-8£jtCs«r^-aay.i 
 
 UC-NRLF 
 
 B 3 T2M M23 
 
STUDIES 
 
 IN THE 
 
 HEGELIAN DIALECTIC 
 
BY THE SAME AUTHOR 
 
 STUDIES IN HEGELIAN COSMOLOGY. 8s. net. 
 
 A COMMENTAEY ON HEGEL'S LOGIC. 12s. net. 
 
 THE NATURE OF EXISTENCE. Vol. I. 22s. 6d. net. 
 
 (Cambridge University Press) 
 
 SOME DOGMAS OF RELIGION. 10s. 6d. net. 
 
 HUMAN IMMORTALITY AND PRE-EXISTENCE. 
 
 (Reprinted from " Some Dogmas of Religion.") 
 
 2s. net. 
 (Edward Arnold) 
 
STUDIES 
 
 IN THE 
 
 HEGELIAN DIALECTIC 
 
 BY 
 
 JOHN McTAGGART ELLIS McTAGGART 
 
 LITT.D. CAMBRIDGE, LL.D. ST ANDREWS, 
 
 FELLOW AND LECTURER OF TRINITY COLLEGE IN CAMBRIDGE, 
 
 FELLOW OF THE BRITISH ACADEMY 
 
 SECOND EDITION 
 
 CAMBRIDGE 
 
 AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 
 
 1922 
 

 CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS 
 
 C. F. CLAY, Manager 
 
 LONDON : FETTERLANE, E.C.4 
 
 NEW YORK: THE MACMILLANCO. 
 
 BOMBAY \ 
 
 CALCUTTA [ MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd. 
 
 iMADRAS J 
 
 TORONTO : THE MACMILLAN CO. OP 
 
 CANADA, Ltd. 
 TOKYO : MARUZEN-KABUSHIKI-KAISHA 
 
 ALL BIGHTS RESERVED 
 
 Fir»t Edition, 1896 
 Second Edition, 1922 
 
TO 
 
 MISS FRANCES POWER COBBE 
 WITH MUCH GRATITUDE 
 
 583471 
 
PREFACE 
 
 THE first four chapters of this book are based on a disserta- 
 tion submitted at the Fellowship Examination of Trinity 
 College, Cambridge, in 1891. The fourth and fifth chapters, nearly 
 in their present form, were pubhshed in Mind (New Series, Nos. 
 1, 2, 8, and 10). A part of the second chapter appeared in the 
 Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale for November 1893. 
 
 In quoting from the Smaller Logic and the Philosophy of 
 Spirit, I have generally availed myself of Professor Wallace's 
 valuable translations. 
 
 I am most deeply indebted to Professor J. S. Mackenzie, of 
 University College, Cardiff, for his kindness in reading the proof- 
 sheets of these Studies, and in assisting me with many most 
 helpful suggestions and corrections. 
 
 The changes in the second edition are not numerous. When 
 they are more than verbal, I have called attention to them in 
 notes. 
 
 J. E. McT. 
 
 December, 1921. 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 THE GENERAL NATURE OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 PAGE 
 
 1. The logical connection of categories ...... 1 
 
 2. The form of this connection is progressively modified . . 2 
 ^_^_^. The dialectic is a process of reconstruction .... 3 
 ^yi. Which takes place by alternate production and removal of 
 
 contradictions ......... 4 
 
 5. An objection to this raised by Hartmann ..... 6 
 
 ^. In what sense the dialectic may be said to be objective . . 6 
 
 J. The imperfection of finite things does not involve, for Hegel, the 
 
 objective reality of the dialectic as a process .... 7 
 
 8. The dialectic does not violate the law of contradiction . . 8 
 
 9. The importance of the idea of negation is only secondary . . 10 
 ^^0. The relation of the dialectic to ordinary thought . . .11 
 
 11. Hartmann' s criticisms of this relation 12 
 
 12. The same continued 14 
 
 '13. The dialectic must prove its validity to the Understanding . 14 
 
 ^^4. The relation of the dialectic to experience 16 
 
 15. The relation of the dialectic to experience further defined . . 17 
 J 6. The basis upon which the dialectic works is the nature of ex- 
 perience 19 
 
 17. The postulate which it assumes is the vaUdity of the category 
 
 of Being 19 
 
 18. And the denial of this postulate is contradictory ... 20 
 
 19. The argument of the dialectic is transcendental . . .21 
 
 20. The epistemological result of the dialectic 22 
 
 21. The negative effects of this 22 
 
 22. Its positive effects . . . . . . . . .23 
 
 23. We are not entitled to consider pure thought as independent 
 
 of experience .......... 24 
 
 24. The relation of Hegel's epistemology to Kant's . . . .25 
 ^&5. The ontological result of the dialectic — ambiguity of the phrase 26 
 
 26. Hegel's deduction of Nature and Spirit from the Logic . . 27 
 
 27. This deduction does not treat pure thought as independent of 
 
 experience .......... 28 
 
 2%. The importance of the ontological result of the dialectic . . 29 
 29. Comparison of Hegel with his immediate predecessors in philo- 
 sophy 30 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS ix 
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 PAGB 
 
 30. Introductory 32 
 
 A 
 
 31. Trendelenburg's view that the dialectic is per se sterile, and gains 
 
 its advance by illegitimate appeals to experience ... 32 
 
 32. The errors involved in this view .33 
 
 33-43. Passages from the Encyclopaedia bearing on this view . . 35 
 
 44. The true relation of the dialectic to experience is not made clear 
 
 by Hegel 48 
 
 45. Reasons for this 48 
 
 46. Hegel's assertion that the dialectic is without presupposition . 50 
 
 B 
 
 47. The relation of the Absolute Idea to experience . . .51 
 
 48. The Absolute Idea transcends contingency, but not immediacy 52 
 
 49. Hegel's definition of the Absolute Idea ..... 53 
 
 c 
 
 50. Professor Seth's view as to the ontological claims of the dialectic 54 
 61. Hegel's description of the transition from Logic to Nature and 
 
 Spirit ........... 55 
 
 52. The interpretation placed on this by Professor Seth ... 56 
 
 53. Who confuses two charges — that Hegel tried to synthetically 
 
 deduce Nature and Spirit from thought, and that he tried to 
 deduce Existence from Essence ...... 58 
 
 54. But the first of these does not involve the second ... 60 
 
 55. Hegel would have been wrong in trying to do the first . . 61 
 
 56. But the arguments in support of the theory that he did try are 
 
 untenable .......... 62 
 
 57. And Hegel says himself that his deduction is of a different nature 63 
 
 58. There is a deduction, but it is not purely synthetic ... 64 
 
 59. The treatment of Contingency in the Logic as bearing on this 
 
 question ........... 65 
 
 60. The second charge — deducing Existence from Essence. We 
 
 cannot do this 67 
 
 61. But if the deduction of Nature and Spirit is purely analytic, this 
 
 second charge must fall to the ground ..... 67 
 
 62. The meaning of the phrase "absolute" as used by Hegel of his 
 
 own philosophy 68 
 
x^: 
 
 X TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 63. Hegel's treatment of Kant's objections to the ontological 
 argument .......... 69 
 
 64. It depends on the different definitions of God adopted by Hegel 
 and Kant 70 
 
 65. Professor Seth's assertion that Hegel depreciates the individual 72 
 
 66. And that his Absolute Spirit is a mere abstraction ... 74 
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 67. Introductory 76 
 
 A 
 
 Mr Balfour's criticism of transcendental arguments ... 76 
 
 69. Which rests on a confusion of the different senses in which we 
 
 may be said to be conscious of an element in experience . 78 
 
 70. The same subject continued 79 
 
 3^- The justification of the Reason to the Understanding. The 
 
 -"""^ longing for the Absolute is not merely ethical or emotional 80 
 
 72. The Understanding demands a complete explanation of the 
 
 universe 82 
 
 73. Which it carmot itself supply 82 
 
 74. Since many of its categories lead to contradictions ... 84 
 ,75. And this must lead to scepticism; not, as Hartmann suggests, to 
 
 y/^ separation between thought and being ..... 85 
 
 76. The Reason can supply such an explanation .... 86 
 
 77. Which the Understanding must therefore accept ... 87 
 
 78. The Understanding and the Reason are not separate and un- 
 
 cormected faculties 88 
 
 B 
 
 79. We are justified in assuming the validity of the category of Being 
 
 as a starting-point 89 
 
 80. As to the process — first from a synthesis to the new thesis . 90 
 
 81. The process from thesis to antithesis. Neither sterile nor em- 
 
 pirical 91 
 
 82. The consideration of the categories in detail is impossible here . 92 
 ?3 The process from thesis and antithesis to synthesis ... 93 
 
 ^^4. Hartmann's objection to the possibihty of this .... 94 
 j^'^ 85. Trendelenburg's objection that the dialectic is merely a history 
 
 of subjective knowledge ........ 95 
 
 86. But, although it only retraces abstractions, it gives new know- 
 ledge 97 
 
 87. And reverses the order of explanation current in science . . 98 
 
 88. Nor is it merely a process of subjective thought ... 99 
 
 .^. 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS xi 
 
 PAGE 
 
 89. The dialectic does not displace the finite sciences, but does not 
 
 depend on them 100 
 
 90. Though an advanced state of the finite sciences may be an aid 
 
 in discovering the dialectic . . . . . . .101 
 
 91. The idea of Motion — according to Trendelenburg introduced 
 
 empirically in the category of Becoming .... 103 
 
 92. But in reahty it is deducible by pure thought .... 103 
 
 93. Nor does Becoming specially involve time or space • . 105 
 
 94. Nor is it, if taken correctly, much more concrete than Being . 106 
 
 c 
 
 95. The ontological validity of the dialectic. The denial of the 
 
 thing-in-itself is justifiable ....... 107 
 
 96. ]VIr Schiller's objection that thought may be inadequate to 
 
 reality 109 
 
 97. Unjustifiable, since reality itself can only be known to us by 
 
 thought 110 
 
 98. Transition from Logic to Nature and Spirit . . . .112 
 
 99. Thought can never be self-subsistent, but must have a given 
 
 datum . . . . . . . . . . .113 
 
 100. The transition might have been made differently. Importance 
 
 of this 114 
 
 101. Lotze's criticism of "the identity of Thought and Being." 
 
 Ambiguity of this phrase . . . . . . .115 
 
 102. Lotze seems to take it as meaning that Being is identical with' 
 
 what is thought about Being 116 
 
 103. In this sense Hegel did not hold the doctrine . . . .117 
 
 104. He held it in the sense that Being is identical with what it 
 
 thinks: — perhaps he was mistaken . . . . .117 
 
 105. The essence of Idealism is the assertion that Being is rational, 
 
 not that it is Thought 118 
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 
 
 106. Introductory 119 
 
 A 
 
 107. Hegel's own expressions on this subject . . . . .119 
 
 108. As the process continues the categories become less stable and 
 
 self-contained . . . . . . . . .121 
 
 109. And the antithesis marks an advance from the thesis . . 122 
 
 1 10. This second change is connected with the first . . . 123 
 
 111. The first is explicitly mentioned by Hegel. The second is not 124 
 
xii TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 112. The change seems to be continuous from category to category 125 
 
 113. Such a change in the method of the dialectic is antecedently 
 
 probable 127 
 
 114. And it is antecedently probable that it will be continuous . 128 
 
 115. The change consists in combining the search for completeness 
 
 and the search for harmony, which were originally separate 
 
 stages 129 
 
 116. Hence the change does not destroy the validity of the process . 131 
 
 117. The subordinate importance of negation in the dialectic is thus 
 
 made still clearer than before 131 
 
 B 
 
 118. Hegel asserts that the dialectic process is an adequate analysis 
 
 of the Absolute Idea 133 
 
 119. But this we now see reasons to doubt 133 
 
 120. Hegel's own premises lead us, on this point, to reject his con- 
 
 clusion 135 
 
 121. The dialectic thus becomes, in a sense, subjective . . . 136 
 
 122. Owing to an inevitable characteristic of our thought . . 138 
 
 123. It does not give a fully adequate account of its own natiu"e . 139 
 
 124. This does not diminish its power of demonstrating that the 
 
 Absolute Idea alone is completely valid of reaUty . . 140 
 
 125. Nor of determining the relative truth of the different categories 142 
 
 126. Nor are we left ignorant of the natiu-e of the Absolute Idea . 142 
 
 127. The essential and unessential elements in the process . . 144 
 
 128. The dialectic process may be looked on as primarily con- 
 
 tinuous. This is confirmed by the inequahty of the sub- 
 divisions of the Logic ........ 145 
 
 129. And by the possibility of discovering direct dialectic connection 
 
 between divisions which are not the lowest .... 146 
 
 130. The effect of this with regard to any error in the detail of the 
 
 dialectic 147 
 
 c 
 
 131. The triad of Logic, Nature, and Spirit 147 
 
 132. This transition is made by a triad of the Notion- type . . 148 
 
 133. But it could be made by a triad of the Being-type . . . 150 
 
 134. This confirms the view taken above of the change of method . 151 
 
 135. The alternative adopted by Hegel was on the whole the best . 152 
 
 136. But the other has some advantages . . . . .153 
 
 137. Which Hegel's does not share 153 
 
 138. The same continued 154 
 
 139. Conclusion 155 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS xiii 
 
 CHAPTER V 
 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 
 
 A PAGE 
 
 140. Difficulties in the way of taking the development of the 
 
 dialectic in time as ultimately real 157 
 
 141. Such a process in time must be finite in length . . . 158 
 
 142. And the question would arise: Why did it begin where it did? 159 
 
 143. Which cannot be avoided by referring it to a timeless basis . 161 
 
 144. Nor by the suggestion that time only begins when change 
 
 begins 162 
 
 145. Nor by arguing that the idea of finite time cannot be con- 
 
 tradictory, since that of infinite time is impossible . . 163 
 
 146. We must rather suppose that the idea of time is not ultimate . 164 
 
 147. The lower stages of the dialectic cannot exist by themselves, 
 
 since they are contradictory ...... 164 
 
 148. And we saw above that the dialectic must be a process of 
 
 reconstruction ......... 166 
 
 149. Hegel's own language is against the theory of development in 
 
 time 167 
 
 B 
 
 150. But the rejection of this theory involves that the universe is 
 
 now perfect 169 
 
 151. Which involves us again in serious difficulties , . . 170 
 
 152. Hegel's answer that evil is a delusion is unsatisfactory . . 171 
 
 153. Since on his theory a delusion could never be completely 
 
 rational .......... 172 
 
 154. The suggestion that the universe is perfect sub specie aetemitatis 173 
 
 155. It is more effective than Hegel's own answer .... 174 
 
 156. And must not be confounded with the theory that imperfec- 
 
 tions of the parts disappear in the whole .... 175 
 
 157. But it was not Hegel's own view — nor wiU it solve the difficulty 176 
 
 158. Which seems to be insoluble ....... 177 
 
 159. And naturally so, since it is, in fact, the problem of the origin 
 
 of evil 178 
 
 C 
 
 160. Can any other theory extricate us from the difficulties which 
 
 are involved in the assertion that the universe is eternally 
 perfect? 180 
 
 161. Not the theory that it is fundamentally irrational . . . 181 
 
 162. An absolute duaUsm is impossible 182 
 
 163. And, if possible, would not solve the difficulty, supposing one 
 
 side predominated 184 
 
xiv TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 164. Or supposing both were exactly balanced .... 184 
 
 165. We should succeed no better with the theory that reality is 
 
 totally indifferent to reason 185 
 
 166. Or indifferent to the higher categories 186 
 
 167. And to take refuge in scepticism proves equally impossible . 187 
 
 168. Oiu' diificulty does not arise from a reductio ad absurdum . 188 
 
 169. And we have no more right to reject the dialectic than we have 
 
 to reject the arguments against it . . . . .189 
 
 170. We may hope for a synthesis of the opposed positions . . 190 
 
 171. Since they are opposed as contraries, not as contradictories . 191 
 
 172. But we do not know of what nature such a synthesis could be, 
 
 nor have we any positive evidence for its existence . . 192 
 
 173. We should have such evidence if we knew that the detail of 
 
 the dialectic were correct throughout 193 
 
 174. Conclusion 194 
 
 175-178. Note on Mr Schiller's paper "The Metaphysics of the 
 
 Time-Process" 195 
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 
 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 A 
 
 179. Hegel makes the highest stage in the nature of Spirit to be 
 
 Philosophy 201 
 
 180. His account of this 202 
 
 181. Philosophy must be considered to be merely a state of know- 
 
 ledge 203 
 
 182. Philosophy, as we have it at present, is clearly not adequate 
 
 for this position 204 
 
 183. And Hegel never attempted to deduce facts from the nature 
 
 of pm'e thought ......... 205 
 
 184. Nor will it suffice to make philosophy end by proving the 
 
 necessity of philosophy 206 
 
 185. Taking a wider meaning of philosophy — ^we shall never be able 
 
 to dispense with immediate data ...... 207 
 
 186. But a perfect system of knowledge is conceivable, in which 
 
 contingency vanishes ........ 208 
 
 187. Such an ideal is remote, but not contradictory . . . 209 
 
 188. It would leave no question unanswered, except Why is the 
 
 universe as a whole what it is? — which is an unmeaning 
 question 211 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 XV 
 
 B PAGE 
 
 189. Even such knowledge, however, is not a complete expression 
 
 of Spirit 212 
 
 190. For volition is not reducible to knowledge .... 213 
 
 191. Though both of them may perhaps be synthesised in a higher 
 
 unity 214 
 
 192. Nor are pleasure and pain reducible to knowledge . . . 214 
 
 193. Though, like volition, they are inseparable from it . . . 215 
 
 194. But can knowledge, as such, be even part of the true nature of 
 
 Spirit? 216 
 
 195. It postulates complete unity and differentiation between 
 
 subject and object . . . . . . . .216 
 
 196. The TAis in knowledge 217 
 
 197. Which is essential to knowledge, and which knowledge must 
 
 always regard as aUen . . . . . . . .218 
 
 198. The This prevents knowledge reaching complete unity and 
 
 differentiation 219 
 
 199. Thus knowledge can never express quite adequately the 
 
 harmony of the universe ....... 220 
 
 200. Nor does the possibihty of self-knowledge get over the difficulty 221 
 
 201. This defect is the reason why we cannot cease to ask. Why is 
 
 the vuiiverse as a whole what it is? — though we know the 
 question to be unmeaning ....... 222 
 
 202. We find some support for this view in the Logic . . . 223 
 
 203. Since philosophy there comes under the subordinate category 
 
 of Cognition 225 
 
 204. Hegel's treatment of the last stages of the Philosophy of Spirit 
 
 is imperfect ......... 226 
 
 205. Philosophy should rather be part of the antithesis — not the 
 
 synthesis . 227 
 
 206. Conclusion 229 
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 207. Introductory 230 
 
 208. The application of the dialectic to determine the nature of 
 
 ultimate reaUty . . . . . . . . .231 
 
 209. The practical importance of this 232 
 
 210. The apphcation of the dialectic to the interpretation of the 
 
 facts round us 233 
 
 211. This is the part of Hegel's system which is now most generally 
 
 received 234 
 
TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PAGE 
 
 212. But it seems doubtful if it is valid 235 
 
 ,213. The first difficulty — we cannot recognise theses, antitheses, or 
 
 syntheses, except in relation to one another . . . 236 
 
 214. Thus we shall require points independently fixed to begin from 
 
 or end at. We have such in the Logic .... 237 
 
 215. But not in the appUcations of the Logic ..... 238 
 
 216. The terms of which, till seen in relation to each other, only 
 
 differ quantitatively ........ 238 
 
 217. The initial point of the Philosophy of Nature, and the final 
 
 point of the Philosophy of Spirit, are exceptions . . . 239 
 
 218. Attempts to fix the extreme points in the Philosophies of 
 
 Nature, Spirit, and Religion ...... 240 
 
 219. in the History of Philosophy and the Philosophy of Law . 241 
 
 220. and in the Philosophy of History. A criticism by Lotze . . 242 
 
 221. The reason of the exceptions mentioned in Section 217 . . 243 
 _^222. The second difficulty. In Religion, History, Law, and Philo- 
 sophy, the dialectic process is affected by external influences 245 
 
 223. And, in another manner, in Natiure and Spirit . . . 246 
 
 224. We know that there is a dialectic process in facts, but are unable 
 
 to trace it . . 247 
 
 225. The third difficulty. The extent and intricacy of the subject- 
 
 matter 248 
 
 226. These difficulties can be avoided by taking abstract qualities, 
 
 rather than actual facts, as the terms of our dialectic . . 249 
 
 227. As in Hegel's treatment of Innocence, Sin, and Virtue . . 251 
 
 228. Or of the conception of Dying to live 252 
 
 229. But the main practical interest of philosophy lies in upholding 
 
 the abstract assertion that reaUty is rational and righteous 252 
 
 230. For this cannot be done at all, except by philosophy . . 253 
 
 231. Nor is this view imduly abstract 255 
 
 y 
 
CHAPTER I 
 
 THE GENERAL NATURE OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 1 . Hegel's primary object in his dialectic is to est ablish the 
 existence of a logical connection between the various categ ories 
 which are involved in the constitution of experien ce. He teaches 
 tnat this connec tion is of such a kind that any categor y, if 
 s crutinised with sufficient care and attention , is found to lead 
 o n to another, and to involve^it, in snnh a manner t|^^ ,|. f ip, f^f,|,^.Tr>pf. 
 t o^use the first of any subje ct while we refuse to use the second 
 of the same subject results in a contradiction. The category thus* 
 reached leads on in a similar way to a third, and the process 
 continues until at last we reach the goal of the dialectic in a ■ 
 category which betrays no instability. - — ^ 
 
 If we examine the process in more detail, we shall find that 
 it advances, not directly, but by moving from side to side, like 
 a ship tacking against an unfavourable wind. The simplest and 
 best known form of this advance, as it is to be found in the earlier 
 transitions of the logic, is as follows. TJie examinatiofr-ef -a- c e rtain 
 category leads us to the conclusion thaLt, if we p redicate if/ of 
 any subject, we are compelled by consistency to predicate of 
 the same subject the contrary of that category. This brings us 
 to an absurdity, since the predication of two contrary attributes 
 of the same thing at the same time violates the law of contra- 
 diction. On examining the two r:nntrnry p7-p,(^jp.a.tps fnrf-.lipr, they 
 are seen to be ■Capable of reconciliation in a J^gher_categor^ 
 which combines the contents of both of them, not merely placed 
 side by side, but..absoxbed,.iiito. a wider idea, as moments or 
 aspects of which they can exist without contradiction. 
 
 This idea of the synthesis of opposites is perhaps the most 
 characteristic in the whole of Hegel's system. It is certainly one 
 of the most difficult to explain. Indeed the only way of grasping 
 what Hegel meant by it is to observe in detail how he uses it, 
 and in what manner the lower categories are partly altered and 
 partly preserved in the higher one, so that, while their opposition 
 
 ,.if-werat 
 
\ 
 
 \ 
 
 2 THE GENERAL NATURE [CH. 
 
 vanishes, the significance of both is nevertheless to be found in 
 the unity which follows. 
 
 Since in this way, and in this way only so far as we can see, 
 two ^ntrary cat egories can be simultaneously true of a subj.ect, 
 and since we must hold these two to be simultaneously true, we 
 arrive at the conclusion that whenever we use the first category 
 we shall be forced on to use the third, since by it alone can the 
 contradictions be removed, in which we should otherwise be in- 
 volved. This third category, however, when it in its turn is viewed 
 as a single unity, similarly discloses that its predication involves 
 that of_its contrary^ and the Thesis and Antithesis thus opposed 
 have again to be resolved in a Syntheses. Nor can we rest any- 
 where in this alternate production and removal of contradictions 
 until we reach the end of the ladder of categories. It begins with 
 tl;e cate gory of Pure Being, the simplest idea of the human mi nd. 
 I t ends with the category which Hegel declares to be th e highest 
 — t heldea which recognises itself in all things. 
 
 2, It must be remarked that the type of transition, which 
 we have just sketched, is one which is modified as the dialectic 
 advances. It is only natural, in a system in which matter and 
 form are so closely connected, that the gradual changes of the 
 matter, which forms the content of the system, should react on 
 the nature of the movement by which the changes take place. 
 Even when we deal with physical action and reaction we find 
 this true. All tools are affected, each time they are used, so as 
 to change, more or less, their manner of working in the future. 
 It is not surprising, therefore, that so delicate a tool as that which 
 is used by thought should not remain unchanged among changing 
 materials. 
 
 "The abstract form of the continuation or advance" says 
 Hegel "is, in Being, an Qtbe3^Qr_.antithesis)jin^tmnsit^ 
 anotJigr; ir^ th e Essenpe , showing or, reflection in its opposite; 
 in ti ie Noti on, the distinction^ of the individual from the uni- 
 versality, which continues itself as such into, and is as an identity 
 with, what is distinguished from it^." This indicates a gradual 
 increase in the directness of the advance, and a diminished im- 
 portance of the movement from contrary to contraxy. But this 
 ^ Encyclopcedia, Section 240. 
 
OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 point, which Hegel leaves undeveloped, will require further con- 
 sideration i. 
 
 3. The ground of the necessity which the dialectic process 
 claims cannot, it is evident, lie merely in the category from which 
 we start. For in that case the conclusion of the process could, 
 if it were valid, have no greater content than was contained in 
 the starting point. All that can be done with a single premise 
 is to analyse it, and the mere analysis of an idea could never 
 lead us necessarily onwards to any other idea incompatible with 
 it, and therefore could never lead us to its contrary. But th^ 
 (^alectic claims to^j)2:QG£ed,iri:)m thB.lQWJQi.±Q..±ha higher, and it 
 claims to _add^ to our knowled^e^ and not merdy.iQ. expound it . 
 At the same time it asserts that no premise other than the 
 validity of the lower category is requisite to enable us to affirm 
 the validity of the higher. ^^ 
 
 The solution of this difficulty, which has bee5.-the-^EQLy.«:a of 
 many attacks on Hegel, lies in the fact t hat/p.e dialectic\iust 
 be looked on as a process , not of constructiqitH ^ttt;^gr^econ- 
 struction . If the lower categories lead on to the higher, and 
 these to the highest, the reason is that the lower categories have 
 no independent existence, bjit arp. only a.bstra.p,t,in|]pi frnn^ thp 
 highest . It is this alone which is independent and real. In it 
 all one-sidedness has been destroyed by the successive reconcilia- 
 tion of opposites. It is thus the completely concrete, and for 
 Hegel the real is always the concrete. Moreover, according to 
 Hegel, the real is always the completely rational. (''The con- 
 summation of the infinite aim... consists merely in removing the 
 
 illusion which makes it seem as yet unaccomplished^.") JJ^qw 
 
 no category except the highest can be completel y rational., since 
 e very lower one involves its contrary . The Absolute Ide a is 
 p resent to us in all reality , in all the phenomena of experience , 
 a nd in our own selves. EverYwhere it is the soul of all reality . 
 But although it is always present to u s, it is not always explicitly 
 present . In the content of consciousness it is present implicitly. 
 But we do not always attempt to unravel that content, nor are 
 our attempts always successful. Very often all that is explicitly 
 before our minds is some finite and incomplete category. When 
 ^ Chap. rv. ^ Enc. Section 212, lecture note. 
 
 t 
 
 
 yji^aJSJ-^ 
 
THE GENERAL NATURE 
 
 [CH. 
 
 this is so, the dialectic process can begin, and indeed must begin, 
 if we are sufficiently acute and attentive, — because the ideal which 
 is latent in the nature of all experience, and of the mind itself, 
 forbids us to rest content with the inadequate category. The in- 
 complete reality before the mind is inevitably measured against 
 the complete reality of th§ mind itself, and it is in this process 
 that it betrays its incompleteness, and demands its contrary to 
 supplement its one-sidedness. " Before the mind there is a single 
 conception, but the whole mind itself, which does not appear, 
 engages in the process, operates on the datum, and produces the 
 result!." 
 
 4. Thg dialecti,c„prjocess_ ig^ not a mere addition to thfi__con- 
 c eption before _as of one casually^ selec^ed^moment after another, 
 but obeys a definite law. The reason of this is that at any point 
 the finite category explicitly before us stands in a definite relation 
 to the complete and absolute idea which is implicit in our con- 
 sciousness. Any category, except the most abstract of all, can 
 be analysed, according to Hegel, into two others, which in the 
 unity of the higher truth were reconciled, but which, when 
 separated, stand in opposition to each other as contraries. If 
 abstraction consists in this separation, then, when we are using 
 the most abstract of the categories, we fall short of the truth, 
 because one side of the completely concrete truth has been taken 
 in abstraction, and from that relatively concrete truth again one 
 side has been abstracted, and so on, until the greatest abstraction 
 possible has been reached. It must therefore cause unrest in the 
 mind which implicitly contains the concrete whole from .which 
 it was abstracted. And through this unrest the imperfection will 
 be removed in the manner described above, that is, by affirming, 
 in the first place, that contrary category, the removal of which 
 had been the last stage of the abstraction, then by restoring the 
 whole in which those two opposites had been reconciled, and 
 so on. 
 
 Thus the first and deepest cause of the dialectic movement is 
 
 t he instability of all finite categori es, due to their imperfect 
 
 ature. The immediate TQi}\}] t of this instability is the production 
 
 o f^ cont r adictio ns. For, as we have already seen, since the im- 
 
 * Bradley's Logic, Book in. Part i. Chap. 2, Section 20. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 5 
 
 perfect category p.nrlp.a.vnnr!^ \,q fp.tnrn to thp. more r.onnr gtfi unity 
 of which it is one side, it is found to involve the other side of 
 that un ity, w hich i s its own contrar y. And, again, to the existence 
 of the contradiction we owe the advance of the dialectic. For 
 i t is the contradiction involved in the impo ssibility of predicating 
 a c ategory "without predicating its opposite which causes us to 
 abandon t hat c ategory as inadequate. We are driven on firs t to 
 its antitheses. And when we find that this inyoly es the predication 
 of the thesis, as much as this latter hadjnvolyed the predication 
 of the antithesis, the_impossibi]ity_of j&icapingfrqm^ontradic 
 in either extreme drives us to remove them by combining both 
 extremes in a synthesis which transcends them. 
 
 5. It has been asserted that Hegel sometimes declares the A 
 contradictions to be the cause of the dialectic movementj^nd j 
 sometimes to be the effect of that movement. This is maintarned<--J 
 by Hartmann^. TS^o~3ouFt~the contradictions are considered as 
 the immediate cause of the movement. But the only evidence 
 which Hartmann gives for supposing that they are also held to 
 be the effect, is a quotation from the second volume of the Logic. 
 In this, speaking of that finite activity of thought which he calls 
 Vorstellung, Hegel says that it has the contradictions as part 
 of its content, but is not conscious of this, because it does not 
 contain "das Uebergehen, welches das Wesentliche ist, und den 
 Wilderspruch enthalt^." Now all that this implies seems to be 
 that the contradictions first become manifest in the movement, 
 which is not at all identical with the assertion that they are 
 caused by it, and is quite compatible with the counter-assertion 
 that it is caused by them. 
 
 Moreover, Hartmann also gives the same account of the origin 
 of the contradictions which I have suggested above. He says 
 "Der (im Hegel'schen Geiste) tiefer liegende Grund der Erschei- 
 nung ist aber die Fliissigkeit des Begriffes selbst^." Fliissigkeit 
 is certainly not equivalent to movement, and may fairly be 
 translated instability. There is then no inconsistency. It is quite 
 possible that the instability of the notion may be the cause of 
 the contradictions, and that the contradictions again may be 
 
 1 Ueber die dialektische Methode, B. ii. 3. * Logic, Vol. n. p. 71. 
 
 3 Op. cit. B. u. 3. 
 
6 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 the cause of the actual motion. Hartmann does not, apparently, 
 see that there is any change in his position when he gives first 
 instability and then motion as the cause of the contradictions, 
 and it is this confusion on his own part which causes him to 
 accuse Hegel of inconsistency. 
 
 He endeavours to account for Hegel's supposed error by saying 
 that the contradictions were given as the cause of the dialectic 
 movement when Hegel desired to show the subjective action of 
 the individual mind, while the dialectic movement was given as 
 the cause of the contradictions when he wished to represent the 
 process as objective. If, as I have endeavoured to show, there 
 is no reason for supposing that Hegel ever did hold the dialectic 
 movement to be the cause of the contradictions, there will be 
 no further necessity for this theory. But it may be well to remark 
 that it involves a false conception of the meaning in which it is 
 possible to apply the term objective to the dialectic at all. 
 
 6. There is a sense of the word objective in which it may be 
 correctly said that the dependence of the contradictions on. the 
 instability of the notion is more objective. than the dependence 
 of the dialectic movement on the contradictions. For the former 
 is present in all thought, which is not the case with the latter. 
 A contradiction can be said to be present in thought, when it 
 is implied in it, even though it is not clearly seen. But it can 
 oply caHiSP th*^ dif^le^tic mj:) yement. when it is clearlv seen . When- 
 ever a finite category is used it is abstract, and consequently 
 unstable, and, implicitly at least, involves its contrary, though 
 this may not be perceived, and, indeed, in ordinary thought is 
 not perceived. On the other hand, the actual dialectic movement 
 does not take place whenever a category is used, for in that case 
 finite thought would not exist at all. It is only when the contradic- 
 tions are perceived, when they are recognised as incompatible, 
 in their unreconciled form, with truth, and when the synthesis 
 which can reconcile them has been discovered, that the dialectic 
 process is before us. 
 
 The contradiction has therefore more objectivity, in one sense 
 of the word, because it is more inevitable and less dependent 
 on particular and contingent circumstances. But we are not 
 entitled to draw the sort of distinction between them which 
 
■mmLm» 
 
 I] OF THE DIALECTIC 7 
 
 Hartmann makes, and to say that while the one is only an action 
 of the thinking subject, the other is based on the nature of things 
 independently of the subject who thinks them. Both relations 
 are objective in the sense that they are universal, and have 
 validity as a description of the nature of reality. Neither is 
 objective in the sense that it takes place otherwise than in thought. 
 We shall have to consider this point in detail later^ : at present 
 wje, can only say thj,t^jtj)j3.ughtkejdialectic process is a valid 
 de scription of reality, r eality itself is not, in its truest nature, a 
 process but a stable and timeless state. Hegel says indeed that 
 reason is to be found in actual existence, but it is reason injts 
 complete and concrete shape , unjier.the highest and absolute foifli 
 of the n otion , a nd not travelling u p from category to category 
 Till the highest is reached, all the results are expressly termed 
 abstract, and do not, therefore, come up to the level of reality. 
 Moreover they contain unsynthesised contradictions, and that 
 which is contradictory, though it may have a certain relative 
 truth, can never exist independently, as would be the case if 
 it existed in the world of fact. XJi© dialectic movement Js indejgd 
 a guidejtO-that world, since the highest category, under whieJi — y~ 
 alone reality c an be constru ed, contains all the lower categories 
 as moments, bu t the gra dual passage from one stage of the notion 
 to anoth^, d uring which the highest yet reached is for the moment 
 regarded as independent and subst antial, is an inadequate ex- 
 wession of the truth . 
 
 7. This is not incompatible with the admission that various 
 isolated phenomena, considered as phenomena and as isolated, 
 are imperfect, for in considering them in this way we do not 
 consider them as they really are. Hegel speaks of the untruth 
 of an external object as consisting in the disagreement between 
 the objective notion, and the object^. From this it might be 
 inferred that even in the world of real objects there existed 
 imperfections and contradictions. But, on looking more closely, 
 we see that the imperfection and contradiction are really, ac- 
 cording to Hegel, due only to our manner of contemplating the 
 object. A particular thing may or may not correspond to the 
 notion. But the universe is not merely an aggregation of particular 
 ^ Chap. V. 2 Enc. Section 24, lecture note. 
 
8 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 things, but a system in which they are connected, and a thing 
 which in itself is imperfect and irrational may be a part of a 
 perfect and rational universe. Its imperfection was artificial, 
 caused by our regarding it, in an artificial and unreal abstraction, 
 as if it could exist apart from other things. 
 
 A diseased body, for example, is in an untrue state, if we 
 merely regard it by itself, since it is obviously faiUng to fulfil 
 the ideal of a body. But if we look at it in connection with the 
 intellectual and spiritual life of its occupant, the bodily imper- 
 fection might in some cases be seen, without going further, to 
 be a part in a rational whole. And, taking the universe as a whole, 
 Hegel declares " God alone exhibits axealagrefiment jolthp, notion 
 and the reahty. All finite things involve an untruth." God, 
 however, is held by Hegel to be the reahty which underlies all 
 finite t hings . It is therefore only when looked at as finite that 
 they involve an untruth. Looked at sub specie Dei they are 
 true. The untruth is therefore in our manner of apprehending 
 them only. It would indeed, as Hartmann remarks, be senseless 
 tautology for Hegel to talk of the objective truth of the world. 
 But this Hegel does not do, ^ It is in the nature of the world.as 
 a whole that it must be objeetivBly-tnie^. But isolated fragments 
 of the world, just because they are isolated, cannot fully agree 
 with the notion, and may or may not agree with a particular 
 aspect of it. According as they do or do not do this Hegel calls 
 them true or false. 
 
 Hegel's theory that the world as a whole must be objectively 
 trujij so rational, and therefore, as he would continue, perfect, 
 conies no doubt in rather rude contact with some of the facts of 
 life. The consideration of this must for the present be deferred^. 
 
 8. We have seen that the motive power of the dialectic lies 
 in the relation of the abstract idea ex plicitly b efoxeJJie-niindto 
 th£_£.Qnci:fitfi_Ldea_ impHcitlyi-before-it-itL. all experience and all 
 consciousness. This will enable us to determine the relation in 
 which the T3eas of contradiction and negation stand to the 
 dialectic. 
 
 It is sometimes supposed that the Hegelian logic rests on a 
 defiance of the law of contradiction. That law says that whatever 
 ^ Cp. Enc. Section 212, quoted on p. 3 above. ^ Chap. v. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 9 
 
 is A can never at the same time be not- A. But the dialectic 
 asserts that, when A is any category, except the Absolute Idea, 
 whatever is A may be, and indeed must be, not-A also. Now if 
 the law of contradiction is rej ected, argument becomes impossible. 
 It is impossible to refute any proposition without the help of 
 this law. The refutation can only take place by the establishment 
 of another proposition incompatible with the first. But if we 
 are to regard the simultaneous assertion of two contradictories, 
 not as a mark of error, but as an indication of truth, we shall 
 find it impossible to disprove any proposition at all. Nothing, 
 however, can ever claim to be considered as true, which could 
 never be refuted, even if it were false. And indeed it is impossible, 
 as Hegel himself has pointed out to us, even to assert anything 
 without involving the law of contradiction, for every positive 
 assertion has meaning only in so far as it is defined, and therefore 
 negative. If the statement All men are mortal, for example, did 
 not exclude the statement Some men are immortal, it would be 
 meaningless. And it only excludes it by virtue of the law of 
 contradiction. If then the dialectic rejected the law of contra- 
 diction, it would reduce itself to an absurdity, by rendering all 
 argument, and even all assertion, unmeaning. 
 
 The dialectic, however, does not reject that law. An un- 
 resolved contradiction is, for Hegel as for every one else, a sign 
 of error. The relation of the thesis and antithesis derives its 
 whole meaning from the synthesis, which follows them, and in 
 which the contradiction ceases to exist as such. "Contradiction 
 is not the end of the matter, but cancels itself^." An unreconciled 
 predication of two contrary categories, for instance Being and 
 not-Being, of the same thing, would lead in the dialectic, as it 
 would lead elsewhere, to scepticism, if it was not for the recon- 
 ciliation in Becoming. "jUie-^yJ^^'^P"'^^^ a.lone iias^iealityy and its 
 el ements derive such importance as^ they have from being, in , 
 
 so far as their truth goes, members of a unity in which their .jJ^^jrv-X- 
 opposition is overcome. 
 
 In fact, so far is the dialectic from denying the law of con- 
 tradiction, that it is especially based on it. The contradictions 
 are the cause of the d ialectic process. But they can only be this 
 * Enc. Section 119, lecture note. 
 
 
10 THE GENERAL NATURE [cH. 
 
 if they are received as marks of error. We are obliged to say 
 ti^at we_fimi the_txuth pLBeing^ not-Being in Beconiing^_ajid 
 inJBecomin^ only^ because, if we endeavour to take them in their 
 independence, and not as synthesised, we find an unreconciled 
 contradiction. But why should we not find an unreconciled 
 contradiction and acquiesce in it without going further, except 
 for the law that two contradictory propositions about the same 
 subject are a sign of error? Truth consists, not of contradictions, 
 but of moments which, if separated, would be contradictions^ 
 but which in their synthesis are reconciled and consistent. 
 
 9. It follows also from this view of the paramount importance 
 of the synthesis in the dialectic process that the. place of negation 
 i&Jhji^jocess is only secojadary^ The really fundamental aspect 
 of^_the_ dialectic is not the tendency of the finite category to 
 negate itself but to complete itself. Since the various relatively 
 perfect and concrete categories are, according to Hegel, made 
 up each of two moments or aspects which stand to one another 
 ^ in the relation of contrary ideas, it follows that one characteristic 
 of the process will be the passage from an idea to its contrary. 
 But this is not due, as has occasionally been supposed, to an 
 inherent tendency in all finite categories to affirm their own 
 negation as such. It is due to their inherent tendency to affirm 
 their own complement. It is indeed, according to Hegel, no 
 empirical and contingent fact, but an absolute and necessary 
 law, that their complement is in some degree their negation. 
 But the one category passes into the other, because the second 
 completes the meaning of the first, not because it denies it. 
 
 This, however, is one of the points at which the difficulty, 
 always great, of distinguishing what Hegel did say from that 
 which he ought in consistency to have said becomes almost in- 
 superable. It may safely be asserted that the motive force of 
 the dialectic was clearly held by him to rest in the implicit 
 presence in us of its goal. This is admitted by his opponents as 
 well as his supporters. That he did to some extent recognise 
 the consequence of this — the subordinate importance which it 
 assigned to the idea of negation — seems also probable, especially 
 when we consider the passage quoted above^, in which the 
 ^ Enc. Section 240, quoted on p. 2 above. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 11 
 
 element of negation appears to enter into the dialectic process 
 with very different degrees of prominence in the three stages of 
 which that process consists. On the other hand, the absence of 
 any detailed exposition of a principle so fundamental as that 
 of the gradually decreasing share taken by negation in the 
 dialectic, and the failure to follow out all its consequences, seem 
 to indicate that he had either not clearly realised it, or had not 
 perceived its full importance. But to this point it will be necessary 
 to return. 
 
 10. What relation, we must now enquire, exists between 
 thought as engaged in the dialectic process, and thought as 
 engaged in the ordinary affairs of life? In these latter we con- 
 tinually employ the more abstract categories, which, according 
 to Hegel, are the more imperfect, as if they were satisfactory 
 and ultimate determinations of thought. So far as we do this 
 we must contrive to arrest for the time the dialectic movement. 
 While a category is undergoing the changes and transformations 
 in which that movement consists, it is as unfit to be used as an 
 instrument of thought, as an expanding rod would be for a yard 
 measure. We may observe, and even argue about, the growth 
 of the idea, as we may observe the expansion of a rod under 
 heat, but the argument must be conducted with stable ideas, 
 as the observation must be made with measures of unaltering 
 size. For if, for example, a notion, when employed as a middle 
 term, is capable of changing its meaning between the major and 
 the minor premises, it renders the whole syllogism invalid. And 
 all reasoning depends on the assumption that a term can be 
 trusted to retain the same meaning on different occasions. Other- 
 wise, any inference would be impossible, since all connection 
 between propositions would be destroyed. 
 
 There are two ways in which we may treat the categories. 
 The first is, in the language of Hegel, the function of the Reason 
 — to perform, namely, the dialectic process, and when that 
 culminates in the highest category, which alone is without con- 
 tradiction, to construe the world by its means. As this category 
 has no contradictions in it, it is stable and can be used without 
 any fear of its transforming itself under our hands. The second 
 function is that of the Understanding, whose characteristic it is 
 
12 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 to treat abstractions as if they were independent realities. They 
 are thus forced into an artificial stability and permanence, and 
 can be used for the work of ordinary thought. Of course the 
 attempt to use an imperfect and unbalanced category as if it 
 were perfect and self-subsistent leads to errors and contradictions 
 — it is just these errors and contradictions which are the proof 
 that the category is imperfect. But for many purposes the limit 
 of error is so small, that the work of the Understanding possesses 
 practical use and validity. If we take an arc three feet long of 
 the circumference of a circle a mile in diameter, it will be curved, 
 and will show itself to be so, if examined with sufficient accuracy. 
 But in practice it would often produce no inconvenience to treat 
 it as a straight line. So, if an attempt is made to explain ex- 
 perience exclusively by the category, for example, of causality, 
 it will be found, if the matter is considered with enough care, 
 that any explanation, in which no higher category is employed, 
 involves a contradiction^. Nevertheless, for many of the every- 
 day occurrences on which we exercise our thoughts, an explanation 
 by the Understanding, by means of the category of causality 
 only, will be found to rationalise the event sufficiently for the 
 needs of the moment. 
 
 11. To this explanation an objection has been raised by 
 Hartmann^. He "emphatically denies" our power to arrest the 
 progress of the Notion in this manner. It might, he admits, be 
 possible to do so, if the Notion were changed by us, but it is 
 represented as changing itself. The human thinker is thus only 
 " the fifth wheel to the cart," and quite unable to arrest a process 
 which is entirely independent of him. 
 
 Now in one sense of the words it is perfectly true, that, if the 
 Notion changes at all, the change is caused by its own nature, 
 and not by us. If the arguments of the dialectic are true, they 
 must appeal with irresistible force to every one who looks into 
 the question with sufficient ability and attention, and thus the 
 process may be said to be due to the Notion, and not to the 
 thinker. But this is no more than may be said of every argument. 
 If it is valid, it is not in the power of any man who has examined 
 it, to deny its validity. But when there is no logical alternative 
 1 E-nc. Sections 153, 154. « Op. cit. B. ii. 6. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 13 
 
 there may be a psychological one. No intelligent man, who care- 
 fully examines the proofs, can doubt that the earth goes round 
 the sun. But any person who will not examine them, or cannot 
 understand them, may remain convinced all his life that the 
 sun goes round the earth. And any one, however clearly he 
 understands the truth, can, by diverting his attention from com- 
 paratively remote astronomical arguments, and fixing it on the 
 familiar and daily appearances, speak of and picture the move- 
 ment as that of the sun, as most men, I suppose, generally do. 
 
 So with the dialectic. The arguments are, if Hegel is right, 
 such as to leave the man who examines them no option. But 
 for those who have no time, inclination, or ability to examine 
 them, the categories will continue to be quite separate and in- 
 dependent, while the contradictions which this view will produce 
 in experience will either be treated as ultimate, or, more probably, 
 will not be noticed at all. And even for the student of philosophy, 
 the arguments remain so comparatively abstruse and unfamiliar 
 that he finds no difficulty, when practical life requires it, in 
 assuming for a time the point of view of the Understanding, and 
 regarding each category as unchanging and self-supporting. This 
 he does merely by diverting his attention from the arguments 
 by which their instability is proved. 
 
 Although therefore the change in the Notion is due to its 
 nature, it does not follow that it cannot be stopped by peculiarities 
 in the nature of the thinker, or by his arbitrary choice. The 
 positive element in the change lies wholly in the Notion, but 
 that it should take place at all in any particular case requires 
 certain conditions in the individual mind in question, and by 
 changing these conditions we can at will arrest the process of 
 the categories, and use any one of them as fixed and un- 
 changing. 
 
 Any other view of the dialectic process would require us to 
 suppose that the movement of the categories became obvious 
 to us, not as the result of much hard thinking, but spontaneously 
 and involuntarily. It can scarcely be asserted that Hegel held 
 such a theory, which would lead to the conclusion that every one 
 who ever used the category of Being — that is every one who ever 
 thought at all, whether he reflected on thought or not, — had gone 
 
k 
 
 14 THE GENERAL NATURE [CH. 
 
 through all the stages of the Hegelian logic, and arrived at all 
 its conclusions. 
 
 12. Another difficulty which Hartmann brings forward in this 
 'connection arises from a misapprehension of Hegel's meaning. 
 He affirms^ that, so far from stopping the dialectic process, we 
 could not even perceive it when it took place. For we can only 
 become aware of the change by comparing stage A with stage 
 B, and how is it possible that we should do this, if A turns into 
 B, beyond our control, whenever it appears? 
 
 In the first place, we may answer, it is possible, as we have 
 seen, to arrest the dialectic movement, in any given case, at 
 will, so that the development of the categories is not beyond 
 our control. In the second place the thesis is not held by Hegel 
 to turn into the antithesis in the simple and complete way which 
 this objection supposes. TJLe. one categor y le ads up to_and 
 postulates th e other but does not become c o mpletely the sam e 
 as_ its successor. The thesis and antithesis ar e said no doubt to 
 be the same, but the same with a^ difference. If we predicate_4, 
 we" are forced to predicate B, but there remains neverthelessL^ 
 distinction between A and B. Itjs just the coexistence of this 
 distinction with the necessary implication of the one category 
 injthe other, which renders the synthesis necessary^ as a recon- 
 ciliati on. If the thesis and antithesis were not different, the 
 simultaneous predication of both of them would involve no 
 difficulty. 
 
 13. Such is the general nature of the dialectic as conceived 
 by Hegel. How does he attempt to prove its truth and necessity? 
 "The proof must be based on something already understood and 
 granted by those to whom it is addressed. And since the proof 
 should be one which must be accepted by all men, we must base 
 it on that which all men allow to be justifiable — the ordinary 
 procedure, that it, of thought in common sense and science, 
 which Hegel calls the Understanding as opposed to the Reason, 
 We must show that if we grant, as we cannot help granting, the 
 validity of the ordinary exercise of our thought, we must also 
 grant the validity of the dialectic. 
 
 This necessity Hegel recognises. He says, it is true, that, since 
 1 Op. cit. B. n. 6. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 15 
 
 only the Reason possesses the complete truth, up to which the 
 merely partial truth of the Understanding leads, the real ex- 
 planation must be of the Understanding by the Reason^. But 
 this is not inconsistent with a recognition of the necessity of 
 justifying the Reason to the Understanding. The course of real 
 explanation must always run from ground to consequent, and, 
 according to Hegel, from concrete to abstract. On the other 
 hand, the order of proof must run from whatever is known to 
 whatever is unknown. When, as we have seen is the case with 
 the dialectic, we start from explicit knowledge of the abstract 
 only, and proceed to knowledge of the concrete, which alone 
 gives reality to that abstract, the order of explanation and the 
 order of proof must clearly be exactly opposite to one another. 
 The justification of the Reason at the bar of the Under- 
 standing, depends upon two facts. The one is the search for the 
 Absolute which is involved in the Understanding, the other is 
 the existence in the Understanding of contradictions which 
 render it impossible that it should succeed in the search. The 
 Understanding demands an answer to every question it can 
 ask. But every question which it succeeds in answering suggests 
 fresh questions. Any explanation requires some reference to 
 surrounding phenomena, and these in their turn must be ex- 
 plained by reference to others, and nothing can therefore be 
 fully explained unless everything else which is in direct or in- 
 direct connection with it, unless, that is, the whole universe, be 
 fully explained also. And the explanation of a phenomenon 
 requires, besides this, the knowledge of its causes and effects, 
 while these again require a knowledge of their causes and effects, 
 so that not only the whole present universe, but the whole of 
 the past and future must be known before any single fact can 
 be really understood. Again, since the knowledge of a pheno- 
 menon involves the knowledge of its parts, and all phenomena, 
 occurring as they do in space and time, are infinitely divisible, 
 our knowledge must not only be infinitely extended over space 
 and time, but also infinitely minute. The connection of the 
 phenomenal universe by the law of reciprocity has a double 
 effect on knowledge. It is true, as Tennyson tells us, that we 
 
 1 Logic, Vol. I. p. 198. 
 
16 THE GENERAL NATURE [CH. 
 
 could not know a single flower completely without also knowing 
 God and man. But it is also true that, till we know everything 
 about God and man, we cannot answer satisfactorily a single 
 question about the flower. In asking any question whatever, 
 the Understanding implicitly asks for a complete account of the 
 whole Universe, throughout all space and all time. It demands 
 a solution which shall really solve the question without raising 
 fresh ones — a complete and symmetrical system of knowledge. 
 
 This ideal it cannot, as Hegel maintains, reach by its own 
 exertions, because it is the nature of the Understanding to treat 
 the various finite categories as self-subsistent unities, and this 
 attempt leads it into the various contradictions pointed out 
 throughout the dialectic, owing to the inevitable connection of 
 every finite category with its contrary. Since, then, it postulates 
 in all its actions an ideal which cannot be reached by itself, it 
 is obliged, unless it would deny its own validity, to admit the 
 validity of the Reason, since by the Reason alone can the con- 
 tradictions be removed, and the ideal be realised. And, when 
 it has done this, it loses the false independence which made it 
 suppose itself to be something different from the Reason. 
 
 14. One of the most difficult and important points in deter- 
 mining the nature of the Hegelian logic is to find its exact 
 relation to experience. Whatever theory we may adopt has to 
 fall within certain limits. On the one hand it is asserted by Hegel's 
 critics, and generally admitted by his followers, that, rightly or 
 wrongly, there is some indispensable reference to experience in 
 the dialectic — so that, without the aid of experience it would 
 be impossible for the cogency of the dialectic process to display 
 itself. On the other hand it is impossible to deny that, in some 
 sense, Hegel believed.that by the dialectic process takfiS^^^lace 
 in pure thought, that, however incomplete the Logic might be 
 without the Philosophy of Nature, and the Philosophy of Spirit, 
 however much the existence of Nature and Spirit might be 
 involved in the existence of pure thought, yet nevertheless 
 within the sphere of logic we had arrived at pure thought, un- 
 conditioned in respect of its development as thought. 
 
 And both these characteristics of the dialectic are, indepen- 
 dently of Hegel's assertion, clearly necessary for the validity of 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 17 
 
 any possible dialectic. The consideration of pure thought, without 
 any reference to experience, would be absolutely sterile, or rather 
 impossible. For we are as unable to employ "empty" pure 
 thought (to borrow Kant's phrase) as to employ "blind" in- 
 tuition. Thought is a process of mediation and relation, and 
 implies something immediate to be related, which cannot be 
 found in thought. Even if a stage of thought could be conceived 
 as existing, in which it was self-subsistent, and in which it had 
 no reference to any data — and it is impossible to imagine such 
 a state, or to give any reason for supposing thought thus to 
 change its essential nature — at any rate this is not the ordinary 
 thought of common life. And as the dialectic process professes 
 to start from a basis common to every one, so as to enable it to 
 claim universal validity for its conclusions, it is certain that it 
 will be necessary for thought, in the dialectic process, to have 
 some relation to data given immediately, and independent of 
 that thought itself. Even if the dialectic should finally tran- 
 scend this condition it would have at starting to take thought 
 as we use it in every-day life — as merely mediating, and not 
 self-subsistent. And I shall try to show later on that it never 
 does transcend, or try to transcend that limitation^. 
 
 On the other hand it is no less true that any argument would 
 be incapable of leading us to general conclusions relating to pure 
 thought, which was based on the nature of any particular piece 
 of experience in its particularity, and that, whatever reference 
 to experience Hegel may or may not have admitted into his 
 system, his language is conclusive against the possibility that 
 he has admitted any empirical or contingent basis to the dialectic. 
 
 15. The two conditions can, however, be reconciled. There 
 is a sense in which conclusions relating to pure thought may 
 properly be based on an observation of experience, and in this 
 sense, as I believe, we must take the Logic in order to arrive at 
 Hegel's true meaning. According to this view, what is observed 
 is the spontaneous and unconditioned movement of the pure 
 notion, which does not in any way depend on the matter of 
 intuition for its validity, which, on the contrary, is derived from 
 the character of the pure reason itself. But the process, although 
 
 1 Chap. n. 
 
18 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 independent of the matter of intuition, can only be perceived 
 
 when the pure notion is taken in conjunction with matter of 
 
 intuition — that is to say when it is taken in experience — because 
 
 it is impossible for us to grasp thought in absolute purity, or 
 
 except as applied to an immediate datum. Since we cannot 
 
 observe pure thought at all, except in experience, it is clear that 
 
 it is only in experience that we can observe the change from 
 
 the less to the more adequate form which thought undergoes in 
 
 the dialectic process. But this change of form is due to the nature 
 
 of thought alone, and not to the other element in experience — 
 
 the matter of intuition^. 
 
 The presence of this other element in experience is thus a 
 
 condition of our perceiving the dialectical movement of pure 
 
 thought. We may go further. It does not follow, from the fact 
 
 that the movement is due to the nature of pure thought alone, 
 
 that pure thought can ever exist, or ever be imagined to exist, 
 
 by itself. We may regard pure thought as a mere abstraction 
 
 of one side of experience, which is the only concrete reality, 
 
 while the matter of intuition is an abstraction of the other side 
 
 of the same reality — each, when considered by itself, being false 
 
 and misleading. This, as we shall see, is the position which Hegel 
 
 does take up. Even so, it will still remain true that, in experience, 
 
 the dialectic process was due exclusively to that element of 
 
 experience which we call pure thought, the other element — that 
 
 of intuition — being indeed an indispensable condition of the 
 
 dialectic movement, but one which remains passive throughout, 
 
 and one by which the movement is not determined. It is only 
 
 necessary to the movement of the idea because it is necessary 
 
 to its existence. It is not itself a principle of change, which may 
 
 as fairly be said to be independent of it, as the changes in the 
 
 pictures of a magic lantern may be ascribed exclusively to the 
 
 ^ Since I am here dealing only with the question of epistemology, it will be 
 allowable, I think, to assume that there is a matter of intuition, distinct from 
 thought, and not reducible to it, (though incapable of existing apart from it,) 
 since this is the position taken up within Hegel's Logic. Whether the dialectic 
 process has any relation to it or not, its existence is, in the Logic, admitted, at 
 least provisionally. If Hegel did make any attempt to reduce the whole universe 
 to a manifestation of pure thought, without any other element, he certainly did 
 not do so till the transition to the world of Nature at the end of the Logic. Even 
 there I believe no such attempt is to be found. 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 19 
 
 camera, and not at all to the canvas on which they are reflected, 
 although, without the canvas, the pictures themselves, and 
 therefore the transition from one to another of them would be 
 impossible. 
 
 16. If this is the relation of the dialectic process to the medium 
 in which it works, what postulate does it require to start from? 
 We must distinguish its postulate from its basis. Its basis is 
 the reality which it requires to have presented to itself, in order 
 that it may develop itself. Its postulate is the proposition which 
 it requires to have admitted, in order that from this premise it 
 may demonstrate its own logical validity as a consequence. Jhe 
 basi&^tthe_dialectic isto be found in the nature of ^ure thought 
 itself, since the reason of the process being what it is, is due, 
 as we have seen, to the nature of the highest and most concrete 
 form of the notion, implicit in all experience. Since pure thought, 
 as we have seen, even if it iJauld-e^dstJ-.t jalLm-aJiy_o.thei.mannfir, 
 CQiild,QDly_ become evident to us in exp eripinr.pi. the basis which 
 the dialectic method will require to work on, may be called the 
 nature^of exp„eriencjB.in, general. 
 
 It is only the general nature of experience — those charac- 
 teristics which are common to all of it — which forms the basis 
 of the process, E or it is not the only o bject of the dialecticjo 
 proye_thatJ;^e_ lower and subordinate categories are unable to 
 explain all parts of experience withou t resorting to the higher 
 c ategories, and finally to the Absolute Idea . It undertakes also 
 to show that thfi_JaH:ex categories ar£ inadequate^-when . con- 
 s idered with sufficient in telligence andjpersistence^ to explain 
 any part of the world. What is required, therefore, is not so 
 much the collection of a large mass of experience to work on, 
 but the close and careful scrutiny of some part, however small. 
 The whole jr hain of ratp.gnrjps is itppli ed in any and every phennz. 
 menon . Particular fragments of experience may no doubt place 
 the inadequacy of some finite category in a specially clear light, 
 or may render the transition to the next stage of the idea par- 
 ticularly ob\aous and easy, but it is only greater convenience 
 which is thus gained; \\ath sufficient power any part, however 
 unpromising, would yield the same result. 
 
 17. The basis of the dialectic process, then, is the nature of \ I _ 
 
<n /- 
 
 20 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 expe rience, in so fa r as the nature of pure thought is contained 
 in. it. If the other element in experience has really a primary 
 and essential nature of its own, it will not concern us here, for, 
 as it takes no part in the development of the idea, its existence, 
 and not its particular qualities, is the only thing with which we 
 are at present concerned. The nature of experienc e however, 
 t hough it is the basis of the dialect ic^jsjiot its logical postulate. 
 For it is not assumed hut as cextaine d-by- the diale ctic, wlipse 
 whol£^bjectJs_t]ie gradual discovery -aiid-denaonstration.. 
 Absolute Idaa, which is the fundamental principle which makes 
 the nature of experience. The general laws governing experience 
 are the causa essendi of the logic, but not its causa cognoscendi. 
 r^The only logical postulate which the dialectic requires is the 
 / admission that experience really exists. The dialectic is derived 
 (from the nature of experie nce, a nd tJierfifmieii-it is 4© hav#-any 
 validity of re al existence, if it is to have, tha.t-i.s-±Q,_sfly, a.riy 
 importance at all, we mustjbe assured of the existence of jpme 
 exper ience — in other words, _t hal-something -is. 
 
 The ohjpp.t of thft dialectic is to discover t he forms and law s 
 of all possible thought . For this purpose it starts from the idea 
 of Being, in which all others are shown to be involved. The 
 application of the results of the dialectic to experience thus 
 depends on the application to experience of the idea of Being, 
 and the logical postulate of the dialectic is no more than that 
 something is, and that the category of Being is therefore valid. 
 It will be noticed that the basis and the postulate of the 
 dialectic correspond to the two aspects of the idea which we 
 mentioned above as the fundamental cause of the process. The 
 basis — the nat ure of p ure thought — i s the complete and con- 
 cre te idea w hichris present in nnr mind s, though only implicitly, 
 and which renders it impossible that we should stop shorty it 
 by permanently _acqjii£scing_in any finite category. The pos- 
 tulate — t he abstract id ea in its highest state of abstraction, 
 ta\ which is admi tted to be valid — is that which is explicitly before 
 the mind, and from which the start is made. 
 
 18. We are justified in assuming this postulate because it is 
 involved in every action and every thought, and its denial is 
 therefore suicidal. All that is required is the assertion that there 
 
 (') 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 21 
 
 is such a thing as reality — that something is. Now the very 
 denial of this involves the reality of the denial, and so con- 
 tradicts itself and affirms our postulate. And the denial also 
 implies the reality of the person who makes the denial. The same 
 dilemma meets us if we try to take refuge from dogmatic denial 
 in mere doubt. If we really doubt, then the doubt is real, and 
 there is something of whose reality we do not doubt; if on the 
 other hand we do not really doubt the proposition that there 
 is something real, we admit its truth. And doubt, as well as 
 denial, places beyond doubt the existence of the doubter. This 
 is, of course, the Cartesian argument, which is never stated by 
 Hegel precisely in this form, but on which the justification of 
 his use of the category of Being, as valid of reality, appears to , . 
 
 depend. 
 
 19. T he dialectical process thus gains its validit y and im- ; yn;>-^v^><' ^ 
 po rtance by means of a transcendental argume nt. T iie highe r n^^^^n^*'' 
 categori es are con nected with the lower in such a ms|.pner tha t ^<yv^ 
 
 t he latter inevitably lead on to the former as the only rneans ^^ ^ / 
 
 by which they can be rescued from the contradictions invol^ d y^ 
 
 injheir .aljstiaciaess. If the lower categories be admitted, and, ^^-^ 
 
 ultimately, if the lowest of all, th.e category of ^eing, be admitted, 
 th.e-test follosEs. But we cannot by the most extreme scepticism 
 deny that something is, and we are therefore enabled to conclude 
 that the dialectic process does apply to something. And as 
 whatever the category of Being did not apply to would not exist, 
 we are also able to conclude that there is nothing to which the 
 dialectic process does not apply. 
 
 It will be seen that this argument is strictly of a transcendental 
 nature^. A proposition denied by the adversary — in this case 
 the validity of the higher categories — is shown to be involved 
 in the truth of some other proposition, which he is not prepared 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. This is a mistake. The description given in the next 
 sentence is not confined to a transcendental argument, but applies to all attempts 
 to convince an adversary. I failed to see that the proposition with which a 
 transcendental argument, in Kant's sense of the term, starts, is always a pro- 
 position which asserts that some other proposition is known to be true. (For 
 example, Kant's transcendental argument on Space does not start from the 
 truths of geometry, but from the truth that we know the truths of geometry d, 
 priori.) Hegel's argument does not start from a proposition of this kind, and 
 I was WTong in supposing that it is, in Kant's sense, transcendental. 
 
22 THE GENERAL NATURE [CH. 
 
 to attack — in this case the validity of the category of Being. 
 But the cogency of ordinary transcendental arguments is limited, 
 and they apply only to people who are prepared to yield the 
 proposition which forms the foundation of the argument, so that 
 they could be outflanked by a deeper scepticism. Now this is 
 not the case with the dialectic. For the proposition on which it 
 is based is so fundamental, that it could be doubted only at the 
 expense of self-contradiction, and the necessity of considering 
 that proposition true is therefore universal, and not only valid 
 in a specially limited argument, or against a special opponent. 
 It is doubtful indeed whether a condition so essential as this 
 is correctly termed a postulate, which seems to denote more 
 properly a proposition which it would be at least possible for an 
 adversary to challenge. At any rate the very peculiar nature of 
 the assumption should be carefully remembered, as it afiords 
 a clue for interpreting various expressions of Hegel's, which 
 might otherwise cause serious difficulties^. 
 
