal 
 and supreme good, there would be two gods. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Our every desire, if we follow the laws imposed upon us 
 by our Maker, will be abundantly satisfied in the next life. 
 Some of these desires will have their fulfilment formally, or 
 exactly as they are shaped. Others, on account of the pe- 
 culiar circumstances attaching to a future state, will be ac- 
 complished, as philosophers say, eminently, in a grander way, 
 or equivalently. The possession of God will be the sum of 
 our delights, and God is infinite in resources to make up for 
 whatever pleasures our future condition will render impos- 
 sible. Thus, there will be no eating, no drinking in Heaven; 
 but, apart from the fact that our lower nature will then make 
 no clamor for sweets it now so much covets, God will be able 
 to pour into our souls a measure of happiness, more than able 
 to atone for these paltry losses. Some philosophers think 
 they see, in the completeness of good things involved in this 
 natural desire of happiness, a proof of the future resurrec- 
 tion of the body. They contend that happiness would be 
 incomplete, unless the body somehow shared after death in 
 the joys accorded the soul. But the time-honored distinction 
 between intensity and extent is an answer to their difficulty. 
 Unless our Creator could in some way make up in intensity 
 for the loss extent, or number of parts affected by bliss, suf- 
 fers, the body would surely have to arise, and live forever 
 like the soul, to enjoy its proper reward. Reason throws no 
 light on the body's destiny after death, because, in the event 
 of its total disappearance, though man's happiness would be 
 
26 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 less in extent, its intensity could be so multiplied, that his 
 loss would become a gain. 
 
 B. God, because simple, and therefore without parts, must 
 be known wholly, if known at all. This circumstance is, how- 
 ever, far from rendering it necessary for the blessed in 
 Heaven to know Him totally or exhaustively, or in such a 
 way that nothing in His nature escapes their knowledge. God 
 is infinite, and to know Him totally is the work of an infinite, 
 not a finite intellect like man's. The familiar example of a 
 mountain seen in the distance may serve to elucidate the point. 
 The whole mountain is seen, without being wholly seen. 
 
 C. We must in our language guard against making God a 
 means to an end. He is not the instrument, through which 
 we attain to happiness. He is our happiness. He is not a 
 thing designed for our use or commodity, but we are things 
 designed for His glory; and, in furthering His glory, we 
 are filling out our destiny. 
 
 D. As a principle of activity, man's intellect is of course 
 finite and limited; but, when the objects, to which man's in- 
 tellect can reach, are taken into consideration, no finite or 
 limited number can represent them. Because of the limita- 
 tions inherent in its activity, man's intellect can know God 
 in only a limited way; because of the multitude of objects, to 
 which it can reach, man's intellect can be filled by nothing 
 created, and therefore by God alone. All being is the ade- 
 quate object of man's intellect, and created being is not all 
 being. Created and uncreated are that, and created is con- 
 tained in uncreated, or actual unproduced, or God. 
 
 E. Between the mind and its object some sort of propor- 
 tion must have place. But this proportion, or likeness, need 
 not necessarily be that of being, or nature. Proportion of fit- 
 ness, constituted by the circumstance, that God as a being can 
 fill a place in man's thoughts, is enough. 
 
 F. Pleasure is good sought on its own single account, and 
 in this particular resembles a last end. It is not, however, a 
 supreme good, able to satisfy every desire; and, in this par- 
 ticular, pleasure falls away from the requirements of an abso- 
 lutely last end. 
 
 G. Individual men tend towards a last end, not that ab- 
 straction called human nature. Pantheists, therefore, are 
 
PRINCIPLES 27 
 
 wrong, when they admit the existence of a last end for human 
 nature, and deny last ends in connection with individuals. 
 
 H. Man's natural desire for happiness is a something he 
 cannot lose. Its accomplishment, because dependent on the 
 acts of his free will, can readily enough be frustrated. 
 
 I. God, pure and simple, is the material object of man's 
 thoughts. God, as He assumes shape in man's mind, is the 
 formal object of these thoughts. Since, therefore, God is in- 
 finite only in Himself, or as material object, man's mind, to 
 have knowledge of Him, need not be infinite. The formal 
 object of a faculty, not its material object, denominates it, 
 puts it in the class of infinites or finites. 
 
 J. As long as man obeys the dictates of reason, so long is 
 he tending towards God, if not formally, at least by inter- 
 pretation. He may not advert to the fact that he is tending 
 towards God, and that would be formal tendency; but in sub- 
 stance he is doing what he would do if he formally tended 
 towards God, and this is tendency by interpretation. 
 
THESIS III 
 
 Man's destiny in this life, his supremest happiness on earth, 
 his relatively last end, consists in drawing closer and closer to 
 his absolutely last end, by the establishment of moral recti- 
 tude in his actions. Between good and bad in the moral 
 order, between right and wrong, an essential, intrinsic differ- 
 ence exists. The immediate measure of moral rectitude is the 
 objective order of things, as understood by the intellect; the 
 mediate measure is God's wisdom and goodness. Jouin, 5-19; 
 Bickaby, 109-126. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 /Man's last end is eternal happiness in the possession of God 
 Life is but a stage in our progress towards God, it is a period 
 (of proof of trial./ We are from the outset vested with heads, 
 ^and hearts, and hands; with all the needed light, and cour- 
 age, and strength, to pursue our appointed journey without 
 mishap. Our supremest happiness here below hinges en- 
 tirely on our present destiny, and our present destiny is of a 
 complexion with our destiny hereafter. Man's history ex- 
 tends beyond the grave, death is far from closing the record. 
 This present life forms, as it were, the first chapter, the years 
 without end to follow make up the rest of the story. But 
 this first chapter is a thing of the utmost concern, it is a 
 thing of the highest importance. All the succeeding chapters 
 borrow from it their light and shade, with it all succeeding 
 chapters must be fair or hideous. Union with God consti- 
 tutes complete happiness; and, unless a man's last moments 
 find him close by the ties of righteousness to his Maker, that 
 man can hope for nothing but most wretched misery. Unless 
 a man's every moment finds him struggling towards this 
 happy consummation, misery will not wait till the hour of 
 death to fasten its hold upon him. What for want of a bet- 
 ter term we call imperfect misery, is the perpetual lot of the 
 
 28 
 
INCOMPLETE HAPPINESS 29 
 
 wicked here on earth. The graduated scale of happiness and 
 woe is the same. A life lived in preparation for supreme 
 felicity constitutes imperfect beatitude, the supremest pos- 
 sible on earth. A life lived in preparation for supreme woe 
 constitutes incomplete wretchedness, the most irksome pos- 
 sible on earth. 
 
 The comparison is between virtue and vice, and between 
 things inseparably connected with both. ^$4^eace of conscience 
 is the one thing inseparably connected with virtue, remorse is 
 the one thing inseparably connected with vicey/ Wealth, pleas- 
 ure and honor are inseparably connected wifii neither virtue 
 nor vice ; and must, therefore, be kept out of the comparison. 
 Virtue with these three concupiscences of life is, of course, 
 happier in point of extent or quantity than virtue without 
 them, though their presence fails to affect necessarily the in- 
 tensity or quality of virtue's happiness. Vice with these three 
 goods of life is less unhappy in point of extent or quantity than 
 vice without them, though their presence never diminishes the 
 annoyance of remorse itself in point of intensity or quality. 
 Poverty, pain and obscurity cannot destroy or diminish peace 
 of conscience ; money, pleasure and honor cannot cure or alle- 
 viate remorse. And again we are talking of normal minds, 
 wide awake to their condition, with a practical realization of 
 peace and remorse. In this whole business intensity or qual- 
 ity counts for more than extent or quantity. There is more 
 money from the viewpoint of extent or quantity in five one- 
 dollar bills than in a single hundred-dollar bill, and yet every- 
 body knows what way a sensible person would look, if invited 
 to choose. Intensity or quality is what makes the difference. 
 A bad life with all the other goods of earth except virtue is 
 more irksome in point of peace and remorse than a good life 
 without all the other goods of earth ; and this is sufficient for 
 our present purpose. Peace of conscience is the hundred- 
 dollar bill, wealth and the other goods of life without virtue 
 are five one-dollar bills. Even if experience failed to bear us 
 out in this statement, philosophy itself is witness that any 
 contrary event would imperil the fitness of things. /t*repara- 
 tion, then, for that absorbing union with God, at the root of 
 every human desire, is the limit set by common sense for well 
 directed act ivity//^ Virtue is as indispensable to happiness 
 
30 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 A 
 
 ere below as it is to happiness in the world to come; and 
 virtue is moral rectitude, the avoidance of evil, the accom- 
 plishment of good/ 
 
 Unless we close our eyes to the light, and do to death the 
 instincts implanted within us, we cannot mistake vice for 
 virtue, we cannot confound evil with good. Between them 
 there is an impassable chasm. No merely accidental, but an 
 essential difference exists between one and the other. And 
 the standard marking this difference is plain. It is the ob- 
 jective order of things, things as they are, things as they 
 ought to seem to you and to me, things as they shall inev- 
 itably seem to you and to me, if we only follow the light 
 vouchsafed us, and cherish conscience for a "friend. This 
 standard never shifts place. Styles of dress change with 
 the season, the etiquette of to-day is other than that of our 
 forefathers; bu^/ne measure of moral rectitude is the same 
 to-day, yesterday and forever. It is founded on the good- 
 ness and wisdom of God/ and partakes of their immutability. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Destiny. End, when viewed as a something imposed on an- 
 other by on'e in a position to exercise this prerogative, is 
 called destiny. Man's last end is an inheritance of his na- 
 ture, and as such proceeds from the author of nature, God. 
 Its fulfilment is a law of nature, and the initial step towards 
 the same, or the right ordering of his life, may with justice 
 be called his destiny. 
 
 Happiness on Earth. We speak at present of incomplete, 
 or imperfect happiness, which consists wholly in the fact that 
 the sum of blessings enjoyed outweighs the sum of evils en- 
 dured, considering only the blessings and evils inseparably 
 connected with virtue and vice, with intensity not extent for 
 standard. 
 
 Moral rectitude. Rectitude is straightness, and the figure 
 of speech at the root of the word fits the thought. Moral 
 rectitude is the shortest distance between two points, our 
 present condition and the felicity of bliss eternal. Its duties 
 lie along a path that never winds to right or left, but keeps 
 straight on. Measured by its requirements, a man's exact 
 
OBJECTIVE MORALITY 31 
 
 position in the matter of living up to his destiny is easily and 
 readily discernible. Morality is the badge of human nature. 
 A moral act necessarily calls for an intellect and a will in the 
 agent. Intellect and will in an agent necessarily call for 
 moral acts. Acts are first said to he moral, and then good or 
 had in the moral order. They are moral from the mere cir- 
 cumstance that they have their origin in an enlightened rea- 
 son, and a will free in its activity. They are good or bad, 
 they derive their righteousness or their malice from their 
 agreement with or divergence from some set standard. This 
 standard is primarily for us the ohjective order of things. 
 When an act falls away from this standard, it is bad ; when it 
 covers the standard, as the rule covers a straight line, the act 
 is good. Men's minds of course differ, and allowance must 
 be made for differences of views sanctioned by Providence. 
 But no believer in God's wisdom, and power, and truthfulness, 
 can for a moment suspect that men's minds in normal condi- 
 tion can confound evil with good, vice with virtue. Had God 
 so constructed intellect. He would be inviting confusion into 
 the universe of morality. He would be cursing our race more 
 heavily than if He allowed the stars to drop from their places, 
 the sun to depart from its course, and baleful comets to run 
 hither and thither at random in the sky. Of course there are 
 intellects, dependent on diseased organs, capable of confound- 
 ing black with white; but these are beside the purpose. 
 Philosophy deals with what is the general rule, not with ex- 
 ceptions. She discusses men taken from the busy walks of 
 life, she does not go to madhouses for subjects. Neither does 
 she pretend to make models of conduct the lives of unfor- 
 tunates, who would be in strait-jackets, if the madhouse had 
 its due. There is, however, such a thing as subjective moral- 
 ity ; and we must recognize the part it plays in the affairs of 
 life. But, be it remarked and well understood that there is in 
 truth no such thing as suhjective morality, pure and simple. 
 My way of thinking, your way of thinking, when they fail 
 to square with the objective order of things, are what I mean 
 by subjective morality, pure and simple; and that kind of 
 morality is a contradiction in terms. Such morality is as 
 little deserving of the name as purely subjective adhesion to 
 a false statement is deserving of the name of certainty. Cer- 
 
32 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 tainty of that kind is perverse stubbornness, has no part with 
 the truth, and is more lamentable than thorough uncertainty 
 or ignorance. Even so, my way of thinking, your way of 
 thinking, if not what they ought to be, are indications of 
 either monstrous iniquity or ignorance. I can by repeated 
 assaults on conscience reduce it to comparative silence, I 
 can by repeated abuse of the light, set up within my bosom, 
 practically extinguish it, I can by constant contact with men 
 given over to a reprobate sense put on their ways, assume 
 their habits of thought, and sin almost without remorse.^^^ut 
 I cannot, no man can, make wrong right. No man can by 
 any process of thought make the crooked line of wickedness 
 identical with the straight line of virtue. ^ 
 
 The man with a moral squint was either born that way, 
 and took no pains to cure the defect, or acquired the habit 
 later in life by repeated acts of disloyalty to conscience. If 
 he was born that way, and honestly tried without any success 
 to better himself, he is a moral imbecile, an idiot, and irre- 
 sponsible. If he acquired the habit, he is a monster of in- 
 iquity ; he has put himself into a hole from which he will 
 never, perhaps, rise; and he is clearly responsible, indirectly 
 or in cause, for every wrong he does the laws of morality. 
 This suhjective morality is a modification, extrinsic and super- 
 added to the action of which there is question. It depends 
 for all its force on the intention, and therefore the knowledge 
 of the agent. It differs entirely from objective morality, 
 which resides wholly in the deed done, which is a something 
 intrinsic and essential to that deed, and is entirely inde- 
 pendent of the agent's intention and knowledge. One is mo- 
 rality of the man, the other is morality of his acts; and, as a 
 man is not good unless his acts are good, subjective morality 
 of itself without objective morality is worth nothing. 
 
 And here new questions arise, those of responsibility and 
 merit. The man whose morality is purely subjective, who 
 does wrong without scruple, may be in one of three classes. 
 He may be an idiot, and is no more responsible for his acts 
 than brute animals. He deserves no reward for whatever is 
 virtuous in his conduct ; he deserves no blame for what would 
 be in another highly reprehensible. He may be the victim of 
 ignorance in no way imputable to him, of ignorance that can 
 
SUMMARY 33 
 
 with no amount of reasonable endeavor be shaken off. In this 
 case, if any such exists, he is ag'ain irresponsible for his con- 
 dition, and for all the wrong it occasions. In neither of these 
 two cases do the acts elicited cease to be immoral or wicked 
 from an objective standpoint. Objective morality is some- 
 thing outside the agent's power, and no ignorance, no idiocy 
 can destroy or change it. Of course the insane and the grossly 
 ignorant are not responsible before the sovereign Judge for 
 their deeds; but responsibility, imputability and demerit are 
 not morality, and should not be confounded with it. Last of 
 all, a man may be the willing victim of ignorance, that he 
 could have easily remedied at some point in his downward 
 career, that he on the contrary fostered and encouraged by 
 every means at his disposal. Such ignorance is of course 
 inexcusable; and purely subjective morality, or immorality, 
 based on it is deserving of condign punishment. 
 
 By way of summary, therefore, we maintain that subjec- 
 tive morality of itself, without objective morality for foun- 
 dation, is nothing. Subjective morality, combined with in- 
 vincible ignorance, is of weight in moral questions ; but such 
 subjective morality is not subjective morality considered in 
 itself. Invincible ignorance makes a wrong conscience right, 
 it never makes an objectively evil act objectively good. The 
 man's intellect is inculpably wrong, his will is right. His 
 Jwill embraces what his intellect represents as right, and the 
 settlement of what is right and wrong, subjectively speaking, 
 is with the intellect, not with the will./ The cases in which 
 subjective morality, or the agent's intention, can justify or 
 condemn a course of conduct, are limited to such sort of acts 
 as are indifferent in themselves to the denominations good 
 and bad. Thus, walking is a healthful exercise for the legs, 
 and depends entirely on purpose and circumstances for its 
 morality. If a man uses his legs on an errand of robbery, 
 walking becomes for him morally culpable. If he uses them 
 on an errand of mercy, or for purposes of worship in the 
 church, walking becomes a virtue, .g^ilful murder of the in- 
 nocent will forever continue to be a crime, no matter what 
 view deluded men take of the tiling. Wilful murder of the 
 guilty by any man or body of men, not vested with the right 
 of life and death, resident in the State, will never be any- 
 
34 GEJnERAL ethics 
 
 thing short of murder/ Lynching, for instance, is on the face 
 of the thing immoral. Circumstances may indeed render its 
 authors more or less responsible for their sin. Zeal for law 
 and order may palliate the crime, a spirit of indignation may 
 fan men's minds to a fury, and rob them for the time being 
 of common-sense; but their method of procediire is wrong, 
 and no amount of zeal, no degree of excitement, no influence 
 of early education can utterly transform the nature of things, 
 and invest crime with the properties of virtue, though in- 
 vincible ignorance or insanity can free the criminal from 
 blame. 
 
 An Essential Difference. This is opposed to an accidental 
 difference. Another name for the same thing is an intrinsic 
 difference, as opposed to extrinsic. The difference between 
 good and bad is essential, inasmuch as no power can remove 
 this quality from good and bad actions. It is intrinsic, inas- 
 much as the acts denominate themselves, independently of all 
 outside interference. This difference would be merely acci- 
 dental, if it were not wrapped up in the very being of the act ; 
 if it could, the act remaining to all intents and purposes 
 identically the same, be present to it to-day and absent from 
 it to-morrow. It would be merely extrinsic, if it owed its 
 whole force to something foreign to the act. Some philos- 
 ophers, whatever their motive, have seen fit to set up a merely 
 accidental and extrinsic difference betweeen good and evil. 
 Thus, Hohhes, Rousseau and Hegel contended- that civil law is 
 the standard of morality. Saint Lambert and Montaigne 
 thought public opinion and tradition the rule. Von H&rf- 
 mann ascribed everything to the stage of evolution compassed 
 by individual consciences. We are ready with good grace to 
 grant that these several standards are immense helps towards 
 detecting the difference between right and wrong. Civil 
 law, for instance, though not very universal in its applica- 
 tions, though it leaves untouched many emergencies liable to 
 occur in a man's daily conduct, is nevertheless uniformly fair 
 in its enactments, and draws a sharp line between good and 
 bad. Public opinion can generally be trusted, tradition is an 
 abundant source of correct moral notions, and conscience when 
 free from bias is unerring. But these measures are all open 
 to serious objection on more scores than one. They are too 
 
ESSENTIAL DIFFERENCE 35 
 
 limited in extent. They are too much subject to change. 
 They are too liable to shift with the whims and fancies of 
 fickle and unstable men. They are entirely subjective, and 
 deliver over to the empire of man responsibilities, more dread- 
 ful than he can with justice be expected to acquit himself of, 
 vesting him with jGod^s prerogative as sole arbiter of right 
 and wrong^Morality, unless it rests on the very nature of 
 things, is settled on altogether too uncertain a foundation. 
 
 Immediate Measure. The measure nearest to hand for 
 practical use. The mediate measure is the more remote, more 
 difficult of access, the last reason and final support of the im- 
 mediate measure, the model according to which the immediate 
 measure is shaped. Room of Measures in the Tower of Lon- 
 don, and measures throughout the kingdom can serve for 
 illustration. 
 
 Objective Order of Things. Order is defined, ^^the arrange- 
 ment of two or more units according to certain definite rela- 
 tions.' ' The order spoken of in the thesis is moral order, not 
 physical; the units composing it are moral beings, with intel- 
 lect and free will, God and men. This moral order is two- 
 fold, objective and subjective. The first depends altogether 
 on things themselves, the second adds to the first the further 
 circumstance of reception into an intellect. The objective 
 order of things is something established by nature, or more 
 properly by the Author of nature. Subjective order is ob- 
 jective order grasped and recognized by the mind, or knowl- 
 edge of things based on the relations in force between the 
 multiplied moral units of creation. Thus, one element of 
 objective order is the place God occupies towards men in the 
 universe. This order, the very nature of things, requires 
 that men acknowledge and worship God. His prerogatives 
 as first cause and last end can be satisfied with nothing short 
 of that twofold homage. Parents are such by nature that 
 order is disturbed, unless children pay them the reverence, 
 obedience and deference due their station. An innocent man 
 has an inalienable right to his life, and only the rankest kind 
 of disorder would refuse to respect his right. But this objec- 
 tive order would be of little avail as a rule of conduct, unless 
 it became part and parcel of a man's intellectual wares by 
 entering his mind. Hence, the standard of morality in its 
 
36 ge5teral ethics 
 
 completeness, is said to be the objective order of things as un- 
 derstood by the intellect. 
 
 Ood's Wisdom and Goodness. God's wisdom, as far as we 
 are at present concerned, is the mind of God made manifest 
 to us in creation. His goodness is His will made manifest to 
 us in the same mirror. 
 
 Proofs I, II, III 
 I. a, Man^s destiny in this life consists in drawing closer 
 and closer to his last end. 
 
 b, His destiny is made good by the establishment of moral 
 rectitude in his actions. 
 
 c, This moral rectitude constitutes man's supremest hap- 
 piness on earth. 
 
 a, This life and the future life are integral parts of man's 
 whole duration. Ergo, man's destiny in this life should be as 
 far as possible identical with that of his future life. But 
 man 's destiny in the life to come is complete happiness, or the 
 secure enjoyment of God forever; and the only condition re- 
 sembling this final state, and at present possible to man, is in- 
 complete happiness, or a closer and closer union with his last 
 end. Ergo, man's destiny in this life consists in drawing 
 closer and closer to his last end. 
 
 b, Near union with God, as man's last end or destiny in this 
 life, 1st, ought to imply man 's highest perfection ; 2nd, ought 
 to be something in man's power; 3rd, ought to contribute its 
 share towards the consummation of nature's universal end. 
 But such is the establishment of moral rectitude in man's 
 actions. Ergo, man's destiny in this life is the establishment 
 of moral rectitude in his actions. 
 
 With regard to the Major. 1st, Because every end implies 
 the agent 's good, the last end implies the agent 's highest good. 
 2nd, Because^an is free, and the working out of his destiny 
 must depend on his own efforts./ 3rd, Because man is a unit 
 in nature, and God's wisdom makes it necessary for the units 
 in nature to work together in harmony. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. 1st, Man's highest good affects 
 what is noblest in man, his reason; reason's most perfect work 
 is order; and moral rectitude or virtue is a life in harmony 
 
PROOFS 37 
 
 with objective order. 2nd, Gifts of body like health, wealth, 
 beauty, are independent of our wishes ; but moral rectitude is 
 the man's own handiwork. 3rd, Creatures inferior to man 
 work unto their ends by nature, or instinct, and necessarily ; 
 man works unto his end by the use of free will, with full lib- 
 erty; and so completes the graded scale of being in the uni- 
 verse. 
 
 /^c, Man 's supremest happiness on earth consists in this, that 
 in the sum total of evil and good, good preponderates. But 
 moral rectitude in a man's life procures this result. Ergo, 
 moral rectitude constitutes man's supremest happiness on 
 earth. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. Apart from the fact that there 
 are higher joys than delights of the body, just men are always 
 the least unhappy. They own a peace the world knows not. 
 Their wills are developed in the right direction by constant 
 exercise in the pursuit of good. Their minds are sharpened 
 by intellectual employment. They escape all the penalties 
 of the law. They are strangers to the annoyance of remorse. 
 They are free from the pains, diseases and early death that 
 wickedness often engenders. 
 
 Confirmation. The happiness bom of moral rectitude, is a 
 figure and shadow of the happiness the blessed enjoy in 
 Heaven. Ergo. 
 
 II. 1st, Were there no essential and intrinsic difference be- 
 tween right and wrong, there would be no acts essentially 
 and intrinsically right and wrong. But many such acts in 
 reality exist. Ergo, between right and wrong an essential 
 and intrinsic difference exists. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. Love of God is an act essen- 
 tially and intrinsically right. It is right now, it was always 
 right, and will forever continue to be right, even if the whole 
 world entered into a conspiracy to call it wrong. Hatred of 
 God is in precisely the same way an act essentially and in- 
 trinsically wrong. 
 
 2nd, Right and wrong have characteristics essentially dif- 
 ferent. Ergo, between right and wrong an essential dif- 
 ference exists. 
 
 With regard to the Antecedent. From proof of next part 
 it will appear, that right is harmony with the objective order 
 
38 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 of things; and wrong, absence of this harmony. Harmony 
 and discord are essentially different. 
 
 III. a, immediate measure; h, mediate measure. 
 
 a, 1st, Acts are right, when in perfect agreement with the 
 dictates of reason ; acts are wrong, when beside these dictates. 
 But the dictates of reason are objective order, as understood 
 by the intellect. Ergo, the immediate measure of moral rec- 
 titude is the objective order of things, as understood by the 
 intellect. 
 
 With regard to the Major. Reason is the guide vouchsafed 
 to man by Grod for his safe conduct, and reason's dictates are 
 the rule of morality. 
 
 With regard ta the Minor. Not to be a purely subjective 
 standard, the dictates of reason must be founded on the ob- 
 jective order of things. Otherwise the dictates are vagaries 
 and hallucinations. 
 
 N.B. The dictates of reason are moral obligations an- 
 nounced by reason, the herald of the Natural Law, and they 
 get fuller consideration in our next thesis. They are practi- 
 cal judgments, not mere speculative statements, and always 
 involve moral necessity or strict obligation, denoted by the 
 word *'must" or ''ought." God must be worshipped, par- 
 ents must be obeyed. "Must" means moral obligation or 
 necessity, not physical. Free agents as such are incapable of 
 physical. Moral obligation means moral necessity of putting 
 or omitting a physically free act, absolutely required for the 
 procurement of a good absolutely necessary for the mun in 
 the moral order. This good is his last end. Moral obligation 
 arises from objective order and divine command together. 
 Kant derives it from objective order alone without God, and 
 this is what his categorical imperative in substance means. 
 Moral obligation arises in part from objective order, because 
 virtue is way to last end, and virtue is harmony with objective 
 order. Not every good act is necessary to last end, but only 
 such good acts as cannot be omitted without detriment to ob- 
 jective order, and reason acquaints us with them. Moral 
 obligation arises in part from divine command, because God 
 alone as Creator is empowered to set man a last end, tie him 
 with a perfect moral bond and give him by way of source and 
 origin virtue and every other perfection. 
 
PROOFS 39 
 
 2nd, Right and wrong proceed from harmony and dis- 
 agreement with nature ; and the immediate measure of moral 
 rectitude is what primarily enables us to distinguish with 
 certainty between them. But to distinguish is to know, and 
 this harmony and disagreement with nature can reach our 
 knowledge only through the intellect, understanding things 
 just as they are, or the objective order of things. Ergo, the 
 immediate measure of moral rectitude is the objective order 
 of things, as understood by the intellect. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. Nature means things as God 
 made them, things just as they are, the objective order of 
 things. 
 
 3rd, Rejection of other standards. Not public opinion, be- 
 cause opinion is rather measured by our standard; opinion is 
 uncertain, changeable and unsafe. Not civil law, because law 
 is rather measured by our standard; law cannot make cer- 
 tain acts good, certain acts bad. 
 
 b, The mediate measure of morality is that on which the 
 immediate measure depends. But its immediate measure, the 
 objective order of things, depends on the wisdom and good- 
 ness of God. Ergo, the mediate measure of moral rectitude is 
 God's wisdom and goodness. 
 
 With regard to the Minor. All creation, signified by the 
 objective order of things, proceeds from the wisdom and 
 goodness of God. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Man's supreme happiness is absence of pain, sickness, 
 sorrow. Answer. Man is made up of body and soul. His 
 body, or sense-appetite, seeks agreeable good, like animals, by 
 instinct ; his soul, or rational appetite or will, seeks becoming 
 good, desirable in itself, without heed to pain and sorrow, 
 when opposed to becoming good. Soul surpasses body, and 
 man's will is man's highest faculty in the order of morality. 
 
 B. Senses ought to be consulted in this life. A^iswer. 
 Complete happiness is impossible in this life. Man's highest 
 good appeals to what is spiritual within him, because intelli- 
 gence is his specific characteristic. When sense wars against 
 reason, it must be repressed. Deficiencies will be more toler- 
 
40 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 able, if in the domain of sense. Of course, the less pain, the 
 better; the more at ease the sense, the better; provided only 
 that reason, or the spiritual element in man, suffers thereby 
 no detriment. If pain of sense, want of bodily comfort, sor- 
 row of soul, contribute to progress in morality, they are to be 
 welcomed with the enthusiasm of fortitude. 
 
 C. Fear of loss is compatible with incomplete happiness, 
 not with complete. 
 
THESIS IV 
 
 A natural law, unchangeable, universal, eternal, has place 
 in men; its complete and full sanction is reserved for the next 
 life; and eternal punishment is not opposed to God's good- 
 ness. This natural law is the foundation and corner-stone of 
 all positive laiv. Jouin, 36-48 ; Rickahy, 133-177. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 We are now satisfied, that the promotion of morality's in- 
 terests in himself and others, is man's present destiny. For 
 the happiness, which righteousness alone can purchase for 
 him, is the nearest possible approach to complete bliss this 
 earth knows. It makes of life a veritable antechamber to a 
 blessed eternity; it leads a man right up to the threshold of 
 God's presence; and God's enduring presence is the ne plus 
 ultra of man 's hopes and desires. We are likewise the happy 
 possessors of a standard sound and true, which will infallibly 
 enable us to detect the ever present difference between right 
 and wrong. The objective order of things, as grasped by the 
 intellect, is our measure; and we feel secure in our posi- 
 tion. For, in trusting our lot to this rule or measure, we are 
 ultimately leaning on the wisdom and goodness of an all-wise 
 and beneficent God. 
 
 But here a difficulty arises. We know that a shadow and 
 image of complete happiness will result to us from steady 
 compliance with the exactions of morality. We know that 
 any falling away from rectitude will be visited with punish- 
 ment, such at least that our days will be more acquainted 
 with woes than with blessings. Incomplete happiness at- 
 taches to virtue ; incomplete misery, to vice. But beyond this 
 we are at sea. Unless we establish in this matter of morality 
 the living presence of law, framed and backed by a being of 
 high authority, rectitude becomes a thing of mere taste, choice 
 between incomplete happiness and incomplete misery, its obli- 
 
 41 
 
42 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 gations are trivial indeed, because self-imposed. Some phi- 
 losophers venture an answer to the difficulty by setting up 
 what they call the autonomy of reason. They follow Kant. 
 They wish wickedness, pure and simple, to be its own full 
 chastisement, and virtue its own reward. In other words, 
 they want no external influence whatever brought to bear on 
 man, in the problem of mapping out his conduct. They want 
 the disgust experienced in deeds of crime, the mind's ill-ease, 
 to be sole bar to the commission of wrong. They would rec- 
 ognize no sin but that superior airy sort of transgression 
 styled philosophic. Theological sin, and the unrest it occa- 
 sions by fear of some personal avenger, they cry down, and 
 declare creatures of superstitious imagination. But the au- 
 tonomy of reason is an afterthought of godlessness, and has 
 atheism for single excuse. As a system, if reduced to prac- 
 tice, it would in one generation involve the world in moral 
 ruin. If reason were its own law, and judge, and headsman, 
 our cities would soon teem with cutthroats, thieves and as- 
 sassins. They are not a polite crew, and the shock their 
 better instincts experience, when engaged in wrong-doing, 
 hardly restrains their hands. The noise made by mere con- 
 sciousness of being out of harmony with nature, makes them 
 lose no very appreciable amount of sleep. Such sanction 
 might possibly exert a check on high-strung, very correct dis- 
 positions ; but it would never reach the multitude in anything 
 like an effective way. 
 
 Law alone, with its tremendous sense of obligation, with 
 its terrifying dread of penalty, can hold our race to the ob- 
 servance of right and the avoidance of wrong. And God 
 would be doing mankind an incalculable injury, He would 
 be raining down evils upon our heads, did He not step into 
 the breach as a legislator, and confirm us in rectitude by law 
 and all the vast machinery of retributive sanction. Were 
 man responsible to himself only for his misdeeds, he would 
 escape with scant justice, and would deny himself in nothing. 
 It is our business to prove that mere knowledge of wrong 
 done, and the confusion springing from such knowledge, are 
 not morality's naked sanction. We have to establish the ex- 
 istence of a law, born with the man, imperatively ordering the 
 fulfilment of all justice, imperatively forbidding the accom- 
 
DIVISION OF LAW 43 
 
 plishment of any evil. We intend to vindicate to this law 
 characteristics wholly its own, ranking it high above all the 
 enactments of human positive law. We intend, further, to 
 make good by positive argument the nature of its sanction, 
 and show that it is the root, foundation and support of all 
 positive law. Unless a man approaches the work of intro- 
 ducing rectitude into his conduct with the deepest respect 
 for natural law, and with a live consciousness of its obliga- 
 tions, he is not fully equipped for the task imposed upon him 
 by nature, and will inevitably miss his destiny. Hence the 
 importance, the necessity, of setting these notions on a firm 
 basis, of demonstrating their objective value, and placing it 
 beyond the reach of dispute and cavil. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Natural Law. Law, taken in its widest sense, is a stand- 
 ard or rule of action, directive of the agent to its proper end. 
 The following table presents at a glance the various possible 
 kinds of law. 
 
 Law, 3^ 
 
 In widest sense, ? 
 
 In less wide sense, ^ 
 
 In strict and proper sense, ^ 
 
 Divine, ^ 
 
 Human, ^ 
 
 Eternal, ^ 
 
 Natural, ^ 
 
 Positive, ^ 
 
 Ecclesiastical, ^9 
 
 Civil, 11/ 
 
 1? The word law is a derivative from the Latin ligare, to 
 bind ; and invariably suggests the idea of obligation. 
 
 ^ Standard or rule of action, directive of agent to proper 
 end. E.g., laws of nutrition, &c., &c. Applicable not only to 
 man and beasts, but to dead matter as well. 
 
 N.B. Action, or motion, from without is not life. 
 
 5 Standard or rule, directive of artistic efforts. E.g., laws 
 
44 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 of painting, sculpture, poetry, oratory. Applicable to be- 
 ings endowed with intellect, and therefore to man alone. 
 
 ^ An ordinance founded on right reason, drawn up and 
 promulgated for the common good by him who has charge of 
 the community affected. Applicable to moral acts alone, to 
 acts proceeding from an intellect and a free will. This defi- 
 nition is taken bodily from St. Thomas, Summa Theol. 1. 2; 
 Q. 90; a. 4., All four causes, material, formal, final and ef- 
 ficient, enter into its composition. It separates law from 
 every conceivable notion resembling the same. It observes 
 due bounds, and keeps law within its own limits. On ac- 
 count of these several qualities the definition is all that can 
 be desired, and commends itself to everybody. Thus, the 
 matter of law is derived from principles vouched for by 
 right reason. No other rule can be of binding force on men 
 possessed of intellects. This is so true that a clearly unrea- 
 sonable law is no law at all. It may be well, however, to 
 remark that, commonly speaking, the only safe position to 
 occupy in this matter is voiced in that saying of moralists, 
 ^'In doubt acquiescence in the will of the superior is a duty.'' 
 The care of a community is so complex a thing, affected by 
 circumstances so far above the understanding and apprecia- 
 tion of individuals governed, that the superior alone, with 
 multiplied advantages at his disposal, and a clear vision of 
 intricate details, can best judge what ruling the exigencies of 
 the case demand. He alone knows best the wants of his em- 
 pire. He alone knows best what good results, in the long 
 run, this or that enactment will, in spite of appearances to 
 the contrary, effect. His practised eye is accustomed to look 
 at things from a higher plane. Individuals in the state look 
 not beyond personal convenience and inconvenience, and 
 would, perhaps, in their selfishness little reck what fate be- 
 fell the government, if only they escaped unhurt from the 
 ruins. Hence, they are wide awake to detect in every new 
 ruling some semblance of injustice. Men are born rebels, 
 and are apt to be prejudiced judges, when passing on a law 
 that interferes with their privileges, or cuts down the measure 
 of their liberties. They easily lose sight of the circumstance, 
 that legislation is primarily for the community 's benefit ; that 
 the individual must on occasions retire into the background, 
 
NATURAL LAW 45 
 
 and submit to the indignity of being trampled upon, just to 
 push the community's interests to the front. Hence, a law 
 is not to be set aside the very first moment a cry of injustice 
 is raised against it. It must be viewed on all sides, its prac- 
 tical workings must be followed down to their minutest de- 
 tails, and the common good, not private advantage, must be 
 the standard of measurement. If, however, it plainly offends 
 against the demands of right reason, it can be rated no law 
 at all, and neglected as such. A law is not a precept. The 
 former affects equally the whole community, the latter is re- 
 stricted to this or that individual. The distinction between 
 the two is brought out in the definition. Of course law is 
 binding, only when it proceeds from a legitimate source, from 
 the representative of authority, who alone enjoys legislative 
 rights, as means to the discharge of his duties. Due promul- 
 gation may be called a necessary property of law. Law is in- 
 tended for human beings; and, as knowledge is the main- 
 spring of all their deliberate acts, knowledge of the law must 
 precede its fulfilment. This necessary condition must not be 
 understood to run counter to that common saying in the 
 courts, ''Ignorance of the law is no excuse." A law may be 
 thoroughly well promulgated, and yet escape the notice of 
 stray members in the community. Promulgation means 
 simply advertisement sufficiently public and widespread to 
 catch the attention of citizens blessed with the ordinary 
 amount of prudence and care. It by no means ensures knowl- 
 edge of the law to such as are too ignorant or too indifferent 
 to help themselves. Sanction, too, capable of frightening off 
 violators, and creating in men a salutary respect for the law, 
 is considered a requisite for every enactment meant to be seri- 
 ously taken. 
 
 ^ Divine law has God for author, and that too in an im- 
 mediate sense. All law proceeds from God as origin. It is 
 strictly divine, only when God is its framer, whether He ac- 
 complishes everything by Himself solely, or uses man as His 
 mouthpiece. 
 
 ? Human law is framed by man without immediate in- 
 terference on the part of God. 
 
 "^ Eternal law. St. Augustine, contra Faustum, 122, c. 27., 
 offers this definition, ^* God's reason or will commanding the 
 
46 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 preservation of natural order, forbidding its disturbance/' 
 God is the supreme Lord of nature. He is King, with the 
 universe for throne, and all the creatures of the universe for 
 subjects. He is, therefore, a legislator as well; and His 
 kingdom is under the sway of laws chosen and appointed by 
 Himself. But He is unchangeable, and what He is to-day, 
 He was and is from all eternity. This code of laws, therefore, 
 for the government of His creatures, had been in His thoughts 
 endless ages of ages before creation proceeded from the 
 strength of His hands. Every lawmaker first submits to his 
 mind for approval, whatever enactments he intends to later 
 on promulgate. He likewise lays before his will tentative 
 drafts of the same, for rejection or adoption. And, when the 
 work of inspection is over, he stands ready to acquaint the 
 world with his wishes. Barring whatever imperfection clings 
 to this method of procedure, God is no exception to the rule in 
 its fundamental points. The laws that now govern nature 
 were first passed upon by His wisdom, and constitute in that 
 stage of the process what we call eternal law. 
 
 5 Natural law, objectively taken, that is, viewed with ref- 
 erence to the source from which it proceeds, is eternal law in 
 its application to man, or become evident in rational nature ; 
 it is man's half of God's eternal law. Subjectively taken, that 
 is, viewed with reference to man, it is an inborn habit of 
 mind, enabling a man to detect the harmony or discord in 
 force between the notions that constitute morality's first prin- 
 ciples. By principles of morality we here mean statements 
 vouched for by reason, and indicative of right and wrong. 
 These principles are various, and are rated in importance 
 according to their different degi'ees of cogency. Thus, first or 
 pmmary principles are such as have in their favor the clearest 
 kind of evidence, and are so plain that even at first sight no 
 man of ordinary common sense can doubt their accuracy. 
 Instances are, ''Man must do good and avoid evil; Man must 
 lead an orderly life ; God must be loved. ' ' Principles of this 
 first class can under no conceivable supposition become void 
 of effect or untrue, and they admit of no ignorance, vincible or 
 invincible. And all this, simply because the above statements, 
 on account of relations intervening between subject and pred- 
 icate, contain necessary truths. Principles, immediately and 
 
GLASSES OF PRECEPTS 47 
 
 with little effort derived from these first or primary prin- 
 ciples, constitute a second class. The ten commandments of 
 the Decalogue are said to be laws of this second class. Some 
 writers except the third, because it singles out the Sabbath. 
 These principles admit of vincible not invincible ignorance. 
 Finally, a third place is occupied hy principles, flowing indeed 
 from first or primary and secondary principles, hut in a some- 
 what hidden and obscure way. They become evident only 
 after mature consideration, and on this account, perhaps, are 
 thoroughly well grasped by only the learned. Polygamy and 
 divorce are examples, alleged by some authors, of laws con- 
 tained in this third class. These last principles admit of 
 even invincible ignorance. 
 
 Eternal law provides for physical and moral order alike; 
 natural law, because meant for men, provides for moral order 
 alone. Substitute moral order for natural order in St. Augus- 
 tine 's definition of eternal law, add promulgated or made 
 manifest in the light of reason, and you have at once natural 
 law objectively taken. Objectively, then, natural law is a 
 divine command issuing from God's reason or will, prescrib- 
 ing the preservation of moral order, forbidding its disturb- 
 ance. Natural law objectively taken is natural law as it 
 exists in God, its maker ; subjectively taken, it is natural law 
 as it exists in man, the person it affects or binds. Subjec- 
 tively taken, natural law is an inborn habit of mind, enabling 
 man to know what he must do and what he must avoid. Man 
 must do only what is in harmony with moral objective order, 
 he must avoid what is at discord with the same order ; and we 
 already proved that this objective order is the measure of 
 morality. He must, therefore, be able to detect this har- 
 mony and discord, and natural law is the means put at his 
 disposal by God. Natural law objectively taken is made up 
 of what we call morality's first principles, commands issuing 
 from the reason or will of God; each of the principles, like 
 all judgments, contains a subject and predicate, and the har- 
 mony or discord the natural law subjectively taken helps the 
 mind to detect is between these subjects and predicates in 
 morality's first principles. Instances are, God is a person 
 who must be worshipped by man. Parents are persons who 
 must be obeyed by their children. Worship is in harmony 
 
48 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 with God, the creator. Obedience is in harmony with parents, 
 makers and guides. Killing is at discord with innocent per- 
 sons. Taking is at discord with what belongs to another. 
 Untruth is at discord with the purpose of language. 
 
 These principles of morality are not mere speculative state- 
 ments, they are practical judgments, with a must or an ought. 
 The harmony or discord is between the subject and predicate, 
 the must or ought is from the divine command prescribing to 
 human nature the preservation of order, forbidding its dis- 
 turbance. This is right or this is wrong, is a mere speculative 
 'statement ; this ought to be done, or this ought to be avoided, 
 is a practical judgment. Mind is not the maker of the nat- 
 ural law, but its herald. God is its maker, man is its subject, 
 and his mind helps him to a knowledge of it, much as the 
 medium that advertises state legislation. In this sense the 
 natural law is said to be written or printed in the mind or 
 heart of man. Therefore principles of morality are practical 
 judgments vouched for by reason, and indicative of right and 
 wrong. 
 
 '^Do good and avoid evil/' is the one first principle by ex- 
 cellence of the natural law, because it implicitly contains the 
 whole law, and because from it all a man's duties are deriv- 
 able. Other principles are variously classified by various au- 
 thors as first, second and third principles; as primary, sec- 
 ondary and remote conclusions from both; as immediate, prox- 
 imate and remote. First, primary and immediate admit of no 
 ignorance, vincible or invincible ; second, secondary and prox- 
 imate admit of vincible ignorance ; third principles and re- 
 mote conclusions admit of even invincible ignorance. In every 
 principle of the natural law the predicate is somehow con- 
 tained in the subject. Otherwise some principles of the nat- 
 ural law would be false. In first or primary principles the 
 predicate is contained in the subject, and its presence cannot 
 be missed by normal minds; it can be seen at a glance. In 
 second or secondary principles the predicate can be discov- 
 ered in the subject with ease, with small or no study. In 
 third principles or remote conclusions the discovery is made 
 with difficulty and at the expense of considerable study. 
 
 Worship of God is a prescription of the natural law. Wor- 
 ship of God in general, without any qualifications, is a pri- 
 
CLASSES OF PRECEPTS 49 
 
 mary principle; external worship is a secondary principle; 
 and worship on the Sabbath, as distinct from other days of 
 the week, can be called a remote conclusion from the other two 
 principles. No ignorance, vincible or invincible, regarding 
 the need of worship in general is possible. Ignorance regard- 
 ing the need of exterior worship is possible, but always vin- 
 cible and inexcusable. Invincible ignorance regarding wor- 
 ship on the Sabbath is easily conceivable. Lies are forbidden 
 by the natural law. The prohibition against lies in general, 
 without any qualifications, is a primary principle. '^Tliou 
 shalt not lie," is a secondary principle easily deduced from 
 the first; and it leaves room for vincible ignorance. Thou 
 shalt not lie, to save an important secret, to avert war, to 
 prevent murder, is a remote conclusion deducible with some 
 difficulty from primary and secondary, and it admits of even 
 invincible ignorance. Theft and murder are against the nat- 
 ural law. Avoid theft, avoid murder are primary principles. 
 Thou shalt not steal, thou shalt not kill are secondary prin- 
 ciples. Thou shalt not steal from motives of kindness to the 
 poor, from motives of religion or piety, to get an education, 
 is a remote conclusion from primary and secondary. Thou 
 shalt not kill at the request of your victim, to do your victim 
 a favor, to benefit the race, to send your victim to Heaven, to 
 propagate the true religion, is a remote conclusion from pri- 
 mary and secondary. 
 
 The nature or substance of the act forbidden by natural law 
 suggests this other division. Some principles turn on acts had 
 in themselves, on their own account, absolutely, in a way in- 
 dependent of every outside consideration. Instances are, 
 hatred of God, blasphemy, idolatry, a lie. Others turn on acts 
 had in themselves, not on their own account, hut on account of 
 a violated right involved in the act itself; not ahsolutely, hut 
 conditionally; not independently, hut with dependence on the 
 right in question. Instances are, theft and murder. Others 
 again turn on acts had in themselves, not on their own account, 
 hut on account of moral risk or danger involved in the act. 
 Instances are, px)lygamy, divorce, heretical and impure read- 
 ing. Things wrong the first way admit no change of matter 
 and are always and everywhere wrong. Things wrong the 
 second and third waj^s admit change of matter; and, the 
 
50 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 change made, they cease to be wrong. God can take away 
 the right involved or the owner can lose it. God can remove 
 the risk and danger or a proportionate cause can justify the 
 risk or danger. 
 
 In their attempts to explain God's approval of polygamy 
 in the Old Law, writers experience trouble, and have recourse 
 to various interpretations of natural law. One school recog- 
 nizes three different types of precepts urged hy the natural 
 law. These types are much the same in nature as the precepts 
 just explained, and are called most universal, remote and more 
 remote; or, with Meyer, primary, secondary and more remote. 
 Examples are, *'Do good, and avoid evil." "Honor thy 
 father and mother." "Be a man of one wife." The Thom- 
 ists, who insist on this classification, teach that God can dis- 
 pense with the natural law in precepts of the third class. 
 Suarez objects to the statement, that God is at liberty to dis- 
 pense with the natural law in any of its enactments. Since 
 we have agreed to regard the natural law as a mere manifesta- 
 tion of the eternal law, his position is well taken ; and we hold 
 with him that God in sanctioning polygamy nowise inter- 
 fered with the operation of the natural law. He procured 
 such a change of circumstances and conditions, that polygamy 
 fell outside of matter under the ban of the natural law. 
 
 Another school, to meet the same difficulty, assigns three 
 ways in which things can run counter to the natural law. It 
 is agreed on all sides that natural law forbids whatever is in 
 itself and intrinsically wrong, not merely in its consequences, 
 not in virtue of some outside prohibition, like civil law or the 
 injunction of a parent. Then come the distinctions. A 
 thing, they say, can be in itself and intrinsically wrong in a 
 threefold way. First, it can he wrong in itself, and abso- 
 lutely; like blasphemy, idolatry and lying. The moral dis- 
 order in this case is something wrapped up in the physical 
 being of the act. Secondly, it can be wrong in itself, not on 
 its own account, and not absolutely; like theft and murder. 
 The moral disorder results not precisely from the physical 
 act, but from the presence of some right connected with it, and 
 violated. The self-same physical act can be entirely blame- 
 less, when exerted to come into one's own property, or to 
 kill a criminal condemned by the state to death. Thirdly, it 
 
CLASSES OF PRECEPTS 51 
 
 can he wrong in itself, not on its own account, hut on account 
 of moral risk or danger it involves, like the perusal of un- 
 chaste or irreligious literature. The moral disorder results in 
 this case from the danger to faith and morals attendant on 
 such reading. With regard to these divisions, it must be 
 remarked that even natural law has no application, when the 
 matter of the act undergoes a certain change. Thus, the 
 forcible removal of what was another 's property will cease to 
 be theft, if the intruder is first invested with a sound claim 
 to it. The midwives of Israel committed no wrong, when 
 they carried off the vessels and ornaments of the Egyptians, 
 simply because God, who is the absolute Lord of everything, 
 transferred to them through Moses dominion or ownership. 
 The same remark holds good in the case of an executed crim- 
 inal. Students of theology and medicine are obliged by their 
 calling to read books, the mere curious perusal of which 
 would be highly sinful, and the need of such reading in their 
 case justifies the risk. 
 
 The first of the classes just enumerated includes only such 
 cases as admit no change of matter. God Himself cannot 
 render blasphemy, lying, idolatry commendable. With re- 
 gard to polygamy, all writers grant, and must maintain, that 
 it is not a crime against the natural law in the first way, and 
 in the same sense as blasphemy, idolatry and lying. Some 
 contend that it resembles theft, inasmuch as the woman's 
 rights are not respected. It must be evident that, were this 
 supposition true, God could have made polygamy in the Old 
 Law legitimate by depriving the woman of whatever rights 
 it would otherwise violate. The most approved writers, how- 
 ever, agree to regard polygamy a wrong against the natural 
 law, inasmuch as it menaces the well-being of marriage, and so 
 damages the race in its origin. It is fraught with danger to 
 the stability and happiness of wedlock, and exposes children 
 to heavy evils. Discontent, jealousy and attendant quarrels 
 are, naturally speaking, sure to reign where polygamy is a 
 recognized practice. God favored the patriarchs and their 
 wives with dispositions above petty grievances of this sort, 
 and in removing danger rendered the condition legitimate. 
 
 A third school professes to find all the sinfulness attaching 
 to polygamy in the single circumstance, that, God's prohihi- 
 
52 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 tion presupposed, the polygamist invades the rights of God, 
 and runs counter to His express wishes. A Catholic eating 
 meat on Friday, would in this supposition be no less an of- 
 fender against the natural law than the Mormon with a house 
 full of wives. A fourth school, finally, distinguishes between 
 enactments of the natural law strictly so called, and mere rec- 
 ommendations urged hy nature as highly becoming, though not 
 of binding necessity. They group under enactments of the 
 first class universal maxims, like, "Do good and avoid evil"; 
 conclusions readily and plainly derivable from these maxims, 
 like the Ten Commandments; and precepts ordaining the 
 avoidance of things intrinsically and absolutely bad, like blas- 
 phemy. Under recommendations urging the proper they 
 group conclusions derivable after some study from univer- 
 sal maxims, like the statutes against polygamy and divorce; 
 precepts ordaining the avoidance of things bad in themselves, 
 not because of themselves, but because of danger attached, like 
 the perusal of immoral literature. 
 
 To choose, now, between the different schools, I venture to 
 think that the explanation offered by the second school is 
 clearest, best defined, and most to the point. Natural laWj 
 therefore, is a mandate of reason, ordering the performance of 
 whatever is good intrinsically and in itself, forbidding things 
 intrinsically and in themselves bad. Seeming exceptions made 
 in the Old Law in the cases of Isaac's intended slaughter, the 
 Hebrew midwives, and polygamy among the patriarchs were 
 simply no violations at all of the natural law. God worked 
 a change in the matter on which these acts turned. He in- 
 vested Abraham with full dominion over his son's life; He 
 transferred to the Hebrew women rights in property that 
 once belonged to the Egyptians; He removed from polygamy 
 all the dangerous abuses that naturally surround such a con- 
 dition, and so rendered it as salutary and secure as mo- 
 nogamy. 
 
 ? Positive divine law is a decree, proceeding with full free- 
 dom from the mind of God, in the interests of common good. 
 The ceremonial prescribed in the Old Law was positive divine 
 law for the chosen people. The utterances in the gospels for- 
 bidding absolute divorce and polygamy, are positive divine 
 law in the new dispensation. Natural law is separated from 
 
 
POSITIVE DIVINE LAW 53 
 
 positive divine law by the absence of freedom in the legisla- 
 tor, and by the nature of the promulgation it demands. God 
 is not free to make lying sinful or virtuous, and the same is 
 true of theft, murder, polygamy and divorce, when no change 
 of matter has taken place. While ordaining certain rites and 
 ceremonies for use in His service, He remained entirely free to 
 select some and reject others. The natural law is such that 
 its actual promulgation has place in the very fact of a hu- 
 man being's existence. Up to that hour it is still possessed 
 of what philosophy calls promulgation in aptitude. Knowl- 
 edge of the natural law escapes a man during the period of 
 infancy, but knowledge of the law must not be confounded 
 with its promulgation-. Positive divine law on the contrary 
 has all its effect, only when received by the subject bound to 
 its -observance, and necessarily supposes some such subject 
 actually existent, and capable at least of grasping its content. 
 Natural law is a means indispensably necessary to the end of 
 man. Positive divine law is, indeed, a means more or less 
 necessary to man's end, but nohow indispensably necessary. 
 This or that positive divine law need never have existed, and 
 man could still compass his end. This or that positive divine 
 law can at any time cease to ex:ist, without in the least jeopar- 
 dizing man 's final interests. 
 
 Natural law is the eternal law in its application to creatures^ 
 endowed with reason, and as such cannot long remain hidden 
 from an enquiring mind. Its decrees are not inscribed on 
 tsfblets of stone, or wood, or written pages, but on a man's 
 heart. Its promptings are ever present, and defy forgetting. 
 The light vouchsafed by nature to all her sons is able to con- 
 vey notions of the natural law, and interpret its dictates. No 
 training in the schools is needed, no labor over long lists of ^^ 
 rules and regulations. These features, peculiar to natural 
 law, constitute another vast difference between itself and posi- 
 tive law, whether human or divine. Positive law is of no 
 avail whatever, unless promulgated or brought to man's no- 
 tice by some such external sign as language, written or spoken. 
 Any body of positive laws can of course include obligations 
 and restrictions already imposed by the natural law. In fact, 
 owing to the weakness inherent in men's minds and wills, it 
 is eminently proper for legislators to insist in clearer terms 
 
54 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 on points already defined by the natural law. This method 
 has a twofold advantage. It makes ignorance less excusable, 
 and adds to the sanction, already awaiting in the next life 
 every violence done the natural law, the further punishment 
 of immediate fine, pain or imprisonment. Law is only then 
 purely and simply positive, when it decrees things not pre- 
 viously settled by natural law ; when it turns on acts, which, 
 in themselves indifferent, become right or wrong according to 
 the good pleasure or wishes of a superior. Positive divine 
 law has God for immediate author. Human positive law 
 has man for immediate author. This human law is either 
 ecclesiastical or civil. 
 
 19 Ecclesiastical law is law uttered hy the Church. 
 
 ^^ Civil law is law uttered hy the state; or hy him in whose 
 person the authority of the state resides. 
 
 TJnchangeahle. The first or primary principles of natural 
 law are absolutely unchangeable. God Himself cannot re- 
 verse them. All its other principles, of an inferior order, are, 
 strictly speaking, as unchangeable as these first or primary 
 principles. God, however, as absolute Lord of the universe, 
 can introduce into the matter, with which these inferior prin- 
 ciples are concerned, changes that modify the whole face of 
 things, and leave no room for the law's application. E.g., 
 Isaac, midwives, capital punishment. 
 
 Universal^ in a Twofold Sense. It hinds all without excep- 
 tion. It is within the reach of every one^s knowledge. There 
 can be no ignorance of primary principles. Whatever igno- 
 rance exists regarding secondary principles, is due entirely to 
 personal and private negligence. It is therefore voluntary, 
 can be readily overcome, and is utterly inexcusable. Invinc- 
 ible ignorance is conceivable in the case of remote conclusions. 
 The essence of human nature is the same in all mankind, and 
 this essence is the foundation of the natural law. We con- 
 tend merely that the natural law is within easy reach of every 
 man's knowledge. We by no means maintain that nations 
 made up of men, whom long centuries of crime have practi- 
 cally changed into beasts, necessarily retain a clear knowledge 
 of nature's requirements in the matter of morality. Neither 
 do we intend to prove that natural law is universally ob- 
 served, or that its principles in their application invariably 
 
SANCTION 55 
 
 fare well. These first principles of morality may be firmly 
 fixed in the minds of a pjeopla, and thearetically respected, 
 without at all hindering that people from making serious mis- 
 takes in their application and practical emplojonent. 
 
 Eternal. It is of as long duration as its counterpart or 
 model, eternal law. It had of course no practical application, 
 until rational creatures appeared on the scene; but the law 
 itself had being from all eternity in the mind of God. No 
 enactment ceases to be a law, simply because actual subjects 
 are wanting to observe it. It is enough if it can later on have 
 such subjects; if, as a matter of fact, it is certainly going to 
 have such subjects at some future period. Eternal law and 
 natural law differ not in point of duration, but in point of 
 subjects. The distinction between the two laws is real and 
 inadequate. In point of subjects from eternity natural law 
 is no worse off than eternal. 
 
 Sanction Means Bernard or Punishment Fixed hy the Law- 
 maker for the Observance or Violation, of His Law. This 
 sanction can be of many kinds. It is internal, when the re- 
 ward or punishment is wholly within the man himself, not 
 due to outside influences. E.g., joy of a good conscience, and 
 remorse. It is external, when some outside agent rewards or 
 punishes. E.g., Heaven or hell. With regard to its effi- 
 ciency, a sanction may be sufficient or insufficient, and that too 
 either absolutely or relatively. It is absolutely sufficient, when 
 it is of itself motive enough to urge a man in every case to the 
 law's observance. It is relatively sufficient, when, of some- 
 what less force, it avails only to urge certain kinds of men 
 in certain kinds of cases to the law's observance. From this 
 description one can easily derive the notion of absolutely and 
 relatively insufficient sanction. Sanction is, besides, perfect 
 or imperfect. Perfect, when the due proportions of justice 
 are kept between a man's deserts and his reward or punish- 
 ment. When the contrary happens, when sanction falls short 
 of justice, it is called imperfect. All sanction has a twofold 
 end or object. It is designed on the one hand to promote 
 the reign of moral order, to keep men to their duty; on the 
 other, to reinstate justice when dethroned by wrong; to dis- 
 charge the debts of justice, when men deserve well of her by 
 the performance of right. Meyer derives the difference in 
 
56 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 force between penalties inflicted from the object this or that 
 sanction proposes to itself. All depends, he says, on the order 
 at stake. If punishment is meted out with reference pri- 
 marily and principally to procuring order in the moral af- 
 fairs of a private individual, the sanction will consist of pains 
 destined almost wholly to cure and correct. Sanction of this 
 sort is proper to boys receiving instruction at the hands of 
 a tutor, and is called medicinal. If punishment is meted 
 out primarily and principally to procure social or political 
 order in the state, the sanction will consist of penalties in- 
 flicted almost wholly with a view to avenging social wrongs, 
 and is called punitive. The amendment of the transgressor, 
 because the common good is in this case of paramount im- 
 portance, occupies only a secondary place. It can be entirely 
 neglected, if any attempt to secure it runs counter to the 
 common good. This observation of Father Meyer is emi- 
 nently correct, and can be of service later on, when the moral- 
 ity of capital punishment is in question. 
 
 Next Life. We are far from wishing to deny that viola- 
 tions of the natural law meet with heavy punishment in this 
 life, or that compliance with its precepts has a reward even 
 in this life. Seneca says, Epist. 22, ' ' AVickedness takes a big 
 swallow of its own poison." St. Augustine, Confess. I, ''It is 
 thy good pleasure, Lx)rd, and it is a fact, that every soul 
 out of harmony with right is its own greatest tormentor." 
 We merely hold that the sanction, as a matter of fact attend- 
 ant on the natural law here below, is wholly inadequate, and 
 far from satisfying the demands of justice. The immortal- 
 ity of the soul is warrant for the reality of a future exist- 
 ence; and reason, apart from revelation, even if solid proofs 
 are wanting, hints darkly at a place of eternal torments. 
 From revelation the prison-house of fire, denominated hell, 
 is an established fact. Philosophy can proceed no farther 
 than prove the need and the compatibility of such a place of 
 torment with God's attributes. 
 
 Positive Law. About the justice and binding force of God's 
 positive enactments there can be no controversy. He is in- 
 finitely wise, infinitely just, and cannot, in virtue of these two 
 attributes, impose on men obligations lacking any essential 
 or necessary characteristic. His true Church, strengthened 
 
CIVIL LAW 57 
 
 by reiterated promises of guidance and assistance, can make 
 no mistake in the field of legislation. But that branch of 
 human positive law denominated civil, because subject to the 
 immediate influence of men, swayed by prejudice and pas- 
 sion, open to moments of forgetfulness and ignorance, can 
 readily enoug^h admit of blunders, and can carry on its rec- 
 ords rules and regulations decidedly wrong and opposed to 
 reason. Such laws, as we have already seen^ are laws only 
 in appearance, and have in reality no binding force what- 
 ever. It may be well, then, to discuss what qualities are 
 needed to render any positive law, notably civil, worthy of 
 consideration, respect and obedience. A law, to be worthy 
 of the name, must, along with due and sufficient promulga- 
 tion, fulfil certain conditions classified under three heads. 
 Some affect the lawmaker; others, the matter contained in the 
 law. The lawmaker must he possessed of genuine authority 
 over the persons, for whom he legislates, in points the law 
 touches. The vitality of all law has its origin in God, and 
 God can seal with His approval only such mandates as pro- 
 ceed from legitimately constituted superiors. In the matter 
 of its prescriptions the law must he just and possihle. It 
 must be just, because otherwise it would not have natural 
 law for foundation and support. It must be possible, in 
 accordance with that worn truth, ''Ad impossible nemo tene- 
 tur." "No man is bound to do the impossible." Justice 
 brands as worthless whatever law conflicts with a citizen's 
 higher duty, whatever law is neither necessary nor useful 
 for the common good. Natural law cries out against any- 
 thing like the sacrifice of a higher duty to lower offices, and 
 the very essence of law, as set forth in its definition, makes the 
 common good an indispensable requisite. The common good 
 must be sought, too, in a fair way. To secure this fairness, 
 the law must with an impartial hand distribute burdens over 
 the whole commonwealth. It must not enrich the wealthy 
 at the expense of the poor. It must not rob the rich, to 
 confirm the idle in their wicked ways. But everything must, 
 as far as possible, be so nicely adjusted that neither the rich, 
 nor the poor, nor the idle can with justice complain. Jus- 
 tice likewise brands as worthless whatever law imposes obli- 
 gations impossible of fulfilment. Impossibility is either phys- 
 
58 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 ical or moral. An obligation is physically impossible of ful- 
 filment, when it simply surpasses the physical strength at a 
 man's disposal, e.g., a law ordering subjects to push moun- 
 tains into the sea. It is morally impossible of fulfilment, 
 when its observance is beyond measure difficult. Liberty can 
 have no play, when a man 's physical force is unequal to some 
 task assigned; and law without liberty is a dead letter. 
 Suarez remarks that the difficulty involved in compliance with 
 voluntary poverty, chastity and obedience, induced God, per- 
 haps, to make these several virtues matter of counsel, not law, 
 in the new dispensation. Several maxims well worth re- 
 membering flow as corollaries from the doctrine just made 
 good. A human enactment at open variance with God's law 
 is no law at all, and entirely void of value. An enactment 
 favoring injustice is no law. Rulers have no right to impose 
 unjust laws on their subjects. Despotism and absolutism are 
 species of government opposed to these maxims; and some 
 philosophers, untrue to their calling, have upheld systems 
 favoring these crimes. MachiavelU, for instance (1469-1527), 
 allows the advantage of men in power to usurp the place of 
 justice. Hohhes (1588-1679) is of opinion that supreme au- 
 thority can make no mistake, incur no blame. Spinoza (1632- 
 1677), because of his pantheistic notions, is guilty of the same 
 folly. Rousseau (1712-1778) attributes to democracy the 
 prerogatives ascribed by Hobbes to monarchy. Hegel and 
 his followers make the state God, and pass by easy steps to 
 the absurdity of a public conscience, the standard and rule 
 of private morality. We who advocate the right are accused 
 of introducing into public affairs baneful subjectivism, deroga- 
 tory to the majesty of the law, and subversive of its efficacy. 
 But the accusation is a vile slander. Our enemies are, on 
 the contrary, subjectivism's most steadfast allies, they degrade 
 law to the level of conscienceless bullying, substitute might 
 for right, and, robbing law of all moral efficacy, arm it with 
 the force and violence of unprincipled coercion and tyranny. 
 Our platform rests on the eternal principles of justice, founded 
 on the eternal law of God, and manifest to man in his reason. 
 These principles are certainly a more objective reality than 
 the empty whims and selfish enactments of greedy rulers. 
 To clothe an unjust enactment with a majesty borrowed from 
 
CIVIL LAW 59 
 
 so sacred a thing as law, is like blasphemy ; and to set might 
 over right is to step from civilization to savagery. To avoid 
 mistakes in practice, too much stress cannot be laid on that 
 principle advanced earlier in the course of these remarks, 
 '\In doubt y acquiescence in the will of a superior is a duty." 
 Duly constituted authority is always in possession, and its 
 rulings must be considered just and fair, until their injus- 
 tice and unfairness are solidly and incontrovertibly proved. 
 If, however, there can be no doubt about a law's injustice, 
 resistance to the law may become a duty or a privilege. If 
 it antagonises some divine good, if it stands up against some 
 law of God, we enjoy no liberty in the matter ; we are bound 
 to disregard the unjust law, and die martyrs rather than 
 observe it. ''We must obey God rather than men.'* A.A.4. 
 If it plainly antagonises some human good, whether it tends 
 to promote private greed at the expense of the public wel- 
 fare, or oversteps the bounds of authority to work harm, or 
 fosters favoritism to the detriment of justice, disobedience be- 
 comes a privilege, of which subjects may avail themselves or 
 not, as they please. Such a law certainly has of itself no 
 claims on the conscience. Conscience, however, may exact 
 the personal inconvenience, arising from obedience, as a lesser 
 evil than the consequent scandal and disturbance. But in that 
 case the obligation arises not from the unjust law, but from 
 the natural duty men lie under of at times sacrificing their 
 own interests to further the interests of society. 
 
 Foundation and Corner-stone. This question has a more 
 important bearing on Ethics than might at first sight be sup- 
 posed. We are at present grounding ourselves in principles, 
 that will afterwards serve us in the solution of difficulties, aris- 
 ing from the post we occupy in affairs. As citizens, we shall 
 be amenable to the law ; and, unless we recognize God in the 
 law, we shall be possessed of only half the truth, and little able 
 to faithfully discharge our duties. Every enactment emanat- 
 ing from legitimate authority has God at its back, and phi- 
 losophy is witness to the fact. If, as we hope to prove, nat- 
 ural law is the foundation and corner-stone of all positive 
 law, and if natural law is God's own decree, men cannot do 
 violence to civil or ecclesiastical law without dishonor to 
 God. Law, therefore, has a double avenger, God and the 
 
60 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 State; and good citizenship becomes a matter of conscience. 
 Law owes only half its efficacy to the legislator's will, the 
 other half descends from Heaven. Fear of God 's wrath must 
 act along with dread of fine and imprisonment, to exercise 
 a salutary restraint on the passions of men. 
 
 In law, as in everything else, we can, with the Scholastics, 
 consider matter and form. Its matter is the substance of the 
 order it contains. Its form is that binding force it possesses, 
 that moral necessity it imposes. We cannot contend that the 
 body or substance of every positive law is contained in the 
 natural law. Many positive laws have for object the per- 
 formance of acts in themselves quite indifferent, about which 
 natural law has not a word to say. But no matter how in- 
 different in itself an act prescribed by positive law may be, 
 we hold that natural law, after human legislation has spoken, 
 vests the act with all the binding force any dictate of the 
 natural law owns. We further hold that, by a process of 
 reasoning, every ruling made by positive law is reducible to 
 a principle hidden somewhere in the natural law. 
 
 Pkoofs 
 
 I. A natural law has place in man. 
 
 II. This natural law is, ^ unchangeable, ^ universal, ° eter- 
 
 nal. 
 
 III. Its complete and full sanction is reserved for the next 
 
 life. 
 
 IV. Eternal punishment is not opposed to God's goodness. 
 V. Natural law is the foundation of all positive law. 
 
 I. 1st, Experience is witness, through the medium of con- 
 science, that certain rules of conduct, exacting obedience, wring 
 acknowledgment from the mind by their clearness. But laws 
 of the kind constitute what we call natural law. Ergo, nat- 
 ural law has place in man. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Worship God, honor parents, 
 do unto others as you would have others do unto you. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. These rules have their origin 
 in human nature, not in prejudice, education or ignorance. 
 They carry authority, and impress man with a sense of re- 
 sponsibility and obligation. 
 
PROOFS FOR PROPERTIES 61 
 
 2nd, Every force in nature, to produce its own proper ef- 
 fect, must be furnished with a certain determinant suited to 
 itself, holding it to a fixed line of action. But natural law is 
 to the human will such a determinant. Ergo, natural law 
 has place in man. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. The most holy will of God 
 and His wisdom demand as much. God cannot be indifferent 
 to the promotion of order in the universe; and, in any hy- 
 pothesis but that set down in the Major, He would have been 
 at too small pains to promote order. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Natural law alone exercises 
 proper and becoming restraint over man. As a free agent no 
 chain but law can bind him. Other agents are limited to 
 this or that effect by a something implanted in their very na- 
 ture. Man, therefore, should be held in check by a law 
 bound up in his nature, born with him, and antecedent to all 
 the declarations of divine and human positive law. 
 
 3rd, The whole world is willing witness to the reality of a 
 natural law. The noblest among the minds of antiquity, 
 poets, philosophers and statesmen, have left us their senti- 
 ments, couched in the choicest and sublimest language, e.g., 
 Oedipus Rex, line 863-871; Antigone, lines 446-460. Plato, 
 Apologia, par. 29, D. Ch. 17. Republic, Bk. 4, par. 427. 
 Gorgias, par. 483, E; par. 4^8, b; par. 491, E; Cicero, pro 
 Milone, Ch. 4, § 10. Philippics XI, C. 12, § 28. De Legibus, 
 I, c. 6 ; II, c. 4. Lactantius, Institut VI, 8. 
 
 II. a, b, c. That is unchangeable, universal and eternal, 
 which is necessarily connected with the essence of rational 
 creatures, which is contained in God's wisdom. But the nat- 
 ural law fulfils this twofold condition. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. ^' Essences are unchangeable, 
 i.e., that by which a thing is what it is, cannot change, as 
 long as the thing remains what it is, for instance, a man. 
 ^' Essences are universal, i.e., wherever a man exists, there 
 also a man's essence exists. N.B. The natural law is for 
 this reason, at least in point of being or reality, universal. 
 It is universally known, from the fact that no human being 
 can be unequal to the task of acquainting himself with his 
 own nature. Ignorance, therefore, of the natural law is the 
 result of accident, not a necessity. Besides, no one is ignorant 
 
62 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 of a certain few very evident principles. ^' Essences are 
 eternal metaphysically, not physically ; in the sense that they 
 have a being without beginning and without end in God's 
 thoughts. Law can exist before its actual subjects exist, as 
 happens when kings make laws with intent that they go into 
 effect a year after their promulgation. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Natural law is reason's inter- 
 pretation of the eternal law, and reason combined with ani- 
 mality is man's essence. The eternal law is God's wisdom, 
 and the natural law is a reflection of the eternal. Objectively, 
 natural law is eternal law, restricted to rational creatures, and 
 in this sense it is eternal. Subjectively, natural law is rea- 
 son's interpretation of eternal law, and in this sense it is tem- 
 poral. 
 
 III. N.B. That some sanction is necessary, must be evi- 
 dent from elementary notions of justice, holiness, wisdom and 
 providence. God could not consistently with His attributes 
 impose on mankind so serious an obligation as the natural 
 law, and then view with indifference its fulfilment and con- 
 tempt. He would be unjust to men, if He failed to reward 
 the doers of the law, and punish its violators. Men can merit 
 de condigno with God because of the implicit promise in God 's 
 gift of free will. This supposed indifference, resulting from 
 the absence of all sanction, would likewise be a blot on His 
 sanctity. He would be decidedly unholy, if He treated alike 
 sinner and saint, rebel and servant. His wisdom could be 
 called into question, and His providence would be empty as 
 a dream. Even human legislators are far-seeing enough, and 
 zealous enough for law and order, to visit with punishment 
 every infraction of their behests. When discussing Kant's 
 autonomy of reason, we agreed that mere consciousness of 
 duty done is not a sufficient reward for virtue, and that mere 
 consciousness of a quarrel with ourselves is not an effective 
 bar against crime. To prove, therefore, that complete and 
 full sanction is reserved for the next life, we argue thus. 
 
 ^' Virtue's complete and full reward cannot be contained 
 in things, that must on occasions be sacrificed for virtue's 
 preservation. But all the good things of this life, yea, life 
 itself, must on occasions be sacrificed for virtue 's preservation. 
 Ergo, complete and full sanction is reserved for the next life. 
 
HELL AND BOD'S GOODNESS 63 
 
 N.B. Reward must be more attractive than the sacrifice. 
 Cause cannot be inferior to effect. The sum of 499 dollars 
 could never be full and complete return for 500 dollars. 
 
 ^' Punishment must be such, that within reason no greater 
 can be devised, because an infinite person is seriously offended. 
 But present punishment falls short of this. Ergo, sanction 
 is reserved for next life. N.B. The Major could read. Sanc- 
 tion, while not unduly severe, must be efficacious. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Defects of present punish- 
 ment. 
 
 The just in this life suffer grievous ills, the wicked flourish. 
 
 The pangs of conscience are trivial compared with the ad- 
 vantages reaped from crime. The good always enjoy a pre- 
 ponderance of blessings over ills. This preponderance ad- 
 mits of degrees. It would be greater than it now is, if the 
 prosperity of the wicked and the grievous ills of the just were 
 interchanged. 
 
 An eternal hell is weak at times to stay the arm of sin; 
 any threat of temporal punishment would on such occasions 
 prove empty and worthless. 
 
 The wicked, who die in their sins, would be able to boast 
 for all eternity of their superiority over God. 
 
 IV. 1st, From the Very Meaning of God's Goodness. In- 
 finite goodness consists in a willingness to so far share itself 
 with free beings as free beings desire union. But eternal 
 punishment is not opposed to this willingness. Ergo, eternal 
 punishment is not opposed to God's infinite goodness. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. If free beings deliberately put 
 themselves out of condition for union with God, the fault lies 
 with themselves alone. God's goodness must not interfere 
 with man's freedom. God stands ever ready to lavish His 
 affections on the sons of men, and pour Himself out on them. 
 He is not otherwise minded even towards sons who have for- 
 feited their inheritance, and consort with the damned. But 
 these sons are now unfortunately capable of hatred only, and 
 utter strangers to emotions of love. They have rejected God, 
 the universal good. Outside of universal good nothing but 
 evil exists, and evil is the formal object of hatred. God's 
 readiness, therefore, meets with an insuperable impediment, 
 and is destined to remain forever void of effect. If the 
 
64 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 damned could love God, there would be no hell. Confirma- 
 fiQfi — God need not give to free creatures favors which they 
 deliberately refuse. God wishes all to be saved with antece- 
 dent will. 
 
 2nd, From the Absurdity Apparent in the Opposite Doc- 
 trine. The denial of eternal punishment involves an absurd- 
 ity. Ergo, eternal punishment is not opposed to God's good- 
 ness. 
 
 With Regard to the Antecedent. Union with God and per- 
 severance in hatred of God are conflicting notions; and, 
 were the punishment of sin anything short of eternal pain, 
 sinners would after death, at some point of time or other, 
 enjoy union with God and remain His enemies. Since man's 
 period of probation closes with death, no power can avail 
 him to change the relation he holds with God in his last mo- 
 ment. Any other view of probation would encourage crime 
 in this life by unduly exalting God's mercy at the expense of 
 His justice and holiness. 
 
 3rd, From the Very Meaning of Sanction. Complete and 
 full sanction necessarily calls for eternal punishment. Ergo, 
 eternal punishment is not opposed to God's goodness. 
 
 With Regard to Antecedent. Complete and full sanction 
 calls for penalties, severe enough to ensure observance of the 
 law. But, in the present order of things, nothing short of 
 eternal pains can effect this result. Even with hell open 
 before them, men daily commit crimes, and, driven by pas- 
 sion, take the dread risk. 
 
 4th, God's goodness suffers no loss, when He allows free 
 beings to choose what they will. But free beings, when they 
 spurn aside their true end, make deliberate choice of ever- 
 lasting pains. Ergo, eternal punishment is not opposed to 
 God's goodness. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. They make choice of God's 
 eternal hatred, without any chance of remedy; and hell is 
 nothing more, nothing less, than God's eternal hatred. 
 
 V. Positive law derives from natural law its binding 
 force, it is void of all effect when opposed to natural law, 
 and is, in the main, only an application of natural law to 
 particular places, times and persons. Ergo, natural law is 
 the foundation and corner-stone of positive law. 
 
PRINCIPLES 65 
 
 With Regard to the Antecedent, God alone is vested with 
 full and independent right to impose obligations on free- 
 born men; and, if natural law contained no injunction re- 
 garding the duty of subjects to their superiors, positive law 
 would be little better than an idle waste of words. The chief 
 reason why most sensible men submit to the requirements of 
 positive law, is found in the circumstance that they recog- 
 nize divinity at its back. They know themselves smart enough 
 to break the law without falling into the law's clutches, they 
 regard it a too easy matter to cheat the law of imprisonment 
 and chains ; but they fear with a wholesome dread that eternal 
 avenger of the law, whose eye never sleeps, whose prison- 
 house never yields up its dead. 
 
 All human positive law, from whatsoever source its matter 
 is derived, gets its form or binding force from natural law. 
 Some positive laws urge matter already prescribed by the 
 natural law, others urge matter in itself indifferent; and 
 even in the latter case some natural law counsels the law- 
 maker to legislate. We are talking in the main of positive 
 laws belonging to the first class, though what we say is in a 
 measure true of so-called purely positive laws. All author- 
 ity is immediately from God; and, the gift once made, nat- 
 ural law prescribes obedience. Without this authority from 
 God, no ruler has the right to make laws for free men against 
 their consent, that is a prerogative of God alone; and God's 
 connection with authority makes the presence of natural law 
 imperative. As a matter of right, positive law without nat- 
 ural law for support, is not worth the paper it is written 
 on. A king may have all the physical force needed to exe- 
 cute his rulings; but might is not right, and, unless natural 
 law sustains him, he has no right whatever to impose his wishes 
 on a free people. More men and better men are kept from 
 theft and murder by fear of God than by fear of fine and im- 
 prisonment ; and the few restrained by these lesser considera- 
 tions alone are beneath our notice. They are not good citi- 
 zens in the full sense of the word. 
 
 Principles I, II, III, IV, V 
 
 I. A. God depends not on eternal law, and yet He owes it 
 to His wisdom to work in harmony with order; and order is 
 
* 
 
 66 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 eternal law. Self-imposed dependence is no real dependence, 
 and, therefore, no imperfection. Dependence implies two, and 
 God is one. The lawmaker is superior to his law, but can 
 elect to observe it. God must choose to observe His law, be- 
 cause He enjoys no freedom of contrariety regarding virtue 
 and sin. 
 
 B. Reason is not the natural law. It makes the law 
 manifest to men. The New York Sun is not the law, though 
 it prints and publishes the law. Were reason the natural law, 
 each individual would be a law to himself; and law is an 
 obligation imposed by another. 
 
 C. The natural law leaves room for civil, because it 
 omits details; and two sanctions are better than one. Some 
 principles in the natural law are obscure, particularly in sec- 
 ond and third classes. 
 
 D. The natural law depends not on the free will of God, 
 but on His wisdom or essence. 
 
 E. First principles of the natural law are the same with 
 all men. Men differ, when they come to apply these first 
 principles. We instance the treatment some savages accord 
 their parents and wives. 
 
 F. Before creation there was no actual subject for nat- 
 ural law. Possible subjects destined to become actual were 
 enough. Distinguish between natural law objectively taken, 
 and subjectively taken. 
 
 G. Natural law is against man's nature, because it de- 
 stroys his freedom. 
 
 Answer: It destroys his moral freedom, not his physical 
 freedom; the licere, not the posse. 
 
 H. Natural law would be inseparable from man 's nature. 
 And yet it is separate from infants and madmen. 
 
 Answer: It is separable from them in nearest first act, 
 and in second act ; not in farthest first act. Second act means 
 actual judgment; nearest first act means readiness due to 
 habits; farthest first act means intellect. 
 
 I. God is free; and, therefore, natural law is not neces- 
 sary. 
 
 Answer: God is free to create, not free to impose law in 
 the hypothesis of creation. Absolutely speaking, God is free ; 
 
PRINCIPLES 67 
 
 hypothetically speaking, He is not free. No outside force 
 compels Him, but His infinite perfection. 
 
 II. J. Principles of natural law. Three classes. First, 
 evident; second, easily deducible from first; third, deducible 
 froan fir^t and second with some difficulty. Examples are, 
 Do good and avoid evil; worship God, honor your parents; 
 fight no duel, tell no lie. Principles of first and second 
 classes are called more general, and cannot be invincibly 
 unknown to any man vested with the use of reason. Prin- 
 ciples of first class are known per se and with evidence. Their 
 matter is evident from study of terms ; their obligation, from 
 study of human nature, inasmuch as man is a being ab alio, 
 not a being a se. 
 
 K. Whole nations went astray regarding theft, suicide, 
 murder. 
 
 Answer: They knew the natural law, and went wrong in 
 its application to particular cases. They killed their parents, 
 to save them from greater evils. Parents asked children to 
 slay them, not to be old and decrepit in next life. Theft was 
 reputed skill; suicide, bravery; wives were sent ahead to 
 be company for husbands. 
 
 L. God can change physical laws. Ergo, natural law. 
 
 Answer: No parity. Not against the nature of a phys- 
 ical force to refuse it cooperation, or oppose impediments, or 
 use it for a contrary purpose, like fire for cooling. Physical 
 forces are mere means, and can be howsoever employed. Man 
 is more than a mere means. He is free, and has initiative of 
 his own. To put an act intrinsically wrong, is against his 
 nature, and God cannot hinder the thing. If God allowed it 
 approvingly, He would be running counter to His wisdom 
 and holiness. 
 
 M. In the cases of Abraham and Isaac, the midwives and 
 Egyptian property, the patriarchs and polygamy, God 
 changed the matter of the law. He did not dispense. 
 
 III. N. There would seem to be no sanction in this life, 
 because pleasure attaches to vice, injustice is profitable, and 
 virtue begets pain. 
 
 Answer: The pleasures of vice are not straight, but 
 blended with manifold evils, that the wicked are little able 
 
68 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 to bear. Profit attaches to injustice, not essentially, but 
 accidentally. Injustice on occasions proves most unprofitable. 
 The pain virtue begets is easily borne, with the help of a good 
 conscience and hope of future ble^edness. One reward is 
 essential to virtue, and can never be absent. It is a help 
 to honorable conduct. Three rewards are connatural, su- 
 premacy of reason, resulting peace, and health of body. Re- 
 wards of a third class morally speaking accrue to virtue ; and 
 they are wealth, honor, esteem, and the like. Such rewards 
 as naturally and morally speaking fall to the lot of virtue, 
 can by accident fail, though not regularly. Virtue, besides, 
 procures untold social advantages, touching family, state and 
 Church. God sometimes visits His friends with adversity in 
 the capacity of a Father, not a lawmaker. He sometimes re- 
 wards the wicked in this life, because the future life will 
 admit of no recompense for the little good they do. 
 
 IV. 0. Heaven and hell encourage men to work from an 
 imperfect motive. But God recommends these motives not 
 in an absolute way, but only in the supposition that other 
 motives fail of influence with human imperfection. The proc- 
 ess is negatively imperfect, or less perfect; not positively, 
 or altogether imperfect. 
 
 P. There would seem to be no proportion between a 
 momentary sin and an eternal hell. 
 
 Answer: No proportion of time, but of justice. 
 
 Q. The purpose of sanction is to correct the criminal, 
 or restrain him from wrong. Eternal punishment defeats 
 purpose. 
 
 Answer: Sanction can be viewed as a threat or an actual- 
 ity. Its purpose as a threat is secondary; its purpose as an 
 actuality is primary. Its complete or combined purpose is 
 the preservation of order. Before order takes harm, it threat- 
 ens; after order takes harm, it punishes, and so restores 
 things to primitive condition of equity. The pendulum 
 swings back. In this life sanction has for secondary purpose 
 the correction of the criminal and restraint of others. Here 
 we are in probation. In the next life probation is at an end, 
 and sanction strikes a balance. Sinners, who refused God 
 glory here, do unwilling homage to His holiness and justice 
 hereafter. 
 
PRINCIPLES 69 
 
 R. Many atheists know nothing of hell. Ergo, no hell 
 for them. 
 
 Answer: They doubt regarding hell, and by their own 
 fault. They are not certain regarding its non-existence. It 
 is enough for the criminal to put an act deserving the pen- 
 alty. Murderers are hanged, whether they know the penalty 
 or not. 
 
 S. Hell itself is not sufficient sanction. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: It furnishes motive enough for the law's observ- 
 ance, though it fails to coerce free men. 
 
 V. T. Every offense against positive law is against nat- 
 ural law, mediately not immediately. A fault against positive 
 law is not necessarily against natural law, because natural 
 law is the remote, not the near cause of positive law. In 
 every such case no natural law would be broken, were it not 
 for the positive law. 
 
THESIS V 
 
 VARIOUS MORAL NOTIONS 
 
 The five caUses of morality, final, material, formal, model 
 and efficient. Generic and specific morality. Objective and 
 subjective morality. Good, bad and indifferent acts. Moral- 
 ity's subjective measure is synderesis and conscience. Moral- 
 ity's efficient cause is intellect and will. Appetite, the pas- 
 sions, and will. Morality's root is freedom of will. Volun- 
 tary and involuntary acts. End and intention. Morality's 
 obstacles, ignorance and error affect the intellect; the pas- 
 sions, notably fear, affect the will; violence affects executive 
 not appetitive factdties, ordered not elicited acts. Jouin, 19- 
 28; 48-56; Bickaby, 27-64. 
 
 Ethics is the science of putting order in man's free acts, 
 with principles derived from reason for ultimate basis, the 
 principles themselves being of the rock-bottom variety, last, 
 farthest away, remotest from the student. Ethics is the study 
 of morality in its last causes, compassed in the light of rea- 
 son. Like everything else, morality has five causes, final, ma- 
 terial, formal, efficient and model. Its final cause, its pur- 
 pose, what the agent seeks in its prosecution, is happiness, 
 complete and incomplete; and this phase of morality was 
 discussed in our first three theses. Its end of deed is order 
 in man's free acts, its end of doer is resulting happiness. 
 Recall clock and clockmaker. Its material cause, its subject- 
 matter, its content, the determinable element of which moral- 
 ity is made, like the body in a man, the bricks and mortar 
 in a house, is distinctively human acts, acts proceeding from 
 a free will and an intellect, adverting to the moral good or 
 evil in a thing. And, though we gave these acts some notice 
 in our first thesis, we delayed their full discussion to this 
 present occasion, because persuaded that we can now under- 
 
 70 
 
OBJECT, END, CIRCUMSTANCES 71 
 
 stand them better. Its formal cause is good and evil in the 
 moral order; and these notions await fuller development. 
 Good and evil in the moral order are regularly designated 
 right and wrong. The second and third paragraphs of our 
 third thesis deal with the formal cause of morality, inas- 
 much as they establish an essential, intrinsic difference be- 
 tween right and wrong acts, and supply us with a standard 
 of measurement, enabling us to detect this essential, intrinsic 
 difference. In other words, some acts are so right, that they 
 get their rightness from nothing outside themselves ; so right, 
 that viewed in themselves they cannot be made wrong by Al- 
 mighty God Himself ; so right, that rightness is of their very 
 essence and inamissible. Other acts are so wrong, that irreg- 
 ularity is in their very substance, irremovable therefrom by 
 God Himself, and beyond being changed by law, custom, con- 
 science or whatever else. Instances of the two classes are, 
 love of God, worship, obedience to parents; and hatred of 
 God, blasphemy, a lie. We distinguish between generic 
 morality, and specific. Generic merely denominates an act 
 moral; specific morality denominates it good or bad, virtue 
 or vice. The generic morality of an act, making it moral, is 
 settled by its origination in an intellect and a will. The spe- 
 cific morality of an act, making it good or bad, is gotten from 
 its harmony in whole, or discord in part, with the objective 
 order of things. The determinants of an act's morality, 
 specifically considered, are its object, its agent's end or in- 
 tention, its circumstances. If all three are in harmony with 
 the objective order, the act in question is morally good; if 
 any one of the three is at discord with the objective order, 
 the act is morally bad. This last statement remains to be 
 proved, and it will get our attention later. For the better 
 understanding of generic and specific morality, it may prove 
 a help to recall animal, man and brute, with their endless 
 varieties. Animal is the genus; man and brute, the species; 
 races of men and breeds of brutes are classes, not species. 
 In much the same way, moral acts are the genus; good and 
 bad acts, or virtues and vices, are the species; while virtues 
 and vices, grouped under particular names, are classes, not 
 species. 
 
 Moral acts, constituted by the fact that they proceed from 
 
72 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 intellect and will, are a genus capable of division into the 
 two species, good and bad acts. Harmony and discord with 
 the objective order are their specific differences. Ethics is 
 practical, and there is question always of an individual con- 
 crete act, and we want to know to what species it belongs. 
 We say that object, end and circumstances are its specific 
 determinants, and we are practically saying that the act is 
 morally good or bad inasmuch as the whole individual moral 
 act is in harmony, or part of it is at discord with the objec- 
 tive order. "Whole individual moral act means object, end 
 and circumstances. Ohject means act, end means moral, cir- 
 cumstances mean individual. Different virtues and different 
 vices are not species properly so called. They are classes 
 under species. Like man and brute in Porphyry's Tree vir- 
 tues and vices are infimae or lowest species. They admit of 
 different classes, but not of different species. An infima 
 species cannot be conceived as a genus containing different 
 species, but only as a species containing different individ- 
 uals, and these in turn constitute different classes. There 
 are no different species of men, though there are different 
 races or classes of men; and so there are no different species 
 of virtue or vice, but only different classes or kinds. Man 
 and brute are different species of animal, because they differ 
 in essence. Justice and charity are not different species of 
 virtue, because they do not differ in essence, inasmuch as they 
 are moral goods. Their essences, namely genus and specific 
 difference, are the same, moral acts in harmony with objective 
 order. Different species must have different essences, differ- 
 ent classes have the same essence and different accidents. No 
 one act can belong to two different species, but the same act 
 can belong to two different classes. One act cannot be at the 
 same time virtuous and vicious, though one act ordered by 
 the will can be at the same time justice and charity, as when 
 a man owes five dollars and gives ten. It is quite possible 
 for a charitable man to become a just man, without ceasing 
 to be charitable; it is quite impossible for a rational animal 
 or a man to become an irrational animal or a brute. And 
 what is true of man as a lowest species, is true of virtue as a 
 lowest species. Though we are not now specially concerned 
 with the classification of the different virtues and different 
 
 J 
 
OBJECT, END, CIRCUMSTANCES 73 
 
 vices, but with the specification of generically moral acts, 
 it is quite true to say that object, end and circumstances 
 classify virtues and vices as well as specify moral acts. Ob- 
 ject, end and circumstances are not the specific differences 
 of good and bad acts, but the specific determinants limited 
 or determined by the specific differences, harmony and dis- 
 cord with the objective order. All three must be in har- 
 mony with the objective order to constitute a good act, dis- 
 cord in any one of the three with the objective order constitutes 
 a bad act. In conjunction with harmony and discord they 
 determine the specific morality of a generically moral act. 
 They contribute jointly with harmony and discord to the 
 whole essence of a morally good or a morally bad act. There 
 are no different species of moral good and moral evil, though 
 tliere are different species of morally good and morally evil 
 acts. Justice is a species of morally good acts, it is not a 
 species of moral good, because no moral good is contradic- 
 torily opposed to it. Man is a species of animal, because 
 brute is contradictorily opposed to him. Justice and injus- 
 tice are not species of virtue, because virtue is not common 
 to the two. Justice and charity are not species of virtue, 
 'because, though virtue is common to the two, their specific 
 differences are the same, and one is not contradictorily op- 
 posed to the other. 
 
 St. Thomas, S. T. 1, 2, q. 19, a. 1, contends that acts get their 
 specific morality from object alone, to later share the preroga- 
 tive with end and circumstances. Therefore object must 
 admit of several meanings. In one sense or Avide sense it 
 includes end and circumstances, in the other it excludes them. 
 In wide sense object of act means the whole term of the man's 
 wish, the whole good thing known to the intellect and sought 
 or chosen by the will, with every attendant circumstance. 
 Like every whole the whole term or whole good has parts, 
 and these parts are what we call the object in strict sense, 
 end and circumstances. Object, therefore, in strict sense, is 
 what the will on its own account and primarily wishes with 
 a bearing on morality. Circumstances are accidents morally 
 affecting the act, whether by way of object or by way of 
 agent; and they are what the will wishes, not on their own 
 account primarily, but on account of object or end and sec- 
 
74 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 ondarily. They are answers to the questions, quis, quid, ubi, 
 quibus auxiliis, cur, quomodo, quando; meaning who, what, 
 where, with what helps, why, how, when. Some circum- 
 stances physically affect the act, and we are not talking of 
 them. An instance would be to give an alms with the left 
 hand or the right hand. Person is a circumstance, quis, or 
 who, and it means here not the bare substance of a person, a 
 mere man, a mere woman, a mere child, but a person as af- 
 fected with modifications that base moral relations, like a 
 father, a mother, a son, a laymam, a priest. Some circum- 
 stances, like quantity, leave their acts in the same class of 
 virtues or vices, as &ve or ten dollars in the case of theft; 
 others, like place, put their acts in different classes, as theft 
 in a church becomes theft and sacrilege. End is itself a cir- 
 cumstance, cur or why, and the same is true of object, quid 
 or what; but just as quid or what, taken as a circumstance, 
 is made to mean quantum, how much, or quale, of what sort, 
 so cur or why taken as a circumstance is made to mean end 
 of deed or finis operis, reducible itself to object. End as dis- 
 tinguished from circumstance means end of doer, finis operan- 
 tis, an intrinsic accident of the agent, not an intrinsic acci- 
 dent of the deed; not the purpose nature attached to the 
 work, but the purpose actuating the agent to perform it. 
 Think of clock, time and money, with time for end of deed, 
 or thing made, and money for end of doer or person making. 
 