 20. Having thus endeavoured to explain the nature of the 
 dialectic, we must ask ourselves at what results we are entitled 
 to arrive by means of that process. These results will be, to begin 
 with, epistemological. For the conditions of the dialectic are, 
 first, the concrete notion, which we are able to examine because 
 it is implicit in all our consciousness, and, second, the category 
 of Being, which we are entitled to postulate, because it is im- 
 possible to avoid employing it in judging experience. Our con- 
 clusions will therefore relate primarily to the general laws of 
 experience, and will so far be, like those of Kant's Aesthetic and 
 Analytic, concerned with the general conditions of human 
 knowledge. And the result arrived at will be that no category 
 will satisfactorily explain the universe except the Absolute Idea. 
 Any attempt to employ for that purpose a lower category must 
 either accept a gradual transformation of the idea employed 
 until the Absolute Idea is reached, or acquiesce in unreconciled 
 contradictions — which involves the rejection of a fundamental 
 law of reason. 
 
 21. This position has two results. In the first place it dis- 
 proves the efforts which are made from time to time to explain 
 
 1 Cp. Chap. n. Section 46. 
 
1] OF THE DIALECTIC 23 
 
 the whole universe by means of the lower categories only. Such 
 an attempt lay at the bottom of Hume's scepticism, when he 
 endeavoured to treat the notion of causality as derived from 
 that of sequence, and to consider all that was added as false 
 and illusive. For absolute scepticism is impossible, and his treat- 
 ment of the higher category as an unwarranted inference from 
 the lower involves the assertion of the validity of the latter. 
 Such an attempt, again, has been made by Mr Spencer, as well 
 as by the large number of writers who adopt the provisional 
 assumptions of physical science as an ultimate position. They 
 endeavour to explain all phenomena in terms of matter and 
 motion, and to treat all special laws by which they may be 
 governed as merely particular cases of fundamental principles 
 taken from physical science. 
 
 But if we agree with Hegel in thinking that the category of 
 Being is inadequate to explain the world which we know without 
 the successive introduction of the categories, among others, of 
 Cause, Life, and Self-Consciousness, and that ea ch, categoxy^in- 
 evitably r equires its successor, all such attempts m us_t,iri£vit£LbIy 
 fajl. Any attempt, for example, to reduce causation to an un- 
 justifiable inference from succession, to explain life merely in 
 terms of matter and motion, or knowledge merely in terms of 
 life, would involve a fatal confusion. For it would be an attempt 
 at explanation by that which is, in itself, incomplete, unreal, 
 and contradictory, and which can only be made rational by 
 being viewed as an aspect of those very higher categories, which 
 were asserted to have been explained away by its means. 
 
 22, Even if this were all, the result of the dialectic would 
 be of great importance. It would have refuted all attempts to 
 establish a complete and consistent materialism, and would have 
 demonstrated the claims of the categories of spirit to a place 
 in construing part at least of the universe. But it has done more 
 than this. For it does not content itself with showing that the 
 lower categories lead necessarily to the higher, when the question 
 relates to those portions of experience in which the higher 
 categories are naturally applied by the uncritical consciousness. 
 It also demonstrates that the lower categories, in themselves, 
 and to whatever matter of intuition they may be applied, involve 
 

 24 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 the higher categories also. Not only is Being inadequate to 
 explain, without the aid of B ecoming, those phenomena which 
 we all recognise in ordinary life as phenomena of change, but 
 it is also unable to explain those others which are commonly 
 considered as merely cases of unchanging existence. Not only 
 is the idea of Substance inadequate to deal with ordinary cases 
 of scientific causation, but without the idea of Cause it becomes 
 involved in contradictions, even when keeping to the province 
 which the uncritical consciousness assigns to it. Not only is it 
 impossible to explain the phenomena of vegetable and animal 
 life by the idea of mechanism, but that idea is inadequate even 
 to explain the phenomena of physics. Not only can consciousness 
 not be expressed merely in terms of life, but life is an inadequate 
 category even for biological phenomena. With such a system we 
 are able to admit, without any danger either to its consistency 
 or to its practical corollaries, all that science can possibly claim 
 as to the interrelation of all the phenomena of the universe, and 
 as to the constant determination of mind by purely physical 
 causes. For not onlj have we justified the categories of spirit, 
 ^llJL-gLli'-g.Xfi-^Ilbjef'^pd fli p, whole world of expe rience to their 
 T^e. We are entitled to assert, not only that spirit cannot be 
 reduced to matter, but also that matter must be reduced to 
 spirit. It is of no philosophical importance, therefore, though 
 all things should, from the scientific standpoint be determined 
 
 ^y material causes. For all material determination is now known 
 
 jto be only spiritual determination in disguise. 
 
 23. The conclusion thus reached is one which deals with pure 
 thought, since the argument has rested throughout on the nature 
 of pure thought, and on that only, and the conclusion itself is 
 a statement as to the only form of pure thought which we can 
 use with complete correctness. But we have not found anything 
 which would enable us to discard sensation from its position as 
 an element of experience as necessary and fundamental as pure 
 thought itself, and if Hegel did draw such a consequence from 
 it, we must hold that he has taken an unjustifiable step forwards. 
 All the thought which we know is in its essential nature mediate, 
 and requires something immediate to act on, if it is to act at 
 all. And this immediate element can be found — so far as our 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 25 
 
 present knowledge is concerned — only in sensation, the necessary 
 background and accompaniment of the dialectic process, which 
 is equally essential at its end as at its beginning. For an attempt 
 to ehminate it would require that Hegel should, in the first place, 
 explain how we could ever conceive unmediated or self-mediated 
 thought, and that he should, in the second place, show that the 
 existence of this self-subsistent thought was impHed in the 
 existence of the mediating and independent thought of every- 
 day life. For since it is only the validity of our every-day thought 
 which we find it impossible to deny, it is only that thought which 
 we can take as the basis of the dialectic process. Even if, in 
 the goal of the dialectic, thought became self-subsistent in any 
 intelhgible sense, it would be necessary to show that this self- 
 subsistence issued naturally from the finite categories, in which 
 thought is unquestionably recognised as mediate only. 
 
 I shall endeavour to prove later on^ that Hegel made no 
 attempt to take up this position. The conclusion of the Logic 
 is simply the assertion that the one category by which experience 
 can be judged with complete correctness is the Absolute Idea. 
 It makes no attempt to transcend the law which we find in all 
 experience by which the categories cannot be used of reality, 
 nor indeed apprehended at all, without the presence of immediate 
 data to serve as materials for them. 
 
 24. To sum up, the general outline of the Hegelian Logic, 
 from an epistemological point of view, does not differ greatly, 
 I believe, from that of Kant. Both philosophers justify the 
 application of certain categories to the matter of experience, 
 by proving that the validity of those categories is impUed in 
 the validity of other ideas which the sceptical opponent cannot 
 or does not challenge^. The systems differ largely in many points, 
 particularly in the extent to which they push their principles. 
 And Hegel has secured a firmer foundation for his theory than 
 Kant did, by pushing back his deduction till it rests on a category 
 — the category of Being, — the validity of which with regard to 
 experience not only never had been denied, but could not be 
 denied without contradiction. It is true also that Kant's work 
 
 ^ Chap. n. Section 48. 
 
 * Note to Second Edition. Cp. note to Section 19. 
 
26 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 was clearly analytic, while Hegel's had also a synthetic side, 
 and may even be said to have brought that side into undue, or 
 at any rate misleading, prominence. But the general principle 
 of the two systems was the same, and the critic who finds no 
 fundamental fallacy in Kant's criticism of knowledge, should 
 have no difiiculty in admitting that the Hegelian Logic, if it 
 keeps itself free from errors of detail, forms a valid theory of 
 epistemology. 
 
 25. But the Logic claims to be more than this, and we must 
 now proceed to examine what has been generally held to be at 
 once the most characteristic and the weakest part of Hegel's 
 philosophy. How far does he apply the results of his analysis 
 of knowledge to actual reality, and how far is he justified in 
 doing so? 
 
 It is beyond doubt that Hegel regarded his Logic as possessing, 
 in some manner, ontological significance. But this may mean 
 one of two very different things. It may mean only that the 
 system rejects the Kantian thing-in-itself, and denies the ex- 
 istence of any reality except that which enters into experience, 
 80 that the results of a criticism of knowledge are valid of reality 
 also. But it may mean that it endeavours to dispense with or 
 transcend all data except the nature of thought itself, and to 
 deduce from that nature the whole existing universe. The 
 difference between these two positions is considerable. The first 
 maintains that nothing is real but the reasonable, the second 
 that reality is nothing but rationality. The first maintains that 
 we can explain the world of sense, the second that we can explain 
 it away. The first merely confirms and carries further the process 
 of rationalisation, of which all science and all finite knowledge 
 consist ; the second differs entirely from science and finite know- 
 ledge, substituting a self-sufficient and absolute thought for 
 thought which is relative and complementary to the data of 
 sense. 
 
 It is, I maintain, in the first of these senses, and the first only, 
 that Hegel claims ontological validity for the results of the Logic, 
 and that he should do as much as this is inevitable. For to dis- 
 tinguish between conclusions epistemologically valid and those 
 which extend to ontology imphes a belief in the existence of 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 27 
 
 something which does not enter into the field of actual or possible 
 knowledge. Such a belief is totally unwarranted. The thing-in- 
 itself as conceived by Kant, behind and apart from the phenomena 
 which alone enter into experience, is a contradiction. We cannot, 
 we are told, know what it is, but only that it is. But this is itself 
 an important piece of knowledge relating to the thing. It involves 
 a judgment, and a judgment involves categories, and we are thus 
 forced to surrender the idea that we can be aware of the existence 
 of anything which is not subject to the laws governing experience. 
 Moreover, the only reason which can be given for our belief in 
 things-in-themselves is that they are the ground or substratum 
 of our sensuous intuitions. But this is a relation, and a relation 
 involves a category. Indeed every statement which can be made 
 about the thing-in-itself contradicts its alleged isolation. 
 
 26. It cannot be denied, however, that Hegel does more than 
 is involved in the rejection of a thing-in-itself outside the laws of 
 experience. Not only are his epistemological conclusions declared 
 to have also ontological validity, but he certainly goes further 
 and holds that, from the consideration of the existence of pure 
 thought, we are able to deduce the existence of the worlds of 
 Nature and Spirit. Is this equivalent to an admission that the 
 worlds of Nature and Spirit can be reduced to, or explained away 
 by, pure thought? 
 
 We shall see that this is not the case when we reflect that 
 the dialectic process is no less analytic of a given material than 
 it is synthetic from a given premise, and owes its impulse as 
 much to the perfect and concrete idea which is implicit in ex- 
 perience, as to the imperfect and abstract idea which is explicitly 
 before the student. For if the idea is, when met with in reality, 
 always perfect and concrete, it is no less true that it is, when 
 met with in reality, invariably, and of necessity, found in connec- 
 tion with sensuous intuition, without which even the relatively 
 concrete idea which ends the Logic is itself an illegitimate ab- 
 straction. This being the case it follows that, as each stage of 
 the Logic insists on going forward to the next stage, so the 
 completed logical idea insists on going forward and asserting 
 the coexistence with itself of sensuous perception. It does not 
 postulate any particular sensuous perception, for the idea is 
 
28 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch. 
 
 equally implicit in all experience, and one fragment is as good as 
 another in which to perceive it. We are thus unable to deduce any 
 of the particulars of the world of sense from the Logic. But we 
 are able to deduce that there must be such a world, for without 
 it the idea would be still an abstraction and therefore still con- 
 tradictory. We are able to predicate of that world whatever is 
 necessary to make it the complement of the world of pure 
 thought. It must be immediate, that thought may have some- 
 thing to mediate, it must be individual and isolated piece from 
 piece that thought may have something to relate. It must be, 
 in short, the abstract individual, which, together with the 
 abstract universal of thought, forms the concrete reality, alike 
 individual and universal, which alone is consistent and self- 
 sustained. 
 
 27. If this is so, it follows that there is nothing mysterious 
 or intricate about the deduction of the world of Nature from 
 the Logic, and of the world of Spirit from the world of Nature. 
 It is simply the final step in the self-recovery of the spirit from 
 the illegitimate abstractions of the understanding — the recovery 
 which we have seen to be the source of all movement in the 
 dialectic. Once granted a single category of the Logic, and all 
 the others follow, since in the world of reality each lower category 
 only exists as a moment of the Absolute Idea, and can therefore 
 never by itself satisfy the demands of the mind. And, in like 
 manner, the world of pure thought only exists as an abstraction 
 from concrete reality, so that, granted pure thought, we are 
 compelled by the necessity of the dialectic to grant the existence 
 of some sensuous intuition also. It is perhaps conceivable that, 
 in some future state of knowledge, the completion of the dialectic 
 process might be seen to involve, not only the mere existence 
 of Nature and Spirit, but their existence with particular charac- 
 teristics, and that this might be carried so far that it amounted 
 to a complete determination, in one way or another, of every 
 question which could be asked concerning them. If this should 
 be the case, we should be able to deduce a priori from the char- 
 acter of pure thought the whole contents of science and history. 
 Even then, however, we should not have taken up the position 
 that the immediate element in Nature and Spirit could be reduced 
 
1] OF THE DIALECTIC 29 
 
 to pure thought. For we should not be endeavouring to deduce 
 the immediate merely from the mediate, but from the mediate 
 compared with the concrete reality of which they are both 
 moments. The true force of the proof would he in the existence 
 of this synthesis. At present, however, the world of sense appears 
 to us to contain a large number of particulars which are quite 
 indifferent to pure thought, so that it might be as well embodied 
 in one arrangement of them as in another. This may possibly 
 be an inevitable law of knowledge. It certainly expresses the 
 state of our knowledge at present. It follows that the Philosophy 
 of Nature and Spirit will consist only in observing the progress 
 of the pure idea as it appears in the midst of phenomena to a large 
 extent contingent to it, and cannot hope to account for all the par- 
 ticulars of experience. But this is all that Hegel attempts to do. 
 He endeavours to find the idea in everything, but not to reduce 
 everything to a manifestation of the idea. Thus he remarks in the 
 Philosophy of Spirit, " This development of reality or objectivity 
 brings forward a row of forms which must certainly be given 
 empirically, but from an empirical point of view should not be 
 placed side by side and outside each other, but must be known 
 as the expression which corresponds to a necessary series of 
 definite notions, and only in so far as they express such a series 
 of notions have interest for philosophic thought^." 
 
 28. If this explanation be correct, it will follow that Hegel 
 never endeavoured to claim ontological validity for his Logic 
 in the second sense mentioned above — by attempting, that is, 
 to deduce all the contents of experience from the nature of pure 
 thought only. The deduction which does take place is not 
 dependent merely on the premise from which it starts, which is 
 certainly to be found in the nature of pure thought, but also 
 on the whole to which it is working up, and which is implicit 
 in our thought. If we can proceed in this way from Logic to 
 Nature and Spirit, it proves that Logic without the additional 
 elements which occur in Nature and Spirit is a mere abstraction. 
 And an abstraction cannot possibly be the cause of the reality 
 from which it is an abstraction. There can be no place here, 
 therefore, for the attempt to construct the world out of abstract 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 387, lecture note, p. 42. 
 
30 THE GENERAL NATURE [ch, 
 
 thought, of which Hegel's philosophy is sometimes supposed to 
 have consisted. 
 
 The importance of the ontological significance of the dialectic, 
 even in this limited extent, is, however, very great. We are now 
 enabled to assert, not only that, within our experience, actual 
 or possible, everything can be explained by the Absolute Idea, 
 but also that all reality, in any sense in which we can attach any 
 intelligible meaning to the word, can also be explained by that 
 idea. I cannot have the least reason to believe in, or even to 
 imagine possible, anything which does not in the long run turn 
 out to contain and be constituted by the highest category. And 
 since that category, as was pointed out above, expresses the 
 deepest nature of the human mind, we are entitled to believe 
 that the universe as a whole is in fundamental agreement with 
 our own nature, and that whatever can rightly be called rational 
 may be safely declared to be also real. 
 
 29. From this account of the Hegelian system it will appear 
 that its main result is the completion of the work which had been 
 carried on by German philosophy since the publication of the 
 Critique of Pure Reason — the establishment, by means of the 
 transcendental method, of the ratioijality of the Universe. There 
 was much left for Hegel to do. For the Critique of Pure Reason 
 was a dualism, and had all the qualities of a dualism. Man's 
 aspirations after complete rationality and complete justice in 
 life were checked by the consideration of the phenomenal side 
 of his own nature, which delivered him over to the mercy of a 
 world in one of whose elements — the irrational manifold — he 
 saw only what was alien to himself. And the defect of the Critique 
 of Pure Reason in this respect was not completely remedied by 
 the Critique of Practical Reason. The reconciliation was only 
 external: the alien element was not to be absorbed or tran- 
 scended but conquered. It was declared the weaker, but it kept 
 its existence. And the whole of this argument had a slighter 
 basis than the earlier one, since it rested, not on the validity of 
 knowledge, but on the validity of the moral sense — the denial 
 of which is not as clearly a contradiction of itself. Moreover, 
 it is not by any means universally admitted that the obligation 
 to seek the good is dependent on the possibility of realising it 
 
I] OF THE DIALECTIC 31 
 
 in full. And if it is not so dependent, then the validity of the 
 moral sense does not necessarily imply the validity of the Ideas 
 of Reason. Even in the Critique of Judgment the reconciliation 
 of the two sides was still external and incomplete. 
 
 Nor had spirit a much stronger position with Kant's im- 
 mediate successors. Fichte, indeed, reduced the Non-Ego to a 
 shadow, but just for that reason, as Dr Caird remarks, rendered 
 it impossible to completely destroy it. And the Absolute of 
 Schelhng, standing as it did midway between matter and spirit, 
 could be but slight comfort to spirit, whose most characteristic 
 features and most important interests had Httle chance of pre- 
 servation in a merely neutral basis. 
 
 Hegel on the other hand asserted the absolute supremacy of 
 reason. For him it is the key to the interpretation of the whole 
 universe; it finds nothing alien to itself wherever it goes. And 
 the re ason for which he thus claimed unrestricted power was^ 
 demonstrated to contain every category up to the Absolute Ide a. 
 It is this demonstration — quite as much as the rejection of the 
 possibility that anything in the universe should be alien to reason 
 — which gives his philosophy its practical interest. For from 
 the practical point of view it is of little consequence that the 
 world should be proved to be the embodiment of reason, if we 
 are to see in reason nothing higher than reciprocity, and are 
 compelled to regard the higher categories as mere subjective 
 delusions. Such a maimed reason as this is one in which we can 
 have scarcely more pleasure or acquiescence than in chaos. If 
 the rational can be identified with the good, it can only be in 
 respect of the later categories, such as End, Life, and Cognition. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 30. In the last chapter I have explained the view of Hegel's 
 philosophy which seems to me the most probable. It is now 
 necessary to examine some objections which have been raised 
 to the possibility of interpreting Hegel in this manner. With 
 regard to three points in particular various commentators have 
 taken a different view of Hegel's meaning. It has been held that 
 the dialectic process has no reference whatever to experience, 
 but takes place in pure thought considered apart from anything 
 else. It has been held that, whether this be so or not, yet at the 
 end of the dialectic we reach, in the Absolute Idea, a form of 
 thought which exists in and by itself, and does not merely 
 mediate data immediately given to the mind by some other 
 source. And, lastly, it has been held that the deduction of Nature 
 and Spirit from Logic is to be taken as an attempt to degrade 
 them into mere forms of the latter, and to declare that all things 
 are reducible to thought alone. 
 
 31. The first of these points has been discussed by Tren- 
 delenburg in his Logische Untersuchungen. According to him, 
 Hegel attempted what was impossible, and achieved what was 
 useless. He attempted, by observation of the pure notion in 
 its most abstract stage, and apart from everything but itself, 
 to evoke all the other stages of the pure notion, and so reach 
 a result of general validity a priori. But since we can extract 
 from an idea, taken by itself, nothing more than is already in 
 it, and since an idea, independent of the data which it connects 
 and mediates, is unthinkable, any such dialectical evolution as 
 Hegel desired was impossible. In point of fact, all appearance 
 of advance from one category to another is due, according to 
 Trendelenburg, to surreptitious appeals to experience. In this 
 way the sterility of pure thought was conquered, but with it 
 the cogency of this dialectic process also disappeared, and it 
 
CH. n] DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS OF THE DIALECTIC 33 
 
 became merely empirical and contingent, without a claim to be 
 called philosophy. 
 
 On the question as to the actual results of the dialectic we 
 shall consider Trendelenburg's views further on. As to Hegel's 
 intention, he says "Although the Wissenschaftslehre of Fichte 
 extracted the Non-Ego from the Ego, yet he does not go on to 
 real notions. The dialectic has appropriated his methods; it 
 takes the same course in position, opposition, and reconciliation. 
 It does not make so much difference that it begins with the 
 notion of Being, for it is the empty image of Being. If it never- 
 theless comes to the notions of reality and to concrete forms, 
 we do not perceive whence it gets to them. For pure thought 
 will not accept them, and then permeate them, but endeavours 
 to make them. Thought, expressed in this way, is born blind 
 and has no eyes towards the outside^." 
 
 32. In answer to this we may quote Mr F. H. Bradley. "An 
 idea prevails that the Dialectic Method is a sort of experiment 
 with conceptions in vacuo. We are supposed to have nothing 
 but one single isolated abstract idea, and this solitary monad 
 then proceeds to multiply by gemmation from or by fission of 
 its private substance, or by fetching matter from the impalpable 
 void. But this is a mere caricature, and it comes from confusion 
 between that which the mind has got before it and that which 
 it has within itself. Before the mind there is a single conception, 
 but the mind itself, which does not appear, engages in the process, 
 operates on the datum, and produces the result. The opposition 
 between the real, in the fragmentary character in which the 
 mind possesses it, and the true reaUty felt within the mind, is 
 the moving cause of that unrest which sets up the dialectical 
 process^." 
 
 The fact seems to be that Trendelenburg's interpretation of 
 Hegel's attempt to construct a dialectic of pure thought, is 
 inadequate in two ways. He supposes, first, that the incomplete 
 thought irom which we start is conceived to exist only in its 
 incompleteness, and is intended to have as yet no actual relation 
 
 1 Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. i. p. 92. My references to this work are to 
 the edition of 1862. 
 
 2 Logic, Book m. Part i. Chap. 2. Section 20. 
 
 M.H. 3 
 
34 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 to the concrete reality to which it is afterwards to attain. In 
 fact, he says, the process does depend on a reference to concrete 
 reahty, but, in so far as this is so, the original attempt, which 
 was to construct an objectively valid dialectic by means of pure 
 thought, has broken down. I shall try, however, to show that 
 such a relation to reality was in Hegel's mind throughout, and 
 that it leads to conclusions of objective validity. If pure thought 
 meant anything inconsistent with this, it would certainly be 
 sterile. But there is nothing in this which is inconsistent with 
 pure thought, for the notion, as contained implicitly in reaUty 
 and experience, is precisely of the same nature as the isolated 
 piece which we begin by consciously observing, though it is more 
 complete. 
 
 And, secondly, Trendelenburg appears to think that thought, 
 to be pure, must be perceived by itself, and not in concrete 
 experience, which always contains, along with pure thought, 
 the complementary moment of sensation. If this was the case, 
 it would most certainly be sterile, or rather impossible. So far 
 from one category being able to transform itself, by the dialectic 
 process, into another, no category could exist at all. For all 
 thought, as we have seen^, requires something immediate on 
 which to act. But this need not prevent the dialectic process 
 from being one of pure thought. As was explained above"^ the 
 only part of experience from which the dialectic process derives 
 its cogency, and the only part which changes in it, is the element 
 of pure thought, although the dialectic process, like all other 
 acts of reasoning, can only take place when the thought is joined 
 with sensation. 
 
 Whether the reference to experience in Hegel's Logic destroys 
 its claims to absolute and a priori validity will be discussed in 
 the next chapter. At present we have to ask whether the appeal 
 to experience is inconsistent with the original intention of the 
 dialectic, as Trendelenburg asserts, and whether it was only used 
 by Hegel because the absurdity of his original purpose drove 
 him, more or less unconsciously, to make such an appeal, or 
 whether, on the other hand, it was all along an essential part of 
 the system that it should have such a relation to experience. 
 » Chap. I. Section 27. ^ Chap. i. Section 15. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 35 
 
 33. At the beginning of Section 6 of the Encyclopaedia Hegel 
 says that "at first we become aware of these contents" of philo- 
 sophical knowledge "in what we call experience.... As it is only 
 in form that philosophy is distinguished from other modes of 
 obtaining an acquaintance with this same sum of being, it must 
 necessarily be in harmony with actuality and experience." This 
 passage supports the view that Hegel was conscious of the 
 manner in which his dialectic rested on experience. For, even 
 if it were possible for philosophy to observe pure thought in- 
 dependently of experience, it is certain that "other means of 
 obtaining an acquaintance with this same sum of being" — 
 science, namely, and common sense — have no field for their 
 action except experience. It is no doubt the case that, as Hegel 
 mentions in Section 8, philosophy has "another circle of objects, 
 which" empirical knowledge "does not embrace. These are Free- 
 dom, Mind, and God." But, although philosophy deals with 
 these conceptions, it does so, according to Hegel, only by starting 
 from empirical knowledge. It is, for example, only by the con- 
 templation of the finite objects perceived by the senses that we 
 arrive at the knowledge of God^. And, as we are now considering 
 the basis, and not the extent, of philosophy, the fact that we 
 can rise to knowledge of that which is never represented in 
 sensuous intuition is not to the point. 
 
 34. Again, in Section 9, he points out that "the method of 
 empirical science exhibits two defects. The first is that the 
 Universal, or general principle contained in it, the genus or kind, 
 &c., is of its own nature indeterminate and vague, and therefore 
 not on its own account connected with the Particular or the 
 details. Either is external and accidental to the other, and it is 
 the same with the particular facts which are brought into union : 
 each is external and accidental to the others. The second defect 
 is that the beginnings are in every case data and postulates, 
 neither accounted for nor deduced. In both these points the 
 form of necessity fails to get its due. Hence reflection, whenever 
 it sets itself to remedy these defects, becomes speculative thinking, 
 the thinking proper to philosophy." Further on in the same 
 section he says that "the relation of speculative science to the 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 12, quoted on p. 36 below. 
 
 3—2 
 
36 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [cH. 
 
 other sciences may be stated in the following terms. It does not 
 in the least neglect the empirical facts contained in the other 
 sciences but recognises and adopts them: it appreciates and 
 apphes towards its own structure the universal element in these 
 sciences, their laws and classifications; but besides all this, into 
 the categories of science, it introduces, and gives currency to, 
 other categories. The difference looked at in this way is only a 
 change of categories." 
 
 The method of philosophy then is separated by no difference 
 of kind from the method of science, and must therefore also 
 deal with experience. It takes the materials of science, and 
 carries further the process of arrangement and analysis which 
 science began. Whether, in doing so, it actually goes so far as 
 to destroy the basis from which it started, is a question which 
 will be considered later i. The changes which it produces are in 
 any case very extensive. Fresh categories are introduced, and 
 not merely as additions, but as altering materially the meaning 
 of the categories of science which now turn out to be abstract 
 and of imperfect validity. The process must not be confounded 
 with one which should simply carry scientific generalisations up 
 to the highest point, using only the categories of science, and 
 making the ordinary scientific presuppositions. The result may 
 in one sense be said to differ from the result of science in kind 
 and not only in degree. But the method only differs in degree. 
 The special categories of philosophy are not introduced "out of 
 a pistol" but are the necessary consequence of reflection on the 
 categories of science and the contradictions they display. And, 
 if there is this continuity between science and philosophy, we 
 are placed in the dilemma of either supposing that Hegel imagined 
 science to be possible without experience, or admitting that for 
 him the dialectic method, the method of philosophy, also required 
 experience as its presupposition. 
 
 35. The whole of Section 12 has a very important bearing 
 on this question. The following extracts are especially significant. 
 Philosophy "takes its departure from experience; including 
 under that name both our immediate consciousness and the 
 inductions from it. Awakened, as it were, by this stimulus, 
 1 Sections 47-49. 
 
11] OF THE DIALECTIC 37 
 
 thought is vitally characterised by raising itself above the natural 
 state of mind, above the senses and inferences from the senses 
 into its own unadulterated element, and by assuming, accordingly, 
 at first a stand-aloof and negative attitude towards the point 
 from which it draws its origin." And further on " On the relation 
 between immediacy and mediation in consciousness. . .here it may 
 be sufficient to premise that, although the two 'moments' or 
 factors present themselves as distinct, still neither of them can 
 be absent, nor can one exist apart from the other. Thus the 
 knowledge of God " (compare Section 1 — " Truth, in that supreme 
 sense in which God and God only is the Truth") "as of every 
 supersensible reality, is in its true character an exaltation above 
 sensations or perceptions: it consequently involves a negative 
 attitude to the initial data of sense, and to that extent implies 
 mediation. For to mediate is to take something as a beginning, 
 and to go onward to a second thing ; so that the existence of this 
 second thing depends on our having reached it from something ^ 
 
 else contradistinguished from it. In spite of this the knowledge s. 
 
 of God is independent (selbststandig) and not a mere consequence ^ 
 
 of the empirical phase of consciousness ; in fact, its independence sj 
 
 is essentially secured through this negation and exaltation. No >- 
 
 doubt, if we attach an unfair prominence to the fact of mediation, ^ 
 
 and represent it as implying a state of conditionedness (Beding- 
 theit), it may be said — not that the remark would mean much — 
 
 ^ 
 
 that philosophy is the child of experience, and owes its rise to *^ "^ 
 
 an a posteriori fact. (As a matter of fact, thinking is always the ^ 
 
 negation of what we have immediately before us.) With as much ^^ ^ 
 
 truth however we may be said to owe eating to the means of t^ ^ 
 nourishment, so long as we can have no eating without them. ji^ JT 
 If we take this view, eating is certainly represented as ungrateful ; vf> 
 it devours that to which it owes itself. Thinking, upon this view 
 of its action, is equally ungrateful." And again, "In relation to 
 the first abstract universality of thought there is a correct and 
 well-grounded sense in which we may say, that we may thank h^ ^ 
 experience for the development of philosophy. For, firstly, the 
 empirical sciences do not stop short at the perception of the 
 individual features of a phenomenon. By the aid of thought, 
 they come forward to meet philosophy with materials for it, in 
 
 5c yu 
 
38 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [oh. 
 
 the shape of general uniformities, i.e. laws and classifications of 
 the phenomena. When this is done, the particular facts which 
 they contain are ready to be received into philosophy. This, 
 secondly, implies a certain compulsion on thought itself to pro- 
 ceed to these concrete specific truths. The reception into philo- 
 sophy of these scientific materials, now that thought has removed 
 its immediacy, and made it cease to be mere data forms at the 
 same time a development of thought out of itself. Philosophy 
 then owes its development to the empirical sciences. In return 
 it gives their contents what is so vital to them, the freedom of 
 thought — gives them, in short, an a priori character. These 
 contents are now warranted necessary, and no longer depend on 
 the evidence of facts merely, that they were so found and so 
 experienced. The fact of experience thus becomes an illustration 
 and image of the original and completely self-supporting activity 
 of thought." 
 
 36. The peculiar importance of this section lies in the emphasis 
 laid simultaneously on both the elements of the dialectic process. 
 On the one hand the start is definitely asserted, as in the quota- 
 tion from Section 9, to be made from experience. On the other 
 hand we are told that the result relates itself negatively towards 
 the point from which it draws its origin. This precludes on the 
 one side the theory that Hegel endeavoured to produce the 
 dialectic process by mere reflection on the nature of pure thought 
 in abstraction, and, on the other side, denies that a reference to 
 experience involves a merely empirical argument. The reception 
 into philosophy of the material furnished by science is declared 
 to be identical with the development of thought out of itself. 
 We are enabled also to understand correctly, by means of this 
 Section, certain expressions with regard to the dialectic process 
 which are occasionally interpreted by critics as meaning that 
 the medium of the Logic is abstract pure thought. For example, 
 here as in other places, Hegel repudiates the idea that "philo- 
 sophy is a child of experience, and owes its existence to an a 
 fosteriori element." Such an idea, we are told, is "unfair." Such 
 expressions might lead us to reject the theory of the dialectic 
 offered above, if it was not for the explanation which here 
 follows them. It is only unfair to say this, Hegel continues, in 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 39 
 
 the same sense in which it would be unfair to say that we owe 
 eating to the means of nourishment. Now it is unquestionable 
 that, without something to eat, eating is impossible, and if 
 eating does not depend on the existence of something to eat, it 
 follows that the existence of experience may be indispensable 
 to the existence of philosophy, although philosophy has been 
 declared not to depend on experience. Mediation, as Hegel uses 
 the word, is not equivalent to dependence, and it is possible for 
 thought to require a mediation by sense, and therefore to be 
 helpless without it, while it is nevertheless, in Hegelian ter- 
 minology, not in a state of dependence (Bedingtheit) on it. 
 Without the data which are supplied to us by sense, the dialectic 
 could not exist. It is not, however, caused by those data, but 
 is necessarily combined with them in a higher unity. It is no 
 more dependent on them than any other abstraction from a whole 
 is on its fellow abstractions from the same whole. Each step 
 which it takes depends, as we have seen, on the relation which 
 the previous step bears to the goal of the process. The whole 
 process may thus fairly be said not to be dependent at all. 
 
 The independence of the idea of God is declared to rest on 
 its negation and exaltation above the empirical side of conscious- 
 ness. This independence cannot possibly mean, therefore, the 
 absence of all connection between the two, for to be related to 
 a thing even negatively, is, as Hegel himself points out on 
 occasion (as in his treatment of the ideas of finitude and infinity, 
 Section 95), itself a condition, and in this sense a dependence. 
 The independence here can only consist in the fact that, although 
 the beginning is in experience, which contains an empirical side, 
 yet in the result the idea of God is separated from the particular 
 empirical facts with which the process started, and is free from 
 all likeness to them, although they form its demonstration and 
 justification. Whether this is possible or not, it appears to be 
 this which Hegel means in asserting his dialectic to be independent 
 of all experience, and this is quite compatible with an experi- 
 ential basis. 
 
 It may be objected that in this Section Hegel is not speaking 
 of his own system, but of the origin of philosophy in general. 
 It is, no doubt, true that the origin of philosophy from a 
 
40 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 liistorical standpoint is one of the points discussed here. But if 
 we look at Section 14, we shall find that the two questions are 
 considered by Hegel as identical. "The same evolution of 
 thought," he says, "which is exhibited in the history of philo- 
 sophy is presented in the System of Philosophy itself." It is 
 clear, therefore, that he regards the process traced in Section 12 
 as one which is not only historically accurate but also philo- 
 sophically valid, and that he holds the relation of experience to 
 the dialectic, which is there defined, as that which really exists. 
 
 37. We find similar statements in his criticism of the In- 
 tuitionist School. In explaining their position, he says (Section 
 70), "What this theory asserts is that truth lies neither in the 
 Idea as a merely subjective thought, nor in mere being on its 
 own account; that mere being fer se, a being that is not of the 
 Idea, is the sensible and finite being of the world. Now all this 
 only affirms, without demonstration, that the Idea has truth 
 only by means of being, and being has truth only by means of 
 the Idea. The maxim of immediate knowledge rejects an in- 
 definite empty immediacy (and such is abstract being, or pure 
 unity taken by itself) and affirms in its stead the unity of the 
 Idea with being. And it acts rightly in so doing. But it is stupid 
 not to see that the unity of distinct terms or modes is not merely 
 a purely immediate unity, i.e. unity empty and indeterminate, 
 but that it involves the principle that one term has truth only 
 as mediated through the other, or, if the phrase be preferred, 
 that either term is only mediated with truth through the other." 
 
 On the one hand then he asserts that truth does not lie in 
 the idea as separated from the sensible and finite being of the 
 world. But the idea in its unity with the sensible and finite 
 being of the world is experience. This unity, however, is only 
 mediate — that is to say, it is not, as the Intuitionists supposed 
 it to be, perceived immediately, nor evident from the nature of 
 thought itself. It lies rather in the mediation of each with truth 
 only by means of the other, which supports the view asserted 
 above — that Hegel makes no attempt to use pure thought in 
 abstraction from the data of sense, but holds truth to lie only 
 in the whole from which these two elements are abstracted. 
 
 Hegel here denies one immediacy and admits another, both 
 
U] OF THE DIALECTIC 41 
 
 of which are called by the same name in English. He denies the 
 validity of intuition, if by intuition is meant Jacobi's unmittel- 
 bares Wissen, which perceives immediately the unity of thought 
 and being. But he admits that intuition, if we mean by it the 
 Kantian Anschauung, is essential to knowledge, for without 
 " the sensible and finite being of the world " the idea has no truth. 
 
 38. Bearing this in mind we are able to see that there is 
 nothing in Section 75 inconsistent with the position I have 
 attributed to Hegel. He there says, "It has been shown to be 
 untrue in fact to say that there is an immediate knowledge, a 
 knowledge without mediation either by means of something else 
 or in itself. It has also been explained to be false in fact to say 
 that thought advances through finite and conditioned categories 
 only, which are always mediated by something else, and to forget 
 that in the very act of mediation the mediation itself vanishes." 
 
 The first of these statements will present no difficulties, for 
 it is quite consistent to deny the existence of immediate know- 
 ledge, while admitting the existence of an immediate element in 
 knowledge. Indeed, the assertion that all knowledge consists in 
 the mediation of the immediate at once affirms that there is an 
 immediate, and denies that it is knowledge. 
 
 Hegel's reminder that in the act of mediation the mediation 
 itself vanishes does not concern us here. For we are now con- 
 sidering the basis on which the dialectic process rests, and not 
 the end which it reaches. The latter must be considered further 
 on. The fact that the dialectic process consists in mediating the 
 immediate is enough to show that it must have some relation 
 to experience, since only in experience can the immediate be 
 found. 
 
 39. Passing on to the Doctrine of the Notion, we have 
 (Section 166, lecture note): "The notion does not, as under- 
 standing supposes, stand still in its own immobility. It is rather 
 an infinite form, of boundless activity, as it were the punctum 
 saliens of all vitahty, and thereby self-differentiating (sich von 
 sich selbst unterscheidend). This disruption of the notion into 
 the difference of its constituent functions, — a disruption imposed 
 by the native act of the notion, is the judgment. A judgment 
 therefore, means the particularising of the notion. No doubt the 
 
42 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 notion is implicitly tlie particular. But in the notion as notion, 
 the particular is not yet explicit, and still remains in transparent 
 unity with the universal. Thus for example, as we remarked 
 before (Section 160, lecture note), the germ of a plant contains 
 I ^ its particular, such as root, branches, leaves, &c., but these 
 
 details are at first present only potentially, and are not realised 
 till the germ uncloses. This unclosing is, as it were, the judgment 
 of the plant. The illustration may also serve to show how neither 
 the notion nor the judgment is merely found in our head, or 
 merely framed by us. The notion is the very heart of things, 
 and makes them what they are. To form a notion of an object 
 means therefore to become aware of its notion; and when we 
 proceed to a criticism or judgment of the object, we are not 
 Hil performing a subjective act, and merely ascribing this or that 
 predicate to the object. We are, on the contrary, observing the 
 object in the specific character imposed by its notion." 
 
 This analogy may illustrate the view which we have been 
 considering. In the growth of a tree the positive element is in 
 the seed only. The air, earth, and water, although they are 
 necessary to the development of the tree, do not play a positive 
 part in its growth. It is the nature of the seed alone which 
 determines that a plant shall be produced, and what sort of 
 plant it shall be. But the surrounding conditions, of suitable 
 soil and so on, are conditions without which the seed cannot 
 realise the end of its nature. In this analogy, the seed will 
 correspond to the category of Being, the completely mature plant 
 to the Absolute Idea, and the air, earth, and water, to the matter 
 of intuition. If we look more closely, the resemblance to actual 
 plant life is not perfect, since different amounts of light, heat, 
 and manure will change the size and colour, though not the 
 ^i species of the flower, which gives to these surroundings a more 
 ''' active part than Hegel allows to the matter of intuition. But 
 since Hegel says, without restriction, that the germ of the plant 
 |u| contains its particulars, he must be supposed to ignore the 
 nil amount of quantitative change which depends on the circum- 
 ■i^ stances in which the plant is placed, and in this case the analogy 
 i J IS exact. 
 ^ The point of the comparison, if the above explanation is 
 
 ,!«( 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 43 
 
 correct, lies in the fact that the growth of the plant has certain 
 conditions which do not determine the nature of the develop- 
 ment, though without their presence the development could not 
 exist at all. That this is the point which Hegel wished to make 
 is rendered probable by his having taken as his example a case 
 of organic life. For in organic life we are able to distinguish 
 between the cause of growth and the essential conditions of it 
 in a way that would be impossible if we were considering an 
 event governed only by mechanical laws. In the latter case we 
 can only say that the cause is the sum of all the necessary con- 
 ditions, and we are unable to consider any one of them as more 
 fundamental than the others. But with organic life we have 
 introduced the idea of a final cause, and we are thus enabled 
 to distinguish between the positive cause and the conditions 
 which are necessary but not positive. Hegel's declaration that 
 the growth of the notion must be judged by the principles of 
 organic growth, enables us to make this distinction, without 
 which we should be unable to understand that the relation held ; 
 
 by the data of sense to the dialectic process should be indis- fp I 
 pensable, and yet negative. 
 
 40. Again (Section 232, lecture note) he says, "The necessity 
 which cognition (Erkennen) reaches by means of demonstration 
 is the reverse of what formed its starting-point. In its starting- 
 point cognition had a given and a contingent content ; but now, 
 at the close of its movement, it knows its content to be necessary. 
 This necessity is reached by means of subjective activity. 
 Similarly, subjectivity at starting was quite abstract, a bare 
 tabula rasa. It now shows itself as a modifying and determining 
 principle. In this way we pass from the idea of cognition to that 
 of will. The passage, as will be apparent on a closer examination, 
 means that the universal, to be truly apprehended, must be 
 apprehended as subjectivity, as a notion self -moving, active, 
 and form-imposing." Hegel is speaking here of finite cognition 
 at the point at which it passes over into volition. But he is 
 speaking of it before the change has yet been made, for the "it," 
 which knows its content to be necessary, can only be taken as 
 meaning cognition. The process here described starts with finite 
 cognition, which is not philosophy, but the ordinary thought of 
 
44 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [OH. 
 
 every-day life. By this process the passage is made to volition. 
 The advance lies in the fact that, while knowledge started from 
 the given and contingent, it now knows its content to be necessary. 
 But when this change has taken place in the content, cognition 
 has become philosophy. (Compare Section 9, quoted on p. 35 
 above. "The second defect is that the beginnings are in every 
 case data and postulates, neither accounted for nor deduced. 
 In both these points the form of necessity fails to get its due. 
 Hence, reflection whenever it sets itself to remedy these defects, 
 becomes speculative thinking, the thinking proper to philo- 
 sophy.") And the universal, under the form of subjectivity, 
 has been apprehended as a self-moving notion, which also shows 
 that by this point knowledge has become philosophy. And the 
 process by which it has advanced begins with the given and the 
 contingent, which can only be found in sense. The advance of 
 the dialectic towards the Absolute Idea has therefore a basis in 
 experience. 
 
 41. In Section 238, Hegel, in considering the organic elements 
 of the speculative method, states that its beginning is being or 
 immediacy. "When it means immediate being the beginning is 
 taken from intuition (Anschauung) and perception — the initial 
 stage in the analytical method of finite cognition. When it means 
 universality, it is the beginning of the synthetic method. But 
 since the Logical Idea (das Logische) is as much a universal as 
 it is in being, since it is as much presupposed by the notion as 
 the notion itself immediately is, its beginning is a synthetical 
 as well as an analytical beginning. 
 
 (Lecture note.) "Philosophical method is analytical as well 
 as synthetical, not indeed in the sense of a bare juxtaposition 
 or mere alternating employment of these two methods of finite 
 cognition, but rather in such a way that it holds them merged 
 in itself. In every one of its movements, therefore, it displays 
 an attitude at once analytical and synthetical. Philosophic 
 thought proceeds analytically, in so far as it only accepts its 
 object, the Idea, and while allowing it its own way is only, as 
 it were, an onlooker at its movement and development. To this 
 extent philosophising is wholly passive. Philosophic thought, 
 however, is equally synthetic, and evinces itself to be the action 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 45 
 
 of the notion itself. To that end, however, there is required an 
 effort to keep back the incessant impertinence of our own fancies 
 and private opinions." 
 
 Continuing the same subject, he says in Section 239, "The 
 advance renders explicit the judgment implicit in the Idea. The 
 immediate universal, as the notion implicit, is the dialectical 
 force, which on its own part deposes its immediacy and uni- 
 versality to the level of a mere stage or 'moment.' Thus is 
 produced the negative of the beginning, the original datum is 
 made determinate: it exists for something, as related to those 
 things which are distinguished from it — the stage of Reflection. 
 
 "Seeing that the immanent dialectic only states explicitly what 
 was involved in the immediate notion, this advance is analytical, 
 but seeing that in this notion this distinction was not yet stated, 
 it is equally synthetical. 
 
 (Lecture note.) "In the advance of the idea the beginning 
 exhibits itself as what it implicitly is. It is seen to be mediated 
 and derivative, and neither to have proper being nor proper 
 immediacy. It is only for the consciousness which is itself 
 immediate, that Nature forms the commencement or immediacy, 
 and that Spirit appears as what is mediated by Nature. The truth 
 is that Nature is due to the statuting of Spirit, (das durch den 
 Geist Gesetzte,) and it is Spirit itself which gives itself a pre- 
 supposition in Nature." 
 
 42. In this passage the double foundation of the dialectic is 
 clearly admitted, and its connection with the double aspect of 
 the process is made clear. We must have, in the first place, pure 
 thought given to us as a fact — we cannot know the nature of 
 thought unless thinking has taken place. From one point of 
 view, then, the dialectic process is the observation of a subject 
 matter already before us. In this aspect philosophy "allows the 
 idea its own way" and "is only, as it were, an onlooker at its 
 movement and development." And in so far as this is so we have 
 the unequivocal declaration that "the beginning is taken from 
 sensation or perception" — since pure thought is never found 
 except as an element in the whole of experience. But at the 
 same time the process is not merely one of empirical selection 
 of first one character and then another from the concrete whole. 
 
46 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [cm 
 
 When once the first and simplest judgment has been made about 
 experience — the judgment which is involved in the application 
 of the category of Being — the various steps of the dialectic 
 process will grow by an inner necessity out of that judgment. 
 This judgment will be the beginning as universality, as the other 
 aspect was the beginning as immediate being; and, in so far as 
 the beginning is universal, the process is synthetic and "evinces 
 itself to be the action of the notion itself." 
 
 The explanation of the union of the two processes lies in the 
 fact that the reality present to our minds in experience is always 
 the full and concrete notion. This is the logical frius of the move- 
 ment, although the unanalysed mass and the abstract notion of 
 Being may be the temporal 'prius in that stage of finite reflection 
 which precedes philosophy. "In the onward movement of the 
 idea the beginning exhibits itself as what it is implicitly. It is 
 seen to be mediated and derivative, and neither to have proper 
 being nor proper immediacy." And again, in Section 242, the 
 notion "is the idea, which, as absolutely first (in the method) 
 regards this terminus as merely the annihilation of the show or 
 semblance, which made the beginning appear immediate, and 
 made itself seem a result. It is the knowledge that the idea is 
 one systematic whole." All less complete ideas are illegitimate 
 abstractions from this whole, and naturally tend therefore to 
 approximate to it. And such a process may be viewed from two 
 sides. It may be regarded from the point of view of the whole — 
 in which case the dialectic process will be viewed as gradually 
 retracing the steps of abstraction which had led to the idea of 
 pure Being, and rebuilding the concrete object till it again co- 
 incided with reality. Or it may be regarded from the point of 
 view of the incomplete and growing notion, when the advance 
 will seem to be purely out of the notion itself. " Seeing that the 
 immanent dialectic only states explicitly what was involved in 
 the immediate notion, this advance is analytical, but seeing that 
 in this notion this distinction was not yet stated, it is equally 
 synthetical." 
 
 And these two aspects — the analytic from the standpoint of 
 the concrete and perfect notion, and the synthetic from the 
 standpoint of the yet imperfect notion, — correspond respectively 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 47 
 
 to aspects for which the beginning is taken from sensation or 
 perception, and from the action of the notion itself. In so far 
 as we look on the motive force of the dialectic process as residing 
 in the completeness of the concrete notion, the process depends 
 on the contemplation of reality and therefore of sensation and 
 perception. For the sensation, although contributing no positive 
 element to the process, is the necessary condition of our becoming 
 conscious of the nature of thought. But in so far as we look on 
 the motive force of the process as supplied by the incompleteness 
 of the growing notion, we shall bring into prominence the fact 
 that the process is after all one of pure thought. And we only 
 get a true view of the whole when we combine the two and see 
 that the stimulus is in the relation of the abstract and explicit 
 idea to the complete and implicit idea, that the process is one of 
 pure thought perceived in a medium of sensation and therefore 
 synthetic and analytic at once. 
 
 43. To this we may add the following extract from the 
 Philosophy of Spirit (Encyclopaedia, Section 447, lecture note), 
 *'In sensation there is present the whole Reason — the collected 
 material of Spirit. All our images, thoughts, and ideas, of ex- 
 ternal nature, of justice, of ethics, and of the content of religion, 
 develop themselves from our intelligence as used in sensation; 
 as they themselves, on the other hand, when they have received 
 their complete explanation are again concentrated in the simple 
 form of sensation.... This development of Spirit out of sensation, 
 however, has commonly been understood as if the intelhgence 
 was originally completely empty, and therefore received all 
 content from outside as something quite strange to it. This is 
 a mistake. For that which the intelligence appears to take in 
 from outside is in reality nothing else than the reasonable, which 
 is therefore identical with spirit, and immanent in it. The activity 
 of spirit has therefore no other goal, except, by the removal of 
 the apparent externality to self of the implicitly reasonable 
 object, to remove also the apparent externaUty of the object 
 to spirit." 
 
 Here we learn that the reasonable, with which the Logic deals, 
 is first given to us in sensation, and as apparently external to 
 self, and that it is by starting from that which is given in 
 
48 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [CH. 
 
 sensation that we learn the nature of spirit. To act in this way 
 is a fundamental characteristic of spirit — "the activity of spirit 
 has no other goal" — and therefore it must be in this way that 
 our minds act when they are engaged on the dialectic process. 
 
 44. I have endeavoured to show, by the consideration of these 
 passages from Hegel's writings, that his method possesses two 
 characteristics. These are, first, that it is a process of pure 
 thought, but only possible in the presence of matter of intuition ; 
 second, that the motive force of the whole process is involved 
 in the relation between the incomplete form of the notion, which 
 at any moment may be explicitly before us, and the complete 
 form which is present imphcitly in all our thought as in all other 
 reality. 
 
 We must now pass to another question. The vaHdity of each 
 stage of the dialectic, as we have seen, depended on the one 
 before, and all of them ultimately on the first stage — the category 
 of Being. The validity of this again we found to depend on the 
 fact that its denial would be suicidal^. 
 
 Now it must be admitted that this is a mere inference, and 
 not explicitly stated by Hegel. Such a statement would be most 
 natural at the beginning of the whole dialectic process, but it 
 is neither there nor elsewhere. No justification whatever is given 
 of the idea of Being. It is merely assumed and all the consequences 
 that follow from it, however cogent in themselves, are left, so 
 to speak, suspended in the air with no explicit argument any- 
 where to attach them to reality. The explanation of this strange 
 peculiarity is, I think, largely to be found in the state of philo- 
 sophy at the time when Hegel wrote. 
 
 45. The argument of the dialectic could, if the theory in 
 the previous chapter is correct, have been arranged as follows. 
 The basis of the whole would be the existence of the 
 world of experience, which no sceptic can wholly deny, since 
 denial itself always imphes the existence of something. The 
 barest admission that could be made, however, with regard 
 to this world of experience, would involve that it should be 
 brought under the category of Being, whose validity would be 
 therefore granted. But as, in the process of the dialectic, the 
 
 1 Chap. I. Section 18. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 49 
 
 category of Being developed contradictions which led up to fresh 
 categories, and so on, the validity of these categories also, as 
 applied to reality, must be granted, since they follow from the 
 validity of the category of Being. 
 
 Kant, who had to establish his system in the face of sceptical 
 criticism, naturally emphasised the transcendental character of 
 the argument, and the cogency with which his conclusions could 
 be applied to the world of reality, involved as they were in 
 propositions which his adversaries were not prepared to dispute. 
 But Hegel's position was different. He lived in an age of Idealism, 
 when the pure scepticism of Hume had ceased to be a living 
 force, and when it was a generally accepted view that the mind 
 was adequate to the knowledge of reality. Under such cir- 
 cumstances Hegel would naturally lay stress on the conclusions 
 of his system, in which he more or less differed from his con- 
 temporaries, rather than on the original premises, in which he 
 chiefly agreed with them, and would point out how far the end 
 was from the beginning, rather than how clearly it might be 
 derived from it. To this must be added Hegel's marked preference 
 for a constructive, rather than a polemical treatment, which 
 appears so strongly in all his works^. But this has exposed his 
 system to severe disadvantages in the reaction against all Idealism 
 which has taken place since his death. For the transcendental 
 form becomes necessary when the attacks of scepticism have to 
 be met, and its absence, though due chiefly to the special char- 
 acter of the audience to whom the philosophy was first addressed, 
 has led to the reproaches which have been so freely directed 
 against Absolute Idealism, as a mere fairy tale, or as a theory 
 with internal consistency, but without any relation to facts. 
 
 The same causes may perhaps account for the prominence of 
 the synthetic over the analytic aspect of the dialectic, which may 
 be noticed occasionally throughout the Logic. The criticism of 
 idealists would naturally be devoted more to the internal con- 
 sistency of the system than to its right to exist at all, on which 
 point they would probably have no objection to raise. To meet 
 such criticisms it would be necessary to lay emphasis on the 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. I have omitted a sentence which implied that 
 Hegel's arguments were transcendental in the Kantian sense. 
 
 M.H. 4 
 
50 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 synthetic side of the process, while to us, who in most cases 
 approach the whole question from a comparatively negative 
 standpoint, it would seem more natural to bring forward the 
 analytic side, and to show that the whole system was involved 
 in any admission of the existence of reality. 
 
 46. Hegel speaks of his logic as without any pre-supposition. 
 This is taken by Trendelenburg as equivalent to an assertion that 
 it has no basis in experience. But we have seen that the only 
 postulate which Hegel assumed was the validity of the category 
 of Being — that is, the existence of something. Now this, though 
 not directly proved, can scarcely be said to be assumed, if it is 
 involved in all other assertions. And a system which requires 
 no other postulate than this might fairly be said to have no pre- 
 supposition. The very fact that the argument exists proves that 
 it was entitled to its assumption, for if the argument exists, then 
 the category of Being has validity, at any rate, of one thing — 
 the argument itself. And this is compatible with all the relation 
 to experience which the dialectic needs, or will admit. 
 
 A parallel case will be found in Hegel's criticism of Kant's 
 refutation of the ontological argument^. He there treats the 
 actual existence of God, who for him is equivalent to the Absolute 
 Reality, as a matter which can be passed over in silence, since 
 its denial — the denial of any reality in the universe — is suicidal. 
 It is really the same fact — the existence of some reality — which, 
 under another aspect, is assumed at the beginning of the Logic. 
 We may reasonably suppose that Hegel treated it in the same 
 way, holding that a postulate which could not be denied without 
 self-contradiction need not be considered as a pre-supposition 
 at all. From all more particular pre-suppositions he doubtless 
 claims that his logic is free. But this claim is not incompatible 
 with the relation of the dialectic to experience, which was 
 suggested in the last chapter. 
 
 It must also be noted that Hegel says of the proofs of the 
 existence of God which are derived from the finite world "the 
 process of exaltation might thus appear to be transition, and to 
 involve a means, but it is not a whit less true that every trace 
 of transition and means is absorbed, since the world, which 
 1 Cp. Sections 63, 64. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 51 
 
 might have seemed to be the means of reaching God, is explained 
 to be a nullity '^Z' And in Section 12, in the passage quoted above, 
 he tells us that philosophy is unfairly said to be the child of 
 experience, since it "involves a negative attitude to the initial 
 acts of the senses." Now in the Logic the result certainly stands 
 in a negative relation to the beginning, for the inadequacy of 
 the category of Being to express reality has been demonstrated 
 in the course of the dialectic. The category of Being would then, 
 in Hegel's language, have been absorbed, and it would be unfair 
 to say that the dialectic depended on it. Under these circum- 
 stances it is only natural that he should not call its validity a 
 pre-supposition. 
 
 47. There is, then, a constant relation to experience through- 
 out the course of the dialectic. But, even if this is so, does that 
 relation remain at the end of the process? It has been asserted 
 that, although throughout the Logic Hegel may treat thought 
 as mediate, and as only existing as an element in a whole of which 
 the other element is an immediate datum, yet, when we reach 
 the Absolute Idea, that Idea is held to be self-centred and capable 
 of existing by itself in abstraction from everything else. It must 
 be admitted that such a transition would be unjustifiable^, but 
 I am unable to see any reason to suppose that Hegel held any 
 such belief. 
 
 We must discriminate between those characteristics of the 
 immediate element of experience which are indispensable if 
 experience is to be constituted at all, and those which are not 
 indispensable. The essential characteristics may all be summed 
 up in immediacy. All thought that we know, or that we can 
 conceive, has its action only in mediation, and its existence 
 without something immediate on which it may act would be a 
 contradiction. On the other hand it is not essential that this 
 immediate should be also contingent. "The contingent may be 
 described as what has the ground of its being, not in itself, but 
 in somewhat else^." Now it is quite possible that, in a more 
 advanced state of knowledge, we might be able to trace back all 
 the data immediately given in experience till we had referred 
 
 1 Enc. Section 50. ^ Cp. Chap. ra. Section 99. 
 
 ' Enc. Section 145, lecture note. 
 
52 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [CH. 
 
 them to an individuality or organic whole from the nature of 
 which they could all be deduced. Contingency would be here 
 eliminated, for all experience would be referred to a single unity 
 and determined by its notion. The only question which could 
 then arise would be, "Why was the ultimate nature of reality 
 thus and not otherwise? " The question would, no doubt, be one 
 to which no answer could be given. This would not, however, 
 render the nature of reality in any way contingent. For such 
 a question would be meaningless. Enquiries as to the reasons of 
 things have their place only within the universe, whose existence 
 they presuppose. We have no right to make them with regard 
 to the universe itself. Thus in the case we have supposed con- 
 tingency would be entirely eliminated, yet immediacy would 
 remain untouched. We should still know reality, not by thought 
 alone, but because it was given to us. 
 
 48. It seems probable that Hegel did suppose that the Absolute 
 Idea, when completely realised, involved the elimination of the 
 contingent, w^hich indeed he treats^ as part of a lower category, 
 which is, of course, transcended in the highest. It may certainly 
 be doubted whether human knowledge could ever attain, as a 
 matter of fact, to this height of perfection. In particular, it may 
 be asked whether such a state of knowledge would not require 
 other means than our present senses for the perception of reality 
 outside ourselves. But whether the elimination of Contingency 
 is or is not possible, the point which is important to us here is 
 that, should it take place, it does not involve the elimination of 
 the immediate, and therefore does not prove that Hegel had any 
 intention of declaring thought to be self-sufficing, even when it 
 reached the Absolute Idea. 
 
 In the stage immediately before the Absolute Idea — that of 
 ordinary cognition and volition — it is evident that the idea is 
 not self-sufficing, since it is certain that we can neither think 
 nor resolve in every-day life without some immediate data. Now 
 the point of transition between this category and the Absolute 
 Idea is stated to be "the unity of the theoretical and practical 
 idea, and thus at the same time the unity of the idea of life with 
 that of cognition. In cognition we had the idea in the shape of 
 1 Enc. Section 145. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 53 
 
 differentiation. The process of cognition has issued in the over- 
 throw of this differentiation, and the restoration of that unity 
 which, as unity, and in its immediacy, is in the first instance 
 the Idea of Life^." In this there is nothing which tends to the 
 elimination of immediacy, or to the self-sufficiency of thought, 
 but only the complete discovery in the outside world of the pure 
 thought which is also in us. 
 
 Again, in the idea of Life, thought is certainly not self-sufficing, 
 since one of the essential characteristics of this category is that 
 the soul is in relation to a body, which involves, of course, sensa- 
 tion. Now the Absolute Idea is a synthesis of this category and 
 the category of Cognition. Thought is mediate in both of these. 
 How then can it be immediate in the synthesis? The correction 
 of inadequacies in the Hegelian logic comes by the emphasis of 
 one side in the thesis and of the other in the antithesis, the 
 synthesis reconciling the two. The synthesis, throughout the 
 entire dialectic, can only advance on the thesis and antithesis 
 on points in which they disagree with one another. On points 
 in which they agree it can make no change. And when, in 
 Absolute Spirit, Hegel reaches that which he unquestionably 
 believes to be self-mediated and self-sufficing, he only does so 
 because it is a synthesis of the mediating logic and the element 
 of immediacy or "givenness" which first occurs in nature. But 
 within the logic there is no immediacy to balance the admitted 
 mere mediacy of the finite categories, and the distinction of 
 mediacy and immediacy cannot therefore, within the logic, be 
 transcended. 
 
 49. We find no sign again of transcended mediation in the 
 direct definition of the Absolute Idea. "Dieses aus der Dif^erenz 
 und Endlichkeit des Erkennens zu sich zuriickgekommene und 
 durch die Thatigkeit des Begriffs mit ihm identisch gewordene 
 Leben ist die speculative oder absolute Idee. Die Idee als Einheit 
 der subjectiven und der objectiven Idee ist der Begriff der Idee, 
 dem die Idee als solche der Gegenstand, dem das Objekt sie ist; 
 ein Objekt, in welches alle Bestimmungen zusammen gegangen 
 sind2." 
 
 The second sentence of the definition asserts that the idea is 
 1 Enc. Section 236, lecture note. ^ Enr. Sections 235, 236. 
 
54 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 the "Gegenstand und Objekt" to the notion of the idea. This 
 cannot, it appears to me, be taken as equivalent to a statement 
 that thought here becomes self-subsistent and self-mediating. 
 It seems rather to signify that that which is immediately given 
 to thought to mediate, is now known to be itself thought, although 
 still immediately given. In other words, the Absolute Idea is 
 realised when the thinker sees in the whole world round him 
 nothing but the realisation of the same idea which forms his own 
 essential nature — is at once conscious of the existence of the 
 other, and of its fundamental similarity to himself. The expression 
 that the idea as such is the object to the notion of the idea seems 
 rather to support this view by indicating that the idea as object 
 is viewed in a different aspect from the idea as subject. If im- 
 mediacy was here gained by thought, so that it required no 
 object given from outside, it would have been more natural to 
 say that the idea was its own object, or indeed that the dis- 
 tinction of subject and object had vanished altogether. 
 
 If this is the correct interpretation of this passage, then 
 thought remains, for Hegel, in the Absolute Idea, what it has 
 been in all the finite categories. Although the content of all 
 experience contains, in such a case, nothing which is not a mani- 
 festation of the pure Absolute Idea, yet to every subject in whom 
 that idea is realised, the idea is presented in the form of immediate 
 data, which are mediated by the subject's own action. The 
 fundamental nature of subject and object is the same, but the 
 distinction between them remains in their relation to one another. 
 
 No doubt Hegel regards as the highest ideal of the dialectic 
 process something which shall be self-mediated, and in which 
 mediation as an external process vanishes. But this he finds in 
 Absolute Spirit, which is a synthesis of the Absolute Idea with 
 the element of immediate presentation. The Absolute Idea is 
 still an abstraction, as compared with the whole of Absolute 
 Spirit, and is not self-mediated. 
 
 50. We have now to consider the third objection which has 
 been raised to the theory of Hegel's meaning explained in the 
 first chapter. This objection is that Hegel has ascribed ontological 
 validity to his dialectic to a greater extent than this theory 
 admits, and that he has attempted to account by pure thought. 
 
II] OF THE DIALECTIC 55 
 
 not only for the rationality, but also for the entire existence of 
 the universe. This is maintained by Professor Seth, who objects 
 to the system chiefly, it would seem, on this ground. He says, 
 for example, "Hegel apparently says, on one occasion, that his 
 own elaborate phraseology means no more than the ancient 
 position that vov<i rules the world, or the modern phrase, there 
 is Reason in the world ^. If the system is reducible to this very 
 general proposition, our objections would certainly fall to the 
 ground^." 
 
 Somewhat earlier he expresses the position, which he believes 
 Hegel to hold, with great force and clearness, Hegel " apparently 
 thinks it incumbent upon him to prove that spirit exists by a 
 necessity of thought. The concrete existence of the categories (in 
 Nature and Spirit) is to be deduced from their essence or thought- 
 nature ; it is to be shown that they cannot not be. When we have 
 mounted to the Absolute Idea, it is contended, we cannot help 
 going further. The nisus of thought itself projects thought out 
 of the sphere of thought altogether into that of actual existence. 
 In fact, strive against the idea as we may, it seems indubitable 
 that there is here once more repeated in Hegel the extraordinary 
 but apparently fascinating attempt to construct the world out 
 of abstract thought or mere universals^." 
 
 51. The passages from which most information on this point 
 are to be expected will be those in the Greater and Smaller 
 Logics, in which the transition to the world of Nature is de- 
 scribed. These are quoted and abridged as follows by Professor 
 Seth. "'The Absolute Idea is still logical, still confined to the 
 element of pure thoughts.... But inasmuch as the pure idea of 
 knowledge is thus, so far, shut up in a species of subjectivity, 
 it is impelled to remove this limitation ; and thus the pure truth, 
 the last result of the logic, becomes also the beginning of another 
 sphere and science^.' The Idea, he recalls to us, has been defined 
 as 'the absolute unity of the pure notion and its reality' — 'the 
 pure notion which is related only to itself; but if this is so, the 
 two sides of this relation are one, and they collapse, as it were, 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 24, lecture note. 
 
 2 Hegelianism and Personality, pp. 124, 125. ' op. cit. pp. 110, 111. 
 
 * Werke, v. pp. 352, 353. 
 
56 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 'into the immediacy of Being.' 'The Idea as the totality in this 
 form is Nature. This determining of itself, however, is not a 
 process of becoming, or a transition ' such as we have from stage 
 to stage in the Logic. 'The passing over is rather to be under- 
 stood thus — that the Idea freely lets itself go, being absolutely 
 sure of itself and at rest in itself. On account of this freedom, 
 the form of its determination is likewise absolutely free — namely, 
 the externality of space and time existing absolutely for itself 
 without subjectivity.' A few lines lower he speaks of the ' resolve 
 (Entschluss) of the pure Idea to determine itself as external 
 Idea.' Turning to the Encyclopaedia we find, at the end of the 
 Smaller^Logic^, a more concise but substantially similar state- 
 ment. ' The Idea which exists for itself, looked at from the point 
 of view of this unity with itself, is Perception ; and the Idea as 
 it exists for perception is Nature... The absolute /reet^om of the 
 Idea consists in this, that in the absolute truth of itself (i.e., 
 according to Hegel's usage, when it has attained the full per- 
 fection of the form which belongs to it) 'it resolves to let the 
 element of its particularity — the immediate Idea as its own 
 reflection — go forth freely from itself as Nature.' And in the 
 lecture note which follows we read, as in the Larger Logic, ' We 
 have now returned to the notion of the Idea with which we 
 began. This return to the beginning is also an advance. That 
 with which we began was Being, abstract Being, and now we have 
 the Idea as Being; but this existent Idea is Nature^.' " 
 
 52. It is certainly possible at first sight to take these passages 
 as supporting Professor Seth's theory. But we must consider 
 that, according to that theory, Hegel is made to occupy a position, 
 not only paradoxical and untenable, but also inconsistent. If, 
 as I have endeavoured to show above, and as is admitted by 
 Professor Seth, Hegel fully recognises the fact that the whole 
 dialectic movement of pure thought only takes place in that 
 concrete whole in which sense data are a moment correlative 
 with pure thought — because thought could not exist at all with- 
 out immediate data — how can he suppose that the movement of 
 pure thought produces the sensations which are the conditions 
 of its own existence? Are we not bound to adopt any other 
 ^ Enc. Section 244. * Hegelianism and Personality, pp. 105, 106. 
 
II] OF THE DIALECTIC 57 
 
 explanation, rather than suppose him guilty of such a glaring 
 contradiction? 
 
 Such an explanation was offered in the last chapter^, where 
 it was pointed out that, as the comparison of the abstract idea 
 with the concrete idea was the origin of the dialectic movement 
 within the Logic, so the comparison of the concrete idea with 
 the full whole of reality, compared with which the concrete 
 notion itself was an abstraction, was the origin of the transition 
 from Logic to Nature and Spirit — a transition in which there 
 was no attempt to construct the world out of abstract thought, 
 because the foundation of the argument was the presence, 
 implicit in all experience, of the concrete reality whose necessity 
 was being demonstrated. 
 
 Such a theory, at one time. Professor Seth was willing to 
 accept as correct, and now considers as "the explanation which 
 a conciliatory and soberminded Hegelian would give of Hegel's 
 remarkable tour deforced His account is substantially the same 
 as that given above. " Here, again, then, as throughout the Logic, 
 it might be said we are merely undoing the work of abstraction 
 and retracing our steps towards concrete fact. This, as we have 
 seen, implies the admission that it is our experiential knowledge 
 of actual fact which is the real motive-force impelling us onward 
 — impelling us here from the abstract determinations of the 
 Logic to the (/^asi-reaUty of Nature, and thence to the full 
 reality of spirit. It is because we ourselves are spirits that we 
 cannot stop short of that consummation. In this sense we can 
 understand the feeling of ' hmitation ' or incompleteness of which 
 Hegel speaks at the end of the Logic. The pure form craves, as 
 it were, for its concrete realisation^." 
 
 He subsequently, however, rejects this position, and indeed 
 seems scarcely to see its full meaning. For his "soberminded 
 Hegehan," who accepts this reading, will, he informs us, "lay 
 as little stress as possible upon the so-called deduction. Further 
 reflection," he continues, "has convinced me, however, that 
 Hegel's contention here is of more fundamental import to his 
 system than such a representation allows. Perhaps it may even 
 be said, that, when we surrender this deduction, though we may 
 1 Section 26. * op. cit. pp. 108, 109. 
 
58 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 retain much that is valuable in Hegel's thought, we surrender 
 the system as a whole. For, however readily he may admit, 
 when pressed, that in the ordo ad individimm experience is the 
 quarry from which all the materials are derived, it must not be 
 forgotten that he professes to offer us an absolute philosophy. 
 And it is the characteristic of an absolute philosophy that every- 
 thing must be deduced or constructed as a necessity of thought. 
 Hegel's system, accordingly, is so framed as to elude the necessity 
 of resting anywhere on mere fact. It is not enough for him to 
 take self-conscious intelligence as an existent fact, by reflection 
 on whose action in his own conscious experience and in the 
 history of the race certain categories are disclosed, reducible by 
 philosophic insight to a system of mutually connected notions, 
 which may then be viewed as constituting the essence or formal 
 structure of reason. He apparently thinks it incumbent on him 
 to prove that spirit exists by a necessity of thought. The con- 
 crete existence of the categories (in Nature and Spirit) is to be 
 deduced from their essence or thought-nature : it is to be shown 
 they cannot not be^." 
 
 53. Now in this passage there are two separate charges made 
 against Hegel, which Professor Seth apparently thinks are 
 identical. The one is that "thought of its own abstract nature 
 gives birth to the reality of things," that is, that, given thought, 
 Nature and Spirit can be deduced. That they are deduced from 
 thought in some way cannot be denied, but Professor Seth 
 rejects the idea that the deduction is partly analytical, and 
 declares that Hegel endeavoured to demonstrate the existence 
 of the worlds of Nature and Spirit by pure synthesis from the 
 world of Logic. But this is not all. Hegel is also accused of 
 endeavouring to prove "the concrete existence of the categories 
 from their essence.'' This is properly a second charge. But 
 Professor Seth appears to identify it with the first, by speak- 
 ing of the concrete existence as "in nature and spirit," and 
 by making essence identical with the nature of thought. This 
 identification is, I venture to think, unjustifiable. 
 
 In the first place every proposition about Nature and Spirit 
 is not one which involves real existence. We might say, for 
 1 op. cit. pp. 109, 110. 
 
II] OF THE DIALECTIC 59 
 
 example, "Dragons must occupy space," or "Angels must have 
 some way of gaining immediate knowledge." Both propositions 
 might be perfectly correct, even if neither dragons nor angels 
 existed, because our propositions would deal only with essence. 
 They might be put in a hypothetical form, such as, "If there 
 were dragons, they would occupy space." (In this discussion I 
 adopt Professor Seth's use of the word essence to signify the 
 nature of a thing, which remains the same, whether the thing 
 exists or not. It must not, of course, be confounded with Hegel's 
 use of the same word to denote the second stage of the Logic, 
 which merely describes one stage among others in what Professor 
 Seth would call the essence of thought.) 
 
 On the other hand, as we have seen above, a proposition 
 relating to pure thought may refer to real existence. " Being is 
 synthesised in Becoming" is such a proposition, for the category 
 of Being is applicable, we know, to real existence. And as the 
 essences of Being and Becoming are united, and as the existence 
 of Being has been proved, we are able to state the proposition 
 concerning the relation of Being and Becoming as one of real 
 existence. 
 
 The confusion of real existence with the worlds of Nature 
 and Spirit is not inexplicable. For all real existence has its 
 immediate side, and must therefore be presented by sense, outer 
 or inner, while thought, again, is correlative to sense, and, so 
 to speak opposed to it, both being complementary elements in 
 experience. Thought consequently gets taken as if it was opposed 
 to real existence. But the fact of the existence of thought can 
 be presented to us by inner sense as something immediate, and 
 we are then as sure of its real existence as we could be of anything 
 in the world of Nature. The office of thought is to mediate ; but 
 it actually exists, or it could not mediate; and in virtue of its 
 actual existence any instance of thought may be immediately 
 known; in which case it is mediated by other thought. The 
 existence of logic proves in itself that we can think about thought. 
 Thought therefore can become a datum, and its real existence can 
 be known. It is true that it is an abstraction, and that its real 
 existence is only as an element of experience. But this is true 
 also of the particulars of sense. 
 
60 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 54. Since, then, propositions concerning Nature and Spirit 
 may be really "essential and hypothetical" while propositions 
 concerning pure thought may deal with real existence, it follows 
 that the deduction of Nature and Spirit from Logic does not 
 necessarily involve the fallacious attempt to argue from essence 
 to existence. This is the case whether the deduction is both 
 analytic and synthetic in its nature, as I have endeavoured to 
 maintain, or is of a purely synthetic nature, as Professor Seth 
 supposes. 
 
 On the first of these suppositions the argument might have 
 been merely from the essence of thought to the essence of Nature. 
 In that case the final conclusion would have run, thought cannot 
 exist without Nature, or, if there is thought there is Nature. 
 Hegel, however, was not satisfied with such a meagre result, and 
 his argument is from existence to existence. The course of the 
 Logic, in the first place, may be summed up thus — we have an 
 immediate certainty that something exists, consequently the 
 category of Being is valid of reality. But the Absolute Idea is 
 involved in the category of Being. Therefore the Absolute Idea 
 is applicable to that which really exists, and we can predicate 
 reality of that Idea. After this follows the transition to the world 
 of Nature, which is of a similar character. The Absolute Idea 
 really exists. But it (since it is of the nature of thought) can 
 only exist in combination with data of sense. Therefore data of 
 sense really exist. Thus the conclusion certainly deals with real 
 existence, but that character has been given to the argument, 
 not by any juggling with pure thought, but by a premise at the 
 beginning relating to real existence — namely, that something must 
 exist. The evidence for this proposition is immediate, for it rests 
 on the impossibility of denying it without asserting at the same 
 time the reality at least of the denial and of the thinker. And 
 this assertion depends on the immediately given, for the existence 
 of the words or ideas which form the denial are perceived by 
 sense, outer or inner, while the existence of the thinker is an 
 inference from, or rather an implication in, the fact that he has 
 sensations or thoughts, of the existence of which — thoughts as 
 well as sensations — he has immediate knowledge. 
 
 The same would be the case if the deduction were purely 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 61 
 
 synthetic, one which endeavoured to make the world of Nature 
 and Spirit a mere consequence and result of the world of thought. 
 The argument would be invalid for reasons which we shall pre- 
 sently notice, but not because it attempted to pass from essence 
 to existence. For we have every right to believe that thought 
 exists, and it is from this existent thought (the presence of which 
 within the Logic passes unchallenged by Professor Seth) that 
 Hegel passes on to Nature and Spirit. 
 
 The two charges then — of deducing Nature and Spirit merely 
 from thought, and of deducing existence from essence — are by 
 no means identical, and must be taken separately. It will perhaps 
 be more convenient to begin with the first, which is the less 
 sweeping of the two. 
 
 55. "Thought out of its own abstract nature gives birth to 
 the reality of things" says Professor Seth in his criticism, and, 
 if this is Hegel's meaning, we must certainly admit that he has 
 gone too far. Thought is, in its essential nature, mediate. As 
 Trendelenburg remarks^ the immediacy of certain ideas in the 
 dialectic is only comparative and equivalent to self-mediation. 
 Real immediacy belongs to nothing but the data of intuition. 
 And therefore thought cannot exist unless it has something 
 immediately given which it may mediate. It is, of course, per- 
 fectly true that the immediate cannot remain unmediated. The 
 only merely immediate thing is the pure sensation, and the pure 
 sensation taken by itself cannot become part of experience, and 
 therefore, since it has certainly no existence out of experience, 
 does not exist at all. But although immediacy, as such, is a mere 
 abstraction, so is mediation, and, therefore, thought. Green's 
 extraordinary suggestion that "the notion that an event in the 
 way of sensation is something over and above its conditions may 
 be a mistake of ours^," and again that "for the only kind of 
 consciousness for which there is reality, the conceived conditions 
 are the reality," ignores the fact that the ideal of knowledge 
 would in this case be a mass of conditions which conditioned 
 nothing, and of relations with nothing to relate. Such an eleva- 
 tion of an abstraction into an independent reality is not excelled 
 
 ^ Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. i. p. CS, 
 2 Works, Vol. n. p. 190. 
 
62 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [CH. 
 
 in audacity by any of the parallel fallacies of materialism, against 
 which Green was never weary of protesting. 
 
 But if thought is a mere element in the whole of reality, having 
 no more independent existence than mere sense has, it is certainly 
 impossible that thought should produce reality — that the sub- 
 stantial and individual should depend on an abstraction formed 
 from itself. And this is what Hegel believed, if we are to accept 
 Professor Seth's statement. 
 
 56. This theory is rendered the more remarkable by the 
 admission that, within the Logic, the deduction has that analytic 
 aspect which is required to make it valid. "The forward move- 
 ment is in reaUty a movement backward: it is a retracing of 
 our steps to the world as we know it in the fulness of its real 
 determinations^." Can we believe that Hegel, after using one 
 method of dialectic process to display the nature of pure thought, 
 employs the same dialectic in an absolutely different sense when 
 he wishes to pass from logic to nature? Logic, Nature, and Spirit 
 are declared to be thesis, antithesis, and synthesis ; so are Being, 
 Not-Being, and Becoming. In the case of the latter it is admitted 
 that the true reality lies only in the synthesis, and that no 
 attempt is made to construct it out of the thesis. What reason 
 is there for supposing such an attempt in the case of the more 
 comprehensive deduction which we are now discussing? 
 
 Professor Seth attempts to answer the question by drawing 
 a distinction between epistemology and ontology in this respect. 
 As to the former, he says, it may be true that Hegel held that 
 we only arrive at a knowledge of pure thought by abstraction 
 from experience, while yet it may be true that he considered that 
 the other element in experience was originally produced by, and 
 is in the objective world dependent on, pure thought. It is 
 perhaps worth remarking that this derives no countenance from 
 Sections 238 and 239 of the Encyclopaedia quoted above^, where 
 the union of analysis and synthesis is spoken of as "the philo- 
 sophic method" and as belonging to "philosophic thought" 
 without any suggestion that it only applies to one department 
 of philosophy. 
 
 But the distinction is one which would only be tenable if the 
 ^ Hegelianism and Personality, p. 92. ^ p^ 44^ 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 63 
 
 elements of which experience is composed were self-subsistent 
 entities, capable of existing apart as well as together. Thus it 
 might be said that, although in a certain experiment oxygen and 
 hydrogen were produced out of water, yet from a scientific point 
 of view we should rather consider them as the elements of which 
 water was made up, they, and not the water, being the ultimate 
 reality. But this analogy will not hold here. For the element 
 of immediacy — the datum given through sense — is as necessary 
 and essential to the existence of the idea, as the sides of a triangle 
 are to its angles. The existence of the immediate element is 
 essential to anything really concrete, and the idea is only an 
 element in, and an abstraction from, the concrete. Now the 
 existence of an abstraction apart from the concrete, or the depen- 
 dence of the concrete on an abstraction from itself, is a contradic- 
 tion. And that the idea is a mere abstraction from experience 
 is not merely an accident of a particular way of discovering it, 
 but its very essence. Its existence lies solely in mediation, and 
 it cannot, therefore, ever be self-sufficient. It is rather an aspect 
 which we can perceive in experience, than an element which can 
 be separated from it, even ideally, without leading us into error. 
 
 Its independent existence would thus be a very glaring con- 
 tradiction. And for Hegel, as for other people, contradictions 
 could not really exist. Each stage in the Logic is a contradiction, 
 it is true, but then those stages have no independent existence. 
 The self-consistent reahty is always behind it. " The consumma- 
 tion of the infinite aim. . .consists merely in removing the illusion 
 which makes it seem as yet unaccomplished^." 
 
 57. And Hegel himself distinctly denies the asserted purely 
 synthetical character of the transition. "It is clear," he says, 
 "that the emergence of Spirit from Nature ought not to be 
 expressed as if nature was the Absolute Immediate, the First, 
 that which originally statutes, and Spirit on the other hand was 
 only statuted (gesetzt) by it; rather is Nature statuted by Spirit, 
 and the latter is the absolute First. Spirit, in and for itself, is 
 not the simple result of Nature, but in truth its own result; it 
 evolves itself out of the assumptions which it itself makes, out 
 of the logical idea and external nature, and is the truth of the 
 ^ Enc. Section 212, lecture note. 
 
64 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [CH. 
 
 former as well as of the latter — that is to say the true form of 
 the Spirit which is merely in itself, and of the Spirit which is 
 merely outside itself. The appearance of the mediation of Spirit 
 by another is transcended by Spirit itself, since this, so to say, 
 has the consummate ingratitude to transcend that through which 
 it seeks to be mediated, to mediatise it, to reduce it to something 
 which only exists through spirit, and in this way to make itself 
 completely independent^," Spirit, the final result of the process, 
 is thus declared to be also its logical ground, and the process of 
 the Idea to Nature and from Nature to Spirit has therefore an 
 analytic, as well as a synthetic aspect, since the end of the process 
 is only to come to explicit knowledge of its ground, which, as its 
 ground, must have been present to it all along, though not yet 
 in full and explicit consciousness. It may be remarked that Hegel 
 uses exactly the same metaphor of ingratitude to describe the 
 relation of Spirit to the apparent commencement of the process, 
 as he used long before to express the connection between pure 
 thought and the empirical details, from the consideration of 
 which pure thought started^. This may serve as a slight additional 
 reason for our belief in the theory that the force of the transition 
 to Spirit lies in the implicit presence of Spirit all along, and not 
 in a merely synthetic advance from pure thought through Nature. 
 For in the logic, as Professor Seth admits, the logical prius of 
 the advance is to be found at the end, and not at the beginning, 
 of the process. We may also compare Section 239 of the Encyclo- 
 paedia, lecture note — "the truth is that Nature is due to the 
 statuting of Spirit, and it is Spirit itself which gives itself a pre- 
 supposition in Nature." This view is incompatible with any 
 attempt to represent Nature as statuted by Logic alone. 
 
 58. To deny the purely synthetic deduction of Nature from 
 Logic, which we have just been considering, is not equivalent 
 to denying that there is any deduction at all intended, which 
 would be obviously incorrect. It is implied that these are the 
 only two alternatives, when Professor Seth tells us that the 
 "soberminded Hegelian," who denies the purely synthetic 
 deduction, "will lay as little stress as possible upon the so-called 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 381, lecture note, p. 23. 
 * Enc. Section 12, p. 36 above. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 65 
 
 deduction. Further reflection has convinced me, however," he 
 continues, " that Hegel's contention here is of more fundamental 
 importance to his system than such a representation allows. 
 Perhaps it may even be said that, when we surrender this 
 deduction, though we may retain much that is valuable in Hegel's 
 thought, we surrender the system as a whole^." No doubt it is 
 essential to the theory that there shall be a deduction, so that 
 the whole system, from the category of Being to Absolute Spirit, 
 shall be bound closely together. But this is not incompatible 
 with the soberminded view of the dialectic, for, as we have seen, 
 the deduction may be one which is analytic as well as synthetic, 
 and may derive its cogency from the implicit presence, at its 
 starting-point, of its result. 
 
 59. The treatment of the problem of contingency in the 
 dialectic presents a curious alternation between two incompatible 
 points of view, by the first of which contingency is treated as a 
 category, while by the second it is attributed to the incapacity 
 of Nature to realise the Idea. It is not necessary to consider 
 here the criticisms which might be made on either of these ex- 
 planations. It is sufl&cient to point out that, while the former 
 does not imply the theory which Professor Seth adopts as to 
 the general purpose of the Logic, the latter is quite incompatible 
 with it. 
 
 As to the first, it is to be noticed that the attempt to convert 
 contingency into a logical category is not necessarily identical 
 with an attempt to ignore reality. " The contingent," says Hegel, 
 "roughly speaking, is what has the ground of its being, not in 
 itself, but in somewhat else.... The contingent is only one side 
 of the actual, the side namely of reflection into somewhat else^." 
 It is thus by no means the same thing as the real, which includes, 
 even if it does not consist exclusively of, the self-subsistent entity 
 or entities which have their ground in themselves, or, if that 
 expression be objected to, are primary and without any ground 
 at all. The elimination of the contingent is thus quite compatible 
 with the existence of factual reality.- This is confirmed by Hegel's 
 remark in the same section that "to overcome this contingency 
 
 1 op. cit. pp. 109, 110. 
 
 2 Enc. Section 145, lecture note. 
 
66 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 is, roughly speaking, the problem of science." For the object 
 of ordinary science is certainly not to ehminate factual reality. 
 
 The same expression suggests that the elimination of con- 
 tingency does not, for Hegel, involve the elimination of im- 
 mediacy. For the object of ordinary science is not to eliminate 
 the data of sense, but to arrange and classify them. And this 
 is confirmed by the definition quoted above. Contingency con- 
 sists in explanation from the outside. That which can be explained 
 entirely from itself would not, it appears, be contingent to Hegel, 
 even if part of the explanation was given in the form of a mere 
 datum. No doubt at present all immediacy, involving as it does 
 presentation in sense, outer or inner, requires explanation from 
 outside, and is therefore contingent. But, as was pointed out 
 above in a different connection^, there is nothing in the nature 
 of immediacy which prevents us from supposing a state of know- 
 ledge in which the immediate data, being traced back to some 
 self-centred reality, should require no explanation from without, 
 and consequently should lose their contingency, while they 
 preserved their immediacy. The introduction, therefore, of con- 
 tingency as a category which, like other categories, is transcended, 
 does not fairly lead to the conclusion that Hegel believed in the 
 possibility of mediating thought ever becoming self-sufficient. 
 
 On the other hand, the theory that contingency is caused by 
 the inabihty of Nature to realise the idea^, is clearly incompatible 
 with an attempt to produce Nature out of pure thought. For, 
 if the world of Nature, as such an attempt would require, is 
 deduced by pure synthesis from the world of reason, and by the 
 free passage of the latter, how can the impotence arise? The 
 only possible explanation of such impotence must be in some 
 independent element, which the idea cannot perfectly subdue, 
 and this is inconsistent with the theory of pure synthesis. It 
 may be doubted whether this view is compatible with the general 
 theory of the dialectic at all. But it is certainly, as Professor 
 Seth admits^, quite incompatible with "an absolute philosophy" 
 in his use of the phrase. If this was Hegel's view of contingency, 
 it must be taken as a proof of the presence of an analytic element 
 in the process. For then the failure of thought to embody itself 
 
 1 Section 47. * Enc. Section 16. » op. cit. p. 139. 
 
u] OF THE DIALECTIC G7 
 
 completely in nature, whether consistent or not, would not be 
 so glaringly inconsistent as in the other case. It might then 
 possibly be a casual error. But it is difficult to suppose that Hegel 
 could have slipped by mistake into the assertion that thought, 
 while producing the whole universe, was met in it by an alien 
 element. 
 
 60, We must now proceed to the second charge made against 
 the transition from the Logic — that it involves an argument 
 from essence to existence. Such an argument would doubtless 
 be completely fallacious. Any proposition about existence must 
 either be directly based on immediate experience of reality, or 
 must be connected, by a chain of inferences, with a proposition 
 that is so based. The difference between the real and the ideal 
 worlds is one which mere thought can never bridge over, because, 
 for mere thought, it does not exist. As Kant says, the difference 
 between twenty real thalers and twenty thalers which are only 
 imagined to be real, does not appear in the idea of them, which 
 is the same whether they exist or not. The difference lies in the 
 reference to reality, which makes no part of the idea. If, there- 
 fore, we confined ourselves to thought, we should be unable to 
 discover whether our thalers were in truth real, or whether we 
 had only imagined their reality. And even if, starting from the 
 nature of thought taken in abstraction from sense, we could 
 evolve the idea of the entire universe (and we have seen^ that 
 without sense we could perceive nothing of the nature of thought), 
 it would remain purely ideal, and never be able to explain the 
 fact that the world actually existed. For the difference between 
 the real world, and a world, exactly hke it, but only imagined 
 to exist, is a difference which pure thought could not perceive, 
 and therefore could not remove. It is impossible to argue that 
 contradictions would drive it on, for the contradictions of thought, 
 as we have seen, arise from its being abstract, and can do no 
 more than restore the concrete whole from which a start was 
 made. If reality was not given as a characteristic of that concrete 
 whole, no abstraction from it will afford a basis from which the 
 dialectic process can attain to reality. 
 
 61. Before, however, we decide that Hegel has been guilty 
 
 ^ Section 14. 
 
 5—2 
 
68 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 of so great a confusion, we should require convincing evidence 
 that his language must be interpreted to mean that existence 
 in reality can be deduced from the essence of thought. And the 
 evidence offered seems by no means sufficient. 
 
 In discussing the first charge made by Professor Seth, I have 
 given reasons for supposing that the analytic aspect of the method, 
 which Professor Seth admits to be present within the Logic, is 
 also to be found in the transition from Logic to Nature and 
 Spirit. Now we have seen above^ that the absence of such an 
 analytic element would not imply of necessity that the argument 
 is from essence to existence. But, on the other hand, the presence 
 of that element would render it certain that no attempt was made 
 to proceed to existence from essence. For the presence of the 
 analytic aspect in the transition means that we are working 
 towards the development, in explicit consciousness, of the full 
 value of the whole which was previously before us in implicit 
 consciousness, and the existence of this whole is the motive force 
 of the transition. If, therefore, the result reached by the dialectic 
 has real existence, so also the datum, of which the dialectic pro- 
 cess is an analysis, must have real existence. The argument is 
 thus from existence to existence. That a movement is in any 
 way analytic implies that its result is given, at any rate implicitly, 
 in its data. But an argument from essence to existence would 
 most emphatically go beyond its data, producing something fresh. 
 If, therefore, we have reason to reject the first charge of Professor 
 Seth against the validity of the transition from the Logic to the 
 rest of the system, the second charge falls to the ground with it. 
 
 62. In defence of his view Professor Seth, pointing out that 
 Hegel calls his philosophy absolute, says that "it is the character- 
 istic of an absolute philosophy that everything must be deduced 
 or constructed as a necessity of thought^," No quotations, how- 
 ever, are given from Hegel in support of this interpretation. And 
 the one definition which Hegel himself gives of the word in the 
 Encyclopaedia turns on quite a different point. "According to 
 Kant, the things that we know about are to us appearances only, 
 and we can never know their essential nature, which belongs to 
 another world, which we cannot approach.... The true statement 
 * Section 54. * op. cit. p. 110. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 69 
 
 of the case is rather as follows. The things of which we have direct 
 consciousness are mere phenomena, not for us only, but in their 
 own nature; and the true and proper case of these things, finite 
 as they are, is to have their existence founded not in themselves 
 but in the universal divine Idea. This view of things, it is true, 
 is as idealist as Kant's, but in contradistinction to the subjective 
 idealism of the Critical Philosophy should be termed absolute 
 ideahsm^." The meaning of the epithet Absolute is here placed 
 exclusively in the rejection of the Kantian theory that knowledge 
 is only of phenomena. But the assertion that reality may in itself 
 become the object of knowledge is not equivalent to the assertion 
 that conclusions regarding reality can be reached by merely con- 
 sidering the nature of thought. If Absolute had this additional 
 and remarkable meaning Hegel would surely have mentioned it 
 explicitly. 
 
 63. Again, Hegel rejects Kant's well-known criticism on the 
 ontological proof of the existence of God, and, as this criticism 
 turns on the impossibility of predicating reality through any 
 arguments based only on the definition of the subject, it has been 
 supposed that Hegel did not see this impossibility. "It would 
 be strange," Hegel says, "if the Notion, the very inmost of mind, 
 if even the Ego, or above all the concrete totality we call God 
 were not rich enough to include so poor a category as Being^." 
 "Most assuredly" is Professor Seth's comment on this, "the 
 Notion contains the category of Being; so does the Ego, that is 
 to say, the Idea of the Ego, and the Idea of God, both of which 
 are simply the Notion under another name. The category of 
 Being is contained in the Ego and may be disengaged from it." 
 But, he continues, "It is not the category 'Being' of which we 
 are in quest, but that reality of which all categories are only 
 descriptions, and which itself can only be experienced, immedi- 
 ately known, or lived. To such reality or factual existence, there 
 is no logical bridge^." 
 
 But before we conclude that Hegel has asserted the existence 
 of such a logical bridge, it will be well to bear in mind his warning 
 in the section quoted above, that in God "we have an object 
 
 1 Enc. Section 45, lecture note. ^ Enc. Section 51. 
 
 * op. cii. p. 119. 
 
70 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [ch. 
 
 of another kind than any hundred thalers, and unlike any one 
 particular notion, representation, or whatever else it may be 
 called." In what this peculiarity consists is not clearly explained 
 here. But in the middle of the preceding section we find, "That 
 upward spring of the mind signifies that the being which the 
 world has is only a semblance, no real being, no absolute truth ; 
 it signifies that beyond and above that appearance, truth abides 
 in God, so that true being is another name for God^." 
 
 Now, if God is identical with all true being, he certainly has 
 "that reality of which all categories are only descriptions." For, 
 if he has not, nothing has it, since there is no reality outside him, 
 and the denial of all reality is as impossible as the denial of all 
 truth, — to deny it is to assert it. For if the denial is true, it must 
 be real, and so must the person who makes it. The only question 
 then is whether the category of Being can be predicated of this 
 real God, and in this case Professor Seth admits that Hegel was 
 quite right in his judgment that the predication could be made, 
 if it was worth while. It would seem then that he is scarcely 
 justified in charging Hegel with endeavouring to construct a 
 logical bridge to real or factual existence, Hegel was speaking 
 of something whose real existence could not be doubted except 
 by a scepticism which extended to self-contradiction. Thus he 
 considered himself entitled to assume in his exposition the actual 
 existence of God, and only deliberated whether the predicate of 
 Being could or could not be attached to this existence. To do 
 this he pronounced to be perfectly legitimate, and perfectly use- 
 less — legitimate, because we can say of all reality that it is; 
 useless, because the full depth of realit}^ in which all categories 
 can be found, is expressed so inadequately by this, the simplest 
 and most abstract of all the categories. 
 
 64. Kant's objections do not affect such an ontological argu- 
 ment as this. He shows, no doubt, that we have no right to 
 conclude that anything really exists, on the ground that we have 
 made real existence part of the conception of the thing. No 
 possible attribute, which would belong to the thing if it existed, 
 can give us any reason to suppose that it does exist. But this 
 was not Hegel's argument. He did not try to prove God's 
 1 Enc. Section 50. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 71 
 
 existence simply from the divine attributes. He relied on two 
 facts. The first was that the conception of God proved that if 
 anything exists, God must exist. The second was that exr 
 perience existed, and therefore God must exist^. The important 
 point in the conception of God, for Hegel's purpose here, was 
 not that he was the most real of beings, nor that he contained 
 all positive qualities, but that he was the only real being. For 
 the existence of an ens realissimum or of an oninitndo realitatis 
 can be denied. But the existence of all reality cannot be denied, 
 for its denial would be contradictory. And, on Hegel's definition, 
 to deny God's existence is equivalent to denying all reality, for 
 "true being is another name for God." 
 
 "If, in an identical judgment," says Kant, "I reject the 
 predicate and retain the subject, there arises a contradiction 
 and hence I say that the former belongs to the latter necessarily. 
 But if I reject the subject as well as the predicate there is no 
 contradiction, because there is nothing left which can be con- 
 tradicted.... The same applies to the concept of an absolutely 
 necessary being. Remove its existence, and you remove the 
 thing itself, with all its predicates, so that a contradiction becomes 
 impossible^." But the Hegelian argument rests on the fact that 
 you cannot remove "the thing itself" because the statement by 
 which you do it, and yourself likewise, are actually existent, and 
 must have some ultimate reality behind them, which ultimate 
 reality, called by Hegel God, is the thing whose removal is in 
 question. Thus there is a contradiction. You can only get rid 
 of the Hegelian God by getting rid of the entire universe. And 
 to do this is impossible. 
 
 It must be noticed, however, that this form of the ontological 
 argument can only prove the existence of a God who is conceived 
 as the sole reality in the universe. If we ourselves, or anything 
 else, are conceived as existing, except as parts of him, then the 
 denial of his existence does not involve the denial of all reality,, 
 and has therefore no contradiction contained in it. Kant's 
 refutation will stand as against all attempts to prove, by the 
 ontological argument, the existence of a God not conceived as 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. The two preceding sentences have been altered. 
 * Critique of Pure Reason, Book ii. Chap. m. Section 4. 
 
72 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [cH. 
 
 immanent in all existence. It will also be conclusive against all 
 attempts to demonstrate, by means of the ontological argument, 
 any particular quality or attribute of God, unless that attribute 
 can be shown to be essential to his all-inclusive reality, in which 
 case, of course, we should, by denying it, deny the reality also. 
 Kant was right in holding that the ontological argument could 
 not establish the existence of a God, as conceived by his dog- 
 matic predecessors, or as conceived by himself in the Critique 
 of Practical Reason. Hegel was right in holding that it was valid 
 of a God, defined in the Hegelian manner. 
 
 65. Professor Seth also relies on Hegel's treatment of the 
 individual character of existence. "He adroitly contrives to 
 insinuate that, because it is undefinable, the individual is there- 
 fore a valueless abstraction^." And he quotes from the Smaller 
 Logic, "Sensible existence has been characterised by the attri- 
 butes of individuality, and a mutual exclusion of the members. 
 It is well to remember that these very attributes are thoughts 
 and general terms.... Language is the work of thought, and hence 
 all that is expressed in language must be universal.... And what 
 cannot be uttered, feeling or sensation, far from being the 
 highest truth is the most unimportant and untrue^." Professor 
 Seth calls this "Hegel's insinuated disparagement of the indi- 
 vidual." But, if anything is disparaged, it is not the individual, 
 but sensible existence. When we say that individuality is not a 
 quality of sensible existence, but depends upon thought, this 
 diminishes the fullness and reality of sensible existence, but not 
 necessarily of individuality. And it is of vital importance which 
 of these two it is which Hegel disparages. For "the individual 
 is the real," and an attack on individuality, an attempt to make 
 it a mere product of thought, would go far to prove that Hegel 
 did cherish the idea of reducing the whole universe to a mani- 
 festation of pure thought. "The meanest thing that exists has 
 a life of its own, absolutely unique and individual, which we can 
 partly understand by terms borrowed from our own experience, 
 but which is no more identical with, or in any way like, the 
 description we give of it, than our own inner life is identical with 
 the description we give of it in a book of philosophy^." But to 
 ^ op. cit. p. 128. ^ Enc. Section 20. ^ Hegelianism and Personality, p. 125. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 73 
 
 deny the importance of the sensible element in experience, taken 
 as independent, is justifiable. 
 
 It is no doubt perfectly true that we are only entitled to say 
 that a thing is real, when we base that judgment on some datum 
 immediately given to us, and also that those data can only be 
 given us by sense, — inner or outer. But it does not at all follow 
 that the sensible, taken by itself, is real. Thought also is essential 
 to reality. In the first place it would be impossible for us to be 
 self-conscious without thought, since mere unrelated sensation 
 is incompatible with self-consciousness. Now without self-con- 
 sciousness nothing would be real for us. Without self-conscious- 
 ness sensations could not exist. For an unperceived sensation 
 is a contradiction. Sensations exist only in being perceived ; and 
 perception is impossible without comparison at the least, which 
 involves thought, and so self-consciousness. 
 
 Mere sensation may surely then be called unimportant — even 
 Kant called it blind — since it has no reality at all, except in a 
 unity in which it is not mere sensation. It is as much an abstrac- 
 tion as mere thought is. The importance lies only in the concrete 
 whole of which they are both parts, and this reality is not to 
 be considered as if it was built up out of thought and sensation. 
 In that case the mere sensation might be said to have some 
 reality, though only in combination. But here the sensation, as 
 a mere abstraction, must be held not to exist in the concrete 
 reality, but merely to be capable of distinction in it, and thus to 
 have of itself no reality whatever. 
 
 It is of course true that it is only the immediate contents of 
 experience which need mediation by thought to give them reality, 
 and not self-subsistent entities, — such as our own selves. But 
 Hegel's charge of unimportance was made against sensations, 
 which are not self-subsistent entities, but simply part of the 
 content of experience. 
 
 In the Introductory Chapter, in which the passage quoted 
 above is found, Hegel was merely trying to prove that thought 
 was essential, not that it was all-sufficient. It will therefore 
 quite agree with the context if we take this view of what it 
 was to which he denied importance. It would certainly have 
 made his position clearer, if he had, at the same time, asserted 
 
74 DIFFERENT INTERPRETATIONS [CH. 
 
 the abstractness and unimportance of thought without sense, 
 as emphatically as he had asserted the abstractness and un- 
 importance of sense without thought, but the former is implied 
 in the passages^ by which the dialectic is made to depend on 
 experience, and explicitly affirmed in the passage from the 
 Philosophy of Spirit^ in which the logical idea is declared to be 
 dependent on Spirit, and to be mediated by it. For in Spirit we 
 have the union of the two sides which, when separated, present 
 themselves to us as the mediating thought and the immediate 
 datum. 
 
 66. We are told also that the tendency of the whole system 
 is towards the undue exaltation of logic and essence, at the 
 expense of nature and reality. In support of this it is said that, 
 although Hegel "talks (and by the idiom of the language cannot 
 avoid talking) of 'der absolute Geist' (the absolute spirit) that 
 by no means implies, as the literal English translation does, that 
 he is speaking of God as a Subjective Spirit, a singular intelligence. 
 . . .The article goes with the noun in any case, according to German 
 usage; and 'absolute spirit' has no more necessary reference to 
 a Concrete Subject than the simple 'spirit' or intelligence which 
 preceded it^." It may be the case that Hegel did not conceive 
 Absolute Spirit as a single inteUigence. Indeed it seems probable 
 that he did not do so, but the point is too large to be discussed 
 here. But even in that case, it does not follow that the Absolute 
 Spirit cannot be concrete. If it is conceived as an organism or 
 society of finite intelligences, it will still be a concrete subject, 
 although it will possess no self-consciousness or personality of 
 its own. If it is regarded as manifested in an unconnected 
 agglomeration of finite intelligences, it may not be a subject, 
 but will still be concrete, since it will consist of the finite in- 
 telligences, which are certainly concrete. No doubt, if a definition 
 or description be asked for of Absolute Spirit, the answer, like 
 all definitions or descriptions, will be in abstract terms, but a 
 definition, though in abstract terms, may be the definition of 
 a concrete thing. Even if the Absolute Spirit was a singular 
 intelligence, any explanation of its nature would have to be made 
 
 ^ Sections 33-42 above. ^ Section 43 above. 
 
 ' Hegelianism and Personality, p. 151. 
 
n] OF THE DIALECTIC 75 
 
 by ascribing to it predicates, which are necessarily abstract 
 terms. 
 
 And against this asserted tendency on Hegel's part to take 
 refuge in abstractions we may set his own explicit declarations. 
 He continually uses abstract as a term of reproach and declares 
 that the concrete alone is true. Now it cannot be denied that 
 Nature is more concrete than the pure idea, or that Spirit is 
 more concrete than Nature. This would lead us, apart from other 
 considerations, to suppose that the logical prius of the universe 
 was to be looked for in Spirit, which is the most concrete of all 
 things^, and not in the Idea, which is only imperfectly concrete, 
 even in its highest form. 
 
 * Philosophy of Spirit, Section 377, p. 3. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 67. The question now arises, whether the dialectic as sketched 
 in the last two chapters, is a valid system of philosophy. The 
 consideration of this question here must necessarily be ex- 
 tremely incomplete. Some seventy or eighty transitions from 
 one category to another may be found in the Logic, and we should 
 have to consider the correctness of each one of these, before we 
 could pronounce the dialectic, in its present form at least, to 
 be correct. For a chain is no stronger than its weakest link, and 
 if a single transition is inconclusive, it must render all that comes 
 beyond it uncertain. All we can do here is to consider whether 
 the starting-point and the general method of the dialectic are 
 valid, without enquiring into its details. 
 
 We shall have in the first place to justify the dialectical pro- 
 \ cedure — so different from that which the understanding uses in 
 
 ^ the affairs of every-day life. To do this we must show, first, that 
 
 the ordinary use of the Understanding implies a demand for the 
 complete explanation of the universe, and then that such an 
 explanation cannot be given by the Understanding, and can be 
 given by the Reason in its dialectical use, so that the Under- 
 standing itself postulates in this way the validity of dialectic 
 rthought. In the second place we must prove that the point from 
 [Which the dialectic starts is one which it may legitimately take 
 I for granted, and that the nature of the advance and its relation 
 to experience are such as will render the dialectic a valid theory 
 Lof^knowledge. In this connection the relation of the idea of 
 Movement to the dialectic process must also be considered. And 
 finally the question will arise whether we are justified in applying 
 this theory of knowledge as also a theory of being, and in deducing 
 the worlds of Nature and Spirit from the world of Logic. 
 
 68. It is to be noticed that the first and second arguments 
 are very similar in their nature. We start respectively from 
 
CH. m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 77 
 
 the common thought of the Understanding, and from the idea 
 of Being, and vve endeavour to J»roye_ the vahdity of the_ 
 spe culative m etho d and of th e Absolute Idea , because they are 
 assumed in, and postulated by, the propositions from which 
 we started. Before going further, therefore, we ought to consider 
 some general objections which have been made against such 
 arguments. 
 
 They have been stated with great clearness by Mr Arthur 
 Balfour in his Defence of Philosophic Doubt. "When a man," 
 he says, "ia,coii3djlcedJ;iy.jaLJb:ajisc£jidenta1 aigumeni^J.t muftt ^_^^ 
 be. ..because he p erceives that a jsfirfcaiiL relation or principle is [, Y3-'»'^-^ 
 necessary to constitute his admitted experience. This is to him nj^,u^jA^L^ 
 a fact, the truth of which he is obliged to recognise. But another 
 fact, which he may also find it hard to dispute, is that he himself, —^ 
 
 and, as it would appear, the majority of mankind, have habitually 
 l^ad this experience..adthouke.vpxthinking.it.under tMsuXelatioo; 
 and this second fact is one which it does not seem easy to in- 
 terpret in a manner which shall harmonise with the general 
 theory. The transcendentalist would, no doubt, say at once that 
 the relation in question had always been thought implicitly, 
 even if it had not always come into clear consciousness; and 
 having enunciated this dictum he would trouble himself no 
 further about a matter which belonged merely to the 'history 
 of the individual.' B_ut if an implicit thought means in this 
 connection what it means eygryBLbLfiie else^jt is simply a thought 
 which is logically bound up in some other thought^^and which 
 for that reason may always be called into existence J?^ it. Now 
 f rom~tEis very definition, it is plain that so long as a thought is 
 implicit it does not exist. It is a mere possibility, which may 
 indeed at any moment become an actuality, and which, when 
 once an actuality, may be indestructible; but which so long as 
 it is a possibility can be said to have existence only by a figure 
 of speech. 
 
 " If, therefore, this meaning of the word ' implicit ' be accepted, 
 we find ourselves in a difficulty. Either an object can exist and 
 be a reality to an intelligence which does not think of it unde» 
 relations which, as I now see, are involved in it, i.e. without which 
 I cannot now think of it as an object; or else I am in error, when 
 
78 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [CH. 
 
 I suppose myself and other people to have ignored these relations 
 in past times^." 
 
 The second of these alternatives, as Mr Balfour points out, 
 cannot be adopted. It is certain that a large part of mankind 
 have never embraced the transcendental philosophy, and that 
 even those who accept it did not do so from their earliest child- 
 hood. It follows, he continues, that we must accept the first 
 alternative, in which case the whole transcendental system 
 "vanishes in smoke." 
 
 69. The dilemma, however, as it seems to me, rests upon a 
 confusion of the two different senses in which we may be said 
 to be conscious of thought. We may be said, in the first place, 
 to be conscious of it whenever we are conscious of a whole ex- 
 perience in which it is an element. In this sense we must be 
 conscious of all thought which exists at all. We must agree with 
 Mr Balfour that "if the consciousness vanishes, the thought 
 must vanish too, since, except on some crude materialistic 
 hypothesis, they are the same thing^." But in the second sense 
 we are only conscious of a particular thought when we have 
 singled it out from the mass of sensations and thoughts, into 
 which experience may be analysed, when we have distinguished 
 it from the other constituents of experience, and know it to be 
 a thought, and know what thought it is. In this sense we may 
 have thought without being conscious of it. And indeed we 
 must always have it, before we can be conscious of it in this sense. 
 For thought first comes before us as an element in the whole 
 of experience, and it is not till we have analysed that whole, 
 and separated thought from sensation, and one thought from 
 another, that we know we have a particular thought. Till then 
 we have the thought without being explicitly conscious that we 
 have it. 
 
 Now I submit that Mr Balfour's argument depends on a 
 paralogism. When he asserts that we must always be conscious 
 of any relation which is necessary to constitute experience, he 
 is using "to be conscious of" in the first sense. When he asserts 
 that all people are not always conscious of all the ideas of the 
 dialectic as necessary elements in experience, he is using "to 
 ^ Defence of Philosophic Doubt, p. 94. ^ o^_ gj^ p jqq^ 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALEOTIC 79 
 
 be conscious of" in the second sense. And if we remove this 
 ambiguity the difficulty vanishes. 
 
 We are only conscious of thought as an element in experience. 
 Of thought outside experience we could not be conscious in any 
 sense of the word, for thought cannot even be conceived except 
 as relating and mediating some data. But thought of which we 
 are not conscious at all is, as Mr Balfour remarks, a non-entity. 
 And no thought does exist outside experience. Both thought 
 and the immediate data which it mediates exist only as combined 
 in the whole of experience, which is what comes first into con- 
 sciousness. In this lie the various threads of thought and sensa- 
 tion, of which we may be said to be conscious, in so far as we 
 are conscious of the whole of which they are indispensable 
 elements. But we do not know how many, nor of what nature, 
 the threads are, until we have analysed the whole in which they 
 are first presented to us, nor, till then, do we clearly see that 
 the whole is made up of separate elements. Even to know this 
 involves some thinking about thought. There is no contradiction 
 between declaring that certain relations must enter into all 
 conscious thought, and admitting that those relations are known 
 as such only to those who have endeavoured to divide the whole 
 of experience into its constituent parts, and have succeeded in 
 the attempt. 
 
 The use of the word ''implicit" to which Mr Balfour objects, 
 can be explained in the same way. If it means only what he 
 supposes, so that an implicit thought is nothing but one "which 
 is logically bound up in some other thought, and which for that 
 reason may always be called into existence by it" — then indeed 
 to say that a thought is impHcit is equivalent to saying that it 
 does not exist. But if we use the word — and there seems no 
 reason why we should not — in the sense suggested by its deriva- 
 tion, in which it means that which is wrapped up in something 
 else, then it is clear that a thing may be impficit, and so not dis- 
 tinctly seen to be itself, while it nevertheless exists and is perceived 
 as part of the whole in which it is involved. 
 
 70. In speaking of such an answer to his criticisms, Mr 
 Balfour objects that it concedes more than transcendentafism 
 can afiord to allow. "If relations can exist otherwise than as 
 
80 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [CH. 
 
 they are thought, why should not sensations do the same? Why 
 should not the 'perpetual flux' of unrelated objects — the meta- 
 physical spectre which the modern transcendentahst labours so 
 hard to lay — why, I say, should this not have a real existence? 
 We, indeed, cannot in our reflective moments think of it except 
 under relations which give it a kind of unity; but once allow 
 that an object may exist, but in such a manner as to make it 
 nothing for us as thinking beings, and this incapacity may be 
 simply due to the fact that thought is powerless to grasp the 
 reahty of things^." 
 
 This, however, is not a fair statement of the position. The 
 transcendentahst does not assert that an object can exist in 
 such a manner as to be nothing for us as thinking beings, but 
 only that it may exist, and be something for us as thinking 
 beings, although we do not recognise the conditions on which 
 its existence for us depends. Thus we are able to admit that 
 thought exists even for those people who have never made the 
 slightest reflection on its nature. And, in the same way, no 
 doubt, we can be conscious of related sensations without seeing 
 that they are related, for we may never have analysed experience 
 as presented to us into its mutually dependent elements of sensa- 
 tion and thought. But it does not follow that sensations could 
 exist unrelated. That would mean that something existed in 
 consciousness (for sensations exist nowhere else), which not only 
 is not perceived to comply with the laws of consciousness, but 
 which actually does not comply with them. And this is quite a 
 different proposition, and an impossible one. 
 
 71. Passing now to the peculiarities of the dialectic method, 
 their justification must be one which will commend itself to the 
 Understanding — that is to thought, when, as happens in ordinary 
 life, it acts according to the laws of formal logic, and treats the 
 various categories as stable and independent entities, which have 
 no relation to one another, but that of exclusion. For if specula- 
 tive thought, or Eeason, cannot be justified before the Under- 
 standing, there will be an essential dualism in the nature of 
 thought, incompatible with any satisfactory philosophy. And 
 since mankind naturally, and until cause is shown to the 
 
 ^ op. cit. p. lOL 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 81 
 
 contrary, takes up the position of the Understanding, it will be 
 impossible that we can have any logical right to enter on the 
 dialectic, unless we can justify it from that standpoint, from 
 which we must set out when we first begin to investigate meta- 
 physical questions. 
 
 The first step towards this proof is the recognition that the 
 Understanding necessarily demands an absolute and complete 
 explanation of the universe. In dealing with this point, Hart- 
 mann^ identifies the longing for the Absolute, on which Hegel 
 here relies, with the longing to "smuggle back" into our beliefs 
 the God whom Kant had rejected from metaphysics. God, how- 
 ever, is an ideal whose reality may be demanded on the part 
 either of theoretical or of practical reason. It is therefore not 
 very easy to see whether Hartmann meant that the longing, as 
 he calls it, after the Absolute, is indulged only in the interest 
 of religion and ethics, or whether he admits that it is demanded, 
 whether justifiably or not, by the nature of knowledge. The 
 use of the term "longing" (Sehnsucht), however, and the 
 expressions " mystisch-religioses Bediirfuiss," and "unverstand- 
 liche Gefiihle," which he appUes to it, seem rather to suggest 
 the former alternative. 
 
 In this case grave injustice is done to the Hegelian position. 
 The philosopher does not believe in the Absolute merely because 
 he desires it should exist. The postulate is not only an emotional 
 or ethical one, nor is the Absolute itself by any means primarily 
 a religious ideal, whatever it may subsequently become. If, for 
 example, we take the definition given in the Smaller Logic, " der 
 Begrifi der Idee, dem die Idee als solche der Gegenstand, dem 
 das Objekt sie ist^," it is manifest that what is here chiefly 
 regarded is not a need of religion, but of cognition. Indeed the 
 whole course of the Logic shows us that it is the desire for 
 complete knowledge, and the impatience of knowledge which is 
 seen to be unsatisfactory, which act as the motive power of the 
 system. It is possible, no doubt, that Hegel's object in devoting 
 himself to philosophy at all was, as has often been the case with 
 philosophers, mainly practical, and that his interest in the 
 absolute was excited from the side of ethics and religion rather 
 
 ^ Ueber die diaUktische Methode, B. n. 4. * Enc. Section 236. 
 
 M.H. 6 
 
82 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [CH. 
 
 than of pure thought. But so long as he did not use this interest 
 as an argument, it does not weaken his position. The ultimate 
 aim which a philosopher has in his studies is irrelevant to our 
 criticism of his results, if the latter are valid in themselves. 
 
 72. The need of the Absolute is thus a need of cognition. We 
 must ask, then, whether the Understanding, in its attempts to 
 solve particular problems, demands a complete explanation of 
 the universe, and the attainment of the ideal of knowledge? This 
 question must be answered in the affirmative. For although we 
 start with particular problems, the answer to each of these will 
 raise fresh questions, which must be solved before the original 
 difficulty can be held to be really answered, and this process goes 
 on indefinitely, till we find that the whole universe is involved 
 in a complete answer to even the slightest question. As was 
 pointed out above^ any explanation of anything by means of 
 the surrounding circumstances, of an antecedent cause, or of its 
 constituent parts, must necessarily raise fresh questions as to 
 the surroundings of those surroundings, the causes of those 
 causes, or the parts of those parts, and such series of questions, 
 if once started, cannot stop until they reach the knowledge of 
 the whole surrounding universe, of the whole of past time, or 
 of the ultimate atoms, which it is impossible to subdivide further. 
 
 In fact, to state the matter generally, any question which 
 the Understanding puts to itself must be either. What is the 
 meaning of the universe? or. What is the meaning of some part 
 of the universe? The first is obviously only to be answered by 
 attaining the absolute ideal of knowledge. The second again can 
 only be answered by answering the first. For if a thing is part 
 of a whole it must stand in some relation to the other parts. 
 The other parts must therefore have some influence on it, and 
 part of the explanation of its nature must lie in these other parts. 
 From the mere fact that they are parts of the same universe, 
 they must all be connected, directly or indirectly. 
 
 73. The Understanding, then, demands the ideal of know- 
 ledge, and postulates it whenever it asks a question. Can it, 
 we must now enquire, attain, by its own exertions, to the ideal 
 which it postulates? It has before it the same categories as the 
 
 1 Section 13- 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 83 
 
 Reason, but it differs from the Reason in not seeing that the 
 higher categories are the inevitable result of the lower, and in 
 believing that the lower are stable and independent. " Thought, 
 as Understanding, sticks to fixity of characters, and their dis: 
 tinctness from one another : every such limited abstract it treats 
 as having a subsistence and being of its own^." It can use the 
 higher categories, then, but it has no proof of their validity, 
 which can only be demonstrated, as was explained in Chap, i., 
 by showing that they are involved in the lower ones, and finally 
 in the simplest of all. Nor does it see that an explanation by 
 a higher category relieves us from the necessity of finding a 
 consistent explanation by a lower one. For it does not know, as 
 the Reason does, that the lower categories are abstractions from 
 the higher, and are unfit to be used for the ultimate explanation 
 of anything, except in so far as they are moments in a higher 
 unity. 
 
 It is this last defect which prevents the Understanding from 
 ever attaining a complete explanation of the universe. There is, 
 as we have said, nothing to prevent the Understanding from 
 using the highest category, that of the Absolute Idea. It contains 
 indeed a synthesis of contradictions, which the Understanding 
 is bound to regard as a mark of error, but so does every category 
 above Being and Not-Being, and the Understanding nevertheless 
 uses these categories, not perceiving that they violate the law 
 of contradiction, as conceived by formal logic. It might there- 
 fore use the Absolute Idea as a means of explaining the universe, 
 if it happened to come across it (for the perception of the necessary 
 development of that idea from the lower categories belongs 
 only to the Reason), but it would not see that it summed up all 
 other categories. 
 
 And this would prevent the explanation from being com- 
 pletely satisfactory. For the only way in which contradictions 
 caused by the use of the lower categories can be removed by 
 the employment of the Absolute Idea lies in the synthesis, by 
 the Absolute Idea, of those lower categories. They must be seen 
 to be abstractions from it, to have truth only in so far as they 
 are moments in it, and to have no right to claim existence or 
 1 Enc. Section 80. 
 
 6—2 
 
84 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 validity as independent. This can only be known by means of 
 the Reason. For the Understanding each category is indepen- 
 dent and ultimate. And therefore any contradictions in which 
 the Understanding may be involved through the use of the lower 
 categories can have no solution for the Understanding itself. 
 Till we can rise above the lower categories, by seeing that they 
 express only inadequate and imperfect points of view, the con- 
 tradictions into which they lead us must remain to deface our 
 system of knowledge. And for this deliverance we must wait 
 for the Reason. 
 ^^ 74. If the lower categories do produce contradictions, then, 
 I we can only extricate ourselves from our difficulty by aid of the 
 / Reason. But are such contradictions produced, in fact, when 
 we treat those categories as ultimate and endeavour to com- 
 pletely explain anything by them? This question would be most 
 fitly answered by pointing out the actual contradictions in each 
 case, which is what Hegel undertakes throughout the Logic. To 
 examine the correctness of his argument in each separate case 
 would be beyond the scope of this work. We may however point 
 out that this doctrine did not originate with Hegel. In the early 
 Greek philosophy we have demonstrations of the contradictions 
 inherent in the idea of Motion, and traces of a dialectic process 
 are found by Hegel in Plato. Kant, also, has shown in his 
 Antinomies that the attempt to use the lower categories as com- 
 plete explanations of existence leads with equal necessity to 
 directly contradictory conclusions. 
 
 r* '^nd we may say on general grounds that any category which 
 / involves an infinite regress must lead to contradictions. Such 
 S. 3T'e7 for example, the category of Force, which explains things 
 ^^ as manifestations of a force, the nature of which must be deter- 
 mined by previous manifestations, and the category of Causality, 
 which traces things to their causes, which causes again are effects 
 and must have other causes found for them. Such an infinite 
 regress can never be finished. And an unfinished regress, which 
 we admit ought to be continued, explains nothing, while to 
 impose an arbitrary limit on it is clearly unjustifiable. 
 
 Again, all categories having no ground of self-differentiation 
 in themselves may be pronounced to be in the long run un- 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 85 
 
 satisfactory. For thought demands an explanation which shall 
 unify the data to be explained, and these data are in themselves 
 various. If the explanation, therefore, is to be complete, and 
 not to leave something unaccounted for, it must show that there 
 is a necessary connection between the unity of the principle and 
 the plurality of the manifestation. 
 
 Now many of the lower categories do involve an infinite 
 regress, and are wanting in any principle of self-differentiation. 
 They cannot, therefore, escape falling into contradictions, and 
 as the Understanding cannot, as the Reason can, remove the 
 difficulties by regarding these categories as sides of a higher 
 truth in which the contradiction vanishes, the contradictions 
 remain permanent, and prevent the Understanding from reaching 
 that ideal of knowledge at which it aims. 
 
 75. On this subject Hartmann^ reminds us that Hegel con- 
 fesses that the Understanding cannot think a contradiction — 
 in the sense of unifying it and explaining it. All, as he rightly 
 points out, that the Understanding can do is to be conscious of 
 the existence of contradictions. This, he contends, will not serve 
 Hegel's purpose of justifying the Reason. For, since the recog- 
 nition of the existence of contradictions can never change the 
 incapacity of the Understanding to think them, the only result 
 would be "a heterogeneity or inconsequence" of being, which 
 presents these contradictions, and thought, which is unable to 
 think them. This inconsequence might end, if Hegel's assertion 
 be correct that contradictions are everywhere, in a total separa- 
 tion between thought and being, but could have no tendency 
 to make thought dissatisfied with the procedure of the Under- 
 standing, and willing to embrace that of the Reason. 
 
 This, however, misrepresents Hegel's position. The con- 
 tradictions are not in being, as opposed to thought. They are 
 in all finite thought, whenever it attempts to work at all. The 
 contradiction on which the dialectic relies is, that, if we use 
 one finite category of any subject-matter, we find ourselves 
 compelled, if we examine what is implied in using, to use also, 
 of the same subject-matter, its contrary. The Understanding 
 recognises this contradiction, while at the same time it cannot 
 
 ^ op. cit. B. II. 4. 
 
86 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 think it, — cannot, that is, look at it from any point of view from 
 which the contradiction should disappear. It cannot therefore 
 take refuge in the theory that there is a heterogeneity between 
 itself and being, for it is in its own working that it finds some- 
 thing wrong. If the law of contradiction holds, thought must 
 be wrong when it is inevitably led to ascribe contrary predicates 
 to the same subject, while if the law of contradiction did not 
 hold, no thought would be possible at all. And if, as the dialectic 
 maintains, such contradictions occur with every finite category 
 — that is, whenever the Understanding is used, the Under- 
 standing must itself confess that there is always a contradiction 
 in its operations, discoverable when they are scrutinised with 
 sufficient keenness. Either, then, there is no vahd thought at 
 all — a supposition which contradicts itself, — or there must be 
 some form of thought which can harmonise the contradictions 
 which the Understanding can only recognise. 
 
 76. But if the Understanding is reduced to a confession of 
 its own insufficiency, is the Reason any better off? Does the 
 solution offered by the Reason supply that complete ideal of 
 knowledge which all thought demands? The answer to this 
 question will depend in part on the actual success which the 
 Absolute Idea may have in explaining the problems before us 
 so as to give satisfaction to our own minds. But the difference 
 between the indication in general terms of the true explanation, 
 and the working out of that explanation in detail is so enormous, 
 that we shall find but little guidance here. It may be true that 
 "the best proof that the universe is rational lies in rationalising 
 it," but, if so, it is a proof which is practically unattainable^. 
 
 The only general proof open to us is a negative one. The 
 dialectic comes to the conclusion that each of the lower categories 
 cannot be regarded as ultimate, because in each, on examination, 
 it finds an inherent contradiction. In proportion as careful con- 
 sideration and scrutiny fail to reveal any corresponding contra- 
 diction in the Absolute Idea, we may rely on the conclusion of 
 , the dialectic that it is the ultimate and only really adequate 
 category^. 
 
 1 Cf. Chap. vn. 
 
 2 Note to Second Edition. A paragraph has been omitted here. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 87 
 
 77. What then should be the attitude of the Understanding 
 towards the Reason? We have shown that the Understanding 
 at once postulates, and cannot attain, a complete and harmonious 
 ideal of knowledge. Supposing that the Reason can, as it asserts, 
 attain this ideal, is the Understanding therefore bound to admit 
 its validity? 
 
 It is no doubt perfectly true, as Hartmann points out^, that 
 our power of seeking for anything, or even the necessity we 
 may be under of seeking it, is not in itself the least proof that 
 we shall succeed in our search. It does not then directly follow 
 that, because there is no other way than the Reason by which 
 we could attain that which the Understanding postulates, we 
 can therefore attain it by means of the Reason. And this might 
 have been a decisive consideration if Hegel had attempted to 
 prove the validity of the Reason to the Understanding in a 
 positive manner. But to do this would have been unnecessary, 
 and, indeed, self-destructive. For such a proof would have gone 
 too far. It would have proved that there was nothing in the 
 Reason which was not also in the Understanding — in other words, 
 that there was no difference between them. If there are two 
 varieties of thought, of which one is higher and more compre- 
 hensive than the other, it will be impossible from the nature of 
 the case for the lower and narrower to be directly aware that 
 the higher is valid. From the very fact that the higher will have 
 canons of thought not accepted by the lower, it must appear 
 invalid to the latter, which can only be forced to accept it by 
 external and indirect proof of its truth. And of this sort is the 
 justification which the Reason does offer to the Understanding. 
 It proves that we have a need which the Understanding must 
 ' recognise, but cannot satisfy. This leaves the hearer with two 
 alternatives. He may admit the need and deny that it can be 
 satisfied in any way, which, in the case of a fundamental pos- 
 tulate of thought, would involve complete scepticism. If he does 
 not do this, he must accept the validity of the Reason, as the 
 only source by which the demand can be satisfied. 
 
 The first alternative, however, in a case like this, is only 
 nominal. If we have to choose between a particular theory and 
 
 ^ op. cit. II. B. 4. 
 
88 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 complete scepticism, we have, in fact, no choice at all. For 
 complete scepticism is impossible, contradicted as it would be 
 by the very speech or thought which asserted it. If Hegel's 
 demonstrations are correct, there is to be found in every thought 
 something which for the Understanding is a contradiction. But 
 to reject all thought as incorrect is impossible. There must 
 therefore be some mode of thought, higher than the Under- 
 standing, and supplementary to it, by which we may be justified 
 in doing continually that which the Understanding will not allow 
 us to do at all. And this is the Reason. 
 
 78. We are thus enabled to reject Hartmann's criticism that 
 the dialectic violates all the tendencies of modern thought, by 
 sundering the mind into two parts, which have nothing in common 
 with one another^. The Understanding and the Reason have this 
 in common, that the Reason is the only method of solving the 
 problems which are raised by the Understanding, and therefore 
 can justify its existence on the principles which the Under- 
 standing recognises. For the distinctive mark of the Reason is, 
 as Hegel says, that "it apprehends the unity of the categories 
 in their opposition," that it perceives that all concrete categories 
 are made up of reconciled contradictions, and that it is only in 
 these syntheses that the contradictory categories find their true 
 meaning. Now this apprehension is not needed in order to detect 
 the contradictions which the finite categories involve. This can 
 be done by the Understanding. And when the Understanding 
 has done this, it has at any rate proved its own impotence, and 
 therefore can scarcely be said to be essentially opposed to Reason, 
 since it has forfeited its claim to any thorough or consistent use 
 at all. 
 
 The w hole justification of the Reason, as the necessary co m- 
 plem ent of the Understanding, is repeated in each triad _oLthe 
 Logic. The fact that the thesis leads of necessity to the antithesis, 
 
 which is its contrary^ is one of the contradictions which prove 
 the impotence of the Understanding. We are forced^ either to 
 admit the syn thesis offered by the Reason, or to deny_the 
 possibility of reconciling the thes is and antithesis. The thesis 
 itself, again, was a modified form of the synthesis of a lower 
 
 ^ op. cit. II. B. 3. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 89 
 
 thesis and antithesis. To deny it will therefore involve the denial 
 of them also, since it offers the only means of removing their 
 contradiction. And thus we should be driven lower and lower, 
 till we reach at last an impossible scepticism, the only escape 
 from which is to accept the union of opposites which we find in 
 the Reason. 
 