 To constitute an act good all the determinants must be 
 good, to constitute an act evil, only one of the three need be 
 evil; and St. Thomas sees in this circumstance another proof 
 of the difficulty attaching to virtue as compared with vice, 
 declaring that the surpassing value of virtue makes the trou- 
 ble worth while. This fact is gathered up in the terse say- 
 ing, ^'Bonum ex Integra causa, malum ex quocunque defectu.^' 
 Good results from a complete and total cause , evil from any 
 defect in the cause. What the agent chooses must be right, the 
 reason why he chooses it must be right, and the circum- 
 stances attaching to what and why must be right. If any 
 of the three happens to be wrong, the whole act is morally 
 wrong. 
 
 Object is finis operis, end of deed; end is finis operantis, 
 end of doer. The object of murder is the destruction of an 
 
OBJECTIVE AND SUBJECTIVE MORALITY 75 
 
 innocent man's life, the object of theft is the seizure of an- 
 other's property against his rational wishes, the object of a 
 clock is the indication of time. The end of murder may be 
 revenge, or plunder, or removal of an unfriendly witness, 
 removal of a Church persecutor, kindness to a parent, and 
 the like. The end of theft may be the purchase of an auto, 
 alms to the poor, gift to a benefactor, payment of a debt and 
 the like. Circumstances affect both object and end. Murder 
 of a father by his son, in a church, to keep him from sin. 
 Object can likewise mean the term of the act, terminus ac- 
 tionis; the person or thing the act touches or affects, God, 
 self, the neighbor, creatures without reason. When God is 
 object, because He is good, without any admixture of evil, 
 no concrete act can be indifferent with regard to object, be- 
 cause turning towards complete good is necessarily good, turn- 
 ing away from complete good is necessarily evil. With self, 
 neighbor and irrational creatures it is different; they are 
 mixtures of good and evil, and turning towards them is not 
 necessarily good, turning away from them is not necessarily 
 evil. To turn towards the good in them, and to turn away 
 from the evil in them are good acts; to turn away from the 
 good in them, and to turn towards the evil in them are bad 
 acts. Therefore, acts bearing on creatures, even in the con- 
 crete, are of indifferent morality on the part of object of the 
 act. This is far from meaning that individual acts in the 
 concrete are ever indifferent. They are always definitely 
 good or evil, but they get their specific or definite morality 
 not from object of act, but from end of agent, and no indi- 
 vidual concrete act is without its definite and determined 
 purpose. Hatred is all right, when aversion from evil in- 
 volves tendency towards good; hate is all wrong, when aver- 
 sion from evil involves aversion from good. To walk, to 
 drink, to talk, are acts with self for object, and these acts 
 are never put without a purpose or motive different from and 
 prior to the acts themselves. Walking, drinking and talking 
 cannot be motives for the wish to walk, drink or talk, because 
 they do not exist before the wish is conceived, and cause must 
 precede effect. Therefore, some motive prior to the wish 
 inspires these several acts, and changes these morally indiffer- 
 ent acts on the part of object to specifically good or evil acts 
 
76 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 on the part of agent. Purposes like prayer, health, temper- 
 ance, kindness, make these acts morally good; purposes like 
 theft, gluttony, drunkenness, anger make these acts morally 
 evil. And what is true of acts with self for object, is true 
 of acts with the neighbor and irrational creatures for object. 
 
 Again, we distinguish between objective morality and sub- 
 jective morality, much as we distinguish between objective 
 certainty and subjective; and, just as purely subjective cer- 
 tainty, without objective for basis and foundation, is error 
 rather than truth, so purely subjective morality, or subjec- 
 tive goodness without objective goodness for basis and founda- 
 tion, is badness or vice rather than goodness or virtue. Hence, 
 a man can be good, though he puts a bad act, he can be bad 
 though he puts a good act, meaning always in the matter of 
 conscience, or subjectively. He can tell a lie and think it a 
 duty. His will is right, his mind is wrong. He can tell the 
 truth and think it a sin. His mind and will are both wrong. 
 One is morality of the man, conscience apart from act; the 
 other is morality of his act, act apart from conscience. Objec- 
 tive morality is in the whole deed or act itself, without any 
 reference whatever to the truth or falsehood of the doer's 
 knowledge ; and of this kind of morality there was question in 
 the second and third paragraphs of our third thesis. The only 
 kind of subjective morality, that regularly deserves notice, is 
 the kind based on objective ; and of this we speak when we say 
 that the specific determinants of morality are the act's object, 
 its doer's end or intention, and the circumstances affecting 
 both. Conscience is the measure of pure subjective morality, 
 and will get our attention later. 
 
 Certainty is entirely a matter of intellect, morality is a 
 matter of intellect and will together. Certainty turns on 
 truth, morality on conduct, and the will has more to do with 
 conduct than the intellect. The intellect is true, objectively 
 and subjectively certain, only when it grasps things as they 
 are, only when it sees murder as murder, theft as theft. It 
 is false, subjectively certain, objectively ignorant or wrong, 
 when it grasps things otherwise than as they are, when it views 
 murder as charity, theft as commendable skill. Intellect is 
 only one factor in morality, will is the other and more im- 
 portant. 
 
MORAL ACTS 77 
 
 All three determinants, object, end and circumstances, have 
 their own objective and subjective morality. Their objective 
 morality is like a fact, and quite independent of the agent's 
 thinking ; their subjective morality is not a fact, but the view 
 the agent 's mind takes of them. Per se, and therefore regu- 
 larly, man's mind hits the truth; per accidens, and therefore 
 in rare and exceptional cases, the mind can miss the truth. 
 In such exceptional cases subjective morality is at variance 
 with objective, and ignorance is usually responsible for the 
 mistake. This ignorance is either vincible or invincible, 
 within the thinker's control or beyond it. Some degree of 
 carelessness attaches to vincible ignorance, and carelessness 
 is blameable and punishable. No such carelessness attaches 
 to invincible, and it is therefore without blame and unpun- 
 ishable. 
 
 Objective morality, as distinguished from subjective, is the 
 morality of the object of the act in strict sense, and end, 
 and circumstances, viewed as facts, as they are in themselves; 
 subjective morality is morality of the same three determinants, 
 as they are viewed by the mind of the agent. And this. is 
 what we mean when we say that subjective is the morality of 
 the man, objective is the morality of his act. A man is not 
 good, unless his purpose and its attendant circumstances are 
 good, as well as the object of his act. Neither is he good, 
 unless the object of his act is good, as well as his end and its 
 attendant circumstances. Every act implies two things, a 
 cause and an effect. A moral act implies a cause viewed 
 morally, and an effect viewed morally. A cause viewed mor- 
 ally involves intellectual knowledge and free will with a bear- 
 ing on moral right and wrong. An effect viewed morally is 
 what results from the activity of a cause viewed morally; it 
 is a physical act proceeding from a free agent, not consid- 
 ered merely in itself, but in its bearing on right and wrong. 
 In every moral act the effect or term of the act fixes its objec- 
 tive morality; the cause, a composite of intellectual knowl- 
 edge and free will, fixes its subjective morality. 
 
 Only free acts are matter for moral acts, choice is exercise 
 of freedom, and choice is impossible without prior intellectual 
 knowledge. Man's one free faculty is his will. His intellect, 
 senses, appetite, locomotion are all necessary faculties, and 
 
78 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 they borrow whatever freedom we attribute to them from the 
 will. Therefore, in strict sense only acts elicited by the will, 
 only wishes as such, only internal acts of the will, begun and 
 finished in the will, elicited and executed by the will, deserve 
 and get the appellation, moral. Every act external to the 
 will, whether it be a thought, or a sensation, or a passion, 
 murder, or theft, viewed as proceeding from intellect, sense, 
 appetite, or hands, is a necessary act, and therefore without 
 its own proper morality ; and every such act borrows morality 
 from intimate connection with the will, from dependence in 
 its first origin on the will, from the fact that, while it is fin- 
 ished or executed by another faculty, it is begun, elicited in 
 the shape of a wish, ordered, commanded, prescribed by the 
 will. 
 
 Hence our distinction between acts elicited by the will and 
 acts ordered by the will. Elicited acts are internal acts, 
 ordered acts are external. Both are moral acts, but after a 
 different manner. Internal acts have their own independent 
 morality, ordered acts have no morality of their own, but 
 a morality derived from and dependent on the influence of 
 the will, the part played by the will in their accomplishment. 
 Murder and theft are always done in the will before they are 
 done by the hands, and as outward or external acts their 
 morality is exactly the same as that of the wish or internal 
 act prompting them. In murder the outward act is in itself 
 necessary, free by participation; the inward act is free in 
 itself. The will makes the murderer kill, much as instinct 
 makes the bird fly, with this difference, that while the will 
 is free, instinct is a necessary agent. 
 
 In the concrete, and viewed as products of an individual 
 man, all acts are either good or bad. In real life there is no 
 such thing as an indifferent human act, a deliberate act 
 neither good nor bad, but between both. In the abstract, and 
 in the field of theory, walking, singing, and a thousand such 
 acts are indifferent in themselves; but in practical every-day 
 life all such acts are necessarily good or bad. Ethics has 
 nothing to do with indifferent acts, because they fall outside 
 its sphere. It is a practical, not a theoretical study. There 
 never was an animal, without its being a man or a brute ; and 
 there never was a moral or distinctively human act, without 
 
SUMMARY 79 
 
 its being definitely good or bad, from a moral point of view. 
 Acts are morally good or bad, when they respectively help 
 or hinder a man in his progress towards his last end, the 
 possession of God in Heaven, the practice of virtue on earth. 
 Man's destiny is the fulfilment of God's wishes in his regard, 
 and we gather God's designs on man from a study of man's 
 nature. Complete happiness is last factor in man's wishes; 
 and, therefore his last end, because there is no good beyond. 
 Because it leads to God or complete happiness, virtue consti- 
 tutes incomplete happiness, the highest possible on earth. 
 Virtue in turn means order in man's free acts, it means the 
 performance of duty ; duty springs from man 's relations with 
 the other moral units in the universe, God and neighbor ; and 
 these relations are based on the objective order of things, 
 things as God made them, things as God views them. 
 
 And now to sum up, an act is first moral, then good or bad. 
 All distinctively human acts are moral. Some are good, 
 others bad; good, when they square with the objective order 
 of things, as grasped by the intellect ; bad, when they are at 
 angles with this order. Objective order is embodied in the 
 eternal law, made manifest to man in the natural law, and 
 pushed to the limit of clearness in positive law; and for this 
 reason, the natural law is morality's model cause. Eternal 
 law is God's reason or will, commanding the preservation of 
 natural order, forbidding its disturbance. Natural law is 
 eternal law, become evident in rational nature; or, an inborn 
 habit of mind enabling man to detect the harmony or discord 
 in force between notions constituting morality's first prin- 
 ciples. Positive law is an obligation founded on right rea- 
 son, drawn up and promulgated for the common good by him 
 who has charge of the community affected. Creatures in- 
 ferior to man, from minerals to brutes, always keep the eternal 
 law, the law set them by God, that aspect of eternal law 
 applicable to irrational nature. A stone miraculously sus- 
 pended in the air, is keeping the law of gravity as far as in 
 it lies. Man is the only rebel in the universe, because man 
 alone is free. Morality's efficient cause is man, viewed as an 
 intelligent, free being. Morality is restricted to man, intel- 
 lect and will are the two faculties in man directly concerned 
 with morality, and of the two will is the more vitally impor- 
 
80 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 tant. It is the work of the intellect to know right and wrong, 
 it is the work of the will to choose between them. In the -field 
 of knowing synderesis and conscience are man's mentors, 
 they are functions of the intellect in its bearing on morality, 
 they are reason restricted to the department of right and 
 wrong. Synderesis is the hahit of morality's first principles; 
 and we saw in our fourth thesis that synderesis is unerring. 
 The natural law is universally known, as well as universally 
 existent. Conscience is the application of synderesis to per- 
 sonal and concrete acts; and conscience can be false as well as 
 true, wrong as well as right. Synderesis is intellect as it 
 comes from the hand of God, conscience is intellect as modi- 
 fied hy man; and the whole truth is summed up in that state- 
 ment from Major Logic, the intellect is per se infallible, and 
 fallible per accidens. Synderesis elicits a speculative judg- 
 ment only, conscience elicits a speculative and a practieal judg- 
 ment. One is Major ; the other theoretically viewed is Minor 
 in the Moral Syllogism, practically viewed it is the conclu- 
 sion. One regulates our thinking, the other our doing. One 
 is truth, the other is morality ; and they are related like Logic 
 and Ethics, inasmuch as Logic lays down rules for right 
 thinking, Ethics lays down rules for right conduct. An ex- 
 ample may make things clearer. Murder is wrong and a 
 thing to be avoided. This particular killing I contemplate 
 would be murder. Therefore I must avoid this particular 
 killing. 
 
 Intellect, therefore, and will, or knowing and choosing, are 
 what give being and essence to our moral acts, and they 
 deserve most serious attention. They get full and complete 
 treatment in Psychology; but, for present purposes, we must 
 be pardoned introducing here certain truths, there proved 
 beyond dispute. We begin with the consideration of man, 
 as composed of body and soul. The two appetitive faculties 
 in man are appetite and will ; the passions are manifestations 
 of appetite, and are nine in number. The will's freedom, 
 the different classes of voluntary acts, the different kinds of 
 intentions need to be explained. The parts ignorance and 
 error, the passions and violence play in morality are questions 
 to be settled. 
 
 Composition of Man. Man is a mystery. He is the mi- 
 
APPETITE AND WILL 81 
 
 crocosm; a mineral, a plant, a brute and an angel. He is a 
 body and soul, matter and spirit. He is one complete sub- 
 stance and nature, made up of two incomplete substances 
 and natures. Only live bodies are human bodies, and they 
 alone are one incomplete substance. A dead body is no hu- 
 man body, it is an aggregate of many different complete sub- 
 stances. 
 
 The incompleteness of the body, as a substance, is situate in 
 the circumstance, that it unites with the soul to form the 
 complete substance, man. Its incompleteness, as a nature, is 
 due to the fact that it derives its activity from the soul. The 
 whole man is a complete substance, because he stands by him- 
 self, and enters into no combination with another. He is a 
 complete nature, because he is the root and principle of all 
 his operations. Body and soul are incomplete after different 
 manners. The body is incomplete and non-subsistent. With- 
 out the soul it falls away and perishes. The soul is incom- 
 plete and subsistent. Without the body it goes on living 
 and acting. And yet the soul is no angel, because its sub- 
 sistence is incomplete; accompanied always by a connatural 
 capacity for union with the body, to constitute one complete 
 substance, man. An angel's subsistence is complete, and void 
 of every such connatural capacity. Only as a composite of 
 body and soul is man a complete substance and a complete 
 nature. As such he is not a body, nor yet a soul; but a 
 man. He is not a body-substance or nature, nor yet a soul- 
 substance or nature ; but a human substance and nature, with 
 activities partaking of the two kingdoms of matter and spirit. 
 
 Hence, he has sense as well as intellect; he has appetite as 
 well as will. In man's present condition his soul is root and 
 principle of his thoughts and wishes, but with extrinsic de- 
 pendence on his body, and this dependence is far from 
 interfering with the soul's spirituality. This extrinsic de- 
 pendence on the body, in a mediate way follows the soul to 
 the next life, because in even its separated condition it 
 thinks and wishes with the mediate help of species or images 
 it carries, and these owe their first origin to phantasms, them- 
 selves products of the composite man. 
 
 Appetite and Will. But we are now concerned with man 
 in this present life ; and, because our topic is Ethics, his will 
 
82 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 demands most immediate attention. In this business of 
 morality the will is the thing, and a man's will is his heart. 
 The will is best defined as a spiritual, inorganic faculty of the 
 soul, appetitive of good at the instigation of the intellect. 
 It is a blind faculty, and gets light from the intellect. It 
 can act with or against the light. Good is its object, and 
 that is the quality intellect calls to its notice. Greater and 
 lesser have weight of course with the will, but no determining 
 or absolute weight. It is free, and can reject the greater 
 good to select the lesser, and all this with an abiding 
 knowledge of their relative worth. Experience is proof, and 
 facts are more stubborn than wrong principles, doped out to 
 strengthen the weak limbs of a lame theory. As soon as the 
 smallest conceivable particle of good sails into the mind's 
 vision, the will is ready to exert its energy. The will is free, 
 we say, and the world agrees with us. We mean the world 
 of common sense. There are a few restless spirits, who stand 
 for determination of will. But they are off the right track, 
 they purposely go wide of common-sense, they are chasing 
 rainbows in a wild search for novelty, no sober study of the 
 truth. The truth of the thing is that the will is free, and 
 Determinists are well acquainted with the fact. They feel 
 free to reject as attractive a good as the truth, and actions 
 are louder than words. When a man says one thing and 
 does another, we claim the privilege of gathering his real 
 sentiments from his deeds; and these idle philosophers talk 
 Determinism to do freedom. The will then is free, and it is 
 too late in the day to endeavor to correct the notion. 
 
 Omitting for the present the soul's executive energies, we 
 attribute to the soul the power to know, and the power to 
 wish; and this twofold power we denominate its cognoscitive 
 and appetitive faculties. Man wishes as he knows, and his 
 knowledge covers two kingdoms, that of sense and that of 
 intellect. His soul is the root of all his activity. Sight and 
 hearing are just as much rooted in his soul as understanding 
 or thought. But here again there is a difference. In opera- 
 tions of sense the soul is intrinsically dependent on matter, 
 in thought its dependence is merely extrinsic. Had man no 
 higher faculty than sense, his soul would be just as material 
 as the brute's. But he has a higher faculty, that of thought; 
 
THE PASSIONS 83 
 
 its operations are intrinsically independent of matter, spirit- 
 ual, inorganic ; and what is highest in a thing gives the thing 
 its name. For present purposes we can call thought the 
 soul's superior knowledge, sensation its inferior knowledge, 
 with intellect and sense for corresponding faculties. Becmise 
 man wishes as he knows, we must recognize a double capacity 
 for willing, a superior will and an inferior will, rational 
 appetite and sensile appetite, one intrinsically independent 
 of organs, the other intrinsically dependent on same. Both 
 are wills, both are appetites ; but for the sake of clearness we 
 call the first, will simply ; the second, appetite. The passions 
 are displays of the appetite, wishes are displays of the will. 
 
 The Passions. Our passions are as dependent on the body 
 as our senses; our wishes are as clear of the body as our 
 thoughts. The passions, like appetite their root, turn always 
 on some particular good or its opposite; and, like sensation 
 as compared with thought, are more manifest and closer 
 to hand than wishes or acts of the will proper. The will 
 has universal good for object, and it always embraces particu- 
 lar goods under the aspect of universals. Man wishes the 
 office of president, not inasmuch as it is the office of presi- 
 dent, but inasmuch as it is honor; he wishes the salary, not 
 inasmuch as it is a set sum of money, but inasmuch as it 
 is money. A hungry man wants food of any kind, food in 
 general. A hungry horse wants this or that particular food, 
 oats, or corn, or hay. 
 
 Passion, if we consult the word's origin, means suffering, 
 a modification induced by impact from another. In oratory 
 the passions are stimulations of pain or pleasure, meant to 
 shape or color a man's opinions. In ethics passions are move- 
 ments of the appetite, set on foot by the actual presence, or 
 vivid representation, of an object wearing the appearance 
 of good or evil. They are acts of the appetite, and have no 
 part in angels or separate souls. And yet these passions 
 have their counterparts in the thoughts and wishes of angels. 
 Love, hate, desire are as native to angels as they are to brutes ; 
 but in angels they exist without any admixture of appetite; 
 they are affairs of the soul, not affairs of the body. Man is 
 capable of the love peculiar to angels, and of the love peculiar 
 to brutes. His will is affected by the senses as well as by 
 
84 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 the intellect. Orators reach the hearts of their listeners by 
 the passions as well as by arguments. And in his own case 
 a man can be orator and audience. Passion always manifests 
 itself in body-change, ''the diffusive wave of emotion." All 
 passion is emotion, but not all emotion is passion. Surprise, 
 laughter, shame, are not passions, because they are impos- 
 sible without intellect. Passions turn on good and evil 
 affecting sense. 
 
 The ancients enumerated nine passions. They are all 
 species of the generic passions, love and hate. Love has good 
 for object; hate, evil. Hate is the negation of love, as evil 
 is the negation of good. 
 
 Desire has absent good for ob- 
 ject. 
 
 Delight has present good for 
 object. 
 
 Hope has hard, but possible 
 good for object. 
 
 Despair has hard and impos- 
 sible good for object. 
 
 Love; good is object, no limit 
 
 Abhorrence has absent evil 
 
 for object. 
 Displeasure has present evil 
 
 Hate; evil is object, no limit^ ^ ^^^ ^^J^^t- 
 
 Fear has hard and unavoid- 
 able evil for object. 
 
 Courage has hard, but avoid- 
 able evil for object. 
 
 Anger is a mixture of desire, displeasure, hope. 
 
 . Desires are physical and psychical. Both are from senses. 
 Imagination has wider play in latter. Physical craves for 
 quantity; psychical, for quality, e.g. A thirsty man crav- 
 ing water and champagne. Physical craves for limited ob- 
 jects ; psychical, for unlimited, not in sense of universal, but 
 in sense of colossal particulars, e. g. A thirsty man wants, 
 not ocean, but enough; a miser' wants all gold. Psychical 
 desires are not intellectual desires. These last contemplate 
 
FREEDOM OF WILL 85 
 
 immaterial goods and material goods viewed in an immate- 
 rial way. Desire of perfect happiness is intellectual. 
 
 Delight, like desire, may be sensual or intellectual. The 
 passion is sensual delight. Like desire, delight may be phys- 
 ical or psychical. Play of imagination makes difference, e. g. 
 a wine-taster. Intellectual delights are superior to sensual, 
 where minds and hearts are cultivated. Regarding the mor- 
 ality of an act done for pleasure, there is a difference between 
 acting for pleasure and living for pleasure. The first is right. 
 
 Delight, like desire, may be sensual or intellectual. The 
 second is wrong. 
 
 Anger is a mixed passion; it is desire of open vengeance for 
 an open slight, attended with displeasure at slight. Hatred 
 is usually chronic, anger is frequently acute. Hatred wishes 
 evil as it is evil ; anger, as it is just. Anger regularly wishes 
 evil in sight of all ; hatred is not seldom content with hidden 
 evil. Anger stops, hatred continues. 
 
 The Will's Freedom. And now we leave the passions, these 
 affections of appetite, to return to the will. Again, the will 
 is a spiritual, inorganic faculty of the soul, appetitive of good 
 at the instigation of the intellect. A voluntary act is such 
 as proceeds from the will with a purpose in mind. Voluntary 
 acts may be necessary or free ; necessary, when the will is cut 
 off from all choice; free, when choice is in its power. In 
 Heaven love of God is a voluntary necessary act. In this life 
 all our deliberate voluntary acts are free. Every good in our 
 acquaintance is a mixture of good and evil, it falls short of 
 the summum bonum or God, who is alone unmixed good. The 
 good in the object stirs desire; the &vil in the object stirs 
 aversion. To desire is to select, to turn aside from is to 
 reject. Therefore, whatever created good falls under our 
 notice is, because of its mixed nature, capable material for 
 selection or rejection, for desire or aversion; and when the 
 will is able to wish or not wish, its act is free. Freedom is 
 an attribute of the will, enabling it, after equipment with 
 every needed prerequisite, to still wish or not wish, to choose 
 this or choose that. This attribute follows the will all the 
 way up to actual exertion of its energy. When it once 
 makes choice, its freedom regarding this particular act is 
 straightway at an end. It cannot wish a thing, and at the 
 
86 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 same time remain free to wish or not wish it. But up to 
 the precise moment wherein it wishes, it certainly remains 
 free to do one thing or the other. In perhaps plainer words, 
 it enjoys antecedent not consequent freedom. When freedom 
 turns on the power to will or not will, it is known as freedom 
 of contradiction. When it turns on the power to positively 
 wish or positively reject a certain thing, it is known as free- 
 dom of contrariety. When it turns on the power to wish 
 this or wish that, it is known as freedom of specification. 
 Thus, when I choose between reading and not reading, I am 
 exercising my freedom of contradiction; when between lov- 
 ing and hating a person, my freedom of contrariety; when 
 between reading and singing, my freedom of specification. 
 The most obvious meaning of freedom is separation or 
 immunity from something. Freedom of will is immunity 
 from determination, from necessary adhesion to some set 
 line of conduct. The determining force can be conceived 
 as intrinsic or extrinsic to the will. Immunity from a de- 
 termining force intrinsic to the will is called freedom from 
 necessity. The other is called freedom from violence. In our 
 present condition, the will in all its deliberate acts enjoys 
 freedom of the first sort. Things would be different, if we 
 saw God face to face. The will in its elicited acts, in acts it 
 begins and finishes, in acts the will itself executes, always 
 enjoys freedom of the second kind. In ordered acts, in acts 
 it begins, to leave to another to finish, in acts it commands 
 another agent to execute, freedom of the second sort may be 
 present or absent. When it is absent, the ordered act is not 
 free. A prisoner in his cell is free to wish as he likes, and 
 the law has no restraining influence over his will in the 
 matter of its elicted acts. It can, however, with chains pre- 
 vent him from walking, and so spoil him of freedom in 
 ordered acts, dependent on his legs for execution. No elic- 
 ited act of the will can be forced, because, in that case, 
 the will would object and not object, a contradiction in terms. 
 Freedom from necessity is the kind we vindicate to the 
 will, and it is called freedom of indifference^ freedom of 
 choice, free will, freedom simply. A spontaneous act is 
 opposed to a forced act, and force is extrinsic. All vital 
 or immanent acts are of such sort. Acts proceeding from 
 
VOLUNTARY ACTS 87 
 
 appetite, whether natural in minerals and plants, sensitive 
 in brutes, or intellectual in man, are spontaneous. The high- 
 est spontaneity of man on earth is freedom, the highest spon- 
 taneity of inferior agents is necessity. Man's indeliberate 
 acts are spontaneous with necessity. A voluntary and fully 
 deliberate act proceeds from the will, with knowledge of end 
 as such, and may be either necessary or free. A free act is an 
 act of the will held to no set shape by anything in the 
 will's nature or constitution. In this life, elicited acts of 
 the will are free, not because they are elicited, but because 
 their every object is a mixture of good and evil. Love of 
 God in Heaven is an elicited act and necessary. Necessity is 
 compatible with elicited acts of the will, as is plain from the 
 case of the blessed in Heaven. Freedom of indifference or 
 choice, or free willy consists in passive and active capacity 
 to wish or not wish in the presence of every needed prerequis- 
 ite for wishing; or it is a power of choice, enabling us in 
 the event of several alternatives to freely choose one and 
 neglect or reject the others. Freedom belongs formally and 
 intrinsically to the will alone. The intellect is not free in 
 the presence of immediately evident truth. Acts of other 
 faculties are free in cause and extrinsically, inasmuch as the 
 will orders or commands them. The will is superior to 
 whatever preponderating influence or inclination urges, it 
 can choose what we here and now know to be worse in pref- 
 erence to what we here and now know to be better, in spite 
 of what Leibnitz says to the contrary. 
 
 Voluntary Acts. Whether free or necessary, all elicited 
 acts of the will are voluntary. No elicited acts of the will are 
 altogether involuntary. Ordered or commanded acts, viewed 
 in their execution, may be altogether involuntary, e. g. im- 
 prisonment or upright position with arm extended. Elicited 
 acts of the will begin and end in the will, ordered acts 
 begin in the will and end in another faculty. Hence, we 
 distinguish between acts altogether voluntary or involuntary, 
 and acts partly voluntary or involuntary. When the act 
 turns on an object desired in itself, and on its own account, 
 it is wholly voluntary. When it turns on an object desired 
 in no way whatever, it is wholly involuntary. When it turns 
 on an object desired indeed, not however on its own account, 
 
88 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 but on account of another closely connected object, it is 
 partly voluntary and partly involuntary. In a partly vol- 
 untary act the will embraces its object, but would never em- 
 brace it, if it could otherwise avoid some evil or compass 
 some good. Sailors, unloading their cargo into the sea dur- 
 ing a storm, are the classical example. We likewise dis- 
 tinguish between a directly voluntary and an indirectly 
 voluntary act. The first turns on an object wished imme- 
 diately and on its own account ; the other, on an object wished 
 not on its own account, but because it follows necessarily in 
 the wake of the wisher's purpose. An indirectly voluntary 
 act differs from a partially voluntary act in this, that the 
 former has for object a good consequent on the wisher's pur- 
 pose, while the latter has for object a good antecedent to the 
 wisher's purpose, a means to his end. Examples may serve 
 to make things clearer. Sailors in a storm lighten their 
 ship of its cargo as a means to securing their safety. Drunk- 
 enness is the indirect voluntary of excessive drinking. Indi- 
 rect voluntary and voluntary in cause are of a kind. The 
 omission of an act likewise constitutes an indirect voluntary. 
 Intentions. Whatever influences the will is called an end 
 or purpose. This end or purpose, viewed as energizing the 
 will, is called the man's intention; and it may be formal and 
 actual or virtual, explicit or implicit, habitual or interpreta- 
 tive. It is formal and actual, when actually known and 
 wished, in a distinct way. Ordinarily our intentions are of 
 this sort. It is virtual, when, ceasing to be actual, it goes on 
 shaping our conduct with force borrowed from its original 
 impulse as an actual intention. In the course of a journey 
 our intention insensibly passes from actual to virtual. A 
 priest baptizing with distractions is another example. It is 
 explicit, when it keeps in view some distinct object ; and our 
 intentions are regularly such at the first. It is implicit, when 
 it keeps in view some object not known with distinctness, 
 but involved in another. Thus, to explicitly purpose a jour- 
 ney is to implicitly purpose car-fare. It is habitual, when 
 once entertained it falls from memory, without being repu- 
 diated or knowingly withdrawn. The Morning Offering 
 influences after this manner all the day's acts. The inten- 
 tion perseveres not in act or in effect, but in habit; and it 
 
IGNORANCE, ERROR, PASSIONS 89 
 
 influences subsequent acts. It is interpretative, when, of no 
 actual or virtual or explicit habitual force, it would influence 
 our conduct, if recognized with distinctness. Interpreta- 
 tive is same as implicit habitual, e.g., desire to be saved is 
 interpretative desire to be baptized. Such an intention suf- 
 fices for the valid reception of Baptism, when intention of a 
 superior kind is impossible. Virtual at least is always re- 
 quired in minister. 
 
 Ignorance and Error. Intellect and will combine to pro- 
 duce free acts. Choice pertains to the will, knowledge to the 
 intellect. Freedom, therefore, can be diminished by hind- 
 rance to choice and hindrance to knowledge. Ignorance and 
 error can affect our minds, passion and fear can affect 
 our wills. Ignorance is described as absence of knowledge. 
 It is that state of mind wherein no judgment or idea is had 
 of the thing unknown. If a man ought to have the knowl- 
 edge in question, his ignorance is positive. If no such obli- 
 gation exists, his ignorance is negative. Examples of neg- 
 ative are ignorance of medicine in a farmer and of philoso- 
 phy in a Freshman. Examples of positive are ignorance of 
 medicine in a physician and of philosophy in a Senior. Ig- 
 norance is vincible, if, with the amount of study, to which a 
 man is held, it can be set aside; if such a measure of study 
 is of no avail to set it aside, the man's ignorance is invin- 
 cible. Vincible ignorance is culpable; invincible, inculpable. 
 Antecedent ignorance has place before the man wakes up to 
 the duty of investigation, and it is invincible as well as in- 
 culpable. Consequent ignorance has place after the man 
 wakes up to the duty of investigation, and it may be vin- 
 cible as well as culpable. Vincible ignorance is of three 
 kinds ; simple^ when some study is employed, but not enough ; 
 stupid or lazy, when little or no study is employed; and. 
 affected, when one purposely avoids every source of infor- 
 mation to continue in his perverse ways. Acts are rendered 
 involuntary by invincible ignorance; not, of course, invol- 
 untary under every respect, but under such respect alone 
 as the ignorance affects or touches them; vincible ignorance 
 leaves them voluntary, but in a diminished degree. Invin- 
 cible ignorance is wished in no way; neither in itself nor in 
 cause. Vincible ignorance is wished in cause. To strike a 
 
90 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 priest, thinking him a layman, is no sacrilege. To eat meat 
 on Friday, without taking means to clear up a suspicion, is 
 sinful. When no such suspicion is present, no sin is com- 
 mitted. To studiously avoid enquiry about a fast-day, for 
 the purpose of enjoying a full meal, is to incur guilt. Error 
 is positive want of conformity between mind and object, it is 
 that state of mind wherein a false judgment is had of some- 
 thing. It is material and formal. Material turns on wrong 
 appearances of things. Formal confounds appearances with 
 facts. Formal error is the acceptance of the false for the 
 true, and admits of distinctions parallel with those of ignor- 
 ance. 
 
 Examples of material and formal are, men seem trees, and 
 men are trees. 
 
 Passion. Passion is sensile appetite, and we have already 
 enumerated its different kinds. With consent of the will for 
 point of departure, passion is antecedent or consequent. 
 When passion turns on moral good, it is altogether honorable. 
 When it turns on moral evil, antecedent passion is involun- 
 tary and without moral blame. Consent of the will changes 
 antecedent to consequent passion, and such passion is volun- 
 tary ; directly, when the will urges or commands it ; indirectly, 
 when disturbance ensues from will 's vehemence. Motus primo 
 primus is altogether antecedent passion. Motus secundo pri- 
 mus means incomplete consent ; it is passion adverted to, and 
 not resisted. Motus secundus means full consent and conse- 
 quent passion. 
 
 Fear and Violence. We single out fear, because it is less 
 a home-product than the other passions, and therefore more 
 compelling. 
 
 Fear can be serious or light, intrinsic or extrinsic. Fear 
 is dread of a threatening evil, apprehended as unavoidable. 
 Serious dreads a great evil, certain or very probable, e. g. 
 death, wounds, property, imprisonment. 
 
 Absolutely serious fear affects an ordinary person. Rela- 
 tively serious fear affects a person of a certain age, sex or 
 disposition. Absolutely light can be relatively serious. 
 
 Light dreads a lesser evil, or a great evil barely probable. 
 Reverential awe can become relatively serious fear, especially 
 in girls. 
 
FEAR 91 
 
 Fear is intrinsic when its cause is a necessary agent whether 
 extrinsic or intrinsic to the person who fears, e. g. a con- 
 tracted disease, meditation on hell, earthquake. 
 
 Fear is extrinsic, when its cause is outside the man and a 
 free agent, e. g. enemy, highwayman, threats. 
 
 Free fear resembles extrinsic and is caused by the free act 
 of a human being, e. g. highwayman. Free fear is just if 
 the person causing it seeks to repel harm. Free fear is un- 
 just, if the person causing it seeks to inflict harm. Nec- 
 essary fear resembles intrinsic and is prompted by a neces- 
 sary cause, e. g. earthquake, volcano, lightning. 
 
 Solutions: In case reason is not dethroned, fear, no matter 
 how serious, leaves the act voluntary in a diminished degree, 
 e. g. martyrs and apostates. Serious fear excuses from posi- 
 tive law, especially human. Unjust fear makes law-instru- 
 ments invalid. Light fear is generally neglected before the 
 law; in conscience it can have some weight in questions of 
 compensation for loss. Violence cannot be done the will. 
 Under violence the man makes free choice of escape from pain. 
 An external act due entirely to violence is no crime in the 
 unwilling agent. 
 
THESIS VI 
 
 A human act gets its specific morality from the object of 
 the act, from the agent's end or purpose, and from circum- 
 stances affecting both. — Jouin, 32-36; Rickaby, 31-41. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 This present thesis fixes the specific determinants of moral- 
 ity. It ai '>vvcrs the question, What makes a moral act good 
 or bad, what makes a moral act the act of one particular vir- 
 tue or vice rather than the act of another? 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Specific Morality. Specific morality is opposed to generic. 
 Specific makes an act good or bad, an act 'of this or that 
 particular virtue or vice. All virtuous acts are specifically 
 the same in first sense, because harmony with objective order 
 is the specific difference. All virtuous acts of different par- 
 ticular virtues are specifically different in second sense, be- 
 cause each particular virtue has its own specific difference; 
 justice being specified by another's due; charity, by kindness 
 to another ; humility, by right esteem of self ; and so of all the 
 different virtues. 
 
 Object, End, Circumstances. All three, object, end and 
 circumstances are specific determinants, and in both senses, 
 fixing classes as well as species. In the briefest language 
 possible, objective morality arises from the object of the act, 
 subjective morality from the agent's purpose, and circum- 
 stances modify object and purpose. Circumstances are 
 summed up in the Latin verse, Quis, quid, ubi, quibus auxiliis, 
 cur, quomodo, quando ? The verse means. Who, what, where, 
 with what helps, why, how, when? Circumstances are ob- 
 jective, when they modify the matter or substance of the act ; 
 subjective when they modify the purpose of the agent. The 
 
 92 
 
OBJECT 93 
 
 object contributes essential, intrinsic morality to the act; the 
 end contributes accidental, extrinsic morality; circumstances, 
 when limited to the object, contribute accidental, intrinsic 
 morality; when limited to the agent, accidental, extrinsic 
 morality. The end contributes essential intrinsic morality 
 to the agent, circumstances contribute essential intrinsic 
 morality to object and agent ; and therefore end and circum- 
 stances are as much specific determinants as object, because 
 a moral act is not object alone, but object, agent and circum- 
 stances taken together. To be a moral act, it must be an in- 
 dividual free act, voluntary and deliberate; and this quality 
 implies end and circumstances. 
 
 Acts indifferent in themselves, because neither good nor 
 bad from the viewpoint of object or matter, get all their 
 morality from the agent's purpose and from circumstances. 
 No deliberate act of the individual is indifferent. To walk 
 and to write are in themselves indifferent ; but no individual 
 can deliberately walk or write without a purpose and circum- 
 stances, that commend or vitiate the act. 
 
 Object. When discussing the natural law in fourth thesis, 
 we already described acts good or evil in themselves. They 
 are opposed to morally indifferent acts, which, having no 
 morality in themselves, get all their morality from purpose 
 and circumstances. Acts are good in themselves, their object 
 is good, when positive harmony with the objective order en-^ 
 ters their constitution; they are bad in themselves, when 
 discord with same attaches to them. We distinguish between 
 inward acts and outward, or overt acts. The will is the moral 
 faculty in man, the intellect is only its helper; and all a man's 
 acts get their moral color from his will. Inward acts are 
 acts elicited and executed by the will, they begin and end in 
 that faculty; outward acts are acts elicited by the will and 
 executed by another faculty ; they begin in the will and finish 
 in some other faculty. Elicited or inward acts have their own 
 independent morality, gotten from object, end, and circum- 
 stances. Ordered or outward acts derive all their morality 
 from their corresponding elicited or inward acts. Murder 
 and theft are perpetrated in the heart, before they are ac- 
 complished by the hands. In every moral act three distinct 
 things are wished, the object of the act, the end or purpose 
 
94 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 selected^ and attendant circumstances, objective and sub- 
 jective. Briefly, all three things are wished, object, end and 
 circumstances. All the three things wished must be morally 
 good, to constitute the act a morally good act. An act is 
 bad, when any one of the three is bad. Hence the axiom, 
 **Bonum ex Integra causa, malum ex quocunque defectu.** 
 *'Good results from a full and complete cause, evil results 
 from a defective cause.'' In plain English, an act is good, 
 when all three constituents or determinants of morality are 
 good; it is bad, when any one of the three is bad. A moral 
 act is a chain made up of three links; it is good, when all 
 three links are good; it is bad, when any one of the three is 
 bad. A chain is no stronger than its weakest link, and this 
 moral chain is no better than its worst link. Therefore, the 
 fact that a deed is good in object, is far from settling its 
 morality. A wrong intention can make the best thing in the 
 world wicked. The fact that a deed is bad in object, quite 
 settles its morality, no intention in the world can save it from 
 blame. When discussing the natural law in our fourth thesis, 
 we described acts good or bad in themselves; and we were 
 talking about object, as distinct from end and circumstances. 
 Whatever good act gets its morality solely from end and 
 circumstances, is in itself morally indifferent. It is not mor- 
 ally good in itself, because in that case object would contribute 
 to its morality. It is not bad in itself, because in that case 
 it could never become good. Whatever act is good or bad 
 prior to end and circumstances, is good or bad in itself, be- 
 cause end and circumstances are the only other sources, the 
 only moral coefficients other than the act itself. Acts, there- 
 fore, are good or bad in themselves, when, abstracting from 
 end and subjective circumstances, they are in harmony or at 
 discord with the objective order; when, morally speaking, 
 they are or are not what they ought to be. Physical good is 
 divided into becoming, agreeable and useful, and moral good 
 admits of the same division. All three physical goods can be 
 basis for moral good, and they eventuate in moral good, only 
 when reason's controlling influence vests them with the qual- 
 ity of becoming good. 
 
 Viewing man as a moral being, his one true and real good 
 is virtue, because it alone appeals to the morally specific por- 
 
END AND CIRCUMSTANCES 95 
 
 tion of his being, the will as arbiter of good and evil. Even 
 study, in itself becoming and real physical good, can by abuse 
 readily become moral evil, and sink to the level of apparent 
 good. Pleasure and wealth, in themselves apparent good, 
 can, under the control of reason and an orderly will, rise to 
 the dignity of true and real goods. Acts can be morally good 
 or evil in themselves in a three-fold way. In themselves, on 
 their own account, and absolutely ; in themselves, on their own 
 account, but not absolutely; in themselves, not on their own 
 account, nor absolutely. Familiar examples of such goods 
 are worship, charity and pious reading. Familiar examples 
 of such evils are blasphemy, theft and dangerous reading. 
 Good and evil of the first kind admit no change of matter. 
 There is a something in the physical act of worship that 
 makes its acceptance by the will a moral good, and this some- 
 thing cannot possibly be separated from the act. There is a 
 something of the same kind in the physical act of blasphemy, 
 and this something makes blasphemy irremediably and neces- 
 sarily bad. Charity and pious reading become evil, when the 
 money given as alms is stolen, when pious reading interferes 
 with some higher duty. Theft and dangerous reading admit 
 change of matter ; and, this change supposed, they cease to be 
 bad. What belonged to another may become mine, and its 
 seizure by me is no theft. What would otherwise be danger- 
 ous reading and wrong, may become a necessary help to the 
 acquisition of medicine or theology and entirely right. 
 
 And now to explain what we mean by in themselves, on 
 their own account and absolutely. Blasphemy, theft and dan- 
 gerous reading are wrong in themselves, because of wrong- 
 ness involved in the three physical acts, because of native and 
 inborn discord with the objective order of things. Blasphemy 
 and theft are wrong on their own account, not on account of 
 an outside cause, like the prohibition of a superior. Danger- 
 ous reading is wrong not on its own account, but on account 
 of nature's decree against incurring danger without good and 
 sufficient reason. Absolutely, implies no possibility of change 
 in matter, and of the three blasphemy alone is absolutely 
 wrong. In no hypothesis can the physical act of blasphemy 
 fail of turpitude. The physical act of deliberately taking 
 something in theft is wrong, only in the hypothesis that it 
 
96 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 is concerned with property belonging to another. The pByS 
 ical act of deliberate dangerous reading is wrong, only in the 
 supposition that the risk is taken without due and sufficient 
 reason. In the case of a child, play on the street against a 
 parent's wishes, is not wrong in itself, or on its own account, 
 or absolutely. The wrongness is not in the play, but in dis- 
 obedience; the wrongness is due to the parent's prohibition, 
 and with the parent's permission it would be entirely right. 
 
 End. In question of ends we hold discourse primarily of 
 the end designated operantis, not operis; the end of doer, not 
 the end of deed. The finis operis is independent of the doer, 
 the finis operantis is wholly under his control. Recall the 
 example of clock and clockmaker. The finis operis of a clock 
 is to tell time, whether the clockmaker likes it or no. In fact, 
 the end of deed cannot be entirely absent from the end of doer. 
 The clockmaker can hardly make a clock without intending 
 it to measure the flight of time. These two ends are like a 
 combination of the object of the act and the agent's purpose, 
 if the act's goodness in itself or badness in itself is conceived 
 as the clock. The end of doer can be best called intention, 
 or end energizing the agent. It gives morality to an act in- 
 different in the abstract, making it a morally good or evil 
 act in the concrete. An evil intention vitiates an act morally 
 good in point of object or circumstances. A good intention 
 cannot change the evil nature of an act bad in point of object 
 or circumstances. And all this is true of good and evil cir- 
 cumstances, with regard to good and evil objects and inten- 
 tions. The agent's intention is his act inwardly taken, and 
 our outward acts get their morality from their corresponding 
 inward acts. Intention is an elicited act of the will, its exe- 
 cution is an ordered act of the will; and ordered acts of the 
 will get their morality from corresponding elicited acts. 
 
 Circumstances. They are modifications of the act and agent 
 due to person, quantity, place, helps, motives, manner and 
 time. That circumstances alter the morality of an act, is 
 evident from the following familiar examples. The execution 
 of a condemned criminal by some private citizen, and by the 
 proper public official. The circumstance of person makes the 
 execution in one case an act of legal justice ; in the other, an 
 act of murder. To steal five cents, and to steal five dollars. 
 
SPECIFIC MORALITY 97 
 
 Quantity makes one sin venial ; the other, mortal. To eat and 
 drink in a hotel, and to eat and drink in a church. Place 
 makes the difference between a meal and a sacrilege. To lie, 
 and to confirm the lie with an oath. Manner adds perjury 
 to falsehood. To drink, and to drink to excess. Quantity 
 changes temperance to drunkenness or gluttony. Time makes 
 eating meat on Friday a sin, likewise the omission of com- 
 munion during the Paschal season. The circumstance, *'in 
 church,'* is as identical with ''meal in church," as meal it- 
 self, circumstance is as identical with individual act as object. 
 
 Specific Morality. A moral act is an act making its agent 
 good or bad, making its agent worthy of praise or of blame. 
 There are three elements in every moral act. It must be in 
 the power of the agent, subject to his ownership, to make him 
 worthy of praise or of blame. It must possess goodness or 
 badness, to communicate the quality good or bad to the agent. 
 It must be known for good or bad to the agent, to stir the 
 agent's mil. Because of the first element, the agent must be 
 able to do or not do the act, and the act itself must originate 
 in free will. The second element is required, because nothing 
 gives but what it first possesses, and the act must be in har- 
 mony or at discord with the objective order. The third ele- 
 ment is needed, to stir the will, which is blind, and wishes 
 only what the intellect first offers. A father's care of his 
 child is a moral act, because it is in his power ; a bird 's care 
 of its young is not a moral act, because it is a matter of in- 
 stinct and beyond the bird's control. The man is physically 
 free to care for or neglect his child; the bird is not free, it 
 is physically necessitated by instinct to care for its young, 
 or in certain contingencies to neglect its young. Instinct in 
 man is subject to the control of his will. 
 
 Generic morality is the feature common to good and bad 
 acts, like animality in man and horse; and origination in in- 
 tellect and will is the one thing common to good and bad acts. 
 Specific morality is one thing for good acts, another thing 
 for bad acts, like reason in man, and sense in horse ; harmony 
 and discord with the objective order being the two differences. 
 Higher species can be considered genera with regard to lower 
 species; and the one thing common to all the virtues is har- 
 mony with the objective order of things ; the one thing com- 
 
98 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 mon to all the vices is discord with the same order. Charity, 
 justice, humility are species of the genus, virtue; injury, in- 
 justice, pride are species of the genus, vice. Virtue and vice 
 are themselves species of the genus, moral acts. 
 
 Object in our thesis means object in strict sense, term of 
 the wish, finis operis. End means intention, and intention 
 means the agent 's apprehension and choice of the act in ques- 
 tion. Circumstances mean modifications, whether of object or 
 of end. These things premised, we are now ready to prove 
 that a human act gets its specific morality, that a moral act 
 gets its goodness or badness, that the act of a set virtue and 
 the act of a set vice get their denomination from the object of 
 the act, from the agent ^s end or purpose, and from circum- 
 stances affecting both. 
 
 PROOF 
 
 Acts are specified by their formal objects, and moral acts 
 are no exception to the rule. But the formal object of a 
 generically moral act is an object good or bad in substance, 
 with all its objective circumstances; apprehended as such by 
 the intellect, and chosen as such by the will, with all its sub- 
 jective circumstances; not the object simply, nor yet the 
 agent ^s apprehension or choice of it, but all three things to- 
 gether. Ergo, human acts get their specific morality from 
 object, end and circumstances. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. The truth is clear in physical 
 acts. Sight is sight because of color, hearing is hearing be- 
 cause of sound. To use the eyes on sweetness, or smoothness, 
 or sound is not to see ; to use the ears on color is not to hear. 
 In moral acts good and evil play the parts of color and sound 
 in vision and hearing. Freedom demands knowledge and 
 choice, or purpose; individuality of act demands circum- 
 stances. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. The object is the subject-mat- 
 ter, substance of the act ; the agent 's apprehension and choice 
 of same are his end or intention; objective circumstances are 
 identified with the object; subjective circumstances, with the 
 agent 's end or intention. When the eye sees green, a particu- 
 lar and present green is its formal object, and the eye makes 
 
 I 
 
PROOF 99 
 
 the green object its own by entering into knowledge-relations 
 with it. Its formal object is not red or an absent green, or 
 a green with which it has no intimate relations. In a parallel 
 way, when the will elicits a moral act, it chooses a particular 
 good or evil object, represented to it as such by the intellect. 
 Its formal object is not an object viewed as true, or one, or 
 beautiful, but an object viewed as good or evil; not a good 
 or evil object, that never through the intellect appealed to the 
 will; not a good or evil object, that, after word from the 
 intellect, the will never concerned itself with. When end 
 vitiates a good object, the will puts a good thing to bad use, 
 and the intellect is its accomplice. When circumstances 
 vitiate an object good in substance and good in purpose, some 
 accidental badness resided in object, or purpose, or both. 
 
 P.S. Examples Wherein One or Several Elements are Pres- 
 ent: To collect money from a debtor, for the purpose of get- 
 ting drunk ; and to steal money from a neighbor for the same 
 purpose. To deny self for the purpose of giving dinner to 
 a beggar. To walk to church for purposes of prayer. To give 
 alms to a poor man, with the design of making him an accom- 
 plice to murder. To give an alms, that a simple lie may be 
 told. Firm will, purposing the lie, vitiates; not inefficax 
 velleitas, mere advertence to wish, caring little whether the 
 lie be told or not, ready to give the alms anyhow. Alms from 
 pity and from vainglory; antecedent purpose vitiates, not 
 concomitant or consequent. A person moved by vainglory 
 to practise daily communion ; intention disappears at the altar ; 
 non est in executione, sed fuit. To give an alms when for- 
 bidden, or though forbidden, or because forbidden; against 
 poverty, against obedience. 
 
 N.B. No good end can justify a bad act ; good end never 
 justifies a bad means ; murder of a Church persecutor, to help 
 religion; defiance of Constitution, to promote Catholic educa- 
 tion. Every bad end vitiates a good act. A good or bad 
 end changes an indifferent act to a good or bad act respec- 
 tively; and this is the one case where end justifies means. 
 It is lawful at times to put a good act, though evil by accident 
 results. The times are, when the good surpasses the evil, 
 and the evil is neither directly nor indirectly intended. The 
 evil is not even indirectly intended, when the good is equally 
 
100 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 immediate with the evil, and not accomplished with the evil 
 for means. The good act is not lawful, if any of the above 
 conditions fail of verification. A general in time of war is 
 allowed to lay waste the enemy's territory to the harm of 
 innocent citizens. A drunken man is guilty of the curses he 
 utters, if he foresees them in some confused way when sober. 
 Cursing is in this case an indirect voluntary, a voluntary in 
 cause. A doctor is not allowed to kill the child to save the 
 mother. He may remove a certainly dead fetus, not a prob- 
 ably dead fetus. He must never expose the child to danger 
 of death without Baptism. He is allowed to administer medi- 
 cine, that may by accident result in the child's death. His 
 whole purpose must be to cure the mother, not to kill the 
 child. 
 
THESIS VII 
 
 Prohabilism is a safe and correct system in matters of con- 
 science. Jouin, 51-56; Rickahy, 152-159. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Rigorism or Absolute Tutiorism, Moderate Tutiorism, Prob- 
 abiliorism, uEquiprobabilism, Probabilism and Laxism are 
 systems in Ethics meant to help a man choose the right line 
 of conduct, when doubt about right and wrong agitates his 
 mind. As long as the doubt remains, he must do nothing, 
 because it is highly immoral to even expose oneself to the 
 danger of doing wrong. It would be in any case to sin, to 
 act with this principle in mind, ^'I don't know, but I'll take 
 the risk." To act with a doubtful conscience is to sin, he- 
 cause it involves contempt of the law. The man acting with 
 a doubtful conscience cares not whether he keeps the law or 
 breaks it. Among all the above systems, Laxism excepted, 
 Probabilism apparently savors most of a risk ; but, as we shall 
 see, the Probabilist runs no risk, enters on no uncertainty, 
 though he neglects the so-called safer course. He is certain 
 that he is right, because a doubtful law certainly has no bind- 
 ing force. Rigorism and Laxism have been condemned by 
 the Church in the persons of Alexander VII, in 1656, and 
 Innocent XI, in 1679. Rigorism was taught by the Jansen- 
 ists, and held that the opinion favoring the law must be fol- 
 lowed as long as the opposing view is not certain. In doubt 
 about Friday, you must abstain from meat, till certain it is 
 not Friday. Laxism held that any opinion, with small or 
 no sound reason in its favor, may be followed. In doubt 
 about Friday, with no good reason for the doubt, you may eat 
 meat. Tenuiter probabile non est probabile pro prudenti. 
 In the case of a prudent man, what is only slightly probable 
 is not probable at all. Moderate Tutiorism and Prohahilior- 
 
 101 
 
^''^'''^^<^' '^'(jiNBRAL ETHICS 
 
 ism have no advocates to-day, and can be neglected. The first 
 held that the opinion favoring the law must be followed, un- 
 less the opposing view is most probable ; the second prescribes 
 the same course, unless the opposite opinion is more probable. 
 Mquiprdbdbilism allows departure from the law, if reasons 
 for its non-existence are as strong, or nearly as strong, as rea- 
 sons for its existence. Things are reversed, if doubt turns 
 on the lapse or cessation of a law. Many Redemptorists pro- 
 fess to derive this last system from St. Alphonsus, though the 
 saint is Probabilism 's staunch defender. Prohdbilism teaches 
 that, in doubt whether an act is permissible or not, true and 
 real probability in favor of the act or its omission makes one 
 or other quite legitirmite, though greater probability attaches 
 to the contrary or so-called safer course. If you have good 
 and solid reasons for thinking that the day of the week is 
 not Friday, you may eat meat, even if you have better and 
 stronger reasons for thinking that it is Friday, provided 
 only that you are not really and truly certain that it is Fri- 
 day. If certain that it is Friday, of course you have no good 
 and solid reason for thinking that it is not Friday. Your 
 reasons must be good and solid, even if weaker than their 
 opposites, because slight reasons are reckoned no reasons by 
 the prudent, and Laxism is condemned by common sense as 
 well as by the Church. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Probabilism. Probabilism is as old as Christianity, and was 
 in common use with the early Fathers and Doctors of the 
 Church. Years ago it was called into question by decisions 
 rendered against Laxism by Alexander VII and Innocent XI ; 
 but it always counted among its defenders the most cele- 
 brated theologians. More recently a wrong understanding 
 of St. Alphonsus gave rise to ^quiprobabilism, and the 
 Church has not directly settled the controversy between ^qui- 
 probabilism and Probabilism. In ^quiprobabilism, if one of 
 the two views is less probable than the other, it must not be 
 followed; if the two views are equally probable, either may 
 be chosen. In some few passages of St. Alphonsus, because 
 of his zeal against Laxism, the less probable view is rated 
 
CONSCIENCE 103 
 
 slightly probable and negligible in itself; and, therefore, its 
 opposite becomes morally certain. Even with Probabilists, 
 when moral certainty arises, only one course of conduct is 
 open, because conscience is in that case certain and not doubt- 
 ful. Moral certainty is firm assent of mind without dread 
 of opposite, all based on laws governing human nature. Phys- 
 ical certainty is a parallel state of mind, based on laws gov- 
 erning physical nature. Metaphysical certainty is a parallel 
 state of mind based on connection of identity between ideas 
 in subject and predicate. Therefore, there are three kinds 
 of certainty, metaphysical, physical and moral; and all three 
 kinds imply firm assent of the mind, and exclude dread of 
 the opposite, possibility of the opposite. In the abstract, 
 physical and moral admit of the dread of possibility, due to 
 a miracle, or to a departure from the laws governing human 
 acts. In the concrete and in particular, even physical and 
 moral as completely exclude this dread and possibility as 
 metaphysical. Abstract possibility of the opposite is com- 
 patible with concrete impossibility of the same; and, unless 
 circumstances rule out the concrete possibility of a miracle 
 or of a departure from said laws, physical and moral certainty 
 are out of the question. Moral certainty is, therefore, just 
 as tight and solid as metaphysical, in point of excluding dread 
 of the opposite; and prohahility never rises to the dignity 
 of moral certainty. Probability always leaves the opposite 
 a concrete possibility. Moral certainty, in strict sense, ex- 
 cludes possibility of opposite ; in wide sense, it excludes posi- 
 tive probability of opposite, admitting its negative probabil- 
 ity, based on slender reasons, accounted none at all by the 
 prudent. 
 
 Conscience. Conscience is from cum and scientia, and 
 means knowledge with a bearing on the good or evil of a par- 
 ticular human act. It is the subjective element in law's 
 application, it is the immediate and proximate measure of a 
 man's moral conduct. It is the work of the intellect in what 
 we already established as the standard of morality, namely 
 the objective order of things as grasped by the intellect. 
 Consciousness is likewise from cum and scientia, and means 
 knowledge with a bearing on the operations of the soul's 
 other faculties. Conscience is not consciousness, nor is it 
 
GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 synderesis, which is the habit of morality's first principles. 
 Conscience is rather the application of synderesis to concrete 
 and particular acts. Both are applications of law to moral 
 acts, both measure man's conduct with law for standard; 
 but, while synderesis in an academic way and out of court 
 decides that murder, for instance, is wrong and must be 
 avoided, conscience in a practical way and in court decides 
 that this particular act, because murder, must be avoided. 
 The object of the particular act, with end and circumstances, 
 and their harmony or discord with the objective order of 
 things embodied in the law, are the objective element in law's 
 application; and this objective element is quite independent 
 of morality's subjective element or conscience. When the 
 moral value of a man*s act is under consideration, objective 
 order measures conscience; when the moral value of the man 
 himself is under consideration, things are reversed, and con- 
 science measures objective order. Morally speaking, a man's 
 act has its matter and form from the act itself, without any 
 reference to conscience; a man's conduct has its matter from 
 his acts, its form from his conscience. A materially bad act 
 is likewise a formally bad act; but materially bad conduct 
 can easily be fonnally good conduct, and vice-versa. God can 
 reward a wicked deed and punish an act of virtue, when con- 
 science is invincibly false. He looks not to the act but to 
 the heart of the agent ; and material virtue, when accompanied 
 by formal wickedness, is unspeakably worse than material sin 
 accompanied by formal righteousness. Beyond doubt, the 
 lay-brother, who drowned Chinese babies, after baptizing them, 
 wafi rewarded for material and formal murder, and the igno- 
 rant fellow who lied, because invincibly persuaded that 
 charity demanded it, was rewarded for a material and formal 
 untruth. Their acts were wrong, their conduct was right. 
 They were false to objective order, but true to conscience, 
 and conscience measures objective order when a man's con- 
 duct is in question, not his acts. Conscience is antecedent, 
 when it turns on present or future acts, and discharges the 
 functions of a guide. It is consequent, when it turns on past 
 acts, and plays the part of a judge. Conscience in strict 
 sense is antecedent. Conscience is reason decreeing the law- 
 fulness or unlawfulness of a particular act. Its decree al- 
 
CONSCIENCE 106 
 
 ways assumes the shape of a practical judgment, the conclu- 
 sion of a moral syllogism, therefore I must do this or avoid 
 that. Distinguish between conscience and its decree. Con- 
 science is the mind exercising a particular function. Its 
 decree is an act of the mind, a judgment. In strict sense, 
 conscience has to do with acts on the eve of being accom- 
 plished here and now. ThB Major in a moral syllogism rep- 
 resents synderesis, the Minor represents conscience theoret- 
 ically viewed, the conclusion represents conscience practically 
 viewed; and therefore the conclusion best deserves the title, 
 decree of conscience. The Major is remote principle or syn- 
 deresis, the Minor is conscience in actu primo proximo, the 
 conclusion is conscience in second act. With truth or har- 
 mony with objective order for viewpoint, conscience is true 
 or false, right or wrong. If the premisses are true, or if they 
 are invincibly false, conscience is right. If the premisses are 
 vincibly false, conscience is wrong. With degree of certainty, 
 or mind's acquiescence, for measure, conscience is certain, 
 probable or doubtful. Recall the states of mind discussed in 
 Logic, certainty, opinion^ doubt. Doubt may be positive or 
 negative. Positive has weighty reasons in its favor; nega- 
 tive has slight or no reasons in its favor. In matters of con- 
 science negative doubt is neglected, because it is of no weight 
 with the prudent. Doubt may be juris or facti. The first 
 turns on a law's existence; the second, on some particular 
 fact. Similar expressions are de jure and de facto in ques- 
 tions of property and authority ; owner de jure and owner de 
 facto ; king de jure and king de facto. A doubtful conscience 
 is in reality no conscience at all, because no actual decision 
 is made. Darkness is the absence of light. In question of 
 lawfulness or unlawfulness, not in question of validity or 
 invalidity, in question of law not of fact, Probabilism with 
 the help of a reflex principle changes a doubtful conscience 
 to a certain conscience, and opens the way to action. A per- 
 plexed conscience sees sin in both alternatives, tender is se- 
 vere with the slightest defects, lax unduly favors freedom. 
 
 Here is the whole truth about the bearing of conscience on 
 morality. To be right, a man must act with at least a morally 
 certain conscience in strict or wide sense, his final practical 
 judgment regarding the lawfulness of an act must be at least 
 
lOe GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 morally certain. His final practical judgment must admit 
 no sound or positive doubt, because to act otherwise would be 
 to expose oneself deliberately to the danger of doing wrong; 
 and moral certainty in wide sense is the highest we regularly 
 reach in daily life. Without detriment to the moral certainty 
 of his final practical judgment, his remote practical judgment 
 can be even positively doubtful or probable, because his con- 
 duct is not based on his remote practical judgment, but on his 
 final practical judgment; and with the help of a reflex prin- 
 ciple he can transform his probable remote judgment into a 
 morally certain final practical judgment; and this in sub- 
 stance is Probabilism. By supposition, then, in Probabilism 
 a man^s remote practical judgment is positively doubtful or 
 probable, the doubt is based on good and sound reasons in 
 the eyes of the wise, the doubt cannot be removed by study 
 or investigation ; one or other course must be taken ; he must 
 not even doubtfully go against the law; with the help of a 
 reflex principle he changes his conscience from doubtful to 
 certain, and neglects the doubtful law. As long as the law 
 remains doubtful, he is of course at liberty to keep it. He 
 is likewise at liberty to neglect it without wrong. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 When conscience returns a clear and positive answer, it 
 must be followed. When conscience is perplexed, a man's 
 first duty is to enquire and seek information. If doubt re- 
 mains after due enquiry, he is not held to the so-called safer 
 course, he is not held to suppose an obligation. Neither is he 
 allowed to act with a doubtful conscience. The Probabilist 
 runs no risk, enters on no uncertainty, though he neglects the 
 safer course so-called. Lacking available direct principles, he 
 calls a reflex principle to his aid. A direct principle lays 
 down the law, when conscience returns a clear and positive 
 answer. A direct principle is no help in this man's case. 
 He judges of his own act, taking into account his imperfect 
 knowledge and limited powers. He makes no attempt to 
 determine what another man with clear and positive knowl- 
 edge ought to do. He calls to his aid this reflex principle, 
 ^*A doubtful law has no binding force/' This is a reflex or 
 
PROOF AND PRINCIPLES 107 
 
 mind-principle, because objectively and outside of the mind 
 nothing is doubtful. The question is, not the law absolutely, 
 but the law as far as I can make it out. Liberty is prior to 
 the law. Liberty is in possession. The law, to bind, must 
 with certainty restrict liberty. Besides, no law binds, till 
 promulgated. Promulgation connotes certain knowledge, not 
 doubtful or probable merely; and, as long as doubt remains, 
 the law is not promulgated for me, and the fault is not on my 
 side. Authority is overwhelmingly on the side of Probabil- 
 ism, and it would be long to quote authors. St. Alphonsus 
 seems to favor ^quiprobabilism and Tutiorism, but he can 
 be explained aright. With St. Alphonsus the safer course is 
 alone morally certain; the safe course is not probable at all, 
 and he is talking against Laxism. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. My doubt must be serious, and hold out against argu- 
 ments for the existence of an obligation. No indulgence must 
 be shown laxity of conscience, which leans on slender doubt. 
 My doubt must persevere after due enquiry, and must be 
 based on positive reasons against the obligation. My doubt 
 must not be simple ignorance, it must be able to tell why. 
 Some minds doubt without being able to give their reasons 
 why. These minds must have recourse to others in moral 
 questions. My reason for doubt can be an intrinsic or extrinsic 
 argument. Hence another's opinion, when creative of solid 
 probability, can suffice. The probability must be compara- 
 tive, it must hold ground in face of opposing arguments. 
 After all has been said, it must be not unlikely. It need not 
 be more likely. That means more probable, not probable 
 simply. My doubt must be practical, not speculative, because 
 Ethics is a matter of conduct, not a matter of theorizing. 
 Theoretically speaking, a man can be saved with confession 
 once a year ; practically speaking, and when easy opportunity 
 offers, he must approach the sacrament oftener to be saved. 
 All the difficulty turns on the varying amount of diligence 
 necessary in enquiry to constitute it moral diligence. Deeper 
 investigation is needed when matter in question is of vital 
 interest, like confession, than when mere observance, like a 
 
108 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 fast-day. In question of rolling stones over a precipice, the 
 doubt must be about the act itself, not about its consequences. 
 It is certainly wrong to take any such risk, and Probabilism 
 has no play. 
 
 B. Frohahilism is availahle only in cases involving the law- 
 fulness or unlawfulness of an act, never in cases involving 
 validity or invalidity; in cases of law, never in cases of fact; 
 because, while doubtful laws are a reality on account of need- 
 ful knowledge and promulgation, facts are nothing unless 
 sure and certain. Lawfulness has an element of suhjectivityy 
 which is altogether absent from validity. The phase of mind 
 of the agent has no influence on the validity or invalidity of 
 an act, or on the reality of a fact ; it has a very perceptible 
 influence on the binding force of a law. A law binds only 
 when known, a fact is a fact whether it is known or not. 
 
 Examples of lawfulness are abstinence on Friday, Mass on 
 Sunday, the Lenten fast. Examples of validity are marriage, 
 ordination, baptism, real bread and real wine, wills, medi- 
 cine. Examples of facts are utterance of a vow, seven years 
 of age, baptism, priesthood, fast broken, debts paid. When 
 a certainly valid sacrament is impossible, a dubiously valid 
 sacrament is better than no sacrament at all, e.g., baptism with 
 perfume, especially when necessity urges, and the sacrament 
 can be afterwards repeated either conditionally or absolutely. 
 Sometimes doubt regarding the lawfulness of an act arises 
 from doubt regarding validity, and Probabilism is of no avail ; 
 because such conduct would betray contempt of virtue and 
 too small fear of sin. To be husband and wife, a man and 
 woman must be certainly married; and a doubtful marriage 
 never makes a man and woman husband and wife; it leaves 
 them single from the viewpoint of morality. Doubt regard- 
 ing facts must be settled some other way, usually by an appeal 
 to fixed principles, deriving their certainty from authority. 
 Some principles of the kind follow. ''Possession is nine- 
 tenths of the law," for money in hand. ''Apart from ques- 
 tions of justice, the probable fulfilment of a law is on a level 
 with its certain fulfilment," for sins told or omitted at con- 
 fession. "Facts must not be presumed, they must be 
 proved," for fast before communion and for utterance of a 
 
PROOF AND PRINCIPLES 109 
 
 vow. ''In doubt stand to presumption," ''Doubts must be 
 settled with the help of what ordinarily happens," for a 
 priest at Communion afraid that he has omitted the Pater 
 Noster, for parts of Office. 
 
THESIS VIII 
 
 VIRTUES AND VICES 
 
 Jouin, 56-70 ; Rickahy, 64^-109. 
 
 Virtue is a Jiahitus operativus bonus, vice is a habitus 
 operativus mains. To translate, virtue and vice are good 
 and had habits with a bearing on work. The expression, with 
 a bearing on work, serves to separate virtue from grace. Vir- 
 tue in simple and strict sense belongs exclusively to the will ; 
 in qualified and wide sense it is applicable to whatsoever fac- 
 ulty in the man. Though prudence resides in the mind, it is 
 directive of the will. A man is simply and in strict sense 
 good, when his will is right. He is good in qualified and wide 
 sense, when his legs are swift, when his eye and hand are 
 ready to art, when his wit is quick ; and we call him not good 
 without any qualification, but a good runner, a good painter, 
 a good scholar. Virtue is not said of irrational agents, be- 
 cause their conduct is fixed for them by instinct. Virtue 
 postulates free will, because it helps to choose between good 
 and evil. Silence is no virtue in a dumb person, temperance 
 in food and drink is no virtue in an angel, because the dumb 
 person and the angel are without any power to choose in 
 these particulars. Silence in a talkative person, and temper- 
 ance in a man are very decided virtues. Virtue, therefore, 
 is a habit; and Aristotle describes habit as a quality super- 
 added to a faculty, rendering it well or ill disposed towards 
 itself or something else. Virtue, whether in strict or wide 
 sense, dwells in some faculty of the soul, and favorably dis- 
 poses that faculty towards itself or towards another. 
 
 The soul is remote principle of all the man's activities; 
 faculties are proximate connatural principles, superadded by 
 nature to the soul; habits are proximate acquired principles, 
 superadded not by nature but by personal endeavor to the 
 faculties. Therefore, the soul helps the man, faculties help 
 
 110 
 
VIRTUES AND VICES 111 
 
 the soul, and habits help the faculties. Suarez offers this defi- 
 nition of a faculty -habit, a quality hard to remove, super- 
 added to the faculty, and meant of itself and primarily to 
 assist the faculty. This definition separates a faculty-habit 
 from a soul-habit, from faculty, from act, from passing dis- 
 positions, and assigns its purpose and efficiency. Habits re- 
 side in faculties, that are vital and somehow intellectual. 
 Infused or supernatural habits are communicated to the fac- 
 ulty by God, and procure, not readiness in supernatural 
 activity, but the very activity itself. Faith as a natural 
 habit, and faith as a supernatural habit can serve for ex- 
 planation. Natural or acquired habits result from reiterated 
 acts of some one kind; they confer not the power to act, but 
 the power to act with ease and readiness. The faculty with- 
 out the habit is simple power to act, the faculty with the habit 
 is power to act with ease and facility. Custom, because par- 
 ent to habit, gets the name second nature. Faculty is first 
 nature, habit is second nature. Habits of sense and habits 
 of appetite explain themselves, likewise habits of mind and 
 habits of will. Habits of will are moral habits, and are good 
 or bad, virtues or vices. Physical habits are of indifferent 
 moral worth, like study, talk, walk, thought. To include 
 virtue in qualified and wide sense, as well as virtue in simple 
 and strict sense, virtue is in general defined a habit perfect- 
 ing, improving, rounding out a rational faculty and bend- 
 ing it towards good. Good here means physical as well as 
 moral good for the faculty, and good in the sense of con- 
 duct ; good for any faculty, and good for the will exclusively. 
 Virtue in simple and strict sense perfects the will, and in- 
 clines it to moral good. Virtue in qualified and wide sense 
 perfects any other faculty, and inclines it to its own improve- 
 ment. A habit that never betrays itself in acts is no virtue, 
 because it falls away from its purpose. It is for facility, and 
 facility without acts is impossible. Prudence, recta ratio 
 agibilium, right order in conduct, is a practical, intellectual 
 virtue ; and for that reason, a moral virtue. It has a directive 
 bearing on the will, and virtues concerned with the will are 
 moral virtues. Here are four definitions of virtue, taken in 
 simple and strict sense. St. Thomas defines virtue as, 
 ''habitus operativus bonus," a good faculty-habit, a good 
 
112 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 habit bearing on activity; and good means moral good, not 
 physical. Aristotle defines virtue as a habit, that makes its 
 owner and his work good. Aristotle again defines virtue as 
 a habit, that chooses the middle course with respect to our- 
 selves, said middle course being fixed by reason, as a man 
 of prudence would determine it; a habit of avoiding what 
 would be excess or defect in the esteem of a prudent man. 
 St. Augustine defines virtue as a good quality of will, a help 
 to right living, and no help to wrong. When St. Augustine 
 adds, ''produced in us by God without our assistance," he 
 is talking of infused virtue. Like freedom, virtue resides in 
 the will as in subject, and in other faculties only inasmuch 
 as they work in connection with, under motion from, or under 
 control of the will. Prudence directs the will. Virtue is a 
 moral habit, moral habits result from moral acts, and moral 
 acts are one way or another acts of the will. Scattered acts 
 of virtue, no result of habit, never make a man simply and un- 
 qualifiedly good. They make him good with a qualification 
 and circumstances. The regularity and constancy secured by 
 habit, alone constitute a man simply and unqualifiedly good. 
 As St. Thomas says, regularity and constancy in good demand 
 that good acts be elicited with readiness, with unbroken uni- 
 formity, and with delight; and these requisites are verified 
 only when virtuous deeds become a habit, a species of second 
 nature. 
 
 The moral virtues are divided into the four cardinal vir- 
 tues, prudence, justice, fortitude and temperance. St. Thomas 
 offers these two reasons for the division. Objective order is 
 the standard of morality, reason must discover this order and 
 propose its commands to the will; the will in turn must exe- 
 cute these commands in its own field and in the field of the 
 passions, whether they tend towards good or away from evil, 
 whether concupiscible or irascible, desire or aversion. Pru- 
 dence, the habit of doing the right thing at the right time, is 
 reason 's helper ; justice, the habit of giving everybody his due, 
 is helper to the will in its own operations; temperance helps 
 the will in its management of appetite's desires; fortitude 
 helps to manage appetite's aversions. Four faculties con- 
 tribute to man's moral acts, intellect, will, appetite of desire 
 
VIRTUES AND VICES 113 
 
 and appetite of aversion; and the four cardinal virtues in 
 order keep these faculties right. Circumspice, age, ahstine, 
 sustine. Be sure you're right, then go ahead. These virtues 
 are called cardinal, because they are to all the other virtues 
 what the hinges are to the door; their support, basis of their 
 utility, and surpassing them all in point of worth and neces- 
 sity. All the other virtues can be referred to these four as 
 parts to a whole. It is easy to see that no moral virtue is 
 complete and perfect without these others. Obedience, for 
 instance, is hard because of pride, sensuality, laziness, dread ; 
 and complete obedience is next to impossible without humility, 
 temperance, diligence, courage. Want of temperance and 
 avarice are often responsible for injustice, and there is no 
 justice where these vices are in control. 
 
 Vice is virtue's contrary. It is habitus operativus malus, 
 a habit helping a faculty to moral evil. We must distinguish 
 in an evil habit or vice, as we distinguish in an evil act, a 
 positive entity and a negative. The negative entity is its 
 malice, and lies in its lack of moral goodness, its lack of har- 
 mony with the objective order. The formal object of a vice 
 is some aspect of inferior good, at odds with the objective 
 order, and inseparably connected with malice. Every virtue 
 can count at least two opposite vices, one by way of excess, 
 the other by way of defect. The seven capital or cardinal 
 sins are rooted in the seven good things most calculated to 
 excite the will to rebellion against reason or the objective 
 order. They are vainglory, gluttony, lust, avarice, sloth, 
 envy and anger. The first four seek good in a disorderly 
 way, the other three shun good because of some evil connected 
 with it. Goods of soul, like praise and honor, excite vain- 
 glory; goods of body with a bearing on the race's preserva- 
 tion, like unholy pleasure, are matter for lust ; goods of body 
 with a bearing on the individual's preservation, like food 
 and drink, excite gluttony ; outside goods like wealth provoke 
 avarice. The good shunned may bo one's own or another's. 
 Sloth shuns one's own good to avoid labor; envy shuns an- 
 other's good without thought of revenge, it is sadness at an- 
 other's good because rated an obstacle to one's own. Anger 
 shuns another's good with thought of revenge. Pride is 
 
114 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 queen of all the vices. In the order of intention pride is 
 first of all the vices, in the order of execution avarice enjoys 
 the prerogative. 
 
 Prudence. Aristotle defines prudence as recta ratio agi- 
 bilium, right decision in things to do, habit of practical not 
 speculative reason, helping to right decisions in question of 
 moral conduct. Art is different, it is recta ratio factihilium, 
 right decision in things to make. Art tends to make some 
 outside work right in physical sense, prudence tends to make 
 some act of the man morally good. Lessius defines prudence 
 as a habit of intellect helping us to know in every emergency 
 what is right and^ what is wrong. There are two kinds of pru- 
 dence, personal and political or state prudence. The chief 
 functions of prudence are euboulia, synesis, gnome, which 
 mean habit of taking advice, habit of giving advice, habit 
 of interpretation. The integral parts of prudence are mem- 
 ory, intellect, foresight, argumentation, skill, openness to in- 
 struction, caution, and wide range of vision. 
 
 Christ in the mystery of His loss in the temple is teaching 
 a profound lesson in prudence. St. Luke tells the story in 
 the ten last verses of his second chapter. ''Did you not know 
 that I must be about my Father's business?" Prudence in 
 practice is the art of doing the right thing at the right time. 
 Wisdom is her handmaid, her counsellor. She guides pru- 
 dence in her choice of conduct. Wisdom is in the mind, pru- 
 dence directs the will ; and both together hath a perfect work. 
 In the realm of conduct the will knows nothing, wishes every- 
 thing; the mind knows everything, wishes nothing. The will 
 stings the mind to industry and borrows in turn from its 
 servant the light it needs. Prudence, then, with the help of 
 wisdom, enables its owner to choose aright, when two lines of 
 conduct are submitted to him for selection. Generally it 
 manifests itself in a fixed phase of mind and will, perpetually 
 ready to abandon the less for the greater. In the case under 
 consideration Jesus had to choose between His Heavenly Fa- 
 ther's business and His Mother's pleasure. His infinite pru- 
 dence saw only one way open; and He tarried three days in 
 the temple, in spite of the pang His stay inflicted on Mary's 
 heart and Joseph's. A mere man, abandoned in the same 
 predicament by prudence, would go terribly wrong and jour- 
 
JUSTICE 115 
 
 ney down to Nazareth with his parents. All our mistakes are 
 due to want of prudence. Every duty we neglect betokens 
 absence of the quality. Every law we break is a departure 
 from its salutary promptings. We are abandoning the greater 
 for the less ; we are sacrificing the service of God for sloth, 
 for selfishness, for personal comfort. It must have cost the 
 Child Christ a heavy pang to inflict this pain on His Mother 
 and St. Joseph. He was as desirous of their holy company 
 as they were of His, His sorrow was an answering echo to 
 theirs. But His Father's business beckoned Him from afar, 
 and He had to follow. Everything must yield before God's 
 service. Next to virtue, life is man's supremest good on 
 earth, and the martyrs surrendered that. In the catalogue 
 of present goods, parents, home and friends rank next to life ; 
 and religious surrender them, making every vocation to the 
 monastery or convent a re-enactment of the sacred mystery 
 we study. 
 
 Justice. Justice is a constant and lasting readiness to ren- 
 der to everybody his due, it is a habit of will prompt and 
 ready to render to everybody his due. Constant and lasting 
 are implied in the word, habit. One act of justice never makes 
 a just man, because justice is a habit. Justice is divided into 
 commutative, distributive and legal. St. Thomas calls legal 
 justice general; he calls commutative and distributive, par- 
 ticular justice. St. Thomas treats this virtue of justice in 
 his Summa 2.2. between Questions 57 and 122. Legal justice, 
 he says, makes a good citizen, commutative and distributive 
 make a good man. 2.2. Q.58. a.6. Justice is directive of a 
 man's conduct towards others, under the aspect of what is 
 due these others. Man can be taken as an individual or as 
 a unit in the state. He has relations with the state as a whole, 
 and legal justice helps him fulfil them. The state as a whole 
 has relations with him, and distributive justice manages 
 them. He has relations with individuals in the state as men, 
 and not as citizens, and commutative justice is the virtue 
 concerned. Legal justice is in the ruler effectively, in the 
 subject executively. The ruler makes the laws, the subject 
 keeps them. The ruler is rendering the state its due, when 
 he makes laws; the subject, when he keeps them; both con- 
 tributing to the common good. Distributive justice is di- 
 
116 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 rective of the state or its head in the distribution of priv- 
 ileges and duties, dignities and burdens, rewards and pen- 
 alties, influencing citizens to accept one and the other with 
 satisfied content. Commutative justice is directive of the 
 individual in transactions with his neighbor, involving sale 
 and purchase and kindred processes, designated in a general 
 way as exchange. Commutare means to exchange, as dis- 
 tribuere means to distribute. 
 
 Justice makes equality between two. In commutative the 
 transaction is between two individuals, buyer and seller, or 
 thief and his victim, as the case may be. One gives money 
 and gets wares, the other gives wares and gets money, and 
 there is equality or justice. One gets wares and gives noth- 
 ing, the other gives wares and gets nothing; and there is in- 
 equality or injustice. The equality and inequality are 
 arithmetical, like 5 and 5, because such equality and inequal- 
 ity are possible in commutative. In distributive the trans- 
 action is between state and citizens. The citizens give serv- 
 ice and get office, the state gets service and gives office. Dis- 
 tributive is less concerned with rewarding citizens than with 
 rewarding them in a proportionate way. If the state with- 
 holds reward, it is offending against legal and commutative 
 rather than against distributive justice. Distributive is hurt, 
 only when some citizen, as compared with another citizen, 
 gets a reward out of all proportion with his deserts. In dis- 
 tributive two citizens deserve well of the whole community 
 or state in different degrees. John is worth 4 degrees to the 
 state in point of meritorious service, and gets in return 8 
 degrees of reward in the shape of honor, dignity or office. 
 If James deserves well of the state to the extent of 2 degrees, 
 distributive justice demands that he get in return 4 degrees 
 of reward, not 6. John gets 4 more degrees than he gave, 
 James gets only 2 more than he gave. The citizens give of 
 their persons and get things, the state gets of their persons 
 and gives things; and, as between persons and things, the 
 only equality possible is geometrical or proportional, in this 
 case, 4:8::2:4. Arithmetical equality is possible between 
 things and things, and commutative justice is concerned ex- 
 clusively with things. In legal justice the transaction is be- 
 tween citizen and state. The state gives law securing com- 
 
JUSTICE 117 
 
 mon good, and gets obedience. The citizen gives obedience, 
 and gets common good. Here there is question of things; 
 and, because of arithmetical equality, if the ruler makes 4 
 laws, every citizen has to keep all 4. The ruler as seat and 
 centre of authority is the state formally taken, citizens are 
 the state materially taken, and the ruler in his capacity of 
 citizen is part of it. In distributive the debt is owed the 
 citizen, and the state pays it. In legal the debt is due the 
 ruler or state, and the citizen pays it. Law is a debt the 
 ruler owes the community, obedience is a debt the community 
 owes the ruler. The ruler gets obedience, and gives common 
 good; the citizen gets common good, and gives obedience. 
 
 Of the three kinds of justice, distributive and legal are the 
 least definite; and, because restitution is practically impos- 
 sible, they are of less importance than commutative in the 
 event of infringement. They are in the main observed, when 
 the ruler does his utmost to distribute favors and burdens 
 with a fair and even hand, when citizens abide by the law 
 in all its details. If worthy citizens fail of their due reward, 
 the ruler cannot make amends without doing injustice to 
 others already in possession of dignities; and to make resti- 
 tution out of his own pocket would not be distributive justice, 
 which is concerned with the state's property, offices and 
 such, not with the ruler's private property. Favoritism and 
 nepotism are offenses against distributive, and they meet with 
 full treatment in the Summa, 2.2. Q.63. God plays no fa- 
 vorites, He is not a respecter of persons, A.A.IO, 34. Pen- 
 alties are restitution in the case of offended legal justice, and 
 the law never expects a criminal to bear witness against him- 
 self. Offenses against commutative justice are clear-cut and 
 well defined, the amount of restitution is a matter of arith- 
 metic, and the obligation stands till the last penny is paid. 
 
 Commutative justice is a process of exchange, and all ex- 
 changes are voluntary or involuntary. Voluntary exchanges 
 constitute business, and base the virtue of justice; involun- 
 tary exchanges base the vice of injustice. With this twofold 
 fact in mind, St. Thomas in his Summa, 2.2. Q.61, a.3, fur- 
 nishes us with a list of ordinary business transactions with a 
 bearing on justice, and a list of ordinary offenses against jus- 
 tice. Voluntary exchanges are involved in buying and sell- 
 
118 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 ing, usufruct, lending and borrowing, renting and hiring, 
 pawning, bailing. Involuntary exchanges are theft, robbery, 
 murder, assault, imprisonment, blows, wounds, lies, detrac- 
 tion, false witness, insult, adultery with wife, seduction of 
 slave. The whole of Question 62 deals with restitution in 8 
 articles. Between Questions 64 and 77, involuntary ex- 
 changes, or species of injustice, are discussed and explained. 
 Between Questions 77 and 79, voluntary exchanges are treated, 
 with special attention to buying, and selling, and interest. 
 Question 79 deals with the integral parts of justice, do good 
 and avoid evil, give everybody his due, and refuse nobody 
 his due. From Question 80 to Question 123, virtues closely 
 connected with justice are discussed, and they are nine in 
 number; religion, filial piety, esteem, truthfulness, gratitude, 
 defense, all enumerated by Cicero in his De Inventione, Book 
 2, along with friendship, generosity and equity. Connected 
 virtues in part differ from, and in part resemble justice. Jus- 
 tice gives everybody his due according to equality. Equality 
 is absent from religion, filial piety and esteem; due is want- 
 ing in the other six. Religion or duties to God cover QQ. 
 81-101; filial piety, 101; esteem, 101-106; gratitude, 106- 
 108; defense, 108; truthfulness, 109-114; friendship or af- 
 fability, 114-117 ; generosity, 117-120 ; equity, 120. He closes 
 with a brief discussion of the Ten Commandments, or pre- 
 cepts of justice, 122. Equity or epikeia, supra justum, is a 
 superior kind of legal justice, because it interprets law not 
 according to words, but according to the mind of the law- 
 maker. No lawmaker can formulate a law able to touch 
 every single occurrence. He legislates for ordinary contin- 
 gencies, for what commonly happens ; and circumstances can 
 quite change cases. 
 
 Fortitude. Cicero defines fortitude as a judicious encoun- 
 ter with danger, and sufferance of trouble, or endurance of 
 effort. It regulates the irascible passions embodying diffi- 
 culty, just as temperance has to do with the concupiscible 
 passions. Fear and courage are the two passions with which 
 fortitude is especially concerned, keeping them both within 
 the bounds of reason. Fear is dread of an evil conceived as 
 unavoidable, courage is dread of an evil avoidable only at 
 the expense of great effort. Fortitude is conspicuous in mar- 
 
FORTITUDE AND TEMPERANCE 119 
 
 tyrdom, and naturally speaking fear of death is the greatest 
 of all fears. Fortitude is more prominent in repressing fear 
 than in exciting courage. It is harder to bear trouble than 
 to attack it ; because, in bearing trouble, the victim is weaker 
 than trouble; in attacking trouble, the threatened victim is 
 stronger than trouble. Besides, trouble in the case of fear is 
 nearer being present, in courage trouble is future and farther 
 in the distance. Fear is long, courage is short. Fear is a 
 sin, when against order; when it flees evils that ought to be 
 met in the performance of duty. Fear is no sin, when it flees 
 evils that ought to be avoided, evils that can be avoided with- 
 out detriment to duty. Timidity is excessive fear, rashness 
 is excessive courage. 
 
 The four virtues connected with fortitude are spirited- 
 nesSy grandeur, patience and perseverance. Inasmuch as it 
 is a judicious encounter with danger, fortitude displays it- 
 self as spiritedness by way of preparation, and as grandeur 
 by way of execution. Inasmuch as it is a judicious endur- 
 ance of effort, fortitude displays itself as patience when trou- 
 ble is short, and as perseverance when trouble is long. Mag- 
 nanimity is grandeur in general, magnificence is grandeur in 
 the department of expense. The latter moves men to make 
 large outlays of money to ensure some grand project. Con- 
 fidence and security are parts of spiritedness. Presumption 
 is an excess of spiritedness. So is ambition, or inordinate 
 greed of honor. Vainglory is likewise an excess of spirited- 
 ness. Desire of glory is not in itself wrong, when the glory 
 sought is solid and true, when the seeker's purpose is right, 
 and the means he uses are legitimate. Desire of vain or empty 
 glory is wrong ; and glory is vain or empty, when based on a 
 thing that deserves no praise, when tribute from a man whose 
 judgment is little worth, when turned to wrong account, not 
 directed to the glory of God or the neighbor's salvation. 
 Vainglory is one of the capital sins, and counts for daughters* 
 disobedience, boastfulness, hypocrisy, novelty, stubbornness of 
 opinion, contrariness of will, and disputatiousness. Want of 
 spirit is opposed to spiritedness by way of defect ; presump- 
 tion, by way of excess. One attempts less than it ought to 
 attempt; the other, more; while spiritedness attempts what 
 it ought to attempt. Stinginess is opposed to magnificence. 
 
120 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 One rates the cost and neglects results; the other rates re- 
 sults and neglects the cost. Extravagance is the opposite 
 of stinginess. One makes man a spendthrift, the other makes 
 him a miser. Patience is a remedy against sadness. All the 
 moral virtues are helps to prevent the passions, in the pres- 
 ence of good or evil, from dragging reason to wrong. Pa- 
 tience, therefore, enables us to bear ills with an even mind, 
 and not desert the right in an attempt to escape them. It is 
 a virtue inferior to prudence, justice, fortitude and temper- 
 ance, as well as to the theological virtues. Perseverance is 
 part of fortitude, because it weakens fear and strengthens 
 courage, always with a view to length of duration. Forti- 
 tude can be the work of a minute, perseverance is the work 
 of years. Softness and stubbornness are opposed to perse- 
 verance by way of defect and excess respectively. St. Thomas 
 deals with fortitude in his Summa, 2.2. QQ. 123-141. 
 
 Temperance. Fortitude controls the irascible passions in 
 their retreat from evil, temperance controls the concupiscible 
 passions in their pursuit of good. Pleasure is the one great 
 good appealing to the concupiscible passions; and God, as a 
 reward and incentive, attaches pleasure to conservation of 
 the race and conservation of the individual. Pleasures of 
 touch contribute to the conservation of the race, pleasures of 
 taste to that of the individual. Therefore, temperance is most 
 conspicuous in control of pleasures of the flesh, and pleasures 
 of the table. Temperance restrains impurity and gluttony. 
 Temperance is not abstinence. One uses pleasure within the 
 bounds prescribed by reason, the other refrains from pleas- 
 ure altogether. Naturally speaking, abstinence from all food 
 and drink would be wrong, because use of some food and 
 drink is a law of nature imposed on the individual. Absti- 
 nence from some certain food or drink would not be wrong, 
 because no set food or drink is necessary to conservation of 
 the individual. Abstinence from all the pleasures of the 
 flesh would not be wrong in any individual, because conserva- 
 tion of the race is a law imposed on no individuals in par- 
 ticular, but on the race in general. If scattered individuals 
 refuse to propagate, the race can still continue; if any in- 
 dividual refuses to eat, he will die. Others can propagate the 
 race in our stead, nobody can eat for us. Therefore, while 
 
FORTITUDE AND TEMPERANCE 121 
 
 total abstinence from wine is quite right and highly com- 
 mendable in any individual, the moderate use of wine is far 
 from wrong. Total abstinence from pleasures of the flesh 
 is the only line of conduct open to individuals outside the 
 condition of marriage, because these pleasures of the flesh are 
 for the conservation of the race, and marriage is the one 
 process appointed by God and nature for the propagation 
 of the race. Moderate use of these pleasures with a view to 
 reproduction is temperance, and peculiarly a virtue of the 
 married. No use of these pleasures, whether moderate or 
 excessive, is alone legitimate with the unmarried. Temper- 
 ance is abstinence from illegitimate pleasure, it is the mod- 
 erate and sensible use of legitimate pleasure. Fasting in 
 food, sobriety in drink, chastity in pleasures of the flesh are 
 forms of temperance. Shame is a kind of chastity. Purity 
 and decency are parts of temperance. Continence, humility, 
 modesty, mildness, mercy, moderation, politeness have family- 
 resemblances with temperance. St. Thomas treats temper- 
 ance in his Summa, 2.2. QQ. 141-171. 
 
THESIS IX 
 
 CHAKACTER AND HABITS 
 
 Morally speaking, character is the man; every man's 
 character is his own work; and our destiny for weal or woe 
 is in our own hands. Character is no very profound mys- 
 tery, it is the plainest of problems. All has been said, when 
 we remark that character is compounded of temperament and 
 habits. Our temperaments are common with other hereditary 
 qualities we get from our parents ; and, whether they are helps 
 or hindrances to virtue and honesty, we must be content to 
 employ them with thankfulness when they are helps, and 
 supplement them with an abundant measure of good will when 
 they are hindrances. No mortal can shift on temperament 
 the blame for mediocrity. Parents are indeed responsible 
 for tendencies and traits their children inherit, they are not 
 responsible for their children's crimes. No man can allow 
 temperament to bind him hand and foot and drag him to 
 ruin, without proclaiming himself an abject slave, without 
 trailing his dignity in the mire, without surrendering his 
 birthright of liberty. Free will holds the key to the situa- 
 tion. Temperament is not omnipotent. It is a mighty factor 
 for good or evil, but it is far from settling the question. Free 
 will is mightier than temperament; the man born for con- 
 spiracy, treason and murder, can by dint of assiduous care 
 become conspicuous for honorable valor, a red-hot patriot, a 
 martyr in the cause of charity. The temperament of a de- 
 generate, when free will is not yet submerged, is as much an 
 instrument for good as the temperament of a saint. The de- 
 generate has a harder road to travel; he has to walk with 
 more care, more circumspection and more courage; but his 
 feet are mercifully fitted for rough as well as smoother roads, 
 and the precautions enumerated are within his power. Tend- 
 encies and traits he inherited from his progenitors can bend, 
 
 122 
 
CHARACTER AND HABITS 123 
 
 without being able to break, his will; and with the iron in 
 his nature he can stiffen his courage to meet whatever strain. 
 Temperament is, therefore, no insuperable hindrance to the 
 cultivation of character; and of the two elements making up 
 character, temperament is less within our power than habit. 
 Our temperament we never make, we receive it ; but free will 
 is its mistress, and, when the heart is alert, temperament never 
 slips control. 
 