 Thus the Reason, though it does something which the Under- 
 standing cannot do, does not really do anything which the 
 Understanding denies. What the Understanding deni es is the .^N^ 
 possibility of_ co inbining two contrary notions as they stand . ^ j ^s^ 
 e ach independent and appa rentl y sp1f-cnmplet e. What the Reason 
 does, is to merge t hese ideas in a higher o ne_,„iJLjgiLicIi iJieir 
 oppositi on, while in one se nse preserved^ Js also transcended. 
 This is not what is denied by the Understanding, for the U nder- 
 stan ding is incapable of realising the position. Reason is not 
 c ontrary to, but beyond the Unde rstandmgr It is true that 
 whatever is beyond the Understanding may be said to be in one 
 sense contrary to it, since a fresh principle is introduced. But 
 as the Understanding has proved that its employment by itself 
 would result in chaos, it has given up its assertion of indepen- 
 dence and leads the way naturally to Reason. Thus there are 
 not two faculties in the mind with different laws, but two 
 methods of working, the lower of which, though it does not of 
 course contain the higher, yet leads up to it, postulates it, and 
 is seen, in the light of the higher method, only to exist as leading 
 up to it, and to be false in so far as it claims independence. The 
 second appears as the completion of the first; it is not merely 
 an escape from the difficulties of the lower method, but it explains 
 and removes those difficulties ; it does not merely succeed, where 
 the Understanding had failed, in rationalising the universe, but 
 it rationalises the Understanding itself. Taking all this into 
 consideration the two methods cannot properly be called two 
 separate faculties, however great may be the difference in their 
 working. 
 
 79. We must now pass to the second of the three questions 
 proposed at the beginning of this chapter — namely, the internal 
 consistency of the system. And it will be necessary to consider 
 in the first place what foundation is assumed, upon which to 
 
90 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 base our argument, and whether we are entitled to this assump- 
 tion. 
 
 Now the idea from which the dialectic sets out, and in which 
 it professes to show that all the other categories are involved, 
 is the idea of Being. Are we justified in assuming the validity 
 of this idea? The ground on which we can answer this question 
 in the affirmative is that the rejection of the idea as invalid 
 would be self-contradictory, as was pointed out above^. For it 
 would be equivalent to a denial that anything whatever existed. 
 And in that case the denial itself could not exist, and the validity 
 of the idea of Being has not been denied. But, on the other hand, 
 if the denial does exist, then there is something whose existence 
 we cannot deny. And the same dilemma applies to doubt, as 
 well as to positive denial. If the doubt exists, then there is 
 something of whose existence we are certain; if the doubt does 
 not exist, then we do not doubt the validity of the category. 
 And both denial and doubt involve the existence of the thinking 
 subject. 
 
 We have thus as firm a base as possible for our argument. 
 It is not only a proposition which none of our opponents 
 do in fact doubt, but one which they cannot by any possibility 
 doubt, one which is involved and postulated in all thought and 
 in all action. Whatever may be the nature of the superstructure, 
 the foundation is strong enough to carry it. 
 
 80. The next consideration must be the validity of the process 
 by which we conclude that further categories are involved in 
 the one from which we start. In this process there are three 
 steps. We go from thesis to antithesis, from thesis and antithesis 
 to synthesis, and from synthesis again to a fresh thesis. The dis- 
 tinctness of the separate steps becomes somewhat obscured 
 towards the end of the Logic, when the importance of negation, 
 as the means by which the imperfect truth advances towards 
 perfection, is considerably diminished. It will perhaps be most 
 convenient to take the steps here in the form in which they exist 
 at the beginning of the Logic. The effect produced on the validity 
 of the process by the subsequent development of the method will 
 be discussed in the next chapter. 
 
 1 Chap. I. Section 18. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 91 
 
 It is not necessary to say much of the transition from the 
 synthesis to the fresh thesis. It is, in fact, scarcely a transition 
 at alP. It is, as can be seen when Recoming passes into Being 
 Deter minate, r ather a c ontemplation- of the sam e truth fr om a 
 fresh .poiiit_.Qfjd.ew — immediacy in the place of reconciling 
 mediation — than an advance to a fresh truth. Whether in fact 
 this new category is always the same as the previous synthesis, 
 looked at from another point of view, is a question of detail 
 which must be examined independently for each triad of the 
 Logic, and which does not concern us here, as we are dealing 
 only with the general principles of the system. But if the old 
 synthesis and the new thesis are really only different expressions 
 of the same truth, the passage from the one to the other is valid 
 even according to formal Logic. Since nothing new is added at 
 all, nothing can be added improperly. 
 
 81. Our general question must be put in a negative form 
 to suit the transition between thesis and antithesis. It would 
 be misleading to ask whether we were justified in assuming that, 
 since the thesis is valid, the antithesis is valid too. For the result 
 of the transition from thesis to antithesis is to produce, till the 
 synthesis is perceived, a state of contradiction and scepticism, 
 in which it will be doubted if either category is valid at all, since 
 they lead to contradictions. Our question should rather be. Are 
 we justified in assuming that, unless the antithesis is valid, the 
 thesis cannot be valid? 
 
 The ground of this assumption is that the one category implies 
 the other. If we examine attentively what is meant by pure 
 Being, we find that it cannot be discriminated from Nothing. 
 If we examine Being-for-self, we find that the One can only be 
 defined by its negation and repulsion, which involves the category 
 of the Many. 
 
 It is objected that these transitions cannot be justified, 
 because they profess to be acts of pure thought, and it is im- 
 possible to advance by pure thought alone to anything new. 
 To this an answer was indicated in the last chapter, where we 
 found that the motive to the whole advance is the presence in 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. This needs some qualification in detail. Cp. my 
 Commentary on HegeVa Logic, Section 13. 
 
92 THE VALIDITY OP THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 experience, and in our minds as they become conscious of them- 
 selves in experience, of the concrete reality, of which all categories 
 are only descriptions, and of which the lower categories are imper- 
 fect descriptions^. Since pure thought has a double ground from 
 which it may work — -the abstract and imperfect explicit idea 
 from which the advance is to be made, and the concrete and 
 perfect implicit idea towards which the explicit idea gradually 
 advances — real progress is quite compatible with pure thought. 
 Because it has before it a whole which is so far merely implicit, 
 and has not been analysed, it can arrive at propositions which 
 were not contained, according to the rules of formal logic, in 
 the propositions from which it starts, but are an advance upon 
 the latter. On the other hand, the process remains one of pure 
 thought only, because this whole is not empirically given. It is 
 not empirically given, although it could not be given if experience 
 did not exist. For it is necessarily in all experience; and being 
 the essential nature of all reality, it can be deduced from any 
 piece of experience whatever. Our knowledge of it is dependent, 
 not on experience being thus and thus, but only on experience 
 existing at all. And the existence of experience cannot be called 
 an empirical fact. It is the presupposition alike of all empirical 
 knowledge, and of all pure thought. We should not be aware 
 even of the existence of the laws of formal logic without the 
 existence of experience. Yet those laws are not empirical, 
 because, although they have no meaning apart from experience, 
 they are not dependent on any one fact of experience, but are 
 the only conditions under which we can experience anything at 
 all. And for a similar reason, we need not suppose that dialectic 
 thought need be sterile because it claims to be pure. 
 
 82. From another point of view, it is sometimes said that 
 the transitions of the dialectic only exist because the connection 
 between the two categories has been demonstrated by means of 
 facts taken from experience. In that case the dialectic, whatever 
 value it might have, could not possess the inherent necessity, 
 which characterises the movements of pure thought, and which 
 its author claimed for it. It could at most be an induction from 
 experience, which could never rise above probability, nor be 
 
 1 Section 32. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 93 
 
 safely applied beyond the sphere in which it had been verified 
 by experience. I have endeavoured to show above that, since 
 thought can be pure without being sterile, it does not follow 
 that an advance must be empirical because it is real. Whether 
 it is in fact empirical or not, is another matter. If we can con- 
 ceive any change in the nature of the manifold of sensations, as 
 distinct from the categories by which they are built up, which 
 would invalidate any of the transitions of the dialectic, then no 
 doubt we should have to admit that the system had broken 
 down. It is of course impossible to prove generally and a 'priori 
 that no such flaw can be found in any part of the system. The 
 question must be settled by an investigation of each category 
 independently, showing that the argument in each depends upon 
 the movement of the pure notion, and not on any particulars 
 of sense. To do this would be beyond the scope of my present 
 essay, but the special importance of the idea of Motion renders 
 it necessary to discuss Trendelenburg's theory that it has been 
 illegitimately introduced into the dialectic by the observation 
 of empirical facts ^. 
 
 83. The remaining transition is that from thesis and antithesis 
 to synthesis. We have seen above^ that if the synthesis does 
 reconcile the contradictions, we are bound to accept it as valid, 
 unless we can find some other means of reconciling them. For 
 otherwise, since we cannot accept unreconciled contradictions 
 as true, we should have to deny the validity of thesis and anti- 
 thesis. And since the thesis itself was the only reconciliation 
 possible for a lower thesis and antithesis, we should have also 
 to deny the validity of the latter, and so on until, in the denial 
 of Being, we reached a reductio ad absurdum. All that remains, 
 therefore, is .to consider whether the synthesis is a sa tisfactory 
 reconc iliation of contradiction s. 
 
 With regard to the general possibility of transcending con- 
 tradictions, we must remember that the essence of the whole 
 dialectic lies in the assertion that the various pairs of contrary 
 categories are only produced by abstraction from the fuller 
 category in which they are synthesised. We have not, therefore, 
 to find some idea which shall be capable of reconciling two ideas 
 1 Sections 91-94. « Section 78. 
 
94 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 whicli had originally no relation to it. We are merely restoring 
 the unity from which those ideas originally came. It is not, as 
 we might be tempted to think, the reconciliation of the contra- 
 diction which is an artificial expedient of our minds in dealing 
 with reality. It is rather the creation of the contradiction which 
 was artificial and subjective. The synthesis is the logical pritis 
 of its moments. Bearing this in mind, we shall see that the 
 possibility of transcending contradictions is a simpler question 
 than it appears to be. For all that has to be overcome is a mistake 
 about the nature of reality, due to the incomplete insight of the 
 Understanding. The contradiction has not so much to be con- 
 quered as to be disproved. 
 
 84. Hartmann objects that the only result of the union of 
 two contraries is a blank, and not a richer truth^. This is certainly 
 true of the examples Hartmann takes, + y and — y, for these, 
 treated as mathematical terms, do not admit of synthesis, but 
 merely of mechanical combination. 
 
 Hegel never maintained that two such terms as these, opposed 
 in this way, could ever produce anything but a blank. Hartmann 
 appears to think that he endeavoured to synthesise them in the 
 passage in the Greater Logic^, when he makes + y and — y equal 
 to y and again to 2y. But clearly neither y nor 2y could be a 
 synthesis oi + y and — y, for a synthesis must introduce a new 
 and higher idea. All Hegel meant here was that both + y and — y 
 are of the nature of y, and that they are also both quantities, 
 so that from one point of view they are both simply y (as a mile 
 east and a mile west are both a mile) and from another point 
 of view they are 2y (as in going a mile east, and then returning 
 westwards for the same distance, we walk two miles). This gives 
 us no reason to suppose that Hegel did not see that if we oppose 
 + yto — y, taking the opposition of the signs into consideration, 
 the result will be 0. 
 
 But this tells us nothing about the possibility of synthesis. 
 For Hegel does not, to obtain a synthesis, simply predicate the 
 two opposite categories of the same subject, — a course which he, 
 like everyone else, would admit to be impossible. He passes to 
 another category, in which the first two are contained, yet in 
 1 op. cit. II. B. 7. 2 Werke, Vol. iv. p. 53. 
 
Ill] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 95 
 
 such a way that the incompatibility ceases. The result here is 
 by no means an empty zero, because the synthesis is not a mere 
 mechanical junction of two contradictory categories, but is the 
 real unity, of which the thesis and antithesis are two aspects, 
 which do not, however, exhaust its meaning. Whether the 
 attempt to find such syntheses has in fact been successful all 
 through the Logic, is, of course, another question. Such a solu- 
 tion however would meet Hartmann's difficulty, and he has 
 given no reason why such a solution should be impossible. The 
 nature of his example in itself proves that he has failed to grasp 
 the full meaning of the process. In algebra there is no richer 
 notion than that of quantity, in which + y and — y are directly 
 opposed. No synthesis is therefore possible, and the terms cannot 
 be brought together, except in that external unity which pro- 
 duces a mere blank. But such a case, which can only be dealt 
 with by the most abstract of all sciences, cannot possibly be a 
 fair example of a system whose whole life consists in the gradual 
 removal of abstractions. 
 
 85. We have seen that the cogency of the entire process rests 
 mainly on the fact that the system is analytic as well as synthetic, 
 and that it does not evolve an entirely new result, but only 
 renders explicit what was previously implicit in all experience. 
 On the ground of this very characteristic of the dialectic, Tren- 
 delenburg denies that it can have any objective validity. It 
 may be convenient to quote his account of the dialectic process, 
 which Professor Seth translates as follows^ : " The dialectic begins 
 according to its own declaration with abstraction; for if 'pure 
 being' is represented as equivalent to 'nothing' thought has 
 reduced the fulness of the world to the merest emptiness. But 
 it is the essence of abstraction that the elements of thought 
 which in their original form are intimately united are violently 
 held apart. What is thus isolated by abstraction, however, cannot 
 but strive to escape from this forced position. Inasmuch as it 
 is a part torn from a whole, it cannot but bear upon it the traces 
 that it is only a part ; it must crave to be completed. When this 
 completion takes place, there will arise a conception which 
 contains the former in itself. But inasmuch as only one step 
 ^ Hegdianism and Personality, p. 92. 
 
96 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [en. 
 
 of the original abstraction has been retraced, the new conception 
 will repeat the process ; and this will go on until the full reality 
 of perception has been restored.... Plainly a whole world may 
 develop itself in this fashion, and, if we look more narrowly, 
 we have discovered here the secret of the dialectic method. That 
 method is simply the art by which we undo or retrace our 
 original abstraction. The first ideas, because they are the 
 products of abstraction, are recognised on their first appearance 
 as mere parts or elements of a higher conception, and the 
 merit of the dialectic really lies in the comprehensive survey 
 of these parts from every side, and the thereby increased 
 certainty we gain of their necessary connection with one 
 another^." And he immediately continues, "What mean- 
 while happens in this progress is only a history of subjective 
 knowledge, no development of the reality itself from its 
 elements. For there is nothing corresponding in reality which 
 answers to the first abstraction of pure being. It is a strained 
 image, produced by the analysing mind, and no right appears 
 anywhere to find in pure being the first germ of an objective 
 development." 
 
 In answer to this objection I may quote Mr F. H. Bradley, 
 "you make no answer to the claim of Dialectic, if you establish 
 the fact that external experience has already given it what it 
 professes to evolve, and that no synthesis comes out but what 
 before has gone in. All this may be admitted, for the question 
 at issue is not. What can appear, and How comes it to appear? 
 The question is as to the manner of its appearing, when it is 
 induced to appear, and as to the special mode in which the mind 
 recasts and regards the matter it may have otherwise acquired. 
 To use two technical terms which I confess I regard with some 
 aversion — the point in dispute is not whether the product is d 
 posteriori, but whether, being a posteriori, it is not a 'priori also 
 and as welF." And in the previous Section, speaking of the 
 difference between common recognition and the dialectic, he 
 says "The content in one case, itself irrational, seems to come 
 to our reason from a world without, while in the other it appears 
 
 ^ Logische U titer suchungen. Vol. i. p. 94. 
 
 * Logic, Book iii. Part i. Chap. ii. Section 20. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 97 
 
 as that natural outcome of our inmost constitution, which satisfies 
 us because it is our own selves." 
 
 86. The process is more than is expressed by Trendelenburg's 
 phrase "the art by which we retrace or undo our original ab- 
 stractions " ("die Kunst wodurch die urspriingliche Abstraction 
 zurlickgethan wird"). For the abstractions are not passively 
 retraced by us, but insist on retracing themselves on pain of con- 
 tradiction. Doubtless, as Trendelenburg says, to do this belongs 
 to the nature of abstractions from a concrete whole. But then 
 the significance of the dialectic might not unfairly be said to 
 lie in the fact that it proved that our more abstract thought- 
 categories were abstractions in this sense — a truth which without 
 the dialectic we should not have known. All analysis results, 
 no doubt, in ideas more or less abstract, but not necessarily in 
 abstractions which spontaneously tend to return to the original 
 idea analysed. The idea of a living fo ot apart fr om the idea of ^| 
 a body does contam acontradiction.VVe know that a living loot v^ v 
 HH only exist in connection with a living body, and if we grant i^ 
 the first to exist at any given time and place we know that we 
 also admit, by implication, the other. Now the idea of a steam 
 flour-mill can in like manner be separated into two parts — that 
 it is moved by steam, and that its object is to grind corn. But 
 to admit that one of these ideas can be apphed as a predicate 
 to any given subject is not equivalent to admitting that the 
 other can be applied to it also, and that the subject is a steam 
 flour-mill. For a machine moved by steam can be used to weave 
 cotton, and water-power can be used to grind corn. We have 
 formed from our original idea two which are more abstract — 
 the idea of a machine moved by steam, and the idea of a machine 
 which grinds corn. But neither of them shows the least impulse 
 to "retrace or undo our original abstraction." 
 
 The important question is, then, of which sort are the abstrac- 
 tions of which Hegel treats in the dialectic? It would, probably, 
 be generally admitted that those which he ranks as the lower 
 categories are more abstract, that is to say have less content, 
 than those which he considers higher. But they may be, for 
 anything that superficial observation can tell us, the real units, 
 of which the higher categories are mere combinations. No one 
 
 M.H. 7 
 
98 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 will deny that the idea of Causality includes the idea of Being. 
 But it might contain it only as the idea of a steam flour-mill 
 contains the idea of steam-power, so that it would not at all 
 follow that the category of Causality is applicable to all being, 
 any more than that all steam-power is used for grinding corn. 
 And we should not be able, from this inclusion of the idea of 
 Being in the idea of Causality, to conclude that the law of 
 Causality was applicable anywhere at all, even if the validity 
 of the idea of Being was admitted. For the particular case in 
 which Being was combined with Causality might be one which 
 never really occurred, just as there might be machines moved 
 by steam-power without any of them being flour-mills. 
 
 87. The dialectic, however, puts us in a different position. 
 From that we learn that Being is an abstraction, the truth of 
 which can be found only in Causality, and in the higher categories 
 into which Causality in turn develops. Being, therefore, in- 
 evitably leads us on to Causality, so that, to whatever subject- 
 matter we can apply the first as a predicate, to that we must 
 necessarily apply the other. 
 
 The same change takes place in the relations of all the other 
 categories. Without the dialectic we might suppose Life to be 
 an effect of certain chemical combinations; with it we find that 
 Chemism is an abstraction from Life, so that, wherever there is 
 Chemism there must be Life also. Without the dialectic, again, 
 we might suppose self-consciousness to be a mere effect of animal 
 life ; with it, we are compelled to regard all life as merely relative 
 to some self-consciousness. 
 
 The result of the dialectic is thus much more than "the in- 
 creased certainty we gain of the necessary connection" of parts 
 of thought "with one another." For it must be remembered 
 that organic wholes are not to be explained by their parts, but 
 the reverse, while on the other hand merely composite wholes 
 can be best explained from the units of which they are made up. 
 We cannot explain a living body by putting together the ideas 
 of the isolated limbs, though we might, if our knowledge was 
 sufficiently complete, explain a limb by the idea of the body 
 as a whole. But we cannot explain the sizes and shapes of stones 
 from the, idea of the beach which they make up, while, on the 
 
ra] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 99 
 
 other hand, if we knew the sizes, shapes, and positions of all the 
 stones, we should have complete knowledge of the beach. And 
 the dialectic professes to show that the lower categories are 
 contained in the higher in a manner more resembling that in 
 which a foot is related to a body, than that in which a stone is 
 related to a beach. The success of the dialectic, therefore, means 
 no less than this — that, for purposes of ultimate explanation, 
 we reverse the order of science and the understanding, and, 
 instead of attempting to account for the higher phenomena of 
 nature (i.e. those which frima facie exhibit the higher categories) 
 by means of the laws of the lower, we account for the lower by 
 means of the laws of the higher. The interest of this for the 
 theoretical reason is obvious, and its importance for the practical 
 reason is no less, since the lower categories are those of matter 
 and the higher those of spirit. 
 
 88. So also it is not fair to say that the process is only one 
 of subjective thought. It is doubtless true that the various 
 abstractions which form the steps of the dialectic have no 
 separate existence corresponding to them in the world of reality, 
 where only the concrete notion is to be found. But the result 
 is one which has validity for objective thought. For it is by 
 that result that we learn that the notion is really a concrete 
 unity, and that there is nothing corresponding in the outside 
 world to the separated fragments of the notion which form the 
 stages of finite thought. This is the same conclusion from another 
 point of view as the one mentioned in the preceding paragraph, 
 and it is surely both objective and important. 
 
 Moreover the objective significance of the dialectic process is 
 not confined to this negative result. For the different imperfect 
 categories, although they have no separate objective existence, 
 yet have an objective existence, as elements in the concrete 
 whole, which is made up of them. If we ask what is the nature 
 of the Absolute Idea, we must, from one side, answer that "its 
 true content is only the whole system, of which we have been 
 hitherto studying the development^." Since the one absolute 
 reality may be expressed as the synthesis of these categories, 
 they have reality in it. 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 237, lecture note. 
 
 7—2 
 
100 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [CH. 
 
 Besides this, in the sphere of our ordinary finite thought, in 
 which we use the imperfect categories as stable and permanent, 
 the dialectic gives us objective information as to the relative 
 amounts of truth and error which may be expected from the 
 use of various categories, and as to the comparative reahty and 
 significance of different ways of regarding the universe, — as, for 
 example, that the idea of Life goes more deeply into the nature 
 of reality than the idea of Mechanism. 
 
 89. We are now in a position to meet the dilemma with which 
 Trendelenburg challenges the dialectic. "Either" he says "the 
 dialectic development is independent, and only conditioned by 
 itself, then in fact it must know everything for itself. Or it 
 assumes finite sciences and empirical knowledge, but then the 
 immanent process and the unbroken connection are broken 
 through by what is assumed from outside, and it relates itself 
 to experience quite uncritically. The dialectic can choose. We 
 see no third possibility^." And just before he gives a further 
 description of the second alternative. "It works then only in 
 the same way and with the same means as the other sciences, 
 only differing from them in its goal, — to unite the parts to the 
 idea of the whole." 
 
 Neither of these two alternatives is valid. The dialectic develop- 
 ment is only so far " independent and only conditioned by itself," 
 that it does not depend on any particular sensuous content of 
 experience, and would develop in the same way, whatever that 
 content might be. But it does not follow that it knows every- 
 thing for itself. All that part of knowledge which depends upon 
 one content rather than another — the whole, that is, of what is 
 ordinarily called science — certainly cannot be reached from the 
 dialectic alone in the present state of our knowledge, and perhaps 
 never will be^. Nor does the dialectic, as we have seen, assume 
 finite sciences and empirical knowledge. In one sense, indeed, 
 their subject-matter is the condition of its validity, for it en- 
 deavours to analyse the concrete idea which is implicit in all 
 our experience. The dialectic may be said therefore, in a sense, 
 to depend on the fact that we have empirical knowledge, without 
 which we should be conscious of nothing, not even of ourselves 
 1 op. cit. Vol. I. pp. 91, 92. 2 cp. Chap. u. Section 59. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 101 
 
 (since it is only in experience that we become self-conscious), and 
 in that case there would be no chance of the complete and concrete 
 idea being implicitly in our minds, which is a necessary pre- 
 liminary to our subsequently making it explicit in the dialectic. 
 
 This however does not make it depend upon the finite sciences 
 and empirical knowledge. It is dependent for its existence on 
 the existence of empirical knowledge, but its nature does not 
 at all depend on the nature of our empirical knowledge. And it 
 would only be this latter relation which would 'break through 
 the immanent process by what is assumed from outside." The 
 process can be, and is, one of pure thought, although pure 
 thought is only given as one element in experience. 
 
 The dialectic retraces the steps of abstraction till it arrives 
 at the concrete idea. If the concrete idea were different, the 
 dialectic process would be different. The conditions of the 
 dialectic are therefore that the concrete idea should be what it 
 is, and that there should be experience in which we may become 
 conscious of that idea. But it is not a condition of the dialectic 
 that all the contingent facts which are found in experience should 
 be what they are, and not otherwise. So far as we know, the 
 relation of the categories to one another might be the same, even 
 if sugar, for example, was bitter to the taste, and hare-bells had 
 scarlet flowers. And if such particulars ever should be deducible 
 from the pure idea, so that they could not be otherwise than 
 they are without some alteration in the nature of the pure idea, 
 then they would cease to be merely empirical knowledge. In 
 our present state the particulars of sense are only empirically 
 and contingently connected with the idea under which they are 
 brought. And although, if the dialectic is to exist, the idea must 
 be what it is, and must have some sensations to complement it, 
 yet the particular nature of those sensations is entirely indifferent 
 to the dialectic, which is not dependent upon it in any sense of 
 the word. 
 
 90. It is no doubt the case that an advanced state of the 
 finite sciences is a considerable help to the discovery of the 
 dialectic process, and this for several reasons. In the first place 
 the labour is easier because it is shghter. To detect the necessary 
 relation between two categories will be easier when both are 
 
102 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 already explicitly before us in consciousness than when only 
 one is given in this way, and the other has to be constructed. 
 The inadequacy, for example, of the category of Teleology would 
 be by itself logically sufficient ground for discovering the category 
 of Life. But it is much easier to see, when that idea is necessarily 
 before us in biological science, that it is the necessary consequence 
 of the idea of Teleology, than it would be to construct it by the 
 dialectic, although that would be possible for a sufficiently keen 
 observer. In the second place, the more frequently, and the 
 more keenly, the finite categories are used in finite science, the 
 more probable it will be that the contradiction involved in their 
 use will have become evident, on some occasion or the other, 
 to some at least of those who use them, and the easier will it 
 be, therefore, to point out the various inadequacies of each 
 category in succession, which are the stepping stones of the 
 dialectic. But all this only shows that the appearance of the 
 theory of the dialectic in a philosophical system is partly deter- 
 mined by empirical causes, which surely no one ever denied. It 
 is possible that we might have had to wait for the theory of 
 gravitation for some time longer, if it had not been for the 
 traditional apple, and no one could go beyond a certain point 
 in mathematical calculation without the help of pens and paper. 
 But the logical validity of the theory of gravitation, when once 
 discovered, does not come as a deduction from the existence of 
 the apple, or of writing materials. With sufficient power, any 
 of the calculations could have been made without the help of 
 writing. Any other case of gravitation would have done as well 
 as the apple, if it had happened to suggest to Newton the problem 
 which lay in it as much as in the other. And, in the same way, 
 with sufficient mental acuteness the whole dialectic process could 
 have been discovered, by starting from any one piece of experience, 
 and without postulating any other empirical knowledge what- 
 ever. For the whole concrete idea lies behind experience, and 
 manifests itself in every part of it. Any fragment of experience, 
 therefore, would be sufficient to present the idea to our minds, 
 and thus give us implicitly the concrete truth, whose presence 
 in this manner is the real source of our discontent with the lower 
 categories, and consequently is the spring of the dialectic process. 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 103 
 
 In any single fact in experience, however trifling and wherever 
 selected, the dialectic could find all the basis of experience that 
 it needs. Doubtless it would have been a task beyond even 
 Hegel's strength to evolve the dialectic without a far larger 
 basis, and without the aid of specially suggestive portions of 
 experience. But this, while it may have some interest for 
 empirical psychology, can have none for metaphysics. 
 
 91 . I have thus endeavoured to show that the dialectic process 
 is related to experience in such a way as to avoid sterility, and 
 at the same time not necessarily to fall into empiricism. We have 
 now to consider Trendelenburg's contention^ that at one point 
 an idea of great importance, the idea of Motion, has in fact been 
 introduced from experience in a merely empirical manner, thus 
 destroying the value of the Logic as a theory of the nature of 
 pure thought. 
 
 He points out that Hegel endeavours to deduce the category 
 of Becoming, which involves the idea of Motion, from the two 
 categories of Being and Not-Being, which are ideas of rest. His 
 inference is that the idea of Motion has been uncritically im- 
 ported from experience, and breaks the connection of the Logic. 
 Certainly no flaw could be more fatal than this, for it occurs at 
 the second step in the dialectic, and, if it is really a flaw, must 
 make everything beyond this point useless. 
 
 It is certainly true that the category of Becoming involves 
 the idea of Motion, and that neither the category of Being, nor 
 the category of Not-Being, do so. There is something in the 
 synthesis which is neither in the thesis nor the antithesis, if 
 each of these is taken alone and separately. This, however, is 
 the necessary result wherever the dialectic process is applied. 
 That process does not profess to be merely analytic of the premises 
 we start from, but to give us new truth. If it were not so, it 
 could have no philosophical importance whatever, but would be 
 confined to the somewhat sterile occupation of discovering what 
 consequence could be drawn by formal logic from the assertion 
 of the simple notion of pure Being — the only premise from which 
 we start. 
 
 92. Whatever Hegel meant by his philosophy, he certainly 
 
 1 op. cit. Vol. I. p. 38. 
 
104 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 meant more than this. We must presume then that he had 
 faced the fact that his conclusions contained more than his 
 premises. And there is nothing unjustifiable, — nothing which 
 necessitates the illegitimate introduction of an empirical element 
 — in this. For we must recollect that the dialectic process has 
 as its basis, not merely the consciously accepted premises, from 
 which it proceeds synthetically, but also the implicit concrete 
 and complete idea which it analyses and brings into distinct 
 consciousness. There is, therefore, nothing unjustifiable in the 
 synthesis having more in it than both the thesis and antithesis, 
 for this additional element is taken from the concrete idea which 
 is the real motive power of the dialectic advance. As this con- 
 crete idea is pure thought, no introduction of an empirical 
 element is necessary. 
 
 And, if we examine the process in detail, we shall find that 
 no such empirical element has been introduced. The first point 
 at which Motion is involved in the dialectic is not that at which 
 the category of Becoming is already recognised explicitly as a 
 category, and as the synthesis of the preceding thesis and anti- 
 thesis. Before we have a category of motion, we perceive a 
 motion of the categories; we are forced into the admission that 
 Becoming is a fundamental idea of the universe because of the 
 tendency we find in the ideas already accepted as fundamental 
 to become one another. There is therefore no illegitimate step 
 in the introduction of the synthesis, for the idea of Motion is 
 already involved in the relation of the two lower categories to 
 each other, and the synthesis only makes this explicit. 
 
 The introduction of empirical matter must come then, if it 
 comes at all, in the recognition of the fact that Being is just as 
 much Nothing, and Nothing is just as much Being. If we start 
 by positing the first, we find ourselves also positing the second. 
 The one standpoint cannot be maintained alone, but if we start 
 from it, we find ourselves at the other. To account for this it is 
 not necessary to bring in any empirical element. For although 
 neither of the two categories has the idea of Motion explicitly 
 in it, each of them is, of its own nature, forced into the move- 
 ment towards the other, by reason of its own incompleteness and 
 inadequacy. Now in this there is nothing that requires any aid 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 105 
 
 from empirical observation. For Trendelenburg remarks himself, 
 in the passage quoted above, that all abstractions "cannot but 
 strive to escape from this forced position." It is thus simply as 
 the result of the nature of pure thought that we arrive at the 
 conclusion that there is a motion of the categories. And, having 
 discovered this, we are only using the data fairly before us when 
 we recognise a category of motion, and so reconcile the contra- 
 diction which arises from the fact that two categories, which 
 profess, as all terms must, to have a fixed and constant meaning, 
 are nevertheless themselves in continual motion. 
 
 Of course all this can only take place on the supposition that 
 experience does exist. For, in the first place, since pure thought 
 is only an abstraction, and never really exists except as an 
 element in experience, it is impossible to come across the ideas 
 of Being and Not-Being at all, except in experience. And, 
 secondly, it is only in experience that the concrete idea is implicit, 
 which brings about the transition from category to category, and 
 so first introduces the idea of Motion. But this, as was pointed 
 out above^, involves no dependence on empirical data. All that 
 is required for the purpose is that element in experience which 
 is called pure thought, and, although this cannot be present 
 without the empirical element, the argument does not in the 
 least depend on the nature of the latter. 
 
 93. We are told also that Becoming involves time and space, 
 which Hegel admits not to be elements of pure thought, but to 
 belong to the world of nature. Now in the first place it does not 
 seem necessary that the Becoming referred to here should be 
 only such as must take place in time or space. It no doubt in- 
 cludes Becoming in time and space. But it would seem to include 
 also a purely logical Becoming — where the transition is not from 
 one event in time to a subsequent event, nor from one part of 
 space to another, but from one idea to another logically con- 
 nected with it. The movement is here only the movement of 
 logic, such as may be said to take place from the premises to 
 the conclusion of a syllogism. This involves neither space nor 
 time. It is, of course, true that this process can only be perceived 
 by us by means of a process in time. We have first to think the 
 ^ Chap. I. Section 15. 
 
106 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 premises and then the conclusion. But this does not make the 
 syllogism itself a process in time. The validity of the argument 
 does not depend upon the fact that we have perceived it; and 
 the movement of attention from one step to another of the 
 process — a movement which is certainly in time — must not be 
 confounded with the logical movement of the argument itself, 
 which is not in time. 
 
 It is again, no doubt, true that if we wish to imagine the 
 process of Becoming, we cannot imagine it, except as taking 
 place in time. But this is no objection. Imagination is a sen- 
 suous process, and involves sensuous elements. It does not follow 
 that it is impossible to think Becoming except as in time. 
 
 If then the Becoming of the Logic includes a species of Becoming 
 which does not take place in time or space, it follows, of course, 
 that the introduction of that category does not involve the in- 
 troduction of time and space into the dialectic. But even if we 
 leave out this point, and confine ourselves to those species of 
 Becoming which can only take place in time and space, it would 
 not follow that these notions have been introduced into the 
 dialectic. For, even on this hypothesis. Becoming only involves 
 time and space in the sense that it cannot be represented without 
 them. It could still be distinguished from them, and its nature 
 as a pure category observed. If indeed the argument by which 
 we are led on from Becoming to the next category was based 
 on anything in the nature of time and space, Trendelenburg's 
 objection would doubtless be made good. But it is no more 
 necessary that this should be the case, because time and space 
 are the necessary medium in which we perceive the idea of 
 Becoming, than that every step of the whole dialectic process 
 should be tainted with empiricism, because every category can 
 only be perceived in the whole of experience, in which it is 
 bound up with empirical elements. And the transition which 
 Hegel gives to the category of Being-determinate does not 
 seem in any way to depend upon the nature of time and space, 
 but rather on the nature of Becoming, as a determination of 
 thought^. 
 
 94. Again, it is said that Being and Not-Being are abstractions, 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. A paragraph has been omitted here. 
 
m] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 107 
 
 while Becoming is a "concrete intuition ruling life and death^." 
 It is no doubt true that we never encounter, and cannot imagine, 
 a case of Becoming without sensuous intuition. But the same 
 might be said of any other category. Thought can never exist 
 without sensation. And the quality of Becoming itself is not 
 sensation, but thought. What becomes, indeed, must be told us 
 by sensation, but that it becomes is as much a conception of pure 
 thought as that it is, or is not. And the ideas of Being and Not- 
 Being are scarcely more abstract than Becoming is. For they 
 also cannot come into consciousness except as combined with 
 intuition. They are doubtless abstract in the sense that we feel 
 at once their inadequacy to any subject-matter. But this is the 
 case to almost the same extent with Becoming, if we take it 
 strictly. As a general rule, when we talk in ordinary discourse 
 of Becoming, or of any other of the lower categories, we do not 
 take it by itself, but mix it up with higher categories, such as 
 Being-determinate, Substance, and Cause. If we do this, Being 
 and Not-Being may pass as concrete. If we do not do it, but 
 confine ourselves to the strict meaning of the category. Becoming 
 shows itself to be almost as abstract and inadequate as pure 
 Being. The philosophy which corresponds to Becoming is the 
 doctrine of the eternal flux of all things, and it is difficult to see 
 how this represents reality much more adequately than the 
 Eleatic Being, or the Buddhist Nothing. Of course Becoming is 
 to some extent more adequate than the categories that precede 
 it, but this is the natural and inevitable result of the fact that 
 it synthesises them. 
 
 95. We must, in conclusion, consider the claims of the Hegelian 
 system to ontological validity. This subject divides itself into 
 two parts. In the first place Hegel denies the Kantian restriction 
 of knowledge to mere phenomena, behind which lie things in 
 themselves which we cannot know and he asserts that the laws 
 of thought traced in the logic, as applicable to all possible know- 
 ledge, are applicable also to all reality. In the second place he 
 deduces from the Logic the philosophies of Nature and Spirit. 
 
 Now as to the first of these two points, I have already en- 
 deavoured to show that any denial of it involves a contradiction'^. 
 ^ Trendelenburg, op. cit. Vol. i. p. 38. * Chap. i. Section 25. 
 
108 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [CH. 
 
 We are told by those who attempt this denial that there are or 
 may be things which we cannot know. But to know of the 
 actuality or possibility of such things is to know them — to know 
 that of which knowledge is impossible. Of course to know only 
 that things are possible, or even that they actually exist, and to 
 know nothing else about them, is very imperfect and inadequate 
 knowledge of them. But it is knowledge. It involves a judgment, 
 and a judgment involves a category. It is thus impossible to 
 say that the existence of anything which does not conform to 
 the universal laws of knowledge is either actual or possible. If 
 the supporters of things-in-themselves were asked for a defence 
 of their doctrine, they would be compelled to relate these things 
 with our sensuous intuitions, through which alone data can be 
 given to our minds. And this relation would bring them in 
 connection with the world of knowledge, and destroy their 
 asserted independence. 
 
 In fact the question whether there is any reality outside the 
 world which we know by experience is unmeaning. There is much 
 reality which we do not know; it is even possible that there is 
 much reality which we never shall know. But it must, if we 
 are to have any right to speak of it at all, belong to the same 
 universe as the facts which we do not know — that is, be con- 
 nected with them by the same fundamental laws as those by 
 which they are connected with one another. Otherwise we can 
 have no justification for supposing that it exists, since all such 
 suppositions must rest on some connection with the world of 
 reality. We are not even entitled to say that it is possible that 
 there may exist a world unconnected with the world of experience. 
 For possibility is a phrase which derives all its meaning to us 
 from its use in the world of experience, and beyond that world 
 we have no right to use it, since anything brought under that, 
 or any other predicate, is brought thereby into the world of 
 the knowable. And a mere empty possibility, not based on the 
 known existence of at least one of the necessary conditions, is 
 too indefinite to possess any significance. Anything, however 
 impossible, may be pronounced possible, if we are only ignorant 
 enough of the subject-matter, for if our ignorance extends to all 
 the circumstances incompatible with the truth of the proposition, 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 109 
 
 all evidence of impossibility is obviously beyond our reach. But 
 the more ignorance is involved in such a conclusion, the less 
 valuable it is, and when it is based on complete ignorance, as 
 any proposition relating to the possibility of a world outside 
 knowledge must inevitably be, the judgment becomes entirely 
 frivolous. It is merely negative and does not, as a real judgment 
 of possibility does, create the slightest expectation of reality, 
 but is devoid of all rational interest. Such a judgment, as 
 Mr Bradley points out, " is absurd, because a privative judgment, 
 where the subject is left entirely undetermined in respect of the 
 suggestion, has no kind of meaning. Privation gets a meaning 
 where the subject is determined by a quality or an environment 
 which we have reason to think would give either the acceptance 
 or the rej ection of X. But if we keep entirely to the bare universal, 
 we cannot predicate absence, since the space we call empty has 
 no existence^." And as Hegel's theory, if valid at all, covers 
 the whole sphere of actual and possible knowledge, any specula- 
 tions on the nature of reality outside its sphere are meaningless, 
 and the results of the dialectic may be predicated of all reality. 
 96. The demand that the dialectic shall confine itself to a 
 purely subjective import, and not presume to limit reality by 
 its results, has been made from a fresh point of view by Mr F. C. S. 
 Schiller. He says "It does not follow that because all truth in 
 the narrower sense is abstract, because all philosophy must be 
 couched in abstract terms, therefore the whole truth about the 
 universe in the wider sense, i.e. the ultimate account that can 
 be given of it, can be compressed into a single abstract formula, 
 and that the scheme of things is nothing more than, e.g., the 
 self-development of the Absolute Idea. To draw this inference 
 would be to confuse the thought-symbol, which is, and must be, 
 the instrument of thought, with that which the symbol expresses, 
 often only very imperfectly, viz. the reality which is 'known* 
 only in experience and can never be evoked by the incantations 
 of any abstract formula. If we avoid this confusion, we shall 
 no longer be prone to think that we have disposed of the thing 
 symbohsed when we have brought home imperfection and con- 
 tradiction to the formulas whereby we seek to express it... to 
 ^ Logic, Book i. Chap. vn. Section 30. 
 
110 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 suppose, e.g., that Time and Change cannot really be charac- 
 teristic of the universe, because our thought, in attempting to 
 represent them by abstract symbols, often contradicts itself. 
 For evidently the contradiction may result as well from the in- 
 adequacy of our symbols to express realities of whose existence 
 we are directly assured by other factors in experience, and which 
 consequently are data rather than problems for thought, as from 
 the 'merely apparent' character of their reality, and the moral 
 to be drawn may only be the old one, that it is the function of 
 thought to mediate and not to create^." 
 
 It is no doubt true that there is something else in our ex- 
 perience besides pure thought — namely, the immediate data of 
 sensation. And these are independent of thought in the sense 
 that they cannot be deduced from it, or subordinated to it, but 
 must be recognised as a correlative and indispensable factor in 
 experience. But it is not an independent element in the sense 
 that it can exist or express reality a'part from thought. And it 
 would have, it seems to me, to be independent in this sense before 
 we could accept Mr Schiller's argument. 
 
 97. Sensation without thought could assure us of the existence 
 of nothing. Not of any objects outside the sentient being— for 
 these objects are for us clearly ideal constructions. Not of the 
 self who feels sensation — for a self is not itself a sensation, and 
 the assurance of its reality must be an inference. Nay, sensation 
 cannot assure us of its own existence. For the very terms ex- 
 istence, reality, assurance, are all terms of thought. To appeal 
 (as Mr Schiller wishes to do, if I have understood him rightly) 
 from a dialectic which shows, e.g. that Time cannot be real, to 
 an experience which tells us that it is real, is useless. For our 
 assurance of reality is itself an act of thought, and anything 
 which the dialectic has proved about the nature of thought would 
 be applicable to that assurance. 
 
 It is difficult to see how sensations could even exist without 
 thought. For sensations certainly only exist for consciousness, 
 and what could a consciousness be which was nothing but a 
 chaotic mass of sensations, with no relations among them, and 
 consequently no unity for itself? But, even if they could exist 
 ^ "The Metaphysics of the Time-Process," Mind, n.s. Vol. iv. No. 14. p. 40. 
 
ml THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 111 
 
 without thought, they could tell us nothing of reality or existence, 
 for reality and existence are not themselves sensations, and all 
 analysis or inference, by which they might be reached from sen- 
 sations, must be the work of thought. 
 
 By the side of the truth that thought without data can never 
 make us aware of reality, we must place the corresponding truth 
 that nothing can make us aware of reality without thought. Any 
 law therefore which can be laid down for thought, must be a law 
 which imposes itself on all reality which we can either know or 
 imagine — and a reality which we can neither know nor imagine is, 
 as I fancy Mr Schiller would admit, a meaningless abstraction. 
 
 To the demand then that we should admit the reality of any- 
 thing although "we have brought home imperfection and con- 
 tradiction to the formulas whereby we seek to express it," I 
 should answer that it is only by the aid of these formulas that 
 we can pronounce it real. If we cannot think it, we have no right 
 to pronounce it real, for to pronounce it real is an act of thought. 
 We should not, therefore, by pronouncing it real, be appealing 
 from thought to some other means of knowledge. We should be 
 thinking it, at the same time, to be real and to be self-con- 
 tradictory. To say that a thing whose notion is self -contradictory 
 is real, is to say that two or more contradictory propositions are 
 true — that is, to violate the law of contradiction. If we do this 
 we put an end to all possibility of coherent thought anywhere. 
 If a contradiction is not a sign of error it will be impossible to 
 make any inference whatever. 
 
 And so it seems to me, in spite of Mr Schiller's arguments, 
 that if we find contradictions in our notion of a thing, we must 
 give up its reality. This does not mean, of course, that we are 
 to say that there was nothing real behind the contradictory 
 appearance. Behind all appearance there is some reality. But 
 this reality, before we can know it, must be re-thought in terms 
 which are mutually coherent, and although we certainly have 
 not "disposed of the thing symbohsed when we have brought 
 home imperfection and contradiction to the formulas whereby 
 we seek to express it," we can only retain our belief in the thing's 
 existence by thinking it under some other formula, by which 
 the imperfection and the contradiction are removed. 
 
112 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 98. There remains only the transition from Logic to Nature 
 and Spirit. From what has been said in Chapters i and ii, it 
 will be seen that the vahdity of this transition must be deter- 
 mined by the same general considerations as determine the 
 validity of the transitions from one category to another within 
 the Logic. For the motive power of the transition was the same 
 — the impatience of its incompleteness felt by an abstraction, 
 since the whole of thought, even when it has attained the utmost 
 completeness of which it is capable, is only an abstraction from 
 the fuller whole of reality. And the method of the transition 
 is also the same — the discovery of a contradiction arising from 
 the inadequacy of the single term, which leads us on to the 
 opposite extreme, which is also found to be contradictory, and 
 so leaves us no refuge but a synthesis which comprehends and 
 reconciles both extremes. I have endeavoured to show in the 
 last chapter that this was all that Hegel ever intended to do, 
 and that no other deduction of Nature and Spirit from pure 
 thought can be attributed to him. We have now to consider 
 whether he was justified in proceeding in this manner. 
 
 Is thought incomplete as compared with the whole of reality? 
 This can scarcely be denied. To admit it does not involve any 
 scepticism as to the adequacy of knowledge. Thought may be 
 perfectly capable of expressing the whole of reality, all that is 
 real may be rational, but it will nevertheless remain true that 
 all that is real cannot be merely reasoning. For all reasoning 
 as such is merely mediate, and it is obvious that a mediation 
 without something which it mediates is a contradiction. This 
 something must be given immediately. It is true that thought 
 itself, as an event in our consciousness, may be given immediately, 
 and may be perceived by inner sense, in the same way that 
 colours, sounds, and the like, may be perceived by outer sense. 
 But this means that thought, considered as it is in the Logic 
 (i.e. not as a datum, but as an activity), can never be self-sub- 
 sistent, but must always depend on something (even if that 
 something is other thought), which presents itself immediately. 
 And thus the Logic, which only deals with the forms by which 
 we may mediate what is immediately given, does not by itself 
 contain the whole of reality. 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OP THE DIALECTIC 113 
 
 99. This is obviously the case while, as at present, a large 
 amount of experience is concerned with physical data apparently 
 entirely contingent to the idea, and with mental data scarcely 
 less contingent. It is quite clear that the Logic does not as yet 
 express the whole universe, while we still find ultimate and un- 
 explained such facts as that one particular number of vibrations 
 of ether in a second gives us the sensation of blue, and that 
 another particular number gives us the sensation of red. But 
 even if the process of rationahsation was carried as far as it 
 could by any possibility go, if all matter was reduced to spirit, 
 and every quality of spirit was deduced from the Logic, never- 
 theless to constitute experience something would have to be 
 immediately given, and the Logic contemplates nothing but 
 thought as it deals with something given already. The existence 
 of thought requires the existence of something given. It is un- 
 deniable that we think. But we could not think unless there 
 were something to think about. Therefore there must be some- 
 thing. This is all of the world of Nature and Spirit which we can 
 deduce from the Logic. Logic must have its complement and 
 correlative, and the two must be united in one whole. This, as 
 I have tried to show, is all Hegel did attempt to deduce from 
 the Logic. But whether this is so or not, we must admit that 
 it is all that he has a right to deduce from it. The concrete whole 
 towards which we are working is the universalised particular, 
 the mediated immediate, the rationalised datum. Logic is the 
 universal, the mediating, the rationalising element. There must 
 therefore be a particular, immediate, given element, and the two 
 must be reconciled. So much we can deduce by pure thought. 
 But if this other element has any other qualities except those 
 just mentioned which make it correlative to Logic, we cannot 
 deduce them. We must treat them as contingent, and confine 
 ourselves to pointing out the way in which the Logic is incarnate 
 in Nature and Spirit, piercing through these contingent par- 
 ticulars. Philosophy can tell us a priori that Nature and Spirit 
 do exist, and that all the categories of the Logic must be realised 
 in them, but how they are realised in the midst of what seem, at 
 any rate at present, to be contingent particulars, must be a matter 
 for empirical observation, and not for deduction from Logic. 
 
114 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 100. In what way does the transition from Logic take place? 
 The suggestion which most naturally occurs to us is that the 
 element which supplements the deficiency of Logic should be its 
 antithesis, and the combination of the two in a concrete whole 
 should form the synthesis. In this case the antithesis would be 
 the mere abstract and unconnected particularity, which is really 
 unnameable, since all names imply that the matter of discourse 
 has been qualified by some judgment. With the very beginnings 
 of Nature, on this view, we pass to the synthesis, for in Nature 
 we have already the idea as immediate, as given, as realised in 
 fact. Spirit and Nature together would thus form the synthesis. 
 Spirit being distinguished from Nature only as being a more 
 complete and closer reconciliation of the two elements. It makes 
 explicit the unity which in Nature is only implicit. But it does 
 not add any aspect or element which is not in Nature, it is more 
 elaborated, but not more comprehensive. 
 
 This, however, is not the course of the transition which is 
 actually adopted by Hegel. In this, while the Logic is the thesis, 
 the antithesis is Nature, and the synthesis is Spirit. The bond of 
 connection here is that they are the universal, the particular, 
 and the individual, and that the individual is the synthesis of 
 the universal and the particular. If it should be objected to this 
 that there is more in Nature than mere particularity, since the 
 idea is realised, though imperfectly realised, in Nature, and the 
 idea is the universal, Hegel's reply, I suppose, would be that this 
 is the case also with every particular thing, since mere particularity 
 is an abstraction. We can never perceive anything without a 
 judgment, and a judgment involves a category. Indeed the very 
 phrase "thing" implies this. 
 
 The difference between the two methods is thus very marked, 
 not only because of the different place assigned to Nature in 
 them, but because in the second the antithesis marks a distinct 
 advance upon the thesis, as a concrete reality, though an im- 
 perfect one, while in the first the thesis and antithesis are both 
 alike mere abstractions and aspects which require a reconciliation 
 before anything concrete is reached. 
 
 Here we have two examples of the dialectic process, each 
 starting from the same point — the Logic — and each arriving at 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 115 
 
 the same point — Absolute Spirit — but reaching that point in 
 different ways. What are we to say about them? Is one wrong 
 and the other right? Or can we argue, from the fact that the 
 principles of the dialectic would seem to justify either of them, 
 to the conclusion that there must be some error in those prin- 
 ciples, since they lead to two inconsistent results? Or, finally, 
 can we pronounce them both to be correct? To these questions 
 Hegel, as far as I can find, affords no definite answer, but one 
 may, I think, be found by following up some indications which 
 he gives. This I shall endeavour to do in the next chapter^. 
 
 101. Before leaving this part of the subject, we must consider 
 some criticisms which have been passed by Lotze on Idealism, 
 the most important and elaborate of which occurs in the Micro- 
 cosmus^. In this he considers the assertion, which he attributes 
 to Idealism, that Thought and Being are identical. He does not 
 mention Hegel by name here, but it would seem, from the nature 
 of the criticisms, and from scattered remarks in other parts of 
 his writings, that he held his criticisms to apply to the Hegelian 
 dialectic. 
 
 Now in what sense does Hegel say that Thought and Being 
 are identical? In the first place we must carefully distinguish, 
 from such an assertion of identity, another assertion which he 
 does make, — namely, that Being is a category, and therefore a 
 determination of thought, and that, in consequence, even the 
 mere recognition that a thing is, can only be effected by thought. 
 He uses this undeniable truth as an argument against appeals 
 from the results of thought to immediate facts. For it means 
 that we can only know that a thing is a fact by means of thought, 
 and that it is impossible to find any ground, upon which we can 
 base a proposition, which does not involve thought, and which 
 is not subject to all the general laws which we can obtain by 
 analysing what is involved in thinking. 
 
 This, however, is not what is meant by Lotze. That the 
 predicate of Being can only be applied by us to a subject by 
 means of thought, is a statement which Lotze could not have 
 doubted, and which he had no reason to wish to deny. He 
 attacks a very different proposition — that everything which is 
 ^ Sections 131 — 138. ^ Book viii. Chap. i. towards the end. 
 
116 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 included under the predicate of Being, tliat is, everything in the 
 universe, is identical with thought. 
 
 This, again, may have two very different meanings. If we 
 call the particular reality, of which we are speaking, A, then 
 we may mean, in the first place, that A's being is identical with 
 B's thought, when B is thinking about A, — or would be so, if B's 
 thought was in a state of ideal perfection. Or we may mean, 
 in the second place, that A's being is identical with his own 
 thought, i.e. that his only nature is to be a thinking being, and 
 his only activity is to think. The first view is that A is identical 
 with what may be thought about him, the second is that A is 
 identical with what he thinks. These are clearly very different. 
 
 102. It is the first of these meanings, it seems, which Lotze 
 supposes his Idealist to adopt. This appears from his considering 
 that he has refuted it by showing that there is always in our 
 knowledge of anything an immediate datum, which thought 
 must accept as given, and without which it cannot act at all. 
 "Thought," he says, "is everywhere but a mediating activity 
 moving hither and thither, bringing into connection the original 
 intuitions of external and internal perception, which are pre- 
 determined by fundamental ideas and laws the origin of which 
 cannot be shown ; it develops special and properly logical forms 
 peculiar to itself, only in the effort to apply the idea of truth 
 (which it finds in us) to the scattered multiplicity of perceptions, 
 and of the consequences developed from them. Hence nothing 
 seems less justifiable than the assertion that this Thinking is 
 identical with Being, and that Being can be resolved into it 
 without leaving any residuum; on the contrary, everywhere in 
 the flux of thought there remain quite insoluble those individual 
 nuclei which represent the several aspects of that important 
 content which we designate by the name of Being^." The fact 
 that there are immediate elements in our knowledge of other 
 things could be no reason for doubting that our nature — and 
 theirs also — lay in thinking, as we shall see later on. But it would 
 doubtless be an excellent reason for denying that our thought 
 of the object could ever be identical with the object itself. And 
 it is this last theory which Lotze must have had in view. 
 * loc. cit. (English Translation, Vol. ii. p. 354, 4th ed.). 
 
in] THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC 117 
 
 103. No doubt Hegel would have been wrong if he had 
 asserted that Thought and Being were identical in this sense. 
 But, as I have tried to show in the last chapter^, there is no 
 reason to suppose that he failed to appreciate the fact that there 
 is an element of immediacy in all knowledge, and that thought, 
 without such data, would not only be inadequate, but completely 
 impotent. The passage which I then quoted from the Philosophy 
 of Spirit^, declares that Spirit is the logical fHus, not only of 
 Nature but of Logic. Now Spirit differs from Logic by reason 
 of the element of immediacy, introduced in Nature, and com- 
 pletely harmonised with Logic in Spirit. It seems clear then that 
 Hegel can never have imagined that pure thought could dispense 
 with the element of immediacy. And, if so, our pure thought 
 by itself could never have been identical with the content of its 
 object. 
 
 104. The necessity of immediacy for thought, however, does 
 not prevent the identity of Thought and Being in the second 
 sense mentioned above. If all reality in the universe consisted 
 simply of thinking beings there would be no lack of immediate 
 data for them to mediate. For thought itself can be observed, 
 and, when observed, forms itself a datum for thought. And a 
 universe of thinking beings, in connection with one another, 
 would find their immediate data, A in B, and B in A. 
 
 In this sense it seems that Hegel did hold the identity of 
 Thought and Being — though the phrase is not a very happy one. 
 That is to say, he held that all reality consisted of self-conscious 
 beings; and it appears from the Philosophy of Spirit that he 
 also held that the highest — the only ultimate — activity of Spirit, 
 in which all others are transcended and swallowed up, is that of 
 pure thought. 
 
 In doing this, he ignored a fact which is made prominent by 
 Lotze in many parts of his system, though not in the chapter 
 from which I have quoted. This is, that Spirit has two other 
 aspects besides thought — namely, volition and feeling — which 
 are as important as thought, and which cannot be deduced from 
 it, nor explained by it. I shall have to consider this point at 
 greater length in Chapter vi, and shall there endeavour to show 
 ^ Sections 56, 57. - Erie. Section 381, lecture note. 
 
118 THE VALIDITY OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. ni 
 
 that, while Hegel was justified in identifying all Being with 
 Spirit, he was not justified in taking the further step of identi- 
 fying the true nature of Spirit exclusively with pure thought. 
 
 105. Such a conclusion, no doubt, would make a considerable 
 change in the Hegelian system. But it would not involve that 
 Hegel had ignored the immediate aspect of reality, nor would 
 it prove that he was wrong in asserting all being to be Spirit. 
 Nor would it make his philosophy less thoroughly Idealistic. For 
 the essence of Idealism does not lie in the assertion of the identity 
 of Thought and Being, though it does lie very largely in the 
 assertion of a relation between them. That relation may be ex- 
 pressed by saying that Thought is adequate to express Being, 
 and Being adequate to embody Thought. On the one hand, no 
 reality exists beyond the sphere of actual or possible knowledge, 
 and no reality, when known as completely as possible, presents 
 any contradiction or irrationality. On the other hand, there is 
 no postulate which Thought demands in order to construct a 
 harmonious and self-consistent system of knowledge, which is 
 not realised in Being. 
 
 Hegel, as we have seen, establishes this by demonstrating 
 that the higher categories are so involved in the lower that, if 
 we say a thing exists at all, we are obHged to bring it under 
 predicates which ensure that it will answer completely to the 
 demands of our reason. In doing this, he arrives at the con- 
 clusions that the true nature of all Being is Spirit, and that the 
 true nature of all Spirit is Thought. But important as these 
 results, — true or false — are, they are only subsidiary as compared 
 with the more general result that Thought and Being — whether 
 identical or not — are yet in complete harmony. From the point 
 of view of theory, we thus know that reality is rational. From 
 the point of view of practice, we know that reality is righteous, 
 since the only view of reality which we can consider as com- 
 pletely rational, is shown to be one which involves our own 
 complete self-realisation. And it is this assertion that reality 
 is both rational and righteous which is the distinguishing mark 
 of Idealism. 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 
 
 106. My object in this chapter will be to show that the 
 method, by which Hegel proceeds from one category to another 
 in his Logic, is not the same throughout, but changes materially 
 as the process advances. I shall endeavour to show that this 
 change may be reduced to a general law, and that from this 
 law we may derive important consequences with regard to the 
 nature and validity of the dialectic. 
 
 The exact relation of these corollaries to Hegel's own views 
 is rather uncertain. Some of them do not appear to be denied 
 in any part of the Logic, and, since they are apparently involved 
 in some of his theories, may be supposed to have been recognised 
 and accepted by him. On the other hand, he did not explicitly 
 state and develop them anywhere, which, in the case of doctrines 
 of such importance, is some ground for supposing that he did 
 not hold them. Others, again, are certainly incompatible with 
 his express statements. I desire, therefore, in considering them, 
 to leave on one side the question of how far they were believed 
 by Hegel, and merely to give reasons for thinking that they are 
 necessary consequences of his system, and must be accepted by 
 those who hold it. 
 
 107. The passage in which Hegel sums up his position on this 
 point most plainly runs as follows: "The abstract form of the 
 advance is, in Being, an other and transition into an other; in 
 Essence, showing or a reflection in the opposite (Scheinen in dem 
 Entgegengesetzten) ; in Notion, the distinction of individual from 
 universality, which continues itself as such into, and is as an 
 identity with, what is distinguished from it^." 
 
 The difference between the procedure in the doctrine of Being 
 
 and in the doctrine of Essence is given in more detail earher. 
 
 "In the sphere of Essence one category does not pass into 
 
 another, but refers to another merely. In Being the form of 
 
 1 Enc. Section 240. 
 
120 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [oh. 
 
 reference is simply due to our reflection on what takes place; 
 but this form is the special and proper characteristic of Essence. 
 In the sphere of Being, when somewhat becomes another, the 
 somewhat has vanished. Not so in Essence: here there is no 
 real other, but only diversity, reference of the one to its other. 
 The transition of Essence is therefore at the same time no tran- 
 sition ; for in the passage of different into different, the different 
 does not vanish: the different terms remain in their relation. 
 When we speak of Being and Nought, Being is independent, so 
 is Nought. The case is otherwise with the Positive and the 
 Negative. No doubt these possess the characteristic of Being 
 and Nought. But the positive by itself has no sense ; it is wholly 
 in reference to the negative. And it is the same with the negative. 
 In the Sphere of Being the reference of one term to another is 
 only impHcit; in Essence, on the contrary, it is explicit. And this 
 in general is the distinction between the forms of Being and 
 Essence: in Being everything is immediate, in Essence every- 
 thing is relative^." 
 
 And again, in describing the transition from Essence to the 
 Notion, he says : " Transition into something else is the dialectical 
 process within the range of Being; reflection (bringing something 
 else into light) in the range of Essence. The movement of the 
 Notion is development ; by which that only is explicitly affirmed 
 which is already impUcitly speaking present. In the world of 
 nature, it is organic life that corresponds to the grade of the 
 notion. Thus, e.g., the plant is developed from its germ. The germ 
 virtually involves the whole plant, but does so only ideally or 
 in thought; and it would therefore be a mistake to regard the 
 development of the root, stem, leaves, and other different parts 
 of the plant as meaning that they were realiier present, but in 
 a very minute form, in the germ. That is the so-called 'box- 
 within-box ' hypothesis ; a theory which commits the mistake of 
 supposing an actual existence of what is at first found only in 
 the shape of an ideal. The truth of the hypothesis on the other 
 hand lies in its perceiving that, in the process of development, 
 the notion keeps to itself, and only gives rise to alteration of 
 form without making any addition in point of content. It is this 
 ^ Enc. Section 111, lecture note. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 121 
 
 nature of the notion — this manifestation of itself in its process 
 as a development of its own self — which is chiefly in view by 
 those who speak of innate ideas, or who, like Plato, describe 
 all learning as merely reminiscence. Of course that again does 
 not mean that everything which is embodied in a mind, after 
 that mind has been formed by instruction, had been present in 
 that mind beforehand in a definitely expanded shape. 
 
 "The movement of the notion is after all to be looked on only 
 as a kind of play. The other which it sets up is in reality not 
 another. Or, as it is expressed in the teaching of Christianity, 
 not merely has God created a world which confronts Him as 
 another; He has also from all eternity begotten a Son, in whom 
 He, a Spirit, is at home with Himself^." 
 
 108. The result of this process may be summed up as follows: 
 The further the dialectic goes from its starting-point the less 
 prominent becomes the apparent stability of the individual finite 
 categories, and the less do they seem to be self-centred and inde- 
 pendent. On the other hand, the process itself becomes more 
 clearly self-evident, and is seen to be the only real meaning of 
 the lower categories. In Being each category appears, taken by 
 itself, to be permanent and exclusive of all others, and to have 
 no principle of transition in it. It is only outside reflection which 
 examines and breaks down this pretence of stability, and shows 
 us that the dialectic process is inevitable. In Essence, however, 
 each category by its own import refers to that which follows it, 
 and the transition is seen to be inherent in its nature. But it is 
 still felt to be, as it were, only an external effect of that nature. 
 The categories have still an inner nature, as contrasted Avith the 
 outer relations which they have with other categories. So far 
 as they have this inner nature, they are still conceived as inde- 
 pendent and self-centred. But with the passage into the notion 
 things alter; that passage "is the very hardest, because it pro- 
 poses that independent actuality shall be thought as having all 
 its substantiality in the passing over and identity with the other 
 independent actuality^." Not only is the transition now necessary 
 to the categories, but the transition is the categories. The reality 
 in any finite category, in this stage, consists only in its summing 
 1 Enc. Section 161, lecture note. ^ Enc. Section 159. 
 
122 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 up those which went before, and in leading on to those which 
 come after, 
 
 109. Another change can be observed as the process con- 
 tinues. In the categories of Being the typical form is a transition 
 from a thesis to an antithesis which is merely complementary 
 to it, and is in no way superior to it in value or comprehensive- 
 ness. Only when these two extremes are taken together is there 
 for the first time any advance to a higher notion. This advance 
 is a transition to a synthesis which comes as a consequence of 
 the thesis and antithesis jointly. It would be impossible to obtain 
 the synthesis, or to make any advance, from either of the two 
 complementary terms without the other. Neither is in any re- 
 spect more advanced than the other, and neither of them can be 
 said to be more closely connected than the other with the syn- 
 thesis, in which both of them alike find their explanation and 
 reconciliation. But when we come to Essence the matter is 
 changed. Here the transition from thesis to antithesis is still 
 indeed from positive to negative, but it is more than merely this. 
 The antithesis is not merely complementary to the thesis, but 
 is a correction of it. It is consequently more concrete and true 
 than the thesis, and represents a real advance. And the transition 
 to the synthesis is not now made so much from the comparison 
 of the other two terms as from the antithesis alone. For the 
 antithesis does not now merely oppose a contrary defect to the 
 original defect of the thesis. It corrects, to some degree, that 
 original mistake, and therefore has — to use the Hegelian phrase- 
 ology — "the truth" of the thesis more or less within itself. As 
 the action of the synthesis is to reconcile the thesis and the 
 antithesis it can only be deduced from the comparison of the 
 two. But if the antithesis has — as it has in Essence — the thesis 
 as part of its own significance, it will present the whole of the 
 data which the synthesis requires, and it will not be necessary 
 to recur to the thesis, before the step to the synthesis is taken. 
 
 But although the reconciliation can be inferred from the second 
 term, apart from the first, a reconciliation is still necessary. For, 
 while the antithesis is an advance upon the thesis, it is also 
 opposed to it. It is not simply a completion of it, but also a 
 denial, though a denial which is already an approximation to 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 123 
 
 union. This element of opposition and negation tends to dis- 
 appear in the categories of the Notion. As these approach the 
 end of the whole process, the steps are indeed discriminated from 
 one another, but they can scarcely be said to be in opposition. 
 For we have now arrived at a consciousness more or less explicit 
 that in each category all that have gone before are summed up, 
 and all that are to come after are contained implicitly. "The 
 movement of the Notion is after all to be looked on only as a 
 kind of play. The other which it sets up is in reality not another." 
 And, as a consequence, the third term merely completes the 
 second, without correcting one-sidedness in it, in the same way 
 as the second term merely expands and completes the first. As 
 this type is realised, in fact, the distinctions of the three terms 
 gradually lose their meaning. There is no longer an opposition 
 produced between two terms and mediated by a third. Each 
 term is a direct advance on the one before it. The object of the 
 process is not now to make the one-sided complete, but the 
 implicit explicit. For we have reached a stage when each side 
 carries in it already more or less consciousness of that unity of 
 the whole which is the synthesis, and requires development rather 
 than refutation. 
 
 110. It is natural that these changes should accompany the 
 one first mentioned. For, as it is gradually seen that each cate- 
 gory, of its own nature, and not by mere outside reflection on it, 
 leads on to the next, that next will have inherent in it its relation 
 to the first. It will not only be the negation and complement 
 of the thesis, but wall know that it is so. In so far as it does this, 
 it will be higher than the thesis. It is true that the thesis will 
 see in like manner that it must be connected with the category 
 that succeeds it. But this knowledge can only give a general 
 character of transition to the thesis, for it only knows that it is 
 connected with something, but does not yet know with what. 
 But the antithesis does know with what it is connected, since it 
 is connected with a term which precedes it in the dialectic pro- 
 cess. And to see how it is inseparably connected with its opposite, 
 and defined by its relation to it, is an important step towards 
 the reconciliation of the opposition. A fortiori the greater clear- 
 ness and ease of the transition will have the same efiect in the 
 
124 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 case of the Notion. For there we see that the whole meaning of 
 the category lies in its passage to another. The second therefore 
 has the whole meaning of the first in it, as well as the addition 
 that has been made in the transition, and must therefore be 
 higher than the first. 
 
 From this follows naturally the change in the relation of the 
 terms to their synthesis. We have seen that, in proportion as 
 the meaning of the thesis is completely included in the meaning 
 of the antithesis, it becomes possible to find all the data required 
 for the synthesis in the antithesis alone. And when each term 
 has its meaning completely absorbed in the one which follows it, 
 the triple rhythm disappears altogether, in which case each term 
 would be a simple advance on the one below it, and would be 
 deduced from that one only. 
 
 111. While Hegel expressly notices, as we have seen, the in- 
 creasing freedom and directness of the dialectic movement, he 
 makes no mention of the different relation to one another assumed 
 by the various members of the process, which I have just in- 
 dicated. Traces of the change may, however, be observed in the 
 detail of the dialectic. The three triads which it will be best to 
 examine for this purpose are the first in the doctrine of Being, 
 the middle one in the doctrine of Essence, and the last in the 
 doctrine of the Notion. For, if there is any change within each 
 of these three great divisions (a point we must presently con- 
 sider), the special characteristics of each will be shown most 
 clearly at that point at which it is at the greatest distance from 
 each of the other divisions. The triads in question are those of 
 Being, Not-Being, and Becoming; of the World of Appearance, 
 Content and Form, and Ratio^; and of Life, Cognition, and the 
 Absolute Idea^. 
 
 Now, in the first of these, thesis and antithesis are on an 
 absolute level. Not-Being is no higher than Being: it does not 
 contain Being in any sense in which Being does not contain it. 
 We can pass as easily from Not-Being to Being as vice versa. 
 And Not-Being by itself is helpless to produce Becoming — as 
 
 ^ I follow the divisions of Essence as given in the EncydopcBdia. 
 2 Cognition is used by Hegel in two senses. Here it is to be taken as Cognition 
 n general, of which Cognition proper and Volition are species. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 125 
 
 helpless as Being is. The synthesis can only come from the con- 
 junction of both of them. On the other hand the idea of Content 
 and Form, according to Hegel, is a distinct advance on the idea 
 of the World of Appearance, since in Content and Form "the 
 connection of the phenomenon with self is completely stated." 
 Ratio, again, although the synthesis of the two previous terms, 
 is deduced from the second of them alone, while it could not be 
 deduced from the first alone. It is the relation of Content and 
 Form to one another which leads us on to the other relation 
 which is called ratio. The idea of Cognition, also, is a distinct 
 advance upon the idea of Life, since the defect in the latter, from 
 which Hegel explains the existence of death, is overcome as we 
 pass to Cognition. And it is from Cognition alone, without any 
 reference back to Life, that we reach the Absolute Idea. 
 
 112. Another point arises on which we shall find but little 
 guidance in Hegel's own writings. To each of the three great 
 divisions of the dialectic he has ascribed a particular variation 
 of the method. Are we to understand that one variety changes 
 into another suddenly at the transition from division to division, 
 or is the change continuous, so that, while the typical forms of 
 each division are strongly characterised, the difference between 
 the last step in one and the first step in the next is no greater 
 than the difference between two consecutive steps in the same 
 division ? Shall we find the best analogy in the distinction between 
 water and steam — a quahtative change suddenly brought about 
 when a quantitative change has reached a certain degree — or 
 in the distinction between youth and manhood, which at their 
 most characteristic points are clearly distinct, but which pass 
 into one another imperceptibly? 
 
 On this point Hegel says nothing. Possibly it had never 
 presented itself to his mind. But there are signs in the Logic 
 which may lead us to beheve that the change of method is 
 gradual and continuous. 
 
 In the first place we may notice that the absolutely pure type 
 of the process in Being, is not to be met with in any triad of 
 Quality or Quantity except the first. Being and Not-Being are 
 on a level. But if we compare Being an sich with Being for 
 another, the One with the Many, and mere Quantity with 
 
126 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [CH. 
 
 Quantum, we observe that the second category is higher than the 
 first in each pair, and that it is not merely the complement of the 
 first, but to a certain degree transcends it. The inherent relation 
 of thesis to antithesis seems to develop more as we pass on, so 
 that before Essence is reached its characteristics are already 
 visible to some extent, and the mere passivity and finitude of 
 Being is partly broken down. 
 
 If, again, we compare the first and last stages of Essence, we 
 shall find that the first approximates to the type of Being, while 
 the last comes fairly close to that of the Notion, by substituting 
 the idea of development for the idea of the reconciHation of 
 contradictions. Difference, as treated by Hegel, is certainly an 
 advance on Identity, and not a mere opposite, but there is still 
 a good deal of opposition between the terms. The advance is 
 shown by the fact that Difference contains Likeness and Un- 
 likeness within itself, while the opposition of the two categories 
 is clear, not only in common usage, but from the fact that the 
 synthesis has to reconcile them, and balance their various 
 deficiencies. But when we reach Substance and CausaUty we 
 find that the notion of contradiction is subordinated to that of 
 development, nearly as fully as if we were already at the begin- 
 ning of the doctrine of the Notion. 
 
 So, finally, the special features of the doctrine of the Notion 
 are not fully exhibited until we have come to its last stage. In 
 the transitions of the Notion as Notion, of the Judgment, and 
 of the Syllogism, we have not by any means entirely rid ourselves 
 of the elements of opposition and negation. It is not until we 
 reach the concluding triad of the Logic that we are able fully 
 to see the typical progress of the Notion. In the transition from 
 Life to Cognition, and from Cognition to the Absolute Idea, we 
 perceive that the movement is all but completely direct, that 
 the whole is seen to be in each part, and that there is no longer 
 a contest, but only a development. 
 
 It is not safe, however, to place much weight on all this. In 
 the first place, while Hegel explicitly says that each of the three 
 doctrines has its special method, he says nothing about any 
 development of method within each doctrine. In the second place 
 the difiiculty and uncertainty of comparing, quantitatively and 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 127 
 
 exactly, shades of difference so slight and subtle, must always 
 be very great. And, so far as we can compare them, there seem 
 to be some exceptions to the rule of continuous development. 
 We find some triads which approximate more closely to the pure 
 Being-type than others which precede them, and we find some 
 which approximate more closely to the pure Notion-type than 
 others which follow them. But that there are some traces of 
 continuous development cannot, I think, be denied, and this will 
 become more probable if we see reason to think that, in a correct 
 dialectic, the development would be continuous. 
 
 113. Before we consider this question we must first enquire 
 whether the existence of such a development of any sort, whether 
 continuous or not, might be expected from the nature of the 
 case. We shall see that there are reasons for supposing this to 
 be so, when we remember what we must regard as the essence 
 of the dialectic. The motive power of all the categories is the 
 concrete absolute truth, from which all finite categories are mere 
 abstractions and to which they tend spontaneously to return. 
 Again, two contradictory ideas cannot be held to be true at the 
 same time. If it ever seems inevitable that they should be, this 
 is a sign of error somewhere, and we cannot feel satisfied with 
 the result, until we have transcended and synthesised the con- 
 tradiction. It follows that in so far as the finite categories 
 announce themselves as permanent, and as opposed in pairs of 
 unsynthesised contraries, they are expressing falsehood and not 
 truth. We gain the truth by transcending the contradictions of 
 the categories and by demonstrating their instability. Now the 
 change in the method, of which we are speaking, indicates a 
 clearer perception of this truth. For we have seen that the process 
 becomes more spontaneous and more direct. As it becomes more 
 spontaneous, as each category is seen to lead on of its own nature 
 to the next, and to have its meaning only in the transition, it 
 brings out more fully what lies at the root of the whole dialectic 
 — namely that the truth of the opposed categories Hes only in 
 the synthesis. And as the process becomes more direct and leaves 
 the opposition and negation behind, it also brings out more clearly 
 what is an essential fact in every stage of the dialectic, — that 
 is, that the impulse of imperfect truth, as we have it, is not 
 
128 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 towards self-contradiction as such, but towards self-completion. 
 The essential nature of the whole dialectic is thus more clearly 
 seen in the later stages, which approximate to the type of the 
 Notion, than in the earlier stages which approximate to the type 
 of Being. 
 
 This is what we might expect a priori. For the content of 
 each stage in the dialectic is nearer to the truth than that of 
 the stage before it. And each stage forms the starting-point from 
 which we go forward again to further truth. At each step, there- 
 fore, in the forward process, we have a fuller knowkdge of the 
 truth than at the one before, and it is only natural that this 
 fuller knowledge should react upon the manner in which the 
 next step is made. The dialectic is due to the relation between 
 the concrete whole, imphcit in consciousness, and the abstract 
 part of it which has become explicit. Since the second element 
 alters at every step, as the categories approximate to the com- 
 plete truth, it is clear that its relation to the unchanging whole 
 alters also, and this would naturally affect the method. And, 
 since the change in the relation will be one which will make that 
 relation more obvious and evident, we may expect that every 
 step which we take towards the full truth will render it possible 
 to proceed more easily and directly to the next step. 
 
 Even without considering the special circumstance that each 
 step in the process will give us this deeper insight into the 
 meaning of the work we are carrying on, we might find other 
 reasons for supposing that the nature of the dialectic process is 
 modified by use. For the conception of an agent which is purely 
 active, acting on a material which is purely passive, is a mere 
 abstraction, and has a place nowhere in reality. Even in the 
 case of matter, we find that this is true. An axe has not the same 
 effect at its second blow as at its first, for it is more or less 
 blunted. A viohn has not the same tone the second time it is 
 played on, as it had the first. And it would be least of all in 
 the work of the mind that a rigid distinction could be kept up 
 between form and matter, between the tool and the materials. 
 
 114. Now these arguments for the existence of change in the 
 method are also arguments for supposing that the change will 
 be continuous. There is reason to expect a change in the method 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 129 
 
 whenever we have advanced a step towards truth. But we 
 advance towards truth, not only when we pass from one chief 
 division of the Logic to another, but whenever we pass from 
 category to category, however minute a subdivision of the pro- 
 cess they may represent. It would therefore seem that it is to 
 be expected that the method would change after each category, 
 and that no two transitions throughout the dialectic would 
 present quite the same type. However continuous the change 
 of conclusions can be made, it is likely that the change of method 
 will be equally continuous. 
 
 It may also be noted that the three doctrines themselves form 
 a triad, and that in the same way the three divisions of each 
 doctrine, and the three subdivisions of each division, form a 
 triad. The similarity of constitution which exists between the 
 larger and smaller groups of categories may perhaps be some 
 additional reason for anticipating that the smaller transitions 
 will exert on the method an influence similar to that of the larger 
 transitions, although, of course, less in amount. 
 
 115. We may therefore, I think, fairly arrive at the con- 
 clusion, in the first place, that the dialectic process does and must 
 undergo a progressive change, and, in the second place, that this 
 change is as much continuous as the process of the dialectic 
 itselfi. Another question now arises. Has the change in the 
 method destroyed its validity? The ordinary proofs relate only 
 to the type characteristic of Being, which, as we have now found 
 reason to believe, is only found in its purity in the very first triad 
 of all. Does the gradual change to the types characteristic of 
 Essence and the Notion make any difference in the justification 
 of the method as a whole? 
 
 This question must be answered in the negative. The process 
 has lost none of its cogency. It consisted, according to the earliest 
 type, of a search for completeness, and of a search for harmony 
 between the elements of that completeness, the two stages being 
 separate. Later on we have the same search for completeness 
 
 1 Note to Second Edition. The change occurs in the characteristics men- 
 tioned in Section 108, and also in those mentioned in Section 109, except the 
 characteristic that the direct transition to the synthesis is from the antithesis 
 alone, and not from both thesis and antithesis. This caimot be continuous, 
 and is found in all the stages after the first. 
 
130 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 and for harmony, but both objects are attained by a single 
 process. In Being, the inadequacy of the thesis led on to the 
 antithesis. Each of these ideas was regarded as an immediate 
 and self-centred whole. On the other hand each of them implied 
 the other, since they were complementary and opposite sides of 
 the truth. This brought about a contradiction, which had to be 
 reconciled by the introduction of the synthesis. Now the change 
 in the process has the effect of gradually dropping the inter- 
 mediate stage, in which the two sides of the whole are regarded 
 as incompatible and yet as inseparably connected. In the stage 
 of Essence, each category has a reference in its own nature to 
 those which come before and after it. When we reach the anti- 
 thesis therefore, we have already a sort of anticipation of the 
 synthesis, since we recognise that the two sides are connected 
 by their own nature, and not merely by external reasoning. Thus 
 the same step by which we reach the idea complementary to our 
 starting-point, and so gain completeness, does something towards 
 joining the two extremes in the harmony which we require of 
 them. For, when we have seen that the categories are in- 
 herently connected, we have gone a good way towards the per- 
 ception that they are not incompatible. The harmony thus 
 attained in the antithesis is however only partial, and leaves a 
 good deal for the synthesis to do. In the Notion, the change is 
 carried further. Here we see that the whole meaning of the 
 category resides in the transition, and the whole thesis is really 
 summed up in the antithesis, for the meaning of the thesis is 
 now only the production of the antithesis, and it is absorbed 
 and transcended in it. In fact the relation of thesis, antithesis 
 and synthesis would actually disappear in the typical form of 
 process belonging to the Notion, for each term would be the 
 completion of that which was immediately before it, since all 
 the reality of the latter would be seen to be in its transition to 
 its successor. This never actually happens, even in the final triad 
 of the whole system. For the characteristic type of the Notion 
 represents the process as it would be when it started from a 
 perfectly adequate premise. When, however, the premise, the 
 explicit idea in the mind, became perfectly adequate and true, 
 we should have rendered explicit the whole concrete idea, and 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 131 
 
 the object of the dialectic process would be attained, so that it 
 could go no further. The typical process of the Notion is there- 
 fore an ideal, to which the actual process approximates more 
 and more closely throughout its course, but which it can only 
 reach at the moment when it stops completed. 
 
 116. The process always seeks for that idea which is logically 
 required as the completion of the idea from which it starts. At 
 first the complementary idea presents itself as incompatible with 
 the starting-point, and has to be independently harmonised with 
 it. Afterwards the complementary idea is at once presented as 
 in harmony with the original idea in which it is implied. All 
 the change lies in the fact that two operations, at first distinct, 
 are fused into one. The argument of the dialectic all through is, 
 If we start with a valid idea, all that is implied in it is valid, 
 and also everything is valid that is required to avoid a con- 
 tradiction between the starting-point and that which we reach 
 by means of the starting-point. As we approximate to the end 
 of the process, we are able to see, implied in the idea before us, 
 not merely a complementary and contradictory idea on the same 
 level, but an idea which at once complements and transcends 
 the starting-point. The second idea is here from the first in 
 harmony with the idea which it complements. But its justifica- 
 tion is exactly the same as that of the antithesis in the Being- 
 type of the process — that is, that its truth is necessarily involved 
 in the truth of an idea which we have already admitted to be 
 valid. And thus if we are satisfied with the cogency of the earlier 
 forms of the process, we shall have no reason to modify our 
 beUef on account of the change of method. 
 
 117. We may draw several important conclusions with regard 
 to the general nature of the dialectic, from the manner in which 
 the form changes as it advances towards completion. The first 
 of these is one which we may fairly attribute to Hegel himself, 
 since it is evident from the way in which he deals with the 
 categories, although it is not explicitly noticed by him. This is 
 the subordinate place held by negation in the whole process. We 
 have already observed that the importance of negation in the 
 dialectic is by no means primary^. In the first place Hegel's 
 
 1 Chap. I. Section 9. 
 
 9—2 
 
132 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 Logic is very far from resting, as is supposed by some critics, 
 on the violation of the law of contradiction. It rather rests on 
 the impossibility of violating that law, and on the necessity of 
 finding, for every contradiction, a reconciliation in which it 
 vanishes. And not only is the idea of negation destined always 
 to vanish in the synthesis, but even its temporary introduction 
 is an accident, though an inevitable accident. The motive force 
 of the process lies in the discrepancy between the concrete and 
 perfect idea implicitly in our minds, and the abstract and imper- 
 fect idea explicitly in our minds, and the essential characteristic 
 of the process is in the search of this abstract and imperfect idea, 
 not after its negation as such, but after its complement as such. Its 
 complement is, indeed, its contrary, because a relatively concrete 
 category can be analysed into two direct contraries, and therefore 
 the process does go from an idea to its contrary. But it does not 
 do so because it seeks denial, but because it seeks completion. 
 
 But this can now be carried still further. Not only is the 
 presence of negation in the dialectic a mere accident, though a 
 necessary one, of the gradual completion of the idea. We are 
 now led to consider it as an accident which is necessary indeed 
 in the lower stages of the dialectic, but which is gradually 
 ehminated in proportion as we proceed further, and in proportion 
 as the materials from which we start are of a concrete and 
 adequate character. For in so far as the process ceases to be 
 from one extreme to another extreme equally one-sided, both 
 of which regard themselves as permanent, and as standing in 
 a relation of opposition towards one another, and in so far as it 
 becomes a process from one term to another which is recognised 
 as in some degree mediated by the first, and as transcending it 
 — in so far the negation of each category by the other disappears. 
 For it is then recognised that in the second category there is 
 no contradiction to the first, because, in so far as the change has 
 been completed, the first is found to have its meaning in the 
 transition to the second. 
 
 The presence of negation, therefore, is not only a mere accident 
 of the dialectic, but an accident whose importance continuously 
 decreases as the dialectic progresses, and as its subject-matter 
 becomes more fully understood. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 133 
 
 118. We now come to a fresh question, of very great im- 
 portance. We have seen that in the dialectic the relation of the 
 various finite ideas to one another in different parts of the pro- 
 cess is not the same — the three categories of Being, Not-Being, 
 and Becoming standing in different relations among themselves 
 to those which connect Life, Cognition, and the Absolute Idea. 
 Now the dialectic process professes to do more than merely 
 describe the stages by which we mount to the Absolute Idea — 
 it also describes the nature of that Idea itself. In addition to 
 the information which we gain about the latter by the definition 
 given of it at the end of the dialectic, we also know that it 
 contains in itself as elements or aspects all the finite stages of 
 thought, through which the dialectic has passed before reaching 
 its goal. It is not something which is reached by the dialectic, 
 and which then exists independently of the manner in which 
 it was reached. It does not reject all the finite categories as 
 absolutely false, but pronounces them to be partly false and 
 partly true, and it sums up in itself the truth of all of them. 
 They are thus contained in it as moments. What relation do 
 these moments bear to one another in the Absolute Idea? 
 
 We may, in the first place, adopt the easy and simple solution 
 of saying that the relation they bear to one another, as moments 
 in the Absolute Idea, is just the same as that which they bear 
 to one another, as finite categories in the dialectic process. In 
 this case, to discover their position in the Absolute Idea, it is 
 only necessary to consider the dialectic process, not as one which 
 takes place in time, but as having a merely logical import. The 
 process contemplated in this way will be a perfect and complete 
 analysis of the concrete idea which is its end, containing about 
 it the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth. And 
 this, apparently, would have been Hegel's answer, if the question 
 had been explicitly proposed to him. For he undoubtedly asserts 
 that the dialectic expresses the deepest nature of objective 
 thought. 
 
 119. But this conclusion seems open to doubt. For the change 
 of method results, as we have seen, from a gradually growing 
 perception of the truth which is at the bottom of the whole 
 dialectic — the unreality of any finite category as against its 
 
134 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 synthesis, since the truth and reality of each category consists 
 only in its reference to the next, and in its passage onwards to 
 it. If this was not true all through the dialectic, there could be 
 no dialectic at all, for the justification of the whole process is 
 that the truth of the thesis and the antithesis is contained in 
 the synthesis, and that in so far as they are anything else but 
 aspects of the synthesis they are false and deceptive. This then 
 must be the true nature of the process of thought, and must 
 constitute the real meaning and essence of the dialectic. Yet 
 this is only explicitly perceived in the Notion, and at the end 
 of the Notion — or rather, as I pointed out above, we never attain 
 to complete perception of it, but only approximate towards it 
 as our grasp of the subject increases. Before this the categories 
 appear always as, in their own nature, permanent and self- 
 centred, and the breaking down of this self-assertion, and the 
 substitution for it of the knowledge that truth is only found in 
 the synthesis, appears as opposed to what went before, and as 
 in contradiction to it, although a necessary and inevitable con- 
 sequence of it. But if this were really so, the dialectic process 
 would be impossible. If there really were any independent 
 element in the lower categories, or any externality in the recon- 
 ciliation, that reconciliation could never be complete and the 
 dialectic could never claim, as it undoubtedly does claim, to sum 
 up all the lower elements of truth. 
 
 The very existence of the dialectic thus tends to prove that 
 it is not in every sense objectively correct. For it would be 
 impossible for any transition to be made, at any point in the 
 process, unless the terms were really related according to the 
 type belonging to the Notion. But no transition in the dialectic 
 does take place exactly according to that type, and most of them 
 according to types substantially different. We must therefore 
 suppose that the dialectic does not exactly represent the truth, 
 since if the truth were as it represents it to be, the dialectic 
 itself could not exist. There must be in the process, besides that 
 element which actually does express the real notion of the tran- 
 sition, another element which is due to the inadequacy of our 
 finite thought to express the character of the reality which we 
 are trying to describe. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 135 
 
 This agrees with what was said above — that the change of 
 method is no real change, but only a rearrangement of the 
 elements of the transition. It is, in fact, only a bringing out 
 explicitly of what is implicitly involved all along. In the lower 
 categories our data, with their false appearance of independence, 
 obscure and confuse the true meaning of the dialectic. We can 
 see that the dialectic has this true meaning, even among these 
 lower categories, by reflecting on what is implied in its existence 
 and success. But it is only in the later categories that it becomes 
 explicit. And it must follow that those categories in which it is 
 not yet explicit do not fully represent the true nature of thought, 
 and the essential character of the transition from less perfect to 
 more perfect forms. 
 
 120. The conclusion at which we are thus compelled to arrive 
 must be admitted, I think, to have no warrant in Hegel. Hegel 
 would certainly have admitted that the lower categories, re- 
 garded in themselves, gave views of reality only approximating, 
 and, in the case of the lowest, only very slightly approximating, 
 to truth. But the procession of the categories, with its advance 
 through oppositions and reconciliations, he apparently regarded 
 as presenting absolute truth — as fully expressing the deepest 
 nature of pure thought. From this, if I am right, we are forced, 
 on his own premises, to dissent. For the true process of thought 
 is one in which each category springs out of the one before it, 
 not by contradicting it, but as an expression of its truest sig- 
 nificance, and finds its own truest significance, in turn, by passing 
 on to another category. There is no contradiction, no opposition, 
 and, consequently, no reconciliation. There is only development, 
 the rendering explicit what was implicit, the growth of the seed 
 to the plant. In the actual course of the dialectic this is never 
 attained. It is an ideal which is never quite realised, and from 
 the nature of the case never can be quite realised. In the dialectic 
 there is always opposition, and therefore always reconciliation. 
 We do not go straight onward, but more or less from side to side. 
 It seems inevitable, therefore, to conclude that the dialectic does 
 not completely and perfectly express the nature of thought. 
 
 This conclusion is certainly startling and paradoxical. For 
 the validity of the dialectic method for any purpose, and its 
 
136 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 power of adequately expressing the ultimate nature of thought, 
 appear to be so closely bound up together, that we may easily 
 consider them inseparable. The dialectic process is a distinctively 
 Hegelian idea. Doubtless the germs of it are to be found in 
 Fichte and elsewhere ; but it was only by Hegel that it was fully 
 worked out and made the central point of a philosophy. And in 
 80 far as it has been held since, it has been held substantially 
 in the manner in which he stated it. To retain the doctrine, and 
 to retain the idea that it is of cardinal importance while denying 
 that it adequately represents the nature of thought, looks like 
 a most unwarranted and gratuitous distinction between ideas 
 which their author held to be inseparable. 
 
 Yet I cannot see what alternative is left to us. For it is Hegel 
 himself who refutes his own doctrine. The state to which the 
 dialectic, according to him, gradually approximates, is one in 
 which the terms thesis, antithesis, and synthesis can have no 
 meaning. For in this state there is no opposition to create the 
 relation of thesis and antithesis, and, therefore, no reconciliation 
 of that opposition to create a synthesis. "The elements distin- 
 guished are without more ado at the same time declared to be 
 identical with one another, and with the whole. . . .The other which 
 the notion sets up is in reality not another^." Now, nowhere in 
 the dialectic do we entirely get rid of the relation of thesis, anti- 
 thesis, and synthesis ; even in the final triad of the process there 
 are traces of it. The inference seems inevitable that the dialectic 
 cannot fully represent, in any part of its movement, the real 
 and essential nature of pure thought. The only thing to be done 
 is to consider whether, with this important limitation, the pro- 
 cess has any longer a claim to any real significance, and, if so, 
 to how much? I shall endeavour to show that its importance can 
 scarcely be said to have diminished at all. 
 
 121. Since the dialectic, if the hypothesis I have advanced 
 be correct, does not adequately represent the nature of pure 
 thought itself, although it does represent the inevitable course 
 our minds are logically bound to follow, when they attempt to 
 deal with pure thought, it follows that it must be in some degree 
 subjective. We hav^ now to determine exactly the meaning in 
 1 Enc, Section 161. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 137 
 
 which we are using this rather ambiguous word. On the one 
 hand it is clear that the dialectic is not subjective in that sense 
 in which the word has been defined as meaning "that which is 
 mine or yours." It is no mere empirical description or generalisa- 
 tion. For, whatever view we may hold with regard to the success 
 or failure of the dialectic in apprehending the true nature of 
 thought, it will not at all affect the question of its internal 
 necessity, and of its cogency for us. The dialectic is not an account 
 of what men have thought, or may think. It is a demonstration 
 of what they must think, provided they wish to deal with Hegel's 
 problem at all, and to deal with it consistently and truly. 
 
 On the other hand, we must now pronounce the dialectic 
 process to be subjective in this sense — that it does not fully 
 express the essential nature of thought, but obscures it more or 
 less under characteristics which are not essential. It may not 
 seem very clear at first sight how we can distinguish between 
 the necessary course of the mind when engaged in pure thought, 
 which the dialectic method, according to this hypothesis, is 
 admitted to be, and the essential nature of thought, which it is 
 not allowed that it can adequately express. What, it may be 
 asked, is the essential nature of thought, except that course 
 which it must and does take, whenever we think? 
 
 We must remember, however, that according to Hegel thought 
 can only exist in its complete and concrete form — that is, as 
 the Absolute Idea. The import of our thought may be, and of 
 course often is, a judgment under some lower category, but our 
 thought itself, as an existent fact, distinguished from the meaning 
 it conveys, must be concrete and complete. For to stop at any 
 category short of the complete whole involves a contradiction, 
 and a contradiction is a sign of error. Now our judgments can 
 be, and often are, erroneous. And so we can, and do, make judg- 
 ments which involve a contradiction. But there would be no 
 meaning in saying that a fact is erroneous, and therefore, if we 
 find a contradiction in any judgment, we know that it cannot 
 be true of facts. It follows that, though it is unquestionably 
 true that we can predicate in thought categories other than the 
 highest, and even treat them as final, it is no less certain that 
 we cannot, with complete truth, explain thought, any more than 
 
138 THE DEVELOPMENT OP THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 any other aspect of reality, by any category but the Absolute 
 Idea. 
 
 This explains how it is possible for the actual and inevitable 
 course of thought not to express fully and adequately its own 
 nature. For thought may be erroneous or deceptive, when it is 
 treating of thought, as much as when it is treating of any other 
 reality. And it is possible that under certain circumstances the 
 judgment expressed in our thoughts may be inevitably erroneous 
 or deceptive. If these judgments have thought as their subject- 
 matter we shall then have the position in question — that the 
 necessary course of thought will fail to express properly its own 
 nature. 
 
 122. The mistake, as we have already noticed, comes from 
 the fact that, whereas the logical relations, which form the 
 content of the Absolute Idea, and express the true nature of 
 thought, consist in a direct development in which each term 
 only exists in the transition to another, the actual process, 
 on the other hand, is one from contrary to contrary, each of 
 which is conceived as possessing some stability and indepen- 
 dence. The reason of this mistake lies in the nature of the process, 
 which is one from error to truth. For while error remains in our 
 conclusions, it must naturally afTect our comprehension of the 
 logical relations by which those conclusions are connected, and 
 induce us to suppose them other than they are. In particular, 
 the mistake may be traced to the circumstance that the dialectic 
 starts with the knowledge of the part, and from this works up 
 to the knowledge of the whole. This method of procedure is 
 always inappropriate in anything of the nature of an organism. 
 Now the relation of the moments of the Absolute Idea to the 
 whole of which they are parts is still more close and intimate than 
 is the relation of the parts of a living organism to the organism 
 itself. And here, therefore, even more than with organisms, will 
 it be inadequate and deceptive to endeavour to comprehend the 
 whole from the standpoint of the part. And this is what the 
 dialectic, as it progresses, must necessarily do. Consequently, 
 not only are the lower categories of the dialectic inadequate 
 when taken as ultimate, but their relation to each other is 
 not the relation which they have in the Absolute Idea, and 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 139 
 
 consequently in all existence. These relations, in the dialectic, 
 represent more or less the error through which the human mind 
 is gradually attaining to the truth. They do not adequately 
 represent the relations existing in the truth itself. To this extent, 
 then, the dialectic is subjective. 
 
 123. And the dialectic is also to be called subjective because 
 it not only fails to show clearly the true nature of thought, but, 
 as we noticed above, does not fully express its own meaning — 
 the meaning of the process forwards. For the real meaning of 
 the advance, if it is to have any objective reality at all — if it 
 is to be a necessary consequence of all attempts at thorough and 
 consistent thinking, must be the result of the nature of thought 
 as it exists. Our several judgments on the nature of thought 
 have not in themselves any power of leading us on from one 
 of them to another. It is the relation of these judgments to the 
 concrete whole of thought, incarnate in our minds and in all 
 our experience, which creates the dialectic movement. Since this 
 is so, it would seem that the real heart and kernel of the process 
 is the movement of abstractions to rejoin the whole from which 
 they have been separated, and that the essential part of this 
 movement is that by which we are carried from the more abstract 
 to the more concrete. This will be determined by the relations 
 in which the finite categories stand to the concrete idea, when 
 they are viewed as abstractions from it and aspects of it — the 
 only sense in which they have any truth. But the true relation 
 of the abstractions to the concrete idea is, as we have already seen, 
 that to which the dialectic method gradually approximates, but 
 which it never reaches, and not that with which it starts, and 
 which it gradually, but never entirely, discards. And so the 
 dialectic advance has, mixed up with it, elements which do not 
 really belong to the advance, nor to the essence of pure thought, 
 but are merely due to our original ignorance about the latter, 
 of which we only gradually get rid. For all that part of the actual 
 advance in the dialectic, which is different from the advance 
 according to the type characteristic of the Notion, has no share 
 in the real meaning and value of the process, since it does not 
 contribute to what alone makes that meaning and value, namely 
 the restoration of the full and complete idea. What this element 
 
140 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE IVIETHOD [ch. 
 
 is, we can learn by comparing the movement of the dialectic 
 which is typical of Being, with that which is typical of the 
 Notion. It is the opposition and contradiction, the immediacy 
 of the finite categories, and the way in which they negate their 
 antitheses, and resist, until forced into submission, the transition 
 to their syntheses. It is, so to speak, the transverse motion as 
 opposed to the direct motion forward. The dialectic always moves 
 onwards at an angle to the straight line which denotes advance 
 in truth and concreteness. Starting unduly on one side of the 
 truth, it oscillates to the other, and then corrects itself. Once 
 more it finds that even in its corrected statement it is still one- 
 sided, and again swings to the opposite extreme. It is in this 
 indirect way alone that it advances. And the essence of the 
 process is the direct part alone of the advance. The whole point 
 of the dialectic is that it gradually attains to the Absolute Idea. 
 In so far then as the process is not direct advance to the absolute, 
 it does not express the essence of the process only, but also the 
 inevitable inadequacies of the human mind when considering a 
 subject-matter which can only be fully understood when the 
 consideration has been completed. 
 
 And, as was remarked above, it also fails to express its own 
 meaning in another way. For the imperfect type of transition, 
 which is never fully eliminated, represents the various categories 
 as possessing some degree of independence and self-subsistence. 
 If they really possessed this, they could not be completely 
 absorbed in the synthesis, and the dialectic could not be suc- 
 cessful. The fact that it is successful proves that it has not given 
 a completely correct account of itself, and, for this reason also, 
 it deserves to be called subjective, since it does not fully express 
 the objective reality of thought. 
 
 124. Having decided that the dialectic is to this extent sub- 
 jective, we have to consider how far this will reduce its cardinal 
 significance in philosophy, or its practical utility. I do not see 
 that it need do either. For all that results from this new position 
 is that the dialectic is a process through error to truth. Now we 
 knew this before. For on any theory of the dialectic it remains 
 true that it sets out with inadequate ideas of the universe and 
 finally reaches adequate ideas. We now go further and say that 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 141 
 
 the relation of these inadequate ideas to one another does not 
 completely correspond to anything in the nature of reahty. But 
 the general result is the same — that we gain the truth by the 
 dialectic, but that the steps by which we reach it contain imper- 
 fections. We shall see that our new view does not destroy the 
 value of the dialectic, if we consider in more detail in what that 
 value consists. 
 
 The importance of the dialectic is threefold. The first branch 
 of it depends chiefly on the end being reached, and the other two 
 chiefly on the means by which it is reached. The first of these 
 lies in the conclusion that if we can predicate any category 
 whatever of a thing, we are thereby entitled to predicate the 
 Absolute Idea of it. Now we can predicate some category of 
 anything whatever, and the Absolute Idea is simply the descrip- 
 tion in abstract terms of the human spirit, or, in other words, 
 the human spirit is the incarnation of the Absolute Idea. From 
 this it follows that the mind could, if it only saw clearly enough, 
 see a nature like its own in everything. The importance of this 
 conclusion is obvious. It gives the assurance of that harmony 
 between ourselves and the world for which philosophy always 
 seeks, and by which alone science and religion can be ultimately 
 justified. 
 
 Hegel was entitled, on his own premises, to reach this con- 
 clusion by means of the dialectic. And the different view of the 
 relation of the dialectic to reality, which I have ventured to put 
 forward, does not at all affect the validity of the dialectic for 
 this purpose. For the progress of the dialectic remains as necessary 
 as before. The progress is indirect, and we have come to the 
 conclusion that the indirectness of the advance is not in any way 
 due to the essential nature of pure thought, but entirely to our 
 own imperfect understanding of that nature. But the whole 
 process is still necessary, and the direct advance is still essential. 
 And all that we want to know is that the direct advance is 
 necessary. We are only interested, for this particular purpose, 
 in proving that from any possible standpoint we are bound in 
 logical consistency to advance to the Absolute Idea. In this 
 connection it is not of the least importance what is the nature 
 of the road we travel, provided that we must travel it, nor 
 
142 THE DEVELOPMENT OP THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 whether the process expresses truth fully, provided that the final 
 conclusion does so. Now the theory propounded above as to the 
 dialectic process leaves the objectivity and adequacy of the result 
 of the dialectic unimpaired. And therefore for this function the 
 system is as well adapted as it ever was, 
 
 125. The second ground of the importance of the Hegelian 
 logic consists in the information which it is able to give us about 
 the world as it is here and now for us, who have not yet been able 
 so clearly to interpret all phenomena as only to find our own 
 most fundamental nature manifesting itself in them. As we see 
 that certain categories are superior in concreteness and truth to 
 others, since they come later in the chain and have transcended 
 the meaning of their predecessors, we are able to say that certain 
 methods of regarding the universe are more correct and significant 
 than others. We are able to see that the idea of organism, for 
 example, is a more fundamental explanation than the idea of 
 causality, and one which we should prefer whenever we can apply 
 it to the matter in hand. 
 
 Here also the value of the dialectic remains unimpaired. For 
 whether it does or does not express the true nature of thought 
 with complete correctness ; it certainly, according to this theory, 
 does show the necessary and inevitable connection of our finite 
 judgments with one another. The utility which we are now con- 
 sidering lies in the guidance which the dialectic can give us to 
 the relative validity and usefulness of these finite judgments. 
 For it is only necessary to know their relations to one another, 
 and to know that as the series goes further, it goes nearer to the 
 truth. Both these things can be learnt from the dialectic. That 
 it does not tell us the exact relations which subsist in reahty 
 is unimportant. For we are not here judging reality, but the 
 judgments of reason about reality. 
 
 126. The third function of the dialectic process is certainly 
 destroyed by the view of it which I have explained above. The 
 dialectic showed, for Hegel, the relation of the categories to one 
 another, as moments in the Absolute Idea, and in reality. We 
 are now forced to consider those moments- as related in a way 
 which is inadequately expressed by the relation of the categories 
 to one another. We are not however deprived of anything 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 143 
 
 essential to the completeness of the system by this. In the first 
 place, we are still able to understand completely and adequately 
 what the Absolute Idea is. For although one definition was given 
 of it by which "its true content is only the whole system of which 
 we have been hitherto studying the development," yet a more 
 direct and independent one may also be found^. Our inability 
 to regard the process any longer as an adequate analysis of the 
 Absolute Idea will not leave us in ignorance of what the Absolute 
 Idea really is. 
 
 And, in the second place, we are not altogether left in the 
 dark even as regards the analysis of the Absolute Idea. The 
 dialectic, it is true, never fully reveals the true nature of thought 
 which forms its secret spring, but it gives us data by which we 
 can discount the necessary error. For the connection of the 
 categories resembles the true nature of thought (which is ex- 
 pressed in the typical transition of the Notion), more and more 
 closely as it goes on, and at the end of the Logic it differs from 
 it only infinitesimally. By observing the type to which the 
 dialectic method approximates throughout its course, we are 
 thus enabled to tell what element in it is that which is due to 
 the essential nature of thought. It is that element which alone 
 is left when, in the typical movement of the Notion, we see how 
 the dialectic would act if it could act with full self-consciousness. 
 It is true that in the lower categories we can never see the tran- 
 sition according to this type, owing to the necessary confusion 
 of the subject-matter in so low a stage, which hides the true 
 nature of the process to which the dialectic endeavours to approxi- 
 mate. But we can regard the movement of all the categories as 
 compounded, in different proportions according to their positions 
 in the system, of two forces, the force of opposition and negation, 
 and the force of advance and completion, and we can say that 
 the latter is due to the real nature of thought, and the former 
 to our misconceptions about it. In other words, the element of 
 imperfection in the dialectic is inevitable, but its amount can 
 be ascertained, and it need not therefore introduce any doubt 
 
 ^ "Der Begriff der Idee, dem die Idee als solche der Gegenstand, dam das 
 Objekt sie ist " — Enc. Section 236. The definition quoted in the text is in Section 
 237, lecture note. 
 
144 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 or scepticism into the conclusions to which the dialectic may 
 lead us. 
 
 127. What then is this real and essential element in the 
 advance of thought which is revealed, though never completely, 
 in the dialectic? In the first place, it is an advance which is 
 direct. The element of indirectness which is introduced by the 
 movement from thesis to antithesis, from opposite to opposite, 
 diminishes as the dialectic proceeds, and, in the ideal type, wholly 
 dies away. In that type each category is seen to carry in itself 
 the implication of the next beyond it, to which thought then 
 proceeds. The lower is only lower because part of its meaning 
 is still implicit; it is no longer one-sided, requiring to be corrected 
 by an equal excess on the other side of the truth. And, therefore, 
 no idea stands in an attitude of opposition to any other; there 
 is nothing to break down, nothing to fight. All that aspect of 
 the process belongs to our misapprehension of the relation of the 
 abstract to the concrete. While looking up from the bottom, we 
 may imagine the truth is only to be attained by contest, but in 
 looking down from the top — the only true way of examining a 
 process of this sort — we see that the contest is only due to our 
 misunderstanding, and that the growth of thought is really direct 
 and unopposed. 
 
 The movement of the dialectic may perhaps be compared to 
 that of a ship tacking against the wind. If we suppose that the 
 wind blows exactly from the point which the ship wishes to reach, 
 and that, as the voyage continues, the sailing powers of the ship 
 improve so that it becomes able to sail closer and closer to the 
 wind, the analogy will be rather exact. It is impossible for the 
 ship to reach its destination by a direct course, as the wind is 
 precisely opposite to the line which that course would take, and 
 in the same way it is impossible for the dialectic to move forward 
 without the triple relation of its terms, and without some opposi- 
 tion between thesis and antithesis. But the only object of the 
 ship is to proceed towards the port, as the only object of the 
 dialectic process is to attain to the concrete and complete idea, 
 and the movement of the ship from side to side of the direct line 
 is labour wasted, so far as the end of the voyage is concerned, 
 though necessarily wasted, since the forward movement would, 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 145 
 
 under the circumstances, be impossible without the combination 
 with it of a lateral movement. In the same way, the advance in 
 the dialectic is merely in the gradually increasing completeness 
 of the ideas. The opposition of one idea to another, and the 
 consequent negation and contradiction, do not mark any real 
 step towards attaining the knowledge of the essential nature of 
 thought, although they are necessary accompaniments of the 
 process of gaining that knowledge. Again, the change in the 
 ship's sailing powers which allows it to go nearer to the wind, 
 and so reduces the distance which it is necessary to travel in 
 order to accomplish the journey, will correspond to the gradual 
 subordination of the elements of negation and opposition, which 
 we have seen to take place as we approach the end of the dialectic. 
 
 128. Not the whole, then, of each category represents the 
 objective nature of the dialectic, but only a certain element in 
 it. And this is the element of unity and continuity. The element 
 which keeps the categories apart, and gives them the appearance 
 of distinction and stability, is just the element which we are 
 now led to believe is due to our incapacity to grasp the nature 
 of thought until we arrive at the end of the dialectic. 
 
 This would seem to render it probable that the dialectic may 
 be looked on primarily as continuous and not discrete. The 
 categories, if this view is right, should not be taken as ultimate 
 units, which are combined in groups of three, and these again 
 in larger groups of three, till at last the whole dialectic is in this 
 manner built up. On the contrary the whole dialectic should be 
 looked on as primarily a unity, which can be analysed into three 
 members, each of which can again be analysed into three mem- 
 bers, and so on, as long as our interest and insight are sufficient 
 to induce us to pursue the division. 
 
 This theory is confirmed by two other characteristics of the 
 dialectic. The first of these is the great difference in the lengths 
 to which the sub-division of the categories is carried in different 
 parts of the system. If, for example, in the Smaller Logic, we 
 take the first division of Essence, which is named Essence as 
 Ground, we find that its first two sub-divisions are called, re- 
 spectively, Primary Characteristics of Reflection, and Existence. 
 In the latter there is no trace of further sub-division, while the 
 
146 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 former is divided again into Identity, Difference, and Ground, 
 and in Difference, once more, we find distinguished Diversity, 
 Likeness and Unlikeness, and Positive and Negative. Similar 
 differences are to be found at other points of the system, and 
 also in the Greater Logic. If the individual categories were 
 ultimate units, such discrepancies in their size and importance 
 would be strange and inexplicable. But if we regard the whole 
 of the dialectic as logically prior to its parts, and the parts as 
 produced by analysis, we have an easy and natural explanation 
 of the inequality — namely, that it is due to some circumstance 
 which rendered Hegel, or which perhaps renders all men, more 
 interested or more acute when dealing with one part of the process 
 than when dealing with another. 
 
 129. There is also a second characteristic of the dialectic 
 which supports this theory. It is not necessary to descend to 
 the lowest sub-divisions which Hegel gives, in order to observe 
 the dialectic process. The larger divisions, also, lead on to one 
 another by the same necessity as the smaller ones do. Reasons 
 could be given, without going into greater detail, why Quality 
 should involve Quantity, and both of them Measure; or, again, 
 why Notion must lead us on to Judgment, and Judgment to 
 Syllogism. An argument which confined itself to so few steps 
 would be far more obscure, and consequently more dangerous 
 and doubtful, than the argument which we actually have in the 
 Logic. But still such a chain of demonstrations could be formed, 
 and in many places Hegel gives us part of it. 
 
 Now this is incompatible with the view of the dialectic as 
 ultimately discrete. For then every larger division would be 
 nothing but an aggregate of smaller ones. No such division could 
 then be used as a transition from the one below it to the one 
 above it, without descending into the lowest sub-divisions. Being 
 an aggregate of separate units, it could not be treated as a 
 coherent whole until all its separate parts had been demonstrated 
 to be hnked together. And the fact that the dialectic process 
 can go from one to another of the larger divisions, ignoring their 
 sub-divisions, will confirm us in supposing that the dialectic is 
 not a chain of links, but rather a continuous flow of thought, 
 which can be analysed into divisions and sub-divisions. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 147 
 
 130. The belief that the dialectic is continuous may have 
 an important influence on our position if we are led, on closer 
 examination, to the conclusion that any of Hegel's transitions 
 are erroneous and cannot be justified. On the hyjDothesis that 
 the steps of the dialectic are discrete, one such error would 
 destroy the validity of the whole process, beyond the point where 
 it occurs, as completely as the two ends of a chain would be 
 separated by the breaking of a single link, even if all the rest 
 held fast. Our only reason for not considering the whole value 
 of the process, beyond the faulty link, as absolutely destroyed, 
 would rest on a rough argument from analogy. It might be said 
 that, if there was a valid dialectic process up to a certain point, 
 and again from that point onwards, it was not probable that 
 there would, at that one point, be an absolute gulf, and we might 
 therefore hope that a fresh transition might be discovered at this 
 point, instead of the one which we had been compelled to reject. 
 But such an analogy would not be very strong. 
 
 On the other hand, the theory of the continuity of the dialectic 
 will make such a discovery much less serious. For if the larger 
 division, in a sub-division of which the fault occurs, forms itself 
 a vahd transition from the division before it to the one which 
 follows it, we shall be sure that to do this it must be a coherent 
 whole, and capable, therefore, of being analysed into a coherent 
 chain of sub-divisions. And therefore, though we cannot be 
 satisfied with the dialectic until we have replaced the defective 
 member with one that will stand criticism, we shall have good 
 grounds for supposing that such a change can be effected. 
 
 131. The gradual change in the method of the dialectic can 
 be well exempUfied by examining the supreme and all-including 
 triad, of which all the others are moments. This triad is given 
 by Hegel as Logic, Nature, and Spirit. 
 
 If we enquire as to the form which the dialectic process is 
 likely to assume here, we find ourselves in a difficulty. For the 
 form of transition in any particular triad was determined by its 
 place in the series. If it was among the earher categories, it 
 approximated to the character given as typical of Being; if it 
 did not come till near the end, it showed more or less resemblance 
 to the type of the Notion. And we were able to see that this was 
 
148 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 natural, because the later method, being more direct, and less 
 encumbered with irrelevant material, was only to be attained 
 when the work previously done had given us sufficient insight 
 into the real nature of the subject-matter. This principle, how- 
 ever, will not help us here. For the transition which we are here 
 considering is both the first and the last of its series, and it is 
 impossible, therefore, to determine its characteristic features by 
 its place in the order. The less direct method is necessary when 
 we are dealing with the abstract and imperfect categories with 
 which our investigations must begin, the more direct method 
 comes with the more adequate categories. But this triad covers 
 the whole range, from the barest category of the Logic— that 
 of pure Being — to the culmination of human thought in Absolute 
 Spirit. 
 
 Since it covers the whole range, in which all the types of the 
 dialectic method are displayed, the natural conclusion would 
 seem to be that one of them is as appropriate to it as another, 
 that whichever form may be used will be more or less helpful 
 and significant, because the process does cover the ground in 
 which that form can appropriately be used; while, on the other 
 hand, every form will be more or less inadequate, because the 
 process covers ground on which it cannot appropriately be used. 
 If we cast it in the form of the Notion, we shall ignore the fact 
 that it starts at a point too early for a method so direct; if, on 
 the other hand, we try the form of the categories of Being, the 
 process contains material for which such a method is in- 
 adequate. 
 
 132. And if we look at the facts we shall find that they confirm 
 this view, and that it is possible to state the relation of Logic, 
 Nature, and Spirit to one another, in two different ways. Hegel 
 himself states it in the manner characteristic of the Notion. It 
 is not so much positive, negative, and synthesis, as universal, 
 particular, and individual that he points out. In the Logic 
 thought is to be found in pure abstraction from all particulars, 
 (we cannot, of course, think it as abstracted from particulars, 
 but in the Logic we attend only to the thought, and ignore the 
 data it connects). In Nature we find thought again, for Nature 
 is part of experience, and more or less rational, and this implies 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 149 
 
 that it has thought in it. In Nature, however, thought is rather 
 buried under the mass of data which appear contingent and 
 empirical; we see the reason is there, but we do not see that 
 everything is completely rational. It is described by Hegel as 
 the idea in a state of alienation from itself. Nature is thus far 
 from being the mere contrary and correlative of thought. It is 
 thought and something more, thought incarnate in the particulars 
 of sense. At the same time, while the transition indicates an 
 advance, it does not indicate a pure advance. For the thought 
 is represented as more or less overpowered by the new element 
 which has been added, and not altogether reconciled to and 
 interpenetrating it. In going forward it has also gone to one 
 side, and this requires, therefore, the correction which is given 
 to it in the synthesis, when thought, in Spirit, completely masters 
 the mass of particulars which for a time had seemed to master 
 it, and when we perceive that the truth of the universe lies in 
 the existence of thought as fact, the incarnation of the Absolute 
 Idea — in short, in Spirit. 
 
 Here we meet all the characteristics of the Notion- type. The 
 second term, to which we advance from the first, is to some 
 extent its opposite, since the particulars of sense, entirely wanting 
 in the first, are in undue prominence in the second. But it is 
 to a much greater extent the completion of the first, since the 
 idea, which was taken in the Logic in unreal abstraction, is now 
 taken as embodied in facts, which is the way it really exists. 
 The only defect is that the embodiment is not yet quite complete 
 and evident. And the synthesis which removes this defect does 
 not, as in earlier types of the dialectic, stand impartially between 
 thesis and antithesis, each as defective as the other, but only 
 completes the process already begun in the antithesis. It is not 
 necessary to compare the two lower terms. Logic and Nature, 
 to be able to proceed to Spirit. The consideration of Nature alone 
 would be sufficient to show that it postulated the existence of 
 Spirit. For we have already in Nature both the sides required 
 for the synthesis, though their connection is so far imperfect, 
 and there is consequently no need to refer back to the thesis, 
 whose meaning has been incorporated and preserved in the anti- 
 thesis. The existence of the two sides, not completely reconciled, 
 
150 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 in the antithesis, in itself postulates a synthesis, in which the 
 reconciliation shall be completed. 
 
 133. But it would also be possible to state the transition in 
 the form which is used in the Logic for the lower part of the 
 dialectic. In this case we should proceed from pure thought to 
 its simple contrary, and from the two together to a synthesis. 
 This simple contrary will be the element which, together with 
 thought, forms the basis for the synthesis which is given in 
 Spirit. And as Nature, as we have seen, contains the same 
 elements as Spirit, though less perfectly developed, we shall find 
 this contrary of thought to be the element in experience, whether 
 of Nature or Spirit, which cannot be reduced to thought. Now 
 of this element we know that it is immediate and that it is 
 particular — not in the sense in which Nature is particular, in 
 the sense of incompletely developed individuality, but of abstract 
 particularity. It is possible to conceive that in the long run all 
 other characteristics of experience except these might be reduced 
 to a consequence of thought. But however far the process of 
 rationalisation might be carried, and however fully we might be 
 able to answer the question of why things are as they are and 
 not otherwise, it is impossible to get rid of a datum which is 
 immediate and therefore unaccounted for. For thought is only 
 mediation, and therefore, taken apart from immediacy, is a mere 
 abstraction. If nothing existed but thought itself, still the fact 
 of its existence must be in the long run immediately given, and 
 something for which thought itself could not account. This im- 
 mediacy is the mark of the element which is essential to experience 
 and irreducible to thought. • 
 
 If then we wished to display the process from Logic to Spirit 
 according to the Being-type of transition we should, starting 
 from pure thought as our thesis, put as its antithesis the element 
 of immediacy and "givenness" in experience. This element can 
 never be properly or adequately described, since all description 
 consists in predicating categories of the subject, and is therefore 
 mediation; but by abstracting the element of mediation in ex- 
 perience, as in Logic we abstract the element of immediacy, we 
 can form some idea of what it is like. Here we should have 
 thought and immediacy as exactly opposite and counterbalancing 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 151 
 
 elements. They are each essential to the truth, but present them- 
 selves as opposed to one another. Neither of them has the other 
 as a part of itself, though they can be seen to be closely and 
 intimately connected. But each of them negates the other as 
 much as it implies it, and the relation, without the synthesis, 
 is one of opposition and contradiction. We cannot see, as we 
 can when a transition assumes the Notion-form, that the whole 
 meaning of the one category lies in its transition to the other. 
 The synthesis of our triad would be the notion of experience or 
 reality, in which we have the given immediate mediated. This 
 would contain both Nature and Spirit, the former as the more 
 imperfect stage, the latter as the more perfect, culminating in 
 the completely satisfactory conception of Absolute Spirit. Nature 
 stands in this case in the same relation to Absolute Spirit as do 
 the lower forms of Spirit, — as less perfectly developed forms of 
 the concrete reality. 
 
 This triad could be proved as cogently as the other. It could 
 be shown, in the first place, that mere mediation is unmeaning, 
 except in relation to the merely immediate, since, without some- 
 thing to mediate, it could not act. In the same way it could be 
 shown that the merely given, without any action of thought on 
 it, could not exist, since any attempt to describe it, or even to 
 assert its existence, involves the use of some category, and there- 
 fore of thought. And these two extremes, each of which negates 
 the other, and at the same time demands it, are reconciled in 
 the synthesis of actual experience, whether Nature or Spirit, in 
 which the immediate is mediated, and both extremes in this way 
 gain for the first time reality and consistency. 
 
 134. The possibility of this alternative arrangement affords, 
 as I mentioned above, an additional argument in favour of the 
 view that the change of method is essential to the dialectic, and 
 that it is due to the progressively increasing insight into the 
 subject which we gain as we pass to the higher categories and 
 approximate to the completely adequate result. For, in this 
 instance, when the whole ground from beginning to end of the 
 dialectic process is covered in a single triad, we find that either 
 method may be used, — a fact which suggests of itself that the 
 two methods are appropriate to the two ends of the series, which 
 
152 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 are here, and here only, united by a single step. Independently 
 of this, however, it is also worth while to consider the possibility 
 of the double transition attentively, because it may help us to 
 explain the origin of some of the misapprehensions of Hegel's 
 meaning which are by no means uncommon. 
 
 135. We saw above that the dialectic represented the real 
 nature of thought more closely in the later categories, when it 
 appeared comparatively direct and spontaneous, than in the 
 earlier stages, when it was still encumbered with negations and 
 contradictions. It would appear probable, therefore, beforehand, 
 that of the two possible methods of treating this particular triad, 
 the one which Hegel has in fact adopted would be the more 
 expressive and significant. On examination we shall find that 
 this is actually the case. For there is no real separation between 
 thought and immediacy; neither can exist without the other. 
 Now, in the method adopted by Hegel, the element of immediacy 
 comes in first in Nature, and comes in, not as an element opposed 
 to, though necessarily connected with, pure thought, but as 
 already bound up mth it in a unity. This expresses the truth 
 better than a method which starts by considering the two aspects 
 as two self-centred and independent realities, which have to be 
 connected by reasoning external to themselves. For by this 
 second method, even when the two terms are finally reconciled 
 in a synthesis, it is done, so to speak, against their will, since 
 their claims to independence are only overcome by the reductio 
 ad absurdum to which they are brought, when they are seen, as 
 independent, to be at once mutually contradictory and mutually 
 implied in each other. In this method the transitory nature of 
 the incomplete categories and the way in which their movement 
 forward depends on their own essential nature, are not sujB&ciently 
 emphasised. 
 
 And we shall find that the subject-matter of the transition 
 is too advanced to bear stating according to the Being-type 
 without showing that that type is not fully appropriate to it. 
 Logic and Immediacy are indeed as much on a level as Being 
 an^ Not-Being. There is no trace whatever in the former case, 
 any more than in the latter, of a rudimentary synthesis in the 
 antithesis. But the other characteristic of the lower type — that 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD 153 
 
 the thesis and the antithesis should claim to be mutually ex- 
 clusive and independent — cannot be fully realised. Being and 
 Nothing, although they may be shown by reasoning to be mutually 
 implicated, are at any rate frima facie distinct and independent. 
 But mediation and immediacy, although opposed, are neverthe- 
 less connected, even prwia facie. It is impossible even to define 
 the two terms without suggesting that each of them is, by itself, 
 unstable, and that their only real existence is as aspects of the 
 concrete whole in which they are united. The method is thus 
 not sufficiently advanced for the matter it deals with. 
 
 136. It is, however, as I endeavoured to show above, probable 
 d priori that neither method would completely suit this particular 
 case. And not only the method which we have just discussed, 
 but the one which Hegel preferred to it, will be found to some 
 extent inadequate to its task here. Hegel's is, no doubt, the 
 more correct and convenient of the two ; yet its use alone, with- 
 out the knowledge that it does not in this case exclude the 
 concurrent use of the other as equally legitimate, may lead to 
 grave miscomprehensions of the system. 
 
 For the use of that method which Hegel does not adopt — the 
 one in which the terms are Logic, Immediacy, and Nature and 
 Spirit taken together — has at any rate this advantage, that it 
 brings out the fact that Immediacy is as important and ultimate 
 a factor in reality as Logic is, and one which cannot be reduced 
 to Logic. The two terms are exactly on a level. We begin with 
 the Logic and go from that to Immediacy, because it is to the 
 completed idea of the Logic that we come if we start from the 
 idea of pure Being, and we naturally start from the idea of pure 
 Being, because it alone, of all our ideas, is the one whose denial 
 carries with it, at once and clearly, self-contradiction. But the 
 transition from Immediacy to Logic is exactly the same as that 
 from Logic to Immediacy. And as the two terms are correlative 
 in this way, it would be comparatively easy to see, by observing 
 them, that neither of them derived its validity from the other, 
 but both from the synthesis. 
 
 137. This is not so clear when the argument takes the other 
 form. The element of Immediacy here never appears as a 
 separate and independent term at all. It appears in Nature for 
 
154 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. 
 
 the first time, and here it is already in combination with thought. 
 And Nature and Logic are not correlative terms, from either of 
 which we can proceed to the other. The transition runs from Logic 
 to Nature — from thought by itself, to thought in union with 
 immediacy. It is not unnatural, therefore, to suppose that im- 
 mediacy is dependent on pure thought, and can be deduced from 
 it, while the reverse process is not possible. The pure reason is 
 supposed to make for itself the material in which it is embodied. 
 "The logical bias of the Hegelian philosophy," says Professor 
 Seth, "tends... to reduce things to mere types or 'concretions' 
 of abstract formulae^." It might, I think, be shown that other 
 considerations conclusively prove this view to be incorrect. In 
 the first place, throughout the Logic there are continual references 
 which show that pure thought requires some material, other than 
 itself, in which to work. And, secondly, the spring of all move- 
 ment in the dialectic comes from the synthesis towards which 
 the process is working, and not from the thesis from which the 
 start is made. Consequently, progress from Logic to Nature 
 could, in any case, prove, not that the additional element in 
 nature was derived from thought, but that it co-existed with 
 thought in the synthesis which is their goal. But although the 
 mistake might have been avoided, even under the actual cir- 
 cumstances, it could scarcely have been made if the possibility 
 of the alternative method of deduction had been recognised. 
 Immediacy would, in that case, have been treated as a separate 
 element in the process, and as one which was correlative with 
 pure thought, so that it could scarcely have been supposed to 
 have been dependent on it. 
 
 138. The more developed method, again, tends rather to 
 obscure the full meaning and importance of the synthesis, unless 
 we realise that, in this method, part of the work of the synthesis 
 is already done in the second term. This is of great importance, 
 because we have seen that it is in their synthesis alone that the 
 terms gain full reality and validity, which they did not possess 
 when considered in abstraction. In the earlier method we see 
 clearly that pure thought is one of these abstractions, as mere 
 immediacy is the other. It is, therefore, clear that each of these 
 ^ Hegelianism and Personality, p. 126. 
 
IV] THE DEVELOPJIENT OF THE METHOD 155 
 
 terms, taken by itself, is a mere aspect, and could not possibly, 
 out of its own nature, produce the other aspect, and the reality 
 from which they both come. From this standpoint it would be 
 impossible to suppose that out of pure thought were produced 
 Nature and Spirit. 
 
 Now, in the type characteristic of the Notion, the same element 
 appears both in thesis and antithesis, although in the latter it 
 is in combination with a fresh element. There is, therefore, a 
 possibility of misunderstanding the process. For an element 
 which was both in thesis and antithesis might appear not to be 
 merely a one-sided abstraction, but to have the concreteness 
 which is to be found in the synthesis, since it appears in both 
 the extremes into which the synthesis may be separated. When, 
 for example, we have Logic, Nature, and Spirit, we might be 
 tempted to argue that pure thought could not be only one side 
 of the truth, since it was found in each of the lower terms — by 
 itself in Logic and combined with immediacy in Nature— and 
 hence to attribute to it a greater self-sufficiency and importance 
 than it really possesses. 
 
 This mistake will disappear when we realise that the only 
 reason that pure thought appears again in the second term of 
 the triad is that the synthesis, in transitions of this type, has 
 already begun in the second term. It is only in the synthesis 
 that thought appears in union with its opposite, and, apart 
 from the synthesis, it is as incomplete and unsubstantial as 
 immediacy is. 
 
 But the change in the type of the process is not sufficiently 
 emphasised in Hegel, and there is a tendency on the part of 
 observers to take the type presented by the earliest categories 
 as that which prevails all through the dialectic. And as, in the 
 earUer type, one of the extremes could not have been found both 
 in the first and second terms of a triad, it is supposed that pure 
 thought cannot be such an extreme, cannot stand in the same 
 relation to Spirit, as Being does to Becoming, and is rather to be 
 looked on as the cause of what follows it, than as an abstraction 
 from it. 
 
 139. I have endeavoured to show that the view of the dialectic 
 given in this chapter, while we cannot suppose it to have been 
 
156 THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE METHOD [ch. iv 
 
 held by Hegel, is nevertheless not unconnected with his system. 
 The germs of it are to be found in his exposition of the changes 
 of method in the three great divisions of the process, and the 
 observation of the details of the system confirm this. But it was 
 not sufficiently emphasised, nor did Hegel draw from it the con- 
 sequences, particularly as regards the subjective element in the 
 dialectic, which I have tried to show are logically involved in it. 
 But there is, nevertheless, justification for our regarding this 
 theory as a development and not a contradiction of the Hegelian 
 system, since it is only by the aid of some such theory that we 
 can regard that system as valid at all. And we have seen that 
 such a modification will not affect either of the great objects 
 which Absolute Idealism claims to have accomplished — the 
 demonstration, namely, that the real is rational and the rational 
 is real, and the classification, according to their necessary rela- 
 tions and intrinsic value, of the various categories which we use 
 in ordinary and finite thought. 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 
 
 140. One of the most interesting and important questions 
 wkich can arise in connection with Hegel's philosophy is the 
 question of the relation between the succession of the categories 
 in the dialectic and the succession of events in time. Are we 
 to regard the complex and concrete Absolute Idea, in which 
 alone true reality is to be found, as gradually growing up in 
 time by the evolution of one category after another? Or are 
 we to regard the Absolute Idea as existing eternally in its full 
 completeness, and the succession of events in time as something 
 which has no part as such in any ultimate system of the universe? 
 