 Our habits we make for ourselves, they are the growth of 
 scattered acts ; and we form habits with our eyes wide open to 
 the process and its consequences. Habits are even less a 
 mystery than temperament. They are facilities along certain 
 lines due to the frequent repetition of separate and distinct 
 acts. Nobody knows with certainty the exact number of times 
 an act has to be repeated to form a habit ; but everybody is 
 agreed that a habit of music, for instance, is out of the ques- 
 tion without days, and weeks, and years of practice. And 
 what is true of music is true of painting, oratory, honesty, 
 veracity, all the arts and all the virtues, our moral as well as 
 our physical activities. Even walking is a habit ; and, though 
 men and women pass from point to point in space with small 
 reflection and less endeavor, it would pay the philosopher to 
 know what mental exertion it costs baby to master this simple 
 habit. 
 
 But what we would most of all insist on, is the circum- 
 stance that our habits are distinctively home-products. We 
 make them, we never receive them ; and we are entirely and 
 utterly responsible for the part they play in our lives. Even 
 when habits are once formed, our wills are free, and quite 
 able to resist them; and, before they are formed, our wills 
 are absolute, and supreme, and omnipotent lords of the sep- 
 arate and distinct acts that originate them. Hence, nobody 
 can hide behind habit for excuse. The criminal who is such 
 from habit, is even more blameworthy than the criminal such 
 by surprise. Habitual crime is the growth of misspent years, 
 and betokens an accumulation of shame. Wrong not rooted 
 in habit may result from defective vigilance, want of experi- 
 ence, overwhelming temptation; and the law is more lenient 
 with first offenders than with veterans in vice. 
 
 Though not omnipotent, habit is a mighty factor in the 
 
124 GENEEAL ETHICS 
 
 formation of character and consequent conduct; and, there- 
 fore, our habits call for supremest care. Education is little 
 worth, unless it contributes to the formation of mental and 
 moral habits bej^ond reproach. Family is a wasted blessing, 
 unless boys and girls come out of it better prepared for the 
 battle of life. Government is a curse, unless its representa- 
 tives are a perpetual incentive to the mental and moral uplift 
 of its citizens. Church itself and religion are of little use, 
 unless their professing members are bettered by contact with 
 their aspirations and ideals. An ideal father and an ideal 
 mother are mortals, whose behavior uniformly provokes chil- 
 dren to the cultivation of every virtue, domestic, civic and 
 religious. The education that ministers merely to the mind, 
 with little or no concern for the heart, is as empty as a game 
 of hazard, and bound to work equal harm to familj^, state 
 and Church. Our years at school are the critical period in 
 our lives. Men and women are made and unmade during 
 this all-important season^ and, if we leave school with wrong 
 habits, we are in imminent danger of ultimate loss, and 
 strenuous endeavor becomes the price of salvation. 
 
 Therefore, we ought to be supremely solicitous about the 
 quality of our habits, and we ought to take serious thought 
 of our equipment in habits. Measures must be taken to 
 break with undesirable habits, and precautions must be em- 
 ployed to strengthen and multiply right tendencies in our 
 character. We must encourage the good in us, keep down the 
 evil; and the whole process is summed up in the one word, 
 control. Nothing so develops character as self-control. Good 
 habits result from repeated acts of virtue, bad habits are 
 broken by repeated victories over temptation to wrong; and 
 control is fully equal to the double task. It is a two-edged 
 sword, it cuts both ways. Man, as now constituted, is in- 
 clined to evil from his youth; he leans towards vice and 
 away from virtue; he is swift to one, slow to the other; and 
 self-control, while it keeps him from slaving to base instincts, 
 urges him to develop the better side of his character. With- 
 out an abiding habit of self-control, success in life is abso- 
 lutely out of the question. Without it, you cannot hope for 
 Heaven; without it, you cannot reasonably expect to escape 
 hell. Self-control is what makes men temperate, pure and 
 
SELF-CONTROL 125 
 
 honest ; want of this quality is responsible for the drunkards, 
 the libertines and the thieves that infest our large and small 
 cities. No one agency that I know is more conducive to the 
 cultivation of self-restraint than family-discipline, school- 
 discipline and the discipline of government or society. Every 
 time a boy obeys his parents at home, he is adding a new 
 asset to his worth as a man. Every time he breaks off play 
 at the sound of the bell, he is laying deep and strong the 
 broad foundation for the towering edifice of a splendid career. 
 These instances of self-control are but the small and humble 
 beginnings of future greatness ; and, if the habit accompanies 
 the boy into the world of industry, politics and business, he 
 will as a rule be soon discovered, he will prove a winner, and 
 the world will love him, the world will load him with the 
 highest honors at its disposal. 
 
 Self-control, then, is the readiest measure of a man's char- 
 acter, and this sober truth deserves a large place in your 
 thoughts. It is the one bit of advice I would impress on your 
 hearts. "Whatever books you read or study in after-life, read 
 and study them with a view to growth in self-control. Cul- 
 tivate a close acquaintance with the sturdy heroes of ancient 
 and modern times, men of stout character, able to encounter 
 and overcome hardships in their campaign for the right. 
 Have nothing but contempt for the mean specimens of hu- 
 manity, glorified in the modern novel and the morning news- 
 paper, men and women that weak they cannot withstand 
 temptation, men and women at the mercy of every vile de- 
 sire that stirs in their bosoms. Have high ideals, live always 
 a little superior to your environment, and never strike your 
 colors to degraded public opinion. Know the right, and do 
 it. Choose your friends with care, be citizens in the republic 
 of saints, and keep company with heroes. To achieve great- 
 ness, is an arduous task, we need every little help; and the 
 example of the illustrious is a tonic for activity in the up- 
 ward process. Scorn to borrow your religion or morality 
 from the world. The Church is their appointed teacher, and 
 to look elsewhere for guidance is like drawing water in a 
 sieve, or planting pumpkins for a harvest of roses. Be men 
 of principle. Be the hero described by Horace. If the world 
 falls in ruins at your feet, present a bold front to the crash. 
 
126 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 Map out your lives along a line of conduct approved of by- 
 faith and reason, and then, whatever happens, keep your 
 course undaunted. You may fail of success, as the term 
 goes; you cannot fail of honor; and to go down to defeat 
 with right, is better than to be crowned a winner with wrong. 
 
THESIS X 
 
 RIGHTS AND DUTIES 
 
 Jouin, 71-75; Bickahy, 244-253. 
 
 Rights are meant by nature to shield men from harm in 
 their intercourse with others, and they accomplish this pur- 
 pose by creating duties in others. They procure the same 
 advantage for God, and prevent men from wronging their 
 Creator. Right equips its owner with the moral power to 
 do or exact something, duty compels its subject to render 
 another his due. Right has at least three meanings, justice, 
 law, moral power. Because right is opposed to wrong or in- 
 justice, right itself is justice or the just thing ; and, because 
 justice is a man's due, discharge of duty is the consumma- 
 tion of justice. Right is a man's due, duty is respect for 
 another's rights; and, therefore, any refusal to fulfil a duty 
 is an injustice or wrong. Because the essential purpose of 
 all law is the establishment of justice, law itself has a claim 
 to the title, right. In fact law, when couched in language, 
 is but the concrete expression of a right; and this is true of 
 every single law, of every collection of laws, and of whatever 
 law borrows part of its compelling force from sources ex- 
 traneous to the subject affected by the law. Civil law is 
 largely a collection of rights the state undertakes to safe- 
 guard; canon law discharges the same function in matters 
 ecclesiastical ; and a law against burglary, with imprisonment 
 for penalty, is concerned with a man's right to his property. 
 Last of all, and in strict sense, right, viewed in its owner or 
 possessor, is the moral and legitimate power to do something 
 oneself, or exact its doing from another; the moral power to 
 demand something, to hold something, or to use something 
 as one's own. We have thus far taken three views of right. 
 Viewed as justice or the right thing, it is a something to be 
 
 127 
 
128 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 rendered by another. Viewed as law, it is a something out- 
 side the owner and compelling others. Viewed as a moral 
 power, it is a something in the owner ; and from this circum- 
 stance right has all its practical value and worth. 
 
 Right primarily means justice. Law is called right, be- 
 cause it is an expression of justice. The moral power to do 
 or exact something is called right, because justice vindicates 
 to everybody his due. Suarez calls law preceptive right; the 
 moral-power, dominion-right. A right, therefore, is man's 
 moral power over what is due him. Duty is not a power, but 
 an obligation. Right means, I can ; duty means, I ought. A 
 right is called a moral power to distinguish it from might, 
 which is physical power. Right touches only what is due 
 the man, because justice is its foundation, and justice gives 
 to everybody only his due, only what belongs to him. A thing 
 is said to belong to a person, when the objective order of 
 things makes it his, when between him and it a necessary re- 
 lationship of connection ensues. This connection is physical 
 and substantial in the case of a man and his life, a man and 
 parts of his body; it is physical and accidental in the case 
 of health, knowledge and the like ; it is moral, when between 
 the man and things external to him, like money, land, repu- 
 tation, esteem, glory or fame. 
 
 A right would be little worth unless it created a duty in 
 others. A right is, therefore, a relation, with its subject, title 
 and term. The subject is owner, the title is whatever fact 
 creates connection between the owner and the thing he owns, 
 and the term is the subject-matter of the right, as well as the 
 person in whom the corresponding duty resides. Holland 
 distinguishes in every right a person of inherence, a person 
 of incidence, a thing and a fact. He omits title, and makes 
 fact mean the peculiar use of the thing or matter conferred 
 on the owner by the right. God has no duties strictly so 
 called, because duty taken that way, connotes a superior. 
 Therefore, as between right and duty, right comes first. In 
 the case of men, right in the person of inherence causes duty 
 in the person of incidence; and, therefore, right precedes 
 duty in the order of nature, though as regards the order of 
 time both are simultaneous. Duty in the person of inherence 
 always causes right in the same; and, therefore, restricting 
 
 3 
 
RIGHT AND MIGHT 129 
 
 the question to the person of inherence, duty always pre- 
 cedes right in the order of nature. 
 
 Right is reducible to justice ; and, because justice is three- 
 fold, commutative, legal, distributive, rights are of three 
 kinds with distinctively peculiar purposes. In commutative 
 justice, the purpose of right is liberty and independence in 
 the disposal of one's goods. In legal justice, the purpose of 
 right is the common welfare. In distributive justice, it is to 
 safeguard the citizen against state-wrongs. A right in com- 
 mutative justice can be surrendered, because no law forbids 
 a man to submit to private wrong. Hence the axioms, "No 
 harm is done a willing victim," and ''Nobody is obliged to 
 use his rights." In legal justice the ruler cannot legitimately 
 cede his right, because laws are made and executed not for 
 the ruler's advantage, but for the welfare of citizens. Hence 
 the ruler is obliged to use his right. 
 
 Right connotes the moral power to employ physical force 
 in its realization, because order demands that the inferior, 
 or physical force be always at the call of the superior, or 
 moral power. In society, to guard against abuses, the ap- 
 plication of this physical force is reserved to the state, and 
 is not left to the caprice of individuals. Physical compulsion, 
 in potency or in act, is not of the essence of a right, it is a 
 complementary property. Rights persevere in the absence 
 of physical compulsion. No citizen is allowed to urge his 
 rights against the state with the help of physical force, though 
 the state enjoys this prerogative as against a citizen. Right 
 order demands as much. In commutative justice, where help 
 from the state is beyond reach, one citizen is allowed to use 
 force against another, when his rights are endangered. Other- 
 wise wrong would be without remedy. 
 
 When talking about good and bad acts, we contended and 
 proved that some acts are intrinsically and essentially good 
 or bad ; that they get their goodness or badness from nothing 
 outside of themselves, like law, or custom, or opinion; and 
 that they are good or bad always, everywhere and in what- 
 ever circumstances. Moral Positivism is opposed to our doc- 
 trine, and maintains that nothing is good or bad in itself and 
 unchangeably, but that good and bad acts are made such by 
 something outside of, and extraneous to the acts themselves. 
 
130 
 
 GENEKAL ETHICS 
 
 Hohhes ascribes all the difference to civil law; Lambert, to 
 custom and public opinion; Mandeville, to the research of 
 eminent scholars; Nietzsche, to pity for the weak; Descartes 
 and Puffendorf, to the will of God ; Darwinists and Positivists 
 in general, to evolution. 
 
 Because rights are but prescriptions of justice, naturally 
 enough they get the same treatment as good and bad acts, at 
 the hands of these enemies to morality. Their sytsem is 
 called Juridical Positivism; and, in a very few words, while 
 refusing independent validity to natural rights, it vindicates 
 validity to only whatever rights are declared such by vested 
 authority. All Moral Positivists belong to this school, along 
 with men like Hobbes, Bentley, Lasson, Hartmann, who make 
 the state sole and single cause of all rights. Rousseau and 
 his followers ascribe right to tacit or expressed agreement 
 among men. Savigny, the founder of the historical school, 
 refers everything to history, public law, and a people's cus- 
 toms. According to him natural rights are no rights at all, 
 but only rules and standards for the establishment of rights. 
 With him rights begin and grow in much the same way as a 
 people's language. 
 
 Against all such false philosophers we contend for a defi- 
 nite collection of natural rights, vested with a validity inde- 
 pendent of all positive law. Life, liberty and the pursuit of 
 happiness are three such rights, enumerated and acknowledged 
 by our Constitution. These rights and a multitude of others 
 descend to man from his Creator, and positive law has noth- 
 ing to do with their creation or production. Its whole busi- 
 ness is to safeguard these rights, by hemming them round 
 with the physical force at its abundant disposal. Bight is 
 reducible to justice, justice gives everybody his due, gives 
 everybody what belongs to him ; and life is ours not by favor 
 of the state, but by the free gift of God. The state has its 
 right to make laws and insist on their observance, not from 
 consent, or agreement, or history; but from God, who gave 
 being to the state, and equipped it with all the means it needs 
 to fulfil its purpose. God never imposed a duty on anybody, 
 without investing him with a right to all needed means. He 
 has imposed a multitude of duties on men ; and, just as these 
 duties bind men without reference to positive law, so the 
 
JURIDICAL POSITIVISM 131 
 
 rights attaching to them are quite independent of human 
 legislation and authority. Positive law, without prior nat- 
 ural law, is a house without a foundation. Kings could make 
 laws till doomsday without any appreciable effect, beyond 
 physical force, unless natural law held subjects to reverence 
 for authority, and obedience to legitimate rulers. Agreements 
 and compacts would be empty scraps of paper, if fidelity to 
 promises were not a prescription of the natural law. No in- 
 ternational law would be possible, because there would be no 
 competent legislator. Every civil law and every custom would 
 be by the very fact just, law could make murder right, cus- 
 tom could make impurity a virtue. 
 
 And just as every positive law borrows all its efficacy from 
 prior natural law, even so every positive right borrows all 
 its strength and force from prior natural right. Positive law 
 is an application of natural law, it makes natural law clearer, 
 it adds to the moral sense of obligation and future sanction, 
 attaching to natural law,, the physical sense of present pen- 
 alty in the shape of fine or imprisonment, attaching to every 
 positive law enacted. When Kant distinguishes between ju- 
 ridical rights and ethical rights, when he separates the jurid- 
 ical order from the ethical order, he forgets that ethical rights, 
 as compared with juridical rights, are the same as natural 
 law, as compared with positive law. When he attributes 
 greater efficacy and sacredness to juridical rights than he at- 
 tributes to ethical rights, he is virtually declaring positive law 
 superior to natural law, man superior to God; he is putting 
 tlie cart before the horse, subordinating cause to effect, attach- 
 ing more importance to the roof than to the foundation. Na- 
 ture confers ethical, or natural rights; law confers juridical 
 rights. Ethical or natural rights are unchangeable at the 
 hands of men, they do allegiance to God alone, and God is 
 their single executive. Juridical rights are open to change 
 with change of legislators, and are in force only as long as the 
 laws creating them remain on the statute-books. Law is law, 
 only when based on justice ; and juridical rights, opposed to 
 ethical rights, are no rights at all. Juridical order is, there- 
 fore, only an integral part of moral or ethical order, and 
 no more separable from the same than the head is from the 
 man. The head cannot be separated from the man, without 
 
132 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 changing its entire complexion and substance. Juridical or- 
 der, separated from ethical order, ceases altogether to be moral 
 order; and rights conferred by law, in opposition to rights 
 conferred by nature, are no rights at all. 
 
 God the author of nature seems destined to get small notice 
 and smaller reverence from present-day writers on Ethics, 
 thanks to the atheistic and irreligious trend of our times. 
 And natural law, which has God for its maker, meets with the 
 same full measure of contempt. One writer on Jurisprudence, 
 Holland by name, wants law in strict sense limited to human 
 positive or civil law; barring from the title natural law, di- 
 vine positive law in Scripture, and Church law. He bars 
 natural law, because it is formulated by an indeterminate 
 authority; Scriptural law, because it is formulated by a su- 
 perhuman authority ; Church law, because it is formulated by 
 a politically subordinate authority. All this is purely arbi- 
 trary, and betrays the man's atheistic tendencies. We grant 
 that law in strict sense cannot be formulated by an indetermi- 
 nate authority, but God in nature, God in Scripture, and 
 Church, are no indeterminate authority, unless we want to 
 turn atheists and infidels. Natural law and Scriptural law 
 are divine law, divine law is as much law as civil law, God 
 is its formulating authority, God is no indeterminate being, 
 and only atheists and infidels can think the thing. Church 
 law is as much law as civil law, the true Church is no inde- 
 terminate authority; and, whatever may be said of other 
 churches, the true or Catholic Church is in its own sphere 
 quite independent of the state, and it never presumes to legis- 
 late outside its own sphere. True, God is a superhuman au- 
 thority; but even civil law, without superhuman authority 
 at its back, is a dead letter and nothing worth. No mere man 
 has a right to legislate for other men. All men are born free 
 and equal, nobody is born a king; and the authority he gets 
 immediately from God is what makes the ruler's pronounce- 
 ments law. Without this authority, his pronouncements are 
 empty words, and of no more worth than mine or yours. 
 Therefore, God must not be denied the quality of lawmaker, 
 simply because He is a superhuman authority. Therefore 
 God's law, whether natural or Scriptural, is more law than 
 civil law. 
 
HOLLAND, KANT AND POSITIVISM 133 
 
 What Mr. Holland, perhaps, means is that God and the 
 Church are less visible and less tangible than the state. But 
 that is his own view of the thing. To the religious mind, and 
 the man of faith, God and the Church are more solemn reali- 
 ties than the state. With Thomasius, Holland wants us to 
 keep our sickles out of theology, forgetting that natural theol- 
 ogy is as much philosophy as logic or psychology or Ethics, 
 and that no part of philosophy, which is knowledge of things 
 in their last cause, can be rightly understood without a fair 
 knowledge of God, the first and last cause of all things. To 
 doubt the propriety of conceiving God as a lawmaker, as Mr. 
 Holland ventures to do, is not to keep one's sickle out of 
 theology, but to assail all theology and all religion with an 
 axe. God is more than a mere information-bureau, equally 
 well satisfied whether His children accept His doctrine or not. 
 He teaches with authority, and He wants His lessons learned ; 
 He is eminently a lawmaker, and sanctions His legislation with 
 hell. He is a Father of too wise a kind to allow His sons to 
 go what way they will. He wants their full obedience ; and, 
 if they refuse it, they know what to expect. And all this is 
 clear from Natural Theology, without any appeal whatever to 
 Supernatural Theology or revelation. Law in strict sense is 
 an obligation or ruling founded on right reason, drawn up 
 and promulgated for the common good by him who has charge 
 of the community affected ; and this definition is as fully veri- 
 fied in natural. Scriptural and Church law as it is in civil 
 law. Natural law is from eternity; positive law, whether di- 
 vine or human, is made or placed in time. 
 
 Holland is imitating Kant when he makes a difference be- 
 tween Ethics and Nomology. Ethics, he says, touches the will, 
 the interior act, and it is a matter of conscience; Nomology 
 touches the outward act, exterior conduct. Civil law belongs 
 to Nomology, and it cannot fathom a man's thoughts or in- 
 tentions with any degree of certainty, and very sensibly leaves 
 them alone. It agrees to interpret them with the help of 
 external acts. Divine law has God for author, and men's 
 thoughts as well as their intentions are no mystery to God. 
 Juridical legality is a different thing from Ethical morality. 
 An act can be all right in the eyes of the law, and all wrong 
 in the eyes of conscience. Civil law makes only indifferent 
 
134 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 acts good or bad, it leaves other acts where it finds them, and 
 makes them merely legal. Ethics makes an act morally good 
 or bad, prior to and independent of all civil law ; and this is 
 the big difference between natural law and positive law. 
 
 The ethical order must not be separated from the juridical 
 order, because the latter is an integral part of the former. 
 Ethical order is like the whole man, juridical order is like 
 his head. Natural law prescribes civil law as a necessary 
 requisite for the welfare of the state, and therefore all civil 
 or positive law is but an emanation from natural law. The 
 juridical order is right, taken as positive law; and all posi- 
 tive law is a derivation from natural law, which in turn is 
 right in the ethical order. When Kant separates the jurid- 
 ical order from the ethical or moral order, when he ascribes 
 all the force and efficacy of juridical rights to positive law, 
 without any reference whatever to natural law, he virtually 
 reduces all right to preceptive, and rejects dominion-right. 
 Preceptive right is a prescription of positive law ; and, without 
 the support of natural law, positive law has no binding force. 
 Dominion-right is a prescription of the natural law, and nat- 
 ural law binds, whether positive law supports it or not. 
 
 Kant denies all ethical or moral right, to admit only jurid- 
 ical right; and, therefore, he denies dominion-right to admit 
 only preceptive right. It is wrong to say that laws urged by 
 civil authority are not in themselves binding on conscience. 
 Civil law looks to the external act, without a care for the 
 motive; natural law looks to external act and motive both. 
 No matter what his motive, civil law certainly binds the man 
 in conscience to put the prescribed external act. Penal laws 
 exert no strain on conscience beyond the acceptance of the 
 penalty incurred; but that is due to the mercy of the law- 
 maker, and a matter of common understanding between ruler 
 and subjects. Obligation to the law is no product of the 
 man himself, it is imposed on him by another, and proceeds 
 from the natural law and its author, God. Therefore, every 
 illegal act is wrong; and yet not every legal act is right, be- 
 cause the juridical order is only a part of the ethical or moral 
 order, and not the whole of it. A man's head can be sound, 
 while the rest of his body is unhealthy. 
 
 Right as law is preceptive right, right as a moral power 
 
DIVISION OF RIGHTS ' 135 
 
 is dominion-right; and the two admit of many divisions. 
 Law is private, public, international. Law is private, when 
 the two parties to the action are citizens, and the state is 
 arbiter; public, when the state has action against the citizen 
 or the citizen against the state, the state in both cases being 
 arbiter ; international, when the parties to the action are two 
 independent states, and the world is arbiter. Private law is 
 substantive and adjective, normal and abnormal, antecedent 
 and remedial, in rem and in personam. Private law is be- 
 tween citizen and citizen. Substantive law defines the rights 
 of individuals, adjective law indicates the process of their en- 
 forcement. Normal law is for persons of ordinary type, ab- 
 normal is for deviations from ordinary type. Antecedent law 
 is for cases before wrong has been committed, remedial is for 
 cases after wrong has been committed. Law in rem is against 
 the world, law in personam is against some definite individual. 
 The six normal antecedent rights in rem are, 1, right to per- 
 sonal safety and liberty; 2, right to society and control of 
 family; 3, right to good name; 4, right to advantages of life 
 in community and free exercise of profession; 5, right to 
 property; 6, right against fraud and deceit. The first of the 
 six secures owner against threats, assault, wounds, imprison- 
 ment, dangerous things and dangerous places. The second 
 secures owner marital rights of husband over wife, parental 
 rights of father over child, tutelary rights of guardian over 
 ward, dominical rights of master over servant. The third 
 secures owner against libel and such like injury. The fourth 
 secures owner a livelihood, use of harbors and rivers, free- 
 dom from malicious prosecution. The fifth secures owner in 
 his possessions. The sixth secures owner against damage 
 accruing from fraud and deceit. The two normal antecedent 
 rights in personam are quasi-contract and contract. Quasi- 
 contract embraces these four headings, domestic, fiduciary, 
 meritorious, officious. Domestic means one member of the 
 family against another member. Fiduciary means trusts, 
 matters of confidence, executors. Meritorious means right to 
 indemnity for services rendered. Officious means use of pub- 
 lic officials like postmen. Contracts are principal and acces- 
 sory. Principal contracts imply no ulterior object, accessory 
 imply security for another contract. Principal contracts are 
 
136 
 
 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 six, alienation, permissive use, marriage, service, negative 
 service, aleatory gain. Accessory contracts are seven in num- 
 ber, suretyship, indemnity, pledge, warranty, ratification, ac- 
 count stated, for further assurance. Remedial law deals with 
 offenses against rights in rem and in personam. Abnormal 
 law is for deviations from ordinary type. Adjective law is 
 opposed to substantive. Substantive creates rights, adjective 
 enforces them. Adjective law is procedure. 
 
THESIS XI 
 
 CONTRACTS 
 Jouin, 140-154; Eickdhy, 253-255. 
 
 The jurisprudence of contracts is a large question, and 
 cannot obviously be treated here in detail. We are studying 
 ethics, not law ; and we necessarily restrict ourselves to what 
 natural law has to say on the subject, leaving the question 
 of positive or civil law in its bearing on contracts to the 
 school of law. A contract is an agreement and consent be- 
 tween several persons regarding some set object. A one-sided 
 or unilateral contract is in itself a mere promise ; and, because 
 of its nature it obliges or binds only one of the two parties 
 to the transaction, hardly deserves the name. Its fulfilment 
 is regularly a matter of fidelity to one's word, not a matter 
 of justice. When, however, it raises the hopes of the prom- 
 isee, and induces him to incur expense, it assumes the pro- 
 portions of a two-sided contract, and involves strict justice. 
 Justice likewise intervenes when the promiser means to bind 
 himself in justice. Contract in strict sense creates a mutual 
 obligation between two or more; and, therefore, only two- 
 sided or bilateral contracts deserve the name in its completest 
 significance. A contract creates rights and duties in both 
 parties to the transaction. Take, for example, the common- 
 est form of contract, that of buying and selling. The buyer 
 assumes the duty of paying the price, and is invested with the 
 right to receive the goods purchased. The seller assumes the 
 duty of delivering the purchase, and is vested with the right 
 to receive the price. The two persons are the efficient cause 
 of the contract, the set object is its material cause, consent 
 and agreement are its formal cause ; and all three causes must 
 fulfil certain conditions. The persons must be fit agents, 
 they must enjoy the use of reason, and they must have full 
 and free dominion over what they dispose of in the contract. 
 
 137 
 
138 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 Natural law is sponsor for these two conditions. A contract 
 means free consent, and that demands the use of reason. A 
 contract is a function of ownership, and nobody gives but 
 what he first possesses. 
 
 Civil law can for the common good prescribe other condi- 
 tions, and their discussion belongs to the school of law. The 
 matter of the contract must be possible, morally as well as 
 physically; and, for obvious reasons, it must be legitimate. 
 The consent given must be of such a nature that it really and 
 truly creates an obligation. In other words, it must be true 
 internal consent as well as external, and it must be entirely 
 free. Natural law stands for the invalidity of feigned con- 
 tracts, empty ceremonies without any intention to form a con- 
 tract or assume an obligation, because natural law's avenger, 
 or God, sees the heart as well as external facts. Civil law, 
 because its maker's vision is restricted to external facts, counts 
 valid every such feigned contract. It argues that the deceiver 
 has violated another's rights, and must indemnify him even 
 to the extent of putting true internal consent. Besides, the 
 party deceived is never obliged to believe the deceiver, when 
 he says that he made no true contract. A contract made with 
 a full sense of obligation, and a determination to never fulfil 
 it, is valid even in natural law. 
 
 Freedom is interfered with by want of knowledge or mis- 
 take, by fear and by violence. Substantial mistake invalidates 
 a contract, e.g., wine and vinegar in a purchase. Accidental 
 mistake, when responsible for the transaction, renders gratui- 
 tous contracts invalid, -onerous contracts repudiable. Ex- 
 ternal violence invalidates contracts. Internal fear, as long 
 as it leaves freedom unimpaired, never invalidates. External 
 fear, induced unjustly to effect contract, invalidates gratui- 
 tous, makes onerous repudiable. 
 
 Quasi-contracts get their validity from law, rather than 
 from self-imposed obligation. Law imposes the obligation, 
 not parties to the contract. No contract is made, law sup- 
 plies, and deals with case in much the same way as if a con- 
 tract had been made. Law casts duty on person of incidence 
 without his agreement. Its four kinds are, family, trust, 
 meritorious, officious. 
 
 Savigny defines a contract, as the union of several in ac- 
 
DIVISION OF CONTRACTS 139 
 
 cordant expression of will, to create an obligation between 
 them. Hence his analysis of a contract into these four ele- 
 ments, several parties, agreement of wills, mutual communi- 
 cation of agreement, intention to create legal relations. About 
 expression of agreement. Pollock says, ''Courts hold men to 
 fulfilment of intention, only when expressed in a manner that 
 would convey to an indifferent person, reasonable and rea- 
 sonably competent in the matter in hand, the sense in which 
 the expression is relied on by the parties claiming satisfac- 
 tion." Justice Blackburn, 1871, says, "Whatever a man's 
 real intention, if he so conducts himself that a reasonable 
 man would believe he was assenting to another's terms, and 
 that the other party agrees, the man would be equally bound 
 as if he had intended to agree." Therefore, not what the 
 man intended, not what the other party supposed him to 
 intend, hut what a reasonable man, i.e., judge or jury, would 
 put upon such acts. This is the objective theory of contracts. 
 Holland sees these six elements in a contract, 1, several par- 
 ties; 2, two-sided act expressing agreement; 3, matter agreed 
 upon both possible and legal; 4, agreement of a nature to 
 produce a legally binding result; 5, such a result as affects 
 the relations of the parties to one another; 6, very generally 
 a solemn form, or some fact affording a motive for the agree- 
 ment. A formal contract observes formalities prescribed by 
 law, usually writing. An informal contract is without pre- 
 scribed formalities, but is based on some fact or considera- 
 tion. The result of a contract is obligation between parties, 
 conferring rights on one, imposing duties on other, partly 
 stipulated in agreement, partly implied by law. 
 
 Holland divides contracts into principal and accessory, and 
 we already enumerated them. Under permissive use he 
 groups loan for consumption, loan for use, and loan for hire. 
 In olden times loan of money ranked as loan of food, and it 
 was a species of permissive use, the kind called loan for con- 
 sumption, as opposed to the kind called loan for use. Inter- 
 est then fell under the contract denominated permissive use 
 for consumption. Such a contract calls for mere return of 
 the food or money borrowed, or their equivalent ; it is of its 
 nature gratuitous, and the right to interest depends on special 
 agreement. Hence the Church's condemnation of interest in 
 
140 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 olden times. All interest was considered usury or excessive 
 interest, because increment, to which the lender was not en- 
 titled. 
 
 Cathrein divides contracts into gratuitous and onerous. 
 Gratuitous are made in the interest of one party; onerous, 
 in the interest of both. In gratuitous all the burden is on 
 one party, in onerous both parties assume burdens. Gratui- 
 tous contracts are promise, gift, loan, deposit. Onerous con- 
 tracts are buying and selling, letting for hire, partnership, 
 interest. In a contract of buying and selling two mutually 
 agree on merchandise to be received or given for a set price, 
 and price usually means money. Between value received and 
 price given there must be some equality, because people are 
 not supposd to be making presents, when assuming onerous 
 contracts. A thing's value is fixed in great measure by its 
 perfection or usefulness in the eyes of men. We distinguish 
 between use-value and exchange-value. Use-value is abso- 
 lute, and depends on the thing's substantial usefulness. Ex- 
 change-value is relative, and depends on the thing's worth, as 
 compared with other salable articles. Air, water, light have 
 great use-value, small exchange-value. Price is exchange- 
 value expressed in terms of money. To be fair and just, a 
 thing's price and its value ought to be equal. Prices go into 
 legal, natural and conventional. Law fixes the legal price, 
 many circumstances fix the natural price, mutual agreement 
 fixes the conventional price. Natural price, because depend- 
 ent on circumstances, admits of a certain latitude; and can 
 be high, medium or low. These circumstances are, the use- 
 fulness of an article, its scarcity, multitude of buyers, abun- 
 dance of money. It is quite fair and proper to charge a 
 price rated just by common opinion. Where law and opin- 
 ion fail to fix prices, agreement must settle things. 
 
 Among other applications, the contract of letting for hire 
 has place between employer and employee. This species of 
 the contract is peculiar, inasmuch as the energies of a hu- 
 man being are involved in the transaction. Besides the pay- 
 ment of just and fair wages, the employer must impose on his 
 workman no condition or burden derogatory to his dignity 
 as a human being. The workman has no right to dispose of 
 his energies in a way unsuited to his dignity as a man, and 
 
EMPLOYER AND WORKMAN 141 
 
 whatever employer compels him to do so is guilty of injus- 
 tice. A just wage is a living wage, and that means money 
 enough to enable the workman to live, and to live comfort- 
 ably; to procure not only the necessaries of life, but a mod- 
 erate share of its luxuries. The workman has no right to a 
 fixed percentage of his employer's profits, because he is not 
 precisely a partner; and yet, other things equal, the more 
 an employer derives from a workman's labor, the higher are 
 the wages due the workman, if price is to be regulated by the 
 usefulness of the commodity purchased. It is extortion pure 
 and simple, to coerce a workman into selling his labor at a 
 price, altogether out of proportion with its value to the pur- 
 chaser. And the immense fortunes, amassed by employers 
 in short intervals of time, quite satisfy me that, whether 
 awake to the fact or not, most employers are enriching them- 
 selves at the expense of their workmen, and actually stealing 
 from the poor. 
 
 Law, public opinion, agreement, unaided by religion, will 
 never be able to establish . justice, as between employer and 
 workman; because money can buy labor-leaders as well as 
 lawmakers, capital can afford to laugh at public opinion, and 
 free agreement is out of the question, when labor has to 
 choose between low wages and starvation. The chiefest rem- 
 edy for injustice is religion and dread of a future punish- 
 ment. ''All things obey money." Eccles. 10.19. God is 
 the only judge industrial thieves need to be absolutely afraid 
 of, because they can on occasions switch human judges with 
 money, nearly everybody having his price; and the one way 
 to escape fear of God and fear of hell, is to shake off all 
 allegiance to religion. This labor-problem, because of its bear- 
 ing on morality, is as much an affair of the Church as it is 
 of the state. Till this problem is satisfactorily settled, it 
 must remain a menace to the salvation of menu's souls; and it 
 is the Church's business to fight every such menace to a fin- 
 ish. All the world is her kingdom, workmen and employers 
 alike belong to her jurisdiction; they are children in her 
 house, and like a good mother she must keep down quarrels 
 in the family. 
 
 And here is the plan our Church proposes. She counsels 
 employers to cultivate with enthusiasm the two virtues of 
 
142 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 justice and charity; she counsels workmen to cultivate with 
 no smaller enthusiasm the two virtues of honest content and 
 conscientious industry. In the matter of pay, justice means 
 a living wage for all, defectives out of the question, and for 
 workmen of superior ability a corresponding increase. A 
 living wage means money enough to decently support the 
 workman and his family, without extraordinary labor on the 
 part of his wife and young children. His wife must care for 
 his home, his young children must get an education, and 
 strengthen their weak bodies by play and exercise for the 
 years ahead. 
 
 The employer, who holds his workman to starvation wages, 
 is guilty of injustice; and the workman's consent to the 
 unholy transaction relieves the employer of no moral re- 
 sponsibilitiy. To take advantage of a poor man's needs, is 
 to rob him ; and to force a hungry man to choose a half loaf, 
 when a whole loaf is his due, differs only a little from holding 
 up a traveler with a pistol. The traveler yields up his purse, 
 to escape with his life ; and the oppressed workman yields up 
 his whole loaf, to escape from starvation. In the one case 
 it is the surrender of the purse or death; in the other it is 
 surrender of the whole loaf or no bread at all. 
 
 And charity is an altogether different virtue from justice. 
 Justice is close and tight, charity is a stranger to narrow 
 notions; it is as wide as the sea. Charity is more than mere 
 justice; to coin a word, it is super justice. Justice gives 
 everybody his due, no more no less; and, if it leans at all, it 
 leans toward severity. Charity leans towards leniency, and 
 its donor glories in his dishonesty towards himself. It gives 
 to everybody more than his due, in the matter of wages as 
 well as of praise ; less than his due, in the matter of penalties 
 as well as of blame. Charity, therefore, is a species of divine 
 superjustice, mercifully meant to correct the shortsighted jus- 
 tice of men. 
 
 The employer is not absolute owner of his wealth, when God 
 is taken into account. No man can, in the name of justice 
 or of charity, appropriate to himself a dollar of the employ- 
 er's legitimate wealth; but God is first owner, God has prior 
 rights, and God can stipulate to what uses the employer must 
 put his wealth. The rich are God's almoners to the poor. 
 
EMPLOYER AND WORKMAN 143 
 
 It is their sacred and solemn duty to relieve the wants of the 
 needy with their superfluous wealth, and to give their work- 
 men sometimes, not in the name of justice, but in the name 
 of charity, a little more than they earn. When employers 
 heed the demands of justice and charity, workmen will have 
 no cause to complain, honest content and conscientious in- 
 dustry will be as easy as they are natural, differences between 
 employers and workmen will disappear, and strife will be 
 at an end. 
 
THESIS XII 
 
 INTEREST 
 
 Jouin, 154-160; Bickahy, 255-263. 
 
 Loan is regularly a gratuitous contract, whether loan for 
 consumption or loan for use. Thus, when a person borrows 
 a loaf of bread to eat it, he is obliged to return to the lender 
 only another loaf of bread of the same quantity and quality. 
 When a person borrows a book to read it, he is obliged to 
 return only the book. In olden times, because money was 
 borrowed only for the purpose of purchasing food and the 
 like, things consumed in their use, without producing new 
 wealth, money-lending was a purely gratuitous contract, and 
 all interest ii^as rightly considered usury or extortion from 
 the poor. Hence, St. Thomas and all Church writers up to 
 his time are violently opposed to the interest, considered per- 
 fectly legitimate in present economic circumstances. 
 
 All the difference is due to the different uses of money in 
 their times and ours. With them money was reckoned a good 
 consumed in its use, a good productive of no new wealth. 
 With us, money is a good not consumed in its use, a good 
 decidedly productive of new and greater wealth, when com- 
 bined with human endeavor. Capital was of no practical use 
 in olden times, to-day it is one of the chief factors in business 
 of whatever sort. Money-lending has passed from loan to 
 letting-for-hire in the catalogue of contracts, from gratuitous 
 to onerous, and all because of different economic conditions. 
 People now rent money to another, as they rent a house ; and 
 they have a perfect right to any just rate of interest they 
 demand. And yet the frauds and thefts, perpetrated in mod- 
 ern times under cover of interest, almost persuade one to 
 think that the world was certainly more honest, even if worse 
 off materially, when all interest was condemned as usury, and 
 
 144 
 
INTEREST AND CHURCH 145 
 
 injustice and extortion ; and, in the esteem of religious minds, 
 growth in material prosperity is small recompense for moral 
 degeneracy. 
 
 To make interest universally legitimate, there must be a 
 something in money, that makes use of it by lender or bor- 
 rower profitable, or productive of ulterior wealth. In other 
 words, money must be fruitful, not barren ; it must resemble 
 a field ready for planting, not a loaf of bread ready for a 
 hungry man. The money-lender must have a title to the 
 interest he claims, and that title must somehow or other be 
 intrinsic to the money itself. A title extrinsic to the money, 
 might suffice to justify interest in the event of some agree- 
 ment between lender and borrower; but nothing short of a 
 title intrinsic in some way to the money, can justify interest 
 in the event of no agreement whatever ; and we contend that 
 money loaned demands interest to-day of its very nature. 
 
 Four extrinsic titles justified interest, even when the Church 
 was loudest in its condemnation of the practice ; and they were, 
 1, loss of opportunity to make money incurred by the loan, 
 or interruption of profit, lucrum cessans; 2, damnum emerg- 
 ens; unusual risk; 3, penalty for delay in payment; 4, legal 
 reward meant for incentive to business. The Church always 
 recognized the legitimacy of these several titles. Besides, peo- 
 ple of great wealth could buy the right to farm revenues, and 
 they could enter partnership, wherein without personal labor 
 their money could earn an increment. It must be remarked 
 that these several titles are extrinsic to the money loaned, and 
 never created a right to compensation without prior agree- 
 ment. 
 
 Hence, the Church regularly and consistently considered 
 interest wrong, and branded all interest usury. It defined 
 usury as any attempt to draw profit and increment without 
 labor, without cost, and without risk, out of the use of a thing 
 that does not fructify. It forbade a man to lend his horse 
 to a neighbor as a gratuitous gift, and then without any warn- 
 ing charge him for the use of it, changing a purely gratuitous 
 contract into an onerous contract. Men of early times saw 
 only one value in money, its substantial value; and interest 
 was something in excess of that value. They saw no fruitful- 
 ness in money, it was Shakespeare's "barren breed of metal" ; 
 
146 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 and to charge extra for fruitfulness, it was on all sides con- 
 ceded not to have, was robbery, injustice, extortion. 
 
 To-day all is changed. Commerce is so easy and extensive, 
 remote regions are so close together because of steam and 
 electricity, communication is so rapid because of telegraph 
 and telephone, that for purposes of business the whole world 
 is no larger than a single trading block in any city; and 
 money has uses it never before enjoyed. Money is become a 
 species of seed, a dollar judiciously planted can grow a thou- 
 sand; and the seed-dealer is justified in charging one price 
 and another for different varieties of seed, not precisely be- 
 cause of their substance, but because of the flowers or fruits 
 they produce. And whereas in olden times the only legiti- 
 mate titles to interest were extrinsic to the money itself, the 
 four enumerated and explained awhile ago, to-day the title 
 to interest is intrinsic to the money itself; not, indeed, simply 
 and without any qualification intrinsic, hut after a manner 
 and with a qualification, accruing to money from modern 
 methods of business. This kind of intrinsic title partakes of 
 the nature of extrinsic and intrinsic titles. It is extrinsic, 
 inasmuch as it is not rooted in the nature of money itself, 
 independent of all circumstances. It is intrinsic, inasmuch 
 as it attaches to money in fixed economic conditions like our 
 own. 
 
 Therefore, the right to interest is not dependent on any 
 civil law, but on the nature of things. For the common good, 
 law can regulate rates of interest, it has no jurisdiction over 
 the legitimacy or the illegitimacy of interest. Laws regulat- 
 ing interest may be just or unjust, and the state framing such 
 laws must consult the objective order of things. In general, 
 a fair rate of interest would be that portion of the profit, 
 made by the borrower, left after deducting a fair recompense 
 for his skill, labor and industry ; and, in the main, that is the 
 ratio just laws everywhere try to determine. Law cannot 
 make wrong right, and plainly exorbitant rates, though sanc- 
 tioned by law, continue offenses against justice. And yet, 
 because, in the matter of justice, the presumption is always 
 in favor of law, nobody need as a rule be disturbed, when he 
 keeps within the limits of the law. 
 
 Money itself is only a medium of exchange, a standard or 
 
INTEREST AND CHURCH 147 
 
 measure of value. When business was small, all trade was 
 simply an exchange of one article for another, and the trans- 
 action was called barter. As business grew, some set article 
 was chosen as a general medium; and it became a standard, 
 a unit for the measurement of value resident in other articles. 
 A sheep could be made the standard ; and horses, cows, houses, 
 everything could be valued in terms of sheep. After cen- 
 turies of experience the world seems to have settled on the 
 precious metals, gold and silver, as money or media of ex- 
 change. Animals, shells, skins, wheat, tobacco, and a multi- 
 tude of other objects have been employed in history as money; 
 but all have yielded place to silver and gold, or to paper, 
 entitling its owner to a definite quantity of silver and gold, 
 when presented to proper authorities. Gold and silver were 
 chosen because of becoming qualities they possess. They are 
 durable, and wear well ; their scarcity adds to their intrinsic 
 value, and gives greater worth to small portions ; they can be 
 carried with ease from place to place ; they are readily di- 
 vided, measured and shaped ; they are homogeneous through- 
 out, and the Same the world over. Coinage, reserved to the 
 ruler, secures citizens, regarding the genuine quality of the 
 realm's money. 
 
 Money, therefore, has a twofold value, material and formal, 
 or moral. Its material value is its use in the arts and the 
 trades. Gold and silver dollars can be turned into jewelery 
 and the like. Its formal or moral value is its use as a me- 
 dium of exchange, its purchasing power. In olden times 
 money's purchasing power was restricted to things consumed 
 in their use ; when loaned, it was lent to purchase things of 
 the kind; and so money never rose to the dignity of a fruit- 
 ful good, productive of new wealth in its use. To-day money 
 purchases things not consumed in their use, things productive 
 of new wealth; and money, assuming the quality of what it 
 can purchase, becomes by the very fact a fruitful good. In 
 consequence, whoever lends money to another, has a right to 
 the profit he might have earned with his money, while it 
 remained with the borrower; and all this, not by virtue of 
 any agreement, but in virtue of the change made in money 
 by modern conditions. In other words, money is now an 
 instrument of business and trade, and it demands a price, 
 
148 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 mucli as the store you rent to another, or the machine hired 
 to manufacture some product. Money, therefore, is a fruit- 
 ful good, because it stands for all purchasable commodities; 
 and the loan of a fruitful good, in strict justice demands more 
 than the mere return of the good, it demands a return of 
 the fruit as well. Ballerini thinks that custom made interest 
 illicit in olden times, because he reckoned it impossible to 
 prove that anything in the nature of money forbids such 
 recompense for its use. But St. Thomas and the others regu- 
 larly appeal to the very nature of money, viewed as a thing 
 consumed in its use. Others favor leaving everything to the 
 intention of the borrower. They would consider interest 
 wrong, in case the borrower meant to purchase food and the 
 like; right, in case he meant to trade with it for purposes 
 of profit. Charity might recognize a difference between the 
 two cases, not justice. The two are onerous contracts. 
 
THESIS XIII 
 
 MERIT AND DEMERIT 
 
 Jcmin, 21-23; Bickahy, 152. 
 
 Merit and demerit are fruits of morality. A man can 
 merit with God and with other men. He can so behave to- 
 wards God and men as to deserve in justice reward at their 
 hands. Merit and demerit result from imputability, that 
 quality which makes man the cause and proprietor of his acts. 
 Only rational beings are capable of merit and demerit, be- 
 cause freedom is a requisite. Imputability implies ownership, 
 and freedom alone vests man with ownership in his acts. 
 Necessary agents are not owners. Merit means right to pay- 
 ment for favor done another, it means reward. Demerit 
 means right or liahility to payment for harm done another, 
 it means punishment or penalty. Justice is the measure of 
 merit and demerit. They even up justice, when the balance 
 swings one side. Justice is the virtue that renders to every- 
 body his due. It is of three kinds, commutative, man to 
 man ; distributive, state to citizen ; legal, citizen to state, cor- 
 porately and individually. Commutative demands strict or 
 arithmetical equality between favor and reward. Distribu- 
 tive demands geometrical equality between favor and reward. 
 Ordinarily a fair distribution of emoluments and burdens 
 satisfies its claims. Legal regularly demands arithmetical 
 equality, and is secured by law. Equity is a merciful provi- 
 sion meant to he corrective of justice. It has application, 
 tvhere reward is due, not in strict justice, hut from a view- 
 point of fairness and honor. It ministers to the incomplete- 
 ness of legal justice. Commutative gets its name from the 
 process of exchange, at the basis of business transactions, like 
 trading, and buying, and selling. In this species of justice 
 arithmetical equality, or that of 5 to 5, is possible, because 
 
 149 
 
150 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 both favor and reward are things, money, for instance, and a 
 horse. Distributive gets its name from the distribution in 
 play, when offices in a government are parcelled out to de- 
 serving citizens. In this species, geometrical equality, or 
 that of 6 and 4 to 3 and 2, is alone possible; because, while 
 the favor is, as it were, a person, the reward is a thing. If 
 a citizen doing 6 points of service gets an office worth 4, a 
 citizen doing 3 points of service ought to get and office worth 
 2. Legal justice in point of equality resembles commutative, 
 differing merely in origin. Physical violence does away with 
 merit and demerit, because it destroys freedom of execution; 
 but the moral violence duty or obligation exerts, because it 
 leaves even the ordered act voluntary, has no destroying in- 
 fluence on merit or demerit. Duty or obligation removes the 
 element of supererogation. 
 
 God can be said to owe things to Himself and creatures. 
 He owes it to Himself to see to the fulfilment of His wisdom, 
 will, and goodness in creatures. He owes creatures equip- 
 ment with requisites to their nature. This second debt is 
 rooted in the first, and so God is under obligation to nobody 
 but Himself. God is just to the wicked, when He punishes 
 the wicked, because it is what the wicked deserve. He is just 
 to Himself, when He spares the wicked, because mercy is 
 what He owes His own goodness. 
 
 Merit is of two kinds, de condigno and de congruo. One is 
 based on strict justice, the other on equity. Harmony or dis- 
 cord with the objective order of things makes an act good or 
 bad. Imputability has its origin in freedom of will, and 
 makes an act blamable or praiseworthy. Justice measures an 
 act's merit or demerit. To merit with men, the favor done 
 must not be payment for antecedent debt, and it must be -a 
 favor asked or desired, or reasonably supposed such. 
 
 Man can merit with God and other men, because he can 
 freely do them a favor. The favor changes the prior condi- 
 tion of justice, and calls for recompense to reestablish justice. 
 Man's merit with God is not absolute, but conditional; and 
 God has put the condition. Man owes everything to God, 
 without right to any return. And yet, in making man free, 
 God changes the aspect of things, and agrees to consider a 
 favor, what is in reality a debt. This gift of free will is a 
 
MERIT AND DEMERIT 151 
 
 virtual promise on the part of God to reward its right use, 
 and punish its abuse, 
 
 God is incapable of intrinsic addition; but man can do God 
 a kindness, by adding to His extrinsic glory; and virtue se- 
 cures this addition. Man is at the same time a servant and 
 a son of God. He merits with God as a son, and as a serv- 
 ant ; supernatural reward as a son, natural reward as a serv- 
 ant. God is first cause of a man's free will, as He is first 
 cause of every effect in the universe. But man is second 
 cause of His free acts, in such manner that he contributes of 
 his own to their reality, and exerts his own independent activ- 
 ity. Man in God's hands is no mere passive instrument, but 
 active as well. God's promise, makes man's merit de con- 
 digno. In the supernatural order this promise is writ in 
 revelation ; in the natural order, on the open page of creation. 
 The discrepancy between man's acts and a supernatural re- 
 ward, is atoned for by the addition of sanctifying grace. 
 That quality renders them supernatural, and enables them to 
 merit de condigno supernatural recompense, or Heaven. 
 
THESIS XIV 
 
 Utilitarianism is wrong, dangerous and absurd. Jouin, 31 j 
 Rickahy, 177-191. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Utilitarianism is a standard of morality, set up by men 
 who want to keep God and a future life out of the question. 
 They ignore immortality, and with it the spiritual side of 
 man's nature. They ?ire not everywhere consistent in their 
 views ; and, when trapped by their own words into some dam- 
 aging admission, never hesitate to seek a refuge in self-contra- 
 diction. William Paley, 1743-1805 ; Jeremy Bentham, 1748- 
 1832 ; James Mill, 1773-1836 ; John Stuart Mill, his son, 1806- 
 1873; John Austin, 1790-1859; and George Grote belong to 
 this school. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Utilitarianism. Its creed is formulated in two principles 
 and a law. First Principle : Man 's last end lies in this world, 
 and is the greatest happiness of the greatest number, mean- 
 ing pleasure as well of the senses as of the understanding. 
 N.B. Cudworth, Butler, Paley, and others, notably older 
 Utilitarians, mention God and a future life with respect. 
 John Stuart Mill and moderns in general resent all reference 
 to God and a future life. 
 
 Second Principle: Useful acts are right, hurtful acts are 
 wrong. Acts are useful, when they result in pleasure; hurt- 
 ful, when they result in pain. Law: General results must 
 be taken into account, not particular; not the immediate re- 
 sult of this particular act, but what would result to society, 
 if this sort of act were generally allowed. 
 
 This last is what Paley calls the Law of General Conse- 
 
 152 
 
UTILITARIANISM 158 
 
 quences. It hits near our standard of morality, the objective 
 order of things; and we have no quarrel with it. But we 
 have a very serious quarrel with the Principle of Greatest 
 Happiness, and the Principle of Utility. We have already 
 proved that man 's absolutely last end, his greatest happiness, 
 lies outside of this world, and is God, intuitively possessed. 
 We have besides proved that his greatest happiness on earth, 
 his relatively last end, is the introduction of moral rectitude 
 into his acts ; and that moral right and wrong are constituted 
 by harmony or discord with the objective order of things. 
 Our three theses are a direct refutation of Utilitarianism. 
 
 If somebody wants to believe in the reality of a future life, 
 the Utilitarians assure him that their doctrine menaces no 
 harm to his aspirations. They are quite accommodating. 
 * ' Take care of the things of earth, ' ' they say, ' ' and the things 
 of Heaven will take care of themselves." Christ taught the 
 contrary, when He called the cares, and riches, and pleasures 
 of life thorns that choke the seed and hinder it of fruit. Our 
 friends meet this difficulty with a new distinction between 
 Hedonism, pleasure for me, and Altruism, pleasure for the 
 other fellow. These thorns of the gospel are the pleasures of 
 Hedonism, not the pleasures of Altruism. Altruism then is 
 their last end. To meet Utilitarianism on common ground, 
 we must for the time being neglect the future life, and dis- 
 cuss with them man's highest good in this present life. We 
 maintain that man's highest good in this life is the establish- 
 ment of moral rectitude in his acts, calling the condition in- 
 complete happiness, because, in life's sum of good and evil, 
 moral rectitude procures the preponderance of good over 
 evil. They maintain that man's highest good in life consists 
 in the greatest happiness of the greatest number of mankind, 
 and they seem to mean by happiness pleasure as well of the 
 senses as of the understanding, physical as well as intellectual. 
 It must be evident that we both agree in making happiness 
 of some kind man's supremest good; and, if we contend for 
 exactly the same kind of happiness, we are fools to quarrel. 
 Our happiness is virtue, it is compatible with pain; it rates 
 one unit of intellectual pleasure superior to many units of 
 physical pleasure; it counts the intensest physical pain man 
 can suffer, death amid the cruellest torments, martyrdom at 
 
154 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 the hands of Nero, less an evil than the slightest departure 
 from the straight line of morality. 
 
 Of course, an ideal conception of incomplete happiness even 
 in our theory would be a blessed aggregate of unvarying vir- 
 tue, pleasure of body, and pleasure of soul, without the small- 
 est trace of pain anywhere in the mixture. It would mean 
 holiness fit for the altars, along with the money of a million- 
 aire ; the wisdom of the most consummate sage history knows ; 
 a mind free from business cares, a heart free from the aches 
 of love; a body without the ills of disease, a soul without a 
 sorrow ; nights of refreshing sleep, days of uninterrupted ease, 
 luxury and exhilarating enjoyment. But we are not the 
 fools to think any such ideal condition possible since the fall. 
 Apart even from the teachings of faith, we know that, ages 
 before the parable of the seed and the sower, pagans like 
 Diogenes and Zeno, Socrates and Plato, in the full light of 
 reason, regarded the riches and pleasures of this life thorns 
 in the field of virtue. Before the ominous words, ''Go sell 
 what thou hast, and give it to the poor," sounded on human 
 ears, mere philosophers had buried their wealth in the sea, as 
 a preliminary to the acquisition of virtue and wisdom. We 
 must be content with the world as it is, we must be practical 
 even in our Ethics, and write down man's highest good a 
 species of happiness possible of attainment. This happiness 
 is necessarily limited, it is incomplete, and we have reason to 
 be thankful for the circumstance. It whets desire for the 
 beyond, holds us to duty, and makes us stronger than un- 
 avoidable pain, that might otherwise overwhelm us with dread. 
 
 Happiness with Utilitarians would seem to be sometimes 
 Hedonism, sometimes Altruism; pleasure for me, and pleas- 
 ure for the other fellow. We repeat again, that if we mis- 
 interpret their writings, we honestly mean no wrong, and 
 stand ready to make them due reparation for our mistake. 
 If their greatest possible happiness of the greatest possible 
 number is virtue, or moral rectitude in man's acts, the fight 
 is over, and we are everlasting friends. If, on the contrary, 
 it is either the Hedonism of Epicurus or the Altruism of mod- 
 ern atheists and materialists, the fight is on, and we are 
 deadly enemies. Mill would seem to make it Hedonism, when 
 he says that acts are right in proportion as they tend to pro- 
 
HAPPINESS 155 
 
 mote happiness, meaning by happiness pleasure and the ab- 
 sence of pain. This doctrine makes good and pleasure iden- 
 tical, accounting the most pleasant pleasure the best pleasure. 
 Paley very logically accepts this view of the thing, and main- 
 tains that pleasures ^differ only in duration or intensity, not 
 in kind. With him pleasure of sense can surpass pleasure 
 of mind. We maintain, on the contrary, that pleasures differ 
 in quality as well as in quantity; that pleasure is not iden- 
 tical with good, but one of its three kinds or species; and 
 that intellectual delight is a better pleasure than sensual, not 
 because it is the more pleasant or lasting, but because it is 
 nobler. 
 
 Good IS of three sorts, becoming, agreeable and useful; 
 honestum, dulce et utile. Becoming good appeals to what 
 is specific in man's nature, his intellect; the agreeable is 
 oftener than not a loud cry to what is generic in man, his 
 animality; the useful is a mere help to the other two. The 
 becoming is loved for itself singly; the agreeable, for the 
 pleasure it creates; the useful, for an ulterior advantage 
 altogether distinct from itself. Good itself is an analogical 
 term; and, arguing from the word perfect, it means, in root, 
 finish, completeness. That is man's good, which finishes, 
 rounds out, completes his being. Primarily, therefore, good 
 signifies the becoming; secondarily, and by analogy of attri- 
 bution, the agreeable; secondarily still, but by analogy of 
 proportion, the useful. Becoming good is loved on its own 
 single account, not because of some third reality its posses- 
 sion secures. Agreeable good is not loved on its own single 
 account, but on account of a third reality its possession se- 
 cures, the satisfied feeling it induces. Useful good would 
 never be missed, if only the advantage it helps to procure 
 could be obtained without its assistance. Examples are knowl- 
 edge, a banquet, and money. Real good is suited to the de- 
 sires most in harmony with the nature that seeks it. What- 
 ever good is opposed to real good is called apparent good. 
 Man's real good is intellectual and spiritual, and, therefore, 
 the becoming. When the agreeable and useful are directly 
 opposed to the becoming, they are only apparent goods. 
 Whatever real goodness they possess, is derived from the 
 becoming, and dependent on the degree in which they meas- 
 
156 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 ure up to the same. An apparent good is a real evil. Nearly 
 every good in nature is a mixture of the three, and it is one 
 or other according to the light in which it is viewed. Thus, 
 knowledge is in itself a becoming good. And yet, because of 
 the pleasure it ministers, and because of the opportunities it 
 affords for honor and wealth, it can readily enough descend 
 to the level of an agreeable or useful good. A banquet is a 
 becoming good, inasmuch as it is quite in harmony with 
 man's rational nature; it is an agreeable good, inasmuch as 
 it procures bodily pleasure; it is a useful good, inasmuch as 
 it wins for the host the favor of his guests. Between agree- 
 able and useful good the distinction is clear and marked. 
 It is not so easy to discern between the becoming and the 
 agreeable. Pain can never be reckoned agreeable good ; it can 
 be reckoned becoming good. 
 
 Pleasure and Pain. Therefore, these few words about 
 .pleasure may help us to better understand things. Feeling 
 cuts so important a figure in modern Psychology that writers 
 assign it a faculty of its own, distinct from the faculties of 
 knowledge and desire, denominated cognoscitive and appeti- 
 tive. Our English word feeling is fruitful in meaning. 
 Maher notes these four, outer sensations, pain or pleasure, 
 excitement, certainty without motives. Examples are, smooth 
 feeling of velvet, to feel hot or cold ; to feel hurt, sad, joyful ; 
 I have a feeling for you ; to feel that it will rain. Emotion 
 occurs often in second and third senses. Passion is intense 
 excitement; affection turns on likes and dislikes with persons 
 for objects; sentiment is emotion in abstract and highly 
 wrought characters, as opposed to practical men. On this 
 question of pleasure and pain rare old Aristotle wrote the 
 final word centuries ago. St. Thomas in this particular makes 
 the Stagirite his model, and voices his sentiments with hardly 
 ' a word of correction. Modern writers are true, only when 
 they keep close to these master-minds; and the measure of 
 their departure from Aristotle is the measure of their folly. 
 Plato is responsible for the opinion that all pleasure is nega- 
 tive and relative. It is negative, inasmuch as it is mere ab- 
 sence of pain. It is relative, inasmuch as it is transition from 
 state of pain to opposite condition. And some pleasures of 
 sense lend color to his theory. Thus, the joy of eating and 
 
PLEASURE AND PAIN 157 
 
 drinking would seem to be dependent on antecedent hunger 
 and thirst. Aristotle, however, calls attention to the fact 
 that pleasures without number betray no such dependence on 
 previous pain. He alleges for examples the delight attaching 
 to mathematics, agreeable sounds and smells, the pleasures 
 of memory, and hope, and imagination. He makes all the 
 reality of pleasure dependent on activity, calling it activity's 
 efflorescence or hloom, — ''nil sine magno Vita labore dedit 
 mortalibus. ' ' Each faculty in man has its own pleasure, de- 
 rivable from judicious exercise. Count the antecedent exer- 
 cise pain, and you have Plato's opinion of relativity. St. 
 Thomas remarks that nobody enjoys uninterrupted pleasure, 
 simply because the quality follows work. The faculty em- 
 ployed, and the object stimulating the faculty, gauge the in- 
 tensity of a pleasure ; and in point of duration it lasts as long 
 as faculty and stimulus are in harmonious relations, one fresh 
 and vigorous, the other fit and suitable. During early pe- 
 riods in the process, pleasure reacts to stimulate energy; but 
 by degrees fatigue results, to first lessen the feeling and 
 eventually close in pain. Hence the need of variety in this 
 business of pleasure. The faculty is dulled by use, and a 
 new stimulus must supplant the old, when fatigue ensues. 
 As faculties are specifically different, pleasures of intellect and 
 sense differ as much as the faculties themselves. Conflicting 
 pleasures neutralize each other, and the faculty in question 
 determines the moral rank of the pleasure. The nobler the 
 faculty, the nobler the pleasure. Pain is pleasure's oppo- 
 site, and eadem est ratio oppositorum. The nature of pain is 
 manifest from our description of pleasure. It can have its 
 origin in faculty or object. It accompanies excess or defect 
 of energy or exercise, and is regularly due to pressure of an 
 unfit or unsuited stimulus. These different characteristics 
 of pleasure and pain have been gathered by Maher into two 
 laws, — 1, Pleasure is healthy exercise or activity, pain is 
 excess or defect of same. 2, Pleasure grows up to a certain 
 limit, then it diminishes and becomes pain. Variety con- 
 tributes to pleasure, because the interval of change is a period 
 of rest, and gives the dulled activity an opportunity to recover 
 its sharpness. Accommodation can explain factitious pleas- 
 ures as well as insensibility to pain. From long use the fac- 
 
158 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 iilty of taste, for instance, loses its edge, and tobacco passes 
 from disagreeable to pleasant. Constant pain in much the 
 same way operates to diminish or quite destroy the discom- 
 fort. 
 
 We maintain against modern writers that pleasure and pain 
 call for no third faculty ^ distinct from man's cognoscitive and 
 appetitive powers. They are hut different aspects of cogni- 
 tion and desire. Touch and taste call for new faculties, dis- 
 tinct and different among themselves; not feeling. Feeling 
 is best described as the tone of a function. The function is 
 exercise of a cognoscitive or appetitive faculty ; the tone in case 
 of pleasure is spontaneous, healthy, harmonious exercise; in 
 case of pain, restrained, unhealthy, excessive exercise. The 
 theories about pleasure and pain are numerous, most of them 
 substantially the same as Aristotle 's ; and, as before remarked 
 regarding wrong theories, the measure of their departure from 
 Aristotle is the measure of their folly. Spinoza leans to 
 Plato 's notion of transition from pain. Kant makes pleasure 
 the promotion of life-processes; pain, the hindrance of life- 
 processes. Schopenhauer and the pessimists view pleasure 
 as escape from pain by filling a want. Descartes and Leib- 
 nitz make it consciousness of perfection possessed. Hamilton 
 calls pleasure the reflex of conscious activity; pain, the reflex 
 of overstrained or repressed exertion. Bain describes them as 
 increase and abatement of vital functions. Physiologists in 
 general view pleasure and pain as integration or disintegra- 
 tion of neural elements. Grant Allen makes pain a destruc- 
 tive act, or insufficient nutrition in sentient tissue. Spen- 
 cer calls pleasure organic equilibrium, or harmonious func- 
 tioning, or struggle for life. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 I. Principle of Greatest Happiness. 
 
 To return now to Utilitarianism. In its selection of man's 
 highest good, as already seen, it veers between Hedonism and 
 Altruism, pleasure for me, and pleasure for the other fellow. 
 Indeed some defenders of the theory try to combine the two. 
 But that is impossible. They are opposite poles. Hedonism 
 is gross selfishness, Altruism rates selfishness the unforgiven 
 
PROOFS 159 
 
 sin. Hedonifsm certainly cannot be man's highest good, be- 
 cause it is pleasure ; pleasure in turn is the effect, activity the 
 cause; and the cause is always superior to the effect. Activ- 
 ity, therefore, is a higher good than the pleasure it pro- 
 duces; and no pleasure, whatever its kind, can be man's high- 
 est good. Becoming good is sought for itself, and for noth- 
 ing beyond. Even knowledge, when sought for pleasure or 
 gain, becomes an agreeable or useful good. Man's highest 
 good, therefore, cannot he pleasure of whatever sort, whether 
 intellectual or sensual, because pleasure is at most an agree- 
 able good, and magi's highest good ought to he a becoming 
 good. Besides, pleasure is always an effect, and effects are 
 inferior to their causes. 
 
 PRINCIPLE 
 
 A. The end is superior to the means. Pleasure is the end, 
 activity is the means. Answer: This is in the order of inten- 
 tion, not in the order of being or reality. Redemption of 
 mankind is the end; the tears and the blood of God are the 
 means. Operis and operantis. Priority in order of being 
 or reality settles dignity. Reversed in two orders of inten- 
 tion and being. End first in intention, last in being. Means 
 last in intention, first in being. Ergo, activity is superior to 
 pleasure, as cause is superior to effect. 
 
 Therefore, knowledge, clear of the pleasure it occasions, 
 can alone be man's highest good. The pleasure may be in- 
 separable from the knowledge, but this is far from consti- 
 tuting the pleasure knowledge itself. God known is man's 
 absolutely highest good, and virtue is his relatively highest 
 good, his highest good in this life. Altruism cannot be man's 
 highest good, because, as understood by the Utilitarians, it 
 neglects two important factors in the makeup of virtue, self 
 and God. Again, if their Altruism means virtue, if it means 
 measuring up to the objective order of things, the exact pay- 
 ment of all our debts to the neighbor, self and God, we have 
 no quarrel with Utilitarianism, and we are Altruists as well 
 as they. But, whatever their real sentiments, the writings of 
 Utilitarians are proof conclusive that they ignore the interior 
 life of the soul, the inner man of the heart, and give human 
 
160 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 society, the neighbor, the place that belongs to God. They 
 mistake the political for the ethical end of life. They provide 
 for a good citizen, a good husband, a good father; but not 
 for a good man. They exaggerate a secondary concern, to 
 minimize or altogether nullify what ought to be man's pri- 
 mary concern and first consideration. Therefore, the Al- 
 truism of the Utilitarians is no more man 's highest good than 
 the Hedonism of Epicureans. It wears a more decent ap- 
 pearance, but there is more logic or common sense in Hedon- 
 ism than in Altruism. Both are vile errors, one from the 
 viewpoint of gentility, the other from the viewpoint of phi- 
 losophy; and only in the eyes of shallow thinkers are of- 
 fenses against gentility viler than offenses against philosophy. 
 Hedonism banishes God and the neighbor from morality, to 
 set up self for idol. Altruism does the same unkindness to 
 God and self, to fall down and worship the neighbor. And 
 there you are. 
 
 II. Principle of Utility. 
 
 The Principle of Utility, which makes acts right or wrong, 
 according as they are useful or hurtful to the greatest num- 
 ber, stands condemned on these four counts: 1, It makes no 
 difference between acts good and had in themselves, confound- 
 ing intrinsic value with extrinsic results; 2, affirms that the 
 motive has nothing to do with the morality of the action; 
 3, levels all distinction between injury and harm; 4, a7id 
 favors the theory confuted by Plato in his Republic, personal 
 indulgence at expense of neighbor. We already proved in 
 Thesis III, that an essential, intrinsic difference exists be- 
 tween right and wrong in the moral order. We argued from 
 example, alleging love and hatred of God as instances; and, 
 for every believer in God, the argument is conclusive. Un- 
 fortunately for them, the Utilitarians prefer to keep God out 
 of the question, and might logically take exception to our 
 method. Love of parents and a lie might, perhaps, prove 
 more acceptable examples; and they are equally well suited 
 to our purpose. Therefore, according to us a lie is essentially 
 and intrinsically bad, because of its very nature it is at odds 
 with the objective order of things, imperatively demanding 
 conformity of language with thought. A lie is radically 
 
PROOFS IW 
 
 wrong, because it is an abuse of language. It is wrong now, 
 it was always wrong, and will forever continue to be wrong, 
 even if God could wish otherwise, even if the whole world 
 entered into a conspiracy to call it right. Love of parents is 
 in precisely the same way an act intrinsically and essentially 
 right. With Utilitarians a lie would be wrong, simply be- 
 cause of its consequences or effects; love of parents would be 
 right for the same reason; and the Law of General Conse- 
 quences, they think, makes their position impregnable. They 
 would contend that lying and hatred of parents, if universally 
 allowed, would work harm to society; and they are not far 
 wrong in their contention. A bad act always breeds bad 
 consequences, and in most cases this secondary norm of util- 
 ity coincides with our own. As a rule. Utilitarians would 
 scruple calling right whatever acts we call wrong, and theo- 
 retically their standard is not blameworthy. But in practice 
 it is open to flagrant abuse, and it is responsible for much of 
 the evil now prevalent in society. Its advocates easily lose 
 sight of the Law of General Consequences, and measure the 
 quality of their acts hy the advantage or disadvantage accru- 
 ing to themselves personally. If he is a Hedonist, the Utili- 
 tarian can see nothing but advantage in a lie, that procures 
 him thousands of dollars to purchase the luxuries of life. If 
 he is an Altruist and a diplomat, the Utilitarian can see noth- 
 ing but advantage in a lie, that would save an entire com- 
 munity from the disasters of war. The temptation, then, is 
 to think a lie right on occasions, and account so-called pru- 
 dential departures from the truth no breach of morality. 
 How often men yield to the temptation, every-day history is 
 witness. Individualism is the rich man's creed, Utilitarian- 
 ism is the hasis of his ethics; and the had philosophyy taught in 
 our present day universities strengthens him in his position 
 of greed and injustice. Less conscientious Utilitarians teach, 
 and avaricious misers among their followers ardently hold, 
 that acts are morally right, when they tend to the doer's 
 profit ; and virtue comes to mean the accumulation of wealth 
 by fair means and foul. If Utilitarianism were not wrong 
 in itself, abuse of its principles is easy, and this abuse is most 
 damaging in its consequences. 
 
 2. We have alsewhere shown motive to be one of morality's 
 
162 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 determinants. Motive is the act in its subjective aspect, and 
 its morality is quite as important as that of the object itself. 
 We are agreed that no individual human act is indifferent, 
 though in the abstract many such acts occur to mind, like 
 walking, singing, study. Acts of the kind derive all their 
 morality from the motive prompting their execution. To walk 
 to the church for purposes of prayer, is right; to make the 
 same journey for purposes of theft, is wrong; and all the 
 difference is constituted by the walker's motive. Motive 
 makes one man a worshipper, the other a thief. And we are 
 not talking about the act of prayer or the theft ; we are talk- 
 ing of the journey itself. The journey made by the pros- 
 pective thief is as morally wrong as the theft he afterwards 
 commits. This truth is even more evident in the case of a 
 good act, done with an evil design. To give alms for the 
 express purpose of making the beggar accomplice to a mur- 
 der, is out and out bad. No matter how useful the gift may 
 prove to the beggar, the act of the giver is thoroughl}'- wicked ; 
 and what would be otherwise virtuous charity, is changed by 
 mere motive to downright murder. This example slightly 
 changed proves Utilitarianism immoral. Suppose the alms 
 given without any wrong intention ; later on, the beggar finds 
 his benefactor engaged in murder, and out of gratitude goes 
 to his assistance. The alms would have bad results and 
 would therefore be wicked, an opinion altogether against 
 common-sense. Our kindness would, then, depend on how 
 people used it. I am aware that a man's motive, when once 
 conceived and embraced, becomes part and parcel of his act, 
 because the motive is the man. I am aware that honest Utili- 
 tarians' would never reckon right, alms bestowed for so un- 
 holy a purpose; and all because conduct of the sort, if uni- 
 versally tolerated, would prove damaging in the extreme. 
 And yet they are highly unphilosophical, when they brand 
 such alms wrong, simply because of consequences or inde- 
 pendently of motive. The fact of the matter is that the act 
 in question is damaging in its consequences, because it is 
 morally wrong, and not vice-versa. Causes never follow their 
 effects; and the act is not, first damaging in its consequences, 
 and then morally wrong; but it is first morally wrong, and 
 then damaging in its consequences. The horse pulls the 
 
PROOFS 163 
 
 wagon; not the wagon, the horse. Scripture is of small 
 weight with the average Utilitarian ; and yet he may, in com- 
 mon with respectable unbelievers, have a measure of reverence 
 for Christ's wisdom. Motive in His divine eyes makes a su- 
 preme difference between acts; and the first half of St. Mat- 
 thew's sixth chapter contains His doctrine on the subject. 
 We commend His words to the careful and reverent perusal 
 of searchers for the truth. The acts discussed are alms, 
 prayer and fasting. 
 
 3. If use and harm are the measures of morality, all differ- 
 ence between mere harm and injury disappears ; and balanced 
 minds are not ready to accept this view of things. Injury 
 adds wilfulness and malice to mere harm, which oftener than 
 not is wholly without the stigma of moral hlame. The pedes- 
 trian, who tramples your watch to pieces on the dark street, 
 works you a lot of harm, but no injury. The enemy, who 
 deliberately and knowingly smashes the same with an axe, 
 over and above the harm he works, does you a downright in- 
 jury. In both cases the harm is practically the same; while 
 injury is absent from one case, present to the other. Even 
 if all men without a single exception were allowed to repeat 
 the act of the innocent pedestrian, it could never become 
 morally wrong, in spite of the harm consequent on its occur- 
 rence. And yet the harm done would prove as much a hard- 
 ship to the watch's owner as the injury done him by his 
 enemy. The effects of the harm and the injury are the same, 
 the moral difference between the two is due to the agent's 
 purpose, motive, intention. 
 
 4. Plato in his Republic confutes a theory of morals, that 
 would seem to coincide in all respects with Utilitarianism. 
 Briefly, it stands for the contention that a man's highest good 
 in this life is his own personal indulgence, at the expense 
 of his neighbors. Society, to keep down fighting and save 
 the race from suicide, hampers this inclination, and blocks 
 each individual citizen's aspirations for his own highest 
 good. It forces him to forego the natural right he has to 
 prosecute his own happiness, at the expense of his neighbors. 
 In this way the interest of society is opposed to the interests 
 of the individual, and life in a state is a real curse and only 
 a makeshift blessing. Tyrants alone, in this theory, compass 
 
164 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 highest good; their subjects, through no fault of their own, 
 are hopelessly unable to realize their destinj^ in this life, that 
 natural desire all men have to enjoy incomplete happiness, the 
 preponderance of good things over evil things. And all be- 
 cause these shortsighted mortals, in common with the Utili- 
 tarians, establish man's highest good in pleasure or advan- 
 tage, his supremest evil in pain or hurt. 
 
 Our theory makes moral rectitude or virtue man's highest 
 good, and no tyrant can effectively keep his subjects from 
 the attainment of this result in their lives. Again, it would 
 be foully wrong to suppose that Christ or the early martyrs 
 failed of man's highest good; and their entire lives were 
 empty of what a Utilitarian world calls happiness or pleas- 
 ure, and were crowded full of misery and pain. They com- 
 passed supremest good or incomplete happiness, simply be- 
 cause what the world calls happiness or pleasure cuts no 
 figure whatever in the thing, and one unit of virtue out- 
 weighs units without number of mere physical pain or men- 
 tal distress. Virtue is no artificial happiness, it is happiness 
 of the solidest sort; and the pain endured for virtue's sake 
 never loses its quality of bitterness. Saints never come to 
 directly like self-denial, they like it only in an indirect way, 
 inasmuch as it secures to them that virtue or holiness, which 
 is the basis and foundation of man's supremest good on 
 earth. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Stoic Formalism. Stoic Formalism is from Kant, and 
 Kant's system of Ethics is a profound mistake. The whole 
 trouble with Kant would seem to be that he has hazy no- 
 tions about God, and denies Him the quality of lawgiver. 
 And all this in spite of an utterance on page 322, to this 
 effect, ''Conscience must be conceived as the subjective prin- 
 ciple of a responsibility for one's deeds before God." Abbott. 
 He recognizes only two lawmakers, self and the state. Self 
 is responsible for ethical law; the state, for juridical law. 
 Hence his autonomy of reason in matter of ethical law. Rea- 
 son is self, reason makes law, defines and imposes duty, sits 
 in judgment, rewards virtue, punishes offenders in the domain 
 of Ethics or internal morality. The state performs exactly 
 
KANT AND ETHICAL DUTY 165 
 
 the same functions in the domain of Nomology, Jurisprudence 
 or external morality. God occurs nowhere, no doubt because 
 He is a noumenon. Natural law with Kant is not divine law 
 at all, it is as much human law as civil law itself, the only 
 difference between the two being that the man makes natural 
 law for himself, the state sets him civil law. In the field of 
 internal morality, in the matter of acts not prescribed by 
 positive law, in question of commands issued by what we 
 persist in calling the natural law, man, according to Kant, 
 is subject to no outside constraint ; he has no Heaven to hope 
 for, no hell to fear. In the field of external morality, in mat- 
 ters provided for by the statutes, in question of murder, eft 
 and other penal offenses enumerated in the code, man is sub- 
 ject to constraint of the state, and enjoys the favor of pos- 
 sible fine or imprisonment as a deterrent from crime. 
 
 With Kant, natural law ought to fare worse at men^s hands 
 than positive law. When a man makes a law for himself, he 
 can as easily neglect it ; when a man is judge and jury in his 
 own case, he is seldom convicted; when he executes law on 
 himself, he gets off with a light sentence. When the state 
 exercises these several prerogatives, the culprit is more likely 
 to get his deserts ; and this single thought would make positive 
 law surer of fulfilment than natural law. God would neglect 
 in the enforcement of His law a most efficacious help, em- 
 ployed by men in the enforcement of their laws. Ethical 
 duty with Kant is self-imposed constraint; juridical duty is 
 constraint imposed by positive law and its author, the state. 
 Self-imposed constraint is no constraint at all; and ethical 
 duty, to have any force, must be constraint imposed by the 
 natural law and its author, God. Therefore, to act from a 
 sense of ethical duty, is to act with an eye to God's attitude 
 towards right and wrong, as well as with an eye to our own 
 attitude towards the same; and Kant's autonomy of reason, 
 and his principle about duty for duty's sake, are only half 
 the truth; and, what is still worse, they are that half of the 
 truth, which apppeals to only a select few in the republic of 
 refined minds and critically exact moral tastes. The sanction 
 of the natural law embodied in an eternal hell, is a much 
 more appealing incentive to virtue than Stoic Formalism or 
 subjective feelings of shame. Remorse of conscience means 
 
166 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 more than shame, it means dread of hell; and the sinner is 
 wide awake to the fact, that he has offended somebody dis- 
 tinct from and greater than himself. 
 
 Utilitarians contend that happiness, or pleasure of mind 
 and body, is man's destiny on earth, his supreme good, his 
 last end; and many contend that it is folly to look higher. 
 We already proved with irrefutable arguments that pleasure, 
 whether of mind or of body, cannot be man's last end, either 
 in this life or in the next. Stoic Formalism, a product of 
 Kant 's philosophy, is the opposite pole to Utilitarianism ; and 
 it contends that duty is man's destiny on earth, to such an 
 extent that it is the single motive able to make his acts moral ; 
 and that pleasure, or whatsoever other motive, renders them 
 unmoral. Duty for duty's sake, is its slogan, and it accounts 
 acts morally good, only when done from a sense of duty; 
 unmoral, when done for pleasure or from any motive save 
 sense of duty. Kant is responsible for the system, and it is 
 in line with his autonomy of reason, to be explained and re- 
 futed in our next thesis. 
 
 Against Utilitarianism and Stoic Formalism we contend 
 that man's absolutely last end, his destiny in the next life, 
 is complete happiness, the possession of God in the beatific 
 vision; that his relatively last end, his destiny on earth, is 
 incomplete happiness or virtue and resulting peace of con- 
 science. The happiness we contend for is not the pleasure of 
 Utilitarianism, nor is it the sense of duty advocated by Stoic 
 Formalism. Happiness, whether complete or incomplete, is 
 not pleasure of mind or body. Complete happiness is a heaped 
 up measure of good with unending duration, a measure of 
 good from which no particle of good is absent, altogether in- 
 compatible with pain and discomfort. Complete happiness 
 is a natural desire, the one necessary wish of every man's 
 heart, the hiding principle of every wish we conceive; and, 
 therefore, our happiness in this sense cannot be excluded ; 
 and, if Kant were right, all our acts would necessarily be un- 
 moral. Virtue is our destiny on earth, and therefore our 
 duty; and the peace of conscience resulting from virtue can- 
 not be excluded from our motive, and again all our acts would 
 be unmoral. The consciousness of duty done is only another 
 
STOIC FORMALISM 167 
 
 pleasure; and, before we do our duty, this pleasure in the 
 order of intention can move us to act, without any detriment 
 to morality. Whatever motive is compatible with virtue, be 
 it pleasure, or wealth, or honor, health, wisdom or charity, 
 can originate a morally good act; and there are virtuous as 
 well as vicious pleasures. 
 
 Arguments against Stoic Formalism 'by Father Cronin, pp. 
 245-263. 
 
 1. It demands too much of human nature. 
 
 2. It is not contained in the idea of moral good. 
 
 3. It is disproved by works of supererogation. 
 
 4. All moral acts would be equally moral. 
 
 5. Eadem est ratio oppositorum. If acts were good solely 
 on account of respect for law, acts would be bad solely on 
 account of disrespect for the law. No criminal ever acts from 
 disrespect for the law ; but from motives of gain, revenge and 
 the like. Ergo, no bad act. 
 
 6. There would be no room for merit. Every good act 
 would be owed. 
 
 7. Happiness is inseparable from moral acts ; and acts would 
 be unmoral, when done from motives of happiness. 
 
 8. Motive would be respect for law as such. Bad legisla- 
 tion is law as such, and bad legislation never bases moral act. 
 
 9. Law is meant for common good, as means to end. To 
 act not for common good, but for law, would be to make means 
 superior to end. 
 
 Arguments in Favor of Stoic Formalism are Fallacious. 
 
 1. It is the creed of the crowd. Morality is in the will, not 
 in the external act. 
 
 Answer: True, but the will gets its morality from object, 
 end, and circumstances ; pure selfishness does not of itself 
 vitiate act ; pleasure is good or bad according to object ; duty 
 is only one object of pleasure ; love of duty is as much a moral 
 principle as duty. 
 
 2. AH outer objects are mere means to pleasure. Ergo, no 
 proper motive. 
 
 Answer: The summum bonum is not a mere means to 
 pleasure, it is happiness itself. It is man's end, not a means 
 
168 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 to his end. It is an affair of the intellect, not of the will. 
 Law varies with the individual, the summum bonum or last 
 principle of morality is the same for all. 
 B. Hedonism.. Father Cronin discusses Hedonism between 
 pages 264 and 304. 
 
 Hedonism of whatever kind is wrong, when it makes pleas- 
 ure man 's last end. Egoistic Hedonism is Hedonism proper ; 
 Universal Hedonism is Altruism or Utilitarianism. Pleasure 
 for me, and pleasure for the other fellow. Some Hedonists: 
 Hohhes says that any object of desire is man's last end, and 
 this is Hedonism's most degraded type. Aristippus makes 
 mental pleasure man's last end. Mill makes higher pleas- 
 ures of mind man's last end; and this is a more refined 
 type. Cudworth makes pleasures of virtue man's last end; 
 and this is higher still. Butler makes pleasures awaiting men 
 in Heaven man 's last end ; and this is the highest of all. 
 
 Answer: Pleasure is not our sole natural end, because it 
 can be spurned aside. Happiness is our sole natural end, be- 
 cause it cannot be spurned aside. Pleasure is not man's last 
 end, because it resides in the will, as the passion of delight 
 resides in the appetite; and no act of the will can be man's 
 last end. 
 Five Arguments from St. Thomas, C.G.3. 26. 
 
 1. Happiness is man's last end, and happiness is not de- 
 light or r pleasure. Pleasure is an act of the will, object is 
 prior to act, and will's object is prior to will's pleasure. Ob- 
 ject is mover, pleasure is movement. Ergo, happiness cannot 
 be an act of the will, it cannot be pleasure. 
 
 2. Happiness is no act of the will, it is not pleasure. It 
 would he either a, desire; h, love; or c, delight, a, Not desire, 
 which tends towards something not yet gotten, b. Not love, 
 because love turns on absent as well as present good, c, Not 
 delight, because delight is the effect ; possession is the cause. 
 
 3. Happiness is not in act of the will, not in pleasure; be- 
 cause pleasure can be true or false, and ever the same with 
 respect to rest or quiescence on part of the will, e.g., a 
 drunken man and a philosopher. Real man and painted man 
 differ by constituents of substance, and intellect makes pleas- 
 ure true or false, not act of the will. 
 
 4. Delight is not desirable of itself, and, therefore, not 
 
STOIC FORMALISM 169 
 
 man's last end. Otherwise all delight would be desirable. 
 Pleasure is of indifferent ethical value, sometimes good, some- 
 times bad; some delight is desirable, other delight is to be 
 shunned. 
 
 5. Nature uses pleasure as means only. Ergo, not man's 
 last end. Right order coincides with order of nature, nature 
 orders things without mistake. Nature orders man as well 
 as animals. Delight is for activity, not the other way about, 
 e.g., use of food for preservation of individual. We eat to 
 live; we do not live to eat. Without delight animals would 
 not eat. Delight is the means, preservation the end. Pleas- 
 ures of marriage are for preservation of race. 
 
 P.S. Title of last end is assigned to activity, whereby ex- 
 terior thing is gained, e.g., act of getting the money is last 
 end, not desire or love of money. God is last end, activity 
 getting God is understanding. We cannot wish what we do 
 not understand. Ergo, happiness is act of the intellect, not 
 act of the will, not pleasure of whatever kind. 
 
THESIS XV 
 
 Ecmt's autonomy of reason is wrong. Russo, pp. 67-70. 
 
 The greatest of all goods in the moral order, because true 
 and absolute, is a good will. All other faculties are good in 
 the moral order, because of something they borrow from the 
 will. Morality is like freedom. It belongs primarily to the 
 will, and is passed along by the will to mind, senses, and all 
 else in the man. Mind in itself is a physical, not a moral 
 good. It is often an apparent good, and always a relative 
 good. It makes a good writer, a good philosopher, but not 
 a good man. Nobody deserves Heaven for proficiency in 
 mathematics pure and simple. Some of the greatest minds 
 history knows are buried in hell. No good will is buried 
 there, because good will means virtue, and virtue is passport 
 to the kingdom of God. Will is choice, and the best will, or 
 the best good, is the best chooser. In morality choice lies be- 
 tween obedience to law and disobedience; and the motive 
 prompting the choice has a decided bearing on its dignity and 
 worth. Respect for the law would seem to be the highest 
 conceivable motive; and therefore two factors conspire to 
 make a perfect will, obedience to law, with respect for the 
 law for single motive or reason why. Obedience and respect 
 are paid to persons, not to things; and, therefore, we might 
 better say, obedience to the lawmaker, and respect for the 
 same. Fear and hope are negatively imperfect motives as 
 compared with love. 
 
 Up to this point we are a unit with Kant. All the differ- 
 ence between us starts here, and it is rooted in the man's 
 stupid conception of the law in question, and of the relative 
 worth of motives urging to its observance. With him, the 
 law to be obeyed is his categorical imperative, "So act that, 
 if you had your way, your conduct would have to be made 
 universal standard for the race.'' His categorical imperative 
 
 170 
 
AUTONOMY AND HETBRONOMY 171 
 
 emanates from his own reason, his practical reason, his will, 
 without God or man at its back to urge its observance. It is 
 his own private affair, a matter of business between himself 
 and himself. If he follows orders, he does himself a kindness ; 
 if he breaks orders, he does himself an unkindness ; and that is 
 all. No created thing is capable of uttering a categorical im- 
 perative, an absolute and necessary imperative, because no 
 created thing is the absolute and necessary, and no effect can 
 surpass its cause. From relative and contingent beings like 
 creatures, and practical reason is a creature, no higher than 
 a relative and contingent imperative can issue. 
 
 And this is what we call Kant's autonomy or autocracy of 
 reason, the enthronement of self as supreme arbiter of every 
 man's destiny, the impudent usurpation by man of rights 
 vested in the Creator, a virtual declaration of man's inde- 
 pendence of everybody, God included, subservient to nobody 
 but himself, subject to only such laws as he makes for him- 
 self, accountable for his conduct to nobody but himself, his 
 own judge, his own jury, his own executioner. He gathers 
 the purely subjective nature of his categorical imperative, the 
 fact that all obligation in the man is due to a command he, 
 and he alone, imposes on himself, from the circumstance that 
 no other absolute and necessary command is conceivable. 
 Everything falling under the experience of our senses is rela- 
 tive and contingent, the categorical imperative, as an abso- 
 lute and necessary something, must have its origin in the 
 practical reason, considered in action, the one phenomenon 
 apart and distinct from sensile occurrences. He sees the 
 absurdity of attributing the qualities, absolute and necessary, 
 to any product of the practical reason; and, therefore, ac- 
 knovjledging his inability to prove the absolute and necessary 
 nature of his categorical imperative, he contends that these 
 two qualities of his categorical imperative are a postulate of 
 his system, and must be accepted without proof. 
 
 He could have easily avoided all trouble by introducing 
 God, the one absolute and necessary being in the universe, 
 and ascribing his categorical imperative not to practical rea- 
 son but to the natural law imposed on man by God, and 
 brought to man's notice by reason. But the poor man is 
 hounded everywhere by that ghost of his own making, nou- 
 
172 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 menaj spirits, thirigs in themselves, too far removed from the 
 senses to base certain knowledge, matter for empty conjecture, 
 sure in the event to propagate ignorance and superstition. 
 God is a noumenon, a pure spirit, beyond the reach of eye, 
 and ear, and all the senses, but quite within the reach of 
 reason, arguing from the reality of patent effects in the uni- 
 verse to the reality of their cause. Man's reason is for nou- 
 mena, as his senses are for phenomena; and if our knowledge 
 is restricted to phenomena, if we have no certain knowledge 
 of noumena, we are little better than brutes, and in many 
 respects their inferiors. 
 
 With practical reason for single origin of the categorical 
 imperative, reason is oMtonomous, its own lawmaker, and 
 every man is his own standard of morality. More than this, 
 every man manufactures his own moral obligations, imposes 
 on himself whatever duties he sees fit to impose, selecting some, 
 rejecting others, always with the proviso that he can reject 
 to-morrow what he selects to-day. In other words, he is 
 morally bound to the performance of this or that particular 
 act, simply because he holds himself to its performance, not 
 because any outside superior issues a command to that effect. 
 Kant stands for autonomy of will, as opposed to heteronomy. 
 We stand for heteronomy of the will, maintaining that God is 
 single author of moral obligation, that reason is the herald 
 God employs to make His wishes known, that the true cate- 
 gorical imperative is the natural law, which is divine legisla- 
 tion, not human, which is found indeed in man 's reason, with- 
 out being derived from it. We can all be found in the Wool- 
 worth Building Friday evening, but the Woolworth is no ex- 
 planation of our origin. The laws of New York can be found 
 in certain printed books, but the printer never made them. 
 Kant wants us to think that we impose obligations on our- 
 selves, simply because we wake up to the fact that we are 
 under obligations. The objective order of things, as set forth 
 in the natural law, arouses us to a sense of obligation, and 
 this objective order of things is the handiwork of God, as 
 well as the natural law embodying it. If man himself is 
 altogether responsible for Kant's categorical imperative, man 
 imposes this obligation on himself either with full freedom 
 or with strict necessity. If with full freedom, it ceases to 
 
AUTONOMY AND HETERONOMY 173 
 
 be real and true obligation ; if with strict necessity, something 
 distinct from the will forces its wishes on the will, and God 
 alone, as maker of the will, enjoys this prerogative. Kant's 
 imperative is a self-imposed command, one and the same per- 
 son is ruler and subject ; and a self-imposed command, because 
 open always to revocation at the will of the subject, carries 
 no binding authority. To save himself from open folly, Kant 
 makes the reason ruler, the will subject ; but reason and will 
 belong to the same man, and no two persons are present. 
 When a man binds himself hy agreement, or vow, the obliga- 
 tion arises not from the man himself, but from a precept of 
 the natural law, an ordinance of God holding rational crea- 
 tures to their promises. The obligation is independent of 
 man's will. He is free to make the agreement or not; but, 
 once the agreement is made, he is not free to assume the obli- 
 gation or not. He is free to put the condition or not; but, 
 with the condition once placed, the obligation follows, no 
 matter what he wishes. 
 
 Besides missing the true nature of the only categorical im- 
 perative worthy of the name, the natural law issuing as a 
 command from God to do good and avoid evil, Kant beauti- 
 fully mixes things in his discussion of motives and their 
 relative dignity. The motive of obedience is the reason why 
 the will obeys, and three possible motives for observance of 
 the natural law at once suggest themselves, respect for the 
 lawmaker, fear of penalty and hope of reward. All three mo- 
 tives are equally relative and contingent. The most perfect 
 motive of the three is respect for the lawmaker; but this is 
 far from rendering the other two positively imperfect or bad. 
 They are at most negatively imperfect, or less good. They 
 possess their own worth, they have their own goodness, though 
 it happens to be inferior to the goodness attaching to respect 
 for the lawmaker. The whole thing is like saying that im- 
 perfect love for God is inferior to perfect love for God, with- 
 out ever becoming hatred. Only a bad motive is a positively 
 imperfect motive. Negatively imperfect motives are good mo- 
 tives of varying degrees. A five-dollar-bill is always money, 
 though it is worth less than a hundred-dollar-bill. Only a 
 counterfeit is no money at all. And all three motives are com- 
 patible, not mutually destructive of one another. Nothing 
 
174 GENERAL ETHICS 
 
 prevents a man from keeping the law out of respect for the 
 lawmaker, from dread of penalty, and from hope of reward. 
 In fact, three motives are better than one, especially when 
 the one chosen is the weakest of the three; and man^s innate 
 selfishness will always make penalty and reward more effective 
 for good thari respect for the lawmaker. 
 