 The succession of categories in Hegel's Logic is, of course, not 
 primarily a temporal succession. We pass from one to another 
 because the admission of the first as valid requires logically the 
 admission of the second as valid. At the same time there are 
 various reasons for accepting the view that one category succeeds 
 another in time. One of the facts of the universe which requires 
 explanation is the existence of time, and it seems at first sight 
 a simple and satisfactory explanation to account for it by the 
 gradual development of the Notion from Pure Being to the 
 Absolute Idea. And Hegel certainly explains the past to some 
 extent by bringing the successive events under successive cate- 
 gories. 
 
 Nevertheless, it seems to me that such a view is incompatible 
 with the system. There are doubtless difficulties in either inter- 
 pretation of Hegel's meaning, but there seems no doubt that 
 we must reject the development of the process in time. In the 
 first place, the theory that time is an ultimate reality would lead 
 to insoluble difficulties as to the commencement of the process. 
 Secondly, the Absolute Idea must be held to be the presupposition 
 and the logical prius of the lower categories. It follows that a 
 theory which makes the appearance of the lower category the 
 
158 THE RELATION OP THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 presupposition of the appearance of the higher one. cannot fully 
 represent the ultimate reality of the process. And, finally, Hegel's 
 language seems to be decisively on the side of the interpretation 
 that the Absolute Idea exists eternally in its full perfection, and 
 the movement from the lower to the higher is reconstruction and 
 not construction. 
 
 141. Let us consider the first of these points. Hegel, of course, 
 maintains that the universe is fully rational. Can we regard as 
 fully rational a universe in which a process in time is fundamen- 
 tally real? The theory before us maintains that the universe 
 starts with a minimum of reality, corresponding only to the 
 category of Pure Being. From this point it develops by the force 
 of the dialectic. Gradually each of the higher categories becomes 
 real, and this gradual evolution of logical completeness makes 
 the process which constitutes the life of the universe. All the 
 facts around us are to be attributed to the gradually developing 
 idea, and when the development is complete, and reality has 
 become an incarnation of the Absolute Idea, then the process 
 will end in perfection. The spiritual character of the universe, 
 up till then explicit and partial, will have become complete and 
 explicit. The real will be completely rational, and the rational 
 will be completely real. 
 
 On this we must remark, in the first place, that the process 
 in time by which the dialectic develops itself must be regarded 
 as finite and not as infinite. Neither in experience nor in a priori 
 criticism can we find any reason to believe that infinite time 
 really exists, or is anything more than an illegitimate inference 
 from the infinite extensibility of time. Nor, if it did exist, could 
 it form part of an ultimate rational explanation of the universe. 
 An unending regress, whether it is true or not, is certainly not 
 a solution which meets the demands of reason. More especially 
 is it impossible that it should be accepted as part of an Hegelian 
 theory. For infinite time would be the strongest possible example 
 of the "false infinite" of endless aggregation, which Hegel in- 
 variably condemns as a mere mockery of explanation. 
 
 And, independently of this, it is clear that an infinite series 
 in time would not be an embodiment of the dialectic. For the 
 dialectic is most emphatically a process with a beginning and 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 159 
 
 an end, and any series which embodies it must have a beginning 
 and an end also. If the dialectic has any truth, there can Be 
 no steps before Pure Being, nor any steps after the Absolute 
 Idea. As the number of steps is finite, either the time taken 
 by each of them is infinite, — and in that case there would be 
 no process at all — or the time taken by the whole series must 
 be finite. 
 
 We may consider, then, that any theory which imagines the 
 dialectic to develop itself in time at all, will regard it as doing 
 so in a limited time. What follows from this hypothesis? 
 
 142. The first difficulty which arises is that every event in 
 time requires a previous event as its cause. How then shall we 
 be able to explain the first event of the complete series? The 
 first event, like all the others, is an event in time, that is, it had 
 a beginning, before which it did not exist. What determined the 
 change which brought it into existence? Whatever determined 
 it must be itself an event in time, for if the cause had not a 
 definite place in the time series it could not account for its effect 
 having one. But in this case it will itself need a determining 
 cause, which will also be an event, and we have thus lost our 
 finite series with a definite beginning, and embarked on an in- 
 finite series, which cannot, as we have seen, be of any assistance 
 to us in our present purpose. 
 
 On the other hand, to deny that the first term of such a series 
 requires a determining cause is impossible. It is perhaps not 
 impossible that our minds should form the conception of some- 
 thing on which other things depend, while it depends itself on 
 nothing. But an event in time could never hold such a place. 
 For an event in time has always before it a time when it was not, 
 and this coming into existence deprives it of the possibility of 
 being self-subsistent. Time, as Hegel says, is still outside itself i. 
 It has no principle of unity or coherence. It can only be limited 
 by something external to it. Our finite series in time can only 
 have the definite beginning which it requires by means of further 
 time beyond it. To fix any point in time is to imply the existence 
 of time upon both sides of it. And thus no event in time could 
 be accepted as an ultimate beginning. On the other hand, some 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 257. 
 
160 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 such event would have to be accepted as the ultimate beginning, 
 if a finite series were to be accepted as an ultimate explanation. 
 If we apply this to the particular problem before us, we shall 
 find that the theory that the Absolute Idea develops in time 
 lands us in a hopeless diSiculty. Let us suppose that all the 
 phenomena of the universe have been accounted for as the mani- 
 festations of the gradually developing Idea, and let us suppose 
 that each of these manifestations of the Idea has been shown 
 to be the logical consequence of the existence of the previous 
 manifestation. Then the final and ultimate fact upon which our 
 explanation will depend will be that, at the beginning of time, 
 the first of the categories — the category of Pure Being — mani- 
 fested itself in reality. And for this fact itself an external 
 explanation is required. No such explanation, indeed, would 
 be required for the deduction of the universe from the idea of 
 Pure Being. If the system is correct, the categories are so in- 
 separably connected that the existence of one stage in the 
 dialectic process implies the existence of all, and the existence 
 of any reality, again, implies the existence of the categories. 
 The category of Pure Being can thus be deduced from the fact 
 that the universe exists, and the fact that the universe exists 
 does not require, as it does not admit, any outside cause. But 
 here, to account for the existence of the universe in time, we 
 have taken as our ultimate fact the realisation of the first category 
 at a particular time. Time is in itself quite empty and indifferent 
 to its content. No possible reason could be given why the process 
 should not have begun a hundred years later than it did, so that 
 we should be at the present moment in the reign of George III. 
 The only way of fixing an event to a particular time is by con- 
 necting it with some other event which happened in a particular 
 time. This would lead here to an infinite regress, and, indepen- 
 dently of this, would be impracticable. For, by the hypothesis, 
 the dialectic development was to account for the entire universe, 
 and there can, therefore, be no event outside it to which it can 
 be referred in order that it can be accounted for itself. And yet 
 the question — why it happened now and not at another time — 
 is one which we cannot refrain from asking, since time must be 
 regarded as infinitely extensible. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 161 
 
 143. Various attempts have been made to evade this difficulty. 
 It has been suggested that the temporal process has its root in 
 a timeless state. If we ask what determined the hrst event, we 
 are referred to the timeless state. If we ask what caused the 
 latter, we are answered that it had no beginning, and consequently 
 required no cause. 
 
 But how could a timeless reality be the cause of a succession 
 in time? It could, no doubt, be the cause of everything else in 
 a series of successive events, except of the fact that they did 
 take place in time. But how are we to account for that? No 
 reconciliation and no mediation is possible upon the hypothesis 
 with which we are here dealing. According to some views of 
 the question, time might be regarded as nothing but a form 
 assumed by eternity, or time and the timeless might be regarded 
 as forms of a higher reality. But such a view is impossible here. 
 The theory which we are here considering had to explain the 
 fact of a succession in the universe, and did so by making the 
 central principle of the universe to be the realisation of the 
 dialectic in time. The realisation in time, according to this theory^ 
 is as much part of the ultimate explanation of the universe as 
 the dialectic itself. By making time ultimate we certainly get 
 rid of the necessity for explaining it. But, on the other hand, 
 we lose the possibility of treating time as a distinction which 
 can be bridged over, or explained away, when we wish to make 
 a connection between time and the timeless. If time is an ultimate 
 fact, then the distinction between that which does, and that 
 which does not, happen in time must be an ultimate distinction ; 
 and how are we to make, if this is so, a transition from the one 
 to the other? 
 
 So far as a thing is timeless, it cannot change, for with change 
 time comes necessarily. But how can a thing which does not 
 change produce an effect in time? That the effect was produced 
 in time implies that it had a beginning. And if the effect begins, 
 while no beginning can be assigned to the cause, we are left to 
 choose between two alternatives. Either there is something in 
 the effect — namely, the quality of coming about as a change — 
 which is altogether uncaused. Or the timeless reality is only a 
 partial cause, and is determined to act by something which is 
 
162 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 not timeless. In either case, the timeless reality fails to explain 
 the succession in time, and we are no better off than we were 
 before. It would be equally available as an explanation if the 
 process had begun at any point besides the one at which it 
 actually did begin, and a cause which can remain the same while 
 the effect varies is obviously unsatisfactory. 
 
 144. It may be objected to this that, if the dialectic process 
 is the ultimate truth of all change, the point in time at which 
 it is to begin is determined by the nature of the case. For time 
 only exists when change exists. The changeless would be the 
 timeless. Therefore the beginning of the change must come at 
 the beginning of time, and there can be no question why it should 
 come at one moment rather than another. 
 
 This, however, will not remove one difficulty. Actual time, 
 no doubt, only began with actual change. But possible time 
 stretches back indefinitely beyond this. It is part of the essential 
 nature of time that, beyond any given part of it, we can imagine 
 a fresh part — that, indeed, we must do so. We cannot conceive 
 time as coming to an end. And with this indefinite stretch of 
 possible time the question again arises — what determined the 
 timeless to first produce change at the point it did, and not in 
 the previous time, which we now regard as possible only, but 
 which would have become actual by the production of change 
 in it? And again there is no reason why the series of actual time 
 should not have been placed later in the series of possible time 
 than it actually was. Actual time begins whenever change begins, 
 and so cannot be regarded as a fixed point, by which the begin- 
 ning of change can be determined. A certain amount of the 
 dialectic process has now been realised in time. Can we give 
 any reason why the amount should not have been greater or 
 less? Yet, if no such reason can be given, the present state of 
 the universe is left unaccounted for by our system. 
 
 The difficulty lies in the fact that we are compelled by the 
 nature of time to regard the time series as indefinitely extended, 
 and to regard each member of it as, in itself, exactly Hke each 
 other member. We may call that part of the series which is not 
 occupied by actual change, possible time, but the very name 
 imphes that there is no reason why it should not have been 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 163 
 
 occupied by events, as much as the actual time which really is 
 occupied by them. And, as possible time is indefinite, it is in- 
 definitely larger than any finite time. The question we have been 
 discussing will then take the form — why is this particular part 
 of the time series filled with reality rather than any other part? 
 And since, apart from its contents, one moment of time is exactly 
 like another, it would seem that the question is insoluble. 
 
 145. It has sometimes been attempted to ignore on general 
 grounds all endeavours to show that development throughout a 
 finite period in time cannot be accepted. Time, it has been said, 
 must be either finite or infinite. If we accept the objections to 
 taking finite time as part of our ultimate explanation, it can only 
 be because we are bound to an infinite regress. An infinite regress 
 involves infinite time. But infinite time is impossible — an unreal 
 abstraction, based on the impossibility of limiting the regress 
 in thought. Any argument which involves its real existence is 
 thereby reduced to an absurdity. And, since the objections to 
 finite time as part of our ultimate explanation do involve the 
 real existence of infinite time, we may, it is asserted, safely ignore 
 the objections and accept the principle. 
 
 The answer which we must make to this, in the first place, is 
 that the argument might as well be reversed. If the difficulties 
 in the way of infinite time are to be taken as a reason for ignoring 
 all difficulties in the way of finite time, why should we not make 
 the difficulties in the way of finite time a ground for accepting 
 with equally implicit faith the existence of infinite time? 
 
 Nor can we escape by saying that we do know finite time to 
 exist, and that therefore we are entitled to ignore the objections 
 to it, while we must accept the objections to infinite time. For 
 we have no more experience of finite time, in the sense in which 
 the phrase is used in this argument, than we have of infinite 
 time. What we meet in experience is a time series, extending 
 indefinitely both before and after our immediate contact with 
 it, out of which we can cut finite portions. But for a theory 
 which makes the development of the Notion in time part of its 
 ultimate formula, we require a time which is not merely limited 
 in the sense of being cut off from other time, but in the sense of 
 having none before it and none after it. Of this we have no more 
 
164 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 experience than we have of infinite time, and if there are diffi- 
 culties in the way of both, we have no right to prefer the one 
 to the other. 
 
 146. Since either hypothesis as to the extension of time leads 
 us into equal difficulties, our course should surely be, not to 
 accept either, but to reject both. Time must, we are told, be 
 either finite or infinite. But there is a third alternative. There 
 may be something wrong in our conception of time, or rather, 
 to speak more precisely, there may be something which renders 
 it unfit, in metaphysics, for the ultimate explanation of the 
 universe, however suited it may be to the finite thought of every- 
 day life. If we ask whether time, as a fact, is finite or infinite, 
 we find hopeless difficulties in the way of either answer. Yet, 
 if we take time as an ultimate reality, there seems no other 
 alternative. Our only resource is to conclude that time is not 
 an ultimate reality. 
 
 This is the same principle which is at work in the dialectic 
 itself. When we find that any category, if we analyse it suffi- 
 ciently, lands us, in its application to reality, in contradictions, 
 we do not accept one contradictory proposition and reject the 
 other. We conclude the category in question to be an inadequate 
 way of looking at reality, and we try to find a higher conception, 
 which will embrace all the truth of the lower one, while it will 
 avoid the contradictions. This is what we ought, it would seem, 
 to do with the idea of time. If it only presents us with a choice 
 between impossibilities, we must regard it as an inadequate way 
 of looking at the universe. And in this case we cannot accept 
 the process in time as part of our ultimate solution. 
 
 147, We now come to the second objection to the develop- 
 ment of the dialectic in time. That which we have just been 
 discussing would equally perplex any other idealistic system 
 which should adopt a time process as an original element. The 
 new difficulty belongs specially to the dialectic. It appears, as 
 we have seen^, to be essential to the possibility of a dialectic 
 process that the highest term, in which the process ends, should 
 be taken as the presupposition of all the lower terms. The 
 passage from category to category must not be taken as an actual 
 
 1 Chap. I. Section 6. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 165 
 
 advance, producing that which did not previously exist, but as 
 an advance from an abstraction to the concrete whole from whi ch 
 the abstraction was made — demonstrating and rendering explicit 
 what was before only implicit and immediately given, but still 
 only reconstructing, and not constructing anything fresh. 
 
 This view of Hegel's system becomes inevitable when we 
 consider, on the one hand, that his conclusion is that all that is 
 real is rational, and, on the other hand, that his method consists 
 in proving that each of the lower steps of the dialectic, taken 
 by itself, is not rational. We cannot then ascribe reality to any 
 of these steps, except in so far as they lose their independence 
 and become moments of the Absolute Idea. 
 
 We are compelled, according to Hegel, to pass from each thesis 
 and antithesis to their synthesis, by discovering that the thesis 
 and antithesis, while incompatible with one another, neverthe- 
 less involve one another. This produces a contradiction, and this 
 contradiction can only be removed by finding a term which 
 reconciles and transcends them. 
 
 Now if we suppose that the dialectic process came into ex- 
 istence gradually in time, we must suppose that all the contra- 
 dictions existed at one time or another independently, and before 
 reconciliation, i.e., as contradictions. Indeed, as the time process 
 is still going on, all the reality round us at the present day must 
 consist of unreconciled contradictions. 
 
 Such an assertion, however, would, it is clear, be absolutely 
 untenable. To say that the world consists of reconciled contra- 
 dictions would produce no difficulty, for it means nothing more 
 than that it consists of things which only appear contrary when 
 not thoroughly understood. But to say that a contradiction can 
 exist as such would plunge us in utter confusion. All reasoning, 
 and Hegel's as much as anybody else's, involves that two contrary 
 propositions cannot both be true. It would be useless to reason, 
 if, when you had demonstrated your conclusion, it was as true 
 to assert the opposite of that conclusion. 
 
 And, again, if contrary propositions could both be true, the 
 special line of argument which Hegel follows would have lost 
 all its force. We are enabled to pass on from the thesis and anti- 
 thesis to the synthesis just because a contradiction cannot be true, 
 
166 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 and the synthesis is the only way out of it. But if contradictions 
 are true, there is no necessity to find a way out of it, and the 
 advance of the dialectic is no longer valid. If the contradictions 
 exist at all, there seems no reason that they should not continue 
 to do so. We should not be able to avoid this by saying that they 
 are real, but that their imperfection made them transitory. For 
 the dialectic process, even if we suppose it to take place in time, 
 is not a mere succession in time, but essentially a logical process. 
 Each step has to be proved to follow from those before it by the 
 nature of the latter. It is clear that it would be impossible, by 
 consideration of the nature of a logical category, to deduce the 
 conclusion that for some time it could exist independently, but 
 that, after that, its imperfection would drive it on to another 
 stage. 
 
 148. It is, too, only on the supposition that reahty always 
 corresponds to the Absolute Idea, and is not merely approxi- 
 mating to it, that we can meet another difl&culty which is pro- 
 pounded by Trendelenburg. Either, he says, the conclusion of 
 the whole process can be obtained by analysis of the original 
 premise, or it cannot. The original premise of the whole process 
 is nothing but the validity of the idea of Pure Being. If the 
 whole conclusion can be got out of this, we learn nothing new, 
 and the whole dialectic process is futile. If, on the other hand, 
 we introduce anything not obtained from our original premise, 
 we fail in our object — which was to prove that the whole system 
 followed, when that premise was admitted. 
 
 We considered this difficulty above^, and came to the con- 
 clusion that the answer was contained in Mr Bradley's statement 
 of the true nature of dialectic. The passage in which he dealt 
 with the matter was, it will be remembered, as follows, "An 
 idea prevails that the Dialectic Method is a sort of experiment 
 with conceptions in vacuo. We are supposed to have nothing but 
 one single isolated abstract idea, and this solitary monad then 
 proceeds to multiply by gemmation from or by fission of its 
 private substance, or by fetching matter from the impalpable 
 void. But this is a mere caricature, and it comes from confusion 
 between that which the mind has got before it and that which 
 
 ^ Chap. II. Section 32. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 167 
 
 it has within itself. Before the mind there is a single conception, 
 but the whole mind itself, which does not appear, engages in 
 the process, operates on the datum, and produces the result. The 
 opposition between the real, in that fragmentary character in 
 which the mind possesses it, and the true reality felt within the 
 mind, is the moving cause of that unrest which sets up the 
 dialectical process." And again: "The whole, which is both 
 sides of this process, rejects the claim of a one-sided datum, and 
 supplements it by that other and opposite side which really is 
 implied — so begetting by negation a balanced unity. This path 
 once entered on, the process starts afresh with the whole just 
 reached. But this also is seen to be the one-sided expression of 
 a higher synthesis; and it gives birth to an opposite which co- 
 unites with it into a second whole, a whole which in its turn is 
 degraded into a fragment of truth. So the process goes on till 
 the mind, therein implicit, finds a product which answers its 
 unconscious idea; and here, having become in its own entirety 
 a datum to itself, it rests in the activity which is self-conscious 
 in its object^." 
 
 If we hold, according to this view, that the dialectic process 
 depends on the relation between the concrete whole and the 
 part of it which has so far become explicit, it is clear that we 
 cannot regard the concrete whole as produced out of the in- 
 complete and lower category by means of the dialectic process, 
 since the process cannot possibly produce its own presuppo- 
 sition. 
 
 149. And finally Hegel's own language appears to be clearly 
 incompatible with the theory that the dialectic is gradually 
 evolved in time. It is true that, in the Philosophy of Religion, 
 the Philosophy of History, and the History of Philosophy, he 
 explains various successions of events in time as manifestations 
 of the dialectic. But this proves nothing as to the fundamental 
 nature of the connection of time with the universe. The dialectic 
 is the key to all reality, and, therefore, whenever we do view 
 reality under the aspect of time, the different categories, will 
 appear as manifesting themselves as a process in time. But this 
 has no bearing on the question before us — -whether they first 
 ^ Logic; Book in. Part i. Chap. ii. Sections 20 and 21. 
 
168 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 came into being in time, or whether they have a timeless and 
 eternally complete existence. 
 
 Even in this part of his work, too, Hegel's adherence to the 
 eternal nature of the dialectic becomes evident in a manner all 
 the more significant, because it is logically unjustifiable. In 
 several places he seems on the point of saying that all dissatis- 
 faction with the existing state of the universe, and all efforts to 
 reform it, are futile and vain, since reason is already and always 
 the sole reality. This conclusion cannot be fairly drawn from 
 the eternity of the dialectic process. For if we are entitled to 
 hold the universe perfect, the same arguments lead us to con- 
 sider it also timeless and changeless. Imperfection and progress, 
 then, may claim to share whatever reality is to be allowed to 
 time and change, and no conclusion can be drawn, such as Hegel 
 appears at times to suggest, against attempting to make the 
 future an improvement on the past. Neither future and past, 
 nor better and worse, can be really adequate judgments of a 
 timeless and perfect universe, but in the sense in which there 
 is a future it may be an improvement on the past. But the very 
 fact that Hegel has gone too far in his application of the idea 
 that reality is timeless, makes it more clear that he did hold 
 that idea. 
 
 There are not, I believe, any expressions in the Logic 
 which can be fairly taken as suggesting the development of 
 the dialectic in time. It is true that two successive categories 
 are named Life and Cognition, and that science informs us 
 that life existed in this world before cognition. But the 
 names of the categories must be taken as those of the facts 
 in which the idea in question shows itself most clearly, and 
 not as indicating the only form in which the idea can show 
 itself at all. Otherwise we should be led to the impossible 
 result that Notions, Judgments, and Syllogisms existed before 
 Cognition. 
 
 A strong assertion of the eternal nature of the process is to 
 be found in the Doctrine of the Notion. "Die Vollfiihrung des 
 unendlichen Zwecks ist so nur die Tauschung aufzuheben, als 
 ob er noch nicht vollfiihrt sey. Das Gute, das absolute Gute, 
 vollbringt sich ewig in der Welt und das Resultat ist, dass es 
 
V] THE RELATION OP THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 169 
 
 schon an und flir sich vollbracht ist und nicht erst auf uns zu 
 warten braucht^." 
 
 Another important piece of evidence is his treatment of his 
 own maxim: "All that is real is rational." To the objections to 
 this he replies by saying that reality does not mean the surface 
 of things, but something deeper behind them. Besides this he 
 admits occasionally, though apparently not always, that con- 
 tingency has rights within a sphere of its own, where reason 
 cannot demand that everything should be explained. But he 
 never tries to meet the attacks made on his principle by drawing 
 a distinction between the irrational reality of the present and 
 the rational reality of the future. Such a distinction would be 
 so natural and obvious, and would, for those who could con- 
 sistently make use of it, so completely remove the charge of a 
 false optimism about the present, that we can scarcely doubt 
 that Hegel's neglect of it was due to the fact that he saw it to 
 be incompatible with his principles. 
 
 Hegel's treatment of time, moreover, confirms this view. For 
 he considers it merely as a stage in the Philosophy of Nature, 
 which is only an application of the Logic. Now if the realisation 
 of the categories of the Logic only took place in time, time would 
 be an element in the universe correlative with those categories, \^ 
 
 and of equal importance with them. Both would be primary \ 
 
 elements in a concrete whole. Neither could be looked on as 
 an application of, or deduction from, the other. But the treat- 
 ment of time as merely one of the phenomena which result from 
 the realisation of the Logic, is incompatible with such a theory 
 as this, and we may fairly conclude that time had not for Hegel 
 this ultimate importance. 
 
 150. We have thus arrived at the conclusion that the dialectic 
 is not for Hegel a process in time, but that the Absolute Idea 
 must be looked on as eternally realised. We are very far, however, 
 from having got rid of our difficulties. It looks, indeed, as if 
 we were brought, at this point, to a reductio ad. ahsurdum. For 
 if the other theory was incompatible with Hegel, this seems to 
 be incompatible with the facts. 
 
 The dialectic process is one from incomplete to complete 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 212, lecture note. 
 
^^ Ij Ml''' 170 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 rationality. If it is eternally fulfilled, then the universe must 
 be completely rational. Now, in the first place, it is certain that 
 the universe is not completely rational for us. We are not able 
 to see everything round us as a manifestation of the Absolute 
 Idea. Even those students of philosophy who believe on general 
 grounds that the Absolute Idea must be manifested in everything 
 are as unable as the rest of us to see how it is manifested in a 
 table or a thunder-storm. We can only explain these things — 
 at present, at any rate — by much lower categories, and we cannot, 
 therefore, explain them completely. Nor are we by any means 
 able, at present, to eliminate completely the contingency of the 
 data of sense, which are an essential element in reality, and a 
 universe which contains an ultimately contingent element cannot 
 be held to be completely rational. It would seem, too, that if 
 we are perfectly rational in a perfectly rational universe, there 
 must always be a complete harmony between our desires and 
 our environment. And this is not invariably the case. 
 
 But if the universe appears to us not to be perfect, can it be 
 so in reality? Does not the very failure to perceive the perfection 
 destroy it? In the first place, the Absolute Idea, as defined by 
 HegeP, is one of self-conscious rationality — the Idea to which 
 the Idea itself is "Gegenstand" and "Objekt." If any part of 
 reality sees anything, except the Absolute Idea, anywhere in 
 reality, this ideal can scarcely be said to have been fulfilled. 
 
 And, more generally, if the universe appears to us to be only 
 imperfectly rational, we must be either right or wrong. If we 
 are right, the world is not perfectly rational. But if we are wrong, 
 then it is difficult to see how we can be perfectly rational. And 
 we are part of the world. Thus it would seem that the very 
 opinion that the world is imperfect must, in one way or another, 
 prove its own truth. 
 
 151. If this is correct, we seem to be confronted with a 
 difficulty as hopeless as those which encountered us when we 
 supposed the dialectic to develop itself in time. These, we saw, 
 were due to our hypothesis being found incompatible with the 
 system, while our present view appears untenable because, 
 though a logical development from the system, it is incompatible 
 1 Enc. Section 236. 
 
is*" 
 
 5 ^*\'] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 171 
 
 W, ^ '^ with the facts. The result with regard to the first is that we come 
 Hj ^Tto the conclusion that the development in time cannot be part 
 ^ V* of Hegel's philosophy. The result of the second would at first 
 ** ^^ sight seem to be that Hegel's philosophy must be abandoned, 
 A " i*. since it leads to such untenable conclusions. 
 
 ^.^^ 
 
 We rejected the hypothesis of the development of the Absolute 
 
 •4^5* ^^^^ ^^ time upon two grounds. The first was that we had to '^^^y- 
 ^ k.^ choose between a false infinite and an uncaused beginning. Each ^^ -^^ 
 3C '^ of these hypotheses left something unexplained and contingent, *'^ "T^y "3l 
 
 U^ V* and was consequently incompatible with a system which de- "^ * if— 
 j|^^ VL manded above all things that the universe should be completely ^ ^ "^^ 
 ^ \^ rationalised, and which believed itself to have accomplished its <^ ^ "^ ' 
 
 * ^ ^ aim. Our second objection was due to the fact that the develop- » ^-*^ ^ 
 C ^ ^ ment of the dialectic at all, upon Hegel's principles, presupposed \^ "^^•^^ 
 ^v^ the existence of its goal, which could not therefore be supposed — ^ '^ 
 
 U» ^ to be reached for the first time by the process. But our difiiculty-, ^'^ ^ 
 ^ ^** ^ now is not at all incompatible with the system. It is one which ^ ^ f| ^ 3 
 
 * ^ must arise from it, and which must, in some form or another, 2 «< -J > -^ 
 ^ ^ ^ arise in any system of complete idealism. Every such system 3^"^ ^ ^ '^ 
 *<S must declare that the world is fundamentally rational and "I^ --^ rtyHft ^ 
 
 ^ ^ righteous throughout, and every such system will be met by ^5 r 
 »» h- ^ the same difficulty. How, if all reality is rational and righteous, J} < „-. m 5 
 
 1^ ^ Ui 
 
 " tne same aimcuity. ±iow, ii an reanty is rational ana rignteous, ^-^ -•v '^ ^ 
 
 — ^ are we to explain the irrationahty and unrighteousness which ^ X ryv ^ ^ 
 
 '"(^^ are notoriously part of our every-day life? We must now con- ^ ^-'^ v 
 
 ^ ^ sider the various attempts which have been made to answer this ^LT ^ 3 "> •■ 
 
 *^ > * question. O '^ •• ^ 
 
 ^ ^ 152. Hegel's answer has been indicated in the passage quoted ^^ ^ ■ 
 
 .'^ above^. The infinite end is really accomplished eternally. It is "^ "^ * 3b 5 
 
 t ^ tt only a delusion on our part which makes us suppose otherwise. \ '^v t^ ^ 
 
 H "*• 11 And the only real progress is the removal of the delusion. The ^ ^ S '^ ^ 
 
 universe is eternally the same, and eternally perfect. The move- ^ ^ X -^ qj 
 
 ment is only in our minds. They trace one after another in ^ "^ ^ ^ ^ 
 
 \ uif) succession the difierent categories of the Logic, which in reality 3^^ 
 
 ^ ^"Cihave no time order, but continually coexist as elements of the^ ^ ^ ^ )2 
 
 t "^ ^Absolute Idea which transcends and unites them. "** ^ -^ H ^ 
 
 \^^ \ This solution can, however, scarcely be accepted, for the ^ I^ f> ^ 
 
 \ reasons given above. How can we account for the delusion that^ f^ JT ** "^ 
 
 ^j- ^ Enc, Section 212, lecture note. ^C ^\ ft / ^ ^ W\ ^ ^ 
 
 5HX Jo ^CNJ H10^ IVWI ^^^ s>^\n^!i>40^ ^ ' 
 J.N3i.y9 Ml 3i,iNy ^\ Uy\^^ JloV s^^, -\^ /,; 
 
172 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 the world is partially irrational, if, as a matter of fact, it is 
 completely rational? How, in particular, can we regard such a 
 delusion as compatible with our own complete rationality? 
 
 To this it may be possibly objected that our argument is based 
 on a confusion. That a thought is a delusion need not imply that 
 it, or the being who thinks it, is irrational. Everything which, 
 like a thought, is used as a symbol, can be viewed in two aspects 
 — firstly as a fact, and secondly as representing, as a symbol, 
 some other fact. In the first aspect we say that it is real or unreal ; 
 in the second that it is true or false. These two pairs of predicates 
 have no intrinsic connection. A false judgment is just as really 
 a fact as a true one. 
 
 Now the conclusion from the Hegelian dialectic was that what- 
 ever was real was rational. We are, therefore, compelled to assert 
 that every thought, and every thinking being, is completely 
 rational — can be explained in a way which gives entire rest and 
 satisfaction to reason. But, it may be said, this is not in the 
 least interfered with by the fact that many real thoughts are 
 defective symbols of the other reality which they profess to 
 represent. The false can be, and, indeed, must be, real, for a 
 thought cannot misrepresent reality unless it is itself real. Till 
 it is real it can do nothing. And if the false can be real, why can 
 it not be rational? Indeed we often, in every-day life, and in 
 science, do find the false to be more or less rational. It is as 
 possible to account, psychologically, for the course of thought 
 which brings out an erroneous conclusion as for the course of 
 thought which brings out a correct one. We can explain our 
 failures to arrive at the truth as well as our successes. It would 
 seem then that there is nothing to prevent ourselves and our 
 thoughts being part of a completely rational universe, although 
 our thoughts are in some respects incorrect symbols. 
 
 153. But it must be remembered that the rationality which 
 Hegel requires of the universe is much more than complete deter- 
 mination under the category of cause and effect — a category which 
 the dialectic maintains to be quite insufficient, unless transcended 
 by a higher one. He requires, among other things, the validity 
 of the idea of final cause. And if this is brought in, it is difficult 
 to see how delusions can exist in a rational world. For a delusion 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 173 
 
 involves a thwarted purpose. If a man makes a mistake, it means 
 that he wishes to know the truth, and that he does not know it. 
 Whether this is the case or not, with regard to simple perception 
 of the facts before us, it cannot be denied that wherever there 
 is a long chain of argument, to which the mind is voluntarily 
 kept attentive, there must be a desire to know the truth. And 
 if this desire is unsuccessful, the universe could not be, in Hegel's 
 sense, completely rational. 
 
 This becomes more evident if we look at Hegel's definition 
 of complete rationality, as we find it in the Absolute Idea. The 
 essence of it is that reality is only completely rational in so far 
 as it is conscious of its own rationality. The idea is to be " Gegen- 
 stand" and " Objekt" to itself. If this is the case, it follows that 
 the rationality of Spirit, as an existent object, depends upon its 
 being a faithful symbol of the rationality expressed in other 
 manifestations of Spirit. The delusion by which Hegel explains 
 all imperfection will of course prevent its being a faithful symbol 
 of that rationality, and will therefore destroy the rationality 
 itself. In so far as we do not see the perfection of the universe, 
 we are not perfect ourselves. And as we are part of the universe, 
 that too cannot be perfect. And yet its perfection appears to 
 be a necessary consequence of Hegel's position. 
 
 . 154. HegeFs attempt to make the imperfection which is 
 evident round us compatible with the perfection of the universe 
 must, then, be rejected. Can we find any other solution which 
 would be more successful? One such solution suggests itself. It 
 was the denial of the ultimate reality of time which caused our 
 difficulty, since it forced us to assert that the perfect rationality, 
 which idealism claims for the universe, cannot be postponed to 
 the future, but must be timelessly and eternally present. Can 
 the denial of the reality of time be made to cure the wound, 
 which it has itself made? Would it not be possible, it might be 
 said, to escape from our dilemma as follows? The dialectic itself 
 teaches us that it is only the concrete whole which is completely 
 rational, and that any abstraction from it, by the very fact that 
 it is an abstraction, must be to some extent false and contra- 
 dictory. An attempt to take reality moment by moment, ele- 
 ment by element, must make reahty appear imperfect. The 
 
174 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 complete rationality is only in the whole which transcends all 
 these elements, and any one of them, considered as more or less 
 independent, must be false. Now, if we look at the universe as 
 in time, it will appear to be a succession of separate events, so 
 that only part of it is existing at any given instant, the rest being 
 either past or future. Each of these events will be represented 
 as real in itself, and not merely a moment in a real whole. And 
 in so far as events in time are taken to be, as such, real, it must 
 follow that reality does not appear rational. If an organic whole 
 is perfect, then any one of its parts, taken separately from the 
 whole, cannot possibly be perfect. For in such a whole all the 
 parts presuppose one another, and any one, taken by itself, must 
 bear the traces of its isolation and incompleteness. Now the 
 connection of the different parts of the universe, viewed in their 
 ultimate reality, is, according to the dialectic, even closer than 
 the connection of the parts of an organism. And thus not only 
 each event, but the whole universe taken as a series of separate 
 events, would appear imperfect. Even if such a series could ever 
 be complete, it could not fully represent the reality, since the 
 parts would still, by their existence in time, be isolated from one 
 another, and claim some amount of independence. Thus the 
 apparent imperfection of the universe would be due to the fact 
 that we are regarding it sub specie temforis — an aspect which 
 we have seen reason to conclude that Hegel himself did not 
 regard as adequate to reality. If we could only see it sub specie 
 aeternitatis, we should see it in its real perfection. 
 
 155. It is true, I think, that in this way we get a step nearer 
 to the goal required than we do by Hegel's own theory, which 
 we previously considered. Our task is to find, for the apparent 
 imperfection, some cause whose existence will not interfere with 
 the real perfection. We shall clearly be more likely to succeed 
 in this, in proportion as the cause we assign is a purely negative 
 one. The appearance of imperfection was accounted for by Hegel 
 as a delusion of our own minds. Now a delusion is as much a 
 positive fact as a true judgment is, and requires just as much 
 a positive cause. And, as we have seen, we are unable to con- 
 ceive this positive cause, except as something which will prevent 
 the appearance from being a delusion at all, since it will make 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 175 
 
 the universe really imperfect. On the theory just propounded, 
 however, the cause of the imperfection is nothing but the fact 
 that we do not see everything at once. Seen as we see things 
 now, reality must be imperfect. But if we can attain to the 
 point of looking at the whole universe sub specie aeternifatis, we 
 shall see just the same subject-matter as in time; but it will 
 appear perfect, because seen as a single concrete whole, and not 
 as a succession of separated abstractions. The only cause of the 
 apparent imperfection will be the negative consideration that 
 we do not now see the whole at once. 
 
 156. This theory would be free from some of the objections 
 which are fatal to a rather similar apology for the universe which 
 is often found in systems of optimism. It is admitted in such 
 apologies that, from the point of \'iew of individuals, the world 
 is imperfect and irrational. But, it is asserted, these blemishes 
 would disappear if we could look at the world as a whole. The 
 part which, taken by itself, is defective, may, we are told, be an 
 element in a perfect harmony. Such a theory, since it declares 
 that the universe can be really perfect, although imperfect for 
 individuals, implies that some individuals, at any rate, can be 
 treated merely as means, and not as ends in themselves. Without 
 enquiring whether such a view is at all tenable, it is at any rate 
 clear that it is incompatible with what is usually called optimism, 
 since it would permit of many— indeed of all — individuals being 
 doomed to eternal and infinite misery. We might be led to the 
 formula in which Mr Bradley sums up optimism: — "The world 
 is the best of all possible worlds, and everything in it is a necessary 
 evil^." For if the universal harmony can make any evil to indi- 
 viduals compatible with its own purposes, there is no principle 
 upon which we can limit the amount which it can tolerate. It is 
 more to our present purpose to remark that such a view could not 
 possibly be accepted as in any way consistent with Hegel's system. 
 It would be in direct opposition to its whole tendency, which is 
 to regard the universal as only gaining reality and validity 
 when, by its union with the particular, it becomes the individual. 
 For Hegel the ideal must lie, not in ignoring the claims of indi- 
 viduals, but in seeing in them the embodiment of the universal. 
 ^ Appearance and Reality, Preface, p. xiv. 
 
176 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 Mr Bradley's own treatment of the problem is, as far as I can 
 see, of a rather similar type. He has to reconcile the harmony 
 which he attributes to the Absolute, with the disharmony which 
 undoubtedly prevails, to some extent, in experience. This he 
 does by taking the finite individual to be, as such, only appearance 
 and not reality, from which it follows that it must distort the 
 harmony of the Absolute, and cannot adequately manifest it. 
 It may be doubted whether we do not fall into more difficulties 
 than we avoid by this low estimate of the conscious individual. 
 But, at any rate, such a solution would be impracticable for 
 anyone who accepted HegeFs version of the Absolute Idea, to 
 which the individual is the highest form that the universal can 
 take. 
 
 Some of the objections which apply to such attempts to save 
 the perfection of the Absolute by ignoring the claims of indi- 
 viduals will not hold against our endeavour to escape from our 
 difficulty by ignoring, so to speak, the claims of particular 
 moments of time. None of those considerations which make us 
 consider each separate person as an ultimate reality, whose claims 
 to self-realisation must be satisfied and cannot be transcended, 
 lead us to attribute the same importance to separate periods of 
 time. Indeed the whole drift of Hegel's system is as much 
 against the ultimate reality of a succession of phenomena, as 
 such, as it is in favour of the ultimate reality of individual persons, 
 as such. To deny any reality in what now presents itself to us 
 as a time-series would indeed be suicidal. For we have no data 
 given us for our thought, except in the form of a time-series, 
 and to destroy our data would be to destroy the super-structure. 
 But while philosophy could not start if it did not accept its data, 
 it could not proceed if it did not alter them. There is then nothing 
 obviously impossible in the supposition that the whole appearance 
 of succession in our experience is, as such, unreal, and that reality 
 is one timeless whole, in which all that appears successive is 
 really co-existent, as the houses are co-existent which we see 
 successively from the windows of a train. 
 
 157. It cannot, however, be said that this view is held by 
 Hegel himself. In the Philosophy of Nature he treats time as 
 a stage in the development of nature, and not as a cause why 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 177 
 
 there is any appearance of successive development at all. Indeed 
 he says there that things are not finite because they are in time, 
 but are in time because they are finite^. It would be thus im- 
 possible, without departing from Hegel, to make time the cause 
 of the apparent imperfection of the universe. 
 
 Everything else in the HegeHan philosophy may indeed be 
 considered as of subordinate importance to the Dialectic, and 
 to its goal, the Absolute Idea. If it were necessary, we might, 
 to save the validity of the Dialectic, reject Hegel's views even 
 on a subject so important as time, and yet call ourselves Hegehans. 
 But we should not gain much by this reconstruction of the 
 system. For it leaves the problem no more solved than it was 
 before. The difficulty which proved fatal to Hegel's own attempt 
 to explain the imperfection comes back as surely as before, 
 though it may not be quite so obvious. However much we may 
 treat time as mere appearance, it must, hke all other appearance, 
 have reality behind it. The reality, it may be answered, is in this 
 case the timeless Absolute. But this reality will have to account, 
 not merely for the facts which appear to us in time, but for the 
 appearance of succession which they do undoubtedly assume. 
 How can this be done? What reason can be given why the eternal 
 reality should manifest itself in a time process at all? If we tried 
 to find the reason outside the nature of the eternal reality, we 
 should be admitting that time had some independent validity, 
 and we should fall back into all the difficulties mentioned in the 
 earlier part of this chapter. But if we try to find the reason 
 inside the nature of the eternal reality, we shall find it to be 
 incompatible with the complete rationality which, according to 
 Hegel's theory, that reality must possess. For the process in 
 time is, by the hypothesis, the root of all irrationality, and how 
 can it spring from anything which is quite free of irrationality? 
 Why should a concrete and perfect whole proceed to make itself 
 imperfect, for the sake of gradually getting rid of the imper- 
 fection again? If it gained nothing by the change, could it be 
 completely rational to undergo it? But if it had anything to 
 gain by the change, how could it previously have been perfect? 
 
 158. We have thus failed again to solve the difficulty. How- 
 
 ^ Enc. Section 258, lecture note. 
 
178 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 ever much we may endeavour to make the imperfection of the 
 universe merely negative, it is impossible to escape from the 
 fact that, as an element in presentation, it requires a positive 
 ground. If we denied this, we should be forced into the position 
 that not only was our experience of imperfection a delusion, but 
 that it was actually non-existent. And this, as was mentioned 
 above, is an impossibility. All reasoning depends on the fact 
 that every appearance has a reality of which it is the appearance. 
 Without this we could have no possible basis upon which to rest 
 any conclusion. 
 
 Yet, on the other hand, so long as we admit a positive ground 
 for the imperfection, we find ourselves to be inconsistent with 
 the original position from which we started. For that position 
 asserted that the sole reality was absolutely perfect. On this 
 hangs the appearance of imperfection, and to this real perfection 
 as cause we have to ascribe apparent imperfection as effect. Now 
 it is not impossible, under certain circumstances, to imagine a 
 cause as driven on, by a dialectic necessity, to produce an effect 
 different from itself. But in this case it does seem impossible. 
 For any self-determination of a cause to produce its effect must 
 be due to some incompleteness in the former without the latter. 
 But if the cause, by itself, was incomplete, it could not, by itself, 
 be perfect. If, on the other hand it was perfect, it is impossible 
 to see how it could produce anything else as an effect. Its per- 
 fection makes it in complete harmony with itself. And, since 
 it is all reality, there is nothing outside it with which it could 
 be out of harmony. What could determine it to production? 
 
 Thus we oscillate between two extremes, each equally fatal. 
 If we endeavour to treat evil as absolutely unreal, we have to 
 reject the one basis of all knowledge — experience. But in so far 
 as we accept evil as a manifestation of reality, we find it im- 
 possible to avoid qualifying the cause by the nature of the effect 
 which it produces, and so contradicting the main result of the 
 dialectic — the harmony and perfection of the Absolute. 
 
 159. We need not, after all, be surprised at the apparently 
 insoluble problem which confronts us. For the question has 
 developed into the old difficulty of the origin of evil, which has 
 always baffled both theologians and philosophers. An idealism 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 179 
 
 which declares that the universe is in reality perfect, can find, 
 as most forms of popular idealism do, an escape from the diffi- 
 culties of the existence of evil, by declaring that the world is 
 as yet only growing towards its ideal perfection. But this refuge 
 disappears with the reality of time, and we are left with an 
 awkward difference between what our philosophy tells us must 
 be, and what our life tells us actually is. 
 
 The aim of the dialectic was to prove that all reality was 
 completely rational. And Hegel's arguments led him to the 
 conclusion that the universe as a whole could not be rational, 
 except in so far as each of its parts found its own self-realisation. 
 It followed that the universe, if harmonious on the theoretical 
 side, would be harmonious also in a practical aspect — that is, 
 would be in every respect perfect. This produces a dilemma. 
 Either the evil round us is real, or it is not. If it is real, then 
 reality is not perfectly rational. But if it is absolutely unreal, 
 then all our finite experience — and we know of no other — must 
 have an element in it which is absolutely irrational, and which, 
 however much we may pronounce it to be unreal, has a dis- 
 agreeably powerful influence in moulding the events of our 
 present life. Nor can we even hope that this element is transitory, 
 and comfort ourselves, in orthodox fashion, with the hope of a 
 heaven in which the evil shall have died away, while the good 
 remains. For we cannot assure ourselves of such a result by any 
 empirical arguments from particular data, which would be hope- 
 lessly inadequate to support such a conclusion. The only chance 
 would be an a 'priori argument founded on the essential rationality 
 of the universe, which might be held to render the imperfection 
 transitory. But we should have no right to use such an argument. 
 To escape the difficulties involved in the present coexistence of 
 rationality and irrationality, we have reduced the latter to such 
 complete unreality that it is not incompatible with the former. 
 But this cuts both ways. If the irrationality cannot interfere 
 with the rationality so as to render their present coexistence 
 impossible, there can be no reason why their future coexistence 
 should ever become impossible. If the irrational is absolutely 
 unreal now, it can never become less real in the future. Thus our 
 ascription of complete rationality to the universe leads us to a 
 
180 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 belief that one factor in experience, as it presents itself to us, 
 is fundamentally and permanently irrational — a somewhat sin- 
 gular conclusion from such a premise. 
 
 To put the difficulty from a more practical point of view, 
 either the imperfection in experience leaves a stain on the per- 
 fection of the Absolute, or it does not. If it does, there is no 
 absolute perfection, and we have no right to expect that the 
 imperfection around us is a delusion or a transitory phase. But 
 if it does not, then there is no reason why the perfection should 
 ever feel intolerant of it, and again we have no right to hope for 
 its disappearance. The whole practical interest of philosophy is 
 thus completely overthrown. It asserts an abstract perfection 
 beyond experience, but that is all. Such a perfection might 
 almost as well be a Thing-in-itself, since it is unable to explain 
 any single fact of experience without the aid of another factor, 
 which it may call unreal, but which it finds indispensable. It 
 entirely fails to rationalise reality or to reconcile it with our 
 aspirations. 
 
 160. The conclusion we have reached is one which it certainly 
 seems difficult enough to reconcile with continued adherence to 
 Hegelianism. Of the two possible theories as to the relation of 
 time to the dialectic process, we have found that one, besides 
 involving grave difficulties in itself, is quite inconsistent with 
 the spirit of Hegel's system. The other, again, while consistent 
 with that system, and, indeed, appearing to be its logical con- 
 sequence, has landed us in what seems to be a glaring contradic- 
 tion to the facts. Is it not inevitable that we must reject a system 
 which leads us to such a result? 
 
 Before deciding on such a course, however, it might be wise 
 to see if we can really escape from the difficulty in such a way. 
 If the same problem, or one of like nature, proves equally in- 
 soluble in any possible system, we may be forced to admit the 
 existence of an incompleteness in our philosophy, but we shall 
 no longer have any reason to reject one system in favour of 
 another. Now, besides the theory which has brought us into 
 this trouble — the theory that reality is fundamentally rational 
 — there are, it would seem, three other possibilities. Reality may 
 be fundamentally irrational. (I shall use "irrational" here to 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 181 
 
 signify anything whose nature and operation are not merely 
 devoid of reason, but opposed to it, so that its influence is always 
 in the opposite direction to that exercised by reason.) Or reality 
 may be the product of two independent principles of rationality 
 and irrationality. Or it may be the work of some principle to 
 which rationality and irrationality are equally indifferent — some 
 blind fate, or mechanical chance. 
 
 These possibilities may be taken as exhaustive. It is true 
 that, on Hegelian principles, a fifth alternative has to be added, 
 when we are considering the different combinations in which 
 two predicates may be asserted or denied of a subject. We may 
 say that it is also possible that the two predicates should be 
 combined in a higher unity. This would leave it scarcely correct 
 to say, without quahfication, that either is asserted or either 
 denied of the sub j ect. But synthesis is itself a process of reasoning, 
 and unites its two terms by a category in which we recognise 
 the nature of each extreme as a subordinate moment, which is 
 harmonised with the other. The harmony involves that, wherever 
 a synthesis is possible, reason is supreme. And so, if the truth 
 were to be found in a synthesis of the rational and irrational, 
 that synthesis would itself be rational — resolving, as it would, 
 the whole universe into a unity expressible by thought. Thus 
 we should have come round again to Hegel's position that the 
 world is fundamentally rational. 
 
 161. We need not spend much time over the supposition that 
 the world is fundamentally irrational — not only regardless of 
 reason, but contrary to reason. To begin with, such a hypothesis 
 refutes itself. The completely irrational cannot be real, for even 
 to say that a thing is real implies its determination by at least 
 one predicate, and therefore its comparative rationality. And 
 our hypothesis would meet with a difficulty precisely analogous 
 to that which conflicts with Hegel's theory. In that case the 
 stumbling-block lay in the existence of some irrationality, here 
 it lies in the existence of some rationality. We can no more deny 
 that there are signs of rationality in the universe, than we can 
 deny that there are signs of irrationality. Yet it is at least as 
 impossible to conceive how the fundamentally irrational should 
 manifest itseK as rationality, as it is to conceive the converse 
 
182 THE RELATION OP THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 process. We shall gain nothing, then, by deserting Hegel for such 
 a theory as this. 
 
 162. It might seem as if a dualistic theory would be well 
 adapted to the chequered condition of the actual world. But 
 as soon as we try to construct such a theory, difficulties arise. 
 The two principles, of rationality and irrationality, to which 
 the universe is referred, will have to be absolutely separate and 
 independent. For if there were any common unity to which 
 they should be referred, it would be that unity, and not its two 
 manifestations, which would be the ultimate explanation of the 
 universe, and the theory, having become monistic, resolves itself 
 into one of the others, according to the attitude of this single 
 principle towards reason, whether favourable, hostile, or in- 
 different. 
 
 We must then refer the universe to two independent and 
 opposed forces. Nor will it make any important difference if 
 we make the second force to be, not irrationality, but some blind 
 force not in itself hostile to reason. For, in order to account for 
 the thwarted rationahty which meets us so often in the universe, 
 we shall have to suppose that the result of the force is, as a fact, 
 opposed to reason, even if opposition to reason is not its essential 
 nature. 
 
 In the first place can there be really two independent powers 
 in the universe? Surely there cannot. As Mr Bradley points out : 
 "Plurality must contradict independence. If the beings are not 
 in relation, they cannot be many; but if they are in relation, 
 they cease forthwith to be absolute. For, on the one hand, 
 plurality has no meaning, unless the units are somehow taken 
 together. If you abolish and remove all relations, there seems 
 no sense left in which you can speak of pluraUty. But, on the 
 other hand, relations destroy the real's self-dependence. For it 
 is impossible to treat relations as adjectives, falling simply inside 
 the many beings. And it is impossible to take them as falhng 
 outside somewhere in a sort of unreal void, which makes no 
 difference to anything. Hence... the essence of the related terms 
 is carried beyond their proper selves by means of their relations. 
 And, again, the relations themselves must belong to a larger 
 reality. To stand in a relation and not to be relative, to support 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 183 
 
 it and yet not to be infected and undermined by it, seem out 
 of the question. Diversity in the real cannot be the plurality 
 of independent beings. And the oneness of the Absolute must 
 hence be more than a mere diffused adjective. It possesses unity, 
 as a whole, and is a single system^." 
 
 The argument has additional strength in this case. For the 
 two forces which we are asked to take as absolutely opposed 
 are, by the hypothesis which assumed them, indissolubly united. 
 Both forces are regarded as all-pervading. Neither can exist by 
 itself anywhere. Every fact in the universe is due to the inter- 
 action of the two. And, further, they can only be described and 
 defined in relation to one another. If the dualism is between the 
 rational and the irrational as such, it is obvious that the latter, 
 at any rate, has only meaning in relation to its opposite. And 
 if we assume that the second principle is not directly opposed 
 to rationality, but simply indifferent to it, we shall get no further 
 in our task of explaining the imperfect rationality which appears 
 in our data, unless we go on to assume that its action is contrary 
 to that of a rational principle. Thus a reference to reason would 
 be necessary, if not to define our second principle, at any rate 
 to allow us to understand how we could make it available for 
 our purpose. 
 
 We cannot, besides, describe anything as irrational, or as in- 
 different to reason, without ascribing to it certain predicates — 
 Being, Substance, Limitation, for example. Nor can we refer to 
 a principle as an explanation of the universe without attributing 
 to it Causality. These determinations may be transcended by 
 higher ones, but they must be there, at least as moments. Yet 
 anything to which all these predicates can be ascribed cannot 
 be said to be entirely hostile or indifferent to reason, for it has 
 some determinations common to it and to reason, and must be, 
 therefore, in more or less harmony with the latter. But if this 
 is so, our complete dualism has been surrendered. 
 
 The two principles then can scarcely be taken as absolutely 
 
 independent. But if they cannot our dualism fails to help us, 
 
 and indeed vanishes. We were tempted to resort to it because 
 
 the two elements in experience — the rationality and the want 
 
 ^ Appearance and Reality, Chap. 13, p. 141. 
 
184 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 of rationality — were so heterogeneous as to defy reduction to a 
 single principle. And if we cannot keep our two principles distinct, 
 but are compelled to regard them as joined in a higher unity, 
 we might as well return expHcitly to monism. 
 
 163. But, even if we could keep the two principles indepen- 
 dent, it seems doubtful if we should be able to reach, by means 
 of this theory, a solution of our difficulty. The forces working 
 for and against the rationaUty of the universe must either be 
 in equilibrium or not. If they are not in equilibrium, then one 
 must be gaining on the other. The universe is thus fundamentally 
 a process. In this case we shall gain nothing by adopting dualism. 
 For the difficulties attendant on conceiving the world as a process 
 were just the reason which compelled us to adopt the theory 
 that the universe was at present perfectly rational, and so pro- 
 duced the further difficulties which are now driving us to look 
 round for a substitute for idealism. If we could have taken 
 development in time as ultimately real, we should have found 
 no hindrance in our way when we endeavoured to conceive the 
 universe as the product of a single rational principle. But we 
 could not do so then, and we shall find it as impossible now. The 
 process must be finite in length, since we can attach no meaning 
 to an actual infinite process. And, since it is still continuing, we 
 shall have to suppose that the two principles came into operation 
 at a given moment, and not before. And since these principles 
 are, on the hypothesis, ultimate, there can be nothing to deter- 
 mine them to begin to act at that point, rather than any other. 
 In this way we shall be reduced, as before, to suppose an event 
 to happen in time without antecedents and without cause — a 
 solution which cannot be accepted as satisfactory. 
 
 164. Shall we succeed any better on the supposition that the 
 forces which work for and against rationaUty are exactly balanced? 
 In the first place we should have to admit that the odds against 
 this occurring were infinity to one. For the two forces are, by 
 the hypothesis, absolutely independent of one another. And, 
 therefore, we cannot suppose any common influence acting on 
 both of them, which should tend to make their forces equal, nor 
 any relationship between them, which should bring about this 
 result. The equilibrium could only be the result of mere chance, 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 185 
 
 and the probability of this producing infinitely exact equilibrium 
 would be infinitely small. And the absence of any a friori reason 
 for believing in such an equilibrium could not, of course, be 
 supplied by empirical observation. For the equilibrium would 
 have to extend over the whole universe, and we cannot carry 
 our observations so far. 
 
 Nor can we support the theory by the consideration that it, 
 and no other, will explain the undoubted co-existence of the 
 rational and irrational in our present world. For it fails to 
 account for the facts. It fails to explain the existence of change 
 — at any rate of that change which leaves anything more or less 
 rational, more or less perfect, than it was before. It is a fact 
 which cannot be denied that sometimes that which was good 
 becomes evil, and sometimes that which was evil becomes good. 
 Now, if the two principles are exactly balanced, how could such 
 a change take place? Of course we cannot prove that the balance 
 between the two forces does not remain the same, if we consider 
 the whole universe. Every movement in the one direction, in 
 one part of the whole, may be balanced by a corresponding move 
 in the other direction somewhere else. As we do not know the 
 entire universe in detail it is impossible for us to refute this 
 supposition. But even this supposition will not remove the 
 diflficulty. We have two principles whose relations to one another 
 are constant. Yet the facts around us, which are manifestations 
 of these two principles, and of these two principles only, manifest 
 them in proportions which constantly change. How is this change 
 to be accounted for? If we are to take time and change as 
 ultimate facts, such a contradiction seems insuperable. On the 
 other hand, to deny the ultimate validity of time and change, 
 commits us to the series of arguments, the failure of which first 
 led us to doubt Hegel's position. If time could be viewed as 
 a manifestation of the timeless, we need not have abandoned 
 monism, for the difficulty of imperfection could then have been 
 solved. If, however, time cannot be viewed in this way, the 
 contradiction between the unchanging relation of the principles 
 and the constant change of their effects appears hopeless. 
 
 165. There remains the theory that the world is exclusively 
 the product of a principle which regards neither rationality nor 
 
186 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch, 
 
 irrationality, but is directed to some aim outside them, or to na 
 aim at all. Such a theory might account, no doubt, for the fact 
 that the world is not a complete and perfect manifestation either 
 of rationality or irrationality. But it is hardly exaggerated ta 
 say that this is the only fact about the world which it would 
 account for. The idea of such a principle is contradictory. We 
 can have no conception of its operation, of its nature, or even 
 of its existence, without bringing it under some predicates of 
 the reason. And if this is valid, the principle is, to some extent 
 at least, rational. 
 
 166. So far indeed, the rationahty would be but slight. And 
 it might be suggested that the solution of the difl&culty would 
 be found in the idea that reality was, if we might so express it, 
 moderately rational. Up to this point we have supposed that 
 our only choice was between a principle manifesting the com- 
 plete and perfect rationahty, which is embodied in Hegel's 
 Absolute Idea, and a principle entirely hostile or indifferent to 
 reason. But what if the ultimate principle of the universe was 
 one of which, for example, the categories of Being and Essence 
 were valid, while those of the Notion remained unjustified ideals? 
 This would account, it might be said, at once for the fact that 
 the universe was sufficiently in accord viath our reason for us 
 to perceive it and attempt to comprehend it, and also for the 
 fact that we fail to comprehend it completely. It would explain 
 the judgment that the world, as we see it, might be better and 
 might also be worse, which common sense pronounces, and which 
 philosophy, whether it accepts it or not, is bound to explain 
 somehow. 
 
 The supporters of such a theory, however, would have a 
 difficult task before them. They might claim to reject Hegel's 
 general theory of the universe on the ground that, on this ques- 
 tion of imperfection, it was hopelessly in conflict with the facts. 
 But when they, in their turn, set up a positive system, and 
 asserted the earher categories to be vahd of reality, while the 
 later ones were delusions, they would have to meet in detail 
 Hegel's arguments that the earlier categories, unless synthesised 
 by the later ones, plunge us in contradictions. The dialectic, 
 being now merely negative and critical of another system, could 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 187 
 
 not be disposed of on the ground that its own system broke down 
 as a whole. Its arguments against the independent validity of 
 the earlier categories would have to be met directly. What the 
 issue of the conflict would be cannot be considered here, as 
 considerations of space have prevented me from including in 
 this book any discussion of the steps of the dialectic in detail. 
 It may be remarked in passing, however, that several of the 
 commentators, who unhesitatingly reject the system as a whole, 
 admit the cogency of the argument from step to step in the Logic 
 — which is all that is wanted here. 
 
 This, at any rate, is certain, that the possibility of explaining 
 the existence of imperfection by such a theory as we have been 
 considering, can give us no grounds for rejecting Hegel's system 
 which we did not possess before. For if the deduction of the 
 categories is defective, Hegelianism must be rejected as unproved, 
 independently of its success or failure in interpreting the facts. 
 And if the deduction of the categories is correct, then the theory 
 of the partial rationality of reality must be given up. For, in 
 that case, to assert the validity of the lower categories without 
 the higher would be to assert a contradiction, and to do this is 
 to destroy all possibihty of coherent thought. 
 
 167. It would seem then that any other system offers as many 
 obstacles to a satisfactory explanation of our difficulty as were 
 presented by Hegel's theory. Is the inquirer then bound to take 
 refuge in complete scepticism, and reject all systems of philosophy, 
 since none can avoid inconsistencies or absurdities on this point? 
 This might perhaps be the proper course to pursue, if it were 
 possible. But it is not possible. For every word and every action 
 implies some theory of metaphysics. Every assertion or denial 
 of fact — including the denial that anything is certain — implies 
 that something is certain ; and a doubt, also, implies our certainty 
 that we doubt. Now to admit this, and yet to reject all ultimate 
 explanations of the universe, is a contradiction at least as serious 
 as any of those into which we were led by our attempt to explain 
 away imperfection in obedience to the demands of Hegel's system. 
 
 We find then as many, and as grave, difficulties in our way 
 when we take up any other system, or when we attempt to take 
 up no system at all, as met us when we considered Hegel's theory, 
 
188 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 and our position towards the latter must be to some degree 
 modified. We can no longer reject it, because it appears to lead 
 to an absurdity, if every possible form in which it can be rejected 
 involves a similar absurdity. At the same time we cannot possibly 
 acquiesce in an unreconciled contradiction. Is there any other 
 course open to us? 
 
 168. We must remark, in the first place, that the position 
 in which the system finds itself, though difficult enough, is not 
 a reductio ad absurdum. When an argument ends in such a 
 reduction, there can never be any hesitation or doubt about 
 rejecting the hypothesis with which it started. It is desired to 
 know if a certain proposition is true. The assumption is made 
 that the proposition is true, and it is found that the assumption 
 leads to a contradiction. Thus there is no conflict of arguments. 
 The hypothesis was made, not because it had been proved true, 
 but to see what results would follow. Hence there is nothing to 
 contradict the inference that the hypothesis must be false, which 
 we draw from the absurdity of its consequences. On the one side 
 is only a supposition, on the other ascertained facts. 
 
 This, however, is not the case here. The conclusion, that the 
 universe is timelessly perfect, which appears to be in conflict 
 with certain facts, is not a mere hypothesis, but asserts itself 
 to be a correct deduction from other facts as certain as those 
 which oppose it. Hence there is no reason why one should yield 
 to the other. The inference that the universe is completely 
 rational, and the inference that it is not, are both deduced by 
 reasoning from the facts of experience. Unless we find a flaw 
 in one or the other of the chains of deduction, we have no more 
 right to say that Hegel's dialectic is wrong because the world 
 is imperfect, than to deny that the world is imperfect, because 
 Hegel's dialectic proves that it cannot be so. 
 
 It might appear at first sight as if the imperfection of the world 
 was an immediate certainty. But in reality only the data of sense, 
 upon which, in the last resort, all propositions must depend for 
 their connection with reality, are here immediate. All judgments 
 require mediation. And, even if the existence of imperfection 
 in experience was an immediate certainty, yet the conclusion 
 that its existence was incompatible with the perfection of the 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 189 
 
 universe as a whole, could clearly only be reached mediately, 
 by the refutation of the various arguments by means of which 
 a reconciliation has been attempted. 
 
 It is, no doubt, our first duty, when two chains of reasoning 
 appear to lead to directly opposite results, to go over them with 
 the greatest care, that we may ascertain whether the apparent 
 discrepancy is not due to some mistake of our own. It is also 
 true that the chain of arguments, by which we arrive at the 
 conclusion that the world is perfect, is both longer and less 
 generally accepted than the other chain by which we reach the 
 conclusion that there is imperfection in the world, and that this 
 prevents the world from being perfect. We may, therefore, possibly 
 be right in expecting beforehand to find a flaw in the first chain 
 of reasoning, rather than in the second. 
 
 This, however, will not entitle us to adopt the one view as 
 against the other. We may expect beforehand to find an error 
 in an argument, but if in point of fact we do not succeed in 
 finding one, we are bound to continue to accept the conclusion. 
 For we are compelled to yield our assent to each step in the 
 argument, so long as we do not see any mistake in it, and we 
 shall in this way be conducted as inevitably to the end of the 
 long chain as of the short one. 
 
 169. We may, I think, assume, for the purposes of our 
 enquiry, that no discovery of error will occur to relieve us from 
 our perplexity, since we are endeavouring to discuss here, not the 
 truth of the Hegelian dialectic, but the consequences which will 
 follow from it if it is true. And we have now to consider what 
 we must do in the presence of two equally authoritative judg- 
 ments which contradict one another. 
 
 The only course which it is possible to take appears to me 
 that described by Mr Balfour. The thinker must "accept both 
 contradictories, thinking thereby to obtain, under however un- 
 satisfactory a form, the fullest measure of truth which he is at 
 present able to grasp^."' Of course we cannot adopt the same 
 mental attitude which we should have a right to take in case 
 our conclusions harmonised with one another. W^e must never 
 lose sight of the fact that the two results do not harmonise, and 
 
 ^ Defence of Philosophic Doubt, p. 313. 
 
190 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 that there must be something wrong somewhere. But we do not 
 know where. And to take any step except this, would imply 
 that we did know where the error lay. If we rejected the one 
 conclusion in favour of the other, or if we rejected both in favour 
 of scepticism, we should thereby assert, in the first case, that 
 there was an error on the one side and not on the other, in the 
 second case that there were errors on both sides. Now, if the 
 case is as it has been stated above, we have no right to make 
 such assertions, for we have been unable to detect errors on 
 either side. All that we can do is to hold to both sides, and to 
 recognise that, till one is refuted, or both are reconciled, our 
 knowledge is in a very unsatisfactory state. 
 
 At the same time we shall have to be very careful not to let 
 our dissatisfaction with the conflict, from which we cannot escape, 
 carry us into either an exphcit avowal or a tacit acceptance of 
 any form of scepticism. For this would mean more than the 
 mere equipoise of the two lines of argument. It would mean, 
 at least, the entire rejection of the one which asserts that the 
 universe is completely rational. And, as has been said, we have 
 no right to reject either side of the contradiction, for no flaw 
 has been found in either. 
 
 170. The position in which we are left appears to be this: 
 If we cannot reject Hegel's dialectic, our system of knowledge 
 will contain an unsolved contradiction. But that contradiction 
 gives us no more reason for rejecting the Hegelian dialectic than 
 for doing anything else, since a similar contradiction appears 
 wherever we turn. We are merely left with the conviction that 
 something is fundamentally wrong in knowledge which all looks 
 equally trustworthy. Where to find the error we cannot tell. 
 Such a result is sufficiently unsatisfactory. Is it possible to find 
 a conclusion not quite so negative? 
 
 We cannot, as it seems to us at present, deny that both the 
 propositions are true, nor deny that they are contradictory. Yet 
 we know that one must be false, or else that they cannot be 
 contradictory. Is there any reason to hope that the solution lies 
 in the last alternative? This result would be less sceptical and 
 destructive than any other. It would not involve any positive 
 mistake in our previous reasonings, as far as they went, such as 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 191 
 
 would be involved if harmony was restored by the discovery that 
 one of the two conclusions was fallacious. It would only mean 
 that we had not gone on far enough. The two contradictory pro- 
 positions — that the world was fundamentally perfect, and that 
 imperfection did exist — would be harmonised and reconciled by 
 a synthesis, in the same way that the contradictions within the 
 dialectic itself are overcome. The two sides of the opposition 
 would not so much be both false as both true. They would be 
 taken up into a higher sphere where the truth of both is preserved. 
 
 Moreover, the solution in this case would be exactly what 
 might be expected if the Hegelian dialectic were true. For, as 
 has been said, the dialectic always advances by combining on 
 a higher plane two things which were contradictory on a lower 
 one. And so, if, in some way now inconceivable to us, the eternal 
 realisation of the Absolute Idea were so synthesised with the 
 -existence of imperfection as to be reconciled with it, we should 
 harmonise the two sides by a principle already exemplified in 
 one of them. 
 
 171. It must be noticed also that the contradiction before us 
 satisfies at any rate one of the conditions which are necessary 
 if a synthesis is to be effected. It is a case of contrary and not 
 merely of contradictory opposition. The opposition would be 
 <jontradictory if the one side merely denied the validity of the 
 data, or the correctness of the inferences, of the other. For it 
 would not then assert a different and incompatible conclusion, 
 but simply deny the right of the other side to come to its own 
 •conclusion at all. But it is a contrary opposition, because neither 
 side denies that the other is, in itself, coherent and valid, but 
 sets up against it another line of argument, also coherent and 
 valid, which leads to an opposite and incompatible conclusion. 
 We have not reasons for and against a particular position, but 
 reasons for two positions which deny one another. 
 
 If the opposition had been contradictory, there could have 
 been no hope of a synthesis. We should have ended with two 
 propositions, one of which was a mere denial of the other — the 
 one, that the universe is eternally rational, the other, that this 
 is not the case. And between two merely contradictory pro- 
 positions, as Trendelenburg points out, there can be no possible 
 
192 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 synthesis^. One only affirms, and the other only denies. And, 
 between simple affirmation and simple negation, we can find 
 nothing which will succeed in reconciling them. For their whole 
 meaning is summed up in their denial of one another, and if, 
 with their reconciliation, the reciprocal denial vanished, the whole 
 meaning would vanish also, leaving nothing but a blank. Instead 
 of having equally strong grounds to believe two different things, 
 we should have no grounds to believe either. Any real opposition 
 may conceivably be synthesised. But it is as impossible to get 
 a harmony out of an absolute blank, as it is to get anything else. 
 
 Here, however, when we have two positive conclusions, which 
 appear indeed to be incompatible, but have more in them than 
 simple incompatibility, it is not impossible that a higher notion 
 could be found, by which each should be recognised as true, and 
 by which it should be seen that they were really not mutually 
 exclusive. 
 
 The thesis and antithesis in Hegel's logic always stand to one 
 another in a relation of contrary opposition. In the higher stages, 
 no doubt, the antithesis is more than a mere opposite of the 
 thesis, and already contains an element of synthesis. But the 
 element of opposition, which is always there, is always an opposi- 
 tion of contraries. Hence it does not seem impossible that this 
 further case of contrary opposition should be dealt with on Hegel's 
 principle. Incompatible as the two terms seem at present, they 
 can hardly seem more hopelessly opposed than many pairs of 
 contraries in the dialectic seem, before their syntheses are found. 
 
 172. It is possible, also, to see some reasons why such a 
 solution, if possible at all, should not be possible yet, and why 
 it would be delayed till the last abstraction should be removed, 
 as the dialectic process rebuilds concrete realities. Our aim is 
 to reconcile the fact that the Absolute Idea exists eternally in 
 its full perfection, with the fact that it manifests itself as some- 
 thing incomplete and imperfect. Now the Absolute Idea only 
 becomes known to us through a process and consequently as 
 something incomplete and imperfect. We have to grasp its 
 moments successively, and to be led on from the lower to the 
 higher. And, in like manner, all our knowledge of its manifesta- 
 ^ Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. i. p. 56. 
 
v] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 193 
 
 tions must come to us in the form of a process, since it 
 must come gradually. We cannot expect to see how all process 
 should only be an element in a timeless reality, so long as we 
 can only think of the timeless reality by means of a process. 
 But, sub specie aeternitatis, it might be that the difficulty would 
 vanish, 
 
 I am not, of course, trying to argue that there is such a recon- 
 ciliation of these two extremes, or that there is the slightest 
 positive evidence that a reconciliation can exist. As we have seen 
 above, the eternal realisation of the Absolute Idea, and the 
 existence of change and evil, are, for us as we are, absolutely 
 incompatible, nor can we even imagine a way in which they 
 should cease to be so. If we could imagine such a way we should 
 have solved the problem, for, as it would be the only chance of 
 rescuing our knowledge from hopeless confusion, we should be 
 justified in taking it. 
 
 All I wish to suggest is that it is conceivable that there should 
 be such a synthesis, although we cannot at present conceive what 
 it could be like, and that, although there is no positive evidence 
 for it, there is no evidence against it. And as either the incom- 
 patibiUty of the two propositions, or the evidence for one of them, 
 must be a mistake, we may have at any rate a hope that some 
 solution may lie in this direction. 
 
 173. If indeed we were absolutely certain that neither the 
 arguments for the eternal perfection of the Absolute Idea, nor 
 the arguments for the existence of process and change, were 
 erroneous, we should be able to go beyond this negative position, 
 and assert positively the existence of the synthesis, although we 
 should be as unable as before to comprehend of what nature 
 it could be. We could then avail ourselves of Mr Bradley's maxim, 
 "what may be and must be, certainly is." That the synthesis 
 must exist would, on the hypothesis we are considering, be 
 beyond doubt. For if both the lines of argument which lead 
 respectively to the eternal reality of the Absolute Idea, and to 
 the existence of change, could be known, not merely to be at 
 present unrefuted, but to be true, then they must somehow be 
 compatible. That all truth is harmonious is the postulate of 
 reasoning, the denial of which would abolish all tests of truth 
 M. H. 13 
 
194 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 and falsehood, and so make all judgment unmeaning. And since 
 the two propositions are, as we have seen throughout this chapter, 
 incompatible as they stand in their immediacy, the only way 
 in which they can possibly be made compatible is by a synthesis 
 which transcends them and so unites them. 
 
 Can we then say of such a synthesis that it may be? Of course 
 it is only possible to do so negatively. A positive assertion that 
 there was no reason whatever why a thing should not exist could 
 only be obtained by a complete knowledge of it, and, if we had 
 a complete knowledge of it, it would not be necessary to resort 
 to indirect proof to discover whether it existed or not. But we 
 have, it would seem, a right to say that no reason appears why 
 it should not exist. If the Hegelian dialectic is true (and, except 
 on this hypothesis, our difficulty would not have arisen), we 
 know that predicates which seem to be contrary can be united 
 and harmonised by a synthesis. And the fact that such a syn- 
 thesis is not conceivable by us need not make us consider it 
 impossible. Till such a synthesis is found, it must always appear 
 inconceivable, and that it has not yet been found implies nothing 
 more than that the world, considered as a process, has not yet 
 worked out its full meaning. 
 
 174. But we must admit that the actual result is rather 
 damaging to the prospects of Hegelianism. We may, as I have 
 tried to show, be sure, that, if Hegel's dialectic is true, then such 
 a synthesis must be possible, because it is the only way of har- 
 monising all the facts. At the same time, the fact that the 
 dialectic cannot be true, unless some synthesis which we do not 
 know, and whose nature we cannot even conceive, relieves it 
 from an obstacle which would otherwise be fatal, certainly lessens 
 the chance that it is true, even if no error in it has yet been dis- 
 covered. For our only right to accept such an extreme hypothesis 
 lies in the impossibility of finding any other way out of the 
 dilemma. And the more violent the consequences to which an 
 argument leads us, the greater is the antecedent probability that 
 some flaw has been left undetected. 
 
 Not only does such a theory lose the strength which comes 
 from the successful solution of all problems presented to it, but 
 it is compelled to rely, with regard to this particular proposition. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 195 
 
 on a possibility which we cannot at present fully grasp, 
 even in imagination, and the realisation of which would 
 perhaps involve the transcending of all discursive thought. 
 Under these circumstances it is clear that our confidence in 
 Hegel's system must be considerably less than that which was 
 possessed by its author, who had not realised the tentative and 
 incomplete condition to which this difficulty inevitably reduced 
 his position. 
 
 The result of these considerations, however, is perhaps on 
 the whole more positive than negative. They can scarcely urge 
 us to more careful scrutiny of all the details of the dialectic than 
 would be required in any case by the complexity of the subjects 
 with which it deals. And, on the other hand, they do supply us, 
 as it seems to me, with a ground for believing that neither time 
 nor imperfection forms an insuperable objection to the dialectic. 
 If the dialectic is not valid in itself, we shall any way have no 
 right to believe it. And if it is valid in itself, we shall not only 
 be entitled, but we shall be bound, to believe that one more 
 synthesis remains, as yet unknown to us, which shall overcome 
 the last and most persistent of the contradictions inherent in 
 appearance. 
 
 175. Note. — After this chapter, in a slightly different form, 
 had appeared in Mind, it was criticised by Mr F. C. S. Schiller, 
 in an article entitled "The Metaphysics of the Time Process." 
 {Mind, N. S. Vol. iv. No. 13.) I have endeavoured to consider 
 his acute and courteous objections to my view with that care 
 which they merit, but I have not succeeded in finding in them 
 any reason for changing the position indicated in the preceding 
 sections. I have already discussed one of Mr Schiller's objections^, 
 and there are some others on which I will now venture to make 
 a few remarks. 
 
 Mr Schiller complains that I overlook "the curious incon- 
 sistency of denying the metaphysical value of Time, and yet 
 expecting from the Future the discovery of the ultimate syn- 
 thesis on which one's whole metaphysics depends^." It was not, 
 of course, from the advance of time as such, but from the more 
 complete manifestation through time of the timeless reality that 
 
 1 Chap. in. Section 96. ^ Qp^ cit. p. 37. 
 
 13—2 
 
196 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 I ventured to expect a solution. But it is, no doubt, true that 
 I did express a hope of the discovery of a synthesis which has 
 not yet been discovered, so that its discovery must be an event 
 in time. I fail, however, to see the inconsistency. Time is 
 certainly, on the theory which I have put forward, only an 
 appearance and an illusion. But then, on the same theory, the 
 inconsistency which requires a synthesis is also an illusion. And 
 so is the necessity of discovering a synthesis for two aspects of 
 reality which are really eternally moments in a harmonious 
 whole. 
 
 Sub sfecie aeternitatis, the temporal process is not, as such, 
 real, and can produce nothing new. But then, sub specie aeterni- 
 tatis, if there is an ultimate synthesis, it does not require to be 
 produced, for it exists eternally. Nor does the contradiction 
 require to be removed, for, if there is a synthesis, the contra- 
 diction never, sub specie aeternitatis, existed at all. Sub specie 
 temporis, on the other hand, the contradiction has to be removed, 
 and the synthesis discovered. But, sub specie teynporis, the time 
 process exists, and can produce something new. 
 
 The inconsistency of which Mr Schiller accuses me comes 
 only from combining the assertions that a change is required, 
 and that no change is possible, as if they were made from 
 the same standpoint. But, on the theory in question, the j&rst 
 is only true when we look at things from the standpoint of 
 time, and the second when we look at them from the stand- 
 point of the timeless idea. That the possible solution is incom- 
 prehensible, I have fully admitted. But I cannot see that it is 
 inconsistent. 
 
 176. Mr Schiller further says, if I understand him rightly, 
 that it is obviously impossible that Hegel could have accounted 
 for time, since he started with an abstraction which did not 
 include it. Without altogether adopting Mr Schiller's explana- 
 tions of the motives of idealist philosophers we may agree with 
 him when he says that their conceptions "were necessarily 
 abstract, and among the things they abstracted from ivas the time- 
 aspect of Reality'^" He then continues, "Once abstracted from, 
 the reference to Time, could not, of course, be recovered.'' And, 
 
 ^ Op. cit. p. 38. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 197 
 
 a little later on, " You must pay the price for a formula that will 
 enable you to make assertions that hold good far beyond the 
 hmits of your experience. And part of the price is that you will 
 in the end be unable to give a rational explanation of those very 
 characteristics, which had been dismissed at the outset as irre- 
 levant to a rational explanation." 
 
 I have admitted that Hegel has failed, not indeed to give a 
 deduction of time, but to give one which would be consistent 
 ^vith the rest of his system. But this is a result which, as it 
 seems to me, can only be arrived at by examining in detail the 
 deduction he does give, and cannot be settled beforehand by 
 the consideration that the abstraction he starts from excludes 
 time. Such an objection would destroy the whole dialectic. For 
 Hegel starts with pure Being, precisely because it is the most 
 complete abstraction possible, with the minimum of meaning 
 that any term can have. And if nothing which was abstracted 
 from could ever be restored, the dialectic process, which consists 
 of nothing else than the performance of this operation, would 
 be completely invalid. 
 
 I have endeavoured to show in the earlier chapters that there 
 is nothing unjustified in such an advance from abstract to con- 
 crete. Of course, if we make an abstraction, as we do in geometry, 
 with the express intention of adhering to it uncritically through- 
 out our treatment of the subject, and ignoring any inaccuracy 
 as irrelevant for our present purposes, — then, no doubt, our final 
 conclusions must have the same abstractness as our original 
 premises. But this is very unlike the position of the dialectic. 
 Here we begin with the most complete abstraction we can find, 
 for the express purpose of seeing how far we can, by criticism 
 of it, be forced to consider it inadequate, and so to substitute 
 for it more concrete notions which remedy its incompleteness. 
 Eight or wrong, this can scarcely be disposed of as obviously 
 impossible. 
 
 Nor does it seem quite correct to say that Hegel's philosophy 
 was "constructed to give an account of the world irrespective 
 of Time and Change^," if, as appears to be the case, "constructed 
 to give" implies a purpose. Hegel's purpose was not to give 
 
 1 Op. cit. p. 38. 
 
198 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. 
 
 any particular account of the universe, but to give one which 
 should be self-consistent, and he declared time and change to 
 be only appearances, because he found it impossible to give a 
 consistent account of the universe if he treated time and 
 change as ultimate realities. He may have been wrong, but 
 his decision was the result of argument, and not a preconceived 
 purpose. 
 
 177. Mr Schiller suggests that the whole device of using 
 abstract laws and generalisations at all in knowledge is one which 
 is justified by its success, and which may be discarded, in whole 
 or in part, for another, if another should promise better. "Why 
 should we want to calculate the facts by such universal formulas ? 
 The answer to this question brings us to the roots of the matter. 
 We make the fundamental assumption of science, that there are 
 universal and eternal laws, i.e. that the individuality of things 
 together with their spatial and temporal context may be neglected, 
 not because we are convinced of its theoretic validity, but because 
 we are constrained by its practical convenience. We want to be 
 able to make predictions about the future behaviour of things for the 
 purpose of shaping our own conduct accordingly. Hence attempts 
 to forecast the future have been the source of half the super- 
 stitions of mankind. But no method of divination ever invented 
 could compete in ingenuity and gorgeous simplicity with the 
 assumption of universal laws which hold good without reference 
 to time; and so in the long run it alone could meet the want or 
 practical necessity in question. 
 
 "In other words that assumption is a methodological device 
 and ultimately reposes on the practical necessity of discovering 
 formulas for calculating events in the rough, without awaiting 
 or observing their occurrence. To assert this methodological 
 character of eternal truths is not, of course, to deny their validity, 
 — for it is evident that unless the nature of the world had lent 
 itself to a very considerable extent to such interpretation, the 
 assumption of 'eternal' laws would have served our purposes 
 as little as those of astrology, chiromancy, necromancy, and 
 catoptromancy. What however must be asserted is that this 
 assumption is not an ultimate term in the explanation of the 
 world. 
 
V] THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME 199 
 
 "That does not, of course, matter to Science, which is not 
 concerned with such ultimate explanation, and for which the 
 assumption is at all events ultimate enough. But it does matter 
 to philosophy that the idtimate theoretic assumption should 
 have a methodological character^." 
 
 178. But, I reply, our habit of abstracting and generahsing 
 (and all universal laws are nothing more than this) is not a tool 
 that we can take up or lay down at pleasure, as a carpenter takes 
 up or lays down a particular chisel, which he finds suited or 
 unsuited to the work immediately before him. It is rather the 
 essential condition of all thought — perhaps it would be better 
 to say an essential moment in all thought. All thought consists 
 in processes which may be described as abstractions and generali- 
 sations. It is true, of course, that we could have no thought 
 unless the complex and the particular were given to us. But it 
 is no less true that everything which thought does with what 
 is given to it involves abstraction and generalisation. 
 
 If we had merely unrelated particulars before us we should 
 not be conscious. And even if we were conscious, unrelated par- 
 ticulars could certainly give us no knowledge. We can have no 
 knowledge without, at the lowest, comparison. And to compare 
 — to perceive a similar element in things otherwise dissimilar, 
 or the reverse — is to abstract and to generalise. Again to find 
 any relation whatever between two particulars is to abstract and 
 to generalise. If we say, for example, that a blow causes a bruise, 
 this is to separate and abstract one quality from the large number 
 which are connoted by the word blow, and it is also to generalise, 
 since it is to assert that a blow stands in the same relation to a 
 bruise, as, let us say, friction to heat. 
 
 Without abstraction and generahsation, then, we can have 
 no knowledge, and so they are not a methodological device but 
 a necessity of our thought. It is, indeed, not certain beforehand 
 that the laws which are the result of generalisation and abstrac- 
 tion will be, as Mr Schiller says, "eternal," that is, will disregard 
 time. But if the result of the criticism of reality does lead us 
 to laws which do not accept time as an ultimate reality, and 
 if these laws do, as I have admitted they do, plunge us into 
 
 ^ Op. cit. p. 42. 
 
 ^ 
 
200 THE RELATION OF THE DIALECTIC TO TIME [ch. v 
 
 considerable difficulties, still we cannot, as Mr Schiller seems to 
 wish, reject the process of generalisation and abstraction if, or 
 in as far as, it does not turn out well. For it is our only mode 
 of thought, and the very act of thought which rejected it would 
 embody it, and be dependent on it. 
 
 There remain other points of high interest in Mr Schiller's 
 paper — his conception of metaphysics as ultimately ethical, and 
 his view of what may be hoped for from time, regarded as real 
 and not as merely appearance. But he is here constructive and 
 no longer critical, and it would be beyond the purpose of this 
 note to attempt to follow him. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 179. From a practical point of view the chief interest in Hegel's 
 system must centre in the last stages of the Philosophy of Spirit. 
 Even if we hold that the pure thought of the Logic is the logical 
 frius of the whole dialectic, and that all Nature and Spirit stand 
 in a purely dependent relation, still our most vital interest must 
 be in that part of the system which touches and interprets the 
 concrete life of Spirit which we ourselves share. And this interest 
 will be yet stronger in those who hold the view, which I have 
 endeavoured to expound in previous chapters, that the logical 
 'prius of the system is not pure thought but Spirit. For then, in 
 the highest forms of Spirit we shall see reaUty in its truest and 
 deepest meaning, from which all other aspects of reality — whether 
 in Logic, in Nature, or in the lower forms of Spirit— are but 
 abstractions, and to which they must return as the only escape 
 from the contradiction and inadequacy which is manifested in 
 them. Upon this view the highest form, in which Spirit manifests 
 itself, will be the ultimate meaning of all things. 
 
 Many students must have experienced some disappointment 
 when, turning to the end of the Philosophy of Spirit, they found 
 that its final stage was simply Philosophy. It is true that any 
 thinker, who has the least sympathy with Hegel, must assign 
 to philosophy a sufliciently important place in the nature of 
 things. Hegel taught that the secrets of the universe opened 
 themselves to us, but only on condition of deep and systematic 
 thought, and the importance of philosophy was undiminished 
 either by scepticism or by appeals to the healthy instincts of 
 the plain man. But there is some difference between taking 
 philosophy as the supreme and completely adequate means, and 
 admitting it to be the supreme end. There is some difference 
 between holding that philosophy is the knowledge of the highest 
 form of reality, and holding that it is itself the highest form of 
 reality. 
 
202 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 It seems to me that Hegel has been untrue to the tendencies 
 of his own system in seeking the ultimate reaUty of Spirit in 
 philosophy alone, and that, on his own premises, he ought to 
 have looked for a more comprehensive explanation. What that 
 should have been, I shall not attempt to determine. I only wish 
 to show that it should have been something more than philosophy. 
 
 180. Hegel does not give any very detailed account of philo- 
 sophy, considered as the highest expression of reality. Most of 
 the space devoted, in the Philosophy of Spirit, to Philosophy 
 is occupied in defending it against the charge of pantheism — 
 in Hegel's use of the word. The following are the passages which 
 appear most significant for our purpose. 
 
 571. "These three syllogisms" (i.e. of religion) "constituting 
 the one syllogism of the absolute self-mediation of spirit, are 
 the revelation of that spirit whose life is set out as a cycle of 
 concrete shapes in pictorial thought. From this its separation 
 into parts, with a temporal and external sequence, the unfolding 
 of the mediation contracts itself in the result — where the spirit 
 closes in unity with itself, — not merely to the simplicity of faith 
 and devotional feeling, but even to thought. In the immanent 
 simpHcity of thought the unfolding still has its expansion, yet 
 is all the while known as an indivisible coherence of the universal, 
 simple, and eternal spirit in itself. In this form of truth, truth 
 is the object of philosophy."... 
 
 572. Philosophy " is the unity of Art and Religion. Whereas 
 the vision-method of Art, external in point of form, is but sub- 
 jective production and shivers the substantial content into many 
 separate shapes, and whereas Religion, with its separation into 
 parts, opens it out in mental picture, and mediates what is thus 
 opened out; Philosophy not merely keeps them together to make 
 a total, but even unifies them into the simple spiritual vision, 
 and then in that raises them to self-conscious thought. Such 
 consciousness is thus the intelligible unity (cognised by thought) 
 of art and religion, in which the diverse elements in the content 
 are cognised as necessary, and this necessary as free," 
 
 573. "Philosophy thus characterises itself as a cognition of 
 the necessity in the content of the absolute picture-idea, as also 
 of the necessity in the two forms — on the one hand, immediate 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 203 
 
 vision and its poetry, and the objective and external revelation 
 presupposed by representation, — on the other hand, first the 
 subjective retreat inwards, then the subjective movement of 
 faith and its final identification with the presupposed object. 
 This cognition is thus the recognition of this content and its form ; 
 it is the liberation from the one-sidedness of the forms, elevation 
 of them into the absolute form, which determines itself to con- 
 tent, remains identical with it, and is in that the cognition of 
 that essential and actual necessity. This movement, which philo- 
 sophy is, finds itself already accomplished, when at the close it 
 seizes its own notion, — i.e. only looks back on its knowledge."... 
 
 574. "This notion of philosophy is the self-thinking Idea, the 
 truth aware of itself (Section 236), — the logical system, but with 
 the signification that it is universality approved and certified 
 in concrete content as in its actuality. In this way the science 
 has gone back to its beginning: its result is the logical system 
 but as a spiritual principle: out of the presupposing judgment, 
 in which the notion was only implicit, and the beginning an 
 immediate, — and thus out of the appearance which it had there 
 — it has risen into its pure principle, and thus also into its proper 
 medium," 
 
 181. The word Philosophy, in its ordinary signification, 
 denotes a purely intellectual activity. No doubt, whenever we 
 philosophise we are acting, and we are also feeling either pleasure 
 or pain. But philosophy itself is knowledge, it is neither action 
 nor feehng. And there seems nothing in Hegel's account of it 
 to induce us to change the meaning of the word in this respect. 
 It is true that he speaks of philosophy as the union of art and 
 rehgion. Both art and religion are more than mere knowledge, 
 since they both present aspects of volition and of feeling. But, 
 if we look back on his treatment of art and religion as separate 
 stages, we shall see that he confines himself almost entirely to 
 the truth which lies in them, ignoring the other elements. And 
 when, in Section 572, he points out how philosophy is the unity 
 of these two, it is merely as expressing the truth more completely 
 than they do, that he gives it this position. There is nothing said 
 of a higher or deeper ideal of good, nothing of any increased 
 harmony between our ideal and our surroundings, nothing of 
 
204 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 any greater or deeper pleasure. Philosophy is "the intelligible 
 unity (cognised by thought) of art and religion, in which the 
 diverse elements in the content are cognised as necessary, and 
 this necessary as free." 
 
 We are thus, it would seem, bound down to the view that 
 Hegel considered the supreme nature of Spirit to be expressed 
 as knowledge, and as knowledge only. There are two senses in 
 which we might take this exaltation of philosophy. We might 
 suppose it to apply to philosophy as it exists at present, not 
 covering the whole field of human knowledge, but standing side 
 by side with the sciences and with the mass of unsystematised 
 knowledge, claiming indeed a supremacy over all other sources 
 of knowledge, but by no means able to dispense with their 
 assistance. Or we might suppose that this high position was 
 reserved for philosophy, when, as might conceivably happen, it 
 shall have absorbed all knowledge into itself, so that every fact 
 shall be seen as completely conditioned, and as united to all the 
 others by the nature of the Absolute Idea. Which of these 
 meanings Hegel intended to adopt does not seem to be very 
 clear, but neither appears, on closer examination, to be accept- 
 able as a complete and satisfactory account of the deepest nature 
 of Spirit. 
 
 182. Let us consider first philosophy as we have it at present. 
 In this form it can scarcely claim to be worthy of this supreme 
 place. It may, no doubt, reasonably consider itself as the highest 
 activity of Spirit — at any rate in the department of cognition. 
 But in order to stand at the end of the development of Spirit 
 it must be more than this. It must not only be the highest 
 activity of Spirit, but one in which all the others are swallowed 
 up and transcended. It must have overcome and removed all 
 the contradictions, all the inadequacies, which belong to the 
 lower forms in which Spirit manifests itself. 
 
 Now all the knowledge which philosophy gives us is, from 
 one point of view, abstract, and so imperfect. It teaches us 
 what the fundamental nature of reality is, and what, therefore, 
 everything must be. But it does not pretend to show us how 
 everything partakes of that nature — to trace out in every detail 
 of the universe that rationality which, on general grounds, it 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 205 
 
 asserts to be in it. It could not, indeed, do this, for, in order to 
 trace the Notion in every detail, it would have first to discover 
 what every detail was. And this it cannot do. For what the 
 facts are in which the Notion manifests itself, we must learn 
 not from philosophy but from experience. 
 
 183. But, it may be said, Hegel did not accept this view. He 
 held that it was possible, from the nature of the pure Idea, to 
 deduce the nature of the facts in which it manifested itself, and 
 on this theory philosophy would cover the whole field of know- 
 ledge, and our criticism would fall to the ground. 
 
 My object here, however, is to show that Hegel's view of the 
 ultimate nature of Spirit is inconsistent with the general prin- 
 ciples established in his Logic, and not that it is inconsistent 
 with the rest of his attempts to apply the Logic. Even, there- 
 fore, if Hegel had attempted to deduce particular facts from 
 the Logic, it would be sufficient for my present purpose to 
 point out, as I have endeavoured to do above, that, on his 
 own premises, he had no right to make the attempt. But, 
 as I have also tried to show, he never does attempt to deduce 
 facts from the Logic, but only to interpret and explain them 
 by iti. 
 
 Moreover, whether we are to consider the applications of the 
 Logic as deductions or as explanations, it is perfectly clear that 
 they are limited in their scope. Hegel says, more than once, 
 that certain details are too insignificant and contingent to permit 
 us to trace their speculative meaning. Even in the cases which 
 he works out most fully, there is always a residuum left un- 
 explained. He may have pushed his desire to find speculative 
 meanings in biological details beyond the limits of prudence, 
 but he never attempted to find any significance in the precise 
 number of zoological species. He may have held that the 
 perfection of the Prussian constitution was philosophically 
 demonstrable, but he made no endeavour to explain, from the 
 nature of the Idea, the exact number of civil servants in the 
 employment of the Crown. And yet these are facts, which can 
 be learned by experience, which are links in chains of causes 
 and effects, and which, hke everything else in the universe, the 
 ^ Chap. II. Sections 55-57. 
 
206 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 dialectic declares on general grounds must rest on something, 
 which is rational because it is real. 
 
 Philosophy then must be contented with an abstract demon- 
 stration that things must be rational, without being able in all 
 cases to show how they are rational. Part of our knowledge will 
 thus remain on an empirical basis, and the sphere of philosophy 
 will be doubly limited. Not only will it be limited to knowledge, 
 but to certain departments of knowledge. An activity which 
 leaves so much of the workings of Spirit untouched cannot be 
 accepted as adequately expressing by itself the ultimate nature 
 of Spirit. Indeed, taken by itself, philosophy proclaims its own 
 inadequacy. For it must assert things to be completely rational, 
 and therefore completely explicable, which, all the same, it 
 cannot succeed in completely explaining. 
 
 184. It has been asserted that it is natural and right that 
 Hegel's system should end simply with philosophy, since it is 
 simply with philosophy that it begins. Thus Erdmann says: "It 
 is with intelligible sarcasm that Hegel was accustomed to mention 
 those who, when the exposition had reached this point, supposed 
 that now for the first time (as if in a philosophy of philosophy) 
 that which was peculiar and distinctive had been reached. Rather 
 has everything already been treated, and it only remains to 
 complete by a survey of it the circle of the system, so that its 
 presence becomes an Encyclopaedia. If, that is to say, religion 
 fallen into discord with thought (as, for that matter, the Pheno- 
 menology of Spirit had already shown) leads to speculative, free 
 thought, while logic had begun with the determination to realise 
 such thought, then the end of the Philosophy of Religion coin- 
 cides with the beginning of the Logic, and the requirement laid 
 down by Fichte that the system be a circle is fulfilled^." 
 
 This, however, scarcely disposes of the difficulty. The object 
 of philosophy is not simply to account for the existence of philo- 
 sophy. It aims at discovering the ultimate nature of all reality. 
 To start with philosophising, and to end by explaining why we 
 must philosophise, is indeed a circle, but a very limited one, 
 which leaves out of account most of our knowledge and most of 
 our action, unless we are prepared to prove independently that 
 
 ^ History of Philosophy, Section 329, 9. 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 207 
 
 all reality is synthesised in the conscious spirit, and all the reality 
 of the conscious spirit is synthesised in philosophising. Without 
 this proof philosophy would leave vast provinces of experience 
 completely outside its influence — a position which may be modest, 
 but is certainly not Hegelian. 
 
 It is true that, on the way to Philosophy as it occurs at the 
 end of the Philosophy of Spirit, Hegel goes through many other 
 branches of human activity and experience. But since the process 
 is a dialectic, the whole meaning of the process must be taken 
 as summed up in the last term. Either then we must make 
 philosophy include all knowledge— to say nothing, for the present, 
 of anything besides knowledge — or else we must admit at once 
 that Hegel is wrong in making philosophy the highest point of 
 Spirit, since at that point we have to find something which 
 adequately expresses all reality, and philosophy, in the ordinary 
 sense of the word, does not even include all cognition of reality. 
 
 185. Let us take then the second meaning of philosophy — 
 that in which we conceive it developed till all knowledge forms 
 one harmonious whole, so that no single fact remains contingent 
 and irrational. 
 
 This ideal may be conceived in two ways. Philosophy would, 
 in the first place, become equivalent to the whole of knowledge, 
 if pure thought could ever reach the goal, at which it has been 
 sometimes asserted that Hegel's dialectic was aiming, and deduce 
 all reality from its own nature, without the assistance of any 
 immediately given data. If this could ever happen, then, no 
 doubt, philosophy and knowledge would be coincident. The only 
 reality would be pure thought. The nature of that thought would 
 be given us by the dialectic, and so philosophy would be able 
 to explain completely the whole of reality. 
 
 But, as we have seen above^, such a goal is impossible and 
 contradictory. For thought is only a mediating activity, and 
 requires something to mediate. This need not, indeed, be any- 
 thing alien to it. The whole content of the reality, which thought 
 mediates, may itself be nothing but thought. But whatever the 
 nature of that reality, it must be given to thought in each case 
 from outside, as a datum. Supposing nothing but thought existed, 
 ^ Chap. II. Sections 55-57. 
 
208 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 still in the fact that it existed, that it was there, we should have 
 an immediate certainty, which could no more be deduced from 
 the nature of thought, than the reality of a hundred thalers could 
 be deduced from the idea of them. 
 
 It is thus impossible that any acquaintance with the nature 
 of thought could ever dispense us with the necessity of having 
 some immediate datum, which could not be deduced, but must 
 be accepted, and we have seen that there are reasons for believing 
 that Hegel never proposed to philosophy such an impossible and 
 suicidal end. There is, however, another sense in which it is 
 possible to suppose that philosophy may become coincident with 
 the whole of knowledge, and thereby make knowledge one single, 
 symmetrical, and perfectly rational system. And it may be said 
 that when philosophy has thus broadened itself to include all 
 knowledge, it may be taken as expressing adequately the whole 
 nature of spirit, and therefore, on Hegel's system, of all reality. 
 Let us examine more closely what would be the nature of such 
 a perfected knowledge. 
 
 186. All knowledge must have immediate data, which are not 
 deduced but given. But it does not follow that knowledge must 
 consequently be left imperfect, and with ragged edges. That 
 which indicates the defect of knowledge is not immediacy, but 
 contingency, in the Hegelian sense of the word, that is, the 
 necessity of explanation from outside. Now all data of knowledge 
 as originally given us, by the outer senses or through introspection, 
 are not only immediate but contingent. But the two qualities 
 do not necessarily go together, and we can conceive a state of 
 things, in which knowledge should rest on data — or, rather, on 
 a datum — which should be immediate, without being contingent. 
 
 Supposing that the theory of the nature of reality, which 
 Hegel lays down in his Logic, is true, then, if knowledge were 
 perfect, the abstract certainty (Gewissheit) of what must be 
 would be transformed into complete knowledge (Erkennen) of 
 what is. We should then perceive all reality under the only form 
 which, according to Hegel, can be really adequate to it — that 
 is, as a unity of spirits, existing only in their connection with 
 one another. We should see that the whole nature of each indi- 
 vidual was expressed in these relations with others. And we 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 209 
 
 should see that that nature, which was what marked him out 
 as an individual, was not to be conceived as something merely- 
 particular and exclusive, so that reality consisted of a crowd or 
 aggregate of separate individuals. On the contrary the nature 
 of each individual is to be taken as determined by his place in 
 a whole, which we must conceive on the analogy of an organism, 
 — a unity manifesting itself in multipUcity. The individual has 
 his entire nature in the manifestation of this whole, as the whole, 
 in turn, is nothing else but its manifestation in individuals. 
 Through this unity the parts will mutually determine one another, 
 so that from any one all the rest could, with sufl&cient insight, 
 be deduced, and so that no change could be made in any without 
 affecting all. This complete interdependence is only approxi- 
 mately realised in the unity which is found in a picture or a 
 living being, but in the Absolute the unity must be conceived 
 as far closer than aesthetic or organic unity, though we can only 
 imagine it by aid of the analogies which these afford us. And 
 in this complete interdependence and mutual determination 
 each individual would find his fullest self-development. For his 
 relations with others express his place in the whole, and it is 
 this place in the whole which expresses his deepest individuality. 
 
 If knowledge ever did fill out the sketch that the Hegelian 
 logic gives, it must be in some such form as this that it would 
 do so. For it is, I think, clear, from the category of the Absolute 
 Idea, that reality can only be found in selves, which have their 
 whole existence in finding themselves in harmony with other 
 selves. And this plurality of selves, again, must be conceived, 
 not as a mere aggregate, but as a unity whose intimacy and 
 strength is only inadequately represented by the idea of Organism. 
 For, if not, then the relations would be merely external and 
 secondary, as compared with the reality of the individuals 
 between whom the relations existed. And this would be incom- 
 patible with Hegel's declaration that the individuals have their 
 existence for self only in their relation to others. 
 
 187. Of course such an ideal of knowledge is indefinitely 
 remote as compared with our present condition. It would 
 require, in the first place, a knowledge of all the facts in the uni- 
 verse — from which we are now separated by no inconsiderable 
 
 M. H. 14 
 
210 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 interval. And, at the same time, it would require a great 
 increase in the depth and keenness of view which we can bring 
 to bear in knowledge, if all that part of reality which we only 
 perceive at present under the lower categories of Being and 
 Essence, is to be brought under the Absolute Idea, and, in place 
 of the inorganic, the merely animal, and the imperfectly spiritual, 
 which now presents itself to us, we are to see the universe as a 
 whole of self-conscious selves, in perfect unity with one another. 
 
 But that the ideal should be remote from our present state 
 need not surprise us. For it is the point at which the world- 
 process culminates, and whatever view we may hold as to the 
 ultimate reality of the conception of process, it is clear enough 
 that, from any point of view which admits of the conception 
 of process at all, we must have a long way still to go before 
 we reach a consummation which leaves the universe perfectly 
 rational and perfectly righteous. It would be more suspicious 
 if any ideal not greatly removed from our present state should 
 be held out to us as a complete and adequate satisfaction. It 
 is enough that this ideal is one which, if Hegel's logic be true, 
 must be attainable sub specie temporis, because, sub specie aeter- 
 nitatis, it is the only reahty. And it is an ideal which is not self- 
 contradictory, for the immediacy of the data is retained, although 
 their contingency has vanished. 
 
 The immediacy is retained, because we should have, as a given 
 fact, to which reason mounts in the process of discovery, and 
 on which it bases its demonstrations in the process of explana- 
 tion, that there are such and such selves, and that they are 
 connected in such and such a way. On the other hand, the 
 contingency has vanished. For while everything is determined, 
 nothing is determined merely from outside. The universe presents, 
 indeed, an aspect of multiplicity, but then it is not a mere 
 multiplicity. The universe is a super-organic unity^, and there- 
 fore, when one part of it is determined by another, it is deter- 
 
 ^ This expression is, I believe, new. I fear that it is very barbarous. But there 
 seems a necessity for some such phrase to denote that supreme unity, which, 
 just because it is perfect unity, is compatible with, and indeed requires, the 
 complete differentiation and individuality of its parts. To call such unity merely 
 organic is dangerous. For in an organism the unity is not complete, nor the parts 
 fully individual (cp. Hegel's treatment of the subject under the category of Life). 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 211 
 
 mined by the idea of the whole, which is also in itself, and the 
 determination is not dependent on something alien, but on the 
 essential nature of that which is determined. Hence determina- 
 tion appears as self-development, and necessity, as Hegel points 
 out at the beginning of the Doctrine of the Notion, reveals itself 
 as in reality freedom. 
 
 188. Neither this, nor any other possible system of knowledge, 
 could give us any ground of determination for the universe as 
 a whole, since there is nothing outside it, by which it could be 
 determined. This, however, would not render our knowledge 
 defective. If we reached this point the only question which 
 would remain unanswered would be: — Why is the universe as 
 a whole what it is, and not something else? And this question 
 could not be answered. But we must not infer from this the 
 incomplete rationality of the universe. For the truth is that the 
 question ought never to have been asked. It is unmeaning, since 
 it applies a category, which has significance only inside the 
 universe, to the universe as a whole. Of any part we are entitled 
 and bound to ask Why, for by the very fact that it is a part, it 
 cannot be directly self-determined, and must depend on other 
 things^. But, when we speak of an all-embracing totality, then, 
 with the possibility of finding a cause, disappears also the 
 necessity for finding one. Independent and uncaused existence 
 is not in itself a contradictory or impossible idea. It is con- 
 tradictory when it is applied to anything in the universe, for 
 whatever is in the universe must be in connection with other 
 things. But this can of course be no reason for suspecting a 
 fallacy when we find ourselves obliged to use the idea in reference 
 to the universe as a whole, which has nothing outside it with 
 which it could stand in connection. 
 
 Indeed the suggestion, that it is possible that the universe 
 should have been different from what it is, would, in such a 
 state of knowledge, possess no meaning. For, from the complete 
 interdependence of all the parts, it would follow that if it was 
 different at all, it must be different completely. And a possibility 
 
 ^ The parts of a super-organic whole are, indeed, self-determined, but not 
 directly. Their self-determination comes through their determination by the 
 other parts. 
 
 14—2 
 
212 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 which has no common element with actuality, which would be 
 the case here, is a mere abstraction which is devoid of all value. 
 
 This, then, is the highest point to which knowledge, as know- 
 ledge, can attain, upon Hegel's principles. Everything is known, 
 and everything is known to be completely rational. And, although 
 our minds cannot help throwing a shadow of contingency and 
 irrationality over the symmetrical structure, by asking, as it is 
 always possible to ask, what determined the whole to be what 
 it is, and why it is not otherwise, yet reflection convinces us 
 that the question is unjustifiable, and indeed unmeaning, and 
 that the inability to answer it can be no reason for doubting 
 the completely satisfactory nature of the result at which we have 
 arrived. 
 
 189. But even when knowledge has reached this point, is it 
 an adequate expression of the complete nature of reality? This 
 question, I think, must be answered in the negative. We have, 
 it is true, come to the conclusion, — if we have gone so far with 
 Hegel — that Spirit is the only and the all-sufficient reality. But 
 knowledge does not exhaust the nature of Spirit. The simplest 
 introspection will show us that, besides knowledge, we have also 
 volition, and the feehng of pleasure and pain. These are frima 
 facie different from knowledge, and it does not seem possible 
 that they should ever be reduced to it. Knowledge, volition, 
 and feeling remain, in spite of all such attempts, distinct and 
 independent. They are not, indeed, independent, in the sense 
 that any of them can exist without the others. Nor is it im- 
 possible that they might be found to be aspects of a unity which 
 embraces and transcends them all. But they are independent 
 in so far that neither of the others can be reduced to, or tran- 
 scended by, knowledge. 
 
 Let us first consider volition. Volition and knowledge have 
 this common element, that they are activities which strive to 
 bring about a harmony between the conscious self and its sur- 
 roundings. But in the manner in which they do this they are 
 the direct antitheses of one another. In knowledge the self 
 endeavours to conform itself to its surroundings. In volition, on 
 the other hand, it demands that its surroundings shall conform 
 to itself. Of course the knowing mind is far from being inactive 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 213 
 
 in knowledge — it is only by means of its own activity that it 
 arrives at the objective truth which is its aim. Nor is the self 
 by any means purely active in volition. For it has sometimes 
 only to recognise and approve a harmony already existing, and 
 not to produce one by its action. And sometimes the surroundings 
 react on the self, and develop it or crush it into acquiescence in 
 facts against which it would previously have protested. 
 
 But it remains true that in knowledge the aim of the self is 
 to render its own state a correct mirror of the objective reality, 
 and that, in so far as it fails to do this, it condemns its own state 
 as false and mistaken. In volition, on the contrary, its aim is 
 that objective reality shall carry out the demands made by the 
 inner nature of the self. In so far as reality fails to do this, 
 the self condemns it as wrong. Now this is surely a fundamental 
 difference. Starting with the aim, which is common to both, 
 that a harmony is to be established, what greater difference can 
 exist between two ways of carrying out this aim, than that one 
 way demands that the subject shall conform to the object, while 
 the other way demands that the object shall conform to the 
 subject? 
 
 190. We may put this in another way. The aim of knowledge 
 is the true. The aim of volition is the good (in the widest sense 
 of the word, in which it includes all that we desire, since all that 
 is desired at all, is desired sub specie honi). Now one of these 
 aims cannot be reduced to the other. There is no direct transition 
 from truth to goodness, nor from goodness to truth. We may 
 of course come to the conclusion, which Hegel has attempted 
 to demonstrate, that the content of the two ideas is the same, 
 that the deepest truth is the highest good, and the highest good 
 is the deepest truth, that whatever is real is righteous, and what- 
 ever is righteous is real. But we can only do this by finding out 
 independently what is true and what is good, and by proving 
 that they coincide. 
 
 If we have come to this conclusion, and established it to our 
 own satisfaction as a general principle, we are entitled, no doubt, 
 to apply it in particular cases where the identity is not evident. 
 To those, for example, who have satisfied themselves of the 
 existence of a benevolent God, it is perfectly open to argue that 
 
214 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 we must be immortal, because the absence of immortality would 
 make life a ghastly farce, or, by a converse process, that tooth- 
 ache must be good because God sends it. But if the harmony 
 of the two sides has not been established by the demonstration 
 of the existence of a benevolent and omnipotent power, or of 
 some other ground for the same conclusion, such an argument 
 depends on an unjustifiable assumption. 
 
 There is nothing in the mere fact of a thing's existence to 
 make it desired or desirable by us. There is nothing in the mere 
 fact that a thing is desired or desirable by us to make it exist. 
 Two mental activities for which the test of vahdity is respectively 
 existence and desirability must surely, therefore, be coordinate, 
 without any possibility of reducing the one to a case or applica- 
 tion of the other. If indeed we considered volition as merely 
 that which leads to action, it might be considered less fimdamental 
 than knowledge, since it would inevitably disappear in a state 
 of perfect harmony. But voHtion must be taken to include all 
 affirmations of an ideal in relation to existence, including those 
 which lead to no action because they do not find reaUty to be 
 discrepant with them. And in this case we shall have to consider 
 it as fundamental an activity of Spirit as knowledge is, and one, 
 therefore, which cannot be ignored in favour of knowledge when 
 we are investigating the completely adequate form of Spirit. 
 
 191. No doubt the fact that knowledge and volition have the 
 same aim before them — a harmony between the self and its 
 surroundings — and that they effect it in ways which are directly 
 contrary to one another, suggests a possible union of the two. 
 The dialectic method will lead us to enquire whether, besides 
 being species of a wider genus, they are not also abstractions 
 from a deeper unity, which unity would reveal itseK as the really 
 adequate form of Spirit. But although this may be a Hegelian 
 solution, it is not Hegel's. Whatever he may have hinted in the 
 Logic — a point to which we shall presently return — in the Philo- 
 sophy of Spirit he attempts to take knowledge by itself as the 
 ultimate form of Spirit. And such a result must, if volition is 
 really coordinate with knowledge, be erroneous. 
 
 192. There is yet a third element in the life of Spirit, besides 
 knowledge and volition. This is feeling proper — pleasure and 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 215 
 
 pain. And this too must rank as a separate element of spiritual 
 activity, independent of knowledge. This does not involve the 
 assertion that we could ever experience a state of mind that was 
 purely pleasure or pain. So far as our experience reaches, on 
 the contrary, we never do feel pleasure or pain, without at the 
 same time recognising the existence of some fact, and finding 
 ourselves to be or not to be in harmony with it. Thus feeling 
 is only found in company with knowledge and volition. But 
 although it is thus inseparable from knowledge, it is independent 
 of it in the sense that it cannot be reduced to it. Knowledge is 
 essentially and inevitably a judgment — an assertion about matter 
 of fact. Now in the feeling of pleasure and pain there is no 
 judgment and no assertion, but there is something else to which 
 no judgment can ever be equivalent. 
 
 Hegel's views as to feeling proper are rather obscure. He 
 says much indeed about Gef iihl, but this does not mean pleasure 
 and pain. It appears rather to denote all immediate or intuitive 
 belief in a fact, as opposed to a reasoned demonstration of it. 
 The contents of Gefiihl and of Philosophy, he says, may be the 
 same, but they differ in form. It is thus clear that he is speaking 
 of a form of knowledge, and not only of pleasure and pain. But 
 whatever he thinks about the latter, it seems certain that they 
 cannot, any more than volition, find a place in philosophy. And 
 in that case Hegel's highest form of Spirit is defective on a second 
 ground, 
 
 193. To this line of criticism an objection may possibly be 
 taken. It is true, it may be said, that philosophy includes neither 
 volition nor feeling. But it implies them both. You cannot have 
 knowledge without finding yourself, from the point of view of 
 volition, in or out of harmony with the objects of pure knowledge, 
 and without feeling pleasure or pain accordingly. This is no 
 doubt true. And we may go further, and say that, on Hegel's 
 principles, we should be entitled to conclude that perfect know- 
 ledge must bring perfect acquiescence in the universe, and also 
 perfect happiness. For when our knowledge becomes perfect, 
 we should, as the Logic tells us, find that in all our relations with 
 that which was outside us, we had gained the perfect realisation 
 of our own natures. Determination by another would have 
 
216 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 become, in the fullest and deepest sense, determination by self. 
 Since, therefore, in all our relations with others, the demands 
 of our own nature found complete fulfilment, we should be in 
 a state of perfect acquiescence with the nature of all things round 
 us. And from this perfect harmony, complete happiness must 
 result. 
 
 Hegel would, no doubt, have been justified in saying that in 
 reaching complete knowledge we should, at the same time, have 
 reached to the completeness of all activities of Spirit. But he 
 did say more than this. He said that complete knowledge would 
 be by itself the complete activity of Spirit. He tried, it would 
 seem, to ignore volition, and to ignore pleasure and pain. And 
 a view of Spirit which does this will be fatally one-sided. 
 
 194. But we must go further. We have seen that knowledge 
 cannot, by itself, be the full expression of the complete nature 
 of Spirit. But can it, we must now ask, be, as knowledge, even 
 part of that full expression? Can it attain its own goal? Or does 
 it carry about the strongest mark of its own imperfection by 
 postulating an ideal which it can never itself reach? 
 
 195. The ideal of knowledge may be said to be the combina- 
 tion of complete unity of the subject and object with complete 
 differentiation between them. In so far as we have knowledge 
 there must be unity of the subject and object. Of the elements 
 into which knowledge can be analysed, one class — the data of 
 sensation — come to us from outside, and consequently involve 
 the unity of the subject and the object, without which it is 
 impossible that anything outside us could produce a sensation 
 inside us. On the other hand the categories are notions of our 
 own minds which are yet essential to objective experience. And 
 these, therefore, involve no less the unity of the subject and the 
 object, since otherwise we should not be justified in ascribing 
 to them, as we do ascribe, objective validity. 
 
 Differentiation of the subject and object is no less necessary 
 to knowledge than is their unity. For it is of the essence of 
 knowledge that it shall refer to something not itself, something 
 which is independent of the subjective fancies of the subject, 
 something which exists whether he likes it or not, which exists 
 not only for him, but for others, something in fact which is 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 217 
 
 objective. Without this, knowledge changes into dreams or delu- 
 sions, and these, however interesting as objects of knowledge, 
 are totally different from knowledge itself. In so far as knowledge 
 becomes perfect, it has to apprehend the object as it really is, 
 and so in its full differentiation from the subject. 
 
 All knowledge, in so far as it is complete, requires unity and 
 differentiation. Perfect knowledge will require perfect unity and 
 differentiation. And since the dialectic has taught us that all 
 knowledge, except that highest and most complete knowledge 
 which grasps reality under the Absolute Idea, is contradictory 
 and cannot stand except as a moment in some higher form — 
 we may conclude that all knowledge implies complete unity and 
 differentiation. For the lower knowledge implies the higher, and 
 the complete unity and differentiation are implied by the higher 
 knowledge. 
 
 This is confirmed by the final results of the Logic. There we 
 find that the only ultimately satisfactory category is one in 
 which the self finds itself in relation with other selves and in 
 harmony with their nature. To be in harmony with other selves 
 implies that we are in unity with them, while to recognise them 
 as selves implies differentiation. 
 
 Knowledge requires, then, this combination of antithetical 
 qualities. Is it possible that this requirement can ever be realised 
 by knowledge itself? 
 
 196. The action of knowledge consists in ascribing predicates 
 to an object. All our knowledge of the object we owe to the 
 predicates which we ascribe to it. But our object is not a mere 
 assemblage of predicates. There is also the unity in which they 
 cohere, which may be called epistemologically the abstract object, 
 and logically the abstract subject. 
 
 Here, — as in most other places in the universe — we are met 
 by a paradox. The withdrawal of the abstract object leaves 
 nothing but a collection of predicates, and a collection of predi- 
 cates taken by itself is a mere unreality. Predicates cannot exist 
 without a central unity in which they can cohere. But when 
 we enquire what is this central unity which gives reality to the 
 object, we find that its unreahty is as certain as the unreality 
 of the predicates, and perhaps even more obvious. For if we 
 
218 THE riNAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 attempt to make a single statement about this abstract object 
 — even to say that it exists — we find ourselves merely adding 
 to the number of predicates. This cannot help us to attain our 
 purpose, which was to know what the substratum is in which 
 all the predicates inhere. We get no nearer to this by learning 
 that another predicate inheres in it. 
 
 Thus the abstract object is an unreality, and yet, if it is with- 
 drawn, the residuum of the concrete object becomes an unreality 
 too. Such a relation is not uncommon in metaphysics. All reality 
 is concrete. All concrete ideas can be split up into abstract 
 elements. If we spHt up the concrete idea, which corresponds 
 to some real thing, into its constituent abstractions, we shall 
 have a group of ideas which in their unity correspond to a reality, 
 but when separated are self-contradictory and unreal. The 
 position of the abstract object is thus similar to that of another 
 ..^ abstraction which has received more attention in metaphysics — 
 
 •^ ^^ the abstract subject. 
 
 ^ *» Mr Bradley has given this abstract object the name of the 
 
 \ r— This, in opposition to the What, which consists of the predicates 
 
 ?\ "^ .^^ which we have found to be applicable to the This. While know- 
 
 ledge remains imperfect, the This has in it the possibility of an 
 indefinite number of other qualities, besides the definite number 
 f^ ^ which have been ascertained and embodied in predicates. When 
 
 ^ knowledge becomes perfect — as perfect as it is capable of be- 
 
 coming — this possibility would disappear, as it seems to me, 
 though Mr Bradley does not mention this point. In perfect 
 1^ ^' knowledge all qualities of the object would be known, and the 
 
 ^ "^ > coherence of our knowledge as a systematic whole would be the 
 '^ Q~ warrant for the completeness of the enumeration. But even 
 ^ ^_j v-', here the abstract This would still remain, and prove itself irre- 
 •^ dugible to anything else. To attempt to know it is like attempting 
 
 ,^ .. ^ to jump on the shadow of one's own head. For all propositions 
 ^ are the assertion of a partial unity between the subject and the 
 I "^ predicate. The This on the other hand is just what distinguishes 
 I ->^ the subject from its predicates. 
 ^ -osf 197. It is the existence of the This which renders it impossible 
 
 >. "^ to regard knowledge as a self-subsistent whole, and makes it 
 ™ necessary to consider it merely as an approximation to the 
 
 
 /«* 
 
 ' -J 
 
 !?r- n,/A-- roHef<<^ 
 
 -^1 
 
 
 5 HOT U-He^t 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 219 
 
 complete activity of spirit for which we search. In the This we 
 have something which is at once within and without knowledge, 
 which it dares not neglect, and yet cannot deal with. 
 
 For when we say that the This cannot be known, we do not 
 mean, of course, that we cannot know of its existence. We know 
 of its existence, because we can perceive, by analysis, that it 
 is an essential element of the concrete object. But the very 
 definition which this analysis gives us shows that we can know 
 nothing about it but this — that there is indeed nothing more 
 about it to know, and that even so much cannot be put into 
 words without involving a contradiction. Now to know merely 
 that something exists is to present a problem to knowledge which 
 it must seek to answer. To know that a thing exists, is to know 
 it as immediate and contingent. Knowledge demands that such 
 a thing should be mediated and rationalised. This, as we have 
 seen, cannot be done here. This impossibility is no reproach to 
 the rationality of the universe, for reality is no more mere 
 mediation than it is mere immediacy, and the immediacy of the 
 This combines with the mediation of the What to make up the 
 concrete whole of Spirit. But it is a reproach to the adequacy 
 of knowledge as an activity of Spirit that it should persist in 
 demanding what cannot and should not be obtained. Without 
 immediacy, without the central unity of the object, the media- 
 tion and the predicates which make up knowledge would vanish 
 as unmeaning. Yet knowledge is compelled by its own nature 
 to try and remove them, and to feel itself baffled and thwarted 
 when it cannot succeed. Surely an activity with such a con- 
 tradiction inherent in it can never be a complete expression of 
 the Absolute. 
 
 198. In the first place the existence of the This is incom- 
 patible with the attainment of the ideal of unity in knowledge. 
 For here we have an element, whose existence in reality we are 
 forced to admit, but which is characterised by the presence of 
 that which is essentially alien to the nature of the knowing 
 consciousness in its activity. In so far as reality contains a This, 
 it cannot be brought into complete unison with the knowing 
 mind, which, as an object, has of course its aspect of immediacy 
 like any other object, but which, as the knowing subject, finds 
 
220 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 all unresolvable immediacy to be fundamentally opposed to its 
 work of rationalisation. The real cannot be completely expressed 
 in the mind, and the unity of knowledge is therefore defective. 
 
 And this brings with it a defective differentiation. For while 
 the This cannot be brought into the unity of knowledge, it is 
 unquestionably a part of reality. And so the failure of knowledge 
 to bring it into unity with itself involves that the part of the 
 object which is brought into unity with the subject is only an 
 abstraction from the full object. The individuality of the object 
 thus fails to be represented, and so its full differentiation from 
 the subject fails to be represented also. The result is that we 
 know objects, so to speak, from the outside, whereas, to know 
 them in their full truth, we ought to know them from inside. 
 That every object^ has a real centre of its own appears from the 
 dialectic. For we have seen that the conclusion from the dialectic 
 is that all reality consists of spirits, which are individuals. And, 
 apart from this, the fact that the object is more or less indepen- 
 dent as against us — and without some independence knowledge 
 would be impossible, as has already been pointed out — renders 
 it certain that every object has an individual unity to some 
 extent. Now knowledge fails to give this unity its rights. The 
 meaning of the object is found in its This, and its This is, to 
 knowledge, something alien. Knowledge sees it to be, in a sense, 
 the centre of the object, but only a dead centre, a mere residuum 
 produced by abstracting all possible predicates, not a living and 
 unifying centre, such as we know that the synthetic unity of 
 apperception is to our own lives, which we have the advantage 
 of seeing from inside. And since it thus views it from a stand- 
 point which is merely external, knowledge can never represent 
 the object so faithfully as to attain its own ideal. 
 
 199. And here we see the reason why knowledge can never 
 represent quite accurately that harmony of the universe which 
 
 ^ In saying "every object" I do not necessarily mean every chair, every 
 crystal, or even every amoeba. Behind all appearance there is reality. This 
 reality we believe, on the authority of the dialectic, to consist of individuals. 
 But how many such centres there may be behind a given mass of appearance we 
 do not know. Every self-conscious spirit is, no doubt, one object and no more. 
 It is with regard to the reality behind what is called inorganic matter and the 
 lower forms of life that the uncertainty arises. 
 
< 
 
 -e 
 
 VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 221 J- 
 
 knowledge itself proves. We saw above that when knowledge ^ 
 
 should have reached the greatest perfection of which it is capable ^ 
 
 there would still remain one question unanswered — Why is the ^ 
 
 universe what it is and not something else? We may prove the ^^ 
 
 question unmeaning and absurd, but we cannot help asking it. ^ 
 
 And the possibility of asking it depends on the existence of the "" 
 
 This, which knowledge is unable to bring into unity with the ^^ 
 
 knowing subject. The This is essential to the reality of the object, "^i 
 and is that part of the object to which it owes its independence 
 of the subject. And the question naturally arises, Why should 
 
 
 UJ 
 
 2^ 
 
 not this core of objectivity have been clothed with other qualities ;;^ 
 
 than those which it has, and with which the subject finds itself 
 in harmony? 
 
 The question arises because the existence of this harmony is 'j ZL I — 
 dependent on the This. The This alone gives reality to the object. 
 If it vanished, the harmony would not change into a disharmony, 
 but disappear altogether. And the This, as we have seen, must 
 always be for knowledge a something alien and irrational, I 
 
 because it must always be an unresolved immediate. Now a 
 harmony which depends on something alien and irrational must 
 always appear contingent and defective. Why is there a This at 
 all? Why is it just those qualities which give a harmony for us 
 that the favour of the This has raised into reality? To answer 
 these questions would be to mediate the This, and that w^ould 
 destroy it. 
 
 200. It may be urged, as against this argument, that we do 
 not stand in such a position of opposition and alienation towards 
 the This in knowledge. For we ourselves are objects of know- 
 ledge as well as knowing subjects, and our abstract personaUty, 
 which is the centre of our knowledge is also the This of an object. 
 Now it might be maintained that the inter-connection of the 
 qualities of all different objects, which would be perfect in perfect 
 knowledge, would enable us to show why all reahty existed, and 
 why it is what it is, if we could only show it of a single fragment 
 of reahty. The difficulty, it might be said, hes in reaching the 
 abstract realness of the real by means of knowledge at all. And 
 if, by means of our own existence as objects we were able to 
 establish a single connection with the objective world, in which 
 
222 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 the immediate would not mean the alien, it is possible that no 
 other connection would be required. The last remaining opposition 
 of the subject to the object would disappear. 
 
 The difficulty, however, cannot be escaped in this way. For 
 the self as the object of knowledge is as much opposed to the 
 self as the subject as any other object could be. We learn its 
 qualities by arguments from data based on the "internal sense," 
 as we learn the qualities of other objects by arguments from data 
 given by the external senses. We are immediately certain of the 
 first, but we are immediately certain of the second. And the 
 central unity of our own nature can no more be known directly 
 in itself, apart from its qualities, than can the central unities 
 of other objects^. ¥/e become aware of its existence by analysing 
 what is implied in having ourselves for objects, and we become 
 aware of the central unities of other things by analysing what 
 is implied in having them for objects. We have no more direct 
 knowledge of the one than of the other. Of course nothing in 
 our own selves is really alien to us, — not even the element of 
 immediacy which makes their This. But then the existence of 
 knowledge implies, as we have seen, that the reality of other 
 things is not really alien to us, although we know it immediately. 
 It is the defect of knowledge that it fails to represent the im- 
 mediate except as alien. " 
 
 201. Here, then, we seem to have the reason why our minds 
 could never, in the most perfect state of knowledge possible, 
 get rid of the abstract idea of the contingency of the whole 
 system. We saw, in the first part of this chapter, that such an 
 idea was unmeaning, since it would be impossible for any reality 
 to be destroyed or altered, unless the same happened to all reality, 
 and the possibility of this, which has no common ground with 
 actuality, is an unmeaning phrase. And we have now seen 
 another reason why the possibility is unmeaning. For we have 
 traced it to the persistence of thought in considering its essential 
 condition as its essential enemy. The existence of such a mis- 
 called possibility, therefore, tells nothing against the rationality 
 of the universe. But it does tell against the adequacy of know- 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. I now think that a self can directly perceive itself 
 Cp. my article on Personality in the Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics. 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 223 
 
 ledge as an expression of the universe. By finding a flLaw in 
 perfection, where no flaw exists, it pronounces its own condemna- 
 tion. If the possibility is unmeaning, knowledge is imperfect in 
 being compelled to regard it as a possibiUty. 
 
 It may seem at first sight absurd to talk of knowledge as in- 
 adequate. If it were imperfect, how could we know it? What 
 right have we to condemn it as imperfect when the judge is of 
 necessity the same person as the culprit? This is, of course, so 
 far true, that if knowledge did not show us its own ideal, we 
 could never know that it did not realise it. But there is a great 
 dijEEerence between realising an ideal and indicatiixg it. It is 
 possible, and I have endeavoured to show that it is actually the 
 case, that knowledge can do the one, and not the other. When 
 we ask about the abstract conditions of reality, it is able to 
 demonstrate that harmony must exist, and that immediacy is 
 compatible with it, and essential to it. But when it is asked to 
 show in detail hoiv the harmony exists, which it has shown must 
 exist, it is unable to do so. There is here no contradiction in our 
 estimate of knowledge, but there is a contradiction in knowledge, 
 which prevents us from regarding it as adequate, and which 
 forces us to look further in search of the ultimate activity of 
 Spirit. 
 
 We saw before that this activity could not consist solely of 
 knowledge, but we have now reached the further conclusion that 
 knowledge, as knowledge, could not form even a part of that 
 activity. For it carries a mark of imperfection about it, in its 
 inability to completely attain the goal which it cannot cease to 
 strive for, and in its dependence on that which it must consider 
 an imperfection. We must therefore look for the ultimate nature 
 of Spirit in something which transcends and surpasses cognition, 
 including it indeed as a moment, but transforming it and raising 
 it into a higher sphere, where its imperfections vanish. 
 