PART II 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 We have thus far dealt in speculation of a general nature, 
 without adverting much to individual emergencies in an indi- 
 vidual life. We have rather laid down rules, sure to find 
 application in every step taken with a bearing on morality. 
 Now we proceed to examine the obligations arising from rela- 
 tions involved in certain conditions and contingencies of life. 
 Man has dealings with God, with himself, and with his fellow- 
 men. He occupies a well defined position in the universe, and 
 his moral worth stands or falls with the attitude he adopts 
 in his every day acts towards God, towards himself, and to- 
 wards his neighbor. This threefold source of duty is common 
 to every man born into the world, and independent of every 
 later arrangement or added condition. It aifects the indi- 
 vidual as such. Nature, however, has besides constituted man 
 a social being. It has ordained that at his very birth he 
 belong to a family, and has made it quite impossible for him 
 to continue in existence without entering into certain amicable 
 relations with his fellows. Hence he finds himself by a very 
 necessity of nature constituted at once a member of civil so- 
 ciety or the state, as well as of domestic society or the family. 
 Besides, God the author of nature has in the person of Jesus 
 Christ established a third society, the Church, and has made 
 membership in it an inevitable duty. These three societies, 
 differing in scope and machinery, secure advantages and im- 
 pose in return corresponding burdens. Fathers, mothers, 
 brothers, sisters, children, rulers and subjects have set func- 
 tions to discharge, and rectitude consists in strict compliance 
 with their several duties. It therefore belongs to this part 
 of Moral Philosophy to put in as clear a light as possible 
 
 175 
 
176 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 man^s obligations as an individual to God, himself and his 
 neighbor, and man 's obligations as a social being to his family, 
 to his government and its citizens, und to the Church ap- 
 pointed of God. 
 
 Religion is the one word expressive of man's duty towards 
 God, and this religion includes worship of mind and body, 
 and steadfast belief in revelation, or the utterances of God. 
 Man is loyal to himself, when he makes good all the claims 
 urged by reason in behalf of his own proper soul and body. 
 Suicide, self-defense and duelling are topics of vital interest 
 in this subject. Truthfulness in speech and the right to prop- 
 erty are points particularly offended against in man 's conduct 
 towards his fellows. In the field of the family, or domestic 
 society, marriage itself, celibacy, polygamy, divorce, education 
 of child and the mutual relations between family and state, 
 are questions of weighty importance. Man's natural instinct 
 for political or civil society, society's end, its constituents, 
 forms of government, state prerogatives, and sedition will 
 occur for discussion in our consideration of civil society. 
 
SECTION I. MAN AS AN INDIVIDUAL 
 THESIS I 
 
 Religion is man*s first duty, a matter of essential necessity 
 to the individual and the state. Worship, interior and ex- 
 terior, private and public, is God^s due. Man's duty towards 
 revelation is to accept it, when. known as such; to diligently 
 seek and find it, when hidden, and when he has reason to sup- 
 pose that it exists. Toleration in matter of dogma is absurd. 
 Jouin, 71-96 ; Bickaby, 191-202. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 We are by supposition dealing with men honest enough to 
 admit God's existence and the fact of creation. We likewise 
 take for granted the possibility and the fact of creation. For 
 proofs of these several points we refer to Natural Theology 
 and forward parts of Metaphysics. Man's duties towards 
 others are based on relations in force between himself and 
 these others; and the first condition that confronts him is, 
 from the very fact of creation, that of utter dependence on 
 God. Man is God 's handiwork, and belongs to Him body and 
 soul. In virtue of His supreme dominion God has an in- 
 alienable right to the completest service of His creature; and 
 must, from the very nature of things, stand vested with a 
 master's control over man's every faculty and energy. Wor- 
 ship, interior and exterior, submission of intellect and will, 
 are the highest conceivable tributes of superiority one ra- 
 tional being can pay another, and religion embodies both. 
 Faith and trust in God's messages, or the acceptance of reve- 
 lation, is an element of religion on which champions of God's 
 cause cannot with too much force insist in these days of irre- 
 ligion and unbelief. Revelation is the channel through which 
 men are advertised of the sort of service God wants, and ex- 
 
 177 
 
178 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 perience is witness that worship weakens and falls dead, when 
 the truths of revelation are once called into question and 
 doubted. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Religion. The word is of Latin origin, and authors are 
 divided between three possible derivations. Lactantius, an 
 eminent scholar and Church-writer, favors religare for root- 
 word. Religion with him means a second bond or moral obli- 
 gation, added to man's first or physical dependence on God 
 for being, preservation, activity and care. Cicero, with whom 
 Lactantius finds fault, ventures relegere, meaning to dwell on 
 in thought, or meditate. His derivation gives large prom- 
 inence to the theoretical side of religion. St. Augustine, see- 
 ing in the Redemption a second choice of God made by fallen 
 man, traces the word to religere, to choose again. In classical 
 Latinity religion is regularly identified with the feeling of 
 respect and veneration entertained towards parents, relatives 
 and friends. 
 
 But whatever may be said of ancient usage, it is quite cer- 
 tain that religion to-day, taken in a strict and technical sense, 
 denotes a something referred to God alone. It is a duty, a 
 moral attitude, or condition, or relation, based on man 's phys- 
 ical dependence on God for existence, preservation, activity 
 and control. It has for foundation the circumstance that 
 God is man's first cause and last end. Hence religion is gen- 
 erally defined, the duty to acknowledge and worship God as 
 first cause and last end. Acknowledgment denotes the free 
 acceptance of a truth, and of whatever responsibilities attach 
 to it. It supposes knowledge, and adds thereto an act of the 
 will. Worship is testimony rendered to divine excellence, 
 coupled with due submission. It is honor combined with sub- 
 mission. 
 
 Religion may be considered objectively or subjectively. 
 Objectively taken, it is a collection of truths expressive of the 
 relations in force between God and man, and a catalogue of 
 the duties hinging on these relations. Subjectively taken, it 
 is the actual or habitual acknowledgment of these truths and 
 performance of these duties. Religion is a branch of justice, 
 because it is God 's due. It includes, among others, truths like 
 
RIGHTS AND DUTIES 179 
 
 the following, God created man, preserves him, exercises over 
 him the controlling influence of a ruler and helper, rewards 
 and punishes him in the next life as a most just judge. It 
 includes the duties of adoration, sacrifice, prayer and faith 
 in God's word. Religion is a branch of justice under the 
 formality of God's due, not under other formalities. Reli- 
 gion is something more than mere good conduct and respect- 
 able behavior. Pagans and modern heretics in reducing the 
 notion to limits so narrow forget that the will, the mainspring 
 of conduct, depends for all its vigor on the mind or intellect. 
 Luther's rule was, faith without good works; now the rule 
 reads, good works without faith. 
 
 Viewed as a body of truths, religion is said to be theoretical, 
 dogmatic, speculative. Viewed as a body of duties, it is said 
 to be practical. Religion in both senses is essential. Theo- 
 retical religion without practical religion is imperfect. Prac- 
 tical religion without theoretical religion is often no better, 
 no more sincere ; and is always subject to decay and death. A 
 religion may be false and wrong in one of two ways, either by 
 paying homage to a false god, or by worshipping the true God 
 in a way opposed to His wishes. Natural religion would be 
 a thing no higher than human reason, with precepts possible 
 of fulfilment to man's unaided resources. But we live in the 
 blessed light of revelation, and the only religion now in vogue, 
 and in vogue from the beginning, is revealed or supernatural. 
 God has in His goodness deigned to stamp with the seal of 
 His own word even such truths and such plain obligations as 
 reason of itself can fathom. 
 
 Duty. Right and duty are correlative terms and insep- 
 arable. Right is one of the terms in our language, conveying 
 notions at first sight whole seas different. Thus, the right is 
 confounded with rectitude and conveys the notion of exact 
 agreement with that straight line of conduct morality bids 
 us walk. A right is something altogether other, and can be 
 best perhaps described as, the moral and inviolable power or 
 strength to do or exact something. The Romans had two 
 words for our one. Right in the first sense, they expressed 
 by rectum; right in the second sense, they expressed by jus. 
 This jus is clearly connected with jubere, to order or legis- 
 late; and since all law is founded on rectitude, the choice 
 
180 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 of the word was happy. A jus or right is an emphatic com- 
 mand, forbidding anybody to interfere with its enforcement. 
 It is creative of a duty in outside agencies, restraining them 
 from opposition to its peaceful fulfilment. Four elements of 
 a right are person of inherence, person of incidence, object, 
 and act. 
 
 Take for example ownership in a house and lot or parcel 
 of ground. The person of inherence is owner, the person of 
 incidence is the rest of the world, the object is the building 
 and piece of ground, the act is use for purposes of residence, 
 sale, changes, repairs, and against trespass. Right, therefore, 
 is an order issuing from the person of inherence or owner, 
 backed by the omnipotence of nature or God, and command- 
 ing the person of incidence, whether a set and definite indi- 
 vidual or the world at large, to reverence the wishes of its 
 owner in at least one respect. God is the avenger of broken 
 rights, and nobody violates a right without disputing the 
 authority of God, and running counter to His wishes. Na- 
 ture, and nature here means God, vests the owner of a right 
 with the authority of a king, and word from him in the mat- 
 ter of his right is word from God. Men on occasions lack 
 the physical strength needed to enforce their rights ; but God 
 is their champion, strength never fails Him, and, whether in 
 this life or the next, God ultimately makes right prevail, by 
 actual accomplishment or, in event of its failure, by penalty. 
 
 Right and duty are therefore closely related, and a knowl- 
 edge of one helps much to a knowledge of the other. A right 
 is a moral force, and depends by no means for its validity on 
 physical superiority. Rights are on this account often tram- 
 pled and violated by might in a world of iniquity and wrong ; 
 but nobody ever maintained that a right lapsed when borne 
 down by might. For the simple reason that they have no 
 intellect or will, and are therefore outside the category of 
 moral beings, animals have no rights. We owe it to ourselves 
 to treat them humanely; but, as far as they are themselves 
 concerned, cruelty to animals is no violation of a right. The 
 obligation engendered in others by the existence of a right is 
 sometimes negative, sometimes positive. There are in other 
 words rights of such a nature that they merely forbid outside 
 interference, without obliging others to help positively to their 
 
MIGHT AND RIGHT ISl 
 
 realization. There are others, on the contrary, of such a 
 nature that they lay on others the responsibility of contrib- 
 uting by positive acts to their issue. Finally, right is founded 
 on law ; and since law without God is a dead letter, any recog- 
 nition of right is silent and sure testimony to the existence 
 Of God. 
 
 Rights are personal or real. A personal right immediately 
 affects the person of the possessor; a real right affects him 
 only through the medium of some second thing. Instances 
 are, the right to life and the right to a piece of property. 
 Rights are likewise natural and inborn, or acquired. They 
 are natural, if derived to man from his very nature. They 
 are acquired, if due to some free act, of which he acquits him- 
 self. Thus, the rights to improve the mind, to defend life 
 when unjustly attacked, to acquire land, are all natural ; and, 
 as such, beyond all possibility of loss or forfeiture. The right, 
 on the other hand, to ownership in this or that particular 
 strip of land, because largely dependent on some special ac- 
 tivity freely exerted, is an acquired right, and admits, of loss 
 or change. Might can with justice and propriety be employed 
 to effect the enforcement of a right. Right, resident as it is 
 in the mind and the will, has claims on man's inferior facul- 
 ties, and can call these forces that constitute physical strength 
 to its assistance. Neither is injustice done the party against 
 whom violence is used. If right primarily binds his mind 
 and will, small wonder if its influence extends to the mem- 
 bers of his body. 
 
 A conflict or collision of rights is quite possible in certain 
 contingencies. In such an emergency only one of the two 
 rights is real. The other is no right at all, but only a shadow. 
 Right cannot in the nature of things be opposed to right. 
 When a clash of the kind occurs, the relative merit of the 
 two claims must be weighed, and the worthier must prevail. 
 Nature again furnishes us with the standard of measurement, 
 and the question must be decided in strict accordance with the 
 demands of nature's order. Thus, when some human enact- 
 ment is in open contradiction with God's law, the human law 
 is no law at all. It must yield, and its framers are vested 
 with no prerogative of authority, as against the source and 
 author of all authority. In every well organized community 
 
182 SPECIAL ETHIQS; 
 
 courts are established, and their word is supreme in the set- 
 tlement of disputes turning on civil rights. No private citi- 
 zen has the power to take the law into his own hands, and 
 decide quarrels with his neighbor. In this plan, justice may 
 on some rare occasions be defeated ; but the order maintained, 
 and the bloodshed avoided, more than compensate for these 
 scattered wrongs. Eights have limits, beyond which they can- 
 not be pushed. No right however valid can sanction the com- 
 mission of sin. When pursuing a right, we must proceed 
 with caution, and avoid offending against the duties of others 
 and our own plain duty. Rights in many cases assume the 
 nature of privileges, and there is no law compelling a man 
 to everywhere make use of his privileges. 
 
 Duty is the source of that inner consciousness of moral re- 
 straint which accompanies every dictate of the natural law. 
 It invariably presents itself in the shape of a command, 
 ordering man to do or avoid something. It is a strict obliga- 
 tion, and man knows that, if he wants to remain true to him- 
 self and his nature, he must satisfy its demands. A duty, in 
 concrete terms, is this or that act urged or forbidden by law 
 and order. God 's rights are the origin of men 's duties ; and 
 God, independent as He is of every superior, is a stranger 
 to duties properly so called. In figurative language we some- 
 times speak of God's duties to Himself and even to men. 
 But in strict usage duty always connotes a superior, a being 
 with full authority to impose the duty. Absolutely speaking, 
 then, right is first of the two in order of time. Confining 
 the question to man, duty always precedes right. All man's 
 rights are founded on the duty binding him to the accom- 
 plishment of the end designed for him by nature's Creator. 
 Whatever conduces to that end, without disturbing the reign 
 of justice, constitutes matter for a right. He is armed with 
 a right to repel whatever seriously and unjustly interferes 
 with his destiny's consummation. 
 
 N.B. Duty manifests the claims of moral rectitude, and 
 rectitude is the observance of relations, or conduct in har- 
 mony with the objective order of things. The order of excel- 
 lence and importance prevalent in duties is, God, self, and the 
 neighbor. Compare Hedonism and Altruism. Ahrens and 
 Damiron would recognize rights in animals, because they are 
 
RELIGION A NECESSITY 183 
 
 called in Holy Writ sons of God, and because we are forbidden 
 to do them injury or cause them pain. We answer, Holy 
 Writ is on occasions poetic, and these scattered passages are 
 to be so interpreted. The Church is judge, not our op- 
 ponents or ourselves. We slay animals for purposes of sus- 
 tenance, comfort and ornament. We must not be wanton in 
 our treatment of animals, because all such conduct is hostile 
 to the growth of mildness and meekness. 
 
 First Duty. In point of time and in point of excellence. 
 This duty of religion, to ensure good results in after life, ought 
 to be impressed on the child 's thoughts from the earliest dawn 
 of reason, and all other duties, even towards his parents, 
 should be unfolded to his growing mind as corollaries flowing 
 from the first. He should be taught that parents, country 
 and friends, high as they stand in his esteem and love, occupy 
 only second place to God, and that at God's call all these and 
 much else besides must be abandoned. 
 
 Essential Necessity. Philosophy recognizes two kinds of 
 necessity, accidental and essential. The former hardly de- 
 serves the name. It represents a thing necessary only after 
 such a fashion that the effect can in certain circumstances 
 have place in its absence, and its functions can always be 
 discharged by some other object. Thus, for instance, brown 
 bread is said to be an accidental necessity of life. Essential 
 necessity truly deserves the name. It represents a thing so 
 necessary that in the event of its absence the effect is simply 
 out of the question. Thus, food of some sort is an essential 
 necessity for continuance in life. This essential necessity, 
 however, admits of degrees. It may be physical, or quasi- 
 physical, or moral. A physical essential necessity forms part 
 of a thing's very being, body in man. A quasi-physical es- 
 sential necessity contributes to a thing's well-being. Want 
 of a necessity of this kind makes itself felt in a wholly differ- 
 ent way from want of an accidental necessity. Sound health, 
 for instance, is a quasi-physical essential necessity for the 
 enjoyment of life. It cannot, like bread, be replaced by some 
 other commodity. A moral essential necessity is an object, 
 thoroughly requisite for the rounding out of a man's moral 
 being. It is an imperative call of conscience, a heavy and 
 unavoidable obligation. Failure to comply with its demands 
 
184 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 disturbs that harmony with the objective order which con- 
 stitutes man's last end or destiny in this life. We contend 
 that religion, objective and subjective, dogmatic and prac- 
 tical, while not a physical essential necessity for individual 
 and state, is for one and the other a quasi-physical and a 
 moral essential necessity. We contend, in other words, that 
 without religion man's physical life is beset with trials, trou- 
 bles and dangers, that the state's welfare is seriously harmed, 
 and that individual and state are out of harmony with recti- 
 tude. 
 
 Individual and State. Religion's bearing on the lives of 
 individual citizens presents no difficulty whatever. Its bear- 
 ing on the state becomes as clear, when we regard the state 
 a moral person, affected with rights it can enforce, with duties 
 it must discharge. With this view of the state we are ac- 
 quainted from common every day experience. Our President 
 and our Governors pay religious tribute to God, by proclaim- 
 ing once a year the advent of Thanksgiving Day, by coun- 
 tenancing religious observance throughout the land, by prayer 
 in our legislative assemblies, and at other functions of state. 
 In distinctively Catholic countries the duty is accomplished 
 with more solemn ceremony. 
 
 Worship. Testimony to divine excellence coupled with due 
 submission. It is honor of a peculiar sort combined with 
 submission. When the acts of homage are internal and 
 unseen of men, the worship is interior. When these acts are 
 external, and plain to the senses, the worship is exterior. 
 Public worship, or social, is homage done God by the state 
 in its representatives, not in private individuals. The ob- 
 servance paid God by citizens in their private capacity con- 
 stitutes private worship. Only the godless deny the necessity 
 of interior worship. But scores of writers endeavor to do 
 away with the need of exterior worship, and public or social 
 worship of whatever sort. Many are urged to take this step 
 by hostility to the Catholic Church, so insistent on exterior 
 worship. As a matter of fact, the vast majority of men 
 to-day outside of the true faith, regard attendance at Sunday 
 service a thing of minor importance, wholly beneath their 
 notice, and no matter of conscience at all. Some, with a fam- 
 ily resemblance to the traitor Judas, prate about the useless 
 
WORSHIP 185 
 
 expenditure of money, wasted in the erection of edifices for 
 purposes of worship. These proclaim with loud mouths that 
 the green fields are God's temple, and that the birds of the 
 air are His choristers. They declare external observances and 
 ceremonies a hollow mockery, superstition ; and never lose an 
 opportunity to inveigh against them. But their own conduct 
 is the weightiest argument against their words. They are 
 monuments of decayed religious spirit, the unfailing growth 
 of negligence in matters external. 
 
 Of the two kinds of worship, interior is, of course, the 
 higher and more precious ; but, constituted as he is, man de- 
 pends for inner emotions on his outward behavior and deport- 
 ment of body. When minded to pray, he needs to be sur- 
 rounded with all the holy images, and with that atmosphere 
 of quiet resident in our churches. He needs to go down on 
 his knees, and fold his hands, and shut his eyes against the 
 thousand distracting objects clamoring for his attention. 
 Even with all the varied helps present in our houses of prayer, 
 it is no easy task to check our senses, and address God with 
 the profound respect, which is His due. Then too, the 
 Creator made our hands, arms, eyes and the other members 
 of the body, as well as the soul; and mind-worship to the 
 exclusion of body-worship is paying only half our debt. 
 Thomasius, Dunzi and Kemmerichius concede a measure of 
 usefulness to exterior worship, but deny reason's ability to 
 prove its necessity. Ahrens, infected with modem rational- 
 ism, frames up a definition of religion, from which he en- 
 tirely excludes the necessity of exterior worship. ''Reli- 
 gion," he says, "is a union of mind and heart with the su- 
 preme being." ''Worship, therefore," with him, "is an 
 intellectual and spiritual work only, which ought to refrain 
 from representing God and His attributes by sensible signs." 
 ' ' One may, ' ' he continues, ' ' call to his assistance some of the 
 fine arts, such for instance as music and song, because these 
 serve to more vividly express our notions of the infinite. ' ' 
 He allows the sense of hearing to play a part in divine wor- 
 ship, he has no place for the eyes, and scents from afar 
 Catholicity's veneration of images 
 
 Eevelation. The word is a Latin derivative from re, back, 
 and velum, a veil. It means therefore the removal of a veil. 
 
186 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 the lifting of some hidden truth into the light. In theology, 
 revelation is defined as, '' A communication from God in lan- 
 guage strictly so called, hy which, on the authority of His 
 testimony. He makes known to men truths in the order of 
 salvation.' ' All creation is said to be a book, which sets forth 
 with a great wealth of detail God's guiding presence, His 
 attributes, and His wishes in our regard. But it conveys 
 lessons through a medium different from language properly 
 so called, and therefore falls short of being revelation. Reve- 
 lation is the word of God, something once uttered by God 
 for men 's spiritual advantage. Its channels are direct speech, 
 the written word, and tradition. He held immediate converse 
 with Moses and the prophets, who afterwards at His express 
 command committed His wishes to writing for the benefit of 
 future ages. This body of revelation is contained in the Old 
 Testament. Later on. He appeared among men, and in the 
 person of Jesus Christ changed much of the old dispensation, 
 and instituted the New Law, destined to govern His people 
 without change or alteration till the end of time. He bade 
 His apostles preach and teach His doctrine throughout the 
 world. St. Matthew and St. John, with the disciples St. Mark 
 and St. Luke, compiled the four Gospels, or narratives of 
 Christ's life. St. Paul and others, under the influence of 
 divine inspiration, wrote a series of letters or documents 
 abounding with rules for the right ordering of Christian life. 
 God ordained that these writings should always remain in 
 the custody of a living Church, which He solemnly founded 
 and placed under the control of St. Peter and his successors 
 forever. This Church is to be the arbiter of all religious 
 disputes, and this Church is to decide beyond all appeal the 
 amplitude of revelation. There is no higher court, empowered 
 to review or reverse its decisions; and God has promised it 
 immunity from error in matters of dogma. It is the guardian 
 and authoritative interpreter of God's word, as contained in 
 the Old and New Testaments; the witness to and the dis- 
 penser of tradition. For revelation is of wider extent than 
 the mere written word, and embraces all the points of* belief 
 insisted on and taught by the Catholic and true Church of 
 Christ, though not explicitly set forth in the pages of Holy 
 Scripture. 
 
REVELATION 187 
 
 Scripture itself bears us out in all these statements, but 
 their further discussion belongs to the domain of theology. 
 "We have said enough to convince any honest mind that revela- 
 tion is no empty dream. Scripture and tradition are its 
 abundant sources, and he who diligently searches can easily 
 recognize the contents of the Bible and the doctrines of the 
 Catholic Church for the word of God. Miracles and proph- 
 ecies are the most obvious of the seals divinity has stamped 
 upon them; and the miracles and the prophecies we appeal 
 to for the heavenly character of our religion, are beyond 
 denial, and beyond serious dispute or doubt. God alone is 
 equal to the infinite task of working real miracles, and utter- 
 ing real prophecies; and when He invests a messenger with 
 these dread prerogatives for credentials of his mission, that 
 messenger is God 's mouthpiece, and the tidings he brings are 
 fresh from the lips of God. 
 
 Faith is the virtue called into play by revelation, and faith 
 is not knowing, but believing. The truths of faith are not 
 blessed with all the light, thrown round the axioms of algebra 
 and geometry. They are obscure, hard to understand, and 
 in some cases absolutely beyond human comprehension. More 
 than any other act of the mind, faith makes large demands 
 on free will ; and this circumstance, constituting faith 's merit, 
 is responsible for faith's small influence with the ill-disposed. 
 As an act of supremest homage, it is only just that it carry 
 along with itself submission of will, the faculty whose sur- 
 render is a most pleasing sacrifice in God's sight. 
 
 Faith of the right kind, faith with the authority of God's 
 word for root and motive, leaves a man no room for choice 
 between dogmas that flatter and dogmas that pinch self. 
 Everj^ statement, whether it pictures forth the ravishing joys 
 of Heaven, or the terrifying flames of hell, must be accepted 
 with the same readiness and good-will. Of course, some of 
 Scripture's utterances have a more important bearing on 
 morality, a more intimate connection with eternal salvation 
 than others; but all, all without a single exception, rest for 
 credence on the self-same support, the knowledge and the 
 truthfulness of God. If God could stoop to the meanness of 
 deceiving man in the most trivial particular, man's trust and 
 confidence in God would be at an end. Faith in any utter- 
 
18d SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 ance of God, no matter how solemn and weighty, would then 
 degenerate to stupidity. People outside our Church, people 
 whose faith is measured by the canons of convenience, set 
 apart certain far-reaching, general and palatable dogmas, and 
 label them fundamental articles. They preach that these 
 alone are to be believed under pain of eternal loss. Other 
 articles of minor importance deserve no attention, though 
 out of respect for God's word they ought not to be wantonly 
 denied. With them, individuals are judge and jury in the 
 selection; and confusion reigns supreme. 
 
 "We too recognize a difference in importance between various 
 parts of Holy Scripture; but no one sentence is so unimpor- 
 tant as not to demand our full faith and belief. We feel at 
 liberty to deny nothing, we feel bound to believe at least 
 implicitly the whole of Scripture's contents, and explicitly 
 believe every dogma duly proposed to our consideration. And 
 since every clause in the Bible descends to us from the same 
 God who teaches the more important articles, our position is 
 alone logical, our position alone approves itself to reason. To 
 accept revelation as such means, therefore, a vast deal more 
 than half-hearted and insincere believers to-day make it mean. 
 To diligently seek and find revelation when hidden, implies 
 a larger amount of labor than most strangers to the truth 
 devote to this undeniable duty. Doubts daily cross their 
 minds, and suspicions concerning the dangerous risks they are 
 taking constantly arise within them. And yet these improv- 
 ident philosophers, because the consequences of their mistake 
 will become fully apparent only in the next life, prefer the 
 ease of uncertainty, and the license their pretended ignorance 
 lends to their low instincts. 
 
 Toleration. Nobody need be informed that the world is 
 sadly full of different religious sects. A walk through our 
 own city, with now and then a glance at the sign-boards con- 
 spicuously displayed at temple entrances, must effectually 
 cure any doubt on the subject. Indifferentism is a rampant 
 sin among us, so rampant that the early signers felt con- 
 strained to introduce into our Constitution a clause ensuring 
 to every citizen immunity from persecution on the score of 
 religion. Be it noted, however, that the toleration sanctioned 
 by our government is merely political ; and therefore not to be 
 
TOLERATION 189 
 
 branded in virtue of our thesis absurd. Dogmatic toleration 
 is as eminently absurd a notion as can well be conceived. 
 Only a disordered mind could seriously entertain it. Political 
 toleration is mere permission, without the declaration of any 
 absolute right, to practise false as well as true religions. Dog- 
 matic toleration is permission along with the assertion of an 
 absolute right to practise false as well as true religions. 
 
 Political tolerance tolerates not mistakes, but people who 
 make the mistakes. It can at heart abominate all false wor- 
 ship, and yet have a word of kindness for the victims of error. 
 It takes men as it finds them, and merely permits all without 
 distinction to practise whatever system of public worship 
 they choose. It seals with its sanction no form of worship 
 at all, but in the interests of peace allows the false and the 
 true to grow up together till the harvest. And God allows 
 that, in a permissive, though not in an approving way. Ar- 
 dent lovers of the truth at first sight revolt against any such 
 proceeding; but after calm consideration they settle down to 
 the conviction, that in the present lamentable state of affairs 
 it is the only feasible method. Christ once rebuked indigna- 
 tion of the kind in St. James and St. John. The Samaritans 
 had shut their gates against His coming and these disciples 
 said, "Lord, wilt thou that we command fire to come down 
 from heaven and consume them? And turning He rebuked 
 them, saying. You know not of what spirit you are. The Son 
 of man came, not to destroy souls, but to save." St. Luke 
 9.54. 
 
 When authority permits a practice as abominable in the 
 sight of God as heresy, it can still be justified on the double 
 plea of inability to remedy the abuse, and refraining from the 
 crime of formal cooperation. Were there no such escape from 
 the difficulty, our rulers would be obliged in conscience to do 
 one of two things. They would have either to expel all sec- 
 taries from the country, or whip them into submission to the 
 true faith. But the one alternative is quite as impracticable 
 and impossible as the other. Adherents to the true religion 
 are not in the majority, and truth's victory would be uncer- 
 tain. It is criminal to undertake any kind of a war without 
 reasonable hope of winning. Catholics outnumber every single 
 sect taken separately; but, in the event of force, error would 
 
190 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 unite against the truth, as against a common foe. Then, too, 
 even were the triumph of truth an assured possibility, the 
 land would have to be deluged with blood, and life would 
 perish from the state. Submission procured by force is simply 
 out of the question. Religion subjectively taken is largely 
 a matter of free will. Liberty enters religion as an essen- 
 tial element, and religion embraced under stress of physical 
 violence is hypocrisy. 
 
 Besides, the state by supposition lends no peculiar support 
 or encouragement to false creeds, and in this particular es- 
 capes censure. Dogmatic toleration would be in effect, if 
 our Constitution anywhere committed itself to the stupidity 
 of declaring all forms of worship equally good. But you will 
 look in vain throughout its pages for any such assertion. 
 Well-meaning Catholics, to conciliate the esteem and friend- 
 ship of separated brethren, sometimes stoop to the meanness 
 of giving expression to sentiments of the kind. But their 
 excuse lies in the fact that they are over-zealous for peace, 
 and speak without due reflection. Rome recognises no com- 
 promise with error. She teaches her children to put on the 
 feelings of charity and forbearance towards error's deluded 
 victims, but denounces error as an unpardonable sin, and 
 commends its slaves to the mercy and justice of God. 
 
 Absurd. The full force of this term implies something more 
 than mere falsehood. It further conveys the notion of silli- 
 ness and open war with reason's most evident dictates. A 
 statement can well be false without being absurd. We are 
 acquainted with many such statements. The falsehood they 
 contain, lies deep beneath the surface, mixed with much that 
 is true, and only diligent search can detect it. But dogmatic 
 tolerance is so repugnant to common sense that we hesitate 
 not to brand it absurd. 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Four Parts— I, II, III, IV 
 
 I. Religion is (a) man's first duty, of essential necessity 
 to (b) individual and (c) State. 
 II. Worship, interior and exterior, private and public is 
 God's due. 
 
PROOFS 191 
 
 III. Man's duty towards revelation is (a) to accept, or 
 
 (b) seek it. 
 
 IV. Toleration in matter of dogma is absurd. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 I. (a) The position and standing of relations fix the po- 
 sition and standing of duties. But of all man's relations 
 those with God are first in time and first in excellence. Ergo, 
 man's duty towards God, or religion, is man's first duty. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Duties are the growth of rela- 
 tions in force between a man and God, himself and his neigh- 
 bors. They are, as it were, an effect, with these several rela- 
 tions for cause ; and effects partake of the nobility inherent in 
 necessary causes. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Existence and reality derived 
 from God and Creator are first requisites for whatever events 
 crowd into a man's after-life. To none therefore are we 
 more under obligation than to God. Nobody has more sacred 
 rights to our homage and service. No conceivable object is 
 worthier of our energies. 
 
 (b) A duty based on a relation arising from man's very 
 nature is a thing of moral essential necessity to the indi- 
 vidual. But religion is a duty arising from just such a rela- 
 tion. Ergo, religion is a thing of moral essential necessity 
 to the individual. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Duties are strict moral neces- 
 sities. Duties arising from man's nature are as close and 
 present to man as his very nature. They can no more be 
 absent from him, they can no more loosen their hold on his 
 allegiance than nature can abandon him, or reside somewhere 
 apart from him. That religion is a quasi-physical essential 
 necessity to the individual, favorable to his happiness, peace 
 and well-being must be evident from the line of reasoning 
 followed in proof of next clause. 
 
 (c) 1°. A moral person immediately dependent on God for 
 maker, helper, guide and rewarder lies under moral essential 
 necessity to acknowledge and worship God. But the state is 
 such a moral person, and religion is this acknowledgment and 
 
192 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 worship. Ergo, religion is a moral essential necessity to the 
 state. 
 
 2°. That without which duties of justice, honesty, and mu- 
 tual harmony can in no wise stand is a quasi-physical essential 
 necessity to the state as such. But religion is a thing of the 
 kind. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Nobody will deny that the du- 
 ties enumerated are of vital importance and large factors in 
 the state's well being. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Remove God from the universe, 
 destroy religion, and all moral obligation falls, sanction is 
 idle, and states go down in ruin. 
 
 II. N.B. Worship offered to God, divine excellence itself, 
 is called, latria. Worship offered the Blessed Virgin Mary, 
 who borrows all her excellence from God, is called, hyperdulia. 
 Worship offered the saints is called dulia. 
 
 The worship belonging to God is at least interior. In the 
 case of individuals it must likewise be exterior or bodily, since 
 man's dependence on God, extending as it does to body and 
 soul, must be shown whole and entire. The worship rendered 
 by the state must be social, and therefore visible or exterior. 
 Public worship is worship rendered by the individuals com- 
 posing a state, not in their private capacity, but as welded 
 together by authority into one body politic. 
 
 III. Man's duty towards revelation is to (a) accept it, or 
 (b) seek it. 
 
 (a) 1°. It is a rational creature's duty to accept for true 
 every statement made by the God of truth and known for such. 
 But man is a rational creature, and revelation is a body of 
 statements made by the God of truth. Ergo, man's duty 
 towards revelation is to accept it when known as such. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Duties are the result of rela- 
 tions, and the relations in force between the Creator and His 
 rational creatures make faith in the Creator's word an im- 
 perative necessity. God therefore has a right to man's men- 
 tal submission when He speaks. That He invariably insists 
 on this right, is evident from the circumstance that He is all- 
 wise and all-true. He cannot, like limited and finite mortals, 
 give expression to utterances, that owing to dearth of knowl- 
 edge are tainted with falsehood. He cannot like fools talk 
 
PROOFS 198 
 
 for the mere sake of talking, without caring whether His 
 listeners heed His words or not. Men can be guilty of folly 
 of the sort; but God has too much reverence for language's 
 end and purpose to so abuse it. When a man of ordinary 
 common sense, blessed with a fair measure of seriousness, 
 vouches for the truth of some fact, he can with reason feel 
 offended at a refusal to abide by his declaration. God's at- 
 tributes would make such a refusal a monstrous crime, and 
 God's attributes make faith in His word an absolute duty. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. That Scripture and tradition, 
 or revelation, are a body of statements made by the God of 
 truth is proved at great length in works on Theology. Phi- 
 losophy left to itself can proceed no farther than demonstrate 
 the necessity of accepting revelation in the event of its being 
 made. It cannot, alone and single handed, conclusively prove 
 that this or that set of truths constitutes revelation. History 
 furnishes us with well attested facts, and philosophy can dis- 
 cover in these facts traces of God's presence. 
 
 Thus, the records of history are witness to the reality of 
 Moses and the prophets, and to certain wonderful or miracu- 
 lous events in their lives. They claimed for themselves the 
 dignity of messengers from God to men, and left in writing 
 to posterity facts, principles, and maxims, that God commis- 
 sioned them to communicate. For credentials they appealed 
 to miracles and prophecies, worked and uttered by them in 
 the name of God. Philosophy is within its own province, 
 when it undertakes to show that the writings of Moses and the 
 prophets derive from these miracles and prophecies a divinity 
 peculiarly their own. These two species of effects are be- 
 yond the reach of power inferior to God's, and God could 
 never sanction lies by the performance of prodigies. When, 
 therefore. He stamped with these seals of His omnipotence 
 and wisdom the claims of Moses and the prophets, He signi- 
 fied as plainly as possible how He wished their statements to 
 be regarded. He signified as plainly as possible that the 
 words they committed to writing were His own words and 
 had Him for author. 
 
 2°. From analogy. To God as the supreme being adora- 
 tion is due ; to God as the supreme good love is due. Ergo, 
 to God as the highest truth faith is due. 
 
IM SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 (b) Contempt of revelation is contempt of God, and in- 
 difference to eternal salvation. But avoidance of contempt 
 for God, and of indifference to salvation, is man's plain duty. 
 Ergo, avoidance of contempt for revelation, diligent search 
 for the truth, is man's duty. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. God wastes no words, and 
 means His every message to be seriously taken. He is like- 
 wise anxious that all His children, without any exception, take 
 full advantage of the instruction He proffers. He occupies 
 the position of Lord and Father, and resents negligent atten- 
 tion on the part of such as He deigns to address. Revelation 
 teems with documents designed for helps to attain to the King- 
 dom of Heaven, and the loss of these necessary helps through 
 sloth is attended with damage and serious responsibility. It 
 is quite impossible for me to think, that to-day's scoffers at 
 religion and revelation are absolutely free from suspicion and 
 anxiety, concerning the doubtful and preposterous position 
 they occupy. And to let one single doubt in this matter of 
 revelation remain unsettled, is to take sides with God's 
 enemies, and to confide to chance eternal destiny for weal or 
 woe. Plungers at a race-track, when placing money on horses, 
 display more skill and prudence than the wiseacres, who, be- 
 cause of trivial difficulties, gamble in risks, and leave Heaven 
 to a game of chance. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. God has well founded claims on 
 our reverence; and, apart from other considerations, we owe 
 it to our souls and bodies to procure for them an abode of 
 comfort, and happiness, and security against the endless ages 
 of ages in store for them beyond the grave. 
 
 IV. 1°. Toleration in matter of dogma supposes that a 
 system of religion false in itself, yea, immoral and unclean in 
 its tendencies, can be an instrument in God's worship. But 
 this supposition is eminently absurd. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. God is truth, God is purity; 
 and falsehood, immorality, and uncleanness can have no part 
 in His service. Any other notion would be unworthy of God 's 
 infinite majesty and degrading in the extreme. 
 
 2°. Toleration in matter of dogma supposes that religion 
 can be manifold in such sort that a duty prescribed by one 
 system can be neglected by another system, or totally con- 
 
PEINCIPLES 195 
 
 demned as dishonest by a third system. But this supposition 
 is eminently absurd. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. The collection of truths and 
 duties embraced in a religion, truly deserving of the name, 
 ought to be one and the same for all mankind. Religion is the 
 outcome of man's dependence on God; and, since the two 
 terms of the relation, human nature and an unchangeable 
 God, are the same the world over and for all time, religion 
 the result of the relation ought to be the same, without 
 shadow or suspicion of change or difference. Artificial 
 changes, wrought in men's minds by education, prejudice, 
 and other external agencies, are no excuse and no ground 
 whatever for declaring that human nature in me is different 
 from human nature in my neighbor. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. In every free act of the will, whether it be prayer or 
 murder, man necessarily keeps his relations with God, mani- 
 festing and acknowledging his quality of dependence on God. 
 Ergo, no religion needed. 
 
 Answer: Materially, I grant; formally, I deny. The de- 
 pendence must not be in the free act, but in the very free- 
 dom of the act. The dependence manifest in the free act it- 
 self never bases religion. Otherwise brutes, plants and min- 
 erals would be capable of religion, and there would be no dis- 
 tinction between the service of brutes and the service of men. 
 The difference would be merely on the part of the servant, 
 not on the part of the service. Other creatures serve God, 
 no matter what they do. Man in his free acts serves God 
 only when he uses his will aright. The service God exacts 
 from men is different from the service He exacts from brutes ; 
 and free will is index of His wishes. 
 
 B. God cannot be acted on. Ergo, He cannot be wor- 
 shipped. 
 
 Answer: He cannot be acted on physically, I grant; 
 morally, as in case of wrong or honor, I deny. Worship in- 
 duces no intrinsic change in God. All the change is outside 
 God. Worship changes us. 
 
196 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 C. God is infinitely perfect. Ergo, He has no need of wor- 
 ship. 
 
 Answer: He has no need of worship, as of a perfection 
 antecedently absent from His being, I grant. He has no need 
 of worship, as of homage which is His due, I deny. The mil- 
 lionaire may have no need of the five dollars you owe him, 
 but the circumstance never excuses you from payment. 
 
 D. Reason would be the basis of moral obligation and the 
 single origin of good and evil. 
 
 Answer: Reason manifests moral obligation, I grant. 
 Reason makes or constitutes it, I deny. 
 
 E. Society owes worship. Ergo the family, and literary, 
 scientific, athletic societies. 
 
 Answer: Complete society, I grant; incomplete, I deny. 
 The family because complete and independent is a moral per- 
 son and held to worship. Private societies of the kind men- 
 tioned, because incomplete and dependent on the state, are 
 no moral persons, and under no such obligation. 
 
 F. The state has a temporal end or purpose. Ergo, no re- 
 ligion. 
 
 Answer: Its first and chief purpose is the temporal pros- 
 perity of its citizens. This purpose it must accomplish in a 
 way befitting its nature, and by nature it is a moral person, 
 under obligations to God. Ergo, while pursuing temporal 
 good, it must not neglect the knowledge and worship of God. 
 
 G. Society is immediately dependent on the free will of 
 man. Ergo, independent of God. 
 
 Answer: In its making, when not yet a person, I grant; 
 when constituted and now a person, I deny. 
 
 H. In spirit and in truth, John 4.23. Ergo, no external 
 worship needed. 
 
 Answer: The true meaning of the passage is a contrast be- 
 tween the Old Law and the New, between the letter or figure, 
 and spirit or truth. Besides, insistence on internal worship 
 is far from condemning external. Christ on no few occasions 
 employed external worship. 
 
 I. The State can get along without religion. Ergo. Schiff, 
 p. 511, n. 510. 
 
 Answer: We could transmit the antecedent and deny the 
 
PRINCIPLES ^ 197 
 
 conclusion as inconsequent. Worship is a need to the state, 
 not precisely because of advantage, but because of the nature 
 of things. The state can get along somehow and imperfectly, 
 I grant ; as nature intended and perfectly, I deny. 
 
 J. Other incentives would hold men to honesty; a sense of 
 honor, for instance. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: We could again transmit. Our argument is not 
 based on advantage, but on the nature of things. These other 
 incentives would be sufficient and efficacious, I deny; insuffi- 
 cient and inefficacious, I grant. 
 
 K. State and religion have two different ends, temporal 
 good and spiritual. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Different, when incompletely viewed, I grant; 
 w^hen viewed in their completeness, I deny. When viewed in 
 their completeness, the ends of the two are one and the same, 
 the glory of God. God is the absolutely last end of every- 
 thing. 
 
 L. Church and state are distinct. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Distinct and separate, I deny; distinct and not 
 separate ; I again distinguish. In the present order of things, 
 with revelation, I grant; in the order of pure nature, with- 
 out revelation, I again distinguish, completely distinct, I deny, 
 incompletely distinct, I grant. In the order of pure nature, 
 the state as supreme authority would determine religion; in 
 the present order, revelation appoints the Church to that 
 office. 
 
 M. *'It would be easier, I think, to build a city without 
 ground, than to establish or preserve a state without God 
 and religion. ' ' Plutarch. ' ' Time destroys extravagant opin- 
 ions, it solidifies the judgments of nature." Cicero, de Nat. 
 Deorum, 2. 
 
 N. No need to pray, because God knows everything. Kant. 
 
 Answer: S. Th. 2.2. q. 83, a. 2. ''Men ought to do things, 
 not for the purpose of changing the arrangements of Provi- 
 dence, but to accomplish results in accordance with these 
 arrangements." We pray to change God's decrees, I deny; 
 we pray to fulfil them, I grant. His decrees are conditioned. 
 Gifts are made us, if we pray ; withheld, if we neglect to do 
 so. He knows from eternity whether He will relieve men 
 
198 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 or not; but this knowledge is terminatively speaking conse- 
 quent on our use of free will, on our choice or rejection of 
 prayer. 
 
 O. Truths above understanding would be a contradiction. 
 Ergo, no revelation. 
 
 Answer: Above all understanding both divine and human, 
 I grant ; above merely human understanding, I deny. 
 
 P. No truth above human understanding, because its object 
 is all being. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Its proportionate object is all being, I deny; all 
 material being is that ; its adequate object is all being, I again 
 distinguish ; inasmuch as the human intellect can understand 
 whatever being is duly presented or brought to its notice, I 
 grant ; inasmuch as all being is as a matter of fact thus duly 
 presented or brought to its notice, I deny. There are more 
 things in Heaven and earth than are dreamt of in our phi- 
 losophy. 
 
 Q. A truth above reason would be against reason, because 
 out of harmony with reason. 
 
 Answer: Out of harmony in a contradictory way, I grant ; 
 in a contrary way, I deny. There is a difference between not 
 being a mjin's friend, not loving him; and being his enemy, 
 hating him. In much the same way to be on no terms of 
 intimacy with reason is not the same as to be opposed to 
 reason. 
 
 R. God has a right not only to worship, but to worship of 
 the kind He wants. 
 
 S. Religion is truth and justice. Truth is one, error is 
 manifold. Justice is one. 
 
 T. Christianity and Judaism are two opposite religions. 
 Ergo, if one was ever right, the other must always be wrong. 
 
 Ansiver: Opposite essentially, with regard to Christ, I 
 deny; opposite accidentally, with regard to circumstances of 
 time and form, with regard to Christ already come and Christ 
 yet to come, I grant. Christianity worships Christ already 
 come, Judaism worships Christ yet to come, the Messiah. 
 
 U. If an opponent admits Scripture. Christ wants one 
 Church, one fold, one Baptism. Christ wants His people to 
 guard against false prophets, and in the event of dogmatic 
 toleration false prophets must grow and multiply. Christ 
 
PRINCIPLES 199 
 
 wants His Church to endure forever. St. Luke, 11.17. 
 * ' Every kingdom divided against itself shall fall. " * ' Now I 
 beseech you, brethren, to mark them who make dissensions 
 and offences contrary to the doctrine which you have learnt, 
 and to avoid them." Rom. 16.17. ''But though we, or an 
 angel from Heaven, preach a gospel to you besides that which 
 we have preached to you, let him be anathema." Gal. 1.8. 
 
 V. Indifferentism and Liberalism are two theories based on 
 toleration. 
 
 Indifferentism f Absolute = No religion is necessary = Altogether wrong 
 is of two J ^"^ against whole thesis, 
 
 kinds 2 1 Relative = Some religion necessary, no one form before 
 t another, f Universal = All forms equally good. 
 -I Particular == All Christianity equally 
 L good. 
 
 Philosophy refutes universal; theology, particular, because 
 revelation enters question. 
 
 Toleration f l^ogmatic = All religions equally good = Toleration of 
 is of two -l error == Indifferentism. 
 
 kinds 1 Political = All public worship is allowed = Toleration of 
 I the erring = Liberalism. 
 
 Dogmatic is freedom of conscience, meaning immunity from 
 all restraint, moral as well as physical ; from all law of nature 
 and all law of God. Political is freedom of worship, im- 
 munity from the moral restraint imposed by law of state and 
 Church, not from law of nature or of God. In a Catholic 
 country, Indifferentism of whatever kind and Liberalism are 
 regularly wrong, circumstances may condone Liberalism. In 
 a mixed country, absolute and relative universal Indifferent- 
 isms are wrong, and the aid of theology must be invoked to 
 prove relative particular Indifferentism wrong. In a mixed 
 country, that Liberalism is right, which for grave reasons 
 tolerates whatever false religions threaten no harm to the first 
 principles of morality; and every other species of Liberalism 
 is wrong. When a false religion threatens the first princi- 
 ples of morality, it must not be tolerated, because it is a 
 menace to not only the welfare but the very life of the state. 
 In the event of legitimate toleration, some grave reason, like 
 the violent disturbance of social order, must be present ; be- 
 
200 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 cause every false religion is an obstacle to the public good, 
 and no risk of the kind can be legitimately taken without a 
 serious and proportionate reason. The religion of the state 
 ought to be one and true; but facts, over which we have no 
 control, make this condition impossible in certain countries 
 called mixed, and a sane Liberalism is the only alternative for 
 them. By a Catholic country we mean a country, wherein 
 morally speaking all the inhabitants profess the true reli- 
 gion. By a mixed country we mean a country, wherein men 
 in sufficiently large numbers to destroy this moral unanimity 
 profess false religions. 
 
 W. A Catholic country has no right to insist on the Cath- 
 olic religion, (1) because God leaves men free; (2) because 
 human reason is open to mistake in the matter of religion; 
 
 (3) because the state has temporal good for end or purpose; 
 
 (4) because a Protestant country would have the same right; 
 
 (5) because the Catholic religion will prevail anyhow, as 
 truth is stronger than falsehood; (6) because peace would be 
 disturbed; (7) because such interference is everywhere re- 
 garded a species of tyranny. 
 
 Answers: (1) God leaves men free physically, I grant; 
 morally, I deny; (2) Reason is fallible with regard to moral- 
 ity's first principles and immediate deductions from same, I 
 deny ; with regard to remoter conclusions, I again distinguish ; 
 if revelation lends reason no support, I grant; if revelation 
 supplements reason, I deny. (3) The state has temporal 
 good for immediate and incomplete end, I grant; for remote 
 and complete end, I deny; that is the glory of God. (4) Ob- 
 jectively, I deny; subjectively, I again distinguish; if error 
 has any right against the truth, I grant ; if error has no such 
 right, I deny. (5) Truth is stronger than falsehood objec- 
 tively and intrinsically, I grant ; subjectively and extrinsically, 
 I deny. Men's passions commonly favor falsehood. (6) 
 Peace would be disturbed in the very nature of things, I 
 deny ; by accident, I again distinguish ; and for this very rea- 
 son toleration is to be conditionally permitted, I grant ; tolera- 
 tion is to be absolutely permitted, I deny. (7) Such inter- 
 ference is erroneously accounted tyranny, I grant; rightly 
 accounted tyranny, I deny. 
 
THESIS II 
 
 Suicide is a sin against nature. Death inflicted in self- 
 defense is under certain conditions justifiable. Private duels 
 are highly absurd, and contrary to the law of nature. Jouin, 
 96-118 ; Rickaby, 202-224. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Religion is the one word expressive of our duties towards 
 God. It is a word of wide significance, and we were able in 
 our first thesis to discuss only its most salient features. From 
 among its varied contents we selected for study worship, 
 revelation, and its concomitant question of religious tolera- 
 tion. Religion, of course, imposes on us the obligation of 
 cultivating whatever virtues have a direct bearing on God. 
 These virtues are in especial, faith, hope and charity; and 
 they are for this reason called the theological virtues. There 
 must, however, be a limit to our treatise, and we prefer to 
 leave the fuller examination of these several topics to cate- 
 chism and the Sunday-school. 
 
 These theological virtues as such would have no place in 
 the natural order, because they have God as known from 
 revelation for material and formal object. And yet corre- 
 sponding virtues in the shape of love, hope, obedience, grati- 
 tude and fidelity would be serious obligations in even the 
 natural order, and God as known by reason would be their 
 object. Man is certainly bound to seek his end or purpose in 
 life. "We described it as proximately the introduction of 
 moral order into his conduct, and ultimately the intellectual 
 possession of God. Viewed one way or the other, this end 
 is an arduous or difficult good, and tendency towards every 
 such good is hope. Man is likewise bound to love God above 
 everything, because right order demands that we make the 
 dignity of love's object the measure of love's quality. God 
 
 201 
 
202 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 is infinite good, the source and origin of all created good, and 
 as such deserves to be loved above everything. Our duty of 
 obedience flows from our relation of creature. We are the 
 work of God's hands, and the artificer is absolute owner of 
 the thing he makes. Gratitude and fidelity are obligations 
 in view of the multitudinous favors conferred on us. 
 
 And now we pass from God to self. Man has duties towards 
 his soul, he has duties towards his body. Obviously we can- 
 not enter into all the questions suggested by these two com- 
 ponent parts of man's being. We choose to busy ourselves 
 in the main with his body, dismissing the soul with these few 
 remarks. Man was created to the image and likeness of 
 God, and this resemblance with the Creator is principally 
 resident in the soul. His intellect and will must be there- 
 fore developed and made grow more and more like their 
 divine prototype by steady improvement. With the Child 
 Jesus he must grow in wisdom, age and grace. His mind 
 must be stored with knowledge, human and divine; his will 
 must strengthen itself in good. All the virtues with a bear- 
 ing on the mind, all the virtues with a bearing on the will, 
 must be sedulously cultivated; and passions, ready helps to 
 wrong conduct, must be subdued and kept in tight check. 
 Intellect and will must be shaped by diligent care into instru- 
 ments calculated to procure their owner's welfare here and 
 hereafter. Mind and heart must be trained along right lines ; 
 and this means education in its fullest and completest sense. 
 This topic of education will get fuller attention when we come 
 to discuss the duties of parents in particular. Suicide, with 
 everything suggestive of suicide, is the chiefest offense man 
 can do his own body ; but this question is so closely connected 
 with self-defense and duelling, that we choose to gather all 
 three topics into one thesis. Suicide is destruction of life, 
 self-defense is its preservation, and duelling partakes of the 
 double malice of murder and suicide. We say nothing of 
 murder, because it is too evident a violation of natural law 
 to need notice. 
 
 Some philosophers, like Thomasius and Schopenhauer, ob- 
 ject to the expression, man's duties towards himself. Regu- 
 larly duties are between two different persons, and even in 
 this case the relations establishing man's duty towards his 
 
SUICIDE 203 
 
 own proper person are fundamentally between himself and 
 God. His duties towards his neighbor rest ultimately on the 
 same foundation; and merely to keep one set of duties apart 
 from the other, we denominate them duties towards self and 
 duties towards the neighbor. The whole man can be said to 
 differ from his parts or faculties, and this circumstance would 
 be basis enough for the expression, duty towards self. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Suicide. Suicide is direct killing of self on one's own initio^ 
 tive. Life, because the root of all succeeding favors, is Heav- 
 en 's first and highest gift ; and, no matter how crowded with 
 misfortunes, it never loses this quality of a gift. All things 
 considered, its chief good lies in the circumstance that it is 
 the one road leading to a happy eternity. Any other view 
 of life's utility is a mistake, and sure to work sad havoc. 
 Some enjoy a gilt-edged existence from the cradle to the 
 grave. Others drag out a short or long period of disease, 
 and want, and disappointment. But all, without a single 
 exception, the poor as well as the rich, the unfortunate as well 
 as the fortunate, can still count life a priceless jewel. When 
 turned to good and proper uses, it can purchase a seat in the 
 kingdom, a title to that supreme happiness, which constitutes 
 man's last end. 
 
 And yet life is something more than a mere gift. It is a 
 responsibility, and its giver attaches to it obligations, that 
 its recipient is not free to abide by or shirk at will. When 
 bom into the world, a man, without being at all consulted 
 beforehand, is set down in the midst of a multitude of rela- 
 tions, which produce unavoidable and stem duties. No man 
 can escape them, no man can afford to trifle with them, with- 
 out diminishing his dignity and suffering irreparable loss. 
 Life is not given to mortals to be squandered on every chance 
 attraction that happens along. It is not a toy meant by its 
 gracious author to be used till it loses the power to please, 
 and then be cast aside. 
 
 Everything in nature points to the fact that God created 
 men as well as other beings to add their little measure to His 
 glory. Everything in nature proclaims Him the author of life 
 
204 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 and death, and He is jealous of His prerogatives. Men, 
 whether they will or not, have to procure the spread of His 
 kingdom, and proclaim His sovereignty. In His all-wise 
 plans every creature has its allotted time for life, and woe 
 to the man who attempts to interfere with the plan. Men 
 cannot call life out of nothing; men usurp a right belonging 
 to God Himself, when without His sanction they put an end 
 to their existence. They deny God service, they rob them- 
 selves of eternal glory, they plunge their families and friends 
 into the depths of disgrace, they bequeath to their descendants 
 a name of ignominy and shame, they curse their country with 
 an example of craven-hearted cowardice and sottish impiety. 
 
 The crime of suicide is thoroughly wicked, and has noth- 
 ing whatever to recommend it to the esteem of men born with 
 high instincts. It is the mad act of a coward, and bravery 
 is dishonored by being mentioned in the same breath with 
 suicide. Fortitude impels the courageous to bear up under 
 troubles that crush men of weaker mould. Fortitude is 
 blessed with long vision, and in the very excess of pain looks 
 forward to the hour when pain will be no more. It knows 
 the weakness inherent in all the ills of this life, and is satis- 
 fied from experience that sufferance is their infallible remedy. 
 With time they wear themselves out, and joy succeeds to sor- 
 row. But the suicide, whose vision is as short as his patience, 
 madly rushes through the first avenue open to escape. In- 
 stead of meeting an enemy to his happiness with a bold front, 
 he turns his back and flees. The pit of hell-fire into which 
 he falls has been robbed by his irreligion of all its dread 
 reality. In the minds of the unfortunates, who trifle with 
 thoughts of suicide, hell and Heaven are dreams, and never 
 awaken serious consideration. They play the coward; and, 
 choosing between a present and a distant evil, between a cer- 
 tain and an uncertain calamity, they avoid the one and fall 
 headlong into the other. 
 
 Climate, heredity, racial characteristics, are not responsible 
 for suicide. They may be occasions, but they are not causes. 
 They may pave the way to self-destruction, but freedom of 
 will always holds the balance of power ; and, if freedom of will 
 has been instructed along right lines of morality, virtue will 
 always assert itself, and suicide will be hated with all the hate 
 
SUICIDE 205 
 
 it deserves. Apart from their piety and religion, the people 
 of Ireland, because of the misery attendant on hundreds of 
 years of oppression, have small incentive indeed to continue 
 a tiresome and from a worldly point of view hopeless exist- 
 ence. And yet consulting tables prepared for the World 
 Almanac by Barker in 1894, Ireland and Spain contribute 
 fewest to the army of suicides. Protestantism, with its im- 
 pious^ principle of private interpretation, is the parent of 
 unbelief, and countries cursed with its blight are rich in un- 
 natural crimes of the sort. Here are a few interesting and 
 instructive statistics culled from the table referred to. 
 
 
 Rate per 
 
 
 Rate per 
 
 Catholic 
 
 100,000 
 
 Protestant 
 
 100,000 
 
 Saxony, 
 
 31.1 
 
 Austria, 
 
 21.2 
 
 Denmark, 
 
 25.8 
 
 France, 
 
 16.7 
 
 Prussia, 
 
 13.3 
 
 Bavaria, 
 
 9.1 
 
 Sweden, 
 
 8.1 
 
 Ireland, 
 
 1.7 
 
 England, 
 
 6.9 
 
 Spain, 
 
 1.4 
 
 Common sense would lead us to expect no other result. Un- 
 belief unsettles all the convictions implanted by faith, and 
 faith is busiest with the reality of life beyond the grave. 
 Faith is our soundest argument for the existence of Heaven 
 and hell ; and, when Heaven and hell become dim realities in 
 men's minds, small wonder if they take all risks to avoid 
 impending evils like disease, disgrace, poverty and disap- 
 pointment. 
 
 Some ancient philosophers, like Seneca, Plato, Socrates and 
 others, defended suicide, but on grounds far different from 
 the silly pretenses set up by their modem imitators. It may 
 be well to remark that the ancients never regarded suicide 
 justifiable, when used as an exit from ills for which the suicide 
 was himself responsible. Socrates thought self-murder eth- 
 ically correct, only because he knew that after condemnation 
 by the state authorities he had to die anyhow. Seneca and 
 the rest thought it a laudable subterfuge only when cornered 
 by adverse circumstances, over which they had no control. 
 The old Romans considered these seven, justifiable causes for 
 suicide. A disgust for life. The wish to be rid of a dis- 
 tressing disease. Regret for the decease of some dear com- 
 panion. Shame at being an insolvent debtor. Ambition to 
 
206 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 be spoken of after death, when there had been no honor in 
 this life. Dementia or insanity. Outrage to a woman's 
 chastity. But modern advocates of the revolting theory 
 preach its adaptability to every occasion. They draw no fine 
 distinctions between evils for which the victim of poison, pis- 
 tol or the knife is himself responsible, and evils brought to his 
 door by friends or strangers. When life from whatever cause 
 grows disagreeably heavy, life, they say, should be pushed 
 aside. We have no excuse to offer for the mistakes made by 
 the wise of old, when defending the theory and practice of 
 suicide. It is explanation enough for us to know that faith 
 in God never had a tight or loose hold on their minds and 
 hearts, that their natural knowledge of God and a future life 
 was dim, obscure and imperfect, and that selfishness, with an 
 inborn tendency to comfort and ease, is as native to the sa- 
 pient philosopher as it is to the ignorant clod. But it is at 
 the same time worth noting, that the higher they climbed in 
 the scale of true wisdom, the less they conceded to this basest 
 of sins. See Cicero, De Senectute, c. 20; Somnium Scipionis, 
 c. 3 ; Virgil, ^neid, VI, 434. 
 
 No well balanced mind can for a moment doubt of the guilt 
 resident in suicide. In every well organized community any 
 attempt at self-murder is a crime punishable with short or 
 long terms of imprisonment. By measures of the sort the 
 state loudly proclaims its belief that suicide is not only a sin 
 against God and reason, but also a crime against a govern- 
 ment 's very existence. In general the state has small concern 
 for sins against God .and reason. It rouses itself to persistent 
 activity against transgressors, mostly when its own life is 
 threatened. With the aid of a little reflection, we can read- 
 ily understand that the encouragement of suicide in a re- 
 public would lead to annihilation. The godless among its 
 citizens, and they always constitute a large number, would 
 be apt at any moment to disappear from its ranks, and leave 
 to survivors an inheritance of untold shame and misery. 
 
 Suicide is so shocking a crime, an act so far beside the 
 promptings of nature, that men usually reckon its perpetrators 
 insane. Intense grief and overwhelmingly sharp pain can, of 
 course, unbalance the mind of a sufferer; and our Church, 
 with this fact in view, and because of the mystery that al- 
 
SUICIDE 207 
 
 ways attaches to a man's last moments, is extremely lenient 
 in the application of its laws against suicide. The circum- 
 stance should not, however, lead us to conclude that every 
 single act of self-murder is the freak of a lunatic. The care- 
 ful preparations, the secrecy of proceeding, the efficacy of 
 the means chosen, the schemes employed, often point to the 
 criminal's full possession of his wits up to the latest breath. 
 Besides, it is ill-directed charity to invariably excuse the folly 
 of the dead by fastening on their posterity the hereditary 
 taint of a reputation for insanity. 
 
 Thoughts of suicide cannot, of course, be seriously enter- 
 tained by minds alive to religious instincts, to the true mean- 
 ing of life and its attendant woes and joys. Minds dead to 
 faith can easily fall a prey to the temptation, when their cup 
 of sorrow overflows, and the future holds out no promise of 
 respite. Incurable disease, disappointment in love or busi- 
 ness, loss of motive, or purpose, or ambition, these several 
 causes will operate to drag down to a suicide's grave the fool, 
 who has cut loose from religion, and entertains only hazy and 
 uncertain opinions concerning Heaven and hell. To the well 
 instructed Christian these several misfortunes present no in- 
 superable difficulty. He knows that disappointment here was 
 the lot God's Son chose for Himself, when He condescended 
 to put on our nature. He knows that every motive or pur- 
 pose, his soul's salvation excepted, is beneath his contempt, 
 unequal to the full dignity of his sublime calling, and worthy 
 of only his waste energies. He reckons it a sin to allow any 
 lesser aim to completely absorb his attention. 
 
 The Christian, therefore, goaded by despair, and urged in 
 weaker moments to the crime of self-murder, must be com- 
 pelled to refresh his memory of the lessons learned from a 
 pious mother in childhood; and, if reason is at his call, he 
 can pass through the temptation with safety. To the irreli- 
 gious we can give no solid advice till they mend their ways, 
 and get into the trend of mind God wants them to follow in 
 His service. We might perhaps endeavor to convince them 
 that no disease is absolutely incurable, that every cloud has 
 a silver lining, that disappointment in love or business has 
 often paved the way to life-long happiness and unprecedented 
 prosperity, and that there is plenty of work in the world for 
 
208 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 the energetic and industrious. But they will find it possible 
 to answer somehow every argument of the sort we have to 
 offer, and we shall find ourselves reduced to silence, or driven 
 in the end to the only true method, the only trustworthy 
 source of encouragement and comfort, religion and faith in 
 its principles. A sovereign remedy for suicide is Shake- 
 speare's ''dread of something after death, that undiscovered 
 country," that pit of fire, a sterner and more substantial 
 reality to men blessed with the instincts of faith than the 
 very ground they tread. Nor ever yet did man or woman 
 take the sad and unholy step of self-murder, until hell by 
 repeated insults to conscience had worn in his or her mind 
 to a thin shadow of itself. 
 
 Against Nature. We intend to prove our verdict against 
 suicide without once appealing to Scripture or the teachings 
 of the Church. And we emphatically condemn the conduct 
 of whatever sages, modern or ancient, from motives of moral 
 cowardice and selfishness ran counter in this respect to the 
 canons of right reason. No man is so wise but that free will, 
 influenced by mean and ungodly motives, can lead him into 
 the commission of horrible crimes. Socrates, Plato and others 
 were lying to their own hearts, when they endeavored to find 
 in philosophy an excuse for turpitude, into which want of 
 courage forced them. 
 
 Self-defense. This term is commonly used to denote the 
 act of opposing force to violence when unjustly attacked. 
 When it results in the death of the offender, no moral wrong 
 attaches to the slayer, if certain conditions have place. One 
 is at liberty to use this prerogative of self-defense, not only 
 when his life is in danger, but also when threatened with the 
 loss of some other great good, like wealth, virtue, bodily in- 
 tegrity. It likewise enables a friend to rescue a friend from 
 death or other heavy loss at the hands of an assassin or 
 thief. Self-defense is no legitimate plea for excuse, when 
 harm is threatened by one in a position to inflict just punish- 
 ment. For instance, the criminal condemned to death by the 
 state has no right whatever to defend himself against the 
 executioner of the law's sentence. A child has no right to 
 
SELF-DEFENSE 209 
 
 resist a parent when chastised ; a pupil has no right to quarrel 
 with a punishment. 
 
 Philosophy further recognises these four conditions as neces- 
 sary of fulfilment. First, the violence done the aggressor 
 must be exerted only while the danger actually exists, not 
 before, not after the attack. Besides, no other method of 
 escape than a return of violence for violence must be in the 
 innocent party's power. If flight is possible, flight must be 
 had recourse to. No amount of dread concerning a reputa- 
 tion for cowardice will justify the killing of another. Sec- 
 ondly, no severer measures must be taken than are absolutely 
 necessary. If a blow in the face will prove sufficient safe- 
 guard, a severe wound with a weapon is not justifiable. If 
 a severe wound will serve to stay the aggressor, the party 
 attacked must rest satisfied with inflicting the wound, and 
 must not proceed to slay his assailant. Thirdly, there must 
 exist between the good defended and the harm done the 
 wrong-doer a well defined proportion. This provision is of 
 special importance, when the protection of wealth or property 
 is in question. Thus, a small sum of money is so little worth 
 in comparison with a human life, that reason cries out against 
 murdering a petty thief to save the contents of a pocketbook. 
 Fourthly, revenge must have no part in the proceeding. No 
 motive but that of self-defense pure and simple will justify 
 an act so serious in its consequences as the destruction of a 
 fellow-being. These four conditions combine to rid an act 
 done in self defense of the moral wrong under other cir- 
 cumstances resident in it. They operate to bring about the 
 state of things expressed by that phrase consecrated in the 
 Latin tongue. ''Servato moderamine inculpatae tutelae," 
 ** Observing always the due measure or moderation that frees 
 self-defense from blame. ' ' 
 
 Of course, these precautions approve themselves to reason. 
 It is, however, one thing to see their force and fairness, when 
 coolly studying the subject; another, to apply them in the 
 heat of action, when pressed into a tight corner, where a 
 second's delay may mean death for the irresolute. Many a 
 crime of murder, we are aware, is committed under the cloak 
 of self-defense, and the Universal Reckoner alone can dis- 
 
210 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 tinguish genuine from spurious cases. Civil law can hardly 
 enter into men's motives. It decides, and generally has to 
 decide, with the help of whatever light facts lend. It must 
 of necessity exercise leniency towards the accused, who enters 
 a plea of self-defense ; and must give him the benefit of every 
 little circumstance that favors his cause. We are ourselves 
 disposed to be easy with the man brought face to face with 
 death through no fault of his own, and forced by a mad 
 adversary to make up his mind without much time for re- 
 flection. Theologians introduce into this question topics, that, 
 without affecting the irreligious, have a practical bearing on 
 the lives of religious people. They ask, for instance, if it is 
 lawful to kill a drunken or mad assailant; if it is lawful to 
 kill in defense of a neighbor ; if it is lawful to kill when limbs 
 are endangered, when chastity is assailed, or honor. They 
 discuss what manner of threat constitutes an assault, and 
 the relative weight of a blow in the face, when aimed at a 
 man of dignity and an ordinary person. 
 
 Duels. Some regard the duel a species of self-defense. It 
 is a means to which so-called gentlemen resort when their 
 honor, not their life or material wealth, is in danger. The 
 barbarous practice is now well nigh dead; but less than a 
 hundred years ago it was conspicuously alive in our own 
 country. Public opinion has finally succeeded in frowning 
 it down, and, though preliminaries are even now arranged 
 in the newspapers, the hostile meeting seldom or never has 
 place. The custom has a long history. Traces of it are found 
 in the earliest writings. It is, however, safe to say that the 
 private duel is an invention of comparatively modern times. 
 David and Goliath, the heroes of Homer, Livy's triplets, the 
 Horatii and Curiatii, fought duels of a harmless and legiti- 
 mate kind. The combatants in these several cases engaged 
 in what for distinction's sake we style a public duel. They 
 were representatives chosen by the leaders of two contending 
 armies to defend by their prowess the fortunes of their re- 
 spective sides, and no moral blame whatever attached to their 
 act or its promoters. If reason sanctions war and allows 
 whole armies of men to perish for the reestablishment of 
 equity and peace, it is difficult to see how reason can enter 
 a disclaimer against a species of combat, which settles the 
 
DUEL 211 
 
 question of supremacy at the expense of one or a half dozen 
 lives. Public duelling would on the contrary appear to be a 
 humane substitute for the horrors of war. If the late rebellion 
 or the recent World-Conflict could have been settled in some 
 such way, a world of loss would have been saved the coun- 
 try. 
 
 Barbarians first gave to single combat a color of religion. 
 They counted it an appeal to the God of right; and, when 
 other testimony was wanting, called on Heaven in this crude 
 way for a decision. The Trial by Ordeal had its origin in 
 the same mistaken notion of Providence. Legislators of the 
 Middle Ages had to consult these superstitions of their people, 
 and enacted stringent measures to regulate loss of life. The 
 Truce of God, established in 1041, forbidding duels, out of 
 respect for the Saviour's Passion, between Wednesday and 
 Monday, served as a check to frequency of duels. Every na- 
 tion in history had its troubles with this abuse. As long 
 as parties to a dispute agreed to submit their differences to 
 the court of single combat, with the approval and under the 
 direction of judicial authority, the evil was somewhat re- 
 stricted, and wore a less repugnant appearance. But, when 
 individuals, without any permission from the state, took jus- 
 tice into their own hands, and made skill in the use of weapons 
 the sole arbiter of right and wrong, duelling lost its religious 
 aspect, and degenerated to wholesale butchery. It was in 
 any event a sad spectacle, and a growth of ignorance; but 
 under these new conditions it was revolting in the extreme 
 and attended with dreadful consequences. 
 
 Frenchmen have always kept well to the front in this par- 
 ticular branch of barbarity. Richelieu opposed the practice 
 with all the strength of his legislative genius; and, to strike 
 terror into its patrons, stopped not at beheading in 1627 one 
 of the nobility. Count Francois de Montmorency. In Ger- 
 many duelling is much in use at the universities; but, as 
 swords are the weapons, and the bodies of the contestants are 
 well protected, these encounters usually result in a few face- 
 scratches, and seldom prove fatal. Among Irishmen Daniel 
 'Council killed at least one adversary on the field of honor, 
 D'Esterre, and his conduct in this particular filled the later 
 years of his life with regret and sorrow. In America Hamil- 
 
212 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 ton and Burr fought a historic duel in 1804. Hamilton, the 
 first treasurer of the United States, was killed, and Burr 
 passed into obscurity and oblivion. Barron and Decatur, a 
 man universally loved and one of our most celebrated commo- 
 dores, fought soon after the War of 1812 at Bladensburg, a 
 village about seven miles outside of Washington. Decatur 
 was killed, Barron was severely wounded. The near neigh- 
 borhood of Bladensburg to Washington, a rendezvous for all 
 the political worthies of the country, made it a desirable loca- 
 tion for battle-ground, and many a duel was negotiated there 
 in the early days of the last century. Clay and Randolph 
 fought in 1826. Andrew Jackson killed a Charles Dickinson, 
 and participated in other affairs. Benton of Missouri killed 
 a Mr. Lucas. Two members of Congress, Cilley of Maine and 
 Graves of Kentucky, fought near Washington in 1838. Cilley 
 was killed. Richard Somers had a record of three duels in 
 one day. Debates on the floor of Congress often precipitated 
 disputes, a challenge followed, and one or both of two fools 
 died in the gray of the morning. 
 
 The custom may fairly be said to have taken its rise from the 
 false notion that chance would favor the party in the right, 
 and so manage matters that the wrong-doer would fall. But 
 chance has no real existence, and God, who disposes of things 
 in creation, has nowhere promised to turn the tide of victory 
 this way or that. He has put at men's disposal other and 
 more efficient remedies for wrongs done their honor, and these 
 remedies are to be sought at the bar of duly constituted 
 tribunals. If survival means vindication, that principal in a 
 duel generally won it, who had the steadier arm, the truer 
 aim, and the better education in the use of weapons. Duel- 
 ling, therefore, defeats the very purpose for which it was 
 instituted. Of course, a certain amount of bull-dog courage 
 is displayed in the acceptance of a challenge, and this circum- 
 stance may help to commend the practice to some. They 
 feel, no doubt, that, whether victor or victim, they have at 
 least proved to the world that they are no cowards, and that 
 friends will applaud their heroism in spite of the insult or 
 insinuation that provoked the combat. 
 
 But common sense has at last begun to assert itself, and the 
 civilization of to-day reserves its applause for valor of a 
 
PROOFS 213 
 
 sterner sort than the recklessness common to duellists and in- 
 furiated bulls. Public opinion' frowns down exhibitions of 
 the kind, and >the makers of our literature have done much 
 to bring about this happy result. Sheridan in his play, ' ' The 
 Rivals," mercilessly ridicules the custom. Writers poke fun 
 at the abominable practice, and take advantage of every op- 
 portunity to show it up in its true colors. The consequence 
 is that lucky rascals, who escaped the death they richly de- 
 served, are no longer reckoned heroes. They are banished 
 from good society, they are approached with horror, and their 
 company is always productive of unease and discomfort. 
 They are rated for what they in reality are, genteel murder- 
 ers, with the blood of fellow-men on their guilty heads, and 
 crying out to Heaven for vengeance. A prize fight would not 
 Seem to be a duel, with this for definition: ^'A combat with 
 deadly weapons, fought in a private cause, without the sanc- 
 tion of public authority, with prior agreement concerning 
 weapons, seconds, place and time.'' 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Three Parts— I, II, III 
 
 I. Suicide. 
 II. Self-defense. 
 III. Duelling. 
 
 PROOFS • 
 
 I. 1°. An act subversive of man's duty to God is a sin 
 against nature. But suicide is an act of the sort. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Reason or nature insists on 
 the observance of relations in force between God and rational 
 creatures. These relations constitute duties, and violence 
 done them is denominated a sin against nature. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. We know from experience, 
 from man's inability to produce life, that God alone is the 
 author and preserver of life. We know, further, that God 
 bestows life with a definite end in view. It is to be scrupu- 
 lously used as a means towards establishing in ourselves and 
 others moral order, and compassing eternal happiness. He 
 
214 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 gives man no absolute dominion over his life, but only what 
 philosophers term use-ownership. Man is therefore obliged 
 to apply life to the uses for which it is plainly intended, and 
 keep to his post just as long as God sees fit to continue his 
 existence. The fact that man is vested with the physical 
 power to put a period to his life, is no sign that God has con- 
 ferred on him absolute dominion over it. The same argument 
 would hold good in the case of a thief unjustly possessed of 
 another's property, or a murderer sending some weaker victim 
 to death. Man's ability to inflict death on himself is only 
 another effect of God's determination to leave His creature 
 absolute freedom of will, and another proof that willingness 
 or refusal to serve is a matter entirely within the domain of 
 man's unrestrained choice. 
 
 2°. An act subversive of man's duty to himself is a sin 
 against nature. But suicide is an act of the kind. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Man has duties towards his 
 soul and body, and by deliberately cutting short his days he 
 works irreparable injury to both. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Life, because of the chance to 
 hope, is always and under whatever circumstances better even 
 for the body than death. As far as the mind is concerned, 
 no ills of life can rob it of opportunities to improve and 
 enjoy itself. No matter what misfortunes overtake a man, 
 no matter what pains and diseases distress him, he has it 
 always in his power to compass his supremely last end, which 
 we long ago agreed to call eternal happiness. He has it 
 always in his power to add by repeated acts of virtue to the 
 degree of glory awaiting him after death. Fortitude, pa- 
 tience, resignation to the Creator's will, all these meritorious 
 acts put on new splendor, when exercised in the midst of 
 trials and difficulties. Pagan poets and philosophers pause 
 in their writings to contemplate and praise the heroism of 
 suffering undergone in the cause of conscience; the sub- 
 limity of manly virtue struggling against odds that would 
 overwhelm natures of a weaker sort. Seneca thinks no spec- 
 tacle so worthy of Jove as that presented by a just man, en- 
 gaged in a battle with adversity. Horace has these lines, 
 **Justum et tenacem propositi virum — Si fractus illabatur 
 orbis — Impavidum ferient ruinae." ''If the world fell in 
 
PROOFS 215 
 
 ruins at his feet, the just and resolute man of principle would 
 present a bold front to the crash." 
 
 3°. An act subversive of man's duty to society is a sin 
 against nature. But suicide is an act of the kind. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Man's birth into society gives 
 rise to a kind of contract. Neighbors, banded together with 
 him for the common good, tacitly agree to procure for him 
 blessings absolutely out of reach in other contingencies. He, 
 on his part, promises in effect to make due return to society 
 for the advantages procured, and in cutting short his life he 
 ignominiously falls away from his promise. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Every member of society is in 
 justice bound to contribute his share towards advancing the 
 interests of the community of which he forms part. He 
 proves recreant to this solemn obligation when from shame, 
 cowardice, or impatience he sneaks from the ranks and lays 
 new burdens on other men's shoulders. I say nothing of the 
 infinite harm a suicide does his family and intimate friends. 
 It may happen that he leaves a wife and children to starve, 
 or eke out a miserable existence on the charity of others. Cer- 
 tainly, he leaves as an inheritance to connections a blot of 
 shame and a measure of disgrace, that no time or endeavor 
 can wholly eradicate. Society has a right to expect from him 
 an example of constancy, courage and magnanimity, and he 
 slinks away conspicuous for weakness, cowardice, and a mean- 
 ness of spirit without parallel. 
 
 II. A legitimate means to the effective preservation of a 
 well founded right is justifiable. But death inflicted in self- 
 defense is a legitimate means to the effective preservation of 
 a well founded right. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. A right vests its owner with 
 the moral prerogative to enforce in others respect for its 
 sacredness. It privileges the owner to use even physical 
 violence, when men deaf to moral instincts attempt to assail 
 it. A right would in any other supposition lose much of its 
 efficacy, and would be of small practical utility. The world 
 would be reduced to chaos, and injustice would everywhere 
 prevail. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Life, liberty and the pursuit 
 of happiness are in the words of our Constitution inalienable 
 
216 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 rights, and all three may be seriously interfered with by at- 
 tempts from without. The death of the offender is at times 
 the only effective bar against loss of life or property, and, 
 as a consequence, desirable and morally correct. In such an 
 event the transgressor, by deliberately putting himself in 
 the wrong, forfeits his right to live, and, if killed, is done no 
 injustice. Nobody can hesitate to regard the assailant 's death 
 an effective means to the preservation of rights involved. 
 That it is a legitimate means, is evident from the circumstance 
 that the innocent party would have to otherwise yield up 
 his own life, or some possession a little less valuable, merely 
 out of kindness to the offender. But kindness or charity of 
 that sort is prescribed by no law of God or man. Love of 
 neighbor sins by excess, when it moves a man to love his 
 neighbor more than himself. To sacrifice one's life for a 
 neighbor's salvation is not to love the neighbor more than 
 self. That would be to sacrifice one's salvation for a neigh- 
 bor's. The killing of an aggressor is not always obligatory. 
 
 III. A means founded on false principles, unsuited to the 
 purpose intended, and wrong in itself, is highly absurd and 
 contrary to the law of nature. But private duels are such 
 a means. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Ethics can borrow no princi- 
 ples from falsehood, and wickedness shields itself behind ex- 
 cuses full of error, and easily detected. It is the mark of a 
 fool to employ in the prosecution of some work agencies cal- 
 culated to operate against and not in favor of the agent's aim. 
 Foolishness degenerates to heinous crime, when the methods 
 adopted, besides being unequal to the end proposed, are at- 
 tended by consequences as serious as those that accompany 
 private duels. A lavish waste of life is a direct insult to 
 Almighty God, and as such deserves the severest condemna- 
 tion on the score of morality. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. The private duel had its origin 
 among barbarians. The Lombards, with whom might always 
 prevailed over right, introduced it throughout Europe. The 
 Greeks and Romans, though acquainted with public duels, 
 were strangers to the other custom. In its origin, therefore, 
 this brutal practice rested on a notion subversive of all moral- 
 ity and truth, the sacredness of physical as compared with 
 
PROOFS 217 
 
 moral force. It was in a manner a necessary growth of early- 
 times, when law and order were subject to great upheavals, 
 and tribunals of justice were little respected. The supersti- 
 tious belief that God would interfere in an extraordinary way 
 to save the innocent and destroy the guilty, was a new and 
 grievous mistake added to the first blunder. In later times 
 revenge was the element uppermost in the minds of com- 
 batants, and duels were tolerated on the plea that individuals 
 have a right to seek on their own private account satisfaction 
 for injury done their honor. But no principle can be falser. 
 No community, no society or state could long subsist, if such 
 a mode of procedure were once sanctioned and came into 
 general use. For the settlement of disputes and reparation 
 of assailed honor we have courts by law established, and death 
 would result to authority, were any other process introduced. 
 Were duels not prohibited by conscience, by reason proclaim- 
 ing the truth, enemies in private life would fall to butchering 
 one another, and the State would become a wilderness. 
 
 The absurdity of duelling is manifest from the fact that it 
 shockingly fails to serve the purpose for which it was insti- 
 tuted. Whether it be viewed as a means of repairing the 
 wrong done a man's honor and reputation, or considered a 
 possible means of revenge, it has no one -feature to recommend 
 it. It is not an apt instrument for satisfaction, because the 
 innocent party is just as likely to forfeit his life as the guilty. 
 The event of the combat proves simply that the survivor man- 
 aged his sword or pistol with more skill and dexterity than his 
 victim. It certainly leaves the guilt or innocence of the sur- 
 vivor as much an open question as it was before the meeting. 
 If the innocent party falls, where is the revenge? Certainly 
 the man guilty of the wrong done by the injury or insult had 
 no claims to revenge, and entered not into the struggle to 
 vindicate himself. Honor is not man's highest good. And 
 true honor is not praise in the mouths of men, but inward 
 consciousness of right conduct and a virtuous life. 
 
 But the characteristic that emphatically condemns duelling 
 is its own objective immorality. It involves a two-fold mal- 
 ice. The duellist commits a double crime with all the malice 
 of attempted murder and attempted suicide; and on no few 
 occasions the two attempts become accomplished realities. 
 
218 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 The duellist, therefore, incurs whatever blame attaches to 
 murder and suicide. In morality, because will is the pre- 
 dominating factor, the difference between the attempt to do 
 evil and the actual accomplishment of evil is accidental, and 
 therefore negligible. 
 
 PEINCIPLES— SUICIDE 
 
 A. Distinguish between direct and indirect killing of self. 
 Direct is suicide. Indirect is death foreseen in some act put 
 for a legitimate purpose. Instances are, a fatal operation, 
 jump from a high window in time of fire, nurse to plague- 
 stricken. 
 
 B. Destruction is supreme act of ownership. Man is vested 
 with no such ownership in life, because its primary purpose 
 is not man's advantage, but the greater glory of God. 
 
 C. Instinct of self-preservation is index of God's will in 
 the matter, and of His disapproval of suicide. 
 
 D. God's permission can be presumed when serious spirit- 
 ual dangers threaten, or life becomes oppressive. 
 
 Answer: Life's chief purpose, the greater glory of God, 
 never becomes impossible; and only in this case can He be 
 supposed to give permission. With His grace, whatsoever 
 spiritual danger can be met and overcome ; and patience is a 
 virtue. 
 
 E. Direct mutilation partakes of the malice of suicide. And 
 yet man is the steward of his life, if not its absolute owner. 
 He is allowed to preserve his life at the expense of a limb. 
 The part ranks lower than the whole. 
 
 P. Saints, who rushed to death, acted under inspiration, 
 or through invincible ignorance, or committed indirect self- 
 killing. 
 
 G. Our second and third arguments against suicide pre- 
 suppose the first. Thus, the drunkard committing suicide 
 after a mission and a good confession would perhaps be con- 
 sulting his own interests, but at the expense of God's rights 
 as owner. With St. Paul we can long to be dissolved and be 
 with Christ, but always in a spirit of resignation to God's 
 will. 
 
 H. We can reject a gift. Life is a gift. Ergo. 
 
PRINCIPLES 219 
 
 Answer: A gift meant primarily for our advantage and 
 subject to absolute ownership, I grant ; a gift meant primarily 
 for the giver's advantage, and subject to only use-ownership, 
 I deny. 
 
 N.B. Suicide is more than rejection, it is destruction of 
 life. 
 
 I. Hume argues thuswise. If we cannot interfere with the 
 course of nature to shorten life, we cannot interfere with the 
 course of nature to prolong it. Eadem est contrariorum 
 ratio. Ergo, it would be wrong to push aside a falling stone 
 that threatened destruction. 
 
 Answer: Use-ownership empowers and obliges us to pre- 
 serve or prolong our life. It vests us with no right to destroy 
 same. That is the exclusive prerogative of absolute owner- 
 ship. We are stewards, not proprietors. 
 
 J. It is lawful to choose a lesser evil for the purpose of 
 escaping a greater. 
 
 Answer: The saying has some force in question of phys- 
 ical evil, none in question of moral evil. In the case of self, 
 it can never become necessary to commit one sin to avoid 
 others. It is always quite possible to avoid all sin. In the 
 case of others, it would be highly wrong to commit one sin to 
 prevent them from committing a thousand. Moral evil is 
 never justified by good. The end never 'justifies the means. 
 Suicide would be the lesser evil only in the supposition that 
 it is not sinful. The smallest sin is a greater evil than phys- 
 ical evil of whatever magnitude. 
 
 K. Suicide is wrong because the man does himself an in- 
 justice. Nobody can do himself an injustice. Volenti nulla 
 fit injuria. 
 
 Answer: Suicide is an injustice to God as well as to its 
 perpetrator. Man has duties towards himself, and to fall 
 away from them is injustice. The saying admits of excep- 
 tions, e.g., fraud in law. 
 
 L. Hunters dispose of birds and beasts without ownership 
 in them. Ergo, a pari, a man ought to be able to dispose of 
 his life without ownership in it. 
 
 Answer: Hunters have no particular or private owner- 
 ship empowering them to exclude others. I grant. Hunters 
 have no universal or general ownership as in things belong- 
 
S30 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 ing to nobody in particulai*, I deny. Birds, beasts and all 
 lower creation are by nature man's property to use them and 
 destroy them as he sees fit. 
 
 M. A criminal condemned to death may lawfully execute 
 himself at the bidding of authority. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: In suicide there is question not of public, but of 
 private authority. Besides, some authors deny the legitimacy 
 of every such proceeding, and they assign two reasons. The 
 state is allowed to kill only as a measure of justice, and no- 
 body can be expected to execute justice on himself. Nobody 
 is a good judge in his own case, and therefore nobody is a 
 fit executioner of himself. Every such arrangement is directly 
 opposed to nature's instinct for self-preservation. Law must 
 be possible. 
 
 N. One must take means to preserve his life and health; 
 generally speaking he need not take extraordinary means, 
 such as occasion serious inconvenience. Serious inconvenience 
 excuses from affirmative law, and God is a prudent law-maker. 
 The penances and fasts of the saints are opposed to no law of 
 nature, even though they weaken the body and shorten life. 
 Spiritual good is of a higher order than life and health. The 
 harm done the body and life is indirect, not direct. 
 
 0. It is often lawful to expose oneself to death, when death 
 is not directly intended, and a proportionate cause justifies the 
 proceeding. Soldiers taken prisoners are not allowed to kill 
 themselves to escape doing service to their captors. Sailors 
 are allowed to jump from a burning vessel into the sea to es- 
 cape death by fire. A soldier in time of war is allowed to set 
 fire to a ship or tower, though it means instant death for him- 
 self, if the act causes heavy damage to the enemy. 
 
 PRINCIPLES— SELF-DEFENSE 
 
 A. This privilege of self-defense extends farther than life 
 or property. A woman has a right to kill an assailant in de- 
 fense of her chastity. Nobody has the right to kill another in 
 defense of his honor or reputation. 
 
 B. An insane or drunken person is an unjust assailant, not 
 formally but materially. The child in a mother's womb is 
 in no sense of the word an unjust assailant. The mother 
 
PRINCIPLES 221 
 
 causes the collision of rights, and must yield to the child. 
 When violence is done her, neither she nor the child is to 
 blame; and yet she comes closer to blame than the child for 
 the condition of affairs, and must suffer accordingly. 
 
 C. Self-defense procures damnation of the assailant. Ergo, 
 wrong. Self-defense sacrifices greater good to lesser. Ergo, 
 wrong. 
 
 Answer: Essentially and of itself, I deny ; accidentally and 
 by way of occasion, I grant. Charity forbids us to procure 
 another's damnation the first way, not the second way, unless 
 the thing can be avoided without great inconvenience, and the 
 neighbor is in extreme need. The thing can be avoided only 
 at the expense of the innocent party's life, and that would be 
 a rather serious inconvenience. The assailant is not in ex- 
 treme need, because he can refrain from attack. Besides, the 
 common good must be taken into account. Without this priv- 
 ilege life would be insecure. 
 
 D. In the case of a drunken or mad assailant damnation 
 would be sure. Ergo, wrong. 
 
 Answer: No moral certainty on these three points, the ex- 
 act spiritual condition of innocent party and assailant, and 
 future salvation of party in the wrong, if spared for con- 
 version. 
 
 E. It is wrong to kill another in defense of reputation or 
 honor, not because reputation is a smaller good than life, 
 property is that, but because the moderamen inculpatae tu- 
 telae is seldom or never verified. It is next to impossible to 
 be sure of the serious harm attaching to slander, calumny and 
 detraction before the harm is actually done, and then it is too 
 late for defense ; defense is out of the question, revenge alone 
 is in order. Besides, escape from the harm is within easy 
 reach of less radical measures. Opposite doctrine would be 
 open to great abuse, and, though no doctrine is to be con- 
 demned because of extrinsic and accidental abuses, every doc- 
 trine, accompanied like this by intrinsic and essential abuses, 
 deserves condemnation. 
 
 F. Reputation is a more precious possession than life. 
 Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Fundamentally taken, inner virtue and honesty, 
 I grant; formally taken, outer esteem and credit, I deny. 
 
222 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Reputation is the judgment passed by others on our conduct 
 and affairs. Honor is outward manifestation of the good 
 esteem we have of others. Fama from fando, to talk, the way 
 men talk about us. 
 
 G. The end never justifies the means. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Homicide is the means, and homicide is not in- 
 trinsically evil. Otherwise capital punishment would be 
 wrong. It is a physical evil and in itself morally indifferent. 
 While the end never justifies an intrinsically evil means, it 
 often justifies a physically evil and a morally indifferent 
 means. 
 
 H. God's right as Master of life and death is violated by 
 the assailant, not by the innocent party. 
 
 I. We must love our enemies, but not more than we love 
 ourselves. In all honesty we could account ourselves worthy 
 of no better fate, were we the unjust assailant. 
 
 J. In this case, we should be in duty bound to kill our 
 assailant. 
 
 Answer: Homicide is an extraordinary means, and we are 
 held to only ordinary means. Circumstances like the support 
 of a family can render self-defense a serious obligation. 
 
 K. Self-defense is not a morally bad act put to compass a 
 good end. It is a morally good act, the preservation of one's 
 life, and from this good act a physical evil follows, loss of 
 life on the part of the unjust assailant. This death is not to 
 be imputed to the innocent slayer, but to the unjust assailant. 
 
 PRINCIPLES— DUELLING 
 
 A. The duel is a species of defense against loss of prop- 
 erty. To refuse a duel means dismissal from the army, re- 
 duction in rank, and consequent loss of livelihood. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: One must lose his livelihood rather than per- 
 petrate an intrinsically evil deed. A duel contracts the mal- 
 ice of attempted murder and attempted suicide, and both 
 deeds are intrinsically evil. A duel is no defense against an 
 unjust assailant; and, therefore, the attempt on a rival's life 
 has all the malice of murder. It is no mere exposure of life 
 to a risk justified by a proportionate cause ; and, therefore, it 
 has all the malice of suicide. We are allowed to undergo dan- 
 
PRINCIPLES 223 
 
 ger to life with a proportionate reason. We are never al- 
 lowed to seek danger to life with or without a proportionate 
 reason. The duellist more than undergoes danger, he seeks 
 it; because by the very seeking of danger he vindicates his 
 reputation for bravery. A nurse in time of the plague merely 
 exposes himself to danger, because his whole purpose is to 
 minister to the sick, and danger contributes nothing to this 
 purpose. In other words, the duellist makes risk to life a 
 means to his end; the nurse employs other means like medi- 
 cine, food, care and attention, and to these means danger is, 
 much against his wishes, inseparably attached. 
 
 B. The state has no right to authorize a duel for the set- 
 tlement of justice between two disputants. It is the state's 
 duty to settle such disputes on their merits, punishing the 
 guilty and freeing the innocent. If unable to arrive at a de- 
 cision, it must give the benefit of the doubt to the accused. 
 The state is not allowed to arbitrarily treat guilty and inno- 
 cent alike by exposing them to the same risk. The state ought 
 to put down duelling, and not encourage it. The Trial by 
 Ordeal was all wrong and the Church consistently opposed 
 it. God has nowhere promised to favor the innocent in tests 
 of the kind. 
 
 C. Duels between students are sometimes against the law 
 of nature, because they lead to serious wounds and mutilation. 
 
 D. Though a prize-fight is not a duel properly so called, 
 on occasions it would seem to be against the law of nature. 
 
 E. It is lawful to use the one and fit means for defending 
 honor. But the duel is such. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: If the one and fit means is at the same time legi- 
 timate, I grant ; otherwise, I deny. A duel is the one and fit 
 means not of itself and by nature, but by accident and the 
 wrong views of men. 
 
 F. The duel is said to be wrong, because the good it effects 
 is out of proportion with the evil. But the preservation of 
 honor, rank and wealth is not out of proportion with risk to 
 life. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Because the immediate effect is out of propor- 
 tion, I grant; because the remote effect is out of proportion, 
 I deny. The immediate effect is to show courage, and that is 
 out of proportion. Honor, rank, property are but the remote 
 
224 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 effects and even they are out of proportion. Honor is two- 
 fold, honor in root, virtue and other good qualities provoking 
 the esteem of others; and formal honor, the good esteem of 
 others. Honor in first sense is intrinsic to the man and su- 
 perior to life. Honor in the second sense is extrinsic to the 
 man and far inferior to life. Honor in root is the man's own 
 affair and cannot be touched by the neighbor. Formal honor, 
 the kind duels mend, is beyond a man 's own control and alto- 
 gether dependent on the neighbor's whim and fancy. 
 
 G. A duel in no way resembles self-defense, because prior 
 agreement is of its essence. This circumstance separates the 
 duel from an ordinary fight or shooting-match. 
 
 H. The man who refuses to honor a challenge is a coward 
 in the eyes of fools alone, and their opinion is no safe stand- 
 ard of morality. Moral courage is of a higher order than 
 physical. 
 
 I. A woman is allowed to defend her honor to the extent of 
 killing an assailant. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Honor in this case means more than mere es- 
 teem ; it means bodily integrity or chastity. 
 
THESIS III 
 
 A lie is always and of its very nature wrong. To safeguard 
 a proportionate right, the use of a broad mental reservation is 
 allowed. Jouin, 106-109 ; Rickahy, 224-237. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 In this matter of man 's duty towards his neighbor, we single 
 out the obligation of truthfulness and respect for the right of 
 property in others. We treat these questions in separate 
 theses, giving our first attention to the moral aspect of lying. 
 Because truth is due the neighbor, and because men have an 
 inviolable right to whatever they legitimately make their own, 
 these two duties are branches or departments of the compre- 
 hensive virtue called justice, that habit of mind and will 
 eternally ready to give to everybody his due. We shall see 
 later that the lie is formally a sin against truth, not against 
 justice. 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Thesis has two parts — 
 I. The lie. 
 II. The reservation. 
 
 PART I. LIE— TERMS 
 
 I. A Lie. The Latin verb mentiri, meaning to lie, fur- 
 nishes us with a true definition of the thing. It is supposed 
 to be a shortened form of the expression, contra mentem ire, 
 or menti ire, and signifies to go against the mind. Hence, 
 a lie is best described as locutio contra mentem, speech or 
 language conveying the opposite of what we have in our mind. 
 It is want of harmony between what we say and what we 
 think. It is opposed to moral truth. Truth is threefold: 
 logical, ontological and moral; and harmony with something 
 is the generic notion common to all three. Logical is har- 
 
 225 
 
226 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 mony of mind with outside things, and affects our knowledge; ; 
 ontological is harmony of things outside with the mind of 
 their fashioner, and is said with reference to creatures and 
 God; moral is harmony of language with thought, and is pe- 
 culiar to intercourse of man with man. As we shall imme- 
 diately see from St. Thomas, deception and intention to de- 
 ceive play no part in the essential constitution of a lie. A 
 material lie can be formal truth, and a formal lie can be ma- 
 terial truth. No moral guilt, of course, attaches to a mere 
 material lie, because moral blame attaches to the will alone, 
 and in a material lie the will is right, the intellect is at fault. 
 
 St. Thomas is a safe guide in philosophy, as well as in 
 theology, and it may, therefore, be useful to here note down 
 what he has to say on the subject. I quote, therefore, at some 
 length from his Summary of Theology. In the 2nd of the 
 2nd part, quest. 110, art. I, he has what follows : 
 
 *' Truth and falsehood are the proper objects of speech. A 
 disordered will can in this matter have one of two intentions 
 or both, either to communicate a falsehood or, as an effect of 
 the communication, to deceive some one. If therefore these 
 three elements are present, viz. : falsehood of communication, 
 a wish to communicate falseness and the desire to deceive, 
 then is the lie a material one, because a falsehood is communi- 
 cated ; a formal one, because it is wilfully and knowingly com- 
 municated; and effective, because deception is wilfully and 
 knowingly intended. Nevertheless, the lie derives its essence 
 from the second element, i.e., the wish to communicate false- 
 ness, or a falsehood wilfully and knowingly communicated. 
 Wherefore a lie receives its name in Latin from the fact that 
 it is something said contrary to the mind's conviction. The 
 circumstance that one designs to affect another 's opinion with 
 falseness belongs not to the nature or essence of a lie, but 
 to a further perfection of the same. Even so with things in 
 nature, an object, when once it assumes the form, attains to 
 its allotted place in the universe of existences, even though 
 the effect generally accompanying the form is for the time 
 being absent, as is evident for instance, in a thing of weight 
 when forcibly held aloft. ' ' 
 
 In the same part and question art. Ill in answer to the 4th 
 difficulty he says: 
 
LIE AND DECEPTION 227 
 
 **The sinfulness of a lie is derived not from the damage 
 alone which it does our neighbor, but from its want of har- 
 mony with the order of reason." 
 
 The learned Doctor 's words are quite plain. His idea seems 
 to be this — A moral falsehood or a lie consists, as far as mat- 
 ter goes, in want of harmony between what is in the mind 
 and the language used to express it. It, therefore, differs 
 from logical falsehood, which means a want of harmony be- 
 tween some object in nature and the mind's conception of it. 
 Hence a logical falsehood can readily enough be foundation 
 for a moral truth ; and a logical truth, foundation for a moral 
 falsehood. Yet, such a factor is the will in all questions of 
 morality, that the material moral falsehood is blameless until 
 the intention of communicating as true matter known and 
 understood to be false accrues to it and by union completes, 
 perfects and finishes the lie properly so called. He insists 
 very much on this point because the introduction of a third 
 element, viz., the deception of our neighbor, is made too much 
 account of by some authors. 
 
 The third element is a merely accidental circumstance, and 
 contributes nothing to the naked essence of a lie. It is quite 
 true that every lie will be accompanied by this third element 
 or characteristic. For, it is difficult to conceive of a false 
 communication known to be such, which will not at the same 
 time procure, at least in intention, a neighbor's deception. 
 But the lie is in full consummated, though this element be 
 entirely wanting. As soon as the speaker attempts in his 
 language to convey an untruth known to be such, so soon does 
 he lie, whether he intends to deceive, or to amuse, or to help, 
 or to injure his neighbor. The injury done his neighbor may 
 be inseparably connected with the lie, and may have been 
 uppermost in the liar's mind; but the injury derives its mal- 
 ice not from the circumstance that it is a lie, but from the fact 
 that it is a wounding of charity, something quite distinct 
 from the virtue of truth. 
 
 PROOF 
 
 I. The lie has its intrinsic malice from this, that it is a 
 falling away from our duty, not precisely to our neighbor, 
 
228 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 but to God and to ourselves. He has wisely ordained, for the 
 good of society, that words should communicate ideas, which 
 would otherwise be so much dead lumber, for purposes of use 
 to the neighbor. He has imbedded within us an instinct, as 
 present as the nose on our face, influencing us to cherish 
 truthfulness in our dealings one with another. The liar reck- 
 lessly tramples this ordinance of God, and stifles within him- 
 self an instinct, which is among Heaven's purest and best 
 gifts. Hence it is that God, who is avenger of broken ordi- 
 nances and a jealous watcher of His gifts to man, punishes 
 in a way known only to His victims the deliberate and down- 
 right liar. I should call for no more potent proof of God's 
 interference in this matter than that furnished by the blush 
 of shame and the self-condemning perturbation, visible all 
 over the countenance of a liar in the beginning of his career, 
 or of the ingenuous youth whose poorly ordered self-love has 
 ensnared him into a cowardly untruth. 
 
 PRINCIPLES— LYING 
 
 A. Hugo Grote, a Hollander, for the seeming purpose of de- 
 ducing principles subversive of society, though flattering the 
 self-love of a dangerous few, offers this wrong definition of a 
 lie: ''A lie,'' he says, '4s language or a manifestation in 
 conflict with a right, which exists and belongs to him to whom 
 the language or manifestation is addressed or directed." 
 
 Were this the proper notion of a lie, to say nothing of other 
 absurdities painfully apparent in it, the liar's sin would in- 
 herit its essence from the injury done his neighbor. The con- 
 clusion, of course, would be that lies told by way of joke, 
 helpful lies, and lies told by men in responsible positions to 
 save a secret, are truths. We have already met this difficulty 
 and shown conclusively enough that the idea of the injury 
 done our neighbor by no means enters into the essential con- 
 struction of a lie, and that it is an after and accidental effect, 
 which may with the same influence on the act denominated a 
 lie be present or absent. Besides, let the two latter species 
 of a lie, countenanced by such false philosophers as Grote, 
 become prevalent, and the intercourse of man with man will 
 soon grow a scourge and a gift for which we should have 
 
PROOF AND PRINCIPLES 229 
 
 small occasion to thank Heaven. Remember, however, that 
 our decided and clearly expressed conviction with regard to 
 the intrinsic evil of lying is based not on the injury done the 
 neighbor, but on this one circumstance that it is an abuse of 
 language, that God and nature intended to be used as a 
 vehicle of thought. The inconvenience done the neighbor is 
 a weighty argument to deter men from lying, and perhaps 
 exerts a more universally dissuasive influence than our meta- 
 physical argument. Still it is an extrinsic element and may 
 lead to false, unfounded notions. 
 
 B. Milton, to prove that lying is at times admissible, asks 
 this empty question: ''If all killing be not murder; nor all 
 taking from another, theft; why must all untruths be lies?" 
 The answer at once suggests itself. Man must not kill an- 
 other when innocent, he must not take from another unless 
 necessity is extremely urgent ; because in the one case and the 
 other man has a right to his life and his property which he 
 has nowise forfeited. It is not his nature to live forever but 
 only as long as the body continues a fit tenement for the soul. 
 Universal ownership is of nature and inamissible ; but particu- 
 lar ownership is based on the man's own individual activity, 
 open to loss, accidental in itself, and natural only inasmuch 
 as it is rooted in the universal ownership which forever re- 
 mains. But the sheriff commits no murder ; the wretch dying 
 of hunger, no theft; because the capital offender against so- 
 ciety loses all prior claims to life, the former owner of the 
 property is, in case of another's dire necessity, divested of 
 his rights, nature depriving the property of any particular 
 and specific owner. The obligation a man owes his rational 
 nature in point of telling the truth can never change. In 
 other words man's claims to life and property do not turn 
 directly and wholly on his rational nature. His bounden 
 duty to tell the truth flows directly from his rational nature. 
 
 C. One author insists very much on what he styles his meta- 
 physical and absolute definition of a lie, viz., the privation 
 of truth that is or ought to be due. The definition goes to 
 greater lengths than is necessary, but its length does not 
 lessen its correctness. It is emphatically correct. His ex- 
 planation, however, of the word "due" is as emphatically 
 incorrect, and evidently introduced to remove difficulties that 
 
230 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 were better removed otherwise. Of course, lying is the priva- 
 tion of truth that is due ; but does it hence necessarily follow 
 that lying is the privation of such truth only as is due the 
 neighbor? Decidedly no! The truth in question may not 
 perhaps be due my neighbor, but I owe it to the God who 
 made me and to myself to use on all occasions language in 
 exact accordance with the ideas in my mind. 
 
 D. If deceit entered into the essential constitution of a lie, 
 the above author's remarks about primary and secondary 
 intentions, or secrecy and deceit, would be to the point. St. 
 Thomas a short while ago made it clear that the lie exists in a 
 finished state before deception enters upon the scene at all. 
 Deception may or may not be present. Its influence on the 
 lie as such is the same. Like all accidents it can, indeed, 
 modify the evil done. It can make it greater by adding a 
 sin of unkindness to that of cheating God's intent, but it 
 cannot make a bit of language truth or falsehood. Like all 
 things intrinsically or of their very nature evil, no conceiv- 
 able intention can make a lie good and praiseworthy. Who 
 can blaspheme without sinning, who can hate God without 
 sinning? But this impossibility arises from the mere cir- 
 cumstance that blasphemy and hatred of God are intrinsically 
 evil. In the same way the second, third, fourth and all the 
 intentions possible in a lie are swallowed up in the first, viz., 
 the wilful and deliberate communication of falseness as truth. 
 This intention comes first, this intention is the life and being 
 of a lie, and not even the gaining of Heaven can justify it. 
 
 E. A lie is wrong because it is an abuse of speech. But 
 other abuses are not wrong. Ergo, neither is a lie for this 
 single reason wrong. To walk on the hands is an abuse of 
 the hands, but not therefore wrong. 
 
 Answer: To walk on the hands is abuse of the hands in 
 strict sense, I deny; in wide sense, I grant. Abuse in strict 
 sense is use that destroys or hinders the purpose intended by 
 nature. Walking on the hands leaves them wholly capable 
 of the functions for which nature intended them. But a lie 
 aims at the destruction of speech's natural purpose, the com- 
 munication of our ideas or of truth. 
 
 F. The purpose of speech is the good of society and the 
 lie far from being a hindrance or a damage to society, is on 
 
PRINCIPLES 231 
 
 no few occasions a positive help and advantage to same. 
 Ergo. A lie can at times happen to be the readiest means to 
 avert a war or a murder. 
 
 Answer: Material advantage is not the criterion of moral- 
 ity, but the objective order of things. A lie is not primarily 
 wrong because it works evil to society, nor is the truth pri- 
 marily good because it is of advantage to society. Harmony 
 with the purpose of speech and discord with same constitute 
 the goodness of truth and the^ malice of lying respectively. 
 Even material advantage can never in the long run result 
 from an intrinsic evil like lying, and this is evident from the 
 Law of General Consequences discussed in the matter of Utili- 
 tarianism. But this is not the root-reason for the immorality 
 of lying. If a lie were allowed, to avert some particular evil 
 like war, or procure some particular good like a livelihood, 
 its approbation would work to the complete destruction of 
 credit among men, and that evil would be worse than a hun- 
 dred wars. 
 
 G. A lie might be permitted for very grave reasons, and 
 within these limits all danger would be removed. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: The danger would still stand, because in that 
 case every individual would be absolute judge of the weight 
 of his reasons; and credit would be universally shaken. Be- 
 sides, the lie is intrinsically and of its very nature wrong, 
 deriving its malice from no such accidental and extrinsic cir- 
 cumstances as harm and advantage. 
 
 H. Homicide in self-defense is right. Ergo, a pari, a lie 
 in self-defense is right. 
 
 Answer: Homicide is not an intrinsic evil, as is evident 
 from war, hanging and self-defense. Homicide is changed to 
 murder by the injustice done the person slain, and by the 
 usurpation of God's rights as the Lord and Master of life 
 and death. A lie is intrinsically wrong, and God Himself 
 cannot make it right. God cannot bestow on others a right, 
 in which He is not Himself vested. 
 
 I. To lie is to talk otherwise than as you think. But the 
 objector on a circle talks otherwise than as he thinks. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: The objector talks as he thinks, but he is at the 
 same time playing the part of another. Actor on stage. 
 
 J. Communication of thought to another, whether by speech 
 
232 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 or other arbitrary signs, is of the essence of a lie. It takes 
 two to converse, and in strict language nobody ever talks 
 to or addresses himself. Therefore, a false statement shouted 
 to vacancy or the wind is not in strict sense a lie. 
 
 K. Lies are usually divided into jocose, officious, official 
 and injurious. Not all jokes are jocose lies. Equivocation 
 and mental reservation save many jokes from the malice of 
 sin. Others, while plain misstatements, are so openly absurd 
 that they can be rated mere material falsehoods, free from the 
 guilt of a formal lie. Instances are, Washington is not dead. 
 Miss Liberty is walking the harbor. And yet many jokes are 
 lies, and their perpetrators incur all the blame of sin. Offi- 
 cious lies are meant to be helpful, injurious are meant to harm. 
 Outside of injurious lies, which wound charity as well as 
 truth, the sin is never more than venial. Official lies are sin- 
 ful subterfuges employed by men in authority to keep state 
 secrets, and are no less blameworthy than the rest. 
 
 L. The mouth that lies kills the soul. Wisdom 1-11. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Formally, I deny; preparatively, I grant. 
 
 PART II— RESERVATION 
 
 II. We now take up a few difficulties, which to some ap- 
 peared so formidable, that only a wide departure from phi- 
 losophy's common notion regarding a lie seemed capable of 
 solving them. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Reservation. Everybody grants that there are secrets with- 
 out end, which must under no consideration be delivered over 
 to unauthorized enquirers. Philosophers are a unit on this 
 point. But how to perform this nice and difficult duty with- 
 out at the same time wounding truth, is a task nowise easy. 
 Deep silence will not, it is quite certain, always extricate the 
 honest man from his straits. His secret may be natural, or 
 a secret of promise, or a secret of trust. We may suppose, 
 too, that matters are come to such a head that a direct answer 
 alone will satisfy the questioner. An innocent mental reser- 
 
MENTAL RESERVATION 233 
 
 vation seems to be on such an occasion the only means of 
 escape. It can be reconciled, too, with our rigorous doctrine 
 on lying, and needs no such laxity of principle as is advocated 
 by some authors. In mental reservation several very impor- 
 tant items must be carefully attended to, not precisely because 
 a lie is told, but because even though the truth is told, such 
 manner of telling the truth is full of danger to mutual con- 
 verse, to the union of families, and to the well-being of the 
 state. Observe, therefore, that the notion uppermost with us 
 in thus hedging about mental reservation with cautious con- 
 ditions is not at all to make lies less frequent, for on no occa- 
 sion do we consider a lie lawful, but only to shield man in 
 his dealings with his fellows. 
 
 There are, then, two sorts of mental reservation, one always 
 to be abominated, the other to be sometimes commended. 
 They are the pure and the broad. He uses a mental reserva- 
 tion, who, when conveying information, so manipulates his 
 words, that the listener will in all probability derive from 
 them only false notions. The pure mental reservation fur- 
 nishes the listener with no external clew to the truth, and 
 renders it absolutely impossible for him to escape the mis- 
 take ; and is in simple language a lie, under no circumstance 
 excusable. 
 
 Pure means language of itself, and from present circum- 
 stances, restricted to one meaning, out of harynony with mind 
 of speaker, in harmony with same when something retained in 
 the mind is added, e.g., ' ' Have you eaten anything ? ' ' "Noth- 
 ing at all," understanding meat. 
 
 Broad means language externally conveying the speaker ^s 
 true mind, intelligible from circumstances, in spite of a cer- 
 tain ambiguity and obscurity. Listener is cause per se of 
 deception, not talker. Proximate end is to convey mind. 
 Remote is to hide truth. Remote end must be legitimate. 
 Hence no broad in contracts, questions of justice, courts of 
 law. Only proportionate cause justifies. 
 
 Protestants are fond of reproaching us with the laxity of 
 our moral theologians in this matter of mental reservations. 
 But, whereas our moralists utterly condemn the pure, to ad- 
 mit the broad mental reservation only for the safeguarding 
 of a proportionate right, Cranmer, Henry VIII 's archbishop 
 
234 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 of London, when taking his oath of fealty to the Pope, con- 
 trived a pure mental reservation, a lie, and so stained his im- 
 mortal soul with a perjury unexampled. 
 
 PROOF 
 
 The broad mental reservation, available only when great 
 interests are at stake, not in every trifling affair, leaves it pos- 
 sible though difficult for the listener to still detect, if he 
 proceeds with prudence, the speaker's meaning. In other 
 words, the speaker returns to the questioner a double answer, 
 a jumble of what is in his mind and what is outside of it. 
 That part of his answer, which is language in harmony with 
 his mind, he considers, and every fair-minded man must con- 
 sider, a sufficiently truthful answer to the question; that 
 which is wide of the mark may be considered something super- 
 added, not intended indeed to form part of the answer to the 
 enquiry made, but to some enquiry that might have been made. 
 If the imprudent listener confounds one part with the other, 
 he has himself to blame ; and no great unkindness is done him. 
 But the lie is absent, not because no injury is directly done 
 the neighbor, but because the group of words can be con- 
 strued into a meaning in perfect harmony with the speaker's 
 mind. 
 
 This I recognize as the limit to which mental reservation 
 can be pushed, when it is borne in mind that only motives as 
 serious and grave as the saving of an innocent life, the reten- 
 tion of a close secret, liable if revealed to undo somebody, the 
 life of a state, can counterbalance, the baneful effects not of a 
 lie ; for, I repeat it, no lie is told ; but of the apparent unkind- 
 ness contained in the very act of giving to the person ad- 
 dressed an opportunity to go astray, and fervently wishing 
 that he may do so. The preservation of a cigarette is not 
 motive enough for a broad mental reservation. For a pure 
 mental reservation, between which and a lie I can see no 
 difference, even the preservation of the innocent is not mo- 
 tive enough. Remark, however, that, when an innocent life 
 is at stake, common charity obliges you to take all legitimate 
 means to its defense; and, therefore, common charity im- 
 peratively demands a broad mental reservation, that namely 
 
PROOF AND PRINCIPLES 235 
 
 which through the agency of some external sign leaves it pos- 
 sible for the person deceived to avoid deception. 
 
 PRINCIPLES— RESERVATION 
 
 A. About the prisoner at the bar in the civil court of jus- 
 tice, this solution appears most praiseworthy and is wholly 
 satisfactory. Words are but arbitrary signs. When, there- 
 fore, the expression, ''Not guilty," has come by the common 
 consent of mankind to mean, "Not proved guilty," a man, 
 though actually guilty, says nothing contrary to what he has 
 in his mind when he answers, ''Not guilty." For, even in 
 his own mind he is not proved guilty, and according to com- 
 mon usage or agreement, which alone imparts meaning to 
 words, he has made no other statement. 
 
 B. The priest is bound by his duty to an authority far 
 higher than that attached to any civil court of justice to pre- 
 serve inviolate a confessional secret. No sane, unprejudiced 
 judge will require at his hands the communication of such 
 a secret. But there are on record instances of bigoted and 
 unscrupulous ministers of the law, who endeavored to wrest 
 from the priest's bosom truths more sacred than fall to the 
 lot of physicians, lawyers or friends. In such cases it is a 
 sacred duty imposed upon the priest to maintain even unto 
 death his seal of secrecy. He is not, however, in any sense 
 of the word permitted to lie. He is at liberty to profess that 
 he knows nothing whatever of the matter in question, but 
 must contrive to give his hearers an opportunity to under- 
 stand, if they will, that he represents a twofold character, that 
 of the priest or representative of Christ, and that of the 
 citizen or subject of the law. He must, without at all com- 
 promising his penitent or endangering the seal of the confes- 
 sional, advertise the questioner of his determination and right 
 to answer all enquiries put to him as a citizen or witness in 
 his capacity of man or of individual of the community, not 
 in his capacity of representative and vice-gerent of God. His 
 answer, therefore, which intimates entire ignorance of the 
 subject under discussion, is not language out of harmony with 
 what he has in his mind, and therefore not a lie. As citizen, 
 he has no knowledge whatever of the point in question ; and 
 
23t SPBGEAL ETHIGS 
 
 ht ImalgBifted Ikis detcnunatkia and lif^ to ipeik in that 
 tmpmaltj on^. As fv as in liim Ucb, Iub language ahould 
 also QoiiTqr to tibe minds of liis bearers an exact represents- 
 of vbat ke widMS to eoHununieate. If tliey foolishly 
 that his denial extends also to knowledge acq[iiired 
 in tibe eonfesBbaal, they ha^e to Uame aaij thenselYes for 
 their ignorances In faet» if. after takinf^ the ground that 
 he is hff ri^ divine entitled to aesuBe these two charaeters 
 of ■an or citiaen and T i c e - gerc nt of CSnist, he should affirm 
 as a wifcnesB on the stand aeqinaintanee with the secrets of 
 Gonfiecsion, he would be guilty of apeecb oat of harmony with 
 what he has in Ins mind, Le^ of a lie. 
 C In point of li nt idninii the seercts of lawyos, j^ysiciaiis 
 next to those of the priest. ProfeBsionsl 
 idiose futh is ^i^ited to £riends» have dotieB 
 in this regard to wbidi tbcy mnst nowise prove ddinquent. 
 Xcw eitl i el cag, socb men, tboof^ tb^ be lawyers, mnst cherish 
 tnith in their ereryday dealings with themselves and others ; 
 thar rfo te, tb^ are not allowed to save a secret at the 
 of truth. But no sodi nnlawfol proceeding is neces- 
 The secret can be saved without any baim to troth. 
 For, apart from profesaonal knowledge which he is by no 
 means sspposed to rereal to an unauthoritative enquirer, the 
 ndnd of the lawyer, physician or friend is a perfect Uank 
 the infocmation desired. An imprudent man may 
 and may so miseonstrue the rei^y made by the 
 lawyer or friend as to &ncy that, when be pr«> 
 €i4y partial ignorance or ign<Hance under one capaory, 
 he e onffJBM to ignunmee under every capacity. But even in 
 this case the deeeptian, which in itsriif would not make the 
 a lie, is the fruit of unprudenee on the part of the 
 can with justice be imputed to the witness 
 only, not a cause or at most a cause by aeei- 
 
 rers that simply stand c& the qnes- 
 betokcn by the c o n unun icatiom of irrele- 
 vant knowledge an unwiDingnem to satisfy morbid curiosity 
 aicv of course^ at all times and on all oeearions licit in tbem- 
 advcs. Tlwy need never be united with falsdiood. though 
 tihi^ cni readily enon^ become fsnlts against cononoii charity. 
 
FJUNdPLBS fSi 
 
 pxvtty rnoek ai tke wjlhlwilding font a 
 
 in itadf bandcM and canbr parted vitk bj tlK 
 
 £. EqaiYioeatianB are not 
 Uie ipeakier s aundiy w t auir, as w^ itaetc gnrat to 
 of this itamp a amitipiifd fani u g, the ^ifakrr ii^ of eoonfu 
 at liberty to attadi to tfaoB arhatevcr one off lAe aeful Bcaa- 
 ihitif ■ Oaritf impomm apoo lam tlie dntf off ffnr- 
 the pcmB addrened with hiirts tufliririn to pot hiat 
 on his guard agaiart deception- Contimial and mnvanantcd 
 cqiDYQeatifln woold be a sin; not, indeed, agamnt troth, hat 
 agaimt the kire off nrighbor whieh natnre 
 a jnrt eauK is prcaent, certain sorts o 
 are not sinfoL The presence off anj eanse whatever esertts 
 no soeh potent jwflnmrr as will dtange a lie to a 0Dod deed. 
 
 this verbal ■ideading is a denial off strai^tfforward charity, 
 which a £dlow-aMn can off ri^kt esaet at oar hands, onl^ in 
 certain nailing enaea. 
 
 To d^nve him, therefore, of this ri^t, it moat fint haie 
 wamt into T**"M»**f with sone r^kt off a 
 in Tirtae off a solid cthieal princi^e, lose fw the 
 ffoiee and cffieaej. In other woed^ sane hi^er 
 
 d c aiit i in g off it, maj be lawfiiDy aiaied at, not 1^ a lie, hat 
 by a legitiaytfe verbal ■ Ml ca diu g. Alie 
 bat it is altogether iHecitiMrtr, 
 itselff or Ac convcraion off the whole world to be had £or a 
 lie, the liar would not be justified. It would, howeicr, be an 
 of an praise to coaqiaaB l&e 
 soul hf the use of 
 or a Itroad SMntal rcaervation, hedeed about by all tha 
 
238 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 been found worthy of censure. ' ' This by no means prevents 
 you or me from adopting opinions at variance with his, or to 
 quote again, "This is said, however, without on that account 
 judging that they are reprehended who follow opinions 
 handed down by other approved authors." 
 
 G. To sum up, and so bring our remarks to a close, this is 
 in short our view of the matter. A lie or a wilful and de- 
 liberate speaking against what is in the mind has a decidedly 
 twofold malice: one, primary, specific and all important; the 
 other, secondary, accidental and of less importance. The 
 primary malice of a lie is bound up in the fact that it is an 
 abuse of the Heaven-sent faculty of speech. Its secondary 
 malice is derived from the circumstance that every lie is an 
 injury done the neighbor. The lie, therefore, can never be 
 justified. Silence, evasions, equivocations, broad mental reser- 
 vations are not lies; and can, therefore, be tolerated when 
 some just cause, some good of more vital concern than the 
 kindness of straightforward truth is the motive that prompts 
 the speaker. Instances — not guilty — not at home ; priest, law- 
 yer, friend ; state officials, * ' What news, my lord ? " ' ' I don 't 
 know; I haven't read the papers." ''Do Christians believe 
 in a Trinity?" ''They believe in only one God." 
 
 H. Mental reservation and lie have the same evil results. 
 Ergo. 
 
 Answer: A lie is wholly misleading; a reservation is par- 
 tially misleading. A lie deceives per se, a reservation deceives 
 per aecidens. This accidental deception makes the indiscrim- 
 inate and universal use of reservation wrong. The legiti- 
 mate use is restricted to safeguarding a proportionate right. 
 A lie is the cause of deception ; a reservation is mere occasion 
 of the same. 
 
 I. Mental reservation is flagrant abuse of language. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: A reservation fills a double function. It conveys 
 our thought and conceals our thought. Inasmuch as it con- 
 veys our thought, it is the truth; inasmuch as it conceals 
 our thought, it is at times a species of unkindness. The deed 
 itself is morally right, our purpose would in other circum- 
 stances be unkind ; but the charity due an imprudent, meddle- 
 some and unauthorized questioner yields in importance to 
 the right we safeguard. Manifestation of our mind is the 
 
ETHICS OF SECRETS 239 
 
 finis operis or proximate end in reservation; concealment is 
 the finis operantis, or remote end. Manifestation comes first 
 in order of execution; concealment comes first in order of 
 intention. 
 
 J. A pure mental reservation is a lie, because the words, as 
 they stand, convey the opposite of what the speaker has in 
 his mind, and no accompanying circumstance helps the lis- 
 tener to a knowledge of what the speaker has in his mind. 
 Here is an instance: '^Have you eaten anything?" ''Not a 
 thing." The party interrogated has eaten a Friday dinner, 
 and he means that he has eaten nothing in the line of meat. 
 A broad mental reservation conveys what the speaker has in 
 his mind in so concealed a way that the listener, if at all im- 
 prudent, will gather the opposite of what the speaker has in 
 his mind, in spite of helps against deception derivable from 
 such attendant circumstances as tone of voice, common usage, 
 gesture, official capacity and the like. Usage after all fixes 
 the value and meaning of words, and usage can alone deter- 
 mine whether any given expression is a pure mental reserva- 
 tion or a broad mental reservation. 
 
 K. Ethics of Secrets: There are three kinds of secrets: 
 1. Natural. 2. Secret of promise. 3. Secret of contract. 
 
 A secret is natural, if the obligation to keep it hidden has 
 its origin in nature. Whatever private knowledge we have 
 of others able, if revealed, to work them harm in point of repu- 
 tation, property and such, constitutes a natural secret. A 
 natural secret becomes a secret of promise, when, after com- 
 ing into possession of the secret, we promise the party in 
 question not to reveal the same. If such promise is exacted 
 from us before we come to knowledge of the secret ; in other 
 words, if the secret is confided to us only after a promise 
 on our part to keep it hidden, the secret of promise becomes 
 a secret of contract. All three kinds impose the obligation of 
 secrecy, but the binding force of the obligation varies with 
 the kind of secret. The order of importance in ascending 
 scale is : Natural, Secret of Promise, and Secret of Contract. 
 To reveal any secret, to whatever class it belongs, some pro- 
 portionate reason must be present. A weightier reason is 
 needed when a secret of contract is in question than when 
 there is question of the other two. Nature forbids us to harm 
 
240 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 another without good and sufficient reason. A promise bind- 
 ing by way of a man's word or by way of justice, according 
 to the intent of the person making the promise, calls for even 
 a better and a weightier reason. The contract involved in a 
 secret of the third kind renders its violation a more serious 
 matter, and only the gravest of reasons can justify the vio- 
 lation of such a secret. The contract in question may be 
 either express or tacit, and it regularly accompanies profes- 
 sional secrets. If serious harm threatens the state, or an in- 
 nocent person, or either of the two parties to the contract, 
 even a secret of contract can without wrong be revealed. If 
 there is question of harm already done, a natural secret, or 
 a secret of promise must be revealed to a judge or superior 
 making lawful enquiry. In this last case a secret of contract 
 is privileged, and must not be revealed even to a judge or 
 superior. In no emergency must the secrecy of the confes- 
 sional be violated. 
 
 L. St. Alphonsus Liguori — Second Commandment. Du- 
 bium 4; 151-172. 
 
 151. Not wrong to swear to equivocal statement, when one 
 has good reason, and the equivocation itself is lawful; to do 
 so without good reason, not perjury, but mortal sin against 
 religion ;■ oath abused. 
 
 Three kinds of equivocation: 
 
 1. Word has two meanings, e.g., volo, from velle and volare. 
 
 2. Word has two senses equally common, e.g., Peter's book 
 whether owner or author. 
 
 3. Word has two senses, common and unusual, e.g., literal 
 and spiritual. 
 
 The Baptist is Elias. St. Matt. 2-14; I am not Elias. St. 
 John 1-21. 
 
 I say no, whether affirmation or negation. 
 
 152. A pure mental reservation is never lawful; a broad is 
 right when good reason is present, e.g., I go not up to this 
 festival day. St. John 7-8 ; He also went up, not openly 7-8 ; 
 openly, from context. 
 
 Of that day and hour no one knoweth, meaning end of 
 world. St. Matt. 24-36. No one knows to tell, from context. 
 Reason for broad, the one legitimate way to hide a secret. 
 
 153. If asked to testify as God's minister, priest can deny. 
 
THESIS lY 
 
 Man's right to ownership, whether temporary or lasting, ^ 
 
 is derived to him, not from any formal compact, nor from any / 
 
 civil law, hut from nature. Jouin, 118-140; Bickaby, 278- • 
 297. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Socialism is the economic error we combat in this thesis. 
 Man's right to property in capital is the precise point at- 
 tacked by Socialism, and we meet the enemy by setting this 
 right to property in whatever good on a basis that cannot be 
 shaken or overthrown If nature equips man with equal right 
 to exclusive ownership in the capital he invests and in the 
 food he eats, no legislation can in ordinary contingencies with 
 justice separate him against his will from his capital or his 
 food. That ownership in capital is a natural right, inde- 
 pendent of compact and civil law, is with us a basic prin- 
 ciple ; and, once this point is settled, Socialism and its philan- 
 thropic but wild contentions in behalf of oppressed labor, fall 
 to the ground. There are other arguments against Socialism, 
 and we mean to call attention to them in due process of time. 
 But in basing man's right to ownership on nature, our pres- 
 ent thesis is a sweeping condemnation of Socialism and kin- 
 dred theories. Socialism and Communism are systems at first 
 sight identical, but very distinct when more closely studied. 
 As long as men possess minds and use them for purposes of 
 study, the two systems stand about equal chances for uni- 
 versal sway. As long as man 's wickedness remains what it is, 
 to encourage oppression of labor and contempt of the poor, 
 so long shall their advocates harangue crowds of listeners in- 
 tellectually too feeble to see beyond appearances, or reason 
 to remote conclusions. 
 
 Socialism assumes the hue of whatever mind falls under its 
 sway, and is therefore as varied in its outlines as the physiog- 
 
 241 
 
242 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 nomies of men. But there are some broad features, and oi 
 these we now insist. He therefore would seem to be a Social{^ 
 ist, who holds it proper and exclusively proper for man to' 
 turn over to the Socialistic commonwealth whatever property- 
 can in good faith be styled capital. He prescribes under 
 pain of sin community of goods not strictly necessary for the 
 consumer's use. He would allow the railroad magnate to 
 earn his annual salary as president of a corporation, but 
 would forbid him to lock up in his private safe more of that 
 salary than would furnish himself and his family with the 
 necessaries or even the luxuries of life. In fact he would 
 make the railroad magnate a paid servant of the common- 
 wealth after confiscating or buying his railroad, and would 
 strip him of his capital and all chance to accumulate capital, 
 reducing him to a level with the operatives he now robs of 
 the fruit of their labors. Millionaires would become extinct 
 specimens, and the state treasury would distribute to the 
 poor a surplus, in comparison with which any prior surplus 
 would be mere pocket-money. The condition of God's poor 
 would be so far bettered that Heaven would become a reward 
 out of all proportion with the small price paid for it. Lei- 
 sure, and ease, and retirement on a competency, would be 
 worn out notions. The whole world would put on the busy 
 appearance of a beehive. After one year all the drones would 
 die, and this gap in nature would remain forever empty. 
 With no fund for a rainy day, work would be eagerly sought 
 and as zealously performed. Industry would be life, idleness 
 would be death. What a picture ! Nobody can immoderately 
 chide the generous but shallow-brained enthusiasts, who see 
 in this wonderful transformation the dawn of millennium. 
 But it costs no great effort to set aside poetry, and view this 
 theory, as all philosophical theories must be viewed, in the 
 even and full light of reason. Socialism, whatever may be 
 said of its possibilities as a system for men with other hearts 
 and other passions than ours, is certainly doomed to remain 
 idle as long as time lasts. Its refutation is clearly and satis- 
 factorily set forth in the arguments to be advanced in sup- 
 port of our thesis. 
 
 The Communist, recognizing no difference between capital 
 and other possessions, cries out for a share in every man's 
 
SOCIALISM AND COMMUNISM 243 
 
 goods; and in return lays open, as well he may, to every 
 chance-comer his own meagre store. Communism is insanity 
 or gross depravity. Communism has no redeeming feature. 
 We are bad enough, when at our best, but make us Com- 
 munists, and we should in a twinkling degenerate to cut- 
 throats, thieves, devils incarnate. There would be no security 
 at home or abroad. Our very friends would mix our cup with 
 poison. Our lot would be incomparably less endurable than 
 that of lions and tigers roaming the jungle. No doubt a 
 chosen few can so discipline their greed, and so develop their 
 esteem of eternal riches, as to work even more strenuously 
 than otherwise without any pecuniary reward in view. But 
 to assert that the whole race is morally capable of such per- 
 fection, and that the whole race is ready and eager to put off 
 selfishness, and sap its strength to feed and clothe the worth- 
 less and idle, is the empty vaunt of ignorance, and worthy of 
 only the man who knows neither himself nor other men. Com- 
 munism maintains that everybody is to own everything, and 
 that the common vagrant and the man who tries to do his 
 duty, the outcast of society and the man high in his neigh- 
 bors' esteem, are in some unexplained way to have an equal 
 share in the enjoyment of this world's goods. 
 
 Our thesis, we flatter ourselves, strikes at the very root of 
 Socialism and Communism. We are far from contending 
 that the natural law imposes on individuals the duty of own- 
 ing goods in severalty, nor yet that natural law absolutely 
 forbids and discountenances community of possessions in any 
 and every possible combination of circumstances. But we do 
 maintain that natural law unequivocally and unmistakably 
 imposes on mankind the duty of refraining from all undue 
 meddling with the neighbour's private property. We do 
 maintain that a man's right to his field and to his capital has 
 all its strength, not from formal compact or civil agreement, 
 with which indeed man can so far tamper as to change or 
 even repeal them; but from nature, which lies outside of 
 man's dominion, and acknowledges obedience to God alone. 
 We do maintain that neither Communism nor Socialism is 
 prescribed by the law of nature or by the obligations of man 
 to man; that they are not expressly, immediately and uni- 
 versally forbidden by the law of nature. We do maintain 
 
244 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 nevertheless that they are implicitly, mediately and in par- 
 ticular circumstances, which now obtain throughout the uni- 
 verse, absolutely condemned by the voice of nature, with in- 
 tent that the condemnation endure until this world of ours is 
 peopled with a race strangers to the passions that agitate our 
 bosoms. We are ready to grant that no peculiar offense is 
 committed, if a body of men come together in harmony and 
 agree among themselves to convey to some common treasury 
 all their wealth, with the understanding that it is to belong 
 to no individual precisely, but to be used by all in common 
 as events fall out. We are ready to further grant that he 
 would be a benefactor of the race, who could so work on the 
 minds and wills of capitalists and landowners as to induce 
 them of their own free-will to divest themselves of their 
 superfluous moneys, and confide the same to the state or to 
 some equally responsible corporation for distribution among 
 the poor. But we reprobate as firebrands to the republic the 
 hot-headed fanatics, who open wide their mouths and cry 
 out that capital is sin, and that ownership of land is a crime 
 against nature. We are not afraid to give utterance to the 
 opinion that all such intemperate zealots should be deprived 
 of the power they wield for harm among the desperate mob 
 and placed with convenient despatch between the four walls 
 of the city-jail. The millionaire may legally be induced to 
 part with his money-bags for the weal of the populace. He 
 is, however, undeniably free to close his ears to all such ex- 
 travagant pleadings of misapplied humanity, and in ordinary 
 contingencies law cannot forcibly extort from him a penny 
 in the name of justice. What has once fairly slipped into 
 his coffers is his in spite of the universe, and this one circum- 
 stance imposes on the world at large the solemn duty of re- 
 specting that right, and allowing him to possess his own in 
 peace. His acquisition of the wealth is no necessity of na- 
 ture, neither is his close retention of the same; but, once 
 acquired, his will about the disposition of his dollars is law, 
 and with all the grim necessity of nature's ordinances debars 
 others from approach, and imperatively demands non-inter- 
 ference. Of course, I speak of wealth legitimately come by, 
 and nowise forfeited by debts afterwards contracted, or at the 
 competent command of higher rights. 
 
OWNERSHIP 245 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Bight. The moral power or force, in itself inviolate, to do 
 or exact something. 
 
 Ownership. The right to claim some external and ma- 
 terial thing as one's own, subject always to restrictions im- 
 posed by higher rights. 
 
 Ownership is one species of dominion or lordship, juris- 
 diction is the other. Dominion or lordship is the right to 
 claim a thing as one's own. Ownership is lordship turning 
 on external and material things like money, land and kindred 
 articles. Jurisdiction is lordship turning on spiritual objects 
 like the minds and wills of men, and it is a prerogative of 
 rulers. The clearest title to lordship is production, and God 
 alone is true Lord, true owner, true ruler, because God alone 
 in true and strict sense makes or produces things. Men 
 make nothing, they merely change things. Men, therefore, 
 are owners and rulers not by essence, not in an independent 
 way, but only by participation, and with utter dependence 
 on God,'s good pleasure. Ownership enables them to dispose 
 of external and material things that really and truly belong 
 to God. Jurisdiction enables them to control minds and wills 
 that really and truly owe allegiance to God alone. 
 
 Ownership, then, is the right to keep and to use external 
 material things as one's own, subject always to restrictions 
 imposed by rights of a higher order. Three elements deserv^e 
 notice. To keep and to use, imply a bond of union between 
 property and owner. As one's own, excludes others from 
 possession and use. Restrictions, remove all danger of Exag- 
 gerated Individualism, which would make individual owner- 
 ship in man entirely independent of God and law. The bond 
 of union is commonly called the title, and is whatever fact 
 stamps and seals the material good in question as property 
 belonging to the owner. In origin it is not civil law, it is 
 not compact, it is not labor alone or work on the ot)ject of 
 ownership. It is what we call occupancy, and occupancy is 
 best described as the actual appropriation of a thing along 
 with the avowed intention of holding on to it ; or more fully, 
 as seizure of material goods belonging to nobody in partic- 
 
SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 vlsr, WI& the int e nt i o i i of rrtainmg tiKn as one's own, 
 witk tlie k^ of dear and manifest sasi>s» 
 ■oraL nese signs are difiBsrcnt in dif > 
 foent cases. Gn^s are li ai f ChUd , antaials are killed or eap- 
 tared, fields are feneed, voncx and deeds are passed, ^eitial 
 are made^ This is effeedre oeenpancj, otlier 
 are legal and politied, txmtL ciWI law and intcmationaL 
 cslnctions ire bnpose are fruitfal in eonseqiMiieeB. In- 
 dhridoal owneisiiip ean eoDide widi ligjits in CSod, and nghts 
 in Ae state; and in ewy soA coHision individiial ownersiiip 
 miBl jidd. Ciod alone is absolute tmmet c^ eveiytliing. He 
 owns the man as wtH as the man's fxwpcrfjy and ean dispose 
 of hotiiaoeordii^toHiseoodpIeBBQre. God nevo* abdicates 
 Hs dominion in men or things^ and He makes men gifts witli- 
 to be tiicir owner. The landlord remains owner 
 he rents his boose to the tenant. As against God, man 
 timn rdati¥e or me^ywnadi^ and he 
 gifts God makes him witk a iriew to the 
 of God's greater i^oiy. Hcnee, the ri^t to indi- 
 Tidaal i wHwiA ip in the rkk never ezenses them foom the 
 ohiigatinM of Parity towards the poor; and denial of diarity 
 on their part is a spedes of robbeiy against God. As against 
 the state and indrFidaals eomposiiig it, man's li^ to indi- 
 Tidoal own»ship is riianhiteL Neither state nor indiTiduals 
 give the li^it, and, Hicnfore, neither state war indrndoals 
 ean take it awaj. And jet in Witoe of the adage that the 
 part is serrant to the whole, the rtate has lig^ds in this mat- 
 ter of own»sh^ that the indiridDal owner most adnowkdge 
 and respect. Tlie state eannot take away the ri^t to individ- 
 nal ownenfcqp, but it ean in e me tgenci es dhrcxt private prop- 
 erty to paWe OSes. It ean call citizens to SHiiee in time of 
 war. and TrrtoaDr deprive them of ownersiiip in thdr own 
 lives, it can impose taxes and cw slnmK , it ean institute ecm- 
 dcmnation i^oeeedings, and c g ereiae all the varioos fdnetians 
 implied in Eminent Domain. 
 
 bunent Domain is no proof that indiridual ownership 
 originates in the state or dTil law. Quite the eontraiy, it is 
 open acknowledgment that the state and law haTe no sach 
 efficacy. In cond emnati on eases the state when possible makes 
 rnmpfWfiStinn to tihe owner, and the prerogatire is exereised 
 
OWNBBSHIP AXD KINDS 247 
 
 only in serious public need. If individual ownership had 
 its origin in state or law, compensation would be no requi- 
 site, and the will of the state in whatever trivial emergency 
 would justify the proceeding. When courts of law settle cases 
 in property, they virtually acknowledge that the right of 
 ownership has a validity all its own, independent of their 
 rulings. They never create or confer ownership, they deter- 
 mine where it exists. They hear testimony, examine docu- 
 ments, and take every means to discover in what party the 
 right resides and decide accordingly, all which would be need- 
 less waste of time, if the court could of itself vest either party 
 to the suit with the disputed right. 
 
 This ownership is of many different kinds, absolute and 
 relative; perfect and imperfect; direct and indirect; transient 
 and permanent; public and private; collective and individual; 
 abstract and concrete. Absolute ownership is independent 
 ownership, and in strict sense accrues to God alone. It 
 means the right to dispose of and use a thing at pleasure, 
 without restrictions imposed by another. Relative ownership 
 IS dependent ownership, and strictly speaking all human 
 ownership is such. It means the right to dispose of and use 
 thing^s, not at pleasure, but within limits prescribed by God 
 or nature. Men have the physical power or freedom to abuse 
 things, but they are without the moral power or right to do 
 so; and aU their ownership is by very nature subservient to 
 the good pleasure of GJod. As between individuals human 
 ownership can be said to be absolute as well as relative. As 
 between state and citizen Eminent Domain is only a seeming 
 denial of absolute ownership. The ri^t to ownership is not 
 taken away by the state, it ceases because of collision with a 
 higher right. Perfect ownership extends to substance and 
 use of a thing, while imperfect extends to only one or other 
 of the two. Imperfect ownership is direct, when it touches 
 the thing's substance; indirect, when it touches the thing's 
 use. Landlord and tenant are examples. 
 
 Ownership is transient or temporary, when it turns on 
 goods consumed or destroyed in their use, on goods that can- 
 not of their very nature successively belong to two or more 
 owners. Food is an example. Ownership is permanent, 
 stable, lasting, when it turns on goods practically inde- 
 
248 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 struetible, and open to successive possession by several. 
 Money, a field, a house, capital are examples. Capital is prac- 
 tically indestructible property, that tends to the production 
 of new wealth, and is opposed to what constitutes transient 
 ownership. Money inve,sted in a business or deposited in a 
 bank can be called capital. The same object can be basis for 
 both transient and permanent ownership. Wine and bread, 
 for instance, can be regarded as food or as articles of trade 
 and commerce. We maintain against Socialism that man, 
 when he acquires dominion over property of either denomi- 
 nation, transient or permanent, food or capital, is only ap- 
 plying a right, with which nature at his birth vested him. 
 We maintain that his right to land and capital is just as 
 sacred as his right to the food he eats, and that he can, there- 
 fore, be no more deprived of one than of the other. Food 
 is a more immediate need to existence than land or capital; 
 but transient ownership without permanent is precarious, in- 
 secure, well nigh impossible; and the owner's title or occu- 
 pancy is equally valid in the two cases. 
 
 Public ownership is ownership vested in a perfect society, 
 like the Church or the state; private ownership is ownership 
 vested in an individual or in an imperfect society, like a 
 business partnership, or the whole human race. Private own- 
 ership, therefore, can be individual or collective. Individual 
 attaches to a definite physical person, and it implies exclu- 
 sion of other owners; collective attaches to a moral person, 
 or to several physical persons taken collectively not distribu- 
 tively. This collective ownership is common ownership, and 
 it can be positivel}^ common or negatively common ownership. 
 In collective ownership goods are common to several in such 
 a way that none of the several can exclude the others from 
 their possession or use. Obviously, such collective ownership 
 is barren and of no practical utility to individuals. Collec- 
 tive ownership is an advantage, only when reducible to indi- 
 vidual ownership. Individual ownership is part and parcel 
 of the very word, property or proprium. 
 
 Collective ownership of this practical kind is positively com- 
 mon ownership and negatively common ownership. Posi- 
 tively common ownership is reducible to individual owner- 
 ship only by favor of all the individuals in the community. 
 
INDIVIDUAL AND COMMON 249 
 
 or by favor of a head or person in authority substituting for 
 all the individuals, never by virtue of independent activity 
 on the part of an ordinary individual in the community. As 
 far as individuals in the community are concerned, positively 
 common ownership remains forever common in potency as 
 well as actually. All power to change positively common 
 ownership to individual ownership resides in the members of 
 the community as a whole, or in a head substituting for these 
 members. Negatively common ownership is reducible to in- 
 dividual ownership, not by favor of community's members 
 or a head, but by virtue of independent activity like occu- 
 pancy on the part of any single member, without reference 
 to the other members or their representative. Negatively 
 common ownership is in itself actually common, but poten- 
 tially individual, reducible to individual by virtue of inde- 
 pendent activity on the part of any single member in the 
 community. This example from Costa-Rossetti, page 363, may 
 serve to elucidate things. Some forest is government prop- 
 erty either in such a way that no citizen is able to cut down 
 and appropriate trees in the forest without permission from 
 all the other citizens or from the head of the government, or 
 in such a way that any citizen is at liberty to cut down and 
 appropriate trees, not already appropriated by others, with- 
 out any permission whatever from his fellow-citizens or the 
 government's head. In the first case individual citizens enjoy 
 positively common ownership in the forest, in the other case 
 citizens enjoy negatively common ownership. 
 
 Of their very nature, and apart from every other consid- 
 eration, the material goods of earth belong to nobody by way 
 of actual individual ownership ; they belong to everybody, 
 not by way of positively common ownership, but by way of 
 negatively common ownership. In other words, actual indi- 
 vidual ownership is not from nature, potential individual 
 ownership is from nature. Positively common ownership is 
 neither actual nor potential individual ownership ; negatively 
 common ownership, though not actual individual ownership, 
 is potential individual ownership. Actual individual owner- 
 ship is not natural, in the sense of inborn, because otherwise 
 everybody at his birth would have a definite supply of ma- 
 terial goods set apart for his own exclusive use. Positively 
 
250 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 common ownership is not natural in the same sense, because 
 otherwise persons born into the world could never on their 
 own initiative become individual owners, but only by favor 
 of every single individual of the race, or by favor of some 
 person in authority substituting for every individual. Nega- 
 tively common ownership of everything is natural in the sense 
 of inborn, because it is the only species of common ownership 
 able to eventuate, with the help of occupancy or personal 
 endeavor, in actual individual ownership, the one kind of 
 ownership universally prescribed or counselled by nature in 
 present circumstances. 
 
 If God wants individual ownership, no right of jurisdic- 
 tion in a ruler can impose collective ownership, because juris- 
 diction in a ruler is subservient to the will of God; and no 
 sane ruler, as a matter of fact, ever attempted the usurpation. 
 That God in present circumstances wants individual owner- 
 ship, is clear from the constitution of man, and from evils 
 inseparably attaching to collective ownership. Had man 
 continued in primitive innocence, or had the race never 
 amounted to more than a few families, collective ownership 
 would have in its favor arguments now altogether wanting. 
 The passions of men and the numerical vastness of the race 
 plainly declare against universal collective ownership. In 
 the present system of individual ownership disputes are all 
 too common, in collective ownership quarrels would be mul- 
 tiplied a millionfold. Therefore, individual ownership is not 
 from nature in such a way that collective ownership is in 
 every conceivable case against nature. Positively common 
 ownership is not from nature at all, but from agreement sanc- 
 tioned by nature in particular instances, as in religious com- 
 munities or associations. Negatively common ownership is 
 from nature in such a way that denial of it in any particular 
 instance is against nature. 
 
 Nobody is bom an actual individual owner by virtue of 
 very birth, nobody is bom neither an actual nor a potential 
 individual owner. Everybody is born a potential individual 
 owner by virtue of very birth. Therefore actual individual 
 ownership is a prescription of nature in much the same way 
 as marriage; and, though Church and state may make laws 
 regulating marriage, they must not absolutely forbid mem- 
 
COMMON AND INDIVIDUAL 251 
 
 bers or citizens to marry. Positively common ownership is 
 no more a prescription of nature than membership in a busi- 
 ness firm; negatively common ownership is a prescription 
 of nature in much the same way as desire of complete happi- 
 ness. Negatively common ownership is everybody's natural 
 right, absolutely inamissible, inalienable and beyond the reach 
 of human legislation, whether ecclesiastical or civil. Nega- 
 tively common ownership is practical potential individual 
 ownership, every practical potency involves future reduction 
 to actuality, and to unduly interfere with actual individual 
 ownership is to violate and attack nature. 
 
 Abstract ownership is another term for negatively com- 
 mon ownership, concrete ownership is another term for indi- 
 vidual ownership. Abstract ownership, then, is that natural 
 right inherent in all new-bom babes, whether they be of noble 
 or plebeian origin, to get and to hold as their own whatever 
 material goods of the earth they may in after-life legitimately 
 acquire. This abstract ownership becomes concrete at what- 
 ever particular moment the child or the man assumes towards 
 a material object some relation which justifies his claim to 
 its exclusive possession. It is a fact readily granted by all 
 that God presented to our race in the person of Adam the 
 territory of the universe with all its splendid blessings. The 
 earth with all its contents was made for Adam and his de- 
 scendants to the end of time. This gift was made to Adam 
 as to an individual, it was made to the rest of the race as it 
 then existed, viz., as to an abstraction, or to some actual non- 
 being. Adam was created not an individual or exclusive 
 owner of the earth and all its goods, but only a negatively 
 common owner. This abstract ownership he converted into 
 concrete ownership with the help of occupancy, and by his 
 own personal endeavor he became individual and exclusive 
 owner of such portions of the earth and its goods as he made 
 exclusively his own. Adam certainly began as an individual 
 owner, because there was nobody to share ownership with 
 him. God never settled unconditionally and unexceptionally 
 whether the descendants of Adam should be positively com- 
 mon or individual owners. He vested them with negatively 
 common ownership, left the future to natural reason, and 
 virtually decreed individual or exclusive ownership as the 
 
252 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 system best suited to ordinary mortals after the fall and a 
 sufficiently widespread growth of the race. 
 
 Eve and her children by virtue of negatively common 
 ownership, their natural right, had full power to become in 
 the nature of things individual owners; but the union be- 
 tween husband, wife and children demanded by the family 
 persuaded them to be content with positively common owner- 
 ship, dependent on Adam's good pleasure. Even nowadays 
 nature counsels collective ownership in the family. When 
 husband and wife keep separate purses, peace in the family is 
 menaced, and mutual union is not what it ought to be. Even 
 nowadays nature counsels positively common ownership in 
 religious communities, in comparatively small gatherings of 
 spiritually minded men, banded together for purposes of 
 perfection along the lines of the gospel. And yet collective 
 ownership is not their natural inheritance in the same sense 
 as negatively common ownership ; and, while surrendering the 
 use of the right, they cannot 9,lienate or surrender the right 
 itself to become individual and exclusive owners. Adam, 
 Eve and their children were, therefore, to all intents and 
 purposes religious in the matter of ownership, with Adam 
 for superior or substitute for the others. 
 
 Had primitive innocence continued, had man's passion or 
 appetite for worldly goods remained forever subservient to 
 reason, the system might have persevered without change 
 and threatened small or no harm to moral order. But the 
 fall of man and consequent loss of primitive innocence made 
 individual ownership the one safe form of ownership for the 
 bulk of mankind. Adam, therefore, and all his descendants 
 began as negatively common owners. Adam changed this 
 negatively common to individual ownership with the help 
 of occupancy. Eve and her children changed it to positively 
 common ownership. When men grew numerous enough to 
 make individual ownership advisable, men changed negatively 
 common ownership to individual with the help of occupancy 
 and kindred titles, like accession or increment, contracts and 
 inheritance. Abraham and Lot possessed land in common 
 till a quarrel between their shepherds urged them to divide 
 their common holdings and live as individual owners or pro- 
 prietors. Abraham on at least two occasions purchased land 
 
COMPACT AND LAW 253 
 
 from the Egyptians, showing that he respected the right to 
 individual ownership in his neighbors. History everywhere 
 bears witness to this ruling of nature in favor of individual 
 ownership, and at the present time no considerable body of 
 men, outside of religious orders, lives according to the tenets 
 of Communism or Socialism. Men like Fourier, 1772-1837, 
 Owen, 1771-1858, and Cabet, 1788-1856, have tried the thing, 
 and egregiously failed. Owen's New Harmony colony in In- 
 diana lasted two years ; Cabet 's Icaria Community in Illinois, 
 after repeated reverses between 1849 and 1895, entirely dis- 
 appeared in the latter year. Nature enters no protest against 
 collective ownership in the family, it enters no protest against 
 collective ow^nership in religion; but it very decidedly pro- 
 tests against collective ownership for the bulk of mankind 
 as constituted since the fall. 
 
 Formal Compact. Civil Law. Nature. The Socialists and 
 Communists, who despair of ever being able to prove that 
 their systems would be more replete with blessings for man- 
 kind than the system of individual ownership, now so uni- 
 versal, attack the justice of man's plea for the right to indi- 
 vidual ownership. For, be it remembered, we maintain that 
 no man can divest himself of his natural right to individual 
 ownership any more than he can divest himself of rational- 
 ity. He can so abuse his faculties as to lose the use of his 
 reason, but the use of reason and rationality or reason itself 
 are two things quite as distinct among themselves as the 
 builder and the house he builds, or the mind and the thought 
 it thinks. Even so, the religious who binds himself by sol- 
 emn vow to poverty, or to life without individual ownership 
 of anything, forever retains that right to individual owner- 
 ship. He goes down to the grave without ever enforcing the 
 right, but the right itself is as present and live in him as it 
 is in the richest landlord or capitalist. He cannot surrender 
 his right to individual ownership. He can and does sur- 
 render all desire to enforce that right. Man's right to indi- 
 vidual ownership is, therefore, so just that he cannot even 
 himself legitimately or otherwise deprive himself of it. It 
 is therefore an indispensable requisite of his nature and our 
 all-wise Maker did not so constitute vis that an element of 
 injustice should be absolutely and unavoidably inseparable 
 
254 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 from our nature. If man's right to individual ownership 
 could fall back for foundation on only a formal compact, as 
 Heyne and Grote opine; or on civil laws, as Montesquieu, 
 Bentham and Hobbes groundlessly imagine, then indeed Henry 
 George and men of his stamp could question the justice or 
 injustice of that right, could examine the terms, and the 
 legality, and the reasonableness of that compact and those 
 civil laws. But, as we mean to show in our proofs, no such 
 supposition is tenable. 
 
 DIVISION 
 Three Parts — I, II, III. Not Compact, Not Law, But Nature 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 I. Whatever is asserted without proof, can likewise be de- 
 nied without proof. But this first theory advances no proof 
 of the fact that an agreement or covenant respecting indi- 
 vidual ownership was once entered into. Therefore, this first 
 theory is simply denied. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: 1°. History, that is most an? 
 cient and authoritative, bears witness to the contrary fact, 
 viz., that, before any agreement was ever entered into, man 
 recognized within himself and applied the right to individual 
 ownership with which he was bom. History, both ancient 
 and modem, is authority for the fact that bodies of men and 
 women, like the primitive Christians and the religious orders, 
 have by a formal compact agreed to relinquish the use of 
 this right, without of course being in the least degree capable 
 of shaking off the right itself. Unlike the propounders of 
 the false theory here refuted, we have ancient historical re- 
 mains, such as monuments and tablets, to which we can refer. 
 The book of Genesis, written by Moses, the most ancient and 
 best authenticated history written, no matter what scoffers 
 say to the contrary, carries the question back twenty cen- 
 turies before Christ and plainly indicates that in the time of 
 Abraham the right to individual ownership was enforced and 
 respected. On two separate occasions at least Abraham buys 
 pieces of land: once for a family burial-plot, again for a 
 camping ground. Gen. 23-6, 8, 9, 11, 14, 18, 20; 33-19. 
 
PROOFS 255 
 
 With the Egyptians, whose history is among the earliest re- 
 corded, Joseph is said to have purchased in time of famine 
 all the land of the people. Monuments have been discovered 
 and are now visible in the museums of Europe, on which are 
 traced distinct and unequivocal records of business transac- 
 tions in property, which would be wholly meaningless if in- 
 dividual ownership were not recognized. One of these monu- 
 ments, that of King Senefra, dates its origin from a period 
 ten or twelve centuries in advance of that of Abraham. 
 
 2°. Another argument might be drawn from the fact that 
 community of goods, as our opponents themselves confess, 
 would never have been necessary if men had not been bom 
 with the same dispositions for virtue and innocence, and that 
 exclusive individual ownership necessarily resulted from dif- 
 ferences of disposition in this matter. But it is a fact wit- 
 nessed to by the wise and the ignorant alike that man was 
 created on a plan of perfectibility, and that, even if Adam 
 had prolonged to his descendants the reign of primitive inno- 
 cence, there would still have prevailed among them degrees 
 of virtue and perfection. 3°. Besides, if community of 
 goods were natural, and exclusive ownership unnatural, the 
 savages roaming the plains and living from hand to mouth 
 would be men more according to God's mind than the in- 
 habitants of cities with all their wisdom and knowledge. 
 4°. The philosophers opposed to us would deplore com- 
 munism as a machine of the devil. But communism is the 
 legitimate outcome of any system that makes man's right to 
 individual ownership depend on human agreement or civil 
 law. For human agreement and civil law admit of change, 
 even when the change is actually from better to worse. 
 
 II. No effect can be ascribed to any cause of a perfection 
 inferior to its own. But individual ownership is a universal 
 custom of universal duration among men. It cannot, there- 
 fore, be referred, as to a cause, to so inconstant .and so re- 
 stricted a factor as civil law. Besides, individuals in society, 
 to create exclusive ownership by civil law, must have had 
 before such a proceeding exclusive rights to the goods and 
 parcels of land deeded over. Otherwise, the whole proceed- 
 ing was illegal and unjust, as the parties engaged in it dis- 
 posed of that which did not belong to them. Right of juris- 
 
256 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 diction could never create the right, because jurisdiction 
 touches the obedience of subjects, not their property. Even 
 nowadays when through some legal scheming a rightful owner 
 is ousted from his property, do fair-minded people for a mo- 
 ment imagine that the schemer assumes or puts on a right to 
 the ill-gotten goods? Does the schemer himself fancy that 
 before God and conscience the theft is justified? By no 
 means. But were civil law the cause of man's right to ex- 
 clusive ownership, the opinions of the fair-minded in the 
 supposed instance would be empty imaginings without any 
 foundation in fact, the stings of conscience would be unneces- 
 sary pain, self-inflicted, without any assignable cause or rea- 
 son. If law could once change positive common to exclusive 
 ownership, law can now change exclusive ownership to posi- 
 tive common. 
 
 III. Man is bom to live an allotted time and work out an 
 allotted destiny, and his Maker has furnished him with nat- 
 ural rights to whatever is needful for that existence and for 
 the attainment of that destiny. But individual ownership 
 is a means necessary to that existence. Therefore man's 
 Maker has furnished him with a natural right to individual 
 ownership, and this individual ownership extends itself to 
 temporary and lasting objects. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: E very-day experience is proof 
 of the first member, conclusive enough to convince the most 
 sceptical. The absurdity of conceiving man alone, creation's 
 noblest work, placed here to no intended purpose, while 
 everything around him works unto an end, is indeed over- 
 whelming. The prudence and justice of his Maker would 
 render it absolutely impossible to fancy man bereft of means 
 necessary to the attainment of his end. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: To foster existence, it is a 
 requisite that man be solicitous about procuring what beseems 
 life. But by very nature man's solicitude is but feebly or 
 not at all aroused save in the search for things that belong 
 to himself alone, that cannot be claimed or appropriated by 
 others. Life without peace would be without joy and would 
 be even impossible. But deprive men of the right to indi- 
 vidual ownership, and life would be a warfare, a struggle for 
 existence in the truest and strictest sense of the word, peace 
 
INDIVIDUAL AND NATURE 257 
 
 would flee the earth. There are innumerable other arguments 
 applicable here, but all will suggest themselves to the enquir- 
 ing mind. I would only note the following. Use or tran- 
 sient dominion is certainly a natural right. It must be plain 
 to all that this right is little worth, unless, for instance, the 
 farmer can raise his crop without fear that a stranger may 
 come in the harvest-time and appropriate his sowing. The 
 sculptor will be little tempted to ply his art, unless secure 
 in the possession of the block of marble on which he works. 
 Laziness, and hunger, and death, are in sure prospect when 
 any chance-comer may with impunity lay hands on the prod- 
 ucts of the industrious. There will be nothing in store to 
 tide the laborer over the darksome days of sickness and old 
 age. His young family will perish before it reaches ma- 
 turity. Charity and bigness of heart in the dispensation of 
 goods will be utter strangers to earth. Add to all this the 
 fact that the lie would be given to the sentiments and opin- 
 ions of our fathers and forefathers, who all strenuously main- 
 tained that the right to exclusive ownership of property is 
 inherent in man, and as much a part of man as his nature. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. In case of extreme need the baker loses his right to 
 individual ownership of part of the bread in his shop. This 
 circumstance is due to a phenomenon in question of rights, 
 which has its parallel in that of physical forces. In the mat- 
 ter of physical forces the weaker by a kind of inherent neces- 
 sity yields to a stronger force. Even so, in rights, which are 
 moral forces, the stronger always takes precedence of the 
 weaker right. But one sort of force never intrenches on the 
 domain of the other. Thus, the strongest imaginable phys- 
 ical force can never obtain legal mastery over the weakest 
 imaginable moral force or right. Necessity or indispensable- 
 ness of the means involved is always the measure of dignity 
 attached to a right. Four kinds of necessity are recognized 
 in the order following: absolute, extreme, serious, common- 
 place. A divine right demands the sacrifice of a human right. 
 The right of a natural society or state, when all the condi- 
 
258 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 tions are the same, demands the sacrifice of a right belonging 
 to an individual of that natural society or state. 
 
 B. The acknowledgment of right to individual ownership 
 is the innocent and accidental occasion of many quarrels and 
 disputes. But such quarrels or disputes are rather the out- 
 come of perverse natures, and with a small amount of com- 
 mon sense can be avoided. But in community of goods 
 quarrels and disputes would constitute the essential and un- 
 avoidable order of the day. 
 
 C. The community of goods in use with the apostles, primi- 
 tive Christians, and religious orders is no denial of the right 
 to individual ownership, but a voluntary and meritorious 
 cession of the practical advantages ordinarily attendant on 
 the application of that right. 
 
 D. Civil law surrounds with all possible safeguards the 
 citizen's privileges accruing to him from the natural right 
 to individual ownership, and takes all possible means to 
 ensure harmony and order among claimants; but civil law 
 by no means creates the right to individual ownership. In 
 all its enactments it supposes the right itself already pos- 
 
 E. Absolutely speaking, it would of course be quite pos- 
 sible for an individual to come into the possession of a whole 
 continent; but relatively speaking, i.e., taking all circum- 
 stances into account, such possession would be utterly im- 
 possible. In Moral Philosophy, as elsewhere remarked, be- 
 cause it is an eminently practical science, circumstances can- 
 not in justice be neglected. Therefore, it is enough to re- 
 mark, as answer to this seemingly formidable objection, that 
 individual ownership of a whole continent is entirely out of 
 the question. God's ownership forbids that the race be 
 pushed into the sea. 
 
 F. Abstract ownership is a natural right emanating from 
 God, and independent of all civil law. Concrete ownership 
 is natural in foundation, strictly human because of occu- 
 pancy, and dependent on civil law in its application. Law 
 cannot in general forbid concrete ownership; but it can pre- 
 scribe methods and limits, to safeguard the common good. 
 Occupancy is more than a mere condition in question of con- 
 crete ownership; it is proximate cause or title. The expres- 
 
PRINCIPLES 259 
 
 sion, this is mine because I made it my own, is proof of 
 occupancy's causality. No danger from Socialism attaches 
 to this concession, because the natural right, or abstract right 
 of ownership, always stands; and this bases concrete owner- 
 ship. Law will enforce right when formalities are observed, 
 not otherwise. Right may be present, State will refuse to 
 recognize ; and all that to further the interests of peace and 
 prosperity. Law never creates or causes the right unless 
 the state is prior owner; it safeguards right already present. 
 It assists the obedient, refuses to assist the disobedient; and 
 these latter must prosecute their right without help from the 
 law. 
 
 G. In spite of individual ownership the use of things re- 
 mains always in a measure common. Concrete ownership is 
 a human right. Divine law ordains that the goods of earth 
 contribute to the support of all mankind. In extreme need 
 human right must yield to divine law, and in this emergency 
 all goods become common, to rescue the needy from destruc- 
 tion. In the same way the rich are obliged in charity, though 
 not in justice, to relieve the needy poor with their superfluous 
 wealth. The poor cannot appeal to this principle as to an 
 excuse for lawlessly plundering the rich. The duty of the 
 rich has its origin in charity, not in justice. Rights and 
 duties in question of justice turn on determined persons and 
 definite matter, not in question of charity. All the needy 
 cannot be relieved; and, therefore, the rich are at liberty to 
 make a judicious selection. Besides, superfluous goods can- 
 not be determined by any hard and fast rule, and everjrthing 
 is left to the prudent charity of the wealthy owner. 
 
 H. Religious never divest themselves of the right to owner- 
 ship, but of its exercise. 
 
 I. The right to use is basis of the right to own, and yet 
 individual ownership seems to destroy the right to use. It 
 destroys in others the right to use, and that is no contradic- 
 tion. 
 
 J. By nature all things are common in negative, not in 
 positive sense. 
 
THESIS V 
 
 Socialism is false in its principles^ morally impossible in 
 itself, and quite absurd. Cathrein, 283-303. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Karl Marx (1818-1883), is the acknowledged founder of 
 present-day Socialism, the species called democratic; and his 
 work on Capital can be taken for a fair exposition of its 
 tenets. It condemns the present condition of society as de- 
 plorable and unjust. It is deplorable, because in business 
 everybody does as he likes, trusts capture the wealth of the 
 world, capital practically destroys competition, and mankind 
 goes into two armies, the classes and the masses, captains of 
 industry and the proletariat, or capitalists and slaves to cap- 
 italists. It is unjust, because capital enriches itself by taking 
 unfair advantage of labor, monopolizing such channels of 
 wealth as land, factories, mines, railways, and seizing every 
 opportunity to rob the masses of the fruit of their labor. 
 
 Marx sees in every product of labor a twofold value: its 
 use value, and its exchange value. A coat's use value is 
 fixed by its physical and chemical properties, which deter- 
 mine its usefulness as an article of wearing apparel. Its 
 exchange value depends on the amount of money it is worth 
 in the market, and is always in excess of its use value. This 
 excess it gets from the workman's labor, which is represented 
 by the difference between the cost of raw material and the 
 selling price. In much the same way, the tailor's labor has a 
 twofold value ; one, use value ; the other, exchange value. Its 
 exchange value is the wages he gets from his employer, its 
 use value is its exchange value along with the profit accruing 
 from such labor to his employer. Suppose a tailor makes 
 a suit of clothes a day. Suppose the suit worth twenty dol- 
 lars, the raw material five, and the tailor's wages five. The 
 cloth's use value will be five. In this way the use value of 
 
 260 
 
SOCIALISM 261 
 
 the tailor's labor, added to the use value of the cloth, gives 
 the market price of the suit, and the excess of use value over 
 exchange value in the tailor's labor represents the employer's 
 profit. This excess of ten dollars the Socialist styles capital, 
 and in his eyes the whole process of commercial profit is a 
 species of robbery. But he is blind to the fact that the em- 
 ployer has a sacred right to wages as well as the tailor, and 
 it is not at all exorbitant to rate what he contributes to the 
 suit of clothes in the way of skill, management, rent and 
 what not, twice as valuable as what the tailor contributes. 
 And this continues true, if the employer be an out and out 
 capitalist, contributing nothing to the industry but his money. 
 For great mental effort was expended somewhere in the 
 accumulation of this money, and such effort deserves a re- 
 ward or wages. The capital invested stands for the work 
 expended in its accumulation. Certainly the employer ought 
 not be allowed to oppress his workmen, or keep their pay 
 down to starvation limits. But that is an affair labor itself 
 must regulate by organization and by appeals to the state 
 when necessary. And all appearance of dishonesty must be 
 avoided, no crime against the natural right of property must 
 be committed in the process, and the wrongs of the poor must 
 be righted without despoiling the rich of that capital, which 
 is as much theirs as the dinner the workman eats is his. 
 
 In spite of what Socialists preach to the contrary, society 
 is not going to right itself by the commission of another 
 colossal wrong. Religion is the God-appointed remedy for 
 this evil, and for whatever other evils afflict mankind. The 
 evolution to which Socialism looks for relief is progress back- 
 wards, and would, if realized, land labor in infinitely worse 
 conditions than it now knows. Socialists see in the gradual 
 diminution of conspicuous capitalists a hasty advance towards 
 the time when the poor, far outnumbering the rich, will in 
 sheer disgust confiscate the goods of the wealthy, and in- 
 augurate a new era of universal prosperity. The world, they 
 think, will undergo a complete revolution in the matter of 
 morality, religion and civil government. God will be de- 
 throned in the universe, religion will be beaten down, indi- 
 viduals will be kings, every man will be his own law, passion 
 will usurp the place of reason, and the world will go its 
 
262 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 own way to perdition. By a most pernicious and offensive 
 propaganda they are getting men's minds and hearts ready 
 for the change. They are preaching atheism everywhere. 
 Fear of God is a check to their iniquitous progress, and this 
 fear must be proved a fiction. The old doctrine of Heaven 
 and hell teaches patience, and impatience with their lot can 
 alone goad the poor to excesses. Conscience, with its an- 
 tiquated standard of morality, bars spoliation of the wealthy ; 
 and conscience must be taught that self-advantage is the first 
 law of nature. The Church is in league with capital to 
 enslave the masses, it is the paid agent of capital, advocating 
 for a pecuniary reward the need of obedience to authority, 
 and encouraging laziness in its ministers, fattening on the 
 credulity of the poor. The State, as at present constituted, 
 is a foe to labor, and capital's most steadfast ally. Govern- 
 ment, therefore, must be overthrown, and on its ruins the 
 socialistic commonwealth of pure democracy must arise. Free 
 love, community of wives, and all their attendant abomina- 
 tions must not only be tolerated, but encouraged ; family life 
 must be forever obliterated; children must be reared by the 
 state, much as ranchmen raise their cattle on the plains. 
 These are some of the flattering inducements they hold out 
 to their followers, and the wonder is that their ranks are 
 not more crowded than they are. 
 
 Socialists regularly and persistently deny that their sys- 
 tem contends for any of the degenerate practices just enumer- 
 ated; but the writings of their leaders give the lie to every 
 such protestation of innocence. They are shrewd dissem- 
 blers; and, where the truth about their theory would hurt 
 the cause, policy urges them to hide its base consequences, 
 and clamor aloud that their one holy purpose is to raise up 
 prostrate labor, and better the condition of the working 
 classes. But accurate quotations from recognized authori- 
 ties on socialism bear honest witness to their true purpose; 
 and we mean, before we finish, to gather a short but startling 
 array of such quotations. Fortunately for the truth, social- 
 ism is its own worst accuser, and its own propagators voice 
 its severest condemnation. These are necessary, logical con- 
 sequences. Fanatics among them are alone logical. Moderate 
 socialists are not true socialists. 
 
EVOLUTION AND PROPAGANDA 263 
 
 The central feature of the whole system is the abolition of 
 individual ownership in capital. Collective ownership vested 
 in the Socialistic Commonwealth will constitute the new order 
 of things. This commonwealth will be radically democratic, 
 a return to the days of Demosthenes, when Athens met in the 
 agora to frame laws, elect officials, and settle weighty affairs 
 of state. It will assume complete control and ownership of 
 such sources of revenue as land, houses, machinery, manufac- 
 tures, mines and railways. Municipal ownership is only a 
 step towards the realization of their plans, and advanced 
 socialists are far from satisfied with this settlement of the 
 question. They complain that municipal ownership merely 
 shifts the trouble without removing it root and branch, be- 
 cause government in this event turns capitalist ; and it makes 
 small difference to labor whether public officials or private 
 citizens prey upon its profits. In this commonwealth all 
 magistrates, without a single exception, will be immediately 
 elected by the people, directly responsible to the people, and 
 subject to the sharpest kind of scrutiny at the hands of the 
 people. They will be labor's paid servants, not its lords and 
 masters. Privileges will be dead, all will be on a level, every 
 citizen will be on an equal footing with his neighbor. Suf- 
 frage will be universal, officials will be closely watched, the 
 common people will frame laws, sentence offenders, and exe- 
 cute judgment; and government will resolve itself into a 
 vast trading concern, with every individual citizen an active 
 partner in the business. Men of special parts will be selected 
 to regulate the manufacture and distribution of products. 
 The proceeds of labor down to the last penny will find their 
 way into the laborer's pocket, and overproduction as well as 
 scarcity will be a thing of the past. Officials will assign to 
 each member of the commonwealth his own proper share and 
 his own fixed kind of labor. Nobody will be allowed to cul- 
 tivate idleness or enjoy superfluous ease. Eights and duties 
 will be distributed with an even hand. There will be no 
 merchants, no buyers and sellers. Goods will be stored in 
 public depots to be distributed among the people in shares 
 determined by individual industry. In lieu of money, pay- 
 checks will be issued, entitling holders to fixed portions of the 
 common products. Transient ownership will stand inviolate, 
 
264 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 and nobody will have a right to interfere with the neighboPs 
 use and management of whatever articles of consumption he 
 justly makes his own. Then follow in funereal order a long 
 line of logical and fatal consequences. 
 
 There will be no God, no religion, no Church, no priests. 
 There will be no family. Instead of marrying, men and 
 women will mate for a short or long season, like the beasts of 
 the field and birds of the air. Children will not know their 
 fathers, and soon after their birth will be handed over to the 
 commonwealth by their mothers, to be reared and educated 
 at the government's expense. Divorce will disappear from 
 the statute-books, when free love is made the uniform prac- 
 tice. Women will be on a footing with men, and work side 
 by side with them in every department of industry. The 
 time mothers hitherto wasted raising a family will be merci- 
 fully saved to labor by the establishment of state-farms for 
 the upbringing of the young. 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Two Parts — I, II 
 
 I. False in principles. 
 II. Impossible and absurd. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 Its three chief principles are, *' the theory of values; ^' the 
 equality of men; ^' materialistic evolution. 
 
 a. Socialists contend that labor gives whatever article of 
 trade its true worth. In other words, they exaggerate labor's 
 exchange value at the expense of the article's use value. In 
 other words, the higher the price of a thing, the higher the 
 wages for making it. But it can readily be shown that mer- 
 chandise is quite as dependent for worth on its use value as 
 on labor's exchange value. A thing's physical and chemical 
 properties have quite as much to do with its price as the 
 labor expended in its manufacture. The labor being the 
 same, wine from one vineyard can be worth a hundred times 
 as much as wine from another vineyard. Labor need have 
 
THEORY OF VALUES 265 
 
 nothing to do with the difference of value in two fields. 
 Wood, wheat, precious stones, in many cases derive their value 
 from natural causes, antecedent to all human endeavor. La- 
 bor, of course, contributes to a thing's worth ; but oftener than 
 not its use value, its substance, is the weightier factor in de- 
 termining price. The exchange value of a workman's labor 
 is not measured by what it takes to support him, but by his 
 strength, skill, energy and experience as well. The operative 
 and the manager can equally well live on five dollars a day, 
 but while the operative ought to be in justice content with 
 five, the manager has a perfect right to demand ten. And 
 in the adjustment of wages, the world of sensible labor will 
 never be led astray by the senseless theories of socialists. 
 
 b. All this socialistic talk about man's equality with man 
 is noxious nonsense; and to nobody is the folly of the thing 
 better known than to socialist orators themselves. As a mat- 
 ter of fact, they reckon themselves leaders, and are not slow 
 to insist on their superiority. They are prophets among the 
 people, and dumb compliance with their wishes is first requi- 
 site for initiation into their company. Men are equal in the 
 abstract, in the possession of human nature with its con- 
 stituent elements; in the concrete, in accidental accomplish- 
 ments, men are as far removed from equality as the remotest 
 star from our earth. Fathers and mothers are above their 
 children, rulers are above their subjects, where money counts 
 the rich are vastly superior to the poor, and in the realms 
 of art a consummate painter or sculptor is hardly on a level 
 with a practical farmer or a man of toil. And socialism can 
 try till doomsday, it will never succeed in eliminating these 
 accidental differences among men. They would persevere in 
 the impossible event of Socialism's establishment, because God 
 wants them, and God 's wishes cannot be frustrated. 
 
 c. The materialistic evolution of socialism is but a con- 
 ceited aping of what is going on in the scientific world, and 
 what one must expect when ill-trained minds of Shakespeare 's 
 mechanicals dabble in philosophy and theology. The pan- 
 theism of Hegel, the materialism of Darwin, now occupy the 
 middle of the stage, and the attention they are getting is a 
 necessary evil. They will die eventually, as all previous 
 errors died; but in the process of their killing they cannot 
 
266 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 but be prominent. On the day of his hanging the condemned 
 criminal gets a whole page in the newspaper, while an hon- 
 ored President meets with the scantest notice. Socialism, 
 to be abreast of the times, casts its lot with modern thinkers, 
 and sees in its establishment the consummation of evolution. 
 Unable to see in man anything higher than mere matter, so- 
 cialists profess to think him hopelessly subject to material 
 forces and economic environment. To know the political 
 economy of an age in history, is to know its religion, its trend 
 of thought, and its civilization. Christianity was accordingly 
 due to the economic notions prevalent in Christ's time; 
 Protestantism started up in obedience to economic changes 
 in human affairs; and Socialism, without any effort on its 
 part, is bound to be the reigning style in the immediate fu- 
 ture. Everything points to its swift inauguration. Religion 
 is fast losing its hold on the minds of men, morality is mak- 
 ing unto itself other standards, trusts are crushing competi- 
 tion, absorbing the wealth of the world, centralizing resources, 
 and cutting down the number of enormously rich men to won- 
 derfully small limits. Machinery is crowding labor out of 
 the market, obliterating the middle class of thrifty workmen, 
 and making wider the line of division between the rich and 
 the poor. Discontent is growing among the masses, and the 
 hour is not far distant when this discontent will make itself 
 felt, when the people will rise in revolt, and the common- 
 wealth will complete the work of centralization begun by the 
 trusts, and vest all ownership of capital in the people. 
 
 But man is not the weather, to be determined by physical 
 and material forces. He has an intelligent mind and a free 
 will, both spiritual, immortal, and in last analysis quite inde- 
 pendent of matter. He is his own master, maps out his own 
 conduct; and, though subject to temporary aberrations from 
 mental and moral straightness, he generally hits the truth, 
 and at least approves of what is right. He is the creature of 
 his environment, but never its unwilling slave. The preju- 
 dices current in this or that age of the world deeply affected 
 successive generations of men, but there were always enough 
 honest men in the world to keep the heritage of truth safe 
 from lasting harm, and help it to ultimate victory. Man's 
 mind was made for the truth, and, though its native imperf ec- 
 
MATERIALISTIC EVOLUTION 267 
 
 tion lays it open to the danger of going wrong at scattered 
 intervals, in the main it steers a straight course, and, acci- 
 dents aside, it invariably finishes where God would have it 
 finish in moral knowledge. If all rivers ran upward, if stones 
 in the air continued to ascend instead of falling to the ground, 
 it would be less a miracle than the altogether unnatural en- 
 slavement of any large collection of minds to moral error. 
 What is in a measure true of even scientific judgments, where 
 passion, prejudice and education play so conspicuous a part, 
 becomes absolutely true in question of ethical judgments, 
 based as they are on human nature, and making mute appeal 
 to the God of nature for a share in His own infallibility. 
 Mind is spiritual energy, it does only partial allegiance to 
 matter, and under ordinary circumstances its testimony is 
 unerring in religion, morality and topics with a bearing on 
 these momentous questions. Political economy had little or 
 nothing to do with the growth of Christianity. Christianity 
 swept the world because its principles are true and stand for 
 the right. It grows, and it must grow till the end of time, 
 because its tenets are as indestructible as the truth, on which 
 they are based. Protestantism is wrong; and, not political 
 economy, but the perverseness of men's hearts is its explana- 
 tion. Its baneful influence was most severely felt in sections 
 of the world where morality was lowest and men's aspirations 
 were grossest. Its first recruits were degenerate priests and 
 nuns, men and women impatient of virtue's restraint; and 
 while its gospel of self-indulgence attracts meaner characters 
 of the sort, its inborn wickedness urges honest and heroic 
 souls to supreme disgust. It is gradually disappearing from 
 the face of the earth, and it is to-day but a mocking 
 shadow of what it was in its origin. In this twentieth cen- 
 tury the line of division between Protestantism and paganism 
 is hardly discernible, and it threatens before the century is 
 over to altogether vanish. Individual ownership, rooted in 
 nature, is championed by Christianity, and stands or falls 
 with its supremacy in the world. Collective ownership is as 
 false as Protestantism, and must share its fate. It may hold 
 men's attention for a long or short period of time, it may 
 make conquests in this or that corner of the world; but it 
 can never hope to prove lasting or compass universality. To 
 
268 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 become socialistic, the world must repudiate nature, Grod, 
 religion, morality; and that catastrophe can never befall the 
 race. 
 
 II. False in principles, socialism is morally impossible in 
 itself and quite absurd. Bare mention of the insoluble prob- 
 lems attaching to the scheme, must satisfy the most incredu- 
 lous about socialism's impossibility as a system. Hard and 
 fast lines would have to be drawn between articles of consump- 
 tion and articles of production; and the wisdom of Solomon 
 would scarcely suffice for the task. To avoid waste, the 
 quantity and quality of needed products would have to be 
 fixed with some degree of exactness; and the world would 
 hardly contain paper enough for lists. To make wise ap- 
 pointments, the commonwealth would have to get into the 
 closest kind of touch with the inclinations and abilities of its 
 citizens. Change of residence or employment would be out 
 of the question, and men would be as much permanent fix- 
 tures as houses or fences. And yet men are not going to lose 
 their love for travel. Some climates, some situations, some 
 skies will always be more appealing than others. Home will 
 be without meaning when house and land are property of the 
 state. Distribution of duties will be a ridiculously wide field 
 for discontent. If everything is left to the free choice of 
 the citizens, there will be a rush for easy and pleasant places. 
 Nobody will want employment of a hard, humble, unhealthy 
 nature. If citizens have no choice in the matter, no more 
 degraded form of slavery can well be conceived. In any 
 event it will be a colossal undertaking to single out the milk- 
 men and miners, factory-hands and farmers, cooks and street- 
 sweepers, nurses and doctors, lawyers and policemen. In- 
 centive to industry will be wanting. Inventive genius will 
 not be cultivated, when the profit accruing from new ma- 
 chinery goes, not to the inventor, but to the people at large. 
 There will be no equality of rights, if some certain men pur- 
 sue the professions like law, medicine, education; and there 
 will be no professions, unless some certain men pursue them. 
 Professions and trades call for years of training, study and 
 patient exercise; and, if no corresponding reward attaches to 
 this excess of labor, men devoting themselves to the trades 
 and professions will be models of unselfishness. If such re- 
 
IMPOSSIBLE SYSTEM 269 
 
 wards are meted out, class distinctions will be inevitable, and 
 the commonwealth will be divided into rich and poor, edu- 
 cated and uneducated, gentle and plebeian, men of brains 
 and men of toil. According to whatever standard products 
 are distributed, innumerable difficulties will arise. If num- 
 ber of heads is the standard, it will be unfair to make no 
 difference between the industrious and lazy, skilled and un- 
 skilled, the strong and the weak. If hours of work are the 
 standard, an active workman will produce in a given time 
 twice as much as a lazy workman, and can well be dissatis- 
 fied if his reward is the same. If excellence of work is the 
 standard, it will be practically impossible to measure the 
 different degrees in occupations like medicine, law, education, 
 agriculture. If activity is the standard, every workman will 
 have to be under the constant supervision of a dozen or more 
 watchers and measurers. If need is the standard, a whole 
 army of judges will scarcely suffice to determine the peculiar 
 needs of each individual in the commonwealth. With no 
 motive for energetic endeavor, men would discharge their du- 
 ties in the most perfunctory manner. There would be no 
 family to care for, no provision to make for rainy days. 
 While young and strong, the necessaries of life would be 
 men's daily wages. When old and infirm, their existence 
 would be, to say the least, precarious. Socialists must, be- 
 sides, have unlimited faith in human nature, when they sup- 
 pose that officials will measure up to requirements in the 
 matter of prudence, wisdom and honesty; that they will be 
 immune from selfishness, satisfied with their pay, wholly in- 
 tent on the common good. They credit the common people 
 with no smaller virtue, when they suppose that subjects will 
 dutifully hang on the nod of superiors, experience no pang 
 of greed, and contentedly pass their lives in hard and humble 
 avocations with a view to furthering common prosperity. In 
 Christian communities, where such virtue is promised a sur- 
 passing reward, where the opposite vices are threatened with 
 dire disaster, saints of the sort are few and far between, rare 
 enough spectacles to excite comment and wonder. 
 
 Absurd, because unworkable — To be a system, it must be 
 workable. Ergo workable and unworkable. 
 
 Scholion — Agrarian or Land Socialism. 
 
270 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Henry George, who died in 1897, advocated a modified 
 form of socialism. He wants the state to become owner of 
 such immovable property as land, fields, forests, mines and 
 houses. His followers are styled Land Socialists or Single 
 Taxers. The arguments they employ are nothing worth. In 
 the main they rest their case on these six. 
 
 1. History is witness that collective ownership of land orig- 
 inally prevailed everywhere, till violence and fraud substi- 
 tuted the present system of individual ownership. 
 
 2. Labor is the single title to individual ownership, and 
 labor cannot produce land. 
 
 3. Without collective ownership of land nobody can appro- 
 priate to his own use the produce of his labor. 
 
 4. Equal right to live postulates equal right to land. 
 
 5. The first to enter a theatre has no right to debar later 
 arrivals from sittings. 
 
 6. Land owners absorb an undue proportion of the world's 
 wealth — ^unearned increment. 
 
 Answers: 1. History bears opposite witness; and we can 
 appeal to the Hebrews, Assyrians, Egyptians and Chinese, in 
 whose early records no trace of collective ownership in land 
 can be found. Whatever may be the truth regarding early 
 ages, it is certain that civilization stands for individual own- 
 ership. 
 
 2. This second argument proves too much, and applies as 
 well to movable as to immovable goods. The labor being the 
 same, statues of gold, marble and wood, are of different val- 
 ues. The sculptor's trade would be worthless, unless he 
 owned the material, in which he worked. 
 
 3. A man has no right to the produce of a farm, unless the 
 farm belongs to him; but he has a right to wages for the 
 labor exerted in cultivating another's farm. 
 
 4. Ownership of land is no requisite for support. Mer- 
 chants traffic in crops, and make a comfortable living without 
 owning a square inch of ground. 
 
 5. The first to enter has a right to debar others from his 
 seat, without preventing others from taking such seats as are 
 empty. 
 
 6. These are the equations he uses to prove the undue in- 
 
HENRY GEORGE 271 
 
 crease of rent, the unearned increment: Crop = rent plus 
 wages plus interest. Ergo, crop minus rent = wages plus in- 
 terest. The higher the rent goes, the lower wages and interest 
 fall ; and the lower the interest, the smaller becomes the crop 's 
 value. He seems to forget that if the crop grows in value 
 as the rent rises, the wages and interest will remain the same, 
 and that a lower rate of interest on a larger principal is 
 equivalent to a high rate of interest on a smaller principal. 
 Five loaves distributed among five men are better than ten 
 loaves distributed among twenty. Similarly, five per cent, 
 of five hundred is greater than ten per cent, of one hundred. 
 Finally, Land Socialism is morally impossible. All land 
 cannot become the state's exclusive property. Three possible 
 methods of public ownership in land suggest themselves. 
 
 1. The state can hold all land as proprietor, and hire men 
 to work it. 
 
 2. The state can hold all land, and rent it to tenants. 
 
 3. The state can leave individual owners in possession, and 
 exact the equivalent of rent as taxes. 
 
 Answer: 1. The first method is condemned by George him- 
 self. It would destroy agriculture, encourage idleness in 
 workmen, spoil the land and do away with the whole class of 
 honest farmers, who cling to homesteads and their clustering 
 traditions. 
 
 2. The second method would prove no less destructive. No- 
 body would improve the land on account of uncertain tenure, 
 the soil would be worked to death for large profits within lim- 
 ited periods. No ditches would be dug, no marshes would be 
 drained, rotation of crops would be neglected, no foresight 
 would be used, no expense with an eye to the future would be 
 undergone, and in short order the land would become a 
 barren waste. 
 
 3. The third method commends itself to George. He would 
 leave the farmers in possession, and exact from them as taxes 
 that portion of the crop equivalent to rent, making some small 
 allowance from same as incentive to make improvements, bet- 
 ter the condition of the land and erect necessary buildings. 
 He thinks that this one source of revenue would meet all the 
 necessary expenses of the government, and would impose no 
 other tribute. Hence his system gets the name of Single 
 
272 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Tax. First of all, it would be difficult to say what propor- 
 tion of the crop would equal rent; what, wages; and what, 
 interest. If a small bonus were offered farmers, they would 
 grow lazy ; if a large bonus were offered, it is hard to see how 
 other taxes could be dispensed with. What has been said of 
 farms can with some unimportant changes be said of real 
 estate in the shape of city sites and residences. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Some Quotations: ''Archbishop Corrigan and Bishop 
 Qtiigley alike charge Socialism with hostility to religion. 
 These charges are unqualifiedly false, and we challenge their 
 authors to quote one phrase from our party platform, that 
 would in any way tend to support their accusations. They 
 cannot do it, for Socialism has no concern with religion." 
 
 —The Worker, Mar. 16, 1902. 
 
 Answer: Socialism is not to be gotten from the platform 
 of a party in New York; but from the writings of its recog- 
 nized leaders and exponents. Socialism is international and 
 was never meant to be sectional. Therefore it ought to be 
 the same all over the world ; and, if the New Yorkers above 
 quoted want to be considered good Socialists, they must change 
 their manner of talk. 
 
 * * There is no such thing as European Socialism or American 
 Socialism. There is only one kind of Socialism the world 
 over, International Socialism." 
 
 — Haverhill, Social Democrat, July 20, 1901. 
 