 202. In doing this we are compelled, of course, to reject Hegel's 
 own treatment of the subject, in the Philosophy of Spirit. But 
 we may, I think, find some support for our position in the Logic. 
 For there, as it seems to me, we find the sketch of a more com- 
 plete and adequate representation of Absolute Reality, than the 
 one which is worked out in the Philosophy of Spirit. 
 
224 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 We have in the Logic, immediately before the Absolute Idea^ 
 a category called Cognition in general. This is again divided into 
 Cognition proper and Volition. These two categories are treated 
 by Hegel as a thesis and antithesis, and, according to the method 
 pursued in every other part of the Logic, the triad should have 
 been completed by a synthesis, before we pass out of Cognition 
 in general to the final synthesis — the Absolute Idea. No such 
 synthesis, however, is given by Hegel as a separate term. Ac- 
 cording to his exposition, the Absolute Idea itself forms the 
 synthesis of the opposition of Cognition proper and Volition, as 
 it does also of the larger opposition of Life and Cognition in 
 general. 
 
 The significance of this part of the Logic for us lies in the 
 fact that Cognition proper requires to be synthesised with Vohtion 
 before we can reach the absolute reality. Of course Hegel is not 
 dealing, in the Logic, with the concrete activities of cognition 
 and voHtion, any more than he is dealing, rather earlier in the 
 Logic, with the concrete activities of mechanism and chemistry. 
 The Logic deals only with the element of pure thought in reality, 
 and, when its categories bear the names of concrete relations, 
 all that is meant is that the pure idea, which is the category in 
 question, is the idea which comes most prominently forward in 
 that concrete relation, and which therefore can be usefully and 
 significantly called by its name. 
 
 This, however, does not destroy the importance of the Logic 
 for our present purpose. Although the concrete activities are 
 not merely their own logical ideas, they must stand in the same 
 relation inter se as the logical ideas do inter se. For the process 
 in the Philosophy of Spirit, as in all the applications of the 
 dialectic, while it does not profess to be logical in the sense that 
 all its details can be logically deduced, certainly professes to be 
 logical in the sense that the relation of its stages to one another 
 can be logically explained^. Indeed, if it did not do this, it could 
 no longer be called an application of the Logic at all, but would 
 be a mere empirical collection of facts. If then the idea of 
 cognition proper — that is, of knowledge as opposed to volition 
 — is by itself so imperfect and one-sided, that it must be tran- 
 1 Op. Chap. VII. Sections 207, 210. 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 225 
 
 scended, and must be synthesised with the idea of vohtion, before 
 the adequate and Absolute Idea can be reached, it would seem 
 to follow that a concrete application of this philosophy is bound 
 to regard cognition as an inadequate expression of the full nature 
 of reahty, and to endeavour to find some higher expression which 
 shall unite cognition and vohtion, preserving that which is true 
 in each, while escaping from their imperfections and one-sided- 
 ness. 
 
 203. It may be objected that Cognition proper, which is 
 treated by Hegel as an inadequate category, denotes only that 
 knowledge which is found in ordinary experience and in science, 
 and that the place of knowledge in its highest shape — the shape 
 of philosophy — must be looked for under the Absolute Idea. 
 This view does not appear tenable on closer examination. At 
 the end of Cognition proper, Hegel tells us, the content of cog- 
 nition is seen to be necessary. This would indicate philosophic 
 knowledge, if "necessary" is taken as referring to the necessity 
 of freedom, which is its normal use in the Doctrine of the Notion, 
 There is certainly a good deal of discussion of philosophic method 
 under the head of the Absolute Idea. But this appears to be 
 introduced, not because this category is the one under which 
 our philosophising comes, but because it is the last category of 
 the philosophy, and it is therefore natural to look back, at this 
 point, on the method which has been pursued. 
 
 The most cogent argument, however, against this view is that 
 the Absolute Idea is defined as the union of Cognition proper 
 with Volition. Therefore the Absolute Idea must be an idea richer 
 and fuller than that of Cognition — richer and fuller by the content 
 of the idea of Vohtion, Now we can have no reason to suppose 
 that philosophic knowledge is the union of ordinary knowledge 
 with volition. For philosophy stands in just the same relation 
 to vohtion as ordinary knowledge does. We never have know- 
 ledge without having vohtion, but neither can be reduced to the 
 other. The Absolute Idea then contains within itself the idea 
 of Knowledge only as a transcended moment. If there is any 
 difference between them, indeed, we must consider the idea of 
 Volition the higher of the two, since it is Volition which forms 
 the antithesis, and we have seen that, in the Doctrine of the 
 
 15 
 
 foRe : 
 
 m00m CAAL M4KX 'i ,i!; 
 
226 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 Notion, the antithesis may be expected to be more adequate 
 than the thesis to which it is opposed^. 
 
 I am not attempting to argue from this that we ought to take 
 Hegel as putting anything more concrete than philosophy into 
 the nature of absolute reality. We are especially bound in the 
 case of so systematic a writer as Hegel, to look for the authori- 
 tative exposition of his views on any subject in the part of his 
 work which professedly deals with that subject. And in the 
 Philosophy of Spirit it seems clear that Hegel means the highest 
 stage of Spirit to be nothing but philosophy. But, in giving the 
 abstract framework of absolute reality in the Logic, he has given, 
 as we have seen above, a framework for something which, what- 
 ever it is, is more than any form of mere cognition. And so, 
 when saying that the conclusion of the Philosophy of Spirit is 
 inconsistent with the general tenor of Hegel's philosophy, we 
 can strengthen our position by adding that it is inconsistent with 
 the final result of the Logic. 
 
 204. Let us now turn to the Philosophy of Spirit, and con- 
 sider the way in which Hegel introduces Philosophy as the 
 culminating point of reality. The three terms which form the 
 triad of Absolute Spirit are Art, Revealed Religion, and Philo- 
 sophy. Of the relation of these three stages he speaks as follows : 
 "Whereas the vision-method of Art, external in point of form, 
 is but subjective production and shivers the substantial content 
 into many separate shapes, and whereas Religion, with its separa- 
 tion into parts, opens it out in mental picture, and mediates what 
 is thus opened out ; Philosophy not merely keeps them together 
 to make a total, but even unifies them into the simple spiritual 
 vision, and then in that raises them to self-conscious thought. 
 Such consciousness is thus the intelligible unity (cognised by 
 thought) of art and religion, in which the diverse elements in 
 the content are cognised as necessary, and this necessary as free^." 
 
 On examining this more closely, doubts present themselves. 
 Is Philosophy really capable of acting as a synthesis between 
 Art and Religion? Should it not rather form part of the anti- 
 thesis, together with Religion? All the stages in this triad of.;^ 
 
 1 Chap. IV. Sections 109, 110. 
 
 2 Enc. Section 572. 
 
vil THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 227 
 
 Absolute Spirit are occupied in endeavouring to find a harmony ^ 
 
 between the individual spirit — now developed into full conscious- • * v^ 
 ness of his own nature — on the one hand, and the rest of the Vi» """ 
 universe on the other hand. Such a harmony is directly and QC ^pt* 
 immediately presented in beauty. But the immediacy makes \P v^j 
 the harmony contingent and defective. Where beauty is present, ^ t^ 
 the harmony exists; where it is not present — a case not un- <w t^ 
 frequently occurring — the harmony disappears. It is necessary Nk* l;;;^ 
 to find some ground of harmony which is universal, and which 't \>n 
 shall enable us to attribute rationality and righteousness to all 
 things, independently of their immediate and superficial aspect. 
 
 This ground, according to Hegel, is afforded us by the doctrines 
 of Revealed Religion, which declares that all things are depen- 
 dent on and the manifestation of a reality in which we recognise 
 the fulfilment of our ideals of. rationality and righteousness. Thus 
 Revealed Religion assures us that all things must be in harmony, 
 instead of showing us, as Art does, that some things are in 
 harmony. 
 
 205. Now Philosophy, it seems to me, can do no more than 
 this. It is true that it does it, in what, from Hegel's point of 
 view, is a higher and better way. It is true that it substitutes 
 a completely reasoned process for one which, in the last resort, 
 rests on authority. It is true that it changes the external har- 
 mony, which Revealed Religion offers, into a harmony inherent 
 in the nature of things. It is true that the process, which is 
 known to Revealed Religion as "a cycle of concrete shapes in 
 pictorial thought," and as "a separation into parts, with a 
 temporal and external sequence," is in Philosophy "known as 
 an indivisible coherence of the universal, simple, and eternal 
 spirit in itself^." But all this does not avail to bring back the 
 simplicity and directness of Art, which must be brought back 
 in the synthesis. Art shows us that something is as we would 
 have it. Its harmony with our ideals is visible on the surface. 
 But Philosophy, like Religion, leaving the surface of things un- 
 touched, points to their inner nature, and proves that, in spite 
 , of the superficial discord and evil, the true reality is harmonious 
 and good. To unite these we should require a state of spirit which 
 1 Enc. Section 57 L 
 
 15- 
 
228 THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 should present us with a harmony direct and immediate on the 
 one hand, and universal and necessary on the other. Art gives 
 the first and Philosophy the second, but Philosophy can no more 
 unite the two than Art can. 
 
 This is clear of philosophy, as we have it now, and so long 
 as it has not absorbed into itself all other knowledge. For it 
 is the knowledge of the general conditions only of reality. As 
 such, it can lay down general laws for all reality. But it is not 
 able to show how they are carried out in detail. It may arrive 
 at the conclusion that all that is real is rational. This will apply, 
 among other things, to toothache or cowardice. Now we are 
 shown by the whole history of religion that optimism based on 
 general grounds may be of great importance to the lives of those 
 who beheve it, and philosophy, if it can give us this, will have 
 given us no small gift. But philosophy will not be able to 
 show us how the rationality or the righteousness come in, either 
 in toothache or in cowardice. It can only convince us that they 
 are there, though we cannot see them. It is obvious that we 
 have as yet no synthesis with the directness and immediacy of 
 art. 
 
 If philosophy should ever, as was suggested in the earlier part 
 of this chapter, develop so as to include all knowledge in one 
 complete harmony, then, no doubt, we should not only know 
 of every fact in the universe that it was rational, but we should 
 also see how it was so. Even here, however, the required syn- 
 thesis would not be attained. Our knowledge would still be only 
 mediate knowledge, and thus could not be the synthesis for two 
 reasons. Firstly, because, as we have seen, it has to regard the 
 immediate element in reality as to some extent alien. Secondly, 
 because the synthesis must contain in itself, as a transcended 
 moment, the immediate harmony of art, and must therefore be 
 hfted above the distinction of mediate and immediate. 
 
 Besides this, a merely intellectual activity could not be the 
 ultimate truth of which art and rehgion are lower stages. For 
 both of these involve not merely knowledge, but vohtion, and 
 also feeling. And so the highest stage of spirit would have to 
 include, not only the perception of the rationahty of all things, 
 which is offered by philosophy, but also the complete acqui- 
 
VI] THE FINAL RESULT OF THE DIALECTIC 229 
 
 escence which is the goal of successful volition, and the pleasure 
 which is the inevitable result of conscious harmony. 
 
 206. The result of all this would appear to be, that, in order 
 to render the highest form of Absolute Spirit capable, as it must 
 be on Hegel's theory, of transcending and summing up all other 
 aspects of reality, we shall have to recast the last steps of the 
 Philosophy of Spirit, so as to bring the result more in accordance 
 with the general outlines laid down at the end of the Logic. 
 Philosophy, together with Revealed Religion, will be the anti- 
 thesis to Art. And a place will be left vacant for a new synthesis. 
 
 It forms no part of the object of this work to enquire what 
 this synthesis may be. My purpose has been only to give some 
 reasons for thinking that Hegel had not found an adequate 
 expression for the absolute reality, and I do not venture to 
 suggest one myself. But we can, within very wide and general 
 limits, say what the nature of such an expression must be. It 
 must be some state of conscious spirit in which the opposition 
 of cognition and vohtion is overcome — in which we neither judge 
 our ideas by the world, nor the world by our ideas, but are aware 
 that inner and outer are in such close and necessary harmony 
 that even the thought of possible discord has become impossible. 
 In its unity not only cognition and volition, but feeling also, 
 must be blended and united. In some way or another it must 
 have overcome the rift in discursive knowledge, and the im- 
 mediate must for it be no longer the ahen. It must be as direct 
 as art, as certain and universal as philosophy^. 
 
 ^ Note to Second Edition. I have discussed this subject further in my Studies 
 in Hegelian Cosmology, Chap. ix. 
 
CHAPTER VII 
 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 207. We have now to enquire in what manner the results 
 which we have gained by the dialectic process are applicable to 
 ly real life. I do not propose to discuss the utility of these results 
 as a guide to conduct, but there is another question more closely 
 connected with the dialectic itself. How, if at all, can the pure 
 theory, which is expounded in the Logic, be so used as to assist 
 in the explanation of the various facts presented to us in ex- 
 perience? Hegel divides the world into two parts — Nature and 
 Spirit. What can his philosophy tell us about them ? 
 
 We have seen in our consideration of the dialectic that there 
 are certain functions, with regard to our knowledge of Nature 
 and Spirit, which pure thought cannot perform, and which there 
 is no reason to think, in spite of the assertions of some critics, 
 that Hegel ever intended it to perform. In the first place, we 
 saw that the concrete world of reality cannot be held to be a 
 mere condescension of the Logic to an outward shape, nor a 
 mere dependent emanation from the self-subsistent perfection 
 of pure thought. For, so far from pure thought being able to 
 create immediate reaHty, it cannot itself exist unless something 
 immediate is given to it, which it may mediate and relate. And 
 we saw that, so far from Hegel's theory being inconsistent with 
 this truth, it is entirely dependent on it. The force of his deduc- 
 tion of Nature and Spirit from Logic lies in the fact that pure 
 thought is a mere abstraction which, taken by itself, is con- 
 tradictory. A ^d therefore, since pure thought unquest ionably 
 exists som ehow, we are led to the conclusion that it cannot exist 
 ind ependently, but must be a moment in that more concr ete 
 f orm of reality, which is expressed imperfectly in Nature a nd 
 a dequate ly in Spi^i^t 
 
 And we saw, in the second place, that even this deduction 
 can only extend to the general nature of the reality, because it 
 is only that general nature which we can prove to be essential 
 
OH. VII] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 231 
 
 for the existence of pure thought. We know, a priori, that the 
 reality must contain an immediate moment, in order that 
 thought may mediate it, that something must be given in order 
 that thought may deal with it. But further than this we cannot 
 go without the aid of empirical observation. No consideration 
 of the nature of pure thought can demonstrate to us the necessity 
 that a particular man should have red hair. To do this we require 
 immediate data. And here again we found no reason to suppose 
 that this limitation of pure thought was ignored by Hegel. His 
 attempts to apply his logical results may have gone too far, but 
 he never, attempted to deduce the necessity of all the facts he 
 was attempting to rationalise. His object was to point out that 
 through every part of reaUty there runs a thread of logical 
 connection, so that the different parts stand in intelligible rela- 
 tions to one another, and to Absolute Reality. But he never 
 tried to deduce the necessity of each detail of reality from the 
 nature of pure thought, or even to hold out such a deduction 
 as an ideal. This is evident, both from the number of details 
 which he mentions without even an attempt to explain them, 
 and also from his own direct statement^. 
 
 208. This then is one way in which we can apply the con- 
 clusions of the Logic in the solution o| more concrete problems. 
 We may trace the manifestations of the dialectic process in the 
 experience round us, and in so far as we do this we shall have 
 rationalised that experience. But, besides this, we may gain 
 some information from the dialectic concerning the ultimate 
 nature of Absolute Being. It will be convenient to consider this 
 latter point first. 
 
 No idea which is self-contradictory can be true until it is so 
 transformed that the contradictions have vanished. Now no 
 category in the Logic is free from contradictions except the 
 Absolute Idea. Reality can therefore be fully apprehended 
 under no category but this. We shall find it to be true of all 
 reality, that in it is found "der BegrifE der Idee, dem die Idee 
 als solche der Gegenstand, dem das Objekt sie ist^." From this 
 
 ^ Cp. Chap. I. Section 27, and the passage from the Philosophy of Spirit there 
 quoted. Also Chap. vi. Section ] 83. 
 2 Enc. Section 236. 
 
232 THE APPLICATION OP THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 we can deduce several consequences. All reality must, on this 
 view, be Spirit, and be differentiated. Moreover, it must be 
 Spirit for which its differentiations are, in Hegel's phrase, "trans- 
 parent," that is, it must find in them nothing alien to itself. It 
 might also be maintained, though the point is too large to be 
 discussed here, that it must consist of finite self-conscious spirits, 
 united into a closely connected whole. And it might not be 
 impossible to determine whether the whole in question was also 
 a self-conscious being, or whether it is a unity of persons without 
 being itself a person. The questions discussed in the last chapter 
 are also examples of the use that may be made, in this con- 
 nection, of the results of the dialectic. 
 
 209, The information thus attained would be enough to 
 justify us in saying that the results of Hegel's philosophy, apart 
 from their theoretic interest, were of the greatest practical im- 
 portance. It is true that such results as these can but rarely 
 be available as guides to action. We learn by them what is the 
 nature of that ideal, which, sub specie aeternitatis, is present in 
 all reality, and which, sm6 specie temporis, is the goal towards 
 which all reality is moving. But such an ideal is, sub specie 
 aeternitatis, far too implicit, and, sub specie temporis, far too 
 distant, to allow us to use it in deciding on any definite course 
 of action in the present. Nor can it be taken to indicate even 
 the direction in which our present action should move. For one 
 of the great lessons of Hegel's philosophy is that, in any progress, 
 we never move directly forwards, but oscillate from side to side 
 as we advance. And so a step which seems to be almost directly 
 away from our ideal may sometimes be the next step on the 
 only road by which that ideal can be attained. 
 
 But those who estimate the practical utility of a theory only 
 by its power of guiding our action, take too confined a view. 
 Action, after all, is always directed to some end. And, whatever 
 view we may take of the supreme end, it cannot be denied that 
 many of our actions are directed, and rightly directed, to the 
 production of happiness for ourselves and others. Surely, then, 
 a philosophical theory which tended to the production of happi- 
 ness would have as much claim to be called practically important, 
 as if it had afforded guidance in action. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 233 
 
 Now such conclusions as to the ultimate nature of things as 
 we have seen can be reached by Hegel's philosophy have obviously 
 a very intimate connection with the problems which may be 
 classed as religious. Is the universe rational and righteous? Is 
 spirit or matter the fundamental reaUty? Have our standards 
 of perfection any objective validity? Is our personaUty an 
 ultimate fact or a transitory episode? All experience and all 
 history show that for many men the answers to these questions 
 are the source of some of the most intense and persistent joys 
 and sorrows known in human life. Nor is there any reason to 
 think that the proportion of such people is diminishing. Any 
 system of philosophy which gives any reasons for deciding such 
 questions, in one way rather than another, will have a practical 
 interest, even if it should fail to provide us with counsel as to 
 the organisation of society, or with explanations in detail of the 
 phenomena of science. 
 
 210. We must now turn to the second way in which Hegel 
 endeavours to apply the dialectic to experience. It is to this 
 that he gives the greater prominence. His views on the nature 
 of absolute reality are to be found in the Philosophy of Spirit, 
 and also in the Philosophy of Religion, but they are not given 
 at any length. On many important points we have no further 
 guide than the development of the Absolute Idea in the Logic, 
 and we must judge for ourselves what consequences can be 
 drawn, from that development, as to the concrete whole of which 
 the Absolute Idea is one moment. 
 
 A much larger portion of his writings is occupied in tracing, 
 in the succession of events in time, the gradual development of 
 the Absolute Idea. To this purpose are devoted almost the whole 
 of the Philosophies of Nature, Spirit, Religion, Law and History, 
 as well as the History of Philosophy. He does not, as has been 
 already remarked, endeavour to deduce the facts, of which he 
 treats, from the Absolute Idea. Nor does he ever attempt to 
 deduce each stage from the one before it. We pass, for example, 
 from Moralitat to Sittlichkeit, from the Persian religion to the 
 Syrian, or from the Greek civilisation to the Roman. But there 
 are, in each case, many details in the second which are not 
 the consequence of anything in the first, and which must be 
 
234 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 explained empirically by science, or else left unexplained. His 
 object is to show that the central ideas of each stage are such 
 that each follows from its predecessor — either as a reaction from 
 its one-sidedness, or as a reconciliation of its contradictions — 
 and that these ideas express, more and more adequately as the 
 process gets nearer to its end, the Absolute Idea which had been 
 expounded in the Logic. 
 
 It is sometimes said that Hegel endeavoured to show that 
 the stages of development, in the various spheres of activity 
 which he considered in his different treatises, corresponded to 
 the various categories of the Logic. This, however, seems an 
 exaggeration. His theories of Nature, Spirit, Religion, and Law 
 are each divided into three main sections, which doubtless corre- 
 spond, and are meant to correspond, to the three primary divisions 
 of the Logic — Being, Essence, and the Notion. But to trace any 
 definite correspondence between the secondary divisions of these 
 works (to say nothing of divisions still more minute) and the 
 secondary divisions of the Logic, appears impossible. At any 
 rate no such correspondence is mentioned by Hegel. The con- 
 nection with the Logic seems rather to lie in the similarity of 
 development, by thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, and in the 
 gradually increasing adequacy of the manifestation of the Absolute 
 Idea, as the process gradually develops itself. 
 
 Of the Philosophy of History, indeed, we cannot say even 
 as much as this. For it is divided, not into three, but into four 
 main divisions, thus destroying the triadic form and the analogy 
 to the three divisions of the Logic. And although Hegel would 
 probably have found no difficulty, on his own principles, in 
 reducing the second and third divisions to one, it is a fact of 
 some significance that he did not think it worth while to do so. 
 It seems to indicate that he attached less importance, than has 
 sometimes been supposed, to the exact resemblance of the 
 scheme of the concrete processes to the scheme of pure thought 
 in the Logic. In the History of Philosophy, again, many of the 
 subordinate divisions are not triple. 
 
 211. The applications of the dialectic to various aspects of 
 reality have been the part of Hegel's work which has received 
 of late years the most notice and approbation. This is, no doubt. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 235 
 
 largely due to a reaction against Hegel's general position. To 
 those who reject that position the whole of the dialectic of pure 
 thought must seem a stupendous blunder — magnificent or 
 ridiculous according to the taste of the critic. With the dialectic 
 of pure thought would fall also, of course, all general and demon- 
 strated validity of its applications. But the brilliance and 
 suggestiveness of ma ny of the details of these app lications Jia.ve 
 of ten_b een acknowledged b y those who_reje ct the syste m, in 
 which they were arranged, and the bas is from which it is sought 
 t o iu stify them . 
 
 Among the followers of Hegel a different cause has led to the 
 same effect. The attraction of Hegel's philosophy to many of 
 them appears to lie in the explanations it can give of garticulaL 
 p arts of experience rather than in its general theory of the natur e 
 of reality . These explanations — attractive by their aesthetic com- 
 pleteness, or because of the practical consequences that follow 
 from them — are adopted and defended by such writers in an 
 empirical way. It is maintained that we can see that they do 
 explain the facts, while others do not, and they are believed for 
 this reason, and not because they follow from the dialectic of 
 pure thought. Hegelian views of religion, of morals, of history, 
 of the state are common enough among us. They appear to be 
 gaining ground in many directions. Nor can it be said that their 
 advocates are neglectful of the source from which they derive 
 their theories. They often style themselves Hegelians. But the 
 dialectic of pure thought tends to fall into the background. 
 HegeTs^explanations of the^ation ality to be found in par ticular 
 s pheres of ^existence a re accepted by many who ignore or rej ect 
 hisjiemonstratio ns that everything w hi ch exists must be rational . 
 
 212. I wish to put forward a different view — that the really 
 valid part of Hegel's system is his Logic, and not his applica- 
 tions of it. In the preceding chapters I have given some reasons 
 in support of the view that the general position of the Logic 
 is justifiable. With regard to its appHcations, on the other hand, 
 although they doubtless contain much that is most valuable, 
 their general and systematic vaHdity seems indefensible. 
 
 As we have already seen, there is nothing in the nature of 
 Hegel's object here, which should render his success impossible 
 
236 
 
 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 
 
 [CH. 
 
 / 
 
 a friori. The difficulties which arise are due rather to the great- 
 ness of the task, and to the imperfection of our present knowledge. 
 These difficulties we have now to consider. 
 
 213. The movement of the Idea, as we learned in the Logic, 
 is by thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, the first two being opposed, 
 and the third reconciling them. If we are able to trace the 
 progressive manifestations of the Idea in facts, these manifesta- 
 tions will arrange themselves in triads of this kind. And Hegel 
 has attempted to show that they do so. 
 
 But how are we to determine which stages are theses, which 
 are antitheses, and which again syntheses? This can, I believe, 
 onlyT)e done safely, in the case of any one term, by observing 
 its relation to others, which have already been grasped in the 
 system. And, as these again will require determination by their 
 relation to others previously determined, we shall be able to 
 build up a dialectic system only if we have fixed points at one 
 or both ends of the chain to start from. We cannot safely begin 
 in the middle and work backwards and forwards. 
 
 TJiere-is -nothing in the nature of any term which can tell us, 
 if we take it in isolation from others, whether it is a thesis or 
 an antithesis — that is, whether it will require, as the process 
 goes forward, the development of another term opposite and 
 complementary to itself, before a synthesis can be reached, or 
 whether it is itself opposed and complementary to some term 
 that came before it, so that a reconciliation will be the next 
 step to be expected in the process. Theses may be said to be 
 positive, antitheses negative. But no term is either positive or 
 negative per se. In a dialectic process we call those terms positive 
 which reaffirm, on a higher level, the position with which the 
 process started, the negative terms being the complementary 
 denials which are necessary as means to gain the higher level. 
 But to apply this test we should have to know beforehand the 
 term with which the process started. Or we may say that the 
 terms are positive which express the reality to which the process 
 is advancing, though they express it inadequately, while the 
 negative terms are those which, in recognising the inadequacy, 
 temporarily sacrifice the resemblance^. But this distinction, 
 
 1 Cp. Enc. Section 85. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 237 
 
 again, is useless until we know what is the last term of the whole 
 process, 
 
 Korjvould it be possible to recognise any term, taken in isola- 
 tion, as a^mtheaia, TTvefy^ernT in a dialectic process, except 
 the first two, contains within itself some synthesis of opposition, 
 for all that is accomplished is transferred to all succeeding terms. 
 On the other hand, every synthesis in a process, except the last, 
 contains within itself a latent one-sidedness, which will break 
 out in the opposition of the next thesis and antithesis, and require 
 for its reconciliation another synthesis. We can therefore only 
 determine that a term is a synthesis if we see that it does reconcile 
 the two terms immediately in front of it — in other words, if we 
 see it in relation to other terms. And the impossibility of recog- 
 nising a synthesis as such, if seen by itself, would be far greater 
 in the applications of the Logic than in the Logic itself. For 
 every fact or event has many sides or aspects, in some of which 
 it may appear to be a reconciliation of two opposites, and in 
 others to be one of two opposites which need a reconcihation. 
 (So Hegel, for example, appears to regard Protestantism as the 
 synthesis of the oppositions of Christianity, and as its highest 
 point, while Schelling opposes it as the "rehgion of Paul" to 
 the "religion of Peter," and looks forward to a "religion of 
 John" which shall unite the two.) Now which of these aspects 
 is the significant one for our purpose at any time cannot be 
 known if the term is looked at in isolation. We can only know 
 that we must take it as a synthesis by seeing that it does unite 
 and reconcile the opposition of the two terms that go before it. 
 That is to say, we can only ascertain its place in the series if 
 we have previously ascertained the places of the adjacent terms. 
 
 214. It would seem, then, that we can only hope to arrive 
 at a knowledge of any dialectic process, when we know, at least, 
 either the beginning or the end of the process as a fixed point. 
 For no other points can be fixed, unless those round them have 
 been fixed previously, and unless we get a starting-point in this 
 manner, we shall never be able to start at all. Now in the Logic 
 we do know the beginning and end. We know the beginning 
 before we start, and, although we do not know the end before 
 we start, yet, when we have reached it, we know that it must be 
 
238 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 the last category of the Logic. We know that the category of 
 Being must be the beginning, because it is the simplest of all 
 the categories. And we should defend this proposition, if it were 
 doubted, by showing that all attempts to analyse it into simpler 
 categories fail, while in any other category the idea of Being 
 can be discovered by analysis. Again, we know that the Absolute 
 Idea is the last of the categories because it does not develop 
 any contradiction, which will require a reconciliation in a higher 
 category. 
 
 215. We can determine in this way the highest and lowest 
 points of the Logic, because all the steps in the Logic are cate- 
 gories of pure thought, and all those categories are implicit in 
 every act of thought. All we have to do, in order to construct 
 the Logic, is to analyse and make explicit what is thus presented. 
 The subject-matter of the analysis can never be wanting, since 
 it is presented in every act of thought, (j^ut when we are trying 
 to discover, in a series of concrete facts, the successive manifesta- 
 tions of the pure Idea, the case is different J For these facts can 
 only be known empirically, and the further off they are in time 
 the more difficult they will be to remember or to predict. We 
 are situated at neither end of the process. Philosophy, religion, 
 history — all the activities whose course Hegel strives to demon- 
 strate — stretch backwards till they are lost in obscurity. Nor 
 are we yet at the end of any of them. Years go on, and new forms 
 of reality present themselves. And this is the first difficulty in 
 the way of our attempts to find the fixed points from which we 
 may start our dialectic. The beginnings of the series are too far 
 back to be remembered. The ends, so far as we can tell, are too 
 far forward to be foreseen. 
 
 216. And, even if we did happen to know the stage which 
 was, as a matter of fact, the first or the last of a dialectic process, 
 should we be able to recognise it as such on inspection? By the 
 hypothesis, its relation to the other terms of the process is not 
 yet known — for we are looking for an independent fixed point 
 in order that we may begin to relate the terms to one another. 
 And, since this is so, one term can, so far, only differ from the 
 others in expressing the Absolute Idea more or less adequately. 
 This is so far, therefore, only a quantitative difference, and thus, 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 239 
 
 below the lowest stage that we know, and above the highest 
 stage that we know, we can imagine others yet, so that our fixed 
 points are still not found. 
 
 If, indeed, each stage in each of the applications of the dialectic 
 clearly corresponded to some one category of the Logic, we might 
 know that the stage which corresponded to the category of Being 
 was the lowest, and that the stage which corresponded to the 
 Absolute Idea was the highest. But this is not the case. As has 
 been mentioned above, the stages in each of Hegel's applications 
 of the Logic are arranged, in some cases, on the same principle 
 as the categories of the Logic, but without any suggestion of 
 such definite correspondence. And so, until the mutual relations 
 of the stages are determined, they can only be distinguished by 
 quantitative differences which can never define the beginning 
 and end of their own series. 
 
 We cannot say of any stage, in any one of the applications 
 of the Logic, that it completely fails to embody the Absolute 
 Idea. For then, according to Hegel, it would have lost all sem- 
 blance of reality, and could not be given in experience. And, 
 if it does embody the Absolute Idea at all, we can always imagine 
 that something may exist which embodies that Idea still less 
 completely, still more abstractly. And so we can never be sure 
 that we have got to the right basis, from which our dialectic 
 process may start. Of course, such quantitative estimates are 
 succeeded by far deeper and more significant relations when 
 once the dialectic process is established. But these will not help 
 us here, where we are seeking the point on which to establish 
 the dialectic process. 
 
 217. In the Philosophy of Nature, indeed, the risk which we 
 run in taking space as our starting-point is perhaps not great. 
 For, since the process of Nature includes all reahty below the 
 level of Spirit, its lowest stage must be that at which reality 
 is on the point of vanishing altogether. And we may take space 
 as representing the absolute minimum of reality without much 
 danger of finding ourselves deceived. But it will be different in 
 dealing with religion, history, law, or philosophy, where the 
 lowest point of the particular process is still relatively concrete, 
 and leaves room for possible stages below it. 
 
240 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 And, except in the Philosophy of Spirit, the same may be 
 said of the highest stage in any process. In none of the applica- 
 tions of the dialectic but this can we hope to meet with a perfect 
 embodiment of the Absolute Idea. For all the other processes 
 deal only with an aspect of reality, and their realisation of the 
 Absolute Idea must be partial, and therefore imperfect. In no 
 religion, in no national spirit, or form of government, in no system 
 of metaphysics^, can we find a complete realisation of the Absolute 
 Idea. And so we are always in uncertainty lest some new stage 
 should arise in each of these activities, which should embody 
 the Absolute Idea a little less imperfectly than any yet known. 
 
 218. Let us consider this in more detail. In the first place, 
 although the Philosophy of Spirit has a well-defined end, and 
 the Philosophy of Nature a fairly certain beginning, yet it is 
 impossible to find a point at which it is certain that the Philo- 
 sophy of Nature ends, and the Philosophy of Spirit begins. What 
 form can we take as the lowest in which Spirit is present? The 
 series of forms is continuous from those which certainly belong 
 to Spirit to those which certainly belong to Nature. If we call 
 everjrthing Spirit, which has the germs of self-consciousness in 
 it, however latent, then we should have to include the whole 
 of Nature, since on Hegel's principles, the lower always has the 
 higher implicit in it. On the other hand, if we reserved the name 
 of Spirit for the forms in which anything like our own life was 
 explicit, we should have to begin far higher up than Hegel did, 
 and we should have the same difficulty as before in finding the 
 exact place to draw the line. 
 
 In the Philosophy of Religion, the points at each end of the 
 process seem uncertain. Might not something be found, by further 
 historical investigation, which was lower even than Magic, and 
 which yet contained the germ of religion, and ought to be treated 
 as a form of it? And at the other end of the series a similar doubt 
 
 ^ In the Philosophy of Spirit, Hegel says that Philosophy is the highest stage 
 of Spirit. But it is clear that Philosophy must here mean more than the existence 
 of a system of metaphysics held by professed metaphysicians as a theory. It 
 must be something which is universally accepted, and which modifies all spiritual 
 life. The highest point which could be reached in such a History of Philosophy 
 as Hegel's would leave much to be done before Spirit had reached its full develop- 
 ment. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 241 
 
 occurs. It is clear, from the Philosophy of Spirit, that Hegel 
 regards Christianity, like all other forms of "revealed religion," 
 as in some degree an inadequate representation of the Absolute 
 Idea. How can his system guard against the possibility that a 
 yet more perfect reUgion may arise, or against the possibility 
 that Christianity may develop into higher forms? Hegel would 
 probably have answered that the Philosophy of Religion has 
 demonstrated Christianity to be the synthesis of all other 
 religions. But if, as we have seen reason to think, the relations 
 of the stages cannot be accurately determined, until one end at 
 least of the series has been independently fixed, we cannot rely 
 on the relation of the stages to determine what stage is to be 
 taken as the highest, beyond which no other is possible^. 
 
 219. In the History of Philosophy we find the same difficulty. 
 Hegel begins his systematic exposition with Thales, excluding 
 all Oriental philosophy. This distinction can scarcely be based 
 on any qualitative difference. The reason that Hegel assigns for 
 it is that seLf-consciousness was not free in the earlier systems^. 
 But in what sense is this to be taken? If implicit freedom is to 
 be taken into account, Hegel himself points out, in the Philo- 
 sophy of Religion, that the Oriental religions had the germ of 
 freedom in them. But if we are only to consider freedom in so 
 far as it is explicit, then we might find it difficult to justify the 
 inclusion of the earlier Greek philosophies, in which the idea of 
 freedom is still very rudimentary. 
 
 The end of the History of Philosophy, as expounded by Hegel, 
 is his own philosophy. Yet since his death several new systems 
 have already arisen. There is no ground to attribute to Hegel 
 any excessive degree of self-confidence. The system in which 
 anyone believes fully and completely will always appear to him 
 the culminating point of the whole process of philosophy. For 
 it has solved for him all the contradictions which he has perceived 
 in former systems, and the fresh contradictions which are latent 
 in it cannot yet have revealed themselves to him, or he would 
 
 1 This criticism does not apply to Hegel's demonstration of the nature of 
 Absolute Religion, which is really an attempt to determine the ultimate nature 
 of reality. (Cp. Section 208.) The difficulty arises when he tries to connect his 
 own idea of Absolute Religion with historical Christianity. 
 
 =' History of Philosophy, Vol. i. p. 117. (Vol. i. p. 99 of Haldane's translation.) 
 M.H. ' i6 
 
242 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 not have complete confidence in it. Thus it naturally seems to 
 him the one coherent system, and therefore the ultimate system. 
 But the appearance is deceptive, and we cannot regard with 
 confidence any theory of the growth of philosophical systems 
 which leaves no room for fresh systems in the future. 
 
 The Philosophy of Law has not quite the same difficulties to 
 meet, since it is rather an analysis of the functions of a state, 
 and of the ethical notions which they involve, than an attempt 
 to describe a historical progression. But it is significant that 
 it ends by demonstrating that the ideal form of government 
 was very like the one under which Hegel was living. There seems 
 no reason to suspect that he was influenced by interested motives. 
 The more probable supposition is that he had come to the con- 
 clusion that constitutional monarchy was the best possible form 
 of government for an European nation in 1820. This is a legitimate 
 opinion, but what is not legitimate is the attempt to lay down 
 a priori that it will always be the best possible form. No form 
 of government can completely embody the Absolute Idea, since 
 the idea of government, as we learn in the Philosophy of Spirit, 
 is itself but a subordinate one. And it is very difficult to predict 
 social changes which are still far distant. So Hegel passed to 
 the conclusion that the best which had appeared was the best 
 which could appear. He thus imposed on empirical variety an 
 d priori hmit, which was not critical but dogmatic, and liable 
 to be upset at any moment by the course of events. 
 
 220. In the Philosophy of History the contingency of the 
 starting-point is still plainer. He begins with China, it is clear, 
 only because he did not happen to know anything older. He 
 had indeed a right, by his own definition of history, to exclude 
 tribes of mere savages. But he could have no reason to assert 
 — and he did not assert — that, before the rise of Chinese civilisa- 
 tion, there was no succession of nation to nation, each with its 
 distinct character and distinct work, such as he traces in later 
 times. He did not know that there was such a succession, and 
 he could not take it into account. But this leaves the beginning 
 quite empirical. 
 
 And he admits in so many words that history will not stop 
 where his Philosophy of History stops. His scheme does not 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 243 
 
 include the Sclavonic races, nor the European inhabitants of 
 America. But he expressly says that the Sclavonic races may 
 have hereafter a place in the series of national developments, 
 and, still more positively, that the United States will have such 
 a place^. All attempt to fix the final point of history, or to put 
 limits to the development which takes place in it, is thus given 
 up. 
 
 In view of passages hke these, it would seem that there is not 
 much truth in Lotze's reproach, that modern Idealism confined 
 the spiritual development of the Absolute to the shores of the 
 Mediterranean^. In the first place Hegel speaks only of this 
 planet, and leaves it quite open to us to suppose that the Absolute 
 Idea might be realised in other developments elsewhere. It is 
 scarcely fair, therefore, to charge such a philosophy with ignoring 
 the discoveries of Copernicus. And, as to what does happen on 
 the earth, Hegel devotes a large — perhaps disproportionately 
 large — part of the Philosophies of Religion and History to China 
 and India, which do not lie very near the Mediterranean. We 
 have seen also that he reahsed that room must be left for the 
 development of Russia and the United States. 
 
 221. It appears, then, that of all the terminal points of the 
 different applications of the dialectic, only two can be indepen- 
 dently recognised, so as to give us the fixed points which we 
 find to be necessary in constructing the processes. These are 
 at the beginning of the Philosophy of Nature, and at the end 
 of the Philosophy of Spirit. Now Nature and Spirit, taken 
 together, form the chief and all-embracing process reaching 
 from the most superficial abstraction to the most absolute reahty, 
 in which the evolution of society, of religion, and of philosophy 
 are only episodes. And it may at first sight seem improbable 
 that we should be able to determine, with comparative certainty, 
 the two points most remote from our present experience — the 
 one as the barest of abstractions, the other as absolute and almost 
 unimaginable perfection — while points less remote are far more 
 obscure. But further reflection shows us that it is just because 
 these points are the extremes of all reality that they are 
 
 1 Philosophy of History, pp. 360, and 83. (pp. 363 and 90 of Sibree's trans- 
 lation.) 2 Metaphysic. Section 217. 
 
 1 6 — 2 
 
244 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 comparatively determinable. Of the first we know that it must 
 be that aspect of reality which, of all conceivable ways of looking 
 at reality, is the least true, the least significant, the least adequate 
 to the Absolute Idea. Of the second we know that it must be 
 a conception of reality in which the Absolute Idea is expressed 
 with perfect adequacy. We have thus the power, since the Logic 
 tells us the nature of the Absolute Idea, to anticipate to some 
 degree the nature of the first and last terms in the main process 
 of reality. We may be justified in recognising Space as the one, 
 and in predicting more or less what is to be expected in the other. 
 But in the subordinate processes of History, Law, Religion and 
 Philosophy, the highest and lowest points are not highest and 
 lowest absolutely, but only the highest and lowest degrees of 
 reality which can be expressed in a society, a creed, or a meta- 
 physical system. How low or how high these can be, we can 
 only know empirically, since this depends on the nature of 
 societies, of creeds, and of systems, all of which contain empirical 
 elements^. And if it can only be known empirically, it can never 
 be known certainly. We can never be sure that the boundaries 
 we place are not due to casual limitations of our actual know- 
 ledge, which may be broken down in the immediate future. 
 
 And so there is nothing mysterious or suspicious in the fact 
 that many philosophers would be quite prepared to predict, 
 within certain limits, the nature of Heaven, while they would 
 own their philosophy quite incompetent to give any information 
 about the probable form of local government which will prevail 
 in London one hundred years hence. For on such a theory as 
 Hegel's we should know that in Heaven the Absolute Idea was 
 completely and adequately manifested. But of the government 
 of London we should only know that, like all earthly things, it 
 would manifest the Absolute Idea to some extent, but not com- 
 pletely. And to determine, by the aid of the dialectic, how much 
 
 1 The subject-matter of metaphysical systems is, no doubt, pure thought. 
 But the circumstances which determine that a particular view shall be held at 
 a particular time and in a particular shape are to a large extent contingent and 
 only to be known empirically. Nor can we determine by pure thought how large 
 an element in the complete perfection of Spirit consists in correct views on general 
 questions of metaphysics — or in other words, what is the relation of the process 
 given in the History of Philosophy to the main process of Spirit. 
 
vu] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 245 
 
 and in what form it would manifest it, we should have to begin 
 by determining the position of the municipal organisation of 
 London in 1996 in a chain which stretches from the barest 
 possible abstraction to the fullest possible reaUty, This we cannot 
 do. Philosophers are in much the same position as Mr Kipling's 
 muleteer — 
 
 "We know what heaven and hell may bring, 
 But no man knoweth the mind of the king^." 
 
 For they are on firmer ground in theology than in sociology. 
 And perhaps there is not much to regret in this. 
 
 222. We_ must now. passi on to a second defect in Hegel's 
 appUcation of his Logic to experience. The difficulty of fixing 
 the first and last points in the dialectic process is not the only 
 obstacle in our way. Much of Hegel's work, as we have seen, 
 consisted in applying the dialectic process to various special 
 fields — to Religion, to History, to Law, and to Philosophy. Now 
 in doing this, he is in each case dealing with only one aspect of 
 reality, leaving out of account many others. Can we expect such 
 a fragment of reality^.taken-hyjitafilf, -tQj3£Lan_example--oi-the 
 
 dialectiQ4irQ£esS? T^ si rip nf rpalit y pan be. rp.fl.lly ygo la-tad-ff^^fn 
 
 ajl the^others, and, u nless we fall in to q"ite r false aibstraction, 
 we^iust allow for the interaction of ^ very asp ect of reality: upian 
 every other aspect TKis is a truth which Hegel fully recognises, 
 and on which, indeed, he emphatically insists. For example, he 
 points out that the constitution possible for a country at any 
 time must depend on its character, and both History and Philo- 
 sophy are, in his exposition, closely connected with Rehgion. 
 
 But these various dialectical processes are not, according to 
 Hegel, synchronous. Philosophy, for example, begins for him 
 in Greece, which in historical development is already in the 
 second stage. History, again, begins for him in China, whose 
 religion on the other hand represents an advance on primitive 
 simphcity. If, then, these three processes react on one another, 
 it follows that the spontaneous development of each according 
 to the dialectic will be comphcated and obscured by an indefinite 
 number of side influences introduced from other aspects of reaUty 
 then in difierent stages. It is true that everything which 
 
 ^ The Ballad of the King^s Jest. 
 
!^ 
 
 
 -^ W 246 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 ■^ influences, like that wliich is influenced, is obeying the same law 
 
 ^ of the dialectic. But still the result will not exhibit that law. 
 
 ''' ii ^ , Suppose a hundred pianos were to play the same piece of music, 
 
 p^ ^. 1^ >:. each beginning a few seconds after its neighbour, while the length 
 
 ^ ^ I ^ «^ of these intervals was unequal and regulated by no principle. 
 
 "T T% T* The effect on the ear, when all the hundred had started, would 
 
 ^tr s^ \, he one of mere confusion, in spite of the fact that they were all 
 
 ^ "3^ ^ playing the same piece. 
 
 jjf jj!I ^ 223. 'The same difficulty will not occur in the process of 
 
 ■^ ^ o Nature and Spirit. For this relates, not to one side of reality 
 
 ^ O SjC only, but to the whole of it, and there are therefore no influences 
 
 "*■ *«A^ •«-- '-^ from outside to be considered. But there is an analogous difficulty, 
 ■"^"^ %^ ^ & J ' 
 
 "^ j^ Q J and an equally serious one. 
 
 44^ Si> .^ It is a fact, which may perhaps be explained, but which 
 
 ^** »L* Ck, cannot be disputed, that, if we consider the world as a dialectic 
 
 . ^ ft/ process, we shall find, when we look at it sub specie temforis, 
 
 
 
 ^ 
 
 that its different parts are, at any moment, very unequally 
 
 advanced in that process. One part of the world is explicitly 
 
 *<^ ^ O > Spirit, another part is that implicit form of Spirit which we call 
 
 ^ I^ t~" ^^ Matter. One creature is a jelly-fish, and another is a man. One 
 
 <icr ^ man is Shakespeare, and another is Blackmore. Now these 
 
 ..^ ^ yl. different parts of the world will react on one another, and, since 
 
 ^ y^ they are engaged in different parts of the process, and we cannot 
 
 ^ -J ^ tU trace any system in their juxtaposition, the course of the dia- 
 
 Uii "^ - - lectic will be altered in each case, as it was in Religion, History, 
 
 IS? o d^'' and Philosophy, by the influence of various other forces, them- 
 
 j^p. ^ selves obeying the same law of the dialectic, but producing, by 
 
 casual and contingent interactions, a result in which it will be 
 
 impossible to trace the dialectic scheme. 
 
 If, for example, we try to follow the working of the dialectic 
 process in the lives of individual men, we find that one of the 
 most prominent facts in the life of each man is his death at a 
 certain time. Whatever importance death may have for his 
 spiritual development, it is obviously all-important to our power 
 of explaining his spiritual development, since with death we 
 lose sight of him. Now it is but seldom that death comes as 
 a consequence or even as a symbol of something significant in 
 a man's spiritual history. It generally comes from some purely 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 247 
 
 material cause — an east wind, a falling tile, or a weak heart. 
 And this is only the most striking of the innumerable cases in 
 which our spiritual nature is conditioned and constrained by 
 outside facts, which may be developing along their own paths, 
 but which, as regards that spiritual nature, must be looked on 
 as purely arbitrary. 
 
 And if the dialectic cannot be observed in the individual, 
 owing to these external disturbances, we shall not be more 
 successful in tracing it accurately in the race as a whole. In 
 the first place, material causes — the Black Death, for example, 
 — often produce results on the spiritual development of nations, 
 or of the civihsed world. And, secondly, the development of the 
 race must manifest itself in individuals, and if it is hampered 
 in each of them by material conditions, it will not exist at all, 
 free from those conditions. This could only be denied on the 
 supposition that, if we took a sufficient number of cases, the 
 results of the external influences would cancel one another, 
 leaving the inherent development of spirit unchecked. This would, 
 however, be a pure assumption, and not likely, as far as we can 
 judge at present, to be in accordance with the facts. For the 
 influence which material causes have on the development of 
 Spirit has a distinctive character, and its effects are more probably 
 cumulative than mutually destructive. 
 
 224. Of course anyone who accepts Hegel's Logic must 
 believe that the nature of the Absolute, taken as a whole, is 
 entirely rational, and that, consequently, all the facts of ex- 
 perience are really manifestations of reason, however irrational 
 and contingent they may appear. But this takes us back to the 
 other practical use of Hegel's philosophy, which we admitted 
 as valid, namely, that it will assure us, on general grounds, that 
 everything must be rational, without showing us how particular 
 things are rational. It will not alter the fact that if we are trying 
 to explain how the various facts of any particular kind are 
 rational, by tracing their dialectical connection with one another, 
 we shall fail in so far as they are influenced by the facts which 
 are not part of that chain, however sure we may be on general 
 grounds that they, like everything else, must be rational. 
 
 The only way in which we could get a dialectic process, deahng 
 
248 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 with actual facts, secure from extraneous influences, would be 
 to trace the connection of the state of the whole universe, taken 
 sub specie temforis, at one moment of time, with the state of 
 the whole universe at some subsequent moment. This, of course, 
 could not be done, unless we knew what the state of the whole 
 universe at one particular moment really was, which is obviously 
 impossible, since, to mention only one point, our knowledge is 
 almost entirely confined to this planet. 
 
 We have found so far, then, that the attempts to trace the 
 dialectic process, as it manifests itself in Religion, Law, History, 
 or Philosophy, suffered under two defects. In the first place, we 
 could not hope to find the fixed points which were necessary 
 before we could begin to construct the dialectic, and, in the 
 second place, the course of the dialectic process must be con- 
 tinually disturbed by external causes. With regard to the main 
 process of Nature and Spirit, we found that it might be free 
 from the first fault, but not from the second. 
 
 225. I need only touch on a third obstacle which presents 
 itself. This consists in the extent and intricacy of the subject- 
 matter which must be known, and unified by science, before we 
 can hope to interpret it by means of the dialectic. The hindrance 
 rhich this throws in the way of Hegel's purpose has perhaps 
 been overestimated by his opponents. For they have represented 
 him as trying to deduce, and not merely to explain, the facts 
 of experience. And they have exaggerated the extent to which 
 he believed himself to have succeeded in making his system 
 complete^. But after allowing for all this, it must be admitted 
 that the task which Hegel did undertake was one which often 
 required more knowledge of facts than he had, or than, perhaps, 
 can be obtained. This difficulty is least prominent in Religion 
 and Philosophy, where the facts to be dealt with are com- 
 paratively few and easy of access. It is most prominent in the 
 Philosophy of Nature, which, as we saw, was comparatively 
 fortunate in being able to fix its starting-point with tolerable 
 certainty. The abuse which has been heaped on this work is 
 probably excessive. But it cannot be denied that it has a certain 
 amount of justification. 
 
 1 Cp. Section 220. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 249 
 
 226. We seem thus reduced to a state of almost complete 
 scepticism as to the value of Hegel's applications of the dialectic, 
 taken as systems. We may continue to regard as true the idea 
 of the evolution, by inherent necessity, of the full meaning of 
 reality, since that follows from the Logic. But Hegel's magni- 
 ficent attempt to trace the working of that evolution through 
 the whole field of human knowledge must be given up. 
 
 Must we give up with it all attempts to apply the conclusions, 
 so hardly won in the Logic, to our present experience, and con- 
 tent ourselves with the information that they can give us as to 
 Absolute Reality seen in its full completeness? It seems to me 
 that we need not do so, and that experience, as we have it now, 
 may be interpreted by means of the dialectic in a manner possibly 
 not less useful, though less ambitious, than that which Hegel 
 himself attempted. 
 
 We saw that two of the difficulties in the way of Hegel's 
 scheme were the multiplicity of the details, which are found in 
 any subject-matter as given in experience, and the fact that the 
 different chains of the dialectic process acted irregularly on one 
 another, so that none of them remained symmetrical examples 
 of the dialectic development. Now both these difficulties would 
 be avoided, if, instead of trying to trace the dialectic process 
 in actual events, which are always many-sided, and influenced 
 from outside, we tried to trace such a process in some of the 
 influences at work on these events, taken in abstraction from 
 other influences. 
 
 For example, it would probably be impossible to trace a 
 dialectic process in the moral history of any man or nation, 
 except in a few prominent features. For the causes which 
 determine moral development are indefinitely complex, and 
 many of them have themselves no moral significance. A man's 
 moral nature is affected by his own intellectual development, 
 by his relations with other men, and by his relations with material 
 things. All these causes, no doubt, also move in dialectic pro- 
 cesses, but they are not processes in unison with the process of 
 his moral nature, and so they prevent it exhibiting an example 
 of the dialectic movement. A man may have committed a sin 
 of which, by the inner development of his own will, he would 
 
 :)^ 
 
250 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 soon come to repent. But if, through some disease, he loses his 
 memory shortly after committing the sin, his repentance may, 
 to say the least, be indefinitely postponed. 
 
 Difiiculties like these arise whenever our subject-matter is 
 concrete moral acts, which have always other aspects besides 
 that of their moral quahty, and which are affected by many 
 circumstances that are not moral acts. Let us now consider what 
 would be the case if we took comparatively abstract moral 
 qualities — e.g. Innocence, Sin, Punishment, Repentance, Virtue. 
 Between these there would be a much greater chance of dis- 
 covering some dialectic connection. By considering abstract 
 qualities we save ourselves, in the first place, from the com- 
 plexity caused by the indefinite multiphcity of particulars which 
 are to be found in any given piece of experience. For we deal 
 only with those characteristics which we have ourselves selected 
 to deal with. And, in the second place, we escape from the 
 difficulties caused by the intrusion of outside influences. For we 
 are not considering what does happen in any actual case, but 
 what would happen if all but a given set of conditions were ex- 
 cluded, or, to put it in another way, what influence on actual 
 facts a certain force tends to exert when taken by itself. We 
 abstract, in the case given above, from all aspects of actions 
 except their morality, and we abstract from all causes which 
 influence action, except the deliberate moral choice of the agent. 
 In the same way, every moving body is under the influence of 
 • an indefinite number of forces. But it is possible to isolate two 
 
 i of them, and to consider how the body would move if only those 
 
 two forces acted upon it. The result, in its abstraction, will not 
 apply exactly to any concrete case, but it may render us im- 
 portant aid in explaining and influencing concrete cases. 
 
 The third difficulty which met us in deahng with Hegel's own 
 applications of the dialectic was the impossibility of determining 
 the relation of the various stages to one another, unless we knew 
 the beginning or the end of the process beforehand, which we 
 seldom did. This difficulty does not arise in our proposed abstract 
 appHcations of the dialectic, on account of their comparatively 
 humble aim. There is no attempt here, as there was before, to 
 construct even a part of the chain of stages which reaches from 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 251 
 
 beginning to end of the whole temporal process. We only assert 
 that, when a certain number of abstract terms are taken in 
 connection with one another, they stand in certain relations 
 which are an example of the dialectic movement. Here we are 
 sure of our starting-point, because we have made it ourselves. 
 
 227. The best example of such an application of the dialectic 
 method, which is to be found in Hegel's own work, is his theory 
 of Sin, referred to above. It is rather implied than directly 
 stated, but, if we compare his treatment of the subject in the 
 Philosophy of Spirit and in the Philosophy of Religion, it appears 
 that he regards Innocence (Unschuldigkeit) and Virtue as the 
 thesis and synthesis of a triad, whose antithesis consists of a 
 subordinate triad, of which the terms are Sin, Punishment, and 
 Repentance. 
 
 This process gains, of course, its simplicity, its independence 
 of external influences, and its fixed starting-point, merely by 
 abstraction — the only way in which definiteness can ever be 
 gained in our present state of imperfect knowledge. And there- 
 fore, like every result gained by abstraction, it is more or less 
 inapplicable to the concrete facts. Its value must depend on its 
 being applicable sufficiently often, and with sufficient exactitude, 
 to make it practically useful. This is the case with all abstrac- 
 tions. No one, for example, ever acted exclusively from purely 
 economic motives, but most people act from them enough to 
 make it worth while to work out what would happen if every one 
 always did so. On the other hand it would not be worth while 
 to work out what would happen if every one desired to suffer as 
 much bodily pain as possible, because few people are greatly 
 influenced by such a desire. 
 
 Now the conditions of Hegel's dialectic of virtue do occur in 
 life sufficiently often and •mth sufficient exactitude to make the 
 knowledge we have gained by the abstraction practically valuable. 
 For whenever men are acting so that their acts have a moral 
 quality — and this is almost always the case — then the moral 
 aspect of a particular action will be one of the most important 
 of the factors which determine whether it shall, under given 
 circumstances, take place or not, and what its results will be, 
 if it does take place. And so the relation which exists between 
 
252 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 the moral aspects of actions and mental states will afford us, 
 in many instances, materials for explaining those actions and 
 states with sufl&cient accuracy, although, resting on abstraction, 
 it will never succeed in giving a complete explanation of the 
 facts in any actual case, and in some cases will give us scarcely 
 any help in explaining them. 
 
 228. Another relation of abstract terms which can often throw 
 great light on experience is that which is sometimes summed 
 up in the maxim, Die to live. Here the thesis is the possession 
 or assertion of something good in itself, while the antithesis is 
 the abandonment or the denial of that good, on account of some 
 defect or narrowness in the statement of the thesis. The synthesis, 
 again, is the enjoyment of the original good in a deeper and 
 better way, when the defect has been purged out by the discipline 
 of the antithesis. As an abstraction, this relation can never 
 express the whole nature of any event. That which, from one 
 point of view, is positive, may from another be negative, and 
 from a third be a reconciUation of two extremes. But when, as 
 often happens, we are looking at things from one limited point 
 of view, and temporarily ignoring others, the arrangement of 
 our subject-matter upon such a scheme may be very valuable. 
 
 229. But, after all, the main practical interest of Hegel's 
 philosophy does not lie in such interpretations, useful and 
 suggestive as they are. It is rather to be found in the abstract 
 certainty which the Logic gives us that all reality is rational 
 and righteous, even when we cannot in the least see how it is so, 
 and also in the general determination of the nature of true reality, 
 which we saw above was a legitimate consequence of the Logic^. 
 In other words, when we ask of what value philosophy is, apart 
 from the value of truth for its own sake, we shall find that it 
 lies more in the domains of religion than in those of science or 
 practice. Its importance is not that it shows us how the facts 
 around us are good, not that it shows us how we can make them 
 better, but that it proves, if it is successful, that they, like all 
 other reality, are, sub specie aeternitatis, perfectly good, and, sub 
 specie temforis, destined to become perfectly good. 
 
 The practical value of the dialectic, then, lies in the demonstra- 
 
 1 Sections 208, 209. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 253 
 
 tion of a general principle, which can be carried into particulars 
 or used as a guide to action, only in a very few cases, and in those 
 with great uncertainty. In saying this we shall seem at first sight 
 to deny that the dialectic has really any practical use at all. But 
 reflection may convince us that the effect of philosophy on re- 
 ligion is quite as practical, and perhaps even more important, than 
 the effect which it might have exercised on science and conduct, 
 if Hegel's applications of the dialectic could have been sustained. 
 
 That the effect on religion is one which we are entitled to 
 consider of practical, and not merely of theoretical interest, was 
 pointed out above^. For, through religion, philosophy will in- 
 fluence the happiness of those who accept its theories, and nothing 
 can have more immediate practical interest than any cause which 
 increases or diminishes happiness. 
 
 230. We may go, I think, even further than this. It is more 
 important, for our general welfare, to be able to apply philosophy 
 to religion, than to science and conduct. We must consider that 
 the general conviction of the rationahty and righteousness of 
 the universe must be reached by philosophy, or else not reached 
 at all — at least as a matter of reasoning. Now the application 
 of the dialectic to the particular facts is not indispensable in 
 the same way. It is true that it is essential to life, and to all 
 that makes life worth having, that we should be able to some 
 extent to understand what goes on round us, and should have 
 some rules by which we can guide our conduct. And, no doubt, 
 it would assist us in both these terms if we could succeed in 
 tracing the manifestations of the dialectic process in the facts 
 around us, and in anticipating the facts in which it will be mani- 
 fested in the future. But still, for these aims, the aid of the 
 dialectic is not essential. The finite sciences can explain the facts 
 of our life, incompletely, indeed, and imperfectly, but still to a 
 great extent, and to an extent which is continually increasing. 
 And we shall find in common sense, and in the general principles 
 of ethics, the possibility of pursuing a coherent and reasonable 
 course of action, even if we do not know the precise position at 
 which we are in the dialectic process towards the perfection which 
 is the goal of our efforts. 
 
 1 Section 209. 
 
254 THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC [ch. 
 
 Here, then, philosophy would be, from the practical point of 
 view, useful, but not necessary. But its importance with regard 
 to religion is greater. We cannot observe that all reahty is rational 
 and righteous as a fact of experience, nor can we make it rational 
 and righteous by any act of ours. If we do believe that it is so, 
 it must either be by some reasoning which falls within the juris- 
 diction of philosophy, or by the acceptance of some form of what 
 Hegel calls Revealed Religion. Now, without considering whether 
 the acceptance of the latter is justifiable or not, it cannot be 
 denied that the number of people to whom it does not seem 
 justifiable is always considerable, and shows no marked signs 
 of diminishing. And many of those who do accept some form 
 of Revealed ReUgion, base their belief in large measure on a con- 
 viction, reached by philosophical methods, that the rationality 
 and righteousness of the universe are antecedently probable, or, 
 at all events, not antecedently improbable^. 
 
 Our religious views then, if challenged, — and they do not often 
 pass now-a-days without being challenged — rest to a larger and 
 larger extent on philosophical arguments. The practical impor- 
 tance of religious views — one way or the other — to the world's 
 happiness, is likely to increase rather than to diminish. For, as 
 increasing wealth and civilisation set a greater proportion of 
 mankind free from the constant pressure of mere bodily wants, 
 the pressure of spiritual needs becomes more clearly felt, and is 
 increased by every advance which is made in intelligence and 
 culture. The more we succeed in removing such of the evils and 
 limitations of life as can be removed, the more clearly do those 
 which cannot be removed reveal themselves, and the more im- 
 perative becomes the demand for some assurance that these also 
 are transitory, and that all things work together for good. Nor 
 does this tendency of our nature deserve to be called, as it often 
 is called, either selfish or abstract. H we care for virtue, we can 
 scarcely fail to be interested in the ultimate righteousness or 
 iniquity of the universe, as judged by our moral ideals. If 
 we care for the men and women we know, it seems not un- 
 natural that we should sometimes ask ourselves what — if 
 
 ^ Cp. Mr Balfour's Foundations of Belief, Part n., Chap. 4, and Part n^, 
 Chap. 5, Section v. 
 
vn] THE APPLICATION OF THE DIALECTIC 255 
 
 anything — will happen to them when their bodies have ceased 
 to exist. 
 
 I maintain, therefore, that we have reached a conclusion which 
 is not really sceptical, even as to the practical value of Hegel's 
 philosophy, when we reject his attempts to trace the manifes- 
 tations of the dialectic process in the particular facts of our 
 experience. For the more important of the practical effects of 
 philosophy is left untouched — more important, because here 
 philosophy is indispensable if the result is to be attained at all. 
 
 231. It may be objected that such a view as this is more than 
 a partial difference from Hegel, and that its abstractness violates 
 the whole spirit of his system. To say that we know of the 
 existence of a rationality and righteousness, which we are yet 
 unable to trace in detail in experience, may appear at first sight 
 to mean a trust in some other-worldly reality. Such a trust would 
 doubtless be completely opposed to the most fundamental prin- 
 ciples of Hegel's philosophy. But this objection misrepresents 
 the position. It is not asserted that the rational and righteous 
 reahty is something behind and separate from experience. On 
 the contrary, it is and must be perfectly manifested in that 
 experience, which is nothing but its manifestation. But we do 
 not see in detail how it is such a manifestation. Thus it is not 
 the reality which is abstract, but only our knowledge of it. And 
 this is not surprising, since all imperfect knowledge must be 
 abstract, and it is matter of common notoriety that our knowledge 
 is as yet imperfect. 
 
 Nor need we much regret such a limitation of the province 
 of philosophy. For if our present knowledge were completely 
 adequate to reality, reality would be most inadequate to our 
 ideals. It is surely at least as satisfactory a beHef, if we hold 
 that the highest object of philosophy is to indicate to us the 
 general nature of an ultimate harmony, the full content of which 
 it has not yet entered into our hearts to conceive. All true 
 philosophy must be mystical, not indeed in its methods, but in 
 its final conclusions. 
 
 PRINTED IN ENGLAND AT THE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS 
 
tfnrTC" '!-♦ 'x -■ 
 
 RETURN CIRCULATION DEPARTMENT 
 
 TO— #^ 202 Main Library 
 
 LOAN PERIOD 1 
 - HOME USE 
 
 2 3 
 
 4 
 
 5 6 
 
 ALL BOOKS NVAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS 
 
 1 -month loans may be renewed by colling 642-3405 
 
 6-month loans may be recharged by bringing books to Circulation Desk 
 
 Renewals and recharges may be made 4 days prior to due dote 
 
 DUE AS STAMPED BELOW 
 
 8K.CIR.APR5 -gg 
 
 
 
 APR 8 2004 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY 
 FORM NO. DD6, 60m, 12/80 BERKELEY CA 94720 
 
 1 ®s 
 
 ( 
 
 G4427Siu>'*"^^ 
 
 
U.C.BERKELEY LIBRARIES 
 
 CDMb7afl^31 
 
 58347i 
 
 LgM4 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY 
 
r.