 Now let us hear how Socialists the world over talk about 
 religion : 
 
 "The possession of the means of livelihood gives to the 
 capitalists the control of the government, the press, the pul- 
 pit, and the schools, and enables them to reduce the working- 
 men to a state of intellectual, physical and social inferiority, 
 political subservience and virtual slavery." — Socialist Plat- 
 form. 
 
 '* Christianity to-day stands for what is lowest and basest 
 in life. Official religion and militarism are the two guardians 
 of capitalism, and the subtle methods of the church in de- 
 stroying the manhood of the soul and keeping it servile are 
 
QUOTATIONS 273 
 
 infinitely more to be dreaded by the socialist movement than 
 the world *8 standing armies." George D. Herron, in Ad- 
 vance. 
 
 ''How has the ruling class established this control over 
 its members and its slaves ? In three ways, through religion, 
 through public opinion, and through the law, with its judges 
 and soldiers. Religion is perhaps the most powerful of these 
 means of maintaining class society, by inducing the members 
 of the subject class to act contrary to their interests and in 
 accordance with that of their masters. Christianity is the 
 most effective of all. It has operated primarily by the offer 
 of rewards in Heaven and the threat of punishment in hell.'' 
 —The People, New York, Feb. 18, 1900. 
 
 ** Christianity is a huge and ghastly parasite, consuming 
 billions of treasure out of the labor and the patience of the 
 people, and is supremely interested in keeping the people in 
 economic and spiritual subjection to capitalism. The spir- 
 itual deliverance of the race depends on its escape from this 
 parasite. The world must be saved from its salvations." — 
 George D. Herron, in Worker, New York, Nov. 10, 1901. 
 
 ''The truth is, as all thinking men are aware, we have no 
 such thing as intellectual honesty in the sphere of religion. 
 The deity men pray to and exhibit in theology is not a moral 
 being. If ever in the history of the world any human in- 
 stitution was completely and finally discredited, it is the reli- 
 gious institution, whose putrid and decaying carcass here at 
 the beginning of the twentieth century menaces the life of 
 men." — William Thurston Brown of Rochester, in Socialistic 
 Spirit, June, 1902. 
 
 "The Church is one of the pillars of capitalism, and the 
 true function of the clergy is to chloroform the workers, to 
 make docile wage-slaves of them, patient and contented with 
 their lot in this world while expecting a glorious reward in 
 the next. — Henry Quelch, in the Social Democrat, March 15, 
 1903. 
 
 "Christianity is an enemy of liberty and of civilization. 
 It has kept mankind in slavery and oppression. The Church 
 and State have always fraternally united to exploit the peo- 
 ple. Christianity and Socialism are like fire and water." — 
 Bebel, 1901, 
 
274 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 No Christianity: 
 
 **One word on that singular hybrid, the Christian Social- 
 ist. The association of Christianity with any form of So- 
 cialism is a mystery, rivaling the mysterious combination of 
 ethical and other contradictions in the Christian divinity Him- 
 self/'— Bax, in ''Ethics of Socialism." 
 
 * ' The terrible condition of our poor is due to the two curses 
 of our country and time. These two curses are Capitalism 
 and Christianity." — Dr. Averling, in To-day. Free-love hus- 
 band of Karl Marx's daughter. Suicide. 
 
 ''That familiar fallacy, the ethics of Christianity and So- 
 cialism are identical. It is not true; we do not ourselves 
 in most cases believe it. We repeat it, because it appeals to 
 the slave-mind of the world. There is no wrong, however ter- 
 rible, which has not been justified by Christianity, no move- 
 ment for human liberty which has not been opposed by it. — 
 The Comrade, N. Y., May, 1903. 
 
 Atheism : 
 
 "And while all of us are thus indifferent to the Church, 
 many of us are frankly hostile to her. Marx, Lassalle and 
 Engels, among earlier socialists; Morris, Bax, Hyndman, 
 Guesde, and Bebel, among present-day Socialists, all are more 
 or less avowed atheists ; and what is true of the more notable 
 men of the party is almost equally true of the rank and file 
 the world over." — James Leatham, in "Socialism and Char- 
 acter. ' ' 
 
 "Marx was an avowed atheist." — Dr. Averling, in "Charles 
 Darwin and Karl Marx." 
 
 "Religion is a fantastic degradation of human nature." — 
 Karl Marx. 
 
 "In politics, the republic; in economy socialism; in reli- 
 gion, atheism. ' ' — Bebel. 
 
 "As the religion of slave industry was Paganism; as the 
 religion of serfage was Catholic Christianity or Sacerdotal- 
 ism; as the religion of Capitalism is Protestant Christianity 
 or Biblical Dogma; so the religion of collective and coopera- 
 tive industry is Humanism, which is only another name for 
 Socialism." — Bax, in the "Modem Revolution," p. 81. 
 
 ' ' The idea of God is the keystone of perverted civilization ; 
 the true root of civilization, the true root of liberty, of equal- 
 
QUOTATIONS 275 
 
 ity, of culture, is atheism.'' — Karl Marx, in ''Secret Society 
 in Switzerland." 
 
 No divinity of Christ : 
 
 ''Can we keep a picture of Christ in our Socialist head- 
 quarters? It can stay, but the picture should be without a 
 halo, and should have the words beneath it : To Christ, who 
 was a man and a martyr to the principle of brotherhood 
 among men." — Oddino Morgari, Turin. 
 
 Science and Religion: 
 
 ' ' Science and religion are in inverse ratio to each other ; the 
 one diminishes and grows weaker in the same proportion that 
 the other increases and grows stronger in its struggle against 
 the unknown." "Under the influence of scientific culture re- 
 ligious convictions will perish by atrophy. ' ' — Enrico Ferri. 
 
 Free-will and Determinism: 
 
 "It is not the conscious mind of man that determines the 
 form of his being, but, vice versa, the social form of his being 
 determines the conscious actions of his mind." — Karl Marx, 
 in "Critique of Political Economy." 
 
 Morality without religion: 
 
 "We bring back ethics from the clouds. Morals being 
 purely secular in origin and purpose should be kept free from 
 all contact with religion." — Spargo, in "Where we Stand," 
 p. 19. 
 
 "Morality and ethics have nothing to do with religion. 
 Fools or hypocrites assert the contrary. They regulate the 
 actions of men towards each other; religion regulates the ac- 
 tions of men towards supernatural beings." — Bebel, in 
 "Woman Past, Present and Future," p. 147. 
 
 Free-love : 
 
 "Three great obstacles block the path of Social reform: 
 private property, religion, and the present form of marriage. ' * 
 — Frederick Engels. 
 
 ' ' Thanks to the wrong conditions of society and the state, 
 woman is to-day without rights and in countless cases is con- 
 demned to wedded or unwedded prostitution. The inter- 
 course of the sexes is unnatural and immoral, — socialism will 
 bring the emancipation of woman as well as of man. It will 
 destroy prostitution, w^hether it walk ashamed under the man- 
 tle of marriage for wealth or convenience, or whether it run 
 
278 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 shameless painted and naked upon the street/' — LiebneSl 
 ''Socialism, What it is." Chicago, Aug. 1, 1901. 
 
 ''Legalized monogamic marriage and prostitution are based 
 essentially on commercial considerations. The one is pur- 
 chase, the other is hire.'' — Bax, in "Outlooks from a New 
 Standpoint. ' ' 
 
 ' ' The reverence of the bourgeoisie for the monogamic prin- 
 ciple now rests almost entirely on the fact, that he objects 
 to being exposed to the danger of having to put his hand in 
 his pocket for the maintenance of his neighbor's children." — 
 Bax, in "Outlooks," p. 151. 
 
 P.S. Herron was deposed from the ministry for abandon- 
 ing his wife and taking a soul-mate. Dr. Averling, already 
 married, lived as a husband with Eleanor Marx, Karl's daugh- 
 ter. When his love grew cold, she drank poison. Averling 
 sex-crazed soon after died. 
 
 B. Encyclical of Pope Lea XIII . ''The Condition of La- 
 bor.'' May 15, 1891. 
 
 Exordium — Elements of conflict between capital and labor 
 are: 
 
 1. Growth of industry 
 
 2. Discoveries of science 
 
 3. Changed relations of masters and workmen 
 
 4. Millionaires and paupers 
 
 5. Trusts and labor-unions 
 
 6. Irreligion. 
 
 Hard to find a remedy because : 
 
 1. Guilds are gone 
 
 2. Religion is repudiated 
 
 3. Usury-sharks are common 
 
 4. Monopoly prevails in trade 
 
 5. Consolidation of interests fosters giant corporations 
 
 6. Contract-labor. 
 
 A. Wrong Remedy — Socialism — collective ownership of 
 capital in land and money. 
 
 1. Socialism hurts labor, because capital is as much a need 
 to workman as it is to his employer. He ought to invest his 
 savings in land and business. Capital is his wages in another 
 shape. 
 
POPE LEO XIII 277 
 
 2. Socialism is unjust, because man has natural right to 
 exclusive ownership on account of reason and knowledge of 
 future. Man differs from brute in this that he sees beyond 
 the present, and makes provision for the future. 
 
 3. The state has no right to interfere with exclusive owner- 
 ship, because the individual and his natural right are prior 
 to state. 
 
 4. Man has a natural right to whatever he honestly makes 
 his own. By work of body and work of mind he makes land 
 and capital his own. By care and improvements the farmer 
 as truly makes the land as the crop he raises. 
 
 5. Mankind approves and has always approved of exclusive 
 ownership, the civil law recognizes and safeguards the right. 
 
 6. God in the seventh and tenth commandments forbids 
 interference with the same. 
 
 7. Man is free to marry, and exclusive ownership of land 
 and capital is more a need when children put in an appear- 
 ance. 
 
 8. The state must respect family rights because of their 
 precedence in point of time and importance. 
 
 9. Socialism cannot legitimately do parents the injustice of 
 robbing them of their children. 
 
 10. In short, socialism would prove a heavy curse. It 
 would introduce disturbance, slavery, envy, evil speech, quar- 
 rels, poverty, neglect of talent, misery and dishonesty, to say 
 nothing of atheism, anarchy and free-love. 
 
 B. Right Remedy — Religion — I, Church, aided by II, State. 
 I. a. The Church is equal to the task. 
 
 1. It can do all that its founder accomplished. 
 
 2. To attempt to do away with classes in society, would 
 be to quarrel with God and court defeat. 
 
 3. To suffer is the lot of humanity, and the poor will be 
 always with us. 
 
 4. Hostility between the classes is not a necessity of nature, 
 b. The Church has efficacious means to destroy hostility, if 
 
 rich and poor heed her advice. 
 
 1. She counsels duty and justice to each class. 
 
 2. The workman must scrupulously keep agreements; do 
 no injury to the employer or his property; earn his wages; 
 resort to no violence, riot or disorder ; and avoid evil men. 
 
278 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 3. The employer must not count his workmen slaves; he 
 must respect them as men and Christians; he must bear in 
 mind that labor is no shame, that it is inhuman to treat men 
 like mere chattels for purposes of gain. 
 
 4. Workmen must be allotted time for duties of piety, safe- 
 guarded from dangerous occasions. They must not be taxed 
 beyond their strength, and due regard must be had for age 
 and sex in the allotment of tasks. They must not be de- 
 frauded of adequate wages, no advantage must be taken of 
 their helplessness. No fraud, or force, or usurious dealings, 
 must be practised by the employer against his workmen. 
 
 5. She reminds both classes of the future life awaiting them 
 and of its paramount importance. 
 
 6. The rich must use their money with a view to salvation. 
 They are almoners to the poor, and exclusive ownership never 
 excuses them from the duty of sharing their goods with the 
 needy in the name of charity. 
 
 7. The poor must be content with the lot of Jesus, Mary 
 and Joseph. They are walking in God's footsteps. Finally, 
 rich and poor alike are sons of God, and in this respect equal. 
 
 c. The Church applies the remedies at her disposal with an 
 unerring hand. 
 
 1. She educates the world with all the authority of her 
 founder; and while most intent on men's spiritual good, she 
 neglects not their temporal welfare. 
 
 2. Deacons were appointed in the early Church to serve 
 at table. 
 
 3. The patrimony of the Church was a mammoth poor- 
 fund. 
 
 4. Her religious congregations have charity in every form 
 for purpose. 
 
 II. The State must cooperate with the Church. 
 
 1. Law must consult the moral well-being of subjects, and 
 must be just to all classes. It must safeguard the whole 
 community and its individual parts, rich and poor alike. 
 
 2. Law must not unduly interfere with liberty, and under- 
 take only what is required for remedy or removal of danger. 
 
 3. Though the rights of all must be religiously respected, 
 the poor are entitled to special consideration. The rich are 
 more able to protect themselves. 
 
POPE LEO XIII 279 
 
 4. In behalf of capital, private property must be guaran- 
 teed; strikes must on occasions be taken in hand by the law. 
 
 5. With regard to workmen, their spiritual and mental in- 
 terests must be ensured. Man cannot give up his soul to 
 servitude. The law must insist on Sunday as a day of rest, 
 and protect the poor from grasping speculators. Hours, 
 child-labor, woman-labor, are within the province of the law. 
 It must take into account that in all contracts rest for soul 
 and body is a condition expressed or understood. 
 
 6. Though wages are largely a matter of free agreement, 
 the law must not allow greedy employers to impose on the 
 poor. Personally, the workman is free to accept or reject 
 terms, but poverty at times reduces him to a state of neces- 
 sity in the matter of agreement, and the law must keep the 
 employer from forcing unreasonable terms on his workmen. 
 The victim of low wages is oftener than not forced and far 
 from free. 
 
 7. The law must encourage economy and ownership among 
 the poor by inculcating thrift. Ownership among the poor 
 has these five excellent results. It brings rich and poor to- 
 gether, it weakens monopoly, it procures abundance and pros- 
 perity in state, it fosters love of country and lowers taxation. 
 
 8. To cooperate with the State, employers and their work- 
 men must get together. Labor must organize for mutual help. 
 Scripture is warrant for organization. The state must recog- 
 nize lesser societies, and encourage rather than hamper them. 
 It should interfere only when such societies threaten the com- 
 mon good. It has no rights regarding societies responsible 
 to the Church. 
 
 9. Unfortunately for labor, workmen's societies are in the 
 hands of the wicked, and spirited Catholic champions ought 
 to take a strong hand in their affairs. 
 
 10. In labor unions piety should not be neglected, officers 
 ought to be prudent and honest. One great need is a com- 
 mittee to settle grievances between workmen and employers. 
 
 Peroration: 
 
 Early Christians can be incentive to courage. They were 
 poor, but winners. Prejudice and money are in the way of 
 success. Workmen, formerly cowards, will be reclaimed to 
 religion and labor. Religion and her ministers must help. 
 
THESIS VI 
 
 The right remedy for labor troubles is union between em- 
 ployers and workmen, based on inequality; consulting the in- 
 terests of both in such a way, that they enjoy life and its 
 comforts along with freedom and peace. Bicsso, 178-191. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 The labor-question is the social question of the hour. This 
 labor problem, because of its bearing on morality, is as much 
 an affair of the Church as it is of the state. Till this prob- 
 lem is satisfactorily settled, it must remain a menace to the 
 salvation of men's souls; and it is the Church's business to 
 fight every such menace to a finish. All the world is her 
 kingdom, workmen and employers alike belong to her juris- 
 diction, they are children in her house; and, like a good 
 mother, she must keep down quarrels in the family. Hence 
 her prayer that workmen and employers may come to a swift 
 understanding, settle their mutual differences, and work to- 
 gether in harmony towards salvation. The Church herself 
 cannot settle the problem, the state itself cannot settle the 
 problem. The Church can help, the state can help ; but, un- 
 less honest cooperation on the part of workmen and employ- 
 ers seconds their efforts, Church and state are practically 
 powerless. The Church can preach, the state can legislate; 
 but their subjects have free wills, and free will is too strong 
 an agency to be overpowered by either a sermon or an army. 
 The man himself holds the single key to the situation. Only 
 the owner of a free will can reduce it to terms, and make it 
 walk right ways with content. When the owner's mind is 
 right, when his will is strong for the good, mistake is a re- 
 mote possibility; and the grace of God is the one lamp to 
 flood the mind with unerring light, the grace of God is vested 
 with some of God's own omnipotence. This grace can be 
 purchased by prayer. When once workmen do their whole 
 
 280 
 
LABOR PROBLEM 881 
 
 duty by employers, when employers do their whole duty by 
 workmen, there will be no labor-problem ; the industrial world 
 will be at peace ; the time, energy and brains hitherto wasted 
 in quarrels, wrangles and disputes, will be saved and made 
 subserve the interests of virtue. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Union. The labor-trouble manifests itself in moral unrest, 
 in mutual hostility between workmen and employers and in 
 wide fluctuations of wealth. Relations between workmen and 
 employers constitute a separate branch of rights and duties, 
 and therefore a distinct branch of Ethics. The workman has 
 a right to wages from his employer, the employer has a right 
 to his workman's labor. It is the workman's duty to give 
 his employer stipulated labor, it is the employer's duty to 
 give his workman stipulated wages. The relations between 
 workman and employer have their origin in an onerous or 
 bilateral contract, creating obligations in the two parties to 
 the contract. 
 
 This contract is the root of all the trouble in lahor-ques- 
 tions, and modern notio7is regarding it are at times absurd 
 and opposed to the natural law. They restrict the contract 
 to the workman singly, without taking into account his wife 
 and children. They reduce the whole question to an effort on 
 the part of the employer to get the greatest amount of labor 
 for the smallest possible wages ; on the part of the workman, 
 to get the greatest possible wages for the smallest amount of 
 labor. They forbid every other consideration to workman 
 and employer. Every such view of the wage-contract is 
 wrong on these several counts. It oppresses the poor, and 
 against all justice forces them to the acceptance of iniquitous 
 conditions and starvation wages. It promotes strife and 
 hatred, goading the poor to desperate measures against the 
 rich. It encourages violence and disorder, inciting the poor 
 to steal, to wantonly destroy property and to defy the law. 
 It hurts wife and children. They must work, to supplement 
 the husband's low wages. No woman can work abroad, and 
 at the same time properly care for her children. The right 
 to an education is sacred in boy and girl, and education calls 
 
282 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 for years of constant and absorbing toil. It tends to utterly 
 destroy the family, keeping its members far enough apart to 
 kill love, and trust, and deep esteem; provoking carelessness 
 and want of interest in domestic concerns, and leading to 
 illicit attachments and unnumbered abuses. The Egoism it 
 encourages threatens the state with disaster, responsible as it 
 is for the luxury, hardness of heart, absence of charity, wide- 
 spread corruption, waste of wealth and consequent dishon- 
 esty, conspicuous in the rich; and in the poor, hate, desire 
 of revenge and plunder, ending in theft, robbery and murder. 
 Other Reasons for Lahor-T roubles, Because Provocative of 
 Disunion. Disappearance of guilds, for which labor-unions, 
 because of irreligion, are no suitable substitute. Every man 
 for himself, on the pretext of liberty and equality. Wide- 
 spread use of machinery takes workmen from their homes to 
 the factory. Speculation, stocks, get-rich-quick concerns, for- 
 tunes made and lost in a day. Civil laws dictated by Liberal- 
 ism; no duties; might over right; opinion of the majority. 
 Laws of succession, and small holdings. Militarism makes 
 young men lazy and morally corrupt. 
 
 Wrong Remedies 
 
 Socialists clamor for equal distribution of profits; work- 
 men and employers on an equality ; proportional shares ; fixed 
 wages along with part of profits, cooperative plan; state con- 
 trol, set wages, hours, work for all, right to employment. 
 
 Conservative Liberals want books open to state for settle- 
 ment of wages and share in profits; officials to regulate rela- 
 tions between workmen and employers; alms to the poor out 
 of taxes, hence progressive taxes. Scientific Liberals or Mal- 
 thusians advocate limiting number of children in family. 
 
 Socialists and Malthusians need no refutation. Conserva- 
 tive Liberals are wrong, their remedies are useless and harm- 
 ful, because opposed to peace of mind, love and mutual trust, 
 common prosperity and secure possession of property. The 
 poor resent favors from the law ; favors would be legal obliga- 
 tion, not displays of kindness ; distribution would be uniform, 
 and blind to concrete circumstances ; officials would seek their 
 own advantage; inspectors without number to guard against 
 graft. Ergo, useless agencies for the promotion of peace and 
 
CONTRACT IN LABOR 283 
 
 good will. Harmful because of tendency to Socialism and 
 baneful centralization. 
 
 Bight Remedy 
 
 In the words of our thesis, union between workmen and 
 employers, based on inequality; consulting the interests of 
 both in such a way that they enjoy life and its comforts along 
 with freedom and peace. The remedy we advocate is a res- 
 toration of the guilds of the Middle Ages, with what changes 
 present conditions demand. In this union the employer must 
 be superior; the workman, inferior. The workman, however, 
 must in no sense of the word be a mere machine in the hands 
 of his employer for the accumulation of wealth. The em- 
 ployer must in kindness provide for the workingman's needs, 
 and help him in various ways to meet his wants and discharge 
 his different duties. He must not be wholly intent on his 
 own advantage, but consult also the good of his workmen. 
 Workmen must be content with their lot, harboring no desire 
 to better their condition by unfair methods or by taking what 
 belongs to others, all intent on using their own rights, caring 
 for their families, and giving the best in them to their em- 
 ployers. 
 
 PROOF 
 
 Along with contract regarding labor and wages, by very 
 force of natural law, workmen and employers have respective 
 rights and duties, looking to their mutual peace and advan- 
 tage. But the union we advocate would secure these rights 
 and duties. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Exaggerated individualism is 
 WTong in employers. They are not absolute lords of their 
 own property. God alone enjoys absolute ownership in 
 things. Man's ownership is limited by moral obligations, 
 with a bearing on less fortunate neighbors. One of the means 
 God employs to procure the advantage and comfort of all, is 
 the unequal distribution of wealth prevalent in the world, 
 enabling the wealthy to cooperate with Providence in alleviat- 
 ing the distresses of the poor. Nobody has the right to turn 
 all his wealth to his own exclusive advantage and comfort. 
 Charity never loses its claims on the wealthy, and whatever 
 
284 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 contracts are made always presuppose in the makers a willing- 
 ness to discharge their duties and respect the rights of others. 
 
 Workmen must avoid whatever savors of socialism, com- 
 munism or injustice. They have families to support and 
 children to educate. Their wives must not neglect domestic 
 concerns or the duties of motherhood. Their children cannot, 
 before they are sufficiently grown, be subjected to long hours 
 of labor without detriment to their health and education. 
 Workmen must be given abundant opportunity to save their 
 souls by prayer and other practices of piety; and time must 
 be allowed them to discharge this duty. They must be en- 
 abled to put by a penny for a rainy day, and so escape starva- 
 tion when disabled by disease, weakness, or old age. What- 
 ever contract the workman makes presupposes in him the wish 
 to comply with his duties, and means to their fulfilment ; and 
 nothing short of force or violence can hinder or impede him 
 in this important matter. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. The union we advocate be- 
 tween workman and employer, far from promoting unfriendli- 
 ness, would contribute much to peace and prosperity. It 
 would, of course, militate against the accumulation of ab- 
 normal fortunes, and so rid the world of whatever sudden 
 reverses and financial upheavals minister to men's sorrow and 
 foment hatred. Employers, therefore, must not unduly tax 
 their workmen's strength, or impose long hours. They must 
 employ women in lighter work, as far as possible in their 
 own homes. They must allow children to work in their fac- 
 tories only when sufficiently grown and sufficiently educated. 
 They must give their workmen a living wage, enabling fathers 
 to support their families without need of hard work on the 
 part of their wives and children. They must keep their hands 
 at work even in business crises and periods of depression, to 
 free them from dread and anxiety when times are busy. They 
 must devise some way of insuring their workmen against acci- 
 dents like sickness, broken health and old age. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Wages. Workmen have a right to fair wages, employ- 
 ers must not be plundered. In this labor-question two ex- 
 
WAGES 285 
 
 tremes must be avoided. Socialism exaggerates the work- 
 man's rights; wrong political economy, the employer's. Sal- 
 ary is wages agreed upon by contract. This contract between 
 workman and employer is onerous and bilateral, creating in 
 both parties definite rights and obligations. Like all con- 
 tracts, to be valid, it must be free from deceit, mistake and 
 violence. The employer purchases not only the workman's 
 labor, but all its fruits. Proudhon distinguishes between the 
 workman 's labor individually taken, and in gross ; giving the 
 employer the first, refusing him the last. Proudhon is wrong 
 for two reasons, 1°. The employer is responsible for hia 
 workmen's labor in gross, because he assembles them, he por- 
 tions out their work, he equips the factory, selects the ma- 
 terial, buys machinery, chooses efficient hands, sells the prod- 
 uct in season. 2°. The workman's efficiency is limited to his 
 labor individually taken; his labor in gross is due to the 
 employer's industry, and therefore belongs to him. Besides, 
 in time of business depression the loss falls on the employer, 
 not on the workmen. Contraries call for kindred treatment ; 
 and, if the loss due to business depression is the employer's 
 burden, the profit due to business prosperity ought to be the 
 employer's reward. 
 
 Socialists like to view the contract between workman and 
 employer in the light of a partnership. It is nothing of the 
 kind. It is a pure and simple contract of buying and selling. 
 In partnership profit and loss are shared, in buying and sell- 
 ing no such division has place. In this matter of wages, the 
 mere fact that workman and employer agree on a definite 
 sum of money, is far from settling the whole question. Of 
 course, the workman owns his labor, and can dispose of it as 
 he chooses. Law perhaps never looks beyond, but conscience 
 may still take offense ; and conscience has claims on employer 
 and workman alike. Fraud, mistake, violence may influence 
 the terms, and so vitiate the whole transaction. A traveller 
 freely yields up his purse to the highwayman, but he sur- 
 renders his money to save his life. In much the same way, the 
 workman may freely contract with his employer for starva- 
 tion-wages ; but, in the event of refusal, death from want may 
 stare himself and his family in the face. He chooses a lesser 
 evil to escape a greater ; and employers, who, to strike unfair 
 
286 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 bargains, take undue advantage of their workmen's helpless- 
 ness, are nothing short of highwaymen. The law protects 
 them, but God has a heavy punishment in store for oppressors 
 of the poor, and for such scoundrels as defraud the laborer 
 of his just wages. In the eyes of the law, if a man wishes 
 to submit to injustice, he may do so. The contract is not void, 
 but voidable. But in the eyes of God the employer, who 
 forces his workman to submit to starvation-wages, is a crim- 
 inal and deserves to be punished. 
 
 This other view may help to a clearer understanding of 
 things. In contracts of buying and selling equality, as far as 
 possible, between the thing purchased and its price must be 
 kept. The employer buys his workman's labor, monopolizes 
 his time and strength, cuts him off from other revenues of sup- 
 port, and reduces him to the condition of wearing out his life 
 in his service. In all fairness the workman must get from 
 his employer in return the means needed to sustain his 
 strength, to minister to his declining years, to repair the 
 waste of his own life by the upbringing of children. And 
 this is practically what we mean by a living wage, a minimum 
 wage, a salary enabling the workman, no matter what the 
 nature of his labor, to comfortably support and educate him- 
 self, his wife and several children. Causes without number 
 operate to raise and lower wages, but no reason can per se 
 justify wages less than this minimum or living wage. Jus- 
 tice is hurt by every departure from this rule, and the em- 
 ployer is ordinarily a thief, because he is enriching himself 
 with the goods of others. If workmen and employers could 
 be once gotten to heed these demands of justice, labor trou- 
 bles would be at an end; and, since no outside agency, like 
 the state or law, seems able to bring about this happy con- 
 summation, the solution lies with the workmen and employers 
 themselves; and union between the two for mutual help and 
 support, a deeper reverence for justice and charity in their 
 mutual dealings, are necessary steps in the process. 
 
 B. Unions and Trusts. Sometimes the workman is to blame 
 for strained relations; at other times, the employer; and in- 
 stead of getting together to settle their differences, they stand 
 farther apart with the help of labor-unions on the one hand, 
 and trusts or monopolies in trade on the other. Labor-unions 
 
UNIONS, TRUSTS, STRIKES 287 
 
 are meant to save workmen from the rapacity of employers, 
 and they accomplish their purpose by regulating wages and 
 the hours of work a day. Their members are enjoined from 
 giving their services to such employers as refuse to abide by 
 the laws of the union ; and thus they hope to put employers 
 of the kind out of business. Employers hit back by a counter 
 combination, refusing to hire union-labor, or maintaining what 
 is called the open shop, where union and non-union labor are 
 indiscriminately employed; and thus they hope to subject 
 the workmen to their own wishes, and nullify the hampering 
 influence of labor-unions. Labor-unions, when no violence or 
 injustice intervenes, are quite legitimate, and ought to be 
 countenanced by the state. What is true of labor-unions is 
 true of trusts and monopolies in trade. "What is allowed one 
 workman or one employer is allowed a multitude of either. 
 But certainly one workman is allowed to refuse his services 
 to whatsoever employer, and one employer is allowed to refuse 
 employment to whatsoever workman. Ergo, unions and trusts 
 are quite legitimate. The whole process is the common exer- 
 cise of a common right. Neither combination hurts the rights 
 of individuals in the other. The purpose of the two is praise- 
 worthy, disposal of their property to best advantage. Be- 
 sides, men have an inborn leaning towards organization and 
 consolidation of interests. It belongs to the state to safe- 
 guard the rights of its citizens, and control of these unions 
 is within the province of government. Labor is the weaker 
 party, as compared with capital, and deserves fuller protec- 
 tion at the hands of the state. Capital has few opponents 
 among writers on political economy. Opponents to labor 
 complain that the methods it employs are inefficacious and 
 productive of evils. Individual workmen, they think, ought 
 to yield to the good of the community at large. Hence, with 
 them, labor-unions ought to be abolished. They ought per- 
 haps to be restrained, but not abolished. Facts prove the 
 efficacy of labor's methods. Times without number employ- 
 ers have yielded to the just demands of their workmen, when 
 threatened by the loss attendant on a walk-out. It is no argu- 
 ment to say that with higher wages prices will be raised to 
 offset the advantage. The raising of prices is no necessary 
 consequence. The employers will simply have to be satisfied 
 
288 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 with smaller profits, and enough dealers will always be found 
 to maintain lower prices. 
 
 C. Strikes. The loss sustained by workmen in course of a 
 strike is their own private affair, and no concern of the state. 
 The state must not unduly meddle with the private affairs of 
 its citizens, the common good is its whole purpose. Strikes, 
 no doubt, work harm to employers and others besides the 
 workmen ; but they are not on this account necessarily wrong. 
 When harm accrues to another from a neighbor's act, no 
 blame attaches to the neighbor, when he has a perfect right 
 to put the act in question. The injured party must have a 
 clear right to restrain the neighbor from said act. A mer- 
 chant is certainly allowed to divert trade from his rival in 
 business, so long as he restricts himself to honorable methods. 
 The workman is clearly within his right, when he refuses to 
 barter his labor for unsatisfactory wages; and a strike in it- 
 self means nothing more. It makes small difference from a 
 moral point of view whether one man strikes or a whole 
 union. 
 
 "When strikers resort to wrong methods, the whole face of 
 the question is changed; and they ought to be restrained, 
 without being robbed of their plain right. Their demands 
 must not be unjust, they must not induce others by force or 
 violence to quit work, they must have recourse to no lawless 
 procedure, they must not with violence prevent others from 
 taking their places. These evils are not of the essence of a 
 strike, which is mere refusal to work. Strikes must not be 
 forbidden because they are sometimes attended with evil con- 
 sequences. That would be poor logic. Abuses in the prose- 
 cution of a right must be checked by the state, but the right 
 itself must be respected. Boards of arbitration appointed by 
 the state might prove a great help to the solution of this 
 question. But the one effective remedy for things is a wider 
 and wider diffusion of religion, and the enthusiastic cultiva- 
 tion of virtue. 
 
SECTION II— DOMESTIC SOCIETY OR THE FAMILY 
 THESIS VII 
 
 Marriage is honorable and in harmony with man*s dignity. 
 Jouin, 160-172; Eickaby, 263-270. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Society in General. We pass now from man as an individ- 
 ual in his private capacity to man as an individual unit in 
 society. We recognize three kinds of complete societies. 
 They are domestic, civil and ecclesiastical, known as family, 
 state and Church. Society itself in the general acceptation 
 of the word means a union of two or more persons with a 
 common aim or purpose. Such a union necessarily supposes 
 in parties to it an intellect capable of grasping a general 
 good, and a free will able to direct the agent's energies. So- 
 ciety is, therefore, a something proper and limited to ra- 
 tional creatures. Instinct guides brute creation in the per- 
 formance of works that imitate the unity of design apparent 
 in human societj^ The characteristic difference between man 
 and brute is thus tersely and beautifully hit off by Lytton in 
 ''My Novel" — ''The herd of deer shuns the stag that is 
 marked by the gunner, the flock heedeth not the sheep that 
 creeps into the shade to die ; but man has joy and sorrow not 
 in himself alone, but in the joy and sorrow of those around 
 him." 
 
 Society is made up of two elements. Multitude constitutes 
 only its material or less important factor; its formal being 
 arises from that unity of purpose or harmony of action de- 
 rived to it from authority. Another item of consequence in 
 the nature of a society is its completeness or incompleteness. 
 The only valid excuse for any society's existence is the defi- 
 nite end or scope it proposes to itself to compass; and this 
 
 289 
 
290 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 end, whatever it may be, furnishes us with a clew to the rank 
 it can with justice claim in the order of societies. Much, too, 
 depends on the solution of the question of a society's com- 
 pleteness or incompleteness. If complete, it can vindicate to 
 itself a species of independence in its own sphere of activity, 
 and can warn off all intruders. If incomplete, it is essen- 
 tially dependent on the complete society of which it forms a 
 branch, and cannot with any show of right object to outside 
 interference. A society is complete, if the end it aims at 
 bears a universal aspect, or at least claims some influence over 
 every single energy exerted by members of the society, or is of 
 such a nature that it cannot be classified under any of the 
 purposes for which other complete societies exist. It is in- 
 complete, if the good aimed at is restricted to certain lines, 
 appeals not to all a man 's energies but only to one or several, 
 and readily ranges itself under the comprehensive object of 
 some known and complete society. Instances of incomplete 
 societies are a Literary Club, a Reading Circle, a Lyceum, a 
 Business Partnership, Knights of Labor. These several bod- 
 ies are all intended solely to promote the intellectual, financial 
 and social interests of their members; and, as such, fall un- 
 der the jurisdiction of that complete society denominated the 
 State. 
 
 Only three societies are recognized as complete, the Family, 
 the State and the Church. All three are man's natural guard- 
 ians from the cradle to the grave in different spheres of ac- 
 tivity. The State is a centre, and procures for a man goods 
 pertaining to this life, and apt to suffer loss in his intercourse 
 with his fellows. The family is the doorway to the state, it 
 is the state in germ, and secures to a man the splendid gifts 
 of existence and an education, enabling him to cope with 
 neighbors in the state. The Church, besides promoting peace 
 and civilization in the state, busies itself with concerns of 
 vaster importance, the business of souls with God, the con- 
 summation of a happy eternity. The family can be best de- 
 scribed as a union of husband, wife and children for mutual 
 assistance, the procreation and education of offspring. It is 
 an institution designed first and foremost for the perpetuation 
 of the species and for the bestowal of that home-training, 
 which rounds out a man's development, without which in 
 
MARRIAGE 291 
 
 spite of State and Church future citizens will necessarily be 
 unfinished and imperfect. Its second scope is the mutual 
 help, assistance and comfort afforded the man and woman thus 
 united ; a help, assistance and comfort they cannot legitimately 
 enjoy in any other condition of life. The State is a complete 
 collection of men banded together for the purpose of safe- 
 guarding their rights and securing their common good. It 
 secures to men material advantages they could never hope to 
 enjoy in their individual capacities, advantages altogether dis- 
 tinct from such as Church and family confer. The Church 
 is a collection of men banded together for purposes of eternal 
 salvation by profession of one and the same faith, and by 
 participation in the same sacraments, under the rule of duly 
 accredited superiors, especially the Pope of Rome. This is 
 an exact description of the Roman Catholic, the only true 
 Church, as propounded by Cardinal Bellarmine. We strenu- 
 ously maintain that no other body of men is truly deserving 
 of the name, Church, and regard all the sects as associations 
 far from divine, human institutions subject to the jurisdic- 
 tion of the several states that countenance their establishment. 
 Every society is, morally speaking and in the eyes of the 
 law, a moral person. Community or singleness of aim makes 
 one the minds and the wills of the individuals, and in the 
 language of philosophy a person is a being possessed of mind 
 and will. Every society is, therefore, from this point of view 
 really and truly vested with rights and amenable* to definite 
 duties. The whole difference between an individual and a 
 society is expressed when we say that the individual is a phys- 
 ical person, the society is a moral person. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Marriage. The family is compounded of at least two ele- 
 ments, conjugal society and paternal. The first results from 
 union of man and wife, and takes its rise from marriage. The 
 second supposes the advent of children, and regulates the 
 relations between parents and offspring. Marriage may be 
 considered as an act or a state. Taken as an act, marriage 
 is a contract by which a man and woman mutually surrender 
 each to the other the use of their bodies for generative pur- 
 
292 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 poses, and bind themselves to live together in unity. Taken 
 as a state, marriage is a union between man and wife with 
 aU the characteristics of a life-partnership, a condition of 
 affairs in which two minds have but a single thought, two 
 hearts do beat as one. 
 
 Marriage is the plan divine wisdom hit upon for the propa- 
 gation of the human race, and the traits of the human species 
 are so admirably adapted to the- plan that extinction is a 
 very remote possibility. The Creator has fitted the two sexes 
 with physical and moral qualities such that one sex is the 
 complement of the other, one fills the other's needs, and the 
 two united in matrimony come near the perfection of an ideal 
 human being. To secure the preservation of the race, God 
 has implanted in men and women a passionate leaning to- 
 wards wedlock. He has at the same time denied man char- 
 acteristic virtues that can be borrowed only from woman. A 
 woman in the same way is something incomplete, unless a 
 man's companionship contributes new perfections to her life. 
 Man has arms and limbs stored with strength, woman is of 
 a more delicate mould. Man's physical force makes him 
 impetuous and brave even to rashness. A woman's bodily 
 weakness renders her slow to violence and timid. Woman's 
 influence curbs man 's fiery spirit, man 's influence raises wom- 
 an 's courage and allays her fears. Man is quick to think, 
 and rushes to conclusions; woman is slower, and by her de- 
 liberateness checks man's mistakes. Man is rough and un- 
 gentle, woman is smooth and mild-mannered ; and the blend- 
 ing of these opposite qualities results in commendable hardi- 
 hood and strength of character. ]\Ian is impatient in the 
 face of obstacles and difficulties, and if left to himself would 
 dash out his life against them ; but woman is patient and long- 
 suffering, and her example is a perpetual incentive to that 
 perseverance, which, combined with energy, is sure to win. 
 Man is something of a stranger to pity and only extreme 
 misery appeals to his attention; woman is all sympathy and 
 awake to every cry of pain or wretchedness. Man is easily de- 
 jected and cast down by adversity, woman never parts com- 
 pany with hope, and is a past grand master in the art of 
 comforting and encouraging. We might thus go on indefi- 
 nitely marking off the traits peculiar to one sex and the 
 
MAN AND WOMAN 293 
 
 other ; but from the few hints set down it must be evident that 
 man and woman were meant by Heaven for mutual help and 
 assistance. When they combine forces, they make of what 
 would be two imperfect lives one single power for happiness, 
 good and blessedness. Of course, this desirable turn of events 
 is had only when man and woman in marriage honestly co- 
 operate with God's designs. If His plans are disregarded, 
 marriage can become a positive curse and a heavy misfortune. 
 The worst evil this earth knows is the abuse of a good thing ; 
 and marriage is so good a thing that Christ Himself went 
 out of His way to grace a wedding with His presence, and 
 bless it with His first miracle. 
 
 Intellectual acumen of very ordinary quality can readily 
 understand what a hell on earth married life can become when 
 accursed of God. The indissolubility of the marriage-tie 
 makes escape impossible. Enforced singleness is the only 
 alternative; and, if offspring has blessed the union, this lone 
 remedy is almost out of the question. A hundred causes are 
 at work after marriage to steal away the allurements, that 
 before the event seemed destined to last forever. Its joys be- 
 come humdrum and tiresome. The monotony of one person's 
 perpetual company is killing. The partners to the contract, 
 like all mortals, have their faults ; and these faults show head 
 with amazing rapidity. Unforeseen difficulties arise, and 
 nothing short of God's grace can keep man and wife to their 
 duties of love, affection and mutual support. If religious 
 need grace to persevere in their heroic purpose, their brothers 
 and sisters in the world need it none the less to live up to 
 th6ir obligations without blame and without reproach. 
 
 Marriage is said to be a lottery. Of course, the risks deter 
 very few from choosing the state, and to be unduly influenced 
 by the dangers inseparably connected with it, would be rank 
 cowardice. To adopt the profession of bachelor from baser 
 motives, would be a crime. About celibacy we shall have 
 more to say later. With God's blessing and a fair measure 
 of good will these dangers can be reduced to mere shadows, 
 and everyday experience is standing proof that they need 
 frighten no man of trust and courage. 
 
 Neglecting for the present details that belong rather to the 
 province of spiritual advice, common sense vouches for the 
 
294 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 supreme need of friendliness and love in the man and woman 
 contemplating marriage. Friendliness is the entrance court 
 to love's shrine, and without love marriage must prove a 
 wretched failure. Kindred tastes, kindred studies, kindred 
 pursuits, may indeed produce friendship and agreeable com- 
 panionship; but without genuine love they cannot serve as 
 solid supports for marriage. The reason is evident. Tastes, 
 studies, pursuits are concerns of the head and hands, they 
 never reach the heart. It is a union that must endure in 
 spite of the senses, in spite of crooked reason, in spite of 
 every conceivable adversary. It is an amalgamation of wills, 
 and a man's will is under control of his heart largely, and 
 love is only another term for the heart 's activity. 
 
 This love is an elusive thing and hard to analyze. That 
 love lives of beauty seems certain, and beauty is of all degrees 
 and phases. To begin with, there is beauty of body and 
 beauty of soul, and the two are independent possessions. 
 Very few of God's creatures own the combination. Beauty 
 of body most frequently turns the head of its possessor, and 
 makes the soul hideous with pride, unkindness and a host of 
 other vices. Lack of bodily charms concentrates the unfor- 
 tunate's attention on the cultivation of inner good qualities, 
 with a view to coyering outward deficiencies. Since, there- 
 fore, this twofold beauty is of rare occurrence in one and the 
 same person, men and women who rush into love must fasten 
 their hearts on one or the other. In choice of an anchor, 
 endurance and strength are deciding characteristics; and as 
 between beauty of body and beauty of soul there can be no 
 quarrel. Growth in years is a condition of our existence, 
 and age develops wrinkles, prime destroyers of fair features. 
 Age bends the body and works sad havoc in its shape. The 
 soul is beyond the reach of time 's ravages, and improves like 
 wine with age. Its beauty lasts forever, and hopes tied to 
 it will never slip their moorings. Of course facial attractions 
 are seldom altogether wanting, and lovers have a knack of 
 discovering lines and curves that escape the untutored and 
 uninterested eye. 
 
 It is no mistake to look for some attractiveness of form and 
 figure in a future partner. The blunder consists in being 
 blind to everything else, and foolishly expecting love to last 
 
LOVE AND MARRIAGE 295 
 
 after its sole motive has disappeared with the progress of 
 years. Lacordaire has some very striking language on the 
 topic. ''Love," he says, ''has but one cause, and that cause 
 is beauty. Whenever man is in presence of a nature in which 
 that terrible gift shines, if he be not sheltered by a divine 
 shield, he will feel its power. However stubborn, however 
 proud he may be, he will come like a child to bend at the 
 feet of that something which he has seen and which has sub- 
 dued him by a look, by a hair of its neck — 'in uno crine 
 colli sui' — according to the admirable language of Scripture. 
 Beauty which is the source of love is also the source of the 
 greatest desolation here below, as if Providence and nature 
 repented of having endowed some of us with so rich and rare 
 a gift." Later on, adverting to the beauty rooted in virtue 
 and holiness of life, he says, "Man is invested with a beauty 
 he had not before. But what beauty? If I look upon you, 
 I see no change. Your face is the face I knew yesterday, and 
 you have even lost something in the correctness of the lines 
 of your physiognomy. "What new beauty have you then re- 
 ceived? Ah, a beauty which leaves you man and is never- 
 theless divine. Jesus Christ has put upon you His own image ; 
 He has touched your soul with His own ; He has made of you 
 and Himself one single moral being. It is no longer you; 
 it is He who lives in you. That beauty which the world sees 
 not, we Christians perceive. It pierces through dishonored 
 humanity. We feel it, we seek it. It attracts us, not for a 
 day, like human beauty; but with the indelible charm of 
 eternity. One day, and perhaps soon, that speech which an- 
 nounces doctrine to you will grow dull. Decline draws near 
 to man with rapidity, and brings with itself solitude and 
 oblivion. When that time comes, there will remain to me 
 in your souls only the recollection of an echo. But to me, 
 as to you, in life as in death, the beauty which comes from 
 Christ will remain ; His visage which is upon us and the love 
 which springs from it, to gladden us while living and to 
 embalm us in the tomb." Conf. 25. 
 
 Honorable means in harmony with man's dignity. Because 
 it is an article of faith with us, and, therefore, a truth con- 
 tained in revelation, that virginity and celibacy are prefer- 
 able to wedlock, and that single blessedness is better and hap- 
 
296 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 pier than marriage, we Catholics are accused by our enemies 
 of belittling matrimony, a great sacrament in God's Church. 
 But the charge is wholly unfounded. In fact, matrimony is 
 nowhere done so much reverence as in our Church. True, 
 our priests, in virtue of their calling, are debarred from all 
 the comforts and solaces of the wedded state. But they make 
 free choice of the sacrifice with their eyes wide open, and are 
 by no means forced into the difficulty. Long before ordina- 
 tion they are made acquainted with the sternness of their 
 vocation, and before they take the final step are unrestrain- 
 edly free to follow any easier path of duty. Far from dis- 
 countenancing marriage, priests are the first to urge its ad- 
 vantages on young men and young women so inclined. They 
 certainly maintain with the Council of Trent that celibacy 
 or virginity is a more desirable state; but prudently warn 
 away from these higher fields of virtue souls not manifestly 
 invited by Heaven. They can appeal to the following facts, 
 when challenged for proof that Catholicity entertains a higher 
 and more sacred esteem for matrimony than sects outside of 
 the true Church. First of all. Catholicity ranks matrimony 
 one of the seven sacraments. It counts entrance into this 
 holy state without confession and a clean heart a sacrilege. 
 It so vindicates matrimony from everything profane, that it 
 forbids the civil power to touch it. It employs the magnifi- 
 cence of its ritual to deck with all possible grandeur the sol- 
 emn ceremony. It sets apart a special Mass, special prayers, 
 special blessings for the occasion. It abominates and anathe- 
 matizes that plague-sore of modern civilization, that foul 
 wrong to Christ and His Church, that menace to peace of 
 families and the life of the state, absolute divorce. The 
 Church has fought many a battle in history to defend mar- 
 riage against the attacks of mad fanatics and rebellious here- 
 tics. The Manichees were among the first to attack its sacred- 
 ness. They condemned it as the immediate means of propa- 
 gating and multiplying original sin. They appealed to pas- 
 sages in St. Paul like the following : 
 
 " It is good for a man not to touch a woman. ' ' 1 Cor. 7. 1. 
 ' ' That they also who have wives be as if they had none. ' ' 1 
 Cor. 7. 29. ''And they who are in the flesh cannot please 
 God." Rom. 8. 8. 
 
MARRIAGE HONORABLE 297 
 
 But the Church for the insults thus offered Christ's doc- 
 trine branded them heretics, and the Church's Doctors rid 
 the faithful of uneasiness and doubt by interpreting aright 
 the texts called into question. In reference to the above ar- 
 guments we say that, regarding the first, God permits the 
 propagation of original sin to avoid extinction of the human 
 race. Regarding the second argument, St. Paul refers to 
 women who are not the wives of the men in question. In 
 reference to the third, St. Paul refers to the married state 
 as being short, and that the end of the world for each indi- 
 vidual man is when he dies. Regarding the last, St. Paul 
 is talking about the spirit and the flesh. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 1. That is honorable and in harmony with man's dignity, 
 which tallies with the divine decrees and with an inborn in- 
 clination rooted in the senses and in reason. But marriage 
 is such. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major. Man's true honor and man's 
 true dignity consist in perfect harmony with his Creator's 
 wishes, and in obedience to legitimate instincts implanted in 
 his bosom. These wishes of the Creator are distinctly legible 
 in His works, these legitimate instincts are keen, and always 
 commend themselves to conscience. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. We gather God's wishes and 
 designs on human nature from arrangements made by His 
 wisdom and plain to the senses. Difference of sex, the whole 
 physiological structure of man and woman, the moral char- 
 acteristics of the one and the other, are evident signs that 
 God wants them to marry. Man's instinctive inclination to 
 wedlock, approved and encouraged by reason, is another over- 
 whelming motive. The desire is not confined to the lower 
 or sensile faculties of man's nature. Marriage with men is 
 a higher and more ennobling act than intercourse between 
 beasts, than union for mere purposes of pleasure. It is a 
 want which, left unfilled, affects a whole life, and makes that 
 nice balance of qualities already referred to either an abso- 
 lute impossibility or a tremendous difficulty. Young men and 
 young women, who with the approval of God and religion 
 
298 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 do violence to the inclination, and sacrifice on the altar of 
 God's love the joys, and the comforts, and the hopes, resident 
 in marriage, are nothing short of heroes and deserve monu- 
 ments. They have at the hands of Catholics, able to appre- 
 ciate the motive and the measure of unselfishness displayed, a 
 reverence, a respect and an affection denied every other ac- 
 quaintance. His vow of chastity is the secret of the priest's 
 success with men. The nun's influence on the street, in our 
 homes, on the battle-field, everywhere, is due to the same 
 cause. And the day of judgment will reveal the mag- 
 nanimity of many a man and woman outside of religion, who 
 from regard for parents or equally high incentives underwent 
 the martyrdom of distasteful singleness. Many an old maid 
 would challenge our admiration, if only the secrets of her 
 heart were laid bare. 
 
 2°. Whatever is necessary to the right increase and preser- 
 vation of the human race, is honorable and in harmony with 
 man's dignity. 
 
 But marriage is such. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Man is the pinnacle of crea- 
 tion and the end or wherefore of the whole visible universe. 
 God, therefore, wishes His most perfect work to prosper and 
 continue till the consummation of time. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor. Marriage is the method by 
 divine law appointed for the propagation and continuance of 
 the human species. Man's offspring, because of peculiar con- 
 ditions, needs during the first period of existence and child- 
 hood the fostering care of a mother and the directive energy 
 of a father. If deprived of this twofold help, children would 
 grow up too weak and too unable to perform the functions 
 of moral and physical life. The race would go to ruin and 
 disappear in a single generation. God has so ordained that 
 the young of other animals either have no need at all of 
 parents after birth, or need their assistance for only a lim- 
 ited period. But the child's helplessness makes the presence 
 of a father and a mother imperatively necessary for years. 
 It is a remarkable fact, too, that the progeny of the nobler 
 animals in brute creation imitate more or less in this par- 
 ticular the offspring of men. 
 
 Other proofs for believers : 
 
PROOFS 299 
 
 Hebr. 13.4. Marriage honorable in all. 
 Gen. 2.24. Mark 10.7. A divine institution. 
 John 2. Christ at Cana. 
 Eph. 5.25. Dignity of sacrament. 
 Multiplication of souls for Heaven. 
 
 Rickaby, p. 264. If one refuses to eat, nobody can eat for 
 him. If one refuses to propagate race, others can supply. 
 Remote obligation, proximate obligation. If race threatened 
 to become extinct, law against bachelors. Some excused ; en- 
 tirely free ; unable to find or to win. Foregoing marriage for 
 purposes of travel, study or devotion can be a good thing. 
 Self-preservation ; old without young ; winter without spring. 
 The two ways of propagating the race are, marriage and 
 promiscuity of love. 
 
 Promiscuity of love is rejected because eventually it would 
 be suicidal, and would lead to infertility, disease ; it has been 
 pronounced physiologically impossible because of resulting 
 barrenness. 
 
 Furthermore, promiscuity of love is against the two ends 
 of marriage — fides, rational; proles, animal. 
 
 The mother imparts love. The father imparts wisdom and 
 firmness. Both manifest interest in the child. There is mu- 
 tual faith. Plato and Aristotle insist on both, on account of 
 opposite characteristics already noted. 
 
THESIS vm 
 
 Celibacy, when love of virtue is its motive, is more excellent 
 than matrimony. Jouin, 172-174. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Celibacy . Word-meaning: Coelibatus or coelebs is from 
 KOLrq, XctTTw) ; or from (coelum, jSatvw) ; or from kolXiI3o's = 
 orbatus = orphaned. The two first derivations mean respec- 
 tively to forego marriage and to journey towards Heaven. 
 
 Celibacy and virginity compared. Virginity means integ- 
 rity, or immunity from pleasures of the flesh. It is twofold, 
 physical and moral. 
 
 Moral, or integrity of mind, is purity, chastity, continency, 
 or a habitual state of opposition to thoughts, desires and deeds 
 connected with suggestions of the flesh. Physical virginity is 
 a corresponding condition of body. Celibacy is life outside 
 of the married state, and its patrons are commonly entitled 
 bachelors and maids. God's law and nature's express pro- 
 hibition against the indulgence of pleasures connected with 
 wedlock, when perpetrated outside of the holy state of mar- 
 riage, make virginity the only approved course compatible 
 with celibacy. Any departure from this stern law constitutes 
 sin, and any other view of celibacy would be wicked. Hence, 
 though celibacy and virginity are distinct ideas, and of very 
 different objective value, they practically coincide, if men 
 and women want to lead upright lives, in strict conformity 
 with God's wishes and the laws of morality. 
 
 Outside of the priesthood and religion, or dedication to 
 God's service by vows, celibacy is always unstable, and re- 
 mains a matter of choice up to the latest breath of the man 
 or woman preferring the condition. But aspirants to the 
 priesthood, or to the perfection of the religious state, must 
 make up their minds once for all, and abide forever after by 
 the decision. Hope of relief, after the step has been once 
 
 300 
 
CELIBACY 301 
 
 taken, would rob the sacrifice of half its heroism. The ir- 
 revocable nature of the obligations assumed by priests and 
 persons consecrated to God renders their conduct to people 
 outside of the Church, and unacquainted with the workings 
 of God's grace, a mystery offering to their shallow ignorance 
 one only solution, that of broken vows and damnable hy- 
 pocrisy. Indeed, without supernatural assistance, without 
 the strictest kind of compliance with the rigorous precautions 
 prescribed by the Church, there would in many instances be 
 no other avenue of escape from the difficulties encountered. 
 
 Celibacy in the Church of Christ is an assured institution. 
 Since that memorable day the Master said to His puzzled 
 apostles, ''He that can take, let him take it," St. Matt. 19.12, 
 multitudes of men and women have heeded the hard counsel, 
 and persevered till death in a life more befitting angelic 
 spirits than bodies of flesh. St. Peter is the only one of the 
 twelve mentioned in the Gospel as married, and tradition is 
 witness that after his call to the ministry he lived apart from 
 his wife. Certainly the custom of clerical celibacy, now and 
 for the past 1500 years universal in the Western Church, 
 dates its origin back to the times of the apostles. The only 
 legislation on this point, explicitly laid down in St. Paul's 
 letters, is a rule to the effect that bishops be men of one wife, 
 i.e., men who never married a second time. But hints about 
 the discipline in use are manifest in Christ's exhortation, 
 ]\ratt. 19.12, in St. Paul's letter, 1 Cor. 7.32, in the Apocalypse, 
 14.4, "There are eunuchs who have made themselves eunuchs 
 for the kingdom of God." ''He that is without a wife is 
 solicitous for the things that belong to the Lord." "These 
 are they who were not defiled with women, for they are vir- 
 gins. ' ' 
 
 The primitive Church knew well the secret of strength 
 hidden in the celibacy of the clergy. It appreciated the value 
 of that apostolic freedom, which cannot be hampered by the 
 cares of a family, and took it for granted that God expects 
 from His ambassadors and representatives the service of an 
 undivided heart. The early Christians, with the words of 
 Christ still ringing in their ears, must have regarded con- 
 tinence a diviner gift than marriage, and would not be in- 
 sensible to the desirableness of this ornament in their priests. 
 
302 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Writers teU us that a marked difference on the score of 
 celibacy existed in the Eastern and Western Churches from 
 the beginning. The Latins always betrayed a decided lean- 
 ing towards strict celibacy as a profession. We have records 
 to prove that in the fourth century celibacy was of obliga- 
 tion for clerics in the three highest orders of subdeacon, dea- 
 con and priest. In the year 305 a council of Spanish and 
 African bishops held at Elvira insisted on the rule, and em- 
 phasized its enforcement by new enactments. About the 
 same time, 325, in a council at Nice an attempt to introduce 
 the same law into the Eastern Church was defeated by the 
 efforts of a holy abbot named Paphnucius. There always, 
 however, existed in the East a tradition to the effect that no 
 cleric should marry after admission to orders, and this law 
 is in force with the Greeks to-day. Pope Siricius in the 4th 
 century under pain of excommunication forbade priests of 
 the Latin communion to have intercourse with their wives, and 
 declared the children of such intercourse illegitimate. At 
 Tours in 567 married monks and nuns were visited with ex- 
 communication, and their marriages were declared null and 
 void. Among the Greeks the ordinary or secular clergy are 
 not by rule celibates. They must, however, marry before 
 elevation to the priesthood, and on the death of his wife the 
 priest must become a monk. Their bishops are chosen, not 
 from the ranks of the secular clergy, but from among the 
 monks or religious. To obviate the difficulty, students in 
 Greek seminaries leave the house of studies before taking 
 deacon's orders, and return married. They are then ready 
 for ordination to the priesthood, and are free to live with 
 their wives after the ceremony. 
 
 Celibacy, as is evident from this circumstance, is a matter 
 of Church discipline, not a restriction imposed on the min- 
 isters of the altar by Christ or the Gospel. As such, the law 
 of celibacy could for sufficient reasons be revoked by the Pope 
 to-morrow. But no such calamity is in near prospect. The 
 so-called reformers in 1520 agreed among themselves to preach 
 down celibacy by word and example, as a thing contrary to 
 the natural law; and, like all advocates of theories grateful 
 to human nature and luxury of sense, soon attracted a crowd 
 to their standard. Level headed students of the impious 
 
CHURCH AND CELIBACY 303 
 
 movement, set on foot by these rebels against Church author- 
 ity, are of opinion that Luther's sensuality had more to do 
 with the revolt than his ambition. It would be sacrilegious 
 and contrary to common sense to imagine that zeal for God's 
 glory had anything to do with the scheme. Monks, and nuns, 
 and priests, who fretted under the discipline of their vows, 
 were only too glad to find an excuse for passion in reform's 
 convenient doctrine. They were only too eager to enroll them- 
 selves with these slaves to passion. Why, even in old Greece 
 and old Rome, the priests of the nation were exempt from the 
 penalties inflicted on celibates in every other walk of life. 
 Vestal virgins, recreant to their vow, were burnt to death. 
 No sacrifice, no act of religious worship was considered com- 
 plete, unless supplemented with a virgin 's prayers. Celibacy 
 with Greeks and Romans was invariably accounted the priv- 
 ilege and the duty of the priesthood. The consecration of 
 this condition to persons immediately connected with the serv- 
 ice of the gods, is a living index of the sacredness of celibacy, 
 and of its superiority from a religious and moral standpoint 
 over matrimony. It is likewise a tribute from antiquity to 
 the good sense displayed by the Church, in imposing the obli- 
 gation on her clergy, a sweeping denial of Protestantism's 
 pretensions to piety, and an emphatic proof that the reform- 
 ers of the sixteenth century were sunk lower in the depths 
 of sensual degradation than the very pagans. 
 
 Virtuo'us Motives. Celibacy, in the words of our thesis, is 
 more excellent than matrimony, only when adopted from vir- 
 tuous motives. When adopted from sinister designs, to enjoy 
 luxury and dissipation with more freedom, to wallow in un- 
 clean pleasure without the care attendant on the raising of a 
 family, it is a crime in the eyes of God and men, deserving 
 of eternal chastisement and the scorn of time. This reflec- 
 tion, no doubt, induced the ancients to enforce against celi- 
 bacy, outside of the priesthood, the severe penalties in evi- 
 dence on their statute-books. In Sparta bachelors were reck- 
 oned infamous. The law permitted women to seize and tor- 
 ture them in the temple. In Rome they were denied the 
 rights of witnesses, their last wills and testaments were not 
 respected, and they were threatened with horrible torments 
 in the future life. Plato saw fit to insert in the code of law, 
 
304 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 framed to regulate his imaginary republic, a clause to the 
 effect that citizens not married before 35 years of age should 
 ever after remain ineligible to offices of whatever sort. Writ- 
 ers remark, however, that, with progress in Greece and Rome, 
 celibacy became daily more common. Athletes, scholars and 
 men of various professions were accorded the privilege of en- 
 joying single blessedness unmolested, and were put on a foot- 
 ing with the priesthood in this particular. Philosophers, like 
 the disciples of Pythagoras and Diogenes, always claimed the 
 right to forego marriage for purposes of study, and had their 
 claim allowed. 
 
 And now a word about modern celibacy, which threatens to 
 become so serious an evil that some legislators have debated 
 the advisability of imposing a yearly tax on bachelors. With- 
 out wishing to range ourselves with Horace's "laudatores 
 temporis acti,'' we feel prone to acknowledge that marriage 
 has lost on the affections of men and women that hold it 
 had a hundred years ago. In the higher walks of life it is 
 infrequent and oftener unhappy than of yore. In the lower 
 levels of society, barring the setbacks consequent on extreme 
 poverty, marriage holds its own ; and, because of the strength 
 locked up in union, will forever retain its charms and attrac- 
 tiveness for the poor. But marriage 's losses are perhaps most 
 noticeable in the middle ranks. Men and women comfortably 
 well off and able with ease to live on the products of their 
 own labor, are daily becoming more and more content with 
 themselves, more and more loath to enter into relations of 
 close affinity with others. 
 
 The ''new woman" is much to blame for the sorry pass to 
 which things are come. She aspires to be in some respects 
 a man. She joins the army of workers, invades the profes- 
 sions, and intrudes herself into employment once considered 
 her brother's peculiar property. Timid man shudders at 
 her energy, and is conscious of a lurking suspicion that mar- 
 riage would mean for him enthrallment. He knows, and 
 knows instinctively, that God mercifully meant him to be 
 head of the family and his partner's superior in matters do- 
 mestic. In the good old times women found it pleasant and 
 easy to acknowledge the supremacy of men, and trusted to 
 their native art and sweetness to cajole husbands into a 
 
MODERN CELIBACY 305 
 
 slavery, blissful, because gilded with ignorance. But now the 
 women ambition and fill with more or less success the parts 
 of men, and even if they never resort in matrimony to open 
 handed revolt, are always in a position to unfurl the stand- 
 ard. 
 
 One writer contends that solicitude for the support of a 
 family makes marriage particularly injurious to the profes- 
 sions. Lawyers, ministers, judges, statesmen, will be in con- 
 tinual search for the dollar. They will in a mercenary spirit 
 pursue methods, preach sermons, hand down decisions and 
 frame laws, all with a view to coin. They will on occasions 
 yield to the temptation to work along dishonest lines, to do 
 violence to the gospel in reducing Christianity to a minimum 
 of hardship, to accept bribes, and open the palm for lobby- 
 ists' money. Their work will certainly not be disinterested; 
 and, when a spirit of self-interest dominates, true work and 
 good results are next to impossible. Domestic felicity is nec- 
 essarily selfish, celibacy is in the nature of things more open 
 to generous impulses. Men wedded to their profession solely, 
 are capable of larger and better work than men wedded to 
 their profession and a wife. Married men must, if true to 
 their obligations, devote no inconsiderable part of their time 
 and attention to the mistresses of their homes. These sug- 
 gest themselves as a few of the motives calculated to nowa- 
 days frighten men away from matrimony. 
 
 Women on their part can afford to be more exacting than 
 formerly in their choice. The new movement in their favor, 
 this modern emancipation of the sex, has thrown open to 
 them many and various avenues for a livelihood. They are 
 in consequence more independent, and less liable to be dis- 
 appointed, when trusting to their own resources. A woman 
 is, besides, never at a loss to make her habitation put on all 
 the appearance of a home. She is easily man's superior in 
 this respect. A bachelor's apartments never wear anything 
 but the semblance of a den. The newspapers, too, make the 
 proceedings of the divorce court public property; and in 
 nearly every case the woman's wrongs fill a large part of the 
 story. From the sad experience of her sisters every woman 
 knows pretty thoroughly the risks she takes when sealing her- 
 self over for better or worse to the amiable tyrant, man. 
 
306 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Thus, the two parties to the contract are thoroughly well 
 advertised of the evils attendant on matrimony, and their 
 dread of the relation rises. The thought robs of some of its 
 humor that title of an old book, "How to be Happy, though 
 Married, ' ^ and vindicates to Fenelon 's description of marriage 
 more common sense than was first granted it, **un etat de 
 tribulation tres penible, auquel il faut se preparer en esprit 
 de penitence, quand on s'y croit appele." **A state of trib- 
 ulation, painful in the extreme, for which he who thinks 
 himself called to it must prepare himself in a spirit of pen- 
 ance. ^ ' But marriage, after all, is an institution of God ; and 
 religion can throw round it a halo able to make it a thing 
 of surpassing beauty. All the evils hitherto mentioned are 
 but accidents. They are not inseparably interwoven with 
 marriage. They all take their rise from a mistaken notion 
 of things, and first put in an appearance when the grace of 
 God has abandoned the hearts of man and wife. The sacra- 
 ment, when worthily received and approached with the proper 
 dispositions, can store two souls with a measure of heavenly 
 strength abundantly able to tide them over all the troubles 
 and trials attached to their station in life. The husband, if 
 docile to the inspirations of grace, will continue to his latest 
 breath what God wants him to be; the wife will prove for- 
 ever a real helpmate, not a stumbling block; and marriage 
 will assume all the proportions of a magnificent blessing. 
 
 There are two kinds of celibacy, virtuous and vicious. Mo- 
 tives make difference. Virtuous has for motive the honor of 
 God, salvation of souls, prayer, study, charity, chastity. Vi- 
 cious has for motive opportunity to sin with freedom; no 
 watchful eye of wife, wrong company possible, excessive ease 
 and leisure. 
 
 More Excellent. The excellence of celibacy is a settled ques- 
 tion with Catholics. The Council of Trent defined it against 
 the reformers, and our thesis is a dogma of faith. Here are 
 the exact words of the definition: **If any one presumes to 
 say that the state of marriage is to be preferred before the 
 state of celibacy and virginity, and that to remain in celibacy 
 or virginity is not better and happier than to be joined in 
 wedlock, let him be anathema." Sess. 24. Can. 10. 
 
 Theologians remark that the goodness and happiness here 
 
TRENT AND CELIBACY 307 
 
 vindicated to celibacy are spiritual, not material, not the re- 
 sult of sensual pleasure. They describe this sort of goodness 
 as union of the soul with God in love, this sort of happiness 
 as the joy resulting to the soul from this union. 
 
 The reformers of the sixteenth century were not the first 
 heretics to attack celibacy. One Jovinian, a writer of St. 
 Jerome 's time, and condemned by Pope Siricius in 363, waged 
 incessant war against the holy custom. Strange to say, he 
 never himself led a wife to the altar, and lived in open con- 
 tradiction with his theories. St. Jerome was so vehement in 
 fighting down the influence of Jovinian 's pernicious doctrine 
 that his zeal sometimes got the better of his prudence, and 
 he seems to inveigh against matrimony. Luther was pleased 
 to denominate virginity, * * unholy superstition, because a man- 
 ner of worship nowhere countenanced by God." He like- 
 wise called it * 'folly," imagining, no doubt, that every man 
 was as incontinent as himself. The rationalists style virgin- 
 ity, ''A horrid monster, destructive of nature." 
 
 We must as mere philosophers endeavor to make good our 
 position without reference to the Scriptures as inspired writ- 
 ings. Passages will, however, be cited from their pages, be- 
 cause we must never forget that we are merely assuming the 
 role of philosophers, without ever ceasing to be in reality 
 children of Christ's Church and Catholics. The perfection 
 and the blessedness of union with God are not notions beyond 
 the reach of any mind acquainted with our earlier statements 
 concerning man's last end. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 1°. In comparison with matrimony, that state is more ex- 
 cellent which has fewer hindrances to union with God and 
 fewer disquieting desires. But celibacy, when love of virtue 
 is its motive, is just such a state. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: The excellence we vindicate to 
 celibacy in this present proof is made up of moral rectitude 
 and resulting happiness. Union with God is the acme of 
 morality; and desire is the root of unrighteousness, as it is 
 the destruction of union. 
 ' With Regard to the Minor: St. Paul urges this advan- 
 
308 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 tage — "He that is without a wife is solicitous for the things 
 that belong to the Lord, how he may please God. But he 
 that is with a wife is solicitous for the things of the world, 
 how he may please his wife, and he is divided.'' 1 Cor. 7.32. 
 
 Another writer, the author of ''Natural Law in the Spir- 
 itual World,'' beautifully shows how attachments of what- 
 ever sort are obstacles to the soul's progress towards God. 
 Taking a tree or plant for instance, he derives lessons from 
 the advantages of an environment free from neighboring trees 
 and plants. He finds that the sole excuse for pruning is the 
 circumstance that profitable growth is developed by lopping 
 off superfluous branches, and confining energy to as few cen- 
 tres as possible. Centralization and unity of endeavor are 
 the secret of success in every department of the universe. 
 Attachments are hindrances in the matter of spiritual de- 
 velopment. Even harmless friendships are a drain on the 
 soul's vitality, and great saints succeeded where others failed, 
 only because their days knew many a sweet hour hidden with 
 God alone. 
 
 2°. A good in the order of virtue is more excellent than a 
 good in the order of nature. But celibacy is a good in the 
 order of virtue; marriage is a good in the order of nature. 
 Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Virtue is, after all, the only 
 true standard of man's excellence. Exercise of mind and will 
 puts him on a plane outside of and above brute creation, to 
 which he is half-brother. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Even naturally speaking, 
 celibacy, when prompted by virtue, is heroic ; and heroism is 
 the badge of manhood. It is the crowning effort of a mind 
 carried to the highest degree of cultivation, of a will schooled 
 to the limit in mastery of self. The ancients in honoring the 
 Yestals, and setting so much store by the prayer of virgin- 
 maidens, paid homage to the excellence resident in celibacy. 
 Celibacy is altogether an affair of the soul, marriage is largely 
 an affair of the body. 
 
 3°. Marriage is largely a process common in effect to man 
 and brute, it is prompted by the animal within us. Celibacy 
 is life in harmony with what is highest and best in us. It is 
 a reminder of the angels. In the words of our Lord, ' ' in the 
 
PROOFS 309 
 
 resurrectiojii they shall neither many, nor be married; but 
 shall be as the angels of God in Heaven." Mt. 22.30. 
 
 4°. Pleasures and cares detract from higher interests. Con- 
 stant endeavor to please one another. Worry and hustle to 
 maintain rank. Education of children. Eagerness for fat 
 inheritances. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. St. Thomas. C.G. 
 
 1. Matrimony for good of race, celibacy for good of indi- 
 vidual. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: What is for good of race need not be executed by 
 each individual. Race will be preserved, even if some re- 
 frain from marriage and adopt celibacy, to better pursue 
 other purposes that make for the good of mankind. 
 
 2. Organs fashioned, inclinations implanted by God. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: This provision was made for the race in gen- 
 eral. All have likewise the power to become carpenters and 
 soldiers. Only a certain few follow these employments. 
 Enough will always get married. Self-denial quite as im- 
 portant as enjoyment. Abstine et sustine. 
 
 3. Good for one, better for many, best for all. Ergo. 
 Answer: The eye is better than the foot and yet man is 
 
 not perfect without the foot. Some must marry, some must 
 remain single. 
 
 4. Virtue in moderation, celibacy an extreme. Ergo. 
 Answer: Extreme all right when it accords with reason. 
 
 Celibacy accords with reason, though angelic, and above the 
 common measure of men. 
 
 5. Concupiscence inflamed, perpetual struggle. Ergo. 
 Answer: Struggle not so perpetual as family cares. 
 
 Temptation comes and goes. Every victory weakens passion. 
 Self-denial and practice deaden desire. Marriage encour- 
 ages the animal and unfits the mind for contemplation. Mar- 
 riage may be better for this or that individual. Hence, ''he 
 that can take, let him take it." 
 
 6. ''Increase and multiply." Gen. 1.28. Ergo. 
 Answer: Obligation for race in general, I grant. Obliga- 
 tion for individuals, I deny. 
 
 N.B. Christ and St. John with many a saint would have 
 
310 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 broken the law. The saying can mean a benediction, not 
 order. Marriage more necessary at the beginning. Hence 
 virginity reserved for Christians. St. Jerome: Matrimony 
 instituted to people the earth ; virginity, to people Heaven. 
 
 B. 1. Tim. 4.2. Doctrine of devils, forbidding to marry. 
 
 Answer: Church never forbids to marry. Men make free 
 choice of celibacy. Church encourages to marry. Men must 
 abide by condition of society they enter. 
 
 1 Cor. 7.2. Let every man have his own wife. 
 
 Answer: Habeat not ducat, keep not take. Question about 
 men already married ; 27. Seek not a wife, no contradiction. 
 
 1. Cor. 7.26. For the present necessity, virginity good. 
 
 Answer: Necessity means family cares, not end of world. 
 St. Paul is an inspired writer. 
 
 1 Cor. 9.5. Power to carry about a woman {aheXKfyqv ywaiKd 
 
 TrepuiyeLv) . 
 
 Answer: St. Paul carried none. Not a wife, but a Chris- 
 tian woman. Holy women in Christ's company. All right 
 among Jews, scandal among Gentiles. Hence St. Paul omitted 
 it. Douay = a woman, a sister ; like viri f ratres. 
 
THESIS IS 
 
 Polygamy, though not against strict natural law, little ac- 
 cords with the same. Jouin, 174-177 ; Bickaby, 270-274. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 The wickedness of an act or state is measured by its de- 
 parture from right reason. When marriage defeats the pur- 
 pose for which God instituted the condition, marriage becomes 
 harmful and morally wrong. In the light of our knowledge, 
 God could have had but two chief ends in view in the insti- 
 tution of marriage, the propagation of the race, and the mu- 
 tual advantage of husband and wife. The first of these mo- 
 tives, far and away the more important, constitutes the pri- 
 mary end of marriage ; the other, quite important too, consti- 
 tutes its secondary motive. Were polygamy opposed to the 
 proper increase of the human family, we should not hesitate 
 to brand the practice a crime against strict natural law. It 
 would seem, however, to fall short of heinousness so grievous, 
 inasmuch as it nowise operates against the due begetting of 
 offspring. The children of such a union have no uncertain 
 father, and the responsibility of support in polygamy, as well 
 as the responsibility of education, attaches to some definite 
 individual. The absence of this feature in polyandry, or life 
 led in common by a woman with several men, renders it pe- 
 culiarly iniquitous, an open violation of strict natural law. 
 Another particularly obnoxious circumstance inseparable 
 from polyandry, is the consequent barrenness of the woman. 
 Such a state of affairs is nothing short of prostitution; and, 
 while it would be the inevitable outcome, if polygamy once 
 became universal, it would be the logical consequence of that 
 equality, supposed to be in force between man and wife. 
 The sexes are so evenly divided, that in the case of universal 
 polygamy there would not be enough women, and sin would 
 be the only recourse for men strangers to restraint. Besides, 
 
 311 
 
312 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 women in this matter of marriage ought to be on an equal 
 footing with men. If the husband in virtue of marriage has 
 exclusive rights over the body of the woman, the wife must 
 be understood to have no less exclusive rights over the body 
 of the man. Polygamy, however, is an open declaration of 
 the contrary. It concedes to woman no right of the kind, 
 and at the same time positively forbids her the measure of 
 liberty granted the man. She is bound to give him her un- 
 divided affection. He is free to parcel out his love as he 
 sees fit. Only women lost to all sense of decency and self- 
 respect could for a moment contemplate such degradation; 
 and polygamy, as a matter of fact, recruits its ranks by 
 yearly inportations of fallen women from large centres. But 
 we are anticipating our proofs. We said, when discussing 
 the natural law, that polygamy was one of the vexed ques- 
 tions in that department of ethics. We then chose that ex- 
 planation of the natural law, which distinguishes three classes 
 of sins against the natural law. To refresh the memory, re- 
 call what was then said. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Polygamy. It is a pretty well settled fact in theology that 
 monogamy was matrimony 's primitive form. An explicit law 
 restricting a man to one wife occurs nowhere in the early 
 pages of Holy Scripture. Pope Innocent III, and all Cath- 
 olics with him, find an implicit declaration of such a law in 
 Gen. 2.24. Adam is addressing Eve, and he says, '^Where- 
 fore a man shall leave father and mother, and shall cleave to 
 his wife; and they shall be two in one flesh." Pope Inno- 
 cent sees in this passage a condemnation of polygamy, saying, 
 **Adam did not say three or more, but two. He did not say, 
 'shall cleave to his wives, but to his wife,' nor was it ever 
 lawful for a man to have more than one wife at a time, un- 
 less God by express revelation allowed him the privilege.'* 
 Many are of opinion that polygamy before the deluge was 
 neither practised nor lawful. The almost fabulous ages 
 reached by men of that period rendered the practice quite 
 unnecessary. God withheld the permission, because fearful 
 that men would easily come to regard polygamy thfe natural, 
 
POLYGAMY 313 
 
 not the exceptional form of marriage. Besides, any wide- 
 spread increase of the human race would have been to little 
 purpose, as nearly all mankind was to perish in the deluge. 
 
 Against Calvin, who agreed to regard the patriarchs of the 
 Old Law common sinners, all Catholics maintain that after 
 the deluge, in virtue of a private revelation communicated to 
 Noah and his sons, polygamy became legitimate, and flour- 
 ished among the chosen people with God's full sanction. The 
 reason assigned by St. Chrysostom and St. Augustine for 
 God's departure from the old rule, was a wish to have the 
 race multiply more rapidly. Some find an objection to Cath- 
 olic doctrine on this score, in the circumstance that with the 
 patriarchs one woman was called wife, the others were called 
 concubines. But our answer is, that the woman styled wife 
 was singled out from the others for the care and government 
 of the house. Her children were the father's heirs. The 
 others were employed altogether for purposes of generation. 
 Their children were never regarded heirs. This distinction 
 is evident from Gen. 25.6, where Abraham gives all his pos- 
 sessions to Isaac ; and to the children of the concubines, gifts. 
 Another objection arises from the rebuke administered to" 
 Solomon in 3 Kings 11. for surrounding himself with a mul- 
 titude of wives. But he sinned by excess in having a thou- 
 sand. He likewise allowed them to call away his heart from 
 God, and had intercourse with strangers and idolaters, against 
 God's express command to the contrary. About the legiti- 
 macy of polygamy among the gentiles, or nations outside of 
 the Hebrew people, writers are divided. Some are of opinion 
 that the practice in their regard never had God 's sanction be- 
 fore or after the deluge. Others incline to the theory that 
 God's wishes were communicated to them through the Jews, 
 and polygamy became their privilege after the deluge. 
 
 Children of the Catholic Church need not be told that 
 Christ instituted a thorough reform in the marriage laws of 
 the Old Dispensation. Whatever may have been the view en- 
 tertained of polygamy before His coming. He not only de- 
 clared sinful, but likewise stamped all unions of the sort null 
 and of no force as marriage-contracts. In the New Law 
 women added to the first and lawful wife deserve only one 
 name, and submit to a life of shame, condemned by the Gos- 
 
314 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 pel and common decency. The Anabaptists in the time of 
 Luther openly defended polygamy as a divine institution. 
 Luther himself encouraged Philip of Hesse, one of his spir- 
 itual children, to keep a second wife in his house for the 
 fuller satisfaction of his passions. Indeed, Protestantism of 
 whatever brand, in sanctioning divorce, lends support to a 
 species of polygamy infinitely more damnable and revolting 
 than Mormonism or the beastly rites of Zululand. Mormo, 
 the mythical founder of Mormonism, during his lifetime 
 strenuously forbade polygamy. One Joseph Smith, a suc- 
 cessor and real founder, introduced the doctrine after a 
 dream, which he dignified with the title of a revelation. 
 There are in our statute-books laws against polygamy; but 
 they are defeated in Utah by the difficulty of procuring un- 
 prejudiced juries, and by the unwillingness of witnesses to 
 testify against offenders. In countries like Turkey, where 
 polygamy is the rule and monogamy supposed to be the excep- 
 tion, men with more wives than one are far from numerous. 
 Only the very rich are able to support a multitude of women ; 
 and poverty, mercifully coming to the assistance of morality, 
 checks the growth of this shocking crime. 
 
 It may be well to pause here for a moment, and set down 
 some of the reasons usually alleged in favor of the statement, 
 that monogamy was marriage's primitive form. God fur- 
 nished Adam with only one Eve ; He employed only one rib, 
 not several. Gen. 2.21. Adam himself, as remarked by Pope 
 Innocent, voiced God's wishes in the rule, ''He shall cleave 
 to his wife — they shall be two in one flesh. ' ' Gen. 2.24. The 
 Jews themselves always reckoned polygamy a thing out of 
 harmony, not in accordance, with the law. Noah and his sons 
 had each a single wife when entering the ark. Job was a 
 man of one wife. St. Peter, to follow Jesus, left his wife, 
 not his wives. Nature declares for monogamy, inasmuch as 
 the ratio of the sexes universally and invariably keeps close 
 to equality. The small excess of male births observable pre- 
 serves a balance against the dangers of death by war and 
 accident, to which men are almost exclusively exposed. Car- 
 dinal Bellarmine finds an argument in favor of monogamy 
 in the Scripture-narrative of Eve's production from the side 
 of Adam. She had her origin not in his head, to denote her 
 
SCRIPTURE AND POLYGAMY 315 
 
 subjection; not in his feet, to free her from the suspicion of 
 servitude; but in his side, to constitute her man's peer and 
 companion. 
 
 The two leading texts of Scripture advanced by the Cath- 
 olic Church to prove polygamy not only a sin, but also a vain 
 pretense of marriage, a species of adultery, are contained in 
 St. Luke 16.18, and St. Mark, 10.11. The passages are as 
 follows, ''Every one that putteth away his wife and marries 
 another committeth adultery against her." The condition 
 of the man who retains his wife and marries another should 
 be no better than that of the man Scripture declares guilty 
 of adultery ; because in the one case and the other the founda- 
 tion for the crime is the same. The first wife, whether put 
 away or retained, remains his lawful wife; and adultery is 
 unchastity between one married and a person not his or her 
 lawful spouse. If, therefore, Christ is authority for the 
 statement that absolute divorce is adultery. He none the less 
 positively declares that polygamy is adultery. He calls things 
 by their right names. He emphatically condemns the one abuse 
 and the other, and He robs of all veneer the revolting crime 
 peculiar to modern fanatics, who seek an excuse for their 
 beastliness in the pages of Holy Writ, and the equally re- 
 volting crime of to-day 's society, countenanced by the corrupt 
 civil law, encouraged by greedy and unprincipled lawyers, 
 and winked at by creatures of money and fashion, who like 
 to look forward to the time when their own turn to apply for 
 a divorce will come. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 That little accords with natural law, which violates the 
 secondary ends of marriage. But polygamy is a thing of the 
 sort. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Natural law is the manifesta- 
 tion of God's eternal law, reason is its herald. Nature, or 
 reason, the voice of God, wants us to apply things to their 
 appointed purposes ; and marriage is no exception to the rule. 
 Marriage, therefore, when used at all, must be a help to the 
 accomplishment of whatever designs God had in instituting 
 the condition. Reason acquaints us with these designs, and 
 
316 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 draws marked lines between their relative importance. It 
 recognizes two distinct intrinsic and inborn purposes insep- 
 arable from marriage, because essential to its existence. They 
 are the contract and the resulting bond or obligation. It 
 recognizes two other intrinsic or inborn purposes, separable, 
 however, from marriage, because accidental additions to the 
 contract and the resulting bond, marriage's constituent ele- 
 ments. These latter purposes are children and mutual com- 
 panionship. The extrinsic, accidental purposes of marriage 
 are too numerous to mention. A few of the most important 
 are the help, the comfort, the pleasure derivable from an- 
 other's labors, consolation, and willingness. These extrinsic 
 purposes are generally entitled the secondary ends of mar- 
 riage, and it must be plain that any wrong done marriage 
 on their score is little in harmony with natural law. For 
 natural law intends agencies or institutions not only to pro- 
 mote the primary and principal purposes for which they are 
 designed, but also to refrain from putting hindrances in the 
 way of their secondary or less necessary purposes. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Polygamy certainly offends 
 against these two secondary ends of marriage, the mutual 
 comfort and assistance of husband and wife, and the sensual 
 gratifications, that act as a remedy for the stings of concupis- 
 cence. Friendship and love must serve as the foundation for 
 whatever offices of kindness have place between the man and 
 woman, and a friendship embracing equally all the wives 
 is an utter impossibility. In the nature of things, one woman 
 will always be conspicuous in the eyes of the husband, she 
 will be more loved than the others, her children will be more 
 petted than those of the others. The first will surely grow 
 old; and, when ugly and cross, will be transplanted by an- 
 other. The patriarchs, no doubt, were able to avoid this mis- 
 take. But nature in them was helped by the abundant grace 
 of God. They were saints, and stood constant guard against 
 surprises by nature. Their love for their wives leaned on 
 supernatural motives for support, and, as these motives un- 
 derwent no change with growth in years and loss of physical 
 beauty, their love persevered till death. Besides, God to 
 prosper His own institution was after a manner obliged to 
 see to it that polygamy among the patriarchs worked no such 
 
SECONDARY PURPOSES OF MARRIAGE 317 
 
 evil results. Now, however, things are different. Polygamy, 
 far from inheriting the blessing of God, rests under the 
 shadow of God's most solemn curse. Small wonder, if it is 
 attended with a thousand inconveniences; small wonder, if 
 corrupt nature wreaks its utmost power for harm on the men 
 and women who 'embrace the condition in defiance of Heaven. 
 Who will attempt to picture forth the quarrels, hates and 
 complaints sure to occur among the women in polygamy? 
 Why, envy and jealousy at the present time, under the sav- 
 ing rule of monogamy, are the root and cause of family dis- 
 orders without number. Peace and quiet can hardly take 
 up a permanent abode under a roof that shelters even two 
 jealous women. Durandus urges against our argument the 
 old objection derived from use and abuse. Polygamy, he 
 says, is nowise to blame for the evils, because they are no 
 necessary result of the system, but only an accident. Bellar- 
 mine makes apt answer when he says that the non-occurrence 
 of these annoyances in polygamy would be a most miraculous 
 accident. Polygamy, besides, reduces woman to the level of 
 a servant or slave. The inferiority it of necessity imposes 
 upon her contributes largely to the disappearance of true 
 love. When a man is blessed with but one wife, he is em- 
 inently careful to keep in her good graces. His wife is as 
 independent as himself, and she can threaten him with pun- 
 ishment, if he persistently misbehaves or refuses point blank 
 to conduct himself properly. 
 
THESIS X 
 
 Incomplete divorce, or separation without any attempt to 
 contract a new marriage is sometimes allowable. Complete 
 divorce, or separation affecting the marriage tie, though not 
 evidently opposed to strict natural law in every conceivable 
 case, is nevertheless out of harmony with that secondary law 
 of nature which counsels the proper. Jouin, 177-185; Bick- 
 aby, 274r-278. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 When we deny that absolute divorce is evidently and in 
 every case opposed to strict natural law, we are far from lend- 
 ing favor to this abomination of modern crime and godless- 
 ness. We merely acknowledge that emergencies can occur, 
 in which reason, unaided by special light from Heaven, can 
 discover in absolute divorce no open and destructive war with 
 marriage's primary purpose, the due propagation of the 
 species. When we supplement that statement with the other, 
 that it is out of harmony with a secondary law of nature, 
 we at the same time vindicate to God sufficient cause for Gos- 
 pel legislation against it, and prove human lawmakers, who 
 dare spread its sanction on their statute-books, enemies to the 
 human race and defiant destroyers of morality. For it is 
 God's business, and the business of human lawmakers, to 
 elucidate points just like the present, not evidently contained 
 in strict natural law, but clearly enough prescribed by reason 
 to rob of all excuse legislators who neglect its warnings. Any 
 attempt on the part of civil authority to run counter to such 
 counsels of nature, is open rebellion against God and con- 
 science, and is sure to have for result the anger of morality's 
 avenger and political ruin; disaster here, and hell hereafter. 
 Human law cannot make a wrong of this sort right, and 
 statesmen may legislate till doomsday, courts may forever 
 continue rendering decisions in accordance with empty stat- 
 
 318 
 
DIVORCE 319 
 
 utes, without ridding of responsibility before God the sly- 
 scoundrels, who take advantage of corrupt and vile laws to 
 escape marital obligations ; without removing from the hearts 
 of these slaves to passion a lingering dread of future punish- 
 ment for violation of God's most sacred, most holy institu- 
 tion. Laws conniving at thievery and murder would be 
 hardly more hostile to reason, more ruinous to morality, than 
 the divorce laws at present in use everywhere. These iniqui- 
 tous devices for the encouragement of evil countenance a 
 polygamy more horrid and revolting than the system in favor 
 with Mormonism. They foster the commission of crimes un- 
 fit even for chaste ears, and promote the reign of injustice, 
 cruelty and hardness of heart among men and women alike. 
 Their very existence is a convincing proof, that the sacred 
 condition of marriage will never enjoy the security it ought 
 to possess, until placed entirely and utterly under control of 
 Church jurisdiction. God meant it to be subject only to 
 the couch of His Church, and society is now reaping the har- 
 vest of ills sown, when misguided zealots first taught that 
 marriage was a department into which the state could in- 
 trude itself. The sons of these fathers may cry out as loud as 
 they will against the dire lengths to which civil authority 
 seems willing to go in the destruction of the marriage bond. 
 But their cries will prove of little avail. The only true rem- 
 edy for the disorder lies in the full restoration of the rights 
 of the Church over all the details of this great sacrament. 
 Politicians and lawyers are not yet grown the honest and God- 
 fearing men, privileged to handle and regulate so holy a con- 
 cern as this great sacrament; and their sacrilegious interfer- 
 ence leaves spots like the smudge of hell-brands. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Divorce. Divortium, the derivative of our English word, 
 is plainly from divertere or divortere, to turn aside; and 
 means journey in a different direction. Divorce is therefore 
 a parting of the ways. The husband and wife break com- 
 pany. He goes to the right, she to the left ; and there is an 
 end. Divorce is of two kinds : incomplete and complete. The 
 former, oftener called in Church and law language separation 
 
320 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 or divorce a mensa et toro, from bed and board, is freedom' 
 from the obligation of support and cohabitation. The party, 
 favored with such a decree, while not at liberty to contract 
 a new marriage, is relieved from the burden of expense and 
 disagreeable company. Such a condition has, of course, its 
 drawbacks. It condemns husband and wife to all the un- 
 pleasantness of enforced singleness ; and often influences them 
 to patch up their differences, and agree to forget the past. 
 It is, when cause is sufficient, entirely legitimate, and the only 
 species of divorce sanctioned by the Gospel and the true 
 Church of Christ. Complete divorce pretends to declare 
 null and void, what God himself by the mouth of Jesus Christ 
 declared forever inviolate. It pretends to loosen a bond or 
 knot that God Himself declared forever in force. It pre- 
 tends to vest a man or woman, in virtue of a decree made by 
 an irresponsible judge, a usurper, in whom no proper juris- 
 diction resides, with leave and license to marry two, three, 
 four, twenty times, every single marriage bond remaining in- 
 tact. It pretends to entrench polygamy, successive if not 
 simultaneous, behind the law; and would make of society, if 
 the instincts of decency were not on occasions stronger than 
 temptation, a veritable pest-house of moral lepers. Briefly, 
 the law of divorce authorizes husband, or wife, or both, for 
 causes listed with a mock gravity in the code, some serious, 
 others trivial, all different in different countries and states, 
 to take new partners, when old grow tiresome, or offensive, 
 or injurious. 
 
 History's earliest reference to divorce is contained in Deu- 
 teronomy 24.1. Moses enumerates among the laws appointed 
 to govern God's people the following: "If a man take a 
 wife and have her, and she find not favor in his eyes for some 
 uncleanness: he shall write a bill of divorce and shall give 
 it in her hand, and send her out of his house. And when she 
 is departed and marrieth another husband," etc. This law 
 admits of two interpretations, and the doctors of Israel at the 
 time of our Lord's coming were divided into two camps. 
 Some, identifying themselves with the school of Schamai con- 
 tended that adultery was the only valid excuse for a divorce. 
 Others, belonging to the school of Hillel, maintained that 
 trivial difficulties and disagreements operated to justify a 
 
DIVORCE IN HISTORY 321 
 
 wife's dismissal. If a woman let the broth burn, if the hus- 
 band found a woman fairer or more to his liking, he was at 
 liberty to send away his first wife, and make room for the 
 second. But the world was 2500 years old when Moses, by 
 reason of their hardness of heart, permitted the Hebrews to 
 put away their wives ; and Christ in St. Matthew 19.8 is au- 
 thority for the statement, that ''from the beginning it was 
 not so." We have already seen that God sanctioned poly- 
 gamy among the patriarchs without at all doing violence to 
 the natural law. He surrounded the exceptional condition 
 with safeguards that effectively hindered the abuses other- 
 wise inseparable from it. God was certainly at liberty to 
 grant the further privilege of divorce to His chosen people, 
 and He was certainly powerful enough, and had enough expe- 
 dients at His service to render the favor innocuous. In fact, 
 divorce is not far removed from polygamy, and it would be 
 quite natural to expect one permission to follow fast on the 
 heels of the other. 
 
 An old historian, Valentinian, dates the first decree of di- 
 vorce in Roman annals 520 years after the foundation of the 
 city. All through the time of the Empire the abuse steadily 
 grew with the decline of morals, that eventually hastened the 
 downfall of imperial Rome. Caesar and Pompey availed them- 
 selves twice of the right conferred by law. Cicero put aside 
 his first wife, to marry a woman of great wealth, and speed- 
 ily got rid of her also. The advent of Christianity changed 
 the whole face of things. The Mosaic Law was abolished, 
 and with it polygamy and divorce disappeared from among 
 the people of God. Christ condemned the two practices in 
 no uncertain terms. Christian princes naturally experienced 
 great difficulty in rooting out of the minds of their people 
 prejudices in favor of the old order. They had necessarily 
 to proceed with slow caution, and gradually introduce into 
 the laws of their kingdoms laws subversive of paganism and 
 in full harmony with Gospel morality. But, whatever the 
 nature of their enactments, no argument can be borrowed 
 from them against the assertion, that absolute divorce from 
 the very foundation of the Church became a matter of an- 
 cient history and fell into disuse. Certainly, no one could 
 for any cause whatever, in the face of Christ's declaration 
 
322 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 against divorce, appeal to its protection and retain the name 
 of Christian. 
 
 And so, down to our own times Catholicity has unflinch- 
 ingly kept its arm raised against this relic of Judaism's per- 
 verseness, this taint on the escutcheon of pagan Rome's gran- 
 deur. One of her Popes could have saved an empire to the 
 faith by weak concession in the matter; but, like Horace's 
 hero, he preferred rather to have the world at his feet in 
 ruins than join hands with iniquity. Surely, the grace of 
 God, and that grand promise made him in the person of St. 
 Peter, could alone carry Pope Clement VII safe through the 
 temptation. The difficulty between Napoleon and Pius VII 
 might also be here discussed. Luther, the head and front of 
 the so-called Reformation, had no such support, and no won- 
 der attaches to his indorsement of the abuse. He had to 
 appeal, in common with the other Reformers, to the Gospels 
 for arguments that gave dubious color to his theories; and, 
 like all false philosophers in a similar position, was not long 
 finding them. He condoned polygamy in Philip of Hesse, 
 *'to provide for the welfare of this monster's body and soul, 
 and to bring greater glory to God. ' ' He quieted the scruples 
 of priests, monks and nuns, who tired of their vows and 
 sought in matrimony release from their self-imposed bond- 
 age. Small wonder, then, if he granted the ordinary faith- 
 ful, who clamored for recognition in the general distribu- 
 tion of favors, the freedom and license native to absolute 
 divorce. 
 
 Protestantism, because without a supreme spiritual head, 
 logically handed over the management of marriage to the 
 tender mercies of the state. Kings, and statesmen, and poli- 
 ticians of every degree of depravity conspired to rob this 
 divine institution of its sacredness; and in Protestant coun- 
 tries marriage is a mockery of the beautiful thing God made 
 it. It is become with them a bare business contract, removed 
 from the jurisdiction of God's visible representative on earth, 
 and subject, like other commercial transactions, to the pas- 
 sions and prejudices of the uninitiated and the profane. The 
 result is that marriage is become an affair of no stability 
 whatever, a companionship, altogether dependent on the 
 shifting whims of men and women. In Prussia, for instance. 
 
DIVORCE-LAWS 323 
 
 as late as 1870, drunkenness, extravagance, and, where no 
 children blessed the union, mutual consent, were some among 
 the trivial causes justifying absolute divorce. Till 1857 Eng- 
 land acknowledged no absolute divorce. In that year adultery 
 and certain other crimes of great enormity were decreed 
 lawful grounds for action. The Civil Code of France exacted 
 no more serious condition than mutual consent of husband 
 and wife. The legislation was changed in May, 1815, and 
 up to 1870 no absolute divorce was recognized in France. 
 
 America is a veritable paradise for discontented couples. 
 Each State has its own catalogue of excuses for the sin of 
 divorce, and the Federal government allows each to go its 
 own chosen way. As matters stand, we are the laughing 
 stock of the nations. Some enthusiasts are of opinion that 
 improvement would result from limiting divorce-legislation 
 to Congress at Washington. Of course, such a procedure 
 would procure uniformity in our marriage-laws; but if this 
 uniformity were based, for instance, on the loose morality that 
 now obtains in Maine, Connecticut, Montana and Illinois, it 
 would prove more of a curse than a blessing. Besides, the 
 individual States are too jealous of their rights to yield with- 
 out reluctance the advantages pecuniary and otherwise, ac- 
 cruing to them from this traffic in sin. In Maine a divorce 
 may be granted, ''when the judge deems it reasonable, and 
 proper, and consistent with peace and morality." In Con- 
 necticut, from 1849 to 1878, divorce-law included ''general 
 misconduct." In the latter year the rather vague and un- 
 certain term was removed from the list of causes. In Mon- 
 tana divorce may be granted, if the party "leaves the peti- 
 tioner and the Territory without intention of returning." 
 Utah grants divorce, "when it is proved that parties cannot 
 live together amicably and separation is desired. ' ' In Illinois 
 the whole question is left to the discretion of the Court. 
 Indiana follows in her footsteps. New Hampshire decrees 
 divorce, when petitioner proves three years' absence, not 
 heard from. New Jersey, adultery and desertion for three 
 years. New York, adultery alone. South Carolina is the 
 only State in the Union that recognizes no absolute divorce. 
 A law to this effect was enacted in 1878. After a glance at 
 divorce legislation in the different States, one is impressed 
 
324 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 with the fact that New England and the Northern States are 
 most lax in this regard, while the South leans towards se- 
 verity. But in virtue of the principle, generally adopted in 
 courts throughout the country, that divorces decreed in one 
 State hold good in every other State, the strictness displayed 
 by this or that State is of very little effect as a hindrance 
 to the spread of divorce and its attendant evils. A bona-fide 
 residence in any State empowers a person to sue for divorce 
 in the name of its particular laws, no matter where the crime 
 charged was committed, no matter where the party against 
 whom proceedings are taken chances to be. The majority 
 of States, New York among others, insist on a residence of 
 one year before filing petition. Some few prescribe two 
 years. Others, like New Jersey in the case of desertion, re- 
 quire three. In other cases New Jersey is satisfied with resi- 
 dence at the time of application. Six months suffice in Ari- 
 zona, California, Idaho, Nebraska and Wyoming. When 
 other notification of defendant is impossible, publication in 
 the newspapers is, as a rule, valid in law. 
 
 The blighting influence of the system on our families and 
 society is bound to grow under the fostering care of greedy 
 lawyers and unprincipled politicians. It is already become 
 a veritable scourge, and honest -minded men of every shade 
 of belief recognize that a halt must soon be called. A writer 
 in the Princeton Review 10.39 brands the practice as New 
 England polygamy ; and, much to the disadvantage of divorce, 
 draws a striking contrast between it and the polygamy of 
 Utah. Divorce is, in sooth, nothing short, of a species of 
 polygamy. The polygamy of Utah is continuous or simul- 
 taneous, that of New England is successive or interrupted. 
 But the one as well eis the other is nothing short of sinful 
 intercourse with a plurality of wives. In Utah the mode of 
 life is banned by law, and men convicted of adopting it are 
 liable to fine and imprisonment. In New England it is not 
 only lawful, but courts of law devote much of their time to 
 rendering decisions in its favor. Citizens of Utah contract 
 alliances of the kind in secret, behind doors locked and barred 
 against officials and unfriendly witnesses. Divorced men and 
 women wed. in the public eye, with a solemnity surpassing 
 in grandeur that which surrounds the weddings of common 
 
NEW ENGLAND POLYGAMY 325 
 
 folk. Church and State lend their august presence to the 
 mock ceremony. The minister is there in robes of office to 
 bless what God. in the same instant curses. The court, the 
 highest judicial authority in the land, lends its seal and sig- 
 nature to grace the occasion, and arms the principals with a 
 lengthy document setting forth their emancipation from mari- 
 tal disabilities. In Utah the polygamist considers himself 
 bound in conscience to display some little affection towards 
 deposed rivals for his love, to keep them under his roof, care 
 for their children, and decently inter them when dead. But 
 polygamy in New England imposes no such burdens. It 
 vests the man with full prerogative to heartily hate the 
 spumed and abandoned wife, to cast her into the street, and 
 make what disposition he likes, or is able to make, of the 
 children. Of course, the women in Utah are constant suffer- 
 ers from the pangs of jealousy; but their pain is lessened, 
 because spread out over a long stretch of time. New Eng- 
 land would seem to behave in a tenderer and more merciful 
 way towards the poor victims. The blow is inflicted in a 
 moment, and all is over. If despair and • dejection succeed 
 to the hope and prospective cheerfulness that never abandon 
 the Mormon woman, New England is not to blame. That 
 misfortune lies with the deluded fool, who ought to sprinkle 
 her woes with patience and cultivate stoutness of heart. She 
 can, besides, derive comfort from the thought that New Eng- 
 land is far more impartial than Utah. The Mormons con- 
 cede to men alone the right to marry often. Their women 
 are as much bound to rest satisfied with one marriage venture 
 as women in monogamy. Mormonism advocates polygamy; 
 it tolerates no polyandry. But the Puritans distribute their 
 favors with a more even and more open hand. Their sense 
 of fairness and justice, no doubt, influences them to include 
 woman in the general amnesty. Women, therefore, are in 
 New England as free to exchange husbands as men are to 
 exchange wives; and polyandry is the crumbling foundation 
 of tottering Puritanism. Polygamy is, besides, a cheap mar- 
 ket-commodity in New England. In Turkey the privilege is 
 so much a luxury that very few are able to avail themselves 
 of it. In Utah it is surrounded with almost the same dis- 
 advantages. No inconsiderable sum of money is needed to 
 
ITHICS 
 
 defray the expenses of a large household of wives and chil- 
 dren. But in New England ten dollars or even fewer will 
 tide a man over each new matrimonial venture. A license, 
 a ring and the auspicious presence of a minister or magis- 
 trate can be procured for even five dollars. 
 
 Another very objectionable feature of divorce-law is the 
 encouragement it offers to crime. Where adultery is the only 
 admissible plea for separation, the man or woman is not long 
 committing the crime. After the necessary sin is committed, 
 he or she rises in open court and unblushingly acknowledges 
 the deed. Witnesses are summoned to narrate all the revolt- 
 ing details of shame, and the court, instead of throwing the 
 self-confessed criminal into jail, makes out for him or her a 
 bill of divorce. Where cruelty must be proved to have the 
 bonds loosed, the dissatisfied party straightway proceeds to 
 make things hot for the other; and, instead of being pun- 
 ished according to deserts, is rewarded with a release. Thus, 
 by a strange perversion, law becomes the aider and abettor 
 of crime, adultery and cruelty go unpunished in courts of 
 justice, and a reward is put on things sinful in the eyes of 
 God and in the eyes of men. 
 
 The children of divorced parents start on the journey 
 through life, equipped with grand ideas of human nature. 
 The two beings by God appointed to introduce them into life, 
 and store their minds by maxim and example with principles 
 calculated to guide their future years, teach them from the 
 very outset the doctrine of devils and iniquity. From them 
 these tender and confiding children learn that quarrels, strife 
 and bitterness are the normal condition of human nature. 
 They learn that marriage is a contract of convenience, of 
 binding force only as long as it subserves the ends of luxury 
 and sensuality. The result oftentimes is, that these children, 
 following in the footsteps of their parents, rush into hasty 
 marriages, satisfied that matters can be mended when the 
 emergency arises. And so the evil is propagated; and so the 
 foundations of the family and of society are being gradually 
 loosened. Parental affection is losing its hold on the youth 
 of the land. Mothers are inculcating as a first duty on their 
 daughters hatred of their father. Fathers are impressing 
 their sons with the supreme importance of despising their 
 
IMPEDIMENTS 327 
 
 mother. Parental authority is fast becoming a by-word. 
 Children can hardly learn obedience from masters, whose 
 example is a continual incentive to unease and rebellious- 
 ness. 
 
 The Catholic Church, the pillar and ground of truth, recog- 
 nizes no ground for absolute divorce. Its authorities have 
 sometimes decreed the dissolution of apparent marriages, and 
 allowed the parties to the false contract to enter new alli- 
 ances. But its decisions are always based on reasons ante- 
 cedent to the marriage in question, not consequent on the 
 same. With God for guide and with the immediate assist- 
 ance of the Holy Spirit, it counts no marriage at all a union 
 vitiated by any one of the fifteen impediments reckoned in- 
 validating. They are : 
 
 1 M' i Tc /substantial — person \ 
 * L accidental — qualities i 
 natural law. 
 
 2. Condition — slave and free — ecclesiastical law. 
 
 3. OrcZers— priest, deacon, subdeacon — ecclesiastical law. 
 Natural — same blood — direct line, in- 
 definitely — collateral line, to 4th de- 
 gree. 
 
 Spiritual — Baptism and Confirmation 
 
 — minister and sponsors with child. 
 Legal — perfect adoption. 
 Adultery only — real, formal, consummated — 
 
 promise — during* life of both. 
 Homicide only — conspiracy, intention, death. 
 ^ Both together. 
 
 6. Different worship — baptized and unbaptized. Mixed 
 marriage, hindering, not invalidating. 
 
 7. Violence — serious, not light — external and free — un- 
 just, intention. 
 
 8. Bond — no mere rumor — moral certainty. 
 
 9. Decency — betrothed to 1st deg. — ratified marriage to 
 4th. 
 
 10. Age— 12 and 14. 
 
 11. Affinity — sexual relation with relative. Licit to 4th; 
 illicit to 2nd. 
 
 4. Relationship. 
 
 5. Crime. 
 
328 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 12. Clandestinity- 
 
 13. Impotence. 
 
 14. Abduction. 
 
 15. Vow — solemn. 
 
 -Trent — priest and two witnesses. 
 
 1. Church law: 
 
 Four lesser impediments, hindering, not invalidating: 
 
 particular — priest or bishop — betrothed 
 with another — suspicion — quarrels. 
 
 general — consent of parents — banns — 
 mixed. 
 
 2. Time — open and closed — solemnities — Advent to Christ- 
 
 mas — ^Ash Wednesday to Easter. 
 
 3. Betrothal. 
 
 4. Vow — simple, not solemn — vow of no marriage, chastity, 
 
 entering religion, priesthood. 
 Dispensations : 
 
 Pour of fifteen from natural law and divine prohibition — 
 
 no dispensation. 
 They are: 
 
 Relationship, 1st degree in direct line, father, mother, 
 brother, sister; marriage-bond; impotence; mis- 
 take. 
 
 Other eleven admit of dispensation — difficulties of procur- 
 ing innumerable. 
 
 Many Protestants, lost to all sense of shame, consider mar- 
 riage an affair of the State exclusively, and pretend to re- 
 gard divorce granted on whatever plea a legitimate proceed- 
 ing, that frees the two married persons in the sight of God 
 from all mutual obligations, and empowers them to form new 
 alliances. Dean Mansel, p. 102, says: **The Church of Eng- 
 land has never authoritatively sanctioned any other separa- 
 tion than that a mensa et toro; and this with an express 
 prohibition of remarriage (Canon 107)." "In practice this 
 legislation is neglected." Knabenbauer, in Matthaeum, 229. 
 Others among them recognize only one legitimate excuse for 
 divorce, and that is adultery. They profess to found their 
 doctrine on words contained in St. Matthew 5.32 and 19.9. 
 "Whosoever shall put away his wife, excepting the cause of 
 fornication, maketh her to commit adultery." "Whosoever 
 
SCRIPTURE AND DIVORCE 329 
 
 shall put away his wife, except it be for fornication, and shall 
 marry another, committeth adultery." Before discussing 
 these two passages, it may be well to set down St. Mark 's and 
 St. Luke's renderings of the same doctrine and St. Paul's 
 references to the same. ''Whosoever shall put away his wife 
 and marry another, committeth adultery against her." St. 
 Mark 10.11. "Every one that putteth away his wife and 
 marrieth another, committeth adultery; and he that marrieth 
 her that is put away from her husband, committeth adultery. ' ' 
 St. Luke 16.18. ''Therefore, while her husband liveth she 
 shall be called an adulteress, if she be with another man." 
 Rom. 7.3. "Not I, but the Lord commandeth that the wife 
 depart not from her husband. And if she depart, that she 
 remain unmarried or be reconciled to her husband." 1 Cor. 
 7.10. The words of St. Mark and St. Luke certainly make 
 no allusion to adultery or anything else as motive for abso- 
 lute divorce. They are nevertheless as reliable witnesses to the 
 truth as St. Matthew ; and could not possibly have omitted so 
 important a point in Christ's doctrine. St. Paul is likewise 
 no authority for absolute divorce. He is plainly for the per- 
 petual indissolubility of marriage, and hints at only one spe- 
 cies of lawful separation, imperfect, or partial divorce, with- 
 out any attempt to contract new alliances. Whatever diffi- 
 culty, therefore, attaches to the words of St. Matthew ought 
 to be settled without injury to the expressions contained in 
 the other Evangelists and in St. Paul's Epistles. A recon- 
 ciliation of the various texts is quite possible, and that recon- 
 ciliation is had in the doctrine propounded by the Catholic 
 Church. According to this doctrine, St. Matthew introduces 
 adultery as a seeming exception to the indissolubility of mar- 
 riage, but only as a legitimate plea for partial divorce, or 
 separation a mensa et toro. In this sense, the man who 
 lives apart from his wife for any reason save that of adultery 
 or its equivalent, is responsible before God for the sins she 
 will almost surely commit because of the violent temptations 
 to which in consequence of past habits she will necessarily 
 be exposed. He will be the indirect cause of her crimes, and 
 will, therefore, be guilty of her adultery in cause or indi- 
 rectly. Whoever attempts to marry a wife thus put away 
 commits adultery formally. Whoever after dismissing his 
 
SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 wife, even for adultery, attempts to marry another, commits 
 adultery formally. 
 
 All tradition is with Catholicity in this interpretation of 
 the text, and absolute divorce properly so called was an abuse 
 introduced into the Scriptures by the so-called reformers. 
 The different stands taken by Catholicity and Protestantism 
 in this matter of divorce, due entirely to the sense laid on a 
 sentence in St. Matthew's Gospel, are only another proof of 
 how necessary a requisite for religion is the establishment of 
 a final court, beyond which in the settlement of Scriptural 
 disputes there can be no appeal. The large part that tradi- 
 tion must likewise play in the formation of belief is also 
 brought into conspicuous notice. The text in question, be- 
 sides the interpretation forced upon it by Protestanism, ad- 
 mits of at least seven others, all decidedly opposed to the 
 theory of absolute divorce. Of these, the first four can be 
 with difficulty defended. We prefer to reject them. Two 
 others we admit, without adopting. The last or seventh we 
 prefer, as most in accordance with the context, and the sur- 
 roundings in which Christ gave utterance to the words. 
 
 The first opinion maintains that Christ busied Himself 
 on this occasion in explaining the Old Law for the benefit 
 of the Jews present. The New Law was not yet in full force, 
 and He availed Himself of chances to explain it in private. 
 According to the Old Law, when adultery intervened, no 
 difficulty presented itself, because the woman was sentenced 
 to immediate death by stoning, and death of course dissolves 
 the marriage bond. 
 
 The second opinion holds that Christ wished the old per- 
 mission concerning absolute divorce to continue during the 
 short period of transition from Judaism to Christianity. 
 
 Dix and Dollinger are authority for the third opinion, that 
 Christ called attention to an impediment, considered invali- 
 dating among the Jews, viz., sins of impurity committed be- 
 fore marriage. 
 
 The fourth opinion, adopted by no less learned a person 
 than Pope Innocent III, has more weight in its favor. It 
 makes Christ's declaration a withdrawal of the ancient priv- 
 ilege enjoyed by the Jews, that, namely, of issuing to their 
 adulterous wives a bill of divorce. This opinion, therefore. 
 
INTERPRETATIONS OF ST. MATTHEW 331 
 
 makes the words of Christ as recorded by St. Matthew read 
 as follows, "Whosoever shall put away his wife, excepting 
 even the cause of fornication, and shall marry another, com- 
 mitteth adultery," etc. 
 
 The fifth opinion is ascribed to a pupil of Cardinal Pa- 
 trizi, himself an eminent exponent of Holy Scripture. This 
 pupil communicated his lights to the cardinal, who at once 
 adopted the explanation offered, and made it his own. It 
 makes the seeming exception introduced by Christ turn on 
 the concubinage of Herod and Herodias. This Herod had 
 taken to wife Herodias, the spouse of his brother; and St. 
 John the Baptist, the Lord's precursor, had met his death 
 for upbraiding the prince with his incestuous marriage. 
 Christ was at the time of the discourse in Herod's dominion, 
 and took advantage, according to the opinion, to administer 
 another rebuke to his sinfulness. He says, therefore, in as 
 many words, *'I except the case of Herod and Herodias. 
 They ought to be separated, because they are living in open 
 concubinage. ' ' 
 
 St. Augustine (de adult, conj. lib. 1, cc. 9.11) adopts and 
 strenuously advocates the sixth opinion, and his authority is 
 of the utmost weight in matters Scriptural. He takes the 
 exceptional clause for an intimation that Christ wishes to 
 altogether prescind from the question of an adulterous wom- 
 an's dismissal. He knew the Jewish prejudices in favor of 
 the Mosaic bill of divorce. He knew the determination of His 
 questioners, the Pharisees, to entrap Him, if possible, in a 
 statement at open variance with the Mosaic Law, and to avoid 
 danger He answers that divorce is nowise permissible out- 
 side of adultery. The case of adultery, for reasons of pru- 
 dence. He declines to discuss. In this opinion. He was asked 
 if divorce was at all permissible. He makes direct answer 
 with regard to every conceivable plea, adultery alone ex- 
 cepted. About adultery He preserves silence. Protestantism 
 can derive no comfort from this interpretation. It would be 
 highly wrong to argue thus, ''Outside of adultery divorce is 
 unlawful. Ergo in case of adultery divorce is lawful." 
 
 Our interpretation, in most general use nowadays, sup- 
 poses Christ to distinguish between perfect and imperfect 
 divorce, and to lay down the whole Catholic law concerning 
 
332 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 each species. With regard to imperfect divorce, He allows 
 separation from bed and board only in the event of adultery 
 or its equivalent, and burdens with the woman's consequent 
 sin the conscience of whatever man sends his wife away for 
 any lesser cause. With regard to perfect divorce, or abso- 
 lute dissolution of the marriage tie, He denies its existence, 
 and proclaims every union founded on such divorce sheer 
 adultery. The words contained in St. Matthew 5.32, hardly 
 admit of doubt, "Whosoever shall put away his wife, except- 
 ing the cause of fornication, maketh her to commit adultery, 
 and he that shall marry her that is put away committeth 
 adultery." The words contained in St. Matthew 19.9 are a 
 little less obvious, and the dispute generally centres round 
 them. ''Whosoever shall put away his wife, except it be for 
 fornication, and shall marry another, committeth adultery; 
 and he that shall marry her that is put away committeth 
 adultery." Protestants want the exceptive clause to be re- 
 peated, so that the text may read thuswise, ''Whosoever shall 
 put away his wife, except it be for fornication, committeth 
 adultery; and whoever shall marry another, unless she has 
 been put away for fornication, committeth adultery." Prot- 
 estants have for this arbitrary repetition of the exceptive 
 clause no conceivable authority in grammar, or logic, or con- 
 text. In a proposition of the kind, when a double subject 
 enters, the exception does not necessarily affect the second 
 of the two members. Instances without number could be 
 cited in proof of the exact contrary. "Whoever kills an- 
 other, except in case of self-defense, and whoever robs his 
 victim is guilty of sin." "Whoever strikes another, unless 
 unjustly attacked, and whoever blasphemes his assailant is 
 guilty of sin." "The executioners of Jesus, unless excused 
 by ignorance, and His blasphemers were guilty of sin. ' ' The 
 whole context bearing on the passage under consideration, 
 the circumstances of time and place and the characteristics 
 of the listeners, are emphatically in favor of our interpreta- 
 tion. Christ expressly revokes the Mosaic privilege, con- 
 ferred on the woman by the bill of divorce. The bill of di- 
 vorce was granted solely vnth a view to rendering her 
 eligible for future marriage. In declaring that the man 
 who marries a woman put away commits adultery. He clearly 
 
RIGHT INTERPRETATION 333 
 
 maintains that she still remains the lawful wife of her first 
 husband. Adultery can have no other meaning. If the mar- 
 riage were dissolved by her sin of adultery, and Christ wished 
 to deprive her, by way of punishment, of the freedom granted 
 her wronged husband, He would call her second attempt at 
 marriage by some other name than that of adultery. Adul- 
 tery means impurity in married persons. 
 
 Returning again to theology's views on the indissolubility 
 of marriage, we can enunciate everything in this short thesis, 
 *'By divine law matrimony, whether between believers or un- 
 believers, whether consummated or not, is in every case in- 
 trinsically indissoluble, i.e., dissolution or divorce is abso- 
 lutely outside the power of the contracting parties. Matri- 
 mony between believers, if consummated, and between un- 
 believers as long as neither husband nor wife receives Bap- 
 tism, is besides extrinsically indissoluble, i.e., dissolution or 
 divorce is outside the power of any being or authority under 
 Heaven, and adultery makes no change in the law." Matri- 
 mony's intrinsic indissolubility is evident from St. Mark 
 10.11— St. Luke 16.18— Rom. 7.3—1 Cor. 7.11. St. Matthew 
 is likewise a witness to the same truth in 5.32 and 19.9 ; but 
 his testimony is somewhat obscure. Church writers say that 
 he introduced the exceptive clause, permitting partial or in- 
 complete separation, i.e., from bed and board, out of defer- 
 ence to the Hebrews for whom he composed his Gospel. 
 These Hebrews, accustomed as they were to the bill of divorce, 
 naturally looked for some loophole of escape from matrimony's 
 iron-bound indissolubility in the New Law. St. Matthew 
 with Christ's sanction offered them the alleviation of partial 
 or incomplete divorce. The other two Evangelists, St. Mark 
 and St. Luke, writing for the Gentiles, men without Jewish 
 prejudices, thought the concession of too small moment to 
 mention it. If Christ had in mind absolute divorce, St. 
 Mark and St. Luke would have done the Gentiles a heavy 
 wrong in hiding from them so sweeping and so all important 
 a permission. 
 
 From the passages cited it must be plain that matrimony 
 is so indissoluble that new nuptials cannot be contracted 
 without adultery, and union with -a second partner during 
 the lifetime of the first is adultery, only in the supposition 
 
334 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 that the first partner forever remains husband or wife, as the 
 case may be. Nothing short of the clearest evidence, gathered 
 from the context or some different Scripture, or the nature 
 of things, will justify the establishment of an exception to 
 this universal law. The entire context of the three Evangel- 
 ists is plainly against any such exception. Christ in every 
 neighboring line is talking of the unity of marriage, its obli- 
 gation of inseparability, e.g., St. Mark 10.9—10.8—10.6—10.7 
 — 10.5. The murmur of discontent or disapproval is a re- 
 markable indication in St. Matthew 19.10. It is a well known 
 fact that there were two schools among the Hebrews, each 
 entertaining its own views with regard to reasons justifying 
 the issuance of a bill of divorce. One school, that of Schamai, 
 rated adultery alone or its equivalent justifiable excuse. The 
 other, that of Hillel, rated any trivial cause of discontent 
 ground sufficient. It is more than probable that the apostles 
 belonged to the school of strict rigidity, and would have had 
 little fault to find with Christ's new legislation, unless it de- 
 creed adultery itself no valid pretext for divorce. 
 
 In the opinion current among Protestants Christ left the 
 indissolubility of marriage just where He found it, and did 
 nothing to provoke a murmur among the followers of Schamai. 
 About different Scriptures, it would be absurd to think that 
 St. Mark and St. Luke composed their Gospels in such a way 
 that their readers to understand would have to consult St. 
 Matthew. In matters less important they might of course 
 have omitted here and there points that seemed to them su- 
 perfluous ; but this privilege of absolute divorce could hardly 
 appear to them too insignificant a thing to be neglected. Be- 
 sides, all the verses preceding and following the disputed 
 verse in St. Matthew leave no room for the exception in favor 
 of adultery read into Scripture by Protestantism. Such an 
 exception is justifiable only when the passage in question ad- 
 mits of no other possible meaning. We have already seen 
 seven different meanings, each of which admirably fits th,e 
 words and admits of defense. Last of all, everybody admits 
 that St. Matthew in these particular passages is obscure and 
 hard to understand. St. Mark and St. Luke are on the con- 
 trary clear as crystal, and impress the mind with their sim- 
 plicity. It is against all rules of interpretation to endeavor 
 
RIGHT INTERPRETATION 335 
 
 to fix the meaning of simple and straightforward statements 
 by reference to statements that are intricate and involved. 
 St. Matthew should, therefore, be elucidated with light bor- 
 rowed from St. Mark and St. Luke ; and any contrary method 
 merits the contempt of scholars. 
 
 In the nature of things, or viewing the matter in the light 
 of common sense, the weight of argument is with Catholicity 
 and overwhelmingly against Protestantism's flimsy pretext 
 for divorce. Reason rebels against any enactment liable to 
 promote the spread of adultery. And Christ would be pro- 
 mulgating just such an enactment, if He sanctioned absolute 
 divorce in the case of even so detestable an evil as marital 
 unfaithfulness. The divorced woman, often the guilty part- 
 ner, would be free to marry again, and would thus enjoy a 
 privilege denied some pious sister, deserted by a worthless 
 husband. The result of such legislation could inevitably be 
 nothing short of the multiplication of unlawful attachments 
 and sinful intercourse. Divorce would be a reward reserved 
 exclusively for adulterous women. Dissatisfied mates would, 
 and dissatisfied mates do, commit adultery with the openly 
 avowed purpose of rendering the law of divorce operative. 
 The law of Christ would be more favorable to the growth of 
 adultery than the Mosaic Law. Moses visited the adulteress 
 with death by choking or stoning. Were Christ's law what 
 Protestantism makes it, sho would be at liberty after her 
 crime to seek comfort in new nuptials. 
 
 St. Paul, in 1 Cor. 7, treats in detail and explicitly the 
 subject of marriage, and therefore, we can trust, • delivers 
 himself of the whole truth. In verse 10 he says, ''the Lord 
 commandeth that the wife depart not from her husband. 
 And if she depart, that she remain unmarried or be recon- 
 ciled to her husband." Plainly, there is question here of 
 separation founded on a solid title, on the adultery of the 
 husband. Were the woman's departure justified by no such 
 reason, St. Paul would be the first to urge her immediate 
 return. When, therefore, he counsels her to remain unmar- 
 ried, and solemnly declares that singleness or reconciliation 
 is the only course sanctioned by God's law, he necessarily un- 
 derstood adultery to be no ground at all for absolute divorce. 
 If the husband's adultery destroyed the marriage bond, the 
 
336 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 wife could with perfect freedom contract a new alliance. 
 Again, in Rom. 7.3, St. Paul gives advice wholly incompatible 
 with modem notions of divorce. "Whilst her husband liv- 
 eth, she shall be called an adulteress, if she be with another 
 man." This rule is absolute, hedged round about with no 
 conditions or exceptions; and is only another index of how 
 Christ wants the exceptive clause in St. Matthew to be in- 
 terpreted. Death, and death alone, can invest the surviving 
 partner with the right to enter a second marriage. 
 
 The Catholic Church, therefore, can never recognize the 
 validity of an absolute divorce, decreed by the civil court. 
 It forever considers divorced men and women as truly mar- 
 ried, as much husband and wife as they were before the State 
 interfered; and never reckons them capable of receiving this 
 sacrament anew. The customs and laws of our country make 
 it more or less necessary for Catholic judges and Catholic 
 lawyers to conduct business on lines opposed to the spirit and 
 principles of their Church. 
 
 About judges, obliged by their office to decree absolute di- 
 vorce, there can be no great difficulty. They are chosen or 
 appointed to decide according to evidence and the law of the 
 land, and if unfaithful to their duty would have to relinquish 
 their position. They can without scruple of conscience issue 
 such decrees, though they inwardly know that before God 
 their decision is far from annulling the marriage contract. 
 All this is true, even if the judge knows to a certainty that 
 the parties concerned are determined to avail themselves of 
 all the privileges allowed by the law. Such a judge lends no 
 formal cooperation to the sinful acts liable to result from 
 his judicial action. He brings no influence to bear on the 
 iniquitous intentions of the divorced parties. On the con- 
 trary, he deprecates their conduct, and sincerely hopes that 
 they will consider the divorce mere separation from bed and 
 board, and act acc^ordingly. Even Catholics are at liberty to 
 take advantage of whatever temporal benefits may accrue 
 from what the State calls an absolute bill of divorce a vinculo ; 
 but this must be done always with the understanding that be- 
 fore God the marriage remains intact till death, and precludes 
 all possibility of wedding another during the lifetime of 
 either. 
 
CATHOLIC JUDGES AND LAWYERS 337 
 
 Catholic lawyers are more open to blame in this matter of 
 divorce than Catholic judges. The lawyer enters more ac- 
 tively into the designs of his client than the judge; and is, 
 therefore, permitted only what the client himself can with a 
 safe conscience attempt. He can without sin push a divorce 
 case, when aware that the marriage attacked was never, on 
 account of some invalidity, a marriage at all, or when the 
 person he aids intends to seek only the temporal redress 
 derivable from incomplete divorce. If he knows for certain 
 that his client is set on marrying anew, after the decree is 
 secured, he cannot with a safe conscience handle the case. 
 Only certain and sure knowledge of the client's unholy in- 
 tention can create in the lawyer this serious obligation of non- 
 interference. Mere rumors, guesses, suspicions are of no 
 weight. 
 
 No one can, of course, deny that our Church's refusal to 
 acknowledge absolute divorce is attended with many evils for 
 unhappy couples. It is a law opposed apparently to human 
 liberty, to the principal end of marriage, and to the happi- 
 ness of many a man and many a woman. And yet all laws 
 are framed with a view to that principle held holy and sacred 
 in legislation, ''Law has for primary object the good of the 
 whole community or multitude, not the particular good of 
 this or that individual." Whilst peremptory denial of the 
 legality of absolute divorce hurts few or many individuals, it 
 nevertheless operates as a salutary check on evils innumer- 
 able in the community. Husbands and wives are bound to 
 swallow their griefs in silence and make little of ordinary 
 difficulties, when they know that they are hopelessly de- 
 barred from relief, offered by the State's loose enactments 
 concerning divorce. Besides, law of its very nature restricts 
 human liberty, and keeps it within the bounds that separate 
 it from license. Whatever injury Church legislation does 
 marriage's principal end, the propagation of children or hu- 
 man happiness, is merely accidental, indirect and confined 
 to a small number of individuals. Its beneficial effects, on 
 the contrary, are inestimable, and far in excess of the incon- 
 veniences it occasions; and in the field of legislation general 
 or public good is the thing of importance. 
 
338 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Three Parts— I, II, III 
 
 I. Incomplete divorce, allowable. 
 
 II. Complete divorce, not evidently and in every conceiv- 
 able case against strict natural law. 
 III. Complete divorce, always against secondary law of na- 
 ture. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 I. In marriage that is allowable, which, resulting in no 
 permanent or undeserved evil, procures peace for the inno- 
 cent, punishes the guilty, and promotes contentment. But 
 incomplete divorce, or temporary separation, is sometimes a 
 thing of the sort. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: A lasting and unbroken union 
 is of course very desirable in marriage ; but disagreements are 
 likely to arise in married life, and render such a union quite 
 out of the question. One party to the contract may behave 
 so scandalously that the severest sort of punishment must be 
 employed against him. In such circumstances every legiti- 
 mate channel of relief must be available, and every penalty 
 short of dissolution must be put at the disposal of the inno- 
 cent. Dissolution itself, were it not for higher reasons con- 
 demned by God Himself, would not be too severe a measure 
 in certain emergencies. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Love may grow cold and fall 
 to intensest hate. Husband and wife cannot in this sad turn 
 of events safely live together under the same roof. Tem- 
 porary separation may work a change in their dispositions, 
 and, when out of one another's sight for a while, the old love 
 may be renewed and former relations may be resumed with 
 pleasure and content. Reconciliations and lifelong happiness 
 are often the consequences of temporary separation. Adul- 
 tery, continued abandonment and persecution are grievous 
 crimes against the innocent partner, and no penalty short of 
 temporary separation is commensurable with the wrong done. 
 
PROOFS S39 
 
 II. Complete divorce, not evidently against strict natural 
 law. 
 
 Evils forbidden by strict natural law are threefold : 
 
 (a) things wrong in themselves, and on their own account. 
 
 (b) things wrong in themselves, not on their own account, 
 but on account of some violated right. 
 
 (c) things wrong in themselves, not on their own account, 
 but on account of danger connected with them. 
 
 But complete divorce is not evidently and in every con- 
 ceivable case evil in any of these three ways. Ergo. 
 
 (a) No one contends that divorce is as much an evil as 
 blasphemy. We have historical evidence of the fact that God 
 once sanctioned absolute divorce. His approval of blasphemy, 
 if such a thing were possible, would not relieve the act of its 
 inherent sinfulness. 
 
 (b) The right violated by divorce would belong to God, 
 or husband and wife, or children of the marriage, or society. 
 God's right in the premises would be made manifest by 
 revelation, and natural philosophy is a stranger to revela- 
 tion. Husband and wife could agree to forego whatever 
 rights divorce would jeopardize. Some unions are never 
 blessed with children, and divorce would not act against 
 children already grown up and freed from parental authority. 
 Society could likewise surrender all rights endangered by 
 the practice, and to-day society practically surrenders these 
 rights. Therefore, the wickedness of divorce is not evidently 
 and in every case derivable from a violated right. 
 
 (c) Dangers, likely to arise from abuse of the privilege, 
 could be reduced to mere shadows, by restricting its use to 
 such exceptionally rare accidents as, for instance, barren- 
 ness, leprosy, impotence. Danger, then, is not an element 
 everywhere and evidently apparent in the institution of di- 
 vorce. 
 
 III. Complete divorce is out of harmony with that second- 
 ary law of nature, which counsels the proper. Everything 
 opposed to the best interests of marriage and a hindrance to 
 the easy accomplishment of marriage's purpose is out of har- 
 mony with that secondary law of nature which counsels the 
 proper. But absolute divorce is a thing of the sort. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Nature is a jealous guardian 
 
SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 of the right ; and reason, her herald, is loud against not only 
 open violations of her plainest laws, but also those lesser evils 
 that threaten harm to her beneficent plans. Absolute divorce 
 hurts marriage in four very vital particulars, and, apart even 
 from the heavy condemnation of God, has nothing to recom- 
 mend it to the mind of the philosopher. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: These four vital particulars 
 are: 
 
 a. Mutual friendliness between husband and wife. 
 
 b. Education of their offspring. 
 
 c. Woman's happiness. 
 
 d. The good of society. 
 
 a. The mere possibility, the remote danger of one day dis- 
 solving partnership, weakens and robs of its chief charm, the 
 friendship peculiarly characteristic of wedded life. Friend- 
 ship is measured by its lasting qualities, and divorce is an 
 enemy to conjugal steadfastness. Distrust is sure to poison 
 every marriage contracted with the understanding that di- 
 vorce is feasible. The woman will labor under a continual 
 suspicion that the man is casting glances in another direction, 
 and that freedom of confidence so essential to the happiness 
 of married life will be entirely wanting. Some wives have 
 been known to accumulate hidden wealth in preparation for 
 emergencies created by the iniquitous law of divorce. Faith- 
 fulness which should be above suspicion is endangered. 
 Wicked companionship with loose friends is rendered easy 
 and possible. Unholy liberties are encouraged, and forbidden 
 loves spring up in the hearts of the dissatisfied. Kent, a man 
 of world-wide reputation in the domain of law, is authority 
 for the statement, that adultery is full often committed to 
 secure a decree of divorce. Mutual forbearance and patience 
 with one another's faults have small or no ground for exer- 
 cise. Absolute divorce provides the quarrelsome with a read- 
 ier and more sweeping remedy. That prudence and caution, 
 absolutely necessary for guidance in so serious and solemn a 
 step, are utterly neglected. Young men and young women 
 rush into marriage, satisfied that they can call the bargain 
 off, if unforeseen difficulties arise. 
 
 b. The education of children bom to divorced couples must 
 be sadly defective. To be complete, this education must be at 
 
COMPLETE DIVORCE HURTS MARRIAGE 341 
 
 the same time intellectual, moral, and physical. To be well 
 balanced, it must be managed by father and mother alike. 
 When this education is finished, the woman is so far on in 
 years that divorce must prove for her injurious in the extreme 
 and peculiarly aggravating. Children should, besides, learn 
 from their parents that love and respect for father and 
 mother, which are the crowning glory of childhood. Divorced 
 fathers and mothers can hardly inspire their children with 
 any such feelings of love and reverence. The child will neces- 
 sarily side with either father or mother, and entertain a deadly 
 hatred for one of the two or both. 
 
 c. In divorce woman is the sufferer. Dread of the untoward 
 event can haunt her like a gaunt spectre. And when the 
 step is taken, she is more at the mercy of fortune than the 
 man. He is hale, hearty and accustomed to work. He can, 
 besides, find new admirers with much more facility than the 
 abandoned woman. A divorced woman, as some writer says, 
 has far fewer attractions than a widow. Marriage on this 
 account ceases to be a fair and equal contract. The woman, 
 when divorce ensues, necessarily starts on an inferior footing. 
 She has lost her virginity, her youth, her beauty, her reputa- 
 tion and good esteem. Men are slower to lose their attractive 
 qualities than women. This unfair advantage procured by 
 divorce to men, moved another writer, no doubt, to say that 
 marriage is a partnership entered into for the exclusive 
 utility of one of the partners. 
 
 d. One of the happy consequences, resulting to society from 
 marriage, is the union and harmony promoted among families 
 and their different members. St. Augustine is of opinion 
 that nature forbids marriage between relatives primarily to 
 tighten the bonds of friendship between individuals of the 
 race, not otherwise united. Relatives are already close 
 enough together without the addition of any further ties of 
 union. Divorce breaks up families. It nourishes lasting 
 hatred between the principals and all connected with them. 
 It disgraces men and women of good reputation, who happen 
 to bear the names of the divorced persons, and always spreads 
 the reign of enmity and discord. 
 
THESIS XI 
 
 Education of children belongs to parents first; to state, last. 
 Jouin, 1S5-19S; 314-321. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Parents are in strict duty bound to procure the physical 
 and moral education of their children. As between state and 
 parents, the parents have prior rights to the child. They, 
 not the state, are its makers, and to the maker belongs what 
 he makes. Education means development, and a child's edu- 
 cation means development of the whole child, body and soul. 
 It means, therefore, development of body, food, raiment and 
 preservation of health; it means instruction, or training of 
 mind; it means morality, or training of will. The state's 
 duty to train the child's mind and to train the child's will, 
 to administer schools and inculcate virtue, is of a kind with 
 the state's duty to supply the child with proper food and rai- 
 ment, and safeguard its health. Its obligation in these sev- 
 eral respects is to keep the parents to their duty, and sup- 
 plement their weakness, when means or good will fail them. 
 When parents are willing and able to proffer their children 
 by themselves or others a measure of instruction suited to 
 their rank in life, when they equip their children with a brand 
 of morality above suspicion, the state's duty is at an end 
 with respect to knowledge and virtue; and it has no more 
 right to interfere with parents in the education of their chil- 
 dren than it has to prescribe the cut of clothes they shall 
 wear, the food they shall eat, or the rules of hygiene they 
 shall follow. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Education. Marriage bases a triple society, conjugal, 
 parental and servant. Marriage is primarily between hus- 
 
 342 
 
INSTRUCTION AND OBEDIENCE 343 
 
 band and wife. Viewed this way, it constitutes conjugal 
 society. Children are the natural outcome of marriage, and 
 at their advent the family becomes parental society. Serv- 
 ants are needed helps to domestic management, and, when in- 
 serted as members in the family, constitute it servant-society. 
 Education presupposes children, and becomes a duty only 
 when the family grows to the proportions of parental society. 
 Education is impossible without obedience; and this is true, 
 whether there is question of developing the body, or the mind, 
 or the will. It is a kindness their elders do the young, sup- 
 posedly unable to care for their bodies and distinguish be- 
 tween true and false, good and evil. Apropos of this it is 
 well worth remarking that father and mother in their rela- 
 tions with children are called parents, not parients. They are 
 people to obey, not people who beget or produce; and usage 
 itself lays more stress on the fact of obedience than on the 
 fact of origin. 
 
 Instruction is, of course, a branch of education ; but, when 
 applied to children, instruction must not be confounded with 
 mere information. And this would seem to be the difference 
 between the two. Instruction in the case of children always 
 connotes in the pupil obedience or submission of mind to the 
 teacher's superior mind. Mere information carries no such 
 obligation, it is altogether a transaction between equals, and 
 no disorder results from its rejection. Between man and man 
 information is the regular process, and it rests entirely with 
 the person informed to accept or spurn aside his informant's 
 views. No mere man, without some accompanying preroga- 
 tive, is allowed to impose his views on others; and nobody 
 can feel hurt, when the world refuses to adopt a theory or 
 statement he is unable to prove to evidence. A teacher, with- 
 out the authority needed to ratify his lesson, is no more a 
 teacher than the morning-paper or a theatrical bill-board; 
 and to endeavor to teach children after this manner, is to 
 put them on an equality with grown men and grown women. 
 Education of the kind would be a denial of education suited 
 to children, and would make education the child's exclusive 
 duty, and nobody else's. 
 
 Obedience, therefore, is an essential feature of education, 
 and to say that the state, as compared with the parents, has 
 
344 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 prior rights in the child 's education, is to assert that a child 's 
 obedience is first due the state and then his parents. States 
 themselves take no such view of the thing. They deal with 
 adults, not with children. They reach children through their 
 parents. They hold parents responsible for their children, 
 and by the very fact proclaim parents their children's imme- 
 diate superiors, entitled first and foremost to their obedience. 
 Citizens are the state's proper subjects, and children are only 
 incipient citizens. They are on the way to full and complete 
 citizenship, a fact accruing to them only when in large meas- 
 ure emancipated from the authority of their parents, and 
 done with the process called education. 
 
 Of course, parents and children alike owe the state a meas- 
 ure of obedience in virtue of authority, without which govern- 
 ment is an impossibility. But it would be folly to contend 
 that the obedience owed the state is as sweeping as the obedi- 
 ence a child owes his parents. State authority is just as 
 sacred as parental authority, but it is necessarily more limited. 
 In both cases it is a means to an end ; and its extent must be 
 gathered from the purpose it is meant to secure. The state's 
 solemn purpose is to promote the common good of its citizens ; 
 and it sins by excess, when by superfluous and harassing en- 
 actments it aspires to undue control of individual liberty and 
 private rights. This is especially the case when it invades 
 the domain of education or religion, because they are dis- 
 tinctively the concern of family and Church. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 Education of children belongs to parents first; to state, 
 last. Rights are based on duties; and priority of duty fixes 
 priority of right. Viewed as a duty, the education of chil- 
 dren touches parents first, the state afterwards. Therefore, 
 in the education of children a parent's rights are prior to 
 those of the state. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Parents were meant by nature 
 to educate as well as produce children. 
 
 1°. For a long stretch of years after birth children are 
 absolutely helpless with regard to the development of their 
 bodies, their minds and their wills. This being the case, God 
 
 I 
 
PROOFS AND PRINCIPLES 345 
 
 must have appointed fixed and definite persons capable of 
 carrying on the work of their education. 
 
 2°. Care of children involves hardship of the sternest sort, 
 and men are not minded to embrace hardships except from a 
 sense of duty. If the duty to educate children fell to the lot 
 of no God-appointed person, everybody would shirk the re- 
 sponsibility, children would go without an education, and 
 God's negligence would contribute to the destruction of the 
 race. 
 
 3°. God has appointed either parents or the state to edu- 
 cate children, and we know from unmistakable signs that par- 
 ents, not the state, are His choice. These signs are the nat- 
 ural love of parents for their children, the title of ownership 
 vested in their very birth, and the child's tendency to look 
 to his parents for help and support. 
 
 4°. The experience of ages and parallel conduct in the no- 
 bler specimens of brute creation strengthen our argument. 
 
 5°. It is preposterous to think that God exempts parents 
 from the duty of education to impose it on a collection of 
 strangers denominated the state. It would be far easier to 
 believe that God wanted farmers to sit in idleness, while neigh- 
 bors with fatuous generosity worked their fields and handed 
 them the profits. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. The arguments alleged for state control of education are 
 chiefly these. 
 
 1°. Children are born members of the state; and, therefore, 
 subject to its control. 
 
 2°. The common good is involved in the education of future 
 citizens. 
 
 3°. A good education in the case of every child is a neces- 
 sary requisite for society. 
 
 4°. Parents get the right to educate their children from the 
 state. 
 
 A7iswer: 1°. Members of the state are not subject in every 
 particular to the control of the state. As individuals, they 
 have prior and independent rights ; and these rights must be 
 respected, not absorbed by the state. Children are citizens 
 
346 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 not immediately, but mediately, in virtue of membership in 
 a family, and care of children devolves first on parents, then 
 on state. 
 
 2°. In the state many particulars are conducive to the com- 
 mon good ; and yet, because of personal and antecedent rights, 
 they must be left to private initiative. Instances are, eugenic 
 marriages, clothing, food, residence. 
 
 3°. This good education can be secured without delivering 
 up education to the state. In this matter the state enjoys 
 only an indirect right ; it can help parents by the erection of 
 schools, by rewards and penalties; but it must not take from 
 the parent what belongs to the parent. 
 
 4°. It is wholly wrong to think that parents get the right 
 to educate their children from the state. The family is prior 
 to the state, and enjoys prior rights, that the state must safe- 
 guard, but never absorb or usurp. 
 
 B. The State and Education. The word education, ex- 
 pressive of a parent's duty to his children, is a comprehen- 
 sive term. It means support of body, food, raiment, and 
 sanitary precautions. It means wise provision for his chil- 
 dren's future. It means the bestowal of opportunities to 
 acquire all the human knowledge necessary for success in life. 
 It means incentives to morality in the shape of good example, 
 rewards and punishments. It means early acquaintance with 
 God and the things of God. Rousseau wants no mention of 
 God till the child is twelve, and sufficiently grown to select 
 his own religion; but that is only another tribute to the man's 
 godlessness, and to his desire to make the world atheistic. 
 
 Regularly, then, and in the natural order, the right to di- 
 rectly and immediately educate their children belongs to 
 parents alone. They have the right to say what branches 
 their children shall learn, what teachers their children shall 
 follow, what books they shall use, how many years they shall 
 spend at school, and whatever minor details are connected with 
 their education. If they object to state-schools on any of 
 these several heads, they are at perfect liberty to withdraw 
 their children and send them elsewhere. 
 
 Parents have duties towards their children in this matter 
 of education; and, if they notably fall away from them, the 
 state has a right to interfere to the extent of safeguarding the 
 
 I 
 
COMPULSORY AND MONOPOLY 347 
 
 common good. It is of prime importance to the state to have 
 educated citizens, and its own welfare is menaced when par- 
 ents grossly abuse their prerogative, and deny their children 
 all opportunity for intellectual improvement. In self-defense 
 the state is obliged on such occasions to interfere, and by wise 
 enactments arouse unnatural parents of the kind to a sense 
 of their duty. Besides, it is the state's duty to safeguard 
 individual rights; the child has rights in education against 
 his parents, and the state is held to assist the child in the 
 prosecution of his rights. These, however, are exceptional 
 cases, scattered instances, and rare enough to leave unchal- 
 lenged our statement, that regularly the right to educate 
 their children belongs to parents alone. 
 
 Moreover, the state's rights in the matter remain always 
 indirect and mediate. Its power is over the parent, not over 
 the child's education. It has no right to educate the child, 
 it has the right to hold the child's parents to their duty. It 
 is to the state's own interest to help parents acquit them- 
 selves of their duty, to build schools everywhere, to equip 
 them with capable teachers, to encourage study among the 
 young by rewards in the shape of degrees, diplomas, certifi- 
 cates and political honors. But in last resort it rests with 
 parents to use these state-schools or not, as they like. They 
 have no duty towards state-schools, save payment of taxes; 
 and the state has no power over the family's internal con- 
 cerns. Their single duty is to educate their children, with 
 the help of the state or without it. If the brand of educa- 
 tion offered by the state is a serious menace to religion and 
 morality, the parents enjoy no freedom. They are bound in 
 conscience to reject all such instruction, and no law of God 
 or man can compel them to subject their growing children to 
 danger of eternal damnation. 
 
 C. Compulsory Education and State Monopoly. Hence we 
 Catholics are uncompromisingly opposed to anjrthing like 
 government monopoly of education, reserving to the State the 
 exclusive right to open schools, as to a thing against the nat- 
 ural law; and the sin is all the more grievous, when parents 
 are compelled by law to send their children to these state- 
 schools for a fixed period. More than this, we contend that 
 the State has no right to compel parents to send their chil- 
 
348 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 dren a certain number of years to any school whatever, even 
 if the school frequented be left to their own choice. 
 
 Monopoly in education is wrong on these several counts. 
 It robs parents of their natural right to educate their chil- 
 dren, and transfers it to the State; especially when parents, 
 unequal themselves to the task, must perforce send them to 
 some school. Instruction and education cannot possibly be 
 kept apart. Instruction has to do with the training of the 
 mind; and moral education is bound to be imperfect, if the 
 mind from the beginning is developed along wrong lines, if 
 a teacher's crooked notions regarding religion and morality 
 are authoritatively impressed on the minds of the young. 
 Moral education means more than the mere inculcation of 
 right principles, it means the reduction of these principles to 
 act; and pupils must be helped in this particular by the ad- 
 vice and example of their teachers. 
 
 Monopoly is an uncalled for restriction of the right to im- 
 part and receive instruction, viewed as mere information, im- 
 plied in the gift of a tongue and ears, made every member 
 of the race. In the natural order, the propagation of false- 
 hood is the one limit to this freedom of instruction. In the 
 supernatural order, the Church is of course supreme; and a 
 profession of faith can with justice be exacted by the Church 
 from the teachers of even profane sciences. Pius IX and 
 Pius X insist with much vehemence on this right of the 
 Church. The gtate has a right to only such measures as make 
 for the common good, and the arbitrary exclusion of private 
 instruction in the field of education is no such measure. On 
 the contrary, it is the most deleterious of measures, because 
 it kills all progress in letters. 
 
 Monopoly would make education dependent on some fac- 
 tion in government. Nobody could teach, unless approved 
 of and educated by this particular faction; and all competi- 
 tion between teachers, so helpful to improvement, would be 
 no more. Certainly, the Church would have no voice in the 
 department of education, and supernatural truth would suffer. 
 
 Compulsory education is of two kinds; one with, the other 
 without monopoly. Compulsory with monopoly is wrong, 
 because it is the usurpation of parental rights, assuming di- 
 rect and immediate control of the child's education, already 
 
CHURCH AND EDUCATION ^9 
 
 proved the exclusive privilege of the parents. Besides, every 
 such system savors of socialism. If the state is once allowed 
 control of the child's education, nothing can prevent it from 
 assuming control of family, property, and of the whole in- 
 ternal administration of the home. 
 
 Compulsory without monopoly is beside the power of the 
 state, unless we maintain that a school education of a fixed 
 kind belongs as a necessary right to the child, or that the 
 common good demands such a course, inasmuch as defective 
 education would contribute harm to the republic, or would 
 prevent children from enjoying political and civic advan- 
 tages. A school education is useful, not necessary. Even if 
 necessary, children as such have no right in the name of rigor- 
 ous or commutative justice against parents. Even if they had 
 such right, reading, writing and arithmetic would be enough 
 for the poor, without robbing parents of their children's help 
 during long years. 
 
 D. The Church and Education. Religion and morality are 
 not an affair of the state in direct sense, but of the Church; 
 and the Church must manage for children, with help from 
 the state. The Church has paramount rights in this business 
 of education. It was established by Christ, to teach religion 
 to the nations, and its authority bears equally on children, 
 parents and state. According to the will of Christ, nobody 
 in the world is exempt from its jurisdiction. In the super- 
 natural order, in the order of faith and morality, it is regu- 
 larly the direct and immediate teacher of all mankind, the 
 one teacher vested with active and passive infallibility, em- 
 powered to control parents in the education of their children, 
 and dictate terms to the state whenever and wherever the 
 profane sciences, like history, physics, chemistry border on 
 its domain. 
 
 Up to the time of the Reformation, it was educator to the 
 world. That revolution substituted the state for the Church ; 
 and ever since history has been one long attempt to exaggerate 
 state prerogatives at the expense of parental and ecclesiastical 
 rights. Our public schools are but a baneful substitute for 
 the cathedral and monastic institutions, established for chil- 
 dren centuries before the appearance of Luther and the spread 
 of his pernicious and destructive doctrines. Over these ca- 
 
350 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 thedral and monastic schools the Church exercised full and 
 complete control. It was supreme arbiter in the field of 
 education, sacred and profane. In sacred matters, with a 
 direct bearing on faith and morality, it recognised no su- 
 perior or rival. Whatever religion parents or state taught 
 children, they had to take from the Church. In profane 
 matters, considered apart from religion and morality, it viewed 
 parents and state in the light of agents or helpers, attribut- 
 ing a fuller right to parents than to state. And all this, 
 because profane matters are subservient to sacred interests. 
 Parents were always reckoned agents born such and irremov- 
 able. It rested with them to choose teachers for their chil- 
 dren, the branches of knowledge they were to pursue, the 
 years they were to spend at school; and, as long as the child's 
 eternal interests were not jeopardized, the Church confided 
 everything to the prudence of parents. 
 
 It recognised no such sweeping power in the state, forbid- 
 ding it to unduly interfere with parents in the conduct and 
 management of their children. It welcomed with gladness 
 every move made by the state in favor of right education, but 
 consistently opposed every attempt on the part of the state to 
 usurp prerogatives belonging to Church and parents. The 
 Church can oblige parents to send their children to schools 
 where religion is taught, can forbid them schools where reli- 
 gion is separated from instruction, because the Church's su- 
 pernatural right weighs against the natural right of parents. 
 The Church can likewise empower the state to insist on at- 
 tendance at religious schools, and in this emergency the voice 
 of the state is the voice of the Church, and the state as vested 
 with the power of the Church is superior to parents. But 
 without such authorization from the Church the state always 
 ranks lower than parents in the education of children. 
 
 Hence the state is guilty of tyrannical usurpation against 
 the Church, when it compels parents to send their children 
 to neutral or mixed schools, condemned by the Church as hurt- 
 ful to faith and morals. With certain restrictions Catholic 
 parents are allowed to avail themselves of such schools, though 
 they are solemnly exhorted to everywhere build and maintain 
 parochial schools, where knowledge of religion and knowledge 
 of letters keep equal pace together. Certainly, no Catholic 
 
BOUQUILLON AND HOLAIND 351 
 
 can with a safe conscience help to the enactment of a law 
 making the attendance of Catholic children at mixed or neu- 
 tral schools obligatory. In countries, where Catholics must 
 choose between compulsory education in godless schools and 
 unlimited freedom in education, the latter alternative is the 
 lesser evil and the more commendable course. It is another 
 case of choosing between dogmatic toleration and political 
 toleration. 
 
 Before the Reformation, state-schools were always under 
 the direct supervision and control of the Church. After the 
 Reformation, denominational schools came into use, and the 
 Church had to be satisfied with the conduct and management 
 of such schools as Catholic children frequented. Then came 
 non-sectarian or mixed schools, in which religion was sup- 
 posedly taught in such a way as to give no just offense to 
 any pupil of whatsoever creed; and this would seem to be 
 the complexion of our public schools. State-schools are rap- 
 idly becoming entirely lay or irreligious, with no concern for 
 religion, teaching at most the broadest kind of humanitarian- 
 ism, and the lay or independent morality introduced into 
 philosophy by Kant. 
 
 E. Controversy between Bouquillon and Eolaind, S.J. 
 Education — To whom does it belong? 
 
 Bouquillon gives it to state first, to parents last. 
 
 Holaind, S.J., gives it to parents first, to state last. 
 
 Holaind, S.J. It is wrong to leave the Church out of the 
 comparison. Its supernatural end ranks it above state and 
 parents. Morality is an integral part of education, revela- 
 tion is exclusively under Church control, and the moral im- 
 possibility of morality without revelation puts all education, 
 in full and complete sense, at the mercy of the Church; makes 
 state and parents subject to her jurisdiction in matters educa- 
 tional. The Church is empowered to teach human as well as 
 divine science, at least in an indirect way, inasmuch as the 
 human sciences are useful or necessary to religion and moral- 
 ity. Faith cannot hurt science, because its exponent, the 
 Church, is infallible; the sciences can hurt faith, because 
 their exponents, mere men, are not infallible. 
 
 The Church can share her prerogative as educator with 
 state and parents; and, when they work under her control. 
 
352 
 
 they are her agents, and they enjoy rights that are far from 
 belonging to them in their own private capacity. The Church 
 counts state and parents her agents after a different man- 
 ner. A father in virtue of paternity has rights over his 
 child, that cannot be disputed by any claimant with a lesser 
 title than paternity; and the Church, taking this fact into 
 account, reckons parents her agents, born such and irre- 
 movable. The state's control of the child is based on no such 
 intimate relation as paternity, and whatever educational pre- 
 rogatives it enjoys, it gets by favor of the Church. The 
 Church cannot be supposed to do favors to her enemies, to 
 reckon agents her deadliest foes; and non-Catholic states, be- 
 cause they work outside her control, are usurpers when they 
 attempt to educate children. 
 
 With these few needed remarks, we leave the Church. Our 
 question is between parents and state. We maintain that 
 education belongs to parents first, to state last. Our op- 
 ponents are of opinion that it belongs to state first, to parents 
 last. They recognize the right to educate in individuals, in 
 the family, in the state, and in the Church; and the order 
 they follow would lead one to think that they subordinate 
 family to state in the matter of educational rights. It is sim- 
 ple nonsense to talk about the individual's right to educate. 
 All individuals have the power to teach, to give useful infor- 
 mation to others; but the others are free to accept or reject 
 the information. The power to teach gives rise to no posi- 
 tive duty of a kindred color in the listener; and a power in 
 me, that creates no such duty in others, can hardly be called 
 a right. Education means more than mere teaching ; it means 
 teaching with authority. It embraces all those functions, 
 which promote not only the preservation and development 
 of the body, but also the perfection of the mind, and the 
 evolution of intellectual and moral powers. To educate is to 
 exercise jurisdiction, it supposes authority in the educator, 
 submission in the pupil. Nobody has the right to educate the 
 children of anybody else, unless their parents give him that 
 power. Paternity is the foundation of jurisdiction in parents, 
 and paternity can be found nowhere outside of parents. The 
 Church can educate, because divine command is a higher title 
 than paternity. 
 
BOUQUILLON AND HOLAIND 353 
 
 And this is the mistake Bouquillon makes in all the quo- 
 tations from Catholic philosophers and theologians he urges 
 to prove the right of the state to educate the young. They 
 have in mind a state with the Church at its back; the state, 
 whose claims he advocates, has no such support. The king 
 they talk about is no mere king, he is a Charlemagne, with 
 the unction of the Church on his forehead; a most dutiful 
 son, actuated in all his conduct by childlike obedience to the 
 Church's wishes. The king Bouquillon talks about is a non- 
 Catholic, and therefore a non-Christian state, whose rulers 
 would count it profanation to be touched by the Church's 
 unction, with whom word from a Mexican rebel weighs about 
 the same as, or even more than, word from a Pope. The 
 truth may as well be told, our country is no truly Christian 
 Country in the full and complete sense of the word, because 
 it is not a Catholic country. ''Extra Catholicism um non da- 
 tur verus Christianismus. " There can be no true Christian- 
 ity without Christ, the Son of the living God. True Chris- 
 tianity means the profession of Christ's doctrine in its en- 
 tirety, not in parts ; it means membership in the Church Christ 
 established, not mere toleration of its members. 
 
 F. Holalnd, SJ., on Family, State, Church and Education. 
 
 Family. Duty and right of the parent. Education be- 
 longs to the parents first, to the state last. It belongs to the 
 parents regularly, directly, and immediately; it belongs to 
 the state in exceptional cases, indirectly, and mediately. 
 Blackstone makes the duty of parents threefold, support, pro- 
 tection and education. Four reasons to prove that this three- 
 fold duty flows directly from natural law. 
 
 1°. Children result from free act of parents, and every 
 moral agent is responsible for consequences of his free acts. 
 Life would be a curse, and no blessing, without support, pro- 
 tection and education. Ergo, parents are held to this three- 
 fold duty, and the obligation is independent of all positive 
 law. 
 
 2°. Nature's chief purpose in marriage is the continuance 
 and perfection of the race. This purpose would be defeated, 
 if parents neglected this threefold duty. Ergo, the obliga- 
 tion is imposed by nature itself. 
 
 3°. A universal impulse, rational, human, reproduced in 
 
354 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 instinct of animals, is unmistakable token of natural law. 
 But the accomplishment of this threefold duty is such an 
 impulse. Ergo, it is imposed by natural law. 
 
 4°. A special and natural fitness indicates a special and 
 natural duty. Parents have a special and natural fitness to 
 educate their children. Ergo, it is their special and natural 
 duty. Nothing can replace the love of a mother, the mild 
 firmness of a father. Sparta never produced a single poet, 
 orator or statesman of superior ability. Rome gave even too 
 much authority to fathers, and had a long line of great men. 
 
 State. In parents this duty of education is a perfect duty, 
 demanded by rigorous or commutative justice; not merely 
 an imperfect duty, based on mere fitness and unenforcible by 
 children. Government takes this latter view, because it wants 
 to absorb individual and family. The state has right to keep 
 education clear of moral poisoning; but it has no right to 
 invade privacy of the home. Sphere of state's activity is 
 fixed by its end or purpose, to maintain peace, protect rights, 
 supply insufficiency of individuals. Its direct object is not 
 individual, but social good. Wrong must be exterior and 
 must visibly attack society, before state can invade the home. 
 
 Seven points to be kept well in mind. 
 
 1°. The family is a true and complete society. 
 
 2°. The family is exterior to the state, with rights and du- 
 ties prior to those of the state, and closer in their origin to 
 nature. 
 
 3°. Education is one of these rights, inalienable, suffering 
 no abridgement or destruction. 
 
 4°. The state cannot at will invade the home. 
 
 5°. The state must help the family in case of extreme need. 
 
 6°. The state must ensure rights in family, when great dis- 
 turbance arises. 
 
 7°. The state must do all this without absorbing rights of 
 the family. It must oblige parents to educate their children, 
 it must not itself educate them. 
 
 Church. Docete omnes gentes, fixes the Church's mission 
 as a teacher. Its jurisdiction extends to human sciences, at 
 least indirectly. Certainly, it has direct control of such 
 natural moral truths as are morally impossible to unaided in- 
 telligence. 
 
BOUQUILLON 355 
 
 G. Bouquillon^s Argument. Bouquillon seems to claim di- 
 rect control of education for the state. Here is his argument, 
 his apodictic syllogism. Major — ''Civil authority has the 
 right to use all legitimate temporal means it judges necessary 
 for the attainment of the temporal common welfare, which 
 is the end of civil society. Minor — Now, among the most 
 necessary means for the attainment of the temporal welfare 
 of the commonwealth, is the diffusion of human knowledge. 
 Conclusion — Therefore civil authority has the right to use 
 the means necessary for the diffusion of such knowledge, that 
 is to say, to teach it, or rather to have it taught by capable 
 agents," p. 12. 
 
 About the Major — If the parents refuse to agree, the means 
 are not legitimate, because the rights of the family are in- 
 vaded. If the parents agree, state education is not compul- 
 sory and the state's right to education is indirect, not direct, 
 getting all its validity from the consent of parents. 
 
 About the Minor — The diffusion of human knowledge to 
 such as are willing to receive it, is not education in strict sense. 
 Jurisdiction is wanting. To teach or instruct the willing, is 
 not to educate, excepting perhaps in part, because independ- 
 ent of revelation, without which morality is impossible. 
 Revelation cannot be received or rejected at will. 
 
 About the Conclusion. To teach or instruct children against 
 the will of their parents, is an illegitimate means to the diffu- 
 sion of knowledge, because it is an invasion of family rights. 
 The state's one legitimate way to diffuse human knowledge, 
 is to build schools, employ capable teachers, furnish suitable 
 text-books, all at the discretion and with the consent of par- 
 ents; to help parents perform their duty, without robbing 
 parents of their sacred right; and all this makes the state's 
 power over education indirect, not direct. The Church is 
 educator by divine command, parents are educators by nature, 
 the state is educator by favor of Church and parents. 
 
 H. Bcniquillon and History. Bouquillon 's arguments from 
 history prove nothing, because princes in question got their 
 morality from Church, acknowledged right of inspection in 
 bishops, and obeyed the Pope. The state has no more right to 
 found mixed or neutral schools than agnostic schools. Such 
 a state ignores revelation, and is incapable of education. 
 
356 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Pope Leo condemns all such schools, as well as Syllabus, 48. 
 Our rulers have on their hands a bad bargain, and they try to 
 meet conditions without hurting anybody. We condemn, not 
 our rulers, but the Catholics who send their their children 
 to such schools without need and without precautions. 
 
 The state has no authority to set aside parents in educa- 
 tion. Injustice is not compatible with authority. The state's 
 rights are therefore limited to the repression of immoral 
 or treasonable teachers, and to the promotion of learning by 
 supplementing private enterprise, and encouraging letters ; to 
 substituting for parents, when they are dead or notoriously 
 vicious, and when nobody is bound to the child by closer 
 ties of relationship. This control is, of course, indirect. 
 
 Church control is higher and more complete than even 
 parental. Her mission is supernatural, the mission of par- 
 ents is natural. The state, in union with the Church, has 
 completer rights than when alone. 
 
 Education is not in state control, simply because the growth 
 of learning is conducive to the common good. Every such 
 argument proves too much, common ownership of property, 
 supervision of the kitchen, and the like. The state must 
 promote the common welfare by social means, without short- 
 ening individual activity or invading the home. Education 
 is an individual good, and the state has only indirect influ- 
 ence over it. Power over cases of neglect implies no power 
 to fix a minimum of education, except, perhaps, for neglected 
 children. Power to punish parents who starve their children, 
 implies no power to settle the number of ounces a child must 
 get. These matters are undefinable a priori, and must be 
 settled in each particular case by a competent judge. 
 
 I. Bouquillon and Authority. Authors Bouquillon quotes 
 are opposed to his theory, Costa-Rossetti ; Jansen; Hammer- 
 stein. 
 
 Costa-Rossetti has this thesis, '* Considering natural law 
 only, parents cannot be compelled by civil authority to send 
 their children to an elementary school, but they may be 
 obliged to do so in particular cases. ' ' 
 
 Three Theses of Jansen. (1) Parents alone have right; 
 (2) Lawful for nobody to instruct without authority from 
 parents; (3) Parents not subject to state-control. 
 
BOUQUILLON 357 
 
 Hammerstein says, Parents are before Church and state 
 in concept and in fact, and without either, parents would 
 have to educate. State has indirect right, namely to sup- 
 ply what is wanting in family, to found and endow schools 
 where needed, to compel negligent parents, to take place of 
 parents for orphans and abandoned children. State has no 
 direct right, and therefore no compulsory, no monopoly, no 
 minimum. Some wrongly hold that children belong to state 
 before parents; and this is worse than Eminent Domain and 
 conscription; it is Socialism. State can insist on necessary 
 education some way; and this is not compulsory education. 
 Church has direct power over religion; indirect power over 
 natural knowledge. 
 
SECTION III— CIVIL SOCIETY, OR THE STATE 
 THESIS XII 
 
 Man is hy very nature a social heing. Jouin, 204r-212; 
 Bickahy, 297-310. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Family, or domestic society, is not equal to man's full evo- 
 lution. State or civil society is a further need. 
 
 State, or civil society, means a complete multitude of men, 
 banded together to safeguard their rights and promote their 
 common good. 
 
 It means new relations, a new bond, new duties, new rights. 
 
 Origin, scope and structure of State are our topics. 
 TERMS 
 
 By Very Nature. Protestants in general derive origin of 
 civil society from compact. They contend that there was no 
 civil society in the primitive state of nature. Hobbes and 
 Rousseau are their standard-bearers. 
 
 Hohhes (1588-1679), instructor to Charles II. 
 
 Man's highest faculty, sensation. Its object, pleasure; 
 opposed to society, and favorable to egoism or selfishness. 
 Hence, solitude, not society in strictest accord with primitive 
 state of nature. Might, the only claim to possession; war 
 and quarrels, natural condition. Interminable disputes, be- 
 cause strength was met by trickery, fraud. Theory proved 
 by conduct of two boys on first acquaintance. Fear, there- 
 fore, led to establishment of civil society; and passage from 
 state of nature to political society had fear for motive. Au- 
 thority needed, to repress turbulent. This authority without 
 bounds or limit ; the more sweeping, the better. 
 
 358 
 
HOBBES AND ROUSSEAU ON STATE 359 
 
 Multitude transfers individual rights and forces to rep- 
 resentative. 
 
 Authority absolute and beyond law; unimpeachable, irre- 
 sponsible, superior to justice itself; disobedience, invariably 
 a crime ; became Church and revelation for subjects. 
 
 With Rousseau (1712-1778), man's natural state is a wan- 
 dering and solitary life, like that of wild beasts. Strength 
 and ferocity from encounters with beasts. Imitate instinct 
 of brute creation for herding together. No higher knowledge 
 than that of sense. No worship, no notions of duty. Free 
 will and intelligence acquired only after the lapse of many 
 ages. Solitary life more in accord with human nature, be- 
 cause more favorable to freedom. Social contract fixed every- 
 thing. Therefore, society accidental, no improvement, a mis- 
 take, a curse. 
 
 Absurdities of Hobbes and Rousseau: 
 
 Hohhes: 
 
 Man inferior to brutes; lions fight with other animals, not 
 among themselves. 
 
 Example of small boy proves the contrary. 
 
 Nature and man's inclination counsel peace, not war; order 
 is nature's first law, and peace is order. 
 
 Wars are fought to establish peace, and settle disturbed 
 relations. 
 
 Hobbes' entire system is death to morality; petrified, 
 adamantine tyranny. 
 
 Rousseau : 
 
 Some refuse to take Rousseau seriously, and regard his 
 theory an elegiac poem in memory of his times' abuses. 
 
 Man has no reason and is limited to sensation. 
 
 Man enjoys freedom without intellect,, freedom's founda- 
 tion. 
 
 All mankind departed from man's natural and proper 
 condition. 
 
 Absolutely no foundation, able to render the theory likely. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 1. From facts. 
 
 2. From man's natural needs. 
 
360 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 3. From speech. 
 
 4. From inborn kindness. 
 
 5. From notion of perfectibility. 
 
 6. From dictate of reason. 
 
 1. The oldest history at our disposal, monuments and kin- 
 dred remains, testify that man always lived in society. Na- 
 ture alone is motive for a fact so universal, so enduring, so 
 constant. 
 
 2. The young of animals are bom equipped for life 's strug- 
 gles, and little dependent for support on parents or others; 
 the children of men are bom absolutely helpless. St. Thomas 
 compares. Food ready for animals; garments, teeth, horns, 
 claws, wings, for defense or flight. Man has reason instead, 
 to direct work of equipment ; a man is not sufficient unto him- 
 self in the work of equipment ; he needs others. Instinct helps 
 animals to choose things beneficial, and avoid things danger- 
 ous or harmful ; young sheep and wolf. Man knows in only a 
 general way; many heads are required to reduce general 
 knowledge to practical utility. 
 
 3. Man enjoys the gift of speech, an accomplishment denied 
 the rest of animal creation. Dogs bark, to express passions 
 in a general sort of way. Man alone is able to express him- 
 self with distinctness and precision. Speech is the bond of 
 society, and can have for design nothing short of communi- 
 cation between man and man. This communication of ideas 
 can have for result nothing short of the formation of families 
 and societies. 
 
 4. Man is by nature prone to spend himself on others, and 
 let them into his joys and griefs. The learned like to share 
 their knowledge with friends. The fortunate add to their 
 store by manifesting to others their success. The wretched 
 derive comfort from the company and commiseration of their 
 neighbors. In a word, man wants others to rejoice and be 
 sad with him; and nothing more provokes uneasiness and 
 dissatisfaction than distressing solitude and the privation of 
 mutual intercourse. 
 
 5. Man is essentially perfectible. He is always on the road 
 with progress, employing his energies to add to whatever 
 wealth preceding ages have bequeathed. His sense of a want 
 
PROOFS 361 
 
 of finish prevents him from ever resting or accumulating 
 moss or rust. Condemned to the task of working out his 
 plans alone and unaided, his lot would be a sorry one, in- 
 viting disappointment and despair. He must face a world 
 of difficulties ; and, to win in the end, must necessarily apply 
 that age-old principle of successful generals, ''Divide and 
 conquer." No one man can hope to advance far into the 
 secrets of a multitude of arts or occupations. Human weak- 
 ness and limitations force us to devote our energies to some 
 particular line of work, and trust to the activities of others 
 for the rest. Progress would be practically impossible, unless 
 the sons took up the task where the fathers left off; unless 
 succeeding generations held fast to and improved on the re- 
 sults achieved by the men of old. Harmony of effort is a 
 prime requisite for anything like remarkable success in hu- 
 man industry. And society is the most powerful engine of 
 war put at man's disposal by nature. 
 
 6. Eeason clamors for order in the various activities of 
 men. And order without society is impossible in the matter 
 of duties, rights, propagation of knowledge and the arts, and 
 the exercise of all the virtues peculiar to humanity. 
 
 P.S. All six arguments indisputably prove man's mem- 
 bership in family, state and Church natural in strict sense, 
 whether immediately or mediately; and we note in passing 
 that this present thesis has a very important bearing on 
 Thesis XIII and Thesis XIV, where authority is the topic 
 discussed. Membership in society makes man a social being, 
 and society is threefold, domestic, civil, ecclesiastical, or fam- 
 ily, state and Church. Man is by very nature a social being, 
 if these three societies are natural to man in strict sense. 
 Recall what we said in General Ethics, Thesis II, about desire 
 of complete happiness and desire of marriage. Natural in 
 strict sense means inborn, prompted and imposed by nature, 
 independent of man's choice and consent, unavoidable. Nat- 
 ural in wide sense means not inborn, not imposed by nature, 
 not independent of man's choice and consent, not unavoid- 
 able; but in harmony with man's dignity as a human being. 
 
 All three societies are strictly natural to man, but in differ- 
 ent ways. Costa-Rossetti, page 409, distinguishes three ways, 
 immediately natural, mediately natural and remotely natural. 
 
362 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 A society immediately or mediately natural is naturalin 
 strict sense, a society remotely natural is natural in wide 
 sense. A society is immediately natural when its purpose and 
 character flow immediately from man 's nature ; and the fam- 
 ily is an instance. Every man is bom into a family, he is 
 always a son of some parents, nature wants parents to be mar- 
 ried, marriage constitutes family, children born out of mar- 
 riage are against nature, branded by the world as things 
 of shame, no free will about entering family. A society is 
 mediately natural, when immediately natural societies are its 
 constituent parts, when its purpose and character flow from 
 man's nature in such a way that the man's free choice has 
 something to do with its organization; and the state and 
 Church are instances. Man is bom into a state, he is always 
 a member of some family, family^ is always a unit in some 
 state. Church is as natural a society as state, because as 
 needful for spiritual prosperity as state is for temporal ; 
 men are born into it, nature wants all men to belong to the 
 true Church, nature wants all men to be Catholic ; it is against 
 nature to be anything else, wrong churches are from compact 
 and civil law, not true Church; God and nature settle that, 
 no moral freedom is left, physical stands; too important to 
 leave to men's choice, eternal salvation is at stake. A so- 
 ciety is remotely natural, when not at variance with man's 
 nature, though its purpose and character are fixed not by 
 man's nature but by his free choice, not imposed by nature, 
 not unavoidable; and a business-partnership is an instance. 
 A society is unnatural when its purpose and character are 
 wicked, when it is without moral union based on duties, when 
 it is in reality no society and ought to be dissolved ; and the 
 Freemasons are an instance. 
 
 Nature definitely settles the family to which a man must 
 belong, no man ever ceases to be the son of his parents. In 
 definitely settling his family, nature definitely settles the 
 state, into which he is born, without definitely settling the 
 state, in which he must live. Though born into a fixed state, 
 a man can change his allegiance from one country to another ; 
 though he cannot change his nationality, he can change his 
 citizenship, but always in such a way that nature wants him 
 
PRINCIPLES 363 
 
 to be always a citizen of some state, leaving the determination 
 of the particular state to his own free choice. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Bousseau says: a. To get down to man's natural con- 
 dition, we must strip him of whatever ornaments and advan- 
 tages the civilization of centuries added to his original per- 
 fections. Stripped of these ornaments, man is nothing more 
 noble than what Rousseau paints him, a wandering beast, 
 without reason, and without social aspirations. 
 
 b. Universal ideas are the immediate effects of language, 
 and language is not at all natural to man, but the result of 
 art and study. It would, therefore, seem that in the state of 
 nature man was wholly destitute of universal ideas. 
 
 c. America and Africa are inhabited by tribes of human 
 beings more like beasts than men, with no religion, no laws, 
 no customs. 
 
 Answer: a. Man must not be stripped of his essence; and, 
 as long as he remains in possession of that, he is the owner of 
 a higher faculty than sense, viz., reason. He is by nature a 
 rational animal, a species of being entirely and utterly dis- 
 tinct from brute creation. 
 
 b. In the supposition of the Nominalists Rousseau's theory 
 about universals would be true ; but that supposition is long 
 since exploded. Universal ideas are independent of words, 
 and owe their being to a process of abstraction founded on 
 the reality of things. Language is no work of art, it is the 
 product of nature, which fits men with organs nicely ar- 
 ranged and admirably intended for the production of articu- 
 late sounds. This language or that language in particular 
 is, of course, a work of art ; but nature evidently had in view 
 the use of some language or other, subject to the choice of 
 different peoples. 
 
 c. No barbarous nation is so poor as not to possess and 
 employ reason in the ordinary affairs of life. Rousseau may 
 endeavor to deceive his readers into believing that rude rea- 
 soning and dense ignorance are no higher essays at knowl- 
 edge than sensation; but the man capable of such folly is, 
 
364 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 either unacquainted with the first rudiments of philosophy^ 
 or dishonest enough to impose on the credulity of others by 
 downright lying. Neither is any nation so barbarous as not 
 to acknowledge a deity and worship him in some way suited 
 to its false and imperfect notions. The mistakes of barbar- 
 ism in the matter of religion and laws are not a gift of nature, 
 but an addition made to nature by the depravity and ^vicked- 
 ness of free agents. Nature even in barbarians rebels against 
 the wrong done her, but she is kept in check by the species of 
 omnipotence resident in liberty's tyranny. 
 
 B. Hohhes says: In state of nature everything common, 
 no private property. Therefore wrongs and universal quar- 
 reling. The arrogant and strong always adding to their 
 stores by oppression and robbery; the mild and gentle in con- 
 tinual strife, to protect themselves and their goods. Differ- 
 ences of disposition beget hatred and contempt. Men travel 
 laden with weapons, citizens lock their doors, the state sup- 
 ports policemen, sheriffs, troops. 
 
 Answer: Hobbes' whole mistake consists in foolishly sup- 
 posing that human nature proceeds from the hands of the 
 Creator with all the imperfections resulting to it from man 's 
 perverseness. Man's power for harm is immense, and the 
 wicked are no true exponents of human nature. To form a 
 fair estimate of what man would be in a state of nature, we 
 must take the virtuous for standard; and surely their dispo- 
 sitions and methods of behavior tally exactly with the require- 
 ments of society. Individual defects ought not to be laid to 
 the account of human nature, and saddled on the back of all 
 mankind. Nature is not to blame for the precautions taken 
 by citizens against danger to life and property, but the pas- 
 sions of men, greed of gain, anger, quarrelsomeness and qual- 
 ities loudly condemned by nature. Even the wicked cannot 
 shake off this inclination towards society, precisely because it 
 is from nature. 
 
 C. If society is a dictate of reason, monks and solitaries 
 are out of harmony with nature, and guilty of a grievous 
 wrong. 
 
 Answer: Society is a dictate of reason meant for mankind 
 as a collection, and as a help to the race's betterment. It is 
 not a dictate meant for each and every individual, as an end 
 
PRINCIPLES 365 
 
 of absolute and supreme importance. For higher purposes 
 and motives a man can with praise abandon society and live 
 apart from his fellows. Naturally speaking, however, and 
 apart from the supernatural advantages accruing to the her- 
 mit, it must be said that normally life in solitude is far in- 
 ferior to life in society. 
 
 D. Differences between Hobbes and Rousseau: 
 
 Hobbes, natural state opposed to society ; Rousseau, natural 
 state outside of society. 
 
 Hobbes, society bettered man's condition; Rousseau, so- 
 ciety, a downright injury to mankind. 
 
 Hobbes, natural state, universal warfare ; Rousseau, natural 
 state, good, peaceful, happy. 
 
 Hobbes, society founded on egoism and fear. From egoism, 
 universal war, because everything in common; fear of death 
 and want of security, desire of society. Each transferred his 
 will to one man or body of men ; hence, Regal Absolutism. 
 
 Rousseau, man in natural state happy with the happiness 
 of brutes, oaks, rivulets, trees. No need of society, but by de- 
 grees compacts were made at the expense of liberty. Hence, 
 "Social Contract.'' 
 
THESIS xm 
 
 A multitude and authority, or subjects and a ruler, are ele- 
 ments essential to civil society, or the State. Jouin, 212-214. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 The Staters Pxtrpose. The State has for object external 
 order, actuated by internal righteousness, and all for com- 
 mon good of the citizens. Kant has another theory about 
 the guiding purpose of political society. He assumes that 
 man's freedom is nothing worth, unless it implies absolute 
 independence of all restraint, moral as well as physical, de- 
 pending solely on itself and on whatever reason, unbiassed 
 by any outside recommendations or impressions, decrees. 
 These impressions serving to destroy freedom are twofold in 
 his hypothesis, inner and outer. The former have their 
 origin in the mind's appetites and desires. The latter are 
 due to outside forces at work against an agent's free choice. 
 The first class of impressions are subject matter for what he 
 styles moral law; the second class, subject matter for what 
 he chooses to designate juridical or judicial law. Moral law 
 is therefore a restraint on nature and inborn factors of dis- 
 order. Juridical law holds in check what enemies threaten 
 an attack on freedom from without. To bring order out of 
 the chaos liable to result from the conflict between will and 
 will in the field of outward agencies, reason and nature made 
 the establishment of the State, or political society, impera- 
 tively necessary. In establishing the State it imposed on the 
 same the obligation of seeing to it that each man's freedom 
 be confined within such limits as not to interfere with the 
 freedom of others. The principle, therefore, of coexistence 
 of individual liberties lies at the root of civil society, and 
 constitutes civil society's sole purpose and aim. This theory 
 of Kant is built from turret to foundation-stone on false prin- 
 
 366 
 
ELEMENTS AND PURPOSE OF STATE 367 
 
 ciples. We call attention to these three statements in par- 
 ticular : 
 
 a. Man is absolutely independent, responsible to no one 
 save himself. 
 
 b. Morality is an affair of abstractions, outside the sphere 
 of concrete realities. 
 
 c. Human liberty, viewed externally, is illimitable and un- 
 confined. 
 
 We beg leave to think that all three statements are un- 
 founded and untrue. 
 
 a. Man is God's creature, and essentially dependent on his 
 Creator, essentially responsible before God for his every act. 
 
 b. Morality's principles, though abstract in themselves, are 
 founded on concrete relations, existent not in the mind solely, 
 but alive and at work in the beings that surround us. Kant, 
 it may be remarked, would blasphemously rate love of God 
 unmoral, because, forsooth, God its object is outside the agent 
 eliciting the act, and because love is accomplished not by rea- 
 son, but by the will. 
 
 c. In the abstract, human liberty may be considered a 
 thing without bound or limit; but in the concrete, in the 
 everyday affairs of men, liberty is decidedly restricted. The 
 object matter on which it exercises itself, the duties incumbent 
 on the free agent in the use of his liberty, certainly operate 
 to render human liberty anything but illimitable and unre- 
 strained. 
 
 In Kant's system society would procure to mankind noth- 
 ing higher than a negative good, the curbing of wicked vio- 
 lence and cessation of quarrels between man and man. If it 
 once set about accomplishing any positive effect, it would at 
 once degenerate to either individualism, or selfishness and 
 despotism. It would either oblige every man to work for him- 
 self solely, or, relieving the State of all moral responsibility 
 in its arbitrary enactments, would rob subjects of the protec- 
 tion now afforded by the salutary restraints morality exer- 
 cises over even the State. The abuses arising from Kant's 
 system are manifold: 
 
 a. All public morality would perish from the earth. The 
 State would be able to prohibit only what actions of mine 
 interfere with the full liberty of my neighbor. Suicide, bias- 
 
368 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 phemy, sacrilege, unholy contracts, public scandals, if done 
 with the full consent of parties concerned, would be no crimes 
 at all. 
 
 b. Religious indifference, political atheism would be men's 
 rights; and the Church would have no voice whatever in the 
 affairs of men. 
 
 c. Finally, government, when closest to its end's fulfilment, 
 would lose its usefulness, its very reason for existence. The 
 State would slowly work out its own destruction, and would 
 ever tend towards self-annihilation. Harmony once secured, 
 men would have no further need of the State's directive and 
 saving influence. In our theory, even with this harmony se- 
 cured, the State would still be a need. Righteousness and 
 common good demand state. State has indirect control of our 
 thoughts and wishes. 
 
 Right System. The State has for object external order, 
 actuated by internal righteousness, and all for the common 
 good of the citizens. The end or object of a thing is that 
 for which it exists, that towards which its energies must tend. 
 We have already described the various classes of ends. To 
 now apply. God's glory is the absolutely last end of society, 
 as it is of everything else in the universe of existences. The 
 relatively last end of society is external order, procured with 
 a view to the common welfare of its members, and actuated 
 by morality or rectitude. Society accomplishes this end, when 
 it secures to citizens means to fully exercise their rights. 
 The means themselves are said to be society's proximate or 
 nearest end. Actual possession by the citizens of these means, 
 or prosperity in first act, is society's remote or more distant 
 end. The actual evolution of faculties and exercise of rights 
 constitute civic prosperity in second act, or in its complete- 
 ness. Order is taken in its philosophic sense, and means a 
 becoming disposition of things, such as allots to each its own 
 proper place. Righteousness is harmony with reason or ob- 
 jective order. If external order were not actuated with 
 righteousness, society would be ethically wrong, and would 
 be in direct opposition with man's natural tendencies. That 
 society has no other purpose than the purpose we assign, is 
 evident from the fact that men enter society with no other 
 end in view. They regard it as an institution designed for 
 
PROOFS AND PRINCIPLES 369 
 
 the relief of individual deficiencies, an aid to the full and 
 peaceful enjoyment of their rights; and, therefore, intended 
 to establish external order, actuated by internal righteousness, 
 for the common good of the citizens. 
 
 The scope of society determined, we can now proceed to 
 discuss its elements or structure. By multitude we under- 
 stand any large or small collection of individuals. Authority 
 in the State is a moral right independent of every other right 
 in its own order, to direct or guide the actions of citizens 
 towards the common good. Scholastics, applying their theory 
 of matter and form, regard the multitude its matter, the au- 
 thority its form. Society is therefore a compound reality, 
 and these two parts are indispensably necessary to its being. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 Society, or the state, is an individual body, not physically, 
 but morally speaking. It is likewise a peaceable and well 
 ordered assembly of many. But we must recognize in every 
 individual body parts blended together, and a principle ef- 
 fecting the union sufficient to constitute the body one. In 
 the same way every peaceable and well ordered assembly 
 necessarily involves the idea of individuals making up the 
 assembly, and some principle capable of maintaining peace, 
 and holding the different wills to harmony. Multitude 
 means the persons forming the state. Authority means prin- 
 ciple procuring unity and preserving order. Ergo. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Subjects are the concrete expressions of multitude ; rul- 
 ers, the concrete expression of authority. 
 
 B. Difference between authority and dominion, or prop- 
 erty : Dominion turns on things ; authority, on persons. Use 
 of dominion is a free act ; exercise of authority, a duty. Do- 
 minion has for object the owner's private profit; authority 
 is for good of community. 
 
 Difference between a subject and a slave: A slave as such 
 is more like a thing or chattel than a person, in point of serv- 
 ice; a subject as such has all the qualifications of a person. 
 
370 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 and enjoys a person's free rights and privileges. A slave is 
 a person and a chattel, a subject is a person and no chattel. 
 A slave is absolutely dependent on the wishes of his master, 
 in point of service ; a subject is moved to act not by the su- 
 perior's will precisely, but by the authority it represents and 
 by the appointment of reason. A slave works unto his mas- 
 ter's gain; a subject aims at the advancement of the whole 
 community. 
 
 C. It is a duty incumbent on the State to procure the pros- 
 perity of every single citizen, whether rich or poor, learned 
 or ignorant, noble or plebeian. Any legislation aiming at 
 the aggrandizement of a certain few to the injury of certain 
 others, is against the first elements of political morality, and 
 grievously wrong. To procure signifies to furnish means, the 
 citizen himself must apply them. 
 
 D. Only admissible form of society, that in which liberty 
 and equality are guaranteed, meaning equality of opportuni- 
 ties. 
 
 I 
 
THESIS XIV 
 
 Authority proceeds immediately from God. In the nature 
 of things, and ordinarily, authority is not conferred on the 
 people. Ordinarily, and in the nature of things, the consent 
 of the people fixes or determines the person in whom author- 
 ity resides. This consent may he implied or expressed, im- 
 mediate or gradual, and cannot always he withheld. Jonin, 
 214^226; Bickahy, 310-338. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Two questions: 
 
 A. Whence comes authority? 
 
 B. How is authority conferred? 
 
 One deals with the origin of authority; the other, with its 
 recipient. 
 
 A. All Catholics are agreed about the origin of authority. 
 Catholics are not a unit on the second question. Rousseau 
 and Hobbes, on account of the theories already alluded to, 
 are logically obliged to invent a false theory about authority's 
 origin. 
 
 The word, immediately, needs explanation. Two ways: 
 Cause immediate, when no other cause intervenes. Election, 
 never a cause. It is a condition. The two ways are posi- 
 tive enactment and law of nature. Moses and Aaron in Holy 
 Scripture received their authority from God in first way, 
 because chosen and appointed by God without any free act 
 on part of people. Positive enactment is likewise the method 
 in force in case of the Sovereign Pontiff. God in revelation 
 instituted the office in such sort that men are forbidden the 
 liberty of changing, limiting or lessening the Pope's author- 
 ity, though they are allowed the privilege of electing or choos- 
 ing an individual for the office. Authority can spring from 
 a law of nature, and, therefore, from God as its immediate 
 cause, in a threefold manner. 
 
 371 
 
372 
 
 •ECIAL ETHICS 
 
 a. It can belong to a subject by very force of creation, and 
 in virtue of the natural order of things. A father's author- 
 ity in the family is an instance. 
 
 b. It can be bestowed by God on a person determined by 
 some such accidental fact as acquiescence or inheritance. The 
 accidental fact is by no means a cause of the acquired au- 
 thority, but at most an indispensable condition. 
 
 c. Finally, it can result from the free choice of a people, 
 expressed by suffrage. Nature in this case advises and coun- 
 sels the act, it gives the act, all its force. It renders the act 
 such a medium that in the event of its absence no authority 
 would accrue to any individual. And yet, because of the in- 
 fluence nature exerts in the performance of the act, and be- 
 cause of the circumstance that the act operates merely to 
 designate the person, on whom God afterwards bestows au- 
 thority, God remains the immediate cause of political su- 
 premacy in even a republic. 
 
 B. The second question about the recipient of authority is 
 more delicate and harder to settle. Apart from certain 
 openly false opinions, the Scholastics themselves are divided 
 on this topic, and proffer apparently different solutions. 
 Everybody is agreed that a multitude, or the people as such, 
 cannot exercise authority. It would be quite out of the 
 question, and simply impossible, for each person to issue 
 orders to his neighbor, and be in turn ordered by the neigh- 
 bor. It would be impossible in the tumult of opinions to 
 decide what person was invested with the prerogatives en- 
 titling him to the obedience of others. A multitude of the 
 kind would be matter without form; and, therefore, no so- 
 ciety at all. Everyone would have to know everything, and 
 everyone would have to pass sentence on every measure and 
 detail of government. Therefore, even if authority were first 
 bestowed by God on the multitude or whole people, an indi- 
 vidual ruler, in whom this authority would be centred, would 
 be a necessity of nature, and as such indispensably necessary. 
 By ruler we mean any person or body of persons legitimately 
 constituted to exercise full dominion of jurisdiction. A mul- 
 titude is a collection of individuals. A people is a multitude 
 of citizens living under the same government. State au- 
 thority is social power existent in particular and determined 
 
AUTHORITY AND ITS RECIPIENT 373 
 
 individuals. There can be no difficulty in understanding that 
 no mere multitude, no people separated from its ruler, is a 
 fit subject for authority. In fact, a multitude as such can 
 never become the actual exponent and agent of authority. 
 All the difficulty lies in determining whether a people can in 
 first act, as they say, retain authority, immediately bestowed 
 on the people by God and wielded by the sovereign in the 
 State. To compare, state is the whole man, body and soul. 
 Authority in ruler is the soul, multitude is the body. 
 
 Philosophy discusses four different systems, advocating 
 each its own theory about the manner of authority's bestowal 
 by God. Their authors are: ^' James I, ^' Taparelli, ^' the 
 Scholastic in general, *• Hohhes and Rousseau. 
 
 1. James I, supported for a long time in his opinion by 
 the University of Oxford, contended that kings and Popes 
 were on a level. Men, therefore, as he thinks, are as unable 
 to tamper with the authority of secular princes as they are 
 to tamper with that of the Sovereign Pontiff. They cannot 
 in justice lessen or change the prerogatives of kings. They 
 cannot frame laws setting bounds to royal wishes, nor can 
 they with any show of right object when their rulers override 
 the limitations of law. James appeals to the instances of 
 Saul and David ; but his appeal is vain, since revelation made 
 their claims good. No modern king has revelation on his 
 side. The divine right of kings is authority's only defense, 
 in the opinion of James, against factions and rebellious sub- 
 jects. Against James we maintain that apart even from 
 the divine right of kings, a people is not at liberty to limit 
 at will power once transferred to the ruler. It is far less able 
 to abolish such power, unless the ruler, abusing his trust, 
 descends to the meanness and injustice of open tyranny. 
 This, too, is the case, in Bellarmine's opinion, though he fa- 
 vors the supremacy of the people to something of an excess. 
 He thinks that a people never completely hands over its au- 
 thority to a king ; but, always retaining it in habit or potency, 
 can in certain cases actually recover it and administer things. 
 
 2. The second system, that of Taparelli and many modern 
 writers among Catholics, advocates God's immediate bestowal 
 of authority on the ruler, and denies to consent of the people 
 everything higher than accidental necessity or importance. 
 
374 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 The ruler, according to these writers, is determined either 
 by some antecedent concrete fact or by the free consent of the 
 people. Hence they count consent of the people necessary 
 only by accident, when the antecedent concrete fact is want- 
 ing. Ordinarily this fact settles succession, and dissent on 
 the part of the subjects is out of the question. The all im- 
 portant fact is described as superiority from the standpoint of 
 domestic headship. The state is in its first origin an out- 
 growth of the family. The father, from ruler in household 
 eoncerns, grew by degrees to exercise political sovereignty 
 over his own immediate family, and families connected with 
 it. As he holds from nature the authority to govern his wife 
 and children, so from nature he holds his right to manage 
 the State. These authors, therefore, consider God's gift of 
 authority immediate, inasmuch as it proceeds from a law of 
 nature. They contend that, in the ordinary course of events, 
 a people's consent is not absolutely necessary; admitting at 
 the same time that contingencies can happen in which this 
 consent becomes a reason why God vests some set person with 
 authority. Different from doctrine of James I, who derives 
 authority from positive divine enactment. Kings, therefore, 
 are on a level with the Pope. People cannot establish, can- 
 not change authority, because it is a divine institution. 
 
 3. The system proposed hy Scholastic philosophy is compli- 
 cated, and offers among others these characteristic points: 
 
 1. Authority universally considered comes immediately from 
 God. 
 
 2. This authority rests immediately in the whole multi- 
 tude. 
 
 (N.B. To at once refute this theory, we answer the three 
 reasons alleged in its support. 
 
 X. Because it is of divine right and granted by God to no 
 one in particular. 
 
 Answer: Impossible, because multitude unfit to govern. 
 It is granted to ruler chosen by people. 
 
 y. Because no one is born a king. All are bom equal. 
 
 Answer: True in the abstract, but circumstances sur- 
 rounding birth make some infants kings. In this Scholastic 
 sense no man could own property by law of nature. The 
 ruler selected by the people is not bom selected. 
 
SCHOLASTIC SYSTEM 375 
 
 z. Because Society ought to be a perfect government, with 
 prerogatives enabling it to protect itself and punish disturb- 
 ers of its tranquillity. 
 
 Answer: This is true enough of a perfect society, consist- 
 ing of ruler and people ; not true of a half -society, consisting 
 solely of subjects without a ruler. It is the ruler's business, 
 not the business of separate individual citizens to protect the 
 state and punish its disturbers). 
 
 3. The multitude can and must make over its authority to 
 some king or governing body, with no vestige of a right to 
 retain it. 
 
 4. The law of nations rules men's choice of form of govern- 
 ment, because prior to government they are without other 
 law. 
 
 5. Political power is from God, but through human counsel 
 as a medium, not through multitude as medium, in which 
 authority first resides. 
 
 (N.B. Difference between civil and ecclesiastical power. 
 In general, civil power is from God by divine law; in par- 
 ticular, from God through the law of nations. Ecclesiastical 
 power is always and in every case God's immediate gift, and 
 positive divine law is its foundation. Political power is vested 
 in the multitude ; ecclesiastical power belongs to one man. In 
 political, multitude controls prerogatives; in ecclesiastical, 
 multitude is without control.) 
 
 6. Men dispose the material for the reception of the form 
 infused by God, i.e., men designate the ruler, God vests him 
 with authority. Suarez says as much in De Legibus, Bk. 3, 
 c. 3, n. 2. 
 
 7. A people never makes complete surrender of its authority 
 to the king. It always retains the authority by way of a 
 habit, or capacity, or in quiet. After the appointment of a 
 king, no two authorities remain capable to pass into act. 
 Nevertheless, it is safe to say that two remain, one in the king, 
 the other in his people; understanding always that the au- 
 thority, resident in the people, is merely habitual, debarred 
 from activity, as long as the king's authority endures. When 
 the king's authority falls, then that of the multitude asserts 
 itself. The people resumes its right to designate a ruler. 
 
 8. Suarez on the authority of Ulpian and St. Augustine in- 
 
376 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 troduces the ''Royal Compact," in virtue of which subjects 
 are considered to transfer all their rights to the king, the 
 king at the same time, or in return for the favor, assuming 
 all the responsibility attaching to government. 
 
 9. A Dominican, Father Victoria, thus sums up the doctrine 
 of the Scholastics: "By divine decree the government holds 
 its power. This power resides by divine and natural right 
 in the government itself, since it devolves on the government 
 to rule and manage itself, and direct all its energies to the 
 common good. Nature makes no difference between individ- 
 uals in a community, before the assignment of a head. When 
 the king is once established on his throne, he must be said 
 to have his authority immediately from God alone, not from 
 the people at all." These statements sound like a contradic- 
 tion in terms; but a distinction may serve to reconcile the 
 two Catholic schools of thought represented by Suarez and 
 Victoria respectively. Victoria contends that the people cre- 
 ate their king, not his royal authority ; Suarez maintains that 
 the people make some person ready and fit for authority. 
 Molina admits that the king is above his people, even col- 
 lectively taken. 
 
 To reconcile apparent contradictions in Suarez and others, 
 we must only suppose that they view authority and society 
 at one time in the abstract ; at another, in the concrete. Ab- 
 stractly considered, like that vague ownership denominated 
 common and everybody's title before occupancy, authority 
 exists in every member composing a society or state. Con- 
 cretely speaking, and taking the state for an established in- 
 stitution made up of a king and subjects, authority exists 
 again in every member comprised in the society or state, but 
 only after such a manner that the people dispose or make 
 ready the matter, choose a ruler, and God in turn impresses 
 on the object of their choice the form of authority. 
 
 Resemblances : 
 
 a. Civil power comes immediately from God through nature, 
 and what comes through nature comes from God. 
 
 b. Certain human acts are necessary to invest one man 
 rather than another with authority. 
 
 c. When no prior right exists, when no right is endangered 
 by such action, a people has from very nature the right, it is 
 
HOBBES AND ROUSSEAU ON AUTHORITY 377 
 
 in fact bound, to specify its own form of government and 
 appoint its own ruler. 
 
 Differences : 
 
 a'. Authority passes immediately from God to the people = 
 abstract. 
 
 Authority passes immediately from God to the state = con- 
 crete. 
 
 b'. Ordinarily, and of itself, authority is the result of 
 "Royal Compact"; of a variety of causes by accident = no 
 ruler fixed, choose ruler. 
 
 Ordinarily, and of itself authority has its origin in family 
 authority or a preceding right ; by accident, in agreement = 
 ruler fixed, no choice. 
 
 c'. No authority can accrue to a king without some sort of 
 consent on the part of his people. Such consent may be im- 
 mediate or gradual, implied or expressed. When a prior 
 right is the foundation of the king's claim, no consent of the 
 people is needed ; but the people can in some cases be obliged 
 to give consent. 
 
 4. A fourth system is that introduced hy Rousseau and 
 Hohhes. 
 
 Rousseau conceives authority as the result of a surrender 
 of free will and rights, made by every member of the state 
 or society. By this surrender every individual deeds over 
 to the whole community his person, and puts under the di- 
 rection and control of a general or universal will all his pow- 
 ers and faculties. Public or social authority is, therefore, 
 with him a sum total of individual wills and liberties, and 
 this sum total constitutes a general or universal will, which 
 is authority, the state. The very act of alliance immediately 
 produces, in place of the single persons closing and sealing 
 this contract, a moral body, a collective group, composed of 
 as many parts as the suffrages or votes represented at the 
 meeting. This moral body assumes at the same time, and by 
 the self-same act, its proper oneness, its personality, its life, 
 its will. 
 
 , Hohhes establishes a like compact, made out of fear and 
 from sense of danger. He then vindicates to the state a 
 power that puts it above conscience and all law, human and 
 divine. 
 
378 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Against Rousseau and Hohhes: 
 
 1.. Contradiction. 2. Liberty inalienable. 3. Leaves no 
 liberty in individual. 4. Transfer in favor of individuals; 
 no society yet; same would command and obey. 5. Man 
 would obey man — real slavery. 6. Authority would vary 
 with sum of votes — arithmetical progression. 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Four Parts— I, II, III, lY 
 
 I. Authority from God. 
 
 II. Not conferred on people. 
 
 III. . People fix ruler. 
 
 IV. Consents. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 I. Authority immediately from God. 
 
 1°. God makes to society immediate gift of that without 
 which society cannot be even conceived of in thought, of that 
 which belongs to the very essence of social order. But au- 
 thority is a thing of the kind. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: The essences of things moral, 
 as natural to man as society, are supplied immediately by 
 God. 
 
 Wilh Regard to the Minor: A thing's essence is made up 
 of its matter and form; and, of these two elements, form is 
 always considered the superior and more important. Au- 
 thority, we have seen, is the form; multitude, the matter of 
 society. Man is made up of body and soul; state, of multi- 
 tude and authority. 
 
 2°. The state receives authority either immediately from 
 God or from the individuals composing the state. But the 
 second member of this dilemma is absurd. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: St. Thomas says, and the 
 world agrees with him, that nobody is bom by very nature 
 a king, because otherwise everybody would be born a king, 
 since nature is the same in all men. Some men are bom 
 kings by accident of birth from royal parents. By birth or 
 nature they are mere human beings, and no better than com- 
 
AUTHORITY AND MULTITUDE 379 
 
 mon children. By royal birth they are kings, and royal is 
 an accident or quality superadded to birth or nature. It is 
 no escape from this argument to say that men transfer to the 
 king not authority properly so-called, but dominion over their 
 own acts. The transaction is nowhere recorded. Besides, it 
 would bind only parties to the contract, not their descendants. 
 Apart from the man himself, God alone is master of a man's 
 dominion over his own acts. The men of 1776 could never 
 transfer to Wilson dominion over the acts of men living in 
 1918. And they never attempted the thing. They could 
 transfer dominion over their own acts to Washington, and the 
 obligation of obedience would bind only such men of 1776 as 
 actually made the transfer, and Washington would have no 
 authority over recalcitrants in the country. 
 
 Obedience to Washington like obedience to Wilson, is not 
 rooted in any authority given them by the people, but in 
 authority given them immediately by God. Authority is do- 
 minion over the conduct or free acts of others. No man of 
 himself enjoys this dominion over others, God enjoys it over 
 all. And God shares this dominion of His with the ruler, 
 to make the state an established fact. Just as Washington 
 in virtue of the dominion or authority immediately conferred 
 on him by God, ruled all the men in America during his presi- 
 dency, recalcitrants as well as friends, so Wilson rules all the 
 men in America in 1918, dissatisfied republicans as well as 
 satisfied democrats. Men of themselves have no right to im- 
 pose obedience on others against their wishes. God has the 
 right to impose obedience on all, whether they are willing or 
 unwilling. In itself a majority has no more right in this 
 matter than an individual. The thing is plain in the case of 
 a king and his successors. The makers of a king could never 
 transfer dominion over the free acts of their descendants to 
 the king's successors. God alone has that power, and there- 
 fore God alone gave the king's successors authority. 
 
 Besides, God never gives authority to a ruler for his own 
 personal advantage, but for the advantage of the state. The 
 gift therefore endures as long as the state endures, and au- 
 thority belongs as much to successors as to the original king. 
 The state as such never transfers authority to the ruler, be- 
 cause no state exists till after the ruler is invested with au- 
 
S80 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 thority by God. When members of a firm give its president 
 certain powers, they give him what they first possessed. 
 When individuals attempt to give authority to a ruler, they 
 attempt to give what they never possessed, namely, dominion 
 over wills different and distinct from their own. 
 
 S°. Positive divine law can be alleged to strengthen the 
 position we take. ''There is no power but from God, and 
 those that are ordained of God. Therefore, he that resisteth 
 the power, resisteth the ordinance of God." Rom. 13.1. If 
 authority came from the people, disobedience would be direct 
 resistance to an ordinance of the people, not to an ordinance 
 of God. 
 
 II. Authority is not conferred on the people. 
 
 1°. Because such bestowal is not evident from nature. The 
 only bestowal evident from nature is bestowal on the complete 
 state, multitude and ruler together ; and this bestowal is veri- 
 fied, whether immediate gift is made to ruler or people. Im- 
 mediate bestowal on the ruler is not evident from the nature 
 of the state, but it is evident from the nature of authority. 
 From its very definition, authority cannot be exercised by 
 the people as such, it can be exercised by the ruler. 
 
 When Bellarmine says that authority as a divine and posi- 
 tive right is bestowed on no man in particular, and there- 
 fore on the multitude, he means that no man in particular 
 has a natural right to authority, that no man is born by very 
 nature a king, that by the nature of the state authority is in 
 the multitude, meaning multitude and ruler together, not 
 separately ; and with Bellarmine we stand for the same state- 
 ment. We deny, however, that authority is in the multitude 
 apart from the ruler, and contend that the very nature of 
 authority demands that it be in the ruler. Intellect is in 
 the man without being in his body, it is in his soul. 
 
 2°. It is absurd to consider the recipient of authority an 
 agent wholly unfitted and unable to exercise it. 
 
 But the people are such an agent. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Adversaries admit the people's 
 incapability to exercise authority ; and, to meet the argument, 
 distinguish between ability in first act or radically, and abil- 
 ity in second act. But ability in first act always implies the 
 remote possibility of passing from a present state of inac- 
 
AUTHORITY AND MULTITUDE 381 
 
 tivity to a future state of full activity. No such possibility 
 can be recognized in the multitude. If the distinction, ' ' rad- 
 ically," means ability to choose the king, or determine the 
 form of government, we readily grant to the people posses- 
 sion of such a power. The people^ therefore, and this is our 
 doctrine, have a full right to create the ruler. They have 
 no right to create or transfer the authority lodged in the ruler 
 selected. 
 
 A power in a person that the person himself cannot exer- 
 cise is a contradiction in terms = power and not power. Au- 
 thority in a multitude that the multitude itself cannot exer- 
 cise is the same. If the king exercises authority only as the 
 agent or instrument of the multitude, he is completely at the 
 mercy of his subjects, and has no real authority at all. 
 
 3°. According to adversaries, e.g., Suarez, De Legibus, 
 Bk. 3, c. 3, n. 2 — men make ready the material, they furnish 
 a subject for the reception of authority. God adds the form, 
 confers authority on this subject. But he that merely pre- 
 pares the material, cannot be said of himself to possess the 
 form. Ergo, authority is not of itself and immediately in 
 men or the multitude. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: This argument may be of little 
 force to any but Scholastics, who are familiar with the theory 
 of matter and form, current in the Schools. We introduce it, 
 however, because of its peculiar strength and cogency, when 
 used against such as admit the theory and accept the phrase- 
 ology. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Form is always absent, until 
 the matter is fully equipped and ready for its advent. As 
 soon as it approaches the matter, complete substance results. 
 If the supposition of our adversaries were correct, society 
 or the state would exist long before they conceive it to be- 
 gin. For the two elements would be a long while present 
 together, and no obstacle would stand in the way of their 
 union. 
 
 4°. Catholics all admit that the republic is not the essen- 
 tial and only natural form of government. 
 
 But whoso lodges authority in the multitude, and then in 
 the ruler, must necessarily adopt this attitude. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Many writers, influenced by 
 
382 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 
 Aristotle's opinion, hesitate not to affirm with him that re- 
 publics are in some respects inferior to other forms of govern- 
 ment. In point of stability history is emphatically in favor 
 of monarchy. Witness the following table. 
 
 Monarchies: 
 
 
 
 
 
 Assyria, 
 
 1449 
 
 years 
 
 Constantinople, 
 
 1121 years 
 
 Egypt, 
 
 1675 
 
 
 England, 
 
 1071 " 
 
 Persia and Media, 
 
 417 
 
 
 France, 
 
 1373 « 
 
 China, 
 
 2000 
 
 
 Germany, 
 
 1000 « 
 
 Roman Empire, 
 
 344 
 
 
 Spain, 
 
 1426 " 
 
 Rome, 
 
 853 
 
 
 Rome, 
 
 525 " 
 
 Republics: 
 
 
 
 
 
 Carthage, 
 
 647 
 
 years 
 
 United States, 
 
 125 years 
 
 Venice, 
 
 1346 
 
 u 
 
 Athens, 
 
 397 " 
 
 Genoa 
 
 855 
 
 (( 
 
 Rome, 
 
 290 " 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: A republic is, in a few words, 
 a state conceding to the people or multitude the largest pos- 
 sible measure of influence in political affairs. If authority 
 is first vested in the people, to be afterwards transferred by 
 them to the ruler, a republic, or better still a democracy pure 
 and simple, is the only form of government certain to com- 
 mend itself to the mind of the philosopher. No man can 
 fairly give what is not his own, and the principle holds good 
 when applied to a people. The people, therefore, must be 
 considered rightful owners of all the authority resident in 
 the ruler, before its transmission and acceptance. Absolute 
 democracy, or pure republicanism, is that manner of govern- 
 ment which vindicates all authority to the people in joint 
 assembly. Whatever different forms of government may now 
 be in use, it is quite certain, according to our adversaries' 
 way of thinking, that absolute democracy ought to have been 
 the original form, because the form most in accord with the 
 dictates of reason. 
 
 It is difficult, besides, for us to see why, if the people were 
 so minded, they could not retain authority and lend it to no 
 individual in particular. For, if in the moment preceding 
 the loan, they were really capable of possession, nothing 
 could possibly occur afterwards to divest them of that right. 
 An attempt to wield power by the whole multitude in com- 
 mon might certainly be attended b}^ innumerable and dis- 
 agreeable inconveniences; but right would nevertheless be 
 
AUTHORITY AND MULTITUDE 383 
 
 on their side, and reason is loud against any spoliation of 
 rights. If the people were incapable of authority in the mo- 
 ment preceding the loan, then they attempted to give what 
 was not their own, and were little better than thieves or rob- 
 bers. It was easy for primitive peoples to see the need of 
 submitting to the patriarch, because nature taught them that 
 the ruler got his authority immediately from God, not from 
 the people. 
 
 To reconcile the two seemingly opposite schools of Catholic 
 thought, it is necessary to merely examine these two state- 
 ments made by Victoria, one of our principal opponents, and 
 see how well they can be made fit with our own doctrine: 
 ''Monarchy is not only just and legitimate rule, but kings 
 have their authority in virtue of a divine decree, and by a 
 natural right. They are not dependent for it on the govern- 
 ment taken collectively, they are not dependent for it on 
 men at all." (No. 8.) In No. 7 he has the following : ''A 
 government, therefore, has power by divine appointment. 
 The material cause, or subject in which this power dwells, 
 is by law of God and law of nature the government itself, 
 because it belongs to the government to administer and man- 
 age itself and turn all its forces to the common good. ' ' Vic- 
 toria certainly never intended to contradict himself. When, 
 therefore, in his second statement he maintains that authority 
 is vested in the government, he cannot mean the people sep- 
 arated from the ruler. When writers of his opinion come 
 to explain themselves, they contend merely that authority 
 resides in the people in root, and consists entirely in their 
 being able, speaking philosophically, to prepare the matter 
 and get ready the subject. They, that with us deny author- 
 ity to the people, readily grant the people all the privileges 
 contended for by the opposite side. We willingly recognize 
 in the people the right to even determine, and appoint, and 
 choose by election, the person on whom God will afterwards 
 bestow the authority. But we emphatically deny that the 
 people are on this account the immediate recipients of au- 
 thority, we deny that authority properly so called rests in 
 the multitude. The motive uppermost with writers of the 
 school opposed to our view, is the fact that God never passes 
 authority to the ruler without the intervention in some way 
 
3^4 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 of popular will, human consent, or some other equally just 
 cause. We certainly pay due deference to the fact, denying 
 at the same time to such intervention the causalty claimed 
 for it by these others, and allowing it only the influence proper 
 to the designation or appointment of the candidate for au- 
 thority. We follow Suarez, Victoria rightly understood fol- 
 lows Suarez ; and we are all one. 
 
 To settle disputes about the title to authority in a state, and 
 decide between the rival claims of a lawful sovereign and a 
 usurper, these various opinions are advanced. Suarez insists 
 on his Royal Compact or Contract. Zigliara leaves everything 
 to election or choice, direct or indirect. Taparelli notes a 
 difference between three several classes of societies. Some 
 he calls natural, others free, others obligatory. In societies 
 of the first class, and the family is an instance, nature itself 
 appoints the ruler or head. In those of the second class, 
 consent is the all important factor. In those of the third 
 class, everything depends on preexisting rights. It must be 
 at first sight evident that consent of some sort or other is a 
 characteristic common to all three classes. In obligatory so- 
 cieties, such, for instance, as result from the subjugation of a 
 people by just process of war, this consent is an obligation 
 freely assumed by the conquered people at the beginning of 
 hostilities. They took up arms with the undestanding that 
 ultimate victor^^ was to decide supremacy, and in agreeing 
 to preliminaries they agreed to the result. In like manner, 
 consent is an element entering into the family. Consent, 
 however, is here, as in the former case, obligatory and exacted 
 by a law of nature. 
 
 Morally necessary consent is as physically free as morally 
 free consent; and one kind is as much consent as the other. 
 Consent, therefore, has place in natural and obligatory so- 
 cieties as well as in free societies. In all three societies con- 
 sent of the governed is title. In natural and obligatory so- 
 cieties this consent is physically free, morally necessary; in 
 free societies it is physically free and morally free. 
 
 Our position then is that taken by Zigliara. We simply 
 change the word, ** choice direct or indirect" to ''consent of 
 the people, whether implied or expressed, immediate or grad- 
 ual." And first, a word about these consents. They are 
 
CONSENT OF GOVERNED 385 
 
 implied and expressed, immediate and gradual, direct and 
 indirect. 
 
 Implied, manifest not from words, but from acts, that suflfir 
 ciently declare the will of parties to the consent. 
 
 Expressed, manifest from words whether spoken or writ- 
 ten. 
 
 Immediate, accomplished at once, without delay or inter- 
 ruption. 
 
 Gradual, given in parts, by some members of the community 
 to-day, by others to-morrow. 
 
 Direct, willed in itself, not through the agency of a second 
 event. 
 
 Indirect, not willed in itself, but in a cause freely assumed 
 and working out the event as a consequence. 
 
 Thus a murderer, though at first sight far from consent- 
 ing to or wishing his execution on the gallows, really makes 
 deliberate choice of that manner of death, when he slays an- 
 other. In the same way, a nation rushes into unjust war 
 with a hatred for defeat and subjugation. But to wish the 
 cause is to wish at the same time the effect. And, if the event 
 of the war is defeat, the nation in the wrong must be said 
 to have accepted defeat or consented to it, when it made 
 ready to march against the enemy. At the dawn of history, 
 children of the patriarchs, by the very fact of residence in 
 territory occupied by their fathers, yielded implied and in- 
 direct consent to be politically controlled by them. These 
 children after attaining their majority were by the law of 
 nature constituted free to move off, settle elsewhere, and 
 establish their own distinct government. Hence, even in pa- 
 triarchal times, though the family or domestic society was in 
 reality the origin of the state or civil society, that very free- 
 dom to withdraw from the patriarch's political influence ren- 
 dered consent necessary to the constitution of individual au- 
 thority. Families, intent on remaining within, the bounds of 
 a patriarch's kingdom, had their origin, of course, at different 
 intervals of time, and paid him the homage of what we call 
 gradual consent. 
 
 III. Consent of people determines person in whom authority 
 resides. 
 
 1°. Moral obligations of obedience to another arise either 
 
386 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 from nature or from free choice. We omit contingent facts, 
 because they are reducible to nature or free choice. But 
 man's moral obligations towards authority, vested in some 
 set person, arise not from nature. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Were the Minor false, some 
 individuals, apart from accidental circumstances of heredity 
 or election, would be born princes, and no such statement is 
 borne out by sound philosophy. St. John Chrysostom on 
 the text, ''All power is from God," Romans, 13.1, says, 
 ''Not the king, but his power." He means that authority is 
 from God, king is from people, by act of selection and free 
 consent. 
 
 2°. A people has the natural right to organize itself into 
 a society. But this right would mean nothing, unless the 
 people's consent were necessary. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: Some see an answer to this 
 argument in the distinction between a free people and a peo- 
 ple already held to preexistent obligations. But the distinc- 
 tion is vain. For the people surrendered their liberty by 
 free consent. If they were unjustly and unwillingly deprived 
 of their liberty, no rights of authority accrued to the despoil- 
 ers. 
 
 3°. Taparelli's division of societies into natural, free and 
 obligatory is complete and in harmony with Logic. But con- 
 sent is a necessary element in each class. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Natural society is that which 
 arises from the family by the ordinary process of evolution. 
 Without at least implied and gradual consent, no family, no 
 number of families, can ever coalesce into a perfect and com- 
 plete civil society. Without such consent, the children after 
 attaining their majority are certainly free to migrate from 
 the domains of their fathers, and cut entirely loose from an- 
 cestral authority. The fact that they remain at home, neces- 
 sarily betokens an act of free consent. Free societies of their 
 very nature suppose consent of the people, and offer no spe- 
 cial difficulty. Obligatory societies arise, either like natural 
 societies from the evolution of families, or from the vicissi- 
 tudes of war; and in each case consent is essential. 
 
 4°. Were consent unnecessary, every family would by the 
 very fact form a state or civil society. 
 
CONSENT OF GOVERNED 387 
 
 But this is absurd. Ergo consent is necessary. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: All the needed elements are 
 present, multitude and authority, at least parental authority. 
 If civil authority is independent of consent, the members of 
 a family owe its head due and full obedience. Civil author- 
 ity is absent from family precisely because consent is needed. 
 Children never consent to father's authority as civil ruler, 
 and nature imposes no such obligation on them. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: Domestic society is specifically 
 different from civil or political. Their scopes, constitutions 
 and methods are quite distinct, and it would be a fatal mis- 
 take to endeavor to apply to the two the same rules for gov- 
 ernment. Civil society, for instance, is endowed with the 
 right to inflict capital punishment, wage war, raise taxes, 
 privileges never even imagined in domestic society. The 
 difference between the two conditions is more than that of 
 mere degree, it is specific. 
 
 IV. Consent may be implied or expressed, immediate or 
 gradual, and cannot always be withheld. 
 
 1°. The people are obliged by nature to adopt government, 
 without which order in the State is an impossibility. 
 
 But it sometimes happens that one certain ruler and one 
 certain form of government are alone feasible. Ergo. 
 
 2°. The people are not allowed to use their freedom to the 
 detriment of preexisting rights. But to refuse consent, is 
 often to make such a use of their freedom. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: The lawful heir has antecedent 
 rights to the throne, and any violation of them is injustice. 
 
 3°. To wage unjust war with a neighbor, is to assume a 
 lower position in the moral scale, and disturb the balance of 
 morality. 
 
 But it can often happen that morality is impossible of ad- 
 justment, unless the wrong-doer accepts the rule of the in- 
 jured party. 
 
 Ergo, consent is of obligation and morally necessary. 
 
 With Regard to the Major: The unjust aggressor indi- 
 rectly chooses the punishment meted out to him, and the 
 nation in the wrong worsted in a conflict of the kind has 
 no ground for complaint, if subjected to the winner's juris- 
 diction. 
 
THESIS XV 
 
 Woman suffrage^ though legitimate in exceptional cases, is 
 fraught with dangers. Jouin, 209-212; Cathrein, 415-419. 
 
 QUESTION 
 
 Family, State and Church are the only complete societies in 
 the world. Society is a moral and lasting union of two or 
 more persons pledged to promote a common aim or purpose. 
 Multitude is matter; moral union or authority, the bond se- 
 curing union, is form. Nature is efficient cause, and this is 
 plain in family, from which nobody can escape. The same 
 is true of state and Church, though the question calls for 
 profounder study. Whatever multitude tallies with the above 
 description is a true society. To be a complete or perfect 
 society, the common aim or purpose must be peculiar and 
 proper to the society in question, outside the domain of other 
 societies, and requisite means must be within the society's 
 reach. Family, state and Church are commonly regarded as 
 complete and perfect, though the family of its very nature 
 grows towards the state, and though state and Church must 
 work together in mutual harmony. Their distinctive domains 
 make them free and independent. They are mutual assist- 
 ance of man and wife, the procreation and education of off- 
 spring; temporal prosperity of people; and spiritual welfare 
 of faithful. This whole question of woman suffrage has to 
 do with the woman's place in the state, and it can be most 
 expeditiously settled by determining her place in the family. 
 Again we pause to define things. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Family is a moral and lasting union of husband, wife and 
 children for mutual assistance, the procreation and educa- 
 
 388 
 
WOMAN SUFFRAGE 389 
 
 tion of offspring. Its main purpose is domestic order and 
 the education of children. 
 
 State is a moral and lasting union primarily of families, 
 secondarily of individuals, banded together for the purpose 
 of safeguarding their rights and securing temporal pros- 
 perity. Its main purpose is the suppression of injustice by 
 law, and the procurement of opportunities for mental, moral 
 and bodily improvement, hard or impossible in family and 
 Church. 
 
 Church is a moral and lasting union of men banded together 
 for purposes of eternal salvation by profession of the same 
 faith, and by participation in the same sacraments, under the 
 rule of duly accredited superiors, especially the Pope of 
 Kome. 
 
 Like everything else, the state has four causes, efficient, 
 final, material and formal. Though the State's material 
 cause, multitude or citizens, is the thing of vital importance 
 in this question of woman suffrage, it will be no waste of 
 time to glance at the other three causes. They furnish 
 Ethics with all the topics discussed in its treatment of civil 
 society or the state. We give only the briefest summary of 
 things. 
 
 Efficient cause is nature, not agreement among men. Op- 
 ponents are Hobbes and Rousseau. Hobbes makes war man's 
 natural condition, men surrendered all to king, absolutism 
 of monarchy. Rousseau makes peace and individualism man's 
 natural condition; people cheated into State, absolutism of 
 democracy. 
 
 Final cause is public prosperity, security in rights, oppor- 
 tunity to improve mind and body beyond private activity. 
 Opponents: Some minimize, coexistence of individual liber- 
 ties; Kant, Fichte, Darwinists. Some exaggerate, public 
 good in itself; Pantheists, Schelling, Hegel. Plato, State a 
 superior man; Leibnitz, Hartmann, Ahrens, culture and civ- 
 ilization. 
 
 Kant's autonomy, despotism, atheistic state; consequences. 
 
 Material cause is people and implicitly territory; not in- 
 dividuals, but families compose state; state supposes family 
 and ministers to its needs; only heads are citizens, men. 
 Others are citizens mediately through head, women and chil- 
 
390 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 dren. Only heads can have part in legislative, executive and 
 judicial functions. Church follows nature. State is organ- 
 ism like plant, made up of heterogeneous, not homogeneous 
 parts. Hence woman suffrage is unnatural and wrong; 
 women are not citizens in immediate sense. Fixed territory 
 is not of essence, but complementary and contributes to per- 
 fection of state. 
 
 Formal cause is authority. Questions: Origin, extent, 
 titles, kinds, functions. 
 
 Extent: morals, religion, Church and state; education, eco- 
 nomic and social matters; Liberalism. 
 
 Titles: inheritance, election, war or conquest, purchase; loss 
 of title. 
 
 Kinds: monarchy, aristocracy, democracy. 
 
 Functions: legislative, executive, judicial. 
 
 Returning now to the state's material cause, or multitude, 
 the family is the seed of the republic. From history it is 
 plain that the first state had its origin in a group of families 
 acknowledging the authority of Adam. His sons settled in 
 his neighborhood, and nature prompted them to do their 
 father this honor. The first state was, therefore, a species of 
 patriarchal government; and can be best described as a per- 
 fect union of several families banded together for the pur- 
 pose of safeguarding their rights and securing their common 
 good. In process of time these families became a village, a 
 town, a city, and country; and the various other titles to 
 authority successively came into play, inheritance, election, 
 conquest and purchase. But all through history states never 
 lost sight of their primary origin. Nature prevented that. 
 They were made up of men, women and children ; but each 
 class had its own fixed function in government. Because 
 the state had its rise in families, not in individuals, the func- 
 tions of man, woman and child in government were settled 
 by the role they played in the family. Children have as 
 much right to claim the suffrage as women, and the average 
 boy is a better politician than his mother. 
 
 Woman's place in the family settles her place in the re- 
 public, and nature is clear about woman's place in the fam- 
 ily. Nature vests parents with power over their children. 
 This power is a necessary consequence from marriage's pur- 
 
STATE FROM FAMILIES 391 
 
 pose, the education of children ; and from the fact that fam- 
 ily is impossible without authority, an essential element of 
 every society. Besides, children get their being and support 
 from their parents, and the circumstance bases a relation 
 of dependence. This power resides in father and mother. 
 One, however, must be first, husband or wife. As a general 
 rule the husband has qualities of mind and body entitling 
 him to the dignity. As compared with the wife, he is less 
 dependent on others, he is more prudent, braver, stronger 
 and firmer. Occasionally a wife surpasses her husband in 
 these respects, but such wives and husbands are exceptions, 
 and in questions of natural ordinances exceptions are neg- 
 lected. The husband chooses the wife, and so starts the fam- 
 ily. The wife is a man's companion, not his slave, nor yet 
 his equal, excepting in her possession of a human nature. 
 Husband and wife ought to work together in mutual har- 
 mony. Home is the wife's proper sphere, her kingdom. The 
 father's power is limited to family's twofold purpose, educa- 
 tion of children and the preservation of domestic order. He 
 is empowered to use the rod, not to mutilate or kill his chil- 
 dren. Education and order can be secured without recourse 
 to the extreme measures legitimately employed by the state. 
 In this matter of paternal authority, nature recognizes three 
 distinct periods in a child 's life : 
 
 Children of unripe and imperfect judgment owe their fa- 
 thers full and entire obedience in every respect, save sin. 
 
 Children of ripe and perfect judgment^ as long as they stay 
 at home, owe their fathers full and entire obedience in matters 
 touching domestic order. 
 
 Children of ripe and perfect judgment, emancipated or 
 married, owe their fathers no obedience, though bound to 
 love, reverence, respect and support them. Man's supremacy 
 in the family is clear from these passages in St. Paul and St. 
 Peter: 
 
 The head of every man is Christ, and the head of the woman 
 is the man. 1 Cor. 11.3. 
 
 Let women be subject to their husbands, as to the Lord. 
 Eph. 5.22. 
 
 Wives, be subject to your husbands as it behooveth in the 
 Lord. Coloss. 3, 18. 
 
392 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 Let wives be subject to their husbands. 1 Peter 3.1. 
 
 And as Catholics we must not disdain borrowing wisdom 
 from the Scriptures. Scripture is word from God, the au- 
 thor of nature; and Scripture is, therefore, a safe source of 
 information regarding natural and unnatural practices. In 
 this sense the law of faith is the law of nature. 
 
 And now to resume, for the purpose of fixing woman's 
 place in the state. The material cause of the state is com- 
 posed not of individuals as such, but of families. Citizens, 
 therefore, are not individuals as such, but heads of families, 
 actually such or such in capacity, men. Women and chil- 
 dren are citizens mediately through husband, and must vote 
 and govern through husband. The State was meant from the 
 start to minister to the needs of the family, not to the needs 
 of the individual as such. Like the human body the state 
 is an organic whole, not made up of individuals on the same 
 footing but of families, and families in turn are made up of 
 husband, wife and children. State supposes the family al- 
 ready constituted and mends its needs. Ergo, not all indi- 
 viduals in the state are citizens, but only family heads, and 
 they alone have capacity to govern, the very essence of citi- 
 zenship according to Aristotle. The state is as much an 
 organism as the human body, and consists of heterogeneous, 
 not homogeneous parts, men, and women and children. The 
 man is the head, the woman is the heart; and the heart must 
 never govern the head. 
 
 This whole question of woman suffrage is only one branch 
 of a larger question, the emancipation of women. The slav- 
 ery of women current with pagans and Turks was long ago 
 abolished by Christianity, and that kind of emancipation is 
 an accomplished fact, though Socialism purposes restoring 
 the old order, and suffragettes are Socialism's helpers. The 
 emancipation, that would make woman man's equal in fam- 
 ily or state, is an utter impossibility, ruled against by nature 
 and destined to forever remain an empty dream, unless the 
 whole world turns monster, and men forget to think. Work 
 away from home for a living is a species of emancipation now 
 on trial, and with certain restrictions it is quite natural and 
 right. Not all women can be wives, because adult women in 
 the world are more numerous than adult men. Some women 
 
POLITICAL EQUALITY 393 
 
 must therefore support themselves. Modem machinery less- 
 ens the value of work at home, and the one remedy is work 
 abroad. As things stand at present, even married women 
 must leave home to help support the family, and the new 
 woman is much to blame for this sad condition of affairs. 
 
 Restrictions: Woman's virtue must not be endangered; 
 time and place can be menaces. Woman's weak strength 
 must not be overtaxed. With the married, care of home must 
 be first consideration. Studies and the professions are a new 
 field open to the activity of women. Medicine is not without 
 its own peculiar dangers for women. Women entering the 
 professions ought to submit to the same tests as men. Co- 
 education is wrong in principle and regularly productive of 
 harm. When woman enters the professions to compete with 
 men, she steps down from her high pedestal. Our thesis, 
 omitting the other phases of emancipation, declares emanci- 
 pation in a political sense unnatural and wrong. Suffrage 
 or the right to vote is the heart of the question. The right to 
 hold office, to act as lawmaker, executive and judge is a 
 logical consequence of the right to suffrage. In a man the 
 right to vote is natural, in virtue of his capacity for headship 
 in the family. In woman the same right is wholly unnat- 
 ural. An unnatural right can be acquired with the conniv- 
 ance of wrong-headed law, and the exercise of every such 
 right is bound to have disastrous consequences. Such conse- 
 quences may be a long or short while working themselves out, 
 but they must eventually show head. 
 
 Liberalism favors woman suffrage ; but, with our knowledge 
 of Liberalism's other wild notions, its advocacy of the cause 
 produces no worry, and strengthens us in our position. The 
 strongest conceivable argument against a theory, is its accept- 
 ance and championship by wrong pholosophy. John Stuart 
 Mill is on the side of woman suffrage, and we know from Utili- 
 tarianism what importance attaches to his opinion. Now and 
 then a Catholic priest or layman raises his voice in its favor. 
 Catholics are, of course, free to take one side or other in the 
 controversy. Our Church has made no doctrinal decision 
 in the matter, even though the spirit of Catholicity revolts at 
 the idea, and all our history is opposed to the practice. The 
 Blessed Virgin Mary is our ideal woman, and nothing in her 
 
394 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 sublime life countenances conduct of the sort. Some of these 
 CathoUcs live in corners of the world where woman suffrage 
 is hy law established, and in these circumstances common 
 wisdom advises Catholic authorities to urge Catholic women 
 to avadl themselves of the unnatural prerogative, and so neu- 
 tralize the harm. It would be decidedly wrong for Catholic 
 women in countries of the kind to allow their wrong-headed 
 sisters to control affairs, and turn the government topsy-turvy. 
 Other Catholic advocates of woman suffrage among clergy 
 and laity are few in number, and, while truth on rare occa- 
 sions fails the majority, it seldom or never rests with the 
 minority. 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 We divide women into (a) married, and (b) single. Our 
 thesis is clear with regard to the married, and only a little 
 less clear with regard to the single. 
 
 (a) (b) We argue from custom. There ought to be no 
 departure from universal custom of long standing without 
 good reason. Woman suffrage is such a departure. Ergo. 
 
 With Regard to the Minor: The reasons alleged assume 
 the shape of objections, and we meet them in our Principles. 
 Reasons against woman suffrage: Women, whether married 
 or single, are not citizens immediately, but through family; 
 and man is head of the family. Wife would be exempt from 
 husband's jurisdiction, quarrels would be multiplied, rights 
 would collide, man's authority would go, and peace would 
 disappear. 
 
 (a) Family would be hurt. Woman's place is home, care 
 of household and children her special charge. Devotion to 
 politics would be as much a duty with women as with men. 
 
 (a) (b) Woman's native modesty would suffer, and pro- 
 priety would be offended. Witness suffragette meetings, 
 parades, campaigns, polls, journeys from home, absence from 
 family. Woman has no head for business of the sort. State 
 affairs are weighty, and call for deep thought and far reaching 
 foresight. Women are proverbially changeable, more open 
 to sentiment than to reason. 
 
 Suffrage is not an inborn right, but a means of govern- 
 ment. Natural has two senses, inborn and becoming. In- 
 
PROOF AND PRINCIPLES 395 
 
 bom in neither man nor woman ; becoming in man, unbecom- 
 ing in woman. It is an acquired right even in man. It is 
 a question of expediency, of the proper. Not that woman is 
 inferior to man, but different from man. Men adapted by 
 nature to some functions, women to others. Hurts woman, 
 politics is modified war, strife, contention, bitterness. Duty 
 and right of protection rest with the male. True government 
 in family.- Woman's true functions superior to man's, to 
 form conscience of child, influence will, control impulses. 
 Cardinal Gibbons says: ''Mary model of women, not Ama- 
 zon, not Spartan, not Venus, not Juno. ' ' Spiritually, woman 
 is same as man. Equal rights, not similar rights. Suffrage 
 alienates from home. To debar woman from vote is not to 
 degrade, to restrict her to home is not to fetter her aspira- 
 tions to higher and better things. Home is more a factor in 
 republic than court or congress. Mothers mould presidents, 
 legislators and judges; woman's noblest work is to care for 
 children. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. "Women have same right as men to good government. 
 Ergo, right to suffrage and office. 
 
 Answer: Argument proves too much. Infants have same 
 right. Pure democracy would be only legitimate rule. Right 
 to be well governed is different from right to govern. Woman 
 suffrage would be worst government in world, because un- 
 natural and wrong. 
 
 B. Women are burdened with taxes and other obligations 
 same as men. Ergo. 
 
 Answer: Equality of burdens is different from equality 
 of rights. Women are not soldiers, sailors. Women are in- 
 dependent and sui juris by accident. They ought to be mem- 
 bers of a family and subject to its head. Exceptions never 
 count in ethics. 
 
 C. Women have been queens. Ergo. 
 
 Ansiver: Cases are rare and exceptional, and happen 
 without harm to family. Women queens for common good, 
 to keep succession in family and smother ambition. Queens 
 govern through men. 
 
396 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 D. No argument against voting for candidate sel( 
 men. Ergo, suffrage at least. 
 
 Answer: Suffrage means universal rights of citizenship. 
 With suffrage women could extend privilege to selection of 
 candidates and every other function of government. 
 
 E. Women make good doctors, lawyers, managers. Ergo, 
 they can vote. 
 
 Answers Nothing follows. Professions are different from 
 suffrage. In the professions men make contracts with them, 
 and are content to use their services. Universal suffrage is 
 different and open to blame ; it is unnatural and wrong. 
 
 F. Unclean houses, impure food, risk of disease, immorality 
 on street, bad plumbing, fire escapes. 
 
 Answer: Woman must leave something for the man to do. 
 If she is much away from home, the house must take care of 
 itself, or the man must turn housekeeper. In her eyes the 
 man, with no care of home to distract him, is unable to regu- 
 late outside conditions. Will she be able to manage things 
 inside and outside? Division of labor. Let her urge the 
 husband to manage neighbors, grocers, plumbers, inspectors, 
 policemen. Men are responsible for outside abuses, only when 
 women stay at home and mind their own concerns. Every 
 woman has her own house to care for. No woman is house- 
 keeper to the city. Men are the city's housekeepers, its citi- 
 zens. 
 
 G. Women are eitizens, mediately, not immediately; and 
 they ought to do their civic duty mediately through men. In 
 civic matters women must be protected by the men. Men 
 have the interests of their mothers, sisters, wives and daugh- 
 ters at heart. Men must regulate the city's sanitary condi- 
 tions, not women. Men are as much opposed to unsanitary 
 conditions as women. Men are as fond of their children as 
 women. Other and better ways than woman suffrage to 
 remedy abuses, more natural, less damaging. Independent 
 women are exceptional; no father, no brother, no husband, 
 no son. 
 
 H. No taxation without representation. 
 
 Answer: Representation is possible without vote. Heads 
 of families represent women. Representation is not personal 
 and immediate management. The colonists never wanted to 
 
PRINCIPLES 397 
 
 enter parliament and vote. They wanted an agent on the 
 ground to present their views. Women have such agents in 
 men. Nature, not election, fixes their agents. Men who im- 
 posed taxes on colonies did not have to pay them. Men who 
 impose taxes on women have to pay them. 
 
 The above principle is per se wrong. In case of law or 
 custom it can happen to be right; and this is true of Eng- 
 land. 
 
 I. Woman must help man in civic matters by her advice, 
 not by ballot. Suffrage is none of her civic duties. 
 
THESIS XVI 
 
 The State enjoys full Legislative, Executive and Judicial 
 rights, the prerogative of Eminent Domain and the War 
 Power. Jouin, 265-284; 351-362; Bickahy, 338-355. 
 
 DIVISION 
 
 Three Parts. I, Legislative, Executive, Jud/icial; II, Do- 
 main; III, War Power. 
 
 I. Legislative, Executive, Judicial. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Legislative rights are the power to make laws and fix penal- 
 ties in general. 
 
 Executive rights are the power to enforce laws, to punish 
 and pardon. 
 
 Judicial rights are the power to decide between right and 
 wrong, and fix penalties in particular. 
 
 Judicial rights are civil and criminal. 
 
 Civil, to render decision in civil suits, determine to which 
 of two parties a right belongs. 
 
 Criminal, to render decision in criminal cases, determine 
 the nature of a fact at variance with law, and settle the pen- 
 alty. 
 
 Penalty is the pain or privation inflicted on the criminal 
 to avenge the wrong done law, and establish anew the dis- 
 turbed reign of justice. In wrong might does violence to 
 right; in punishment right asserts its supremacy, and brings 
 might to grief. 
 
 Punishment ought to be, as far as possible, reparative, me- 
 dicinal, corrective. 
 
 Reparative is calculated to mend disturbed relations and 
 reestablish order. 
 
 Medicinal is calculated to cure men and reform them. 
 
 Corrective is calcuJated to act as a deterrent from evD. 
 
 398 
 
LEGISLATIVE, JUDICIAL, EXECUTIVE 399 
 
 PROOF 
 
 All three rights are necessary means to state's end or pur- 
 pose. Confusion would reign in state without Legislative. 
 Legislative would be a dead letter without Executive and 
 Judicial. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. For three reasons Aristotle thinks it better to rule by 
 written laws than by judge merely. 
 
 1°. Fewer wise men are needed. A few lawmakers would 
 be enough, many judges would be needed. 
 
 2°. Lawmakers have plenty of time to study and reflect; 
 judges must decide in a hurry. 
 
 3°. Lawmakers deal with future and universal contingen- 
 cies; judges, with present facts and particular cases. No 
 chance for greed, hatred, anger, revenge with lawmaker; 
 judges, open to all these emotions. 
 
 B. Rules for lawmakers: 1°. Let your laws be as few in 
 number as possible. 2°. An unjust law is no law. 3°. An 
 impossible law is no law. 
 
 C. Capital punishment is just : 
 
 1°. Right to amputate limb that threatens harm to whole 
 body. S.T.2.2.q.64.a.2. State is the body, a bad citizen, like 
 a murderer, is such a limb. Ergo. 
 
 2°. Right to inflict penalty in proportion with harm done 
 or attempted, e.g., treason, arson, murder. 
 
 3°. All civilized peoples, God Himself in laws of Hebrews, 
 sanction capital punishment, e.g., Exodus 22.18. Wizards 
 thou shalt not suffer to live. Ps. 100.8, In the morning I put 
 to death all the wicked of the land. David. 
 
 4°. It is lawful to kill animals for man's use. By abuse 
 of free will, the criminal virtually though not formally loses 
 the dignity of a man, descends to the low level of an animal, 
 and ceases to be sui juris. 
 
 5°. God takes life when state takes life, because God arms 
 state with the prerogative. 
 
SPECIAL ETHICS 
 II. Eminent Domain. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 Eminent Domain means power to make whatever use of 
 citizens' property the existence and welfare of the govern- 
 ment demand. Hobbes vests in the state thorough ownership 
 of its citizens' goods. He makes citizens, viewed as pro- 
 prietors, like sons with regard to their father. Sons have no 
 ownership against father, citizens have none against state. 
 Hobbes is wrong, ^' because state can claim only what is neces- 
 sary, and mere use without full ownership is sufficient ; ^' be- 
 cause state-ownership of everything would create indiffer- 
 ence, and hurt prosperity and progress ; ^' because the state 
 is altogether different from the family; citizens get only 
 well-being from the state; sons get being from their father; 
 citizens are less dependent on the state than sons are on their 
 father. 
 
 PROOF 
 
 State enjoys Eminent Domain, because it is a means neces- 
 sary to the state's end and a means not otherwise available. 
 
 PRINCIPLES 
 
 A. Taxes are contributions made the state by citizens or 
 subjects to advance common interests and defray public ex- 
 penses. Instances are property tax, customs, revenues, per- 
 sonal tax and the like. 
 
 B. State is vested with the right to impose taxes, 1°, be- 
 cause they are necessary means to state's end; without taxes 
 revenue would be uncertain and precarious, while debts would 
 be fixed, certain and steady; 2°, because citizens ought to pay 
 for advantages the state secures to them. 
 
 C. Only the supreme power in the state can lawfully im- 
 pose taxes, 1°, because means belong to him alone, who pro- 
 cures end; 2°, because private citizens would otherwise enjoy 
 others' goods. 
 
 D. This power is limited to strict necessity, because other- 
 wise a perversion and abuse of means. 
 
WAR AND SEDITION 401 
 
 E. No taxation without representation. Per se, this saying 
 is wrong. Per aecidens, in case of law or custom it can be 
 right. Charles I and Parliament. American Colonies and 
 England. 
 
 III. War Power. Four parts, a, 1), c, d. 
 
 a. War Power vested in state extends to offensive as well as 
 defensive war. 
 
 b. Right to declare war is prerogative of supreme power. 
 e. Sedition is intrinsically wrong. 
 
 d. Precautions before, during and after war. 
 
 TERMS 
 
 War Power is power to protect the commonwealth against 
 enemies. 
 
 War is state or condition of nations forcibly contending for 
 right. 
 
 Defensive war is war waged to keep off an enemy. Offen- 
 sive war is war waged to avenge wrong and establish security. 
 
 N.B. War without any real or apparent right is murder. 
 
 Sedition is a rising in arms as between people and ruler, or 
 as between factions among the people. 
 
 N.B. The belligerency of rebels is recognised only after 
 they have by certain signs proved themselves capable of au- 
 tonomy. International law is obscure and unsettled on this 
 point. 
 
 Sedition is offensive warfare of people against legitimate 
 ruler. Two kinds of tyranny are of rule and of title. 
 
 Tyranny of rule is abuse of power, title intact ; and it is no 
 legitimate excuse for offensive warfare, which would be sedi- 
 tion. 
 
 N.B. It is legitimate excuse for defensive, if ruler attacks, 
 because citizens have same rights as individuals. 
 
 Tyranny of title or right means no title, no legitimate ruler ; 
 and it is legitimate excuse for offensive warfare, which is 
 then no sedition. Tyranny of rule leads to loss of title, with- 
 out being actual forfeiture. 
 
402 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 PROOFS 
 
 a. Defensive war: 
 1°. Nations enjoy rights of individuals and self-defense is 
 
 a personal right. 
 
 2°. Often it is the only means of securing safety to the re- 
 public. 
 
 Offensive War: 
 
 1°. Justice among nations is necessary. Otherwise natural 
 law as between nations would be without sanction ; no future 
 life for nations; international law of no force, because na- 
 tions are sovereign. Often war is only available means; or- 
 der must be reestablished by its violators or by the wronged. 
 
 2°. Safety insecure, if defensive war is alone legitimate; 
 wrongs could never be repaired; wicked would prosper and 
 grow in power after each attack. 
 
 3°. Enemy must often be attacked in midst of preparations ; 
 otherwise defeat is certain. 
 
 b. War is prerogative of supreme power. Order demands 
 as much. 
 
 1°. If private citizens exercised war prerogative, nations 
 would be kept busy settling feuds and personal quarrels. 
 
 2°. Individuals are prone to exaggerate their petty griev- 
 ances. 
 
 3°. Jurisdiction over people belongs to ruler, not to indi- 
 viduals ; call for volunteers belongs to supreme power. 
 
 c. Sedition is intrinsically wrong. 
 
 1°. Against common good; it attacks the very form of so- 
 ciety, authority. 
 
 2°. Done without right; war prerogative belongs to ruler. 
 
 N.B. Same arguments hold for factions. Defensive war 
 is not wrong — because subjects have same rights as individ- 
 uals. 
 
 d. Precautions before, during and after war. 
 
 Before war, three things, 1°. Grave and just cause. 2°. 
 Just motive. 3°. Probable success. 
 1°. Some grave and just causes: 
 Puff endorf mentions : 
 
WAR AND PRECAUTIONS 403 
 
 1. Protection of self and property against attempts at in- 
 jury and destruction; 
 
 2. Insistence on clear rights denied by others ; 
 
 3. Recompense for wrongs suffered at the hands of an 
 enemy ; 
 
 4. Demand of pledges against future insult and injury. 
 Suarez mentions: 
 
 1. A nation 's refusal to observe the common law of nations. 
 N.B. Refusal to promote commerce is no good excuse. 
 
 2. Serious wrong done a nation 's reputation and good name. 
 N.B. Indignity done an ambassador. 
 
 3. Danger threatening an allied nation, when that nation 
 has a right to wage war and intends to do so. 
 
 Some iveak and insufficient reasons: 
 
 1. Suspicions founded on no external facts, and wholly des- 
 titute of moral certainty. 
 
 2. Violations of natural law perpetrated at home, with citi- 
 zens for victims. 
 
 3. Monarch's religion, if without oppression and tyranny. 
 
 4. Zeal for true religion and progress of civilization. 
 
 5. Desire to seat a certain family on throne, even to the 
 advantage of other nations. 
 
 2°. Motive must he right — Suarez assigns two. a, to maJ^e 
 good injuries done by another, and b, to punish offenders. 
 If offender stands ready to make satisfaction, war is out of 
 the question. 
 
 N.B. The ruler of the wronged republic fixes the penalty. 
 
 3°. Hope of success — Necessary for offensive war, of less 
 moment for defensive. Reason is evident. Otherwise nation 
 would be exposed to certain danger. 
 
 Precautions during war: 
 
 1. Plots are legitimate; lies and violations of treaties are 
 not legitimate. Plots involving lies are wrong. Deception 
 is quite possible without a lie. 
 
 2. International law must be respected. 
 
 3. The innocent must never suffer direct injury, indirect 
 injury can be legitimate. 
 
 4. Evils not calculated to help along the cause must be 
 avoided. 
 
404 
 
 SPECIAL ETHICS 
 
 5. Poisoning of water, death by treachery and the like are 
 forbidden by international law. 
 
 Precautions after war: 
 
 By strict right the winner can inflict on the loser whatever 
 punishment is necessary to repair his losses, secure himself 
 against the recurrence of difficulties, and establish himself in 
 peace. The instinct of Christianity has done much to moder- 
 ate the cruelties formerly practised in the name of strict 
 right. Certainly the victor is not now allowed to slay the 
 defenseless or sell captives. The law of nations sets salutary 
 limits to the right of conquest. 
 
 THE END 
 
INDEX 
 
 Abhorrence, 84. 
 
 Abraham, and Isaac, and murder, 
 52. 
 
 Abraham, and Lot, and ownership, 
 252. 
 
 Absence of pain and sorrow, 39. 
 
 Absolute ownership, 247. 
 
 Absolutism, 58. 
 
 Abstract ownership, 251, 258. 
 
 Acquired desire, 21. 
 
 Acts good and bad in themselves, 
 160, 161. 
 
 Adam and Eve and ownership, 251, 
 252. 
 
 Aequiprobabilism, 102. 
 
 Agents, three classes, 10. 
 
 Ahrens, on worship, 185. 
 
 Allen, on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Alphonsus, St., on probabilism, 
 102, 107; on reservation, 237, 
 240 
 
 Altruism, 154, 155; and ethical 
 end of life, 159. 
 
 American duels, 212. 
 
 Appetite, sensitive and rational, 
 81, 82. 
 
 Aristippus and Hedonism, 168. 
 
 Aristotle and happiness, 21, 23, 
 24; on virtues, 112; on habits, 
 110; on prudence, 114; on art, 
 114; on pleasure, 157. 
 
 Augustine, St., on happiness, 20; 
 on religion, 178. 
 
 Austin, 152. 
 
 Authority, 371-388; two questions, 
 origin and recipient, 371; imme- 
 diate by positive divine law and 
 by law of nature, 372; Scholas- 
 tics on recipient, 372; four sys- 
 tems on recipient, 374; Moses, 
 Aaron and Pope, 371; parents 
 and rulers, 372; multitude not 
 recipient, 372, 380; James I, 
 373; Taparelli, 374, 384, 386; 
 Scholastics in general, 374, 375, 
 376; Hobbes and Rousseau, 377; 
 in multitude in root, 383; mul- 
 
 405 
 
 titude unfitted to exercise, 380. 
 
 Autonomy of Reason, 170-175; 
 Kant's categorical imperative is 
 subjective, 171, 172; autonomy 
 of will as opposed to heteron- 
 omy, 172. 
 
 Averling, Dr., 274, 276. 
 
 Bain on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Ballerini, on interest, 148. 
 
 Barter, 147. 
 
 Basic truths, 5, 6. 
 
 Bax, 274, 276. 
 
 Beatific vision, 21. 
 
 Bebel, 274, 275. 
 
 Becoming, agreeable, useful good, 
 155. 
 
 Bellarmine, on authority, 380. 
 
 Bentham, 152; on ownership, 254. 
 
 Blackburn, on contracts, 139. 
 
 Blamelessness and blessedness, 3. 
 
 Boethius, on happiness, 19, 20. 
 
 Bonum ex Integra causa, 74, 94. 
 
 Bouquillon, Dr., on education, 351; 
 his argument, 355; and history, 
 356; and authority, 357. 
 
 Brown, W. T., 273. 
 
 Butler, 152; 168. 
 
 Buying and selling, 137, 140. 
 
 Cabet, and colony, 253. 
 
 Capital Sins, Seven, 113. 
 
 Capital, a natural right, 241 ;| 
 permanent ownership, 248; with 
 Socialism, 261; in olden times, 
 144. 
 
 Categorical imperative, 38; of 
 Kant, 170; subjective, 171; 
 natural law, the one true, 172. 
 
 Catholic Church, and celibacy, 301, 
 302; recognizes no complete di- 
 vorce, 336. 
 
 Catholic country and mixed, 200; 
 and Protestant, 200. 
 
406 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Catholicity, more rational than 
 Rationalism, 4. 
 
 Cathrein, on contracts, 140. 
 
 Cause, definition and division of, 
 11; eflficient and final, 12. 
 
 Celibacy, 300-311; definition, 300; 
 and virginity, 300; more excel- 
 lent than marriage, Trent, 306, 
 307, 308; clerical, 301; in East 
 and West, 302, 303; Elvira, 
 Nice, Paphnutius, Pope Sirieius, 
 and Tours, 302 ; and Luther, 303, 
 307; and St. Thomas, 309; and 
 St. Paul, 308, 310; increase and 
 multiply, 310; Jovinian and St. 
 Jerome, 307; good in order of 
 virtue, 308 ; virtuous and wicked, 
 303, 306; heroism and influence, 
 298; with Greeks and Romans, 
 303; Vestals, 303, 308; Trent, 
 on, 306; apostolic labors, 301; 
 modern, 304. 
 
 Certainty, objective and subjective, 
 76; kinds, 103. 
 
 Chance, and Epicurus, 9. 
 
 Character and Habits, 122-127. 
 
 Character, 122; temperament and 
 habits, 122; and parents, 122; 
 and free will, 122. 
 
 Cicero, on religion, 178, 197; on 
 suicide, 206. 
 
 Circumstances, 73, 74, 75, 96. 
 
 Citizen, man immediately, woman 
 and child mediately, 389, 394; 
 Aristotle on, 392. 
 
 Civil law, and natural rights, 130; 
 without natural law, 131, 132; 
 division of, 135; definition of, 
 44, 54; requisite conditions of, 
 57, 58. 
 
 Clement VII, Pope, and Henry 
 VIII, 322. 
 
 Conmiunism, 241, 243; restricted, 
 243; Fourier, Owen, Cabet, and 
 colonies, 253. 
 
 Commutative, distributive, legal 
 justice, 115, 116, 117, 149. 
 
 Complete happiness, definition, 19 ; 
 a natural desire, 20, 22; pos- 
 sible of fulfilment, 21, 23; pos- 
 session of God, 20, 21, 22, 24; 
 last in series of wish-factors, 
 18; implicit and explicit influ- 
 ence of, 22; objectively and sub- 
 
 jectively taken, 20; no created 
 good, 21, 23, 24. 
 
 Compulsory education, 347, 348, 
 350. 
 
 Condition is no cause, 12. 
 
 Conscience, and subjective moral- 
 ity, 76; and kinds, 104, 105, 
 106; and objective order, 104. 
 
 Consent of governed, 374, 377; no 
 authority without, 386; deter- 
 mines ruler, 386; in monarchy, 
 in conquest, 385; morally neces- 
 sary, is physically free, 384; 
 kinds of consent, 385, 387; in 
 patriarchal state, 385; St. Chry- 
 sostom on, 386. 
 
 Contracts, and quasi-contracts, 137, 
 138. 
 
 Contracts, 137-144; unilateral and 
 bilateral, 137; gratuitous and 
 onerous, 140; buying and sell- 
 ing, 140, 137 ; causes and condi- 
 tions in, 140; consent, mistake, 
 violence, fear, 138; quasi-con- 
 tracts, 138; Savigny, Pollock, 
 Blackburn, Holland on, 139; 
 Cathrein on division of, 140. 
 
 Control, and character, 124; and 
 family discipline, 125; and high 
 ideals, 125; Horace on, 125. 
 
 Costa-Rossetti, on common owner- 
 ship, 249; on strictly natural 
 society, 362. 
 
 Courts and duel, 223. 
 
 Cranmer and lie, 233. 
 
 Cronin, on Stoic Formalism and 
 Hedonism, 167, 168. 
 
 Cudworth, 152, 168. 
 
 D 
 
 Deliberate and intentional, 7. 
 
 Deliberate acts, 13. 
 
 Delight, 84. 
 
 Dependence, extrinsic and intrinsic, 
 81. 
 
 Descartes, on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Desire, 84; psychical, 84; knowl- 
 edge measures, 22; not accom- 
 plishment, 21; natural, two 
 kinds, 20. 
 
 Despair, 84. 
 
 Despotism and law, 58. 
 
 Destiny in this life, 28-33 ; 36, 37 ; 
 
INDEX 
 
 407 
 
 incomplete happiness, virtue, 28 ; 
 definition, 30; three qualities, 
 36. 
 
 Determinism, 82. 
 
 Dictates of reason, 38. 
 
 Diogenes, 154; and celibacy, 304. 
 
 Displeasure, 84. 
 
 Divorce, 318-342; definition, 319; 
 complete, a vinculo; incomplete, 
 a mensa et toro, 320 ; in history, 
 320, 321, 322, 323, 324, 325; 
 Catholic Church, against com- 
 plete, 322, 327; grounds for law 
 against, 318; Deuteronomy, 320; 
 schools of Schamai and Hillel, 
 320, 334; Old Law and New, 
 321; with Protestants Christ 
 never changed Old Law, 334 ; St. 
 Paul condemns complete, 335; 
 Catholic judges and lawyers, 
 336; unhappy couples, 337; 
 strict natural law, and second- 
 ary law of nature, 339, 340, 341 ; 
 and Scripture, 328, 329,, 330, 
 331, 332, 333, 334, 335; New 
 England polygamy, 324, 325; 
 Caesar, Pompey, Cicero, 321; 
 adultery, no cause for complete, 
 justifies incomplete, 329; St. 
 Mark and St. Luke clearly 
 against, 329 ; wrote for Gentiles, 
 333; in Scripture clear passages 
 explain obscure, not vice-versa, 
 334. 
 
 Divorce-laws, wrong, encourage 
 crime, 319, 326; in different 
 States, 323, 324. 
 
 Doubt, and its qualities, 107, 108. 
 
 Doubtful law has no binding force, 
 lOG. 
 
 Duel, 210-214; 216-218; 222-225; 
 in history, 210; barbarians, 211; 
 in France, in America, 211, 212; 
 false notions, 212; in modern 
 times, 213; prize-fight, 213; 
 wrong means, 216, 217; Lom- 
 bards, Greeks, Romans, 216; su- 
 perstition, revenge, courts, 217; 
 innocent and guilty equal, 217; 
 murder and suicide, 217; de- 
 fense of property, 222 ; challenge 
 and cowardice, 213; honor, 224. 
 
 Dunzi, on worship, 185. 
 
 Duty, 127, 128; definition, 182; to 
 
 God, 201; to self, 202; religion, 
 firsi: and essential, 183, 184, 191, 
 192; to accept revelation, 192, 
 193; to seek revelation, 194; rea- 
 son manifests, never makes, 196 ; 
 of prayer, 197; one religion for 
 all, 188, 189, 194, 198; results 
 from relation, 175; for duty's 
 sake, 166, 167. 
 
 E 
 
 Education of Child, 342-358; duty 
 and right of parents prior to 
 state's; duty and right of state, 
 when parents fail, 342; parents, 
 not parients, 343; instruction, 
 not mere information, it con- 
 notes obedience, 343; obedience 
 to parents first, 344 ; family prior 
 to state, 344; signs that God 
 appointed parents educators, 
 345 ; God never exempts parents, 
 345; state must safeguard, not 
 absorb independent rights, 346; 
 state's right to educate, indirect, 
 346, 347 ; functions of education, 
 346 ; Rousseau, and young child, 
 and God, 346; monopoly of, and 
 compulsory, 347, 348, 349; 
 Church and, 349, 350, 351, 354; 
 state and, 350, 351; state with 
 and without Church, 351, 352, 
 353; state and common good, 
 355; Bouquillon and Holaind, 
 on, 351-358; Costa-Rossetti, 
 Jansen, Hammerstein, on, 356; 
 without consent of parents, il- 
 legitimate, 355. 
 
 Eight Beatitudes and happiness, 
 19. 
 
 Elicited and ordered acts, 78. 
 
 Emancipation of mankind, 1. 
 
 Eminent Domain, 400. 
 
 Employer and Workman, 280-289; 
 labor-problem and Church, its 
 solution, 280; rights and duties 
 of, 281, 283, 284; contract, root 
 of trouble, 141, 281; reasons for 
 troubles, 282; wrong remedies, 
 socialism, liberalism, malthusi- 
 anism, 282; right remedy, union 
 between both, 283; exaggerated 
 
•40« 
 
 INDEX 
 
 individualism, 283; wives and 
 children, 284. 
 
 End, definition and division of, 10, 
 11; a cause, 7, 11, 15; last end 
 and deliberate act, 7, 13, 14, 15; 
 and intention, 7 ; and destiny, 
 9; absolutely and relatively last, 
 10, 15, 16; proximate and inter- 
 mediate, 1 1 ; which, for which, 
 in which, 11; of doer and of 
 deed, operis and operantis, 11, 
 74, 75, 76 ; every effect is agent's 
 end, 15; end contributes more 
 than saw or hammer to house, 
 15; mediate and immediate in- 
 fluence of, 15 ; never justifies 
 bad means, 17, 99; efficacy, 
 moral, not physical, 17; an ef- 
 fect, in order of execution, 17; a 
 determinant of morality, 162; in 
 Scripture, 163. 
 
 Engels, F., 275. 
 
 Epicurus, and finality, 9; and 
 chance, 9; and happiness, 21, 
 23, 154. 
 
 Epikeia, or equity, 118, 149. 
 
 Equality of men, 265; of man and 
 woman, natural, domestic, in- 
 dustrial, political, 392. 
 
 Essential difference, and accidental, 
 34, 35, 37. 
 
 Ethics, definition of, 1 ; important, 
 1; practical, 2; division of, 3, 
 4; novelties in, 2. 
 
 Ethical Duty, self-imposed, 164, 
 165. 
 
 Ethic and Nomology of Kant, 133, 
 134, 165. 
 
 Evolution, materialistic, 265, 266, 
 267. 
 
 Extrinsic glory of God, 151. 
 
 Faith, and pagans, 179. 
 
 Family, woman's place in state set- 
 tled by woman's place in, 390; 
 parents and children in, 391; 
 Scripture on, 391. 
 
 Fear, and kinds, 90. 
 
 Ferri, 275. 
 
 Finality, 8, 9; Epicurus, and, 9. 
 
 Finis operis and operantis, 75, 96. 
 
 Formally, eminently, virtually, 25. 
 
 Fortitude, 118; Cicero, on, 118. 
 Fourier and colony, 253. 
 Freedom of will, 85, 86, 87; from 
 
 necessity and from violence, 86. 
 Free will, 6. 
 Freemasons, unnatural society, 
 
 362. 
 
 George, Henry on ownership, 254; 
 on Land-Socialism, 270, 271, 272. 
 
 Gibbons, Cardinal; Mary, model 
 of women, 395. 
 
 God; existence, dominion, 6; im- 
 plicitly last end of every wish, 
 16; laiown whole, not wholly, 
 26; not a means, 26, 167; alone 
 able to fill mind, 25; as material 
 and formal object of mind, 27; 
 wisdom and goodness of, 36; 
 a noumenon, ruled out by Kant, 
 172. 
 
 Good and evil, distinguishable, 30; 
 difference between. 34, 35, 36, 
 37; good and kinds, 155, 156. 
 
 Greatest Happiness; virtue, not 
 pleasure, 153, 154, 168; knowl- 
 edge clear of pleasure, 159; not 
 Altruism, 159, 169; Christ and 
 martyrs, 164. 
 
 Greeks Vnd duel, 210, 216. 
 
 Grote, 152. 
 
 Grotius, on lie, 228; on ownership, 
 254. 
 
 Habit, with Aristotle, 110; with 
 Suarez, 111. 
 
 Hamilton, on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Hammerstein, on education, 357. 
 
 Happiness, man's search, 3. 
 
 Harm and injury, different, 163. 
 
 Harmony and discord with ob- 
 jective order, 37, 38. 
 
 flartmann, on standard, 34. 
 
 Hate, 84. 
 
 Head, servant to heart, 2. 
 
 Hedonism, 153, 154, 155, Cronin 
 on, 168; St. Thomas, on, 168; 
 Hobbes and Aristippus on, 168. 
 
 Hegel, on standard, 34; on law, 58. 
 
 Hell, compatible with God's good- 
 
INDEX 
 
 409 
 
 ness, 63, 64; no imperfect mo- 
 tive, 68; proportion with sin, 
 68; and natural law, 166. 
 
 Herron, G. D., 273, 276. 
 
 Heyne, on ownership, 254. 
 
 Hobbes, on standard, 34; on law, 
 58; on Hedonism, 168; on state, 
 359, 364, 365; on authority, 377; 
 on ownership, 254. 
 
 Holaind, on education, 351, 352, 
 353, 354. 
 
 Holland, on right, 128; on natural 
 law, 132, on theology, 133; on 
 contracts, 139. 
 
 Hope, 84. 
 
 Human acts and their elements, 
 13. 
 
 Ignorance, and kinds, 89; vincible, 
 invincible, 32. 
 
 Incomplete Happiness, virtue, 20, 
 28, 29. 
 
 Inditi'erentism, 199. 
 
 Individual ownership, 248; God 
 and nature want, 250, 256, 257; 
 potential and actual, 250; for- 
 mal compact and law, 253; not 
 from law, 254, 255 ; from nature, 
 256, 257; and Christianity, 267. 
 
 Individualism and Utilitarianism, 
 161. 
 
 Intensity and extent, 25, 28. 
 
 Intention, kinds, 17, 88. 
 
 Intentional and deliberate, 7. 
 
 Interest, 144-149; a loan, 144; St. 
 Thomas on, 144, 148; titles to, 
 extrinsic, 145; intrinsic, 146; 
 law regulates rates, nature gives 
 right, 146; Ballerini on, 148; 
 and Church, 140. 
 
 Intrinsic diflFerence and extrinsic, 
 34, 37. 
 
 James I, on authority, 373. 
 Jansen, on education, 356. 
 Jerome, St., on celibacy, 307. 
 Jovinian, and celibacy, 307. 
 Judaism and Christianity, 198. 
 Juridical Positivism, 130, 131, 132. 
 Juridical rights and ethical, 131. 
 
 Justice, 115; St. Thomas, on, 115, 
 
 116, 117, 118; commutative, 116, 
 
 117, 118; distributive 116, 117, 
 118; legal, 116, 117, 118; Cicero 
 on, 118; and kinds, 149. 
 
 K 
 
 Kant, and categorical imperative, 
 38; and autonomy of reason, 
 170-175, 62; and Stoic Formal- 
 ism, 164, 165, 166; and coexist- 
 ence of individual liberties, 366, 
 367; on moral obligation, 38; 
 reason, its own law, 42; sanc- 
 tion of natural law, 42; philo- 
 sophic sin, 42; on juridical 
 rights and ethical, 131; on 
 Ethic and homology, 133, 134; 
 on preceptive rights and do- 
 minion rights, 134, on pleasure, 
 158; on prayer, 197. 
 
 Kemmerichius, on worship, 185. 
 
 Knabenbauer, on divorce, 328. 
 
 Labor-problem, and Church-plan, 
 140, 141; charity and justice in, 
 142. 
 
 Labor-unions, 286, 287. 
 
 Lactantius, on religion, 178. 
 
 Lambert, on standard, 34. 
 
 Last end, first cause, 15. 
 
 Last extrinsic and intrinsic end, 9. 
 
 Law, diagram and definitions, 43, 
 44, strict and wide sense, 43, 44 ; 
 its causes, 44; in doubt, 44, 45; 
 not precept, 45; promulgation, 
 45; ignorance no excuse, 45; 
 divine, 45 ; human, 45 ; eternal, 
 45 ; natural, 46-53 ; positive 
 divine, 53, 54 ; ecclesiastical, 54 ; 
 civil, 54; differences between 
 positive divine and natural, 53, 
 54; matter and form, 57; re- 
 sistance to unjust law, 59; Des- 
 potism and Absolutism, 58; law- 
 maker, 45 ; necessity of, 42 ; law 
 and conscience, 43, 59; natural 
 and positive. 64, 65. 
 
 Law of General Consequences, 152, 
 IGl. 
 
 Laxism, 101. 
 
410 
 
 INDEX 
 
 Leatham, J., 274. 
 
 Leo XIII, Pope, Encyclical on La- 
 bor, synopsis, 276-280. 
 
 Legislative, judicial, executive, 398. 
 
 Leibnitz, on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Liberalism, 199. 
 
 Lie, 225-233; definition, 225; St. 
 Thomas on deception in, 226, 
 227; material and formal, 226; 
 abuse of speech, and malice of, 
 228, 238; Grotius on, 228: Mil- 
 ton on, 229 ; privation of truth 
 due, 229; procuring good, 231; 
 for few grave reasons, 231 ; 
 homicide and lie, 231 ; no mortal 
 sin, 232. 
 
 Liebnecht, 275. 
 
 Life, present and future, 36; a 
 responsibility, 203, 219; for 
 God's glory,^203. 
 
 Living wage, 142, 143. 
 
 Loan, and kinds, 144. 
 
 Lombards and duel, 216. 
 
 Love, 84; love and beauty, Lacor- 
 daire on, 294, 295. 
 
 Luther and good works, 179; and 
 celibacy, 303, 307. 
 
 Lynching, wrong, 34. 
 
 M 
 
 Machiavelli, on law, 58. 
 
 Maher, on feeling, 156; on pleasure 
 and pain, 157. 
 
 Man, the microcosm, 81. 
 
 Mansel, and divorce, 328. 
 
 Marriage, 289-300; act and state, 
 291; plan of Creator, 292, 297; 
 man and woman, 292, 297; right 
 increase of race, 298; friendli- 
 ness and love, 294; with Catho- 
 lics, 296; honorable, 296, 297, 
 298; not preferable to celibacy, 
 Trent, 296; Scripture for, 299; 
 Rickaby, 299; Manichees and, 
 296; St. Paul on, 297; and 
 woman, 304, 305; and the pro- 
 fessions, 305; Fenelon on, 306; 
 evils are but accidents, 306 ; im- 
 pediments invalidating and hin- 
 dering, 327, 328; dispensations, 
 328; Church must manage, not 
 politicians and lawyers, 318; 
 
 hurt by divorce in four particu- 
 lars, 340, 341. 
 
 Marx, Karl, 260 ; values, 260, 264 ; 
 atheist, 274. 
 
 Matthew, St., seven interpreta- 
 tions of, 19, 9; 329, 330, 331, 
 332; wrote for Hebrews, 333. 
 
 Means, 17. 
 
 Mental Reservation, 233-241 ; se- 
 crets to keep, 233, 239 ; pure and 
 broad, 232, 233, 238, 239; not 
 guilty, not at home, 235, 238 ; 
 Cranmer, 233; priest, lawj-er, 
 doctor, 235, 236; evasions, 
 equivocations, 236, 237; unkind- 
 ness of, 234; St. Alphonsus on, 
 237, 240; effect of, 238; no abuse 
 of language, 238. 
 
 Merit and Demerit, 149-152; im- 
 putability and freedom, 150; 
 with God, with men, de con- 
 digno, 150, 151; subjective 
 morality and, 32. 
 
 Meyer, on natural law, 50; on 
 sanction, 56. 
 
 Midwives of Israel, and theft, 51. 
 
 Might and right, 129, 181. 
 
 Mill, J. S., 152, 154, 168; on suf- 
 frage, 393. 
 
 Milton, on lie, 229. 
 
 Molina, on authority, 376. 
 
 Money, fruitful, 144; a species of 
 seed, 146; medium of exchange, 
 metals, coinage, 147. 
 
 Monopoly in education, 347, 348, 
 349. 
 
 Montesquieu, on ownership, 254. 
 
 Moral notions, 70-92. 
 
 Moral acts and good acts, 31. 
 
 Morality, its causes, final, 70; ma- 
 terial .and formal, 71; model, 
 79; efficient, 79; generic and 
 specific, 71, 92, 97, 98; specific 
 determinants, 71 ; objective and 
 subjective, 76, 77, 78, 31; sub- 
 jective and conscience, 76; ig- 
 norance and, 76, 77 ; internal and 
 external acts, 78, 96; indifferent 
 acts, 78; of man and his acta, 
 32. 
 
 Moral obligation, and Kant, 38; 
 from objective order and divine 
 command, 38. 
 
 Moral Positivism, 129, 130. 
 
INDEX 
 
 411 
 
 Motives of men, 18, 19; for obedi- 
 ence, with Kant, 173. 
 Murder, 49, 50. 
 
 N 
 
 Natural Law, 41-70; definition, 
 46; division, 47; objectively 
 and subjectively, 46, 47; and 
 Decalogue, 47; and polygamy, 
 47, 50, 52; three classes of prin- 
 ciples, 46; principles are prac- 
 tical judgments, 48, 49; ignor- 
 ance of, 49 ; three classes of acts 
 forbidden, 50; change of matter, 
 50, 51; four schools of inter- 
 preters, 50, 51, 52; Meyer's 
 classification, 50; Thomists and 
 Suarez on dispensations, 50; in- 
 trinsically wrong acts, and their 
 three classes, midwives of Israel, 
 51; dangerous reading, 51; 
 strict enactments, and recom- 
 mendations, 52; choice between 
 diff'erent schools, 52; knowledge 
 of, 54; unchangeable, universal, 
 eternal, 54, 55 ; sanction of, in 
 this life and in next, 55, 56; 
 foundation of civil law, 59; ex- 
 istence proved, 60, 61; qualities 
 proved, 61 ; sanction proved, 62, 
 63; sanction and Kant's auton- 
 omy, 42, 62; foundation of civil 
 law proved, 65, 66; not reason, 
 66; application of, 67; subjects 
 before creation, 66; infants and 
 insane, 66; principles, 67; na- 
 tions astray, 67; physical law 
 and exceptions, 67; Abraham 
 and Isaac, 67. 
 
 Necessity, and four kinds, 257. 
 
 Negatively common ownership, 
 249 ; a natural right, 250. 
 
 Neutral schools, and mixed, 351. 
 
 No taxation without representa- 
 tion, 396, 401. 
 
 Noumena, phenomena, and natural 
 law, 165. 
 
 O 
 
 Object, 72, 93; end of deed, 75, 
 76, 96, 97. 
 
 Object, end and circumstances, 72- 
 78; 93-101. 
 
 Objective morality, 32. 
 
 Objective order, and subjective, 35, 
 72. 
 
 Order of execution and of inten- 
 tion, 7. 
 
 Owen and colony, 253. 
 
 Ownership, 241-260; in capital, 
 with socialism, 241, 242; and 
 communism, 243, 245; and so- 
 cialistic commonwealth, 242 ; and 
 natural law, 243; and civil law, 
 258; and jurisdiction, 245; and 
 production, 245; elements of, 
 245; exaggerated individualism, 
 245; and occupancy, 246, 259; 
 God and charity, 246; State and 
 Eminent Domain, 247; kinds of, 
 247, 248 ; Costa-Rossetti on com- 
 mon, 249; Adam and Eve, 251, 
 252; primitive innocence and, 
 252 ; Abraham and Lot, 252 ; re- 
 ligious, 253, 258. 
 
 Paley, 152, 155. 
 
 Paphnutius, on celibacy, 302. 
 
 Paradox, end and beginning, 7. 
 
 Particular good tends to universal, 
 16. 
 
 Passions, 83, 84; diagram and 
 definitions, 84. 
 
 Paul, St., on celibacy, 308, 310. 
 
 Penal laws, and conscience, 134. 
 
 Perfect ownership, 247. 
 
 Personal indulgence at expense of 
 neighbor, 163. 
 
 Pius VII, Pope, and Napoleon, 322, 
 
 Plato, 63; on suicide, 205; on 
 bachelors, 303. 
 
 Pleasure and pain, 156; Aristotle, 
 St. Thomas, Plato, on, 156, 157 ; 
 Spinoza, Kant, Schopenhauer, 
 Descartes, Hamilton, Bain, Al- 
 len, Spencer on, 158; faculty 
 for, 158; feeling, 156; laws of, 
 157; processes, 157. 
 
 Plutarch, on religion, 197. 
 
 Pollock, on contracts, 139. 
 
 Polygamy, 311-318; monogamy 
 primitive form of marriage. 
 Pope Innocent III on Adam, 
 
412 
 
 INDEX 
 
 312, 314; patriarchal and Cal- 
 vin, St. Chrysostom and St. 
 Augustine, 313; Solomon, Abra- 
 ham and concubines, 313; and 
 gentiles, 313; and Church in 
 New Law, 313, 315; Anabaptists 
 and Luther, 314; compared with 
 divorce, 314, 315; in Utah and 
 Turkey, 314; Noah, Job, and St. 
 Peter, 314; modern, 316; woman 
 in, 317; Durandus on, 317; 
 hurts secondary purposes of mar- 
 riage, 315; in Old Law and New, 
 47, 50, 52, 53. 
 
 Positivism, moral and juridical, 
 129, 130, 131. 
 
 Positively common ownership, 249 ; 
 from compact, 254; use of 
 things, 259. 
 
 Price, 140. 
 
 Pride and wickedness, 5. 
 
 Principle of utilitv refuted, 160, 
 161, 162, 163, 164. 
 
 Probabilism, 101, 102, 103; law- 
 fulness not validity, 108. 
 
 Probabiliorism, 102. 
 
 Proudhon, on wages, 285. 
 
 Prudence, 111, 112, 114, 115; func- 
 tions of, 114; and wisdom, 114; 
 Christ in the temple, 114, 115. 
 
 Public ownership, 248. 
 
 Pythagoras, and celibacy, 304. 
 
 Q 
 
 Quelch, H., 273. 
 
 Quotations from Socialists, 272, 
 273, 274, 275. 
 
 Cicero on, 197; Scripture for 
 one, 198; remedy for suicide, 
 207. 
 
 Remorse implies hell, 166. 
 
 Republic and monarchy compared, 
 382. 
 
 Responsibility, 33. 
 
 Resurrection of body, 25. 
 
 Revelation, definition, 186; chan- 
 nels of, 186; Bible and Tradi- 
 tion, 186; Church, custodian and 
 interpreter of, 186; miracles and 
 prophecies, seals of, 187; funda- 
 mentals and non-fundamentals, 
 more important and less im- 
 portant, 187, 188; must accept, 
 192, 103; must seek, 194; mys- 
 teries in, 198. 
 
 Rights and Duties, 127-137, 179, 
 180; animals have none, 180; 
 personal and real, 181; collision 
 of, 181; courts to settle, 182. 
 
 Right, and its three meanings, 
 127; Suarez on, 128; of owner- 
 ship, 128; Holland on, 128; 
 precedence in right and duty, 
 128, 182; surrender of, 129; and 
 might, 129. 
 
 Rigorism, 101. 
 
 Rolling stones over a precipice, 
 108. 
 
 Romans and duel, 210. 
 
 Rousseau, on standard, 34; on law, 
 58; on child and God, 346; on 
 state, 359. 363, 364, 365; on au- 
 thority, 377; social contract, 
 377. 
 
 S 
 
 Rationalists defy reason, 4, 5. 
 
 Reading, dangerous, 51. 
 
 Real good and apparent, 155. 
 
 Reason, weak without revelation, 
 4, 5. 
 
 Religion, definition, 178, 179; ob- 
 jective and subjective, 178, 179; 
 dogmatic and practical, 179; 
 natural and supernatural, 179; 
 man's first duty, 183, 191; essen- 
 tial necessity, 183, 191; and 
 state, 184; Schiff on, 196; end 
 of religion, 197; Plutarch and 
 
 Sanction and kinds, 55. 
 
 Savigny on contracts, 139. 
 
 Scepticism, 6. 
 
 SchifT, on religion, 196. 
 
 Scholastics, on authority, 374, 375, 
 376; resemblances and differ- 
 ences, 377. 
 
 Schopenhauer on pleasure, 158; on 
 duty, 202. 
 
 Secrets, natural, of promise, of 
 contract, 239, 240. 
 
 Sedition, 401, 402. 
 
 Self-defense, 208-210, 215, 221, 
 222; conditions for lawful, 209, 
 
INDEX 
 
 413 
 
 210; means to preserve right, 
 215; chastity and, 220; unjust 
 assailants, 221 ; drunken assail- 
 ant, 221; honor, 221; end and 
 means, 222; duty to kill, 222; 
 love of enemy, 222. 
 
 Self and state sole lawmakers, 164. 
 
 Seneca on sanction, 56 ; on suicide, 
 205. 
 
 Senses and supreme good, 39. 
 
 Senses of words, 240. 
 
 Shakespeare on money, 145; on 
 suicide, 208. 
 
 Siricius, Pope, on celibacy, 302, 
 
 Socialism, 260-280; and Marx, 
 260; and millionaires, 242; and 
 Heaven, 242 ; and industry, 242 ; 
 restricted Socialism, 244 ; danger 
 to republic, 244; wages of em- 
 ployers, 261; religion, remedy, 
 261 ; evolution and propaganda, 
 262; from leaders and their 
 writings, 262, 272, 273; and 
 municipal ownership, 263; and 
 atheism, 262, 264; consumer, 
 263; Church and, 202, 264; 
 clergy and, 262, 264; state, free 
 love, family, children, 262, 264; 
 commonwealth, 263, 264; un- 
 natural, 266; morally impos- 
 sible, 268, 269. 
 
 Socialistic commonwealth fea- 
 tures, 263, 264. 
 
 Society, complete and incomplete, 
 
 289, 290; family, state, Church, 
 
 290, 291; brutes, 289; matter 
 and form of, 289; origin is na- 
 ture, 358-366; family leads to 
 state, 358; Hobbes and Rousseau 
 on, 359, 363, 364, 365; origin 
 from nature proved, 360, 361; 
 monks and nuns, 364; Free- 
 masons, 362; St. Thomas on, 
 360. 
 
 Socrates, 154; on suicide, 205. 
 
 Soul, immortal, 6. 
 
 Spargo, 275. 
 
 Sparta, on bachelors, 303. 
 
 Special Ethics, 175-404; division 
 
 of, 175; Individual, 177-289; 
 
 Family, 289-358; State, 358- 
 
 404. 
 Species in moral acts, 72, 73. 
 Spencer on pleasure, 158. 
 
 Spinoza on law, 58; on pleasure, 
 158. 
 
 Spontaneous acts, 86. 
 
 Standard of morality, immediate 
 and mediate, 35, 36, 39, 38; not 
 law, not public opinion, 34, 35, 
 39; objective order grasped by 
 intellect, 35, 36, 38, 39. 
 
 State, its structure, 366-371; its 
 purpose, Kant, and right system, 
 366, 367, 368; its inatter and 
 form, 369, 381; subject and 
 slave, 369; causes of, 389; ef- 
 ficient, formal, final, 389; ma- 
 terial, 389, 390; heterogeneous, 
 392; and prerogatives, 398-404; 
 legislative, judicial, executive, 
 398; Aristotle on rule by law 
 and by judge, 399; St. Thomas 
 on capital punishment, 399 ; Em- 
 inent Domain and Hobbes, 400; 
 War-Power, 401, 402, 403; taxes, 
 400 ; end, material and spiritual, 
 196, 197. 
 
 Stoic Formalism, 164-168; Cronin 
 on, 167, 168. 
 
 Strikes, 288. 
 
 Suarez, natural law, 50; on coun- 
 sel and law, 58; on right, 128; 
 on authority, 375; and Royal 
 Compact, 376, 377 ; and Victoria, 
 376, 383, 384; matter and form, 
 381. 
 
 Subjective morality, 31, 32. 
 
 Substance, complete and incom- 
 plete, 81. 
 
 Suff'rage, inborn right in nobody; 
 natural in man, unnatural in 
 woman, 395. 
 
 Suicide, self-defense and duel, 201- 
 225. 
 
 Suicide, 203-209; 213-216; 218- 
 221; crime and cowardice of, 
 
 204, statistics, 205 ; Seneca, Pla- 
 to, Socrates, Cicero, Virgil, on 
 
 205, 206; state and lunacy, 206 j 
 religion, one remedy, 207; 
 Shakespeare, 208; against God, 
 213; against self, 214; against 
 society, 215; indirect killing, 
 218; instinct, 218; no permis- 
 sion of God, 218; mutilation, 
 218; saints rushing to death, 
 218; drimkard after confession. 
 
414 
 
 INDEX 
 
 218; rejecting a gift, 219; Hume 
 and, 219; escape from greater 
 evil, 219; volenti nulla injuria, 
 219; hunters kill birds, 219; 
 criminal killing himself, 220 ; op- 
 erations, 220 ; exposure of self to 
 death, 220. 
 Synderesis and conscience, 80. 
 
 Taparelli, on consent of people, 
 374, 384, 386, 387. 
 
 Temperance, 120, 112; and absti- 
 nence, 120, 121. 
 
 Tenuiter probabile, 101. 
 
 Thanksgiving Day, 184. 
 
 Theft, 49. 
 
 Thomas, St., on law's causes, 44; 
 on specific morality, 73, 74; on 
 society, 360; on virtues. 111; on 
 cardinal virtues, 112; on in- 
 terest, 148, 144; on lie, 226, 227; 
 celibacy, 309; nobody born a 
 king, 378; on prayer, 197. 
 
 Thomasius and Holland on theol- 
 ogy, 133; on duty, 202; on wor- 
 ship, 185. 
 
 Toleration, Constitution and, 188; 
 political and dogmatic, 189, 190; 
 Samaritans and, 189; political, 
 by accident lawful, 189; dog- 
 matic, absurd, 190, 194; Indif- 
 ferentism. Liberalism and, 199, 
 200. 
 
 Tongiorgi division of Ethics, 4. 
 
 Transient ownership, 248. 
 
 Trial by Ordeal, 211. 
 
 Truce of God, 211. 
 
 Trusts, 287. 
 
 Truth and its kinds, 226. 
 
 Tutiorism, 101. 
 
 U 
 
 Vice and formal object, 113. 
 
 Virgil and suicide, 206. 
 
 Violence and kinds, 91. 
 
 Virtues and Vices, 110-122; in 
 general, 110; with St. Thomas, 
 112; with St. Augustine, 112; 
 with Aristotle, 112. 
 
 Virtue and preponderance of bless- 
 ings, 37. 
 
 Volitum and praecognitum, 13. 
 
 Voluntary acts, and kinds, 14, 87, 
 88. 
 
 Vow, obligation from natural law, 
 not from man, 173. 
 
 W 
 
 Wages, Proudhon on, 285; no 
 partnership, buying and selling, 
 
 285, 286; law and conscience on, 
 
 286. . 
 
 Wage-trouble and religion, 141. 
 
 War, definition and kinds, 401; 
 legitimate, 402; precautions be- 
 fore, during, after, 402, 403. 
 
 Will and appetite, 13, 82. 
 
 Woman suffrage, 388-398; argu- 
 ments against, 394; arguments 
 for, 395, 396; unnatural, 393; 
 Catholics and, 393; J. S. Mill 
 and, 393. 
 
 Worship and natural law, 48 ; 
 definition of, 184; division of, 
 184; external and internal, pub- 
 lic and private, 184, 185; Thom- 
 asius, Dunzi, Kemmerichius, 
 Ahrens on external, 185; latria, 
 hyperdulia, dulia, 192; God's 
 due, 192; acts morally on God, 
 195; needed by God, 196; so- 
 ciety owes, 196; in spirit and 
 truth, 196; freedom of, 199, 200. 
 
 Usury and Church, 145. 
 Utilitarianism, 152-170. 
 
 Value, 140. 
 
 Zeno and happiness, 21, 23, 24; 
 
 and wealth, 154. 
 Zigliara, on consent of people, 384, 
 
 385. 
 
re 30372 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY