UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN OIEGO 
 
 3 1822 01583 6927 
 
 Central University Library 
 
 University of California. San Diego 
 Note: This item is subiect to recall after two weeks. 
 
 Date Due 
 
 UCSD Lib.
 
 ^ 
 
 \ 
 
 UN'S*?' ST,' O-
 
 A HISTORY 
 
 OF 
 
 ENGLISH UTILITARIANISM 
 
 ERNEST ALBEE, Ph.D. 
 
 INSTRUCTOR IN THE SAGE SCHOOL OF FHILOSOPHV, CORNELL UNIVERSITY 
 
 LONDON 
 SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO., LTD. 
 
 NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN CO. 
 1902
 
 LI BRJu*^ 
 
 S C R » P^^^-^T\S T I T U T I O N 
 
 O F "'Dt?f55«V '^ O GR A P H Y 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CAL/KORNIA 
 
 LA JOLLA. CMJLuTpOftNiA
 
 Zo tbe /iDemor^ 
 
 OF 
 
 S. A. AND R. P. A. 
 
 B 
 
 IS! 
 A3
 
 PREFACE. 
 
 Nobody would deny that the History of Ethics is a very 
 essential part of the History of Philosophy, and, so far as 
 ethical theories have formed an organic part of the general 
 systems of ancient and modern philosophers, they may be 
 said to have received due recognition at the hands of the 
 historian. But, as the general tendency of English thought 
 has been (or for a long time was) practical rather than 
 speculative, it has happened, not unfortunately, that the 
 progress of ethical theory in England has, on the whole, 
 been less involved with the rise and decadence of definite 
 systems of Metaphysics than has been the case on the 
 continent. Problems belonging distinctly to Ethics have 
 for the most part been discussed on their own merits — 
 except, perhaps, where theological issues have been raised. 
 And if English philosophers have not always put forth 
 the profoundest theories regarding the nature and meaning 
 of morality, they have at least done inestimable service in 
 the way of clear thinking and consistent reasoning. 
 
 Now the result of this comparatively non-metaphysical 
 character of English Ethics is that it has by no means 
 taken its true place in the general History of Philosophy. 
 Properly speaking, we have no history of English Ethics. 
 Dr. Whewell, indeed, published in 1852 his Lectures on the 
 History of Moral Philosophy in England ; but this book 
 was hardly calculated to serve more than a temporary 
 purpose. It everywhere shows marks of haste, as might
 
 vi Preface. 
 
 perhaps be expected from its mode of composition, and 
 the writer is so concerned to refute theories incompatible 
 with his own, that his expositions, even aside from their 
 necessary brevity, are generally unsatisfactory and some- 
 times quite misleading. A very different book is Professor 
 Sidgwick's Outlines of the History of Ethics for English 
 Readers, first published in i886. This is all that a mere 
 ' outline ' could very well be ; but, when it is considered 
 that Chapter iv. of this little volume, on " Modern, Chiefly 
 English, Ethics," is only about one hundred pages long, 
 it will readily be seen that it does not by any means 
 pretend to be an adequate history of the subject. Other 
 ' outlines ' might be mentioned, such as the interesting 
 one contained in Professor Wundt's Ethik ; but none of 
 these really supply, or pretend to supply, a need which 
 we doubtless all feel. 
 
 Since, then, we have no adequate history of English 
 Ethics, the attempt has been made in this volume to 
 cover a part of the ground by tracing the rise and de- 
 velopment of Utilitarianism in England. No one of the 
 writers considered — not even Hume or Mill — is individ- 
 ually of such importance for English Ethics as Bishop 
 Butler ; but, taken as a whole, Utilitarianism may fairly 
 be regarded as England's most characteristic, if not most 
 important, contribution to the development of ethical theory. 
 This being the case, its history certainly deserves careful 
 and somewhat extended treatment. The author hopes 
 that, whatever may be the shortcomings of the following 
 chapters, he will not be accused of treating the subject 
 either carelessly or in a partisan spirit. The greater 
 part of the matter of the first five chapters has al- 
 ready appeared as a series of articles in the Philo- 
 sophical Review (published from May, 1895, to July, 1897), 
 and for the privilege of using here the matter of those
 
 Preface. vii 
 
 chapters, in a somewhat extended and otherwise modified 
 form, the author is indebted to the editors and publishers 
 of the Review. The remaining chapters of the book 
 appear for the first time, except the first section of the final 
 chapter, as indicated in the text. A paper based upon 
 the manuscript of that part of the chapter was read before 
 the American Psychological Association, at the Baltimore 
 Meeting, December, 1900, and was afterwards printed in the 
 Philosophical Review. 
 
 Cornell University, 
 May, 1901.
 
 CONTENTS. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 Introduction xi 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 Richard Cumberland i 
 
 CHAPTER n. 
 
 Richard Cumberland {continued) 28- 
 
 CHAPTER HI. 
 
 Shaftesbury and Francis Hutcheson : their Relation to Utili- 
 tarianism 52 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown 64 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 David Hume gi 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 David Hartley 113. 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 Abraham Tucker 130 
 
 CHAPTER VIII. 
 Abraham Tucker {continued) 146
 
 X Contents. 
 
 CHAPTER IX, 
 
 PAGE 
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Bentham 165 
 
 CHAPTER X. 
 John Stuart Mill 191 
 
 CHAPTER XI. 
 John Stuart Mill {continued) 219 
 
 ' CHAPTER XII. 
 John Stuart Mill {continued) 242 
 
 CHAPTER XIII. 
 Herbert Spencer 268 
 
 CHAPTER XIV. 
 Herbert Spencer (continued) ......... 292 
 
 CHAPTER XV. 
 Herbert Spencer {continued) ......... 329 
 
 CHAPTER XVI. 
 Henry Sidgvvick 358 
 
 CHAPTER XVII. 
 Henry Sidgvvick {continued) 381 
 
 CHAPTER XVIII. 
 Henry Sidgvvick {continued) 400 
 
 Index 
 
 419
 
 INTRODUCTION. 
 
 The barbarous terminology employed in certain modern 
 systems of philosophy has often been censured, and with 
 considerable justice ; but the habit of using in a technical 
 sense words that already have a popular meaning, or words 
 that inevitably suggest others having a popular meaning, has 
 its own decided drawbacks. The technical use of the term 
 Utilitarianism, with which we shall constantly have to do in the 
 following chapters, partly illustrates this. Though first used by 
 one of the later exponents of Universahstic Hedonism, as 
 standing for that principle, it has never become entirely divested 
 of certain associations connected rather with the ordinary 
 meaning of the word ' utility,' and with the supposed practical 
 applications of the Utilitarian theory, than with the essential 
 logic of the theory itself. When one speaks of English Utili- 
 tarianism, therefore, it is not wholly evident, without explana- 
 tion, whether one mainly refers to a very important practical 
 movement of English thought, extending through the closing 
 years of the eighteenth century and about the first half of 
 the nineteenth century, or to a very familiar, to us probably 
 the most familiar, type of abstract ethical theory. 
 
 There is a reason for this confusion, which should not 
 be overlooked, even apart from the possible ambiguity 
 of the term Utilitarianism. Bentham and James Mill, 
 two of the three " English Utilitarians " to whom Mr. 
 Leslie Stephen devotes much the greater part of his very 
 interesting and valuable work bearing that title, were much 
 more interested in the supposed practical applications of the 
 theory of Utility than in the theory itself considered merely
 
 xii Introduction. 
 
 as belonging to Ethics as one of the philosophical disciplines. 
 In a less degree the same tendency may be traced in the writ- 
 ings of J. S. Mill, to whom the third volume of Mr. Stephen's 
 work is mainly devoted, though of the importance of his actual 
 contributions to philosophy proper there can be no serious 
 question. 
 
 Now it is this social and political side of the Utilitarian 
 movement that Mr. Stephen has had principally in view in 
 his admirable account of the " English Utilitarians ". A mere 
 examination of the analytical table of contents of his three 
 volumes would show how small a proportion is devoted to 
 theoretical Ethics. Yet the doctrine of Universalistic He- 
 donism, as Professor Sidgwick aptly termed it, had been 
 largely developed as an ethical theory proper before Bentham 
 wrote, and before he and the two Mills undertook to deduce 
 from it their characteristic views on society and government. 
 And though Utilitarianism as an ethical theory seems to have 
 lost ground, on the whole, during the past two or three 
 decades, it has certainly outlived the practical Utilitarian 
 movement referred to above, and still demands the thoughtful 
 consideration of all students of Ethics. 
 
 In truth, this is the one easily recognisable type of ethical 
 theory which has had both a perfectly continuous and a fairly 
 logical development from the beginnings of English Ethics 
 to tJie present time. Such being the case, it has seemed 
 worth while to trace its development in considerable detail 
 in the present volume. It must always be remembered that 
 we are here primarily concerned with the development of 
 an abstract type of ethical theory, and not with the practical 
 corollaries, social and political, which by some have been 
 supposed to result from the theory. It is important to keep 
 this in mind, for some of the greatest names connected with the 
 practical Utilitarian movement are of comparatively minor 
 consequence for the history of the development of Universal- 
 istic Hedonism considered merely as a type of ethical theory^.
 
 Introduction. xiii 
 
 while other names, almost forgotten in some instances, 
 assume an unexpectedly commanding position. 
 
 But, even within the sphere of theoretical Ethics, an impor- 
 tant distinction has often been made between so-called " Theo- 
 logical Utihtarianism " and non-Theological Utilitarianism. 
 It will be well to pause for a little, in order to note just what 
 this distinction reduces to. The term " Theological Utili- 
 tarianism " is itself rather misleading, as it almost inevitably 
 suggests an affinity with certain early forms of ethical theory 
 which regarded morality as depending upon the arbitrary will 
 of God. J. S. Mill himself was guilty of serious confusion 
 on this point in his early essay on Professor Sedgwick's 
 Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge 
 (1835), though he tacitly corrected his error three years 
 later in his well-known essay on Bentham. With less 
 justification, Mr. Spencer made practically the same mis- 
 take more than forty years afterward, in the chapter on 
 ■" Ways of Judging Conduct " in his Data of Ethics. 
 
 The true distinction may conveniently be indicated by 
 briefly comparing Paley and Bentham in a single respect. 
 The criterion of morality was the same for both. Actions 
 were regarded by both as right or wrong, because they made 
 for or against ' the greatest happiness of the greatest number ' ; 
 and the ' greatest happiness ' was taken by both to mean 
 the ' sum of pleasures,' with a consistent disregard of so-callLd 
 ' qualitative distinctions '. So far they agreed ; but Paley, 
 unlike Bentham, thought it necessary, not merely to mention, 
 but to lay very special stress upon the doctrine of rewards 
 and punishments after death, in order to prove that it is 
 for the ultimate interest of the hypothetically egoistic moral 
 agent to act for the common good. In so doing, he was 
 merely taking what had long been the characteristic position 
 of " Theological Utilitarianism ". More than half a century 
 before, the Rev. John Gay, in his anonymous Preliminary 
 Dissertation (173 1) prefixed to Law's translation of King's
 
 xiv Introduction. 
 
 Origin of Evil, had aptly defined obligation, from this point 
 of view, as " the necessity of doing or omitting any action 
 in order to be happy " ; and he had pertinently added that, 
 therefore, complete obligation can come only from the author- 
 ity of God, " because God only can in all cases make a man 
 happy or miserable ". 
 
 Now it is important to notice that this theory of obligation, 
 however far it may fall short of satisfying the general moral 
 and religious consciousness of the present day, was the logical 
 result of hedonism working itself out on the principles of 
 eighteenth century individualism. Bentham would have 
 found himself in the same logical predicament as the " Theo- 
 logical Utilitarians," if he had worked the problem out to 
 the end, instead of practically neglecting it. Certainly he 
 would have recognised our complete obligation to do what is 
 right and avoid what is wrong, and, since he was as much com- 
 mitted as the so-called " Theological Utilitarians " to the view 
 that the moral agent could ultimately will only his own 
 happiness, the very serious question would have arisen for 
 him as for them, whether the selfish interest of the individual 
 and the interest of society would coincide in each particular 
 case, leaving the possibility of a future life out of considera- 
 tion. It would have been no answer to say that, if it is not at 
 present for the interest of the individual to do right in all 
 cases, it ought to be made so by those very improvements in 
 legislation in which Bentham himself was primarily interested, 
 for even he could not have maintained that any general 
 enactments would meet all special cases. The plain truth is, 
 that if one begins by assuming an interest of the individual 
 separate from that of society, in the sense of typical 
 eighteenth century hedonism, one is logically driven to take 
 refuge in the doctrine of rewards and punishments after 
 death, in order to preserve the notion of our complete 
 obligation to do what is right and avoid what is wrong, which 
 all accredited moralists hold practically in common.
 
 Introduction. xv 
 
 In so-called " Theological Utilitarianism," then, we find a 
 theory of obligation based upon a theory of the moral motive 
 which, so far from being peculiar to that school, was the 
 conventional one during a large part of the eighteenth cen- 
 tury. This form of ethical theory, whatever may be its other 
 defects and shortcomings, does not gratuitously introduce 
 theological considerations, but reserves them for the solution 
 of a difficulty which could not otherwise be resolved — except 
 by giving up the individualistic theory of the moral motive 
 which had led to the theory of obligation itself. It thus 
 represents the almost inevitable tendency of the earlier form 
 of consistent Utilitarianism, i.e., Utilitarianism basing upon 
 the selfish theory of the moral motive. On the other hand, 
 nineteenth century Utilitarianism represents a constant, 
 though not uniformly successful, attempt to transcend this nar- 
 row theory of the moral motive, with the result that the Utili- 
 tarian theory of obligation has been profoundly modified, 
 and brought into much closer relation to the highest concrete 
 moral ideals. In truth, the degree of divergence between the 
 spirit of typical eighteenth century and typical nineteenth 
 century Utilitarianism can only be appreciated by those who 
 have traced the development of the theory with considerable 
 care. 
 
 One other problem should be kept in mind from the very 
 beginning, that of the so-called ' qualitative distinctions ' 
 between pleasures and pains. The frequent emphasis upon 
 ' happiness,' or even ' pleasure,' in early systems of Ethics is 
 not decisive, as indicating their hedonistic character, for some 
 kinds of happiness may be put on an entirely different plane 
 from others, being regarded as of greater intrinsic worth or 
 dignity, quite apart from the matter of intensity and duration. 
 It almost goes without saying that, in so far as such ' quaH- 
 tative distinctions ' are consciously emphasised, the system in 
 question departs from typical hedonism, and indeed, strictly 
 speaking, becomes differentiated from hedonism altogether;
 
 xvi Introduction. 
 
 for an ethical system cannot logically begin by affirming that 
 all moral values are to be computed in terms of pleasure, and 
 then add that pleasures themselves are of greater or less value, 
 not merely in terms of intensity and duration, but in propor- 
 tion as they involve something else distinct from pleasure. 
 At the same time, the explicit repudiation of ' qualitative dis- 
 tinctions ' by hedonistic writers naturally came somewhat 
 after they had practically adopted what was for them the 
 only consistent position, and hardly dates back as far as 
 the middle of the eighteenth century. 
 
 J. S. Mill's emphatic insistence upon ' qualitative distinc- 
 tions,' which was too flagrant an inconsistency to exert much 
 influence upon the further development of Utilitarianism, 
 was, nevertheless, rather more than a mere reversion to the 
 old confusion on the subject. It was one of those partly 
 unconscious, but logically important, concessions to Intuition- 
 ism, which we shall find to characterise, in very different ways, 
 the various forms of later Utilitarianism represented by the 
 ethical writings of Mill himself, of Mr. Spencer, and of Pro- 
 fessor Sidgwick. For it will appear, as we proceed with our 
 investigation, that the history of Utilitarianism exhibits two 
 fairly distinct phases : first, the gradual development of the 
 theory in the direction of formal consistency down to about 
 the beginning of the nineteenth century ; and secondly, the 
 later development, often at the expense of formal consistency, 
 but always in the direction of doing justice to the concrete 
 moral ideals which had been partly lost sight of in the earlier, 
 more abstract form of the theory. This later and larger de- 
 velopment of Utilitarianism, while particularly open to criti- 
 cism in detail, since it was always in some danger of over- 
 stepping its own first principles, is nevertheless one of the 
 most significant chapters in the History of Ethics, and con- 
 tains much that is still worthy of the thoughtful consideration 
 of those who are doing constructive work in Ethics at the 
 present time.
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 RICHARD CUMBERLAND, 
 
 While the doctrine of Utilitarianism has played a most con- 
 spicuous part in English Ethics since the time of Paley and 
 Bentham, it is not commonly realised that the essential 
 features of the system were roughly stated and in part de-^ 
 veloped by a contemporary of the Cambridge Platonists. It: 
 is true that Bishop Cumberland's treatise, De legibus naturae, 
 like most ethical works of the time, was largely controversial 
 in character, having been written to refute Hobbes. More- 
 over, the jural aspect of the system, implied by the very title 
 of the treatise, tends to obscure what for us is by far its most 
 important feature. And even this is not all. The ' common 
 good ' which Cumberland regarded as the end of all truly 
 moral action includes ' perfection ' as well as ' happiness,' 
 which leads to serious confusion in the working out of the 
 system. But, making all allowances for what was incidental 
 in the external form of the work, and for the confusion of two 
 principles which have long since become clearly differentiated, 
 it is well worth while to examine with some care the ablest, 
 or at any rate the most successful, opponent of Hobbes and 
 the true founder of English Utilitarianism. 
 
 It would be quite impossible adequately to treat of any im- 
 portant ethical system, without taking some account of the 
 views of the author's contemporaries ; but this is particularly 
 necessary in the case of early writers. In their works we are 
 almost sure to find in artificial combination principles which 
 are now regarded as logically distinct, and the only possible 
 explanation of the actual form of the system in question is 
 often to be sought in contemporary influences. Sometimes, 
 of coiirse, an investigation of this sort is difficult, and, however 
 
 I
 
 2 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 carefully prosecuted, yields no very certain results. Fortu- 
 nately we are not thus hampered in the case of Cumberland. 
 We shall find difficulty and uncertainty enough in certain 
 aspects of his system, but there is little doubt with regard to 
 the formative influences in his case. In his view of the nature 
 of man, Cumberland stands in the closest and most obvious 
 relation to Grotius and Hobbes — his relation to the former 
 being that of substantial agreement ; to the latter, that of 
 opposition. We must, then, consider in the briefest possible 
 way the ethical views of these two authors — particularly as 
 regards the then current conception of Laws of Nature — and 
 also notice the tendencies represented by the various opponents 
 of Hobbes. 
 
 The idea of Laws of Nature was, of course, by no means 
 original with Grotius. A Stoical conception at first, it had 
 exercised a profound influence upon Roman Law, and had 
 reappeared as an essential feature in the system of Thomas 
 Aquinas. Here, however, as Professor Sidgwick points out, 
 it " was rather the wider notion which belongs to Ethics than 
 the narrower notion with which Jurisprudence or Politics is 
 primarily concerned ".^ It is one of the most important ser- 
 vices of Grotius that he distinguished between the provinces 
 of Ethics and Jurisprudence, the result being as fortunate for 
 the former as for the latter.^ However, as Professor Sidg- 
 wick remarks, while the distinction is clearly enough made in 
 the body of his epoch-making work, De jure belli et pads, 
 still, in the general account which he gives of Natural Law, 
 the wider ethical notion is retained. It will be important for 
 the reader to keep this in mind. 
 
 In one of the earlier passages of the Prolegomena to his De 
 ■iure belli et pads, Grotius makes a significant statement regard- 
 ing his view of the nature of man. Among the properties 
 which are peculiar to man is a desire for society, and not only 
 so, but for a life spent tranquilly and rationally.^ The asser- 
 
 ^ Hist, of Ethics, p. 159. 
 
 '^See Jodl, Geschichte der Etkik, vol. I., p. 102. 
 
 'Whewell's ed., vol. I., p. xli.
 
 Richard Ctiniberland. 3 
 
 tion that by nature each seeks only his own advantage, cannot 
 be conceded. Even animals manifest an altruistic instinct in 
 caring for their young, while children show compassion at a 
 very early age. In adult man, that which in the lower stages 
 of development had manifested itself as instinctive altruistic 
 conduct, becomes self-conscious and rational. And this tend- 
 ency to the conservation of society is the source of ' Jus ' or 
 Natural Law, properly so called.^ Natural Law would remain 
 even if there were no God. But of the existence of God we 
 are assured, partly by reason, partly by constant tradition. 
 And here we are brought to another origin of * Jus,' i.e., the 
 free will of God. But even Natural Law, though it proceed 
 from the nature of man, may yet rightly be ascribed to God, 
 because it was by His will that such principles came to exist 
 in us.- 
 
 The relation between Natural Law and that which proceeds 
 from the arbitrary will of God is of some importance. Appar- 
 ently the latter is always in addition to the former, never in 
 contradiction with it,^ though it must be confessed that the 
 author's treatment is wavering. As Professor Sidgwick says,'* 
 according to Grotius Natural Law may be overruled in any 
 particular case by express revelation. It is to be noted, 
 however, that this does not mean that Natural Law, as such, 
 can be superseded by Divine Law, but rather that a special 
 act which would ordinarily be a transgression of Natural Law 
 may be right merely because God has commanded it. At best, 
 however, this seems to contradict the fundamental principles 
 of the system. But, apart from the question of a possible 
 conflict between Natural and Divine Law, there is a further 
 difficulty. Divine Law is what the name would indicate. 
 In the case of such law, it may be said : God did not command 
 the act because it was just, but it was just because God com- 
 manded it.° In the case of Natural Law, the reverse would 
 seem to hold true ; but the language of Grotius on this point 
 
 1 Whewell's ed., vol. I., p. xliv. -Ibid., p. xlvii. 
 
 ^ See, e.g., ibid., p. Ixxii. 
 
 * Hist, of Ethics, p. i6o. ^De jure, p. 20.
 
 4 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 is somewhat ambiguous. For instance, we have seen that 
 Natural Law may be ascribed to God, "because it was by 
 His will that such principles came to exist in us " ; but, on the 
 other hand, Grotius holds that just as God cannot make twice 
 two not be four, He cannot make that which is intrinsically 
 bad not to be bad.^ The undoubted confusion which one 
 finds here suggests the difficulty of mediating between the 
 views later represented by Descartes and by Cudworth : (i) 
 that moral distinctions depend upon the arbitrary will of God ; 
 and (2) that they do not thus depend. 
 
 From the above it will be seen that Grotius insists upon the 
 social and the rational nature of man. As to the proximate 
 (not ultimate) origin of Natural Law, there seems to be a slight 
 ambiguity. Now it appears to be founded upon the primitive 
 altruistic instinct, and now upon the rational nature of man.^ 
 Probably it would be fair to say that, according to Grotius, the 
 two are equally essential to human nature, which he regards as 
 logically prior to Natural Law, just as that is logically prior to 
 particular civil laws. The relation between Natural Law and 
 Divine Law has just been considered. Logically, the latter 
 should always be in addition to, never in conflict with, the 
 former. When Grotius practically does allow such conflict, we 
 must regard it as a natural, but not a necessary, concession to 
 theology. Again, the relation of God to Natural Law is not 
 quite clear. On the whole, however, Grotius would seem to 
 hold that certain things are right, others wrong, in the nature 
 of things, i.e., apart from the will of God. Whether the nature 
 of things be ultimately the same with the nature of God, we 
 do not here need to ask. The question would hardly have 
 occurred to Grotius. 
 
 When we turn to the writings of Hobbes, we are at once 
 confronted with a very different, and much more original, 
 system of thought ; but it is to be carefully noted that his 
 ethical and political philosophy is not so closely connected with 
 his mechanical philosophy as he himself would have had us 
 
 ' De jure, p. 12. 
 
 '■'C/. Cumberland, who probably follows Grotius here, as so often.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 5 
 
 believe. Certainly it is quite comprehensible by itself. In- 
 deed, in the course of his expositions, Hobbes ordinarily refers 
 to common experience rather than to his own first principles. 
 The starting-point of his ethical speculation is probably to 
 be found in the then current conception of Laws of Nature, ^ 
 which we have just been considering. This will be assumed 
 to be the case in what follows. 
 
 In order fully to understand Hobbes's view of the nature of 
 man, we must distinguish (i) man's need oi society; (2) his 
 fitness for society ; and (3) his love of society, for its own 
 sake, (i) That man has need of society — in the sense of an 
 organised commonwealth — Hobbes would have been the first 
 to insist. Out of society, indeed, man cannot continue to 
 exist at all. But (2) man's fitness for society does not by any 
 means keep pace with his need of the same. Children and 
 fools need society, if possible, more than others, and yet they 
 " cannot enter into it," in Hobbes's sense of the words. In- 
 deed, many, perhaps most, men remain throughout life ' unfit * 
 for society, either through defect of mind or want of educa- 
 tion.2 The main reason for this unfitness, however, is man's 
 fundamental egoism. If it be asked : (3) Does man love 
 society for its own sake } Hobbes replies with a decided 
 negative. " All society ... is either for gain or for glory ; 
 that is, not so much for love of our fellows as for the love of 
 ourselves." ^ So much is plain, but it is not equally plain in 
 w^hat terms we are to express this primitive egoism. Some- 
 times pleasure as such would seem to be the end ; sometimes 
 (probably more often) self-preservation. 
 
 Starting, then, with the assumption of man's original and 
 ineradicable egoism ; and the further assumption that nature 
 has made men essentially equal in faculties both of body 
 and of mind,* so that all may aspire to everything — it is easy 
 to see that the hypothetical ' state of nature ' must be a 
 ' state of war,' with all the attendant evils which Hobbes so 
 
 ' C/. Sidgwick's Hist, of Ethics, p. 162. 
 
 2 See De cive. Works, Molesworth's ed., vol. II., p. 2, note. 
 
 ^ Ibid., p. 5. *See Leviathan, vol. III., p. no.
 
 6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 tersely, yet vividly describes. ^ How are men to escape the 
 consequences of their own anti-social natures ? The possibility 
 of deliverance depends upon the fact that man is not merely a 
 bundle of selfish appetites, but, as Hobbes says : " True 
 Reason is ... no less a part of human nature than any other 
 faculty or affection of the mind ". Moreover, ' True Reason * 
 is " a certain law " ? 
 
 It is natural that one should ask just what is meant by 
 ' True Reason,' and Hobbes has a note on the subject,^ which, 
 however, is not particularly illuminating. " By Right Reason 
 in the natural state of man," he says, " I understand not, as 
 many do, an infallible faculty, but the act of reasoning, that is, 
 the peculiar and true ratiocination of every man concerning 
 those actions of his which may either redound to the damage 
 or benefit of his neighbours." He further explains that he calls 
 reason " true, that is, concluding from true principles, rightly 
 framed, because that the whole breach of the Laws of Nature 
 consists in the false reasoning, or rather folly, of those men 
 who do not see those duties they are necessarily to perform 
 towards others, in order to their own conservation ".^ In a 
 word, there is no infallible faculty of Right Reason that can be 
 implicitly trusted. It can only be proved right by the event, 
 and the test is the conservation of the individual. 
 
 Right Reason, however, in the sense above explained, leads 
 us to formulate certain Laws of Nature. Such a " law ' is de- 
 fined as " the dictate of Right Reason, conversant about those 
 things which are either to be done or omitted for the constant 
 preservation of life and members, as much as in us lies ". The 
 first and fundamental Law of Nature is " that peace is to be 
 sought after, where it may be found ; and where not, there 
 
 ' See Leviathan, vol. III., p. 113. For passages which seem to show that, 
 in his description of the ' state of nature,' Hobbes does not understand that he is 
 giving an historical account of the origin of human society, see, e.g., Leviathan, 
 vol. III., p. 114, and particularly the last part of the interesting note in De cive, 
 vol. II., p. 10. 
 
 ^De cive, vol. II., p. 16. ^ Ibid. 
 
 ^See, also, Dc corpore politico, vol. IV., p. 225, where the author says: " But 
 this is certain, seeing Right Reason is not existent," etc.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 7 
 
 to provide ourselves for helps of war "} From this law, all 
 the others — twenty in De cive, eighteen in Leviathan — are 
 derived. " They direct the ways, either to peace or self- 
 defence." 
 
 We are not here concerned with the enumeration and de- 
 duction of the particular Laws of Nature, which will readily 
 be found by referring to Leviathan, De cive, or De corpore 
 politico. The question as to their exact significance {qua 
 Laws of Nature), however, is of the greatest importance for 
 the system ; and it is just here that the expositions of Hobbes 
 are least helpful. The philosopher himself says : " The Laws 
 of Nature are immutable and eternal : what they forbid can 
 never be lawful ; what they command can never be unlawful ".- 
 At the same time it is important to observe that in a state 
 of nature it would be irrational for a man to obey these laws, 
 for he would have no assurance that others would do the same. 
 Such conduct would defeat the end which all these laws have 
 in mind, i.e., the preservation of the individual. Indeed, as 
 Hobbes reminds us, they are not ' laws ' at all in the ordinary 
 sense, " since they are nothing else but certain conclusions, 
 understood by reason, of things to be done and omitted " ; ^ 
 whereas the element of compulsion is essential to ' law ' in the 
 strict sense. 
 
 In order that there may be any security whatever, a govern- 
 ment of some sort must be established. The many conflicting 
 wills must be changed into one, not by a change in human 
 nature — which, of course, is impossible — but yyy the several 
 individuals submitting themselves either to a " council " or to 
 " one man ". In this compact, the individual gives up all but 
 the right of defending himself against personal violence. To 
 the governing power belong the " sword of justice " and the 
 " sword of war," and — what necessarily follows — judgment as 
 to the " right use " of each. But this is not all. Since differences 
 of opinion concerning " vieuin and tnum, just and unjust, 
 
 ^ De cive, vol. II., p. i6. Cf. Leviathan, vol. III., p. 117. 
 '^ De cive, vol. II., p. 46. ^Ibid., p. 49.
 
 8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 profitable and unprofitable, good and evil, honest and dis- 
 honest," ^ etc., are productive of discord, the civil power must 
 define the above. Also, the supreme power of the State is to 
 be judge of all theological doctrines, in so far as they tend 
 to practical results. In short, this power is " absolute," as 
 Hobbes himself frankly calls it. 
 
 We must now ask : What has become of the Laws of 
 Nature, with which we started ? We have already seen that 
 Hobbes refers to them as " eternal and immutable ". In the 
 latter part of De cive ^ he says, using words that Cudworth 
 himself could not have objected to : " Natural [Law] is that 
 which God hath declared to all men by His eternal word born 
 with them, to wit, their natural reason ; and this is that law 
 which, in this whole book, I have endeavoured to unfold ". 
 But suppose that civil laws should be in opposition to these 
 Laws of Nature .'' Hobbes meets the query with characteristic 
 boldness. " By the virtue of the natural law which forbids 
 breach of covenant, the Law of Nature commands us to keep 
 all the civil laws. For where we are tied to obedience before 
 we know what will be commanded us, there we are universally 
 tied to obey in all things. Whence it follows, that no civil 
 law whatsoever, which tends not to the reproach of the 
 deity ^ . . . can possibly be against the Law of Nature. For 
 though the Law of Nature forbid theft, adultery, &c. ; yet, 
 if the civil law commands us to invade anything, that invasion 
 is not theft, adultery, &c." * The conclusion to which we are 
 brought by the philosopher himself is rather startling : Noth- 
 ing in the civil laws can be against the Laws of Nature, 
 because not only is the civil power behind the Laws of 
 Nature that which makes them properly ' laws,' but also it is 
 that, and that alone, which gives them their content. It 
 makes comparatively little difference what the Laws of 
 
 "^De cive, p. 77. — Note the heterogeneous items. ^See p. i86. 
 
 *This is only an apparent exception, for it would be precisely for the civil 
 power to decide, in any particular case, what was, or was not, " to the reproach 
 of the deity ". 
 
 *D« cive, pp. 190, 191.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 9 
 
 Nature command or forbid, so long as it lies wholly with the 
 civil power to define the terms used. 
 
 Some pages back it was seen that there was ambiguity in 
 Hobbes's use of ' Right Reason '. In De corpora politico we are 
 told : " But this is certain, seeing Right Reason is not existent, 
 the reason of some man or men must supply the place there- 
 of "> In other words, the arbitrary use of civil power must 
 make up for the lack of Right Reason in man. Again, in 
 Leviathan : " The unwritten Law of Nature ... is now be- 
 come, of all laws, the most obscure, and has consequently the 
 greatest need of able interpreters "?■ But who should be the 
 interpreter 1 Hobbes candidly remarks : " The interpretation 
 of the Laws of Nature, in a commonwealth, dependeth not on 
 the books of moral philosophy. . . . That which I have 
 written in this treatise concerning the moral virtues . . . 
 though it be evident truth, is not therefore presently a law ; 
 but because in all commonwealths in the world it is part of the 
 civil law." No amount of valid reasoning can vindicate the 
 Laws of Nature. Nothing but their presence in the statute- 
 books of the commonwealths of the world can do that. And 
 the reason why they can be said to be so universally recog- 
 nised is that the same power, in each particular case, that 
 compels obedience to them, also practically furnishes them 
 with their content It may also be noticed that Hobbes has 
 proceeded deductively — in appearance, at least — in arriving at 
 his Laws of Nature. If presence in the statute-book be the 
 only test, he should have proceeded inductively. The utter 
 confusion which we find here requires no comment. The 
 Laws of Nature, with which our philosopher began, have 
 vanished into thin air. We learn what is good for us as well 
 as what is right, what is true as well as what is just, from the 
 powers that be. There would be no place for a theorist like 
 Hobbes himself in his own ideal state. 
 
 It was inevitable that a theory of political absolutism like 
 •that of Hobbes — involving as it did a wholly egoistic system 
 
 ^See vol. IV., p. 225. *See vol. III., p. 262.
 
 lo History of Utilitarianis7n. 
 
 of Ethics, the unlovely character of which the philosopher' 
 was at no pains whatever to conceal — should excite the most 
 violent opposition. But while the ethical writers of his own 
 time and country were practically unanimous in their opposi- 
 tion to Hobbes, their methods of attack were by no means the 
 same. Some were more incensed at the brutal egoism of 
 the system, others at the arbitrary character which Hobbes 
 had assigned to moral distinctions ; though it is fair to sup- 
 pose that all were a good deal disturbed by both sides of his 
 doctrine. A general statement like this, however, is apt to 
 be misleading, as it does not suggest the complexity of the 
 facts. It is probable that in periods of controversy, quite as 
 much as in periods of constructive work, the individualities of 
 prominent writers play a determining part in shaping their 
 productions. Hence we must be on our guard against sup- 
 posing that the conventional division of the opponents of 
 Hobbes into ' schools ' is wholly satisfactory. For instance, 
 Whewell classes together : (i) Sharrock, Henry More, and 
 Cumberland, and (2) Cudworth and Clarke ; while Professor 
 Sidgwick, on the other hand, distinguishes between (i) the 
 " Cambridge Moralists," including all the above but Sharrock, 
 Cumberland, and Clarke, and (2) Cumberland. This does not 
 imply any essential difference in the way that Whewell and 
 Professor Sidgwick interpret the doctrines of the authors 
 named. Any such classification is largely a matter of con- 
 venience and more or less arbitrary. For our present pur- 
 pose, three men may fairly be taken as typical of the 
 tendencies represented by the opponents of Hobbes, viz., 
 Cudworth, More, and Cumberland. 
 
 Cudworth, of course, stands for Intellectualism. He would 
 reduce morality to a system of truths. The result is that, 
 in his unfinished Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable 
 Morality, we have a noteworthy system of Metaphysics, rather 
 than a direct and explicit treatment of what are ordinarily 
 regarded as the problems of Ethics. Indeed, so much is Cud- 
 worth concerned to establish a system of " eternal and immu- 
 table " truths, among which are the truths of Ethics, that never
 
 Richai^d Cumberland. \i 
 
 once, in the course of the treatise just mentioned, does he take 
 the trouble to combat the egoism of Hobbes. Obviously we 
 are not concerned with his system here. Cumberland, on the 
 other hand, is singularly devoid of metaphysical interests, and 
 the passages in his treatise De legibus naturae which do inci- 
 dentally treat of metaphysical questions, are certainly the 
 least satisfactory part of his work. To the side of Hobbes's 
 system which teaches the arbitrary character of moral dis- 
 tinctions, he replies by reproducing what we have already 
 seen to be the views of Grotius regarding Natural Law ; 
 while, in opposition to the egoism of Hobbes, he teaches 
 what practically amounts to the system of Universahstic 
 Hedonism. As the first English writer standing for this 
 principle, he has been taken as the subject of the first two 
 chapters of the present volume. 
 
 More, whose Enchiridion Ethicuni enjoyed an enormous 
 popularity in its own generation, ^ is particularly hard to 
 classify ; but it is certainly safe to say that he occupies a posi- 
 tion logically intermediate between the other two. The fact 
 that he so nearly refrained from publishing his own work, 
 owing to the supposed objections of Cudworth, is in itself a 
 sufficient indication that the two authors concerned regarded 
 their systems as standing for very much the same principles. 
 On the other hand, however, while Cudworth had practically 
 neglected the affective side of our nature in his own treatise. 
 More makes the * Boniform Faculty ' (which is at once the 
 touch-stone of virtue and that by which virtue in the moral 
 agent is immediately and certainly rewarded) not only co- 
 ordinate with Right Reason, but constantly suggests its 
 primacy. It is difficult to express in a few words More's view 
 of the relation in which these two faculties stand to each 
 other. Sometimes he even seems to identify them ; but, if 
 one may venture upon a very concise statement, the case 
 stands thus. In a ' state of grace,' the ' Boniform Faculty ' 
 (which plays much the same part as conscience) is all-sufficient. 
 
 ^ See Whewell's Hist, of Mor. Phil, in England, Lect. iii. In spite of its 
 opularity, however, the Enchiridion has never been translated into English.
 
 12 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 No appeal to Right Reason is necessary, or desirable. But, 
 " since there are some men who have lost all sense of God 
 and divine things, and recognised no fixed rule in their 
 faculties," these " must be approached in another way," i.e., 
 by Right Reason. The author therefore draws from this 
 store " certain principles immediately true, and in need of 
 no proof, but from which almost all moral reasoning (as 
 mathematical demonstrations from common axioms) may be 
 clearly and easily deduced ". These he calls ' Noemata '. 
 
 An examination of these * Noemata ' at once shows that we 
 no longer have to do with the intellectualism of Cudworth. 
 The first twelve * Noemata ' treat of our duty toward ourselves, 
 and might fairly be termed ' maxims of prudence '. The Good 
 is here defined (not quite adequately for the system) as that 
 "which to any perceptive life, or stage of such life, is grate- 
 ful, pleasing, and suitable, and connected with the preservation 
 of the percipient ".^ The remaining eleven ' Noemata ' con- 
 cern our duties to God and to other men. Two of these 
 might seem quite distinctly to point in the direction of Uni- 
 versalistic Hedonism. " That good which you prefer for 
 yourself in given circumstances, you ought to prefer for an- 
 other in the same circumstances, so far as it is possible without 
 injury to any third person." ^ And again, " If it is good that 
 one man should be suppHed with means to live well and 
 happily, it follows by a sure and wholly mathematical analogy 
 that it is twice as good for two men to be supplied, three 
 times for three, a thousand times for a thousand," etc.^ 
 
 It might very well seem as if, in More, we had already 
 found an exponent of the Utilitarian principle ; but this is 
 certainly not the case. The system is one of the most per- 
 plexed in the whole history of English Ethics, but on the 
 point just referred to, at least, the author does not leave us in 
 doubt. Even in the ' Scholia ' appended to the chapter in 
 which the ' Noemata ' are treated, we find a significant state- 
 ment of the author's position. Referring to previous attempts 
 
 1 Noema i., p. 25, of the fourth ed. of the Enchiridion. 
 ^Ibid. xiv., p. 29. 'Ibid, xviii., p. 30.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 13 
 
 to find some one principle, into which morality could be re- 
 solved, he shows that some have taken ' sociality ' as the first 
 and simplest principle ; others, ' zeal for the public good ' — 
 " both parties supposing that there is no perfection or happi- 
 ness pertaining to human nature which is not bound up with 
 communion or society "?■ But " it is the internal life of the 
 mind, and the pleasure which is derived from a sense of virtue," 
 that is the proper object of Ethics.- This would exist, if 
 there were only one man in the world.^ It is not evident 
 whom More has in mind here, and the criticisms which follow 
 do not apply to Universalistic Hedonism (which had not yet 
 been advanced as an ethical theory, at least in England *) ; 
 but it is clear that More himself had no thought to develop 
 what some would now recognise as a possible Intuitional 
 basis of the Utilitarian principle.^ As a matter of fact, the 
 system is a curious combination of Intuitionism and uncon- 
 scious, undifferentiated Hedonism. More says, in substance : 
 A thing is simply and absolutely good which is pleasing, not 
 to the animal appetite, which man has in common with the 
 brutes, but to the Boniform Faculty, which distinguishes him 
 as a man.® He frequently admits, however, that this par- 
 ticular kind of pleasure is not sufficient in order to perfect 
 happiness. A certain amount of external goods is also 
 necessary.'' The Good, then, is happiness, and happiness is 
 pleasure — but pleasure of a particularly refined sort, such 
 as only a person of developed moral sensibilities could 
 enjoy. The happiness considered is almost always that of 
 the agent ; but it would be as unjust to call the system 
 Egoistic as it would be misleading to call it Utilitarian. In 
 place of ' sociality,' or * zeal for the public good,' More pro- 
 poses, as the necessary unifying principle, " true and sincere 
 
 1 See p. 33. 2Seep^5^ ^Seep. 36. 
 
 * The Enchiridion was published in 1667, and Cumberland's De legibiis 
 naturae did not appear till 1672. 
 
 *C/, Sidgwick's Methods of Ethics, pp. 379 et seq, 
 
 ®See p. 47. Also the ' scholia ' appended to ch. ii., in which More attempts 
 to distinguish his own view from ' Epicureanism '. 
 
 "> See, e.g., p. 2.
 
 14 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 love of God," 1 and holds that all the ' Noemata ' may be 
 reduced to this. In short, we have here a theological system 
 of Ethics, unconsciously hedonistic, but never more than 
 vaguely suggesting Utilitarianism. If More had recognised 
 the hedonistic side of his own system, it is not impossible 
 that he might have made ' the greatest happiness of the 
 greatest number ' the end of moral action, but the important 
 fact for us is that he did not develop his system in this 
 direction. 
 
 We may now turn to a more careful examination of the first 
 English moralist who can properly be termed a Utilitarian. 
 We have not here, as often happens, the difficulty of keeping 
 in mind two or more ethical works by the same author, 
 possibly differing in point of view, when considering any 
 particular problem arising in connection with the system. In 
 fact, the task might seem to be an easy one, as we have to 
 depend, for our knowledge of Cumberland's Ethics, wholly 
 upon the treatise entitled Da legibus naturae^ which was 
 first published in 1672. This, however, is by no means the 
 case. While a thinker of no ordinary ability, and standing 
 for a principle which has become clearly differentiated in the 
 later development of English Ethics, Cumberland is so utterly 
 lacking in a talent for exposition that the adequate presenta- 
 tion of his views is a matter of peculiar difficulty. Indeed, 
 even apart from its singular lack of method, the fact that the 
 work is so largely controversial in character, increases the 
 difficulty of extracting from it the author's own system. The 
 order of exposition is in many respects so unfortunate that 
 one is tempted to disregard it altogether ; but, even at the 
 expense of some repetition, it seems desirable to begin by 
 
 1 See p. 37. 
 
 ^ The whole title reads : De legibus naturae : disquisitio philosophica, in qua 
 ear um forma, snmma capita, ordo, promulgation et obligatio e rerum natura inves- 
 tigantur ; quia etiam elementa philosophiae Hobbianae, cum moralis turn civilis, 
 considerantur et refutantur. The passages cited in the following exposition will 
 be from the English translation by John Maxwell, published in 1727, and all 
 references will be to the pages of that edition.
 
 Richard Cu7itberland. 15 
 
 noticing the principal points in the author's own somewhat 
 elaborate Introduction. Here he was certainly writing with 
 his whole system in view,i and it is well to let the somewhal 
 heterogeneous elements that enter into it appear first in as 
 close combination as they are capable of. After this general 
 survey of the system, based upon the Introduction, we shall 
 neglect the author's own order of exposition, and consider 
 topically all the important problems which are discussed in 
 the treatise. 
 
 Cumberland begins by asserting that the Laws of Nature 
 are the foundation of all moral and civil knowledge. They 
 may be deduced in two ways : (i) From the manifest ' effects ' 
 that flow from them ; (2) from the ' causes ' whence they 
 themselves arise. The author chooses to adopt the latter 
 method, i.e., that of ' arguing from cause to effect '. The 
 former is practically the inductive, the latter the deductive 
 method. Two objections are commonly made to the induc- 
 tive method, as applied to the solution of the present problem, 
 (i) It is said that we cannot infer from the writings of a few 
 men, or even nations, what are the opinions or judgments 
 of all men. (2) Even if the above objection did not hold, 
 ' the authority of a known law-giver ' is wanting to give these 
 judgments the force of ' laws ' to all men.^ To neither of 
 these objections does Cumberland himself attach much weight. 
 The agreement of men is practically complete as to the things 
 most essential, e.g., worship of some deity, and a degree of 
 humanity sufficient to prevent murder, theft, and adultery. 
 Again, if the Laws of Nature be ' laws ' at all, they need no 
 new authority superadded to that originally belonging to 
 them. However, to establish the existence of Natural Laws 
 beyond the possibility of a doubt, Cumberland proposes to 
 reverse the usual order of treatment. He says : " I have 
 thought it proper to make a philosophical inquiry into their 
 causes \i.e., those of the Laws of Nature], as well internal 
 
 ' It is to be noticed that he constantly uses the past tense, showing what has 
 been the method of exposition in the following work. 
 '^The reference here is plainly to Hobbes.
 
 1 6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 as external, the nearer and the more remote ; for by this 
 method we shall at last arrive at their first Author, or efficient 
 Cause, from whose essential perfections, and internal sanction 
 of them, by rewards and punishments, we have shown that 
 their authority arises " } 
 
 It will be seen that the method to be employed can hardly 
 be described by the single word ' deductive '. First, we must 
 work back to the First Cause ; then, from the nature of the 
 deity, as well as from human nature, which will have been 
 considered on the way, certain results will follow. The 
 * Platonists,' to be sure, find an easy way out of the difficulty 
 by assuming ' innate ideas * ; but Cumberland is obliged to 
 confess that he has " not been so happy as to learn the 
 Laws of Nature in so short a way ".^ Not that he will 
 oppose those who believe themselves more fortunate in this 
 respect ; but it seems ill-advised to base everything upon 
 " an hypothesis which has been rejected by the generality 
 of philosophers, as well heathen as Christian, and can never 
 be proved against the Epicureans, with whom is our chief 
 controversy ". The reference to the ' Epicureans ' is signif- 
 icant. The author proposes to fight Hobbes with his own 
 weapons. And, this being the case, he sets out to prove 
 that " the Nature of Things, which subsists and is continually 
 governed by its First Cause, does necessarily imprint on 
 our minds some practical propositions . . . concerning the 
 study of promoting the joint felicity of all rationals ; and that 
 the terms of these propositions do immediately and directly 
 signify, that the First Cause, in his original constitution of 
 things, has annexed the greatest rewards and punishments 
 to the observance and neglect of these truths ". Whence 
 it manifestly follows that these are ' laws,' " Laws being noth- 
 ing but practical propositions, with rewards or punishments 
 annexed, promulg'd by competent authority " ? 
 
 The fir.st point to be established, then, is that there are 
 Laws of Nature, in the legitimate sense of the words. Having 
 
 'Seep. 13. *See p. 14. ^Ihid.
 
 Richard Cumber layid. 17 
 
 indicated his line of argument, which we shall consider later, 
 Cumberland proceeds to the more characteristic and con- 
 structive part of his doctrine. From a consideration of the 
 practical propositions which may fairly be ranked as Laws 
 of Nature, 1 it appears that they may be reduced to one 
 universal Law. This may be expressed as follows : " The 
 endeavour, to the utmost of our power, of promoting the 
 common good of the whole system of rational agents, con- 
 duces, as far as in us lies, to the good of every part, in which 
 our own happiness, as that of a part, is contained. But con- 
 trary actions produce contrary effects, and consequently our 
 own misery, among that of others." - 
 
 This reduction of the several Laws of Nature to a single 
 ultimate one, regarding conduct on the part of the individual' 
 that shall conduce to the common weal, is shown by the 
 author to be useful in a double way: (i) it is easier to re- 
 member \sic\ one principle than many ; and (2) " a certain 
 rule or measure is afforded to the prudent man's judgment,, 
 by the help whereof he may ascertain that just measure in 
 his actions and affections in which virtue consists ".-^ This 
 is eminently characteristic. The author's aim is practical 
 throughout.'* If he attempts to rationalise morality, to give 
 a scientific explanation and justification of the existing moral 
 code, it is in order that his work may prove an important 
 help to right living. It is probable that Cumberland, like 
 some contemporary writers, considerably exaggerates the 
 ' practical ' value of correct ethical theory. 
 
 The relation between Cumberland's Laws of Nature and 
 Cudworth's Eternal Truths should be noticed. How shall 
 we distinguish the so-called ' practical principles,' which we 
 have been considering, from others equally ultimate, e.g., 
 those of mathematics 1 We say that the former ' oblige ' us ; 
 the latter not — but why } Simply by reason of the nature 
 of the effects, according to Cumberland. We can afford to 
 disregard many, at least, of the truths of geometry ; not so 
 
 ^Cumberland nowhere attempts exhaustively to enumerate them. 
 "^ See p. 16. * See p. 30. * See p. 36. 
 
 2
 
 1 8 History of Uiilitarianis7n. 
 
 the moral law, for our happiness — and, as the author shows 
 later, even our preservation — depends upon our observance 
 of it. The criterion, then, is frankly one of ' consequences ' 
 — a fact that must be borne in mind. But these ' conse- 
 quences,' in part at least, are not arbitrary. " The happiness 
 of each individual (from the prospect of enjoying which, or 
 being deprived of it, the whole sanction is taken) is derived 
 from the best state of the whole system, as the nourishment 
 of each member of an animal depends upon the nourishment 
 of the whole mass of blood diffused through the whole." ^ 
 Now the actions which, by virtue of their own ' natural ' 
 force and efficacy, are calculated to promote the common 
 good, are called ' naturally good '. Again, the common good 
 being the end, " such actions as take the shortest way to this 
 effect . . . are naturally [called] ' right,' because of their natural 
 resemblance to a right line, which is the shortest that can be 
 drawn between any two given points, . . . but the rule itself 
 is called ' right,' as pointing out the shortest way to the end ".^ 
 
 All this is characteristic and important, making allowance 
 for the quaint use of language. The comparison of humanity 
 to an organism is one to which the author frequently recurs.^ 
 That there is no ' categorical imperative ' for Cumberland is 
 clear. The Laws of Nature themselves have, and need, a 
 * reason for being '. Conduct in accordance with them con- 
 duces to the common weal. It is with reference to this end 
 that even they are * right '. 
 
 The Introduction closes with a confession on the part of 
 the author that his work is not altogether literary in style or 
 method. The passage is itself, perhaps, calculated to em- 
 phasise this statement : " Its face is not painted with the 
 florid colours of Rhetoric, nor are its eyes sparkling and 
 sportive, the signs of a light wit ; it wholly applies itself, as 
 it were, with the composure and sedateness of an old man, 
 to the study of natural knowledge, to gravity of manners, 
 and to the cultivating of severer learning ".* 
 
 'See p. 21. '■'See p. 22. 'See, e.g., p. 115. *See p. 36,
 
 Richard Cumberland. 19 
 
 We shall now neglect the author's own order of exposition 
 almost entirely, and endeavour to see the system as a whole, 
 both in its strength and its weakness. It might seem as if 
 we were logically bound to begin with a consideration of the 
 Nature of Things, as Cumberland himself professes to do.^ 
 A very casual examination of the De legibus naturae, how- 
 ever, would be sufficient to show that the titles of the 
 chapters give but a very indefinite idea of the nature of their 
 contents. What Cumberland actually does, at the beginning 
 of his treatise, is to explain at considerable length and with 
 great care his notion of Laws of Nature. It is probable, 
 however, that he was induced to do this largely for contro- 
 versial reasons ; and, as we are principally concerned with the 
 constructive part of the work, we may neglect this order, 
 although it is quite impossible to separate the constructive 
 entirely from the controversial. It must always be remem- 
 bered — the title of the treatise to the contrary notwith- 
 standing — that the jural aspect of the system is not its most 
 essential feature. Cumberland held the views that he did 
 regarding Natural Laws in common with a great many of his 
 contemporaries — perhaps the majority of those representing 
 the conservative tendency.- His originality consisted in his 
 attempt to discover an underlying principle from which all 
 the special moral ' laws ' or ' practical propositions ' could be 
 deduced. 
 
 It does not seem best, then, to begin, as Cumberland actu- 
 ally did, with an examination of the concept of Natural Law. 
 Nor is one tempted to begin with the Nature of Things, 
 ostensibly the first topic treated. Cumberland uses that ex- 
 pression throughout the treatise as if its meaning were per- 
 fectly clear and understood by everybody. His utterances on 
 the subject, however, have all the confusion to which an 
 author is hable whose interests are wholly practical, and who 
 yet is obliged to speak in terms of an implicit metaphysic. 
 At present we need notice only two passages. " The Nature 
 
 1 See title of first chapter. 
 
 '^ Even Locke was influenced later by the current view.
 
 20 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 of Things does not only signify this lower world, whereof 
 we are a part, but its Creator and Supreme Governor, God. 
 ... It is certain that only true propositions, whether specula- 
 tive or practical, are imprinted on our minds by the Nature 
 of Things, because a natural action points out that only 
 which exists, and is never the cause of any falsehood, which 
 proceeds wholly from a voluntary rashness, joining or sepa- 
 rating notions which Nature has not joined or separated." ^ 
 Again, " We cannot doubt of the nature of created beings, 
 but that both things external, exciting thoughts in us, and 
 our mind comparing these thoughts, are the causes of Neces- 
 sary Truths ".2 The vagueness and inconsequence of these 
 remarks speak for themselves, and show how unsatisfactory 
 Cumberland is when on metaphysical ground. It is hardly 
 necessary to call attention to his agreement with Descartes 
 as to the origin of human error. 
 
 On the whole, it seems best to begin our examination of 
 the system by considering the author's view of the nature of 
 man and of society. We have seen that Hobbes regarded 
 society as artificial. According to his view, it was made up 
 of a certain number of mutually repellent atoms, each atom 
 being the radically and unalterably egoistic individual. The 
 * contract * was a device by which the antagonistic wills of an 
 indefinite number of self-seeking individuals gave place to 
 the * one will ' of the sovereign. Cumberland pronounces 
 emphatically against this view. When Hobbes likens men 
 to ' wolves,' ' bears,' ' serpents,' ^ etc., he is guilty of libel 
 against human nature. Referring to such remarks, our 
 author says : " If they were true, it were evidently impossible 
 to reduce such beasts of prey, always thirsting after the blood 
 of their fellows, into a civil state ".^ The compact would 
 avail nothing, unless there were something in human nature 
 that would make men abide by their promises. Cumberland 
 might have added that Hobbes is not at liberty to make any 
 
 ^ See p. 191. 2 See p. 192. 
 
 ^De homine, vol. II. (Latin works, Molesworth's ed.), p. 91. 
 
 *See p. 295.
 
 Richard Cttinberland. 21 
 
 ultimate appeal to reason in the matter — even as showing 
 what is for the individual's selfish interest — for men learn 
 what is ' good ' for them, as well as what is ' right,' from the 
 powers that be. 
 
 Hobbes had regarded the instinct of self-preservation, if 
 not the conscious seeking of one's own pleasure, as the 
 fundamental spring of human action. For Cumberland, on 
 the other hand, sympathy is as much an attribute of human 
 nature as a desire for one's own happiness. If this were not 
 so, as is suggested above, society itself could not exist. To 
 be sure, the author sometimes insists upon the pleasures of 
 (a not too expensive) benevolence in a way to lead one to 
 suspect that, after all, egoism may be at the basis of appar- 
 ently disinterested conduct ; ^ but such passages hardly need 
 detract from the force of distinct utterances, Hke the above, 
 regarding the impossibility of a society composed of ab- 
 solutely egoistic individuals. The discussions regarding al- 
 truism vs. egoism which we meet with in the treatise, are 
 sometimes quite confusing on account of the author's naive 
 certainty that the good of the individual and the good of 
 society are always (in the particular case as well as in the 
 long run) identical. We have seen that, in the Introduction, 
 society is already compared to an organism.^ Such being 
 its nature, it is idle to speak of the good of one part as 
 opposed to the good of another ; for the good of any particular 
 part {i.e., any individual) clearly must depend upon the 
 * health of the social organism,' as Mr. Stephen would say. 
 Cumberland does not go so far as some modern writers in 
 pushing this analogy, but it helps to bring out an important 
 side of his system. 
 
 So much in general regarding man's ' fitness ' for society, 
 so far as an original tendency in the direction of altruistic, as 
 well as egoistic, conduct is concerned. Here man is regarded 
 from the standpoint of society, which is to be compared to 
 an organism rather than to a collection of mutually repellent 
 
 1 See, e,g.^ p. 211. ^ See also p. 115.
 
 2 2 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 atoms. When Cumberland has the individual more particu- 
 larly in mind, he is apt to insist more upon the ' rational ' 
 nature of man. Before considering this question as to the 
 meaning and scope of Right Reason, let us notice two defini- 
 tions, and also the author's brief inventory of the powers of 
 the mind. " By man," he says, at the beginning of Chap, ii., 
 " I understand an animal endowed with a mind ; and Hobbes 
 himself, in his treatise of Hnuian Nature, acknowledges the 
 mind to be one of the principal parts of man ". By ' animal ' 
 is understood " what the philosophers agree is to be found in 
 brutes : the powers of receiving increase by nourishment, of 
 beginning motion, and of propagating their species ". It is 
 not quite clear that Cumberland would allow sensation to 
 brutes.^ However, he sometimes refers to sub-human mani- 
 festations of sympathy. As regards the mind, he says : " To 
 the mind we ascribe Understanding and Will ; to the Under- 
 standing we reduce Apprehending, Comparing, Judging, 
 Reasoning, a Methodical Disposition, and the Memory of all 
 these things, and of the objects about which they are conver- 
 sant. To the Will we ascribe both the simple acts of choos- 
 ing and refusing, and that vehemence of those actions which 
 discovers itself in the passions, over and above that emotion 
 or disturbance of the body, which is visible in them." - 
 
 Such details are merely preliminary, and we shall now ask 
 what is meant by ' Right Reason,' an expression which is 
 constantly recurring in the treatise. Hobbes had practically 
 denied that there was any such faculty in man. In Cumber- 
 land's system, on the other hand, Right Reason plays an im- 
 portant, if a somewhat Protean part. Here, as in the case of 
 the Nature of Things, we find a degree of confusion that can 
 only be explained by the fact that the author's interests are 
 purely practical, and that he is speaking in terms of an incon- 
 
 ^ See, e.g., p. 94. Also cf. Dr. Frank E. Spaulding's /Jfc/myrf C«w6<rWa«<f ah 
 Begriinder der englischen Ethik, p. 26. There is an immense amount of physio- 
 logical data in the treatise, and it is sometimes hard to tell whether Cumberland 
 is speaking in terms of psychology or of physiology. 
 
 "^ See p. 94.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 23 
 
 sistent metaphysic that he has never taken the trouble to 
 think out The following curious passage is perhaps the 
 author's most explicit statement regarding the nature of Right 
 Reason. He says : " I agree, however, with him [Hobbes], 
 that by Right Reason is not to be understood an infallible 
 Faculty (as he affirms many, but I know not who, to under- 
 stand it) ; but yet by it is to be understood a faculty not false 
 in these acts of judging. Nor is it properly understood to 
 be an act of reasoning (as he too rashly asserts), but an effect 
 of the Judgment ; that is, true propositions treasured up in 
 the memory, whether they be premises or conclusions, of 
 which some that are practical are called ' laws,' for actions are 
 compared with these in order to examine their goodness, not 
 with those acts of reasoning which discover them ; yet I 
 willingly allow that these acts of reasoning are also included 
 in the notion of Right Reason." ^ And then, as against 
 Hobbes's view that, out of civil society, " every man's proper 
 reason is to be esteemed, not only the standard of his own 
 actions, which he does at his own peril, but also the measure 
 of other men's reason with respect to his affairs," ^ Cumber- 
 land adds that this cannot be the case, " For, out of civil so- 
 ciety, any one may distinguish Right Reason without making 
 a comparison with his own. Because there is a common 
 standard . . . the Nature of Things, as it lies before us, care- 
 fully to be observed and examined by all our faculties." 
 
 The first of the passages just quoted is one of the most per- 
 plexed in the whole treatise. Right Reason is not an " in- 
 fallible faculty," yet " not false in these acts of judging " ; it is 
 not properly an " act of reasoning," but the resulting " true 
 propositions " — yet these " acts of reasoning " are, after all, to 
 be included under Right Reason. This seems hopeless, but 
 perhaps we may find what Cumberland means by not expecting 
 to find too much. First, with regard to that other expression 
 so often used, ' The Nature of Things '. Cumberland is a 
 
 ^ See p. 103. 
 
 2 This would apply, of course, only in the ' state of nature '.
 
 24 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 wholly nafve realist. By the Nature of Things he seems to 
 mean all that actually and objectively is — including God as 
 well as His world. And it is needless to say that Cumberland's 
 God is a ' transcendent ' (as opposed to an ' immanent ') deity. 
 This Nature of Things being posited, we have a perfectly ob- 
 jective standard as regards not only theoretical truths but 
 practical propositions. The Reason of man is such as to fit 
 him to apprehend this Nature of Things exactly as it is, 
 always provided that he does not, by a ' free ' act of will, 
 choose to assent to that which is not clear and distinct. 
 Cumberland's test of truth and theory of error are the same 
 as Descartes's ; he differs from the founder of modern phil- 
 osophy, of course, in his rejection of ' innate ideas '. For 
 Cumberland, then, having no theory of cognition other than 
 that of common-sense, and caring only for the truth of the de- 
 liverances of Right Reason, it is a matter of indifference 
 whether we call the latter a * faculty,' an ' act of reasoning,' or 
 the resulting * true propositions '. In the last resort, Cumber- 
 land, like Descartes, seems to depend upon the necessary 
 truthfulness of God. 
 
 We now see what, in general, Cumberland holds regarding 
 the nature of man. He is not without original altruistic in- 
 stincts, and is, moreover, essentially a rational being. That 
 his instinctive altruism tends to fit him for society goes with- 
 out saying. But this alone is not sufficient. Alongside of 
 the altruistic instincts, are others that must be recognised as 
 egoistic. The relation in which the two stand to each other 
 is not clearly indicated, but, at any rate, it is evident that they 
 would be likely to conflict, if reason did not furnish a rule of 
 conduct. Now man's rational character fits him for society 
 in a double way.^ (i) It enables him to see his own interests, 
 not as something apart from, but in relation to, the common 
 weaL (2) It enables him to apprehend and desire the Good, 
 .qua Good, quite independently of the question as to whose 
 
 ' This will appear from what follows regarding the motive of the individual 
 agent.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 25 
 
 Good it may be.^ Thus, " whoever determines his Judgment 
 and his Will by Right Reason, must agree with all others 
 who judge according to Right Reason in the same matter "? 
 Hence, to use Cumberland's own expression, " the funda- 
 mental cornerstone of the Temple of Concord is laid by 
 Nature ". 
 
 In any system of Ethics, it is of course necessary to dis- 
 tinguish between the (objective) ' end ' of moral action and the 
 ' motive ' of the individual agent. We have already seen, in 
 the Introduction, what the ' end ' dictated by Right Reason is, 
 and we shall have to consider it more at length later ; but it is 
 important for us here to ask more particularly than we have 
 yet done, regarding the motive of the individual agent, 
 whether, and if so, how, he can directly will the ' common 
 good '. Here, again, Cumberland's utterances are confusing. 
 For instance, in Chap. ii. he says : " Universal benevolence is 
 the spring and source of every act of innocence and fidehty, of 
 humanity and gratitude, and indeed of all the virtues by which 
 property and commerce are maintained "? But when later, 
 in the next chapter, he attempts to explain how man can 
 will the common good, he rests the argument mainly upon 
 the rational nature of man ; and proposes to demonstrate the 
 possibility of altruistic conduct a priori to those who acknowl- 
 edge the nature of the will to consist in " the consent of the 
 mind with the judgment of the understanding, concerning 
 things agreeing among themselves ".* Since the understand- 
 ing is able to judge what is ' good ' for others, as well as for 
 the agent himself, there is no reason why one cannot act in a 
 purely altruistic way. Just what Cumberland means here will 
 be seen more clearly by referring to what he says regarding 
 Hobbes's contention that we first desire things, and then call 
 them ' good '. Cumberland holds, on the contrary, " that 
 things are first judged to be good, and that they are after- 
 wards desired only so far as they seem good ".^ 
 
 ^ It will readily be seen that this second function of Right Reason is hardly 
 jconsistent with the principles of the system, 
 
 '^ See p. 107. 3 See pp. 114, 115. ■•Seep. 173. *Seep, 168.
 
 26 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 All this, of course, is unsatisfactory. From a general state- 
 ment of the universality of a certain degree of benevolence, 
 we have passed to a bit of more than questionable psychol- 
 ogy, used to explain the possibility of altruistic conduct. 
 But Cumberland does not always attempt to rationalise the 
 matter in this way. Somewhat earlier in the treatise,^ he 
 attempts to show how altruistic feelings would naturally 
 arise and be fostered, not only among men, but also among" 
 the higher animals. We may omit as irrelevant the first two 
 considerations urged and pass to the third, which is, that " the 
 motion of the blood and heart, which is necessary to life, is 
 befriended by love, desire, hope, and joy, especially when con- 
 versant about a great good ", But a good known to extend 
 to the most possible will by that very fact be recognised as 
 the greatest. Hence benevolent affections will conduce to 
 ^Q. preservation of man or animal, as the case may be. A 
 fourth argument is " that animals are incited to endeavour the 
 propagation of their own species by the force of the same 
 causes which preserve the life of every individual, so that 
 these two are connected by [a] tie evidently natural "? The 
 details of the argument are not particularly convincing. The 
 important point is : Cumberland argues that altruism first 
 appears as sexual love and the parental instinct to protect 
 offspring. Having once arisen, there is no reason why it 
 may not extend ever so much further. 
 
 But in the latter part of the treatise, there is an interesting- 
 passage which should not be neglected. The author says : 
 " No one does truly observe the law unless he sincerely pro- 
 pose the same end with the legislator. But, if he directly and 
 constantly aim at this end, it is no diminution to the sincerity 
 of his obedience that, at the instigation of his own happiness, 
 he first perceived that his sovereign commanded him to re- 
 spect a higher end." ^ There is a suggestion here that the 
 individual first comes to act in an (objectively) altruistic way, 
 because he finds that it conduces to his own happiness ; but,. 
 
 ' See pp. 122 et seq. ^ See p. 128. ' See p. 275.
 
 Richard Czimberiand. 2 J 
 
 this habit having been established, he comes to act for the 
 common weal without any thought of self. This doctrine 
 will be found clearly worked out in the case of two, at least, 
 of Paley's predecessors, i.e., Gay and Tucker. 
 
 From the above it will be seen that, while Cumberland's 
 view of the nature of man is in striking contrast to that of 
 Hobbes, and in substantial agreement with that of Grotius, 
 his treatment of the motive of the individual is rather vague 
 and unsatisfactory. It is difficult to say whether, according to 
 Cumberland, moral action is ever prompted by purely dis- 
 interested benevolence or not. To be sure, all discussions of 
 the kind are likely enough to end in misunderstanding, because 
 the ' egoism ' and the ' altruism ' of which we speak with so 
 much confidence are themselves more or less of the nature of 
 abstractions. Granted that the good of the individual is inex- 
 tricably connected with the good of society in many respects, 
 why should we expect to find the ' self-regarding ' and the 
 ' other-regarding ' affections clearly differentiated ? If Cum- 
 berland had contented himself with showing that, in the case 
 of beings endowed with sympathy, ' egoism ' and ' altruism ' 
 must often coincide, we should have had no reason to com- 
 plain of his treatment. But this he did not do. To what an 
 extent he was capable of confusion on this point may be seen 
 by referring to the more than paradoxical passage in the In- 
 troduction,! in which he attempts to prove that he who per- 
 forms good actions in gratitude for benefits already received, 
 shows less generosity than one who is moved to action " by the 
 hope only of good ". The relation of Cumberland's bio- 
 logical proof of altruism to Evolutional theory is obvious. 
 At the same time, it should be noted that his position here is 
 not inconsistent with his own essentially static view of the 
 Nature of Things. 
 
 ^ Not previously quoted. See p. 29.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 
 RICHARD CUMBERLAND (continued). 
 
 Having considered somewhat at length Cumberland's view 
 of the nature of man, we shall now turn to the second main 
 division of our exposition, which depends essentially upon 
 the above, i.e., his doctrine of the Good. Although the 
 author is particularly concerned to show the eternity and im- 
 mutability of the Laws of Nature, this jural aspect of the 
 system, which will be considered later, must not blind us to 
 the fact that for Cumberland there is nothing corresponding 
 to Kant's ' categorical imperative '. On this point he is quite 
 explicit, as might be expected from the general character of 
 the system. He says : " These propositions are called practi- 
 cal, nor is it necessary that they should be pronounced in the 
 form of a gerund, 'this or that ought to be done,' as some 
 school-men teach ; because that fitness which is expressed by 
 a gerund wants explanation ".^ The form of the propositions 
 makes no particular difference, as the author goes on to show. 
 They may be given : (i) as statements of fact, i.e., that cer- 
 tain things necessarily conduce both to the ' common good ' 
 and to that of the individual agent ; or (2) as commands, i.e., 
 as Laws of Nature ; or (3) as ' gerunds,' in the sense indi- 
 cated above. Evidently we have here to do with an Ethics 
 of the Good, and not with a Duty Ethics. 
 
 But what is the Good } Cumberland has much to say re- 
 garding the good of each and the good of all, ' natural ' good 
 and ' moral ' good ; but he nowhere tells us as definitely as we 
 
 1 See p. 180. 
 (28)
 
 Richard Cumberland. 29 
 
 could wish exactly what the Good is. It is a little curious 
 that, just after remarking that " it is of the last consequence 
 to establish a well-grounded and irrefragable notion of 
 Good," 1 he should make no serious attempt to do so, but in- 
 dulge in a number of characteristic criticisms of Hobbes. 
 Throughout the treatise Cumberland is concerned to oppose 
 the two following related views of Hobbes regarding the 
 Good : (i) that the [natural] Good for each man is merely 
 what he wants ; and (2) that, before the establishment of the 
 State and the enacting of civil laws, there is no ' measure ' of 
 the Good. 
 
 We have already seen that, in opposition to Hobbes's doc- 
 trine that we call a thing good because we want it, Cumber- 
 land holds that we want it because first we believe it to be 
 good.2 As regards the view that in a ' state of nature ' there 
 is no ' common measure,' the author somewhat naively asserts 
 that of course there is — the Nature of Things.^ In the same 
 paragraph, however, he explicitly says : " Whatsoever pro- 
 position points out the true cause ot preservation does at the 
 same time show what is true good ". Later in the treatise. 
 Good is defined as : " that which preserves, or enlarges and 
 perfects, the faculties of any one thing or of several ". And a 
 few lines further on : " that is good to man which preserves 
 or enlarges the powers of the mind and body, or of either, 
 without prejudice to the other ".* 
 
 The first passage quoted may sound like Hobbes ; but of 
 course what Cumberland has in mind, when he speaks of pre- 
 servation, is the preservation, not primarily of the individual, 
 but of society — the ' health of the social organism,' as Mr. 
 .Stephen would say. Another important difference is that Cum- 
 
 ^ See p. i6g. 
 
 ^ Connected with this is the question regarding the permanence of the Good. 
 Cumberland holds that " Hobbes's fiction that good and evil are changeable is 
 perfectly inconsistent with the necessary and immutable causes, which he every- 
 where asserts, of the being and preservation of man " (p. 62). It is to be doubted; 
 if this is at all conclusive against Hobbes. 
 
 ' See p. 62. * See p. 165.
 
 30 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 berland's idea of the Good, from this point of view, includes 
 perfection as well as preservation. Indeed, the emphasis is 
 certainly to be laid upon perfection. Man is not merely a 
 bundle of egoistic appetites, but a being essentially rational 
 — a personality to be developed. 
 
 But in Chap. v. we have an example of the other set of 
 passages, even more numerous, which might be cited as show- 
 ing that Cumberland's ideal was that of ordinary Hedonism. 
 " I proceed more fully to explain the common, which also I 
 call the public good. By these words I understand the aggre- 
 gate or sum of all those good things which either we can 
 •contribute towards, or are necessary to, the happiness of all 
 rational beings, considered as collected into one body, each 
 in his proper order." ^ The ' rational ' beings referred to are 
 God and all men. Animals are placed practically on the same 
 level with the vegetable world. " The perfection ^ of these 
 things is not properly, at least not ultimately, sought after ; 
 their use and concurrence with our actions towards the good 
 of rational beings is the thing intended." 
 
 As it is not clear — thus far, at any rate — in what terms 
 Cumberland would have defined the Good, if he had been 
 forced to be more exact, it becomes important to consider his 
 treatment of happiness. This is decidedly careless, and some- 
 times ' circular,' i.e., the Good is frequently defined in terms 
 of happiness, while happiness is sometimes ^ defined as ' the 
 possession of good things '. Indeed, Cumberland occasion- 
 ally uses the words interchangeably even in the same sen- 
 tence. However, allowing for his careless use of language, 
 with which we are already familiar, his theory seems to be that 
 human happiness results largely from action, particularly from 
 the exercise of one's intellectual powers. For instance, in 
 treating of the rewards that attend observance of the Laws 
 of Nature, he speaks of " that pleasure or part of our happi- 
 ness which is necessarily contained in such natural employ- 
 
 ' See p. 202. The title of this long and important chapter is : " Of the Law 
 of Nature and its Obligation ". 
 
 - Note the use of the word. ' See, e.g., p. 43.
 
 Richa7'd Cumbei'land, 31 
 
 ment of the human faculties as leads to the best end ... for 
 all exercise of natural powers, especially of the highest order, 
 in which we neither miss our aim nor turn out of the direct 
 road, is naturally pleasant " } Now freedom from evil or 
 uneasiness may depend upon external circumstances ; no 
 other pleasures than the so-called ' active ' ones take their 
 rise from within ourselves. Hence this is the only happiness 
 to which moral philosophy directs us.- But again, Cumber- 
 land says : " I have no inclination very curiously to inquire 
 whether the happiness of man be an aggregate of the most 
 vigorous actions, which can proceed from our faculties ; or 
 rather a most grateful sense of them, joined with tranquillity 
 and joy, which by some is called pleasure. These are in- 
 separably connected, and both necessary to happiness." ^ 
 This is one of the most ambiguous of the passages making 
 for hedonism.* It will be noticed, however, that ' tran- 
 quillity' is distinctly stated to be an essential constituent of 
 happiness. 
 
 As regards the nature, or rather the cause, of this tran- 
 quillity, the author speaks earlier in the treatise of an ' essen- 
 tial part ' of happiness, i.e., " that inward peace which arises 
 from an uniform wisdom, always agreeing with itself ".^ If 
 we act differently toward others from what we do toward our- 
 selves, we have the discomfort that attends any inconsistency. 
 But, in addition, " that great joy is also wanting which arises 
 in a benevolent mind from a sense of the felicity of others ", 
 Of course, tranquillity does not depend entirely upon ' con- 
 sistency' in thought and action. We saw but a moment ago 
 that it depended materially upon external things. It also 
 depends largely, according to Cumberland, upon the con- 
 
 1 See p. 100. Cf. p. 211, where Cumberland emphasises the pleasures of 
 success in one's undertakings. 
 
 ^This passage should not be too much insisted on. By itself, it is mis- 
 leading. 
 
 ^ See p. 2og. 
 
 •• Strictly speaking, of course, it leaves open the question as to what terms we 
 shall use (hedonistic or otherwise) in defining the Good. 
 
 * See p. 44.
 
 32 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 sciousness of having deserved well of our fellows. But it is 
 characteristic of our author to insist upon the partial depend- 
 ence of tranquillity upon having acted consistently. 
 
 So far, then, happiness is seen to consist principally in 
 (i) the pleasures attending our normal, particularly our intel- 
 lectual, activities ; (2) tranquillity, which depends partly upon 
 {a) external circumstances, {])) the feeling that we have been 
 ' consistent ' in thought and action, {c) the consciousness that 
 we have acted for the common weal ; and (3) the pleasure 
 which results from a knowledge of the happiness of others. 
 
 What shall be said, then, with regard to Cumberland's 
 view of the Good in general } We have seen that he speaks, 
 now in terms of ' preservation ' and ' perfection,' now in terms 
 of ' happiness '. In one passage, while maintaining the some- 
 what trite thesis that ' virtue is its own reward,' he says : " I 
 care not in this argument to distinguish between the health of 
 mind and the consciousness or enjoyment thereof by reflec- 
 tion, since nature has so intimately united these two, that the 
 free exercise of the virtues and the perception or inward sense 
 thereof are inseparable ".^ A statement like this must put 
 us on our guard against expecting too definite an answer to 
 the question which we are considering. ' Happiness ' always 
 attends ' perfection ' ; ' perfection ' is necessary in order that 
 we may attain * happiness '. Practically, then, it makes little 
 difference which we say — and Cumberland's aim was pre- 
 eminently a practical one, as we have seen. I do not believe 
 that it is possible dogmatically to decide on either interpreta- 
 tion. We should be forcing a distinction, important for us, 
 upon an author who regarded it with frank indifference. 
 Indeed, it would be much truer to say that both happiness and 
 perfection, in our understanding of the words, are included in 
 the author's conception of the Good. 
 
 It should be noticed, however, that Cumberland's actual 
 treatment of ' happiness ' is a good deal clearer than his treat- 
 ment of ' perfection ' ; and there is always the lurking possi- 
 
 ^ See p. 265.
 
 Richard Ctuuberland. 33 
 
 bility that the latter may be regarded as of such importance, 
 because it is a necessary means to the former. The general 
 impression which the system gives one certainly is that, on the 
 whole, it is hedonistic. At the same time, it would be sheer 
 misrepresentation to hold that it is consistently so. It is 
 much better to let the two principles, which we now regard as 
 logically distinct, stand side by side, recognising, however, that 
 greater emphasis is laid upon ' happiness ' than upon ' per- 
 fection '. 
 
 This comparatively vague treatment of ' perfection ' has led 
 Professor Sidgwick to hold that Cumberland " does not even 
 define perfection so as strictly to exclude from it the notion of 
 moral perfection or virtue, and save his explanation of moral- 
 ity from an obvious logical circle "} I am inclined to think, 
 however, that Professor Sidgwick exaggerates the ambiguity of 
 Cumberland's notion of ' perfection '. As Dr. Spaulding has 
 shown,2 the ' perfection ' referred to is a ' perfection of mind 
 and body,' ^ which is explained as the ' development of their 
 powers '.■* This will be plain if we keep in mind what Cum- 
 berland says regarding ' naturally ' good things. These are 
 defined as (i) those which adorn and cheer the mind, and (2) 
 those which preserve and increase the powers of the body.^ 
 
 We shall now have to notice the distinction (just mentioned) 
 which Cumberland makes between what is ' naturally ' and 
 what is ' morally ' good. This has been ignored hitherto, be- 
 cause it is likely to lead to confusion. What things ' naturally ' 
 good are, we have just seen. On the other hand, " only 
 voluntary actions conformable to some law, especially that of 
 Nature," are ' morally ' good. It is quite misleading, when 
 Cumberland insists that ' natural ' good is more extensive 
 than ' moral ' good. It is not a matter of more or less, but of 
 what we may call, for convenience, the ' substantive ' and the 
 ' adjective ' use of the word ' good '. Certain things, once for 
 all, do, according to the eternal nature of things, conduce to 
 
 ' See Hist, of Ethics, p. 173. 
 
 '^ See Richard Cumberland, pp. 55 et seq. ^See p. 305. 
 
 ■• See pp. 165 et seq., already cited. ^ See p. 203.
 
 34 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 man's preservation, perfection, and happiness. These are 
 ' naturally ' good, or, as we now prefer to say, they constitute 
 the Good On the other hand, those ' voluntary actions ' 
 which conduce to the Good, and so fulfil the Laws of Nature, 
 are called ' morally ' good. This is a somewhat unfortunate 
 use of language, for it looks at first as if Ethics had to do 
 only with the ' morally ' good. This is so far from being true 
 that ' natural ' good is the ultimate, not that which is ' morally ' 
 good ; otherwise Cumberland would be involved in a manifest 
 circle at the very outset. But while Ethics must needs begin 
 with a consideration of ' natural good ' — ' the Good,' as we 
 shall call it — it is not equally concerned with all that would 
 ideally go to constitute the Good. Cumberland himself, in 
 the first chapter of the treatise, ^ calls our attention to the use- 
 fulness of the Stoics' distinction between things in our power 
 and things out of our power. Now Ethics, from the nature of 
 the case, must be practically limited in its scope to a considera- 
 tion of things in our power. At the same time, to limit the 
 Good to things in our power would be obviously stultifying, 
 whether we accept preservation, perfection, or happiness (in 
 our sense of the word) as the criterion. The only type of 
 Ethics which can do that is the ' duty Ethics,' the Ethics of the 
 * good will ' ; and, however heterogeneous the elements may 
 be that enter into Cumberland's system, he surely is not logic- 
 ally affiliated to the Kantian school. 
 
 So far we have been considering the Good quite in general. 
 As a matter of fact, of course, when the Laws of Nature are 
 under consideration, Cumberland has in mind, not the good of 
 any individual or class merely, but the good of all — or rather, 
 to be more exact, the good of the greatest number. Indeed, 
 that this good of the whole is greater than the (hypothetical) 
 good of the isolated part, and therefore the ' greatest end ' of 
 human action, Cumberland practically puts among self-evident 
 truths.2 But, as he says, " the good of the collective body is 
 no other than the greatest which accrues to all, or to the major 
 
 1 See p. 63. 2 See p. 97.
 
 Rickiwd Cumberland. 35 
 
 part of the whole ".1 Although he speaks of society as an 
 organic whole — particularly when he is concerned to show 
 that the good of each ultimately coincides with the good of all 
 others — he never loses sight of the claims of the individual, 
 as some modern theorists, standing on much the same ground, 
 are inclined to do. 
 
 It is to be remembered that the ' greatest end ' is nothing- 
 less than the 'joint felicity of <^// rationals,' so that the happi- 
 ness or glory of God is included, as well as the happiness of 
 all men. If there be question as to the ' parts ' of the 
 ' greatest end,' and their ' order,' we are told : " that part of 
 the end will be superior which is grateful to the nature of the 
 more perfect being. So that the glory of God is chief, then 
 follows the happiness of many good men, and inferior to this 
 is the happiness of any particular person. - 
 
 Thus far we have neglected what Cumberland himself may 
 very well have regarded as most important, i.e., the jural 
 aspect of the system. As we have already seen, he begins 
 with an elaborate discussion concerning the Laws of Nature. 
 It did not seem best to follow his order of exposition, because 
 this appeared to have been dictated largely by controversial 
 considerations. Moreover, it is important to see that — from 
 our present point of view, at least — the system stands alone, 
 without the assistance of this scaffolding of Natural Laws.-^ 
 At the same time, one would have but a very inadequate idea 
 either of the external form of the system or of the author's 
 actual application of his unifying principle, without a knowl- 
 edge of the substance of what he says regarding the Laws of 
 Nature. To this subject, then, we shall proceed. It will form 
 the third, and last, main division of our exposition. 
 
 Hobbes himself had admitted Laws of Nature, but in a 
 sense wholly different from that ordinarily attaching to the ex- 
 pression, as used by his contemporaries — indeed, in a sense not 
 
 1 See p. 60. 2 See p. 280. 
 
 ' Of course this is not intended to beg the question as to the ultimate validity 
 of a Utilitarian system.
 
 36 History of Uti/itariamsm. 
 
 easy to define, as we have seen. Cumberland returns to the 
 original conception of Natural Laws,i and is intensely in 
 earnest in maintaining their existence. 
 
 It will be remembered that our author discards the doctrine 
 of ' innate ideas '. We must, then, learn the Laws of Nature 
 from experience. How does experience teach us .'' In early 
 childhood, we act in a practically purposeless way until we 
 come to recognise the different effects of different kinds of 
 actions, not only upon ourselves, but upon others as well. 
 " Hence,'' as Cumberland naively says, " we draw some conclu- 
 sions concerning actions acceptable to God, but many more 
 concerning such as are advantageous and disadvantageous to 
 men." ^ When, in mature years, these conclusions come to 
 be accurately expressed in a general form, they are called 
 ' Practical Propositions '. We have already seen that the 
 form of these propositions is immaterial. They may be ex- 
 pressed (i) as statements of fact, (2) as commands [laws], or 
 (3) ^s ' gerunds '. Notwithstanding this, however, in the main 
 body of the work, Cumberland almost always speaks of 
 Practical Propositions as Laws, and is particularly concerned 
 to show that they are technically such. 
 
 Hobbes had insisted that a Law must be clearly promulgated 
 by a competent authority, i.e., by one having power to enforce 
 obedience ; and had denied that the so-called Laws of Nature 
 possessed either of these requisites. Cumberland, on the 
 other hand, while accepting Hobbes's definition of a Law, 
 attempts to show that the Laws of Nature are ' Laws ' in pre- 
 cisely Hobbes's sense of the word. At the beginning oF 
 Chap, v., he defines the [general] Law of Nature as " a 
 proposition proposed to the observation of, or impressed upon, 
 the mind with sufficient clearness, by the Nature of Things, 
 from the will of the First Cause, which points out that pos- 
 sible action of a rational agent, which will chiefly promote the 
 common good, and by which only the entire happiness of 
 particular persons can be obtained "? The former part of 
 
 ' As held, e.g., by Grotius. 
 
 ^ See p. 179. ^ See p. 189.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 37 
 
 the definition contains the ' precept,' the latter the ' sanction ' ; 
 and the mind receives the ' impression ' of both from the 
 Nature of Things. Neither words nor any arbitrary signs 
 whatever are essential to a Law. Given a knowledge of 
 actions and their consequences, we have all that is needed. 
 
 With regard to the clearness that is to be looked for in the 
 Laws of Nature, Cumberland says : " That proposition is pro- 
 posed or imprinted by the objects with sufficient plainness, 
 whose terms and their natural connection are so exposed to 
 the senses and thoughts, by obvious and common experience, 
 that the mind of an adult person, not labouring under any 
 impediment, if it will attend or take notice, may easily observe 
 it".i There are such propositions. They are analogous to 
 the following : Men may be killed by a profuse loss of blood, 
 by suffocation, by want of food, etc. 
 
 These propositions, then, are given in human experience 
 with sufificient clearness. Is there any power behind them, 
 capable of enforcing obedience } The very fact that certain 
 consequences, good or bad, apparently always ensue upon cer- 
 tain classes of actions, would of itself suggest that this is the 
 case. But we can go further. The Law of Nature, as above 
 stated, points out the way to the common Good ; God must 
 desire the common Good ; therefore these [derived] proposi- 
 tions must be regarded as Laws of God — in which case there 
 can be no question as to the ' competent authority '. The 
 good or evil consequences which result from actions, must be 
 regarded as * sanctions,' divinely ordained. In a word, these 
 Practical Propositions, derived from experience, are not only 
 Laws, but Laws in the completest possible sense. 
 
 We are now quite prepared to understand Cumberland's 
 notion of Obligation. He says : " Obligation is that act of a 
 legislator by which he declares that actions conformable to his 
 law are necessary to those for whom the law is made. An 
 action is then understood to be necessary to a rational agent, 
 when it is certainly one of the causes necessarily required to 
 that happiness which he naturally, and consequently neces- 
 
 ' See p. 192.
 
 38 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 sarily, desires." ^ Obligation is regarded as perfectly immu- 
 table, for it could change only with the Nature of Things.^ 
 That anything in what is so vaguely termed the Nature of 
 Things ^ could change, Cumberland did not for a moment 
 suppose. 
 
 In treating of obligation, the author sometimes uses lan- 
 guage which might suggest determinism. It is to be re- 
 membered, however, that he is an uncompromising libertarian 
 — so far, at least, as it is possible to define the position of one 
 so little given to metaphysical speculation or the precise use 
 of metaphysical language. By the ' necessity ' and ' immuta- 
 bility ' of the Laws of Nature, he simply means that, if certain 
 acts are performed, certain consequences will necessarily 
 ensue, now and always. That the acts themselves, in the par- 
 ticular case, are determined, he would deny. We have already 
 seen that human error is explained by Cumberland in the same 
 way as by Descartes — i.e., as resulting from a rash use of 
 our Free Will, where we arbitrarily assent to that which is 
 not clear and distinct. 
 
 It might seem highly improbable that so prominent and 
 zealous a Churchman as Cumberland, in treating of the ' sanc- 
 tion ' of the Law of Nature, would fail to insist upon rewards 
 and punishments after death ; yet such is the case. In the 
 Introduction, he states that he has abstained from ' theological 
 questions,' and has attempted to prove his position from 
 ' reason ' and ' experience '.^ The treatise as a whole bears 
 out this statement fairly well, it being understood that by 
 ' theological questions ' Cumberland means those pertaining 
 to revelation. In one passage, he says : " Among these re- 
 wards [attending obedience to the Laws of Nature] is that 
 happy immortality which natural reason promises to attend 
 
 ^ See p. 233 ; cf. p. 206. - See p. 226. 
 
 ^ This is a good case to illustrate the ambiguity of the expression ' Nature of 
 Things '. Does the ' immutable Nature of Things ' mean certain physical and 
 other laws which remain constant ? Or does the ' immutability ' extend to the 
 natures of particular classes of beings ? 
 
 * See p. 34.
 
 Richard Cumberland. 39 
 
 the minds of good men, when separated from the body " ; ^ 
 but this is almost the only instance in which he directly refers 
 to the future life in connection with the ' sanction,' and it is 
 significant, perhaps, that even here he does not refer to future 
 punishments. Cumberland's reticence on this subject is by 
 no means difficult to explain, and it argues nothing against 
 his orthodoxy. In the first place, as we have seen, he wished 
 to confute Hobbes on his own ground. Moreover, he doubt- 
 less knew perfectly well that, for those who believed in im- 
 mortality, rewards and punishments after death would be 
 regarded as constituting by far the most important part of the 
 sanction, whereas, to those who were sceptical in the matter, 
 such considerations would not appeal at all. 
 
 But what Cumberland lost by confining himself to a con- 
 sideration of the consequences of actions that might be ex- 
 pected to ensue in this present life, he endeavoured to make 
 up by distinguishing sharply between (i) ' immediate ' [inter- 
 nal] and (2) ' mediate ' [external] consequences. The former 
 are emphasised considerably at the expense of the latter, 
 doubtless for the reason that here one might plausibly claim 
 greater certainty. The wicked may, in particular cases, ap- 
 pear to flourish in our own day, as they did in David's time ; 
 but the ' external ' consequences of actions are by no means 
 the only ones. By the ' internal ' consequences, Cumberland 
 might seem to mean simply the approval or disapproval of 
 conscience, but this is by no means the case. He says : 
 " The immediate connection between every man's greatest 
 happiness of mind, that is in his power, and the actions which 
 he performs to promote most effectually the common good of 
 God and men, consists in this : that these are the very actions, 
 in the exercise and inward consciousness whereof every man's 
 happiness (as far as it is in his own power) consists ". This 
 is supposed to be " after the same manner as we perceive a 
 connection between the health and unimpaired powers of the 
 body and its actions "? The case, then, is regarded as analo- 
 gous to the connection between feeling well and being well 
 
 ' See p. 267. ' See p. 207.
 
 40 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 physically. If this seem like begging the question, it is to be 
 observed further that man can find free scope for the varied 
 activities (particularly mental) in which his happiness so largely 
 consists, only by acting for the common weal. 
 
 As regards the ' mediate ' effects, or external consequences 
 of actions, Cumberland acknowledges that we have here to do, 
 not with certainty, but with probability merely. Still it is a 
 very high degree of probability. In the long run, actions 
 tending to promote the common weal must lead to a maximum 
 of possible happiness for the individual agent ; actions against 
 the common weal, to a maximum of possible unhappiness. If 
 advantages are not to be procured in this way, i.e., by acting 
 for the common weal, they come under the head of ' things not 
 in otu: power '. The Divine moral government of human 
 affairs (here and now) is referred to as tending still further to 
 justify the author's position. 
 
 The treatment of this subject is considerably perplexed, 
 partly owing to the author's attempt to avoid the appearance 
 of harbouring egoism in his system — an attempt, it should be 
 added, which is not uniformly successful. From the contro- 
 versial point of view, he doubtless had good reason to insist 
 upon the greater importance of the internal sanction, and, 
 indeed, his general position may very well be in accord with 
 human experience ; but it is to be doubted if the distinction 
 will bear the weight which is actually put upon it in the 
 treatise. For, by employing it, Cumberland attempted to 
 prove the complete sufficiency of the ' sanction,' as given in 
 the present life, for every moral agent whatsoever. 
 
 It will be seen that the whole account of ' obligation ' 
 brings out, in clear relief, the egoistic elements in the system. 
 Cumberland's theory of obUgation (so far as his explicit treat- 
 ment is concerned) is not essentially different from Paley's, 
 though it must be conceded that it is expressed in a much less 
 offensive way. One may surmise that this appearance of 
 egoism would have been more effectually guarded against, 
 had it not been for the fact that the jural treatment of moral- 
 ity involving emphasis on reward and punishment, was made
 
 Richard Cumberland. 41 
 
 necessary by the author's desire to fight Hobbes on his own 
 ground. 
 
 Cumberland's deduction of the particular Laws of Nature 
 from the general Law, which we have thus far been consider- 
 ing, is by no means elaborate. It is contained in the three 
 short chapters : vi., " Of Those Things which are Contained ui 
 the General Law of Nature " ; vii., " Of the Original of Do- 
 minion and the Moral Virtues " ; viii., " Of the Moral Virtues 
 in Particular ".1 The last chapter, ix., " Corollaries," as the 
 name might suggest, does not properly belong to the system- 
 atic part of the treatise. We shall now notice the principal 
 points in the three chapters first mentioned. 
 
 Chapter vi., " Of Those Things which are Contained in the 
 General Law of Nature," is very short, and even so contains a 
 good deal that has been treated before. This is rather disap- 
 pointing, for it is just here that we should naturally look for 
 the most important part of the ' deduction '. Two questions 
 are proposed by the author: (i) What things are compre- 
 hended in the conmion Good } and (2) What actions tend to 
 promote it ? The answer to the first question contains nothing 
 new or to the present purpose. As regards actions tending to 
 promote the common Good, Cumberland divides them into 
 classes, each corresponding to the particular ' faculty ' of the 
 mind supposed to be principally involved. Hence we have 
 (i) acts of the Understanding, (2) acts of the Will and Affec- 
 tions, or acts of the Body determined by the Will. Under 
 the former head Cumberland treats of Prudence, which he 
 divides into {a) Constancy, and {b^ Moderation. Constancy, 
 again, may manifest itself either as Fortitude or as Patience ; 
 while Moderation implies Integrity and Diligence, or Industry. 
 
 Passing to ' acts of the Will ' enjoined by the Law of 
 Nature, these are all found to be included in ' the most ex- 
 
 ' The first five chapters are : i., " Of the Nature of Things " ; ii., " Of Human 
 Nature and Right Reason"; iii., "Of Natural Good"; iv., "Of the Practical 
 Dictates of Reason " ; v., " Of the Law of Nature and its Obligation ". These 
 titles, however, as already said, do not give a very definite idea of the nature of 
 the contents of the several chapters.
 
 42 History of Uti/itarianism. 
 
 tensive and operative benevolence '. The author says : " It 
 belongs to the same benevolence to endeavour that nothing 
 be done contrary to the common good, and to correct and 
 amend it if there has ; hence Equity [or Justice] is an essential 
 branch of this virtue ".^ This Universal Benevolence also 
 includes Innocence, Gentleness, Repentance, Restitution, and 
 Self-denial ; and, further, Candour, Fidelity, and Gratitude. 
 " In these few heads," says Cumberland, " are contained the 
 primary special Laws of Nature and the fundamental prin- 
 ciples of all virtues and societies ".^ 
 
 In this connection, Cumberland asserts that some actions 
 may be regarded as morally ' indifferent,' but the term is mis- 
 leading. Those actions without which it is impossible to 
 obtain the end proposed are ' necessary ' ; those to which there 
 are others equivalent, i.e., equally calculated to conduce to 
 the common weal, are termed ' indifferent '. Every action, 
 then, may very well have a moral character ; and yet it may 
 be no more efficacious in promoting the ' greatest end ' than 
 certain other actions. Accordingly it may, in this sense only, 
 be termed ' indifferent '. These cases, we are told, leave room 
 for the greatest individual freedom ; also for positive laws 
 contracting such liberty within narrower bounds. 
 
 It will be seen that, however original and important ma}' 
 have been Cumberland's idea that the particular laws of moral 
 action, or Laws of Nature, could be deduced from one princi- 
 ple, viz., that requiring of all moral agents conduct that should 
 conduce to the common Good, his ' deduction ' of these particu- 
 lar Laws thus far contains little or nothing calling for remark, 
 unless it be the naive application of a more than usually 
 crude ' faculty psychology,' where he distinguishes between 
 acts of the Understanding and those of the Will and Affec- 
 tions. This, however, is not relevant to the present discussion. 
 
 The two remaining chapters, vii., " Of the Original of 
 Dominion and the Moral Virtues," and viii., " Of the Moral 
 Virtues in Particular," treat incidentally of a great variety of 
 
 1 See p. 309. '^See p. 311.
 
 Richard Cu}?ibc7'/a)id. 43 
 
 topics, but are principally concerned with the Laws of Nature 
 which have to do with the distribution and tenure of property. 
 
 It will be remembered that Hobbes had maintained, though 
 not in so many words, that ' self-preservation is the first law 
 of nature ' ; and also, as regards property, that in a state of 
 nature each had a ' right ' to all — which, of course, means 
 only that each had a ' right ' to all that he could get and keep.^ 
 Otherwise stated, self-preservation (or the conscious seeking 
 of one's own happiness) was regarded not only as a ' right,' 
 but as the only original spring of action, while brute force was 
 regarded as the only criterion. Possession was ten-\.er\\.\\s of 
 the law ; though, of course, this possession on the part of the 
 strongest could be only of the most temporary character, 
 owing to the (approximate) ' original equality ' of men. 
 
 Now, as regards the former, self-preservation, Cumberland 
 does not admit either that men have a primary and inalienable 
 right to preserve themselves, or that the desire of self-preserva- 
 tion is naturally their ruling motive. He had already said, in 
 Chapter i., " Of the Nature of Things " : " It cannot be known 
 that any one has a right to preserve himself, unless it be known 
 that this will contribute to the common good, or that it is at 
 least consistent with it. ... A right even to self-defence cannot 
 be understood without respect had to the concessions of the 
 Law of Nature which consults the good of all." - This is 
 nothing if not explicit ; but it is to be noticed that we are 
 here concerned only with the question as to what is to be re- 
 garded as the ultimate ethical principle. As regards our mode 
 of action, this very ' good of all,' which is the ethical ultimate, 
 demands that (in all ordinary circumstances) " every one should 
 study his own preservation, and further perfection "? The 
 degree to which one should subordinate one's own interests to 
 the common Good, depends, of course, upon circumstances. 
 That it may extend even to the sacrifice of one's life, Cumber- 
 land would have been the last to deny. In such a case he 
 
 ' As a matter of fact, this hypothetical ' right to all things ' extended not only 
 to the material good things of life, but to everything whatever. 
 ' See p. 67. » See p. 69.
 
 44 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 would have maintained his general thesis, that the good of all 
 and the good of each coincide, by insisting upon the benefits 
 already received by the individual at the hands of society.^ 
 We have already seen that this does not really prove his point. 
 
 Passing then to Cumberland's deduction of the right to 
 personal property, we must remember that he was confronted 
 with Hobbes's doctrine that, in a state of nature, each had a 
 * right ' to all. His argument, which practically is, that so- 
 ciety could not exist without proprietorship in the case of at 
 least some things, however sound it may be in itself, can 
 hardly be called the conclusive answer to Hobbes that he 
 himself supposed it to be. The difference between the two 
 was primarily regarding the nature of man, and not so much 
 regarding the conditions under which society could exist. For 
 it was just Hobbes's contention that society could not exist in 
 what he chose to call a ' state of nature ' ; hence the absolute 
 need of founding the State, and such a state as the ' Leviathan ' 
 that he described. The irrelevance of a good many of the 
 author's particular criticisms of Hobbes cannot but strike the 
 reader. 
 
 The controversial part of the treatise, however, is not that 
 with which we are mainly concerned, so we pass on to Cum- 
 berland's own deduction of the right to property. It is some- 
 what important to notice the exact form of the argument. " It 
 has been proved," he says, " that in the common happiness are 
 contained both the highest honour of God, and the perfections 
 both of the minds and bodies of men ; moreover, it is well 
 known from the Nature of Things that, in order to these ends, 
 are necessarily required both many actions of men, and uses of 
 things which cannot, at the same time, be subservient to other 
 uses. From whence it follows that men, who are obliged to 
 promote the common good, are likewise necessarily obliged to 
 consent that the use of things and labour of persons, so far as 
 they are necessary to particular men to enable them to promote 
 the public good, should be so granted them, that they may not 
 
 ^ See, e.g., p. 27.
 
 Richard Ciivtberland. 45 
 
 lawfully be taken from them, whilst the aforesaid necessity 
 continues ; that is, that those things should, at least during such 
 time, become their property and be called their own. But 
 such necessity continuing, by reason of the continuance of like 
 times and circumstances, a perpetual property, or right to the 
 use of things, and to the assistance of persons necessary, will 
 follow to each person during life." ^ 
 
 It is to be noticed that there are two parts of this de- 
 duction : (i) the argument for the original partition of goods ; 
 (2) the argument for the permanence of that partition.^ These 
 should be carefully distinguished. It is precisely in the con- 
 fusion of the two that the obscurity of Cumberland's treatment 
 of property lies. 
 
 (i) As regards the (original) teniporajy right to the use of 
 things and the services of other people, there seems to be no 
 difficulty. Without some external things, the individual can- 
 not exist, still less be of any service to his fellow-men. More- 
 over, as the author says, " the same nourishment and necessary 
 clothing which preserves the life of one man cannot at the 
 same time perform the same office for any other ". Hence, in 
 practice, some of the things essential to the maintenance of 
 life must be divided in order to be used at all. This applies 
 absolutely, however, only to food and clothing. Cumberland 
 certainly has a great deal more than these in mind. Indeed, 
 he shows that in a state of nature, preceding the complete 
 division of things, frequent disputes would arise " where it 
 was not very evident what was necessary to each " ? These, 
 and also the sloth of those * neglecting to cultivate the common 
 fields,' would inevitably, he thinks, lead to the further division. 
 
 (2) But this division, having once been made, \s final, owing 
 to the assumed continuance of ' like times and circumstances '. 
 The too easy transition from (i) to (2) is the weak point in 
 the deduction. Some division had to be made ; a certain 
 division has actually been made ; and the complete and abid- 
 
 ' See p. 313. Cf. pp. 64 et seq. This is put in the form of a Law on p. 315, 
 which, of course, involves nothing but a purely verbal change. 
 ^ Involving inheritance, of course. ^ See p. 321.
 
 46 Histo}'y of Utilitarianism. 
 
 ing justice of this division Cumberland accepts as a matter of 
 course. We need not discuss the division, he says, " because 
 we all find it ready made to our hands, in a manner plainly 
 sufficient to procure the best end, the honour of God and the 
 happiness of all men, if* they be not wanting to themselves".^ 
 That there is any way radically to remove the hardships of 
 the present distribution (which certainly is not worse than it 
 was in Cumberland's time), it would perhaps be difficult to 
 maintain ; but the author's breezy optimism with regard to the 
 felicity resulting from the existing distribution, is a little amus- 
 ing, in the light of the economic problems of the present day. 
 The choice, according to his view, would seem to be between 
 the present system and " violating and overturning all settled 
 rights, divine and human, and endeavouring to introduce a 
 new division of all property, according to the judgment or 
 affections of [some] one man ".- 
 
 Indeed, Cumberland's argument for the existing distribution 
 of wealth is curiously analogous to that of Hobbes for the 
 absolute character of the then existing government. Hobbes 
 had practically said : Any government is better than none ; 
 choose between an absolute government (the only stable one) 
 and none at all. Cumberland, as we have seen, practically 
 says : Some division of property had to be made ; this actually 
 was made ; choose between this and " violating and over- 
 turning all settled rights ". In this connection, he remarks 
 that, with Grotius, he highly approves of that saying of Thucy- 
 dides : " It is just for every one to preserve that form of 
 government in the state, which has been delivered down to 
 him ". 
 
 According to Cumberland, then, our ultimate right to that 
 which we legally possess, under the existing order of things, 
 depends upon the fact that a recognition of the sanctity of 
 property is essential to the stability of society ; not so much 
 upon the fact that our property enables us to promote the 
 common good. If the latter were really the criterion, a partial 
 
 ^ See p. 322, particularly the passage at the foot of the page. 
 2 See p. 323.
 
 Richard CuTnberland. 47 
 
 redistribution of property every now and again might seem to 
 be the inevitable consequence. My only object in referring 
 to this is to call attention to the fact — somewhat important, 
 as it seems to me — that Cumberland's criterion for the distri- 
 bution of property applies only, or mainly, to the (hypothetical) 
 original partition of the same ; not to the actual distribution 
 as we now find it. And the (actual) ' original partition,' surely, 
 was made upon anything but ethical principles. 
 
 With the last chapter, viii., " Of the Moral Virtues in Par- 
 ticular," we are not here specially concerned, as the funda- 
 mental principles have already been considered. The mode of 
 treatment is sufficiently indicated by the following passage : 
 " The special laws of the moral virtues may, after this manner, 
 be deduced from the law of Universal Justice. There being a 
 law given which fixes and preserves the rights of particular 
 persons, for this end only, that the common good of all be pro- 
 moted by every one, all will be laid under these two obligations, 
 in order to that end : (i) To contribute to others such a share 
 of those things which are committed to their trust, as may not 
 destroy that part which is necessary to themselves for the 
 same end ; (2) to reserve to themselves that use of what is their 
 own, as may be most advantageous to, or at least consistent 
 with, the good of others." 1 Thus abstractly stated, the prin- 
 ciples may seem commonplace enough ; but it is characteristic 
 of the best side of Cumberland's ethical theory that, in carry- 
 ing them out, he preserves so true a balance between duties of 
 ' giving ' and duties of ' receiving '. He himself says that, if 
 confusion be attributed to him by reason of his recognition of 
 the two classes of duties, the confusion must be attributed to 
 Nature herself. Here, again, as so often, he illustrates his 
 position by reference to what we know to be the conditions 
 necessary to the preservation and health of any organism. 
 His deduction of the particular virtues under each class, we 
 need not stop to consider. 
 
 Although Cumberland's ethical system has been treated 
 
 ' See p. 329.
 
 48 History of Utilitarianis77i. 
 
 topically throughout, in these two chapters, it seems desirable 
 to restate, as briefly as may be, the principal results of our 
 investigation. This is the more necessary on account of the 
 somewhat heterogeneous elements that enter into the system. 
 I. Hobbes had regarded man as a bundle of egoistic instincts, 
 and had practically denied the existence of Right Reason. 
 Cumberland insists, on the other hand, that the non-rational 
 side of human nature manifests altruistic as well as egoistic 
 tendencies ; and also that man is essentially a rational being. 
 Our sympathetic feelings are emphasised more when the author 
 is thinking of society as an organic whole, while the rationality 
 of man is usually brought out into strong relief when the dis- 
 cussion is regarding the individual. That the existence of 
 sympathetic feeling ' fits ' us for society is evident, of course. 
 Our rationality, on the other hand, ' fits ' us for society in a 
 double way: (i) It enables us to see our own good as indis- 
 solubly connected with the good of society, and so leads to 
 objectively moral conduct from ultimately egoistic motives ; 
 (2) it enables us to recognise and desire the Good in and for 
 itself — irrespective of the question as to whose good it may be. 
 The difference between these two parts which Reason plays 
 is important. The second is, perhaps, hardly consistent with 
 the general tendency of the system. Cumberland's view, th^t 
 benevolent feeling first came into human life as sexual love 
 and the parental instinct to protect the young, has been suffi- 
 ciently noticed ; as also his view that the kindly affections (re- 
 garded physiologically) tend toward the conservation of the 
 individual, while the contrary is true of the malevolent affec- 
 tions. It should also be kept in mind that, when opposing the 
 egoism of Hobbes, the author always attempts to prove, not 
 simply that man is, to a certain degree, benevolent ; but that 
 he must be so, from the nature of the human organism and its 
 relation to that greater organism, society, of which it is a 
 constituent part. Cumberland's treatment of the benevolent 
 feelings inevitably suggests the Evolutional view, but it is easy 
 to see that it is consistent with his own static view of things. 
 On the whole, we are left somewhat in doubt as to whether
 
 Richard Cumberland. 49 
 
 the motive of the moral agent is ever wholly altruistic. At the 
 same time, as we have already seen, perhaps this is not one 
 of the things which we should criticise in the system, as the 
 question is a somewhat abstract one, which naturally did not 
 trouble Cumberland, whose aim throughout was eminently 
 practical. It was enough for him that we are practically altru- 
 istic in many of our actions, i.e., free from selfish calculations 
 regarding a probable reward. 
 
 II. Turning to the problem of the Good, we were obliged 
 to conclude that the Good is described, now in terms of ' pre- 
 servation ' or ' perfection,' now in terms of ' happiness '. As 
 regards the first set of passages. Professor Sidgwick probably 
 exaggerates the ambiguity of Cumberland's notion of ' perfec- 
 tion'. From this point of view, the Good is that which pre- 
 serves and perfects both mind and body. As regards the pas- 
 sages which seem to make ' happiness ' the end, we were 
 obliged to ask what was meant by ' happiness,' for the term is 
 very vaguely used by early ethical writers. It was found to 
 h& pleasure depending upon (i) the unimpeded (and effective) 
 normal activities of mind and body ; (2) a tranquil frame of 
 mind, which, in turn, depends upon {a) external circumstances, 
 (J)) the feeling that we have acted ' consistently,' {c) the con- 
 sciousness that we have acted for the common weal ; and (3) 
 a knowledge that others around us are happy. It will also be 
 remembered that Cumberland distinguishes between what is 
 ' naturally ' and what is ' morally ' good. ' Natural ' good is 
 the ultimate for Ethics. On the other hand, only voluntary 
 actions which tend to that which is ' naturally ' good, are 
 ' morally ' good. So much for the Good in general. Of 
 course, what Cumberland sets up as the (objective) end of all 
 truly moral action is the Good of all, or of as many as 
 possible. 
 
 III. As regards the Laws of Nature, we saw that the system 
 did not really need such a scaffolding, and, indeed, that it was 
 rather hampered than helped by it. At the same time, we had 
 to recognise that the external form of the system was practi- 
 cally determined by this conception ; also that it was here that 
 
 4
 
 50 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 we must look for Cumberland's application of his unifying prin- 
 ciple, i.e., his deduction of the particular virtues. Hobbes had 
 demanded that a Law should be ' clearly promulgated by a 
 competent authority ' ; and had denied that, in this sense, the 
 Laws of Nature were Laws at all. Cumberland, on the other 
 hand, is concerned to show that they are technically such. 
 They are ' clearly promulgated,' for the effects of actions are 
 uniform ; and we cannot doubt of the ' competent authority ' 
 in this case, for it is none less than the First Cause, the 
 Author of Nature. The effects of actions were found to be 
 treated only in so far as they belonged to the present life ; but 
 a sharp distinction was made between the ' immediate ' [inter- 
 nal] and the ' mediate ' [external] effects, for the confessed 
 reason that ' mediate ' effects were somewhat uncertain. The 
 deduction of the particular Laws of Nature was found to be 
 hardly adequate, but, on the whole, consistent. 
 
 What shall be said of the system which we have been exam- 
 ining } Cumberland's philosophical style is radically bad, his 
 order of exposition almost uniformly unfortunate. Moreover, 
 a good many of his very numerous criticisms of Hobbes are 
 somewhat wide of the mark. It might seem as if there were 
 little use in attempting to revive interest in this practically 
 forgotten moralist. Yet the curious fact is, that Cumberland 
 alone, of the English ethical writers of his time, sounds modern, 
 as we read him to-day. Hobbes and Cudworth were greater 
 men ; More had a more charming personality ; but when we 
 read their works, we feel that Absolutism, Intellectualism, and 
 theological Mysticism, as foundations of ethical theory, belong 
 essentially to the past. Cumberland, on the other hand, 
 ' builded better than he knew '. He was the first exponent, in 
 England, at least, of a tendency which for a long time practi- 
 cally dominated English Ethics. And even this is not all. 
 Though writing nearly two centuries before Darwin, he viewed 
 society as an organic whole. Perhaps no single phrase would 
 express his ideal so completely as ' the health of the social or- 
 ganism ' ; and yet we regard that formula as the peculiar prop-
 
 Richard Cumberland. 51 
 
 erty of the present generation. Moreover, if he recognises 
 ' preservation ' and ' perfection,' on the one hand, and ' happi- 
 ness,' on the other, as parallel principles, we must concede that 
 neither of these principles has definitely supplanted the other 
 even yet. Indeed — if one may venture to attribute anything 
 like unanimity to the constructive ethical hterature of the last 
 few years — it may be said that what is now being sought, more 
 than anything else, is some principle at once comprehensive 
 enough to combine these two seemingly antagonistic notions 
 in a higher synthesis, and definite enough to serve as the basis 
 of a coherent system of Ethics.
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 SHAFTESBURY AND FRANCIS HUTCHESON : THEIR RELATION 
 TO UTILITARIANISM. 
 
 While we are certainly bound to recognise in Cumberland's 
 De legibus naturae, published in 1672, the first statement by 
 an English writer of the Utilitarian principle, it would be idle 
 to claim that the system of the Bishop of Peterborough is free 
 from ambiguity, or even internal contradictions. Indeed, 
 throughout the treatise ' perfection ' (in the sense of highest 
 development of the powers of mind and body) is regarded as 
 a principle parallel to that of ' the greatest happiness of all '. 
 It is only by noting the greater emphasis laid upon the Utili- 
 tarian principle, the greater actual use made of it in rationalis- 
 ing morality, that we are able confidently to place Cumberland, 
 where he belongs, at the head of the distinguished list of 
 English Utilitarian moralists. 
 
 We shall now attempt to trace the further development of 
 the ' greatest happiness ' principle. The first step might seem 
 to be an obvious one ; for Locke— whose Essay, it will be 
 remembered, was first published in 1689-90 — is popularly 
 regarded not only as a Utilitarian, but as the founder of Eng- 
 lish Utilitarianism. One can hardly understand the prevalence 
 of this mistaken view, particularly as no recognised authority 
 on the history of English Ethics seems really to have com- 
 mitted himself to such an interpretation of Locke. ^ 
 
 ^ It is to be admitted that Whevvell's treatment of Locke's system, at once 
 careless and somewhat partisan, would be almost sure to mislead the ordinary 
 reader. He takes no pains to distinguish between the supposed tendency of the 
 system of thought as a whole and what Locke actually set forth as his own 
 views on ethical subjects. At the same time, he does mention, toward the end 
 
 (52)
 
 Shaftesbury and Francis Hutcheson. 53 
 
 The fact is that Locke, while he devoted the first book of 
 the Essay to controverting the doctrine of ' innate ideas ' (as he 
 understood it), is by no means opposed to Intuitional Ethics in 
 its more moderate form. To be sure, he holds that " good and 
 evil . . . are nothing but pleasure or pain, or that which 
 occasions or procures pleasure or pain to us ".^ If he had 
 actually worked out his ethical theory on this basis, we should, 
 of course, find him standing for acknowledged Hedonism; 
 but this he did not do. One has to gather his views on the 
 subject from works devoted to other matters, mainly from the 
 Essay and the Reasojiableness of Christianity. If the result 
 is not altogether satisfactory, we must be particularly careful 
 not to read into the philosopher's views on Ethics a consistency 
 not to be found there. On the one hand, he was not a little 
 influenced by the then almost universal conception of Laws of 
 Nature ; and, on the other, he seems to hold the contradictory 
 theses (i) that human reason is not able to arrive at proper 
 notions of morality, apart from revelation ; ^ and (2) that 
 moral, like mathematical, truths are capable of rigorous and 
 complete demonstration.^ Often, indeed, Locke is concerned 
 to show that the practice of virtue is conducive to happiness ; 
 but this, in itself, proves nothing. Nearly all his contempo- 
 raries, of whatever ethical school, did the same. It is wholly 
 characteristic, when he speaks of Divine Law as " the eternal, 
 immutable, standard of right "."* In fact, apart from certain 
 more or less doubtful corollaries from his philosophical system 
 — like his position that the truths of Ethics are capable of 
 quasi-mathematical demonstration — his ethical speculations 
 were mainly on the theological plane. In so far as this was 
 true, he did not, of course, definitely commit himself to any 
 particular ethical theory. It would thus hardly be too much 
 
 of his exposition, certain features of the ethical system proper which ought to 
 keep one from regarding it as standing for the ' greatest happiness ' principle. — 
 See Hist, of Mow Phil, in England, Lect. v. 
 
 ^ Essay, Bk. II., ch. xxviii., § 5. 
 
 ^ See, e.g., Reas. of Chr., Works, vol. VII., p. 141. 
 
 •" See, e.g., Essay, Bk. III., ch. xi., § 16. 
 
 ^Reas. of Chr., Works, vol. VII., p. 133.
 
 54 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 to say that Locke had no ethical system at all, in the strict 
 sense of the word. This implies nothing whatever in disparage- 
 ment of the philosopher, but simply that he never gave to 
 Ethics a sufficient amount of consecutive attention to develop a 
 coherent system of his own. There is, of course, no doubt 
 that Empiricism, which Locke did so much to inaugurate, had 
 most important consequences for Ethics ; but these will best 
 be considered when we come to examine the earlier form of 
 Associationist-Utilitarianism. 
 
 The case of two other important English philosophers, 
 whose interests were pre-eminently ethical, viz., Shaftesbury 
 and Hutcheson, presents much more difficulty. While it 
 is quite unusual, and, as it seems to the present writer, 
 equally unjustifiable, to class them as Utilitarians,^ their 
 systems do stand in a relation to Utilitarianism sufficiently 
 close to require careful examination. And, unfortunateh-. 
 it is quite impossible adequately to treat this matter with- 
 out devoting to it more space than would be proper in a 
 History of English Utilitarianism. To do so, would mean to 
 exhibit in detail all sides of these complex systems, and then 
 to show the subordinate importance of their Utilitarian aspect. 
 We must therefore confine ourselves here to a brief, if not 
 somewhat dogmatic, presentation of what is, in itself, worthy of 
 much more elaborate treatment. 
 
 Two questions, m particular, occupied the ethical writers 
 of the period which we are considering : (i) What is the 
 ' end ' of moral action ? (2) What is the nature of man, 
 and in what relation does this stand to the ' end ' ? But it 
 might very well happen — did constantly happen, in fact — that 
 different writers would give a very different emphasis to these 
 two questions, fundamentally related as they are. Thus 
 Shaftesbury ^ was so concerned with the question regarding 
 
 1 The relation of Hutcheson to Utilitarianism is much closer than that of 
 Shaftesbury, as we shall presently see. 
 
 2 The first edition of the Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times, 
 was published in three volumes, in 1711. The following references are to the 
 second edition, published in 1714.
 
 Shaftesbury and Francis Hutcheson, 55 
 
 the nature of man, and with his idea that virtue is ' natural, 
 and consists in a proper ' balance ' of the affections, that he 
 practically failed to give the first question, that regarding the 
 ' end ' of moral action, explicit treatment. As a result, while 
 we find in his system by far the best refutation of Hobbes 
 which had appeared up to his time, it is particularly hard to 
 say exactly how he would have defined the Good. 
 
 But first, with regard to the nature of man. Nothing is 
 more absurdly fictitious, according to Shaftesbury's view, than 
 Hobbes's ' state of nature '. In the first place, we can find no 
 true starting-point for Ethics in the individual. Try as we 
 may, we still find him forming part of a system. ^ But, keep- 
 ing to the individual for the sake of the argument, "the 
 creature must have endured many changes ; and each change, 
 whilst he was thus growing up, was as natural, one as another. 
 So that either there must be reckoned a hundred different 
 states of nature ; or, if one, it can be only that in which nature 
 was perfect, and her growth complete"- Again, nothing is 
 so natural as that which conduces to preservation, whether the 
 creature in question be man or animal. Then, " if eating and 
 drinking be natural, herding is so too. If any appetite or 
 sense be natural, the sense of fellowship is the same." ^ 
 
 We are thus prepared to see that the popular antithesis 
 between egoism and altruism — upon which any theory of 
 absolute egoism, like that of Hobbes, must be based — is 
 largely artificial. We may very well distinguish the ' natural ' 
 [social, benevolent] affections from the ' self ' affections [love 
 of life, bodily appetites, etc.], and both of these from the 
 ' unnatural ' affections [malevolence, etc.] ; * but only the last 
 are really bad. ' Self ' affections are not only permissible, but 
 necessary, while the ' natural ' affections may exist in excess, 
 and thus defeat themselves. Virtue, then, consists not so 
 much in a triumph of the one set of impulses over the other as 
 
 ^Inquiry concerning Virtue, "Characteristics," vol. II., pp. i6 et seq. 
 
 - The Moralists, vol. II., p. 316. 
 
 "Freedom of Wit and Humour, vol. I., p. no. 
 
 * Inquiry, vol. II., pp. 86 et seq.
 
 56 Histoiy of Utilitarianism. 
 
 in a proper ' balance ' between the two. As we have seen, 
 man finds himself part of a system from the very first. Since 
 he is originally a social being, he derives his greatest happiness 
 from that which makes for the existence of society and the 
 common weal. Hence the good of all tends to become realised 
 through the enlightened endeavours of each to attain his own 
 true happiness ; for vice, according to Shaftesbury, ultimately 
 springs from ignorance. Therefore " the question would not 
 be, Who loved himself, or Who not ? but Who loved and 
 served himself the rightest, and after the truest manner ? " ^ 
 
 Virtue, then, consists in the harmony of the first two classes 
 of affections. But the necessary concomitant of virtue is 
 happiness, just as pleasure attends the right state of the phys- 
 ical organism. The good man is his own best friend, the bad 
 man his own worst enemy ; for every good act tends to har- 
 monise the affections, every bad act to derange them. 2 
 Whether happiness itself be the Good, we shall have to ask 
 almost immediately. Here we are only concerned with its 
 relation to virtue, as the necessary concomitant of the latter. 
 
 Before leaving Shaftesbury's treatment of the nature of man, 
 it will be necessary to consider his doctrine of a ' moral sense '. 
 The importance of this doctrine for the system is, of course, 
 variously estimated ; ^ but certainly it cannot by any means be 
 ignored. As the name would imply, the ' moral sense ' is 
 original. It is analogous to the faculty by virtue of which, as 
 Shaftesbury assumes, we are able in some measure to appre- 
 ciate the beautiful from the very first. But it is to be noted 
 that both these faculties require cultivation. Thus the ' moral 
 sense ' is hardly the infallible guide which Butler thought he 
 found in Conscience. It also differs from the latter in that it 
 seems to belong almost wholly to the affective side of our 
 nature. But though it acts, in a way, independently of reason, 
 
 ' Freedom of Wit and Humour, vol. I., p. 121. 
 
 ^Inquiry, vol. II., p. 85. 
 
 ^Professor Sidgwick very justly says: "This doctrine, though characteristic 
 and important, is not exactly necessary to his main argument ; it is the crown 
 rather than the keystone of his ethical structure ".—See Hist, of Ethics, p. 187.
 
 Shaftesbury and Fra7icis Hutcheson. 57 
 
 it is never in contradiction with the latter. On the contrary, 
 its deliverances may be vindicated by reference to reason and 
 experience. When it is perverted, this is through habitual 
 wrong action (which deranges the affections), or through super- 
 stition. 
 
 Turning now to the author's account of the ' end ' of moral 
 action, we are prepared for some ambiguity. Of course the 
 good of all must be the end, or must be implied by the end/ 
 since the author begins with the conception of man as a social 
 being. But what is the Good ? Shaftesbury's frequent use of 
 the word * happiness ' is not in itself decisive. Happiness, as 
 we have just seen, is the necessary concomitant of the right 
 state of the being in question. This latter seems generally 
 to be regarded as the thing most important ; ^ at the same time, 
 it is impossible to deny that the author's interpretation of the 
 Good often seems clearly enough to be hedonistic.^ In Cum- 
 berland we found ' happiness ' and ' perfection ' as distinct, but 
 parallel principles. In Shaftesbury, on the other hand, we do 
 not find them thus in mechanical juxtaposition, but wrought 
 together, so that they appear as different aspects of the same 
 fact of moral health or harmony. Therefore, we have here a 
 system more difficult than even that of Cumberland to place 
 under one of the conventional modern rubrics. The good of 
 society is the test, indeed, but what this good is, Shaftesbury 
 nowhere quite clearly states. The system would seem to bear 
 at least a closer relation to the modern doctrine of ' Self-realisa- 
 tion ' than to Utilitarianism, and this, in spite of the author's 
 habitual emphasis of the affective side of our nature, at the 
 expense of the cognitive and volitional sides.* It will be re- 
 membered that he constantly insists upon the importance of an 
 harmonious development of the truly human nature, even 
 
 ^ See, e.g., Inquiry, vol. II., p. 78. 
 
 ^See, e.g., ibid., pp. 14 ef seq. Cf. Sidgwick, Hist. 0/ Ethics, p. 184, note. 
 
 ^ See, e.g.. Inquiry, vol. II., pp. 99 et seq. 
 
 * This one-sidedness of Shaftesbury's system doubtless arose in part from the 
 fact that he was contending explicitly against Hobbes and implicitly against the 
 Intellectualists.
 
 58 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 where he is concerned to show that the practice of virtue is 
 conducive to the agent's own happiness, and seldom, if ever, 
 suggests definite hedonistic calculations as determining the 
 morality of a given action or class of actions. In what has 
 just been said, the complication arising from Shaftesbury's 
 theory of a ' moral sense ' has been purposely neglected. For 
 many this would at once determine the non-Utilitarian char- 
 acter of the system ; but it should be remembered that the 
 importance of this theory for the system as a whole is variously 
 estimated. 
 
 It is customary to regard Hutcheson's system ^ as the logical 
 development of Shaftesbury's ; but, while true in a sense, this 
 view requires important modification. Though we have 
 already found in Shaftesbury's system practically all the 
 elements that enter into Hutcheson's, the different em- 
 phasis which is given to two of these in the latter system 
 should be carefully noted. Shaftesbury, in his explicit opposi- 
 tion to Hobbes and his implicit opposition to the Intellec- 
 tualists, had tended to identify virtue with benevolence. At the 
 same time, his fundamental thought seems to have been that 
 virtue consists in the harmony of the ' natural ' and ' self ' 
 affections. With Hutcheson, on the other hand, benevolence 
 becomes much more prominent, and is practically regarded as 
 the beginning and the end of virtue. Again, Shaftesbury had 
 assumed the existence of a ' moral sense,' but his system is 
 quite intelligible without it. On the other hand, it would 
 hardly be too much to say that Hutcheson's main object was to 
 prove the existence of a ' moral sense,' distinct from self- 
 interest. 
 
 Let us consider the ' moral sense ' first. This is defined as 
 " that determination to be pleased with the contemplation of 
 those affections, actions, or characters of rational agents, which 
 
 ' The Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design and the Inquiry 
 concerning Moral Good and Evil appeared in 1725 ; the Essay on the Nature and 
 Conduct of the Passions and Affections, and Illustrations upon the Moral Sense, 
 in 1728, The System of Moral Philosophy was pubHshed posthumously in 1755.
 
 Shaftesbtuy and Francis HtUclieson. 59 
 
 we call virtuous ". It is universal in distribution, immediate in 
 action, and original in character. We are obliged to assume 
 such a faculty, mainly because it is impossible to reduce our 
 moral judgments to considerations of self-interest. This 
 doctrine of a ' moral sense ' is not to be confused with that of 
 ' innate ideas,' to which it bears " no relation ".^ The ' moral 
 sense ' requires education and development, like our other 
 faculties. In respect of importance, it appears to be designed 
 for regulating and controlling all our powers.^ It is to be ob- 
 served that this faculty approves always, and only, of benevo- 
 lence in the moral agent ; ^ also that " it gives us more pleasure 
 and pain than all our other faculties ".* 
 
 As we have just seen, benevolence, in this system, is the 
 very essence of virtue ; and (as with Shaftesbury) it is in the 
 truest sense ' natural,' not a subtle refinement of egoism. 
 Indeed, Hutcheson's extreme insistence on benevolence results 
 in a one-sidedness which cannot be overlooked. Yet the 
 author admits that the want of some degree of self-love would 
 be " universally pernicious," ^ and even holds that one may 
 treat oneself as one would a third person " who was a com- 
 petitor of equal merit ".^ He attempts to avoid the difficulty 
 — a real one for a system identifying virtue with benevolence- — 
 by showing that we may moralise our naive tendency to pursue 
 our own happiness by remembering always that a due regard 
 for it is necessary for the good of all. Again, he does not 
 claim, of course, that the benevolence in which virtue practi- 
 cally consists is felt equally for all men ; but rather likens it to 
 gravitation, which " increases as the distance is diminished "? 
 
 The relation between benevolence and the ' moral sense ' in 
 the system is now tolerably plain. The fact that we approve 
 benevolence, and nothing but benevolence, as virtuous, proves 
 the existence of the ' moral sense '. If we had no such faculty, 
 
 ^Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue, second ed., 
 p. xvi. Of course this is only Hutcheson's view of the matter. 
 ^System of Moral Philosophy, vol. I., p. 6i. 
 ^Inquiry, pp. 196 et seq. ^ Ibid., p. 242. 
 
 ^ Ibid., p. 172. ''Ibid., p. 174. 'Ibid., p. 220.
 
 6o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 we should approve only what was advantageous to ourselves. 
 On the other hand, it is our ' moral sense ' that proves the 
 essence of virtue to consist in benevolence. We must avoid 
 confusion on one point, however : benevolence, as an impulse 
 to virtue, is quite distinct from the ' moral sense,' as a disposi- 
 tion to receive pleasure from the contemplation of virtue. We 
 do not act benevolently for the pleasure which we may thus 
 obtain. That would be a contradiction in terms.^ 
 
 So much, then, for benevolence and the * moral sense,' as the 
 two most important aspects of man's moral nature. Taken 
 alone, however, they are not sufficient. Our natural benevo- 
 lence is a merely general tendency impelling us to conduct for 
 the good of our fellows, particularly those standing to us in the 
 closest relations of life. As such, it needs guidance. And 
 again, the ' moral sense ' — so far, at least, as we have yet 
 seen — simply approves of actions performed from benevolent 
 motives. Thus it approves of what is ' formally ' good,^ the 
 good intention. But when we are electing what course of 
 action we shall pursue, we are to aim at that which is ' materi- 
 ally ' good. Here it is still, perhaps, the ' moral sense ' that 
 gives us the clue, but for practical guidance we must depend 
 largely upon our cognitive powers, as employed with reference 
 to an external criterion. 
 
 It will be best to let the author give his own account of this 
 very important matter. " In comparing the moral qualities of 
 actions, in order to regulate our election among various actions 
 proposed, or to find which of them has the greatest moral 
 excellency, we are led by our moral sense of virtue to judge 
 thus : that in equal degrees of happiness, expected to proceed 
 from the action, the virtue is in proportion to the number of 
 persons to whom the happiness shall extend ; (and here the 
 dignity or moral importance of persons may compensate num- 
 bers) and, in equal numbers, the virtue is as the quantity of 
 the happiness, or natural good ; or that the virtue is in a com- 
 pound ratio of the quantity of good and number of enjoyers. 
 
 ^ Inquiry, p. ii6. 
 
 -The distinction is made by Hutcheson himself. See System, vol. I., p. 252.
 
 Shaftesbury and Francis Htitcheson. 6i 
 
 In the same manner, the moral evil, or vice, is as the degree 
 of misery, and number of sufferers ; so that, that action is best 
 which procures the greatest happiness for the greatest num- 
 bers ; and that worst which, in Hke manner, occasions misery." ^ 
 
 This looks at first like Utilitarianism pure and simple ; but 
 Hutcheson is mainly interested in that which \s fonnally good, 
 the benevolent intention, and he develops a calculus, the object 
 of which is to show the degree of morality of a given action in 
 terms of the net benevolence of the agent, i.e., excess of 
 benevolence over self-interest. He begins with five ' axioms '. 
 For example : Let M = moment of good ; B = benevolence ; 
 and A = ability. Then M = B x Ar These apparently 
 simple ' axioms ' lend themselves to decidedly elaborate com- 
 putations, the ultimate object of which, in each case, is to 
 ascertain the value of B. It must always be remembered, 
 however, that M (the amount of happiness produced by the 
 action) is assumed in these computations as a known quantity. 
 Now M must be learned from experience, and the ' hedonistic 
 calculus ' of the Utilitarian must be employed to find it. Thus 
 the calculus referred to supplements, but does not supplant, 
 the ' hedonistic calculus '. In spite of the ' moral sense,' the 
 actual content of the moral laws would have to be largely 
 determined by Utilitarian methods.-^ 
 
 It may still seem as if the system were Utilitarianism in 
 disguise — and Hutcheson does actually stand in a much 
 closer relation to the ' greatest happiness ' theory than does 
 Shaftesbury — ^but the matter is not so simple as would at first 
 appear. That which makes for happiness is the ' materially ' 
 Good, to be sure ; but we have seen that " the dignity or moral 
 importance of persons may compensate numbers ". Moreover, 
 as might be expected, when the happiness of only one person 
 is under consideration, the qualitative distinction between pleas- 
 ures is regarded as absolute. The author says : " We have 
 an immediate sense of a dignity, a perfection, or beatific quality 
 in some kinds, which no intenseness of the lower kinds can 
 
 ^Inquiry, p. 177. ^Ibid., pp. 183-188. 
 
 "Such is actually Hutcheson's procedure in many of his deductions.
 
 62 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 equal, were they also as lasting as we could wish "> And this 
 feeling of human dignity, we are told, is something which we 
 have quite independently of the ' moral sense '.- 
 
 It is further to be noted that, while Hutcheson came a good 
 deal nearer than Shaftesbury to stating the Utilitarian principle 
 (and was apparently the first English writer to hit upon the 
 exact Utilitarian formula), he also emphasised the doctrine of a 
 ' moral sense ' much more strongly than Shaftesbury had done. 
 This results in a very considerable complication. The ' moral 
 sense ' is by hypothesis ultimate. Now, not only is it, accord- 
 ing to Hutcheson, the touchstone of virtue ; but from it, either 
 directly or indirectly, are derived the major part of our 
 pleasures and pains. Obviously this has an important bearing 
 upon the ' hedonistic calculus,' which we found to be logically 
 implied by the system. In computing the ' material ' goodness 
 of an action, we must take into account, not merely the 
 natural effects of the action, but these comphcated with the 
 much more important effects of the ' moral sense ' itself. The 
 result is that the ' hedonistic calculus,' as ordinarily under- 
 stood, is pushed into the background. Indeed, as we have 
 had occasion to notice, when Hutcheson actually develops a 
 ' calculus,' it is to ascertain the amount of benevolence implied 
 by a given action, not the amount of happiness which may be 
 expected to result from it, this latter, curiously enough, being 
 assumed as a known quantity. 
 
 From what has been said, it will be seen that the system 
 which we have been examining is not properly Utilitarian. Of 
 course, if the author had been as predominantly interested in 
 the ' materially ' good as he actually was in the ' formally ' 
 good, and had avoided certain minor inconsistencies, his system 
 would have closely resembled that of J. S. Mill; but, on 
 the one hand, we are not at liberty to neglect the emphasis 
 which he actually gave to the different sides of his system, and, 
 on the other, it is now generally admitted that J. S. Mill was 
 not a consistent exponent of Utilitarianism. In short, Hutche- 
 
 1 System, vol. I., p. 117. -Ibid., p. 27.
 
 Shaftesbury and Francis Hutcheson. 63 
 
 son is the ' Moral Sense ' philosopher par excellence. To lose 
 sight of this, is to misinterpret his system. The g-eneral drift 
 of his argument is plain. If we approve or disapprove of 
 actions, we must do so from motives of self-interest or from 
 motives independent of self-interest. The author's first step is 
 to prove the disinterestedness of our moral judgments. This, 
 he thinks, shows conclusively the existence of a ' moral sense,' 
 and so vindicates his characteristic position. 
 
 It hardly need be said, that the two very suggestive systems 
 which we have been examining necessarily appear at a dis- 
 advantage in being compared with a type of ethical theory to 
 which they do not properly belong. Most certainly they are 
 not to be criticised merely for teaching more than can be com- 
 prehended within the bounds of the Utilitarian formula. Sub- 
 sequent ethical theory for a long time represented an increasing 
 degree of differentiation, which could only end in one-sidedness 
 all round. In our own generation, there is a marked tendency 
 to return to that more comprehensive view of man which 
 Shaftesbury, in particular, did so much to work out, and to 
 attempt a synthesis which shall do justice to our human nature 
 as a whole.
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 GEORGE BERKELEY, JOHN GAY, AND JOHN BROWN. 
 
 Those who are inclined to regard Utilitarianism as neces- 
 sarily irreligious in its tendency, would do well to examine 
 somewhat carefully the numerous ' replies,' explicit and im- 
 plicit, called forth by the writings of Shaftesbury and Hutche- 
 son. These ' replies * naturally represented various points of 
 view, but they were more similar in spirit than the reader of 
 our own day would be likely to expect The almost universal 
 verdict of those who opposed the ' Moral Sense ' ethics was, 
 that it claimed too much for human nature, i.e., that it assumed 
 a degree of unselfishness and a natural inclination toward 
 virtue on the part of the moral agent, which by no means 
 corresponded with the hard facts. Now it is highly important 
 to notice from what quarter these attacks for the most part 
 came. Mandeville, indeed, whose Fable of the Bees, or 
 Private Vices Public Benefits (17 14), represented the extreme 
 form of this view that Shaftesbury had paid too high a com- 
 pliment to human nature, was as far as possible from being 
 a theologian, though he cynically suggested that, by proving 
 the utter selfishness and insincerity of man (in his unregenerate 
 state), he had put himself on the side of orthodox belief. But, 
 as a matter of fact, by far the greater number of such protests 
 came from the theologians themselves. They thought, and 
 were right in thinking, that the ' Moral Sense ' ethics, in its 
 attempt to prove the perfect naturalness of virtue, had done 
 something to obscure the notion of moral obligation. In fact, 
 they commonly went to the extreme of believing that the 
 * aesthetic ' view of morality involved consequences dangerous 
 
 (64)
 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown. 65 
 
 to religion itself. For if the ultimate ground of obligation lay 
 in a refined sensitiveness to differences between right and 
 wrong actions, what should be said to a man who might affirm 
 that, just as he had no very good ear for music, he was unable 
 to perceive the ethical differences commonly recognised ? 
 Moreover, if the ' moral sense ' were sufficient, why did we 
 need religion at all ? 
 
 In short, a very large proportion of the earlier theological 
 opponents of the ' Moral Sense ' philosophers agreed in believ- 
 ing that self-interest was the ruling principle of human nature. 
 This being the case, all depended upon showing that it was 
 for the agent's interest to be moral. Now no amount of 
 argument could prove that this would always hold true, if we 
 should leave out of account the supernatural sanctions of 
 morality. Hence what we would now term ' Theological 
 Utilitarianism ' seemed the only natural position for orthodox 
 Christianity. It may seem a little strange to those who know 
 Bishop Berkeley only, or mainly, as the enthusiastic exponent 
 of ' immaterialism ' and the champion of orthodoxy against 
 the free-thinkers, that he should have been one of the very 
 first of the opponents of Shaftesbury to put this doctrine of 
 so-called ' Theological Utilitarianism ' into definite form. But 
 one has only to examine his sermon on " Passive Obedience " 
 (17 1 2) to see that this is the case. His principal object here, 
 as the full title of the sermon would indicate, was to empha- 
 sise the duty of complete submission to recognised civil author- 
 ity ; but he gives, near the beginning of the sermon, the most 
 definite statement to be found in his works of his theory of 
 the ultimate ground of moral obligation.^ 
 
 The argument is as follows. Since self-love is the ruling 
 principle of human action, we naturally term things that make 
 for or against our happiness ' good ' or ' evil,' as the case may 
 be. " It is the whole business of our lives to endeavour, 
 by a proper application of our faculties, to procure the one 
 and avoid the other." At first, pleasures and pains of sense 
 are all that appeal to us ; but even on this plane experience 
 
 ' See Works (Fraser's ed.), vol. III., pp. no et seq. 
 
 5
 
 6^ History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 soon shows that we must often forego a present pleasure, 
 if we would avoid a greater future pain. " Besides, as the 
 nobler faculties of the human soul begin to display themselves, 
 they discover to us goods far more excellent than those which 
 affect the senses." This naturally impresses upon us still 
 further the lesson of self-control. But since all that is tem- 
 poral is ' less than nothing ' in comparison with that which is 
 eternal, and since we further learn by the ' light of nature ' 
 that there is a Divine Being who alone can make us either 
 eternally happy or eternally miserable, it clearly follows that 
 we should implicitly obey the will of God. But what is the 
 will of God ? Since He is a Being of infinite goodness, He can 
 will nothing but that which is good. Further, since He can- 
 not Himself be conceived as standing in need of anything. He 
 must will the good of His creatures, and that alone. But this 
 we have seen to be happiness. And " as nothing in a natural 
 state can entitle one man more than another to the favour of 
 God, except only moral goodness ... it follows that, antece- 
 dent to the end proposed by God, no distinction can be con- 
 ceived between men. ... It is not therefore the private good 
 of this or that man, nation, or age, but the general well-being 
 of all men, of all nations, of all ages of the world, which God 
 designs should be procured by the concurring actions of each 
 individual." 
 
 How shall this ' great end ' of all human action be attained ? 
 Only two methods of divine moral government would seem 
 possible, (i) We might be left to do that which, in the 
 particular case, should seem likely to conduce to the public 
 good ; or (2) the Divine Being might enjoin " the observation 
 of some determinate, established laws, which, if universally 
 practised, have, from the nature of things, an essential fitness 
 to procure the well-being of mankind ; though, in their parti- 
 cular application, they are sometimes, through untoward 
 accidents, and the perverse irregularity of human wills, the 
 occasions of great sufferings and misfortunes, it may be, to 
 very many good men ". Against the first possible method, 
 Berkeley makes two objections. First, it is impossible
 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown. 67 
 
 accurately to foresee the consequences of our action in any 
 particular case ; and even if it were possible, such calculation 
 " would yet take up too much time to be of use in the affairs 
 of life ". And secondly, we should in this case be without an 
 infallible standard of conduct. 
 
 General rules, then, are absolutely necessary. How shall 
 they be ascertained ? Here Berkeley seems to follow Cumber- 
 land closely. " Whatsoever practical proposition doth to 
 right reason evidently appear to have a necessary connection 
 with the universal well-being included in it, is to be looked 
 upon as enjoined by the will of God." These propositions, 
 he goes on to show, may be called Laws of Nature, " because 
 they are universal, and do not derive their obligation from any 
 civil sanction, but immediately from the Author of nature 
 Himself ". Or again, they may be termed Eternal Rules of 
 Reason, " because they necessarily result from the nature of 
 things, and may be demonstrated by the infallible deductions 
 of reason ". Here Berkeley pauses to insist in the strongest 
 terms that these laws are to be observed in all cases whatever, 
 and at the expense of no matter what real or apparent hard- 
 ship to oneself or others. No exhaustive enumeration of the 
 Laws of Nature (or Laws of Reason) is attempted, but those 
 mentioned correspond to the commands of the Decalogue. 
 
 It will readily be surmised that this sermon would hardly 
 have been noticed at such length, but for a special reason. 
 While the argument is clear and tolerably consistent, it does 
 not represent any real advance upon Cumberland's treatment, 
 unless perhaps we may regard as such the tacit omission of 
 ' perfection ' (of mind and body) as a principle parallel to that 
 of ' the greatest happiness of all '. The real significance of 
 the sermon lies in the fact that it expresses, with clearness and 
 precision, the view that almost inevitably commended itself 
 to those orthodox theologians of the day who thought they 
 detected dangerous tendencies in the ' Moral Sense ' ethics. 
 It will be necessary to examine Berkeley's ethical theory a 
 little further, in order that we may be able to distinguish from 
 it a theory stated anonymously nineteen years later, which was
 
 68 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 destined to exert a very marked influence upon the further 
 development of ethical speculation in England. 
 
 In the first place, it will be noticed that Berkeley accepts, 
 without any attempt at further analysis, the then current con- 
 ception of Laws of Nature. His treatment here, as already 
 indicated, is a pretty close reproduction of that of Cumberland. 
 This does not of itself make against the general Utihtarian 
 character of his doctrine, but it plainly tends to emphasise the 
 eternal and absolute character of particular moral laws in a 
 way that would hardly result from the mere consideration of 
 consequences. So long as the Laws of Nature were taken 
 with absolute seriousness, the belief in them tended to retard 
 the development of ethical theory ; and this quite apart from 
 the particular ' method ' of Ethics in question. 
 
 We have seen that Berkeley starts from the assumption that 
 self-interest is the universal spring of human action, and this, 
 would seem to differentiate his view from that of Cumberland ; 
 but Berkeley's writings are not quite free from ambiguity on 
 this point. He sometimes assumes the social nature of man, 
 without, however, attempting an a priori demonstration of the 
 necessity of altruism, as Cumberland had done. In this con- 
 nection, the question naturally arises, whether he recognised 
 qualitative differences between pleasures, and here again we 
 are left in uncertainty. This is rather curious, for a large part 
 of the Second Dialogue in Alciphron, or the Minute Philos- 
 opher {iy2)2), is devoted to a consideration of the question as 
 to what pleasures are most desirable. Sometimes he seems 
 to insist upon the dignity of human nature ; ^ but after all 
 the general drift of the argument is to show that the ' plea- 
 sures of imagination ' and ' pleasures of reason ' are greater, 
 or at any rate more permanently satisfactory, than the 
 * pleasures of sense '. It would not do to insist too much 
 upon his treatment here, however, for it might reasonably be 
 held that Berkeley is using an argumentum ad homineniy 
 since the argument is directed, for the most part, against those 
 
 ^ See Works, vol. II., p. 80, Cf. an important passage on p. 89.^
 
 George Berkeley^ John Gay, and John Brown. 69 
 
 who are gratuitously assumed to hold a particularly unworthy 
 view of what things are desirable for man. 
 
 Two other points may properly be noticed. In the first 
 place, Berkeley frankly depended upon the doctrine of future 
 rewards and punishments in a way that Cumberland had, pre- 
 sumably from controversial considerations, refrained from do- 
 ing. Henceforth this was to be the most characteristic feature 
 of the doctrine of the so-called ' Theological Utilitarians '. 
 Secondly, Berkeley states with admirable clearness two of the 
 three main reasons against depending upon the computation 
 of consequences in the particular case, viz.: (i) that it is im- 
 possible to predict the consequences of any particular action, 
 and (2) that at the moment of action there would be no time 
 for deliberate computations, even if such computations were 
 capable of yielding exact results. The other obvious reason 
 is, that at the moment of action self-interest is likely to be, 
 more than ever, a complicating factor in our moral judgments. 
 These three arguments were destined to play an important 
 part in Utilitarian discussions during the rest of the eighteenth 
 century. To those who favoured the Utilitarian doctrine, 
 they were regarded as a sufficient demonstration of the neces- 
 sity of ' general rules,' while to many of the opponents of 
 Utilitarianism, they seemed conclusive against the doctrine 
 itself. 
 
 It might seem highly improbable that an anonymous disser- 
 tation of only about thirty pages, prefixed to a translation, 
 actually by another hand, of a third writer's Latin work, should 
 be one of the most interesting and important contributions to 
 the early development of the ' greatest happiness ' principle. 
 Yet such undoubtedl)'- is the Preliminary Dissertation : con- 
 cerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or Morality, now 
 known to have been written by the Rev. John Gay, prefixed to 
 Law's translation of King's Origin of Evil. The first edition 
 (of the translation and the Dissertation) was published in 173 1 ; 
 the second, " revised and enlarged " — an almost exact reprint, 
 so far as the Dissertation is concerned — in 1732.
 
 70 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 A few dates should be kept in mind here. The first edition 
 of Shaftesbury's Inquiry concerning Virtue and Merit was pub- 
 h'shed in 1699 ; that of Hutcheson's Inquiry into the Original 
 of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue in 1725. Hume's ethical 
 system first appeared in 1740, as the third book of the Treatise 
 of Human Nature, the other two books having been published 
 the year before. Gay's Dissertation, therefore, appeared six 
 years after Hutcheson's first ethical work, and nine years 
 before the corresponding work of Hume. It is interesting to 
 note that Gay's true successors, Tucker and Paley — for Hume 
 does not seem to have been influenced by him — belong to a 
 later generation. The Light of Nature Pursued was first 
 published in ly 62>-y 7, 2ind XhQ Aloral and Political Philosophy 
 in 1785. 
 
 We shall now turn to the Prelitninary Dissertation itself, 
 and give it the very careful examination which its importance 
 justifies. The author's own order of exposition, which is not 
 uniformly fortunate, will be followed substantially, except 
 where notice is given to the contrary. This is possible on 
 account of the brevity of the Dissertation, and desirable, on the 
 whole, as it will facilitate a comparison of the substance of this 
 remarkable essay — which is not, for most, readily accessible ^ — 
 with the other ethical works named above. 
 
 Gay begins by remarking that, though all writers on morality 
 have practically agreed as to what particular classes of actions 
 are virtuous or the reverse, they have at least seemed to differ 
 in their answers to the related questions : (i) What is the 
 ' criterion ' of virtue ? and (2) What is the motive by which 
 men are induced to pursue it ? Both of these questions must 
 be considered, of course, in any treatment of Ethics, and the 
 author's own view is that the same principle, or the same set 
 of principles, will be found to solve both. 
 
 It is therefore indifferent which side of the moral problem 
 we consider first. But, before attempting anything constructive, 
 
 ^ Since the above was written, the Dissertation has been reprinted in Mr. 
 Selby-Bigge's British Moralists (vol. II., §§ 849-887), but the text there followed 
 is that of the fifth edition (1781).
 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown, 71 
 
 Gay stops to notice a current view. Some hold that a rational 
 creature will choose only that which, on the whole, is calculated 
 to bring him most happiness ; further, that virtue does bring 
 the agent most happiness ; and that therefore it will be chosen 
 just in proportion as one is rational.^ Moreover, they hold 
 that whatever is an ' object of choice ' is ' approved of '. Gay 
 seems to object to this view mainly because it implies too great 
 a degree of self-consciousness on the part of the agent. He 
 admits that Hutcheson 2 has made abundantly plain : (i) that 
 most men do actually approve virtue without knowing why ; 
 and (2) that some pursue it even in opposition to their own 
 apparent advantage. But Hutcheson was not content with 
 emphasising the facts ; he had recourse to a ' moral sense ' to 
 explain moral approval, and a ' public or benevolent affection ' 
 to explain apparently disinterested conduct. This, however, is 
 cutting the knot instead of untying it. We may very well be 
 practically benevolent and capable of forming what seem like 
 ultimate moral judgments, and yet these phenomena of our 
 moral life may be perfectly explicable without assuming un- 
 known ' faculties ' or ' principles '. 
 
 So much for the point of departure. We are now ready to 
 follow the author's own attempt at a solution of the problems 
 of Ethics. At the very beginning, unfortunately, he entangles 
 himself and his readers in a fruitless discussion regarding the 
 meaning of the term ' criterion,' which we may safely omit.^ 
 In this discussion, however, he has occasion to define virtue, 
 and the definition — ^which he wrongly supposes would be 
 accepted by all, despite differences in ethical theory — is impor- 
 tant for his own treatment of Ethics. He says : " Virtue is 
 the conformity to a rule of life, directing the actions of all 
 rational creatures with respect to each other's happiness; to 
 which conformity every one in all cases is obliged : and every 
 
 * Here Gay carelessly speaks of virtue as being " always an object of choice "* 
 ' Referred to as " the ingenious author of the Inquiry into the Original of our 
 
 Idea of Virtue ". 
 
 ^ Gay's own use of ' criterion ' is not quite exact, as will be seen later ; but 
 
 the omitted discussion throws practically no light on his use of the word.
 
 72 Histoiy of Utilitarianism. 
 
 one that does so conform is, or ought to be, approved of, 
 esteemed, and loved for so doing ".^ In justification of this 
 definition. Gay observes that virtue always implies some re- 
 lation to others. " Where self is only concerned, a man is 
 called ' prudent ' (not virtuous), and an action which relates 
 immediately to God is styled ' religious '." Again, as we have 
 already seen, whatever men may believe virtue to consist in, 
 they always assume that it implies ' obligation,' and that it 
 deserves ' approbation '. 
 
 Before treating directly of the ' criterion ' of virtue, the 
 author chooses to consider ' obligation '. This section ^ of the 
 Dissertation is so important — particularly with a view to sub- 
 sequent ethical theory, as represented by Tucker, Paley, and 
 Bentham — that the first two paragraphs may be quoted in 
 full. 
 
 " Obligation is the necessity of doing or otnitting any action 
 in order to be happy : i.e., when there is such a relation between 
 an agent and an action that the agent cannot be happy without 
 doing or omitting that action, then the agent is said to be 
 obliged to do or omit that action. So that obligation is evi- 
 dently founded upon the prospect of happiness, and arises 
 from that necessary influence which any action has upon pre- 
 sent or future happiness or misery. And no greater obligation 
 can be supposed to be laid upon any free agent without an 
 express contradiction.^ 
 
 " This obligation may be considered four ways, according 
 to the four different manners in which it is induced : First, 
 that obligation which ariseth from perceiving the natural con- 
 sequences of things, i.e., the consequences of things acting 
 according to the fixed laws of nature, may be called natural. 
 Secondly, that arising from merit or demerit, as producing the 
 esteem and favour of our fellow-creatures, or the contrary, is 
 usually styled vij'tuous.^ Thirdly, that arising from the 
 
 ^ See p. xxxvi. (second ed.). "^I.e., § ii. 
 
 ' C/. Paley's Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy , Bk. II., ch. ii. 
 
 "* The confusion here is only in the form of expression.
 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown, y^ 
 
 authority of the civil magistrate, cwz/. Fourthly, that from 
 the authority of God, religious."^ 
 
 Gay proceeds to show that complete obligation can come 
 only from the authority of God, " because God only can in all 
 cases make a man happy or miserable ". A few paragraphs 
 further on the author is as explicit as one could wish on this 
 point — a very important one, as hardly need be remarked, for 
 the early Utihtarians, who, with the exception of Cumber- 
 land, Hartley, and Hume, agree in regarding the motive 
 of the moral agent as ultimately egoistic. He says : " Thus 
 those who either expressly exclude, or don't mention 
 the will of God, making the immediate criterion of virtue to 
 be the good of mankind, must either allow that virtue is not 
 in all cases obligatory (contrary to the idea which all or most 
 men have of it) or they must say that the good of mankind 
 is a sufficient obligation. But how can the good of mankind 
 be any obligation to me, when perhaps in particular cases, such 
 as laying down my life, or the like, it is contrary to my 
 happiness ? " ^ 
 
 We are now prepared to return to the question regarding the 
 ' criterion ' of virtue. Since complete obligation can come 
 only from God, the will of God is the immediate rule or cri- 
 terion,^ though not the ' whole will of God,' since virtue was 
 defined as ' the conformity to a rule directing my behaviour 
 with respect to my fellow-creatures '. But, as regards my 
 fellows, what does God will that I do .' From the infinite 
 goodness of God it follows that He must desire the happiness 
 of men. Hence He must will such conduct on my part as is 
 calculated to conduce to their happiness. Thus, the will of 
 God is the ' immediate criterion ' of virtue, but the happiness of 
 mankind is the ' criterion ' of the will of God. Hence we must 
 consider the consequences of actions, and from these deduce 
 all particular virtues and vices. 
 
 * Cf. Bentham's Principles of Morals and Legislation, ch. iii., particularly 
 §§ ii.-vi. 
 
 "^ See p. xli. (In the second edition one must look out for errors in paging- 
 The correct paging is given here.) 
 
 'Observe the ambiguity in the use of 'criterion,' referred to in note above.
 
 74 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 We now have in outline all the essential principles of Gay's 
 ethical system proper. The remainder of the Dissertation 
 consists in an attempt to furnish an adequate psychological 
 foundation for the principles above set forth. It will be 
 noticed that this second part ^ was as important for the de- 
 velopment of the Associationist Psychology as both parts 
 were for the development of early Utilitarian theory. 
 
 The author begins by remarking that man is a being capable, 
 not only of passively experiencing pleasure and pam, but of 
 foreseeing the causes of these and governing himself accord- 
 ingly. The ' end ' of action — that pursued for its own sake — 
 is pleasure. That which man finds calculated to produce 
 pleasure, he calls the ' Good,' and approves of it ; while his 
 attitude is precisely the contrary in the case of that which is 
 known to have painful consequences. Now Good or Evil, 
 when thought of, give rise to a proportionate present pleasure 
 or pain. This is called ' passion,' and the attending desire, 
 ' affection '. Hence, by reflecting upon Good and Evil, desires 
 and aversions are excited which are (roughly) distinguished 
 as Love and Hatred. From these, variously modified, arise all 
 the other ' passions ' and ' affections '. It is a mistake to sup- 
 pose that these latter are implanted in our nature originally, 
 like our capacity for experiencing pleasure or pain. 
 
 When directed toward inanimate objects, the passions and 
 affections ^ are Hope, Fear, Despair, and its unnamed opposite. 
 As a matter of fact, however, our pleasures and pains depend 
 quite as much upon other conscious agents as upon inanimate 
 objects. Hence, as Gay says : " As I perceive that my happi- 
 ness is dependent on others, I cannot but judge whatever I 
 apprehend to be proper to excite them to endeavour to promote 
 my happiness, to be a means of happiness, i.e., I cannot but 
 approve it". Moreover, since others can be induced to act for 
 my happiness only by the prospect of their own future happi- 
 ness, I cannot but approve of " the annexing pleasure to such 
 
 ^ This division of the Dissertation into two parts is not explicitly made by 
 Gay. At the same time his order of exposition inevitably suggests it. 
 ' Gay makes no serious attempt to keep the two separate.
 
 George Berkeley^ John Gay^ and John Brown. 7 5 
 
 actions of theirs as are undertaken upon my account ". And, 
 since we desire what we approve of,^ we desire the happiness 
 of those who have done us good. That in the agent (a volun- 
 tary action or series of such actions) which constitutes the 
 ground for the approbation and love just accounted for, is 
 called the ' merit ' of the agent ; the contrary, ' demerit '. 
 
 But here a difficulty arises. How can there be ' merit ' in 
 the action of another, when that action is performed (ulti- 
 mately) for the agent's own happiness ? The main reason why 
 this seems paradoxical, or worse, to common-sense is that 
 common-sense does not distinguish between an ' inferior ' and 
 an ' ultimate ' end. In by far the greater part of human 
 actions, it is an ' inferior ' end that the agent has in mind. 
 Thus, though the happiness of the agent is always the ' ulti- 
 mate' end, all that the beau immediately desires is to please 
 by his dress, and all that the student immediately desires is 
 knowledge. For any such ' particular ' end, we may, of course, 
 inquire the reason ; but to expect a reason for the ' ultimate ' 
 end is absurd. " To ask why I pursue happiness, will admit 
 of no other answer than an explanation of the terms." 
 
 But, to proceed, when the ' particular ' end of any action is 
 the happiness of another, that action is ' meritorious '. On 
 the other hand, " when an agent has a view in any particular 
 action distinct from my happiness, and that view is his only 
 motive to that action, tho' that action promote my happiness 
 to never so great a degree, yet that agent acquires no tnerit ; 
 i.e., he is not thereby entitled to any favour and esteem ". It 
 makes a great difference, indeed, whether another aims at my 
 favour in general, or only at some particular end which he 
 has in view. " I am under less obligation {caeteris paribus) 
 the more particular his expectations from me are ; but under 
 obligation I am." 2 
 
 Gay concludes by noticing a possible " grand objection " to 
 his theory. It is this. The reason or end of action must 
 always be known to the agent ; otherwise, it would not actu- 
 
 ' The apparent logical inversion here is Gay's. ^ See p. xlviii.
 
 76 History of Uti litarianism. 
 
 ally be his motive. The problem here is not why one should 
 be grateful, but why one is so. As Hutcheson has shown, 
 the majority of mankind approve of virtue immediately, and 
 apparently without regard to their own interest. Must we not, 
 then, after all, assume that author's ' moral sense ' and ' public 
 affections ' .^ 
 
 The reply given to this supposed objection is substantially 
 as follows. The matter of fact here appealed to has already 
 been admitted, and it is perfectly consistent with oUr theory. 
 " As, in the pursuit of truth, we don't always trace every pro- 
 position whose truth we are examining, to a first principle or 
 axiom, but acquiesce as soon as we perceive it deducible from 
 some known or presumed truth ; so in our conduct we do not 
 always travel to the ultimate end of our actions, happiness: 
 but rest contented as soon as we perceive any action subser- 
 vient to a known or presumed means of happiness. . . . And 
 these RESTING PLACES ^ are so often used as principles, 
 that at last, letting that slip out of our minds which first 
 inclined us to embrace them, we are apt to imagine them not, 
 as they really are, the substitutes of principles, but principles 
 themselves." Hence people have imagined ' innate ideas,' 
 * instincts,' and the like ; and the author adds : " I cannot but 
 wonder why the pecuniaiy sense, a sense of power and party, 
 &€., were not mentioned, as well as the moral, — that oi honour, 
 order, and some others "? 
 
 More exactly, the true explanation is this. " We first 
 perceive or imagine some real good, i.e., fitness to promote 
 our happiness, in those things which we love and approve of." 
 Hence we annex pleasure to the idea of the same, with the 
 result that the idea and the attendant pleasure become indis- 
 solubly associated. Gay's first example is the one which has 
 since become so well known in this connection, i.e., the love of 
 money. It is matter of experience that money, first desired 
 merely for what it will procure, sometimes itself becomes the 
 exclusive object of pursuit. In the same way knowledge, 
 
 ^ The large capitals are Gay's, and they occur here only. 
 ^ See pp. Hi., liii.
 
 George Berkeley^ John Gay, and John Brovo^i. yj 
 
 fame, etc., come to be regarded as ends in themselves. Now 
 this principle is quite sufficient, he holds, to explain our dis- 
 interested practice of virtue, as well as certain perverted 
 tendencies of human nature. 
 
 As regards these latter, Gay treats in particular of envy, 
 emphasising the fact that we never envy those who are very 
 much above or below us, but rather those who may fairly be 
 regarded as in some sense competitors. The teleology is 
 plain, he thinks : the success of those with whom we either 
 directly or indirectly compete means less chance for ourselves. 
 " This," as he quaintly adds, " may possibly cast some light 
 upon the black designs and envious purposes of the fallen 
 angels. For why might not they have formerly had some 
 competition with their fellows ? And why may not such 
 associations be as strong in them as [in] us ? " 
 
 At the very close of the Dissertation the author barely 
 refers — though what he says is perfectly clear and to the 
 point — to another consideration which does much to make his 
 general (hedonistic) position plausible. It is not necessary, 
 he says, that we should form associations like those above 
 described for ourselves. We may very well take them from 
 others, i.e., " annex pleasure or pain to certain things or 
 actions because we see others do it, and acquire principles of 
 action by imitating those whom we admire, or whose esteem 
 we would procure. Hence the son too often inherits both 
 the vices and the party of his father, as well as his estate." 
 In this way we can account for national virtues and vices, 
 dispositions and opinions, as well as for what is generally 
 called ' prejudice of education '. 
 
 We should now probably agree that, even from the empiri- 
 cal point of view, the phenomena to which Gay refers would 
 have to be explained, not merely by 'association,' but partly 
 by heredity and partly by what we can hardly avoid calling^ 
 the ' instinct of imitation '. Such considerations at once add 
 plausibility to the hedonistic aspect of Gay's system, and 
 suggest the important limitations of the principle of ' associa- 
 tion,' which he inclines to regard as all-sufficient. Perhaps it
 
 yS History of Utilitai^ianistn. 
 
 was from a certain paternal tenderness for the infant prin- 
 ciple of ' association ' that Gay neglected to press an argument 
 which might have threatened to prove a two-edged sword. 
 
 The Dissertation was so distinctly a new departure that it is 
 difficult to avoid remarking at once upon Gay's relation to 
 subsequent ethical theory. How completely his position was 
 adopted by Tucker and Paley, will be evident to any one 
 acquainted with those writers who has carefully followed the 
 above. Here, however, we must rather attempt to show the 
 relation of the author of the Dissertation to those of his prede- 
 cessors who had been either directly or indirectly concerned 
 with the development of the Utilitarian principle. 
 
 Cumberland had seemed to make both ' the greatest happi- 
 ness of all ' and ' the perfection of body and mind ' the moral 
 end, and this without suspecting any difficulty in so doing ; 
 while Locke, though deeply interested in Ethics on the theo- 
 logical and practical side, and, in the general sense of the word, 
 a hedonist, could hardly be said to have a coherent ethical 
 system of his own. Shaftesbury and Hutcheson, on the other 
 hand, had done much for the development of English ethical 
 theory, but their relation to hedonism was only indirect. In 
 Gay's Dissertation we have, in its complete and unmistakable 
 form, what we later shall have to recognise as the first char- 
 acteristic phase of English Utilitarianism.^ 
 
 ^ It is important to remember that, while Hume, who published his ethical 
 system in its first form only nine years after the Dissertation, was incomparably 
 superior to Gay, both as a thinker and as a writer, he did not happen to state the 
 Utilitarian doctrine in the form which was destined first to be developed. Indeed, 
 it may be doubted if this was a matter of chance. Hume's system, much more 
 complex than Gay's, and, one may add, on a distinctly higher plane, was not 
 calculated to appeal to writers like Tucker, Paley, and Bentham, whose single 
 aim appears to have been simplicity of theory. All the writers just named form 
 a perfectly definite school (Bentham and most historians of Ethics to the contrary 
 notwithstanding), while the phase of Utilitarianism which Hume represents was 
 not further developed until comparatively recent times. Historically, then, 
 Hume stands outside the direct line of development, though he doubtless repre- 
 sents the Utilitarian position, as we now understand it, much more adequately 
 than any one else who wrote in his own, or even in the succeeding, generation.
 
 George Bei'keley, John Gay, and Johi Brown. 79 
 
 Evidently the more particular comparison must be between 
 Gay and Cumberland, for these authors alone, up to this time, 
 had really stated the ' greatest happiness ' principle in fairly 
 scientific form. Cumberland, as we have just seen, defined 
 the Good, now in terms of ' happiness,' now in terms of ' per- 
 fection,' though the emphasis, on the whole, seems clearly 
 enough to be on the hedonistic aspect of the system. Gay, on 
 the other hand, consistently defined the Good as Happiness, 
 and Happiness as ' the sum of pleasures '. Moreover, though 
 he does not discuss the question of possible * qualitative dis- 
 tinctions ' between pleasures, it is evident that for him such 
 distinctions would have no meaning. This, again, is an ad- 
 vance upon Cumberland, for though the latter author by no 
 means commits himself to the theory of ' qualitative distinc- 
 tions,' and sometimes appears to hold the opposite view, 
 there is a serious ambiguity in his treatment which was almost 
 inevitable, considering that he practically carries through 
 Happiness and Perfection as co-ordinate principles. 
 
 As regards the motive of the moral agent, there is in Gay 
 no trace whatever of the confusion which is so striking in 
 Cumberland. It is true that Cumberland had held, what 
 Shaftesbury later made evident, that man is essentially a social 
 being and that the true Good must be a common good. His 
 actual treatment, however, is quite confusing; generally the 
 agent's motive in moral action seems to be regarded as altru- 
 istic, but sometimes the language used seems to imply at least 
 a very considerable admixture of egoism. In Gay, on the con- 
 trary, we find even a fictitious simplicity. All the phenomena 
 of moral action, as we have seen, are explained by the ' asso- 
 ciation of ideas ' and what has more recently been termed the 
 ' law of obliviscence '. We begin as egoists, and, indeed, 
 throughout our lives we uniformly seek our own pleasures, 
 avoid our own pains. But it amounts to much the same thing 
 as if we were originally altruistic to a certain degree. For, 
 although our own happiness is always our ' ultimate ' end, it 
 is by no means always our ' proximate ' end. The system 
 theoretically allows for cases of extreme self-sacrifice.
 
 8o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Whether it really affords a satisfactory explanation of these, 
 is a question which we hardly need enter upon here. The 
 present generation is not likely to make, or allow, extraor- 
 dinary claims for the unaided principle of ' association '. 
 
 So much for the treatment of the ' criterion ' of moral action 
 and of the motive of the moral agent by the two authors whom 
 we are comparing. Closely related to the latter question is 
 that of the ultimate meaning of ' obligation '. It will be re- 
 membered that Cumberland's treatment of obligation was not 
 altogether consistent with his system as a whole. Instead of 
 basing upon the essentially social nature of man and claiming 
 here, as generally elsewhere, a certain degree of altruism for 
 the moral agent, he merely tries to show that it is greatly for 
 the selfish advantage of any given individual to lead the moral 
 life, even when extreme sacrifices are demanded. This was 
 doubtless done in order to meet Hobbes on his own ground, 
 but the same reason led Cumberland to confine his arguments 
 to consequences that might be expected in this present life. 
 For obvious reasons, he does not make out a perfectly clear 
 case. 
 
 Gay was not hampered with any such controversial con- 
 siderations. His treatment is only too clear and consistent 
 throughout. " Obligation is the necessity of doing or omitting 
 any action in order to be happy. . . . And no greater obligation 
 can be supposed to be laid upon any free agent without an 
 express contradiction." This, of course, is the logical conse- 
 quence of his theory of the moral motive ; and he immediately 
 goes on to enumerate " the four different manners in which 
 [obligation] is induced ". These are precisely what appear 
 later as Bentham's four " sanctions ". But how can compiete 
 obligation (which common-sense demands) be vindicated if 
 we define obligation as has just been done ? Gay sees very 
 clearly that we must here depend upon the power and wisdom 
 of the Divine Being, " because God only can in all cases make 
 a man happy or miserable ". And there is no restriction to 
 rewards and punishments as given in this present life. This 
 position was, of course, adopted by Tucker and Paley, the
 
 George Berkeley, John Gay, and John Brown. 8i 
 
 only difference being that Paley particularly insists upon 
 rewards and punishments after death. This whole question 
 as to the meaning of ' complete obligation ' for Utilitarianism 
 in its earlier form, would have to be discussed at some length, 
 if we were comparing Paley and Bentham with Gay and with 
 each other. Here it is enough to notice that, if we assume the 
 necessarily egoistic nature of the motive of the moral agent, 
 and at the same time attempt to preserve the absolute char- 
 acter of obligation. Gay's position is the only logical one, 
 
 In Cumberland we found some confusion in the use of the 
 expression ' Right Reason '. The author had evidently been 
 somewhat influenced by the intuitionists and intellectualists, 
 though he opposed most of their characteristic doctrines, and 
 this without really having worked out his own position in de- 
 tail. Nothing corresponding to this confusion is to be found 
 in Gay. He does, indeed, in one passage seem to distinguish 
 between Experience and Reason, but this is misleading, for he 
 immediately adds : " You either perceive the inconveniences 
 of some thing.s and actions, when they happen, or yon foresee 
 them by contemplating the nature of the things and actions ". 
 Reason here is evidently nothing but the faculty of predicting 
 upon the basis of past experience. 
 
 Again, in Cumberland we are constantly confronted with 
 the then almost universally current conception of Laws of 
 Nature. It is easy to show that the system does not really 
 depend upon this scaffolding, but that, on the contrary, it is 
 rather cumbered than helped by it. At the same time, this 
 conception of Natural Laws not only gives its name to Cum- 
 berland's treatise, but almost wholly determines its external 
 form. The reader hardly needs to be reminded that Gay's 
 remarkable essay is entirely free from such superfluities. One 
 point, however, should be noticed in this connection. Gay 
 refers, of course, to the Will of God as the ' immediate cri- 
 terion ' of morality ; but the Divine Will itself is determined 
 to that which will bring the greatest happiness to mankind, or, 
 as the author himself expresses it, " The happiness of mankind 
 is the criterion of the Will of God ". The Utilitarian prin- 
 
 6
 
 82 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 ciple, then, is clearly regarded as ultimate. It would be a 
 gross misunderstanding of Gay to class him with those who 
 make morality depend upon the arbitrary will of God. 
 
 It will be noticed that neither Cumberland nor Gay dis- 
 cusses the possibility of the ' hedonistic calculus '. Neither of 
 them seems to suspect any difficulty in the matter, and appar- 
 ently this had never been distinctly raised as an objection 
 to hedonism up to the time that we are considering. Perhaps 
 this was to be expected, for such refinements are likely to 
 belong to a later stage of ethical discussion ; but it does at 
 first seem rather strange that, while Gay was the earliest 
 consistent exponent of the Utilitarian principle, he did not 
 anywhere use the formula, ' the greatest happiness of the 
 greatest number '. Hutcheson, it will be remembered, had 
 used this very formula, though it does not for him express the 
 whole essence of morality, as it would have done for Gay ; and 
 Gay must have been familiar with Hutcheson's writings, for 
 he controverts them intelligently. 
 
 It would be quite too ingenious to suggest that Gay re- 
 frained from using the expression precisely because Hutcheson 
 had happened to use it. He seems to have been willing 
 to avail himself of all that he considered true in the Inquiry. 
 The only importance which really can be attached to the omis- 
 sion is this : Gay and his immediate successors ^ held clearly 
 and definitely to the view that, in the last resort, all human 
 motives are selfish. From this standpoint, the now accepted 
 formula is by no means so inevitable as it would be, if one 
 admitted the existence of disinterested sympathy and insisted 
 that this latter must be present in the case of all truly moral 
 action. 
 
 In taking leave of this remarkable essay, we should not for- 
 get that its full significance can be appreciated only after one 
 has taken the trouble to trace back many of what are com- 
 monly regarded as characteristic doctrines of Tucker and 
 
 ^ With the exception of Hartley and Hume (whose treatment of ' sympathy ' 
 is ambiguous in Book HI. of the Treatise, but who admits a certain degree of 
 native altruism in the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals).
 
 George Berkeley, fohn Gay, and Jo kit Brown. 83 
 
 Paley to this their undoubted source. However much these 
 authors did to fill in the outline — and Tucker, at least, did a 
 very great deal — it must be granted that the whole outline 
 of Utilitarianism, in its first complete and unencumbered form, 
 is to be found in Gay's Preliminary Dissertatiofi. 
 
 It will readily be seen that Gay's importance for Ethics was 
 due, not merely to the fact that he stated the Utilitarian 
 doctrine for the first time m perfectly clear and unambiguous 
 form, but quite as much to the fact that he provided the doc- 
 trine with at least the essentials of a psychological foundation. 
 This first appearance of what we may call * scientific method ' 
 in the literature of Utilitarianism, was destined to have most 
 important consequences. In truth, it is only when we take 
 these consequences into consideration, that we are able fully to 
 appreciate the very great difference between a production like 
 the sermon on " Passive Obedience" and the Dissertation. But, 
 before we proceed further in the direct line of our investi- 
 gation, it will be well to pause for a little, and, neglecting the 
 strict chronological order, notice a belated criticism of Shaftes- 
 bury which appeared about twenty years after Gay's remark- 
 able essay. The propriety of noticing this here will be 
 apparent from the fact, that the part of the Essays on the 
 Characteristics which we shall examine consists almost wholly 
 in the careful development of Gay's theory of the moral 
 motive. 
 
 It may be doubted whether this book, published in 175 1 by 
 the Rev. John Brown, has been at all generally appreciated 
 in recent years, though J. S. Mill and Professor Fowler have 
 spoken of it in the highest terms. ^ Indeed, it is one of the 
 very few controversial books of this period that can still be 
 read with satisfaction. Even the Bishop of Cloyne was by no 
 means always just or courteous to his opponents,^ but Brown 
 
 * It must have been popular at the time when it was published, for the third 
 edition was printed the year after the first. 
 
 ^See, e.g., the Third Dialogue of Alciphron, where Shaftesbury's views are 
 criticised— particularly the passage in which Shaftesbury himself is described 
 under the name Cratylus.— Works, Eraser's ed., vol. II., p. 128.
 
 84 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 is almost uniformly so. Nor did this prevent him from being 
 one of the most effective critics of his generation. It will be 
 remembered that the Essays were three in number, the first 
 being on " Ridicule, considered as a Test of Truth " ; the 
 second, on " The Obligations of Man to Virtue, and the Neces- 
 sity of Religious Principle " ; and the third, on " Revealed 
 Religion and Christianity ". The second alone is to the 
 present purpose. 
 
 The author begins by remarking that, just as the rainbow 
 seems to the uninstructed to possess an ' original ' beauty, but 
 yet is as capable of scientific explanation as the more common- 
 place phenomena of nature, so virtue must not hastily be re- 
 garded as an ultimate, since it may be explained by reference 
 to the end to which all good actions conduce. He then pro- 
 ceeds to argue in a rather ingenious way that, while Wollaston, 
 Clarke, and Shaftesbury, each from his own point of view, 
 professed to vindicate the absolute character of virtue, they all 
 really introduced hedonistic considerations at the crucial point. 
 Moreover, he holds that " if we appeal to the common-sense 
 of mankind, we shall see that the idea of virtue hath never been 
 universally affixed to any action or affection of the mind, 
 unless where this tendency to produce happiness was at least 
 apparent ".^ The two following arguments for happiness 
 as the criterion of morality seem to the author particularly 
 convincing, (i) " Those very affections and actions which, n 
 the ordinary course of things, are approved as virtuous, do 
 change their nature, and become vicious in the strictest sense, 
 when they contradict this fundamental law of the greatest 
 public happiness. ' (2) " With such uncontrolled authority 
 does this great principle command us, that actions which are 
 in their own nature most shocking to every humane affection 
 lose at once their moral deformity, when they become sub- 
 servient to the general welfare, and assume both the name and 
 the nature of virtue." An example of the first would be an 
 act of dishonesty committed for the sake of one's own child ; 
 of the second, the execution of a notorious criminal by due 
 
 ^ Essay II., § iii., p. 133 (first ed.).
 
 George Bei'keley, John Gay, and John Brown. 85 
 
 process of law. Thus virtue is found to be nothing else than 
 " the conformity of our affections with the public good : or 
 the voluntary production of the greatest happiness ".^ 
 
 There follows a rather severe criticism of Mandeville, which, 
 as a whole, does not concern us. One passage, however, is 
 interesting. Mandeville had insisted upon the extreme varia- 
 bility of moral ideas in different countries and in different 
 ages of the world. Without by any means denying all the 
 alleged facts, Brown argues that a sound critic would dis- 
 criminate. " If from the variety of opinions among mankind 
 as to some virtues or vices, he concluded these were variable ; 
 then from the universal agreement of mankind with regard to 
 other virtues and vices, he would conclude these w&rejixed and 
 invariable^ This, of course, is the natural reply ; but Brown 
 very pertinently adds : ' And 'tis evident that both their 
 consent and disagreement arise from the same principle " (i.e., 
 regard for the common weal under existing circumstances). 
 In short, Shaftesbury and Mandeville, though representing 
 quite opposite points of view as regards the nature of virtue — 
 the one assigning to it an intrinsic, the other a wholly con- 
 ventional character — made the same fatal mistake of neglect- 
 ing the objective end of virtuous action, the recognition of 
 which alone can put morality on a safe foundation. 
 
 Having thus obtained a tolerably clear notion of what virtue 
 itself is, we are at once confronted with the question .- What 
 are the motives by which mankind can be induced to the 
 practice of it ? Here, as before, we must avoid sentimen- 
 tality. It will appear upon examination that " the only reason 
 or motive, by which individuals can possibly be induced or 
 obliged to the practice of virtue, must be the feeling immediate, 
 or the prospect of future private happiness ".- To the 
 followers of Shaftesbury, this will doubtless seem like an 
 
 ' See § iii., p. 136. The author here definitely refers to " the Preliminary 
 Dissertation to Dr. Law's translation of King's Origin of Evil," and advises the 
 reader who is curious to examine further into this subject to consult both that 
 and certain of the translator's notes. 
 
 '^See § vi., p. 159.
 
 86 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 unworthy account of the matter ; but it is to be remarked 
 that the words ' selfishness ' and ' disinterestedness ' have been 
 used in a very loose and indeterminate manner. " In one 
 sense a motive is called disinterested, when it consists in a 
 pure benevolent affection, or a regard to the moral sense. 
 In another, no motive is disinterested ; for even in acting 
 according to these impulses of benevolence and conscience, 
 we gratify an inclination, and act upon the principle or im- 
 mediate feeling of private happiness." This becomes evident 
 from the fact that " a motive, from its very nature, must be 
 something that affects ourself. . . . Now what can possibly 
 affect ourself^ or determine us to action, but either the feeling 
 or prospect of pleasure or pain, happiness or misery 't " In- 
 deed, if we push the argument further, " 'tis evident, even to 
 demonstration, that no affection can, in the strict sense, be 
 more or less selfish or disinterested than another ; because, 
 whatever be its object, the affection itself is still no more 
 than a mode either of pleasure or of pain, and is therefore 
 equally to be referred to the mind or feeling of the patient, 
 whatever be its external occasion ".^ But, while all this is 
 true, the followers of Shaftesbury are perfectly right in holding 
 that, as sources of happiness, the benevolent affections clearly 
 have the advantage over those ordinarily termed selfish. The 
 preceding argument, which appears to have retained its co- 
 gency for many even to the present day, is open to the most 
 serious objection. It will call for special discussion, when we 
 come to consider the second form of Hume's ethical theory. 
 Here it has seemed to merit the explicit treatment that has 
 been accorded to it, for this is probably the most definite 
 statement that we have (up to the date of the publication of 
 Brown's book) of the view held practically in common by the 
 earlier Utilitarians. 
 
 We have now seen what virtue is, and what is the universal 
 character of human motives. There remains the crucial 
 question : " How far, and upon what foundation, the uniform 
 practice of virtue is really and cleai-ly connected with the 
 
 1 See § vi., p. 163.
 
 George Berkeley^ John Gay, and John Brown. 87 
 
 happiness of every individual ? " And just here it is to be 
 noted that morahsts have made the serious mistake of dis- 
 cussing the ' sources of happiness ' too much in the abstract. 
 These are three : sense, imagination, and the passions. The 
 shghtest observation will convince us, however, that they are 
 of varying importance for different temperaments. " In some, 
 the pleasures and pains of sense predominate ; imagination 
 is dull, the passions inactive. In others, a more delicate frame 
 awakens all the powers of the imagination ; the passions are 
 refined, the senses disregarded. A third constitution is carried 
 away by the strength of passion ; the calls of sense are con- 
 temned, and imagination becomes no more than the necessary 
 instrument of some further gratification." ^ The differences 
 between moralists, with regard to their theory of the moral 
 motive, are thus susceptible of a psychological explanation. 
 Each has unconsciously appealed, and appealed only, to those 
 of like mental constitution with himself. And while this is an 
 important commentary on the majority of the ethical systems 
 that have come down to us, it shows in a rather startling light 
 their essential weakness. Morality is a very serious matter, 
 and it is important to the last degree that the motives 
 to right action presented shall be such as to appeal to all 
 men. 
 
 If we revert to the classification of temperaments just 
 adopted, it will be evident that those susceptible only, or 
 mainly, to pleasures and pains of sense will be quite oblivious 
 to aesthetic or benevolent considerations. Private interest 
 is all that can possibly appeal to them. In the case of the 
 second class, those of a distinctly aesthetic temperament, it 
 is to be remembered that a pronounced taste for the fine arts 
 argues little or nothing for sound moral perceptions. Some- 
 times, indeed, we are tempted to believe that the two are hardly 
 compatible. And even of the third class, for whom the passions 
 are the chief sources of pleasure, it must be said that, if we 
 find here the best of men, we also find the worst. We must 
 not avoid the difficulty by terming the baser affections ' un- 
 
 ' See § vii., p. 169.
 
 88 History of Utilitarianis7ii. 
 
 natural,' as Shaftesbury has done. Whether ' unnatural ' or 
 * natural,' they seem to be thoroughly rooted in far too many 
 cases, and it is not so certam as one would like to believe 
 that they are " a source of constant misery " to the agent, as 
 Shaftesbury claimed. There are, to be sure, rare cases. 
 " where the senses are weak, the imagination refined, and the 
 public affections strongly predominant ".^ In such cases, 
 virtue is indeed its own reward ; all right actions are then 
 spontaneous in the strictest sense. But how few these cases 
 are! 
 
 One touch alone was needed to complete the gloomy pic- 
 ture, and the author adds this with cool precision. Shaftesbury 
 had allowed himself to emphasise the external consequences 
 which naturally follow upon good and bad actions, though 
 this looks like deserting his characteristic position, that happi- 
 ness is essential to virtue and inseparable from it, while un- 
 happiness is equally bound up with vice. Waiving the matter 
 of consistency, however, this raises a general and very serious 
 question : Are moralists right in holding, as many of them 
 seem to do, that virtue is the parent of external happi- 
 ness just as vice undoubtedly is of external misery, and this 
 in the natural course of things? The fact seems to be that 
 the happy consequences which are commonly attributed to 
 virtue, belong not so much to positive virtue as to ' innocence '. 
 The man who indulges in no vices, and who never disregards 
 the rights of others, undoubtedly reaps a certain reward, 
 though it can hardly be claimed that this is proportionate to 
 the corresponding punishments which naturally attend vice 
 and crime. But this is as far as the argument holds. " If 
 we rigorously examine the external consequences of an active 
 virtue in such a world as this, we shall find, it must be often 
 maintained at the expense both of health, ease, and fortune ; 
 often the loss of friends, and increase of enemies ; not to 
 mention the unwearied diligence of envy, which is ever watch- 
 ful and prepared to blast distinguished merit. In the mean- 
 time, the innoxious man sits unmolested and tranquil ; loves 
 
 ^ See ^ vii., p. i86.
 
 Geoj'ge Berkeley, John Gay, and John Bi'own. 89 
 
 virtue, and praiseth it ; avoids the miseries of vice, and the 
 fatigues of active virtue ; offends no man, and therefore is 
 beloved by all." ^ 
 
 Let us return, then, to the question how private and public 
 happiness may be shown to coincide. This agreement is neces- 
 sary in order to the realisation of the moral end, but impossible 
 in the natural course of things — except for the favoured few, 
 as we have seen. One thing alone can achieve for humanity 
 this all-important result : " the lively and active belief of an 
 all-seeing and all-powerful God, who will hereafter make them 
 happy or miserable, according as they designedly promote or 
 violate the happiness of their fellow creatures ' . " And this," 
 adds the author, " is the essence of religion." - Here we find 
 Theological Utilitarianism stated in its most impressive form. 
 We are no longer, as when dealing with Berkeley, confronted 
 with Laws of Nature or of Reason, the ultimate ground of 
 which, to be sure, is Utilitarian, but which are to be accepted 
 as absolute and obeyed without any thought of further an- 
 alysis. The Good is the happiness of mankind ; and to this 
 we must actively contribute, according to our best knowledge 
 and abihty, at all times and under all circumstances. There 
 is no suggestion of difficulty in ascertaining what does contri- 
 bute to the common weal ; the real problem for Brown is : 
 How can we will what we perfectly well know to be for the 
 good of mankind, when this does not happen to coincide with 
 our private interest "" 
 
 It is to be noted that he does not base his argument upon 
 any theological dogma like that of the ' total depravity ' of 
 man in his natural condition. There are some, he admits, who 
 have a moral endowment such that they seem hardly to need 
 even the internal sanctions of religion, much less its external 
 sanctions. But these are very few. And what shall be said 
 of the vast majority, to whom neither the beauty of lioliness 
 nor considerations of disinterested benevolence directly ap- 
 peal 1 Morality is a matter of awful consequence, not merely 
 to the few, but to all men absolutely without exception. Must 
 
 ' See § viii., p. 198, ••! See !} ix., p. 210.
 
 90 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 not the motives, then, be such as will appeal to all ? And if 
 so, nothing but religion, with its doctrine of rewards and 
 punishments after death — the rewards, in particular, being 
 insufficient in this life — can reclaim the world from the lamen- 
 table condition in which we find it. This argument, that the 
 sanctions of morality must be such as to appeal to all men, 
 may provoke a sneer, for the implication would seem to be 
 that the motives presented must be low enough to appeal 
 to all ; but Theological Utilitarianism has at least something 
 to say for itself on this point. In the case of those who have 
 made little or no progress in the moral life, the motive will 
 doubtless be low enough, if one please to call it so, since it will 
 amount to little or nothing more than a desire to ' flee the 
 wrath to come ' ; but it may be said of the stern law, not merely 
 of the old dispensation, but of the new as well, that it is ' a 
 school-master to lead us ' to something far better. 
 
 No comparison has been made between Brown's treatment 
 of Ethics and that of Gay, for this has not seemed necessary. 
 The most characteristic feature of the Dissertation, i.e,, the 
 psychological foundation of the system, and, in particular, the 
 explanation of the genesis of practical altruism, is not treated 
 at all, but for this we are directly referred by the author to the 
 Dissertation itself. The importance of Brown's work arises 
 from the fact that it is, in some respects, the best statement 
 we have of the Utilitarian doctrine, from the distinctly theo- 
 logical point of view. Paley afterward presented the theory 
 in a much more clear-cut and systematic form ; but it may be 
 doubted whether his clever formulas (often adapted from Gay) 
 do not on the whole detract from, rather than add to, the 
 real impressiveness of the position. It seems fair to assume 
 that Theologiccil Utilitarianism will never regain its former 
 importance ; but it represents a very significant, and perhaps 
 necessary, stage in the development of moral theory. Until 
 the student has brought himself to appreciate its force, such 
 as it is, he will find a difficulty in understanding much of what 
 is most characteristic in the English Ethics of the eighteenth 
 century.
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 DAVID HUME. 
 
 We must not look for perfect continuity in the development 
 of Utilitarianism, even after the doctrine had once been clearly 
 enunciated. Two of the most prominent writers of the Utili- 
 tarian school, Tucker and Paley, were destined to carry out, 
 almost to the letter, the scheme of moral theory which Gay 
 had outlined in his Preliminary Dissertation of 1731 ; but 
 the next writer standing for the ' greatest happiness ' principle 
 appears to owe nothing to Gay. On the contrary, so far as 
 formative influences are concerned, Hume seems to have taken 
 his starting-point in Ethics from those who, like Shaftesbury 
 and Hutcheson, had maintained the existence of a ' moral 
 sense '. 
 
 This is by no means to say that Hume was himself a ' Moral 
 Sense ' philosopher. Quite as much as anything else, his 
 object was to show that what the ' Moral Sense ' writers had 
 professed to explain by merely referring to a supposed 
 ' faculty,' could really be explained in a scientific way, accord- 
 ing to the most general principles of human nature. Still, his 
 primary contention was that morality was founded, not on 
 ' reason,' as he expressed it, but on ' sentiment ' ; that our 
 starting-point in ethical discussions must always be the fact 
 of our approval of moral actions — a fact which could not, by 
 any possibility, be explained on purely rational principles. 
 In emphasising ' feeling ' at the expense of ' reason,' Hume 
 was clearly with the ' Moral Sense writers, and it is fair to 
 assume that he was historically, as well as logically, related 
 to them in this respect. 
 
 (91)
 
 92 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Although Hume's writings are so much better known at 
 first hand than those of Cumberland and Gay — the most 
 prominent of his Utilitarian predecessors — it is more difficult 
 than might be supposed to present his views on Ethics in a 
 way to leave no room for misunderstanding. In the first place, 
 one has to keep in mind Hume's relation to the ' Moral Sense ' 
 school, and avoid attributing either too much or too little 
 importance to this relation ; and, in the second place — what 
 is much more important — one has to decide, after the most 
 careful examination and comparison, whether one shall accept 
 his earlier or his later treatment of Etliics as the more 
 adequately representing his system. 
 
 As regards Hume's relation to the ' Moral Sense ' philos- 
 ophers, little need be said at present. It is worth noticing, 
 however, that the apparently complex character of his ethical 
 system has led some to believe that its general drift is some- 
 what ambiguous, and that to the end it holds a rather close 
 relation to the ' Moral Sense ' school.^ This view is, in my 
 opinion, by no means correct ; but as the mistake is a natural 
 one, a comparison may prove helpful. In the case of Hutche- 
 son, we found a moralist whose doctrine could hardly be under- 
 stood without comparing it carefully with the ' greatest 
 happiness ' principle. At the same time, we found that, in its 
 general tendency, it was radically distinct from that principle. 
 Exactly the opposite, it seems to me, is true in the case of 
 Hume. While he certainly was influenced by the ' Moral 
 Sense ' writers, ' utility ' is with him by no means a subsidiar)'^ 
 principle, as with Hutcheson, but incontestably the basis of 
 his whole ethical system. This is a dogmatic statement ; but 
 its truth will, I think, become abundantly plain as we proceed 
 with our examination of Hume's treatment of the subject 
 
 The second difficulty which we noticed, that regarding the 
 two forms in which Hume has left us his ethical theory, 
 
 ' See, e.^.. Professor Hyslop's Elements of Ethics, p. 84 ; also, for a much 
 more guarded statement, referring only to the later form of Hume's ethical 
 theory, see Mr. Selby-Bigge's Introduction to his edition of Hume's Inquiries 
 p. xxvi.
 
 David Hnuie. 93 
 
 requires more immediate and altogether more serious atten- 
 tion. It will be remembered that his first treatment of Ethics 
 appeared as Book III. of the Treatise of Human Nature in 
 1740, the year after the publication of the other two books. 
 The Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals did not appear 
 till 175 1, three years after he had published the hiquiry con- 
 cerning Human Understanding, in which he had presented, in 
 a more popular form, the substance of Book I. of the Treatise. 
 The story of Hume's chagrin at the poor reception which 
 his juvenile work met with, and of his explicit repudiation of 
 the Treatise in after years, as not giving his mature views on 
 philosophical subjects, is too familiar to admit of repetition. 
 Critics are now perfectly agreed that the Inquiry concerning 
 Human Understanding, however superior in style to the first 
 book of the Treatise, is an inadequate statement of the author's 
 views on metaphysics ; and, since one is bound to disregard 
 Hume's own judgment concerning the relative merits of Book 
 I. of the Treatise and the corresponding Inquiry, it is natural 
 that the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals should 
 have been estimated in much the same way, in spite of the 
 fact that Hume himself considered the second Inquiry as "of 
 all [his] writings, historical, philosophical, or literary, incom- 
 parably the best ". The present tendency plainly is either (i) 
 to regard the two statements of his ethical theory as practi- 
 cally equivalent, and therefore to prefer Book III. of the 
 Treatise merely as historically prior ; or (2) to hold that, in the 
 Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, as well as in the 
 Inquiry concerning Hiunan Understanding, there is an ob- 
 servable falling off in thoroughness of treatment which is by 
 no means compensated for by the undoubted improvement in 
 style. 
 
 I cannot believe that either of these views is correct. It 
 must never be forgotten that, in his later years, Hume was 
 perfectly right in regarding the Treatise of Human Nature as 
 a work abounding in serious defects, mainly such as betray the 
 youth of the author. It is in spite of these defects that the 
 book takes its place as perhaps the most remarkable single
 
 94 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 work in English philosophical literature. The common state- 
 ment that Book I. of the Treatise is to be preferred to the 
 first Inquiry because it is ' more thorough ' — while perfectly 
 true — might be misleading to one not equally acquainted 
 with both works. A great many of the perversely subtle dis- 
 cussions in the Treatise, which Hume ruthlessly pruned away 
 in revising it, were not only mere digressions, tending seriously 
 to confuse the reader, but they were, in themselves, by no 
 means uniformly convincing. To do away with many of 
 these discussions was in itself a real advantage ; but, un- 
 fortunately, Hume was not so much trying to improve the 
 book as trying to make it more acceptable. The result is that, 
 along with what was at once irrelevant and of doubtful validity, 
 he omitted much that was really essential to the adequate 
 statement of his peculiar views on metaphysics. 
 
 One would naturally expect to find much the same thing 
 true in the case of the Inquiry concerning the Principles of 
 Morals. As a matter of fact, however, in spite of what is 
 apparently the current view, I am strongly of the opinion that 
 the Inquiry is not only a clearer, but a better statement of 
 Hume's ethical theory than the third book of the Treatise. 
 Here the elimination has nearly always conduced to that really 
 consecutive treatment which is so important in any philosophi- 
 cal work, and nothing in the least essential to the system as a 
 whole seems to have been left out. Much more important for 
 us, however, is the fact that, in the second Inquiry, Hume 
 does away with the one exasperating ambiguity of his earlier 
 work, i.e., his treatment of ' sympathy '. Other comparisons 
 between the Inquiry and the corresponding book of the 
 Treatise will be made, as it becomes necessary. This, how- 
 ever, is so important that we must take account of it at the 
 very beginning. 
 
 In both the Treatise and the Inquiry — though the order 
 of exposition in the two works differs otherwise, in certain 
 respects — Hume begins with the fact of moral approbation. 
 He first shows — in the Treatise at considerable length ; in 
 the Inquiry more briefly, but perhaps as convincingly — that
 
 David Hume. 95 
 
 moral approbation cannot ultimately be fomided upon prin- 
 ciples of mere reason. After thus clearing the ground, he 
 attempts to explain our approbation of moral conduct by refer- 
 ring, not to a supposed ' moral sense,' but to what he assumes 
 to be the springs of human action and the determining effects 
 of human experience. 
 
 Now the important difference between the standpoint of 
 the Treatise and that of the Inquiry^ just referred to, consists 
 in the radically different answers given in the two works to 
 the question : What are the springs of action — the funda- 
 mental tendencies of human nature? In the Treatise, these 
 are held to be (i) egoism, (2) limited altruism, and (3) ' sym- 
 pathy '. The relation between them is difficult to state in a 
 few words — indeed, so far as ' sympathy ' is concerned, diffi- 
 cult to state at all — but Hume's position in the Treatise 
 apparently is that human nature is essentially egoistic. As 
 regards altruism, he holds distinctly that we have no particu- 
 lar love for our fellow-beings as such.^ Our limited altruism 
 manifests itself only in the case of those standing to us in the 
 closest relations of life, and in a way which does not permit us 
 to suppose that it is an original principle of human nature, 
 strictly co-ordinate with the self-regarding tendency. 
 
 At this point Hume employs the rather mysterious principle 
 of ' sympathy '. For him, in his earlier work, as for many of 
 the later empiricists, ' sympathy ' is produced through the 
 ' association of ideas '. His peculiar mode of explanation is as 
 follows — the point being to show that in this case an ' idea ' 
 is practically converted into an ' impression '. The ' impression 
 of ourselves ' is particularly vivid, and by ' association ' it hap- 
 pens that a corresponding (though of course not equal) vivid- 
 ness is imparted to that which relates to ourselves. But other 
 human beings are similar to ourselves. This relation of ' simi- 
 larity ' makes us vividly conceive what concerns them, the other 
 relations of ' contiguity ' and ' causation ' \i.e., kinship here] 
 assisting in the matter. Thus our idea of another's emotion 
 
 1 Treatise, Bk. III., Pt. II., § i.
 
 96 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 may become so vivid as to give rise to the same emotion in 
 ourselves.^ In spite of its obvious ingenuity, this explanation 
 of ' sympathy ' is far from being satisfactory. One readily 
 sees that for Hume, as for the Associationist school in general, 
 ' sympathy is left in a condition of unstable equilibrium, 
 liable at a touch to be precipitated into egoism pure and 
 simple. 
 
 This aspect of Humes system, in its earlier form, is the 
 more confusing for the reason that he never seriously attempts 
 to state the relation between our derived ' sympathy ' and our 
 fundamental self-regardmg tendency. The result is a degree 
 of theoretical confusion that can only be appreciated by those 
 who have read the Treatise with considerable care. It should 
 be observed that one does not here refer to the inevitable 
 ambiguity of the words ' egoism ' and ' altruism,' as ordinarily 
 used,2 but rather to the fact that Hume professes to explain — 
 almost in the sense of explaining away — what we ordinarily 
 understand by (general) ' sympathy,' without anywhere telling 
 us exactly what he claims to have reduced it to. 
 
 If Hume's treatment of ' sympathy ' were the same in the 
 Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals as in Book III. of 
 the Treatise — which is apparently the careless assumption of 
 those who regard his position in the two works as identical — 
 we should need to examine the mysterious principle consider- 
 ably in detail. As a matter of fact, however, Hume seems to 
 have been keenly aware that his earlier treatment of ' sym- 
 pathy ' was a mistake, and a bad one ; and he gives us what he 
 would probably have regarded as the best possible antidote in 
 what he says on the same subject in the Inquiry. ^ There he 
 means by the word ' sympathy ' nothing essentially different 
 from the general benevolent tendency, the degree of which he 
 shows his good judgment in not attempting to define, but 
 
 1 See Treatise, Bk. II., Pt. I., § xi. 
 
 ^ This ambiguity, of course, depends upon the unwarranted abstraction made 
 by those who speak as if ' egoism ' and ' altruism ' stood for two absolutely dis- 
 tinct tendencies of human nature. 
 
 ' See, e.g., § V., pt. ii., et seq. ; also Appendix ii.
 
 David Htmie. 97 
 
 which he regards as the foundation of the historical develop- 
 ment of morality. 
 
 The significance of this change can hardly be overrated. 
 It does away at once with an almost indefinite amount of theo- 
 retical confusion, and puts Hume on the right track just where 
 his historical, but not logical, successors — Tucker, Paley, and 
 Bentham — were destined to go astray. Nor must it for a 
 moment be supposed that Hume is here going to the other 
 extreme, and contending for the existence of a perfectly differ- 
 entiated ' altruism ' in our human nature, as opposed to an 
 equally differentiated ' egoism ' — as Hutcheson, for example, 
 had mistakenly done. He rather shows that, in the last 
 resort, this distinction resolves itself into an abstraction, and 
 holds, in language which Butler himself would have had to 
 commend : " Whatever contradiction may vulgarly be supposed 
 between the selfish and social sentiments or dispositions, they 
 are really no more opposite than selfish and ambitious, selfish 
 and revengeful, selfish and vain ". And one is almost startled 
 at the agreement with Butler, when he immediately adds : " It 
 is requisite that there be an original propensity of some kind, 
 in order to be a basis to self-love, by giving a relish to the 
 objects of its pursuit ; and none more fit for this purpose than 
 benevolence or humanity "?■ 
 
 To conclude, then : in place of the three quasi-distinct (but 
 by no means co-ordinate) principles — egoism, limited aJtruism,^ 
 and ' sympathy ' — which had been assumed in the Tteatise, 
 we have ' sympathy,' in the ambiguous sense first explained, 
 struck out in the Inquiry, and a human nature there assumed 
 which, as Hume sometimes has occasion to show, necessarily 
 implies at least a certain degree of the benevolent tendency, 
 alongside of the equally essential self-regarding tendency — 
 the two becoming differentiated, in so far as they do become 
 differentiated at all, only in the course of human experience. 
 
 ^ See Inquiry, § IX., pt. ii. Butler's Sernihns upon Human Nature had been 
 published in 1726. 
 
 "^ Our limited altruism is mentioned here as a quasi-distinct principle, because 
 it implies another kind of association, i.e., by 'causation,' besides association by 
 ' similarity ' and by ' contiguity,' which are involved in our general sympathy. 
 
 7
 
 98 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 While I am inclined to lay a great deal of stress upon this 
 change of position on the part of Hume, I cannot at all agree 
 with Mr. Selby-Bigge, when he says (in the brief, but mainly 
 admirable introduction to his edition of Hume's two Inquiries) : 
 "In the Enquiry {concerning the Principles of Morats] there is 
 little to distinguish his [Hume's] theory from the ordinary 
 ' moral sense ' theory, except perhaps a more destructive use 
 of ' utility ' ".1 For, as Mr. Selby-Bigge himself points out, 
 even freer use is made of the principle of ' utility ' in the Inquiry 
 than in the Treatise. And I cannot at all follow him when he 
 adds : " It would be easy to draw consequences from this prin- 
 ciple which would neutralise the concessions made to benevo- 
 lence, but he [Hume] is content himself to leave it without 
 development, and to say in effect that utility pleases simply 
 because it does please ". Why the admission of a certain 
 undefined degree of native altruism and the use of the prin- 
 ciple of ' utility ' should be regarded as necessarily conflicting, 
 I have never been able to understand. As in most discussions 
 where abstract ' egoism ' and abstract ' altruism ' figure, the 
 supposed difficulty resolves itself into an ambiguity in the use 
 of words. Even if the hedonist, in order to be consistent, is 
 obliged to hold that one is always determined to act for one's 
 own pleasure,^ he is not therefore committed to egoism in any 
 offensive sense. If one derive pleasure from the pleasure of 
 others, one is just so far altruistic. Whether or not one does 
 derive pleasure from the pleasure of others, is solely a question 
 of fact; and the inevitable answer cannot properly be used 
 
 ^ See p. xxvi. 
 
 * The expression ' determined to act for one's own pleasure ' is in itself seri- 
 ously misleading. Even when we are acting with a direct view to our own future 
 pleasure, it is, of course, the present pleasure attaching to the idea of our future 
 pleasure, not the future pleasure itself, which determines our action. And to 
 assume that no idea but that of our own future pleasure can attract us, manifestly 
 begs the whole question. In the text, however, I have attempted to show that, 
 even if the hedonist admit that, in his view, we always act for our own pleas- 
 ure, he is not committed to 'egoism,' in the derogatory sense. — All this, of 
 course, has nothing to do with the ultimate validity of hedonism, which the 
 present writer would by no means admit.
 
 David Hume. 99 
 
 against ' Universalistic Hedonism ' or any other recognised 
 type of ethical theory. 
 
 Having considered the relation between the standpoint of 
 Book III. of the Treatise and that of the Inquiry concerning 
 the Principles of Morals, as regards the springs of human 
 action, we shall now proceed to an examination of Hume's 
 ethical system as a whole. In order to understand his mode 
 of procedure, either in the Treatise or in the Inquiry, one 
 should keep in mind the distinction, explicit in the former 
 work, implicit in the latter, between what he calls the ' natural * 
 and the ' artificial ' virtues. For instance, in the Treatise 
 Hume contends that justice is an ' artificial ' virtue, while he 
 regards benevolence, in its various forms, as ' natural '.^ By 
 ' artificial ' he does not mean, as he explains, that which is a 
 superfluity in organised society ; on the contrary, he holds 
 that a recognition of justice is basal to all social life whatever. 
 He simply means that the utility which, as he is going to 
 show, all virtues have in common, is indirect in the case of 
 justice and other ' artificial ' virtues, while direct in the case of 
 all the so-called ' natural ' virtues.^ More particularly, he 
 means — what, to be sure, is not strictly true — that the effect 
 of the so-called ' natural ' virtues is immediately and always 
 an increase of happiness, while, in the case of justice, etc., 
 this is manifestly true only in the long run. 
 
 This at first looks like one of the many fine distinctions 
 which Hume draws in the Treatise only to practically neglect 
 them in the Inquiry, and that to the manifest advantage of his 
 exposition. As a matter of fact, however, the position, though 
 unsound, is characteristic. While Hume does not directly 
 speak of ' artificial ' as opposed to ' natural ' virtues in the 
 Inquiry, he does not seem really to appreciate his mistake and 
 
 1 It will be seen that the term ' natural,' as here applied, is rather misleading, 
 since Hume does not admit native altruism in the Treatise. 
 
 -The other virtues beside justice which Hume designates as 'artificial' are 
 allegiance, modesty, and good manners. The ' natural ' virtues specified are 
 meekness, beneficence, charity, generosity, clemency, moderation, and equity. — 
 See Treatise, Bk. HI., Pt. HI., § i.
 
 lOO History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 give up the distinction altogether. In both works he is pri- 
 marily concerned to show the relation of the several virtues to 
 what he recognises as the springs of human action, the funda- 
 mental impulsive tendencies of human nature. Now he holds 
 with much truth that, in the case of justice, for example, we 
 have no mere native impulses which of themselves are suffi- 
 cient to explain either the fact that we approve justice, or the 
 fact that we ourselves practise this virtue. But when he 
 comes to treat the so-called ' natural ' virtues, he seems to 
 assume — in the later as well as in the earlier work — that the 
 virtues in question are, on the one hand, the direct result of 
 our natural springs of action, and, on the other hand, that their 
 effects are immediately and always fortunate 
 
 Keeping in mind, then, this distinction, which, though not 
 consistently carried out, really determines in a general way 
 the form of exposition in both the Treatise and the Inquiry, we 
 are now prepared to notice Hume's more specific treatment of 
 the problems of Ethics. As will readily be seen, it is not 
 without significance that in the Treatise he considers justice 
 before benevolence, while in the Inquiry he does the contrary : 
 for in the Treatise he is concerned to prove, not only the 
 general utilitarian character of justice, but that it is ultimately 
 based on (practically) egoistic principles ; while in the Inquiry 
 he begins with the assumption that the measure of benevolence 
 is the measure of virtue, and that benevolence is good because 
 it results in the increase of human happiness. As I regard 
 the position taken in the Inqimy as more consistent and 
 more characteristic, for reasons sufficiently given above, I shall 
 mainly follow that work rather than the Treatise, in the present 
 account of Hume's proof of the utilitarian principle.^ 
 
 Hume's treatment of benevolence in the Inquiry is very brief. 
 In fact, after he had. given up his peculiar view of ' sympathy,' 
 as worked out in the Treatise, he probably thought that little 
 remained to be said on the subject. The possibihty of such a 
 virtue could hardly have seemed to him to need proof, for in 
 
 1 Important differences of treatment in the two works will of course be noted.
 
 David Hume. loi 
 
 this later work he had once for all assumed a certain degree 
 of altruism, as belonging to human nature ; and it must be 
 remembered that he did not seriously consider, or even dis- 
 tinctly recognise, the question how, given altruistic as well as 
 egoistic tendencies, the developed virtue of benevolence (as 
 distinguished from mere impulsive kindliness) was to be 
 explained. 
 
 Beginning, as he nearly always does, with our actual ap- 
 proval of moral actions, Hume remarks that the very words 
 we use to describe " the benevolent or softer affections " indi- 
 cate the universal attitude toward them. He says : " The 
 epithets sociable, good-natured, humane, merciful, grateful, 
 friendly, generous, beneficent, or their equivalents, are known in 
 all languages, and universally express the highest merit which 
 human nature is capable of attaining " )■ But Hume further 
 points out that, when we praise the benevolent man, there is 
 one circumstance which we always insist upon, i.e., the happi- 
 ness of others which inevitably results from his habitual mode 
 of action. Now, since benevolence does have this universal 
 tendency to make for happiness, it seems fair to assume that 
 utility forms at least a part of the merit of benevolent actions. 
 But the further we examine into the matter, the more utility 
 is found to be an adequate explanation of our approbation of 
 such actions, while other modes of explanation in a correspond- 
 ing degree lose their plausibility. The practically inevitable 
 presumption, then, is that utility is the sole ground of our 
 approbation of benevolent actions. It remains to be seen, of 
 course, whether it will prove sufficient to explain the other 
 great social virtue, justice, as well as a number of self-regard- 
 ing virtues which will be mentioned later. 
 
 Before leaving this present subject of benevolence, however, 
 it will be well to see how Hume's treatment of the virtue 
 accords with his mature view regarding the springs of human 
 action. It has been said that benevolent actions please on 
 account of their utility, meaning by this their tendency to 
 
 1 See Inquiry, § II., pt. i.
 
 I02 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 produce pleasure, either in particular individuals or in mankind 
 at large. Why does utility please, even when we have no 
 private interest at stake ? In Hume's earlier treatment of 
 Ethics, it was just here that he had been obliged to have re- 
 course to the principle of (derived) ' sympathy,' thus reducing 
 our apparent altruism to terms of something very like egoism. 
 In the present work, he expressly states that the selfish prin- 
 ciple is inadequate, and that the use of it by philosophers to 
 explain the phenomena of our moral life results from a love 
 of fictitious simplicity.^ Man does have an original altruistic, 
 as well as egoistic, tendency, the one being just as ' natural ' 
 as the other. But this is not all. Hume further points out 
 that sensibility to the happiness and unhappiness of others 
 and moral discrimination keep pace with each other. It will 
 thus be seen that he makes the former, i.e., ' sympathy ' in its 
 ordinary sense, the foundation of moral development. 
 
 Now there is a difficulty here, already mentioned, which 
 Hume quite forgets to take account of in his treatment 
 of benevolence. How do we pass from the mere impulse to 
 benevolent action, whether strong or weak, to a virtue of 
 benevolence, which latter, of course, implies an objective stand- 
 ard .<• It must be admitted that, when Hume incidentally 
 tries to answer this question, somewhat later in the Inquiry, 
 his account of the matter, though interesting, is hardly ade- 
 quate. His view seems to be that human intercourse involves 
 meeting our fellows half-way ; that language is formed, not for 
 expressing that which is merely subjective, but that which 
 may, in a sense, be regarded as objective. He says : " The 
 intercourse of sentiments, therefore, in society and conversa- 
 tion, makes us form some general unalterable standard, by 
 which we may approve or disapprove of characters and man- 
 ners "? Here, apparently, we have the germ of Adam Smith's 
 characteristic notion of the ' ideal impartial spectator '. 
 
 After having argued that benevolence, as a virtue, is actu- 
 ally approved on account of its utility, Hume proceeds to the 
 
 ' See Inquiry y Appendix ii. ^ Ibid., § V., pt. ii.
 
 David Hume. 103 
 
 consideration of justice. His treatment of this virtue in the 
 Inquiry substantially corresponds to his previous treatment in 
 the third book of the Treatise, so far as his attempt is merely 
 to show its general utilitarian origin. Minor differences in 
 the two expositions need not detain us, but it may be well to 
 note in passing that here, as in the case of benevolence, we 
 ultimately are confronted with the question as to ' why utility 
 pleases,' and that the question would have to be answered 
 somewhat differently in the two works, in a way to correspond 
 to the different springs of action recognised. What has been 
 said regarding this question in the case of benevolence will, of 
 course, apply in all essential respects in the present ca^e of 
 justice. 
 
 At the beginning of his treatment of justice, Hume properly 
 enough remarks that all are so completely agreed as to the 
 utility of this virtue that nothing need be said on that score. 
 His object, of course, is to show, not merely that justice is 
 useful, but that its character as a virtue is determined wholly 
 by its usefulness. It should be noted that here, as in the third 
 book of the Treatise, Hume writes of justice as if the virtue 
 had a bearing only upon cases where external goods are in 
 question. Later we shall find reason seriously to object to 
 this view. Granting, however, for the present, that justice is 
 to be taken in this restricted sense, Hume's line of argument 
 is at least plausible. He says, as every one will remember, 
 that justice would have no meaning if there were either (i) an 
 unlimited supply of the goods in question, or (2) perfect gener- 
 osity in human nature. As a matter of fact, of course, most 
 external goods are limited in quantity ; and here, as in the 
 Treatise, Hume holds that the egoistic impulses predominate, 
 although he forsakes his former position to the extent of 
 admitting a certain degree of original altruism. Our natural 
 tendency, then, would be in the direction of appropriating 
 more than belonged to us. But, since the same tendency 
 is present in all others, society can only exist in a per- 
 manent form where property rights are to some extent 
 recognised.
 
 I04 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Since justice has no meaning for Hume, apart from the 
 insufficient supply of external goods and the predominant self- 
 ishness of man, it might seem as if he would have us look for 
 a thorough-going utility in all the particular rules of justice. 
 As a matter of fact, however, he suggests that we do not need 
 to carry our analysis very far to see that these rules are some- 
 times, in the last resort, more or less arbitrary. Such cases 
 Hume attributes to the natural processes of the ' imagination,* 
 as determined by the all-important principle of the ' associa- 
 tion of ideas '.^ It must not be supposed that we really have 
 two principles operating here, utility and some arbitrary prin- 
 ciple — the two standing to each other in an unknown relation. 
 The (^//-important thing is that principles of some sort should 
 be recognised, where the ownership of property is concerned. 
 Beyond a certain point, Hume would seem to say, it makes no 
 very great difference how goods are apportioned, at least in 
 the hypothetical first instance — and it is there, mainly, that 
 the ' imagination ' is conceived to come in as a complicating 
 factor.2 
 
 Such, then, is Hume's actual treatment of justice reduced 
 to its lowest terms. Up to this point, we have admitted his 
 assumption that justice concerns only our pecuniary dealings 
 with others. But is this really true.^ In order not to misin- 
 
 ' " Sometimes the interests of society may require a rule of justice in a par- 
 ticular case ; but may not determine any particular rule, among several, which 
 are all equally beneficial. In that case, the slightest analogies are laid hold of, 
 in order to prevent that indifference and ambiguity, which would be the source 
 of perpetual dissension. Thus possession alone, and first possession, is supposed 
 to convey property, where nobody else has any preceding claim and pretension. 
 Many of the reasonings of lawyers are of this analogical nature, and depend on 
 very slight connexions of the imagination." — See Inquiry, § III., pt. ii. 
 
 ^ It is interesting to see how English ethical writers, from the time of Hobbes 
 to that of Paley, were unable to free themselves entirely from the conception of a 
 ' state of nature ' and a ' compact ' made when men entered into society. With 
 those who accepted the doctrine, wholly or in part, we are not here concerned ; 
 but it will be found that those who expressly repudiate this view {e.g., Hume and 
 Paley) often lapse into a mode of speech which seems to imply it. An inter- 
 esting case will be found in Paley's Moral and Political Philosophy, Bk. III., 
 Pt. II., ch. V.
 
 David Hume. 105 
 
 terpret Hume's position, we must keep in mind that he treats 
 the obhgation of promises in connection with justice, and as 
 necessarily arising from it. But the ultimate reference is 
 always to external goods, and the two complications always 
 are the insufficiency of such goods and the excess of human 
 egoism. It will hardly be denied that, while justice should 
 always be differentiated as clearly as possible from benevo- 
 lence, its scope is inevitably much greater than Hume seems 
 prepared to admit. Let us suppose, for the moment, that 
 there were an unlimited supply of the good things of life, and 
 that, at the same time, human nature were as predominantly 
 altruistic as it often seems to be egoistic. Even in this 
 doubly millennial condition of things, it would still be abso- 
 lutely necessary, in order that society might exist at all, that 
 men should be able in some measure to depend upon each 
 other. It is only upon the basis of some definite expectations 
 that one can live with one's fellows from day to day. Even 
 in the family, justice of a sort would seem to be as necessary 
 as anywhere else — a necessary foundation for enlightened 
 benevolence. 
 
 We may now examine the remaining part of Hume's sys- 
 tematic treatment of Ethics. In considering this somewhat 
 briefly, we shall merely be following the author's own example. 
 And first we must notice Hume's general classification of the 
 virtues. In the Inquiry} as well as in the third book of the 
 Treatise^ he distinguishes between virtues which are (i) 'use- 
 ful to oneself,' e.g., prudence, constancy, good judgment, etc. ; 
 
 (2) * immediately agreeable to oneself,' e.g., magnanimity ; 
 
 (3) ' useful to others,' e.g., justice and benevolence ; and (4) 
 ' immediately agreeable to others,' e.g., politeness, wit, and 
 cleanliness. Even a somewhat casual examination of this 
 classification will reveal its artificial character. At the same 
 time, before criticising Hume, it is important to see exactly 
 what he means. For instance, let us take the first class of 
 virtues, those ' useful to oneself ' — prudence, constancy, etc. 
 
 'See§§ VI., VII., VIII., IX. 
 •See Bk. III., Pt. III., § i. (end).
 
 io6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Hume does not by any means set himself the gratuitous task 
 of showing that these virtues are, as a matter of fact, useful to 
 oneself. The question really is : Why do I commend pru- 
 dence, etc., in another ? The value to the community of 
 prudence in the individual, even when exercised in his own 
 affairs, is not what is here emphasised, though that would 
 seem to be the most natural line of argument. Hume is 
 rather concerned to show, in his later work, that it cannot be 
 from motives of self-love that one commends prudence in 
 others. Indeed, he holds that it is more clearly impossible to 
 resolve moral approbation into self-love here than in the case 
 of justice. In his somewhat obscure account of this matter in 
 the third book of the Treatise, Hume had seemed to hold that 
 we unconsciously put ourselves in the place of the person sym- 
 pathised with, and, in a sense, feel for ourselves, rather than 
 strictly feel for him. On the other hand, in the Inquiry, 
 which we are here following, he explicitly abandons all such 
 speculations, and not only accepts, but emphasises, the fact 
 that an original altruistic tendency in human nature must be 
 admitted. 
 
 In distinguishing the virtues which are ' immediately a^ee- 
 able ' to oneself from those which are merely ' useful,' Hume 
 carelessly adopts a terminology which, in a writer less clear 
 than himself, might lead to confusion. Pleasure is the ulti- 
 mate test, of course, in one case as much as in the other — 
 the only difference being that in the second class of virtues, 
 as the name would imply, the pleasure is experienced immedi- 
 ately, while in the first class it results rather in the long run. 
 As a matter of fact, however, when all allowances are made, 
 one can hardly defend Hume in adopting a classification which 
 seems to explain magnanimity as a virtue, on the ground that 
 we approve it because it is immediately agreeable to its fortu- 
 nate possessor ! Virtues of the third class, justice and benevo- 
 lence, are perhaps naturally enough termed ' useful to others,* 
 though ultimately the distinction between the first two classes 
 of virtues (self-regarding) and the last two classes (other- 
 regarding) breaks down, even under Hume's own handling.
 
 David Hume. 107 
 
 The fourth class of virtues, those ' immediately agreeable to 
 others ' — politeness, wit, cleanliness — are apparently not all 
 on the same plane, and further illustrate the difficulty of 
 making the distinction just noted. 
 
 In fact, this whole classification and treatment of the par- 
 ticular virtues, first adopted in the Treatise, and retained 
 without important revision in the Inquiry, seems out of place 
 in the latter work, since there Hume once for all admits an 
 original sympathetic tendency in human nature. It would 
 have been much more consistent for him to show that both 
 the self-regarding and the other-regarding virtues are ulti- 
 mately to be recognised as virtues, because they conduce to 
 the common weal, or — if we may use the phrase now so hack- 
 neyed, which had already, in Hume's time, been employed by 
 Hutcheson — ' the greatest happiness of the greatest number '. 
 
 No account of Hume's ethical system, however brief, can 
 afford to neglect the admirable Conclusion to the Inquiry, in 
 which he takes a comprehensive view of the issues which have 
 been raised and met separately, and makes a final plea for 
 the vaUdity of his general position.^ Like most of the 
 preceding chapters, or ' sections,' the Conclusion is divided 
 into two parts. The first and more important part of 
 the argument attempts in outline a sort of natural history 
 of morals, while the second part gives an account of the 
 ground of moral obligation. It will be found that the second 
 part is too much of the nature of an argumentum ad homifiem, 
 and fails to do justice to the spirit of the first part, to which 
 latter we shall principally direct our attention. 
 
 Hume begins by arguing that, whatever philosophers may 
 teach, we never actually continue to approve of any quality in 
 
 ' See § IX. A less satisfactory form of the same argument may be found at 
 the end of Book III. of the Treatise (see §§ v. and vi.) ; but this may be safely 
 neglected here, not only because the whole argument is put in a more convincing 
 foMn in the later work, but also, and particularly, because the principle of 
 sympathy, or humanity, upon which the recognition of moral distinctions is 
 supposed ultimately to depend, is developed here, as throughout the Inquiry, in 
 a much more satisfactory manner than in the Treatise.
 
 io8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 human nature, which does not at least appear to be either 
 useful or agreeable to ourselves or others. The apparent 
 approval of celibacy, fasting, penance, etc., is to be attri- 
 buted to superstition and false religion, and it is important 
 to notice that, in the course of a healthy intellectual and moral 
 development, such fictitious virtues are gradually transferred 
 to the opposite column, and placed in the catalogue of vices. 
 So far we have little but a reaffirmation of the author's general 
 position, marred somewhat by his continued use of the arti- 
 ficial division, just criticised, of moral actions into those which 
 give pleasure either directly or indirectly to oneself or others. 
 But now Hume pertinently points out that he has avoided 
 becoming entangled in the wearisome dispute concerning the 
 degrees of benevolence or self-love which prevail in human 
 nature. " It is sufficient for our present purpose," he says, 
 " if it be allowed, what surely, without the greatest absurdity 
 cannot be disputed, that there is some benevolence, however 
 small, infused into our bosom." No matter how faint these 
 generous sentiments may be thought to be, they must at any 
 rate direct the determinations of our mind where everything 
 else is equal, and " produce a cool preference of what is useful 
 and serviceable to mankind, above what is pernicious and 
 dangerous ". 
 
 The result is most important : " A moral distinction, there- 
 fore, immediately arises ; a general sentiment of blame and 
 approbation ; a tendency, however faint, to the objects of the 
 one, and a proportionable aversion to those of the other". 
 Avarice, ambition, vanity, and all the other passions which are 
 commonly, though improperly, comprised under the general 
 head of ' self-love,' are to be ruled out as wholly inadequate to 
 explain our original recognition of moral distinctions, not 
 because they are too weak, but because they have not a 
 ' proper direction ' for that purpose. They wholly fail to 
 explain that principle of objectivity which we demand and 
 recognise in moral judgments. This implies some sentiment 
 which is at once common to all mankind, and so comprehensive 
 as to extend to all mankind, no matter how remote from our-
 
 David Hume. 109 
 
 selves in space or time. Nothing but the sentiment of 
 humanity, here insisted upon, can reasonably be regarded as 
 the ultimate cause of the all-important phenomenon which 
 we are attempting to explain. An important auxiliary senti- 
 ment, however, which does much to re-enforce our strictly 
 moral sentiments, is to be found in that very love of fame, 
 which has so often been regarded as a merely selfish passion. 
 This tends to make us regard our own conduct objectively, 
 and to keep alive in us the highest ideals ; and it further begets 
 in noble natures that habit of self-reverence which is the 
 surest guardian of every virtue. ^ 
 
 As already indicated, the second part of the Conclusion, 
 concerning the ground of moral obligation, is hardly in the 
 spirit of the first part. There the common feeling of humanity 
 had been treated as the ultimate ground of our recognition 
 of moral distinctions ; here one would naturally expect Hume 
 to take the same principle as a starting-point, from which to 
 revise the conception of moral obligation. As a matter of 
 fact, however, he mainly contents himself with commending 
 his system to those who hold the selfish theory of the moral 
 motive rather than his own. The principal question con- 
 sidered, then, is how far morality is for the interest of the 
 individual, abstractly considered, although in the course of 
 this very argument he makes the highly significant remark, 
 already quoted, that " whatever contradiction may vulgarly be 
 supposed between the selfish and social sentiments or dis- 
 positions, they are really no more opposite than selfish and 
 ambitious, selfish and revengeful, selfish and vain ". 
 
 Returning still again to his artificial classification of the 
 virtues, he does not, of course, have to prove that the virtues 
 which are such because they conduce either directly or in- 
 directly to the pleasure of the individual agent are for the 
 
 ^The last paragraph of part i. of this section, in which Hume reverts to his 
 characteristic sceptical position, on the ground that " an hypothesis, so obvious, 
 had it been a true one, would, long ere now, have been received by the unani- 
 mous suffrage and consent of mankind," can hardly be regarded as significant 
 here, except, perhaps, as indicating the author's personal attitude.
 
 I lo History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 individual's selfish interest, for that follows from the definitions 
 themselves. And he points out that it is really superfluous 
 to prove that the ' companionable virtues/ i.e., those ' immedi- 
 ately agreeable to others,' like good manners and wit, decency 
 and genteelness, are more desirable than the contrary qualities. 
 The only real problem arises in the case of justice, the typical 
 virtue of the remaining class, i.e., the class of virtues ' useful 
 to others '. That * honesty is the best policy ' is a good 
 general rule ; but how about the possible exceptions, where a 
 man may seem to be the loser by his integrity .'' Hume practi- 
 cally admits that he has no arguments of a strictly logical 
 kind with which to meet this real or supposed difficulty, but 
 rather lays stress upon the inward peace of mind, consciousness 
 of integrity, etc., which, as he says, " are circumstances very 
 requisite to happiness, and will be cherished and cultivated 
 by every honest man, who feels the importance of them ". It 
 will readily be seen that this appeal to our moral consciousness 
 hardly meets the theoretical difficulty — the self-imposed diffi- 
 culty of eighteenth century individualism — which was to show 
 that morality was for the advantage of the moral agent, not as 
 a social being, with no interests wholly separate from those 
 of society, but rather as an isolated centre of self-interest. 
 The only logical solution, from that point of view, was that of 
 the so-called ' Theological Utilitarians,' who frankly depended 
 upon the doctrine of rewards and punishments after death. 
 
 Such was Hume's system as actually worked out by him- 
 self. When we come to compare it with that of Gay — his 
 only predecessor who had stated the Utilitarian principle in a 
 perfectly unambiguous form — we see at once what an impor- 
 tant advance had been made in the development of ethical 
 theory. Gay's system had been as frankly individualistic, in 
 its way, as that of Hobbes ; but, at the same time, it had 
 avoided those offensive paradoxes of the earlier doctrine, which 
 had undoubtedly kept many from appreciating the plausibility 
 of the egoistic position. Indeed, it would be quite unfair to 
 put Gay and his successors {i.e., those Utilitarian writers who
 
 David Hume. 1 1 1 
 
 maintained the egoistic character of the motive of the moral 
 agent) in the same category with Hobbes. Gay and the others 
 never employed egoism as a means by which to viUfy human 
 nature, but rather seem to have regarded it as a tempting 
 device for simplifying ethical theory. Moreover, they partly 
 succeeded in disguising its essentially unlovely character by 
 supposing the development of a derived ' sympathy ' through 
 the ' association of ideas '. Hume had at first allowed himself 
 to use * association ' in much the same way ; but the very fact 
 that his explanations in the Treatise are so much less clear 
 than those of Gay in the Dissertation^ suggests a lack of cer- 
 tainty in his own mind as to the validity of the method ; and, 
 as we have seen, he entirely gave up, in his later work, any 
 attempt to reduce the altruistic tendencies of human nature 
 to terms of something else. 
 
 Taken by itself, Hume's recognition and defence of original 
 altruism could not be regarded as an important contribution to 
 English Ethics. From the time of Cumberland to that of 
 Shaftesbury and Hutcheson, there had never been wanting 
 those who, from one point of view or another, opposed the 
 egoistic position of Hobbes. But of all those moralists, Cum- 
 berland alone can properly be termed a Utilitarian, and even 
 he, it will be remembered, had carried through ' the perfection 
 of mind and body ' as a principle parallel to that of ' the great- 
 est happiness of all '. Hume, then, was the first to hold the 
 Utilitarian doctrine in its unmistakable form and at the same 
 time to admit, and defend, the altruistic tendencies of human 
 nature. 
 
 Gay had vigorously, and more or less successfully, opposed 
 the ' Moral Sense ' theory, as held by Shaftesbury and Hutche- 
 son. While, however, he was greatly in advance of those 
 writers in clearness and simplicity of ethical theory, he by no 
 means equalled them in his grasp of the fundamental facts of 
 oiu- moral experience. Hume was as sure as Gay had been 
 that we must not explain the phenomena of our moral life by 
 referring them, or any part of them, to a special faculty like 
 the ' moral sense ' ; but he took a much broader view of human
 
 1 1 2 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 nature than Gay had done, and, from first to last, attributed 
 more importance to the part played by the affective side of 
 our nature in the formation of moral judgments. In fact, he 
 has sometimes been misjudged on account of this very catho- 
 licity of treatment. As we have had occasion to note, there 
 are even those who hold that he never quite departed from 
 the ' Moral Sense ' theory. I can only regard this view as a 
 serious mistake. We have seen again and again, that, while 
 he always begins with the fact of moral approbation, as 
 applying to a particular class of actions, it is his special 
 endeavour to show how this approbation arises, according to 
 the recognised principles of human nature. With all his faults 
 as a philosopher and as a moralist, Hume was far too scientific, 
 both in his ideals and his methods, to be guilty of any flagrant 
 form of ' faculty psychology '. 
 
 We can only speculate as to just what Hume's system might 
 have become, if the author had given up his artificial and 
 somewhat misleading classification of the virtues. It is fair 
 to remark, however, that, if he had been more thorough in his 
 revision of the third book of the Treatise, and had definitely 
 shown, what certainly was implicit in his system, that all the 
 virtues are such because they conduce to ' the greatest happi- 
 ness of the greatest number,' he would have stated the Utili- 
 tarian principle practically in its modern form. As it was, he 
 freed the doctrine from the unfortunate dogma that the motive 
 of the moral agent is always, in the last resort, egoistic. This 
 was a distinct advance upon Gay, which, however, was wasted 
 upon Tucker, Paley, and Bentham, all of whom reproduce the 
 position of the Dissertation. Even as stated to-day, the 
 ' greatest happiness ' theory does seem likely to be accepted 
 as the final word of Ethics ; but it would hardly be too much 
 to claim that \\\& Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, 
 with all its defects and shortcomings, is the classic statement 
 of English Utilitarianism.
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 DAVID HARTLEY. 
 
 The first writer who made the attempt systematically to de- 
 velop the theory of the Association of Ideas, as outlined by 
 Gay, and to show, more in detail, the consequences of this 
 theory for Ethics, was the physician David Hartley. He 
 did this in his well-known Observations on Man, his Frame, 
 his Duty, and his Expectations, which was first published 
 in 1749. Probably no writer on philosophical subjects has 
 gained more from mere priority of publication. Even at the 
 present day, the Associationist theory is often called by his 
 name, although he was confessedly not the originator of 
 the theory, and developed it with a clumsiness which can 
 only be appreciated by those who know his book at first 
 hand. Ten years before the publication of the Observa- 
 tions, Hume had published the first two books of the 
 Treatise of Human Nature, in which, while apparently work- 
 ing in independence of Gay, he had not indeed treated the 
 principle of Association directly and at length, but had pre- 
 supposed it throughout, and with a perfect understanding of 
 its implications. By the time Hartley published, the theory 
 seems to have become, in a sense, pubhc property; and it 
 was probably this fact, almost as much as the undoubted 
 dulness of Hartley's style and the crudeness of his general 
 treatment, that caused the book to make so slight an im- 
 pression at the time of publication. Although the Associa- 
 tionist Psychology was so important for the further develop- 
 ment of English Utilitarianism that the early form of the 
 theory will soon have to be considered at some length, it will 
 
 C113) 8
 
 114 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 be more helpful to take Tucker, who published only nineteen 
 years later, as its exponent At the same time. Hartley can- 
 not with propriety be neglected : first, because of his tradi- 
 tional position in the history of the principle which we are 
 considering ; and, secondly, because he was not, as constantly 
 assumed, the typical early Associationist. 
 
 This misapprehension as to Hartley's real originality and 
 importance, however, is something for which he himself was 
 not at all responsible. If his manner is dry and uninteresting, 
 the tone of his treatise is modest and unassuming throughout. 
 For instance, in the Preface to his Obsei'vations, he says : 
 " About eighteen years ago I was informed that the Rev. 
 Mr. Gay, then living, asserted the possibility of deducing all 
 our intellectual pleasures and pains from association. This 
 put me upon considering the power of association. Mr. Gay 
 published his sentiments on this matter, about the same time, 
 in a Dissertation on the Fundamental Pi'inciple of Virtue pre- 
 fixed to Mr. Archdeacon Law's translation of Archbishop 
 King's Origin of Evil." Such a statement might seem 
 natural and almost inevitable, under the circumstances, but 
 Hartley's frankness in acknowledging his obligations to Gay 
 is in shining contrast to the strange reticence of some of his 
 more gifted successors. 
 
 The Introduction to Part I. of the Observations is per- 
 fectly clear and business-like — a very necessary guide, in fact, 
 through the arid tracts that are to follow. We shall do well 
 to note a few of the distinctions at once. Sensations and 
 ideas are clearly distinguished, and defined in what we would 
 now regard as the conventional way, except that they are 
 made to include pleasures and pains. The ideas which 
 resemble sensations are called ' ideas of sensation ' ; all the 
 rest are called ' intellectual ideas '. As will appear later, 
 ideas of sensation are the elements of which all the rest 
 are compounded. The faculties of the mind recognised are 
 memory, imagination (or fancy), understanding, affection, and 
 will. Only two of the definitions require further notice. 
 " The affections have the pleasures and pains for their objects;
 
 David Hartley. 115 
 
 as the understanding has the mere sensations and ideas. By 
 the affections we are excited to pursue happiness, and all its 
 means, and to fly from misery, and all its apparent causes. 
 The will is that state of mind which is immediately previous 
 to, and causes, those express acts of memory, fancy, and bodily 
 motion, which are termed voluntary." 
 
 Now it must always be remembered that Hartley is con- 
 cerned to prove, not merely the association of ideas, but his 
 peculiar ' doctrine of vibrations,' by which he explains all 
 neural phenomena. The former is to explain our mental life 
 down to its smallest details; the latter is to explain the 
 necessary physiological accompaniments of all mental life. 
 While this frank recognition of, and insistence upon, the 
 physiological concomitants of our mental life must be re- 
 garded as an indication of the scientific spirit of Hartley, 
 his recklessness in elaborating his theory of vibrations far 
 beyond what neurological science in his own day (or, of course, 
 later) would justify, could only result in disaster. Wherever 
 he thinks he finds a mental law, he provides it with a parallel 
 hypothetical physiological law, until the reader holds his 
 breath at the audacity of this plodding and seemingly un- 
 imaginative scientist In our brief examination of Hartley's 
 psychological system, we shall, of course, neglect this ' deadly 
 parallel ' mythological neurology ; but, in so doing, we 
 must not forget that a part of the great crudeness which we 
 shall have to notice, was not improbably due to this fanciful 
 attempt to keep the mental and the physical series exactly 
 parallel 
 
 A few words, however, regarding the ' theory of vibra- 
 tions ' before we dismiss it altogether. We are told that 
 " the white medullary substance of the brain, spinal marrow, 
 and the nerves proceeding from them, is the immediate in- 
 strument of sensation and motion " }■ In the case of simple 
 sensations, we must suppose a simple vibration in this sub- 
 stance ; in the case of complex sensations, associated vibra- 
 tions. But " sensory vibrations, by being often repeated, 
 
 1 See Pt. I., prop, i., p. 5 (of " sixth edition, corrected," 1834).
 
 1 1 6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 beget, in the medullary substance of the brain, a disposition 
 to diminutive vibrations, which may also be called vibrati- 
 uncles, and miniatures, corresponding to themselves respec- 
 tively".^ To the vibratiuncles, correspond simple ideas; 
 to associated vibratiuncles, complex ideas. There are also 
 ' motory vibrations,' which contract the muscles and so cause 
 automatic movements ; while voluntary and semi-voluntary 
 movements must be explained by corresponding ' motory 
 vibratiuncles '. One might, perhaps, expect some theory 
 regarding the relation of mind and body from Hartley, since 
 he attempts so minutely to trace out the psycho-physical 
 parallelism. The nearest approach to such a theory seems 
 to be the following : " If we suppose an infinitesimal elemen- 
 tary body to be intermediate between the soul and gross 
 body, which appears to be no improbable supposition, then 
 the changes in our sensations, ideas, and motions, may corre- 
 spond to the changes made in the medullary substance, only 
 as far as these correspond to the changes made in the elemen- 
 tary body ".2 It was probably well that Hartley did not carry 
 his speculations further in this direction. 
 
 Leaving, then, this very debatable territory, let us examine 
 the essentials of Hartley's psychology proper. Sensations, 
 by being often repeated, leave certain vestiges, types, or 
 images, of themselves, which may be called ' simple ideas of 
 sensation '. But " any sensations, A, B, C, &c., by being 
 associated with one another a sufficient number of times, get 
 such a power over the corresponding ideas, a, b, c, &c., that any 
 one of the sensations, A, when impressed alone, shall be able to 
 excite in the mind b, c, &c., the ideas of the rest ".-^ After 
 this very clear statement of the general principle of association^ 
 Hartley goes on to show, in the usual way, how simple ideas 
 go to form complex ones by means of association. That this 
 is true in very many cases, seems to him certain. The pre- 
 sumption, therefore, is that the same principle will hold 
 throughout our mental life, and that all our complex ideas 
 
 ' See Pt. I., prop, ix., p. 37. 
 
 ^Ibid., v., p. 22. -'Ibid., x., p. 41.
 
 David Ha7'tley. 1 1 7 
 
 may finally be resolved into their constituent parts, i.e., 
 simple ideas of sensation. 
 
 When we pass beyond mere sensation, and come to con- 
 sider our intellectual life, we are confronted, at the very 
 outset, with a conspicuous example of association. " Words 
 and phrases must excite ideas m us by association, and they 
 excite ideas in us by no other means." ^ After makmg cer- 
 tain obvious remarks on this score, the indefatigable writer 
 launches out into elaborate speculations regarding the origin 
 of language, not omitting to consider what language may 
 have been before and after the Fall of Man. i he language 
 of Paradise was presumably monosyllabic, as man's intel- 
 lectual nature had hardly yet been awakened. In this connec- 
 tion, the author remarks that " to set a value upon knowledge 
 considered in itself, and exclusively of its tendency to carry 
 us to God, is a most pernicious error, derived originally from 
 Adam's having eaten of the tree of knowledge ".- Rational 
 assent and dissent are explained by the author by means of 
 association. He says : " Rational assent then to any propo- 
 sition, may be defined, a readiness to affirm it to be true, 
 proceeding from a close association of the ideas suggested 
 by the proposition, with the idea, or internal feeling, belong- 
 ing to the word truth ".^ * Practical ' assent is nothing but 
 " the natural and necessary consequence of rational, when 
 sufficiently impressed ". It hardly need be pointed out that 
 association, as here invoked, explains nothing, since the 
 ' idea, or internal feeling, belonging to the word truth ' is 
 taken for grcinted. Of course a single passage is likely to 
 caricature a writer's solution of a difficult problem ; but that 
 can hardly be claimed in the present case. The following 
 passage is perhaps the clearest and most plausible of many 
 to the same general purpose. " Now the cause that a person 
 afifirms the truth of the proposition twice two is finir, is the 
 entire coincidence of the visible or tangible idea of twice two 
 with that of four, as impressed upon the mind by various 
 
 ^ See Pt. I., prop. Ixxix., p. 169. 
 
 -Ibid., Ixxxiii., p. 188. ^ Ibid., Ixxxvi., p. 204.
 
 1 1 8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 objects. We see everywhere that twice two and four are 
 only different names for the same impression. And it is mere 
 association which appropriates the word truth, its definition, 
 or its internal feeling, to this coincidence. " ^ 
 
 So much, in brief, concerning our purely intellectual life ; 
 but, according to Hartley, " our passions or affections can be 
 no more than aggregates of simple ideas united by associa- 
 tion "? This was, of course, the natural consequence of 
 regarding pleasures and pains as ' ideas '. It would be 
 quite hypercritical to raise the difficulty which modern 
 psychology might find here, as to whether feeling, as such, 
 is capable of revival in memory, like sense-perception, and so 
 capable of association. None of the early Associationists 
 dreamed of any such difficulty. Certainly no part of Hartley's 
 treatise is better known than his chapters on " The Six Classes 
 of Intellectual Pleasures and Pains "? These are the plea- 
 sures and pains (i) of imagination, (2) of ambition, (3) of 
 self-interest, (4) of sympathy, (5) of theopathy, and (6) of 
 the moral sense. Before considering these, however, and the 
 order in which they are developed, it will be best to notice 
 briefly Hartley's general account of the passions, which will 
 be found really to include his treatment of the will. Since 
 all the passions arise from pleasure and pain, the first and 
 most natural division is into ' love ' and ' hatred,' the former 
 arising from the thought of what gives us pleasure, the latter 
 from the thought of what gives us pain. But we axe so con- 
 stituted that pleasure and pain impel us to action. Thus 
 ' active ' love becomes ' desire,' and ' active ' hatred ' aver- 
 sion '. These are the moving forces in man. Action is first 
 automatic : the child originally grasps at the attractive play- 
 thing or withdraws his hand from the fire that burns him 
 ' from the mechanism of his nature ' ; but in time he learns, 
 partly by repetition of this mechanical process, and partly as 
 a result of imitating others or being instructed by them, to 
 
 ^ See Pt. I., prop. Ixxxvi., p. 204. 
 
 ^ Ibid., Ixxxix., p. 231. 'Ibid., xciv., pp. 262 et seq.
 
 David Hartley, 1 1 9 
 
 pursue whatever he loves and desires, and to flee from every- 
 thing which he hates. ^ 
 
 Now the logic of this might seem to be, that man must 
 always do what he likes and refrain from doing what he 
 dislikes — in other words, act always for the increase of his 
 own happiness or the diminution of his own pain. Hartley 
 recognises that this was a very common, perhaps the most 
 conmion, theory in his own day. But against this view he 
 declares unequivocally, though recognising no original prin- 
 ciple of sympathy. And this is what principedly distinguishes 
 him from all the other Associationists who attempted to 
 derive sympathy from something else. He holds that the 
 complicated phenomena of human action in no way counte- 
 nance " the notion of an essential, original, perpetual desire 
 of happiness, and endeavour to attain it "? Is sympathy 
 factitious .'' Well, so are several of the other principles on 
 which adults habitually act. This is his general position ; 
 the argiunents by which he sustains it will be noticed im- 
 mediately. After the preceding, little remains to be said 
 concerning the wiU. In a single passage, the author says 
 practically all he has to say about that faculty. " The will 
 appears to be nothing but a desire or aversion sufficiently 
 strong to produce em action that is not automatic primarily 
 or secondarily. At least it appears to me, that the substitu- 
 tion of these words for the word will may be justified by the 
 common usage of language. The will is therefore that 
 desire or aversion which is strongest for the then present 
 time." 3 
 
 In order to understand human volition, then, we must in- 
 vestigate the genesis of our ' intellectual affections,' for these 
 are much more important in determining us to action than 
 mere pleasures or pains of sense. Hartley outlines his whole 
 treatment in a long paragraph which it is necessary to quote, 
 since it not only throws the strongest light upon his view of 
 what actually determines the will in adult Hfe, but explams 
 
 ' See Pt. I., prop. Ixxxix., p. 232. 
 
 ^ See ihid., p. 233. ' See ihid.
 
 I20 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 his peculiar position, just mentioned, regarding sympathy, 
 and, in truth, suggests his whole ethical theory. He says : 
 " As sensation is the common foundation of all these, so each 
 in its turn, when sufficiently generated, contributes to gener- 
 ate and model all the rest. We may conceive this to be done 
 in the following manner. Let sensation generate imagina- 
 tion; then will sensation and imagination together generate 
 ambition ; sensation, imagination, and ambition, self-interest ; 
 sensation, imagination, ambition, and self-interest, sympathy; 
 sensation, imagination, ambition, self-interest, and sympathy, 
 theopathy ; sensation, imagination, ambition, self-interest, 
 sympathy, and theopathy, the moral sense : and, in an in- 
 verted order, imagination will new model sensation ; ambition, 
 sensation and imagination ; self-interest, sensation, imagina- 
 tion, and ambition ; sympathy, sensation, imagination, ambi- 
 tion, and self-interest ; theopathy, sensation, imagination, 
 ambition, self-interest, and sympathy ; and the moral sense, 
 sensation, imagination, ambition, self-interest, sympathy, and 
 theopathy : till at last, by the numerous reciprocal influences 
 of all these upon each other, the passions arrive at that 
 degree of complexness, which is observed in fact, and which 
 makes them so difficult to be analysed." ^ 
 
 This quaint passage can hardly fail to provoke a smile ; but, 
 as already suggested, it is very significant in several ways, 
 (i) It throws light upon Hartley's otherwise inexplicable 
 classification of the ' intellectual affections '. A mere glance 
 would show that the classification was not psychological, but 
 developed with a view to Ethics. This passage, showing the 
 supposed genesis of the ' intellectual affections,' explains the 
 peculiar order in which the various classes of those affec- 
 tions appear in Hartley's list. Since all except pleasures 
 and pains of sensation were to be proved factitious, and 
 since sympathy was to be vindicated as no more factitious 
 than the others, this was the order correspondmg to the 
 supposed order of development. (2) That the develop- 
 ment itself, as here explained, is problematical in the ex- 
 
 ' See Pt. I., prop. Ixxxix., p. 232.
 
 David Hartley. i 2 i 
 
 treme hardly need be pointed out. The reader feels as 
 if he were being treated to a not over-skilful exhibition 
 of psychological sleight of hand. At least this remark 
 applies to the first part of the explanation, where the 
 ascent from pleasures and pains of sensation to those of 
 theopathy and moral sense is explained. And it may be added 
 that the author's more extended treatment of the same 
 subject makes the details of his theory hardly, if at all, more 
 plausible. But (3) the last part of the explanation, where 
 the author shows how the ' higher ' affections (however 
 generated) are bound to react upon the ' lower,' and make 
 them essentially different in the civilised adult from what 
 they would otherwise be, is calculated to make the discerning 
 reader somewhat lenient ; for it was just this very important 
 reciprocal influence which the Associationists, particularly 
 those of early date, were accustomed to neglect. But, unfor- 
 tunately, what Hartley gains in our estimation here, in one 
 respect, he loses in another. It was most important to call 
 attention to this reciprocal influence between one part or 
 side of our nature and all the rest ; but the resulting compli- 
 cation is greater than Associationism had the apparatus to 
 cope with. That was doubtless why this idea of Hartley's 
 was not carried further. 
 
 The * rule of life ' which Hartley lays down, has been so 
 completely foreshadowed by his psychological explanation 
 of our ' intellectual affections,' that there can be little doubt 
 that his ethical theory, in outline at least, anticipated this part 
 of his psychology. The two, in fact, as we find them, are 
 inseparable. The classification and explanation of our ' in- 
 tellectual affections ' furnishes the outline for his unsystem- 
 atic and decidedly clumsy treatment of Ethics proper. 
 Beginning with sensation, he shows, as might be expected, 
 that the pleasures of sensation ought not to be made a pri- 
 mary pursuit. 1 The reasons given for this are largely of the 
 obvious prudential kind; but he also resorts to a kind of 
 a priori reasoning from analogy, which is to become more 
 
 * See Pt. II., prop. 1., pp. 454 et seq.
 
 122 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 and more prominent as he proceeds with his treatment of 
 Ethics. That which is prior in nature is always less perfect 
 than that which is posterior ; but we have seen that pleasures 
 and pains of sensation are prior to the ' intellectual affec- 
 tions ' ; therefore they " cannot be supposed of equal value 
 and dignity with the intellectual, to the generation of which 
 they are made subservient ". Hartley is always true to this 
 belief in the qualitative distinctions between pleasures, which 
 forms an essential feature of his ethical system. Just as 
 sympathy, though factitious as regards its origin, is practically 
 co-ordinate with egoism, as a principle of human action, and 
 should be more than that ; so the distinction between ' higher ' 
 and ' lower,' though explained in terms of development, is 
 to all intents and purposes an ultimate distinction, one of 
 kind and not of degree. Those who speak of Hartley in 
 general terms as the typical Associationist-Utilitarian, should 
 be very careful to recall these cases where his interpretation 
 of the logical consequences of his method was precisely the 
 reverse of that of his successors of whatever ethical school. 
 
 But if the pleasures of sense should not be made a primary 
 pursuit, neither should those of the imagination.^ Our re- 
 gard for these, as for the pleasures of sensation, should 
 be regulated by the precepts of benevolence, piety, and the 
 moral sense. The arguments advanced here are very 
 similar to those advanced with reference to sensible pleasures. 
 For instance, as sensible pleasures were presumably of less 
 worth than the intellectual, because prior, so here we have 
 to do with the earliest, and therefore presumably the lovv^est, 
 intellectual pleasures. And when the author comes to treat 
 of the pleasures and pains of ambition, much the same argu- 
 ments, adapted as the case requires (since we are one step 
 higher in the series), have to do service again. The prudential 
 arguments, also, are repeated with considerable emphasis in 
 each case. 
 
 If the remainder of Hartley's treatment of the ' rule of 
 life ' consisted merely in repeating, as he is bound to do, 
 
 ' See Pt. II., prop. Iv., pp. 473 el ieq.
 
 David Hartley. 123 
 
 almost the same arguments at each successive step, as show- 
 ing that the ' lower ' pleasures must be subordinated to the 
 ' higher,' it would hardly be necessary to proceed with our 
 exposition, since the reader could readily anticipate the course 
 of the argument for himself. But a glance at the list of 
 ' intellectual affections,' which Hartley takes as the outline 
 for his treatment of Ethics, will show that we still have to 
 deal with the relative value of the pleasures and pains of 
 ' self-interest,' ' sympathy,' ' theopathy,' and the ' moral sense '. 
 Evidently we come here to the very core of his ethical system. 
 Neglecting the form of exposition, which, as just said, can 
 readily be surmised from the preceding, let us first examine 
 the position of self-interest in Hartley's system. Three kinds 
 of self-interest are recognised: (i) 'gross' self-interest, or 
 the pursuit of the means for obtaining the pleasures of sensa- 
 tion, imagination, and ambition ; (2) ' refined ' self-interest, or 
 the pursuit of the means for obtaining the pleasures of sym- 
 pathy, theopathy, and the moral sense ; and (3) ' rational ' 
 self-interest, or the pursuit of such things as are believed 
 to be the means for obtaining our greatest possible happiness, 
 "at the same time that we are ignorant, or do not consider, 
 from what particular species of pleasure this our greatest 
 possible happiness will arise "} 
 
 Now, apart from the general criticism that the classification 
 as a whole is on a questionable principle, this very analysis 
 shows that to make one class of ' intellectual affections ' 
 pleasures and pains of ' self-interest,' was absurd. There is 
 nothing in self-interest, by itself considered, to afford the 
 basis for a particular class of affections. ' Gross ' self-interest, 
 according to Hartley, is satisfied by the three ' lower ' classes 
 of pleasures, in the ascending order of sensation, imagination, 
 and ambition ; ' refined ' self-interest, by the three ' higher ' 
 classes of pleasures, in the order of sympathy, theopathy, and 
 moral sense. It might be assumed, as a matter of course, 
 that Hartley would put ' refined ' self-interest upon a higher 
 plane than ' gross ' self-interest, since it must look for its 
 
 ' See Pt. II., prop. Ixv., p. 491.
 
 I 24 History of Utilitai'ianisin. 
 
 satisfaction to the * higher ' pleasures, just mentioned. He 
 does, indeed, show that ' gross ' self-interest being incompatible 
 with the pleasures of theopathy and the moral sense, is " an 
 insuperable objection to its being made our primary pursuit," 
 — this quite apart from the fact, strongly urged, that it tends 
 to defeat itself. But when he comes to show that neither 
 should ' refined ' self-interest be made our primary pursuit, he 
 says : " Refined self-interest, when indulged, is a much deeper 
 and more dangerous error than the gross, because it shelters 
 itself under sympathy, theopathy, and the moral sense, so as to 
 grow through their protection ". Moreover, " the pride attend- 
 ing on refined self-interest, when carried to a certain height, 
 is of an incorrigible, and, as it were, diabolical nature "?- 
 
 What, then, one is moved to ask, can ' rational ' self- 
 interest (the third kind) mean, according to Hartley's system ? 
 Earlier in the book, he says of ' rational ' self-interest : " This 
 is the same thing with the abstract desire of happiness, and 
 aversion to misery, which is supposed to attend every in- 
 telligent being during the whole course of his existence "? 
 Now this ' abstract desire of happiness ' must be for the 
 pleasures within the reach of the agent, and there are no such 
 pleasures, except those already enumerated. There can be 
 no doubt that on this point Hartley is, even more than 
 ordinarily, confused. His clearest statement is the following : 
 " Rational self-interest may therefore be said to lie between 
 the impure motives of sensation, imagination, ambition, gross 
 self-interest, and refined self-interest, on the one hand, zmd 
 the pure ones of sympathy, theopathy, and the moral sense, 
 on the other ; so that when it restrains the impure ones, or 
 cherishes the pure, it may be reckoned a virtue ; when it 
 cherishes the impure, or damps the pure, a vice "? 
 
 This, of course, is hopeless. We only begin to understand 
 the author, when, in the course of his practical observations, 
 he says, e.g. : " However the gross or refined self-interest 
 
 ' See Vl. II., prop. Ixv., p. 494. 
 -See Ft. I., prop, xcvi., p. 291. 
 'See Ft. II., prop. Ixv., p. 495.
 
 David Hartley. i 2 5 
 
 may, upon certain occasions, be disappointed, the rational 
 one never can, whilst we act upon a principle of duty ". The 
 statement is confused, but Hartley probably means to say that 
 we must never act from considerations of purely personal 
 interest at all ; if we do our whole duty, our higher interest 
 will take care of itself. This comes out most clearly, when 
 Hartley explains his characteristic doctrine of ' self-annihila- 
 tion '. He proposes to mediate between the egoistic and 
 altruistic theories regarding the motive in moral action ; but, 
 as will be seen, he really declares for one side in the contro- 
 versy. His conclusion is as follows .- " The virtuous disposi- 
 tions of benevolence, piety, and the moral sense, and 
 particularly that of the love of God, check all the foregoing 
 ones, and seem sufficient utterly to extinguish them at last. 
 This would be perfect self-annihilation, and resting in God 
 as oiur centre. And upon the whole, we may conclude, that 
 though it be impossible to begin without sensuality, and sen- 
 sual selfishness, or to proceed without the other intermediate 
 principles, and particularly that of rational self-interest ; yet 
 we ought never to be satisfied with ourselves, till we arrive 
 at perfect self-annihilation, and the pure love of God." ^ 
 
 We are now in possession of all that is really essential to 
 Hartley's system. We need not be thrown off the track, 
 even when, in treating of the pleasures of sympathy, the 
 author shows that these, on the one hand, increase those of 
 sensation, imagination, ambition, and self-interest, and, on the 
 other hand, unite with those of theopathy and the moral 
 sense ; and when he adds .- " They are self-consistent, and 
 admit of an unlimited extent : they may therefore be our 
 primary pursuit "? Of course, this is not what Hartley 
 really means to say, for he has just urged that ' refined ' self- 
 interest is even more dangerous (because more insidious) than 
 ' gross ' self-interest. Hence, of course, the pleasures of 
 sympathy are by no means to be indulged in {qua pleasures) 
 without restriction. What he doubtless means is, that the 
 principle of sympathy is to be allowed perfectly free play. 
 
 ' See Pt. II., prop, l.wii., p. 497. - Ibid., Ixviii., p. 498.
 
 126 History of Utilitarianisfn. 
 
 The confusion results from Hartley's inveterate habit of 
 appealing constantly to egoistic motives, while holding all 
 the time that, not egoism, but self-annihilation is the true 
 principle of human action. Indeed, he says : " Since benevo- 
 lence is now proved to be a primary pursuit, it follows, that 
 we are to direct every action so as to produce the greatest 
 happiness, and the least misery, in our power. This is that 
 rule of social behaviour, which universal unlimited benevo- 
 lence inculcates." ^ 
 
 It might seem as if, after all Hartley's logical inconsistencies, 
 he had ended by stating Utilitarianism in its modem form : 
 the ' greatest happiness of the greatest number ' the end 
 of moral action, and the motive of the agent, in very con- 
 siderable degree, at least, unselfish. But in the application 
 of his principles. Hartley halts far behind Gay and Hume. 
 He says : " It is impossible for the most sagacious and ex- 
 perienced persons to make any accurate estimate of the future 
 consequences of particular actions, so as, in all the variety 
 of circumstances which occur, to determine justly, which action 
 would contribute most to augment happiness and lessen 
 misery". Then, instead of showing, as Tucker and Paley 
 did later, that, owing to such difficulties, we must act, not 
 from computations in the particular case, but with a view to 
 the general consequences of given classes of actions, he lays 
 down ten rules, which amount really to shirking the considera- 
 tion of external consequences almost altogether. The first 
 rule is, that we follow the Scriptural precepts in the natural, 
 obvious, and popular meaning of them ; the second, that we 
 have great regard for our own moral sense, and that of others. 
 Hartley says : " This rule coincides remarkably with the 
 foregoing. They are together the chief supports of all that 
 is good, even in the most refined and philosophical, as well 
 as in the vulgar ; and therefore must not be weakened, or 
 explained away." The third rule, indeed, is that we are 
 to take account of consequences, and let such considerations 
 have some influence with us, but never in opposition to the 
 
 ' See Pt. II., prop. Ixx., p. 504.
 
 David Hartley. 127 
 
 first two rules. The other rules mentioned are purely prac- 
 tical precepts, and need not be considered here. 
 
 With characteristic infelicity, Hartley confuses his treat- 
 ment of the relation of Ethics to Religion by urging that the 
 love of God procures a pleasure superior in kind and degree 
 to all the rest, and that this is one important reason why it 
 should be our primary pursuit and ultimate end. Neglecting 
 this inconsistency, we may find Hartley's real meaning in the 
 first part of the same proposition, where he shows that " the 
 love of God regulates, improves, and perfects all the other 
 parts of our nature "}■ A very commonplace statement this, 
 it may be thought, and the following reflections are, on the 
 whole, far from intellectually illuminating ; but their dulness 
 should not blind us to one very important fact, viz., that 
 according to Hartley we need religion, not primarily because 
 we need to remain in constant fear of a God who has it in 
 His power to inflict unlimited punishments, or to bribe us with 
 rewards beyond computation, but because self-annihilation 
 and communion with God presuppose each other, are two 
 essential phases of our growth in moral perfection, so that at 
 the last feax is lost in love. An examination of the text would 
 perhaps show that Hartley is even less of a theologian than a 
 moral philosopher, in the sense of technical proficiency ; but 
 we can forgive much in the man who saw * through a glass 
 darkly ' what was beyond the vision of so many of the ac- 
 credited theologians of his own and later times. 
 
 Inseparably connected with Hartley's view of the relation 
 of Ethics to Religion, is his theory of the moral sense. As we 
 have just seen, he holds that we cannot determine the morality 
 of actions primetrily with respect to consequences ; but that 
 we must act always with a view to Scriptural precepts, taking 
 very particular pains to do nothing that shall blunt the moral 
 sense, either in ourselves or in others. When he comes to 
 consider the moral sense directly, he says that this " ought 
 to be made the immediate guide of our actions on all sudden 
 emergencies ; and therefore its pleasures may be considered 
 
 ^ See Pt. II., prop. Ixxi., p. 514.
 
 128 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 as making part of our primary pursuit " } Since this con- 
 fusion is of the same kind that we have repeatedly noticed, 
 and since the author's real meaning is sufficiently plain, we 
 may properly neglect it. 
 
 For Hartley's clearest account of the genesis of the moral 
 sense, we must look to his earlier analysis of the pleasures 
 and pains pertaining to that faculty. After some rather 
 scattering observations, he concludes : " And thus we may 
 perceive, that all the pleasures and pains of sensation, 
 imagination, ambition, self-interest, sympathy, and theopathy, 
 as far as they are consistent with one another, with the frame 
 of our natures, and with the course of the world, beget in us 
 a moral sense, and lead us to the love and approbation of 
 virtue, and to the fear, hatred, and abhorrence of vice "? The 
 meaning seems to be, that the harmony of our other affections 
 in some way produces the moral sense ; but for Hartley, as 
 for others, the moral sense, when once it exists, exercises a 
 regulative function, one very important object of which is 
 to produce a harmony of all the other affections. We are 
 not reassured, when he immediately adds : " This moral sense 
 therefore carries its own authority with it, inasmuch as it 
 is the sum total of all the rest, and the ultimate result from 
 them ; and employs the force and authority of the whole 
 nature of man against any particular part of it, that rebels 
 against the determinations and commands of the conscience 
 or moral judgment ". Later in the book, Hartley says : 
 " The moral sense is generated chiefly by piety, benevolence, 
 and rational self-interest ; all of which are explicit guides of 
 life in deliberate actions " ; ^ but this only makes the con- 
 fusion worse. These vague and partly conflicting accounts of 
 the genesis of the moral sense are hardly calculated to give us 
 a firm conviction of its authoritative character. The difficulty 
 is not so much that it has in some way been developed in the 
 course of human experience, as that we are left so largely in 
 the dark as to how it was developed, and exactly what it is. 
 
 ^ See Pt. II., prop. Ixxiv., p. 531. 
 
 2 See Pt. I., prop, xcix., p. 311. •' See Pt. II., prop. Ixxiv., p. 532.
 
 David Hartley. 129 
 
 The preceding exposition will probably convince the reader 
 that Hartley's system is principally important, as being the 
 first elaborate attempt to work out the Associationist theory, 
 with reference both to Psychology and to Ethics. Of the 
 value of his contribution to Psychology, we shall be able 
 better to judge when we have examined Tucker's system. 
 Until then, indeed, we can hardly be said to have anything 
 with which to compare it. On the other hand, it is perfectly 
 clear that this first attempt systematically to develop As- 
 sociationism produced very little of permanent value for 
 Ethics. We have but to compare Hartley's treatment of 
 Ethics with the outline sketched by Gay, in order to see how 
 greatly inferior it is both in consistency and originality ; while 
 it goes without saying that Hartley contributed nothing to 
 ethical literature at all comparable in value with even the 
 first (and, in the present writer's opinion, inferior) version 
 of Hume's theory, which had been published as Book III. 
 of the Treatise nine years before the Observations. But, 
 more particularly, we must notice that Hartley was not the 
 typical Associationist-Utilitarian, as is frequently assumed. 
 Unlike any of that school who immediately followed, he held 
 (i) that there are qualitative differences between pleasures ; 
 (2) that ' derived ' sympathy, and not the pursuit of one's 
 own ultimate happiness, must be regarded as the true motive 
 in moral action ; and (3) that the consideration of conse- 
 quences should play a very subordinate part in determin- 
 ing the rightness or wrongness of actions. This last feature of 
 Hartley's system, indeed, nearly excludes him from the Utili- 
 tarian school altogether. Hutcheson actually conceded 
 almost, if not quite, as much to the importance of the conse- 
 quences of actions as did Hartley. The ethical part of the 
 Observations remains an instructive example of a truth with 
 which one is often impressed in the History of Philosophy : 
 that those who are the first to employ a new ' method ' are 
 often more blind even than their own contemporaries as to 
 its logical consequences.
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 ABRAHAM TUCKER. 
 
 Gay's Preliminary Dissertation — which, as we have seen, 
 appeared in 1731 as an essay prefixed to Law's translation 
 of King's Origin of Evil — had a most peculiar fate. Pub- 
 lished anonymously, it seems never to have been claimed by 
 the author, whose first name, even, is not generally known. ^ 
 Though this remarkable essay was the first statement of 
 Utilitarianism in its completely differentiated form, Hume 
 does not mention it, or show that he was acquainted with it, 
 either in Book III. of the Treatise of Human Nature (1740) 
 or in the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals (175 1). 
 Hartley, indeed, with a scrupulousness which the more gifted 
 writers of his own and the succeeding generation might well 
 have imitated, did mention " the Rev. Mr. Gay " as having 
 suggested to him, through his reported views and his pub- 
 h'shed Dissertation, " the possibility of deducing all our in- 
 tellectual pleasures and pains from association ". This was 
 in the preface to the well-known Observations on Man, pub- 
 lished in 1749. Hartley's actual treatment of 'association,' 
 however, was quite different from that suggested by Gay, 
 while his particular applications of the principle to the solu- 
 tion of ethical problems differed still more from those to be 
 found in the Preliminary Dissertation. 
 
 ' Whewell was probably right in thinking that he had identified him with 
 " John Gay, who took the degree of B.A. at Sidney College in 1721, and was 
 afterwards Fellow of the College ". See Lectures on the History of Moral 
 Philosophy in England, Lect. x. Other writers commonly follow Hartley's 
 example, and refer to him as " the Rev. Mr. Gay ". 
 
 (130)
 
 Abraham Tucker. 131 
 
 But nineteen years after the publication of Hartley's 
 book — thirty-seven years after the publication of the Dis- 
 sertation itself — the first four volumes appeared of a work 
 entitled The Light of Nature Pursued {iy62,), published under 
 the obvious pseudonym of " Edward Search ". Here, to be 
 sure, we have no direct mention of Gay ; but the work con- 
 sists largely in the complete and systematic development of 
 the fundamental ideas of the Dissertation, as regards both 
 Psychology and Ethics. It would be difficult to mention two 
 ethical writers standing for almost exactly the same general 
 principles, who differ so much in style and method of treat- 
 ment as do Gay and Abraiiam Tucker. Not only was the 
 Preliminary Dissertation severely compressed and published 
 anonymously, but it was, in itself, a singularly impersonal 
 essay. Regarding the author, one can only infer that he 
 was a remarkably clear, logical, and original thinker, though 
 with hardly a reahsing sense of the complexity of the phenom- 
 ena of our moral life. In the case of Tucker, on the other 
 hand, in spite of his employment of a whimsical pseudonym, 
 the personality of the author is always before us. Indeed, 
 for purposes of illustration, he does not hesitate to refer to 
 his own courtship. We see him in his book for what he 
 actually was in life, an English gentleman of the old school, 
 full of humanity and good sense, and possessed of an infinite 
 leisure which one envies him far more than his wealth : 
 setting about his task each day with the consciousness that 
 he may devote the rest of his life to it, if he will ; now dis- 
 playing great keenness of insight in his treatment of psycho- 
 logical and ethical problems ; now indulging in fantastical 
 speculations like that regarding the ' vehicular soul ' ; now 
 concerned with the revision of theology according to the dic- 
 tates not of the head but of the heart ; and now discussing 
 current metaphysical problems with unbounded good nature, 
 it is true, but with an utter failure to comprehend their import 
 which reminds one of Dr. Johnson's classic refutation of 
 idealism. 
 
 In a word, we find in Tucker the almost perfect embodi-
 
 132 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 merit of old-fashioned English good-nature and good sense, 
 so long as he is concerned with the concrete realities of 
 human experience ; but when he ventures upon distinctly 
 metaphysical ground, we find this charming old gentleman 
 alternating between the complacent obstinacy of common- 
 sense and the wildest vagaries of a metaphysical dreamer. 
 His style is as diffuse as well could be, but is uniformly 
 clear, and his illustrations have sometimes been mentioned 
 as about the best in English ethical literature. It will readily 
 be seen that the portentous bulk of Tucker's work — the 
 conclusion was published posthumously in three volumes in 
 1777 — ^would alone make it impossible to follow the author 
 exactly, as regards order of treatment, even if one desired to 
 do so. But the lack of methodical arrangement in the 
 Light of Nature would make this undesirable in any case. 
 We shall, however, attempt to follow the main thread of the 
 argument which knits together the mass of material con- 
 tained in the first three or four of the seven octavo volumes.^ 
 
 In order to understand Tucker's ethical system, with which 
 alone we are here primarily concerned, we must first examine 
 its psychological foundation. Moreover, it will be well to 
 do this in some detail, for the Light of Nature probably 
 contains a better account than any other single work of the 
 psychological views held practically in common by the older 
 school of Utilitarians. Tucker begins by once for all, and 
 confessedly, adopting Locke's psychology as the basis for 
 his own. He is fond of emphasising small differences on 
 occasion, but he never pretends to depart materially from his 
 master where fundamentals are concerned. And yet, it would 
 be grossly inaccurate to describe Tucker's psychology as 
 merely a reproduction of Locke's. The principle of the 
 Association of Ideas — hardly more than indicated by his 
 
 1 The whole work is divided into three Parts (not so called, however) of quite 
 unequal length. These are (i) " Human Nature," (2) " Theology," (3) " Lights 
 of Nature and Gospel Blended". The first two Parts are important, while the 
 third, though constituting almost exactly half the work, is of very minor conse- 
 quence. For brevity, these main divisions will be designated in future references 
 as Parts I., II., and III,
 
 Abraham Tucker. 133 
 
 master,! and employed only to explain the vagaries of our 
 mental life — plays in Tucker's system the all-important part. 
 This makes it the more strange that he should omit all men- 
 tion of Gay, and speak of Hartley — whose Obset'vations on 
 Man had long been published — very seldom, and then almost 
 always to criticise him adversely. But if Tucker fails to confess 
 his obligations to these two writers, as modern literary courtesy 
 would seem to require, he does something to make up for it 
 by his constant references to Locke, for whom he seems to 
 have entertained an extravagant admiration. All of Hume's 
 philosophical works had, of course, appeared some time before 
 the publication of the first four volumes of the Light of 
 Nature; but his influence is difficult, if not impossible, to 
 trace. ^ As might be expected, moreover, Butler's Sermons 
 upon Huntaji Nature (1726), with their very suggestive treat- 
 ment of the psychology of desire, etc., were wasted on Tucker, 
 as, indeed, they were on all the earlier Utilitarians. 
 
 Having thus noticed Tucker's general relation to his pre- 
 decessors, we may profitably turn at once to his own treatment 
 of Psychology. The question of mental ' faculties ' he dis- 
 poses of, not very satisfactorily, in a few words. " Hence 
 we may reasonably gather that the mind possesses two 
 faculties ; one by which we perform whatever we do, and 
 another by which we discern whatever presents itself to our 
 apprehension. The former has usually been styled the Will, 
 and the latter the Understanding." -^ The author immediately 
 goes on to explain that he regards will as ' active ' and 
 understanding as ' passive '. As we shall have occasion to 
 notice later, however, this ' activity ' of the will is vaguely 
 
 ^ This refers, of course, to Locke's explicit treatment of Association. 
 
 - We fail to detect Hume's influence just where it might be expected to show 
 itself. It would be anticipating to go into details, but one point will perhaps 
 serve to illustrate. In his treatment of the for him all-important principle of 
 Association, Tucker does not recognise the (at least apparent) difference be- 
 tween ' association by contiguity ' and ' association by similarity '. This had 
 been clearly done by Hume in the Treatise (1739; see Bk. I., Pt. I., § iv.), and 
 later in the Inquiry concerning Human Understanding (1748 ; see § III.). 
 
 '•' See Pt. I., ch. i., § 2 (second ed.).
 
 134 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 conceived by him. Though Tucker theoretically recognises 
 only the two faculties above named, he puts pleasure and pain 
 on an entirely different footing from other ' sensations ' and 
 ' ideas '. The former always tend to make us do, or cease 
 from doing, something ; the latter cannot by themselves even 
 be conceived as having such an influence. We shall therefore 
 be justified in treating separately pleasure and pain, as well 
 as ' satisfaction ' and ' dissatisfaction,' which are employed 
 merely as more general terms. This will conduce to clearness 
 of exposition and do no violence to Tucker's own views. ^ 
 
 And, first, let us consider his account of the cognitive side 
 of our experience. What is said concerning ' sensation ' and 
 ' reflection ' ^ amounts to little more than a reassertion of the 
 general Lockean position with regard to the origin of our 
 knowledge. Hartley's influence, however, may also be de- 
 tected here, as, for instance, in the following peculiar passage : 
 " I have before declared that by the term ideas, I do not under- 
 stand the very perceptions of the mind, but the figure, motion, 
 or other modification, of some interior fibres, animal spirits, or 
 other substances, immediately causing perception ; which sub- 
 stances I have since called the mental organs ".^ This is 
 rather worse than Hartley himself — to whom, by the way, no 
 allusion is here made — but it is only fair to Tucker to say that 
 he does not follow up this attempt to translate the mental 
 into imaginary physiological terms, which so greatly detracts 
 from the value of Hartley's own work. 
 
 Tucker's account of ' association ' is more characteristic. 
 When ideas, originally obtained through * sensation ' or * re- 
 flection,' have co-existed in the mind a sufficient number of 
 times, they may combine in either of two ways : (i) by ' com- 
 position,' when they fuse, so as to form one single complex 
 idea ; (2) by ' association ' proper, " when they appear in 
 couples, strongly adhering to each other ". The most ob- 
 vious case of association is that between words and their 
 meanings. In fact, all the examples given are of what would 
 
 * See, particularly, Pt. I., chs. v., vi. 
 
 " See Pt. I., chs. vii., viii. '■' Ibid., ch. viii., § 3.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 135 
 
 now be called ' association by contiguity,' as opposed to ' as- 
 sociation by similarity '. Here Tucker seems to follow 
 Hartley (1749) and neglect Hume (1739V Of course it was 
 later held by certain Associationists, that all cases of so- 
 called ' association by similarity ' could be reduced to terms 
 of what they assumed to be the more fundamental form, 
 ' association by contiguity ' ; but — even apart from the appar- 
 ently insuperable difficulties in the way of such simplification 
 — this is a refinement of the Associationist doctrine with 
 which we are not concerned at present. If Tucker had left 
 the theory of ' association ' here, his treatment could not have 
 been regarded as really important. It would have been little 
 more than a popular version of what Hume had expressed 
 both more briefly and more exactly, and of what Hartley had 
 worked out in almost wearisome detail. But the author seems 
 to have in mind a teacher more suggestive, from his point of 
 view, than either of the others — the writer of the Disserta- 
 tion. For he immediately goes on to consider what he calls 
 ■ trains '. Associations are by no means exhausted by the 
 cases where two ideas only go together. As a rule, several 
 ideas follow in succession, all having reference to some general 
 topic, and these Tucker calls a ' train '. The fact that such 
 ' trains ' are the rule, and not the exception, is sufficiently 
 evident As to their origin, he says .- " Desire, curiosity, 
 amusement, voluntary attention, or whatever else carries the 
 notice frequently through a number of ideas always in the 
 same series, links them into a train "? Incidentally, the 
 author commits himself to the view, that we must recognise 
 cases where the connecting links are physiological rather than 
 mental, in other words to what, in comparatively recent times, 
 has become familiarly known as the theory of ' unconscious 
 cerebration '. 
 
 But even this is only preliminary to Tucker's main pur- 
 pose, though many rambling discussions intervene before 
 he again takes up what is really the thread of the present 
 
 ^ Hume had, of course, clearly recognised both kinds of association. 
 2 See Pt. I., ch. x., § 3.
 
 136 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 argument. At length he says, following Gay almost exactly, 
 so far as the principle is concerned : " But daily experience 
 testifies that conviction will often remain after the grounds 
 of it have slipped out of our thought : whenever we reflect on 
 the thing proved, there occurs a judgment of its being true, 
 united in the same assemblage without aid of any proof to 
 support it ; and this many times after the proofs are so far 
 gone out of our memory that we cannot possibly recall them. 
 By this channel we are supplied with many truths, commonly 
 reputed self-evident, because though we know them assuredly 
 for truths, we cannot discover how we came by that knowl- 
 edge. In like manner we have store of propensities, gener- 
 ally esteemed natural, because we cannot readily trace them 
 to any other origin than that quality of affecting us, assigned 
 by nature to certain ideas. But having shown how translation 
 prevails in satisfaction, as well as assent, there will appear 
 reason to conclude, that we derive our inclinations and moral 
 senses through the same channel as our knowledge, without 
 having them interwoven originally into our constitution." ^ 
 
 I have chosen to quote Tucker's own language here — 
 though it may require a few words of explanation, and though 
 the last passage carries us beyond his treatment of mere 
 cognition — for it shows at once what his position is, as re- 
 gards Intuitionism and the Moral Sense doctrine, and also 
 how exactly he follows Gay at this, the crucial point of his 
 whole argument. What Tucker means here, and what he 
 sufficiently explains elsewhere, though hardly in the proper 
 context, is practically as follows. Our thought proceeds, as 
 we have seen, not ordinarily by isolated ' associations,' but in 
 continuous ' trains '. Now, these ' trains ' may be, and fre- 
 quently are, repeated. And the more they are repeated, the 
 more two things tend to happen : (i) some part of the * train ' 
 comes more and more to absorb our attention, while (2) — 
 what is equally important — the remaining parts gradually 
 drop out of consciousness. Thus, a, b, c, etc., may be the 
 original steps by which we reached some important truth, M. 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. xviii., § i.
 
 Abraham J 7uker. 137 
 
 It might seem at first as if habit would tend to make indehble 
 the series as a whole. As a matter of fact, however, it does 
 nothing of the kind ; and this because the really interesting 
 thing is My and not the antecedent steps, which latter fall 
 more and more into the background until they may become 
 wholly forgotten. This, of course, will make M stand out as 
 a fictitious ultimate, e.g., as a particular ' intuitive ' truth. 
 Now this theoretically deceptive, but practically economical, 
 principle is what Tucker means by ' translation *. It applies 
 constantly, not only to the development of our cognitions, 
 but to that of our emotions and passions as well ; and in this 
 latter function, particularly, it becomes for Tucker the uni- 
 versal solvent of the difficulties of Ethics. 
 
 Let us now turn to the author's treatment of the affective 
 and volitional side of our nature. As we have already noted, 
 he recognises only two ' faculties,' Understanding and Will. 
 At the same time, his treatment of pleasure and pain could 
 hardly have been more distinct from his treatment of our 
 other perceptions, if he had assigned them to a third ' faculty,' 
 as was later done by members of the Associationist school. 
 So far, then, there is no difficulty ; but for Tucker, as for 
 other determinist Associationists, the will is little more than 
 the resultant of a psychic parallelogram of forces — the 
 ' forces ' in the case being, of course, pleasurable or painful 
 perceptions. Thus, in treating of pleasure and pain, ' satis- 
 faction ' and ' dissatisfaction/ as constituting motives, we shall 
 necessarily be considering, at the same time, the more im- 
 portant part of what he has to say regarding the will. 
 
 We may profitably begin by raising Tucker's own question : 
 What is it that gives ' weight ' to our motives ? Certain 
 things attract us, others repel us. Why? The obvious 
 answer is, that the former suggest what we call ' pleasurable,' 
 the latter what we call ' painful ' experiences — for surely ideas, 
 merely as such, do not lead to action. But we must be more 
 careful in the use of language, if we would express the exact 
 truth. The author says .- " Pleasure in vulgar estimation
 
 138 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 stands opposed to business, duty, works of use and necessity : 
 yet in all these we feel some engagement, self-approbation 
 or complacence of mind, that carries us through with them. 
 Pleasures, usually so called, often lose their gust, they satiate 
 and cloy upon repetition, and nauseate instead of inviting. 
 Therefore Mr. Locke has fixed upon the term Satisfaction, 
 as being more extensive, comprehending all that complacence 
 we feel as well in business as diversion^ as well in the works 
 of prudence as in the starts of fancy." ^ This term ' satis- 
 faction ' is adopted by Tucker, and there he practically lets 
 the matter rest, though he says a good deal more by wa)' of 
 popular explanation and illustration. 
 
 It must not be supposed, however, that he is attempting to 
 evade a difficulty which he sees by the use of an ambiguous 
 term. For Rim, there is no other difficulty in the case than 
 this, that positive and unmistakable pleasures and pains are 
 less numerous than we are apt to suppose, and therefore not 
 sufficient to determine all our actions. It never seems to 
 occur to him as a possibility, that we can desire anything 
 qualitatively different from our own greater pleasure or less 
 pain. ' Satisfaction ' and ' dissatisfaction,' therefore, are 
 merely more general terms than pleasure and pain, in the 
 sense that they include even the lowest possible stages of these 
 latter, such as we habitually disregard in our ordinary experi- 
 ence. There is nothing to indicate that Tucker was even 
 acquainted with Butler's view, that the major part of our 
 desires, even those of sense, ' terminate in the object '. From 
 the latter point of view, so familiar at the present time, the 
 word ' satisfaction ' would of course take on an entirely dif- 
 ferent meaning from that just explained. 
 
 But, while Tucker never doubts that ' satisfaction ' and ' dis- 
 satisfaction ' alone can constitute a motive, he is not quite clear 
 as to how we are induced to seek our own future satisfaction, 
 avoid our own future dissatisfaction — and yet this, according 
 to his view, is precisely that in which all deliberate action 
 ultimately consists. He points out that " it is not very sstis- 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. vi., § i.
 
 Abj'aliaiu Tucker. 139 
 
 faction, but the prospect or idea of it " that leads to action. 
 Indeed, he says : " Since, then, expectation is not the same 
 with the thing expected, it follows that we may pursue satis- 
 faction without being in a state of enjoyment, and fly uneasi- 
 ness without being in a state of suffering "} But if the idea of 
 satisfaction, not satisfaction itself, is what moves one, why 
 may not other ideas conceivably have the same effect ? Or, 
 if one adopt the altogether safer position, that it is the 
 ' satisfaction ' attaching to some idea and not the idea attach- 
 ing to ' satisfaction ' that constitutes the motive, the question 
 immediately arises : Why may not ' satisfaction ' attach to 
 other ideas besides that of one's own future pleasure ? But 
 Tucker did not follow up this question, so fraught with danger 
 for one holding, as he does, that one can ultimately desire 
 nothing but one's own satisfaction.^ 
 
 But if Tucker is somewhat confused on the question as to 
 what, exactly, constitutes a motive, he is not only consistent, 
 but perfectly explicit in the statement of his general hedon- 
 istic position. He will hear nothing of ' qualitative distinc- 
 tions,' as applying to pleasures and pains. He says : 
 " Satisfaction is always one and the same in kind, how much 
 soever it may vary in degree, for it is that state the mind is 
 thrown into upon the application of things agreeable ; and 
 whatever possesses that quality in equal degree, whether 
 meats and drinks, or diversion, or gain, or acquisition of power, 
 or reflection on past performances, fills it with the same con- 
 tent and complacence : wherefore the various species of 
 motives must be distinguished by the variety of vehicles 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. vi., § 5. 
 
 - In one passage, Tucker seems to be on the point of at least partially ex- 
 tricating himself from his confusion on this matter. He says that, in one 
 sense, " present satisfaction is the end we have constantly in view on proceeding 
 to action" (Pt. I., ch. vi., § 6). But he immediately explains that "the satis- 
 faction we propose in every exertion of our activity is that of the moment next 
 immediately ensuing, and this may be called present satisfaction without any 
 impropriety of speech". Clearly this does not enable the author to escape 
 from the theoretical difficulty mentioned above, though it does probably show 
 that he vaguely felt the difficulty.
 
 140 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 containing satisfaction ".^ These ' vehicles ' the author quite 
 arbitrarily, and rather inconsistently, reduces to ' pleasure,' 
 ' use,' ' honour,' and ' necessity ' — terms which might prove 
 misleading, if his meaning were not otherwise clear. This 
 denial of ' qualitative distinctions ' between different classes 
 of pleasures and pains, sounds commonplace enough now, 
 for we are all agreed that it is the only consistent view for 
 hedonism ; but, while other English writers {^.g.■> Gay) had 
 held views from which this position alone was logically de- 
 ducible, Tucker was the first, so far as I am aware, to state 
 it in so many words.^ 
 
 In his account of the ' genesis of pleasures,' Tucker is 
 true to his universally convenient principle of ' translation '.^ 
 Nature gives us at first only the pleasures of ' sensation ' and 
 ' appetite ' ; but soon ' reflection ' comes upon the scene, and 
 supplies us with the many and various pleasures which we call 
 ' mental,' as distinguished from those which depend entirely 
 upon the condition of the body. These ' mental,' or so-called 
 ' higher,' pleasures constitute by far the greater part of our 
 enjoyments in adult life, as any one will readily see from 
 his own experience. But they differ from ' pleasures of sense,' 
 not by any means qualitatively, but merely by virtue of the 
 complexity of the associations which they involve, and the 
 dropping out of the intermediate links which would otherwise 
 betray their lowly origin. In short, the * higher ' pleasures are, 
 as a class, more ' translated ' than the ' lower ' ones ; and the 
 ' higher ' any individual pleasure is, the more ' translated ' it 
 will always on inspection prove to be. 
 
 But, while we can desire nothing but our own ' satisfaction,' 
 according to Tucker, we are often thwarted in our attempt to 
 secure that which we desire ; and hence arise the ' passions '. 
 We cannot follow the author through his explanation of the 
 genesis and development of the particular passions. Often, 
 perhaps usually, he is perversely ingenious. For example, 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xvi., § i. 
 
 ^Others, of course — e.g., Hutcheson -liad explicitly maintained the contrary. 
 
 " See Pt. I., ch. xxii.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 1 4 1 
 
 he says of revenge : " The desire of revenge is not a natural 
 but a translated desire : we first look upon it as a means of 
 procuring ease to ourselves, and security from injury ; but 
 having often beheld it in this light, the end at length drops 
 out of sight, and desire, according to the usual process of 
 translation, rests upon the means, which thenceforward be- 
 come an end whereon our views will terminate ".^ In other 
 words, revenge, so far from being an original tendency of 
 human nature, is to be regarded as a highly ' translated ' pas- 
 sion. And, as regards the other ' passions ' and ' affections ' — 
 the ' affections ' differing from the ' passions ' only in their less 
 degree of intensity — not only is the love of money derived, 
 as Gay had shown, but also that of liberty and power ; nay, 
 even the so-called ' instinct of self-preservation ' ! Surely this 
 must be regarded as the reductio ad absurdutn of the concep- 
 tion of mind as a tabula rasa, helped out by the principles of 
 ' association ' and ' translation '. 
 
 Such explanations hardly do Tucker justice, and may best 
 be viewed as curiosities of his psychology ; but there is an- 
 other explanation, analogous to the above, which can by no 
 means be neglected, viz., the author's derivation of ' sym- 
 pathy ' by means of ' translation '. He says : " We are not 
 long in the world from our first entrance before we perceive 
 that our pleasures and pains depend much upon the actions 
 of those about us : on a little further progress, we discover 
 that their actions follow their disposition of mind, and after- 
 wards learn to distinguish those dispositions by certain marks 
 of them in their looks and gestures. This makes children 
 perpetually attentive to the motions and countenance of 
 persons into whose hands they fall : nor does there want an- 
 other cause to render them more so, for havmg but few 
 stores in their own imagination, they catch the ideas of other 
 people to supply themselves with employment. And in our 
 advanced years we cannot well carry on any business or 
 argument, or enjoy the pleasures of conversation, without 
 entering into the thoughts and notions of one another. When 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. xxi., § 6.
 
 142 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 we arrive at the use of understanding, the judgment of others 
 weighs with us as a just and natural evidence, inducing us to 
 judge accordingly ; but we have seen how the judgment of 
 expedience, frequently reiterated, transfers satisfaction upon 
 the measures so conceived expedient : and we purposely 
 imitate the ways and manners of our teachers, or other per- 
 sons whom we esteem more expert and knowing in an}' 
 matter than ourselves. Thus we acquire much of our sym- 
 pathy by inadvertent notice, and add more by design and 
 industry ; until custom in both ways has worked out trains 
 wherein imagination learns to run involuntarily and mechani- 
 cally. This appears most evident in compassion, for we can- 
 not help sympathising with distress, though we feel it painful 
 to ourselves, and know it can afford no relief to the party 
 suffering." ^ 
 
 It has seemed best to quote this long passage in full, not 
 only because of the great importance of the matter in question 
 for Tucker's ethical theory, but also because the explanation 
 itself is by no means as simple and unambiguous as it seems 
 to be at first. In fact, this is a good example of the way in 
 which the author occasionally makes a number of fairly just 
 observations, without trying sharply to distinguish the prin- 
 ciples involved. As it stands, the explanation is open to 
 serious criticism. All is ostensibly due to habit and the 
 principle' of ' translation ' ; but an original curiosity and imi- 
 tative tendency have also been tacitly assumed, and, what is 
 much more important, the chasm between feeling like others 
 and feeling for them has apparently not been bridged over 
 at all. But it would be unjust to criticise this attempt to ex- 
 plain the derivation of ' sympathy,' without giving in the same 
 connection the author's explanation of the origin and growth 
 of ' love ' (in the most general sense). This explanation, 
 practically identical with Gay's, is a good deal more plausible 
 than the other, though not, perhaps, in the last resort much 
 more convincing. We first care for people because they give 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xix., § 2.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 143 
 
 us pleasure ; and so, as Tucker observes, " a child's first love 
 is his nurse ". But when the association becomes fixed, the 
 person is loved ' disinterestedly,' as we say, that is, quite inde- 
 pendently of pleasure then afforded.^ Here, again, the state- 
 ments contain a certain modicum of truth. But why is it that 
 certain people do originally please us, while others do not ? 
 And, in general, why do we differ so much from each other 
 in our original likes and dislikes ? Precisely because we are 
 each a bundle of tendencies and predispositions, instead of 
 the receptive waxen tablet that Tucker, following Locke, 
 assumes. 
 
 As already indicated, Tucker has not much of a strictly 
 psychological character to say about the Will, except what 
 has necessarily been involved in the preceding. Will is the 
 ' active ' side of mind, as opposed to Understanding, the 
 ' passive ' side ; but he nowhere gives a clear account of what 
 is to be understood by mental activity. All the mechanism 
 of thought and feeling are explained by the principles of 
 ' association ' and ' translation,' and nothing practically is 
 left for the will to do but to follow the strongest motives 
 thus supplied. The efficient force seems to be in the ' emo- 
 tions ' and ' passions,' cind also in the feelings of lesser in- 
 tensity. Particular passages might prove misleading. For 
 instance, in one of the earlier chapters of his work, Tucker 
 criticises Hartley for maintaining the essential ' passivity ' of 
 the mind. He says : " Thus the mind remains totally in- 
 active, reduced to one faculty alone, for the Will, which he 
 terms expressly a certain state of the vibratiuncles, belongs 
 to the ether, not to her : she sits a spectator only, and not an 
 agent of all we perform ; she may indeed discern what is doing, 
 but has no share in what is done .- like the fly upon the chariot 
 wheel, she fancies herself raising a cloud of dust, but contri- 
 butes nothing towards increasing it "? This, however, is 
 merely the protest of common sense against reducing the 
 mind to what our more modern theorists would call an ' epi- 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. xxi., § lo. - Ihid., ch. iii., § 2.
 
 144 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 phenomenon ' ; it implies no theory at all as to what the 
 mental activity contended for really is, or how this is related 
 to the ' passive ' side of the mind, which alone is treated in 
 detail or with any attempt at scientific precision. 
 
 Another passage, which occurs somewhat later in the book, 
 may properly be noted in this connection. The author says : 
 " To prevent mistakes, when I speak of the efficacy of motives 
 and of their moving the mind to exert herself, I desire it may 
 be understood that these are figurative expressions ; and I 
 do not mean thereby to deny the efficacy of the mind, or to 
 assert any motion, force, or impulse imparted to her from 
 the motives, as there is to one billiard ball from another upon 
 their striking : but only to observe that motives give occasion 
 to the mind to exert her endeavours in attaining whatever 
 they invite her to, which she does by her own inherent 
 activity, not by any power derived from them " ?- Taken by 
 itself, this passage might seem to make seriously against the 
 interpretation of Tucker's theory of the will here given. Read 
 in the light of his general treatment, however— in the course 
 of which he never even attempts to give an intelligible 
 account of the nature of mental ' activity ' — it will be found 
 to be of significance only as showing how difficult it some- 
 times is to make our author give an account of himself, when 
 he employs the terminology of a ' faculty ' psychology. 
 
 Indeed, there is little to detain us here, for nearly all that 
 Tucker says directly about the will refers to the metaphysical, 
 rather than psychological, question regarding the so-called 
 ' freedom of the will '. Into this wearisome controversy, we 
 need not follow him. It is enough to remark that he is an 
 out-and-out determinist, and that he defends his position not 
 only with great vigour, but with very considerable skill. - 
 One should remember, however, that the arguments employed 
 here by Tucker were by no means so trite then as, in many 
 cases, they are now. In fact, owing to the great popularity 
 of his book. Tucker was probably not an unimportant factor 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. v., § 3. 
 
 ^See, e.g., the whole of ch. v. (Pt. I.), on " Motives ".
 
 Abraham Tucker. 145 
 
 in reducing the arguments for determinism to what we would 
 now regard as their traditional form. 
 
 Such, in brief, is the psychological basis of Tucker's ethical 
 system. Any attempt to give in a few pages the substance of 
 what in the original occupies several hundred, must neces- 
 sarily be somewhat unsatisfactory. At the same time, if 
 much has been lost, something at least has been gained. 
 One must remember that Tucker's style is almost unpardon- 
 ably diffuse — the chapter on " Satisfaction," for instance, 
 occupies nearly a hundred pages — and also that he makes little 
 pretence to methodical arrangement, so that the book itself 
 IS likely to leave a rather vague impression, unless it has 
 been read with considerable care. But at any rate, we have 
 been able to see, in sufficient detail, how Tucker followed up 
 the fruitful suggestions of Gay, whom he does not mention 
 at all ; and we have probably been led to suspect that, though 
 he seldom mentions Hartley except to criticise him adversely, 
 he had by no means failed to profit by the fact that he pub- 
 lished the first instalment of his own work nineteen years 
 after the appearance of the Observations on Man. Still, his 
 definite obligations to Hartley are not easy to make out, 
 while there is little or nothing in his treatment of psycho- 
 logical problems to suggest Hume's influence. Even his 
 direct obligations to Gay, though more than probable, could 
 hardly be proved. The fact is that Tucker was a writer of 
 very considerable originality in Psychology as well as in 
 Ethics ; and that the first part of his Light of Nature, though 
 far from corresponding to one's ideal of a scientific treatise, 
 was decidedly the best account of the Associationist Psychol- 
 ogy, which had appeared up to his time. Indeed, it might 
 reasonably be held that the later Associationists were a good 
 deal more successful in concealing, than in actually removing, 
 the defects of method which we have had to notice in this 
 part of Tucker's work. 
 
 10
 
 CHAPTER VIII. 
 
 ABRAHAM TUCKER (continued). 
 
 As was almost inevitable, considering its psychological foun- 
 dation, Tucker's ethical system, to which we must now turn, 
 was radically opposed to Rationalism, Intuitionism, and the 
 ' Moral Sense' theory. Locke, indeed, as we have had occasion 
 to notice, did not actually construct a system of Ethics upon the 
 basis of his own philosophy ; Tucker's system, on the other 
 hand, was the legitimate result of thoroughgoing Empiricism. 
 Before taking up the constructive side of his treatment of 
 Ethics, it may be well to consider, in a general way, his attitude 
 toward the three types of ethical theory just mentioned. 
 Tucker has little to say in direct criticism of the Rationalists. 
 We can readily surmise, however, what form his objections to 
 that ethical school would have taken, if he had been more ex- 
 plicit. First, according to his own theory of knowledge, he 
 would have had to deny the existence of any abstract faculty 
 of ' reason,' capable of discerning ultimate and absolute truth. 
 In one characteristic passage, he does say in so many words 
 that we must be content with ' moral certainty '. Secondly, 
 he always held, of course, that our recognition of moral dis- 
 tinctions could be adequately explained by experience. 
 Thirdly, he was as sure as Hume had been that what we call 
 ' reason ' can never itself directly lead to action. It may 
 discover the means by which to attain some end ; but the end 
 itself must be otherwise supplied, viz., by the affective side of 
 our nature. This would plamly make a rationalistic system 
 valueless, even if it could be logically constructed. 
 
 As regards Intuitionism in general, Tucker's whole system 
 
 (146)
 
 Abraham Tucker. 147 
 
 was intended largely as a confutation of those who refused 
 to go behind the mere facts of our moral experience, and who 
 would not even attempt to find a scientific explanation for 
 them. The ' Moral Sense ' theory, on the other hand, as the 
 particular form of Intuitionism which was most in evidence 
 among philosophical writers of this period, comes in for more 
 specific notice. Tucker criticises this theory much as Gay 
 had done in the Dissertation. He regards it as a mere 
 substitute for ethical theories based upon ' innate ideas,' the 
 existence of which latter Locke had once for all disproved 
 in the first book of his Essay. All the supposed phenomena 
 of the ' moral sense ' may be explained by experience, as 
 showing the expediency or inexpediency of particular classes 
 of actions. And the author holds consistently that we obtain 
 our first notions of moral good and evil, rather by observing 
 the conduct of others, than by reflecting upon our own.^ It 
 must not be supposed, however, that our so-called ' moral 
 sense ' is less valuable because acquired. Tucker is always 
 ready to emphasise the truth, sometimes forgotten in ethical 
 discussions, that as moralists we all begin, or should begin, 
 with the same facts of moral experience, and that to explain 
 these facts, when such a thing can be done, is by no means 
 necessarily to explain them away. 
 
 Let us now examine the author's attempt to place Ethics 
 upon what he regarded as the only sure foundation, viz.^ 
 that of htuTian experience. He begins by raising the tradi- 
 tional question : What are we to regard, not merely as good, 
 but as the Ultimate Good ? And he indicates the general 
 character of his own solution as follows : " Upon perusal of 
 the chapter of satisfaction and those of the four classes of 
 motives, whoever shall happen to think they contain a just 
 representation of human nature, need not be long in seeking 
 for this summum bonum : for he will perceive it to be none 
 other than pleasure or satisfaction, which is pleasure taken 
 in the largest sense, as comprising every complacence of 
 
 ^ See Pt. I., ch. xxiv., i^ 13.
 
 148 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 mind together with the avoidance of pain or uneasiness " y 
 As we have already seen, Tucker emphasises the so-called 
 ' higher ' or ' intellectual ' pleasures at the expense of the 
 so-called ' lower ' ones. In this he agrees with Hartley ; 
 but, unlike Hartley, he holds that ' satisfaction ' is one, and 
 that concrete satisfactions differ only in degree. The sum 
 total of these concrete satisfactions is what we mean by 
 ' happiness '. If any one would after all deny that happiness 
 is the Good, Tucker thinks he may be silenced by being 
 reminded that, as a matter of fact, it is the one thmg univer- 
 sally sought. 
 
 But while Tucker is an uncompromising hedonist, he fully 
 appreciates the importance of acting according to * general 
 rules,' and not seeking particular pleasures too eagerly, as if 
 ends in themselves. He thus describes the proper task of the 
 moralist : " As we cannot upon every occasion see to the end 
 of our proceedings, he will establish certain rules to serve as 
 landmarks for guiding us on the way. These rules, when 
 he has leisure and opportunity for mature consideration, he 
 will build on one another, erecting the whole fabric upon the 
 basis of sumniuni bonuvi before described. But because 
 their reference to the ultimate end cannot be continually 
 kept in mind, he will inure himself and everybody within 
 his reach, by such methods as he shall find feasible, to look 
 upon them as good in themselves, that they may become 
 influencing principles of action." ^ This is wholly character- 
 istic, and more important than might appear. It should 
 always be remembered that early Utilitarianism was not a 
 ' calculating ' ethics, in the offensive and obviously imprac- 
 ticable sense of the words. Neither Tucker nor Paley, for 
 example, taught that we are to determine the morality of a 
 particular action by computing its probable effects in the 
 individual case. On the contrary, they both msisted that 
 we must act on general principles of expediency, not merely 
 because we are intellectually finite beings, but because we are 
 largely creatures of habit Bentham later seemed to hold, 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxvii., § 2. ^ gee ihid., § 8.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 149 
 
 not only that we may, but that we must, thus compute in the 
 individual case — instead of acting according to * general 
 rules ' of utility — but, if this was really his view, it was merely 
 one of that arrogant writer's improvements in Utilitarianism 
 which did so much to bring the doctrine into needless dis- 
 credit. 
 
 We have seen that Hutcheson, though not really a hedonist 
 himself, assumes without question the possibility of com- 
 puting with sufficient exactness the effects of different kinds 
 of actions, as regards their tendency to make for the general 
 happiness or unhappiness, and of thus determining their 
 ' objective ' goodness or badness. In fact, up to this time 
 the difficulty regarding the ' hedonistic calculus ' seems hardly 
 to have been raised, except by Hartley. ^ It is characteristic 
 of Tucker's perfect frankness and honesty, that he should 
 emphasise, if not over-emphasise, this difficulty. For instance, 
 he says : " Our tastes, varying as much as our faces, make us 
 very bad judges of one another's enjoyments. . . . Nor do we 
 judge much better of our own pleasures, for want of being 
 well aware of their aptness to cloy upon repetition, and to 
 change their relish perpetually according to our disposition 
 of body or mind, or the circumstances we happen to stand in : 
 neither can we trust even experience itself in this case, for 
 because a thing has pleased us once, we cannot always be 
 sure it will do so again. . . . But if we make mistakes in esti- 
 mating pleasures singly, we commit more in computing the 
 value of a series of them taken collectively. . . . Therefore we 
 are forced to take our pleasures in the lump, and estimate 
 them upon view ; as a man who guesses at a flock of sheep 
 by the ground they cover, without being able to count them, 
 and who will do it very imperfectly, until he has gotten an 
 expertness by long and careful practice. For absent enjoy- 
 ments, whether past or future, being not actually existent, 
 we cannot hold them as it were in our hand to weigh them, 
 but must judge by the representative idea we have of them 
 m our imagination ; and we ordinarily determine their value 
 
 ' Berkeley also had suggested the difficulty, but only in a very general way.
 
 150 History of Utilitarimiisni. 
 
 by the degree of desire we feel in ourselves towards them." ^ 
 This is decidedly interesting, for it shows that, while Tucker 
 himself was a thoroughgoing hedonist, he anticipated nearly 
 all the objections which anti-hedonists have so long been 
 accustomed to raise against the possibility of the ' hedonistic 
 calculus '.2 But it never seems to have occurred to the author 
 that computations of this sort, being so difficult, may be 
 impossible. 
 
 One point should be carefully noted in this connection. 
 When considering Hutcheson's relation to hedonism, we saw 
 that for him the ' hedonistic calculus ' would be considerably 
 complicated by the fact that the ' moral sense,' by hypothesis 
 ultimate, was itself, according to his view, the source of a 
 very great part of our pleasures and pains. Evidently there 
 is no corresponding complication for Tucker, since all of our 
 pleasures and pains are held by him to be derived from the 
 primary ones of ' sensation ' and ' reflection,' through the 
 agency of ' association ' and ' translation '. 
 
 There are two questions, obviously very closely related, 
 which every moralist must face : (i) What is the [objective] 
 Good ? (2) How is this calculated to appeal to the individual 
 agent .-' To decide either of these questions without reference 
 to the other — or, indeed, to give either undue emphasis — is 
 to make a mistake which is sure to be serious, and which 
 very well may prove fatal. The conspicuous weakness of the 
 early rationalistic systems is, that they give no intelligible 
 account of how that which is ideally right can be willed by 
 the agent. On the other hand, the early hedonists were so 
 deeply interested in this very question, that they were some- 
 what hampered in their treatment of the Good. Tucker is 
 no exception to the general rule. In fact, he sometimes 
 allows himself to use language which would seem to indicate 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxii., §§ 11, 12. 
 
 * Except the very important one, which was not clearly recognised and 
 urged until a good deal later, that hedonistic values vary with the development 
 of moral character. Spencer makes effective use of this objection in his early 
 criticism of the Expediency Philosophy in Social Statics (1851).
 
 Abraham Tticker. 1 5 1 
 
 that the Good is one's own happiness, without much refer- 
 ence to that of others. He says, for example, " nor would I 
 advise a man ever to deny himself, unless in order to 
 please himself better another time "} It is probably need- 
 less to say that passages like this do Tucker injustice. He 
 incidentally points out — in other passages too numerous to 
 quote, or even definitely to refer to — that we find our greatest 
 ' satisfaction ' in the most intimate relations of life, where, of 
 course, a good deal of what we are apt to call ' self-sacrifice ' 
 is necessarily involved. But the theoretical question regard- 
 ing the motive of the moral agent cannot be disposed oi by 
 merely referring to such passages, in however amiable a light 
 they may exhibit the author. 
 
 Tucker's explicit treatment of this question seems always to 
 imply that real disinterestedness must not be looked for any- 
 where. In what one is bound to recognise as a characteristic 
 passage, he says, in effect : Honesty is the best policy, and 
 if men were omniscient, a sense of honour would be need- 
 less.2 Understanding, of course, that the author here in- 
 dulges in some rhetorical exaggeration, let us attempt to see 
 exactly what he means. In the first place, it should be 
 stated that, throughout the First Part of the treatise, on 
 " Human Nature " — ^which might very well be supposed to 
 contain his final view of the matter — he confines himself to the 
 consideration of consequences which may be expected to 
 ensue in the present life and according to the natural coursfe 
 of events. For the moment, let us assume this to be his 
 ultimate view. What, then, does the passage just referred 
 to mean .? Hardly what it seems to say ; for an omniscient 
 rogue, surely, would be able to do much that was wrong 
 without suffering the consequences, while, on the other hand, 
 cases are not far to seek where perfect honesty has led to 
 disaster, even death itself. 
 
 Indeed, the case of Regulus is brought up early in the 
 First Part of the Light of Nature, and throughout the greater 
 portion of the Second Part that unhappy hero is kept on 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxvii., S 6. '^ Ibid., xxiv., § 8.
 
 152 History of Utilita7'ianism. 
 
 trial for ' imprudence ' ! Now, obviously no approximation 
 to omniscience on the part of Regulus would show that, 
 under the peculiar circumstances in which he was placed, it 
 was ' good policy ' for him to be ' honest,' if this present 
 life be all, and if ' good poHcy ' be equivalent to one's selfish 
 interest. As Gay had pertinently remarked : " God alone can 
 in all cases make a man happy or miserable " ; and obviously 
 He does not always, or perhaps usually, bestow adequate 
 rewards or inflict adequate punishments in this life — particu- 
 larly if by these we are to understand ' external ' rewards and 
 punishments. Such perfect distributive justice, which alone 
 can constitute ' complete obHgation,' according to this view 
 of the moral motive, must be looked for in the life to come. 
 The reader may be relieved to know that Regulus is finally 
 acquitted on this ground. In the interesting chapter on 
 " Re-enlargement of Virtue," with which Part II. on " Theo- 
 logy " ends, Tucker says that he has refrained before from 
 referring to rewards and punishments after death merely to 
 show that, in the last resort, we cannot afford to leave them 
 out of consideration. Concerning the particular case of 
 Regulus, he says : " Therefore now we may do ample justice 
 to Regulus, whom we left under a sentence of folly for throw- 
 ing away life with all its enjoyments for a phantom of 
 honour. . . . For he will now plead that it was not a phantastic 
 joy in the transports of rectitude, nor the stoical rhodo- 
 montade of a day spent in virtue containing more enjoyment 
 than an age of bodily delights, nor his inability to bear a 
 life of general odium and contempt, had his duty so required, 
 which fixed him in his resolution : but the prudence of the 
 thing upon a full and calm deliberation. Because he con- 
 sidered himself as a citizen of the universe, whose interests 
 are promoted and maintained by the particular members 
 contributing their endeavours towards increasing the quantity 
 of happiness, wherever possible, among others with whom 
 they have connection and intercourse. . . . He was persuaded 
 likewise that all the good a man does, stands placed to his 
 account, to be repaid him in full value when it will be most
 
 Abraham Tucker. 153 
 
 useful to him : so that whoever works for another, works for 
 himself ; and by working for numbers, earns more than he 
 could possibly do by working for himself alone." ^ 
 
 The passage just quoted might give a wrong impression, 
 if no reference were made to Tucker's peculiar theory regard- 
 ing ' equality,' set forth in a preceding chapter.^ Hitherto 
 this has been neglected, because it is one of the eccentricities 
 of his system, which has had no appreciable effect upon sub- 
 sequent ethical theory, and which the author does not succeed 
 in making even plausible. He holds that, of all the attri- 
 butes of God, ' equity ' is the one of which we have the 
 clearest conception. But from the * equity ' of God, he 
 claims, " it follows unavoidably that there must be an exact 
 equality of fortunes among us, and the value of each 
 person's existence, computed throughout the whole extent 
 of his Being, precisely the same ". And this, for him, means 
 even more than might appear. Not only are the inequalities 
 of external fortune to be made up in the future life : but the 
 evils resulting from our own wickedness are by no means to 
 have an indefinite duration. In some way, not sufficiently 
 explained, our natures are to be purified and our individual 
 accounts of happiness made to balance in the end. " After 
 Favour has had her course, and Justice been satisfied, it 
 remains that Equity should be satisfied too." ^ And equity 
 means an equal amount of happiness for each, apparently 
 regardless of the question of deserts. Probably Tucker 
 would say that, in the strict sense, we have no ' deserts,' 
 since our good or bad characters must be regarded as results 
 of the preceding course of events, which God has ordered 
 for some good purpose.* For the apparent evils in the world, 
 God Himself is in the last resort responsible ; and it must 
 be that He has ordained a final equality of happiness for all. 
 This rather crude form of Theological Universalism might 
 be neglected, but for the fact that Tucker tries partly to 
 
 ^ See Pt. II., ch. xxxi., § 5. 
 
 - Ibid., ch. xxvii. ' Ibid., §§ 2, 4. 
 
 * He does say practically this in ibid., ^ 3.
 
 154 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 base upon it his argument for the reasonableness of altru- 
 istic action. Since the value of every one's existence is the 
 same, we must esteem every one alike, harbour no hatred, 
 work for the general fund of happiness, etc. " Hence follows 
 a general connection of interests throughout the imiverse, a 
 partnership in one common stock, which cannot be increased 
 or diminished in any individual without proportionably 
 afifecting the share of every other." ^ It is hardly necessary 
 to point out that such an attempt as this to bridge over the 
 chasm between egoism and altruism is foredoomed to failure. 
 The difficulty remains precisely where it was before. 
 
 Is Tucker's system, then, a ' selfish ' theory of morality ? 
 To a large and quite unnecessary extent, yes ; and yet I 
 think that both Tucker and Paley have often been misunder- 
 stood in this respect. The fact that nearly all men are practi- 
 cally ' sympathetic,' practically capable of some degree of 
 self-sacrifice, is fully recognised by both of them ; and they 
 further agree that, in the present life at least, our greatest 
 pleasures are derived from the exercise of the ' social affec- 
 tions '. Their view of concrete human nature, therefore, is 
 radically different from that of Hobbes, and not so very 
 unlike our own. What we are bound to object to, is their 
 futile attempt to explain ' sympathy ' as a mere product of 
 ' translation '. Here they both followed Gay exactly, and 
 did not profit by the later form of Hume's ethical theory, 
 as found in the Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals. 
 Now their choice in this matter was of the greatest import- 
 ance, for it determined the type of Utilitarian theory to which 
 they must always be assigned ; it identified them with the old 
 order, not the new. Tucker developed Gay's theory ; Paley 
 reduced Tucker's to concise and manageable form ; Bentham, 
 in fancied (or, at any rate, professed) independence of them 
 both, and of Hume as well, tacitly neglected the theo- 
 logical 2 sanction — ^which, as we shall see later, he was not 
 
 ' See Pt. III., ch. xxxviii. (the concluding chapter of the work), § 3. 
 '^ The theological sanction is mentioned in all three of his slightly differing 
 lists of the sanctions, but does not play any part in his actual treatment.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 155 
 
 in a position logically to do — and also introduced certain 
 refinements into the ' hedonistic calculus '. But all this 
 development and modification was external ; the theory was 
 one and the same at the core. It remained so until there was 
 a general return to Hume's later position, that a certain de- 
 gree of original altruism must be conceded to human nature. 
 Not until then could ' the greatest happiness of the greatest 
 number ' be regarded as (in part, at least) the motive as well 
 as the objective ' end ' of all truly moral action. 
 
 We have now examined all the fundamental principles of 
 Tucker's ethical system, and have attempted to see them in 
 their proper relation to each other. We may therefore pass 
 on immediately to his treatment of the particular virtues. 
 Here he is for once comparatively brief, and we may prof- 
 itably follow his example, for we are only concerned with 
 his consistency or inconsistency in the handling of his own 
 first principles, and his success or failure in deducing from 
 these what we all recognise as the rules of concrete morality. 
 Tucker, whose undoubted originality never shows itself in 
 felicitous order of exposition, begins by adopting the con- 
 ventional list of four ' cardinal virtues ' — Prudence, Fortitude, 
 Temperance, ajid Justice — and by translating the distinctions 
 thus made into terms of his own system. It is natural that 
 he should regard Prudence as the chief virtue, and as practi- 
 cally comprehending the others, which, as he says, " relate 
 to the removing three certain obstacles in our nature most 
 apt to disturb and stop us in the exercise of prudence ".^ 
 ' Moral prudence,' which is here meant, should be distinguished 
 from ' physical prudence '. The latter depends upon sagacity, 
 experience, etc. ; the former, on the other hand, consists in 
 " making the best use of the lights we have ". In most 
 cases where moral action is concerned, it is easy enough to 
 see what should be done ; what we most need to cultivate 
 in ourselves is a disposition actually to follow our own best 
 judgment. 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxx., 45§ i et seq.
 
 156 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 As a matter of fact, Tucker does not succeed very well in 
 differentiating ' moral ' from ' physical ' prudence ; and his 
 general treatment of Fortitude (moral, rather than physical, 
 courage) and Temperance (self-control, in the most general 
 sense) contains little that is worthy of note. Incidentally, 
 however, when showing that by Fortitude he does not mean 
 mere physical courage, Tucker makes a remark which affords 
 an interesting commentary on his system. He says : " Now 
 we must acknowledge this insensibility a very useful quality 
 to the public, for without it, perhaps, we could not properly 
 man our fleets nor recruit our armies : yet is it so far from 
 deserving the name of virtue, that it seems scarce compatible 
 with the principal of them, I mean prudence, which grows out 
 of caution " } Two things must be noted with regard to 
 this interesting passage. First, it shows how completely 
 Tucker was committed to the view that virtue must make 
 not only for happiness, but for the happiness of the individual 
 moral agent. In fact, a possible conflict between public and 
 private interest is here suggested ; and the implication seems 
 to be that in such a case the latter must prevail, if we would 
 be truly virtuous ! But, secondly — what is quite as important 
 — the passage quoted suggests a theory which Tucker else- 
 where 2 sets forth regarding the teleology of moral appro- 
 bation, as actually bestowed. According to his view, we do 
 not by any means approve conduct in exact proportion to its 
 intrinsic Tightness — i.e., tendency to promote happiness. For 
 the conduct that is absolutely necessary, both for the in- 
 dividual and for society, largely takes care of itself — for 
 example, the mother may in all ordinary cases be depended 
 upon to care for her child. If she does this, we do not think 
 of approving her action ; but if she wholly neglects her child, 
 we are horrified. In a word, there is an economy of moral 
 approbation : we approve of actions necessary for the com- 
 mon good largely in proportion as this very approval is itself 
 necessary in order to get them done. Let us return to the 
 case of mere physical courage, which Tucker has said is not 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxxi., § i. ^ Ibid., xxxiv., § 6.
 
 Abraham Tticker. 157 
 
 a virtue ; but yet is apparently necessary for the public good. 
 It is easy to see what he would have to say of this, in order 
 to be consistent. We do not call physical courage (by itself) 
 a virtue, because we do not have to do so ; because the 
 supply is equal to the demand. But if, for any reason, the 
 supply should fall short, we might be driven into calling 
 brute courage even the chief of all the virtues — as our bar- 
 barous ancestors actually did.^ 
 
 The treatment of Justice is much more satisfactory than 
 that of the three other ' cardinal virtues '. This more or 
 less resembles Hume's account of the same matter, but there 
 is nothing to prove a real dependence of Tucker's work upon 
 Hume's. Indeed, as regards mere form, Tucker's treatment 
 resembles Cumberland's rather more closely than it does 
 Hume's ; though here, again, there is nothing to prove direct 
 imitation. As the arguments here given for the Utilitarian 
 origin of the notion of justice are wholly the now familiar 
 ones, we may pass over them somewhat rapidly. Men have 
 to depend for their very existence, not to say comfort, upon 
 certain products of the earth. These, however, cannot be 
 used in common without constant disputes arising ; and, 
 moreover, the natural products of the earth will not suffice, 
 unless improved by human labour, and no one will work un- 
 less he knows that he is going to receive the benefits himself. 
 Certain rules, implying a mutual recognition of rights, would 
 insensibly arise, and lay the foundation for the institution 
 of private property. The obligation of truth and fidelity 
 may readily be explained in the same way, for without these 
 human intercourse and co-operation would be impossible. 
 
 The above arguments for the Utilitarian origin of justice 
 and veracity seem to Tucker so obvious that he does not 
 dwell upon themu It must not be supposed, however, that 
 the author regards the notion of justice as something which 
 
 ^ There is doubtless a limited amount of grim truth in Tucker's view ; but I 
 do not think that what must be conceded on this point will be found to make 
 for any great degree of relativity in our moral judgments, or for Utilitarianism, 
 as against other systems.
 
 158 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 has to be developed anew in the experience of each in- 
 dividual. Our particular notions regarding what is just, are 
 almost always learned, or adopted, from the community in 
 which we live, so that the explanation given above refers 
 only to the ultimate origin of the notion under consideration. 
 But precisely because we do, to so large an extent} take our 
 ideas of justice on trust, our obligation to practice this virtue 
 appears to be the ultimate thing which common sense regards 
 it ; hence justice and ' interest ' are popularly contrasted. 
 But if we could see to the end, and know our true interest, 
 we should need no other guide. As it is, we have need 
 enough of the restraints of justice, and should never allow 
 ourselves to act against the general principles which men, on 
 the basis of an unconscious induction from experience, have 
 agreed in calling ' just '. 
 
 It is interesting to note that Tucker holds what we would 
 now agree in regarding as the consistent Utilitarian theory 
 of punishment. Indeed, he seems to believe, not only that 
 punishment should be applied according to Utilitarian prin- 
 ciples, but that it actually is so applied, at least in the great 
 majority of cases. To quote his own e.xpression : " The 
 law carries always a prospect forwards ".^ The logically 
 primary form of punishment, according to his view, is the 
 payment of damages for the injury done, whatever that may 
 be. But since, in many instances, reparation is impossible 
 from the nature of the case, punishment would naturally be 
 inflicted in order to prevent the repetition of the offence ; 
 and this (logically) derived form of punishment may be re- 
 garded as normal in the complicated relations of civilised 
 society. It follows, of course, from this point of view, that 
 punishment should not be more severe than the given case 
 requires, for that would mean so much gratuitous suffering 
 in the world ; but Tucker does not mention the reformation 
 of the criminal as an end to be held in view by the legislator 
 or judge. While he fails to recognise the hold which the 
 notion of ' retributive justice ' still retains even in the common 
 
 ' See Pt. I., ch. xxxiii., S5 5.
 
 Abraham Tucker. 159 
 
 law, he has a ready explanation for this notion, which he 
 regards as a manifest perversion of true, i.e.. Utilitarian, 
 justice. If we regard the law as a personality, as is some- 
 times done for convenience, we may bring the idea of punish- 
 ment under the idea of reparation, not to the party injured, 
 but to the law itself. But here the principle of ' translation ' 
 comes in : we forget that we are merely employing a figure 
 of speech, when we speak of injury as being done to the 
 law itself, and regard this as a statement of the actual fact. 
 The obviously Utilitarian links in the chain of association 
 drop out of consciousness, and we come to regard the relation 
 between the infringement of law and punishment as logically 
 necessary, and not merely as extremely desirable, provided 
 that the pimishment inflicted be just and humane. 
 
 So far, the author believes he has shown that the general 
 rules of justice are founded upon utility, and upon that alone ; 
 and here, as always, he holds that the interested individual is 
 not a good judge as to the desirability of an infringement of 
 a general rule. But suppose it could be shown, in some par- 
 ticular case, that unjust conduct was certainly for the general 
 advantage ? Then we should have to consider the undoubted 
 mischief of a bad example. But suppose, further, that the 
 act in question could be concealed from all the world t Still 
 we should have to take into account the bad influence upon 
 the agent's own character. The result, then, is merely to 
 bring out what Tucker consistently holds throughout his 
 treatise, that moral actions must, on strictly Utilitarian prin- 
 ciples, be according to general rules, and not according to 
 any attempted computation in the particular case. 
 
 When the author comes to treat of Benevolence, he is 
 somewhat hampered by the fact that this virtue is not really 
 provided for by the old Greek scheme of the virtues which he 
 had happened to adopt. He tries to show that, strictly speak- 
 ing, benevolence would come under justice, since we must 
 put under the latter head " whatever we do for the benefit 
 or pleasure of others without [immediate] regard to our own ". 
 At the same time, he practically breaks loose from his classifi-
 
 i6o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 cation, and treats benevolence as a fifth ' cardinal ' virtue. 
 Indeed, he later suggests that benevolence may ultimately 
 be regarded as the root, and justice as the branch, although 
 it will be remembered that his actual treatment of justice 
 would not seem to corroborate this view. Of course, Tucker 
 does not here mean that benevolence itself is ' original,' 
 though he holds with Gay that, at the moment of action, one 
 must forget that one is determined by motives of self-interest. 
 The explanation is evidently to be found in the all-cogent 
 principle of ' translation '. What was previously said re- 
 garding the author's derivation of ' sympathy ' and ' love,' 
 will apply here, at least sufficiently for the present purpose. 
 In this connection. Tucker again refers to his theory of moral 
 approbation. He says : " As commendation and a return of 
 good offices tend to encourage benevolence, therefore it de- 
 serves them : for we have seen in a former place, that honour 
 and reward belong properly to where they will do most 
 service. But the reward must not constantly follow too close 
 upon the action, for then it will be apt to catch the eye, and 
 become the end expected at every performance, which will 
 render it selfish." ^ 
 
 Tucker naturally has much to say in praise of benevolence, 
 but his treatment of this virtue after all rather tends to bring 
 out the egoistic elements in his system. It is needless to go 
 into details here, particularly as we have already discussed, 
 somewhat at length, the author's view regarding the motive 
 of the moral agent. It may be noted that — while he care- 
 lessly allows himself to say that, if benevolence were universal, 
 it would bring back the Golden Age — he is, nevertheless, 
 quite inclined to question the sentimental view that all would 
 be happy, if everyone were only good. In one characteristic 
 passage, he says .- " Were all our artisans and professors to 
 barter their knowledge and dexterity for a proportionable 
 degree of virtue, the world would suffer greatly by the ex- 
 change : we should all be ready, indeed, to help one another, 
 
 ' See Pt. 1., ch. xxxiv., § 6.
 
 Abraham Tucker. i6i 
 
 but could do no good for want of knowing how to go about 
 it ".1 
 
 We have already somewhat carefully compared Gay's out- 
 line of an ethical system, as given in the Dissertation, with 
 Cumberland's extended treatment of Ethics in his De legibus 
 naturae. We noticed in the Dissertation an unmistakable 
 departmre from the position of Cumberland in various im- 
 portant respects. It is needless to recapitulate here. What 
 is important to observe in the present connection, is the fact 
 that Tucker follows Gay as against Cumberland in every 
 case where we have had occasion to notice an important 
 difference in theory between those two authors. On the 
 other hand, it is hardly necessary for our present purpose 
 to compare Tucker's ethical theory at all minutely either with 
 that of Hartley or with that of Hume. One thing, however, 
 should always be remembered. We have seen that the 
 earlier form of (completely differentiated) Utilitarianism is 
 mainly distinguished from the later form by its different 
 treatment of the motive of the moral agent. It is interesting 
 to compare Gay, Hume, Hartley, and Tucker, in this very 
 important respect. Gay, of course, was the first to explain 
 apparent altruism as a development from egoism, by means 
 of the ' association of ideas ' and the further process which 
 Tucker afterward called ' translation '. According to his 
 view, we begin and end as egoists, though not in the sense 
 of Hobbes. Hume, in apparent independence of Gay, 
 developed in succession two quite different views of human 
 nature, as regards the origin of ' sympathy '. In the Treatise 
 he explains ' sympathy ' by the ' association of ideas,' and, 
 though his method of explanation is somewhat different from 
 that of Gay, the result at which he arrives is much the same, 
 for it amounts to treating egoism as the original, ineradicable 
 tendency of human nature, and apparent altruism as little 
 more than a development from egoism. But in the Inquiry 
 he entirely gives up any such attempt to reduce the one 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. xxxv., § 8, 
 II
 
 1 62 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 principle to terms of the other. Egoism and altruism are 
 there regarded as co-ordinate tendencies of human nature ; 
 not, apparently, in the sense that they are absolutely distinct 
 from each other, but rather in the sense that they are parallel 
 differentiations of something in our nature more aboriginal 
 than either. In taking up this later position, he anticipated 
 what we may call the later, as opposed to the earlier, Utili- 
 tarianism. 
 
 We have seen that Hartley interpreted the results of 
 ' association ' and ' translation ' quite differently from his suc- 
 cessors. For in his view it is possible to forget oneself more 
 and more until one finally loses oneself in love for one's 
 fellow men. still more in love for God ; and in a similar way, 
 while our ' higher ' pleasures are regarded by him as de- 
 veloped from our ' lower ' ones, by increasingly elaborate 
 combinations at each step, he is unlike the others in re- 
 garding the ' higher ' pleasures as differing from the ' lower ' 
 ones, not only in degree, but in kind. All this, of 
 course, would make Hartley difficult to classify, according 
 to the principle which we have adopted, if we should 
 regard his conclusions as the logical result of his own 
 first principles and of the method which he employs. 
 But this we can by no means do. In short, we find in 
 Hartley what we often find in pioneers of any new tendency 
 of philosophical thought, a writer who hardly appreciates 
 the full significance of the principles with which he deals. 
 Tucker, on the other hand, represents the return to Gay, 
 which was to characterise all the writers standing for what 
 we here call the earlier form of Utilitarianism. According to 
 this view, there are no qualitative distinctions between pleas- 
 ures, and altruism is merely a more highly developed {i.e., 
 a more many-sided) egoism. 
 
 But if we must say that Tucker only filled in the outline 
 of ethical theory which Gay ^ had already supplied — and this, 
 
 ^ Tucker's direct dependence upon Gay could hardly be proved. It should 
 be remembered that he published thirty-seven years later.
 
 Abraham Tucke7'. 163 
 
 curiously, without giving credit for it, as we should have 
 expected — ^we are making a statement which, though true, 
 is by itself seriously misleading. If it be thought that little 
 skill or originality was required to follow out the line of 
 argument which the author of the Dissertation had sug- 
 gested, one has only to examine Hartley's well-known work 
 to be convinced of the contrary ; for though the Observa- 
 tions 071 Man is so largely a failure, from the point of view 
 both of psychological and of ethical theory, we have no right 
 to assume that the author was altogether a mediocre man. 
 In fact, it probably takes quite as much originality consist- 
 ently to develop a theory on the basis of a few suggestions, 
 as to provide the original scheme itself. The path was really 
 untried to a very large extent even after Hartley had done 
 his imperfect work. 
 
 Tucker is a writer whose actual ability and discrimination 
 we are apt greatly to underrate. His faults are almost fatally 
 calculated to obscure his merits. Not only was he recklessly 
 diffuse, but he was so utterly lacking in metaphysical talent 
 and training that the considerable part of his treatise which 
 he devotes to theological discussions is practically valueless. 
 But his skill and originality in the treatment of psychological 
 and ethical problems is in the most striking contrast to his 
 weakness as a theologian. Many passages in the Light of 
 Nature, which are likely to impress one as being rather 
 commonplace, are actually the first tolerably satisfactory 
 treatment of the topics in question from the Associationist 
 point of view ; so that, if Tucker was careless in not giving 
 credit to others, he is probably himself to be regarded as 
 ' more sinned against than sinning '. Indeed, the defects in 
 his treatment of psychological and ethical problems will quite 
 commonly be found to be defects inherent in the Associa- 
 tionist theory itself, and not due to any individual weakness 
 or superficiality on his part. Moreover, while his far too 
 bulky treatise will doubtless continue unread by the general 
 student, it is to this that one must look for the first full state- 
 ment of the theory which Paley practically adopted entire,
 
 164 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 and made almost universally popular in his own generation 
 by his singular felicity as an expositor ; which Bentham and 
 his followers, on the other hand, chose to disregard, though 
 their own ethical theory is reducible to substantially the same 
 principles.
 
 CHAPTER IX. 
 
 WILLIAM PALEY AND JEREMY BENTHAM. 
 
 It is customary to regard Bentham as the typical exponent 
 of Utilitarianism in its earlier form, while Paley, though 
 frequently given more credit than he deserves on the score 
 of originality, is generally classed as a ' theological ' moralist, 
 and therefore put on quite a different plane. For reasons 
 which will appear in the course of this chapter, the present 
 writer is obliged partly to dissent from this traditional esti- 
 mate of the two authors — and, in particular, from the opinion 
 that Bentham contributed anything essentially new to ethical 
 theory. Whether or not these reasons are sufficient, the reader 
 must, of course, decide for himself. But, in any case, it will 
 certainly be well for him to abstract as far as possible from 
 the populcir verdict regarding the theologian and the legis- 
 lative reformer, in order that he may be able to form an in- 
 dependent judgment as to the true position of each in the 
 history of English Ethics. The two are as different as 
 possible from each other in their attitude toward their pre- 
 decessors. In a well-known passage in the preface to his 
 only ethical work, Paley expresses with perfect frankness 
 his very great indebtedness to Tucker. ^ Bentham, on the 
 
 ^ " There is, however, one work to which I owe so much, that it would be 
 ungrateful not to confess the obligation : I mean the writings of the late 
 Abraham Tucker, Esq. ... I have found in this writer more original thinking 
 and observation upon the several subjects that he has taken in hand, than in any 
 other, not to say, than in all others put together. His talent also for illustration 
 is unrivalled. But his thoughts are diffused through a long, various, and irregular 
 work. I shall account it no mean praise, if I have been sometimes able to dis- 
 
 (165)
 
 1 66 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 other hand, always writes as if he were the first propound er 
 of the Utilitarian principle. Indeed, in a conversation re- 
 corded by his disciple Bowring, he is made to speak as if his 
 only indebtedness to others consisted in the fact that he had 
 been deeply impressed by Dr. Priestley's incidental use of 
 the expression, ' the greatest happiness of the greatest num- 
 ber,' in his Treatise on Government (1768).^ 
 
 The use which Paley made of the works of previous writers 
 can, for the most part, be easily determined, and may be 
 described sufficiently for our present purpose in a few words. 
 He reduced the unwieldy bulk of Tucker's hopelessly diffuse 
 Light of Nature to clear, definite, and — to his contemporaries 
 — convincing form. And, as we have just seen, he makes no 
 secret of his obligations to Tucker. By what seems a curious 
 fatality, however, he failed to mention Gay, exactly as 
 Tucker had done, though he, at any rate, evidently had the 
 Preliminary Dissertation constantly in mind. In fact, of 
 all the writers whom we have thus far considered. Hartley 
 is the only one, except the Rev. John Brown, who admits 
 definitely his obligations to Gay. But Paley's silence regard- 
 ing the Dissertation can hardly be interpreted as indicating 
 disingenuousness on his part, for his order of exposition, 
 totally different from that of Tucker — if, indeed. Tucker can 
 be said to have followed any definite order at all — is obviously 
 an adaptation of Gay's, and he sometimes reproduces passages 
 from the Dissertation almost word for word. Moreover, 
 as the Dissertation was always published as introductory 
 to the translation of King's Origin of Evil by Paley's own 
 patron, Bishop Law, his acquaintance with the book could 
 not possibly have been denied, and seems to have been tacitly 
 admitted. 
 
 On the other hand, it would be difficult, if not impossible, 
 to determine exactly Bentham's indebtedness to previous 
 
 pose into method, to collect into heads and articles, or to exhibit in more 
 compact and tangible masses, what, in that otherwise excellent performance, is 
 spread over too much surface." — See Moral and Political Philosophy, p. xix. 
 (i8i5 ed.). ' See Deontology, vol. I. (appendix), p. 300.
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Bentham. 167 
 
 ethical writers. Like the school which he inaugurated, he 
 was singularly lacking in the historical spirit. Many of his 
 references to non-Utilitarian systems seem to imply an almost 
 startling ignorance of their true character, while he never for 
 a moment appears to admit, in his published works, that 
 others besides himself had stated the Utilitarian principle. 
 One is willing to believe that he was as nearly unacquainted 
 with the previous development of English Ethics as it was 
 possible for an intelligent writer on kindred subjects to be ; 
 but Utilitarianism had been so distinctly in the air for more 
 than a generation before he published h\s P rinciples of Morals 
 and Legislation that he could not possibly have failed very 
 substantially to profit by the fact. 
 
 Probably Bentham and his immediate followers alike be- 
 lieved that he was making an entirely new departure in his 
 attempt to treat Ethics without reference to theological con- 
 siderations.^ Indeed, this seems to have been the verdict 
 of most writers on English Ethics. It would be anticipating 
 to discuss the question of Bentham's originality at length 
 here, but it will be remembered that both Gay and Tucker 
 had avoided the theological reference, except where their 
 systems logically required it. For example, Gay had held 
 that complete obligation can come only from God, " because 
 God only can in all cases make a man happy or miserable ".- 
 Bentham found himself face to face with the same difficulty in 
 working out the Utilitarian doctrine. Perfect obligation to 
 follow the fundamental principles of morality was tacitly con- 
 ceded by him, as it is by practically all morahsts ; and obliga- 
 tion for Bentham, as for Gay, Tucker, and Paley, could mean 
 only that it must ultimately be for the agent's own interest 
 to be virtuous. The main difference, then, between his pro- 
 cedure and theirs, lies in the fact that he practically shirked 
 the difficulty that the ' sanctions ' are not sufficient in this 
 present life, and implied, rather than directly argued, that if 
 
 * The 'theological sanction' appears in Bentham's list, but he practically 
 neglects it in his treatment of Ethics. 
 ^ See Dissertation, % ii.
 
 1 68 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 it is not for the individual's interest to be virtuous, as things 
 are now, it ought to be made so, and this by the very improve- 
 ments in legislation in which he was primarily interested. 
 But clearly his position as a reformer does not help him to 
 escape the very grave difficulty which besets every Utilitarian 
 system that assumes the selfish motive of the agent in moral 
 action. It therefore seems to the present writer that Ben- 
 tham's non-theological treatment of Ethics merely indicates 
 his individual attitude, and does not, in itself, represent an 
 advance in ethical theory. ^ 
 
 Paley's direct treatment of Ethics is contained in his well- 
 known Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy, pub- 
 lished in 1785. This book is fatally easy to caricature, and 
 certainly it is not based upon the loftiest conception of human 
 nature ; but one must lay aside one's prejudices, as far as 
 possible, if only to understand the significant fact that it 
 was immediately adopted as a text-book in Cambridge Uni- 
 versity, and that it held undisputed sway there for a very 
 considerable time. And it must not be supposed that Cam- 
 bridge University was peculiar in its attitude toward the 
 question as to the foundation of morality. It merely 
 happened to represent, more exactly than Oxford, the pre- 
 vailing tendency of the time and country. Moreover, Paley's 
 treatise is by no means as disagreeable in tone as one might 
 be led to expect from the classic passages which are so sure 
 to be quoted by adverse critics. The author wrote with 
 great clearness and force, as well as with much good sense 
 and unruffled good temper. Indeed, his tone throughout 
 the Principles is really admirable, as compared with that 
 of Bentham in his corresponding works. 
 
 Paley's aim, like that of most writers on Ethics in his own 
 
 ' Of course, the mere fact that he treated the Utilitarian doctrine from the 
 non-theological point of view, was an important influence in the direction of 
 completely secularising the doctrine ; but he nowhere shows how one can 
 dispense with the theological sanction in a system of Ethics where the motive 
 of the agent is assumed to be necessarily egoistic. This, in fact, is impossible, 
 if the notion of complete obligation is to be retained.
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Benthavi. 169 
 
 time, was eminently practical. Ethics was of importance for 
 him, not primarily as a philosophical discipline, but as a help 
 toward right conduct. His treatment, therefore, is concrete 
 from the very beginning. After showing the insufficiency of 
 such codes as the ' Law of Honour ' and the ' Law of the 
 Land,' he raises the question : Do we find in the Scriptures 
 a complete rule of life 1 His answer, it will be remembered, 
 is, that the Scriptures were designed, not so much to bring 
 to our notice new rules of morality, as to enforce by sufficient 
 sanctions those already evident through natural reason. 
 This, of course, is characteristic, though not of the best 
 side of Paley's system. One is disappointed that he does 
 not call attention to the fact — important, if somewhat obvious 
 — that the Scriptures do not, of themselves, commit us to any 
 particular type of ethical theory. 
 
 Upon what, then, are we to depend, in directing our con- 
 duct in the complex relations of ordinary life '^. Paley will 
 not listen to the ' Moral Sense ' philosophers, whose char- 
 acteristic position he regards, not only as theoretically un- 
 sound, but as practically objectionable. His arguments 
 against the existence of a ' moral sense ' are what had already 
 become the familiar ones. In the main, he merely reproduces 
 what Gay and Tucker had said more clearly, because more 
 at length ; but he does justice to the importance of the almost 
 universal tendency to imitate which, in the case of young 
 children, he is inclined to call an ' instinct '. This neither 
 of the others can really be said to have done. But, apart from 
 its theoretical unsoundness, Paley regards the ' Moral Sense ' 
 doctrine as pernicious in its tendency, because it leads to 
 arbitrariness in moral judgments. " Nothing is so soon 
 made as a maxim." ^ It is evident that he would have 
 objected equally to the position, that all we have to do is to 
 * follow conscience ' ; for he insists that what we really need 
 is some objective standard in Ethics, and that this can be 
 found only when we come to consider carefully the conse- 
 
 * See Bk. I., ch. v., p. 14 (1816 ed.).
 
 I 70 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 quences of our different classes of actions. For Paley, as 
 for nearly all writers on Ethics, the consequences of actions 
 are equivalent to their results expressed in hedonistic terms. ^ 
 And he is perfectly explicit in his use of the word ' happiness '. 
 For him, as for both Gay and Tucker, happiness is merely a 
 ' sum of pleasures ' ; and he also follows Tucker almost 
 verbally in his denial of qualitative differences between plea- 
 sures and pains.2 Like Tucker, again, he emphasises the 
 much greater importance of the so-called * higher ' pleasures, 
 and holds that the greatest permanent satisfaction is to be 
 found in the exercise of the ' social affections '. 
 
 The Good, then, is ' happiness,' in the sense of a ' sum of 
 pleasures,' or the decided preponderance of pleasures over 
 pains in a sufficiently long succession of human experiences. 
 Hence, in defining Virtue as " the doing good to mankind, 
 in obedience to the will of God, and for the sake of everlast- 
 ing happiness," ^ the author states in epitome all that is 
 absolutely essential to his system. His familiar and rather 
 unsavoury treatment of Obligation, as the being " urged by 
 a violent motive resulting from the command of another " *— 
 which, of course, is implied in the definition of virtue, just 
 quoted — -will be found, upon examination, to be an almost 
 literal reproduction of the corresponding passage in Gay's 
 Dissertation. Indeed, in this case, he certainly has not 
 improved upon the author whom he has imitated. 
 
 The only difference between ' prudence ' and ' duty,' ac- 
 cording to this theory of obligation, is that in the one case 
 we consider what we shall gain or lose in the present world, 
 
 ' It is rather curious that non-hedonistic writers should so general!)- look 
 askance at all theoretical discussion regarding the good and bad consequences 
 of actions, as if to admit the importance of consequences were to play into the 
 hands of Hedonism. These consequences, of course, may be important to any 
 degree whatever ; only they may be explained as good or bad, not merely in 
 terms of Hedonism, but in terms of any other recognised form of ethical theory, 
 with the single exception, perhaps, of Intuitionism — and this would be an ex- 
 ception only when held in its naive form. 
 
 '•* See Bk. I., ch. vi., p. 17. 
 
 "Ibid., vii., p. 32. ■* See Bk. H., ch. ii., p. 44.
 
 William Paley and Je^^etny Be^ttham. 1 7 i 
 
 while in the other case we consider also, and particularly, 
 what we shall gain or lose in the world to come.^ We have 
 seen that Gay and Tucker, starting with the same view that 
 human nature is essentially egoistic — mitigated, of course, 
 by the use of the principle of ' translation ' — had found it 
 impossible to vindicate objectively altruistic conduct without 
 taking the future life into consideration. Paley frankly rests 
 his whole system upon the theological doctrine of rewards 
 and punishments after death. What had been kept more 
 or less in the background by the other two writers, becomes 
 in his case most unpleasantly explicit. But while one is 
 sure to be repelled by this side of Paley's system, one must 
 be very careful not to confound the egoism of Paley with 
 the egoism of Hobbes. According to Hobbes, men are 
 essentially anti-social beings : in their * natural ' state, they 
 desire only the gratification of their passions and the sub- 
 jugation of their fellows. Paley, on the other hand, em- 
 phasises the fact, already made prominent by Tucker, that we 
 find our most lasting satisfaction precisely in the exercise 
 of the ' social affections '.- Indeed, if one read between the 
 lines in a work like Paley's, one cannot help seeing how 
 obscure, upon examination, the apparently evident distinction 
 between theoretical egoism and theoretical altruism becomes 
 — always supposing, of course, that man is regarded as origin- 
 ally a social being.^ 
 
 The author's transition from his general definition of virtue 
 to his method of arriving at the rules of concrete morality, 
 is closely imitated from Gay.* It is hardly necessary to 
 trace the successive steps, as they are so generally familiar. 
 The rules of action must, according to the formula adopted, 
 result from the will of God. But what is the will of God ? 
 From the very conception of God as a being of infinite 
 
 ' See Bk. II., ch. iii., p. 47. -See Bk. I., ch. vi., p. 25. 
 
 ■" The egoism of Paley's system becomes offensive only by reason of his 
 constant reference to the theological sanction, as making it for the agent's 
 selfish interest to be moral. Tucker was much more careful in this respect. 
 
 * See Bk. II., chs. iv., v., and vi.
 
 172 Hist 07'}' of U till tai^iani sin. 
 
 goodness, it follows that He must desire the happiness of 
 men ; and what we should thus a priori deduce from the 
 necessary character of God, is borne out by the numberless 
 beneficent contrivances in which nature abounds. The ob- 
 vious conclusion is, that the method of learning the will of 
 God concerning any action, by the ' light of nature,' is to 
 inquire into the general tendency of such actions to promote 
 or diminish the common happiness. Paley takes no pains 
 to use language that might be expected to conciliate his 
 opponents. He says .- " Whatever is expedient is right. 
 It is the utility of any moral rule alone which constitutes 
 the obligation of it." ^ 
 
 Paley shows his good judgment in following Gay and 
 Tucker with regard to the necessity of acting according to 
 general rules,^ instead of attempting to show that we may, 
 at least roughly, compute the consequences in each particular 
 case. He does not, to be sure, treat the matter at length 
 and adequately, as Tucker had done ; but he puts it even 
 more concretely when he says, e.g. : " The particular conse- 
 quence of coining [counterfeiting] is, the loss of a guinea, or 
 of half a guinea, to the person who receives the counterfeit 
 money : the general consequence (by which I mean the 
 consequence that would ensue, if the same practice were gener- 
 ally permitted) is, to abolish the use of money ".-^ In this con- 
 nection, he is able to show that the principle of ' doing evil 
 that good may come ' is as obviously fallacious according to 
 Utilitarianism as according to non-Utilitarian systems. 
 
 It is needless, for our present purpose, to follow Paley 
 through his somewhat artificial classification of duties and 
 his deduction of the particular virtues.'* Some of his de- 
 ductions are rather more satisfactory than those of Tucker ; 
 
 ' See Bk. II., ch. vi., p. 53. 
 
 "Ibid., chs. vii. and viii. "'Ibid., ch. viii., p. 60. 
 
 ^ Paley recognises three classes of 'relative' duties (i.e., duties to others): 
 (i) 'determinate' (e.g., property, promises, etc.); (2) 'indeterminate' (e.g., 
 charity, resentment, anger, etc.); and (3) those 'which result from the consti- 
 tution of the sexes'. Besides these, he considers: (4) duties to ourselves (e.g., 
 self-defence) ; and (5) duties toward God (e.g., worship).
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Bent ham. 173 
 
 but this is merely on account of his greater skill as an ex- 
 positor. On the whole, they are less adequate than those of 
 his predecessor. For the most part, he keeps clear of theories 
 which are incongruous with his own fundamental principle 
 of utility. But in one case, at least, he allows himself to 
 base his treatment upon the conception of ' natural rights ' 
 in a way that Tucker, apparently, had always carefully 
 avoided doing. When treating of the duty of charity, he 
 says : " All things were originally common. No one being 
 able to produce a charter from Heaven, had any better title 
 to a particular possession than his next neighbour. There 
 were reasons for mankind's agreeing upon a separation of 
 this common fund ; and God for these reasons is presumed 
 to have ratified it But this separation was made and con- 
 sented to, upon the expectation and condition that every 
 one should have left a sufficiency for his subsistence, or the 
 means of procuring it : and as no fixed laws for the regula- 
 tion of property can be so contrived, as to provide for the 
 relief of every case and distress which may arise, these cases 
 and distresses . . . were supposed to be left to the voluntary 
 bounty of those who might be acquainted with the exigencies 
 of their situation, and in the way of affording assistance." ^ 
 
 This would seem to imply an actual original compact, the 
 idea of which is expressly repudiated by Paley himself in 
 the latter part of his book. Examples like this are interest- 
 ing, as showing what a strong hold the related notions of 
 ' natural rights ' and ' natural laws ' still had at the time that 
 we are considering, even upon an author like Paley. It 
 should be admitted, however, that such inconsistencies mean 
 less in Paley's case than they would in that of the average 
 ethical writer, for his interests were almost wholly practical, 
 and, where it was possible, he seems purposely to have 
 avoided all controversy with regard to current and generally 
 accepted theories, as being beside his purpose. 
 
 Brief as our review of Paley's system has been, it has 
 probably shown that the author was essentially a great ex- 
 
 1 See Bk. III., Pt. II., ch. v., p. 179.
 
 174 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 positor, and not the originator of anything really new in 
 ethical theory. There was, of course, the greatest difference 
 between the originality which Tucker displayed in working 
 out a fairly coherent ethical system upon the basis of the 
 outline suggested in Gay's Dissertation, and that which 
 enabled Paley to make almost universally popular for the 
 time what had been thus completely developed. At the 
 same time, here, as so frequently in the history of thought, 
 the clearest exponent of the principle in question receives 
 the popular credit, at the expense of those who had actually 
 originated the principle and worked it out. 
 
 We have confined ourselves entirely to an examination of 
 Paley's ethical treatise, and it is not at all necessary, for our 
 present purpose, that we should consider his other works, 
 which are not only very well known, but not in the least 
 calculated to modify one's impression of his system. But, 
 before leaving the author of the Moral and Political Phil- 
 osophy, it may be well to recall what manner of man he was. 
 Paley may have been rather too liberal in some of his views, 
 particularly on political subjects, to obtain the preferment 
 in the Church to which his very considerable talents seem to 
 have entitled him ; but, on the whole, he was a man pre- 
 eminently in touch with his time, for better and for worse. 
 He seems to have been free from strong feeling of any sort. 
 If one has to regret the lack of spirituality in his writings, 
 one must at least give him credit for abstaining from violent 
 polemics, and for writing in a straightforward and manly 
 way. Moreover, he made no extreme claims to originality. 
 It is true that he desired to be thought " something more than 
 a mere compiler," as he certainly was ; but even when he did 
 not explicitly acknowledge his indebtedness to others, he took 
 no pains to conceal it. He was not at all the type of man 
 who wastes energy in pushing personal claims of priority. 
 
 When we turn to Benthara, we soon find that we have to 
 do with a very different personality. Though brought up a 
 Tory, he was by temperament ' of the opposition ' — in all
 
 William Paley and feremy Bentham. i 7 5 
 
 respects a Radical. He generall}' writes clearly, and not 
 without force ; but he constantly loses his temper, and even 
 goes out of his way to vilify those whom he opposes by 
 imputing to them interested motives.^ The result is that, 
 however much the reader may happen to sympathise with the 
 general tenor of his thought, he is almost sure to find his 
 works irritating in style and method. Yet it was this very 
 fervour of the reformer that commended Bentham so strongly 
 to certain young men of radical tendencies in his own day. 
 While Paley 's Moral and Political Philosophy met with extraor- 
 dinary success as a text-book, the author could not properly 
 be said to have founded a ' school '. His work rather made 
 explicit what had long been implicit in the ethical teaching 
 of his own University. Bentham, on the other hand, was 
 regarded, both by himself and by his immediate followers, 
 as the inaugurator of a perfectly new regime. The statement 
 of Whewell, that " The school of Bentham, for a time, 
 afforded as near a resemblance as modern times can show, 
 of the ancient schools of Philosophy, which were formed and 
 held together by an almost unbounded veneration for their 
 master, and in which the disciples were content to place their 
 glory in understanding and extending the master's prin- 
 ciples," 2 is doubtless an exaggeration, but hardly so mis- 
 leading as Mill would have us believe.^ 
 
 In considering Bentham's ethical system, it is important to 
 decide, once for all, what works we should be prepared to 
 recognise as authoritatively representing his doctrine. Three 
 only need come under consideration : his Fragment on 
 Government (1776), his Principles of Morals and Legislation 
 (printed in 1780, but not published till 1789), and his pos- 
 thumous work, Deontology (edited by his literary executor, 
 Bowring, and published in 1834V Of these, the Fragment 
 
 ^ See, e.g.. Principles of Morals and Legislation, ch. i., S xiii., note. 
 
 - See Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy in England, Lect. xiii. 
 
 ■^ See Autobiography , p. loi. 
 
 * A useful epitome of his ethical doctrine will be found in the Principles of 
 Legislation prefixed to the Theory of Legislation, first published bj- Dumont in 
 France.
 
 176 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 on Government, which deals only very incidentally with 
 ethical problems, is of importance for us only as indicating 
 the author's attitude at the time when it was published. It 
 is sufficient to note that, as early as 1776, he had adopted 
 the general position with which his name later became identi- 
 fied, and also that the tendency toward violent polemics, 
 which later became so disagreeable a feature of his workf, 
 was already clearly apparent. The Principles of Morals and 
 Legislation is by far the best known of the three works 
 mentioned, and it is upon this that expositions of Bentham's 
 ethical system are commonly based. But, while one can 
 clearly enough gather the author's general views on Ethics 
 from the first few chapters of this book, one should always 
 remember that it is primarily of Jurisprudence, and not of 
 theoretical Ethics, that Bentham is here treating. In the 
 case of a writer representing a really new principle in Ethics, 
 or one more difficult to expound in comparatively summary 
 fashion, this might lead to serious confusion, seeing that the 
 relation between Ethics and Jurisprudence must itself be 
 regarded as a vexed question. ^ 
 
 The Deontology, then, is the only work which Bentham 
 wrote on Ethics proper. But here we are confronted with 
 a difficulty quite as serious as that just noted in the case of 
 his Principles of Morals and Legislation ; for the Deontology, 
 which was a posthumous publication, was not merely ' edited,' 
 in the ordinary sense, but (in part, at least) arranged from 
 Bentham's papers by his enthusiastic friend and admirer, 
 John Bowring, whom he had made his literary executor.^ 
 The general impression seems to be, that Bowring took un- 
 
 1 For Bentham's distinction between the two, see Deontology, vol. I., ch. ii., 
 p. 27. He says, in substance: "Where legal rewards and punishments cease 
 to interfere with human actions, there precepts of morality come in with their 
 influences. ... In a word, Deontology, or Private Ethics, may be considered 
 the science by which happiness is created out of motives extra-legislational — 
 while Jurisprudence is the science by which law is applied to the production of 
 felicity." 
 
 ^ It appeared in 1834, two years after Bentham's death, and, so far as I am 
 aware, only one edition was printed.
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Bent ham. 177 
 
 warranted liberties with the manuscripts, many of which had 
 been handed over to him during- Bentham's lifetime. But, 
 while it would be rash to assert the contrary, I am not aware 
 that any conclusive evidence to this effect has ever been 
 produced. 1 Indeed, most of the blemishes which are found 
 in the book, and which would make one willing to believe 
 that it had been changed here and there by another hand, 
 can be almost exactly duplicated from those of Bentham's 
 works which were published during his lifetime, and about 
 whose authenticity there has never been the shadow of a 
 doubt. Moreover, the style in many of the more important 
 passages, including some of the most disagreeable, is un- 
 mistakably Bentham's. It should be further noted that, 
 although there are two volumes of the Deontology — (i) 
 " Theory of Virtue " and (2) " Practice of Virtue " — the first 
 volume alone is of theoretical importance ; and it is mainly 
 with regard to the second volume, as it seems to the present 
 writer, that the question of authenticity arises.^ 
 
 If the Deontology represented any material departure in 
 theory, or even in treatment, from the Principles of Morals 
 and Legislation, this question of authenticity would become 
 one of capital importance. This, however, is not the case ; 
 and, as the expositions in this book are by far the most 
 complete treatment of ethical problems to be found in Ben- 
 tham's works, it cannot properly be neglected. In fact, it 
 will be largely followed in the present exposition, because the 
 book is out of print and very rare, while an excellent reprint 
 of the Principles of Morals and Legislation is readily obtain- 
 able. At the same time, no distinctive opinion will here be 
 attributed to Bentham, for which warrant is not to be found 
 in his other works, and parallel references will be given in 
 all cases of importance. 
 
 ^ It is probable that J. S. Mill was largely responsible for this general opinion. 
 
 ^ The difference in style between the first volume and much of the second 
 volume is unmistakable. If Bowring was responsible for the literary form of 
 the second volume, as seems probable, since the style often resembles that 
 which he ordinarily uses, it is difficult to believe that he tampered much with 
 the first volume, which certainly reads like Bentham from beginning to end. 
 
 12
 
 178 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Gay had remarked, at the beginning of the Dissertation, 
 that the theoretical differences between morahsts were less 
 than might appear. Indeed, he suspects " that they only 
 talk a different language, and that all of them have the 
 same criterion in reality, only they have expressed it in 
 different words ". The suggestion doubtless is, that we must 
 look for latent Utilitarianism in non-Utilitarian systems. 
 Paley — apparently following the Dissertation — expresses 
 himself in a similar way, but is more explicit. He says : 
 " ' The fitness of things,' means their fitness to produce happi- 
 ness ; ' the nature of things,' means that actual constitution 
 of the world, by which some things, as such and such actions, 
 jFor example, produce happiness, and others misery ; ' reason ' 
 is the principle by which we discover or judge of this con- 
 stitution ; * truth ' is this judgment expressed or drawn out 
 into propositions ". And, again, Paley follows Gay in the 
 doubtful thesis that " This is the reason that moralists, from 
 whatever different principles they set out, commonly meet 
 in their conclusions ".^ 
 
 Bentham, on the other hand, never mentions non-hedonistic 
 systems, except in terms of contempt The following pas- 
 sages — taken almost at random from the Principles and the 
 Deontology — speak for themselves. " The various systems 
 that have been formed concerning the standard of right and 
 wrong, may all be reduced to the principle of sympathy 
 and antipathy. . . . They consist all of them in so many 
 contrivances for avoiding the obligation of appealing to any 
 external standard, and for prevailing upon the reader to 
 accept of the author's sentiment or opinion as a reason for 
 itself." 2 " He who, on any other occasion, should say, ' It 
 is as I say, because I say it is so,' would not be thought to 
 have said any great matter : but on the question concerning 
 
 ^ See Bk. II., ch. i., pp. 42, 43. The rather obvious reason why moralists 
 ' meet in their conclusions ' is, that they begin by (at least provisionally) assuming 
 the same concrete moral principles, i.e., the prevailing ones of their own age 
 and country. 
 
 ^ See Principles, ch. ii., § xiv.
 
 William Pa ley and Jeremy Benthani. 179 
 
 the standard of morality, men have written great books, 
 wherein from beginning to end they are employed in saying 
 this and nothing else." ^ " The suminum bonum — the sovereign 
 good — what is it ? ... It is this thing, and that thing, and 
 the other thing — it is anything but pleasure — it is the Irish- 
 man's apple-pie made of nothing but quinces. . . . While 
 Xenophon was writing history, and Euclid giving instruction 
 in geometry, Socrates and Plato were talking nonsense under 
 pretence of teaching wisdom and morality." ^ * Moral sense,' 
 ' common sense,' ' understanding,' * reason,' * right reason,* 
 ' nature,' and ' nature's law,' ' natural justice,' natural equity,' 
 ' good order,' * truth ' — " all these are but the dogmas of men 
 who insist on implicit obedience to their decrees ".^ 
 
 Unlike his Utilitarian predecessors, then, Bentham becomes 
 nervous, and often violent, at the mere mention of the term 
 ' summum bonum ' ; but his own treatment of the question 
 as to the fundamental ground of morality is in all essential 
 respects identical with theirs. Not only does he, of course, 
 regard happiness as the true Good, but his argimients to 
 substantiate this view are those which had long been familiar 
 before he wrote. Indeed, in the Principles of Morals and 
 Legislation, he can hardly be said to argue the matter at all ; 
 but rather assumes dogmatically the Utilitarian criterion of 
 morality. The Good is ' happiness ' and ' happiness ' is 
 merely the ' sum of pleasures,' as Gay and Tucker had held. 
 Moreover, there are no ' qualitative distinctions ' between 
 pleasures, as Tucker had explicitly taught — all concrete 
 differences being reducible to differences of intensity and 
 permanence. Not only does each seek his own happiness, 
 but each is incomparably the best judge of what will make 
 for his own happiness, as Tucker had been at pains to point 
 out. Like Tucker, again, Bentham remarks that the words 
 ' pleasure ' and ' pain ' are likely to prove misleading in ethical 
 discussions, because they seem to imply too much, and sug- 
 gests ' well-being ' and its contrary as convenient substitutes, 
 
 ^ See Deontology, vol. I., ch. i., p. 9. 
 
 "^ Ibid., ch. iii., pp. 39, 40. 'Ibid., ch. iv., p. 71.
 
 i8o History of Uiilita7'ianisfn. 
 
 more general in meaning — just as Tucker had suggested the 
 terms ' satisfaction ' and ' dissatisfaction ' } 
 
 Of course Bentham is not to be blamed for not developing 
 the hedonistic conception of the Good beyond what had been 
 done, e.g., by Paley — for the simple reason that Paley and 
 his predecessors had already stated Hedonism in perfectly 
 unmistakable terms. But even in 1834, Bentham's ardent 
 disciple, Bowring, was able to write: "It was in 1785 that 
 Paley published his Elements of Moral and Political Phil- 
 osophy. He mentions the principle of utility, but seems to 
 have no idea of its bearing upon happiness. And if he had 
 any such idea, he was the last man to give expression to it." '^ 
 Then follows a passage of personal abuse which it is the more 
 unnecessary to quote, as Whewell has already done so in his 
 Lectures. 
 
 But it might seem at first as if there were a difference 
 between Bentham, on the one hand, and Gay, Tucker, and 
 Paley, on the other, inasmuch as Bentham once for all 
 adopted the formula, ' the greatest happiness of the greatest 
 number,' as the comer-stone of his system. In other words, 
 the previous Utilitarian systems — except Cumberland's, 
 Hume's (in its later form), and Hartley's ^ — had assumed that 
 all motives were ultimately selfish, while Bentham's, by virtue 
 of its very formula, suggested devotion to one's fellow men. 
 It cannot be too strongly insisted, however, that there is no 
 theoretical difference between the four authors on this ques- 
 tion regarding the motive of the moral agent. Bentham 
 used the ' greatest happiness ' formula because he was a 
 reformer — obviously a fortuitous circumstance from the point 
 of view of theoretical Ethics. Certainly none of the authors 
 just mentioned had emphasised more strongly than Bentham 
 does the necessary egoism of the individual. For instance, 
 
 1 See Deontology, vol. I., chs. iv. and v. 
 
 2 See appendix on " History of the Greatest Happiness Principle," by 
 Bowring, Deontology, vol. I., p. 310. 
 
 ' Which, however, is so peculiar that its Utilitarian character might, with 
 some show of justice, be denied.
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Benthain. i8i 
 
 he says : " A man, a moralist, gets into an elbow-chair, and 
 pours forth pompous dogmatisms about duty — and duties. 
 Why is he not listened to ? Because every man is thinking 
 about interests.'' And again : " To prove that the immoral 
 action is a miscalculation of self-interest — to show how 
 erroneous an estimate the vicious man makes of pains and 
 pleasures, is the purpose of the intelligent moralist ".^ In- 
 deed, Bentham is at a disadvantage here, as compared with 
 the others, because he is nowhere quite explicit with regard 
 to the origin of sympathy and its place in his system. It 
 may be well to note, in this connection, that he consistently 
 holds that " the good produced by effective benevolence 
 is small in proportion to that produced by the personal 
 motives ". 
 
 Not only, then, is the Good pleasure, according to Ben- 
 tham's view ; but the good immediately sought is not the 
 pleasure of ' the greatest number,' but rather one's own. 
 How may the good of each and the good of all be shown to 
 coincide } For clearly they must coincide, if a multitude of 
 self-seeking individuals are capable of working out a common 
 good. This is a question which had been discussed, not only 
 by the earlier Utilitarians, but by writers like Shaftesbury 
 and Hutcheson, who could not properly be classed with them. 
 Indeed, up to this time, the non-Utilitarian writers seem to 
 have had better success than the Utilitarians in their attempts 
 to reconcile public and private interest. It is unnecessary to 
 recapitulate here what has been discussed at length in the 
 proper connection. For our present purpose, it is enough 
 to notice that Bentham did not profit by the suggestions of 
 those who, like Cumberland and Shaftesbury, had attempted 
 to demonstrate the necessarily organic character of society. 
 Though adopting the ' greatest happiness ' formula, his logi- 
 cal position is distinctly that of eighteenth century Individu- 
 alism. 
 
 From this point of view, rewards and (more particularly) 
 
 ' See Deontology, vol. I., p. 12.
 
 1 82 History of Utilitaria^iism. 
 
 punishments, or, as Bentham chooses to call them, ' sanctions,' 
 must be looked to, in order to effect this reconciliation. 
 Bentham's list of these ' sanctions ' differs somewhat, as re- 
 gards their number, in his various works bearing upon Ethics. 
 In the Fragment on Government^ three are mentioned : (i) 
 the ' political,' (2) the ' religious,' and (3) the ' moral '. In 
 the Principles of Morals and Legislation, four are recog- 
 nised : (l) the 'physical,' (2) the 'political,' (3) the 'moral' 
 or ' popular,' and (4) the ' religious '} In the Deontology, 
 Bentham succeeds in distinguishing five 'sanctions': (i) the 
 ' physical ' {i.e., natural consequences, abstracting from one's 
 relations to other human beings) ; (2) the ' social ' or ' sym- 
 pathetic ' {i.e., consequences which result from one's personal 
 or domestic relations) ; (3) the ' moral ' or ' popular ' {i.e., 
 public opinion) ; (4) the ' political ' or ' legal ' ; and (5) the 
 ' religious ' or ' superhuman '?• It is to be doubted if he 
 improved matters by trying to distinguish sharply between 
 (2) and (3) ; indeed, he himself hardly insists upon the separa- 
 tion. If we neglect this rather fine distinction, and regard 
 the list of ' sanctions ' in the Principles of Morals and Legis- 
 lation as his complete list, an interesting comparison suggests 
 itself. For this list of ' sanctions ' — often regarded as par- 
 ticularly characteristic of Bentham — is identical with that 
 given by Gay in the Dissertation. 
 
 It might be imagined by one who knew the early Utili- 
 tarians only at second hand, that Bentham's treatment of the 
 particular virtues, as following from the Utilitarian principle, 
 must be more definite and consistent than that of his prede- 
 cessors ; but, if anything, the contrary is true. Indeed, if we 
 go so far as to rule out the Deontology altogether as un- 
 reliable — as I am not myself prepared to do — we must admit 
 that Bentham never even attempted to give a systematic 
 treatment of the particular virtues. The Fragmejit on 
 Government, of course, contains nothing of the kind ; and, 
 in the Principles of Morals and Legislation, where he wds 
 
 ^ See ch. iii. 2 ggg ^qJ j^ (.j, ^jj
 
 William Pa ley and Jeremy Bent ham. 183 
 
 writing mainly from the point of view of Jurisprudence, he 
 very properly omitted any such treatment of the virtues. 
 In the latter work, when writing of the distinction between 
 Ethics and Jurisprudence, he merely remarks that the virtues 
 may conveniently be divided into those of (i) ' prudence,' 
 (2) ' probity ' [justice], and (3) ' beneficence ' } 
 
 In the Deontology^ then, upon which we must here depend, 
 Bentham begins by dividing virtue into two branches: (i) 
 ' prudence,' and (2) ' effective benevolence '. Quite after the 
 manner of Cumberland, ' prudence ' is regarded as having its 
 seat in the understanding ; ' effective benevolence,' principally 
 in the affections. ' Prudence,' in turn, is divided into (<a;) ' self- 
 regarding,' and (Jj) ' extra-regarding ' ; while ' effective bene- 
 volence,' again, is either (a) ' positive ' (i.e., productive of 
 positive pleasure) or (d) ' negative ' (i.e., calculated to diminish 
 pain).2 The latent confusion here, which Bentham might 
 easily have avoided by retaining his earlier classification, 
 hardly needs to be pointed out ; indeed, the distinctions thus 
 made are practically unmanageable. In his actual treatment 
 of the virtues, he seems to use the term ' prudence ' only in the 
 first sense. This was, perhaps, almost inevitable ; but the 
 result is, that he is at a very serious disadvantage, not only 
 as compared with Hume, but as compared with Tucker and 
 Paley, in his treatment of what was for them all the funda- 
 mental virtue — Justice. In fact, Bentham's deduction of the 
 particular virtues, so far as he considers them at all, is so 
 manifestly weak, that one must charitably conclude that this 
 part of the Deontology was — by him, at least — unfinished. 
 If our knowledge of Ethics were confined to what is con- 
 tained in the Deontology, we would have to agree most 
 emphatically with Bentham, when he says : " Though the 
 Linnaeus of Natural History has appeared in the world, and 
 restored its chaos into order and harmony, the Linnaeus of 
 Ethics is yet to come ".^ 
 
 ' See ch. xvii., § 6. 
 
 ^See vol. I., ch. i., pp. 15, 16; also chs. xi., xii., xiii., and xiv. 
 
 •^ See Deontology, vol. I., ch. xv., p. 202.
 
 184 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 One important topic — Bentham's treatment of the hedon- 
 istic calculus — remains to be considered. Here, if anywhere, 
 we must look for originality in Bentham's treatment of ethical 
 problems. We have seen that both Tucker and Paley taught, 
 not only that we could not predict consequences in any 
 particular case exactly enough thus to determine the right- 
 ness or wrongness of the proposed action ; but also that 
 there are obvious reasons, from the Utilitarian point of view, 
 why we should not attempt to do anything of the kind. In 
 other words, we must confine ourselves, in the main, to a 
 consideration of the ' general ' consequences of different 
 classes of actions, and thus act upon a basis of ' general rules '. 
 We further saw that both authors were willing enough that, 
 at the time of action, the agent should regard the moral law 
 as an end in itself. 
 
 To Bentham, on the other hand, this probably would have 
 seemed a pitiful subterfuge. He apparently holds that we 
 not only may, but must compute in the particular case, and 
 be largely determined by such computations. And, if there 
 be virtue in terminology, he elaborated a formidable instru- 
 ment for the hedonistic calculus. ^ The value of pleasures 
 and pains must be estimated in terms of their ' intensity,' 
 ' duration,' ' certainty,' ' proximity,' and ' extent '. But this 
 is not all. A pleasure or pain may be ' fruitful ' or ' barren,' 
 ' pure * or ' impure '. Of the distinctions thus made, the first 
 five hardly require explanation. ' Extent ' may properly be 
 put by itself, as it refers merely to the number of individuals 
 concerned. It is the multiplier, and not the multiplicand. 
 ' Certainty ' and ' proximity,' as the words would imply, refer 
 only to the probability or improbability of the pleasures or 
 pains being experienced, so that in the last resort ' intensity ' 
 and ' duration ' are all that have to be considered. So far, 
 Bentham's treatment of the hedonistic calculus in the Deon- 
 tology corresponds exactly to his treatment in the Principles 
 of Morals and Legislation. We have to be more careful, 
 
 ^ See, in particular, Deontology, vol. I., ch. iv.
 
 Williain Pa ley and Jereviy Bent ham. 185 
 
 however, in the case of ' fecundity ' and ' purity '. In the 
 Principles, the ' fecundity ' of a pleasure or pain is defined as 
 " the chance it has of being followed by sensations of the 
 same kind : that is, pleasures, if it be a pleasure : pains, if 
 it be a pain ".^ Its ' purity,' on the other hand, is defined as 
 " the chance it has of not being followed by sensations of 
 the opposite kind : that is, pains, if it be a pleasure : plea- 
 sures, if it be a pain ". In the Deontology, the author says : 
 " A pleasure or a pain may be fruitful or barren. A pleasure 
 may be fruitful in pleasures, or fruitful in pains, or fruitful in 
 both ; and a pain, on the contrary, may be fruitful in plea- 
 sures or pains, or both." ^ As regards ' purity,' he says in the 
 same work : " A pleasure is considered pure, in the degree in 
 which it is unaccompanied by counterbalancing pains — a pain 
 is pure, in the proportion in which it is unaccompanied by 
 counterbalancing pleasures " ? 
 
 It will readily be seen that, as used in the Principles, 
 ' fecundity ' and ' purity ' both refer to the future. Given a 
 pleasure or a pain, we call it ' fruitful,' if it is likely to be 
 followed by other affections of the same kind ; ' pure,' if it 
 is not likely to be followed by other affections of the opposite 
 kind. In the Deontology, as will be noted, the same terms 
 are used, but with a somewhat different signification. The 
 ' fruitfulness ' or * barrenness ' of the particular pleasure or 
 pain is here regarded as its productiveness or unproductive- 
 ness of future affections — whether of the same or of the 
 opposite kind, or of both. ' Purity ' and ' impurity,' on the 
 other hand, apparently refer merely to the unmixed or mixed 
 character of our affections, i.e., pleasure without pain, or 
 pain without pleasure. I do not understand that Bentham 
 necessarily commits himself to the dubious position that we 
 have states of consciousness which are at the same time 
 pleasurable and painful. It is enough that, in some cases, 
 circumstances are such that our consciousness vibrates back 
 
 ^ See ch. iv., § iii. 
 
 ■^ See vol. I., ch. iv., p. 62. ^ See ibid., p. 76.
 
 1 86 Hisloiy of Utilitarianisfn. 
 
 and forth between pleasure and pain with rapid alternation. 
 Roughly speaking, we might say that pleasures and pains 
 experienced under such conditions were ' impure/ in Ben- 
 tham's sense. Perhaps it may seem finical to criticise Ben- 
 tham's choice of technical terms ; but it will be seen that the 
 word ' fecundity,' as here applied, is rather misleading, as it 
 almost inevitably suggests a causal relation between plea- 
 sures and pains themselves, which the author could not have 
 intended. 
 
 After thus considering the general aspects of pleasure- 
 pain, Bentham gives an elaborate classification of pleasures 
 and pains in both the Principles and the Deontology. In the 
 Deontology, \h^ list is as follows: (i) pleasures and pains of 
 sense, (2) pleasures of wealth, with the corresponding pains 
 of privation, (3) pleasures of skill and pains of awkwardness, 
 (4) pleasures of amity and pains of enmity, (5) pleasures of 
 good reputation and pains of ill-repute, (6) pleasures of power, 
 (7) pleasures of piety, with their contrasted pains, (8) plea- 
 sures and pains of sympathy or benevolence, (9) those of 
 malevolence, (10) those of memory, (11) those of imagination, 
 (12) those of expectation, and (13) those of association. The 
 list given in the Principles is practically the same, except that 
 still another class of pleasures is added, i.e., those of relief. 
 Such minor differences may be neglected ; but Bentham him- 
 self pertinently points out that " Of the whole list of pains 
 and pleasures, two classes only regard others — they are those 
 of benevolence and malevolence. All the rest are self- 
 regarding." 1 It goes without saying that this list is a purely 
 arbitrar}^ one, having no warrant in Psychology, and that it 
 is hardly, if at all, calculated to assist us in the actual com- 
 putation of pleasures and pains. In fact, the list is mainly 
 interesting, because it illustrates particularly well a limitation 
 of Bentham's which has often been pointed out, viz., his 
 narrow and mechanical view of human nature. 
 
 Such, then, was Bentham's treatment of the hedonistic 
 
 ' See vol. I., ch. iv., p. 66,
 
 William Pa ley and Jeremy Bent ham. 187 
 
 calculus. Without entering on any more general criticism of 
 Bentham's Utilitarianism, we are now prepared to ask two 
 questions : (i) Were the refinements which he introduced of 
 practical importance ? (2) Was he right in holding, as he at 
 least seemed to do, that we should largely depend upon such 
 computations as we can make in the individual case ? The 
 first question need not detain us long. The distinctions which 
 we have just been examining seem, on the whole, to be help- 
 ful, though the particular words used to designate them do 
 not always appear to be the best that might have been chosen. 
 Any such related technical terms, which tend to abbreviate 
 discussion, are likely to have considerable currency ; and this 
 has undeniably been true of those under consideration. At 
 the same time, I fail to see that anything essentially new was 
 contributed by Bentham even here, except the terms them- 
 selves ; for all the distinctions are rather obvious, and ap- 
 parently they had all been (at least, implicitly) recognised 
 before. 
 
 The second question, viz., whether Bentham was right in 
 holding, as he at least seemed to do, that we may, and must, 
 compute the probable consequences (including, of course, the 
 remote consequences) in the particular case, and act accord- 
 ingly — is in itself more important ; but it hardly seems to 
 admit of serious debate. For the question, of course, is not 
 whether the moral agent is to take the probable consequences 
 of his contemplated act into consideration — every sane man, 
 whatever his ethical creed, is likely to do that — but whether 
 such particular computations are to take precedence of general 
 rules. Since we are not omniscient, we cannot predict with 
 certainty the consequences of any action taken by itself. 
 Moreover, it is important that we should not make the 
 attempt : first, because we have not sufficient time for elabo- 
 rate computations in a particular moral exigency ; and 
 secondly, because we are in no proper frame of mind to judge 
 impartially in those cases where our own interests are to any 
 important extent at stake. 
 
 In truth, all this is so evident that one might be tempted to
 
 1 88 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 believe that Bentham has commonly been misunderstood on 
 the point in question ; but to the present writer this seems 
 hardly possible. There is no doubt, of course, that in the 
 Principles of Morals and Legislation the hedonistic calculus 
 is employed in the interest of ' general rules,' since the laws 
 which the author has in mind would necessarily, qua laws, 
 be general in their application. In the Deontology, however, 
 where the object is to guide the individual agent in his moral 
 life, computations in the particular case seem, not merely 
 often, but generally, to be suggested, while there is no 
 single passage in the book which insists upon the importance 
 of general rules, as opposed to such particular computations. 
 The passages illustrating this general drift of the argument 
 are far too numerous to quote. The following, which may 
 fairly be regarded as typical, will probably suffice. Bentham 
 says : " The province of Deontology is to teach him [the 
 moral agent] a proper arithmetic, is to lay before him a fit 
 estimate of pain and pleasure — a budget of receipt and dis- 
 bursement, out of every operation of which he is to draw a 
 balance of good ".^ And again the author says .- " Vice may 
 be defined to be a miscalculation of chances : a mistake in 
 estimating the value of pleasures and pains. It is false moral 
 arithmetic ; and there is the consolation of knowing that, by 
 the application of a right standard, there are few moral 
 questions which may not be resolved with an accuracy and a 
 certainty not far removed from mathematical demonstra- 
 tion." 2 
 
 It is evident, however, that Bentham's attempt to reduce 
 our moral judgments to a series of problems in ' moral 
 arithmetic ' was not a success, and tended to put the Utili- 
 tarian doctrine itself in a false light. In fact, it would hardly 
 be too much to say that Bentham blundered into an unten- 
 able position here, which his Utilitarian predecessors had 
 had the good judgment to avoid. Of course, it is sometimes 
 
 ^ See vol. I., ch. xiv., p. 192. 
 
 -See vol. I., p. 131. For other passages illustrating this general line of 
 argument, see, e.g., ibid., pp. 60, 68, 79, 84, 118, 156, 168, 190, 269.
 
 William Paley and Jeremy Bentham. 1 89 
 
 held that, since such particular computations are, on the one 
 hand, impossible, and, on the other hand, dangerous to 
 attempt. Utilitarianism as a system falls to the ground. The 
 argument, however, does not seem at all conclusive. To say 
 that we must act according to ' general rules,' is merely to 
 recognise that we are finite beings ; and surely this evident 
 fact does not make for or against any particular form of 
 ethical theory. Indeed, we must be very careful not to cite 
 the concrete difficulties of our moral experience, as if they 
 disproved the validity of ethical theories different from our 
 own. No ethical theory can help us in such cases ; we must 
 rather depend upon what may fairly be called ' moral tact '. 
 As Kant long ago pointed out in another connection, there 
 can be no rules for the application of rules. 
 
 We have now examined with some care all that seems 
 really essential in Bentham's ethical system. The results of 
 our examination may be summed up in a few words. Ben- 
 tham's conception of the Good was in all respects identical 
 with that of his Utilitarian predecessors ; and his adoption 
 of the * greatest happiness ' formula did not imply a departure 
 from what had become the traditional view of the Utilitarians, 
 that the motive of the agent is uniformly egoistic. Moreover, 
 he did not go beyond the others in showing how, in the 
 natural order of things, public and private interest coincide ; 
 but depended wholly upon the four ' sanctions ' which Gay 
 had already distinguished. The ' theological sanction,' in- 
 deed, though named by him in each of his three lists, is practi- 
 cally disregarded in his treatment of Ethics. His actual pro- 
 cedure in this respect was doubtless an important influence in 
 secularising Utilitarianism, but this was mainly due to his 
 reputation as a writer on Jurisprudence. It is always to be 
 remembered that, with his selfish theory of the moral motive, 
 he was not himself in a position to explain complete obliga- 
 tion without reference to rewards and punishments after death. 
 His deduction of the particular virtues, again, was clearly 
 inferior to that which we find in the works of Tucker and 
 Paley — not to mention Hume, whose work was, of course, on
 
 IQO History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 a very different and altogether higher plane. This, however, 
 was at least partly due to the fact that he was treating 
 primarily of Jurisprudence in his completed works. Indeed, 
 the one important respect in which Bentham departs from his 
 predecessors is in his dubious attempt to reduce Ethics to 
 * moral arithmetic,' in the grimly literal sense. This, however, 
 cannot be regarded as a real advance in ethical theory, but 
 quite the contrary. The inevitable conclusion, then, seems 
 to be that Bentham contributed almost nothing of importance 
 to Ethics, considered strictly as such, though he unquestion- 
 ably did more than any of his contemporaries to bring the 
 Utilitarian theory into popular ethical discussions. In fact, 
 there were very special reasons why he was constitutionally 
 unfitted to transform the older Utilitarianism, which, as a 
 mere theory, had already been completely developed before 
 he wrote, into anything like the modern form of the doctrine. 
 These fatal limitations would have to be considered here, but 
 for the fact that J. S. Mill has performed the task once for 
 all in his classic essay on Bentham (1838), to be duly examined 
 hereafter, which perhaps may itself, without exaggeration, 
 be said to mark the transition from the eighteenth century 
 Utilitarianism to that of the present time.
 
 CHAPTER X. 
 
 JOHN STUART MILL. 
 
 In the last chapter, Paley and Bentham were considered 
 together, in order that it might be evident how essentially 
 similar their distinctively ethical views really were. It is, how- 
 ever, equally certain that to their own generation, and quite 
 as much to themselves, they must have seemed to stand for 
 very different, if not antithetical, tendencies. Paley, indeed, 
 had held somewhat liberal, though by no means radical, 
 views on politics, which probably stood in the way of his 
 rapid advancement in the Church ; but this was purely ac- 
 cidental. Berkeley, as will be remembered, had expressed 
 similar ethical views in his sermon on " Passive Obedience," 
 although his main purpose was to urge upon his hearers an 
 attitude toward the powers that be, very different from that 
 which Paley later advocated in his Political Philosophy. And 
 it is not easy to say that one was more consistent than the 
 other. There was nothing in the doctrine of so-called 
 ' Theological Utilitarianism,' either in its earlier or in its later 
 form, which logically demanded of its adherents either a con- 
 servative or a liberal attitude toward the State. This must 
 have been partly recognised by Paley's contemporaries, as 
 otherwise his Moral and Political Philosophy would never 
 have enjoyed such almost universal popularity. 
 
 Bentham, on the other hand, was first, last, and always a 
 reformer and a radical. This was the light in which he was 
 regarded both by his contemporaries and by himself. Such 
 being the case, it was perfectly natural that he should develop 
 anti-theological tendencies, for the influence of the Church, 
 
 (191)
 
 192 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 on the whole, was strongly in the direction of conservatism. 
 Here again, however, the relation between political attitude, 
 on the one hand, and religious and ethical theory, on the other, 
 was largely a fortuitous one. Religious orthodoxy easily 
 may, and often does, go with political heterodoxy, while the 
 contrary combination is still more frequent. So far as the 
 anti-theological (or at least non-theological) side of Bentham's 
 doctrine is concerned, there can be no serious question. But 
 it certainly seemed to Bentham himself and to most of those 
 immediately associated with him in the reform movement, 
 that the principle of ' the greatest happiness of the greatest 
 number,' in the technical sense of the formula, was the neces- 
 sary foundation of their schemes of practical reform. They 
 hardly realised that those holding ethical theories radically 
 different from their own might consistently enough admit 
 that ' the greatest happiness of the greatest number ' is, under 
 all ordinary circumstances, the true end of co-operative social 
 action. 
 
 In truth, we should now probably agree in holding, not only 
 that our attitude toward religion does not necessarily commit 
 us for or against radicalism, liberalism, or conservatism, but 
 also that any political attitude consistent with the ordinary 
 notions of ' good morals,' which we all hold practically in 
 common, is logically compatible with any recognised form of 
 ethical theory. We agree that the common good should be 
 the end of all governmental action ; and we further agree, in 
 the main, as to what concrete things are good. There are 
 two respects, however, in which we may differ to almost any 
 extent. First, we may differ as to how the concrete good of 
 society is practically to be attained (in other words, in political 
 ' opinions ') ; and secondly, we may differ as to the abstract 
 terms in which the concrete ' good ' is to be defined (difference 
 in ethical and political theory). The mistake of Bentham 
 and his followers was in assuming a logical relation between 
 theoretical Ethics proper and practical methods of government. 
 
 It would be quite outside our present purpose to trace 
 the fortunes of the so-called ' Bentham school '. None of
 
 John Stuart Mill. 193 
 
 the writers thus designated, whether properly or improperly, 
 can be said to have really contributed to theoretical Ethics, 
 with the very important exception of J. S. Mill ; and all of 
 Mill's more important writings on Ethics were published after 
 the well-known essay on Bentham (1838), which shows in the 
 most unmistakable way that he was thus early very far from 
 being a mere disciple of the older moralist. In truth, it will 
 be remembered that, in an often-quoted passage in the Auto- 
 biography, Mill denies outright that there was any ' Bentham 
 school,' in the sense ordinarily understood. His contention 
 is that the purely personal influence ot his father, James Mill, 
 was greater than that of Bentham, though he acknowledges 
 that his father's total influence was very considerably less. 
 He says : " The influence which Bentham exercised was 
 by his writings. Through them he has produced, and is 
 producing, effects on the condition of mankind, wider and 
 deeper, no doubt, than any which can be attributed to my 
 father. He is a much greater name in history. But ray 
 father exercised a far greater personal ascendency." ^ He 
 then goes on to indicate circumstantially the various channels 
 of his father's influence. The first impression might be that 
 Mill considerably overrated this influence ; but the facts, so 
 far as they are generally accessible, seem on the whole to 
 bear out his statement of the case. One has only to read 
 any of the authoritative accounts of the elder Mill's life ^ to 
 see how closely and continuously he was in touch with the 
 men who were most prominently engaged in this liberal 
 propagandism, and how he was regarded by them. But all 
 this is really a digression, and we shall best proceed at once 
 to an examination of the ethical doctrine of J. S. Mill himselT, 
 after giving necessary attention to the formative influences 
 of his childhood and early youth. 
 
 The strange experiment which James Mill tried in the 
 
 ^ See pp. loi et seq. 
 
 2 See, in particular, the valuable life of James Mill by Professor Bain; also 
 the second volume of Mr. Leslie Stephen's admirable work on the Utilitarians. 
 
 »3
 
 194 History of Utilitarimiism, 
 
 education of his eldest son has been described so often, and 
 from such different points of view, that it would be almost 
 an impertinence to speak of it here at any length. It will 
 be remembered that James Mill, himself one of the busiest 
 of men, irritable and somewhat harsh by nature, constantly 
 engaged in literary work (which, perhaps, less than any other 
 admits readily of systematic interruption), undertook to be 
 his son's only schoolmaster from the very beginning. That 
 he accomplished the seemingly impossible, is doubtless an 
 interesting fact, for it exhibits in a most striking light the 
 remarkable intellectual endowments of both father and son. 
 But this was, perhaps, the most costly education of which we 
 have definite record, not less for student than for teacher. 
 If the victim had been one whit less than he was, he very well 
 might have been ruined for life by the forcing process that he 
 was put through. We do not refer merely to the fact that 
 he began the study of Greek at three, and other similar studies, 
 ordinarily considered to belong to a secondary, rather than 
 to a strictly primary education, at a correspondingly early 
 age. It is, we believe, reported of Mill's gifted contemporary, 
 Thirwall, that he began to read Latin at three and Greek 
 at four. But the future Bishop and historian of Greece was 
 doubtless most fortunate in being permitted the conventional 
 education of his class, after this startling exhibition of infant 
 precocity. Mill, on the contrary, utterly lost his boyhood, 
 with all the humanising effects of normal early associations. 
 As a natural result, in after years he never quite found his 
 fellowmen. 
 
 The particular studies to which J. S. Mill devoted himself 
 in his early years, were not essentially different from those 
 which formed the staple of higher education at that time — 
 except that he was made to give some attention to Political 
 Economy, which was then still an infant science. The 
 peculiarity in his case lay in the fact that the ground covered 
 was unusually large, and that these studies were pursued 
 under the private tuition of his father and, for the most part, 
 at an extremely early age. But in another aspect, much
 
 John Shtaid Mill. 195 
 
 more important for us, his early training was, as he himself 
 points out in the Autobiography, for the time and country 
 in which he lived, almost unique. He was brought up from 
 the first without any religious belief, in the ordinary accepta- 
 tion of the term. James Mill had, indeed, begun his career 
 with a theological training ; but he soon found it impossible 
 to retain his early religious views. His son points out that 
 his difficulties had been " moral, still more than intellectual ". 
 " He found it impossible to believe that a world so full of evil 
 was the work of an Author combining infinite power with 
 perfect goodness and righteousness." ^ Moreover, he seems 
 to have held that positive religion was distinctly detrimental 
 to good morals, on the ground that it was a fatally convenient 
 pretext by which to justify the existing order of things, in- 
 volving, as this does, so many evils that may be remedied. 
 Morality, he believed, must cease to be a matter of mere 
 tradition and be founded upon some definite objective prin- 
 ciple. 
 
 The glimpse of James Mill's private views on Ethics and 
 Religion that is afforded in this part of the Autobiography 
 is decidedly interesting. The following passage is particu- 
 larly significant. " In his views of life he partook of the 
 character of the Stoic, the Epicurean, and the Cynic, not in 
 the modern, but the ancient sense of the word. In his 
 personal qualities the Stoic predominated. His standard of 
 morals was Epicurean, inasmuch as it was Utilitarian, taking 
 as the exclusive test of right and wrong, the tendency of 
 actions to produce pleasure or pain. But he had (and this 
 was the Cynic element) scarcely any belief in pleasure. . . . 
 He thought human life a poor thing at best, after the fresh- 
 ness of youth and of unsatisfied curiosity had gone by. . . . 
 He would sometimes say, that if life were made what it might 
 be, by good government and good education, it would be worth 
 having : but he never spoke with anything like enthusiasm 
 even of that possibility." ^ 
 
 1 See p. 39. '^ See pp. 47 et seq.
 
 196 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 We are so constantly reminded of the complex character 
 of J. S. Mill's ethical system, that it is most interesting to 
 find sentiments like these attributed by him to his father. 
 The sentences quoted are even more significant in their proper 
 context. Almost as interesting as this (at first sight) para- 
 doxical combination of theoretical hedonism with practical 
 asceticism, is the sense of irremediable evil in the world which 
 we find liere. Both of the Mills were inclined to regard 
 not unfavourably the Manichaean doctrine. J. S. Mill took 
 a much less despondent view than his father of the possi- 
 bilities of the race ; but he never, at least in his mature years, 
 entertained anything like Bentham's breezy, if somewhat 
 shallow, optimism. 
 
 The influence of Bentham himself upon J. S. Mill was, of 
 course, partly personal and partly philosophical. The elder 
 Mill was already a friend of Bentham, when his son was but 
 three years of age, and the precocious child and youth met 
 the reformer frequently and on familiar terms. It was prin- 
 cipally through his writings, however, that Bentham influenced 
 Mill. There is an interesting passage in the Autobiography, 
 m which the author tells how, when reading in the direction 
 of law as a boy of fifteen or sixteen, he became acquainted 
 for the first time with Bentham's doctrine in its technical 
 form, as interpreted by Dumont in the Traite de Legislation} 
 Unfortunately, however, it seems to have been the worst in 
 Bentham, as well as the best, that attracted his early admira- 
 tion ; for he cites in particular the chapter in which Bentham 
 impatiently dismisses all non-hedonistic theories as dogmatism 
 in disguise. If Mill had at this time been better read in 
 ethical literature, it might have occurred to him that, in the 
 very chapter cited, Bentham shows himself a good deal more 
 of a dogmatist than the men whom he criticises ; and that 
 his cheerful ignorance of nearly all systems opposed to his 
 own, as shown here and elsewhere, is perhaps the most amaz- 
 ing phenomenon of the ethical literature of his day. But one 
 
 ^ See p. 64.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 197 
 
 must remember that Mill had read no modern philosophy at 
 this time. It was after this, according to his own account, 
 that he became acquainted even with English writers like 
 Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Hartley, and Brown. ^ This being 
 the case, one is rather puzzled to understand why, when he 
 wrote the Autobiography, Mill should have taken his juvenile 
 impressions of Bentham so seriously. He says, e.g. : " I now 
 had opinions ; a creed, a doctrine, a philosophy ; in one among 
 the best senses of the word, a religion ; the inculcation and 
 diffusion of which could be made the principal outward purpose 
 of a life "? 
 
 For several years Mill seems to have remained almost 
 wholly under the influence of Bentham's writings and his 
 father's personality, and, in the enthusiasm of youth, he doubt- 
 less developed much of that spirit of partisanship which in 
 after years he so much deprecated. The first step in the 
 direction of what he calls his ' youthful propagandism ' was 
 the foundation of the " Utilitarian Society ". This was in 
 the year following that in which he first became acquainted 
 with Bentham's writings. The fact is of interest merely 
 because this was the first time that the word ' Utilitarian ' 
 had been used by hedonists themselves, as representing their 
 doctrine. In a passage often quoted, Mill says : " I did not 
 invent the word, but found it in one of Gait's novels, the 
 Annals of the Parish, in which the Scotch clergyman, of whom 
 the book is a supposed autobiography, is represented as warn- 
 ing his parishioners not to leave the Gospel and become utili- 
 tarians. With a boy's fondness for a name and a banner I 
 seized on the word, and for some years called myself and 
 others by it as a sectarian appellation. ... As those opinions 
 attracted more notice, the term was repeated by strangers 
 and opponents, and got into rather common use just about the 
 time when those who had originally assumed it, laid down 
 that along with other sectarian characteristics." ^ 
 
 Passing over Mill's very circumstantial account of his early 
 
 1 See p. 69. 2 See p, 67. 
 
 •^ See pp. 79 et seq, ; cf. Uiilitarianism, p. 9, note.
 
 198 History 0/ Utilitarianism. 
 
 achievements as a writer, during the two years following the 
 foundation of the first Westminster Review in 1824 — which, 
 as a mere tour de force on the part of a youth who had not 
 yet attained majority, are perhaps the most striking feature 
 of his whole literary career — we shall pause to notice only 
 one more stage of his mental history, as given in the Auto- 
 biography. At length, in the autumn of 1826, the young 
 writer had to pay the penalty for his abnormal education and 
 life experience up to that time. His own account of what he 
 calls " A Crisis in my Mental History " is perhaps the best 
 known chapter in the Autobiography, and so calls for no re- 
 production here. For some months all sources of satisfac- 
 tion seemed for ever dried up for this ' disquisitive young man,' 
 as Peacock had called him soon after he made his appearance 
 at the India House — this martyr, one would be inclined to 
 add, of a monstrous training. With capacities of almost the 
 highest order, and living among those who, of all Englishmen 
 at that time, had the word ' freedom ' oftenest on their lips, 
 J. S. Mill had in reahty lived under quite as narrow and 
 tyrannical a regime as fell to the lot of the average young 
 school-man of the Middle Ages. It was, perhaps, not alto- 
 gether to his discredit that he had serious doubts, at the time 
 of which we speak, as to whether life was worth living. With 
 considerable confidence we may answer for him, that such a 
 life as his own had been up to this time was scarcely to be 
 reckoned so. This period of unrest and inner conflict was of 
 some months' duration ; but in the end it was decided that 
 the world should lose a singularly perfect calculating-machine 
 and gain another human philosopher. 
 
 We may now take leave of the Autobiography (1873), and 
 trace the development of Mill's views on Ethics from his 
 earlier published writings. Unfortunately he never wrote a 
 detailed treatise on the subject. Apart from the well-known 
 Utilitarianism (1863), we have to depend upon miscellaneous 
 essays or upon chapters in his various works, where the ex- 
 pression of his own views on Ethics is incidental rather than
 
 John Stuart Mill. 199 
 
 the main purpose. This is in itself a serious disadvantage, 
 but the diflficulty is greater than this alone would indicate. 
 After his early course in rigorous Benthamism, and the crisis 
 in his mental life which we have just considered, he drifted 
 insensibly away from many of his earlier tenets, without by 
 any means realising the extent of the divergence of his later 
 from his earlier views. This being the case, it will be neces- 
 sary to consider his various writings which bear upon Ethics 
 separately, in spite of the obvious inconvenience of this 
 method. 
 
 And first, it will be desirable to see how, after he became 
 an independent ethical writer, he chose to define his posi- 
 tion toward Paley and Bentham. Unfortunately, we have 
 to depend, for his estimate of Paley, upon his not very satis- 
 factory essay on Professor Sedgwick's Discourse on the 
 Studies of the University of Cambridge (1835).^ This does 
 not by any means exhibit Mill at his best ; for the most part, 
 the essay reads like a mere apology for the position of 
 Bentham. It will be remembered that the Discourse itself 
 attracted a very great deal of attention at the time, and had a 
 most important influence toward modifying the whole scheme 
 of philosophical studies at Cambridge. Most students of 
 Ethics at the present day, having heard so much of the Dis- 
 course before reading it, are probably at a loss to understand 
 why it should have exerted such a considerable influence. It 
 makes no philosophical pretensions whatever, being written 
 more in the form of a sermon than that of even a popular 
 lecture on philosophy. But it was an earnest and most effec- 
 tive protest, from the point of view of an English churchman 
 of this period, against the tendencies of English Empiricism, 
 as represented by Locke ; and, in particular, against the 
 ethical system of Paley. It is rather startling to find that 
 Locke was being taught at this time without any special 
 notice being taken of his lineal successors of the English 
 Empirical school. Moreover, the criticism of Paley, to which 
 
 ^ London Review, April, 1835.
 
 200 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 by far the most important part of the Discourse is devoted, 
 is anything but fair, and certainly does not show that Pro- 
 fessor Sedgwick appreciated the strength (such as it was) of 
 Paley's position. But, after all abatements, the Discourse 
 brings out with a good deal of force the fact, which must long 
 have been more or less definitely appreciated, that Paley's 
 system did not really do justice to the higher, more ideal side 
 of the Christian doctrine. In this connection, Professor Sedg- 
 wick undertakes to criticise the hedonistic position in general ; 
 although it must be admitted that this part of the Discourse 
 is far from being either clear or convincing. 
 
 Now, in the essay which we are considering. Mill does an 
 unconscious injustice to Professor Sedgwick, albeit we must 
 confess that the latter's friends were largely to blame for 
 the misunderstanding. In short, he seems to assume through- 
 out that the Discourse is a philosophical disquisition, and that 
 it is to be criticised accordingly. This will perhaps partly 
 account for the unfortunate tone of the essay, even of the part 
 which directly refers to Paley, and with which alone we are 
 here concerned. Mill says : " Of Paley's work, though it 
 possesses in a high degree some minor merits, we think, on the 
 whole, meanly "} One reason for this, perhaps, is, that Mill 
 appreciates Paley's position as little, or almost as little, as 
 Professor Sedgwick himself had done. For instance, he says : 
 " In the first place, he does not consider utility as itself the 
 source of moral obligation, but as a mere index to the will 
 of God, which he regards as the ultimate groundwork of all 
 morality, and the origin of its binding force. . . . The only 
 view of the connection between religion and morality which 
 does not armihilate the very idea of the latter, is that which 
 considers the Deity as not making, but recognising and 
 sanctioning, moral obligation." ^ 
 
 The first sentence quoted would seem to indicate that, 
 according to Paley, morality is essentially arbitrary in its 
 character — depending ultimately upon the mere will of God. 
 
 ^ See Dissertations and Discussions (first ed.), vol. I., p. 114. 
 ■ See ibid., p. 125.
 
 fohn Stuart Mill. 201 
 
 This is a point which we have already discussed in connection 
 with Gay's Dissertation, which Paley follows here exactly. 
 According to the selfish theory of moral action, complete 
 obligation could indeed come only from the will of God, 
 because God alone has it in His power to provide adequate 
 rewards and punishments. But it was precisely the point of 
 the argument of both Gay and Paley, to show that the will 
 of God was not arbitrary in this case, but rather that the 
 Divine Being was necessarily determined to will that human 
 beings should perform such actions as would be conducive 
 to the greatest happiness of all — which alone, according to 
 their view, could be regarded as the true Good. Their idea 
 of the objective end of all moral action was precisely the same 
 as that of Mill himself,^ the difference between their position 
 and his being, of course, that they depended to a large extent 
 upon supernatural sanctions, the belief in which seemed to 
 Mill, on the other hand, worse than useless. In the last 
 chapter, we saw that Bentham, at any rate, had no logical ob- 
 jection to urge against the Theological Utilitarians on this 
 point. Mill, on the contrary, seems already to assert the 
 existence of a certain degree of altruism as the necessary 
 foundation of morality. What is implicit here, becomes per- 
 fectly explicit in his later teaching. 
 
 Mill further objects to Paley that throughout his conclu- 
 sions are the starting-point of his premises. " His book is one 
 of a class which has since become very numerous, and is likely 
 to become still more so — an apology for commonplace. . . . 
 He took the doctrines of practical morals which he found 
 current." ^ A little further on. Mill adds : "If he had started 
 from any other principle, we have as little doubt that he would 
 have arrived at the very same conclusions ". This arraign- 
 ment is by no means so serious as the writer seems to sup- 
 pose. If Paley began by accepting the notions of morality 
 which were almost universally current in his time, and 
 attempted to rationalise them, he did v/hat any moralist in a 
 
 ^ Mill saw his mistake later. Cf. ibid., pp. 345, 346 ; also vol. II., p. 455. 
 - See p. 128.
 
 202 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 similar position should do. The corrective use of Ethics must 
 come later. Whether or not one is a reformer by nature and 
 education, it is dangerous to begin with an eccentric morality 
 of one's own. It may very well be true that, if Paley had 
 ' started from any other principle,' he would have reached 
 the ' same conclusions '. We have no reason to assume, how- 
 ever, that the ' conclusions ' were not his honest convictions 
 with regard to what things were right and what wrong. If 
 our concrete notions of right and wrong were as likely to 
 waver or to change as our purely theoretical views concerning 
 a possible science of Ethics, the case would be a serious one 
 indeed. In short, as we saw at the beginning of this chapter, 
 the acceptance of Hedonism, whether theological or non-theo- 
 logical, does not by any means commit one for or against any 
 of the radical views with regard to government and society 
 which appealed to Mill so strongly at this time. 
 
 We have allowed ourselves to say of this essay that it reads, 
 for the most part, ' like a mere apology for the position of 
 Bentham '. To Mill himself such a characterisation would 
 doubtless have seemed unjust. In the Autobiography he says : 
 " And here, I imagined, was an opportunity of at the same 
 time repelling an unjust attack, and inserting into my defence 
 of Hartleianism and Utilitarianism a number of the opinions 
 which constituted my view of those subjects, as distinguished 
 from that of my old associates. In this I partially succeeded, 
 though my relation to my father would have made it painful 
 to me in any case, and impossible in a Review for which he 
 wrote, to speak out my whole mind on the subject at this 
 time." 1 The last sentence quoted is particularly significant. 
 Though nearly thirty years of age, and a writer for serious 
 periodicals during almost half of this time, Mill was not yet 
 in a position to say quite what he thought, or all that he 
 believed, for fear of calling down upon his head the paternal 
 wrath. This is not said in any spirit of ridicule. On the 
 whole, the younger Mill was right, even apart from his filial 
 feelings. He was obliged constantly to co-operate with his 
 
 ' See p. 20I.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 203 
 
 father, not only in the daily work of the India Office, but in 
 the reform movement which they both had so much at heart. 
 Any breach between them would have been a serious matter, 
 from a public no less than a private point of view. How 
 great this restraining influence really was, may be sur- 
 mised by those who will take the trouble to compare this 
 essay with the one on Bentham (1838), which was published 
 two years after James Mill's death, and to which we shall 
 almost immediately proceed. 
 
 But, before leaving this essay on the Discourse, it is fair 
 to ask : Where are we to look for those ' new opinions ' of 
 Mill, which distinguished him from his former associates .'' 
 The mere fact that the young writer, with his wider interests 
 and sympathies, now and again expressed himself as neither 
 Bentham nor James Mill would have done, is not to the point, 
 for we cire here concerned merely with abstract ethical theory. 
 There is, however, one divergence from the older ' greatest 
 happiness ' theory which is of real, and even considerable, 
 importance. This is with regard to the motive of the moral 
 agent. Unfortunately, Mill is not quite fair to Professor 
 Sedgwick here. He says : " The remainder of Mr. Sedgwick's 
 argument — if argument it can be called — is a perpetual 
 ignoratio elenchi. He lumps up the principle of utility — 
 which is a theory of right and wrong — ^with the theory, if 
 there be such a theory, of the universal selfishness of man- 
 kind. We never know, for many sentences together, which 
 of the two he is arguing against ; he never seems to know 
 it himself. He begins a sentence on the one, and ends it on 
 the other. In his mind they seem to be one and the same." ^ 
 
 As against many anti-Utilitarian writers of the present day, 
 this would be perfectly legitimate and most damaging criticism ; 
 but Professor Sedgwick was hardly to be blamed for connect- 
 ing the Utilitarian doctrine with the selfish theory of moral 
 action, for this latter had been as strongly insisted upon by 
 Bentham as by Paley, and, indeed, in quite as offensive 
 
 ' See Dissertations, vol. I., p. 154.
 
 204 History of U ti litarianism. 
 
 terms. Mill was quite right in refusing to follow his im- 
 mediate predecessors in this matter, but at any rate he ought 
 to have given due notice of the fact. It must have been rather 
 provok-ing to Professor Sedgwick and his friends, that Mill 
 should blame him for not making a distinction which — 
 except by Hume (in the second form of his theory) and by 
 Hartley (whose treatment of Ethics had been too confused 
 to influence his immediate successors) — had never been 
 clearly made up to this time by prominent writers on the 
 Utilitarian side. 
 
 The essay on Bentham (1838) ^ is, in every way, far more 
 important than that which we have just been considering. 
 For one at all acquainted with the history of English Ethics, 
 and, in particular, with Bentham's writings, it is perhaps the 
 very best introduction to Mill's own system. With all its 
 remarkable qualities, however, this essay is rather a strange 
 production. One is not surprised that it should have puzzled 
 and irritated both friends and enemies. While professing, 
 and doubtless intending, to put Bentham on a very high 
 pedestal, Mill in reality proved himself a most dangerous 
 idol-breaker. He begins by characterising Bentham as " the 
 great subversive, or, in the language of continental phil- 
 osophers, the great critical, thinker of his age and country," 
 — ' the great questioner of things established '. But Ben- 
 tham's positive qualities, according to Mill, were even more 
 important. Though not a ' great philosopher,' he was a 
 ' great reformer in philosophy,' one of the ' great teachers 
 and permanent intellectual ornaments of the human race '. 
 This is a very large claim. How is it established 1 It seems 
 that Bentham " introduced into morals and politics those 
 habits of thought and modes of investigation, which are essen- 
 tial to the idea of science ; and the absence of which made 
 those departments of inquir\', as physics had been before 
 Bacon \sic\ a field of interminable discussion, leading to no 
 result "? But more particularly : " Bentham's method may 
 
 ^ London and Westminster Review, August, 1838. 
 ^See Dissertations, vol. I., pp. 339 et seq.
 
 John Stuart Mill, 205 
 
 be shortly described as the method of detail ; of treating 
 wholes by separating them into their parts," etc. If it be 
 asked whether this method was after all so very original, Mill 
 replies : " Whatever originality there was in the method— in 
 the subjects he applied it to, and in the rigidity with which 
 he adhered to it, there was the greatest. Hence his intermin- 
 able classifications. Hence his elaborate demonstrations of 
 the most acknowledged truths." Those who are at all familiar 
 with Bentham's ' interminable classifications ' (often enough 
 on no apparent logical or psychological principle) and his 
 ' elaborate demonstrations ' of the commonplace, will hardly 
 agree that it is here that we must look for the secret of his 
 strength. 
 
 In truth, as Mill admits : " The generalities of his philos- 
 ophy itself have little or no novelty : to ascribe any to the 
 doctrine that general utility is the foundation of morality, 
 would imply great ignorance of the history of philosophy, 
 of general literature, and of Bentham's own writings. He 
 derived the idea, as he says himself, from Helvetius ; and it 
 was the doctrine no less, of the religious philosophers of that 
 age, prior to Reid and Beattie. We never saw an abler de- 
 fence of the doctrine of utility than in a book written in 
 refutation of Shaftesbury, and now little read — Brown's 
 Essays on the Characteristics. ... In all ages of philosophy, 
 one of its schools has been utilitarian — not only from the time 
 of Epicurus, but long before. It was by mere accident that 
 this opinion became connected in Bentham with his peculiar 
 method." ^ But, as if to bewilder the reader completely, 
 Mill adds two or three pages further on : " This [peculiar 
 method of Bentham's], which he calls the exhaustive method, 
 is as old as philosophy itself. Plato owes everything to it, 
 and does everything by it ; " etc. In short, this ' great re- 
 
 1 See ibid., pp. 345, 346. Cf. with Mill's previous remarks on Paley, whose 
 system is practically the same as that of Brown. See also a passage in the 
 essay on Whewell {Dissertations, vol. II., p. 455), where Mill speaks of several 
 writers, "all of whom, as explicitly as Bentham, laid down the doctrine that 
 utility is the foundation of morals ".
 
 2o6 History oj (Jtititai^ianism. 
 
 former of philosophy ' was such, not because he had anything 
 in Ethics really new to impart, for hedonism is as old as 
 philosophy ; but rather by virtue of his peculiar method, that 
 of ' detail ' — which, in turn, is acknowledged to be as old as 
 philosophy, or at least as old as Plato. The novelty, appar- 
 ently, consisted merely in applying this ' exhaustive method ' 
 to the problems of morals and legislation as they appeared 
 to the hedonist. Apart from rhetoric, this apparently means 
 that Bentham insisted upon a more definite treatment of par- 
 ticular legal or ethical problems than was common among his 
 contemporaries. So far he was undoubtedly in the right, and, 
 as Mill points out, exercised a salutary influence upon his 
 opponents as well as upon his followers. But can we agree 
 that this constitutes him a ' great reformer ' m moral phil- 
 osophy ? In truth, method has been a sort of fetish through- 
 out a large part of the development of modern, as well as of 
 ancient, philosophy. The really important question with re- 
 gard to any particular philosopher is not : What method has 
 he followed } but : What has he actually accomplished, or put 
 others in the way of accomplishing, by virtue of his method ? 
 When Mill tries to answer the question, as to what Bentham 
 did thus actually accomplish, he concedes almost everything 
 that Bentham's bitterest opponents would need to claim. He 
 very properly remarks that the success of one who attempts 
 the adequate treatment of Ethics " will be proportional to two 
 things : the degree in which his own nature and circumstances 
 furnish him with a correct and complete picture of man's 
 nature and circumstances ; and his capacity of deriving light 
 from other minds ".^ In the last respect, he admits that Ben- 
 tham was lamentably deficient. " His writings contain few 
 traces of the accurate knowledge of any schools of thinking 
 but his own; and many proofs of his entire conviction that 
 they could teach him nothing worth knowing. For some of 
 the most illustrious of previous thinkers, his contempt was 
 unmeasured." All ethical theories differing from his own, 
 he dismissed as ' vague generalities '. Mill very suggestively 
 
 ' See pp. 350 et seq.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 207 
 
 remarks : " He did not heed, or rather the nature of his mind 
 prevented it from occurring to him, that these generahties con- 
 tained the whole unanalysed experience of the human race ". 
 And then Mill proceeds to show, in an admirable passage too 
 long to be quoted, that he who thus neglects, not only the 
 speculations of previous moralists, but ' the general opinion 
 of mankind ' on moral subjects, cannot take even the first 
 necessary step toward a truly objective treatment of Ethics. 
 
 One of the two most important qualifications for a moral 
 philosopher, then, Bentham utterly lacked, according to his 
 former disciple. Did he possess the other qualification ? 
 Was he able, from the completeness of his own experience 
 and from sympathy with the many sides of human nature, 
 to make up what he lost by this ignorant contempt for pre- 
 vious thinkers ? No, we are told : " In many of the most 
 natural and strongest feelings of human nature he had no 
 sympathy ; from many of its graver experiences he was alto- 
 gether cut off; and the faculty by which one mind under- 
 stands a mind different from itself, and throws itself into the 
 feelings of that other mind, was denied him by his deficiency 
 of imagination ".^ His knowledge of human nature was not 
 only wholly empirical, but with " the empiricism of one who 
 has had little experience. . . . Other ages and other nations were 
 a blank to him for purposes of instruction. . . . His own lot was 
 cast in a generation of the leanest and barrenest men whom 
 England had yet produced ; and he was an old man when a 
 better race came in with the present century. He saw ac- 
 cordingly in man little but what the vulgarest eye can see ; 
 recognised no diversities of character but such as he who runs 
 may read." And again : " Nothing is more curious than the 
 absence of recognition in any of his writings of the existence 
 of conscience, as a thing distinct from philanthropy, from 
 affection for God or man, and from self-interest in this world 
 or in the next ". But even this is not all. Not only does he 
 overlook the moral part of man's nature, in the strict sense of 
 the term, the desire of perfection or the feeling of an accusing 
 
 1 See pp. 353 et seq.
 
 2o8 History of Utilitarianis^n. 
 
 conscience ; " he but faintly recognises, as a fact of human 
 nature, the pursuit of any other ideal end for its own sake ". 
 The ' sense of honour,' ' love of beauty/ ' love of order,' ' love 
 of power,' ' love of action ' — " none of these powerful con- 
 stituents of human nature are thought worthy of a place 
 among the ' Springs of Action ' '. 
 
 Such was Bentham's theory of the world. What will it 
 accomplish for Ethics ? Mill says : " It will do nothing for 
 the conduct of the individual, beyond prescribing some of the 
 more obvious dictates of worldly prudence, and outward pro- 
 bity and beneficence ".^ That very important part of Ethics, 
 moral ' self-education,' is left out entirely. As regards one's 
 attitude toward society, " a moralist on Bentham's principles 
 may get as far as this, that he ought not to slay, burn, or 
 steal " ; but, apparently, not much further. Such a doctrine 
 " will enable a society which has attained a certain state of 
 spiritual development, and the maintenance of which in that 
 state is otherwise provided for, to prescribe the rules by which 
 it may protect its material interests. It will do nothing (ex- 
 cept sometimes as an instrument in the hands of a higher 
 doctrine) for the spiritual interests of society ; nor does it 
 suffice of itself even for the material interests." In short, 
 Bentham's philosophy can only " teach the means of organ- 
 ising and regulating the merely business part of the social 
 arrangements. . . . He committed the mistake of supposing 
 that the business part of human affairs was the whole of them ; 
 all at least that the legislator and the moralist had to do 
 with." Bentham's services in the field of Jurisprudence and 
 of practical reform are spoken of in the last part of the essay 
 at considerable length and with (at least partly) deserved ap- 
 preciation ; but Mill has already allowed himself to say what 
 is manifestly true, and what takes away much from the force 
 of his eulogium. " A philosophy of laws and institutions, not 
 founded on a philosophy of national character, is an absurdity. 
 But what could Bentham's opinion be worth on national 
 character .^ How could he, whose mind contained so few and 
 
 ^ See pp. 363 et seq.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 209 
 
 so poor types of individual character, rise to that higher 
 generalisation ? " ^ 
 
 This essay has been noticed at such length, and, as far as 
 possible, reproduced in Mill's own words, for two reasons. 
 First, in spite of its simple, though partly unconscious, severity, 
 it is in the main a perfectly just criticism. At the present day, 
 two generations after this essay was published, many of the 
 criticisms are such as would be almost sure to occur to a writer 
 on ethical theory ; but it has seemed best not to weaken the 
 force of the criticisms by putting them in terms of the 
 commonplace of current ethical discussion. What Mill has 
 done once for all, does not need to be done again in a neces- 
 sarily far less satisfactory manner. Secondly, as already said, 
 this essay is perhaps the very best introduction to Mill's own 
 system, seeing that some of the most important of Mill's own 
 contributions to Ethics may be directly deduced from it. One 
 might even say that, just as Mill here cuts himself loose from 
 the narrow and partisan traditions of Benthamism proper, so 
 the hedonism of the nineteenth century here takes final leave 
 of much that was most characteristic of the hedonism of the 
 eighteenth century. This is not to say that Mill himself 
 founded a new school. From beginning to end, he met with 
 serious, and (from the point of view of logical consistency) 
 sometimes well-grounded, opposition from the Utilitarians of 
 his own generation. But he did something far better than 
 found a new school ; he raised the whole plane of ethical 
 discussion, and did much to show what the points at issue 
 really were. The hedonists, on the one hand, finally took the 
 trouble to try to understand their opponents, while, on the 
 other hand, it gradually dawned upon the opponents of hedon- 
 ism, that the stock arguments against Paley and Bentham 
 would not suffice against Utilitarianism in its regenerated 
 form. 
 
 Mill's essay on Coleridge (1840)2 should always be read 
 in connection with the one on Bentham, though greatly in- 
 
 ' See p. 366. 
 
 '^London and Westminster Review, March, 1840. 
 14
 
 210 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 ferior to that in most respects. The weakness of the essay 
 may be described in a word : it is an external criticism from 
 beginning to end, by one who regarded Coleridge merely as 
 the typical conservative, as opposed to Bentham, the typical 
 progressive philosopher. This conveniently shows how 
 dangerous it is to estimate a philosophical method by its real 
 or supposed practical consequences. In respect to practical 
 reforms, Bentham was indeed for, as Coleridge was against, 
 many innovations ; but when we consider how the two stand 
 with regard to the development of speculation in England, 
 we find that Mill's estimate is almost the exact contrary of 
 what we would now probably agree in regarding as the truth. 
 Though neither was strictly an original philosopher — though, 
 in fact, there is very little propriety in calling Bentham a 
 philosopher at all — the type of Utilitarianism for which Ben- 
 tham stood was certainly the logical result of the whole pre- 
 vious development of English Empiricism ; while Coleridge, if 
 he originated little, did much to bring his countrymen to 
 understand and appreciate those German modes of thought 
 which, for better or for worse, were destined to change the 
 whole face of English philosophy in little less than two 
 generations. In short, if Coleridge was a reactionary in his 
 views on Church and State, he was to some extent a prophet 
 of the future in his rejection of the traditional English Em- 
 piricism and his (not always critical) acceptance of German 
 methods in philosophy ; while Bentham's treatment of Ethics 
 (in which alone he enters the field of philosophy proper) may 
 almost be regarded as the reductio ad absurduin of English 
 Empiricism working, not only in opposition to, but in prac- 
 tical ignorance of, the principles of the Critical Philosophy. 
 But if Mill's criticism of Coleridge is unsatisfactory, ^ in 
 that he failed to appreciate the real significance of Coleridge's 
 
 1 In the last part of the essay, Mill makes the rather peculiar confession that, 
 " of Coleridge as a moral and religious philosopher (the character which he 
 presents most prominently in his principal works), there is neither room, nor 
 would it be expedient for us to speak more than generally ". (See Dissertations, 
 vol. I., p. 458.)
 
 John Stuart Mill. 2 1 1 
 
 position in the English philosophy of the day, one can find 
 no fault whatever with the tone of the essay which we are 
 examining. It is more than courteous throughout, and, so 
 far as the writer's intentions are concerned, appreciative. 
 Indeed, there are passages which almost surprise one by what 
 is conceded to the opposite school. This may have been 
 partly due to Mill's early, and somewhat intimate, acquaint- 
 ance with Frederick Maurice and John Sterling, both of whom 
 were, of course, very decidedly under the influence of Cole- 
 ridge. In the Autobiography, Mill admits that both of these 
 young men had been of ' considerable use ' to his development, 
 while he says of the latter : " With SterHng I soon became very 
 intimate, and was more attached to him than I have ever been 
 to any other man ".^ For Mill, then, Coleridge was the great 
 awakener of the spirit of philosophy " within the bounds of 
 traditional opinions "? Bentham had asked of every doctrine : 
 Is it true ? Coleridge asks : What does it mean ? Both types of 
 mind are necessary, if there is to be intellectual or spiritual 
 progress. " Whoever could master the premises and combine 
 the methods of both, would possess the entire English phil- 
 osophy of his age." ^ The great danger in philosophy is 
 that one will mistake a part of the truth for the whole. As 
 the French Eclectics held, in controversies both sides are apt 
 to be right in what they affirm, wrong in what they deny. 
 
 This frank recognition of the claims of a thoughtful con- 
 servatism is especially significant, when we remember what 
 had been the early formative influences in Mill's case. Unlike 
 his father and Bentham, he saw clearly that if we would im- 
 prove upon the past, we must begin by understanding it, and 
 by learning from it. In this connection, Mill pays a very high 
 compliment to what he calls the ' Germano-Coleridgean ' 
 school. He says : " They were the first (except a solitary 
 thinker here and there) who inquired with any comprehensive- 
 ness or depth, into the inductive laws of the existence and 
 growth of human society. . . . They thus produced, not a piece 
 
 ^ See Autobiography, p. 154. 
 
 2 See Dissertations, vol. I., pp. 393 et seq. 'Ibid., p. 397.
 
 2 1 2 Histojy of Utilitarianism, 
 
 of party advocacy, but a philosophy of society, in the onh 
 form in which it is yet possible, that of a philosophy of his- 
 tory ; not a defence of particular ethical or religious doctrines, 
 but a contribution, the largest made by any class of thinkers, 
 towards the philosophy of human culture." ^ 
 
 If Mill is to be criticised here, it must certainly be for con- 
 ceding, not too little, but too much to those who had attempted 
 to formulate a Philosophy of History. Indeed, as criticism of 
 the school of thought which he is examining, this is not 
 calculated to impress the reader ; but, considered from an- 
 other point of view, it is most important for those who would 
 understand the difference between the new Utilitarianism 
 (which practically dates from these earlier writings of Mill) 
 and the old. The older form of the doctrine had been abstract 
 in the extreme. Man had been considered as an isolated 
 unit, moved in all respects by considerations of his own 
 pleasure-pain, which, of course, made his social relations ex- 
 traneous. This was, indeed, the natural view for those who 
 started from, and throughout depended upon, the analytical 
 method. But writers like Mill began to see that morality, like 
 everything else, had had a development ; that there were 
 ' laws of permanence ' and ' laws of progress ' for society : 
 and that our theorising in Ethics, in order to be sound, must 
 be based upon at least a general comprehension of these 
 laws. 
 
 This transition from the abstract to the (at least partially) 
 concrete method of treatment was of the greatest importance 
 for Utilitarianism. It is true that the doctrine rapidly lost 
 much of its original simplicity, that many of its defenders, 
 prominently Mill himself, fell into more or less palpable con- 
 tradictions ; but the compensations were great. More and 
 more the doctrine came into touch with the historical and 
 with the truly scientific spirit ; more and more it was made 
 to square with the moral consciousness ; and if the result 
 does not seem to most of us to have been a triumph for the 
 
 1 See p. 425.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 213 
 
 doctrine itself, it has certainly been to advance ethical theory, 
 and to show that the original hard and fast distinction between 
 hedonistic and non-hedonistic theory was based upon a mis- 
 conception. In short, we have learned as much from Mill 
 and his successors as from their antagonists, that, if we would 
 know the truth about Ethics, we must go back to Bishop 
 Butler, and base our theory, not upon one side of human 
 nature, but upon human nature as a whole. 
 
 That this interest in what he was content to call by the 
 rather vague name ' Philosophy of History ' was by no means 
 a passing phase in Mill's own intellectual development, is 
 shown by several of his best known essays published shortly 
 after that on Coleridge, viz., M. de Toqueville on Democracy 
 in America (published later in 1840), Michelefs History of 
 France (1844), and Giiizot's Essays and Lectures on History 
 (1845). It would be quite aside from our purpose to examine 
 these essays at all in detail, but a few things may properly be 
 noted. While Mill regards England as decidedly behind the 
 continent in the scientific writing of history (though he has the 
 most cordial, and, indeed, somewhat uncritical, praise for 
 Carlyle's French Revolution^, it is evidently the current his- 
 torical literature of France, rather than of Germany, with 
 which he is thoroughly acquainted at first hand. This takes 
 away something from the force of his frank preference for the 
 current French histories. Mill recognises three stages ^ in 
 the evolution of historical method: (i) the naive stage, which 
 is characterised by constantly reading present conceptions 
 into the past ; (2) the merely accurate stage, which describes 
 the facts as nearly as possible as they were, but without enter- 
 ing at all elaborately into the causes of progress or decadence ; 
 and (3) the ' scientific ' stage, where these causes are them- 
 selves subjected to the most thorough investigation. It is 
 this third stage that the author has generally in mind when 
 he speaks of the ' Philosophy of History,' though he hardly 
 uses the term with perfect consistency. If these essays con- 
 
 ^ See Dissertations, vol. II., pp. 124 et seq.
 
 2 14 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 tain little or nothing that is strictly original, and nothing 
 directly applying to Ethics, it is certainly interesting to find 
 the late disciple of Bentham making clear to his countrymen, 
 as Michelet and others (not holding a brief for the Church) 
 had made clear in their historical writings, how enormous had 
 been the debt of Europe during the Middle Ages to the 
 Catholic Church. Hardly less interesting is it when, in the 
 essay on Guizot, he says that, when the history of the Middle 
 Ages comes to be adequately treated, it will be universally 
 recognised " that at no period of history was human intellect 
 more active, or society more unmistakably in a state of rapid 
 advance, than during a great part of the so much vilified 
 feudal period ".^ Plainly Mill is no longer under the spell 
 of the eighteenth century. 
 
 In speaking of the later essays mentioned above, we have 
 left unmentioned the fact that, as the reader will remember. 
 Mill's System of Logic had been published in 1843. The 
 sixth book of the Logic, which appears to have been written 
 in 1 840, dealt with the " Logic of the Moral Sciences ". This 
 will call for careful consideration later, but first it will be 
 desirable to notice Mill's well-known essay, Dr. Whewell on 
 Moral Philosophy (1852).^ This is quite different in tone 
 from the essays which had immediately preceded it. For the 
 most part, those had been decidedly appreciative of ten- 
 dencies of thought very different from those to which the 
 author had been subjected in childhood and early youth ; 
 and, if the essay on Coleridge is hardly a success as a sym- 
 pathetic study, it is at least a good deal more conciliatory 
 in tone than the one on Bentham, which had been published 
 in the same periodical {London and Westminster Review) 
 two years before. In this essay on Whewell, it must be con- 
 fessed that Mill's tolerance breaks down. This may have 
 been partly due to the fact that his marriage with Mrs. Taylor 
 had taken place the year before, and that her mfluence here, 
 as certainly later, had been in the direction of confirming 
 
 ^ See Dissertations, vol. II., p. 273. 
 ^ Westminster Review, October, 1852.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 215 
 
 him in the earlier and more uncompromising form of his 
 doctrine. But it should also be remembered that Whewell's 
 writings were specially calculated to arouse a polemical atti- 
 tude in a critic belonging to the Utilitarian school, for, doubt- 
 less without in the least intending it, he had managed to give 
 his contemporaries a lamentably warped and distorted notion 
 of what Utilitarianism really was. 
 
 With most of Mill's particular criticisms of Whewell, we are, 
 of course, not here concerned ; but two of them have an im- 
 portant bearing upon the general question as to the end of 
 moral action, and so demand notice. Whewell had allowed 
 himself, in a rather rhetorical passage, to use some very 
 characteristic question-begging epithets. As Mill says : " He 
 appropriates to his own side of the question all the expressions, 
 such as conscience, duty, rectitude, with which the reverential 
 feelings of mankind towards moral ideas are associated. . . . 
 Dr. Whewell is assuming to himself what belongs quite as 
 rightfully to his antagonists. We are as much for conscience, 
 duty, rectitude, as Dr. Whewell. The terms, and all the 
 feelings connected with them, are as much a part of the ethics 
 of utility as of that of intuition. The point in dispute is, 
 what acts are the proper objects of those feelings ; whether 
 we ought to take the feelings as we find them, as accident or 
 design has made them, or whether the tendency of actions 
 to promote happiness affords a test to which the feelings of 
 morality should conform. In the same spirit. Dr. Whewell 
 announces it as his opinion, as the side he takes in this great 
 controversy, ' that we must do what is right, at whatever cost 
 of pain and loss '. As if this were not everybody's opinion ; 
 as if it was not the very meaning of the word right. The 
 matter in debate is, what is right, not whether what is right 
 ought to be done. Dr. Whewell represents his opponents as 
 denying an identical proposition, in order that he may claim 
 a monopoly of high principle for his own opinions. The same 
 unfairness pervades the whole phraseology." ^ 
 
 It cannot be too strongly insisted that, while Mill expresses 
 
 ' See Dissertations, vol. II., pp. 459, 460.
 
 2 1 6 History of UtilitaHanism. 
 
 himself with perhaps needless emphasis, he is perfectly right 
 here, not only as against Whewell, but as against the question- 
 begging procedure of many later anti-hedonistic writers. The 
 facts of our moral experience are what they are ; their ex- 
 planation is quite a different matter. Since our principal 
 interest here is historical, however, it may be well to pause a 
 moment, in order to see how it was possible that contemporary 
 writers of such undoubted intellectual eminence as Mill and 
 Whewell should be at issue on so seemingly simple a matter. 
 The fact is, that the Utilitarianism which Mill is here uphold- 
 ing is something quite different from the narrower Utilitarian- 
 ism of the preceding generation, to which (hardly with justice) 
 Whewell had continued to direct his criticisms. It is 
 broader and deeper, more in touch with the ordinary moral 
 and religious consciousness. But there was some excuse for 
 the Utilitarians of the earlier generation, if they were inclined 
 to look a little askance at the vocabulary of conventional 
 ethical discussion, inasmuch as these very terms were being 
 constantly thrust in their faces, as if they were in themselves 
 conclusive arguments against any attempt at a scientific ex- 
 planation of the moral life. 
 
 Not less suggestive than the preceding, is Mill's answer 
 to Whewell's contention that Utilitarianism must fall to the 
 ground, because we cannot calculate all the consequences of 
 any action. This, unfortunately, is too long to be quoted at 
 large ; but the general line of argument may be gathered 
 from the following. " If Dr. Whewell can point out any 
 department of human affairs in which we can do all that would 
 be desirable, he will have found something new. But because 
 we cannot foresee everything, is there no such thing as fore- 
 sight.-* . . . Dr. Whewell, in his zeal against the morality of 
 consequences, commits the error of proving too much. 
 Whether morality is or is not a question of consequences, he 
 cannot deny that prudence is ; and, if there is such a thing 
 as prudence, it is because the consequences of actions can 
 be calculated Prudence, indeed, depends on a calculation of 
 consequences of individual actions, while for the establish-
 
 John Stuart Mill. 217 
 
 ment of moral rules it is only necessary to calculate the 
 consequences of classes of actions — a much easier matter." ^ 
 But if it be urged that, even so, Utilitarian morality seems to 
 admit of possible exceptions to its own general rules, Mill 
 shows that it is in no worse case than other forms of ethical 
 theory. He says : " That the moralities arising from the 
 special circumstances of the action may be so important as to 
 overrule those arising from the class of acts to which it 
 belongs, perhaps to take it out of the category of virtues into 
 that of crimes, or vkc versa, is a liability common to all ethical 
 systems "? 
 
 What Mill says here is quite true, but he might easily have 
 made his case even stronger. An ethical writer who shuts 
 his eyes to the evident fact, that a conscientious moral agent 
 is sometimes confronted with duties, both of the highest order, 
 which apparently conflict, hardly deserves the attention of 
 any serious reader. And yet there is a manifest tendency, 
 even at the present time, for non-hedonistic writers to point 
 triumphantly to these concrete difficulties of the moral life 
 (which, of course, may be distressing in the extreme to a really 
 conscientious person), as if, in themselves, such difficulties were 
 a refutation of Utilitarianism. Nothing could be more ridi- 
 culously unfair. The difficulties just referred to, be it ob- 
 served, are practical before they are theoretical — i.e., the 
 question what is right in this particular case arises before the 
 question why is the one action or the other right. The 
 theoretical difficulty, therefore, arises for any system of Ethics 
 which attempts to explain our moral life. To say that these 
 difficulties of actual moral experience are not difficulties for 
 one's own particular type of ethical theory, is in itself enough 
 to condemn the theory utterly. In cases like those just men- 
 tioned, is the Self-realisation theory, e.g., one whit better 
 off than Utilitarianism ? Certainly not. The question of 
 ' more ' or ' less,' ' whole ' or ' part,' is much more extensive 
 than that of the hedonistic calculus. If it is difficult, in these 
 
 ' See Dissertations, vol. II., pp. 473, 474. - See p. 477.
 
 2 1 8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 hopelessly perplexing cases, to say which of two possible 
 courses of action will bring more happiness to the greater 
 number, is it easier to say which conduces more to self-realisa- 
 tion ? Merely to put the question, is to answer it. 
 
 But while there is no logical justification for using against 
 Utilitarianism the practical difficulties of our moral life — which 
 are bound to remain difficulties for any form of ethical theor>' 
 worthy of the name — there is an historical explanation for this 
 still prevailing tendency, which is rather interesting. In spite 
 of the undoubted variety of ethical theory which appears 
 in the course of the development of English Ethics, the per- 
 ennial conflict, almost down to the time that we are consider- 
 ing, had been between the various forms of Intuitionism and 
 those of Hedonism. Now the earlier Intuitionism tended to 
 refer back to a few convenient ' first principles,' and discount 
 explanations ; while Utilitarianism, with all its faults and 
 weaknesses, which certainly were many, did try to provide 
 explanations. The result was that the ' burden of proof ' 
 was constantly shifted to the side of the Utilitarian. If he 
 could not explain away the difficulties outstanding, then In- 
 tuitionism was supposed to hold the field. In the past two 
 generations, we have pretty generally outgrown this naive 
 method of argument (which the present writer would by no 
 means attribute to thoughtful Intuitionists of the present day), 
 seeing that it is generally admitted, that it is incumbent on one 
 form of ethical theory not less than another to offer explana- 
 tions that shall be satisfactory to the scientific intelligence.
 
 CHAPTER XI. 
 
 JOHN STUART MILL {continued). 
 
 Having traced the development of Mill's views on Ethics, 
 by means of the Autobiography and his contributions to 
 various periodicals, from his first stage of enthusiastic Ben- 
 thamism to what proved his relatively permanent, if not 
 strictly final, position, we are now prepared to give careful at- 
 tention to his later writings, which, though in no case amount- 
 ing to a systematic treatment of Ethics, have at least the 
 substantial advantage of being constructive and not merely 
 critical. And first we have to notice Book VI. of his System 
 of Logic, "On the Logic of the Moral Sciences". Here, 
 indeed, as regards the chronological order, we have to retrace 
 our steps. In the last chapter, it seemed best to include our 
 mention of the essays on Michelet (1844), Guizot (1845), ^-^^^ 
 Whewell's Moral Philosophy (1852), in order that the critical 
 essays, later as well as earlier, might be considered together. 
 The sixth book of the Logic was probably written in 1840, 
 i.e., in the same year as the essays on Coleridge and De 
 Toqueville. The Logic was not published, however, till 1843, 
 and we shall use the text of the standard eighth edition 
 (1872). 
 
 Mill begins his treatment of the " Logic of the Moral 
 Sciences " by remarking that, while we are practically agreed 
 as to the method of investigation to be employed where the 
 physical nature of man is concerned, this is by no means the 
 case where the laws of mind, and especially those of society, 
 are in question. In truth, it is even a matter of controversy 
 whether these are capable of strictly scientific treatment. 
 
 (219)
 
 2 20 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 But if we are really in earnest with these sciences, true scien- 
 tific method must be applied here also ; and general scientific 
 method is always one and the same thing. Now, Mill says, 
 " at the threshold of this inquiry we are met by an objection, 
 which, if not removed, would be fatal to the attempt to treat 
 human conduct as a subject of science. Are the actions of 
 human beings, like all other natural events, subject to invari- 
 able laws ? " 1 
 
 This, of course, raises the whole controversy concerning the 
 freedom of the will, which, from at least the time of Pelagius, 
 has divided both the philosophical and the religious world. 
 We find one side holding the doctrine of necessity, which 
 regards human volitions and actions as necessary and inevi- 
 table ; while the other side " maintains that the will is not 
 determined, like other phenomena, by antecedents, but deter- 
 mines itself ; that our volitions are not, properly speaking, the 
 effects of causes, or at least have no causes which they uni- 
 formly and implicitly obey "? Mill complains of the mislead- 
 ing terms in which these doctrines are commonly set forth ; 
 and. in particular, he objects to the use of the word ' necessity,' 
 as standing for determinism. Correctly understood, the doc- 
 trine called ' Philosophical Necessity ' is merely this : that if 
 we could know perfectly the motives present in the agent's 
 mind, and also his character and disposition, we would be able 
 to predict his action in a given case, just as we would be able 
 to predict any physical event, if we could know all the con- 
 ditions. Now our assurance of this does not conflict in the 
 slightest degree with our ' feeling of freedom,' so constantly 
 appealed to in this controversy. We may be free, and yet it 
 may be practically certain to those who know us best, how 
 we will use our freedom in a given case. And if this be true 
 in the simpler cases, why would it not also be found true in 
 the more complex ones, if only the observer could have an 
 adequate knowledge of the character and circumstances ? 
 
 Thus far, as will be seen, Mill's argument is merely the con- 
 
 ^ See Logic, vol. II., p. 419. -Ibid., p. 421.
 
 John Stuart MilL 221 
 
 ventional one for determinism. At this point, however, he 
 attempts to silence the scruples of the libertarian in a rather 
 peculiar way. What really troubles the libertarian, he thinks, 
 is the idea of compulsion commonly associated with the idea 
 of causality. We feel that we are not compelled, as by some 
 magical force, to obey a particular motive ; and we are quite 
 right. " But neither is any such mysterious compulsion now 
 supposed, by the best philosophical authorities, to be exer- 
 cised by any other cause over its effect." ^ In short, reduce 
 the conception of causality to that of invariable sequence, and 
 Mill seems to think that little or nothing remains, to which 
 the libertarian can object. It is rather difficult to take this 
 quite seriously. Most certainly it is proper, when discussing 
 freedom of the will, to clarify our ideas as much as possible 
 on the general subject of causality ; but the plain fact is, that 
 what libertarians have always mainly objected to in deter- 
 minism (whether rightly or wrongly), has been the putting of 
 physical and mental causality on the same plane. It will 
 readily be seen that, however we might see fit to modify our 
 general conception of causality, this difficulty would remain 
 exactly what it was before. 
 
 Mill goes on to show, by the usual Hne of argument, that 
 determinism and fatalism are two very different doctrines ; 
 but he rather surprises one, almost at the beginning of his 
 discussion, by remarking that the determinist (or ' necessi- 
 tarian,' as he calls him), " is apt to be, with more or less of con- 
 sciousness on his part, a fatalist as to his own actions, and to 
 believe that his nature is such, or that his education and 
 circumstances have so moulded his character, that nothing can 
 now prevent him from feeling and acting in a particular way, 
 or at least that no effort of his own can hinder it " ? This is 
 not an isolated instance of the facility with which Mill can at 
 times confuse metaphysical issues. And in this particular 
 case, the effect is, quite needlessly to detract from the force 
 of his own argument. In short, he confuses fatalism (the 
 
 1 See p. 423. 2 gee p, 425.
 
 222 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 doctrine that what is to happen will happen, all ordinary 
 causes to the contrary notwithstanding) with a view which he 
 attributes to many determinists regarding the unchangeability 
 of individual character. li. has often been shown — in recent 
 years, e.g., by Fouillee ^ — that the doctrine of fatalism does 
 not arise from too much, but from too little, attention being 
 paid to the ascertainable causes of human actions. Now the 
 class of determinists to which Mill refers, and which can hardly 
 have been as large as his language would seem to indicate, 
 were doubtless wrong in over-emphasising the ' unchange- 
 ability of character ' ; but this does not at all make them 
 fatalists. They, as much as Mill himself, were in search of 
 the ascertainable causes ; they, as much as he, were prepared 
 to admit that actual effort in opposition to the unfortunate 
 tendencies of one's own character would have its effect : they 
 simply made the serious mistake of exaggerating what we may 
 call the ' inertia ' of individual character. 
 
 But, while Mill's discussion is hardly satisfactory as a treat- 
 ment of the metaphysical question of freedom, it throws an 
 interesting light upon his own ethical theory, for he goes, if 
 anything, to the extreme in his view of the extent to which 
 we may change our own characters. He begins by very 
 properly remarking that, while the individual's character is 
 formed by his circumstances, " his own desire to mould it in 
 a particular way, is one of those circumstances, and by no 
 means one of the least influential ". And he proceeds to 
 show that we are exactly as capable of making our own 
 character, if we will, as others are of making it for us. Later 
 he makes the more original remark that, "if we examine 
 closely, we shall find that this feeling, of our being able to 
 modify our own character if we wish, is itself the feeling of 
 moral freedom which we are conscious of".^ And he con- 
 cludes this phase of the discussion by making the following 
 suggestive observation. " The free-will doctrine, by keep- 
 
 ^ See ha liherte et le diterminisme, ch. ii. 
 - See p. 427.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 223 
 
 irig in view precisely that portion of the truth which the word 
 Necessity puts out of sight, namely the power of the mind to 
 co-operate in the formation of its own character, has given to 
 its adherents a practical feeling much nearer to the truth 
 than has generally (I believe} existed in the minds of necessi- 
 tarians. The latter may have had a stronger sense of the 
 importance of what human beings can do to shape the char- 
 acters of one another ; but the free-will doctrine has, I believe, 
 fostered in its supporters a much stronger spirit of self- 
 culture." 
 
 Now what shall be said of the possibility of a science of 
 human nature ? In the preceding discussion, according to 
 Mill, we have seen no reason for denying that human actions 
 take place according to laws. But any class of phenomena, 
 subject to laws, is legitimate subject-matter for a science. 
 The mere difficulty of ascertaining all the laws, is not as seri- 
 ous as might at first appear. Take the case of meteorology: 
 Nobody doubts that the phenomena with which this science 
 attempts to deal are subject to law ; and the extreme com- 
 plexity of the phenomena, and the resulting difficulty of ascer- 
 taining the precise nature of the particular laws involved, 
 does not by any means keep the scientist from making them 
 the object of most careful research. This, to be sure, is the 
 case of a very imperfect science ; but we need not look 
 far to find a science midway between this condition of ex- 
 treme imperfection and the relative perfection of the more 
 developed physical sciences. The theory of the tides, 'Tidol- 
 ogy,' as Dr. Whewell proposes to call it, is a convenient 
 example. What depends on the attraction of the sun and 
 moon is perfectly understood, and the results can be accurately 
 predicted even tor an unknown, but definite, part of the earth's 
 surface. But circumstances of a local nature, like the char- 
 acter of the sea-bottom, the degree of confinement from 
 shores, the prevailing direction of the winds, etc., come in to 
 complicate. These can be partly calculated and allowed for, 
 but not completely, with the result that the actual tides in 
 given places do not precisely agree with our predictions.
 
 224 History of Utilitarianis^n. 
 
 Still the approximation is sufficient to make ' Tidology * not 
 only a science, like meteorology, but a science largely avail- 
 able in practice, as meteorology has not (or in Mill's day had 
 not yet) become. 
 
 Now this is all that is, or should be, meant by sciences 
 that are not ' exact sciences '. Once having admitted that 
 human actions are conformable to law, there is no reason 
 why the science of human nature should not, in time, become 
 as much of a science as ' Tidology '. And one thing should 
 never be forgotten. Even if the science of human nature 
 could conceivably become perfect, which is absurd, certain 
 prediction could be made only on the basis of complete data 
 in the given case, which, of course, we never can have. We 
 must not, therefore, underrate the probable usefulness of this 
 proposed science, which, for obvious reasons, must to the end 
 remain imperfect. Mill says : " An approximate generalisa- 
 tion is, in social inquiries, for most practical purposes equi- 
 valent to an exact one : that which is only probable when 
 asserted of individual human beings indiscriminately selected, 
 being certain when affirmed of the character and collective 
 conduct of masses ".^ 
 
 After giving a brief outline of his own psychological views, 
 which need not detain us, since it consists merely in the 
 reaffirmation of the general principles of the traditional As- 
 sociationist school (particularly as represented by James Mill's 
 Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind), Mill passes 
 on to a consideration of * Ethology,' the proposed new ' science 
 of the formation of character '. And first he calls attention 
 to what he has already, when treating of induction, had 
 occasion to call ' empirical laws '. Such a law is " an uni- 
 formity, whether of succession or of coexistence, which holds 
 true in all instances within our limits of observation, but is 
 not of a nature to afford any assurance that it would hold 
 beyond those limits "?■ General observations on human 
 affairs, collected from common experience, are precisely of 
 this nature. The really scientific truths which we are seek- 
 
 ' See p. 434. ■^ See p. 448.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 225 
 
 ing, however, are not these ' empirical laws,' but the causal 
 laws which explain them. The ' empirical laws,' in fact, are 
 at best almost always a more or less vague statement of the 
 complex result of the operation of two or more laws of the 
 scientific kind. 
 
 What, then, is the proper method of investigation for Ethol- 
 ogy ? Nobody who realises the extreme complexity of the 
 phenomena to be explained can be seriously in doubt. Taken 
 by itself, the inductive method would be almost useless, by 
 reason of the amount of material to be treated and the result- 
 ing confusion. The deductive method, surely, which sets out 
 from general laws (in this case, those of mind), and verifies 
 their consequences by specific experience, is alone applicable. 
 In fact, there are but two methods of discovering the laws of 
 nature, the deductive method just mentioned and that of 
 experimentation. But experimentation is obviously impos- 
 sible here, and, if possible, experiments could not be per- 
 formed with any approach to scientific accuracy. The 
 deductive method, then, is our only resource. Mill says: 
 " The laws of the formation of character are, in short, deriva- 
 tive laws, resulting from the general laws of mind ; and are 
 to be obtained by deducing them from those general laws ; 
 by supposing any given set of circumstances, and then con- 
 sidering what, according to the laws of mind, will be the 
 influence of those circumstances on the formation of char- 
 acter ".1 This new science, then, is to be called Ethology, or 
 the Science of Character. It is the science which corresponds 
 to the art of education in the widest sense, including the for- 
 mation of national or collective character, as well as in- 
 dividual. If the possible results in this direction are not all 
 that could be desired, we must remember that a degree of 
 knowledge far short of the power of actual prediction, is often 
 of much practical value. " It is enough that we know that 
 certain means have a tendency to produce a given effect, and 
 that others have a tendency to frustrate it." ^ 
 
 1 See p. 457. '^ See p. 458. 
 
 15
 
 226 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 The relation between Ethology and Psychology must always 
 be kept clearly in mind. Mill says : " While on the one hand 
 Psychology is altogether, or principally, a science of obser- 
 vation and experiment, Ethology, as I have conceived it, is, 
 as I have already remarked, altogether deductive. The one 
 ascertains the simple laws of Mind in general, the other traces 
 their operation in complex combinations of circumstances. 
 Ethology stands to Psychology in a relation very similar to 
 that in which the various branches of natural philosophy 
 stand to mechanics. The principles of Ethology are properly 
 the middle principles, the axiomata media (as Bacon would 
 have said) of the science of mind : as distinguished, on the 
 one hand from the empirical laws resulting from simple ob- 
 servation, and on the other from the highest generalisations." ^ 
 And, in this connection. Mill naturally quotes Bacon's famous 
 observation, that the axiomata media of every science prin- 
 cipally constitute its value. 
 
 Such, then, is the greatly needed science of Ethology, with- 
 out which, in Mill's view, there can be no truly scientific 
 Sociology. The remainder of the sixth book of the Logic is 
 devoted to a criticism of what the author regards as false 
 methods, and an elaboration of what he regards as the true 
 method, of the latter science. But we cannot follow Mill 
 further in this direction. As would be surmised, since Ethol- 
 ogy is regarded as the necessary connecting-lmk between 
 Psychology and Sociology, the proper method of Sociology 
 is held to be deductive also — " not," as the author explains, 
 "after the model of geometry, but after that of the more 
 complex physical sciences ".- 
 
 It is hardly necessary to state that Mill had to give up his 
 project of founding the new science of Ethology, and that 
 this made impossible the further, and more considerable, task 
 of writing a work on Sociology along the lines laid down in 
 the last part of the sixth book of the Logic. Such being the 
 ease, it may seem needless to have examined Mill's treatment 
 
 ' See p. 458. 2 See pt 488.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 227 
 
 of the Logic of the Moral Sciences at such length. This has 
 been done, however, for a very definite reason. It will be 
 remembered that the first draft of the sixth book of the Logic 
 was probably written in 1840, only two years after the publi- 
 cation of the important essay on Bentham. In that remark- 
 able but perplexing critique, Bentham's great merit in Ethics 
 was held to have been his attempt to apply ordinary scientific 
 method to the subject matter of that science. It was not 
 claimed that the net result of his attempt was specially im- 
 portant, but the attempt itself was regarded as little less than 
 epoch-making. It might seem to one reading the essay on 
 Bentham without reference to Mill's other works, that the 
 writer was here giving rather perfunctory praise to the elder 
 moralist, whom he felt obliged in most respects to criticise so 
 severely. But Mill's own perfectly serious attempt in the 
 same general direction, which we have just been considering 
 a good deal in detail, proves conclusively the contrary. To 
 be sure, the science of Ethology was not to be a substitute 
 for Ethics ; but it was once for all to furnish that discipline 
 with a strictly scientific basis. And in that sense (indirectly, 
 if not directly), Ethics was at last to come within the scope 
 of true scientific method. 
 
 Mill's inevitable failure here was, perhaps, as instructive 
 as success in some other direction would have been. For 
 success in this direction was found to be impossible, not 
 from any individual fault or weakness on the part of Mill, 
 but from the nature of the case. Whatever, in the last 
 analysis, Ethics may be thought to be, one may hold with 
 perfect confidence that it is not a natural science merely, 
 nor an art founded upon a natural science — which is as far 
 as possible from implying that it does not need to take 
 cognizance of all the facts of moral experience and develop- 
 ment that can pwDssibly be obtained. In short, Mill had not, 
 any more than the Evolutionists later, discovered a new 
 ' method,' which was to revolutionise Ethics. And it can 
 hardly be thought fanciful to suggest, that the essential 
 barrenness of the method outlined in this part of the Logic,
 
 2 28 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 and Mill's lack of success in carrying out even the initial 
 step in constructing, at least in outline, the new science of 
 Ethology, was one important reason why he never undertook 
 to write a systematic treatise on Ethics.^ 
 
 In following the development of Mill's ethical views, it 
 seems necessary here to depart from the order of publication. 
 The reason will appear from the following passage, taken from 
 the ' Introductory Notice' prefixed by Miss Helen Taylor to 
 three of Mill's essays, Nature^ The Utility of Religion, and 
 Theism, first published (together) in 1874, the year following 
 Mill's death. " The two first of these three Essays were 
 written between the years 1850 and 1858, during the period 
 which intervened between the publication of the Principles 
 of Political Economy [1848], and that of the work on Liberty 
 [1859] ; during which interval three other Essays — on Justice, 
 on Utility, and on Liberty — were also composed. Of the five 
 Essays written at that time, three have already been given to 
 the public by the Author. That on Liberty was expanded into 
 the now well-known work bearing the same title. Those on 
 Justice and Utility were afterwards incorporated, with some 
 alterations and additions, into one, and published under the 
 name of UtilitM'ianisni [1863]. The remaining two — on 
 Nature and on the Utility of Religion — are now given to the 
 public, with the addition of a third — on Theism — ^which was 
 produced at a much later period. . . . [This last] was written 
 between the years 1868 and 1870, but it was not designed as 
 a sequel to the two Essays which now appear along with it, 
 nor were they intended to appear all together." This definite 
 statement, from one who had such exceptional opportunities 
 to know the exact facts of the case, must be accepted as 
 authoritative. And the information which it conveys is in- 
 teresting. The essay on " Nature " and that on the " Utility 
 of Religion " may confidently be attributed to the period dur- 
 
 ^ It is rather strange that this chapter was not thoroughly revised, after MilJ 
 had given up the projected science of Ethology as an impossibility.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 229 
 
 ing which the first draft of Liberty and that of Utilitarianism 
 were written. Moreover, since these two essays were appar- 
 ently not recast, like the others, they may properly be con- 
 sidered first. 
 
 When Mill wrote the essay on " Nature," he must already 
 have given up the project of writing a book on Ethology, for, 
 according to Professor Bain.^ his disappointment in this re- 
 spect was what led him to go on with the Political Economy, 
 which, as will be remembered, was published in 1848. Thus 
 much, at any rate, his position must have changed since the 
 time when he wrote the sixth book of the Logic. What he 
 seems to have proposed to himself, in writing the essay which 
 we are to examine, was neither to attack the defunct doctrine 
 of Laws of Nature, nor precisely to attack Natural Theology, 
 but to clear up, as far as might be, what he regarded as the 
 fatally ambiguous, and often question-begging, use of the 
 concept * nature ' in ethical speculation. How, then, is the 
 word ' nature ' actually used in philosophical discussions .'' 
 In one definite and justifiable sense, it may be taken to mean 
 " the sum of all phenomena, together with the causes which 
 produce them; including not only all that happens, but all 
 that is capable of happening ; the unused capabiHties of causes 
 being as much a part of the idea of Nature, as those which 
 take effect "? But ' nature ' is constantly used in a popular 
 sense, as opposed to that which is ' artificial '. This obviously 
 conflicts with the preceding (strictly scientific) definition, ac- 
 cording to which art is as much a part of nature as anything 
 else, since it is a part of the universal world-process. 
 
 Such being the two principal senses of the word ' nature,' 
 in which sense, if either, is it used to convey ideas of com- 
 mendation, approval, and even moral obligation ? For that 
 the word is thus used, even at the present time, seems to Mill 
 beyond question. He says : " Though perhaps no one could 
 now be found who, like the institutional writers of former 
 
 1 See J. S. Mill : a Criticism, p. 79. 
 
 2 See Three Essays on Religion, p. 5.
 
 230 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 times, adopts the so-called Law of Nature as the foundation of 
 ethics, and endeavours consistently to reason from it, the 
 word and its cognates must still be counted among those 
 which carry great weight in moral argumentation " } It looks 
 at first, indeed, as if we were confronted with another actual 
 use of the word ' nature ' at the very threshold of our investi- 
 gation. "All inquiries are either into what is, or into what 
 ought to be : science and history belonging to the first divi- 
 sion, art, morals, and politics to the second. But the two 
 senses of the word Nature first pointed out, agree in referring 
 only to what is." Mill does not, however, admit a third use 
 of the word here. He says : " Those who say that we ought 
 to act according to Nature do not mean the mere identical 
 proposition that we ought to do what we ought to do. They 
 think that the word Nature affords some external criterion 
 of what we should do . . . they have a notion, either clearly 
 or confusedly, that what is, constitutes the rule and standard 
 of what ought to be." ^ Such, then, is the view which is to 
 be examined in the present essay. 
 
 Now, when we are told to ' follow nature ' in moral conduct, 
 is * nature ' understood in what we have called the first, or 
 philosophical sense } Manifestly not, for then the admonition 
 would have no meaning. We must follow nature, in this sense, 
 whether we will or no. The only moral precept that could 
 be given from this point of view would be, ' study nature ' ; 
 and, however, important this precept may be, it can only lead 
 to intelligent moral action. Right moral action, to be sure, 
 implies this, but also a great deal more. Clearly we have no 
 criterion of right conduct afforded here. But how would it 
 be, if we should take ' nature * in the second sense, as stand- 
 ing for that which takes place without human intervention } 
 Here the precept ' follow nature ' would be worse than super- 
 fluous and unmeaning ; it would be palpably absurd and self- 
 contradictory. Mill says : " If the artificial is not better than 
 the natural, to what end are all the arts of life } To dig, to 
 
 ^ See Three Essays on Religion, p. 11. ^ See p. 13.
 
 John Stuart MilL 231 
 
 plough, to build, to wear clothes, are direct infringements of 
 the injunction to follow nature. . . . All praise of Civilisation, 
 or Art, or Contrivance, is so much dispraise of Nature ; an 
 admission of imperfection, which it is man's business, and 
 merit, to be always endeavouring to correct or mitigate.' ^ 
 
 We must evidently look further, if we would understand the 
 real hold which this vague principle still has in the minds of 
 thinking men. Mill argues that this principle in the last re- 
 sort depends upon the view that, since nature is the work of 
 God, we may and do find in nature distinct traces of a divine 
 moral order, which, of course, it is our duty to imitate. Here, 
 obviously, we come to close quarters with Natural Theology. 
 But before proceeding further, we must divest ourselves of 
 certain preconceptions. We are often reminded of the awe 
 which thoughtful men feel in the presence of some of the 
 mightier aspects of nature. This awe, however, has no 
 strictly moral significance ; in fact, we feel it most, when view- 
 ing (at a sufficient distance) the phenomena of nature which 
 are most capable of inflicting harm upon man. After this 
 brief warning, the author comes to close quarters with the 
 essential question at once ; and his arraignment of ' nature,' 
 taken as a moral order, is rather striking, if somewhat rhetori- 
 cal and not wholly relevant 
 
 He says : " In sober truth, nearly all the things which men 
 are hanged or imprisoned for doing to one another, are nature's 
 everyday performances. Killing, the most criminal act re- 
 cognised by hiunan laws. Nature does once to every being 
 that lives ; and in a large proportion of cases, after protracted 
 tortures such as only the greatest monsters whom we read of 
 ever purposely inflicted on their living fellow-creatures. . . . 
 All this, Nature does with the most supercilious disregard 
 both of mercy and of justice, emptying her shafts upon the 
 best and noblest indifferently with the meanest and worst ; 
 upon those who are engaged in the highest and worthiest 
 enterprises, and often as the direct consequence of the noblest 
 
 ^ See pp. 20, 21.
 
 232 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 acts ; and it might almost be imagined as a punishment for 
 them. . . . Next to taking Hfe (equal to it according to a high 
 authority) is taking the means by which we live ; and Nature 
 does this too on the largest scale and with the most callous 
 indifference. A single hurricane destroys the hopes of a 
 season ; a flight of locusts, or an inundation, desolates a dis- 
 trict ; a trifling chemical change in an edible root, starves a 
 million of people. . . . All which people are accustomed to 
 deprecate as ' disorder ' and its consequences, is precisely a 
 counterpart of Nature's ways. Anarchy and the Reign of 
 Terror are overmatched in injustice, ruin, and death, by a 
 hurricane and a pestilence." ^ The argument that all things 
 are nevertheless ' for the best,' is not applicable here ; for, 
 if we are to imitate nature, it must be the nature that we 
 know, and not the hidden ways of a mysterious Providence. 
 Moreover, if good sometimes comes out of evil in the natural 
 course of things, it must not be forgotten that this is quite 
 as often the case with human crimes ; and, still further, it must 
 be recognised that it happens as frequently that evil comes out 
 of good. On the whole, however, good produces good, and 
 evil, evil. ' To him that hath shall be given.' 
 
 The inevitable conclusion for Mill is, that the order of 
 nature, as we know it, is not a moral order — or, at any rate, 
 only partially such. If an omnipotent God can will happiness, 
 and does will misery, there is but one legitimate conclusion. 
 But suppose that God has willed virtue instead of happiness. 
 Then we can only say that His purpose has been equally 
 frustrated. The natural theologians have failed lamentably 
 in that they have proved practically nothing by trying to prove 
 too much. " The only admissible moral theory of Creation 
 is that the Principle of Good cannot at once and altogether 
 subdue the powers of evil, either physical or moral ; . . . but 
 could and did make [man] capable of carrying on the fight 
 with vigour and with progressively increasing success." This 
 is evidently said by Mill, not in irony, but in perfect good 
 
 ^ See pp. 28-31.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 233 
 
 faith, for he goes on to show that this view, whether specula- 
 tively tenable or not, would really satisfy our moral nature. 
 He even goes so far as to add : " And I venture to assert that 
 such has really been, though often unconsciously, the faith 
 of all who have drawn strength and support of any worthy 
 kind from trust in a superintending Providence ".^ 
 
 But if only a part of the order of nature, at any rate, can 
 be as the Divine Being intended, it becomes highly im- 
 portant to discover what part. It would be most natural to 
 point out those primitive impulsive tendencies in man which, 
 not altogether fortunately, liave received the name ' instincts '. 
 Apart from the very serious difficulty of saying just what are 
 * instincts,' however, it remains true that nearly every respect- 
 able attribute of humanity is the result, not of instinct, but 
 of a victory over instinct. Only in a highly artificialised 
 condition of human nature, could the notion grow up, that 
 goodness was natural. Indeed, the victory over fear, one of 
 the most powerful emotions of human nature, shows how 
 artificial is the condition even of the savage. Sympathy, 
 though in a sense natural, requires a great deal of cultivation. 
 Veracity, one of the highest virtues, is plainly artificial, for all 
 savages are liars. And the same might be proved of all the 
 other virtues. 
 
 And here we come to what, for Mill, is the gist of the 
 whole matter. He says : " If it be said, that there must be 
 the germs of all these virtues in human nature, otherwise 
 mankind would be incapable of acquiring them, I am ready, 
 with a certain amount of explanation, to admit the fact. But 
 the weeds that dispute the ground with these beneficent germs, 
 are themselves not germs but rankly luxuriant growths, and 
 would, in all but some one case in a thousand, entirely stifle 
 and destroy the former, were it not so strongly the interest 
 of mankind to cherish the good germs in one another, that 
 they always do so, in as far as their degree of intelligence 
 {in this as in other respects still very imperfect) allows. . . . 
 
 1 See p. 39.
 
 234 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Even those gifted organisations which have attained the like 
 excellence by self-culture, owe it essentially to the same cause ; 
 for what self-culture would be possible without aid from 
 the general sentiment of mankind delivered through books, 
 and from the contemplation of exalted characters real or 
 ideal ? This artificially created or at least artificially perfected 
 nature of the best and noblest human beings, is the only 
 nature which it is ever commendable to follow." ^ Mill con- 
 cludes from the above and similar arguments, that " con- 
 formity to nature, has no connection whatever with right and 
 wrong ".^ 
 
 If it were worth while, one could easily show that this 
 essay is by no means a complete success as a piece of destruc- 
 tive criticism. Of the two senses which Mill allows to the 
 word ' nature,' the first or ' scientific ' sense is by no means 
 a common one in actual philosophical discussions — least of all 
 in ethical discussions — while the second meaning of the word, 
 in which it is merely opposed to ' artificial,' is left ambiguous. 
 If by natural, in this sense, we are to mean only what is his- 
 torically aboriginal, it is easy to prove that nothing of any 
 value in human life as we know it, particularly in the moral 
 life, is natural. But Shaftesbury had long ago shown the 
 absurdity of this use of the word ' natural '. In short, Mill 
 is unconsciously unjust to the real or supposed theory which 
 he is attempting to controvert, in his very statement of the 
 problem ; and if the theory had possessed more vitality, it 
 would hardly have been damaged by such criticism : but there 
 are two respects in which the essay is important, as defining 
 the author's own point of view. 
 
 First, this is the clearest statement we have of Mill's atti- 
 tude toward Natural Theology, with the exception of the 
 essay on Theism, also published in this volume, but belong- 
 ing, as already explained, to a much later period, and there- 
 fore less valuable as a commentary upon his strictly ethical 
 writings. He maintains, as we have seen, that the order of 
 
 ^ See pp. 53, 54. 2 ggg p_ 52.
 
 John Shcart Mill. 235 
 
 nature is not a moral order, but that, on the contrary, it 
 abounds in what we should condemn most strongly, if we 
 could know that it was the result of intention accompanied 
 by absolute power. If, then, there be a God of Nature 
 (divinely good, as we must on other grounds suppose). He 
 must be finite, and not infinite, as the theologians feel bound 
 to assume. In short, we must suppose that there are two 
 conflicting powers in the world, one making for good and 
 one making for evil. In this case, it will be our duty and 
 privilege to ally ourselves with the beneficent power ; and we 
 can have the assurance that, however, slight our influence 
 may be, it will really count, and count on the right side. All 
 this is hypothetical, however ; the implication seems to be 
 that there is not a sufficient basis for even such a Natural 
 Theology. On the other hand, it must be admitted that, if 
 such a theory does not wholly satisfy the mind, it does satisfy 
 the heart. There is nothing in it which, like the conventional 
 Natural Theology, is repugnant to our highest moral ideals. 
 In the essay on Theism, Mill's last work, he remains constant 
 to this view as to the moral aspect of the Manichasan doc- 
 trine — ^which, it will be remembered, he distinctly attributes 
 to his father in the Autobiography — the difference being, that 
 in the latter essay he seems to take a good deal more seriously 
 the general arguments for Theism. 
 
 Secondly, we must notice the bearing of this essay upon 
 Mill's view of human nature and the possibility of moral 
 development. This is not quite easy to state in exact terms. 
 The author is so concerned to disprove the theory that the 
 order of nature is essentially a moral order, that he very 
 nearly goes to the extreme of regarding it as not merely a 
 non-moral, but what we might call an anti-moral, order. In 
 other words, it looks as if he regarded the great forces of 
 nature as making for evil decidedly more than for good. But 
 if the general conditions and efficient forces, as much in man 
 himself as in the external world, are so strongly set against 
 the moral order, how can any artificial process of cultivating 
 the good and eliminating the evil in human nature, such as
 
 236 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 that which Mill describes, be regarded as sufficient? The 
 author seems to forget that, though cultivation may accom- 
 plish much, soil and climate, and, more particularly, the 
 original nature of the plant, are most important considerations. 
 Moreover, if we must employ this analogy, whence did the 
 desire to cultivate arise ? In the passage above quoted, Mill 
 has seemed to refer this to a tendency on the part of each to 
 encourage in others conduct calculated to conduce to his own 
 good. This was perfectly consistent with the older Utili- 
 tarianism, which admitted of an extreme separation between 
 the objective end of moral action and the motive of the moral 
 agent ; but such a view is hardly consistent with Mill's theory, 
 which admits a certain primitive altruistic tendency in human 
 nature. In short, it seems as if Mill, in arguing against a 
 somewhat naive form of Natural Theology, has overstated his 
 case, with results distinctly detrimental to his own ethical 
 system. 
 
 Let us now turn to the essay on the " Utility of Religion," 
 which, as already explained, belongs to the same period as 
 that which we have just been considering. The purpose of 
 this essay may be stated in a few words. If the dogmas of 
 religion must be regarded as certainly true, the ' utility ' of 
 religion follows as a matter of course. Our eternal weal or 
 woe depends upon our making it the guide of our lives. But 
 in a sceptical age like our own, when the theoretical grounds 
 of religious belief are freely investigated and by many found 
 wanting, such an inquiry can by no means be regarded as 
 gratuitous. Of course, it would be gratuitous, if we had 
 passed from perfect faith to complete doubt or negation ; 
 but nobody claims that this is the case. Now in this condition 
 of uncertainty as regards the theoretical grounds of religion, 
 it is natural that theologians should, perhaps unconsciously, 
 insist more and more upon the supposed fact of our absolute 
 need of religion as a moralising power, and that they should 
 hold that this indirectly affords a strong presumption of its 
 truth. Mill's purpose, then, is to investigate the questions .-
 
 John Stuart Mill. 237 
 
 (i) Is religion really, at the present time, as great a moralising 
 power as is constantly assumed ? (2) Even if so, is it the only 
 power capable of producing the desired results. 
 
 The keynote of the whole discussion is struck in the follow- 
 ing remark by the author. " It is usual to credit religion 
 as such with the whole of the power inherent in any system 
 of moral duties inculcated by education and enforced by 
 opinion." ^ The point, of course, is, that morality has almost 
 always been taught in connection with religion during the 
 past, so that we cannot assume, without further argument, 
 that an equally systematic non-religious moral education 
 would not produce equally good results. Mill first insists 
 upon the enormous influence of authority upon the human 
 mind. " Authority is the evidence on which the mass of man- 
 kind believe everything which they are said to know, except 
 facts of which their own senses have taken cognizance." 
 But next we have to consider the power of education. This, 
 the author confidently holds, is almost boundless. He even 
 goes so far as to say : " There is not one natural inclination 
 which it is not strong enough to coerce, and, if needful, to 
 destroy by disuse ". And he immediately adds, what, of 
 course, is most important to his argument : " In the greatest 
 recorded victory which education has ever achieved over a 
 whole host of natural inclinations in an entire people — the 
 maintenance through centuries of the institutions of Lycurgus 
 — it was very little, if even at all, indebted to religion. . . . 
 The root of the system was devotion to Sparta, to the ideal 
 of the country or State." If we would understand the possi- 
 bility of such a phenomenon, we must try to realise the full 
 meaning of public opinion. " The love of glory ; the love of 
 praise ; the love of admiration ; the love of respect and 
 deference ; even the love of sympathy, are portions of its 
 attractive power. . . . The fear of shame, the dread of ill- 
 repute or of being disliked or hated, are the direct and simple 
 forms of its deterring power." Moreover, "when once the 
 
 ^ See p. 77.
 
 238 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 means of living have been obtained, the far greater part of the 
 remaining labour and effort which takes place on the earth, 
 has for its object to acquire the respect or the favourable 
 regard of mankind ; to be looked up to, or at all events, not 
 to be looked down upon by them ".^ 
 
 Turning from this great and almost compelling force of 
 public opinion, let us examine what is peculiar to religious 
 teaching. It is not without significance. Mill thinks, that 
 preachers and religious writers are always complaining of the 
 inconsiderable effect that religious motives have, in ordinary 
 life, and this in spite of the tremendous penalties denounced. 
 The plain fact of the matter is, that the vagueness of men's 
 ideas of future retribution and their belief that, if they repent 
 before death, they will escape punishment altogether, take 
 away a great part of the terrors that might be expected to 
 attach to such a doctrine. When a strong present tempta- 
 tion arises, therefore, it is natural that it should often prevail. 
 But Mill does not dwell upon this aspect of the question, which 
 he rightly terms " the vulgarest part of it ". He is more 
 than ready to admit that the higher advocates of religion are 
 far from regarding it as " an auxiliary to the thief-catcher 
 and the hangman ". " In their view of the matter, the best of 
 mankind absolutely require religion for the perfection of their 
 own character, even though the coercion of the worst might 
 possibly be accomplished without its aid." ^ 
 
 But just here Mill is guilty of serious, though doubtless 
 unintentional, unfairness to his opponents. He wrongly 
 identifies the position which he has just stated, in terms that 
 no one could object to, with the theory that moral truth can 
 be revealed only by religion. It hardly needs to be pointed 
 out that there is no necessary connection between these 
 views. One may perfectly well believe — many do believe — 
 that the essential principles of moral conduct, so far at least 
 as our human relations are concerned, may be demonstrated 
 quite apart from religion, and yet hold that, while religion is 
 
 1 See p. 87. 2 See p. 95.
 
 Joh7i Stuart Mill. 239 
 
 by no means needed as " an auxiliary to the thief-catcher and 
 the hangman," it is of inestimable value as affordmg a hope, 
 which no mere examination of the facts of human experience 
 could wholly justify, that good will finally prevail over evil, and 
 that the struggle itself, even when it seems to be a losing one, 
 is not wholly in vain. Mill himself says somewhat later : 
 " So long as human life is insufficient to satisfy human aspira- 
 tions, so long there will be a craving for higher things, which 
 finds its most obvious satisfaction in religion ".^ 
 
 The author admits that some Christian precepts seem to be 
 on a higher plane than any which have preceded them. But 
 he argues that this benefit has been gained once for all. Pre- 
 cepts like the ' new commandment to love one another ' have 
 become the common property of humanity, and could only 
 be lost by a return to primeval barbarism. Moral truths of 
 any sort are strong enough in their own evidence to retain the 
 belief of mankind, when once they have acquired it. The 
 supposed supernatural character of moral truths, moreover, 
 is a positively dangerous view in one important respect, for 
 it keeps us from analysing and criticising our moral principles, 
 and separating the good from the bad. At the same time, 
 Mill admits that " the value ... of religion to the individual, 
 ... as a source of personal satisfaction and of elevated feelings, 
 is not to be disputed " ; and we saw, at the end of the last 
 paragraph, that he was capable of defining that value in most 
 appreciative terms. 
 
 But is rehgion the only source of such satisfaction } Do 
 we, in particular, have to assume personal immortality, in 
 order to obtain such satisfaction } If individual life is short, 
 that of the species is long. " Its mdefinite duration is practi- 
 cally equivalent to endlessness ; and being combined with 
 indefinite capability of improvement, it offers to the imagina- 
 tion and sympathies a large enough object to satisfy any 
 reasonable demand for grandeur of aspiration." By referring 
 to the sentiment of disinterested devotion to the Republic, 
 
 ' See p. 104.
 
 240 History of Utilitarianism, 
 
 which existed for many generations among the Romans, who 
 were otherwise a selfish people, Mill argues that the love of 
 that larger country, the world, may be nursed into similar 
 strength, both as a source of elevated emotion and as a prin- 
 ciple of duty. As this moral education progresses, men will 
 think less and less of definite personal rewards or punish- 
 ments, and more and more of the approbation of the highest 
 moral natures, whether among the living or the dead. " For," 
 as the author very truly remarks, " the thought that our dead 
 parents or friends would have approved our conduct is a 
 scarcely less powerful motive than the knowledge that our 
 living ones do approve it " ; and the thought that Socrates, or 
 Antoninus, or Christ would have sympathised with us and 
 have approved our actions, " has operated on the very best 
 minds, as a strong incentive to act up to their highest feel- 
 ings and convictions ".^ 
 
 And here follows one of the most impressive passages to be 
 found in Mill's philosophical writings. " To call these senti- 
 ments by the name morality, exclusively of any other title, 
 is claiming too little for them. They are a real religion ; of 
 which, as of other religions, outward good works (the utmost 
 meaning usually suggested by the word morality) are only 
 a part, and are indeed rather the fruits of the religion than 
 the religion itself. The essence of religion is the strong 
 and earnest direction of the emotions and desires towards an 
 ideal object, recognised as of the highest excellence, and as 
 rightfully paramount over all selfish objects of desire." ^ 
 This is the climax of the argument, and here the essay might 
 will have ended. Mill's following apology for the Religion 
 of Humanity, and his attempt to show its superiority to any 
 form of supernatural religion, is by no means calculated to 
 bring conviction. But we must never forget the seeming 
 paradox with which we are here confronted, viz., the fact that 
 it was an agnostic who first brought the Utilitarian doctrine 
 into closest touch, not only with our moral, but with our 
 
 ' See p. log.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 241 
 
 religious consciousness. There is one characteristic remark, 
 after the author has said all that he can for the Religion of 
 Humanity. Speaking of the one " real and valuable con- 
 solation " which the sceptic loses, the hope of a reunion in 
 the life to come with the friends whom he has lost here, Mill 
 says : " That loss, indeed, in neither to be denied nor ex- 
 tenuated. In many cases it is beyond the reach of comparison 
 or estimate ; and will always suffice to keep alive, in the more 
 sensitive natures, the imaginative hope of a futurity which, 
 if there is nothing to prove, there is as little in our knowledge 
 and experience to contradict." ^ After this concession to our 
 human feelings, however, he remarks that one of the great 
 Eastern religions offers, not immortality, but annihilation, as 
 the end supremely to be desired ; and he concludes the essay 
 by saying : " It seems to me not only possible but probable, 
 that in a higher, and, above all, a happier condition of human 
 life, not annihilation but immortality may be the burdensome 
 idea ; and that human nature, though pleased with the present, 
 and by no means impatient to quit it, would find comfort and 
 not sadness in the thought that it is not chained through 
 eternity to a conscious existence which it cannot be assured 
 that it will always wish to preserve ". 
 
 ^ See p. 120. 
 
 16
 
 CHAPTER XII. 
 
 JOHN STUART MILL {continued). 
 
 It will be remembered that we have rehable testimony to 
 the effect that the essays on " Nature " and on " The UtiHty 
 of ReHgion," which we have been examining, were written at 
 about the same time as Mill's well-known book On Liberty, 
 published in 1859. If this were not the case, it would be 
 natural to assign them to a somewhat different period ; not 
 because the Liberty, which we are now to consider, exactly 
 contradicts what we have seen to be the doctrine of the two 
 other essays, but because it seems to represent the develop- 
 ment of an earlier tendency of the author's thought. It hardly 
 need be pointed out how different Mill's whole treatment of 
 religion was from what would have been possible for an 
 eighteenth century writer of either party. Agnosticism with 
 a keen appreciation of at least much that is essential to re- 
 ligion, would have sorely puzzled a reader of even the preced- 
 ing generation. Still less would Mill's idea of the perfectibility 
 of an originally unpromising human nature, and the possibility 
 of merging one's individual interests in the general interests of 
 society, not merely present but future, have met with a sym- 
 pathetic response at an earlier time. Hartley, indeed, had 
 thrown out such a suggestion, though in a crude form, but 
 his immediate successors had let this idea severely alone. The 
 essay on Liberty, on the other hand, though decidedly of the 
 nineteenth century in certain essential respects, which will 
 be considered in due time, to all intents and purposes takes 
 eighteenth century individualism as its starting-point. In 
 short, the difference in tone between the essays on " Nature " 
 
 (242)
 
 John Shmrt Mill. 243 
 
 and " The Utility of Religion," on the one hand, and the book 
 On Liberty, on the other hand, was the difference between 
 emphasising the social character of man as agamst individual- 
 ism and emphasising the claims of the individual as against 
 society. 
 
 This difference in tone, which it is much easier to recognise 
 than to describe in exact terms, makes it somewhat important 
 to fix the date of the composition of the book. Fortunately 
 Mill himself has given us very exact information, in the Auto- 
 biography, as to both the time and the circumstances of its 
 composition. He says : " During the two years which im- 
 mediately preceded the cessation of my official life, my wife 
 and I were working together at the Liberty. I had first 
 planned and written it as a short essay in 1854. It was in 
 mounting the steps of the Capitol, in January, 1855, that the 
 thought first arose of converting it into a volume. None of 
 my writings have been either so carefully composed, or so 
 sedulously corrected as this. After it had been written as 
 usual twice over, we kept it by us, bringing it out from time 
 to time, and going through it de novo, reading, weighing, and 
 criticising every sentence. Its final revision was to have been 
 a work of the winter of 1858-9, the first after my retirement, 
 which we had arranged to pass in the South of Europe." 
 After speaking of the death of his wife, he says : " After my 
 irreparable loss, one of my earhest cares was to print and 
 publish the treatise. , . . The Liberty was more directly and 
 literally our joint production than anything else which bears 
 my name. . . . The whole mode of thinking of which the book 
 was the expression, was emphatically hers. . . . My great readi- 
 ness and eagerness to learn from everybody, and to make room 
 in my opinions for every new acquisition by adjusting the old 
 and the new to one another, might, but for her steadying 
 influence, have seduced me into modifying my early opinions 
 too much." 1 
 
 The dates given above may, of course, be accepted with 
 
 ^ See Autobiography, pp. 250-252.
 
 244 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 perfect confidence, for not only is the author himself the 
 witness, but the circumstances under which the book was 
 written were obviously such as to impress themselves indelibly 
 upon his memory. But what has just been quoted raises a 
 general question of considerable interest : Was Mill's intellec- 
 tual debt to his wife such as he would give us to understand, 
 here and in other well-known passages in his writings ? Con- 
 clusive evidence one way or the other would, of course, be 
 practically impossible to obtain, since we have no reason to 
 believe that there are existing manuscripts which would 
 decide the matter ; but it may safely be assumed that, when 
 Mill expressed himself as he does in the present instance, the 
 emotional element came in to such an extent as makes it 
 necessary to take his statements with very great caution. 
 
 But while Mill's strictly intellectual debt to his wife was 
 almost certainly far less than he himself would lead us to 
 suppose, there is no question whatever that her influence 
 upon his development was considerable. In the passage 
 quoted from the Autobiography , her influence is described as 
 a ' steadying ' one, which kept Mill from departing too far 
 from his earlier position. One may doubt whether the adjec- 
 tive is well chosen. So far as one can trace her influence in his 
 writings, it would seem rather to have been merely reaction- 
 ary. The difference in tone between the essay on Whewell 
 (1852) and the immediately preceding essays has been noted. 
 This was certainly not an improvement, but may plausibly 
 be traced to his wife's influence, since their marriage had taken 
 place the preceding year. In the Liberty, on the other hand, 
 there is much less asperity of tone to criticise, but the apparent 
 difference in the general drift of this book from that of his 
 other writings of the same period may not unreasonably be 
 attributed to the fact that his wife's influence comes out much 
 more strongly here. At any rate, here, if anywhere, we must 
 look for her influence, since Mill tells us definitely that the 
 central idea of the essay was primarily hers rather than his 
 own. 
 
 The problem of this little book is clearly developed by Mill
 
 John Stuart Mill. 245 
 
 in the introductory chapter. The old struggle between liberty 
 and authority was at first between subjects, or some class of 
 subjects, and the government. It might have seemed as if this 
 conflict would necessarily cease, when what we call ' self- 
 government ' became, for a given nation, an accomplished fact ; 
 but the event has shown that this is by no means the case. 
 The reason is that the ' people ' who exercise power are not 
 always the same people over whom it is exercised. In truth, 
 the tyranny of majorities is perhaps the most dangerous of all 
 tyrannies. Society tends " to fetter the development, and, if 
 possible, prevent the formation, of any individuality not in 
 harmony with its ways, and compel all characters to fashion 
 themselves upon the model of its own " } Restraints of some 
 kind are, of course, absolutely necessary ; without them 
 neither life nor property would be safe. But how far should 
 society interfere with the action of the individual ? Govern- 
 ments, as a matter of fact, act upon no settled principles. 
 The likes or dislikes of a particular society at a particular time 
 decide the matter. Now, Mill tells us, the object of this essay 
 is to assert one very simple principle, viz., " that the sole end 
 for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, 
 in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their number, 
 is self-protection. . . . His own good, either physical or moral, 
 is not a sufficient warrant." ^ 
 
 The following chapters, as will be remembered, are devoted 
 to " The Liberty of Thought and Discussion," " Individuality, 
 as One of the Elements of Well-being," " The Limits to the 
 Authority of Society over the Individual," and " Applications ". 
 It should be noticed at the outset that one of these chapters, 
 at least, the first mentioned, is not as closely connected with 
 the general thesis as might appear. Mill's defence of freedom 
 of discussion, on grounds of general utility, is not essentially 
 different from what any enlightened Englishman might write 
 at the present day on the same subject. It differed from con- 
 
 ^ See Liberty, p. 13 (third ed.). 
 
 2 See pp. 21, 22. Mill explains that this principle applies only to civilised 
 adults.
 
 246 Hisitoiy of Utilitarianisni. 
 
 temporary discussions, only in that the principle was rather 
 more strongly emphasised. In short, Mill's argument does not 
 necessarily depend upon the individualistic principle, which it 
 is the main purpose of this essay to maintain. In the chapter 
 on the " Limits to the Authority of Society," on the other 
 hand, this principle is naturally brought out with perfect clear- 
 ness. Even when we agree with Mill's conclusions, however, 
 which is not difficult in most cases, the arguments employed 
 are hardly convincing to one who sympathises with the general 
 trend of ethical theory at the present day. 
 
 This chapter is, in fact, an interestmg example of ' putting 
 the new wine into old bottles '. We have already several times 
 had occasion to notice how far Mill had departed from the 
 older Utilitarian school, in holding to the original character 
 of sympathy, and therefore to the possibility of strictly dis- 
 interested action. And yet, the present discussion depends 
 almost entirely upon the distinction between the self-regarding 
 and the other-regarding virtues — the question being : In how 
 far, if at all, have we a right to enforce upon others conduct in 
 accordance with the self-regarding virtues ? When a man's 
 conduct is, even in an inferior degree, anti-social. Mill admits 
 that we have a right to coerce him ; but when he gives himself 
 up to bestial excess, like habitual drunkenness, he claims that 
 we have no such right — unless, of course, this makes him 
 transgress the recognised rights of others. But the recogni- 
 tion of primitive sympathy would seem logically to break down 
 this hard and fast barner between self-regarding and other- 
 regarding virtues, even if the general Utilitarian principle, 
 properly understood, had not done so already. If man must 
 be regarded as really a social being from the first, it may, 
 indeed, be convenient to use some such classification of the 
 virtues as that just mentioned ; but the classification should 
 always be regarded as a convenience only, and never as the 
 basis for an argument. As a member of society — and Mill 
 would have been the first to recognise social obligations — a 
 man of bestial tastes and habits is worse than useless ; in fact, 
 he may become a positive menace to society, in proportion to
 
 John Stuart Mill. 247 
 
 his position in life and to his still unextinguished talents. 
 Mill, indeed, partly recognises all this, but not to the extent 
 of seeing how largely it vitiates his argument. It is hardly 
 necessary to explain that what has just been said is not 
 intended as an argument for the too paternal interest of the 
 State in the habits of its citizens. The desirability of such 
 control is a practical question, to be decided in each case on its 
 own merits ; in truth, no government could possibly afford to 
 decide such questions on purely abstract principles. There 
 is a good deal of legislation to-day that would have been 
 branded as ' socialistic ' thirty years ago. This is not, we may 
 surmise, because we are becoming converted to socialism, 
 but because the mere word ' socialism ' has less terrors for us 
 than it once had, and because we tend more and more to 
 decide each question, as it comes up, on its own merits, only 
 taking care not to establish dangerous precedents. 
 
 If the essay on Liberty had contained nothing different from 
 what we have thus far noticed, it could hardly have been re- 
 garded as permanently important, except as pointing out the 
 real danger to democracy which lies in the almost inevitable 
 tyranny of public opinion. But by far the most original and 
 important part of the essay is the third chapter, " Of Individu- 
 ality, as One of the Elements of Well-being ". It is here 
 that Mill's discussion of the general question of Liberty brings 
 him into closest relation to Ethics proper. What is particularly 
 interesting, however, is the fact that the arguments advanced 
 in this chapter, whether good or bad, have a much looser 
 relation to the general individualistic position of the book 
 than would at first appear. It will be remembered that, in 
 the preceding chapter, Mill had been vindicating perfect free- 
 dom of speech. Here he comes to the question, how far 
 freedom of action should be permitted. Nobody pretends that 
 actions should be as free as opinions. The individual should 
 not make himself obnoxious to others ; but in matters that do 
 not primarily concern others, individuality should by all means 
 assert itself. " As it is useful that while mankind are imper- 
 fect there should be different opinions, so is it that there should
 
 248 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 be different experiments of living ; that free scope should be 
 given to varieties of character, short of injury to others ; and 
 that the worth of different modes of life should be proved 
 practically, when any one thinks fit to try them." ^ So far 
 Mill is saying no more than might be urged from quite various 
 points of view in favour of such freedom of action as will keep 
 society from a condition of stagnation ; but from this point 
 onward, throughout the chapter, he takes for his text the 
 saying of Wilhelm von Humboldt that " the end of man, or 
 that which is prescribed by the eternal or immutable dictates 
 of reason, and not suggested by vague and transient desires, is 
 the highest and most harmonious development of his powers 
 to a complete and consistent whole " ; and that therefore the 
 object " towards which every human being must ceaselessly 
 direct his efforts, and on which especially those who design to 
 influence their fellow-men must ever keep their eyes, is the 
 individuality of power and development ".^ 
 
 It hardly need be pointed out that a good deal more is im- 
 plied by this passage from von Humboldt than the assertion 
 of the importance of individuality as such. And Mill himself, 
 almost unconsciously, as it would seem, does a good deal to 
 work out the principle to its logical conclusion. For instance, he 
 says : " Among the works of man, which human life is rightly 
 employed in perfecting and beautifymg, the first in importance 
 surely is man himself. . . . Human nature is not a machine to be 
 built after a model, and set to do exactly the work prescribed 
 for it, but a tree, which requires to grow and develop itself on 
 all sides, according to the tendency of the inward forces which 
 make it a living thing," ^ And again, he says : " ' Pagan self- 
 assertion ' is one of the elements of human worth, as well as 
 ' Christian self-denial '. There is a Greek ideal of self- 
 development, which the Platonic and Christian ideal of self- 
 government blends with, but does not supersede. It may be 
 better to be a John Knox than an Alcibiades, but it is better 
 to be a Pericles than either ; nor would a Pericles, if we had 
 
 ^ See p. loi. 2 See p. 103. ' See pp. 106, 107.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 249 
 
 one in these days, be without anything good which belonged 
 to John Knox."^ Passages like this almost seem to imply 
 that self-development is an end in itself, without direct refer- 
 ence to hedonic results, either to oneself or to others. While 
 it would be unjust to insist too strongly upon the inconsistency 
 of such passages with Mill's general hedonistic position, it is 
 necessary always to keep them in mind as tending to show 
 how complex his ethical theory really was. What Mill did not 
 see was, that if one take this principle of self -development 
 seriously, it by no means lends itself to the purposes of in- 
 dividualism, or even to those of hedonism. 
 
 In passing to the well-known Utilitarianism, first printed 
 in Eraser s Magazine in 1861, and reprinted (without changes) 
 in book form in 1863, we come, of course, to Mill's most com- 
 plete statement of his mature views regarding Ethics. After 
 our rather careful examination of his previous ethical writings, 
 however, we shall find little that is strictly new here, and, since 
 this small volume is more universally famihar than any other 
 book in the whole literature of English Utilitarianism, it would 
 be gratuitous to reproduce its arguments in any detail. It 
 seems best, therefore, to take up the principal points of the 
 essay as briefly as may be, and to see in each case, on the 
 one hand, how this last statement of Mill's ethical views cor- 
 responds with his own earlier treatment and that of his 
 immediate predecessors, and, on the other hand, how it corre- 
 sponds with the recognised Utilitarian theory of the present 
 'day. 
 
 It is probably significant that in the " General Remarks," 
 with which Mill prefaces his treatment, there is no parade of 
 scientific method. He says : " The intuitive, no less than what 
 may be termed the inductive, school of ethics, insists on the 
 necessity of general laws. They both agree that the morality 
 
 ^ See p. H2. It will doubtless occur to the reader that the examples which 
 Mill gives here are the reverse of instructive. John Knox presumably was not 
 lacking in 'Christian self-denial,' but he had in addition a rather unusual amount 
 of what might, not unfairly, be termed ' Pagan self-assertion'.
 
 250 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 of an individual action is not a question of direct perception, 
 but of the application of a law to an individual case. They 
 recognise also, to a great extent, the same moral laws ; but 
 differ as to their evidence, and the source from which they 
 derive their authority." ^ Mill seems no longer to be labouring 
 under the delusion, that the thorough-going application of 
 Bentham's ' method of detail ' is sufficient to solve the diffi- 
 culties of Ethics ; on the contrary, by this time the real issues 
 are pretty well cleared up in his mind. He does, however, 
 insist upon one very important point, when he says, regarding 
 non-hedonistic systems : " I might go much further, and say 
 that to all these a priori moralists who deem it necessary to 
 argue at all, Utilitarian arguments are indispensable ".^ 
 
 This is a claim which, in various forms, had been ad- 
 vanced by nearly all Mill's Utilitarian predecessors, and, such 
 being the case, one may well give it a final scrutiny. It would 
 be easy to brush this aside as an unproved assumption, but, in 
 the opinion of the present writer, it is rather more than that. 
 The fact is, that the very moralists who have spoken most 
 scornfully of the ' doctrine of consequences ' have without ex- 
 ception found it extremely difficult, if not impossible, to leave 
 consequences altogether out of account. By some strange 
 fatality, however, the opponents of Utilitarianism have suc- 
 ceeded in putting themselves in the wrong by almost univer- 
 sally conceding to the Utilitarians that, z/" consequences are ta 
 be regarded, they must be construed in hedonistic terms. There 
 was nothing to do, then, from this point of view, but to deny 
 that the lightness or wrongness of actions depends to any large 
 extent upon their consequences — with the unfortunate result 
 above indicated. For, no matter how ' internal ' one's concep- 
 tion of morality, one cannot safely deny that the ' conse- 
 quences ' of actions may be important to any degree whatever. 
 To overlook or deny this fact, is to blind oneself to one of the 
 most serious aspects of the moral life. But these good or bad 
 consequences are by no means necessarily such, merely be- 
 
 1 See p. 3. -See p. 5.
 
 John Stnart MilL 251 
 
 cause of the happiness or unhappiness which they imply. 
 They may consistently be shown to be good or bad, because 
 they tend for or against whatever one may regard as of 
 supreme importance in the moral life. 
 
 Mill next goes on to explain " What Utilitarianism Is ". 
 He begins by defining utility as happiness, and happiness as 
 ' pleasure, and the absence of pain '. In the same way, un- 
 happiness is defined as ' pain, and the privation of pleasure '. ^ 
 
 { That concrete desirable things are as numerous for Utilitarians 
 I as for others, he very properly insists ; but holds, of course, \r^C) 
 
 that they are "desirable either for the pleasure inherent iri~l yr,^ / 
 themselves, or as means to the promotion of pleasure and, [^^ ^ 
 the prevention of pain ". Moreover, he remarks that " there 
 is no known Epicurean theory of life which does not assign 
 to the pleasures of the intellect, of the feehngs and imagina- 
 tion, and of the moral sentiments, a much higher value as 
 pleasures than to those of mere sensation " } But just here 
 Mill makes his famous distinction. He does not agree with 
 traditional Utilitarianism in holding that this superiority of 
 mental over physical pleasures is due to their greater per- 
 — manence, safety, uncostliness, etc., but insists that pleasures 
 are essentially different in kind (or value) as well as in degree.y 
 Quite in the spirit of Hutcheson, he appeals to that " sense of 
 dignity, which all human beings possess in one form or other, 
 and in some, though by no means in exact, proportion to their 
 higher faculties, and which is so essential a part of the happi- 
 ness of those in whom it is strong, that nothing which con- 
 flicts with it could be, otherwise than momentarily, an object 
 of desire to them "? Moreover, he says : " If it may possibly 
 be doubted whether a noble character is always the happier 
 for its nobleness, there can be no doubt that it makes other 
 people happier, and that the world in general is immensely 
 a gainer by it ".^ 
 
 Since nothing in Mill's ethical writings has been so thor- 
 oughly discussed as this admission on his part of qualitative 
 
 1 See p. II. -Seep. 13. =* See p. i6.
 
 m^ CvntrAdt(J> himself 
 
 252 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 distinctions between pleasures, and since there is perfect agree- 
 ment at the present day among competent critics, of whatever 
 ethical convictions, as to the inconsistency of this view with 
 his general hedonistic position, it would be an impertinence 
 to argue the matter again here. The inconsistency, in truth, 
 may be expressed in a word : If all good things are good in 
 proportion as they bring pleasure to oneself or others, one 
 cannot add to this statement that pleasure itself, the assumed 
 criterion, is more or less desirable in terms of something else 
 {e.g., human dignity) which is not pleasure. At the same time, 
 it would be a grave mistake to suppose that this was merely 
 one of Mill's many careless slips. The inconsistency is not 
 superficial, it is vital. In this very chapter, when criticising 
 the way in which Utilitarianism has commonly been presented, 
 Mill has said : " To do this in any sufficient manner, many 
 Stoic, as well as Christian elements require to be included "} 
 And we have seen how, in the most important chapter of the 
 Liberty, he appropriates von Humboldt's impressive statement 
 of the all-importance of self-development as an essential con- 
 stituent of well-being. 
 
 Mill next considers the objection that happiness cannot be 
 the end, because it is unattainable in this life. Incautiously 
 admitting, as it would seem, that the burden of proof is on 
 his side, he enters upon a brief and rather superficial argu- 
 ment for (hedonistic) optimism. Into this, we need not follow 
 him. As might be expected, he exaggerates, as usual, the 
 power of education to alter the manifestations of human nature, 
 particularly in the direction of sympathy and intelligence. 
 Even poverty and disease, as implying acute suffering on the 
 part of large numbers, are to disappear. It is hard to see 
 why hedonists have so commonly admitted that the concrete 
 difficulties of the moral life are difficulties for them, more than 
 for others. In the present case of optimism versus pessimism, 
 it would be a simple matter to show that hedonism is no better 
 and no worse off than any other recognised form of ethical 
 
 See p. II.
 
 John Stua^'t Mill. 253 
 
 theory. For surely there are as many possible forms of 
 optimism and pessimism as there are possible definitions of 
 the Good. And it may be observed that, if happiness is by no 
 means universal, it is probably quite as frequent a phenomenon 
 as moral perfection. 
 
 On the other hand, Mill is undoubtedly right, when he 
 shows the absurdity of objecting to Utilitarianism as a ' god- 
 less doctrine,' and says : " Whatever aid religion, either natural 
 or revealed, can afford to ethical investigation, is as open to the 
 Utilitarian moralist as to any other ". He might very properly 
 have added, what he has elsewhere pointed out, that, as a 
 matter of fact, Theological Utilitarianism was for a long time 
 the common orthodox view, as against those who held various 
 forms of the ' Moral Sense ' theory. He is also right, as against 
 those who brand Utilitarianism as the doctrine of ' expedi- 
 ency,' since this is plainly a question-begging epithet as 
 here applied ; but he is plainly careless when, speaking of the 
 virtue of truthfulness, he says : " Yet that even this rule, 
 sacred as it is, admits of possible exceptions, is acknowledged 
 by all moralists ".^ How about Kant, whom he has under- 
 taken to criticise in the first chapter ? 
 
 Somewhat earlier in this chapter, Mill considers a question 
 that would more properly come up for discussion in the next 
 chapter, where he treats of " The Ultimate Sanction of the 
 Principle of Utility". And he is again careless in the way 
 just noted. He is answering the supposed objection that the 
 Utilitarian doctrine is too high in its demands. " They say 
 it is exacting too much to require that people shall always act 
 from the inducement of promoting the general interests of 
 society. But this is to mistake the very meaning of a standard 
 of morals, and to confound the rule of action with the motive 
 of it. It is the business of ethics to tell us what are our 
 duties, or by what test we may know them ; but no system 
 of ethics requires that the sole motive of all we do shall be a 
 feeling of duty. ... It is the more unjust to Utilitarianism that 
 
 J See p. 33.
 
 2 54 History of Utilita7'ianism. 
 
 this particular misapprehension should be made a ground of 
 •objection to it, inasmuch as Utihtarian moralists have gone 
 beyond almost all others in affirming that the motive has 
 nothing to do with the morality of the action, though much 
 with the worth of the agent." ^ 
 
 In the first place, it hardly need be remarked that a very 
 important system of Ethics, just mentioned, which Mill has 
 criticised in the course of his " General Remarks," does hold 
 precisely that " the sole motive of all we do [if it is to be 
 strictly moral] shall be a feeling of duty ". It may, indeed, 
 with considerable justice be retorted, ' so much the worse for 
 Kant ' ; but Mill betrays his lack of an intimate knowledge of 
 modern ethical literature, when he allows himself to make 
 sweeping statements with so little caution. But in the second 
 place, and more particularly, has Mill a right to appropriate 
 the argument of the earlier Utilitarians, that the motive has 
 •nothing to do with the morality of the action ? That was 
 part and parcel of what we may call the extreme ' dualism ' 
 of their ethical theory : their contention that the end of moral 
 action and the motive which leads to it must be different, 
 since one can will only one's own happiness. But, as we have 
 seen, it was Mill's great merit to revive Hume's view (as given 
 in the second form of his ethical system), and show that man 
 is originally sympathetic, and that therefore he can, to a 
 certain extent, directly will the common good, although other 
 motives do, as a matter of fact, generally come in to com- 
 plicate. 
 
 In the next chapter, to which, as already said, this discus- 
 sion properly belongs. Mill shifts his position and says — 
 speaking of the psychological basis of the feeling of obliga- 
 tion — " But there is this basis of powerful natural sentiment ; 
 and this it is, which, when once the general happiness is recog- 
 nised as the ethical standard, will constitute the strength of 
 the Utilitarian morality. This firm foundation is that of the 
 social feelings of mankind. . . . The social state is at once 
 
 ^ See p. 26.
 
 John Shtart Mill. 255 
 
 so natural, so necessary, and so habitual to man, that, except in 
 some unusual circumstances, or by an effort of voluntary ab- 
 straction, he never conceives himself otherwise than as a 
 member of a body ; and this association is riveted more and 
 more, as mankind are further removed from the state of savage 
 independence." ^ Of course, this is Mill's true, and only con- 
 sistent, position ; but it at once separates him from the 
 eighteenth century Utilitarians, whose characteristic argu- 
 ments, for that reason, he has no right to use. And how does 
 the last part of the passage just quoted square with Mill's 
 conception of the ' natural ' as developed in the essay on 
 " Nature," apparently written at about the same time } This 
 unconscious shifting of the point of view, in the course of 
 an argument of any length, or in different writings, even of 
 the same period, makes Mill a somewhat obscure writer on 
 Ethics to those who take the trouble to read him carefully. 
 But, in the present case, there can be no doubt as to what 
 Mill really means. Earlier in this same (third) chapter, when 
 distinguishing between the ' external ' and the ' internal ' sanc- 
 tions of morality, he says : " The principle of utility either has, 
 or there is no reason why it might not have, all the sanctions 
 which belong to any other system of morals. Those sanctions 
 are either external or internal. Of the external sanctions it 
 IS not necessary to speak at any length. . . . The internal 
 sanction of duty, whatever our standard of duty may be, is one 
 and the same — a feeling in our own mind ; a pain, more or 
 less intense, attendant on violation of duty, which in properly 
 cultivated moral natures rises, in the more serious cases, into 
 shrinking from it as an impossibility. This feeling, when 
 disinterested, and connecting itself with the pure idea of 
 duty, and not with some particular form of it, or with any of 
 the merely accessory circumstances, is the essence of Con- 
 science. . . . The ultimate sanction, therefore, of all morality 
 (external motives apart) being a subjective feeling in our own 
 minds, I see nothing embarrassing to those whose standard 
 
 ^ See p. 46.
 
 256 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 is utility, in the question, What is the sanction of that particu- 
 lar standard ? We may answer, The same as of all other moral 
 standards — the conscientious feelings of mankind." ^ These 
 ' conscientious feelings of mankind,' however, are of course 
 not regarded by Mill as intuitive. In the last resort, the feel- 
 ing of duty depends upon that powerful natural sentiment, 
 social feeling or sympathy, which we have been examining. 
 This, then, and nothing else, is " the ultimate sanction of the 
 greatest-happiness morality " ? 
 
 The fourth chapter of the Utilitarianism treats " Of What 
 Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility is Susceptible " — a ques- 
 tion which might very properly have been considered first. 
 After making the obvious remark, that questions of ultimate 
 ends do not admit of proof, in the ordinary acceptation of the 
 term, the author indicates the general drift of his argument, 
 very concisely, as follows : " No reason can be given why the 
 general happiness is desirable, except that each person, so far 
 as he believes it to be attainable, desires his own happiness. 
 This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof 
 which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, 
 that happiness is a good : that each person's happiness is a 
 good to that person ; and the general happiness, therefore, a 
 good to the aggregate of all persons. Happiness has made out 
 its title as one of the ends of conduct, and consequently one of 
 the criteria of morality." - But to prove it to be the sole 
 criterion, it is necessary to show that people never desire any- 
 thmg else. It will be seen that the method by which Mill 
 would prove the general principle of utility is closely analogous 
 to that by which Hume tried to prove the Utilitarian character 
 of the particular virtues. 
 
 In the main. Mill's arguments are the conventional ones of 
 Associationist-Utilitarianism, and so do not call for special 
 examination. His position, of course, is defined by his often- 
 quoted remark in this chapter, that " desiring a thing and find- 'A \;^ 
 ing it pleasant, aversion to it and thinking of it as painful, are \ 
 
 1 See pp. 40-42. ^ See p. 50.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 257 
 
 t phenomena entirely inseparable, or rather two parts of the 
 same phenomenon ". One of his explanations, however— 
 the crucial one, since he depends upon it to show that the 
 Utilitarian theory provides for the fact, that the virtuous man 
 may will that which is contrary to his own happiness — requires 
 careful consideration. He says : " The distinction between 
 will and desire ... is an authentic and highly important psy- 
 chological fact ; but the fact consists solely in this — that will, , . 
 like all other parts of our constitution, is amenable to habity ' /\ 
 and that we may will from habit what we no longer desire for 
 itself, or desire only because we will it. It is not the less true 
 that will, in the beginning, is entirely produced by desire ; 
 including in that term the repelling influence of pain, as well 
 as the attractive one of pleasure." ^ 
 
 This is perhaps all the more instructive, because it only 
 brings out what is latent in the traditional Associationist- 
 Utilitarian theory of the will. What, then, does this often 
 reiterated theory mean ? Suppose we leave out of account, 
 Jor^the moment, the question how this ' habit ' of the will has 
 arisen, and accept the facts as we seem to find them. Lest 
 it be thought that the above quotation is ambiguous in its 
 admissions, the reader is reminded that just before Mill has 
 said : " In case of an habitual purpose, instead of willing the 
 thing because we desire it, we often desire it only because we 
 will it "? Now this cannot be a case where habit makes a men- 
 tal process unconscious or only semi-conscious, because we still 
 hear of desire and will. And that being the case, pleasure- 
 pain must still, just as at the beginning of our conscious ex- 
 perience, come in as determining factors. Only here pleasure 
 and pain attach respectively to actions in accordance with, or 
 against, certain tendencies of the will (call them ' habits/ if 
 you please) that we have to recognise as facts, however they 
 may be explained. 
 
 This, then, would appear to be the meaning of the common, 
 though seemingly paradoxical, statement that we desire a 
 
 1 See p. 60. 2 ggg p jg_ 
 
 17
 
 258 History of Utilitarianisiu. 
 
 thing at present because we will it. In other words, there are 
 certain things toward which our nature, as at present con- 
 stituted, tends. To let our nature, in these respects, have its 
 way, produces pleasure ; to balk our nature, in these respects, 
 produces pain. But this is a very different thing from saying 
 that at present we necessarily act for pleasure, or the avoid- 
 ance of pain, as such. When Mill says that will goes back 
 to desire (in the sense of desire for pleasure), this can, accord- 
 ing to his own statement, be only historically true. We had 
 no such tendencies as the ones just noticed at first ; these are 
 ' habits ' that have developed as a result of our acting, in the 
 first place, solely for pleasure and the avoidance of pain. 
 
 Now suppose we do not agree that the character was 
 a tabula rasa at first ; but hold rather that some of the tend- 
 encies which are so apparent in adult life were potentially 
 present at the beginning — ^what becomes of this traditional 
 form of the hedonistic theory of desire ? In short, in how far 
 does this theory depend upon the extremely dubious tabula 
 rasa assumption ? It is hardly necessary to say that the 
 above is not intended as a summary refutation of the general 
 doctrine of hedonism, but as an attempt to state a really serious 
 difficulty which constantly presents itself, when one is dealing 
 with the apparently simple ana unambiguous theory of the will 
 held practically in common by the Associationist-Utilitarians. 
 At the same time, when the full force of this difficulty is appre- 
 ciated, one has taken the first and most important step toward 
 recognising the substantial truth of Butler's analysis of desire, 
 which does so much to transform the problems of Ethics. 
 
 It will be remembered that we have the reliable testimony 
 of Miss Helen Taylor, Mill's step-daughter, in her preface to 
 the posthumously published Three Essays on Religion (1874), 
 that the long chapter on Justice, which concludes the little 
 volume we are examining, was first composed as a separate 
 essay. We are told that this essay on Justice and another on 
 Utility, written at about the same time, " were afterwards 
 incorporated, with some alterations and additions, into one, 
 and published under the name of Utilitariajiisni ". While this
 
 John Stuart Mill. 259 
 
 chapter is a most admirable exposition of Justice, from the 
 Utilitarian point of view, it will hardly require extended 
 notice here, first, because it is little more than a consistent 
 application of the traditional Utilitarian method, and secondly, 
 because it is perhaps as familiar as any chapter in Mill's 
 philosophical writings. 
 
 The general drift of the argument may be indicated very 
 briefly. In all ages of speculation, one of the strongest ob- 
 jections to the Utilitarian doctrine has been found in the 
 absolute character which common sense has attributed to 
 Justice. Since this has been so long the stronghold of In- 
 tuitionism. Mill accepts it as a test case. In the first place, 
 he analyses the notion of Justice with some care, and in a way 
 that partly reminds one of Professor Sidgwick's later and much 
 more elaborate analysis in the Methods of Ethics. The ques- 
 tion then arises, whether the feeling or sentiment which 
 attaches to the idea of Justice is such as would have originated 
 in considerations of general expediency. And Mill bluntly 
 states his thesis as follows : " I conceive that the sentiment 
 itself does not arise from anything which would commonly, 
 or correctly, be termed an idea of expediency ; but that, 
 though the sentiment does not, whatever is moral in it does ".^ 
 
 The author's preceding analysis has shown that the two 
 essential elements in the sentiment of Justice are: (i) the 
 desire to punish a person who has done harm, and (2) the 
 knowledge or belief that there is some definite individual, or 
 individuals, to whom harm has been done. Now the desire 
 to punish is held by Mill to be " a spontaneous outgrowth 
 from two sentiments, both in the highest degree natural, and 
 which either are or resemble instincts ; the impulse of self- 
 defence,^ and the feeling of sympathy ". The former has 
 nothing moral in it, when considered apart from the social 
 sympathies, to which it should be subordinated. If, on the 
 
 ^ See p. 76. 
 
 ^ This should be distinguished from Mr. Spencer's ' instinct of personal 
 rights' (Social Statics, 1851), which is also supposed to be helped out by 
 sympathy.
 
 26o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 other hand, it be morahsed by sympathy for others, it will be 
 brought into play only when conformable to the common good 
 — in which case, the Utilitarian test is inevitable. 
 
 But we are constantly told that Utility is an uncertain 
 standard, that we must obey the immutable dictates of Justice, 
 which are self-evident, and therefore independent of the fluctu- 
 ations of private or public opinion. Here Mill suggests what 
 would seem to be the obvious line of argument, though it had 
 been practically overlooked both by the orthodox Intuitionists 
 and by Mr. Spencer in Social Statics (185 1). We have no 
 right whatever to assume that the notion of Justice is free from 
 ambiguity. Indeed, Mill says : " So far is this from being the 
 fact, that there is as much difference of opinion, and as fierce 
 discussion, about what is just, as about what is useful to 
 society "} After citing a number of cases which go to prove 
 this contention, he argues that an external standard of some 
 kind is absolutely necessary, and that the only practicable 
 standard is Social Utility. This is by no means to assign to 
 Justice a minor place in the moral code. Mill says in conclu- 
 sion : " Justice remains the appropriate name for certain 
 social utilities which are vastly more important, and therefore 
 more absolute and imperative, than any others are as a class 
 (though not more so than others may be in particular cases) ; 
 and which, therefore, ought to be, as well as naturally are, 
 guarded by a sentiment not only different in degree, but also 
 in kind ; distinguished from the milder feeling which attaches 
 to the mere idea of promoting human pleasure or convenience, 
 at once by the more definite nature of its commands, and by 
 the sterner character of its sanctions ".2 
 
 ^ See p. 82. It will be remembered that Professor Sidgwick, though by no 
 means wholly opposed to Intuitionism, comes to much the same conclusion in 
 \v\% Methods of Ethics. 
 
 ^ See p. 96. All of Mill's writings bearing at all directly upon Ethics have now 
 been noticed, with the exception of the last of the posthumously published Three 
 Essays on Religion, the rather long essay on " Theism '". Even a brief examina- 
 tion of this may safely be omitted here, in spite of the pathetic interest which 
 attaches to this last, if also least satisfactory, of the author's many philosophical 
 writings. Though rather more systematic than the other two essays, on " Nature '*
 
 John Stuart Mill. 261 
 
 In estimating the significance of Mill's position in the de- 
 velopment of English Utilitarianism, it is particularly impor- 
 tant that we should keep in mind both the nature of his early- 
 environment and training, and the various changes that his 
 ethical views underwent even after the important essay on 
 Bentham (1838), which marks the beginning of his really 
 independent work in Ethics, and therefore the beginning of 
 a new phase of Utilitarian theory. Quite apart from what 
 may be thought of the unique pedagogical experiment which 
 was performed upon Mill by his father, in place of the con- 
 ventional school and university training of his generation, it 
 must be counted a distinct misfortune, on the whole, that he 
 inherited ready-made his earliest views on Ethics and Politics, 
 as well as on Psychology. Not that these views were neces- 
 sarily, or probably, further from the truth than those which 
 he would have adopted, if left to himself ; but it is nothing 
 less than pathetic, when we view the situation at this distance, 
 that the young apostle of freedom and reform should have 
 lived in an atmosphere such that anythmg like real intellectual 
 freedom was for himself an impossibility. 
 
 Mill began writing for various periodicals as early as 1824, 
 
 and on "The Utility of Religion" — which cover much the same ground, but 
 which appear to have been written more than ten years earHer — it does not, like 
 them, belong to a period when Mill was doing important work, and so is of much 
 less value as a commentary upon his other writings bearing more directly upon 
 Ethics. Moreover, as Miss Taylor states in the preface to the volume in which 
 it appears, this last essay was not revised by the author, as it certainly would 
 have been before he himself would have given it to the world. But even apart 
 from this, just in proportion as the treatment is more elaborate than that in the 
 two earlier essays, it shows Mill at a disadvantage, for he was never less at 
 home than in these theological discussions. The difference in tone between 
 this last essay and the two others, which has often been commented upon, is 
 undeniable. Mill is at the end much more sympathetic toward Theism than he 
 had been at any previous time — a fact which did not fail to suggest edifying 
 reflections when the Three Essays on Religion were first published. But this 
 apparent change of personal attitude affects his treatment of the arguments 
 themselves less than might be expected. The principal difference is that, in 
 the essay on Theism, he concedes more than he had in the others to ' The 
 Utility of Religion'. Properly speaking, Mill remained an agnostic to the last, 
 but with an increasing appreciation of the ethical value of religious ideals.
 
 262 Histoiy of Utilitarianism. 
 
 while still a mere boy, but for the next twelve years the 
 opinions which he expressed could from the nature of the case 
 be only partly his own — or his own, in the sense that they 
 were largely accepted from others — although at first they 
 appear to have been surrounded with all the halo of youthful 
 enthusiasm. His father, the stern task-master of his child- 
 hood, was the tacitly recognised censor of all that he wrote. 
 The nature and degree of this control is evident, when one 
 compares the essay on Sedgwick's Discourse (1835) with the 
 very different essay on Bentham (1838). Indeed, Mill himself 
 says of the former essay in the Autobiography, in a passage 
 previously quoted : " My relation to my father would have 
 made it painful to me in any case, and impossible in a Review 
 for which he wrote, to speak out my whole mind on the sub- 
 ject at this time " } The very important essay on Bentham, 
 then, pubhshed two years after his father's death, was at once 
 his ' Declaration of Independence ' and his first noteworthy 
 contribution to Ethics. 
 
 In the exercise of his newly asserted freedom, Mill ex- 
 pressed himself regarding the fatal shortcomings of Ben- 
 thamism with an emphasis which he might possibly have 
 avoided later. And as he is generally right in this destructive 
 part of the essay, the result is one of the most damaging 
 critiques in the whole range of English ethical literature. But 
 while his whole moral personality revolted against the hide- 
 bound doctrine which had done so much to fetter his own 
 earlier development, he still made a very high claim for Ben- 
 tham. Though not a ' great philosopher,' he was to be re- 
 garded as a ' great reformer in philosophy,' since he was the 
 lirst to apply ' scientific method ' to the treatment of moral 
 problems, from the hedonistic point of view. This does not, 
 of course, mean what it might mean to us now, for Bentham 
 was as innocent of any intimate knowledge of the Biology 
 or the Psychology of his day, as he was of the previous de- 
 velopment of ethical theory. The ' scientific method,' or 
 
 ^ See p. 201.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 263 
 
 ' method of detail/ as Mill sometimes calls it — ^which in one 
 passage he admits to be " as old as philosophy itself " — 
 consisted in the employment of elaborate analysis and classi- 
 fication in place of what Bentham and his followers doubtless 
 regarded as the barren, semi-rhetorical method of the past. 
 
 Mill's description of the ' scientific method ' which he attri- 
 butes to Bentham in this essay is extremely vague, if not 
 partly self-contradictory ; but one cannot doubt the sincerity 
 of his praise of the elder moralist for what he attempted in 
 this direction, since in Book VI. of the Logic, on " The Logic 
 of the Moral Sciences," which appears to have been begun 
 about two years later, he himself made a much more elaborate 
 attempt to provide a ' scientific ' foundation for Ethics, by 
 developing in outhne the idea of a new science, ' Ethology,' or 
 the ' Science of the Formation of Character '. The inductive 
 science. Psychology, was to be the ultimate foundation ; and 
 the new science, Ethology, necessarily deductive, because of 
 the complexity of the data with which it would have to deal, 
 was to form the necessary connecting-link between Psychol- 
 ogy, on the one hand, and Sociology, on the other, the latter 
 also, of course, being conceived as necessarily deductive in its 
 method. 
 
 It was highly characteristic of Mill's more than catholic 
 acceptance of partly conflicting principles, that in 1840, when 
 he was beginning to work out, more or less on the lines of 
 Benthamism, this hopelessly abstract, and therefore practically 
 valueless ' scientific method ' for the treatment of the moral 
 sciences, he should also have published the essay on Cole- 
 ridge, in which he seems to be meeting what he calls the 
 ' Germano-Coleridgean ' school fully half-way. And still more 
 significant is the fact that Mill retained this chapter in his 
 Logic to the end, and therefore long after he had given up 
 the proposed science of Ethology as impracticable — which 
 meant the implicit surrender of the whole position. 
 
 After the very appreciative essay on Coleridge, just men- 
 tioned, and the equally sympathetic essays on De Toqueville 
 (1840), Michelet (1844), and Guizot (1845), which show that
 
 264 History of Utilitarianisin. 
 
 Mill was coming more and more to appreciate the significance 
 of the historical method, not only for itself, but for its bearing 
 upon the moral sciences, and which therefore indicate a still 
 further divergence from the spirit of Benthamism — which had 
 been above all things unhistorical — one is hardly prepared 
 for the very severe essay on Whewell (1852), parts of which 
 sound almost like the very early essay on Sedgwick's Discourse 
 (1835). Making due allowance for the fact that Whewell 
 had justified rather severe criticism by his use of ' question- 
 begging epithets/ etc., this essay seems really to indicate a 
 partial and temporary reaction toward the earlier phase of 
 Mill's thought, while he was still under the spell of Bentham. 
 As explained in the proper context, this change of attitude 
 may plausibly be attributed to the influence of Mill's wife, 
 whom he had married the year before, and whose influence, 
 where it can be located, seems always to have been in the 
 direction of confirming him in the earlier and more uncompro- 
 mising form of his doctrine. 
 
 The two posthumously published essays on " Nature " and 
 on " The Utility of Rehgion " (probably written between 1 848 
 and 1859) by no means show Mill at his best in philosophical 
 argumentation : but they serve to bring out in an interesting 
 way, first, his partial acceptance of the Manichaean doctrine, 
 which in the Autobiography he attributes to his father, at 
 least in the sense that the elder Mill entertained it as a specu- 
 lative possibility ; and secondly, his almost naive belief in the 
 perfectibility of human nature — and this, in spite of the fact 
 that, according to his own account of the matter as here given, 
 the great forces not only in external nature, but in man him- 
 self, are strongly set against the moral order. In the latter 
 essay, in particular, he urges that religion, as ordinarily under- 
 stood, is by no means the indispensable moralising factor that 
 it is commonly assumed to be, though his attitude toward re- 
 ligion in this essay, as in nearly all of his later writings, is 
 partly one of appreciation for the ideals it represents. In 
 fact, he would apply the name ' religion ' to the higher morality 
 for which he himself pleads, for he says : " The essence of
 
 John Stuart Mill. 265 
 
 Teligion is the strong and earnest direction of the emotions 
 and desires towards an ideal object, recognised as of the 
 highest excellence, and as rightfully paramount over all selfish 
 objects of desire ".^ 
 
 In the case of the Liberty (1859) — which belongs to about 
 the same period, though it was probably written somewhat 
 later — we again find evidence of conflicting tendencies in Mill's 
 intellectual development. The main idea of the essay, which 
 he distinctly attributes to his wife, is the assertion of the rights 
 of the individual as such, almost in the sense of eighteenth 
 century Individualism. But the argument in the chapter on 
 " Individuality, as One of the Elements of Well-being " (by far 
 the most important one for Ethics) really depends upon the 
 implicit assumption that harmonious self-development is prac- 
 tically an end in itself, an assumption which carries him far 
 beyond what at least seemed to be his original thesis, and 
 by no means in the direction of consistent Utilitarianism. 
 
 When we finally turn to the Utilitarianism (1863), we find 
 little that is strictly new, but much to confirm us in the opinion 
 that the partial divergence from the Utilitarian method, which 
 had been so noticeable in some of Mill's previous ethical writ- 
 ings, was not a matter of chance, depending upon the nature 
 of the particular discussion, but indicative of tendencies which, 
 if they had been completely developed, would have meant the 
 practical surrender of the Utilitarian position itself. The 
 classic instance, of course, is Mill's emphatic assertion of the 
 existence of ' qualitative distinctions ' between pleasures. As 
 already pointed out, this must be very carefully distinguished 
 from the author's many careless slips in the course of particu- 
 lar arguments. It was a distinct and most important con- 
 cession, if not to Intuitionism, at least to the ideal of the 
 harmonious development of the human personality, as an end 
 in itself. 
 
 But over against this most important concession to non- 
 hedonistic ethical methods, must be placed Mill's not infre- 
 
 ^ See p. 109.
 
 266 History of Uiilitarianisin. 
 
 quent employment of arguments which properly belong to the 
 older type of Utilitarianism, and not to the more modern 
 form of the doctrine which he had himself done so much to 
 inaugurate. A typical example, which we have noticed in the 
 Utilitarianism, is the way in which he appropriates the char- 
 acteristic argument of the earlier Utilitarians, that the motive 
 has nothing to do with the morality of the action, considered 
 in itself. This is a manifest inadvertence, since in the next 
 chapter, as we have seen, sympathy is regarded — quite con- 
 sistently with Mill's general position, and that of all the later 
 Utilitarians — as " the ultimate sanction of the greatest happi- 
 ness morality . So, too, in the essay on " Nature," he had 
 allowed himself to argue for the ' artificial ' character of all 
 the virtues, which, according to his view as there expressed, 
 would never have come into being, " were it not so strongly 
 the interest of mankind to cherish the good germs in one 
 another ". This, of course, is the familiar argument of the 
 older type of Utilitarianism, which logically results from the 
 assumption that all motives are ultimately selfish. In the 
 Utilitarianism, on the other hand. Mill avoids this confusion 
 of the two points of view in the corresponding discussion. 
 Though the moral feelings are " not innate, but acquired," 
 in his own opinion, " they are not for that reason the less 
 natural ". And he adds : " It is natural to man to speak, to 
 reason, to build cities, to cultivate the ground, though these 
 are acquired faculties ".^ This, of course, means that man is 
 a social (and therefore partly sympathetic) being from the 
 first, and that therefore civilisation and morality are ' natural ' 
 and not merely ' artificial ' — which is the exact contrary of 
 the position which Mill had carelessly taken not long before 
 in the other essay, on " Nature ". 
 
 But this almost mechanical combination of the old and the 
 new, which one so often discovers in Mill's ethical writings, 
 must not blind us to the fact, that to him we owe the modern 
 form of Utilitarianism more than to any other single influence. 
 
 * Cf. Three Essays on Religion, p. 53, and Utilitarianism, p. 45.
 
 John Stuart Mill. 267 
 
 Indeed, these inconsistencies were doubtless in the first in- 
 stance largely due to the fact that he was a pioneer in the new 
 ethical movement. His incautious admission of ' qualitative 
 distinctions' between pleasures has, of course, been avoided 
 by later writers of the same school ; but it would hardly be 
 possible to estimate the extent of his influence in the direction 
 of humanising the Utilitarian doctrine, and making it square 
 with the highest concrete moral ideals. The social nature of 
 man, and the complexity of that nature, were recognised by 
 him almost from the first, and though he never himself ac- 
 cepted the theory of organic Evolution, he did much to pre- 
 pare his contemporaries to recognise the importance of the 
 idea of development as applied to Ethics. In his hands, the 
 older analytic Utilitarian method was gradually transformed 
 into the synthetic method of to-day. And not least re- 
 markable is the fact, that this professed agnostic did more 
 than any of his theological predecessors to bring Utilitarianism 
 into touch with the higher, more ideal side of religion. 
 Seldom, indeed, has a personahty counted for more in the 
 whole history of Ethics. 
 
 From first to last critics have dwelt altogether too much 
 upon the manifest inconsistencies in Mill's ethical writings, 
 and have failed to do anything like justice to the perfect 
 candour and broad-mindedness that made him take serious 
 account of the very facts of our moral experience which pre- 
 sented the most serious difficulties to his own ethical theory. 
 Just because of this fair-mindedness, this constant endeavour 
 to do justice to our moral nature as a whole — not because of 
 his inconsistencies, as some would hold — Mill belongs, not 
 merely to the Utilitarians, but to those who have found the 
 Utilitarian theory insufficient, and have attempted to transcend 
 it, while doing full justice to the measure of truth which it 
 contains.
 
 CHAPTER XIII. 
 
 HERBERT SPENCER. 
 
 After the publication of the Origin of Species (1859), ^^ ^^^ 
 inevitable that the idea of evolutional development should 
 sooner or later be applied to morality. In truth, it appeared 
 to certain writers of the following two or three decades that 
 the theory of Evolution afforded a perfectly new method of 
 Ethics, from which the most important results might confi- 
 dently be expected. Nothing could be more natural ; but it 
 happened in this case, as generally, when epoch-making 
 theories are exploited, that the collateral issues were at first 
 somewhat confused. We have seen that Mill was grievously 
 disappointed, when he earlier made the attempt to apply 
 * scientific method ' to the subject-matter of Ethics. This was 
 not because Ethics is a discipline which cannot permit of the 
 same rigorous analysis that we employ in the case of the 
 physical sciences, but because the writer on Ethics primarily 
 attempts, what the physical scientist, qua scientist, can never 
 for a moment permit himself — an evaluation, as opposed to a 
 mere explanation, of the facts with which he has to deal. In 
 a similar way, we have quite generally, if only somewhat 
 gradually, come to see that the idea of development according 
 to law, while of great importance for Ethics, as tending to 
 bring into prominence a multitude of facts that had previously 
 been far too generally neglected, does not of itself inform us 
 as to the worth or meaning of life, or as to the essential nature 
 of morality. Not that the work of the so-called Evolutional 
 moralists has by any means been in vain. Quite as much as 
 any other recent school, they have helped to broaden the whole 
 
 (268)
 
 Herbert Spencer. 269 
 
 field of ethical discussion. But their contribution has mainly 
 been to the data of the science ; they have by no means sup- 
 plied it with a new and definitive method. 
 
 It would, of course, be wholly apart from the purpose of 
 this book to examine Evolutional Ethics as such. In spite 
 of the varying tendencies represented by the writers usually 
 assigned to this school, they all agree in differentiating their 
 method more or less sharply from that of traditional Utili- 
 tarianism. Their most prominent representative, however, 
 can by no means be neglected, partly because he enjoys a 
 popular reputation second to none among the English hed- 
 onists of the latter part of the nineteenth century, but more 
 particularly because his ethical theory is much less dependent 
 upon the Evolutional method which he adopts than is com- 
 monly recognised. It will be remembered that Mr. Spencer's 
 first book having a bearing upon Ethics was published eight 
 years before the Origin of Species, his last only nine years 
 ago. During these forty-two years, most of which have been 
 devoted to other subjects, his views on Ethics have naturally 
 undergone some modifications, yet there is an underlying con- 
 sistency which one misses m the ethical writings of J. S. Mill 
 — and this, although Mr. Spencer shows a frankness equal to 
 that of Mill in pointing out the modifications of his doctrine 
 of which he is himself conscious. 
 
 In truth, a special reason for considering his ethical writings 
 at length in this connection is, that his doctrine is presented 
 in what may be called a pre-Evolutional form in Social Statics 
 (1851), as well as in a form ostensibly depending upon the 
 theory of Evolution in the Principles of Ethics (1879- 1893). 
 A comparison of the later with the earlier form of the system 
 is as interesting as it is instructive. Moreover, the extreme 
 claims for Evolutional Ethics, made in the Data of Ethics 
 (1879), are considerably diminished before the completion of 
 the Principles. We must not anticipate on this point, but no 
 passage in Mr. Spencer's works does more credit to his single- 
 minded love of truth, all his own former prepossessions to the 
 contrary notwithstanding, than that in the Preface to his con-
 
 270 History of Uiilitarianism. 
 
 •eluding contribution to Ethics, Negative Beneficence and 
 Positive Beneficence (1893), where he says : "The Doctrine of 
 Evolution has not furnished guidance to the extent I had 
 hoped. Most of the conclusions, drawn empirically, are such 
 as right feelings, enlightened by cultivated intelligence, have 
 already sufficed to establish." 
 
 The earliest draft of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory is to be 
 found in the first, or theoretical, portion of his well-known 
 Social vS/<a:/zVj' (1851), and also in the concluding chapters of 
 the same book. The long, but rather unsystematic. Introduc- 
 tion is mainly devoted to a severe criticism of the Doctrine 
 of Expediency, the gist of which is as follows. All men seek 
 a guide for conduct, but a practical guide in the form of a 
 general principle seems to remain a desideratum. The Doc- 
 trine of Expediency (Bentham's principle of ' the greatest 
 happiness of the greatest number ') has indeed been confidently 
 recommended as such a guide ; but a rule, principle, or axiom, 
 in order to have any theoretical or practical value, must have a 
 definite meaning. We must therefore take it for granted that, 
 when Bentham announced ' the greatest happmess of the 
 greatest number ' as the canon of social morality, he supposed 
 mankind to be unanimous in their definition of ' greatest 
 happiness '. 
 
 "This was a most unfortunate assumption," says Mr. Spencer, 
 ■" for no fact is more palpable than that the standard of happi- 
 ness is infinitely variable. In all ages — amongst every people 
 — by each class — do we find different notions of it entertained." 
 After giving a number of rather striking examples, he says : 
 " Generalising such facts, we see that the standard of ' greatest 
 happiness ' possesses as little fixity as the other exponents 
 of human nature ". And he goes on to show that the reason 
 for this is simple enough. Happiness signifies a gratified 
 state of all the faculties. The gratification of a faculty is 
 produced by its exercise, provided that the exercise be propor- 
 tionate to the power of the faculty. But the faculties of men 
 -differ as regards their ratio to each other in each case ; more-
 
 Herbert Spencer. 271 
 
 over, there is in each a different balance of desires. " Conse- 
 quently the notion of happiness must vary with the disposi- 
 tion and character ; that is, must vary indefinitely." According 
 to the author's view, this leads to the inevitable conclusion 
 that " a true conception of what human hfe should be, is 
 possible only to the ideal man. . . . And as the world yet 
 contains none such, it follows that a specific idea of ' greatest 
 happiness ' is for the present unattainable." ^ But even if 
 we were agreed as to what constitutes the ' greatest happiness,' 
 there would yet remain the unwarranted assumption that it 
 is possible for the self-guided human judgment to determine, 
 with something like precision, by what methods it may be 
 obtained. In support of this latter position, Mr. Spencer 
 mentions a number of cases of mistaken legislation. And he 
 characteristically adds : " But why cite individual cases ? Does 
 not the experience of all nations testify to the futility of these 
 empirical attempts at the acquisition of happiness .^ What is 
 the statute-book but a record of such unhappy guesses 1 or 
 history but a narrative of their unsuccessful issues ? " ^ 
 
 Here, in fact, the drift of the argument changes somewhat. 
 The author proceeds to criticise the Expediency Philosophy 
 less as a method of Ethics than as a mistaken political theory. 
 A fatal objection to this theory is, that it assumes the eternity 
 of government, while in reality government is not essential, 
 but incidental. " Daily is statecraft held in less repute. . . . 
 As civilisation advances, does government decay. To the bad 
 it is essential ; to the good, not. ... Its continuance is proof 
 of still-existing barbarism." ^ Note, then, the predicament 
 of the Expediency Philosophy : " A system of moral phil- 
 osophy professes to be a code of correct rules for the control of 
 human beings. . . . Government, however, is an institution 
 originating in man's imperfection ; an institution confessedly 
 begotten by necessity out of evil. . . . How, then, can that be 
 a true system of morality which adopts government as one of 
 its premises ? " 
 
 1 See Introduction : ' The Doctrine of Expediency,' ^ 2. 
 ^ See ihid., % 3. '■^ See ibid., % 4.
 
 272 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Mr. Spencer sums up his objections as follows : " Of the 
 Expediency Philosophy it must therefore be said, in the 
 first place, that it can make no claim to a scientific character, 
 seeing that its fundamental proposition is not an axiom, but 
 simply an enunciation of the problem to be solved. 
 
 " Further, that even supposing its fundamental proposition 
 were an axiom, it would still be inadmissible, because expressed 
 in terms possessing no fixed acceptation. 
 
 " Moreover, were the Expediency theory otherwise satisfac- 
 tory, it would be still useless ; since it requires nothing less 
 than omniscience to carry it into practice. 
 
 " And, waiving all other objections, we are yet compelled 
 to reject a system, which, at the same time that it tacitly 
 lays claim to perfection, takes imperfection for its basis." ^ 
 
 The rest of the Introduction is taken up with a vindication 
 of the Moral Sense doctrine in a qualified form. This we may 
 pass over somewhat rapidly, both because the author's views on 
 the subject were at this time very imperfectly worked out, and 
 because they later were fundamentally changed. The drift of 
 the argument is as follows. It seems probable that the moral 
 law of society, like its other laws, originates in some attribute 
 of human nature. Answering to each of the actions which 
 we need to perform for the sake of physical health, we find in 
 ourselves some prompter called a desire. May we not there- 
 fore assume that there is also some inner tendency or principle 
 impelling us to morality, i.e., a Moral Sense ? It is not enough 
 to disprove the existence of such an instinct, to insist upon 
 what are properly to be regarded as perversions of the instinct. 
 All instincts may be perverted. Moreover, even the disciples 
 of Bentham are, in the last resort, obliged to depend upon an 
 intuition of this much derided Moral Sense for the foundation 
 of their own system. In truth, only the hopelessly prejudiced 
 can fail to recognise, on every hand, the workings of such a 
 faculty. 
 
 " But how, it may be asked, can a sentiment have a percep- 
 
 ' See Introduction : ' The Doctrine of Expediency,' § 5.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 273 
 
 tion ? How can a desire give rise to a moral sense} Is there 
 not here a confounding of the intellectual with the emotional ? " 
 Mr. Spencer admits that the objection — which, as will be seen, 
 he states very clearly — seems a serious one, and would be 
 fatal, were the term ' sense ' to be understood in its strictest 
 acceptation. Indeed, his answer to the objection is by no 
 means convincing. The problem, as he himself points out, is 
 to explain " how from an impulse to behave in the way we call 
 equitable, there will arise a perceptioji that such behaviour is 
 proper — a conviction that it is good ". He says : " This instinct 
 or sentiment, being gratified by a just action, and distressed 
 by an unjust action, produces in us an approbation of the one, 
 and a disgust towards the other ; and these readily beget 
 beliefs that the one is virtuous, and the other vicious " } 
 Speaking of the Moral Sense and Intuitional schools of Ethics, 
 he says : " Unsuccessful as these writers have been in the 
 endeavour to develop a philosophical morality, all of them, if 
 the foregoing reasoning be correct, have consulted a true 
 oracle. Though they have failed to systematise its utterances, 
 they have acted wisely in trying to do this. An analysis of 
 right and wrong so made, is not indeed the profoundest and 
 ultimate one ; but, as we shall by-and-by see, it is perfectly in 
 harmony with that in its initial principle, and coincident with 
 it in its results." One other passage is well worth reproduc- 
 ing : " If Bentham is right in condemning Moral Sense, as an 
 ' anarchical and capricious principle, founded solely upon in- 
 ternal and peculiar feelings,' then is his own maxim doubly 
 fallacious. Is not the idea, ' greatest happiness,' a capricious 
 one } Is not that also ' founded solely upon internal and 
 peculiar feelings '.''... At the worst therefore, in so far as 
 want of scientific precision is concerned, a philosophy founded 
 on Moral Sense, simply stands in the same category with all 
 other known systems." ^ 
 
 Such are the principal ideas of the Introduction, expressed 
 largely in the author's own words. Before proceeding with 
 
 ' See Introduction : ' The Doctrine of the Moral Sense,' § 5. 
 - See ihid., § 6. 
 
 18
 
 2 74 History of iltilitarianisin. 
 
 our examination of the rest of the book, in so far as that is 
 necessary for our purpose, it will be well to pause for a little, 
 in order to grasp the fundamental conception upon which 
 both the critical and the (at least implicitly) constructive part 
 of the Introduction depend. It would be quite possible for 
 a careless reader to mistake the drift of Mr. Spencer's earlier 
 criticism of what he terms the Expediency Philosophy. His is 
 not one of the familiar attempts to show in detail the difficulties 
 attending the hedonistic calculus. If such were the case, it 
 would have been wholly unnecessary to reproduce his criticism 
 at such length. As a matter of fact, his point of view is not 
 easy to define in brief terms, but it plainly depends upon 
 his conception of the perfect man in a perfect society, as the 
 necessary postulate in a scientific system of Ethics. This 
 paradoxical conception, which has remained to the end an 
 important feature of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory, will later 
 require careful consideration. Here we are concerned with it 
 only as affording his point of departure in criticising Utili- 
 tarianism. His meaning seems to be, that a direct computation 
 of the consequences of actions, in terms of happiness and un- 
 happiness, can never afiFord the foundation for a scientific 
 Ethics, not merely, or principally, because experience shows 
 that individuals derive pleasure or pain, as the case may be, 
 from very different things ; but because it is absolutely certam, 
 on general principles, that every advance in morality in- 
 volves a shifting of the scale of hedonistic values. Other- 
 wise expressed, individuals and nations are constantly, if 
 generally very slowly, discarding one scale of hedonistic 
 values for another, previously assumed to be ultimate, and 
 this in proportion to the development of moral character. 
 Reduced to its lowest terms, this means that hedonistic values 
 vary as moral character varies. 
 
 By many ethical writers of the present day, this is regarded 
 as perhaps the strongest argument for holding that, m some 
 sense or other, character or personality is the ultimate for 
 Ethics, and not happiness. Mr. Spencer, however, does not 
 seem to entertain this view even as an abstract possibility ;
 
 Herbert Spencer. 275 
 
 but, assuming that moral values must ultimately be interpreted 
 in hedonistic terms, without anything like a careful examina- 
 tion of other types of ethical theory, he concludes that only 
 the scale of hedonistic values that would appeal to the perfect 
 man in a perfect society (in which alone, apparently, he could 
 exist) is the true scale of such values. Apparently, then, 
 this postulate of the perfect man in a perfect society, however 
 great the difficulties which it involves, is far from being a 
 merely arbitrary and eccentric assumption on the part of the 
 author, in this earlier exposition of his ethical theory ; he 
 seems here to regard it, rather, as the only possible salvation 
 of hedonism. Nothing could well be more instructive than 
 such an implicit criticism of hedonism itself, coming from 
 one of its most prominent and able advocates. It is rather 
 important to remember that this view, when first set forth by 
 Mr. Spencer, was held in connection with the Moral Sense 
 doctrine. Such an intuitional adjunct to his system would 
 tend to prevent that further analysis which might have sug- 
 gested to him, that he was really making hedonism depend 
 upon some other undefined principle. It is probably signifi- 
 cant that Mr. Spencer's later criticisms of Utilitarianism vary 
 considerably in method from this earlier and, in the present 
 writer's opinion, much more effective one. 
 
 We have now to see how the principles of the Introduction 
 are worked out in the earlier and later parts of the 
 body of the book, the intermediate portions not being to the 
 present purpose, as they have not to do with theoretical 
 Ethics. The title of the first chapter, " Definition of Mo- 
 rality," is somewhat misleading. Instead of attempting 
 clearly to differentiate the subject-matter of Ethics from 
 that of other sciences or disciphnes, the author insists still 
 further upon the necessity of regarding the moral law as the 
 law of the perfect man. He argues that a system of pure 
 Ethics cannot recognise evil, or any of those conditions which 
 evil generates. Indeed, he says : " It entirely ignores wrong, 
 injustice, or crime, and gives no information as to what must 
 be done when they have been committed. It knows no such
 
 276 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 thing as an infraction of the laws, for it is merely a statement 
 of what the laws are. It simply says, such and such are the 
 principles on which men should act ; and when these are 
 broken it can do nothing but say that they are broken," ' 
 And he argues in justification of this position, that he is merely 
 putting Ethics on the same plane with the several sciences. 
 The geometrician, e.g., has to assume that the various figures 
 with which he deals are perfect each after its kind. In a 
 similar way, physiology treats of the functions of our different 
 organs in their normal state ; it has nothing to say of disease 
 or any of the problems arising in connection with disease. 
 
 It does not seem to have occurred to Mr. Spencer that such 
 comparisons amount to little more than figures of speech, 
 unless re-enforced by arguments which, in his own treatment, 
 are not forthcoming. Even apart from the important dis- 
 tinction between the normal and the abnormal, the method 
 of the sciences is necessarily abstract in a sense that is 
 not always appreciated by those who triumphantly point to 
 science as that which describes things or events as they are or 
 take place in the concrete, the principal reason being that the 
 scientist has to take one thing at a time. A given physical 
 law, e.g., states what would take place under certain definite 
 conditions, abstracting from all other complicating conditions. 
 In this sense, science is quite as abstract as Mr. Spencer 
 would make it ; but one must carefully observe that the ab- 
 stractions of the scientist, if legitimate, are always perfectly 
 clear. We are never left in doubt as to what is meant by 
 a perfectly straight line or a perfect curve of a particular 
 order ; nor do we fail to understand the physicist, when he 
 tells us that things would happen exactly thus and so in the 
 external world, if the conditions specified were the only 
 conditions present. But the perfect man is an abstraction 
 of an entirely different kind — an abstract and ultimate ideal, 
 the true meaning of which, at any given stage of ethical 
 reflection, can be only very vaguely indicated. To say, then, 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. i., § 3.
 
 Herbei4 Spence7-. 277 
 
 that the very possibility of a scientific Ethics depends upon 
 our beginning with, and perpetually referring to, an ideal 
 which by no possibility can be made perfectly definite, is 
 surely to put Ethics itself in a most dangerous position. 
 Moreover, an Ethics which should refuse to take account of 
 moral evil as well as moral good, and to define the relations 
 of those standing for the good to those responsible, so far as 
 human beings are responsible, for the evil in the world, would 
 surely have little to do with what we all understand by moral 
 conduct. One must hasten to remark that Mr. Spencer's 
 own ethical system is by no means such as to come under 
 this necessarily sweeping condemnation, but we must clearly 
 recognise the danger of the methodological principle with 
 which he starts out. 
 
 The next topic treated is " The Evanescence of Evil ". 
 Here biological science affords the point of departure, although 
 it must be remembered that the author was not yet writing 
 in the light of modern evolutional theory. ^ All evil results 
 from the non-adaptation of constitution to conditions. But 
 evil perpetually tends to disappear ; adaptation is going on 
 all the time. This universal law of physical modification 
 is the law of mental modification also. Now the best condi- 
 tion of society plainly requires that each individual shall have 
 such desires only as may be satisfied without trenching upon 
 the ability of other individuals to obtain like satisfaction. 
 Of course, we are not thus perfectly adapted at present ; 
 and the principal reason is, that we retain certain traits that 
 were necessary in the original predatory life of the race. 
 All sins of men against each other, in the last resort, reduce 
 to sacrificing the welfare of others to one's own. This was 
 once necessary, but is no longer so. We are still in the pro- 
 
 ^ Of course ' adaptation of constitution to conditions ' conveniently indicates 
 the general direction of evolutional development ; but what is most characteristic 
 in modern evolutional theory is the attempt to show how such adaptation is 
 brought about — what are the ' factors of evolution,' and how they operate. It 
 is hardly necessary to say that no account of the ' factors of evolution ' is given 
 in Social Statics, which, as we have seen, was published eight years before the 
 Origin of Species.
 
 278 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 cess of adaptation to the changed conditions. Progress, which 
 can only consist in such adaptation, is not an accident, but 
 a necessity.^ The behef in human perfectibiHty merely 
 amounts to the belief that man will finally become completely 
 suited to his mode of life. " Thus," to quote Mr. Spencer's 
 own words, " the ultimate development of the ideal man is 
 logically certain — as certain as any conclusion in which we 
 place the most implicit faith ; for instance, that all men will 
 die." 2 
 
 Various things might be said regarding this decidedly sum- 
 mary treatment of the problem of evil. Even admitting the 
 unproved assumption that there is nothing in any sense 
 essential in morality, but that it consists merely in the com- 
 plete adaptation of the individual to his environment, it is 
 plain that the biological analogy is misleading, particularly 
 when made to do service as an argument. In the first place, 
 complete adaptation to environment, in the case of any given 
 species, is always rather an ideal than a fact The most we 
 can say is, that there is always a tendency toward such com- 
 plete adaptation. But secondly, adaptation of an animal 
 species to its environment means adaptation to relatively 
 permanent and comparatively simple physical conditions. On 
 the other hand, adaptation of man to his environment — if, as 
 is here certainly the case, man is to be regarded as more than 
 a mere physical organism — means indefinitely more than this. 
 Even physically considered, his environment is subject to 
 constant, and sometimes radical, change as the result of his 
 own exertions, in his capacity as an intellectual being capable 
 of devising means to the attainment of his desired ends. But 
 what we may call his ' psychical environment ' is much more 
 important, and this plainly is subject to almost endless modi- 
 
 ^ It is rather curious that Mr. Spencer has never questioned the legitimacy 
 of this optimistic assumption. In the later form of his system, where he pro- 
 fesses to depend upon the theory of Evolution, Evolution itself is always re- 
 garded as that which makes for ' progress '. But how about the phenomena 
 of ' degeneration ' ? (C/. the book on that phase of Evolution by Professor 
 E. R. Lankester.) 
 
 2 See Pt. I., ch. ii., §4.
 
 He7^bert Spencer. 279 
 
 fication. Every stage of intellectual or moral progress or 
 decadence on the part of the social group to which he belongs 
 means a change in what we here call the ' psychical environ- 
 ment '. To say that, in the last resort, this constantly chang- 
 ing psychical environment is wholly dependent upon physical 
 environment, would really be practically to beg the whole 
 question ; and what the complete adaptation of man to his 
 total environment, psychical as well as physical, would 
 mean — that, surely, would be a problem for omniscience 
 itself. 
 
 Having thus cleared the ground, and acquainted us with 
 his own fundamental postulates, in large part, at least, Mr. 
 Spencer proceeds to a still further criticism of the Expediency 
 Philosophy, as introductory to the constructive portion of the 
 book, which is immediately to follow. He says : " If, instead 
 of proposing it as the rule of human conduct, Bentham had 
 simply assumed ' greatest happiness ' to be the creative pur- 
 pose, his position would have been tenable enough. Almost 
 all men do in one way or other assert the same. . . . The doc- 
 trme is taught by all our religious teachers ; it is assumed 
 by every writer on morality : we may therefore safely con- 
 sider it as an admitted truth." ^ But he goes on to show that 
 it is something quite different to assume that ' greatest happi- 
 ness' should be Xh^ immediate Kxva oi va2iV\. That has been 
 the fatal error of the Expediency Philosophers. " They have 
 not observed that the truth has two sides, a Divine side and 
 a human side. ' We, as human beings, must confine ourselves 
 to the attempt to ascertain the general conditions, by con- 
 forming to which this greatest happiness may be obtained. 
 
 First and foremost among these conditions is the social 
 state itself. There is really no option as to whether we shall 
 live in or out of society ; that is decided for us. Now it is 
 evident that, in order to realise the greatest sum of happi- 
 ness in society, men must be such that " each can obtain 
 complete happiness within his own sphere of activity, without 
 
 1 See Pt. I., ch. iii., § i.
 
 28o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 diminishing the spheres of activity required for the acquisi- 
 tion of happiness by others ".^ This, then, is the first and 
 most fundamental of those fixed conditions to the attainment 
 of greatest happiness, necessitated by the social state ; and it 
 is the fulfilment of this condition which we express by the 
 word Justice. But this non-interference is not all that is re- 
 quired, though in itself more important, as we shall see later, 
 than any other single principle whatever. We must add : 
 " The human constitution must be such as that each man may 
 perfectly fulfil his own nature, not only without diminishing 
 other men's spheres of activity, but without giving unhappi- 
 ness to other men in any direct or indirect way ". This may 
 be called Negative Beneficence. Later we shall see that this 
 principle needs to be kept quite separate from the preceding. 
 But further, the sum-total of happiness will be greatly in- 
 creased, if men are so constituted that each, in addition to the 
 pleasures that come to him immediately, can sympathetically 
 participate in the pleasurable emotions of all others. The 
 observance of this condition of happiness may be called Posi- 
 tive Beneficence. But even still the enumeration is incom- 
 plete. Another principle must be recognised, which, indeed, 
 has been tacitly presupposed throughout. " Lastly," says Mr. 
 Spencer, " there must go to the production of the greatest 
 happiness the further condition, that, whilst duly regardful 
 of the preceding limitations, each individual shall perform all 
 those acts required to fill up the measure of his own private 
 happiness." ^ 
 
 Such, then, are the conditions absolutely requisite, in order 
 to the attainment of greatest happiness. The author says . 
 " We have no need to perplex ourselves with investigations 
 into the expediency of every measure, by trying to trace out 
 its ultimate results in all their infinite ramifications — a task 
 which it is folly to attempt. Our course is to inquire con- 
 
 ' Later in Social Statics appears the more exact formula for the same prin- 
 ciple : " Every man has freedom to do all that he wills, provided he infringes 
 not the equal freedom of any other man " (see Pt. I., ch. vi., § i). 
 
 2Pt. I., ch. iii., §2.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 281 
 
 cerning such measure, whether or not it fully recognises these 
 fundamental necessities, and to be sure that it must be proper 
 or improper accorduigly. Our whole code of duty is com- 
 prehended in the endeavour to live up to these necessities." ^ 
 If it be objected that the foregoing classification of the con- 
 ditions needful to greatest happiness is in some degree arti- 
 ficial, the author admits that, under a final analysis, all such 
 distinctions as those above made must disappear ; ^ but he 
 insists that similar criticisms may be passed upon all classifi- 
 cations whatever. 
 
 At length we have, in briefest possible outline, the essentials 
 
 of Mr. Spencer's own ethical system, in its earlier form. 
 And it will be seen at a glance that, however much he may 
 have changed his mind on special points, he has employed 
 the same classification and, roughly speaking, the same method 
 to the end. This, then, is the ' scientific ' method, which we 
 are to accept and rigorously to carry out, in place of the 
 discredited Expediency Philosophy. We must now inquire, 
 and that very carefully, whether we have here a really new 
 theory, or the unconscious revival of an old one. We have 
 been told that we must not pursue the greatest happiness 
 directly, for that would mean committing ourselves to the 
 perfectly hopeless task of computing exactly the consequences 
 of actions in the particular case ; we must rather act with a 
 view to the fundamental conditions of the greatest happiness, 
 or, in other words, according to certain general rules. So far, 
 it must be denied emphatically that the doctrine above set 
 forth is new. In truth, it would be possible to show a rather 
 startling similarity between this earlier, pre-Evolutional form 
 of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory, in which he recognises the 
 greatest happiness of man as the Divine Idea in creation, and 
 the later form of so-called Theological Utilitarianism. Both 
 theories recognise the Divine Idea, or creative purpose, as 
 being the greatest happiness of man ; both show that for 
 
 1 Pt. I., ch. iii., § 2. 
 
 2 He admits this verbally, but is inconsistent in his peculiar treatment of 
 Justice, as will be seen laler.
 
 282 History of Uiiiitarianism. 
 
 very practical reasons, reasons of utility itself, one must act 
 according to general rules, which plainly make for the common 
 welfare, and not either follow the will-o'-the-wisp of selfish 
 gratification or entangle oneself with special problems of 
 what Bentham only too aptly termed ' moral arithmetic '. 
 
 But we must be warned by some of the author's own mis- 
 takes, and not carry a tempting comparison too far. The 
 reader has doubtless already noted Mr. Spencer's insistence 
 upon the all-importance of Justice. This, to be sure, does not 
 in itself differentiate his treatment of Ethics from that of 
 preceding hedonistic writers. In fact, any sane moralist is 
 pretty sure to recognise the extreme importance of the prin- 
 ciple of Justice, however defined, and to grant it a certain 
 primacy over other principles. But it is to be noted that 
 Mr. Spencer — unlike earlier, or indeed later, hedonistic writers 
 — first, practically identifies the principle of Justice with that 
 of non-interference with the free activities of others, and 
 secondly, gives to the principle a special intuitive character, 
 as will be explained immediately, which comes very near to 
 putting it on a plane by itself, i.e., making it differ from other 
 ethical principles, not only in degree, but in kind. This last 
 feature of the author's treatment was perhaps not urmatural,. 
 considering the rather vague and confusing Intuitionism of 
 his earlier ethical position ; but it is hardly necessary to re- 
 mind the reader that this same discrimination in favour of 
 Justice, which makes it in a sense more ultimate than even 
 hedonism itself, is fully as characteristic of Mr. Spencer's later 
 as of his earlier treatment. At the proper time, this very 
 serious difftculty in the system which we are examining will 
 have to be squarely met ; here it is mentioned merely by way 
 of anticipation. 
 
 At the beginning of Part II. of the Social Statics, which 
 immediately follows the discussion which we have been con- 
 sidering, the author attempts to deduce his fundamental 
 principles somewhat less abstractly for the benefit of those 
 who may find the previous argument difficult to follow. This 
 attempted simplification of the same general argument we
 
 Herbert Spencer. 283, 
 
 may, of course, safely omit. But in this connection we shall 
 find stated, more clearly than elsewhere in this book, the 
 exact relation between the primary principle, Justice, and the 
 secondary principles. Prudence, Negative Beneficence, and 
 Positive Beneficence. Mr. Spencer says : " Justice imposes 
 upon the exercise of faculties a primary series of limitations, 
 which is strictly true as far as it goes. Negative beneficence im- 
 poses a secondary series. It is no defect in the first of these that 
 it does not include the last The two are, in the main, dis- 
 tinct ; and, as we have just seen, the attempt to unite them 
 under one expression leads us into fatal errors." ^ Then, after 
 repeating that the secondary laws are greatly inferior, as re- 
 gards exactness, to Justice, he says : " Not being able to 
 define specifically the constitution of the ideal man, but being 
 able to define it generically only ... we are quite incompetent 
 to say of every particular deed whether it is or is not ac- 
 cordant with that constitution. Or, putting the difficulty in 
 its simplest form, we may say, that as both of these supple- 
 mentary limitations - involve the term happiness, and as 
 happiness is for the present capable only of a generic and 
 not of a specific definition, they do not admit of scientific 
 development. Though abstractedly correct limitations, and 
 limitations which the ideal man will strictly observe, they 
 cannot be reduced to concrete forms until the ideal man 
 exists." ^ The last passage, in particular, is important. The 
 supplementary principles, of whatever sort — and these are 
 three, according to Mr. Spencer, Prudence, Negative Benefi- 
 cence, and Positive Beneficence — are subordinate to Justice, 
 not only because they lack the definite, intuitive character of 
 Justice, but because they all equally involve the conception 
 
 ^ See Pt. II., ch. iv., § 4. (It should be noted that the chapters are numbered 
 continuously, without regard to the part to which they belong.) 
 
 ^ The supplementary principles directly referred to, as the context would 
 show, are due regard for one's own welfare (Prudence) and Negative Benefi- 
 cence. What Mr. Spencer says in this passage would, of course, apply with 
 equal force to Positive Beneficence. 
 
 •' See ihid., § 5.
 
 284 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 ■of happiness, which latter is capable only of a generic, and not 
 a specific, definition — until the advent of the perfect man. 
 
 Before passing on to the latter part of the Sociat Statics — 
 for of course we are not here concerned with the numerous 
 chapters in which the author applies his fundamental prin- 
 ciples to the solution of special political and social problems 
 — it will be well to notice a few passages in what he calls his 
 " Secondary Derivation of a First Principle ". He is here 
 concerned to show that there is in man a special faculty by 
 virtue of which he tends both to assert his own rights and to 
 recognise the rights of others. As might be expected, this 
 faculty turns out to be the Moral Sense itself, exercising its 
 most characteristic function. Mr. Spencer definitely lays 
 down and defends the thesis, that " this first and all-essential 
 law [Justice], declaratory of the liberty of each limited only 
 by the like liberty of all, is that fundamental truth of which 
 the moral sense is to give an intuition, and which the intellect 
 IS to develop into a scientific morality ". He then says : 
 " From the above accumulation of evidence it is inferred that 
 there exists in man what may be termed an instinct of per- 
 sonal rights — a feeling that leads him to claim as great a 
 share of natural privilege as is claimed by others — a feeling 
 that leads him to repel anything like an encroachment upon 
 what he thinks his sphere of original freedom ".^ Somewhat 
 later he adds : " Seeing, however, that this instinct of personal 
 rights is a purely selfish instinct, leading each man to assert 
 and defend his own liberty of action, there remains the ques- 
 tion — Whence comes our perception of the rights of others } " 
 
 In general, Mr. Spencer agrees with the method adopted 
 by Adam Smith in his Theory of Moral Sentiments, where, of 
 course, this and other important phenomena of our moral life 
 are explained by the principle of Sympathy. But he makes 
 the following criticism of Smith's actual treatment -. " Not re- 
 cognising any such impulse as that which urges men to 
 maintain their claims, he did not see that their respect for the 
 
 1 See Pt. II., ch. v., § 2.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 285 
 
 claims of others, may be explained in the same way. He 
 did not perceive that the sentiment of justice is nothing but 
 a sympathetic affection of the instinct of personal rights — 
 a sort of reflex function of it. . . . It was elsewhere hinted, 
 that though we must keep up the distinction between them, 
 it is nevertheless true that justice and beneficence have a 
 common root, and the reader will now at once perceive that 
 the common root is — Sympathy." 1 It is further argued that,. 
 if our perceptions of justice are generated in the way alleged, 
 " it will follow that, other things equal, those who have the 
 strongest sense of their own rights, will have the strongest 
 sense of the rights of their neighbours ". Of course it is not 
 claimed that this is absolutely true, but only that, " in the 
 average of cases, we may safely conclude that a man's sense 
 of justice to himself, and his sense of justice to his neighbours, 
 bear a constant ratio to each other " ? 
 
 The passages above quoted contain, perhaps, the most 
 satisfactory statement to be found in the Social Statics regard- 
 ing that constitution of human nature, by virtue of which the 
 moral law is at once to be apprehended and gradually realised. 
 They also throw an interesting light upon Mr. Spencer's 
 earlier conception of the Moral Sense. We have already seen 
 that this has to do mainly with the one ethical principle which 
 is perfectly free from ambiguity, and therefore capable of 
 strictly scientific development — Justice. And we are now led 
 to see, what has probably been suspected by the reader 
 hitherto, that, in its operation, the moral sense manifests itself 
 more as an instinct (implying an impulsive tendency) than as 
 a faculty of abstract moral intuitions. In fact, the author is. 
 always comparing it with the instincts which lead us to satisfy 
 our various bodily wants. 
 
 It is difficult to see, from the hints afforded, how this funda- 
 mental tendency of human nature, primarily impulsive m 
 character, is capable of such development as to make possible 
 a scientific Ethics. Is it too much to suggest that, here 
 
 1 See Pt. II., ch. v., § 5. - See ibid., % 6.
 
 2 86 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 again, Mr. Spencer is partly misled by his dependence upon 
 biological analogies? Most assuredly the moralist, of what- 
 ever school, should take the most careful account of those 
 forces of human nature which make for conduct. But those 
 same forces, or tendencies, of human nature, no matter how 
 fundamental, must be morally justified, if justihed at all, by 
 showing that they make for the ultimate end of conduct, the 
 Summuvi Bonum. Logically, the only escape from an Ethics 
 of the Good is to stop with naive Intuitionism, the essential 
 characteristic of which is an implicit denial that the several 
 parts of the moral law can be rationalised by being brought 
 under a single higher principle. And this, without question, 
 is the very antithesis of scientific ethical method. In the 
 earlier form of his system, at any rate, Mr. Spencer seems to 
 run great risk of becoming entangled with two ultimates : 
 Justice, considered as an absolute principle, which therefore 
 needs no further justification, and Happiness, considered as 
 an ultimate, though an ultimate not capable of exact compre- 
 hension ; and two methods, the one Intuitive, the other 
 Hedonistic — and this quite apart from his questionable inter- 
 pretation and explanation of the Moral Sense itself. 
 
 As already suggested, it would be quite apart from our 
 present purpose to consider Mr. Spencer's own applications of 
 his first principle, or axiom, of freedom from interference, i.e., 
 Justice, to prove the several rights upon which he so strongly 
 insists — the rights of life, personal liberty, use of the earth, 
 property, exchange, free-speech, etc. Nor are we concerned 
 with his discussions (in Part III), also from the point of view 
 of Justice, interpreted as the principle of non-interference, 
 regarding the proper constitution of the State. It may be 
 doubted whether any prominent writer belonging strictly to 
 the present generation would attempt the solution of so many 
 practical problems, mainly of state-craft, by the application of 
 a single abstract principle. So far from being a matter of 
 strict logic, such application is necessarily a matter of in- 
 dividual judgment, even allowing, for the sake of the argu- 
 ment, the validity of the first principle assumed. An interest-
 
 Hei'bert Spencer. 287 
 
 ing illustration of this rather obvious truth may be found in 
 the author's earlier treatment of the land question, where, 
 quite contrary to his later judgment in the matter, he advo- 
 cates the nationalisation of land, on the ground that a mon- 
 opoly of land-ownership by individuals interferes with the 
 equal freedom of others. 
 
 Part IV. of the Social Statics, which concludes the work, is 
 essentially different in character from what precedes. Not 
 that the views set forth are incompatible with those which we 
 have already examined ; but what the writer here attempts is 
 something radically different. He says : " Social philosophy 
 may be aptly divided (as political economy has been) into 
 statics and dynamics ; the first treating of the equilibrium of 
 a perfect society, the second of the forces by which society is 
 advanced towards perfection. . . . Hitherto we have concerned 
 ourselves chiefly with the statics, touching upon the dynamics 
 only occasionally for purposes of elucidation. Now, however, 
 the dynamics claim special attention." ^ The treatment here 
 given, however, is both very brief and quite unsystematic, a 
 last word being devoted to various subjects. Hence, pro- 
 bably, the title of the long chapter which practically consti- 
 tutes this final part of the book — " General Considerations ". 
 
 The course of civilisation, we are told, could not have been 
 different from what it has been. What might have been in 
 the abstract {i.e., according to a different scheme of creation), 
 we cannot say. " But given an unsubdued earth ; given the 
 being — man, appointed to overspread and occupy it ; given 
 the laws of life what they are ; and no other series of changes 
 than that which has taken place, could have taken place." - 
 The primitive man had to be a savage, for it was his function 
 to clear the earth of races endangering his life and occupy- 
 ing the space required for mankind. It was necessary that he 
 should have the desire to kill, and that he should be devoid 
 of sympathy, or possess but the germ of it. A thoroughly 
 civilised community could not be formed out of men qualified 
 
 1 See Pt. IV., ch. xxx., § i. ^ See ibid., % 2.
 
 288 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 to wage war with the pre-existing occupants of the earth. 
 The barbarising of colonists, who live in close contact with the 
 lower races, is universally admitted. The gist of the matter 
 is : the primitive man had to be one whose happiness was 
 obtained largely at the sacrifice of the happiness of others. 
 But we have already seen that the ultimate man must be 
 one who can obtain happiness without deducting from the 
 happiness of others. Moreover, we have seen that progress, 
 what we call ' moral progress,' is a necessary law. Why, then, 
 does the needed adaptation to new conditions, in which pro- 
 gress consists, take place so slowly ? 
 
 The reason is, that the new conditions themselves have 
 arisen but slowly. Warfare between man and the creatures 
 at enmity with him has continued up to the present time, and 
 over a large portion of the globe is going on still. The 
 destructive propensities which inevitably thus arise, are per- 
 petuated by the custom of game-preserving. But, what is 
 more important, the old predatory instinct is in a sense self- 
 maintained for it generates between men and men a hostile 
 relationship, similar to that which it generates between men 
 and inferior animals. In short — and here we come to the 
 earlier statement of one of the author's most characteristic 
 views — human character has changed slowly, because it has 
 been subject to two conflicting sets of conditions. " On the 
 one hand," to use his own words, " the discipline of the social 
 state has been developing it into the sympathetic form ; whilst 
 on the other hand, the necessity for self-defence partly of man 
 against brute, partly of man against man, and partly of so- 
 cieties against each other, has been maintaining the old un- 
 sympathetic form." 1 The two codes thus resulting are, of 
 course, what the author in his later writings terms the ' ethics 
 of amity ' and the ' ethics of enmity '. Only when warfare 
 has largely ceased, can the former code, which is to develop 
 into the code of the perfect man, have a normal, and reason- 
 ably rapid, development 
 
 ^ See Pt. IV., ch. xxx., § 3.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 289 
 
 At this point Mr. Spencer somewhat compHcates his argu- 
 ment by showing that warfare itself has had its uses, even on 
 the social side. For what are the pre-requisites to a conquer- 
 ing race ? Numerical strength or improved methods of 
 warfare, both of which are indications of advancement. 
 " Evidently, therefore, from the very beginning, the conquest 
 of one people over another has been, in the main, the con- 
 quest of the social man over the anti-social man ; or, strictly 
 speaking, of the more adapted over the less adapted." But 
 we must very carefully observe what may at first seem to the 
 reader a rather fine distinction. Mr. Spencer says : " Whilst 
 the injustice of conquests and enslavings is not perceived, 
 they are on the whole beneficial ; but as soon as they are felt 
 to be at variance with the moral law, the continuance of them 
 retards adaptation in one direction, more than it advances it in 
 another : a fact which our new preacher of the old doctrine, 
 that might is right, may profitably consider a little ".^ 
 
 Before sympathy arises, indeed, hero-worship plays a 
 humanising part. It is found among all savage and bar- 
 barous peoples, as well as among those of higher development. 
 Indeed, without such a check upon anti-social propensities, it 
 is difficult to see how many primitive societies could exist. 
 But we must recognise it for what it is : "a sentiment which 
 leads men to prostrate themselves before any manifestation 
 of power, be it in chief, feudal lord, king, or constitutional 
 government, and makes them act in subordination to that 
 power ". In proportion to the lack of moral sense, will be the 
 degree of such submission to mere authority. This, in fact, 
 is absolutely necessary. Where reverence for the moral law is 
 lacking, reverence for mere authority must take its place ; 
 otherwise there would be complete lawlessness or barbarism. 
 In short, as the author says : " We must admit that this power- 
 worship has fulfilled, and does still fulfil, a very important 
 function, and that it may advantageously last as long as it 
 can ".2 All this is quite as characteristic of the later, as of the 
 
 1 See Pt. IV., ch. xxx., § 4. - See ihid., §§ 6, 7. 
 
 19
 
 290 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 earlier, form of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory. He consistently 
 holds throughout, that what he calls the ' pro-moral ' paves 
 the way for the strictly moral, the latter, of course, being an 
 ideal to which humanity tends always to approximate, rather 
 than an accomplished fact. The civilised races are at present 
 in an intermediate position, and the radical confusion to be 
 found in their ethical ideals is largely to be explained by the 
 essential inconsistency between the ' ethics of amity ' and the 
 ' ethics of enmity '. 
 
 Perhaps it may seem that a disproportionate amount of 
 space has been devoted to this rather minute reproduction 
 and criticism of the earlier, and confessedly inadequate, state- 
 ment of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory. Such a mode of treat- 
 ment, however, has seemed necessary for two principal reasons. 
 First, the Social Statics, in its original and complete form, is 
 now withdrawn from circulation, being superseded by a re- 
 vised and greatly abridged edition (1892), which is almost 
 useless for our present purpose. Secondly, there is a 
 special reason for presenting the earlier form of the system 
 in detail, before considering the later form. Far more ade- 
 quately than any other single writer, Mr. Spencer is commonly 
 supposed to represent Evolutional Ethics. It is generally 
 assumed, alike by friendly and adverse critics, that his success 
 or failure in solving the problems of Ethics is due principally 
 to his rigorous application of Evolutional principles. But it" 
 is highly important, in an historical and critical examination 
 like the present one, not to take things for granted. We shall 
 have to look as carefully for similarity as for dissimilarity 
 between the later and the earlier form of this important 
 system, remembering always that the earlier form, which has 
 just been reviewed, appeared eight years before the publica- 
 tion of the Origin of Species, and that, whatever its merits, 
 we have found it to be nothing if not highly abstract in char- 
 acter. And one must not, by any means, permit oneself here 
 that hopelessly vague use of the word ' Evolution ' which 
 makes it stand merely for continuous development according
 
 Hei'bert Spencer. 291 
 
 to some undefined law or laws. That is what the scientist 
 very properly criticises in some writers who constantly urge 
 that we must go back to the early Greek philosophers to find 
 the first Evolutionists. The theory of Evolution, from which 
 Evolutional Ethics takes its name, is, of course, the modem 
 scientific theory of the development of organic forms by means 
 of certain more or less definitely determined ' factors of 
 Evolution,' as Mr. Spencer has called them. And it is hardly 
 necessary to point out that, of ethical systems really depend- 
 ing upon the theory of Evolution, one which should employ 
 the principle of ' the inheritance of acquired characteristics,' 
 and base important arguments upon this principle (as Mr. 
 Spencer actually does in his later ethical writings), would 
 differ in many important respects from one which should either 
 deny the validity of this principle altogether, or allow to it 
 only a secondary role. For the influence of the theory of 
 Evolution proper upon Mr. Spencer's ethical system, then, we 
 must of course look to the later form of his doctrine ; and 
 the extent of such influence can hardly be greater, at any 
 rate, than that represented by the divergence of the later from 
 the earlier form.
 
 CHAPTER XIV. 
 
 HERBERT SPENCER {continued). 
 
 Between the publication of the Social Statics (1851) and 
 that of the Data of Ethics (1879), nearly thirty years had 
 elapsed, and during this time the sciences, particularly the 
 biological sciences, had made unexampled progress. More- 
 over, it is probable that no single scholar, in the English- 
 speaking world, at least, had followed this progress with 
 keener interest or with a more comprehensive grasp of its 
 general significance than Mr. Spencer. His equipment, there- 
 fore, on the strictly scientific side, was most complete, when 
 he attempted to realise his early ideal of a scientific Ethics. 
 Unfortunately, however, he had retained almost undiminished 
 two of his early prejudices : first, a frank contempt for His- 
 tory as such ; and secondly, a decided lack of appreciation, at 
 least, for the classic works of Philosophy, even those in the 
 field of Ethics itself The natural result was that, while a 
 polymath in quite the literal sense, so far as the literature of 
 science was concerned, Mr. Spencer had never taken the 
 trouble to master the literature of the discipline which he 
 proposed to reform ; nor had he, by any means, fitted himself 
 to take the historical point of view, even when his own treat- 
 ment logically required this. In the case of any but a highly 
 original thinker such a mixed preparation for the task in 
 hand could hardly have failed to lead to disastrous results. 
 As it is, we are bound to recognise a considerable debt to the 
 author of the Synthetic Philosophy for his later contributions 
 to a discipline in which he was, perhaps, never completely at 
 home. 
 
 (292)
 
 Herbert Spencer. 293 
 
 The Data of Ethics, ostensibly only the first of the six 
 Parts of the proposed (and now happily executed) Principtes 
 of Ethics, is a great deal more than either its title or its place 
 in the scheme of the whole work would suggest. From it, in 
 truth, one could obtain a satisfactory general knowledge of 
 the later form of Mr. Spencer's ethical system, though the 
 great importance of Part IV. — fustice (1891) — is by no means 
 to be questioned. The decidedly inferior importance of the 
 remaining parts, interesting as these are, will call for explana- 
 tion and discussion later. Here it may be premised that the 
 reason is not to be found in the failure of Mr. Spencer's 
 powers as a thinker and writer, but rather in the peculiar 
 structure of the system itself. But what one would particu- 
 larly insist upon at present, is the extreme importance of the 
 Data of Ethics, as giving an intelligible, and fairly adequate, 
 statement of the author's system as a whole. 
 
 Nothing could well seem to differ more, as regards method, 
 from the highly abstract Social Statics than the first two 
 chapters of the Data of Ethics, on " Conduct in General " and 
 " The Evolution of Conduct ". In the former work, we were 
 somewhat abruptly introduced to the conception of the ideal 
 man in an ideal society, as the necessary starting-point for 
 Ethics ; in the latter, we are told that we must begin by re- 
 garding conduct as a whole, in a sense an organic whole, of 
 which moral conduct, ordinarily so-called, is only a part, inex- 
 tricably bound up with the rest. By conduct is here meant the 
 adjustment of acts to ends, whether on the part of man or of 
 the lower animals. This adjustment, of course, may be uncon- 
 scious or conscious,^ relatively simple or almost indefinitely 
 complex. And, exactly as in the case of biological investi- 
 gations, we must interpret the more developed by the less 
 developed. This naturally leads to a consideration of the 
 evolution of conduct. Plainly such evolution, when we take 
 
 1 This is rather impHed than stated in the passages we are discussing, and 
 Mr. Spencer's emphasis on the complexity rather than the consciousness of 
 human adjustments, as that which differentiates man from the lower animals, 
 is itself an error and the source of others in his system.
 
 294 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 the whole animal kingdom into consideration, must mean at 
 least a more and more perfect adjustment of acts to ends 
 subserving individual life and the rearing of offspring. But 
 something else is presupposed, or neither of the above kinds 
 of adjustment could attain its highest form. The multi- 
 tudinous creatures which fill the earth are interfered with by 
 each other. A grim ' struggle for existence ' is being carried 
 on all the time, so that the gain of one animal or species 
 means the loss of another. 
 
 " This imperfectly-evolved conduct," says Mr. Spencer, " in- 
 troduces us by antithesis to conduct that is perfectly evolved 
 Contemplating these adjustments of acts to ends which miss 
 completeness because they cannot be made by one creature 
 without other creatures being prevented from making them, 
 raises the thought of adjustments such that each creature may 
 make them without preventing them from being made by 
 other creatures." But even this is not all. The author adds : 
 " A gap in this outline must now be filled up. There remains 
 a further advance not yet even hinted. For beyond so behav- 
 ing that each achieves his ends without preventing others 
 from achieving their ends, the members of a society may give 
 mutual help in the achievement of ends." And he urges in 
 conclusion that " Ethics has for its subject-matter, that form 
 which universal conduct assumes during the last stages of its 
 evolution "?■ 
 
 When examining the Social Statics, we were obliged to 
 conclude that Mr. Spencer was not infrequently led astray by 
 scientific analogies that did not hold. How is it with his use 
 of the idea of ' Evolution ' in the present case } Conduct, we 
 have been told, is a whole, and " we must interpret the more 
 developed by the less developed ". Organic evolution is to 
 afford us the clue. But, without warning, we take leave of 
 the struggle for existence, without which organic evolution 
 means exactly nothing, and consider how rational beings, not 
 so much do as should, behave toward each other — Justice and 
 
 J See ch. ii., §§ 6, 7.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 295 
 
 Beneficence being thus represented as pertaining to the ' last 
 stages ' of the * evolution of conduct '. Are we any longer 
 interpreting the ' more developed ' by the ' less developed ' ? 
 Are we still holding to the original meaning of the word 
 ' Evolution ' ? Or are we not rather using ' Evolution ' for 
 development in general, and assuming a development that 
 implies reason and moral personality ? Assuming, however, 
 the legitimacy of the author's conception of a perfectly con- 
 tinuous evolution of conduct, from the lowest animals up to 
 ideal man, we are prepared for his definition of good and bad 
 conduct. The conduct which we call good is the relatively 
 ' more evolved ' conduct ; and bad is the name we apply to 
 conduct which is relatively ' less evolved '. But why, on scien- 
 tific grounds merely, should Evolution be thus constantly 
 identified with what we, from our human point of view, call 
 progress ? Degeneration {e.g.., of cave animals) is as good a 
 case of evolutional development {i.e., adaptation to a given 
 environment) as any other. 
 
 But now a further question arises, according to the author : 
 " Is there any assumption made in calling good the acts con- 
 ducive to life, in self or others, and bad those which directly 
 or indirectly tend towards death, special or general .' " And 
 he himself makes the followmg reply : " Yes, there is one 
 postulate in which pessimists and optimists agree. Both 
 their arguments assume it to be self-evident that life is good 
 or bad, according as it does, or does not, bring a surplus of 
 agreeable feeling. . . . The implication common to their 
 antagonistic views is, that conduct should conduce to preserva- 
 tion of the individual, of the family, and of the society, only 
 supposing that life brings more happiness than misery." Mr. 
 Spencer concludes : " If we call good every kind of conduct 
 which aids the lives of others, and do this under the belief 
 that life brings more happiness than misery ; then it becomes 
 undeniable that, taking into account immediate and remote 
 effects on all persons, the good is universally the pleasur- 
 able ".1 
 
 ^ See ch. iii., §§ g, lo.
 
 296 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Such is Mr. Spencer's very summary vindication of hedon- 
 ism. The criticism of other types of ethical theory, which 
 immediately follows, adds little or nothing to the force of the 
 argument, as it almost wholly lacks the originality which 
 characterised the early attack upon the Expediency Philo- 
 sophy in Social Statics. Generally speaking, the argument 
 contained in the passages just quoted is an excellent example 
 of what may be called the ' either — or ' method of solving 
 philosophical problems. It is, of course, possible to state 
 almost any problem in Metaphysics or Ethics, so as to make 
 one of two conclusions seem inevitable. In fact, it takes a 
 great philosopher even to state fairly, in the first instance, the 
 essential problems of philosophy. But taking the argument 
 as it stands, and looking at it a little more closely, it will 
 readily appear that there may logically be just as many forms 
 of Optimism or Pessimism as there are different theories re- 
 garding the nature of the Good. If the Good, whatever the 
 Good may be, is attainable ; then life is worth living — other- 
 wise not. Moreover, the fact — which can hardly be denied — 
 that the Good has some relation to happiness, even a very 
 close relation, by no means proves that it is itself identical 
 with happiness. In truth, this argument of Mr. Spencer's is 
 perhaps the shortest cut to hedonism, with which the present 
 writer is acquainted. He seems to have no suspicion of the 
 many pitfalls that lie in the way of one, who would solve the 
 oldest puzzles of Moral Philosophy in such summary fashion. 
 
 Lest this criticism — ^which, of course, implies that Mr. 
 Spencer has not taken the trouble to understand certain 
 types of ethical theory differing from his own — may seem too 
 severe, let us carefully examine the well-known chapter on 
 *' Ways of Judging Conduct," which immediately follows. 
 After quite properly insisting that intellectual progress is by 
 no one trait so adequately characterised, as by development of 
 the idea of causation, and indicating briefly how long it has 
 taken for the full implications of this idea to be recognised, 
 the author says : " Why do I here make these reflections on 
 what seems an irrelevant subject } I do it because on study-
 
 Herbert Spencer. 297 
 
 ing the various ethical theories, I am struck with the fact that 
 they are all characterised either by entire absence of the idea 
 of causation, or by inadequate presence of it. Whether theo- 
 log-ical, political, intuitional, or utilitarian, they all display, 
 if not in the same degree, still, each in a large degree, the 
 defects which result from this lack." ^ 
 
 At first, this general indictment of all previous ethical theories 
 may seem rather staggering ; but if the reader pursues the 
 argument further, he will see reason as he proceeds to dis- 
 trust its validity, and will end by retaining a large portion of 
 his respect for the ethical speculation of the past. Note first 
 the division of all ethical theories into theological, political, 
 intuitional, and utilitarian. Of ' theological ' theories, we are 
 told : " Religious creeds, established and dissenting, all em- 
 body the belief that right and wrong are right and wrong 
 simply in virtue of divine enactment. And this tacit assump- 
 tion has passed from systems of theology into systems of 
 morality. . . . We see this in the works of the Stoics \sic\ as 
 well as in the works of certain Christian moralists." ^ It is 
 interesting to learn that the Stoics, with their pantheistic 
 tendencies, were guilty of making morality depend upon the 
 arbitrary will of God ; and the ' Christian moralists ' re- 
 ferred to are unnamed, except Jonathan Dymond, a recent 
 Quaker writer, who of course cannot properly be taken as 
 typical. To attribute this error to theological moralists in- 
 discriminately, is most unjust. To say nothing of more recent 
 writers, the so-called ' Theological Utilitarians ' (who appar- 
 ently would have to be classed in this category, since Utili- 
 tarianism is here, as elsewhere, treated by Mr. Spencer as a 
 non-theological system) were as far as possible from holding 
 this view, though they have sometimes been misunderstood, 
 as by J. S. Mill in his early essay on Sedgwick's Discourse. 
 It will be remembered that this error was tacitly corrected by 
 Mill three years later, in the essay on Bentham. 
 
 As regards ' political ' systems of morality, which imply " the 
 
 1 See ch. iv., § 17. 2 See ibid., § 18.
 
 298 Histoiy of U ti lit ari autism. 
 
 belief that moral obligation originates with Acts of Parliament, 
 and can be changed this way or that way by majorities," we 
 must confess that this type of ethical theory has escaped 
 our observation. The fling, apparently, is at all those who 
 " ridicule the idea that men have any natural rights, and 
 allege that rights are wholly results of convention " — another 
 example of the 'either — or ' method, previously mentioned. 
 That the ' pure intuitionists ' have not paid a due regard to 
 natural causation, may be cheerfully conceded to the author. 
 But the ' pure intuitionists ' seem here to be identified with 
 those who " affirm that we know some things to be right and 
 other things to be wrong, by virtue of a supernaturally given 
 conscience "} What is to distinguish them from the class 
 of theological moralists ? 
 
 Mr. Spencer's startling indictment of all previous Moral 
 Philosophy, then, reduces itself to his old dissatisfaction with 
 the Expediency Philosophy, so forcibly expressed in Social 
 Statics. In fact, a comparison would show that the criticism 
 here given is much less effective than the earlier one. Is 
 this because Mr. Spencer no longer cares, in this particular 
 connection, to avail himself of his conception of the perfect 
 man in the perfect society as the initial postulate of a scien- 
 tific Ethics .'' The gist of the earlier criticism, as will be re- 
 membered, was : that every advance in morality involves 
 a shifting of the scale of hedonistic values, so that only 
 the scale of such values that would appeal to the perfect man 
 could be regarded as the true or permanent scale. Hence the 
 hedonistic calculus will at any rate remain impossible until the 
 advent of the perfect man. In its way, this earlier mode of 
 attack was most effective, for it went to show that hedonistic 
 values vary with the development (or decadence) of moral 
 character ; but it plainly was dangerous to hedonism in any 
 form. Perhaps it is significant that Mr. Spencer does not 
 return to it in his later criticisms of Utilitarianism. 
 
 He proposes, indeed, a method of treatment for Ethics 
 
 1 See ch. iv., §§ ig, 20.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 299 
 
 which might seem the very antithesis of his earlier method. 
 He says : " A preparation in the simpler sciences is pre- 
 supposed. Ethics has a physical aspect ; since it treats of 
 human activities which, in common with all expenditures of 
 energy, conform to the law of the persistence of energy : 
 moral principles must conform to physical necessities. It has 
 a biological aspect ; since it concerns certain effects, inner and 
 outer, individual and social, of the vital changes going on in 
 the highest type of animal. It has a psychological aspect ; 
 for its subject-matter is an aggregate of actions that are 
 prompted by feelings and guided by intelligence. And it 
 has a sociological aspect ; for these actions, some of them 
 directly and all of them indirectly, affect associated beings. 
 What is the implication } Belonging under one aspect to 
 each of these sciences — physical, biological, psychological, 
 sociological — it can find its ultimate interpretations only in 
 those fundamental truths which are common to all of them." ^ 
 Hence, of course, the four chapters — better known by title, 
 perhaps, than any others in the book — " The Physical View," 
 " The Biological View," " The Psychological View," and " The 
 Sociological View ". 
 
 There is something at first sight tempting in this proposal 
 to reduce the relatively indefinite science, or discipline, of 
 Ethics, to terms of sciences as definite in their scope and 
 method as Physics, Biology, and Psychology — though, per- 
 haps, even the prudent scientist would prefer, for the present, 
 to steer clear of Sociology. And the case of Physiology- 
 might plausibly be cited in justification of such a mode of 
 procedure, since the progress of that science has plainly been 
 in the direction of reducing its facts and principles, as far as 
 possible, to terms of physics and chemistry. But one very 
 important difference must be noted between what Mr. Spencer 
 proposes here and what the physiologist has found an ex- 
 tremely useful, if not indispensable, methodological principle- 
 Physics, chemistry, and physiology are alike explanatory 
 
 ^ See ch. iv., § 22a.
 
 300 History of Utiliiarianisni. 
 
 sciences pure and simple. They do not for a moment admit 
 of evaluations or appreciations : ' good ' and ' bad ' are for 
 them — as for all explanatory sciences, whether dealing with 
 the external or with the internal world — meaningless terms. 
 Ethics, on the contrary, while by no means neglecting the 
 mere facts of human character and conduct, always discrim- 
 inates between that which has worth and that which has not — 
 the standard, of course, being that which is assumed to be 
 the Good, except in the case of Intuitionism, where the evalua- 
 tion is made with direct reference to certain immediate feel- 
 ings or intuitions of the moral agent, assumed to be ultimate. 
 But while, to the present writer, the method here involved 
 seems highly questionable, for reasons partly indicated, it is 
 frankly to be admitted that Mr. Spencer is not alone in failing 
 to recognise, or refusing to admit, this line of demarcation 
 between the descriptive and explanatory sciences, on the one 
 hand, and the normative sciences, on the other. Let us, then, 
 consider his ' physical view ' of Ethics. This, as the author 
 explains, means considering conduct " as a set of combined 
 motions ". And he says : '' Taking the evolution point of 
 view, and remembering that while an aggregate evolves, not 
 only the matter composing it, but also the motion of that 
 matter, passes from an indefinite incoherent homogeneity to a 
 definite coherent heterogeneity, we have now to ask whether 
 conduct as it rises to its higher forms, displays in increasing 
 degrees these characters ; and whether it does not display 
 them in the greatest degree when it reaches that highest form 
 which we call moral " } The author argues that this is the 
 case. From the lower animals up to man, there may be ob- 
 served an increasing degree of the coherence of motions. 
 And the same thing is equally manifest, as we trace the con- 
 dition of man from a savage state to the highest modern 
 civilisation. All this, observe, is the coherence of physical 
 motions, considered strictly as such — an abstraction, to realise 
 the exact import of which is a considerable intellectual feat 
 
 1 See ch. v., § 24.
 
 Herbert Spencer, 301 
 
 (The present writer must acknowledge that he has never 
 accomphshed it, to his complete satisfaction.) Mr. Spencer 
 adds : " Now mark that a greater coherence among its com- 
 ponent motions, broadly distinguishes the conduct we call 
 moral from the conduct we call immoral. The application 
 of the word dissolute to the last, and of the word self- 
 restrained to the first, implies this. ... In proportion as the 
 conduct is what we call moral, it exhibits comparatively 
 settled connections between antecedents and consequents. 
 . . . Contrariwise, in the conduct of one whose principles are 
 not high, the sequences of motions are doubtful." ^ 
 
 Frankly speaking, this seems to me one of the most un- 
 helpful abstractions ever made in the name of Ethics. From 
 the proposition that the ' coherence ' of physical motions 
 increases, as we ascend from the lower to the higher mani- 
 festations of life, we are led on to the very different proposi- 
 tion that, the more moral conduct is, the greater will be this 
 coherence of the motions involved. This last proposition seems 
 more than doubtful. Some forms of dissipation, particularly 
 drunkenness, might appear to bear out the statement ; but 
 how about a life more or less deliberately devoted to crime } 
 Certainly there is greater coherence in the manipulations of 
 the counterfeiter and the expert safe-opener than most moral 
 men, not manually expert, could ever lay claim to. And as 
 for the possibility of predicting conduct (whether considered 
 as a mere series of physical motions or otherwise), what con- 
 duct could be easier to predict than that of a man hopelessly 
 given over to a particular vice } Almost precisely the same 
 criticisms apply to the author's contention, that increasingly 
 moral conduct implies an increasingly ' definite ' set of physi- 
 cal motions. It is not to the point to urge that " the con- 
 scientious man is exact in all his transactions ". The de- 
 faulting bank clerk, who falsifies his accounts, in order to con- 
 ceal his own crime, has to be as exact as if he were keeping 
 the books properly ; and generally he needs to be more,. 
 
 ^ See ch. v., § 25.
 
 302 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 rather than less, expert than the honest man. But this exact- 
 ness, or expertness — do they, as appHed to a series of physical 
 motions, considered merely as such, really mean anything at 
 all ? More plausible is the final argument, which goes to 
 show that the highest morality implies an increasing ' hetero- 
 geneity ' of motions. But what a ridiculously unsafe criterion 
 this would be, by which to distinguish moral from immoral 
 conduct ! 
 
 The ' physical view ' of morality, then, turns out to be not 
 only highly abstract, but extremely fanciful. We now pass 
 on to the ' biological view '. From the standpoint of biology, 
 the perfectly moral man is one in whom the physiological 
 functions of all kinds are duly fulfilled. Either defect or ex- 
 cess in the performance of function results in a lowering of 
 life for the time being. Hence the performance of every 
 function is, in a sense, a moral obligation. The author hastens 
 to remark that this principle, viz., that the performance of 
 every function is a duty, strictly applies to ideal humanity 
 only, not to humanity as now existing. At present, the per- 
 formance of every function by each would involve interference 
 of one individual with another ; ^ but when man is completely 
 evolved, this will not be the case. Another important result 
 of such complete evolution will be, that immediate pleasures 
 and pains, accompanying the exercise of our various functions, 
 will be safe guides of conduct, as of course they are not now — 
 though it is universally true that every pleasure increases 
 vitality for the time being, while every pain decreases vitality. 
 While freely admitting that, as we are at present constituted, 
 pleasures are not always connected with actions which should 
 be performed, nor pains with actions which should be avoided, 
 Mr. Spencer says : " Along with complete adjustment of 
 humanity to the social state, will go recognition of the truths 
 that actions are completely right only when, besides being 
 conducive to future happiness, special and general, they are 
 immediately pleasurable, and that painfulness, not only ulti- 
 
 ^ I.e., ' injustice,' which, as will be rcmeinbered, is tlie cardinal sin, according 
 to Mr. Spencer,
 
 Herbert Spencer. 303 
 
 mate but proximate, is the concomitant of actions which are 
 wrong "} 
 
 It cannot be denied that the ' biological view ' of morality 
 possesses at least one very important advantage over the 
 ' physical view,' viz., the propositions involved are sufficiently 
 definite to admit of clear comprehension. Let us begin by 
 examining the first, that complete or ideal morality means, 
 among other things, the due performance of all physiological 
 functions. There is, undoubtedly, an important element of 
 truth in this statement. Complete mental health, so desirable 
 for the moral life, is hardly possible without a fair degree of 
 physical health ; and this, of course, implies the due perform- 
 ance of at least many physiological functions. That the 
 moral agent should have a conscientious regard for his health, 
 even under existing conditions, goes without question. But 
 it is only too evident that, as things are now, the teachings 
 of biology (or rather, of hygiene) and those of Ethics by no 
 means necessarily coincide. And one must carefully observe 
 that this is not all. Strictly moral considerations apart, every 
 man who fills a real place in society, no matter how humble, 
 often finds himself obliged to work when it is undoubtedly 
 more or less detrimental to his health ; and those whose ser- 
 vices are at all indispensable to their fellow-men, particularly 
 at critical times, not infrequently have to take considerable 
 personal risks. It should be noted that one does not here 
 refer to cases of unnecessary hardship. The difficulty is, that 
 each has, or should have, his own work, which no other can 
 perform equally well — at least, without some slight prepara- 
 tion. Moreover, that all-round physical development here im- 
 plied, which is so desirable in itself, is practically impossible 
 for those who have to devote themselves constantly to any 
 specialised form of labour, whether physical, or mental, or 
 both. 
 
 Such considerations may seem irrelevant, as they plainly 
 refer to existing conditions, while Mr. Spencer claims only 
 
 ' vSee ch. vi., § 39.
 
 304 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 that the due performance of all physiological functions will be 
 a moral duty in the ideal, or completely evolved, society. But 
 why is it that a perfectly normal physical life — implying, as 
 Mr. Spencer would say, ' the due performance of all physio- 
 logical functions ' — is impossible for the great majority at the 
 present time ? The principal reason would seem to be that 
 very tendency toward specialisation of physical and mental 
 activities, which is the most characteristic feature of modern 
 civilisation. How far specialisation should go, is, of course, 
 a perfectly fair, and indeed a very serious, question ; but is 
 it conceivable that future generations will succeed in doing 
 away with specialisation, either altogether or in any large 
 measure ? If not, Mr. Spencer's physiological ideal will hardly 
 be attainable even in a society ' completely evolved ' — what- 
 ever that may mean. 
 
 So far, as will be remembered, we have left out of account 
 strictly moral considerations. When we take the point of 
 view of Ethics proper, it becomes evident that a necessary 
 result of increasing specialisation has been a great increase in 
 the complexity of human relations — including, of course, 
 moral relations. More and more it has become morally re- 
 prehensible, even if not socially impossible, for a man to ' live 
 unto himself alone, or die unto himself alone '. Will this 
 complexity of human relations decrease as social evolution 
 approaches its goal — granting that there is any definite, and 
 therefore stationary, goal } If not, we shall apparently have 
 to remain to the end ' members of one body,' whether one take 
 this as the language of Christian theology or that of the most 
 recent Evolutional Ethics, with its fundamental conception of 
 society as an organism. Hence, from the strictly ethical point 
 of view, it would seem still more improbable, that the in- 
 dividual member of the society of the future will necessarily 
 have either the duty or the privilege of duly performing- 
 all physiological functions. 
 
 We must now examine the second principal thesis which 
 Mr. Spencer defends in this chapter on the ' biological view ' 
 of morality. This, as will be remembered, is : that pleasures
 
 Herbo't Spencer. 305 
 
 and pains will finally become so adjusted to the performance 
 of special functions, that each will exactly correspond to acts 
 to be performed or avoided. This may seem like trenching on 
 the field of psychology ; but the author urges that this im- 
 mediate connection between feeling and function must be 
 considered here, since it has played such an important part 
 in organic evolution. Among the lower animals, indeed, a 
 fair degree of adaptation such as that described must be as- 
 sumed, since without it a given animal species would tend to 
 become extinct. Through the different stages of human civ- 
 ilisation, however, it must be confessed that this adjustment 
 has been far from perfect. This has been mainly due to the 
 necessity of a continuous partial readjustment to continually 
 changing conditions of life. But when the final stage of 
 evolution is reached, the adjustment will be perfect ; and 
 hence the immediate pleasures and pains accompanying func- 
 tions will be a safe indication as to whether they are to be 
 performed or avoided. In fact, as Mr. Spencer explicitly says, 
 in the passage previously quoted, actions will then be com- 
 pletely moral, only if they are immediately pleasurable to the 
 agent, as well as calculated to bring future pleasures to himself 
 and others. 
 
 This very argument for what Mr. Spencer would call com- 
 plete ' asstho-physiological ' adaptation in the future, tends to 
 bring out in strong relief the difficulties of his conception of 
 the perfectly evolved society. These we shall have to touch 
 upon almost immediately ; but it seems necessary to pause 
 a moment, in order to note another example of the habit which 
 the author has of running one principle into another. The 
 only excuse, as he himself admits, for introducing psychical 
 phenomena at this point, is that the immediate connections 
 between pleasures and pains and the performance of particu- 
 lar physiological functions play a very important part in 
 organic evolution itself. Now, after arguing that this kind 
 of adjustment will become perfect in the completely evolved 
 condition of man, he draws, as a sort of corollary, the ethical 
 conclusion that when such perfect adjustment obtains, moral 
 
 20
 
 3o6 History of UtilitarianiSDi. 
 
 actions will be immediately pleasurable to the agent, as well 
 as ultimately pleasant in their effects on the agent and others. 
 This is a radically different principle, involving the whole 
 moral nature of the completely evolved man, for it is too 
 plain to admit of argument, that the rightness or wrongness 
 of a moral action of any consequence involves very different, 
 and generally much more complicated, considerations than 
 does the due performance of any particular physiological 
 function, considered as such. Otherwise expressed : granting 
 that immediate pleasures and pains, connected with the per- 
 formance of physiological functions, should become even in- 
 fallible hygienic guides for the individual, they would not 
 necessarily, or even conceivably, be therefore trustworthy 
 guides to the complete satisfaction of the agent himself, 
 according to any recognised form of Egoism ; and they would 
 wholly leave out of account the moral relations of the agent 
 to others. It is disconcerting to find such inadvertencies in a 
 * scientific ' treatment of Ethics. 
 
 Let us now pass on to our delayed examination of the 
 general difficulties involved in Mr. Spencer's conception of an 
 ideal, or completely evolved, society. Such an examination 
 seems necessary here, for this is the first time in the Data 
 of Ethics that he has allowed himself to base an important 
 argument on the assumed certainty of an ideal society in the 
 remote future ; and the question immediately arises, whether 
 his conception of the ideal society has become more definite 
 since the publication of Social Statics. There is nothing, 
 in the present volume, at any rate, to indicate this. The ideal 
 society is still regarded merely as a society composed of 
 individuals completely adjusted to their environment. In our 
 examination of Social Statics, we saw that this conception of 
 the complete adjustment of man to his environment involved 
 serious difficulties, of which the author took no account. 
 Roughly speaking, these were : that man is constantly, and 
 in many cases materially, changing even his physical 
 environment ; and, secondly, that what we may call the 
 ' psychical ' environment of any group, whether larger or
 
 Herbert Spencer. 307 
 
 smaller, is subject to still greater modificatioil. In short, we 
 saw that while, for organic evolution, the environment is 
 relatively stationary, and not too complex for fairly adequate 
 comprehension, the total (physical and ' psychical ') environ- 
 ment to which the completely evolved man is to become 
 perfectly adapted, is so largely a matter of his own creation — 
 so constantly changing, and by no means necessarily always 
 in the direction of improvement ^ — that the perfect adaptation 
 or adjustment predicted is difficult even to conceive. 
 
 Now in the Data of Ethics, where, of course, the author 
 attempts to do justice to both the ' dynamic ' and the ' static ' 
 view of morality, these difficulties, so far from diminishing, 
 become considerably accentuated. We have seen that Mr. 
 Spencer admits, with his usual candour, that the adjustment 
 of immediate pleasures and pains to the performance of parti- 
 cular physiological functions is less reliable in man than in 
 the lower animals, and less reliable in a high civihsation, up to 
 the present, than in the original savage condition of man ; 
 and he suggests what is doubtless the true explanation, that 
 the continually changing conditions of life have necessitated 
 continuous partial readjustment. This, observe, is considering 
 the matter from what Mr. Spencer, at any rate, would call the 
 merely biological point of view. The ' changing conditions 
 of life ' referred to are not modifications in his environment 
 produced by man himself, but the changmg conditions in- 
 volved in the development of humanity from a savage, and 
 therefore wholly militant, condition to a completely civilised, 
 and therefore wholly industrial, condition, through the rather 
 complicated transitional condition of militant-industrialism 
 in which we find ourselves at present. The fact that all this 
 involves a good deal that is peculiar to Mr. Spencer's socio- 
 logical views, may be neglected for the present. But what 
 we must insist upon observing is, that perfect adjustment 
 (whether of the particular kind which we have been consider- 
 ing, or any other) has hitherto been impossible, on the author's 
 
 ^ Cf. periods of decadence in history. But Mr. Spencer despises the ' gossip ' 
 of history.
 
 3o8 History of Utilitarianism, 
 
 own showing, because society as a whole has never — crystal- 
 lised. One must be pardoned for the physical comparison, 
 since no other would exactly express the sinister meaning. 
 The actual attainment of a stationary goal, no matter how 
 many aeons ahead, would mean, not highest life, but death — 
 this from the point of view of sociology, but much more from 
 the point of view of Ethics. 
 
 This is the really fatal objection ; but, leaving out of view 
 all such difficulties, however unsurmountable, and assuming 
 for the moment that the complete adaptation of man to his 
 environment is no more difficult to conceive than a correspond- 
 ingly perfect adaptation of a given animal species to its 
 merely physical environment, the very serious question re- 
 mains : By what ' factors of evolution ' is such complete 
 adjustment to be effected .-' Natural selection, which plays 
 such an important — even if not, as some have claimed, a 
 nearly all-important — part in organic evolution proper, is 
 largely done away with in civilised human society. The ' un- 
 fit ' are not allowed to be eliminated by the simple, if ruthless, 
 methods of nature, owing to our deeply-rooted conviction of 
 the sanctity of human life. We shall, indeed, find that Mr. 
 Spencer's later interpretation of the principle of Justice makes 
 it largely consist in letting the individual take the natural 
 consequences of his actions ; but, as just pointed out, the all- 
 important consequence, elimination or death as the result 
 of ' unfitness,' is not permitted. The possibility of the perfect 
 adaptation of man to his environment, therefore, would seem 
 to depend almost entirely upon the * inheritance of acquired 
 characteristics '. If the increment of adaptation to environ- 
 ment, which has taken place in the individual (in this case, 
 the human) organism, as a result of its life-experience, can be 
 transmitted in part to offspring, then a constant progress in 
 the direction of complete adaptation may conceivably go on 
 without the operation of natural selection ; otherwise, appar- 
 ently not 
 
 So far as the present writer is aware, this ' factor ' of evolu- 
 tion (' inheritance of acquired characteristics ') had hardly
 
 Herbert Spencer. 309 
 
 been called in serious question at the time when the Data of 
 Ethics was published (1879), though there had, of course, been 
 the greatest diversity of opinion as to its relative importance. 
 One would be far from assuming that Weismann has entirely 
 proved the non-inheritance of acquired characteristics ; but, 
 so far as an outsider can judge of the results of this highly 
 technical controversy, they have at least gone to show that 
 this principle must be employed with very much greater 
 caution than has been customary hitherto. To have an ethical 
 postulate of the last importance for his system practically 
 depend upon a biological principle by no means universally 
 recognised, is certainly an unfortunate predicament for one 
 who would found a ' scientific ' Ethics. 
 
 The interesting chapter in which Mr. Spencer sets forth 
 his ' psychological view ' of morality need not detain us long. 
 In terms of his own psychological system, which it is wholly 
 unnecessary to criticise here, he traces briefly the develop- 
 ment of motives from the lowest, such as would appeal to 
 organisms barely endowed with sentiency, to the most com- 
 plex, re-representative, or ideal, that can appeal to the highly 
 civihsed man. This development from simple to complex, 
 from what we call ' lower ' to what we call ' higher ' motives, 
 manifestly implies an increasing degree of subordination of 
 present to future ends. " Hence," as the author says, " there 
 arises a certain presumption in favour of a motive which refers 
 to a remote good, in comparison with one which refers to a 
 proximate good." ^ But he very properly argues that this 
 presumption must not be transformed into an ascetic dogma. 
 The feelings, e.g., which prompt one to comply with the funda- 
 mental requirements of health, may, and often do, have as 
 high an authority as any. Moreover, one must admit that it 
 is quite possible to go too far in subordinating present to 
 future good. 
 
 The earliest regulation of human conduct, we are told, is 
 by means of three external controls, political, religious, and 
 
 ^ See ch. vii., § 42.
 
 3IO History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 social. These, for the most part, operate simultaneously, 
 leading men to subordinate proximate satisfactions to remote 
 satisfactions ; yet it must be observed that they do not con- 
 stitute the moral control proper, but are only preparatory to 
 it — " are controls within which the moral control evolves ". 
 Mr. Spencer says : " The restraints properly distinguished as 
 moral, are unlike these restraints out of which they evolve, 
 and with which they are long confounded, in this — they refer 
 not to the extrinsic effects of actions but to their in- 
 trinsic effects " y His meaning is made plain by the con- 
 text : motives truly moral cannot spring from a foresight 
 of rewards or punishments that may be expected at the 
 hands of the State, of one's fellow men, or even of a Divine 
 Being ; they are constituted by representations of conse- 
 quences which the acts naturally produce. He says : " These 
 representations are not all distinct, though some of such are 
 usually present ; but they form an assemblage of indistinct 
 representations accumulated by experience of the results of 
 like acts in the life of the individual, super-posed on a still more 
 indistinct but voluminous consciousness due to the inherited 
 effects of such experiences in progenitors : forming a feeling 
 that is at once massive and vague ". 
 
 In further justification of this view, he quotes a passage from 
 his well-known letter to J. S. Mill, a part of which may be 
 given here, as it indicates his later ^ attitude toward Intuition- 
 ism. " Just in the same way that I believe the intuition of 
 space, possessed by any living individual, to have arisen from 
 organised and consohdated experiences of all antecedent 
 individuals who bequeathed to him their slowly-developed 
 nervous organisations — just as I believe that this intuition, 
 requiring only to be made definite and complete by personal 
 experiences, has practically become a form of thought, ap- 
 
 ^ See ch. vii., § 45. 
 
 2 Not necessarily his latest. His "Inductions of Ethics" (Part II. of the 
 Principles, published in 1892) seem to imply throughout an unconditional re- 
 jection of Intuitionism, which is rather more than is expressed by the passage 
 here quoted.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 311 
 
 parently quite independent of experience ; so do i believe 
 that the experiences of utility organised and consolidated 
 through all past generations of the human race, have been 
 producing corresponding nervous modifications, which, by 
 continued transmission and accumulation, have become in us 
 certain faculties of moral intuition — certain emotions respond- 
 ing to right and wrong conduct, which have no apparent 
 basis in the individual experiences of utility." ^ 
 
 So much for the origin of what are taken to be particular 
 moral intuitions. How does there arise the feeling of moral 
 obligation in general ? We are told : " The answer is that it 
 is an abstract sentiment generated in a manner analogous to 
 that in which abstract ideas are generated ".- All particular 
 moral feelings have in common complexity and re-representa- 
 tive character, being occupied with the future rather than the 
 present. Hence ^ the idea of ' authoritativeness ' has come 
 to be connected with them, and this idea is naturally carried 
 over, so as to form an essential moment of the abstract senti- 
 ment of duty. But, besides authoritativeness, there is the 
 further, and apparently more characteristic, element of ' co- 
 erciveness . This has arisen mainly as the result of the 
 agent's fear of political and social (and probably one should 
 add, religious) penalties. Now since this second element of 
 ' coerciveness,' or moral obligation proper, has arisen in con- 
 nection with the ' extrinsic,' as opposed to the ' intrinsic,' or 
 natural, consequences of actions, it may be expected to di- 
 minish in proportion as moral conduct ceases to depend upon 
 merely external restraints. This leads to the author's char- 
 acteristic, but rather startling conclusion, that the sense of 
 duty or moral obligation is transitory ; that it will diminish 
 until it finally disappears with the complete adaptation of man 
 to the social state. 
 
 We have seen that the ' physical ' and the ' biological ' 
 views of morality are open to serious criticism, not only as 
 to results, but as to method. It might appear that, from the 
 
 1 See ch. vii., S 45. 2 ggg ihid., % 46. 
 
 •* It will be noted that this is one of the author's many facile inferences.
 
 3 1 2 History of Utilitarianism, 
 
 point of view of method, at any rate, the present chapter, on 
 the ' psychological view,' would call for substantially the same 
 criticism, since the general introduction to these four ' views ' 
 of morality puts them ostensibly on the same plane. But 
 what Mr. Spencer actually attempts in this chapter, is not, 
 properly speaking, to reduce Ethics to terms of something 
 else ; he attempts, rather, to give a psychological account of 
 the origin of our particular moral intuitions and of our general 
 feeling of duty. As an attempt, this is perfectly legitimate ; 
 and to use such results, if obtainable, for the purposes of 
 Ethics, is, of course, equally legitimate. In truth, so far from 
 this attempt being peculiar to the author of the Data of 
 Ethics, it is one that had been made by all previous hedonist- 
 empiricists, and that is certain to be made as long as such a 
 school exists. 
 
 The question as to whether Mr. Spencer has succeeded in 
 this attempt, is, of course, quite another matter. In his own 
 opinion, he has successfully mediated between Empiricism and 
 Intuitionism, as they have existed in the past, by his character- 
 istic theory, that the results of the moral experience of the 
 individual have been transmitted from generation to genera- 
 tion, until the fundamental * moral intuitions,' so-called, like 
 those concerning the spatial relations of things, have become 
 for the individual, as at present constituted, practically innate 
 ' forms ' of thought or feeling — though, of course, ultimately 
 explainable as the result of the experience of the race. This 
 theory raises epistemological and metaphysical questions, 
 which cannot properly be discussed here, even superficially ; 
 but it will readily be seen that, from the point of view of 
 epistemology, the theory does not really transcend empiricism 
 and methods opposed to it, but rather decides in favour of 
 empiricism itself. Moreover, the essential difficulties of em- 
 piricism — whatever those may be thought to be — are not in 
 any true sense done away with, but merely thrust further 
 back. In truth, it may be seriously doubted if Mr. Spencer 
 has really improved at all upon the traditional arguments for 
 empiricism, as applied to Ethics, since he has again staked
 
 Herbert Spencer. 313 
 
 everything upon the vahdity of the biological principle of the 
 ' inheritance of acquired characteristics '. 
 
 What calls for more special consideration, in the present 
 connection, is the author's well-known, but paradoxical view, 
 that the feeling of duty will finally become extinct, with the 
 perfect adaptation of man to the social condition. It hardly 
 need be pointed out that this view, however startling in itself, 
 is a practically necessary corollary from the general theory of a 
 ' completely evolved ' society, with which we have by this time 
 become so familiar. And it serves, in a very interesting way, 
 to illustrate still further the difficulties of that highly abstract 
 theory. But first, let us realise, as clearly as may be, what this 
 view is in itself. The argument briefly is, that the feeling of 
 duty, or moral obligation proper, implying the idea of ' co- 
 erciveness,' has arisen mainly in connection with the three 
 external controls of conduct ; and that therefore, when the 
 thought of ' extrinsic ' consequences makes way for the thought 
 of * intrinsic,' or natural, consequences on the part of the 
 agent — as will necessarily take place with the moral progress 
 of the individual and of the race — inclination will take the 
 place of duty, and man will become spontaneously, if not 
 mechanically, moral. As the author expresses it : " The 
 higher actions required for the harmonious carrying on of 
 life, will be as much matters of course as are those lower 
 actions which the simple desires prompt " }- 
 
 It is difficult to see how morality necessarily becomes in- 
 ternal and spontaneous, as opposed to external and con- 
 strained, by the mere fact that the agent passes from a con- 
 sideration of ' extrinsic ' to a consideration of ' intrinsic,' or 
 natural, consequences — granting that such a thing is ever 
 wholly possible. The development of altruism, to a proper 
 degree and under control of reason, would seem to be the 
 desideratum — not disregard for the approval of one's fellow- 
 men or even for that of the Divine Being. In truth, this hard 
 and fast distinction between ' extrinsic ' and ' intrinsic ' con- 
 
 * See ch. vii., § 46.
 
 314 History of Utilitarianisin. 
 
 sequences is another of the misleading abstractions which one 
 so often meets with in Mr. Spencer's ethical writings. What 
 could be a more ' natural ' consequence of any form of recog- 
 nised wrong-doing than the disapproval, perhaps abhorrence, 
 of one's fellow-men ? But let us not tamper with the author's 
 terminology ; it is most convenient in the present connection. 
 Granting that any human being could perform the psycho- 
 logical and moral feat here indicated — granting that he could 
 wholly neglect all ' extrinsic ' consequences, including the 
 approval or disapproval of his fellow-men, and fix his mind 
 upon the ' intrinsic,' or natural, consequences alone — how 
 would it fare with his moral life ? The ' intrinsic ' conse- 
 quences would obviously supply as many egoistic motives as 
 the * extrinsic,' and he would wholly lose the moralising in- 
 fluence of enlightened public opinion. One may be an in- 
 dividualist in theoretical Ethics, like Mr. Spencer ; most 
 fortunately one cannot be a practical individualist in the sense 
 just indicated. To be that would mean, to be a moral monster. 
 But, it may be objected, the rise and growth of altruism has 
 really been presupposed by the author. To this it may be 
 replied, that we must not make of altruism still another ab- 
 straction : in the social nature of man, without which morality 
 would be impossible, regard for the feelings of others and re- 
 gard for their opinions are so inextricably involved, that 
 neither can develop, or even continue to exist, in isolation from 
 the other. 
 
 But, neglecting these and similar considerations, the force 
 of Mr. Spencer's argument seems also to depend upon the 
 assumption that, if we ever outgrow the feeling of duty, as 
 something external and coercive, nothing but inclination can 
 take its place. Are these, then, the only alternatives.-' The 
 whole History of Ethics goes to prove the contrary : from 
 Socrates to the present time — Mediasvalism apart — Ethics has 
 nearly always been regarded by some influential school or 
 schools as the doctrine of the Good. From that point of view, 
 this antithesis between duty, in the grimly forbidding sense, 
 and inclination tends to disappear. On the one hand, indeed^
 
 Herbert Spencer. 315 
 
 the Good is regarded as something which appeals to one's 
 higher, or whole nature ; but, on the other hand, to identify 
 it with the necessary object of inclination would be fatally 
 misleading. ' Desirable ' — even ' above all things desirable ' — 
 and ' desired ' are, unfortunately, not convertible terms. True, 
 as moral progress is made, ' desirable ' and ' desired ' tend to 
 approximate ; but there is one fatal difficulty with all truly 
 human ideals, whether ethical or other, and that is, that the 
 more we attain, the more do new and unimagined vistas open 
 up before us. Now it is perfectly conceivable that, in the 
 course of the moral development of the race, duty may take 
 on a very different aspect from that which it now presents ; 
 but that the * springs of action ' will ever by themselves be 
 sufficient to make us automatically live up to our highest 
 ideals of the moral Good is wholly inconceivable. And this 
 is because man is not a mere organism to be adjusted to a 
 comparatively stationary external environment, but a person- 
 ality, capable of practically endless development. 
 
 There ostensibly remains to be considered the ' sociological 
 view ' of morality ; but, as a matter of fact, the chapter de- 
 voted to this subject contains little or nothing of importance 
 for Ethics that had not been at least implied, either in Book 
 IV. of the Social Statics, or in the preceding chapters of the 
 Data of Ethics. It will therefore be sufficient to notice very 
 briefly, partly by way of review, Mr. Spencer's highly charac- 
 teristic theory of the evolution of society. All along we have 
 seen that, generally speaking, this evolution has been from a 
 wholly militant condition toward a wholly industrial condition, 
 though the latter condition is still far ahead. Now in the 
 militant condition two codes will necessarily spring up, one of 
 ' enmity ' toward alien societies, and one of ' amity ' ^ toward 
 other individuals of the same society. The one, in fact, is as 
 necessary as the other : co-operation within and antagonism 
 
 1 Of course 'amity,' as here used, is a relative term. The 'code of amity* 
 does not necessarily signify more than a code, as between members of the same 
 society, which makes co-operation of the necessary kind and to the necessary 
 degree possible.
 
 o 
 
 1 6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 to all that which is without. While this militant condition 
 continues, either wholly or in any large degree, the very 
 existence of society demands a constant subordination of the 
 interests of the individual to those of the State ; but, in so far 
 as mutual aggression between societies ceases, this need for 
 the sacrifice of private claims to public claims ceases also. 
 Moreover, as mutual external aggressions cease, mutual in- 
 ternal aggressions will also tend to cease. Not only so, but 
 co-operation will become more complex and effective. But 
 we must go further still — and the reader will readily see that 
 from this point Mr. Spencer's sociology, so far as here set 
 forth, practically coincides with his ethics. After pointing out 
 that non-interference (Justice, in its more obvious phase) is 
 not enough, he says : " Daily experiences prove that every one 
 would suffer many evils and lose many goods, did none give 
 him unpaid assistance. The life of each would be more or 
 less damaged had he to meet all contingencies single-handed. 
 Further, if no one did for his fellows anything more than was 
 required by strict performance of contract, private interests 
 would suffer from the absence of attention to public interests. 
 The limit of evolution of conduct is consequently not reached, 
 until, beyond avoidance of direct and indirect injuries to 
 others, there are spontaneous efforts to further the welfare of 
 others." ^ And it is hardly necessary to remark that for the 
 later, as well as for the earlier, form of Mr. Spencer's ethical 
 theory, Justice and Beneficence (Negative and Positive), to- 
 gether with a due regard for his own welfare on the part of 
 the agent, constitute the whole of Ethics. 
 
 Having followed Mr. Spencer through the arguments con- 
 tained in the first eight chapters of the Data of Ethics, which 
 explain his views on scientific ethical method, and which 
 happen to form exactly the first half of the book, we are in 
 a position to make some interesting comparisons. In the 
 Social Statics both the very interesting destructive criticism of 
 the Expediency Philosophy and the outline of the author's 
 
 ^ See ch. viii., § 54.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 317- 
 
 own system are frankly shown to depend upon his character- 
 istic, but paradoxical, conception of the perfect society of the 
 future. We are told that the moralist must deal with the 
 perfect man, just as the mathematician deals with the hypo- 
 thetically perfect geometrical figure ; hence evil cannot even 
 be recognised by a scientific system of Ethics. When stated 
 in such terms, it is evident that the system, whatever its other 
 defects or merits may be, is one of the most abstract ever 
 formulated ; and, moreover, that the abstract criterion con- 
 stantly referred to, the perfect man in the perfect society, 
 can never be completely understood until the millennial condi- 
 tion of society actually arrives. Now in the Data of Ethics 
 the method adopted seems at first to be almost the opposite of 
 that employed in the earlier book. Organic evolution is to 
 afford the clue ; so we begin by considering the evolution 
 of conduct in its most general sense, i.e., the mere adaptation 
 of acts to ends, whether conscious or unconscious. After not- 
 ing that such adaptation becomes more and more complex 
 and efficient, as we ascend from the lowest animals up to man, 
 we are, apparently, invited to regard the evolution of human 
 conduct as on the same plane, except that men ' look before 
 and after,' and are thus able to contrive means for the attain- 
 ment of the ends desired. But, before we are fully aware 
 of what has happened, the grim struggle for existence has 
 been banished from our mental vision, and social evolu- 
 tion — a ' power which makes for righteousness,' whether 
 we will or no — is represented as necessarily leading up 
 to a state of things where man is ' completely adapted ' to 
 the social condition. This, upon inspection, turns out to be 
 precisely Mr. Spencer's old, pre-Evolutional ideal of ' the 
 perfect man in the perfect society'. It is true that the 
 expression ' completely adapted,' already used in Social Statics, 
 may seem to define the perfect man in evolutional terms ; 
 but we have elsewhere considered in some detail the diffi- 
 culty of even conceiving what such ' complete adaptation ' 
 would mean. 
 
 More particularly, Mr. Spencer objects to all previous
 
 3i8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 systems of Ethics, on the ground that they either wholly, or in 
 very large measure, neglect the principle of causation. As we 
 have seen, however, this alarming indictment practically re- 
 duces itself to his old objection to the Expediency Philosophy. 
 He then attempts to put Ethics on a strictly scientific basis, 
 by (at least ostensibly) reducing certain of its most general 
 principles to terms of Physics, Biology, Psychology, and 
 Sociology. The results, as we so recently found, are hardly 
 reassuring. The ' physical view ' turned out to be not only 
 so abstract as almost to baffle definite comprehension, but 
 extremely fanciful, and, where one can test it, by no means 
 uniformly in accord with the facts. The ' biological view ' 
 — that the ' completely adapted ' man will find it not only his 
 privilege, but his duty, to perform duly all physiological func- 
 tions, and, moreover, that for him the immediate pleasures or 
 pains, attending the performance or avoidance of functions, 
 will be safe guides, not only to hygienic, but to moral con- 
 duct — we found to involve the most serious difficulties, unless 
 the highest civilisation of the future prove to be almost the 
 antithesis of what we understand by civilisation now. The 
 ' psychological view ' turned out to be Mr. Spencer's own 
 version of the empirical explanation of the origin of our 
 recognition of particular moral principles and of duty in 
 general ; and we saw that he had by no means necessarily 
 improved matters by staking everything upon the ' inheri- 
 tance of acquired characteristics '. The evanescence of the 
 feeling of duty predicted also appeared to present the gravest 
 difficulties, though doubtless a legitimate, and perhaps neces- 
 sary, corollary from his fundamental conception of a perfect, 
 or completely evolved, society. Finally, the ' sociological 
 view ' presented little or nothing really novel, since it repre- 
 sented merely the author's characteristic theory (already indi- 
 cated in Social Statics) as to the route to be followed by 
 humanity in its progress toward perfection. 
 
 We must now ask : Is this later treatment really new ? Is 
 the author really depending upon the most advanced modern 
 science as the foundation for his ethical system.? Or is he
 
 Herbert Spencer. 319 
 
 not rather, quite unconsciously, of course, providing us with 
 an ostensibly scientific (in particular, evolutional) develop- 
 ment of the very same conception which, nearly thirty years 
 earlier, and eight years before the publication of the Origin 
 of Species, had dominated the Social Statics ? Now, apart from 
 the author's abandonment of the Moral Sense theory, not 
 only does this seem to the present writer to be the case, but 
 the newly-provided scientific approaches to this long-cherished 
 ideal seem dubious in the extreme. Evolution is appealed to 
 as the universal solvent of difficulties ; but, as here employed, 
 it is no longer analogous to the principle of organic evolution, 
 with its ruthless destruction of the unfit. It is rather the 
 principle of universal and continuous progress on the part of 
 human society, conceived as a hope rather than proved as a 
 fact — ^with a convenient disregard for what history has to say 
 of periods of political and social decadence, or even for what 
 biology has to say of the highly interesting, if not morally 
 inspiring, phenomena of organic degeneration. So far, then, 
 all the aids of modern science to the contrary notwithstanding, 
 the author seems to stand practically where he did in the 
 Social Statics — always excepting his later rejection of the 
 Moral Sense theory — and to base everything upon his appar- 
 ently arbitrary belief in the necessity of a perfect society in 
 the remote future. 
 
 The remainder of the Data of Ethics may be considered 
 very briefly, for the ground covered will become increasingly 
 familiar to one who has read the Social Statics at all carefully. 
 Mr. Spencer never seems perfectly satisfied with his later 
 criticisms of Utilitarianism, for he returns to the subject again 
 and again. He is never tired of insisting that the hedonistic 
 calculus, as ordinarily understood, is an impossibility ; but, 
 on the other hand, he never gives sufficiently definite informa- 
 tion as to what we are to employ in place of it. The sugges- 
 tions, however, always take the form of insisting that certain 
 very general principles of conduct are necessary in any pro- 
 perly organised society, no matter what the external environ-
 
 320 History of Utilitarianisju. 
 
 merit and therefore the prevailing mode of life of the individual 
 members, and no matter what the stage of development of 
 the given society ; and, moreover, these general principles 
 finally turn out to be adumbrations of his own ethical prin- 
 ciples — ^Justice, Negative Beneficence, and Positive Benefi- 
 cence, enlightened Self-Interest being always presupposed. 
 
 This, of course, is merely the doctrine of the Social Statics 
 over again ; and one must remark here, as in the last chapter, 
 that this insistence upon the necessity of general rules, as the 
 direct guides of action, is by no means a novelty in English 
 Utilitarianism. Nobody but Bentham, in fact, seems to have 
 failed to recognise the need of depending upon such general 
 rules. The principal difference between Mr. Spencer and 
 other hedonists, writing before and after the publication of 
 the Data of Ethics^ is, that he prefers to represent the general 
 principles of Ethics as general conditions of the efficiency 
 of society, while the others are content to represent them 
 merely as general conditions of the greatest happiness. For 
 ordinary purposes, the two methods practically coincide in 
 their results ; and, where there is divergence, the advantage 
 is by no means necessarily on the side of Mr. Spencer — if 
 happiness be really the ultimate end. A society, e.g., might con- 
 ceivably be ideally efficient in a practical way, and yet neglect 
 all things aesthetic. Presumably this would result in a great 
 diminution of happiness ; but we are not quite sure that such 
 considerations would move the author of the Synthetic Phil- 
 osophy. One always has a suspicion that, like Plato, he would 
 banish the poets from his ideal state. 
 
 As we have just seen, Mr. Spencer is not always fortunate 
 in his attempts to differentiate his own treatment of Ethics 
 from that of traditional Utilitarianism, since he generally tends 
 to over-emphasise differences in method ; but it should be 
 noted that the later chapters of the Data of Ethics are a 
 decided improvement upon some of the earlier chapters in one 
 respect, at any rate, viz., they keep to the real problems of 
 Ethics. Highly interesting, even if by no means satisfactory, 
 are the four chapters in which he defines the relations between
 
 Herbert Spencer. 321 
 
 egoism and altruism in his own system. In the chapters 
 " Egoism versus Altruism " and " Altruism versus Egoism," as 
 the titles themselves would indicate, he gives an ex parte 
 statement of what may be said for egoism and for altruism, 
 separately considered. In spite of the confessedly abstract 
 method here adopted, he discusses the problems involved with 
 admirable candour and great ability. After exhibiting this 
 opposition between egoism and altruism in a perhaps too 
 striking light, even for his purpose — which manifestly is to 
 state the difficulty rather than to indicate his own solution — 
 he goes on to show how impossible it is to construct an ethical 
 system in terms of either the one or the other. The chapter 
 devoted to this discussion, " Trial and Compromise," while 
 evidently correct as regcurds its main thesis, is open to criti- 
 cism, as the author is plainly unfair to Utihtarianism, e.g., in 
 representing it as logically a system of mere altruism. More- 
 over, while egoism and altruism are thus held apart almost as 
 if they were separate entities, in a way that Mr. Spencer him- 
 self could not admit when treating the problem of their 
 relation constructively, he does a good deal to prejudice the 
 case in favour of egoism, by insisting upon such evident truths 
 as that, " other things equal, ideal feelings cannot be as vivid 
 as real feelings " ; that " much of the happiness each enjoys 
 is self-generated and can neither be given nor received " ; 
 and that " the pleasures gained by efficient action — by suc- 
 cessful pursuit of ends, cannot by any process be parted with, 
 and cannot in any way be appropriated by another " } Still, 
 one should observe, he does not really attempt (in this discus- 
 sion, at least) to reduce altruism to egoism in the way that 
 the earlier Associationists had done ; but, on the contrary, 
 regards them as co-essential. Hence the title of the next 
 chapter, " Conciliation ". 
 
 Here, without giving quite sufficient notice, the author 
 drops his confessedly abstract method of treatment, and pro- 
 ceeds to give his own solution of the apparent antinomy upon 
 
 1 Seech, xiii., §§ 86-88. 
 21
 
 32 2 History of Utilitariaiiisni. 
 
 which he has dwelt so long. He argues that during evolution 
 there has been going on a conciliation between the interests of 
 the species, the interests of the parents, and the interests of 
 the offspring. More exactly, he says : " As we ascend from 
 the lowest forms of life to the highest, race-maintenance is 
 achieved with a decreasing sacrifice of life, alike of young in- 
 dividuals and of adult individuals, and also with a decreasing 
 sacrifice of parental lives to the lives of offspring " }■ Simi- 
 larly, he argues that, with the progress of civilisation, like 
 changes have taken place among human beings. Parental 
 altruism is, of course, already highly developed ; and, with 
 further evolution, causing, along with higher nature, dimin- 
 ished fertility, and therefore smaller burdens on parents, it 
 may be expected to develop still further. Now altruism of 
 a social kind cannot, of course, be expected to equal parental 
 altruism in degree ; but it may confidently be expected to 
 become equally spontaneous, and such that lower egoistic 
 •satisfactions will continually be subordinated to this higher 
 ■egoistic satisfaction — and this, not from a feeling of obligation, 
 but rather from natural inclination. Before such general 
 sympathy can develop on a large scale, however, society must 
 outgrow the condition of habitual militancy ; and it goes 
 without saying that, even then, a long time will be required 
 by society, in which to outlive the effects of that pernicious 
 regime. But finally, with complete adaptation of man to the 
 social condition, this most desirable result will be attained. 
 Does this mean that man, beginning as an individual with 
 merely selfish interests, will finally become, in the true sense 
 of the word, a social being } Mr. Spencer says : " In natures 
 thus constituted, though the altruistic gratifications must re- 
 main in a transfigured sense egoistic, yet they will not be 
 egoistically pursued — will not be pursued from egoistic mo- 
 tives " ?■ This passage is made still more ambiguous by its 
 context, for the time-honoured example of the miser and his 
 money — so popular, as we have seen in previous chapters, 
 
 1 See ch. xiv., § 92. ^See ibid., § 95.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 323 
 
 with the earlier Associationist-Utilitarians, who held to the 
 necessary egoism of the moral agent — is employed by the 
 author. But it would hardly do to class Mr. Spencer with the 
 older school of Utilitarians, the hneal descendants of Gay, 
 as regards this important matter of the moral motive, for he 
 has just argued for the necessity of a certain degree of altruism 
 from evolutionary considerations. 
 
 In truth, it is most difficult satisfactorily to define Mr. 
 Spencer's position ; and the reason, apparently, is that he has 
 ended, as he began, an individualist — not as a result of his 
 devotion to the general theory of Evolution, but in spite of 
 this. Here, as so often, we have to note the striking corre- 
 spondence between the Evolutional and the pre-Evolutional 
 form of his ethical theory. In this case, indeed, it is a corre- 
 spondence practically amounting to identity. Evolution is 
 generally supposed to develop a tendency only when it is 
 needed, and only in proportion as it is needed ; but in the 
 later, so-called ' Evolutional,' form of Mr. Spencer's ethical 
 theory, as in the earlier one set forth in Social Statics, it is 
 made to appear that, in the triumphal progress of humanity 
 toward perfection, altruism will be developed in proportion 
 as it is not needed. This is not an imaginary difficulty. In 
 this very chapter we are told : " Sympathy can reach its full 
 height only when there have ceased to be frequent occasions 
 for anything like serious self-sacrifice ".^ 
 
 The last chapter of any length in the Data of Ethics is 
 most appropriately devoted to " Absolute and Relative 
 Ethics ". This, in fact, is the one fundamental distinction, 
 based on Mr. Spencer's early faith in a perfect society in the 
 remote future, which has both given unity to the book as 
 a whole and served principally to distinguish the author's 
 treatment of Ethics from that of traditional Utilitarianism. 
 The chapter is of importance, not because it represents any 
 appreciable change of opinion on the part of the author, but 
 because the first part is somewhat more definite than the 
 
 ^ See ch. xiv., § 96.
 
 324 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 corresponding discussion in Social Statics, and therefore more 
 subject to exact criticism. In the earher book we began 
 with the point of view of ' Absolute Ethics/ and saw that from 
 that standpoint all considerations of evil — or pain, which for 
 Mr. Spencer is the same thing — had to be ruled out. In the 
 Data of Ethics, on the contrary, we have been largely con- 
 cerned with the conception of a gradually developing, or 
 ' evolving,' morality, and accordingly have had our attention 
 frequently directed to the fact that, as things are now con- 
 stituted, there are multitudinous cases where there is no abso- 
 lute right or wrong, but only a right which, on inspection, 
 turns out to be a least wrong. One must observe that the 
 author is not insisting upon the apparent conflict of real 
 duties, as a result of the complex relations which are inevitable 
 in modern civilisation. Duty, in fact, as we have seen, is re- 
 garded by him as only a passing phase of the moral experience 
 of the race. 
 
 As Mr. Spencer defines it, " the absolutely good, the abso- 
 lutely right, in conduct, can be that only which produces pure 
 pleasure — pleasure unalloyed with pain anywhere. By impli- 
 cation, conduct which has any concomitant of pain, or any 
 painful consequence, is partially wrong ; and the highest claim 
 to be made for such conduct is, that it is the least wrong 
 which, under the conditions, is possible — the relatively right." ^ 
 The author freely admits that humanity must still, for a very 
 long time, content itself principally with the ' relatively 
 right ' ; but he pauses to give two concrete illustrations of what 
 he means by the ' absolutely right,' taken from the existing 
 order of things. He first asks us to consider the relation of a 
 healthy mother to a healthy infant, and says : " Between the 
 two there exists a mutual dependence which is a source of 
 pleasure to both. In yielding its natural food to the child, 
 the mother receives gratification ; and to the child there 
 comes the satisfaction of appetite — a satisfaction which ac- 
 companies furtherance of life, growth, and increasing enjoy- 
 ment. Let the relation be suspended, and on both sides there 
 
 ' See ch. xv., § loi.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 325 
 
 is suffering. . . . Thus the act is one that is to both exclusively 
 pleasurable, while abstention entails pain on both ; and it is 
 consequently of the kind we here call absolutely right." ^ 
 
 It will be noted that the author confines himself to a single, 
 and that a merely physiological, relation between mother and 
 child — and one which, by the way, is far less likely to be per- 
 fectly normal in civilisation than in a savage state of society. 
 Does Mr. Spencer mean to imply that, in general, the relations 
 of mother to child can conceivably become wholly pleasurable 
 on both sides, no matter how healthy both may be } It will 
 no longer suffice to say, as an ordinary Utilitarian might do, 
 that the mother's pleasures may, and should, be greatly in 
 excess of her pains. That would not at all answer the require- 
 ments of the author's characteristically abstract ideal. As long 
 as any suffering whatever is involved, the relation is ' imper- 
 fectly moral '. In fact, this relation between mother and child 
 is one of the least happy that could have been chosen, as an 
 example of the ' absolutely right,' for here, at any rate, we may 
 assert with perfect confidence that some degree of suffering 
 and self-sacrifice will always be necessary, no matter how 
 ' completely evolved ' society may be. Would it, in fact, be 
 going too far to say that, according to Mr. Spencer's paradoxi- 
 cal standard, maternity is bound to remain to the end one of 
 the most ' imperfectly moral ' of human relations .'* If any 
 reductio ad absurdum of the conception of ' absolute morality ' 
 were needed, this ought to serve. 
 
 The author's other example of ' absolutely right ' conduct, 
 is that of a father of healthy mind and body, who takes a 
 keen interest in the sports and tasks of his young children. 
 But here again, it must be remembered that the predominantly 
 pleasurable will not serve the purpose. As long as the 
 male parent permits himself to indulge in any acts of real 
 self-devotion for the benefit of his offspring, so long will this 
 relation also remain ' imperfectly moral ' — and this, no matter 
 how necessary the sacrifice or how worthy those for whom it 
 has been made may prove themselves in later years. 
 
 ' See ch. xv., g io2.
 
 326 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 The above examples, be it observed, are supposed to re- 
 present the nearest approach to ' absolute morality ' at present 
 attainable. The author admits that the intercourse of adults 
 yields relatively few cases that fall completely within the 
 same category. The rank and file of humanity do not find 
 their necessary work in life an unmixed pleasure ; but it is 
 argued that ' social discipline ' will finally bring this about. 
 And, with his fatal infelicity in the choice of examples, Mr. 
 Spencer says : " Already, indeed, something like such a state 
 has been reached among certain of those who minister to our 
 aesthetic gratifications. The artist of genius — poet, painter, 
 or musician — is one who obtains the means of living by acts 
 that are directly pleasurable to him, while they yield, im- 
 mediately or remotely, pleasures to others." Plainly the man 
 of genius is here mentioned merely as one who is so fortunate 
 as to be able to live by congenial work. Up to the present, the 
 man of genius has far too often found it difficult to support 
 himself at all by his own exertions ; but this is perhaps the 
 least important aspect of the matter. With his abnormally 
 sensitive temperament, his striving, often hopeless, after ideals 
 the highest, if not actually unattainable, and the grudging re- 
 cognition accorded him by the world at large during his years 
 of probation, he is about as far as possible from being the 
 satisfied, and therefore happy man — the man ' perfectly ad- 
 justed to his environment ' — of Mr. Spencer's imagination. 
 In fact, of all men, the man of genius is, and must remain, one 
 of the least adjusted to the society in which he finds himself. 
 In this very paragraph, by an odd juxtaposition, is a most 
 significant reference to the so-called ' absolute morality ' of a 
 benevolence that costs nothing. " Some one who has slipped 
 is saved from falling by a bystander : a hurt is prevented and 
 satisfaction is felt by both. A pedestrian is choosing a dan- 
 gerous route, or a fellow-passenger is about to alight at the 
 wrong station, and, warned against doing so, is saved from 
 evil : each being, as a consequence, gratified." ^ 
 
 ^ See ch. xv., § 102,
 
 Herbert Spencer, 327 
 
 After these examples, which are instructive only as ex- 
 hibiting, in a concrete way, the difficulties of Mr. Spencer's 
 hopelessly vague, and otherwise more than paradoxical, con- 
 ception of ideal morality, he proceeds to treat of the relation 
 between * Absolute Ethics ' and ' Relative Ethics ' in what he 
 terms a ' systematic ' way. All that follows on this score is an 
 almost literal reproduction of the treatment in Social Statics^ 
 and so calls for no special notice here. As before, the gist 
 of the argument is, that Ethics must deal with the perfect man 
 in the perfect society for just the same reason that the geo- 
 metrician deals with hypothetically perfect figures, the physiol- 
 ogist with normal, as opposed to pathological, organic 
 processes, etc. And, as before, we must remark that such 
 scientific analogies are seriously misleading, even apart from 
 the distinction already referred to between explanatory and 
 normative sciences ; since the legitimate abstractions of science 
 are always indispensable aids to clearness, while the abstract 
 ideal of the perfect man becomes always more vague upon 
 repeated examination. But all this has been discussed at 
 length in the proper context. Here the important thing to 
 notice is, that while Mr. Spencer's later criticisms of Utili- 
 tarianism differ from his earlier ones, in that they do not so 
 obviously depend upon his fundamental conception of the 
 perfect man in the perfect society, he never for a moment 
 gives up his distinction between ' Absolute Ethics ' and ' Rela- 
 tive Ethics,' but rather expounds it in precisely the same 
 way, and makes it equally essential to the structure of his 
 ethical system as a whole. 
 
 The final chapter of the Data of Ethics, on "The Scope of 
 Ethics," is also, for the most part, a mere reproduction of what 
 had been given in the Social Statics. Here, as there, the 
 interests of self are regarded as largely separate from the 
 interests of others, so that we have a personal ethics (that of 
 Prudence) and a social ethics. The latter, again, is divided 
 into Justice, Negative Beneficence, and Positive Beneficence, 
 which are defined precisely as before. Moreover, as the author 
 points out, each of these divisions and subdivisions has to be
 
 o 
 
 28 History of Utilitarianisvi, 
 
 conceived first as a part of ' Absolute Ethics ' and then as a 
 part of ' Relative Ethics ' — though under ideal conditions Ne- 
 gative Beneficence (which consists in avoiding acts that would 
 give unnecessary pain to others) " has but a nominal exist- 
 ence ". The relations between these general principles of 
 conduct are much less clearly indicated here than in the corre- 
 sponding discussion in Social Statics ; but a comparison of the 
 two will show that the author's later view, so far as here de- 
 veloped, corresponds exactly with his earlier one. Here, as 
 there, Justice is regarded as the one exact principle, while 
 Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence are regarded 
 as necessarily inexact, since they involve (at least indirectly) 
 calculations of pleasures and pains. This absolute priority of 
 the principle of Justice, retained in the later form of the system, 
 will almost immediately call for careful consideration. In the 
 Social Statics, as will be remembered, a Moral Sense was as- 
 sumed, and its one clear intuition was held to be precisely that 
 of Justice. In the Data of Ethics, the Moral Sense has been 
 tacitly given up. That, in fact, is the one essential difference, 
 as regards method, between the later book and the earlier one. 
 We shall have to ask ourselves, in the following chapter, 
 whether the peculiar treatment of Justice, retained in the later 
 form of Mr. Spencer's system, is a logical deduction from his 
 revised premises or a mere survival from the earlier form of 
 his system.
 
 CHAPTER XV. 
 
 HERBERT SPENCER (continued). 
 
 It now remains to examine, somewhat briefly, Mr. Spencer's 
 later ethical writings, in which he develops the principles 
 set forth in the Da/a of Ethics. As he explains in the Preface 
 to Justice (1891), declining health and decreasing power of 
 work during the years following the publication of the Data 
 made it necessary for him to depart from the order of treatment 
 originally intended. Passing over Part 1 1, of the Principles 
 of Ethics, "The Inductions of Ethics," and Part III., "The 
 Ethics of Individual Life," he proceeded at once, after four 
 years of compulsory inaction (1886- 1890), to the composition 
 of Part IV., " The Ethics of Social Life : Justice ". Such a 
 choice was, indeed, a foregone conclusion. It was already 
 evident from numerous statements in the Data of Ethics, that 
 for the later, as for the earlier form of the system. Justice was 
 the one ethical principle susceptible of rigorously scientific 
 treatment. Following the order of publication, we shall now 
 proceed to examine the earlier, and more strictly theoretical, 
 portion of this book. 
 
 Since we found in the Data of Ethics that it is necessary 
 to begin with a consideration of * conduct in general,' regarded 
 from the Evolutional point of view, it is evident that here we 
 must first consider animal ethics. The cardinal and opposed 
 principles of animal ethics, as conceived by the author, are 
 stated as follows : " During immaturity benefits received must 
 be inversely proportionate to capacities possessed. Within 
 the family group most must be given where least is deserved, 
 if desert is measured by worth. Contrariwise, after maturity 
 
 (329)
 
 ;^2,o History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 is reached benefit must vary directly as worth : worth being 
 measured by fitness to the conditions of existence." ^ These 
 principles are alike essential to the continuance of the species, 
 and hence equally fundamental to animal ethics ; but, as we 
 are here concerned only with the principle of Justice, we may 
 properly neglect the necessary care of offspring, which would 
 belong to another branch of animal ethics, and confine our- 
 selves to a consideration of sub-human justice. Under its 
 biological aspect, this is the well-known principle of ' the 
 survival of the fittest ' ; in ethical terms (which the author 
 assumes are applicable here), it means that " each individual 
 ought to be subject to the effects of its own nature and result- 
 ing conduct ". Now it is to be observed that, throughout sub- 
 human life, ' ought,' as here used, and ' is ' would coincide, 
 but for one very important complication. This is, that the 
 wholesale destruction of many of the lower forms of life often 
 interferes seriously with the survival of the variations that 
 would otherwise prove themselves ' the fittest '. Among such 
 lower organisms, a high rate of multiplication is necessary, in 
 order to counteract this indiscriminate destruction. The mani- 
 fest implication is, that sub-human justice is extremely imper- 
 fect among the lowest organisms, but tends to become more 
 and more perfect as organisation becomes higher. 
 
 If all animals led solitary lives, the above description of 
 sub-human justice would be sufficiently exact ; but among 
 gregarious creatures another element emerges, and one of the 
 greatest importance. Mr. Spencer says : " Each individual, 
 receiving the benefits and the injuries due to its own nature 
 and consequent conduct, has to carry on that conduct subject 
 to the restriction that it shall not in any large measure impede 
 the conduct by which each other individual achieves benefits 
 or brings on itself injuries. The average conduct must not be 
 so aggressive as to cause evils which out-balance the good 
 obtained by co-operation. Thus, to the positive element in 
 sub-human justice has to be added, among gregarious creatures^ 
 
 ^ See ch. i., §§ 2 et seq.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 331 
 
 a negative element." ^ But even this is not all. Among- 
 certain of the higher gregarious animals, more or less con- 
 certed action on the part of the stronger males for the defence 
 of the females and the young, in case of danger, is an estab- 
 lished, and, as one can readily see, a necessary custom. This, 
 of course, means a temporary subordination of the interest of 
 the individual to that of the herd ; but evolution itself neces- 
 sarily provides that such self-subordination shall go no further 
 than the actual needs of the species demand. In the absence 
 of external enemies, this last qualification of the original 
 principle of Justice would, of course, have no meaning. 
 
 Thus far the author's treatment has been simple and con- 
 sistent, because up to this point the ordinary distinction 
 between what is and what ought to be has not arisen. ' The 
 survival of the fittest ' has been limited only by the indiscrimi- 
 nate destruction of certain of the lower forms of life. When, 
 he begins the treatment of human justice, this is at first repre- 
 sented as a mere extension of animal justice, more perfect in 
 degree, but not differing in kind. The only clear intimation 
 we receive that we are passing beyond the inevitable working 
 of the biological principle of ' the survival of the fittest,' is 
 afforded by a passage in which the natural effects of bad, or 
 imperfectly adapted, actions are mentioned. " To what extent 
 such ill, naturally following from his actions, may be voluntarily 
 borne by other persons, it does not concern us now to inquire. 
 The qualifying effects of pity, mercy, and generosity, will be 
 considered hereafter in the parts dealing with ' Negative 
 Beneficence ' and ' Positive Beneficence '. Here we are con- 
 cerned only with pure Justice." ^ On the assumption, then,, 
 that we are still on the plane of the previous discussion, we 
 are asked to note that human justice is more perfect than that 
 holding among the higher animals, as was to be expected from 
 man's higher organisation. The lower rate of mortality, which 
 results from man's foresight and greater ability to provide 
 for the future, makes it possible for the individual members of 
 
 1 See ch. ii., § 8. 2 gee ch. iii., § 12.
 
 332 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 human society to experience the good or bad effects of their 
 conduct for a correspondingly longer time. Hence well 
 adapted and ill adapted conduct are far more likely to lead to 
 their legitimate results in human society than even among the 
 higher animals. 
 
 If the matter were as simple as this, it is safe to say that 
 Mr. Spencer's book would never have been written. The most 
 stpking form of ' sub-human justice ' is the constant elimina- 
 tion of the unfit. Now the mere fact that, in civilised human 
 society, the unfit are not weeded out in this convenient fashion, 
 introduces a serious complication, if, with the author, we con- 
 ceive of justice in quasi-biological terms. With his unfailing 
 habit of arguing from analogy, when an analogy is in sight, Mr. 
 Spencer has assumed, rather than proved, that human justice, 
 as here defined, is more perfect than animal justice, in pro- 
 portion to man's higher organisation — and this, in spite of 
 the obvious fact, that the principle of * the survival of the 
 fittest,' which is the very essence of ' sub-human justice,' is only 
 allowed a comparatively restricted range in civilised human 
 society. In truth, it is one important thesis of the present 
 book, that human justice ought, in this respect, to corre- 
 spond a good deal more closely to animal justice than is actu- 
 ally the case. 
 
 We have seen that, among the higher animals, the partial 
 or complete sacrifice of individuals to the good of the species 
 is already occasionally necessary. Mr. Spencer admits that, 
 in the highest gregarious creature, man, this qualification of 
 primitive justice assumes large proportions. " No longer, as 
 among inferior beings, demanded only by the need for defence 
 against enemies of other kinds, this further self-subordination is, 
 among human beings, also demanded by the need for defence 
 against enemies of the same kind." But he hastens to add : 
 " The self-subordination thus justified, and in a sense rendered 
 obligatory, is limited to that which is required for defensive 
 war "y And, in accordance with his characteristic view, now 
 
 ^ Seech, iii., § 15.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 335 
 
 so familiar, he urges that even such self-subordination is only 
 a passing phase of human morality, which will disappear on 
 the advent of universal peace. Such being the case, it belongs 
 to ' Relative ' and not to ' Absolute ' Ethics. That self-sacrifice 
 in all its forms will be unnecessary in a ' perfectly adapted ' 
 society, is one of the author's many puzzling assumptions. 
 
 So far we have considered hirnian justice, as it were, from 
 the outside, and as a sort of inevitable extension of animal 
 justice. It now remains to see how our conception of justice 
 has arisen. We found that Mr. Spencer's earlier account of 
 this matter in Social Statics was extremely vague and unsatis- 
 factory. There, of course, he ostensibly takes the Intuitional 
 point of view ; but, after stating his thesis — that " this first 
 and all-essential law [Justice], declaratory of the liberty of 
 each limited only by the like liberty of all, is that fundamental 
 truth of which the moral sense is to give an intuition, and 
 which the intellect is to develop into a scientific morality" — 
 he makes it appear that, in the last resort, the Moral Sense 
 is reducible to a merely egoistic ' instinct of personal rights *. 
 Even with the help of his Intuitional assumptions, therefore, 
 the author regards the conception of justice, as actually enter- 
 tained, as being inexplicable without assuming the co-operation 
 of sympathy. Indeed, he complains that even Adam Smith 
 " did not perceive that the sentiment of justice is nothing but 
 a sympathetic affection of the instinct of personal rights ". 
 
 The confusion here between Intuitionism and Empiricism is 
 evident. In the Data of Ethics, on the other hand, Intuition- 
 ism has already been tacitly given up, and Mr. Spencer 
 attempts to mediate between the two methods by his charac- 
 teristic theory, that what we take to be moral intuitions are to 
 be explained as results of the accumulated experience of the 
 race, as transmitted by the ' inheritance of acquired char- 
 acteristics '. This theory, however, as we saw, is only Em- 
 piricism in disguise, with the additional disadvantage of making 
 the explanation depend entirely upon a biological principle by 
 no means universally admitted, and one which, even when ad- 
 mitted, is now employed with very much greater caution than
 
 334 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 hitherto. Moreover, the explanation given in the Data of 
 Ethics is unsatisfactory for the further reason, which more 
 particularly concerns us here, that it does not tell with suffi- 
 cient definiteness how we come to apprehend the one ethical 
 principle which is perfectly free from ambiguity, viz.. Justice. 
 This, of course, is precisely what the author here attempts to 
 explain. And it is instructive to note the similarity between 
 this later explanation, which is supposed to depend upon the 
 theory of Evolution, and the one given in Sociat Statics forty 
 years before. 
 
 Mr. Spencer begins by distinguishing between the ' senti- 
 ment ' and the ' idea ' of Justice, the principal difference being 
 that the former is somewhat vague, while the latter is capable 
 of becoming perfectly distinct. He finds no difficulty with 
 the ' egoistic sentiment of justice,' since this, as in the earlier 
 work, is practically assumed as a sort of instinct {i.e., ' in- 
 stinct of personal rights '), which is sure to develop with the 
 general development of the individual and of the race. The 
 real question is : How are we to explain the development of 
 the * altruistic sentiment of justice ' ? This is not easy from 
 the author's individualistic point of view, for, as he himself 
 points out : " On the one hand, the implication is that the 
 altruistic sentiment of justice can come into existence only 
 in the course of adaptation to social life. On the other hand, 
 the implication is that social life is made possible only by 
 maintenance of those equitable relations which imply the 
 altruistic sentiment of justice. How can these reciprocal 
 requirements be fulfilled ? " ^ 
 
 The answer given is on lines already suggested in the 
 Data of Ethics, where it was explained how we pass from the 
 ' extrinsic ' to the ' intrinsic ' view of morality, though the 
 previous discussion is not referred to here. Since the ' altru- 
 istic ' sentiment of justice is, by hypothesis, lacking, a ' pro- 
 altruistic ' sentiment of justice must take its place. This 
 develops as a result of the four ' extrinsic ' controls of con- 
 
 ' See ch. iv., § 19.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 335 
 
 duct, with which we are already familiar : the dread of 
 retahation, the dread of social dislike, the dread of legal 
 punishment, and the dread of Divine vengeance. By these 
 four controls, united, as the author says, ' in various propor- 
 tions,' social co-operation is made possible even before sym- 
 pathy develops in any considerable degree. But given a 
 common life, whether of the herd or of any group in primitive 
 society, and sympathy tends to develop. 
 
 The explanation of the development of sympathy which 
 follows is by no means new. It is really very similar to the 
 one so long ago given by Tucker in his Light of Nature 
 (1768), and substantially identical with the one which Mr. 
 Spencer himself had given in his Principles of Psychology. 
 The nature of the explanation is sufficiently indicated by the 
 following passage : " In a permanent group there occur, 
 generation after generation, incidents simultaneously draw- 
 ing from its members manifestations of like emotions — re- 
 joicings over victories and escapes, over prey jointly captured, 
 over supplies of wild food discovered ; as well as laments 
 over defeats, scarcities, inclemencies, &c. . . . Thus there is 
 fostered that sympathy which makes the altruistic sentiment of 
 justice possible." ^ The similarity between this and Tucker's 
 explanation may not at first be evident ; but comparison will 
 show that both begin by assuming primitive egoism, and pro- 
 ceed to argue that, since men are bound to feel more or less 
 like each other, in similar circumstances, they must end by 
 feeling for each other. How this transition is effected, viz., 
 that from feeling like to feeling for others (which, of course, 
 is what we mean by altruism), is left almost, if not quite, as 
 mysterious by Mr. Spencer as by Tucker. If man really 
 begins as a practical individualist, sympathy must necessarily 
 remain factitious to the end. It is interesting to see that, 
 in this, as in many other respects, Mr. Spencer stands in 
 much closer relations to the eighteenth century British mor- 
 alists than to the more recent Evolutional school, which takes 
 
 ^ See ch. iv., § 20.
 
 336 Histoiy of Utilitarianism. 
 
 seriously the helpful, if by no means ultimate, conception of 
 society as an organism. 
 
 But, to proceed, Mr. Spencer argues that, when sympathy 
 is once developed, the * altruistic ' sentiment of justice is 
 sure to develop alongside of the ' egoistic ' sentiment of 
 justice. Men will come to feel strongly, even if still somewhat 
 vaguely, for the rights of others as well as for their own. 
 It goes without saying that this development is conditioned 
 in important respects by the growth of ' the faculty of mental 
 representation ' ; and here, as so often elsewhere, it is argued 
 that the sentiment of justice, like moral development in 
 general, must remain imperfect until society has completely 
 outgrown the militant condition. In short, the only real 
 difference between this later, and last, explanation of the 
 derivation of the sentiment of justice and that given in the 
 Social Statics, is that here, as in the Psychology, an explanation 
 of the origin of sympathy has also been given. The author 
 remains true to his original position, that " the sentiment of 
 justice is nothing but a sympathetic affection of the instinct 
 of personal rights — a sort of reflex function of it ". And 
 this explanation, surely, is by no means dependent upon the 
 theory of Evolution. 
 
 Thus much as to the origin of the relatively vague ' senti- 
 ment ' of justice. By itself, this would be insufficient ; the 
 * idea ' of justice must become definite and objective. How 
 is this possible ? The explanation given is rather surprising : 
 " The idea emerges and becomes definite in the course of the 
 experiences that action may be carried up to a certain limit 
 without causing resentment from others, but if carried beyond 
 that limit produces resentment. Such experiences accumu- 
 late ; and gradually, along with repugnance to the acts which 
 bring reactive pains, there arises a conception of a limit to 
 each kind of activity up to which there is freedom to act." ^ 
 And it is important to note that, according to Mr. Spencer, 
 not equality, but inequality, is the primordial ideal suggested. 
 
 ^ See ch. v., § 21.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 337 
 
 If each is to receive the benefits and evils due to his own 
 nature and consequent conduct, then, since men differ in their 
 powers, there must be differences in the results of their con- 
 duct. Such, at any rate, is the author's rather abstract ex- 
 planation. More convincing is his contention that, where 
 habitual wax has developed political organisation, the idea of 
 inequality necessarily becomes predominant. In fact, he 
 points out that, in such a condition of society, " the inequality 
 refers, not to the natural achievement of greater rewards by 
 greater merits, but to the artificial apportionment of greater 
 rewards to greater merits ". Regimentation pervades the 
 civil, as well as the military organisation ; and the idea of 
 justice conforms to the social structure. Such an ideal of 
 justice could not, of course, be permanent ; but the modern 
 revolt from it has been to the other extreme. Instead of an 
 artificial inequality, an at least equally artificial equality is 
 held by many, especially by Bentham and his followers, to 
 represent the essential character of justice. By a decidedly 
 strained interpretation of the Utilitarian formula, the author 
 argues that its logical result would be nothing less than 
 communism. 
 
 Here, again, Mr. Spencer proposes to mediate. He says . 
 " If each of these opposite conceptions of justice is accepted 
 as true in part, and then supplemented by the other, there re- 
 sults that conception of justice which arises on contemplating 
 the laws of life as carried on in the social state. The equality 
 concerns the mutually-limited spheres of action which must 
 be maintained if associated men are to co-operate harmoni- 
 ously. The inequality concerns the results which each may 
 achieve by carrying on his actions within the implied limits^ 
 No incongruity exists when the ideas of equality and in- 
 equality are applied the one to the bounds and the other to the 
 benefits. Contrariwise, the two may be, and must be, simul- 
 taneously asserted." ^ It remains only to find a formula for 
 the compromise here suggested. This must unite a positive 
 
 ^ See ch. v., § 25. 
 22
 
 338 Histo7'y of Utilitarianism. 
 
 with a negative element. As the author says : " It must be 
 positive in so far as it asserts for each that, since he is to 
 receive and suffer the good and evil results of his actions, he 
 must be allowed to act. And it must be negative in so far as, 
 by asserting this of every one, it implies that each can be 
 allowed to act only under the restraint imposed by the pres- 
 ence of others having like claims to act. . . . Hence, that which 
 we have to express in a precise way, is the liberty of each 
 limited only by the like liberties of all. This we do by 
 saying : — Every man is free to do that which he wills, pro- 
 vided he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man." ^ 
 
 At length we have obtained a formula for the principle 
 which Mr. Spencer regards as absolutely fundamental to 
 Ethics, being thus on an entirely different plane from Pru- 
 dence, Negative Beneficence, and Positive Beneficence, all of 
 which share in the general ambiguity of the conception of 
 happiness, upon which they equally depend. That this prin- 
 ciple is identical with the principle of Justice, as formulated 
 in Social Statics, is evident.^ There, however, the prin- 
 ciple was represented as being our one perfectly clear in- 
 tuition coming from the Moral Sense, the existence of which 
 the author then assumed. At the same time, as pointed out 
 a few pages back, it was apparently only the ' instinct of 
 personal rights ' that was regarded as strictly intuitive — a 
 rather curious intuition of justice, which, however formulated, 
 is generally supposed to imply impartiality, if it implies any- 
 thing. In order to the development of the sentiment of 
 justice, as universally understood, the co-operation of sym- 
 pathy (assumed rather than derived, though not necessarily 
 assumed as an ultimate) was held to be necessary, so that 
 justice was represented as a sort of ' reflex function ' of the 
 ' instinct of personal rights '. We have already remarked 
 
 iSee ch. vi., § 27. 
 
 2 In fact, the final form given to the principle in Social Statics is as follows : 
 " Every man has freedom to do all that he wills, provided he infringes not the 
 equal freedom of any other man ", See ch. vi., § i.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 339 
 
 upon the confusion of Intuitionism and Empiricism which one 
 finds here. Now, according to Mr. Spencer's explanations in 
 the present volume, as we have so recently seen, the ' senti- 
 ment ' of justice is developed in much the same way. The 
 * egoistic sentiment of justice ' is practically assumed here, as 
 the ' instinct of personal rights ' had been in the earlier 
 volume. In order to the development of the ' altruistic senti- 
 ment of justice,' sympathy must co-operate, as was also held 
 in Social Statics. The difference is, that here sympathy is 
 not assumed, but shown to have been developed while society 
 was being held together by a provisional sentiment — the ' pro- 
 altruistic sentiment of justice,' which results from the four 
 external controls of conduct. But when once sympathy is 
 sufficiently developed, the ' altruistic sentiment of justice ' will 
 necessarily develop as the counterpart of the ' egoistic senti- 
 ment of justice '. Whether these two forms of the ' sentiment ' 
 of justice, at first so sharply differentiated, tend later to 
 blend into a general ' sentiment ' of justice, we are not in- 
 formed ; but such would seem to be the implication. 
 
 The author's peculiar method of explaining the transition 
 from the ' sentiment ' to the ' idea ' of justice, has already been 
 indicated. Evidently it reduces itself to the rather surprising 
 statement that men obtain the ' idea,' as opposed to the mere 
 ' sentiment,' of justice, by experience of the fact that there 
 are certain limits beyond which their fellows will not tolerate 
 interference ! Well may he add : " It is a long time before the 
 general nature of the limit common to all cases can be con- 
 ceived "y If this were the true origin of our idea of justice, 
 it would be long indeed. Not only so ; but there would in- 
 evitably be a different * idea ' of justice for every race, if not 
 for every minor social group, for the degree of human long- 
 suffering is plainly a variable. And, in truth, it has been 
 argued by the author that, up to the present time, two radically 
 different ideals or ' ideas ' of justice have actually been de- 
 veloped, one implying a more or less artificial inequality, the 
 
 ^See ch. v., § 21.
 
 340 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 other a decidedly artificial equality. The true formula — which, 
 so far from being evidently true, has been left for Mr. Spencer 
 to enunciate — is supposed to unite the elements of truth in 
 the two prevailing, but antagonistic views. 
 
 It is not strange that Mr. Spencer feels it necessary to 
 subjoin a defence of ' the authority of this formula '.^ He 
 laments the general contempt for ' abstract principles,' and 
 argues that " it is only where the ethics of amity are entangled 
 with the ethics of enmity, that thoughts about conduct are 
 confused by the necessities of compromise ". This last is 
 itself quite confusing, since the author has just urged strongly 
 in favour of his own formula for justice, that it stands for a 
 highly satisfactory compromise between the two one-sided 
 views. Again, he answers the supposed objection that this 
 principle belongs to the class of a priori beliefs, though his 
 own derivation of the principle, as indicated above, has sug- 
 gested anything but that difficulty ; and, in this connection, he 
 repeats his old argument, which goes to show that what often 
 pass for a priori principles are the inherited results of race 
 experience. From such general considerations, he concludes : 
 " No higher warrant can be imagined ; and now, accepting the 
 law of equal freedom as an ultimate ethical principle, having 
 an authority transcending every other, we may proceed with 
 our inquiry "? 
 
 It will thus be seen that the author's later explanation of 
 the genesis of the ' sentiment ' and the ' idea ' of justice 
 consists merely in working out in some detail the suggestions 
 already made in Social Statics — unless we except the peculiar 
 account given of the transition from the ' sentiment ' to the 
 ' idea ' of justice, which, as we have seen, is by far the weakest 
 part of the whole explanation. Moreover, it is plain that 
 this similarity between the explanation given in Social Statics 
 and that given in the present volume, is made possible only by 
 the fact, that the earlier view involves something rather less 
 than a Moral Sense, while the later view involves something 
 
 1 See ch. vii. 2 See ibid., § 35.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 341 
 
 rather more than ordinary Empiricism would admit in that 
 characteristic ultimate, which, though not so called, is in reality 
 the old ' instinct of personal rights '. 
 
 All this, of course, does not by any means involve the theory 
 of Evolution. In how far does Mr. Spencer's general treat- 
 ment of Justice, in the present volume, depend upon that all- 
 important biological theory ? The answer is not difficult : 
 Merely in professedly regarding ^ human justice — as con- 
 ceived by himself and defined in his favourite formula — as 
 being an inevitable evolutional development from sub-human 
 justice, which he has shown to be practically identical with 
 the ' survival of the fittest '. It has often been demonstrated 
 that what we commonly mean by justice cannot be explained 
 in terms of anything analogous to this brute survival of the 
 merely strongest in the struggle for existence. It has not, 
 perhaps, so often been pointed out that, while Mr. Spencer's 
 conception of the essential nature of justice is undoubtedly 
 different from the ordinary one, it equally implies a departure 
 from the inevitable course of Evolution considered strictly as 
 such. In short, the opposition between what merely is and 
 what ought to be, really exists quite as much for Mr. Spencer 
 as for any other moralist — except in so far as he takes refuge 
 in his unproved assumption that human society will eventually 
 become perfect. 
 
 Let us consider this a little more closely. ' Animal justice ' is 
 reducible to the ' survival of the fittest '. Now the ' survival of 
 the fittest ' — and the originator of this useful phrase doubtless 
 knew, best of all men, that by ' the fittest ' is here meant 
 only ' the fittest to survive ' — is a fact. It would have to be 
 recognised as such even by one who should deny the validity 
 of the theory of Evolution itself ; much more is it recognised 
 by the enormous majority who do accept the general theory 
 of Evolution, however they may differ as to the particular 
 factors involved, and the relative importance of these factors. 
 Is human justice — defined as the principle that ' every man is 
 
 ^ Often, when it suits the needs of a particular argument ; not consistently, 
 as the sequel will show.
 
 342 History of Utilitarianism, 
 
 free to do what he wills, provided he infringes not the equal 
 freedom of any other man ' — also a statement of what in- 
 evitably happens in the natural course of events ? By no 
 means ; for ' is free,' we must read ' ought to be free,' in order 
 to give the formula an intelligible meaning. And that is 
 what Mr. Spencer himself really does, though one is obliged 
 to suspect that his use of the indicative mood here is not 
 wholly a matter of chance. In fact, this facile transition from 
 what evidently is to what he thinks ought to be, or vice versa, 
 in the course of an argument of any length, is a source of 
 almost endless ambiguity, which conceals a radical confusion of 
 thought, in the author's later ethical writings, where he pro- 
 fesses to depend upon the theory of Evolution for guidance. 
 One of the early passages in the Data of Ethics, already 
 quoted, conveniently illustrates this. It may be the more 
 pardonable to quote it again, since it plainly refers to the 
 very principle which we are considering. " This imperfectly- 
 evolved conduct introduces us by antithesis to conduct that 
 is perfectly evolved. Contemplating these adjustments of acts 
 to ends which miss completeness because they cannot be made 
 by one creature without other creatures being prevented from 
 making them, raises the thought of adjustments such that each 
 creature may make them without preventing them from 
 being made by other creatures." ^ 
 
 In short, human justice, even as conceived by Mr. Spencer, 
 is no inevitable extension of ' animal justice,' of which latter 
 it is only too obviously the ' antithesis '. It is rather what 
 one man, at any rate, thinks ought to be, and this not so much 
 because he is an evolutionist — for he held the doctrine firmly, 
 and stated it in precisely the same way, before he or any one 
 else had adequately formulated the theory of Evolution — but 
 rather because he is, and has been, first, last, and always an 
 individualist. To be sure, this conception of justice happens 
 to be less obviously inconsistent with Evolutional theory than 
 some of the other results of the author's individualism. It 
 
 ^ See ch. ii., § 6. Of course the italics are not in the original.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 343 
 
 involves no manifest absurdity from the evolutionary point of 
 view, as when it was seriously argued in the last part of the 
 Data of Ethics, that sympathy will be developed with the 
 future moral progress of the race, very much in proportion as 
 it is not needed. At the same time, it makes individual wel- 
 fare an end in itself in a way that the theory of Evolution 
 would never suggest, and that the perfectly consistent Evolu- 
 tionist could by no means admit without reservations that 
 never occur to Mr. Spencer. 
 
 Indeed, one may go further than this. The highly abstract 
 principle of Justice, as here defined, so far from being shown 
 to have been necessarily involved in the actual evolution of 
 society, is practically treated as a * categorical imperative,' 
 an ' absolute ought '. ' Though the heavens fall,' Mr. Spencer 
 would seem to say, ' every man must be granted the right to 
 do as he pleases, so long as he does not interfere with any 
 one else in the exercise of this divine right.' In other words, 
 though the principle of Justice is no longer held by Mr. 
 Spencer to be the one intuition of our Moral Sense, as was at 
 least ostensibly done in the earlier form of his theory, it is 
 actually treated as such by him, after he has explained its deri- 
 vation in empirical terms. Of course he admits that Justice 
 is not the only principle of Ethics ; that Prudence, Negative 
 Beneficence, and Positive Beneficence must also be taken 
 into account But these latter principles all depend upon the 
 indefinite conception of general happiness, while Justice does 
 not. Is such a combination of practical Intuitionism, as 
 regards Justice, and Universalistic Hedonism, as regards the 
 remaining principles of morality, really workable } This very 
 serious question can only be answered, if answered at all, 
 in the sequel. 
 
 We are as little concerned here, as in our treatment of 
 the earlier form of Mr. Spencer's ethical system, to take 
 account of the numerous applications of this highly abstract 
 principle of Justice. Such applications must necessarily be a 
 matter of individual judgment ; and, moreover, any such 
 attempt to solve many of the most important practical prob-
 
 344 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 lems of government by the application of a single abstract 
 principle is a proceeding which logically belongs to the 
 methods of eighteenth century, as opposed to nineteenth 
 century thought. It will be remembered that the author con- 
 tends for the following Natural Rights : ' the right to physical 
 integrity/ ' the rights to free motion and locomotion,' ' the 
 rights to the uses of natural media,' ' the right of property,' * the 
 right of incorporeal property,' ' the rights of gift and be- 
 quest,' ' the rights of free exchange and free contract,' ' the 
 right of free industry,' ' the rights of free belief and worship,' 
 ' the rights of free speech and publication,' not to mention 
 the less definite ' rights ' of women and children. 
 
 Do these rights, however understood, owe their origin to 
 the principle of Justice, as here defined .'' On this point an 
 early reviewer of Justice admirably said : " Of the various 
 Natural Rights specified by Mr. Spencer, I think it must be 
 said that not one of them is, or can be, deduced from the law 
 of equal freedom. They are the conditions which have been 
 found, in some cases, necessary, in others, expedient, for the 
 maintenance of human society. . . . We learn them from his- 
 tory, not from deduction ; and we see at the same time that 
 they are not universally applicable. The ' right of free speech 
 and publication ' may at times be properly withheld, and I 
 have not observed any censure of the Indian government for 
 its recent withdrawal of the right from certain native writers. 
 ' The right of free exchange ' exists nowhere in the world out- 
 side of Great Britain ; and certainly American citizens are 
 peculiarly sensitive to their rights. If we believed that ' free- 
 dom of worship ' imperilled the public welfare, no assertion of 
 individual rights would prevent its abolition {cf. the great 
 Mormon case, Reynolds versus United States). ' The right 
 to property ' is one of the most sacred of rights ; yet it may be 
 modified or set aside for the good of the community, as is 
 illustrated by recent land-legislation in England. Even ' the 
 right to life ' is qualified by the state's need of soldiers." ^ 
 
 ^ See review oi Justice by President J. G. Schurman, Philosophical Review, 
 vol. I., No. I, p. 84.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 345 
 
 We have now examined all that is really distinctive in the 
 later form of Mr. Spencer's ethical theory. The remaining 
 Parts of the Principles of Ethics, published during the two 
 years following the publication of Justice (Part IV.), need not 
 detain us long. In 1892 appeared Part II., "The Inductions 
 of Ethics," and Part III., " The Ethics of Individual Life," 
 completing the first volume of the Principles ; and in 1893 
 appeared Part V., " Negative Beneficence," and Part VI., 
 " Positive Beneficence," completing the second volume, and 
 the work as a whole. The topics treated in these concluding 
 Parts are, of course, intrinsically of great importance ; but 
 the author's handling of them is almost exactly such as could 
 have been predicted on the basis of what is contained in the 
 Social Statics and the Data of Ethics. Moreover, as we shall 
 see, there is comparatively little in Parts III., V., and VI. to 
 distinguish the author's treatment from that of traditional 
 Utilitarianism. 
 
 " The Inductions of Ethics " (Part II.) consists almost wholly 
 of a mass of sociological details, so arranged as to illustrate 
 the moral development of the race, according to the author's 
 point of view. As might be expected, Mr. Spencer constantly 
 takes occasion to justify his characteristic distinction be- 
 tween the ' ethics of enmity ' and the ' ethics of amity ' by 
 reference to the sociological facts here collected. At first, these 
 supposed facts, taken from the most various sources, seem to 
 be accepted most uncritically ; but the author himself warns 
 us, in his closing " Summary of Inductions," against taking 
 particular statements with too much confidence. After speak- 
 ing of the difficulty of dealing with phenomena so complex as 
 those which form the data of sociology, he very justly says : 
 " To the difficulties in the way of generalisation hence arising, 
 must be added the difficulties arising from uncertainty of the 
 evidence — the doubtfulness, incompleteness, and conflicting 
 natures, of the statements with which we have to deal. Not 
 all travellers are to be trusted. Some are bad observers, some 
 are biassed by creed or custom, some by personal likings or 
 dislikings ; and all have but imperfect opportunities of getting
 
 34^ History of UtilitarianisTn. 
 
 at the truth. Similarly with historians. Very httle of what 
 they narrate is from immediate observation. The greater 
 part of it comes through channels which colour, and obscure, 
 and distort ; while everywhere party feeling, religious bigotry, 
 and the sentiment of patriotism, cause exaggerations and sup- 
 pressions. Testimonies concerning moral traits are hence 
 liable to perversion." ^ 
 
 After all deductions have been made, however, the author 
 holds that one conclusion must be drawn from the sociological 
 material here collected : the Moral Sense theory, as ordinarily 
 understood, is wholly untenable. Mr. Spencer's definite state- 
 ment regarding his own change of view on this important 
 matter is well worth quoting. He says : " Though, as shown 
 in my first work. Social Statics, I once espoused the doctrine 
 of the intuitive moralists (at the outset in full, and in later 
 chapters with some implied qualifications), yet it has gradu- 
 ally become clear to me that the qualifications required 
 practically obliterate the doctrine as enunciated by them ".- 
 
 But while he has changed his mind regarding the existence 
 of a Moral Sense, he gives emphatic testimony to his con- 
 tinued belief in the perfectibility of human society. He says : 
 " There needs but a continuance of absolute peace externally, 
 and a rigorous insistence on non-aggression internally, to 
 ensure the moulding of men into a form naturally characterised 
 by all the virtues " ? 
 
 When we turn to " The Ethics of Individual Life " (Part 
 III.), it is to be remembered that we are dealing with the Part 
 of the Principles immediately preceding " Justice ". The 
 chapters belonging to this third, and concluding. Part of Vol. 
 I. contain almost nothing that is new, at least concerning the 
 essential principles of Ethics, as understood by the author. 
 The general title itself is, of course, significant as indicating 
 that Mr. Spencer remains true to his original individualism. 
 There is, it seems, an " Ethics of Individual Life," as opposed 
 to the " Ethics of Social Life " — Justice and Beneficence. 
 This is developed on the lines already suggested in the Data 
 
 1 See Pt. II., ch. xiv., § i88. ^ gee ibid., § 191. " See ibid.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 347 
 
 of Ethics ; the only difference between the treatment here 
 given and that of ordinary recent Utihtarianism being, that 
 the good of the individual is regarded as something not 
 necessarily connected with the good of the whole — which, 
 of course, again suggests the author's affinity to the eighteenth 
 century moralists. The bulk of these chapters, however, is 
 devoted to good advice rather than to the systematic treat- 
 ment of Ethics. It may be interesting to know what are Mr. 
 Spencer's personal views on ' activity,' ' rest,' ' nutrition,' 
 ' stimulation,' etc. ; but these cannot be said to belong to 
 the History of Ethics. 
 
 More important are " Negative Beneficence " (Part V.) and 
 " Positive Beneficence " (Part VI.), since we must look here 
 for the necessary mitigation of the stern principle of Justice ; 
 but it cannot be denied that these concluding Parts of the 
 Principles are seriously disappointing. That the principle of 
 Justice, all-important though it may be in its own sphere, is 
 not the whole of Ethics, is fully recognised by Mr. Spencer. 
 Indeed, as we have just seen, he has already (in Part III.) 
 attempted to treat systematically of the duties which we owe 
 merely to ourselves, and which thus, according to his own 
 point of view, fall entirely outside the sphere of Justice. We 
 have seen, however, that the actual treatment is hardly impor- 
 tant, since — apart from the practical counsels above referred 
 to — it amounts to little more than a reiteration of the author's 
 view of the claims of the individual, considered merely as such. 
 The method of treatment adopted, so far as it has to do with 
 theoretical Ethics at all, is practically reducible to the Utili- 
 tarian method in its earlier, and by this time somewhat anti- 
 quated, form. The difficulty of adjusting this method of treat- 
 ment to the peculiar treatment of Justice — in which, of course, 
 Mr. Spencer stands alone among English hedonists — is, in- 
 deed, apparent ; but it does not come up in an acute form, 
 for the " Ethics of Individual Life " and that part of the 
 " Ethics of Social Life " which belongs to the sphere of Justice 
 are, at any rate, alike consistent deductions from the individu- 
 alistic assumptions of the system.
 
 348 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 When, however, the author begins to treat systematically 
 of Beneficence, this difficulty arising from the employment of 
 two apparently distinct methods becomes a serious matter. 
 As already said, the principle of Justice, though no longer 
 held to be our one clear intuition derived from a Moral Sense, ^ 
 is actually regarded by Mr. Spencer, in the later as in the 
 earlier form of his system, as a practical ultimate, and there- 
 fore as not depending upon considerations of * greatest happi- 
 ness '. On the other hand. Beneficence — a principle with 
 which the author can dispense as little as any other moralist — 
 is, to all intents and purposes, treated in terms of traditional 
 Utilitarianism.2 What will happen in the case of the (at 
 least apparent) conflict between the principle of Justice and 
 that of Beneficence 'i One would by no means hold Mr. 
 Spencer responsible for the practical difficulties of the moral 
 life, viz., the occasional conflict of duties, as some anti-hedon- 
 ist critics are in the habit of doing in similar cases. As we 
 have repeatedly seen, such difficulties are practical before they 
 are theoretical ; hence they are bound to be difficulties for 
 any system of Ethics. But the peculiar difficulty which we 
 have to recognise here is : the lack of any single, clearly- 
 defined, organising principle, upon which the particular prin- 
 ciples of morality — Justice as much as any other — can be 
 shown to depend. Probably this is why the author's treatment 
 of all moral principles besides Justice is as empirical as his 
 treatment of Justice had been abstract and theoretical. From 
 his point of view, indeed, very little of a strictly theoretical 
 character can be said of any moraJ principle other than Jus- 
 tice — the only one, as he has so often insisted, that is capable 
 of a perfectly definite, and therefore strictly scientific, treat- 
 ment. 
 
 The difficulties which attend an individualistic treatment 
 of Beneficence are avoided at the outset in the introductory 
 chapter on " Kinds of Altruism ". Mr. Spencer says, e.g. : 
 
 ' As in the earlier, not necessarily the later, part of Social Statics. 
 ^Cf. the author's admission on this point in the passage already quoted from 
 the Preface to Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 349 
 
 " As distinguished from egoistic actions, altruistic actions in- 
 clude all those which either negatively by self-restraint, or 
 positively by efforts for their benefit, conduce to the welfare 
 of fellow-men : they include both justice and beneficence ".^ 
 As will readily be seen, this use of ' egoistic ' and ' altruistic,' 
 as applied to actions, leaves out of account the moral motive 
 altogether. That justice and beneficence, however defined, 
 should be kept distinct, so far as possible, Mr. Spencer very 
 properly insists. He further maintains " that the primary law 
 of a harmonious social co-operation may not be broken for the 
 fulfilment of the secondary law ; and that therefore, while en- 
 forcement of justice must be a pubKc function, the exercise of 
 beneficence must be a private function "? When stated in such 
 general terms, this principle also may at first commend itself ; 
 but one must remember that by justice is here meant the prin- 
 ciple of non-interference, which has important corollaries as 
 regards theory of government. While many practical states- 
 men have a healthy dread of a too paternal government, it 
 is safe to say that no practical statesman ever did, or ever will, 
 try to keep justice and beneficence, in whatever sense under- 
 stood, separate in the way that Mr. Spencer would seem to 
 require. It would, e.g.^ take but a famine or a pestilence to 
 show how unworkable such an abstract theory would be. More- 
 over, every government is, and must be, ' paternal ' in the 
 sense that it provides for the common good in many ways 
 that can by no means be included under the single head of 
 Justice, according to any legitimate interpretation of that 
 principle. 
 
 The distinction between Negative Beneficence and Positive 
 Beneficence, here again insisted upon and made the basis of 
 treatment, is that which the author had already clearly drawn 
 in Social Statics. Negative Beneficence, of course, consists 
 in avoiding the infliction of unnecessary pain upon others, 
 when strict Justice, as here understood, would permit this ; 
 while Positive Beneficence consists in voluntarily adding to 
 
 1 See Pt. v., ch. i., § 389. «See ibid., § 390.
 
 350 History of UtilitaTianisin. 
 
 the pleasures of others. It is imphed here, as elsewhere, 
 that under the latter head are included " those kinds of actions 
 alone recognised in the ordinary conception of beneficence ". 
 If this be so — and the statement could probably be contro- 
 verted — it is only because justice is ordinarily understood 
 not only in a different sense from that of Mr. Spencer, but in 
 a larger sense. To the ordinary moral consciousness, it doubt- 
 less seems only just that one should avoid causing others un- 
 necessary pain ; and when the writer on systematic Ethics 
 prefers not to include this under the head of Justice in the 
 strict sense, he nearly always provides for the principle in his 
 own way. This distinction, then, between Negative Benefi- 
 cence and Positive Beneficence, so far from being an important 
 invention of Mr. Spencer's, can hardly be regarded as more 
 than a subdivision convenient for himself, and partly necessi- 
 tated by his narrow and peculiar conception of Justice. Often, 
 indeed, this distinction must have proved inconvenient even to 
 its originator. He more exactly defines Negative Beneficence 
 as " the species of beneficent conduct which is characterised 
 by passivity in deed or word, at times when egoistic advantage 
 or pleasure might be gained by action ".^ It has frequently 
 been pointed out by moralists of the most diverse tendencies, 
 that ' activity ' and ' passivity,' as applied to moral conduct, 
 are very misleading terms for Ethics ; since, in a great number 
 of possible cases, ' passivity ' is the full equivalent of ' activity '. 
 It is only fair to say that the author avoids such difficulties in 
 his own treatment ; but this is only by the careful choice of 
 examples. 
 
 It is wholly unnecessary to consider in detail these con- 
 cluding Parts of the Principles of Ethics, for here, as in Part 
 III, " Ethics of Individual Life," Mr. Spencer contents himself, 
 for the most part, with giving and defending his individual 
 opinion with respect to each of the practical problems dis- 
 cussed. These are by no means without interest, particularly 
 as being the opinions of one who has impressed his personality 
 
 1 See Pt. v., ch. i., § 394.
 
 Herbert Spencer. 351 
 
 so strongly upon his contemporaries ; but here, as before, we 
 must remark that such discussions do not belong to the techni- 
 cal treatment of Ethics. It would hardly be going too far to 
 say that it is only in the final chapter of Part V., on " The 
 Ultimate Sanctions " {i.e., of Negative Beneficence), that the 
 author reverts, for the time being, to theoretical Ethics. Here 
 it is held merely, that " the admitted desideratum being main- 
 tenance and prosperity of the species, or that variety of the 
 species constituting the society, the implication is that the 
 modes of conduct here enjoined under the head of Negative 
 Beneficence, have their remote justification in their conducive- 
 ness to such maintenance and prosperity " — the assumption, 
 of course, being that ' maintenance and prosperity of the 
 species,' if adequately provided for, will ultimately conduce to 
 ' greatest happiness '. The author pertinently adds : " Of 
 course these considerations touching the nature of Beneficence 
 at large, here appended as a commentary on the actions classed 
 under the head of Negative Beneficence, equally apply, and 
 indeed apply still more manifestly, to the actions classed under 
 the head of Positive Beneficence " } 
 
 It should perhaps be noted that little is said in these 
 concluding Parts of the Principles regarding the distinction 
 between ' Absolute ' and ' Relative ' Ethics. Presumably, how- 
 ever, this is not because the author has by any means given up 
 his belief in a perfect society in the remote future, so strongly 
 reaffirmed in Part II., " Inductions of Ethics," published the 
 year before. It is doubtless because the treatment here given 
 is almost wholly practical, as already indicated, and so natu- 
 rally keeps to the present conditions of social life. There are, 
 indeed, passages almost pathetic, in which the author points 
 out how completely, in his own opinion, ' the time is out of 
 joint ' ; but it would be wholly unwarranted to infer from these 
 that he has given up his original optimism with regard to the 
 future of society, so firmly held through a long life of almost 
 unremitting labour, under adverse physical conditions that 
 
 1 See Pt. v., ch. viii., §§ 426, 427.
 
 352 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 would long ago have discouraged a literary worker of less 
 heroic mould. 
 
 Little need be said by way of resumi, after our somewhat 
 extended examination of both the earlier and the later form 
 of Mr. Spencer's ethical system, since this examination has 
 already involved the necessary general, as well as special, 
 comparisons and criticisms. Nothing more than the merest 
 outline of results will be attempted in what follows. In the 
 earlier (what we have ventured to term) ' pre-Evolutional ' 
 form of the system, we have found an interesting but highly 
 abstract theory of morality, confessedly based upon the 
 author's characteristic, though paradoxical, conception of the 
 perfect man in the perfect society — with which alone, indeed, 
 he holds that scientific Ethics properly speaking has to do. 
 From this point of view, as he himself insists, not even the 
 existence of evil can be recognised. The perfect man is 
 the only object of interest for the scientific moralist, just as 
 the hypothetically perfect geometrical figure of whatever 
 kind for the scientific mathematician. Moreover, a Moral 
 Sense must be recognised — though this, upon further examina- 
 tion, resolves itself into an ' instinct of personal rights,' which 
 is supposed to be helped out by ' sympathy '. 
 
 The ' Expediency Philosophy,' as represented by Bentham, 
 is discredited, not merely, or perhaps principally, because ex- 
 perience shows that the hedonistic calculus involves insuper- 
 able difficulties, but because it may be proved a priori to be 
 impossible, if only we consider that, with every stage of 
 intellectual or moral progress (or decadence) on the part of 
 the individual, the community, the nation, or the race, there 
 would necessarily be a partial shifting of the scale of 
 hedonistic values. In place of this wholly inadequate method, 
 which involves the impossibility of particular computations, 
 we must employ one which shall determine the general condi- 
 tions to efficient social life and therefore, indirectly, to the 
 ' greatest happiness,' which must still be regarded as the ulti- 
 mate ideal. These are reducible to the principles of Justice,
 
 Herbert Spencer. 353 
 
 Negative Beneficence, and Positive Beneficence, enlightened 
 self-interest being always pre-supposed. Even from the 
 author's abstract statement of these principles, however, a 
 serious difficulty was apparent. Though all were designed 
 to supplant the ' hedonistic calculus,' all except Justice 
 were admitted to depend in the last resort upon the concep- 
 tion of happiness, which, as the severe criticism of the ' Ex- 
 pediency Philosophy ' went to show, is bound to remain 
 indefinite until the perfect society shall become an accom- 
 plished fact. 
 
 Justice, on the other hand, already defined as the principle 
 that " every man has freedom to do all that he wills, provided 
 he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man," ^ was 
 held to be our one perfectly clear moral intuition, derived 
 from an ultimate Moral Sense — though, as we have seen, 
 the author's direct treatment of the Moral Sense in Social 
 Statics is decidedly wavering. As a result, we have found that, 
 in this earlier work, at any rate, the author is practically an 
 Intuitionist as regards Justice, while his proposed treatment 
 of the remaining principles of morality, hardly more than 
 indicated here, practically coincides with that of traditional 
 Utilitarianism, the inadequacy of which he has been at such 
 pains to point out. In so far as he has merely insisted upon 
 the necessity of general rules instead of particular computa- 
 tions, he has reverted unconsciously to the traditional Utili- 
 tarian position as against Bentham, or at any rate as against 
 the interpretation that has generally been put upon Bentham's 
 doctrine. 
 
 It will be remembered that, in the earlier form of Mr. 
 Spencer's ethical theory, our attention was directed almost 
 wholly to the * static ' aspect of morality, as the title of the 
 book itself would indicate. In the Data of Ethics^ on the 
 other hand, in which the later form of the system as a whole 
 was at least clearly indicated, the author attempts to do 
 justice to both the ' static ' and the ' dynamic ' views, but with 
 
 ^ See Social Statics, ch. vi., § i. 
 23
 
 354 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 special emphasis upon the latter. As a result, it looks at first 
 as if the method employed were as concrete as the earlier 
 method had been confessedly abstract. Organic evolution is 
 to afford the clue, and we are invited to consider carefully 
 what makes for the ' evolution of conduct '. It appears, how- 
 ever, that the ' last stages of evolution,' to which we must 
 hopefully look forward, mean practically the doing away 
 with that ' struggle for existence ' which has been recognised 
 hitherto as the very essence of organic evolution. In fact, 
 the author's cardinal principle, Justice — still defined as the 
 principle of non-interference, but now supposed to have an 
 evolutional origin — seems to imply the precise opposite of the 
 actual trend of Evolution ; for so long as there is any real 
 ' struggle for existence,' it is only too obvious that interference 
 of the ultimate kind is always present. 
 
 In truth, as we proceed further with the Data of Ethics and 
 the remaining parts of the Principles, it becomes more and 
 more evident that we are being conducted as directly as 
 possible to what practically amount to Mr. Spencer's earlier 
 ethical conclusions, not because these are the result of the 
 Evolutional method as applied to ethical problems, but rather 
 in spite of what Evolution itself would appear to dictate. The 
 four chapters devoted respectively to the ' Physical View,' 
 the ' Biological View,' the ' Psychological View,' and the 
 * Sociological View ' of morality, seem to have been intended 
 as a preliminary statement of the method adopted ; but we 
 have seen, in perhaps wearisome detail, how vulnerable this 
 ' scientific ' method is, and how elaborately it seems to have 
 been contrived to lead up to the desired results. 
 
 The one really important change in the Principles of Ethics, 
 so far as method is concerned, is the rejection of Intuition- 
 ism ; but the difference even in this respect is less than would 
 at first appear, for in the later chapters of Social Statics the 
 Moral Sense, originally taken as ultimate, had already been 
 reduced to a sort of ' instinct of personal rights,' which had 
 to be helped out by ' sympathy,' and to this latter assumption 
 Mr. Spencer really adheres to the end. According to the later
 
 Herbert Spencer. 355 
 
 and more elaborate, but hardly more convincing argument, 
 the general ' sentiment ' of Justice is developed much as 
 before, the factors being the so-called ' egoistic sentiment of 
 justice ' (i.e., the original ' instinct of personal rights ') and 
 * sympathy ' (this latter now being treated as derived, instead 
 of assumed as given). When sympathy has developed suffi- 
 ciently, the ' altruistic sentiment of justice ' will necessarily 
 develop as the counterpart of the ' egoistic sentiment of 
 justice ' ; and the implication would seem to be that the two 
 will eventually blend into a general ' sentiment of justice '. 
 
 So far, of course, the apprehension of Justice is confessedly 
 indefinite. Must we then give up the perfectly definite ' idea ' 
 of Justice, as opposed to the vague ' sentiment ' of the same 
 — that ' idea ' which was assumed in the earlier part of Social 
 Statics to be the one clear intuition of the Moral Sense? 
 By no means. After a satisfactory conclusion has once been 
 reached, Mr. Spencer is never greatly troubled with his re- 
 vised premises. And in this case, the short cut to the desired 
 conclusion is rather staggering, for apparently he argues 
 that men obtain the perfectly definite ' idea ' of Justice, still 
 expressed by the original formula, by experiencing the fact 
 that there are certain limits beyond which their fellows will 
 not, as a matter of fact, tolerate interference! From all 
 such difficulties the author may be depended upon to emerge 
 triumphant. After his strangely confused argument, he says, 
 in a passage previously quoted : " No higher warrant can be 
 imagined ; and now, accepting the law of equal freedom 
 as an ultimate ethical principle, having an authority transcend- 
 ing every other, we may proceed with our inquiry " }■ 
 
 All this is highly instructive. A reader unfamiliar with the 
 earlier form of Mr. Spencer's ethical system might well wonder 
 how it came about that a principle thus empirically derived, 
 and in such roundabout fashion, should straightway be treated, 
 to all intents and purposes, as a ' categorical imperative '. 
 The explanation is simple. Though this highly abstract 
 
 ^See yustice, ch. vii., § 35.
 
 356 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 principle of Justice is far from resulting from any legitimate 
 application of the theory of organic Evolution, it pointedly 
 illustrates the evolution of Mr. Spencer's own theory. Mani- 
 festly it is a survival from the ' pre-Evolutional,' Intuitional 
 form of the theory. But this is not all ; for its logical origin 
 we must go back further still. This emphatic assertion of the 
 rights of the individual as such was by no means a new doc- 
 trine, when set forth in Social Statics half a century ago ; 
 rather was it a definite and picturesque application of 
 eighteenth century Individualism, though carried to an extreme 
 that the average eighteenth century philosopher would pro- 
 bably have avoided. In fact, it seems to the present writer 
 that, in order to do Mr. Spencer justice, one must regard him 
 as the last great Individualist, in the eighteenth century sense 
 of the word, rather than as the true exponent of Evolutional 
 Ethics. 
 
 In the earlier form of the system, again, we found that, 
 while the principle of Justice was treated as an ultimate in- 
 tuition, the remaining principles of Ethics, Prudence, Negative 
 Beneficence, and Positive Beneficence, were apparently left to 
 be treated in the traditional Utilitarian fashion, depending 
 as they all do upon what the author regarded as the hopelessly 
 indefinite conception of happiness. In the later form of the 
 system, as given in the Principles of Ethics, this strange com- 
 bination of practical Intuitionism, as regards one ethical 
 principle, and Utilitarianism, as regards all the rest, is unmis- 
 takable. We have repeatedly seen that the author's absolute 
 principle of Justice by no means results from evolutionary con- 
 siderations. Now Mr. Spencer himself seems finally to have 
 conceded that Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence, 
 as defined by himself, are principles that must stand on their 
 own merits. In the passage already quoted from the Preface 
 to Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence, he admits : 
 " The Doctrine of Evolution has not furnished guidance to 
 the extent I had hoped. Most of the conclusions, drawn em- 
 pirically, are such as right feelings, enlightened by cultivated 
 intelligence, have already sufficed to establish."
 
 Herbert Spencer. 357 
 
 Since, then, these principles depend upon the variable 
 quantity, happiness, they are not at present susceptible of 
 exact scientific treatment ; and Mr. Spencer contents himself 
 almost wholly with practical counsels, instead of approaching 
 the problems involved from the point of view of systematic 
 Ethics. For the truly scientific treatment of these principles, 
 we must wait until the perfect society actually exists — a some- 
 what novel form of moral agnosticism, which must have been 
 anything but satisfactory to one with the most genuine moral 
 convictions, whose long-cherished, and indeed highest, am- 
 bition had been to place Ethics once for all upon a strictly 
 scientific foundation.
 
 CHAPTER XVI. 
 
 HENRY SIDGWICK. 
 
 Nearly a quarter of a century after Social Statics, but five 
 years before the Data of Ethics, appeared the first edition of 
 Professor Sidgwick's MetJiods of Ethics {1874). This was 
 early seen to be a work of very considerable importance, not 
 merely as an elaborate criticism of the various forms of ethical 
 theory recognised by the author, but as an independent contri- 
 bution to the literature of Utilitarianism ; and it is hardly 
 necessary to say that it has continued to be so regarded by 
 competent critics up to the present time. We shall therefore 
 be justified in treating it as the last authoritative utterance 
 of traditional Utilitarianism. 
 
 The purpose of the book may best be expressed in the 
 author's own words. In the Preface to the first edition he 
 says : " Its distinctive characteristics may be first given nega- 
 tively. It is not, in the main, metaphysical or psychological : 
 at the same time it is not dogmatic or directly practical ; it 
 does not deal, except by way of illustration, with the history 
 of ethical thought : in a sense it might be said to be not even 
 critical, since it is only quite incidentally that it offers any 
 criticism of the systems of individual moralists. It claims to 
 be an examination, at once expository and critical, of the 
 different methods of obtaining reasoned convictions as to what 
 ought to be done which are to be found — either exphcit or 
 implicit — in the moral consciousness of mankind generally : 
 and which, from time to time, have been developed, either 
 singly or in combination, by individual thinkers, and worked 
 up into the systems now historical." 
 
 (358)
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 359 
 
 Though the Methods of Ethics has been carefully revised 
 five times (the revised editions bearing the dates 1877, 1884, 
 1890, 1893, and 1 90 1 1), the author has never permitted him- 
 self to deviate from the programme which he first announced. 
 The titles of some chapters have been changed, and many 
 passages have been carefully rewritten, sometimes with the 
 implicit confession of a slight change of view regarding the 
 particular point at issue ; but the framework of the book 
 remains almost precisely what it was, even down to its minor 
 details, while by far the greater part of the treatment is 
 unchanged in essential respects. It is rather important to 
 keep this fact in mind, for the numerous references to current 
 ethical literature in the later editions of the Methods might 
 give the impression that the book in its present form had been 
 more recently planned and written than is actually the case. 
 In the following exposition and criticism, the text of the last 
 edition will be followed, except where notice is given to the 
 contrary ; but the treatment in the first edition will always be 
 kept in mind, and will be referred to when comparison seems 
 desirable. 
 
 It will readily be seen that Professor Sidgwick has under- 
 taken a most difficult task. Ostensibly critical, for the most 
 part, his treatment is almost bound to be implicitly constructive 
 from the very beginning, and this not from any mere bias 
 on his own part, but from the nature of the case. Abstracting, 
 as he purposely does, from the historical development of ethical 
 theory, he could not have attempted an answer to such ques- 
 tions as that of the number of possible ' Methods of Ethics,' and 
 
 1 The edition just published (igoi) represents Professor Sidgwick's final re- 
 vision of the work up to p. 276. The passages quoted from this edition in the 
 following chapters, however, are practically identical with the corresponding 
 ones in the fifth edition (1893). In the Preface to the last edition is printed, 
 from one of the author's manuscripts, a very condensed account of the develop- 
 ment of his ethical views down to the time of the publication of the first edition 
 of the Methods, showing what he owed successively to Mill, Kant, Butler, and 
 Aristotle, in working out his own system. It is interesting to know that the 
 valuable analysis of the morality of common sense (Bk. III., chaps, i.-xi.) was 
 the part of the book first written.
 
 360 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 the relation of these to " the moral consciousness of mankind 
 generally," with any hope of success, except from a somewhat 
 definite point of view of his own. For this reason we need 
 to see, in the first place, how the author, consciously or un- 
 consciously, defines his own position, particularly with re- 
 gard to the feeling of moral obligation and the related 
 problem as to the motive of the moral agent. 
 
 Traditional Intuitionism had consistently held that the feel- 
 ing of obligation was sui generis, not by any means to be reduced 
 to terms of anything else. Moreover, it had held that the 
 mere consciousness that an action was right or wrong could 
 in some way become a motive for performing it or abstaining 
 from it. Traditional Utilitarianism, on the other hand, had 
 always tended to regard the feeling of obligation as reducible 
 to terms of interest, though not in the sense of conscious 
 personal interest, operating at the moment of action. English 
 Utilitarians had generally attempted to explain this, hke so 
 many other phenomena of our moral life, by means of the 
 principles of ' association of ideas ' and ' translation '. This, 
 however, was not the strongest part of their argument. Their 
 truly characteristic position — which they regarded as unassail- 
 able, and from which their treatment of obligation was a sort 
 of corollary — was, of course, that no merely rational considera- 
 tions can move the agent to action, but only his own pleasur- 
 able or painful feelings. 
 
 So long as these contrary, if not, as they long seemed, 
 absolutely contradictory, doctrines were set forth in such ab- 
 stract terms, there could be little hope of an understanding. 
 Down to the time of J. S. Mill they may be said to have had 
 a practically independent, though parallel, development ; but 
 in Mill's ethical writings certain intuitional elements, or what 
 had previously passed for such, began to appear. The most 
 prominent, of course, was the author's insistence upon ' quali- 
 tative distinctions ' between pleasures. So flagrant an incon- 
 sistency as this could hardly prove a permanent influence in 
 the further development of Utilitarian theory ; but Mill did 
 much to make both his contemporaries and his successors
 
 Henry Sidgivick. 361 
 
 take account of the worth and meaning of human personahty 
 and regard self-development as practically an end in itself. 
 It thus became a question how far Utilitarianism could 
 rationalise these and other concrete aspects of the moral life, 
 which had at least been pointed out with considerable effect 
 by Intuitional writers. 
 
 But this was not all. We have seen that, in his earliest 
 important contribution to Ethics, his well-known essay on 
 Bentham (1838), Mill had complained that the elder moralist, 
 when he dismissed all ethical theories differing from his own as 
 ' vague generalities,' " did not heed, or rather the nature of his 
 mind prevented it from occurring to him, that these gener- 
 alities contained the whole unanalysed experience of the human 
 race ". The reference apparently was to certain supposed 
 moral intuitions, and the language of appreciation used was 
 certainly a novelty in the literature of Utilitarianism. Only 
 thirteen years later, Mr. Spencer published his Social Statics, 
 in which, while confessedly a Hedonist, in spite of his rejection 
 of the ' Expediency Philosophy ' of Bentham, he went so far 
 as to proclaim himself also an Intuitionist, though in a some- 
 what qualified sense. His position in this respect, though it 
 was one from which he retreated later, must be counted 
 among his early inconsistencies ; but the mere fact that mor- 
 alists representing such different tendencies as Mill and Mr. 
 Spencer should both have come so near to Intuitionism, was 
 not wholly a matter of chance. It was undoubtedly a sign of 
 the times, showing that the older Utilitarianism, admirably 
 consistent for the most part, but so abstract that it simply 
 failed to take account of much that was highly significant in 
 the moral life, was entering upon a new stage of development 
 
 Professor Sidgwick had far too logical a mind to combine 
 Intuitionism with Utilitarianism in this merely mechanical 
 way ; but his attitude toward the data of the moral life was, 
 from the first, similar in that he insisted upon certain aspects 
 of morality which the earlier Utilitarians had practically neg- 
 lected. Unlike Mill and Mr. Spencer, however, he seems 
 to have appreciated the difficulties of the task which he had
 
 362 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 undertaken. Probably it is not without significance that 
 chapter iii, of Book I. of the Methods of Ethics has successively 
 borne the titles " Moral Reason," " Reason and Feeling," and 
 " Ethical Judgments ". The more important changes, how- 
 ever, seem to have been made in the second edition (1877), 
 in the Preface to which the author says -. " Even before the 
 appearance of Mr. Leslie Stephen's interesting review in 
 /^r«J^r (March, 1875), I had seen the desirability of explaining 
 further my general view of the ' Practical Reason,' and of the 
 fundamental notions signified by the terms ' right,' ' ought,' 
 &c. With this object I have entirely rewritten chap. iii. of 
 Book I., and made considerable changes in chap, i." The 
 fact of these alterations is not mentioned with the purpose of 
 suggesting, that Professor Sidgwick has changed his mind in 
 any essential respect on the very important subject to which 
 this chapter is devoted ; but the difficulty which he has 
 found in satisfactorily expounding his views is worthy of 
 notice, for it is in this chapter that he first makes that serious 
 attempt to do justice to Intuitionism, which has so largely 
 determined the peculiar form of his own ethical theory. 
 
 The treatment in the first edition is very brief, and may be 
 indicated sufficiently for our present purpose in a few words. 
 The author points out that two difficulties are often raised 
 with regard to the conception of Practical Reason. " It is 
 maintained, first, that it is not by the Reason that we appre- 
 hend moral distinctions, but rather by virtue of some emotional 
 susceptibility commonly called a Aloral Sense ; and, secondly, 
 that the Reason cannot be a spring of action, as it must always 
 be Feeling that stimulates the Will." ^ As regards the first ob- 
 jection, that it is not by Reason that we apprehend moral 
 distinctions, the author indicates his own position quite clearly 
 as follows : " It seems, therefore, to belong to reason not 
 merely to judge of the relation of means to ends, or of the 
 consistency of maxims : but also to determine the ultimate 
 ends and true first principles of action " ? This might seem 
 like Intuitionism (or Intellectualism) pure and simple, but the 
 
 ^ See p. 22. ^ See p. 26.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 363 
 
 author holds that " such an intuitive operation of the practical 
 reason seems ... to be somewhere assumed in all moral 
 systems ". Earlier in the chapter he has argued that Hobbes 
 identifies Reason with Rational Self-love, Bentham with con- 
 duct calculated to conduce to ' the greatest happiness of the 
 greatest number,' etc.^ It will readily be seen that ' Reason ' 
 is here used in a sense by no means free from ambiguity. 
 
 As regards the second objection to the conception of ' Prac- 
 tical Reason,' viz., that Reason cannot itself be a spring of 
 action, the author suggests a characteristic compromise. After 
 stating that, in his opinion, it is needless to ask whether a 
 mere cognition can act upon will and prompt to action — since 
 " no one is competent or really concerned to maintain that the 
 apprehension of duty is a state of consciousness which occurs 
 without any emotional element " — he says : " It is enough if 
 it be granted that there exists in all moral agents as such 
 a permanent desire (varying, no doubt, very much in strength 
 from time to time, and in different persons) to do what is right 
 or reasonable because it is such "? As a note appears the 
 following altogether too liberal concession to Intuitionism. 
 " It can hardly be said that Intuitional Morahsts generally 
 have been disposed to over-estimate the actual force of the 
 practical reason. Certainly neither Clarke nor Kant have 
 fallen into this error." The author concludes : " We may 
 assume then as generally admitted that the recognition of any 
 action as reasonable is attended with a certain desire or im- 
 pulse to do it : and that in this sense the Reason may be 
 affirmed to be a spring of action ".^ All this, it must be remem- 
 bered, is supposed to represent not merely the author's own 
 point of view, but the concensus of opinion among moralists. 
 It is not strange that he found it necessary to state his position 
 more clearly. Moreover, in spite of the ambiguous use of 
 ' Reason,' referred to above, it is evident that the treatment 
 here given is already implicitly constructive, and concedes a 
 good deal more to Intuitionism than had been customary 
 among previous Utilitarian writers. 
 
 ^ See p. 23. 2 See p, 27, s gee p. 28.
 
 364 History of UtilitaHanisin. 
 
 As already indicated, the important changes in this chapter 
 were made in the second edition of the Methods (1877) ; but 
 for the sake of brevity, we shall turn at once to the latest 
 version (1901). Here * reasonable ' conduct is identified with 
 that which ' ought ' to be done ; ' non-rational ' conduct, there- 
 fore, being regarded as that which takes place in accordance 
 with mere desires and inclinations. Of course, the question at 
 once arises, whether this antithesis between ' reason ' and 
 ' desire ' is not a misapprehension, i.e., whether the conflict 
 is not after all a conflict between different desires and aver- 
 sions, " the sole function of reason being to bring before the 
 mind ideas of actual or possible facts, which modify . . . 
 the resultant force of our various impulses "} Now Professor 
 Sidgwick argues that this is not the case. The gist of the 
 whole chapter, in its revised form, is, that strictly moral judg- 
 ments are essentially different from any prudential judgments 
 whatsoever, and that therefore the notion of ' ought ' is in the 
 last resort irreducible to terms of anything else. 
 
 His own language on this very important matter should be 
 noted : " It seems then that the notion of ' ought ' or ' moral 
 obligation ' as used in our common moral judgments, does not 
 merely import (i) that there exists in the mind of the person 
 judging a specific emotion (whether complicated or not by 
 sympathetic representation of similar emotions in other 
 minds) ; nor (2) that certain rules of conduct are supported 
 by penalties which will follow on their violation (whether such 
 penalties result from the general liking or aversion felt for the 
 conduct prescribed or forbidden, or from some other source). 
 What, then, it may be asked, does it import? What defini- 
 tion can we give of ' ought,' * right,' and other terms expressing 
 the same fundamental notion ? To this I should answer that 
 the notion which these terms have in common is too elemen- 
 tary to admit of any formal definition." ^ 
 
 1 See p. 25. 
 
 2 See pp. 31, 32. In what follows the author explains that, when he speaks 
 of this notion as ultimate and unanalysable, he does not mean to rule out 
 mental development ; but only to insist that " as it now exists in our thought, [it] 
 cannot be resolved into any more simple notions ",
 
 Henry Sidgivick. 365 
 
 In this later version, as in that which appeared in the first 
 edition of the Methods, Professor Sidgwick refuses to admit 
 that he has made any concessions to Intuitionism as a differ- 
 entiated form of ethical theory. He says explicitly : " Nothing 
 that has been said ... is intended as an argument in favour 
 of Intuitionism, as against Utilitarianism or any other method 
 that treats moral rules as relative to General Good or Well- 
 being ". In fact, he holds that " the notion ' ought ' — as ex- 
 pressing the relation of rational judgment to non-rational 
 impulses — will find a place in the practical rules of any egoistic 
 system, no less than in the rules of ordinary morality, under- 
 stood as prescribing duty without reference to the agent's 
 interest ". And he adds : " According to my observation of 
 consciousness, the adoption of an end as paramount — either 
 absolutely or within certain limits — is quite a distinct psychi- 
 cal phenomenon from desire : it is a kind of volition, though it 
 is, of course, specifically different from a volition initiating a 
 particular immediate action ".^ 
 
 Such, in substance, is one of the four most significant 
 chapters in the Methods of Ethics, in its earliest and in its 
 latest form. Perhaps it may now be surmised why the 
 original title of the chapter, " Moral Reason," was changed, 
 first to " Reason and Feeling," and then to " Ethical Judg- 
 ments ". In the earlier treatment it was held that Reason (in 
 a sense not sufficiently defined) does determine ends, and par- 
 ticularly the ultimate end, in moral conduct ; and, moreover, 
 that it is as z/" reason were itself capable of affording a motive 
 to right conduct, though not necessarily the only one, since 
 " we may assume ... as generally admitted that the recog- 
 nition of any action as reasonable is attended with a certain 
 desire or impulse to do it ". Indeed, as we saw, the author 
 made the much too generous admission that " it can hardly be 
 said that Intuitional Moralists generally have been disposed 
 to over-estimate the actual force of the practical reason ". In 
 this earlier version of the chapter, then, the concession to 
 
 1 See pp. 35-37.
 
 366 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Intuitionism seems unmistakable, and the only reason why 
 it cannot be still more clearly proved is to be found in the 
 ambiguous use of the word ' reason,' to which we have already 
 referred. 
 
 Is this ambiguity cleared up in the later version ? It is 
 difficult to see that this is the case. As already indicated, the 
 greater part of the chapter is devoted to showing that the con- 
 ception of ' ought ' is irreducible to terms of anything else. 
 Not that this notion may not have been developed, like 
 all our others, but that it now has all the simplicity 
 which introspection would seem to show. And still the 
 claim is made that all this is not to be counted against 
 Utilitarianism, or even against Egoism. Evidently ' ought ' 
 is here used in a more general sense than that of ordinary 
 Intuitionism, but the author's absolute refusal to resolve 
 the conception of obligation, as had been done by all 
 the earlier English hedonists, at least down to the time of 
 J. S. Mill, is most significant ; while he plainly remains true to 
 his original position that, while it may not, perhaps, properly 
 be held that reason, apart from all feeling, can afford the moral 
 motive, it is nevertheless much as z/"this were the case, since 
 we nearly all desire, more or less strongly, to do that which 
 is reasonable merely because it is such — a position which at 
 least brings him mto a good deal closer relation to traditional 
 Intuitionism than to traditional Utilitarianism. 
 
 So much, then, concerning Professor Sidgwick's treatment 
 of " Moral Reason," as given in the first of what we have 
 ventured to call the four most significant ^ chapters of the 
 book. The others will be found to be -. chapter iv. of Book I., 
 which, in its latest as in its earliest form, bears the title, 
 " Pleasure and Desire " ; chapter vi., also of Book L, first 
 called " The Methods of Ethics," and later, " Ethical Principles 
 and Methods " ; and chapter xiii. of Book III., on " Philoso- 
 phical Intuitionism," which contains the most important part 
 of the author's proof of Utilitarianism. The chapter on 
 
 1 I.e., significant, as tending to define the author's own position.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 367 
 
 " Pleasure and Desire " has been a good deal less modified in 
 successive editions than the one which we have just examined, 
 and so can be considered rather more briefly, though it is 
 hardly less important as preparing us for the author's char- 
 acteristic treatment of Ethics. Evidently we here come to 
 close quarters with the problem as to what can constitute a 
 motive. We say ' can ' advisedly, for the psychological ques- 
 tion : What can constitute a motive ? is very properly treated 
 as logically preceding the question : What ought the motive 
 to be, if the action is to be truly moral ? 
 
 It will hardly be necessary to compare the earliest and the 
 latest versions of this chapter, since the gist of the argument 
 is the same in both. Perhaps it is worth noticing, however, 
 that the author was careless in the first edition, to the extent 
 of seriously misinterpreting Mill's theory of desire. After 
 quoting the well-known passage in the Utilitarianism, in which 
 Mill maintains that " desiring a thmg and finding it pleasant, 
 aversion to it and thinking of it as painful, are phenomena 
 entirely inseparable, or rather two parts of the same phenom- 
 enon," and further that " we desire a thing in proportion as 
 the idea of it is pleasant," the author says : " On this view 
 the notions ' right ' and ' wrong ' would seem to have no 
 meaning except as applied to the intellectual state accompany- 
 ing volition : since if future pleasures and pains be truly re- 
 presented, the desire must be directed towards its proper 
 object. And thus the only possible method of Ethics would 
 seem to be some form of Egoistic Hedonism."^ 
 
 This is the familiar mistake, now generally recognised as 
 such, of treating this problem too much in the abstract. It 
 may plausibly be urged that, if that motive is always followed 
 which appeals most strongly to oneself, then all motives are 
 on the same plane, i.e., equally selfish ; but the fallacy is not 
 far to seek. What attracts or repels depends very largely 
 upon the character of the particular moral agent, and char- 
 acters vary almost indefinitely. Psychologically the motives 
 
 ^ See p. 31.
 
 368 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 of Judas and his Master may have been ahke, in that they 
 were equally strong ; ethically, of course, they were as differ- 
 ent as the extremes of character which they represented. 
 In other words, so far from Mill's theory of desire necessarily 
 leading to Egoistic Hedonism, it is compatible with any degree 
 of altruism which, on other grounds, may be attributed to 
 human nature.^ 
 
 But the author is not really attacking a phantom. He seems 
 to confuse with Mill's theory of desire the very different posi- 
 tion of traditional Utilitarianism, which was, not merely that 
 " desiring a thing and finding it pleasant, aversion to it and 
 thinking of it as painful " are the same thing considered from 
 different points of view, but that ultimately only pleasure as 
 such can be desired, and con.sequently only the agent's own 
 pleasure. This is really the theory to a consideration of which 
 this chapter is principally devoted ; and it will be found that 
 the author's conclusions are not only in conflict with those 
 of the older Utilitarians, but come perilously near to carrying 
 him beyond Utilitarianism altogether. Neglecting other 
 differences of treatment in the earlier and the later editions, 
 which are immaterial, so far as the main argument is con- 
 cerned, we shall now confine ourselves to the latest version. 
 
 The point of departure is afforded by Butler's familiar 
 analysis of desire, which had been so strangely disregarded 
 by nearly all previous hedonistic writers. Butler, of course, 
 had held that particular passions or appetites are " necessarily 
 presupposed by the very idea of an interested pursuit ; since 
 the very idea of interest or happiness consists in this, that an] 
 appetite or affection enjoys its object ". After arguing that 
 Butler has over-stated his case — since pleasures of sight, hear- 
 ing, and smell, as well as many emotional pleasures, do not 
 seem to imply previous desires — Professor Sidgwick concedes 
 the essential point. He says : " But as a matter of fact, it ap- 
 pears to me that throughout the whole scale of my impulses, 
 sensual, emotional, and intellectual alike, I can distinguish 
 
 ^ Of course we are not here concerned with the question as to whether Mill's 
 theory was correct.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 369 
 
 desires of which the object is something other than my own 
 pleasure "} Of hunger, e.g., he gives practically the same 
 account as Butler had done. It is a direct impulse to the eating 
 of food. Of course, pleasure may be anticipated as a result of 
 the satisfaction of this craving, and such is very often the case ; 
 but there could be no pleasure of satisfaction, and therefore no 
 anticipation of such pleasure, were not the craving itself an 
 original, objective tendency. 
 
 The same line of argument would obviously apply to our 
 other so-called ' natural ' appetites and desires ; but, as a 
 matter of fact. Professor Sidgwick does not take the trouble 
 to develop the argument further in this direction. What he 
 does particularly insist upon is the fact that, in the case of the 
 so-called ' pleasures of pursuit,' which, as he remarks, " con- 
 stitute a considerable item in the total enjoyment of life," a 
 certain disinterestedness is always implied. One could not, 
 e.g., experience the pleasures of the chase, if one did not 
 for the time become objectively absorbed in it. In all such 
 cases — and they really include nearly all the so-called ' active ' 
 pleasures, mental as well as physical — self-conscious Epi- 
 cureanism would defeat its own end. Here, indeed, the par- 
 ticular end which is for the time disinterestedly, in the sense 
 of objectively, sought, is not organic to our nature like our 
 various original appetites. It may even be a thing as insignifi- 
 cant as success in some game which we play for a first and 
 only time. This might seem to constitute a very important 
 difference ; but the author would doubtless have explained, if 
 it had seemed to him necessary to explain anything so obvious,, 
 that the impulse to activity of some sort, whether physical or 
 mental, is as original as any of our bodily appetites. 
 
 Professor Sidgwick is rather more cautious than Butler in 
 employing this theory of the objective character of our pri- 
 mary desires to prove the possibility of disinterested action ; 
 but he pertinently urges, e.g., that " the much-commended 
 pleasures of benevolence seem to require, in order to be felt 
 
 ^ See p. 45. 
 
 24
 
 ^yo History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 in any considerable degree, the pre-existence of a desire to do 
 good to others for their sake and not for our own ". Of 
 course, arguments hke this are not intended to emphasise 
 the extra-regarding impulses at the expense of the self-regard- 
 ing ones. The two alternate with such rapidity that they often 
 seem to blend. But, so far as concerns what is actually in the 
 mind, Professor Sidgwick says : " A man's conscious desire is, 
 I think, more often than not chiefly extra-regarding ; but " — 
 as he is careful to add — " where there is strong desire in any 
 direction, there is commonly keen susceptibility to the corre- 
 sponding pleasures ; and the most devoted enthusiast is sus- 
 tained in his work by the recurrent consciousness of such 
 pleasures ")■ This seems to be a perfectly just analysis, as far 
 as it goes, and, as will be seen, it wholly avoids the confusion 
 which we had occasion to notice in the earlier version of the 
 first part of this chapter, where the author was arguing, as 
 against J. S. Mill's contention that " we desire a thing in pro- 
 portion as the idea of it is pleasant," that this would commit 
 one to Egoistic Hedonism. At the same time, this present 
 account of the matter shows that Mill's analysis of desire, like 
 that of his predecessors, was insufficient. 
 
 It will be seen, then, that Professor Sidgwick is as far as 
 possible from admitting, what appeared to most of the earlier 
 English Utilitarians so obviously true, that each can only 
 desire pleasure as such, and consequently only his own plea- 
 sure. In fact, he says : " Our conscious active impulses are 
 so far from being always directed towards the attainment of 
 pleasure or avoidance of pain for ourselves, that we can find 
 everywhere in consciousness extra-regarding impulses, directed 
 towards something that is not pleasure, nor relief from pain " - 
 The logic of all this is clear : there is, according to his view, 
 no theoretical difficulty in admitting a certain degree of 
 original altruism, if this seems necessary on other grounds. 
 As regards the traditional view of Associationism, that our 
 original impulses were all directed toward pleasure or from 
 
 ^ See pp. 50, 51. 2 See p. 52.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 371 
 
 pain, and that any impulse otherwise directed must be ex- 
 plained by the principles of ' association ' and ' translation/ 
 he says explicitly : " I can find no evidence that even tends to 
 prove this : so far as we can observe the consciousness of 
 children, the two elements, extra-regarding impulse and desire 
 for pleasure, seem to coexist in the same manner as they do 
 in mature life. In so far as there is any difference, it seems to 
 be in the opposite direction ; as the actions of children, being 
 more instinctive and less reflective, are more prompted by 
 extra-regarding impulse, and less by conscious aim at pleasure. 
 No doubt the two kinds of impulse, as we trace back the devel- 
 opment of consciousness, gradually become indistinguishable : 
 but this obviously does not justify us in identifying with either 
 of the two the more indefinite impulse out of which both have 
 been developed." ^ All this is most admirably expressed. 
 The abstractions of the older Associationist-Utilitarianism 
 have been left far behind ; we are beginning with what 
 practically amounts to Butler's analysis of desire. It remains 
 to be seen how far the author will commit himself to what 
 would appear to be the logical implications of this analysis. 
 After these discussions, the importance of which for the 
 constructive part of the book could not easily be exaggerated. 
 Professor Sidgwick takes up the ' freedom of the will,' in the 
 sense of indeterminism. Both sides of the argument are very 
 clearly and impartially presented. On the determinist side, 
 there is held to be " a cumulative argument of great force," 
 against which is to be set " the immediate affirmation of con- 
 sciousness in the moment of deliberate action " ; ^ and the two 
 seem to be regarded by the author as about equally convinc- 
 ing. It may seem a httle strange that the immediate verdict 
 of consciousness should be taken quite so seriously in a book, 
 the most prominent characteristic of which is a tendency 
 toward almost painfully rigorous analysis ; for, whatever may 
 be the merits of this wearisome controversy, it is plain that the 
 verdict of consciousness in this case is, after all, only a fact of 
 
 ^ See p. 53. "^ See pp. 62-65,
 
 372 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 consciousness, and one which may itself quite possibly be sus- 
 ceptible of explanation. 
 
 Perhaps it would be fair to regard this as one of Professor 
 Sidgwick's partly unconscious concessions to Intuitionism ; 
 but, on the whole, his attitude is most fortunate, for he is able 
 to show very clearly that one's decision in this matter does not 
 commit one for or against any recognised form of ethical 
 theory. Whether happiness or perfection be regarded as the 
 end of action, this end cannot properly be held to be either 
 more or less desirable because our actions are supposed to be 
 either free or determined. Certain theological problems, e.g., 
 that regarding * retributive justice,' are indeed involved ; but 
 it is far wiser not to entangle ourselves with such problems 
 in the present connection. And it is fair to add, what the 
 author does not happen to mention, that a developed theo- 
 logical system is almost sure to have quite as much trouble 
 with the conception of an absolute freedom of the will as with 
 determinism. 
 
 The ground having thus been cleared. Professor Sidgwick 
 proceeds at once, in Chapter vi., to an investigation of the 
 possible Methods of Ethics. Considering its very important 
 consequences, this preliminary discussion is much too brief, 
 occupying in fact only about twelve pages of the elaborate 
 treatise in its final form. In truth, it is rather necessary to 
 compare the latest version of this chapter with the one to be 
 found in the first edition of the Methods, in order fully to 
 understand how the author arrives at his conclusions, identical 
 in both and of the very greatest importance as determining 
 the whole method of treatment followed in the body of the 
 book. 
 
 Let us examine briefly the substance of the chapter in its 
 original form. As we have before had occasion to notice, the 
 prevailing motive in conscious action is not always an impulse 
 toward the attainment of pleasure or the avoidance of pain. 
 Among our disinterested motives " we may place the desire 
 to do what is right and reasonable as such, of which the char- 
 acteristic is that, as Butler says, it claims supremacy : i.e., that
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 2)Th 
 
 in so far as we are moral beings we think that it ought to 
 prevail, whether it does or not "} Now the methods of 
 systematising conduct that claim to be reasonable are limited 
 in number. In the first place, Happiness seems to be a reason- 
 able end ; but, if it be regarded as the ultimate end, the ques- 
 tion immediately arises : Whose happiness is to be assumed 
 as the ultimate end of action ? The author holds that there 
 are " two views and methods in which Happiness is regarded 
 as the ultimate and rational end of actions : in the one it is the 
 agent's happiness which is so regarded, in the other the happi- 
 ness of all men, or all sentient beings ". Of course it would 
 be possible to adopt an intermediate position, and regard the 
 happiness of some limited portion of mankind as the end, 
 but such a limitation would plainly be arbitrary. So much for 
 Happiness ; but Perfection or Excellence is also thought a 
 rational end, and may be regarded as an end in itself. And, 
 as in the case of happiness, the perfection aimed at may be 
 either individual or universal, though in actual systems of 
 Ethics one's own perfection seems to be the ideal presented. 
 Moreover, it is a common opinion that a great part of truly 
 moral action is done merely because it is right or good, because 
 duty so dictates. This is what is commonly called the In- 
 tuitional theory of morals. 
 
 It may at first appear that this list is not exhaustive. Many 
 religious persons, e.g., regard the Will of God as the highest 
 reason for acting in a given way, while philosophical schools 
 which are at least historically important have advanced the 
 principle of ' living according to Nature ' as the true ultimate. 
 At first these principles may seem distinct from those above 
 mentioned ; but further examination will show that they either 
 lie beyond the scope of this inquiry, or that they resolve them- 
 selves into the others — or perhaps into a confused blending 
 of two or more of these. While fully admitting the difficulties 
 inevitably encountered, when such classifications are attempted, 
 the author says : " In the meantime the list of first principles 
 
 ' See pp. 58 et seq. Note the concession to Intuitionism. This passage does 
 not occur in later versions.
 
 374 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 already given seems to include all that have a primd facie 
 claim to be included : and to afford the most convenient 
 classification for the current modes of determining right con- 
 duct. At the same time I do not wish to lay stress on the 
 completeness or adequacy of the classification. I do not pro- 
 fess to prove a priori that there are these practical first prin- 
 ciples and no more. They have been taken merely empirically 
 from observation of the moral reasoning of myself and other 
 men, whether professed moralists .or not : and though it seems 
 to me improbable that I have overlooked any important phase 
 or point of view, it is always possible that I may have done 
 so." 1 
 
 Let us inspect a httle more carefully our proposed classifi- 
 cation. When Perfection is taken as the end of action, the 
 agent's own perfection seems nearly always to be what is 
 meant, and, moreover, this is commonly understood as moral 
 perfection. But what is to be the test of such perfection ? 
 One seems almost inevitably to be thrown back upon intuitive 
 moral judgments, so that this method may properly be taken 
 as a form of Intuitionism. On the other hand, if we conceive 
 Happiness to be the end, it is necessary to distinguish very 
 sharply between Egoism and Utilitarianism {i.e., Universalistic 
 Hedonism). This, it should be remembered, is one of the 
 author's fundamental positions. Speaking of the tendency to 
 confuse the two forms of hedonistic theory, he says : " Such 
 a rapprochement encourages a serious misapprehension of 
 both the historical and the philosophical relations of these 
 methods to the Intuitional or Common-Sense Morality ".^ 
 
 Indeed, as he goes on to urge, the distinction between one's 
 own happiness and that of people in general is so natural and 
 obvious, and so continually forced upon us by the circum- 
 stances of life, that we must look for some good reason for the 
 persistent confusion between the two which we so commonly 
 find. " And," he adds, " such a reason is found in the theory 
 of human action held by Bentham (and generally speaking by 
 
 ^ See pp. 64, 65. 
 
 ^As we shall see later, this statement requires considerable modification.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 375 
 
 his disciples), which has been discussed in a previous chapter. 
 Though ethically Epicureanism and Benthamism may be 
 viewed as standing in polar opposition, psychologically Ben- 
 tham is in fundamental agreement with Epicureans. He 
 holds that a man ought to aim at the maximum felicity of men 
 in general ; but he holds, also, that he always does aim at 
 what appears to him his own maximum felicity — that he 
 cannot help doing this — that this is the way his volition in- 
 evitably acts." 1 
 
 The above almost literal reproduction of the substance of 
 this chapter in its original form has seemed desirable, first, 
 because the first edition of the Methods is not, of course, 
 readily accessible to most readers, and secondly, because this 
 earliest version shows exactly how the author came to classify 
 the Methods of Ethics as he has once for all done. Before 
 criticising this classification, it is important to note certain 
 differences in the latest version, published twenty-seven years 
 afterward (1901).^ One modification had long before become 
 necessary. Some reference, at least, had to be made to the 
 principle of Self-realisation as affording a possible Method 
 of Ethics, for this had actually become one of the most impor- 
 tant ' methods ' in the hands of contemporary ethical writers. 
 Curiously enough, however, this principle is hardly more than 
 mentioned in the later form of the present chapter, in which 
 the author explains and defends his own classification. Practi- 
 cally the only reference to it is to be found in the revised 
 form of the passage in which ' God's Will ' and ' living accord- 
 ing to Nature ' are considered only to be rejected, as prin- 
 ciples not deserving the position of separate Methods of 
 Ethics. 
 
 Professor Sidgwick says : " Many religious persons think 
 that the highest reason for doing anything is that it is God's 
 Will : while to others ' Self-realisation ' or ' Self-development,' 
 and to others, again, ' Life according to Nature ' appear the 
 
 1 See p. 67. 
 
 2 The latest version is not essentially different from some which preceded it, 
 but is referred to here as indicating the author's final position.
 
 376 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 really ultimate ends ". But he almost immediately adds : 
 " God, Nature, Self, are the fundamental facts of existence ; 
 the knowledge of what will accomplish God's Will, what is 
 ' according to Nature,' what will realise the true Self in each of 
 us, would seem to solve the deepest problems of Metaphysics 
 as well as of Ethics. But just because these notions combine 
 the ideal with the actual, their proper sphere belongs not to 
 Ethics as I define it, but to Philosophy — the central and 
 supreme study which is concerned with the relations of all 
 objects of knowledge." ^ 
 
 There follows a further examination of the conceptions of 
 ' conformity to God's Will ' and ' life according to Nature,' as 
 affording guides for conduct ; but we are informed in a note, 
 that the notion of ' Self-realisation ' will more conveniently 
 be considered in the following chapter, which is devoted to 
 an examination of Egoism. It will thus be seen that, at the 
 crucial point of the discussion, where the author is once for all 
 deciding what shall be regarded as the typical Methods of 
 Ethics, the issue with Self-realisation is avoided rather than 
 met. This would be very difficult to understand, if we were 
 not able to refer back to the earliest version of this chapter 
 (1874), where the author quite naturally overlooked the signifi- 
 cance of this possible method,^ which, if taken seriously, 
 tends so materially to discredit the classification here adopted. 
 But, even so, it is rather puzzling to find that, while the earliest 
 form of this chapter represented the classification of ethical 
 methods adopted as tentative rather than as logically complete 
 and final, the later versions are much more dogmatic in tone, 
 and do not appear to suggest any doubt as to the complete 
 adequacy of the classification. Perhaps it became evident to 
 Professor Sidgwick himself, that, if the classification should 
 prove seriously defective, this would have to be regarded as 
 very seriously detracting from the validity of the results ob- 
 tained ; for, as we shall soon see, given the classification, the 
 results are almost a foregone conclusion. 
 
 ^ See p. 79. 
 
 2 It will be remembered that Bradley's Ethical Studies, e.g., was published 
 two years later.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 2>ll 
 
 But, before we venture to criticise this classification further, 
 it will be well to avoid possible misconceptions by noticing 
 certain additional explanations of the terms Egoism and In- 
 tuitionism, as here used, which will be found in the conclud- 
 ing chapters of Book I. And, as before indicated, under the 
 discussion of Egoism we shall find the author's further, and 
 final, explanation of his refusal to recognise Self-realisation 
 as an independent Method of Ethics. Neglecting the order of 
 exposition, we may first notice that what is here said of In- 
 tuitionism, though admirably clear and to the point, as far as 
 it goes, does not really add much to our understanding of the 
 author's position. He very properly suggests that we must 
 distinguish three forms of Intuitionism : (i) the 'ultra-intui- 
 tional ' view, which " recognises simple immediate intuitions 
 alone [referring to the particular act in question] and discards 
 as superfluous all modes of reasoning to moral conclusions " ; 
 (2) the ordinary intuitional view, " of which the fundamental 
 assumption is that we can discern certain general rules with 
 really clear and finally valid intuition " ; and (3) what may be 
 called Philosophical, as opposed to Perceptional or Dogmatic, 
 Intuitionism — i.e., the form of Intuitionism which, " while ac- 
 cepting the morality of common sense as in the main sound, 
 still attempts to find for it a philosophic basis which it does 
 not itself offer : to get one or more principles more absolutely 
 and undeniably true and evident, from which the current rules 
 might be deduced, either just as they are commonly received 
 or with slight modifications and rectifications ".^ 
 
 It is to be observed, that no further attempt is here made 
 to show that systems which regard Perfection as the end 
 necessarily come under the head of Intuitionism. If, as the 
 author has previously assumed, the ' perfection ' meant is 
 merely ' moral perfection,' no objection can well be made ; 
 but if, as certain later passages in the book would seem to in- 
 dicate, the principle of Self-realisation is regarded as one form 
 of the perfection doctrine, it will readily be seen that the 
 classification is, in this respect, rather seriously misleading. 
 
 ^ See pp. 100-102.
 
 378 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 As already indicated, however, the only further reference 
 made to Self-realisation, in the chapters which we are consider- 
 ing occurs in the discussion as to the precise meaning of 
 Egoism. The chapter devoted to this discussion we shall now 
 briefly examine. One possible ambiguity in the use of the 
 term Egoism would be almost sure to suggest itself. Egoism 
 might stand for ' self-preservation ' as well as for the consistent 
 pursuit of one's own happiness. In fact, it is often self-pre- 
 servation rather than pleasure that Hobbes appears to have 
 in mind in the development of his system. Professor Sidgwick 
 does not, however, point out that there is also a possible 
 ambiguity in the use of ' self-preservation ' ; but rather im- 
 mediately remarks that " in Spinoza's view the principle of 
 rational action is necessarily egoistic, and is (as with Hobbes) 
 the impulse of self-preservation ". By itself this would be 
 seriously misleading, but the author himself adds : " Still it is 
 not at Pleasure that the impulse primarily aims, but at the 
 mind's Perfection or Reality : as we should now say, at Self- 
 realisation or Self-development ".^ 
 
 Even if this were all that needed to be said on this point, 
 it would be evident that ' self-preservation ' in this sense is 
 by no means the equivalent of * egoism,' as ordinarily under- 
 stood, for the realisation of an ideal self is plainly something 
 very different from the satisfaction of what may be called 
 one's ' empirical self,' with all its peculiarities and even per- 
 verted tendencies. Moreover, if allied with any metaphysical 
 theory, Egoism, in the strict sense, could only go with one 
 which should regard the individual being as, at least practi- 
 cally, a metaphysical ultimate ; whereas it is only too evident 
 that, in Spinoza's system, the individual as such is only a 
 passing phase or manifestation of the Universal Substance. 
 
 But, neglecting this historical reference, which can hardly 
 be regarded as fortunate, let us consider the author's final 
 reason for neglecting Self-realisation as a separate Method of 
 Ethics. He says : " It may be said, however, that we do not, 
 
 ^ See p. 90. 
 
 I
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 379 
 
 properly speaking, ' develop ' or ' realise ' self by yielding to 
 the impulse which happens to be predominant in us ;^ but by 
 exercising, each in its due place and proper degree, all the 
 different faculties, capacities, and propensities, of which our 
 nature is made up. But here there is an important ambiguity. 
 What do we mean by ' due proportion and proper degree ' ? 
 These terms may imply an ideal, into conformity with which 
 the individual mind has to be trained, by restraining some of 
 its natural impulses and strengthening others, and developing 
 its higher faculties rather than its lower : or they may merely 
 refer to the original combination and proportion of tendencies 
 in the character with which each is born. . . . According to the 
 former interpretation rational Self-development is merely an- 
 other term for the pursuit of Perfection for oneself : while 
 in the latter sense it hardly appears that Self-development 
 (when clearly distinguished) is really put forward as an abso- 
 lute end, but rather as a means to happiness." ^ Hence the 
 author concludes that, on the whole, " the notion of Self- 
 realisation is to be avoided in a treatise on ethical method, 
 on account of its indefiniteness ". 
 
 It is doubtless true, that writers standing for the Self- 
 realisation theory have often laid themselves open to the 
 charge of indefiniteness in their treatment of ethical problems ; 
 but it is only fair to say, that neither of the two interpretations 
 of the principle of Self-realisation which Professor Sidgwick 
 here allows could be admitted as adequately characterising 
 the method, even when somewhat carelessly employed. The 
 second of the supposed alternatives may, of course, be dis- 
 missed at once. No ethical writer worthy of consideration 
 has held that the ' due proportion and proper degree ' of 
 development of the various sides of our nature " merely refer 
 to the original combination and proportion of tendencies in 
 the character with which each is bom ". 
 
 On the other hand, it is rather misleading merely to speak 
 in general terms of " an ideal, into conformity with which 
 
 ^ See p. gi.
 
 380 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 the individual mind has to be trained, by restraining some of 
 its natural impulses and strengthening others, and developing 
 its higher faculties rather than its lower," for this is adopting 
 precisely the language of ordinary Intuitionism rather than 
 that of Self-realisation. ' Higher ' and ' lower ' are, indeed, 
 conceptions which exist for Self-realisation, as for all other 
 recognised Methods of Ethics ; ^ but they are by no means 
 necessarily regarded by the moralist of that school as in- 
 tuitive ultimates. On the contrary, they are supposed to be 
 explainable in terms of the more or less complete ; moreover, 
 the Self which is to be developed is, of course, a social or 
 ideal self, with all the implications which this involves, and 
 not merely what we have just ventured to call the ' empirical 
 self,' which latter is obviously the result of heredity and en- 
 vironment in each particular case. It is hardly necessary 
 to say that no attempt is here made to explain, much less 
 to vindicate, the Self-realisation theory. I would merely sug- 
 gest that, even in the last edition of the Methods, it is not 
 stated in terms that could be accepted by its supporters. 
 
 Professor Sidgwick concludes this discussion as follows : 
 " To sum up. Egoism, if we merely understand by it a method 
 that aims at Self-realisation, seems to be a form into which 
 almost any ethical system may be thrown, without modifying 
 its essential characteristics. And even when further defined 
 as Egoistic Hedonism, it is still imperfectly distinguishable 
 from Intuitionism if quality of pleasures is admitted as a con- 
 sideration distinct from and overruling quantity. There 
 remains then Pure or Quantitative Egoistic Hedonism, which, 
 as a method essentially distinct from all others and widely 
 maintained to be rational, seems to deserve a detailed 
 examination." .^ 
 
 ^ Of course the hedonist recognises th.Q prima facie distinction between ' higher ' 
 
 and ' lower,' but explains it in his own way.
 
 CHAPTER XVIL 
 
 HENRY SIDGWICK (continued). 
 
 After these careful, if also somewhat tedious preliminaries, 
 we are at length in a position to appreciate the exact signifi- 
 cance of the author's classification, upon which so much 
 depends. It is hardly necessary to say more at present re- 
 garding his failure to recognise Self-realisation as one of the 
 Methods of Ethics. Such an omission would hardly be pos- 
 sible in a recent ethical treatise ; but we are always to re- 
 member that Professor Sidgwick has strictly adhered to the 
 lines laid down in the first edition of the Methods (1874), 
 which, to mention only two significant dates, was published 
 two years before Bradley's Ethical Studies (1876) and nine 
 years before Green's Prolegomena to Ethics (1883). Neglect- 
 ing, then, what would otherwise seem so strange an omission, 
 and confining ourselves to the classification as actually given 
 in all editions of the Methods, we shall do well to scrutinise 
 this classification somewhat carefully before we proceed. 
 
 We find what purport to be three distinct Methods of Ethics, 
 Egoism (or Egoistic Hedonism), Intuitionism, and Utilitarian- 
 ism (or Universalistic Hedonism) ; and the implication, at 
 least in the later editions of the Methods, would seem to be 
 that this division must be regarded as exhaustive. No ob- 
 jection, of course, could possibly be made to regarding Intui- 
 tionism as a separate Method of Ethics ; but it is the author's 
 peculiar view, that what he terms Egoism is even more dis- 
 tinct from Intuitionism and Utilitarianism than these are from 
 each other. In fact, it is largely by emphasising the antithesis 
 between Egoistic Hedonism and Universalistic Hedonism, 
 
 (381)
 
 382 Histoiy of Utilitarianism. 
 
 that he is able to show what he conceives to be the com- 
 paratively close relation between Universalistic Hedonism and 
 Intuitionism. 
 
 But a very serious objection at once presents itself. Is 
 Egoism a Method of Ethics at all, even according to the 
 author's carefully formulated definitions ? There is, indeed, 
 no question that many English moralists, from the time of 
 Hobbes down at least to the time of J. S. Mill, held that the 
 motive of the moral agent was necessarily egoistic ; and 
 nobody held this view more strongly than Bentham himself, 
 as Professor Sidgwick candidly admits. If, then, all were to 
 be classed as Egoists who held this theory of the moral motive, 
 we should plainly have to include all the English Utilitarians 
 before Mill, with the exception of Cumberland, Hartley, and 
 Hume {i.e., as represented by the second form of his theory). 
 In truth, we should have to go much further than this, and 
 include other moralists wholly outside the Utilitarian school, 
 for the selfish theory of the moral motive was a natural result 
 of eighteenth century individualism. Even the greatest of 
 English moralists, Butler himself, would not wholly escape, 
 according to Professor Sidgwick's interpretation of his doc- 
 trine, for he elsewhere says : " It is by no means Butler's 
 view (as is very commonly supposed) that self-love is naturally 
 subordinate to conscience. . . . He treats them as independent 
 principles, and so far co-ordinate in authority that it is not 
 ' according to nature ' that either should be over-ruled. . . . He 
 even goes so far as to ' let it be allowed ' that ' if there 
 ever should be, as it is impossible there ever should be, any in- 
 consistence between them,' conscience would have to give way."^ 
 
 Plainly, then, the egoistic theory of the moral motive cannot 
 be what Professor Sidgwick means, when he speaks of Egoism 
 as constituting a separate Method of Ethics. A ' Method of 
 Ethics,' as clearly indicated in the Preface to the first edition, 
 is one of " the different methods of obtaining reasoned con- 
 victions as to what ought to be done which are to be found — 
 either explicit or implicit — in the moral consciousness of man- 
 
 ^ See History of Ethics, pp. 194, 195.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 383 
 
 kind generally: and which, from time to time, have been 
 developed, either singly or in combination, by individual 
 thinkers, and worked up into the systems now historical ". 
 Now it may confidently be maintained that not one of the 
 many moralists referred to above, as holding or seeming to 
 hold the egoistic theory of the moral motive, ever so much 
 as suggested that one could obtain " reasoned convictions 
 as to what ought to be done " by merely computing what 
 would bring the most pleasure to one's self. It was character- 
 istic of the essential dualism of their general view of Ethics 
 to consider the subjective end of action, or the motive of tlie 
 moral agent, quite apart from the objective end, or standard of 
 whatever sort, which was supposed to determine the morality 
 of human actions. Even Hobbes, the arch-egoist, according 
 to the ordinary conception of Egoism, was no exception, for 
 he explicitly held that those things are ' right ' or ' wrong ' 
 which are declared to be such by the constituted civil autho- 
 rity ; and perhaps no English moralist would have been more 
 averse to having the individual decide for himself what was 
 * right * or ' wrong ' on the basis of a deliberate computation 
 of his private chances of happiness. 
 
 Who, then, is the Egoist intended .'* It would not do to 
 urge that certain depraved characters do, as a matter of fact, 
 appear to seek their own happiness regardless of all else ; for, 
 even when free rein is given to the self-seeking impulse, it 
 is apparently never claimed by the agent himself that a ^iven 
 action is to be regarded as moral, on general principles, merely 
 because it promises to conduce to his own selfish pleasure, ^ 
 though, of course, his moral judgments in particular cases may 
 be fatally warped by selfish considerations. Moreover, it is 
 wholly needless to point out that Egoism is used by the author, 
 not by any means as a term of reproach, but as a convenient 
 designation for what he conceives to be one of the three pos- 
 sible Methods of Ethics. All this is puzzling in a writer so 
 logical, for the most part, as Professor Sidgwick. One can 
 
 ^This would be too flagrant a contradiction even for the immoral con- 
 sciousness.
 
 384 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 only conclude that, in his very serious, and largely successful, 
 attempt to differentiate the modern form of Utilitarianism, 
 for which he himself stands, from the older form which based 
 upon the assumed necessary egoism of the moral agent, he 
 has unconsciously developed, in what he terms Egoism, the 
 conception of a form of hedonistic theory which in reality has 
 never existed in Modern Ethics, and which never could exist 
 as a ' Method of Ethics,' if by this we are to understand a 
 method of " obtaining reasoned convictions as to what ought 
 to be done ". 
 
 It would almost seem that Professor Sidgwick wished to 
 forestall this criticism in a passage which appeared for the 
 first time in the fifth edition of the Methods (1893). This is 
 at the beginning of Book II., which is devoted to an examina- 
 tion of the ' method ' of Egoism. In the first four editions of 
 the treatise, he seems to have suspected no difficulty, for he 
 had said : " It is, perhaps, a sufficient reason for considering 
 this \i.e., Egoism] first of the three systems ^ with which this 
 treatise is principally concerned, that there seems to be more 
 general agreement among reflective persons as to the reason- 
 ableness of its fundamental principle, than exists in the case 
 either of Intuitionism or of that Universalistic Hedonism 
 to which I propose to restrict the name of Utilitarianism ".^ 
 On the other hand, the passage referred to above, as having 
 first appeared in the fifth edition, reads as follows : " It may be 
 doubted whether this {i.e.. Egoism] ought to be included 
 among received ' methods of Ethics ' ; since there are strong 
 grounds for holding that a system of morality, satisfactory to 
 the moral consciousness of mankind in general, cannot be 
 constructed on the basis of simple Egoism. In subsequent 
 chapters I shall carefully discuss these reasons .- at present it 
 seems sufficient to say — ^what will hardly be denied — that no 
 principle of conduct is more widely accepted than the pro- 
 position that it is reasonable for a man to act in the manner 
 most conducive to his own happiness." ^ Then, as in all 
 
 ^ ' Methods ' in fourth edition. 
 
 * See p. 107 (first edition). ' See p. 119 (fifth edition).
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 385 
 
 previous editions, he goes on to show that ethical writers as 
 different as Bentham, Butler, Clarke, and Berkeley, ahke, 
 though in somewhat different terms, concede the ultimate 
 reasonableness of acting for one's own happiness. 
 
 But if the object of this belated passage really was to fore- 
 stall the very serious criticism, that the first of the author's 
 three Methods of Ethics is not a ' method ' of Ethics at all, 
 it is not difficult to show that it wholly fails in its purpose. 
 With all respect to Professor Sidgwick, one must submit that 
 it is by no means sufficient to point out that " no principle of 
 conduct is more widely accepted than the proposition that it 
 is reasonable for a man to act in the manner most conducive 
 to his own happiness ". In truth, there is a double ambiguity 
 here. Does ' reasonable,' as here used, mean ' reasonable, 
 other things being equal ' or ' ultimately reasonable ' ? If 
 the former, the principle is indeed generally admitted by those 
 who admit the claims of happiness at all, but it is irrelevant 
 in a discussion with regard to what mode of conduct is ' ulti- 
 mately reasonable '. Again, if ' ultimately reasonable ' is what 
 is meant, it becomes extremely important to know in what 
 sense acting for one's own happiness is to be so regarded. 
 
 It proves altogether too much to refer to the concessions of 
 Bentham, Butler, Clarke, and Berkeley on this point. Each 
 of the first three, at any rate, had a method different from that 
 of either of the others for determining the rightness or wrong- 
 ness of actions ; but all, being alike of the eighteenth century,,, 
 were inclined to admit that it must be for the agent's selfish 
 interest to be moral. So we are brought back to the selfish 
 theory of the moral motive, which, as we have already seen, 
 and as this mention of Bentham, Butler, Clarke, and Berkeley 
 aptly illustrates, cannot by itself possibly be regarded as 
 affording the basis for a separate Method of Ethics. In a 
 word, while many of the older English moralists, otherwise 
 representing the most diverse tendencies, held the ego- 
 istic theory of the moral motive, or at least used language 
 that would permit of that interpretation, not one of them ever 
 claimed, or so much as suggested, that one could determine 
 
 25
 
 386 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 the morality of actions by computing one's private chances of 
 happiness. 
 
 In fact, a careful reading of Book II., on " Egoism," in any 
 one of the slightly differing versions, will show that what is 
 really considered is the practicability of ordering one's life on 
 the principle of Egoistic Hedonism, not whether morality 
 itself can be rationalised by the application of that principle. 
 It is hardly necessary to say that the method of treatment, in 
 this respect, differs very materially from that employed in 
 Book III., on " Intuitionism," and in Book IV., on " Utili- 
 tarianism ". Still, the substance of Book II. is by no means 
 unimportant, for it is here that Professor Sidgwick first con- 
 siders in detail both the implications and the real or supposed 
 difficulties of Hedonism in general. Indeed, it will be found, 
 in many cases, that important problems connected with He- 
 donism are discussed only in this book. 
 
 The fundamental assumption of Hedonism as such is shown 
 to be ' the commensurability of pleasures and pains '.^ Un- 
 less a more or less definite quantitative comparison be possible, 
 it is plain that both Egoism and Utilitarianism must be re- 
 jected as impracticable methods. It is sometimes claimed 
 that certain pleasures and pains are so intense that any com- 
 parison between them and others is out of the question, but 
 this particular objection to the hedonistic calculus can hardly 
 be sustained. We commonly assume that " all the pleasures 
 and pains that man can experience bear a finite ratio to each 
 other in respect of pleasantness and its opposite ". This idea 
 of an arrangement of pleasures and pains in a scale, as greater 
 or less in some finite degree, might seem to involve the as- 
 sumption of a ' hedonistic zero,' or perfectly neutral feeling. 
 It is not necessary to decide whether this strictly neutral 
 feeling ever occurs ; but it is worth noticing that a state 
 very nearly approximating to this is even common. At the 
 same time this fact would not seem to present any special 
 
 ^ See pp. 123 et seq.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 387 
 
 difficulty. The celebrated dictum of Epicurus, that the state 
 of painlessness is equivalent to the highest possible pleasure, 
 is too paradoxical to require definite refutation. 
 
 The first real difficulty occurs, when we try to define pleas- 
 ure and pain for purposes of quantitative comparison. Mr. 
 Spencer defines pleasure as " a feeling which we seek to bring 
 into consciousness and retain there " ; but, while adequate for 
 purposes of distinction, this definition is hardly appropriate 
 for purposes of quantitative comparison, since it can hardly 
 be held that pleasures are greater or less, exactly in proportion 
 as they exercise more or less influence in stimulating the will 
 to actions tending to sustain or produce them.^ For the 
 present purpose, it will be convenient to define pleasure as 
 " feeling which, when experienced by intelligent beings, is at 
 least implicitly apprehended as desirable or — in cases of com- 
 parison — preferable ". As regards the old problem concerning 
 the so-called ' qualitative distinctions ' between pleasures, we 
 may fairly conclude that, " when one kind of pleasure is 
 judged to be qualitatively superior to another, although less 
 pleasant, it is not really the feeling itself that is preferred, but 
 something in the objective conditions under which it arises " ; 
 for it seems impossible to find in feeling as such any other 
 preferable quality than that which we call ' pleasantness '.^ 
 
 After this admirably clear statement of the general aspects 
 of the problem, Professor Sidgwick proceeds to examine care- 
 fully and most impartially certain of the more common ob- 
 jections to the hedonistic calculus. It is impossible here to 
 go into details ; but, on the whole, it must be conceded that he 
 allows to the objections mentioned fully as much weight as 
 they deserve. Unfortunately, however, he does not consider 
 the objection which Mr. Spencer had urged with such force in 
 Social Statics (1851), viz., that the hedonistic calculus is im- 
 possible, because there would necessarily be an important 
 shifting of the scale of hedonic values with every stage 
 of intellectual or moral progress (or decadence), whether on 
 the part of the individual, the community, the nation, or the 
 
 ^ See p. 126. 2 ggg p J29.
 
 388 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 race.^ In the opinion of the present writer, this is the one 
 really fatal objection to the hedonistic calculus. And it will 
 be seen to have an important theoretical, as well as practical, 
 bearing ; for if the assumed ultimate, happiness, be found 
 to vary in proportion as something else varies, external 
 conditions remaining the same, there is at least a very strong 
 presumption that it may prove not to be the true ultimate 
 after all. 
 
 On the other hand, altogether too much weight seems 
 generally to have been attached to the objection, that the 
 quantitative comparison of particular pleasures and pains can- 
 not be carried to the point of scientific precision ; for the com- 
 parison actually attempted nearly always is, not between 
 particular pleasures and pains, but between the pleasurable 
 or painful results of certain classes of actions, where the 
 known actual preferences of ourselves and others are at least 
 of considerable assistance. The difficulties involved in such a 
 comparison are, indeed, very serious from any point of view ; 
 but they would not necessarily be unsurmountable, if it were 
 not for the inevitable shifting of the scale of hedonic values 
 referred to above. In truth, as we had occasion to notice 
 in a previous chapter, the question of more or less, whole or 
 part, is one which arises not only in connection with the 
 hedonistic calculus, but for any method of Ethics which seri- 
 ously attempts to explain how we are to determine the right- 
 ness or wrongness of particular classes of actions. Otherwise 
 expressed, this difficulty is practical before it is theoretical ; 
 for the moment we transcend the crudest form of Intuition- 
 ism, which refuses to go beyond what is conceived to be the 
 infallible verdict of ' conscience ' in each individual case, we 
 discover that the regulation of conduct must depend upon a 
 comparison of values, extrinsic or intrinsic, which, from the 
 very nature of the case, can never become mathematically 
 exact. 
 
 ^ It will be noted that this is a somewhat free rendering of Mr. Spencer's 
 objection, but the attempt has been made to state it in its most comprehensive 
 form.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 389 
 
 The final chapter of Book II., originally called " Other 
 Forms of the Egoistic Method," then " Other Methods of 
 Egoistic Hedonism," and finally, " Deductive Hedonism," has 
 been considerably changed since it first appeared ; but the 
 modifications are not of a kind to detain us. What the author 
 has throughout been concerned to prove is, that no hedonistic 
 method is in the last resort able to dispense with the hedonistic 
 calculus. In the first edition it was clearly shown that, though 
 Mr. Spencer had objected so strongly to the hedonistic cal- 
 culus, he had in reality by no means supplied a deductive 
 method which would take its place, and, moreover, that the 
 other less ambitious indirect methods of determining what 
 will make for happiness or its contrary are too vague to be 
 of much practical assistance. In the later form of the chapter, 
 ' Scientific Hedonism ' is examined a good deal more care- 
 fully, but with practically the same result. The author very 
 justly concludes that, try as we may to avoid it, we are inevi- 
 tably thrown back upon the empirical method, i.e., some form 
 of the hedonistic calculus, so long as we hold to Hedonism at 
 all. It would hardly be possible to do justice to his very 
 cogent argument by any brief paraphrase ; and perhaps this 
 is the less necessary since, in our detailed examination of 
 Mr. Spencer's ethical writings, we have already found how 
 little is really accomplished here by the parade of scientific 
 method. 
 
 At this point Professor Sidgwick somewhat abruptly takes 
 leave of Hedonism for a considerable time, and devotes Book 
 III. to a sympathetic, but at the same time very searching, 
 examination of Intuitionism. We have seen that the title 
 of Book II., i.e., " Egoism," is a little misleading, since the 
 greater part of the book is really devoted to a consideration 
 of the more general aspects of Hedonism. In fact, we have 
 purposely abstracted from the particular applications to Ego- 
 ism, since this is so far from deserving the dignity of a 
 separate Method of Ethics. Now it should be carefully noted 
 that by far the greater part of Book III., which itself is about
 
 390 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 twice the length of any other book in the treatise, is devoted, 
 not to an examination of Intuitionism as a separate Method 
 of Ethics, but to an extremely careful analysis of what the 
 author terms ' the morality of Common Sense '. 
 
 Such a method of treatment was perfectly logical, and 
 perhaps necessary ; but it is important to keep in mind that 
 the moral judgments of Common Sense, whatever these may 
 turn out to be, are by no means the peculiar property of 
 Intuitionism. They may be thought more or less significant, 
 and obviously they are susceptible of quite different inter- 
 pretations and evaluations from the points of view of the 
 various types of ethical theory ; but, as facts of the moral life, 
 they must be taken account of in any adequate treatment of 
 Ethics, provided, of course, that they are not too vague and 
 conflicting to admit of fairly satisfactory formulation. To the 
 present writer it seems, that Professor Sidgwick has contri- 
 buted something of great importance to Ethics by carrying 
 through this rigorous analysis of our common moral judg- 
 ments, before making any serious attempt to evaluate them 
 or to prove or disprove anything by them. The common 
 defect of such discussions is, that the writer who attempts them 
 carries a brief in his hand ; but every candid reader must 
 admit that nothing could well be more judicial than the temper 
 which Professor Sidgwick manifests throughout. Of course, 
 it is easy to criticise any work of this kind. ' Common Sense ' 
 is a vague term, and what are given as the apparent moral 
 judgments of the plain man may seem alternately naive and 
 sophisticated ; but, on the whole, it may fairly be conceded 
 that the author has performed this very important and diffi- 
 cult task more satisfactorily than any other English writer has 
 done up to the present time. 
 
 It would be quite impossible to examine this part of the 
 Methods of Ethics in detail, without devoting to such an 
 examination more space than would here be warranted. Only 
 a few points will be noticed. In this case, no stress is laid 
 by the author upon the provisional classification adopted. 
 The verdict of the common moral consciousness regarding
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 391 
 
 the principal recognised virtues is subjected to the most 
 minute and searching examination. The greatest importance 
 is naturally attached to Benevolence and Justice, to each of 
 which a long chapter is devoted. It is not strange that the 
 result of such careful analysis should be much the same in all 
 cases. The original dogmatic propositions of common sense 
 are found to require important limitations, these limitations 
 also being at least partly recognised by common sense itself. 
 But the further the analysis is carried, the more difficult it 
 becomes to state the exact nature of the limitations required. 
 Common sense is found often to be at variance with itself, 
 so that in many cases it looks as if the original principles 
 threatened to elude us altogether — at any rate, unless we 
 should take refuge in some definite form of ethical theory, 
 which would at once carry us beyond the point of view of the 
 ' plain man,' with which alone we are concerned at present. 
 
 We should naturally expect to find the greatest clearness 
 and consistency in the case of our conception of Justice, but 
 this turns out to be especially difficult to define satisfactorily. 
 Nothing, in fact, could well afford a greater contrast to Mr. 
 Spencer's recklessly dogmatic treatment of this virtue than 
 Professor Sidgwick's very elaborate and extremely able an- 
 alysis of our actual everyday judgments as to what things are 
 just or the contrary. Incidentally, indeed, he shows how 
 perfectly impossible it is to regard ' freedom from interference ' 
 as a principle at once practically intuitive and sufficient to 
 rationalise our ordinary conceptions of Justice. 
 
 After this very elaborate examination of the actual moral 
 judgments of Common Sense, Professor Sidgwick raises the 
 question : Do we find here a sufficient basis for dogmatic 
 Intuitionism ? He himself, though by no means wholly op- 
 posed to Intuitionism as such, is far from drawing this conclu- 
 sion. We require of an axiom, that it shall be (i) stated in 
 clear and precise terms, (2) really self-evident, (3) not conflict- 
 ing with any other truth, and (4) supported by an adequate 
 ' concensus of experts '. Now he admits that, in the previous 
 examination of the morality of Common Sense, he has dis-
 
 392 History of Utilitainanism.. 
 
 covered few, if any, maxims that fulfil these conditions. Of 
 these maxims of Common Sense, he very truly says : " So long 
 as they are left in the state of somewhat vague generalities, 
 as we meet them in ordinary discourse, we are disposed to yield 
 them unquestioning assent, and it may be fairly claimed that 
 the assent is approximately universal — in the sense that any 
 expression of dissent is eccentric and paradoxical. But as 
 soon as we attempt to give them the definiteness which science 
 requires, we find that we cannot do this without abandoning 
 the universality of acceptance. We find, in some cases, that 
 alternatives present themselves, between which it is necessary 
 that we should decide ; but between which we cannot pretend 
 that Common Sense does decide, and which often seem equally 
 or nearly equally plausible." ^ 
 
 All this, of course, is not to be understood as implying that 
 we are left in doubt as to what is right or wrong in ordinary 
 conduct. On this point. Professor Sidgwick carefully defines 
 his position at the end of the chapter. He says : " The 
 notions of Benevolence, Justice, Good Faith, Veracity, Purity, 
 etc., are not necessarily emptied of significance for us, because 
 we have found it impossible to define them with precision. 
 The main part of the conduct prescribed under each notion 
 is sufficiently clear : and the general rule prescribing it does 
 not necessarily lose its force because there is in each case a 
 margin of conduct involved in obscurity and perplexity, or 
 because the rule does not on examination appear to be abso- 
 lute and independent In short, the Morality of Common 
 Sense may still be perfectly adequate to give practical guid- 
 ance to common people in common circumstances : but the 
 attempt to elevate it into a system of Intuitional Ethics brings 
 its inevitable imperfections into prominence without helping 
 us to remove them." ^ 
 
 It remains to see whether some other form of Intuitionism 
 may not promise success, where ordinary dogmatic Intuition- 
 ism is so manifestly doomed to failure. The attempt has 
 sometimes been made to show that moral judgments strictly 
 
 ^See p. 342. ^See pp. 360, 361.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 393 
 
 apply, not to acts, but to desires or affections. It is natural 
 to fall back upon this view, when the difficulties of ordinary 
 Intuitionism become too apparent ; but Professor Sidgwick 
 very truly observes, that nearly all the difficulties which we 
 have previously encountered reappear in a different form, when 
 we try to arrange motives in order of excellence, while " such 
 a construction presents difficulties peculiar to itself, and the 
 attempt to solve these exhibits greater and more fundamental 
 differences among Intuitive moralists, as regards Rank of 
 Motive, than we found to exist as regards Rightness of 
 outward acts "?■ In the pages which follow, these criticisms 
 are abundantly sustained ; but the particular arguments em- 
 ployed hardly need detain us. It is perhaps enough to notice 
 that the tendency toward subjectivity, which is commonly 
 recognised as the greatest danger of Intuitionism as such, is 
 needlessly accentuated in this form of the doctrine. We may 
 therefore properly pass on at once to Philosophical In- 
 tuitionisnL 
 
 Here, again, it seems desirable to notice the author's earlier 
 treatment, as contained in the first edition of the Methods, 
 before taking up the later form of the same discussion. He 
 begins with an important word of caution. We must very 
 carefully guard against a certain class of ' sham axioms,' 
 which have not infrequently deluded even moralists of con- 
 siderable repute.2 For example, it has been urged that the 
 dictates of Wisdom and Temperance may be reduced to the 
 following intuitive principles : (i) It is right to act rationally; 
 and (2) it is right that the lower parts of our nature should 
 be governed by the higher. But the tautology becomes 
 obvious, when we find that ' acting rationally ' is merely 
 another phrase for ' doing what we see to be right,' and that 
 the ' higher part ' of our nature, to which the ' lower parts ' 
 are to defer, is nothing other than ' reason ' itself. These 
 definitions may be found in modern writers ; but it must be 
 observed that nearly the whole of the ethical speculation of 
 
 1 See p. 365. 2 See pp 353 ^t gg^^
 
 394 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 Greece, though in many respects of the greatest interest and 
 value, has this incurable defect. Is there any way of avoid- 
 ing such circular reasonings, and attaining clear intuitive truths 
 of substantial value ? The author replies : " I believe that 
 there is such a way : though we must be careful not to ex- 
 aggerate the amount of the moral knowledge to which it con- 
 ducts us. And I think we may find it by following the two 
 thinkers who in modern times have most earnestly maintained 
 the strictly scientific character of ethical principles: viz.y 
 Clarke in England, and Kant in Germany." ^ 
 
 Abstracting from the particular form of Clarke's theory^ 
 which is largely determined by his anxiety to exhibit the 
 supposed parallelism between ethical and mathematical truths, 
 we may note that he recognises two fundamental ' rules of 
 righteousness ' ; the first of which he terms ' Equity,' and the 
 second ' Love,' or ' Benevolence '. The clearest of his three 
 slightly differing statements of the Rule of Equity is as fol- 
 lows : " Whatever I judge reasonable or unreasonable that 
 another should do for me : that by the same judgment I 
 declare reasonable or unreasonable, that I should in the like 
 case do for him ". This principle is accepted by the author 
 as really self-evident, " as much so as the axioms of mathe- 
 matics, whether or not it be desirable to classify it with them ". 
 At the same time, he admits that this principle is prima facie 
 insufficient for the complete determination of just or equitable 
 conduct. 
 
 As for Clarke's ' second branch of the Rule of Righteous- 
 ness ' with respect to our fellow creatures, his well-known 
 principle of ' universal Love or Benevolence,' the elaborate 
 formula which he actually gives is not altogether fortunate ; 
 but it should be observed that " what Clarke urges is, that the 
 Good of any one individual cannot be more intrinsically desir- 
 able, because it is his, than the equal Good of any other 
 individual. So that our notion of Ultimate Good, at the 
 realisation of which it is evidently reasonable to aim, must 
 include the Good of every one on the same ground that it 
 
 1 See p. 357.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 395 
 
 includes that of any one." ^ This principle, again, seems to 
 be as much a self-evident truth as the principle of Equity. 
 
 There follows an interpretation and criticism of Kant's 
 ethical theory (the details of which are omitted in later 
 editions), which is intended to show that two propositions, 
 substantially identical with those just examined, are there 
 propounded as the chief ultimate principles of conduct. These 
 are : " First, that nothing can be right for me which is not 
 right for all persons in similar circumstances : and secondly, 
 that I cannot regard the fulfilment of my desires, or my own 
 happiness, as intrinsically more desirable (or more to be re- 
 garded by me as a rational end) than the equal happiness of 
 anyone else ". The author concludes .- " But now, of these 
 two propositions, the first is a necessary postulate of all ethical 
 systems, being an expression of what is involved in the mere 
 conception of objective Tightness and wrongness in conduct : 
 while the second is the fundamental principle of that particular 
 system which (in Book I.) we called Utilitarianism ".- 
 
 The significance of this second principle in such a connec- 
 tion is particularly emphasised. In fact, the author maintains 
 that " we have found it as the final outcome of philosophical 
 Intuitionism, the final result of inquiry after really clear and 
 self-evident ethical axioms, as conducted by philosophers who 
 are commonly regarded as eminent examples of the Intuitional 
 mode of thought ". And he closes the chapter with a criti- 
 cism of Mill's proof of the principle of Utility, as given in 
 Chapter iv. of the Utilitarianism. Mill argued that, since 
 each does actually desire his own happiness, it must be ad- 
 mitted that ' the greatest happiness is desirable ' — in the sense 
 that this is what each individual ought to desire, or at least 
 to aim at realising in action. But it may fairly be claimed 
 that this argument leads primarily to the principle of Ego- 
 istic, instead of Universalistic Hedonism, and that the only 
 way of meeting this objection is to show, substantially as 
 Clarke and Kant have done, the necessary universality of the 
 
 ^ See p. 360. 2 ggg p 264.
 
 396 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 ultimate end, as recognised by Reason. " Thus Utilitarianism 
 appears as the final form into which a really scientific In- 
 tuitionism tends to pass." 
 
 But there is one remaining difficulty here, which the author 
 very pertinently points out, after having seemed to overlook 
 it altogether. Omitting details, it is this : " The hedonistic 
 interpretation which Mill and his school give to the principle 
 of Universal Benevolence, seems inadmissible when the prin- 
 ciple is enunciated as a self-evident axiom. In thus enunciat- 
 ing it, we must use, as Clarke does, the wider terms ' Welfare ' 
 or ' Good,' and say tha.t each individual man, as a rational 
 being, is bound to aim at the Good of all other men. This 
 brings us naturally to the question. What is ' Good ' ? which, 
 it seems, still remains to be determined." ^ 
 
 When the later form of this very important chapter is com- 
 pared with the above reproduction of the treatment in the 
 first edition, it will be found that certain differences worth 
 mentioning begin to appear at the point where the question 
 is raised : What may really be accepted as valid intuitions .-* 
 Instead of directly appealing to the well-known axioms of 
 Clarke and to his own manifestly one-sided interpretation of 
 Kant, Professor Sidgwick directly argues that " whatever 
 action any of us judges to be right for himself, he implicitly 
 judges to be right for all similar persons in similar circum- 
 stances "? And he holds that a corresponding proposition 
 may be stated with equal truth in respect of what ought to 
 be done to — not by — difTerent individuals. These principles 
 appear in the Golden Rule, ' Do to others as you would have 
 them do to you ' ; but that formula is obviously inexact, for 
 one might wish for another's co-operation in sin, and be willing 
 to reciprocate it. " In short the self-evident principle strictly 
 stated must take some such negative form as this ; * it cannot 
 be right for A to treat 5 in a manner in which it would 
 be wrong for B to treat A, merely on the ground that they 
 
 ^ See p. 366. The author's answer to this question will be carefully con- 
 sidered later. 
 
 ^ See pp. 379 et seq.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 397 
 
 are two different individuals, and without there being any 
 difference between the natures or circumstances of the two 
 which can be stated as a reasonable ground for difference of 
 treatment." While such a rule manifestly does not give 
 complete guidance in respect to just conduct, its practical im- 
 portcuice cannot be questioned, and its truth, so far as it goes, 
 appears to be self-evident. A somewhat different application 
 of the same fundamental principle, that individuals in similar 
 circumstances should be treated similarly, appears in that 
 ' impartiality in the application of general rules ' which is so 
 important an element in the common notion of Justice, in 
 fact, the author's extremely careful analysis of the ordinary 
 conception of Justice went to show, that no other element 
 than this could be intuitively known with perfect clearness 
 and certainty. 
 
 Besides the principle just explained, which is regarded as 
 affording an intuitive foundation for the conception of Justice, 
 there are two others, referring respectively to rational Pru- 
 dence and Benevolence, which to Professor Sidgwick appear 
 also to be intuitively apprehended. He says : " The proposi- 
 tion * that one ought to aim at one's own good ' is sometimes 
 given as the maxim of Rational Self-love or Prudence : but 
 as so stated it does not clearly avoid tautology ; since we may 
 define ' good ' as ' what one ought to aim at '. If, however, we 
 say ' one's good on the whole,' the addition suggests a prin- 
 ciple which, when explicitly stated, is, at any rate, not tauto- 
 logical. . . . All that the principle affirms is that the mere 
 difference of priority and posteriority in time is not a reason- 
 able ground for having more regard to the consciousness of 
 one moment than to that of another." It is rather important 
 to note that, while this principle is often stated in hedonistic 
 terms, it does not seem to have any logical connection with 
 the principle that ' pleasure is the sole Ultimate Good '. All 
 that is necessarily implied is, that the Good be " conceived as 
 a mathematical whole, of which the integrant parts are realised 
 in different parts or moments of a lifetime " } 
 
 1 See pp. 381, 382. The validity of this assumption will be examined later.
 
 398 Histoiy of Utilitaidanism. 
 
 And now we come to the crucial point of this argument, 
 which, on account of its great importance for the author's 
 treatment of Ethics, has been Hterally reproduced. Professor 
 Sidgwick says : " So far we have only been considering the 
 ' Good on the Whole ' of a single individual : but just as this 
 notion is constructed by comparison and integration of the 
 different ' goods ' that succeed one another in the series of our 
 conscious states, so we have formed the notion of Uni- 
 versal Good by comparison and integration of the goods of 
 all individual human — or sentient — existencies. And here 
 again, just as in the former case, by considering the relation 
 of the integrant parts to the whole and to each other, I obtain 
 the self-evident principle that the good of any one individual 
 is of no more importance, from the point of view (if I may say 
 so) of the Universe, than the good of any other ; unless, 
 that is, there are special grounds for believing that more good 
 is likely to be realised in the one case than in the other. And 
 it is evident to me that as a rational being I am bound to aim 
 at good generally, — so far as it is attainable by my efforts, — 
 not merely at a particular part of it. From these two rational 
 intuitions we may deduce, as a necessary inference, the maxim 
 of Benevolence in an abstract form : viz. that each one is 
 morally bound to regard the good of any other individual 
 as much as his own, except in so far as he judges it to be 
 less, when impartially viewed, or less certainly knowable or 
 attainable by him." ^ 
 
 From the whole preceding argument, the author concludes 
 that in the principles of Justice, rational Prudence, and Bene- 
 volence, as commonly recognised, there is at least a self-evident 
 element, immediately cognisable by abstract intuition. And 
 he adds : " I regard the apprehension, with more or less dis- 
 tinctness, of these abstract truths, as the permanent basis of 
 the common conviction that the fundamental precepts of 
 morality are essentially reasonable ". It will be remembered 
 that, in the first version of this chapter, these principles, or 
 what corresponded to them, were supposed to be taken from 
 
 1 See p. 382.
 
 Henry Sidgivick. 399 
 
 Clarke and Kant, the Intuitional moralists par excellence. In 
 the later form of the chapter, which we have just been examin- 
 ing, the reference to Clarke and Kant follows the much more 
 elaborate, though hardly more satisfactory, vindication of the 
 principles which are accepted by the author as ultimate intui- 
 tions. And it is to be noted that the present reference 
 to Kant is much more guarded than the earlier one. In fact, 
 the earlier careful, if by no means satisfactory, interpretation 
 of Kant is reduced to a single colourless paragraph. The 
 concluding criticism of Mill is presented in practically the same 
 form, the author's claim, of course, being, that Utilitarianism 
 absolutely requires the Intuitional basis which he has himself 
 attempted to supply, particularly in his vindication of the 
 intuitive character of the principle from which that of rational 
 Benevolence is deduced. 
 
 In order to do justice to this interesting attempt to exhibit 
 Utilitarianism as, on the one hand, the logical result of Philo- 
 sophical Intuitionism itself, and, on the other hand, as abso- 
 lutely requiring the Intuitional basis above indicated, it will 
 be necessary somewhat later to examine carefully the final 
 chapter of Book III., which is devoted to a consideration of 
 " Ultimate Good " — for Professor Sidgwick's proof of Utili- 
 tarianism is confessedly not yet complete, the nature of the 
 Good having been left indeterminate. Here we are only 
 concerned to understand the general significance of this final, 
 and, as he believes, decisive part of the argument. At first 
 this might look like forsaking the Intuitional method alto- 
 gether, for apparently it is the very essence of Intuitionism to 
 hold that certain actions are intrinsically right or wrong, not 
 right or wrong because they conduce to some ultimate end of 
 action conceived to be the Good. But Professor Sidgwick 
 defends himself, in all of the slightly differing versions of this 
 chapter, by arguing that the ultimate intuitive principles at 
 which he has arrived, as a result of his careful analysis of the 
 Morality of Common Sense, viz.. Justice, rational Prudence, 
 and Benevolence, all have to do with the apportionment of 
 the Good, which itself has been left undefined.
 
 CHAPTER XVIII. 
 
 HENRY SIDGWICK {continued).^ 
 
 In his examination of Intuitionism, and his attempt to dis- 
 cover in it a residuum of tenable doctrine, Professor Sidgwick 
 has, in one respect at least, observed most commendable 
 caution. He has pitilessly analysed the conventional tauto- 
 logical propositions, and candidly pointed out the inconsist- 
 encies that are inevitable, so long as Intuitionism is regarded 
 as affirming an aggregate of independent, but at the same 
 time absolutely vahd, particular principles, corresponding in 
 detail to the various recognised virtues. The result of this 
 searching examination, as will be remembered, is a good 
 deal the same in the latest as in the earliest edition. 
 In the first edition of the Methods (1874), Samuel Clarke's 
 maxims of Equity and Beneficence were accepted as really 
 intuitive — " as much so as the axioms of mathematics ". 
 In the later editions (e.g., sixth edition, 1901), the state- 
 ments are somewhat more guarded ; but it is still held that 
 in the principles of Justice and Benevolence, as commonly 
 recognised, " there is at least a self-evident element, im- 
 mediately cognisable by abstract intuition," ^ while a third 
 intuitive principle, that of rational Prudence, is also admitted. 
 The explicit formulation of this third principle in the later 
 
 ^A paper entitled "An Examination of Professor Sidgwick's Proof of Utili- 
 tarianism," based upon the first part of this chapter, and closely following 
 the present text, was read before the Philosophical Section of the American 
 Psychological Association at the Baltimore Meeting, December, 1900, and was- 
 afterward printed in the Philosophical Reviezv, May, igoi. 
 
 2 See p. 382. 
 
 (400)
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 401 
 
 editions need not be regarded as in itself particularly signifi- 
 cant, since it might very reasonably be held that the principle 
 was implicitly recognised as intuitive in the earlier treatment ; 
 but it is to be noted that, in the later and more elaborate 
 form of the author's proof of Utilitarianism, with which we are 
 here more particularly concerned, this principle of rational 
 Prudence is regarded as in a sense more ultimate than that of 
 Benevolence, since it is accepted as logically co-ordinate with, 
 if not logically prior to, the more general principle (not named, 
 as we shall see) from which that of Benevolence is deduced. 
 
 Assuming, then, as of course we must, that this later 
 enumeration of three intuitive principles, corresponding to the 
 virtues, rational Prudence, Benevolence, and Justice, accurately 
 represents the author's later, if not also his earlier, view as to 
 the Intuitional foundation of Ethics, it may be well first to 
 recall the precise form in which these principles are given. 
 The two which are certainly treated as intuitive are : (i) the 
 principle which is supposed to underlie the ordinary conception 
 of Justice, viz., that " it cannot be right for A to treat 5 in a 
 manner in which it would be wrong for B to treat A, merely 
 on the ground that they are two different individuals, and 
 without there being any difference between the natures or 
 circumstances of the two which can be stated as a reasonable 
 ground for difference of treatment " ; ^ and (2) the principle 
 of rational Prudence just mentioned, viz., that one part of a 
 given conscious experience is not to be regarded, other things 
 being equal, as of more importance than any other equal part 
 of the same experience. The precise formulation of the 
 third supposed intuition, from which the abstract principle of 
 rational Benevolence is directly deduced, will be considered 
 when we come to see how it is actually derived by the 
 author. 
 
 Now, in connection with these supposed intuitions, three 
 closely related questions at once present themselves : (i) Are 
 any or all of these principles to be accepted as really intuitive, 
 
 ^ See pp. 380 et seq. 
 26
 
 402 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 without further examination? (2) What, exactly, does each 
 of these principles imply ? (3) Are they all to be regarded as 
 strictly on the same plane ? If the first question be answered 
 in the affirmitive, the two others may perhaps be regarded as 
 superfluous ; otherwise they will most certainly be relevant. 
 As regards the first question, it is difficult to see that Professor 
 Sidgwick has taken the necessary steps to prove that any of 
 these principles are intuitive, even granting for the time that 
 they all may very well be such. Throughout the treatise he 
 has studiously avoided all metaphysical and epistemological 
 questions, and, on the whole, this has been most fortunate for 
 his treatment of Ethics ; but it is difficult to see how one is 
 to prove that the principles in question are strictly intuitive, 
 without for the time passing over into Epistemology. Pro- 
 fessor Sidgwick says, indeed : " No psychogonical theory has 
 ever been put forward professing to discredit the propositions 
 that I regard as really axiomatic " ; but this is evading the 
 issue rather than meeting it. The question is one, not of the 
 psychological origin, but rather of the epistemological signifi- 
 cance, of these principles ; and to call principles intuitive 
 without committing oneself to any particular theory of knowl- 
 edge looks almost like begging the question. The mere fact 
 that, when separately considered, they commend themselves to 
 common sense — which seems to be the test actually depended 
 upon by the author — is plainly insufficient ; for the result of 
 philosophical reflection very commonly is, to show that what 
 common sense unites, must be separated, and that what 
 common sense separates, must be united. 
 
 Since, then, we cannot accept these principles as intuitive 
 without further examination, and since we cannot directly 
 raise epistemological questions without entering into those 
 very discussions which the author explicitly avoids, it seems 
 fairest to pass on at once to the two remaining very closely 
 related questions : What, exactly, does each of these principles 
 imply } And, in particular, are they all to be regarded as 
 strictly on the same plane 1 Professor Sidgwick himself sug- 
 gests one important difference, in making the transition from
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 403 
 
 his treatment of the so-called intuition of Justice to that of 
 the intuitions which are supposed to correspond to rational 
 Prudence and Benevolence. He says : " The principle just 
 discussed [Justice], which seems to be more or less clearly 
 implied in the common notion of ' fairness ' or ' equity/ is ob- 
 tained by considering the similarity of the individuals that 
 make up a Logical Whole or Genus. There are others, no less 
 important, which emerge in the consideration of the similar 
 parts of a Mathematical or Quantitative Whole." ^ 
 
 Now it is partly because the principle of Justice, as here 
 formulated, does not depend upon this conception of a merely 
 quantitative whole, which to many seems inapplicable to 
 Ethics, that it almost inevitably appears more ultimate than 
 the other two principles, in the particular form here given, 
 whether or not we think proper to ascribe to it a strictly in- 
 tuitive character. Moreover, it is to be carefully noted that 
 this principle, viz., that " it cannot be right for A to treat B 
 in a manner in which it would be wrong for B to treat A, 
 merely on the ground that they are two different individuals," 
 is much more extensive in its application than what is ordi- 
 narily understood by Justice. This fact seems hardly to be 
 recognised by the author. Yet from the mere statement of 
 the principle, it is evident that it applies at least to all our 
 moral relations to others. It is thus a regulative principle, 
 applicable to rational Benevolence quite as much as to 
 Justice, though so abstract that the subordinate principles. 
 Justice and Benevolence, as ordinarily understood, need to be 
 formulated before this very general principle can be of much 
 practical assistance in directing moral conduct. But if one 
 consider the matter more closely, it will be evident that this 
 same abstract principle, here called that of Justice, applies not 
 merely to all our conduct which directly concerns others, but 
 equally to that part of our conduct which more immediately 
 concerns ourselves ; for any recognised form of ethical theory 
 requires some reason for our treating ourselves differently 
 
 ^ See pp. 380, 381.
 
 404 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 from others, though the reasons accepted as vaUd no doubt 
 vary considerably. 
 
 It thus gradually becomes evident, that the principle which 
 we are examining is not a particular ethical principle at all, 
 but rather an abstract statement of that postulate of objec- 
 tivity, or impartiality, which is implied in all ethical reasoning 
 as such. Whether or not one call this postulate an intuition, 
 depends, of course, upon one's theory of knowledge. At any 
 rate, from the epistemological point of view, it would appear 
 to be on a plane with the most fundamental methodological 
 postulates of the various sciences and disciplines ; it is not 
 a particular principle referring to any one side of our moral 
 experience more than to all others. 
 
 When we come to consider the supposed intuitions corre- 
 sponding to rational Prudence and Benevolence, as here for- 
 mulated, it soon becomes evident that we are dealing with 
 relatively subordinate principles, and principles that involve 
 certain assumptions that are likely to make them less univer- 
 sally acceptable. The principle of rational Prudence, viz., 
 that one should aim at one's good on the whole, looks at first 
 very innocent, at any rate so long as the Good is left unde- 
 fined, and so long as the point insisted upon merely is that 
 " difference of priority and posteriority in time is not a reason- 
 able ground for having more regard to the consciousness of 
 one moment than to that of another ". But when it becomes 
 evident that this principle is regarded as logically separate 
 from, and apparently as logically prior to, that of Benevolence, 
 it needs little argument to prove that this supposed intuition 
 is by no means free from certain assumptions which them- 
 selves assuredly have no intuitive basis. 
 
 The most important, perhaps, is the extremely dangerous 
 assumption that there is a good for me that is originally and 
 to the end separate from the good of others. This inevitably 
 commits one to that " dualism of the Practical Reason " which 
 Professor Sidgvs'ick himself frankly admits in the final chapter 
 of the Methods. But that is not all. When Professor Sidg- 
 wick argues that all that is necessarily implied is, that the
 
 Henry Sidgivick. 405 
 
 Good be " conceived as a mathematical whole, of which the 
 integrant parts are realised in different parts or moments 
 of a lifetime," he partly suggests a really serious difficulty. 
 As a matter of fact, the Good is here assumed to be not 
 merely a mathematical whole — which might vaguely suggest 
 certain internal relations — but a quasi-physical aggregate, as 
 opposed to an organic whole. And this plainly begs the 
 question, as against certain forms of ethical theory for which 
 the author has no sympathy, as, for instance. Self-realisation. 
 
 How important this latter assumption really is, can readily 
 be seen from the use which Professor Sidgwick makes of it ; 
 for he immediately proceeds to base his further argument 
 upon this questionable analogy. Just as the notion of in- 
 dividual good is " constructed by comparison and integration 
 of the different ' goods ' that succeed one another in the series 
 of our conscious states," so the notion of Universal Good may 
 be found " by comparison and integration of the goods of all 
 individual human — or sentient — existencies ". In other words, 
 consider the Good, whatever that may prove to be, in 
 abstraction from the nature of the being for whom it is the 
 Good, and the question of more or less is all that remains.^ 
 Mathematics, the most abstract of all the sciences, is at least 
 ideally applicable here in the most thoroughgoing fashion, 
 precisely because we are dealing with something that is already 
 abstract 
 
 It should be observed that we have not even yet obtained 
 the desired intuition of rational Benevolence — which is 
 emerging rather slowly for an intuition — viz., the principle 
 " that each one is morally bound to regard the good of any 
 other individual as much as his own, except in so far as he 
 judges it to be less, when impartially viewed, or less certainly 
 knowable or attainable by him ".2 This is confessedly a 
 deduction, though a perfectly logical one, from the more 
 
 ^ It should be noted that the question of more or less may be an important 
 question for Ethics, without by any means being the only one. This whole 
 matter has been discussed in preceding chapters. 
 
 "^ See p. 382.
 
 406 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 general principle — here employed, but unnamed — that ' the 
 good of one individual is not as such to be preferred to that 
 of any other individual '. 
 
 Now what is this unnamed principle, here treated as the 
 real ultimate, from which the principle of rational Benevo- 
 lence is regarded as merely a corollary ? Professor Sidgwick 
 does injustice to the strength of his own argument, such as it 
 is, by representing this principle as suggested by a mathe- 
 matical analogy, i.e., by arguing that, just as one part of the 
 individual's good is of no more importance than any other 
 equal part, so one part of the total Good (or good of all) is 
 of no more importance than any other equal part of the 
 same. This is making the all-important transition from the 
 subjective, in the sense of merely self-regarding, attitude 
 to the objective ethical attitude altogether too easily. ^ As 
 a matter of fact, this unnamed principle, here treated as an 
 ultimate, is merely the original so-called principle of Jus- 
 tice, translated into terms of the Good. Any deduction 
 from it, therefore, like the abstract principle of Benevolence, 
 involves the same assumption, viz., that moral distinctions 
 are to be interpreted in terms of the Good, instead of in 
 terms of Duty, Good Will, etc. — an assumption which, no 
 matter how capable of being justified by argument, can by no 
 means be regarded as intuitive. Regarding the author's ab- 
 stract principle of Benevolence, then, we must conclude : (i) 
 that it is a deduction from another principle, rather than a 
 separate intuition ; and (2) that the principle from which it is 
 deduced cannot possibly be regarded as an intuition, even 
 though we should accept the so-called principle of Justice as 
 such. 
 
 So much, then, for the three fundamental so-called ' intui- 
 tions,' which are regarded by Professor Sidgwick as affording 
 the needed Intuitional foundation for Ethics,^ By themselves, 
 
 1 Note again the author's difficuhy with " the duahsm of the Practical Reason " 
 in the final chapter. 
 
 ^Of "the axiom of Rational Benevolence" in particular, he has said a little 
 before, that it is, in his view, "required as a rational basis for the Utilitarian 
 system ".
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 407 
 
 however, these abstract principles are insufficient, according to 
 his own admission ; for he holds that they all equally imply 
 a Good, still undetermined, of which they are to be regarded 
 as distributive principles. That this is true even of Justice, 
 is asserted in the following definite statement : " Justice (when 
 regarded as essentially and always a Virtue) lies in distributing 
 Good (or evil) impartially according to right rules ".^ 
 
 Before passing on to this second main division of the author's 
 proof of Utilitarianism, which fortunately will not detain us 
 long, viz., the determination of the nature of the Good, which 
 all of the so-called ' intuitions ' are supposed to imply, and of 
 which they are regarded as ' distributive ' principles, two pre- 
 liminary criticisms require to be made, (i) The very abstract 
 principle of Justice, at any rate — which has turned out to 
 be merely the postulate of objectivity, or impartiality, implied 
 in all ethical reasoning — does not logically imply an apportion- 
 ment of the Good, as the author holds that all of these prin- 
 ciples do, precisely because it is so abstract that it applies to 
 the Duty Ethics as well as to the various forms of the Ethics 
 of the Good. (2) It must not hastily be assumed that even 
 the subordinate principles, rational Prudence and Benevo- 
 lence — which, as here formulated, do undoubtedly imply the 
 conception of the Good — are necessarily to be regarded as 
 distributive, rather than as regulative, principles. Whether 
 they are to be the one or the other, depends entirely upon the 
 nature of the Good, still undetermined. 
 
 It is impossible here to enlarge upon this distinction between 
 ' distributive ' and ' regulative ' principles ; but fortunately it 
 is at once fairly obvious and quite commonly recognised. If 
 the Good be conceived as something, e.g., Happiness, which is 
 to be portioned out, as nearly as may be, into equal parts, 
 these principles will of course have to be regarded as ex- 
 ternally distributive. If, on the other hand, the Good be 
 conceived as organic in character, e.g.. Self-realisation or even 
 Health of the Social Organism, we can no longer speak of 
 
 ' See p. 393.
 
 4o8 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 distribution merely, as if a lump sum of money were to be 
 impartially divided. On the contrary, all the principles 
 of Ethics — these as much as any others — must then be re- 
 garded as internally regulative, and as deriving their specific 
 character from the concrete nature of the Good. 
 
 But let us return to Professor Sidgwick's own argument. 
 What is the Good, which is supposed to be implied by all 
 three of these principles, here treated as distributive .' It 
 should be carefully noted that this problem, by far the most 
 important of all for any form of ethical theory except pure 
 Intuitionism, is not here discussed with anything like philoso- 
 phical thoroughness. The attempt rather seems to be to 
 show what, on the whole, commends itself to common sense 
 as the Good. This is particularly disappointing, since the 
 investigation of this problem has been deferred so long. 
 
 Professor Sidgwick begins by arguing that it will not do 
 to say that * Virtue is the Good '. That would involve one in 
 an obvious logical circle, since we have just seen that our 
 three ultimate intuitions regarding what is virtuous all have 
 to do with the apportionment of the Good. The purely 
 logical difficulty may perhaps be avoided, if the ' good will ' 
 itself be affirmed to be the Good ; but this is fundamentally 
 opposed to common sense, " since the very notion of subjective 
 rightness or goodness of will implies an objective standard, 
 which it directs us to seek, but does not profess to supply " }■ 
 From this point the argument moves only too rapidly. 
 " Shall we then say that Ultimate Good is Good or Desirable 
 conscious or sentient Life .' " This seems to accord with 
 common sense ; but it must be observed that not all psychical 
 existence can be regarded as ultimately desirable, " since psy- 
 chical life as known to us includes pain as well as pleasure, 
 and so far as it is painful, it is not desirable ". This, of course, 
 frankly assumes that ' desirable ' consciousness is Happiness 
 or Pleasure. Now the author urges that this is the only 
 possible criterion of feeling as feeling ; and further that both 
 
 1 See p. 394.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 409 
 
 cognition and volition, taken strictly by themselves, are quite 
 neutral in respect of desirability. The further details of the 
 argument may safely be neglected, for, as will readily be seen, 
 the result is a foregone conclusion. By this highly abstract 
 method — which practically begs the question, by arbitrarily 
 isolating the different sides of consciousness — Happiness, or 
 Pleasure, is vindicated as the only practicable test of what is 
 desirable in conscious life. And the Good being thus defined, 
 the author holds that we are finally at liberty to regard the 
 three genuine moral intuitions, relating respectively to rational 
 Prudence, Justice, and Beneficence, as affording the needed 
 Intuitional basis of pure Universalistic Hedonism, or Utili- 
 tarianism. ^ 
 
 Little need be said by way of summary. As the chain 
 is no stronger than its weakest link, it is evident that Professor 
 Sidgwick's proof of Utilitarianism equally involves the validity 
 of his treatment of what he regards as the fundamental moral 
 intuitions and his hasty determination of the nature of the 
 Good, which he holds that all of these intuitions imply. As 
 regards the three supposed intuitions, we found that they were 
 by no means on the same plane. The so-called intuition of 
 Justice turned out to be merely the postulate of objectivity, or 
 impartiaUty, implied in all ethical reasoning, and not a separate 
 intuition, referring to one part of moral conduct more than 
 to others. From the epistemological point of view, therefore, 
 it appeared to be closely analogous to the most fundamental 
 methodological postulates of the various sciences and dis- 
 ciplines. 
 
 Moreover, to the relatively subordinate principles of rational 
 Prudence and Benevolence, also assumed as intuitive, and ap- 
 parently as being on the same plane with that of Justice, two 
 special criticisms were found to apply, (i) The assumption of 
 an original separateness between the interest of each individual 
 
 ^ Sometimes the axiom of rational Benevolence is referred to as if it alone 
 afforded the requisite Intuitional basis for Utilitarianism. See p. 387.
 
 4IO History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 and that of all others could not be conceded. (2) We found that 
 only the principle of rational Prudence was really treated as a 
 separate intuition, that of Benevolence having been arrived at 
 indirectly. The first step was the disguised translation of the 
 original principle of Justice into terms of the Good — a con- 
 version which itself should have been justified by argument. 
 The second step was a deduction from this principle in its 
 modified form. The principle of Benevolence, therefore, as 
 here formulated, is at least twice removed from being an in- 
 tuition in the proper sen.se, even if the author's abstract prin- 
 ciple of Justice be regarded as such. 
 
 Again, we have seen that these principles do not, as the 
 author claims, all imply a Good, still undetermined, of which 
 they are to be regarded as ' distributive ' principles. The so- 
 called principle of Justice is so abstract that it does not neces- 
 sarily imply the conception of the Good at all. Even rational 
 Prudence and Benevolence, as here formulated, are not neces- 
 sarily to be regarded as ' distributive ' principles merely. That 
 will depend upon the nature of the Good, still left undeter- 
 mined ; for if the Good, e.g., turn out to be Self-realisation, 
 or even Health of the Social Organism, no particular principle 
 of Ethics can be regarded as externally distributive ; but all 
 must rather be regarded as internally regulative, and as 
 deriving their specific character from the concrete nature of 
 the Good. Finally, even assuming these principles to be ' dis- 
 tributive,' the author's hasty determination of the nature of 
 the Good hardly pretends to be a philosophical treatment of 
 this all-important problem ; but is rather an attempt to justify 
 Utilitarianism to common sense. When he practically rests 
 his case upon the argument, that pleasure is the only possible 
 criterion of the value of feeling as feeling, he unconsciously 
 begs the question, which is, and must remain, whether or not 
 the value of conscious life is to be determined solely in terms 
 of feeling. 
 
 It is a natural, if also rather unexpected, result of Professor 
 Sidgwick's order of treatment, which follows from his peculiar
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 411 
 
 classification, that the concluding book of the Methods of 
 Ethics^ Book IV., " Utilitarianism," contains comparatively 
 little that is of importance for systematic Ethics. The general 
 implications of Hedonism as such, together with the special 
 difficulties that are sure to arise in connection with any form 
 of hedonistic theory, have already been considered at length 
 in Book II., " Egoism " — with the result, indeed, that many of 
 the difficulties of Utilitarianism have probably been either 
 long forgotten by the reader, or confounded with those which 
 more particularly belong to the so-called method of Egoism. 
 Moreover, by far the most important constructive argument 
 of the treatise, the author's elaborate proof of Utilitarianism, 
 which we have just examined in considerable detail, comes at 
 the end of Book III., " Intuitionism ". This is perhaps natural 
 enough, since it is the whole point of the argument to provide 
 Utilitarianism with an Intuitional basis ; but the fact remains 
 that, before the reader begins the concluding book of the 
 treatise, which, from its title, one would naturally expect to 
 be devoted to a judicial examination of Utilitarianism, he is 
 wholly committed to that method, provided that he has ac- 
 cepted the preceding arguments as valid. 
 
 In truth, what the author seems to have attempted, in this 
 concluding book of the Methods, was not a further and more 
 elaborate examination of the method of Utilitarianism as such, 
 but rather a justification of that method to common sense. 
 Apart from the two brief introductory chapters, which mainly 
 consist in a resume of what is given in more satisfactory form 
 elsewhere, and the equally brief concluding chapter, on " The 
 Mutual Relations of the Three Methods," nearly the whole 
 book is devoted either to tracing out in detail the correspond- 
 ence between Utilitarian morality and the morality of 
 Common Sense, or to settling questions connected with the 
 practical application of the Utilitarian method. While, there- 
 fore, these discussions are in themselves both interesting and 
 valuable, they are hardly of a kind to detain us here ; and we 
 may best pass on almost immediately to the final chapter,
 
 412 History of Utilitarianism, 
 
 referred to above, which will be found to afford an interesting 
 commentary upon certain of the author's presuppositions. 
 
 It is perhaps worth noticing that, while Book IV. of the 
 Methods of Ethics has been modified less (or in less important 
 respects) in succeeding editions than any other book of the 
 treatise, some of the chapters have received titles quite differ- 
 ent from the original ones in the later editions. For example, 
 the third chapter, which is the first of any length in the book, 
 originally had the title, " The Proof of Utilitarianism (con- 
 tinued) ". This chapter, though very little modified, has re- 
 ceived in later editions the much more appropriate title, 
 " The Relation of Utilitarianism to the Morality of Common 
 Sense " — which, in fact, exactly describes the nature of the 
 discussion. The final chapter, on the other hand, which we 
 are now to examine, has in later editions the title, " The 
 Mutual Relations of the Three Methods," though this is less 
 accurately descriptive of its real character, even in its some- 
 what modified form, than the original title, " The Sanctions 
 of Utilitarianism ". 
 
 The real problem considered, in the later as in the earlier 
 form of this chapter, is the reconciliation of duty and interest ; 
 and the solution of the problem, so far as any solution is 
 offered, is much less important than the very prominent place 
 given to the discussion itself. In short, the last chapter of 
 this elaborate treatise on the Methods of Ethics frankly 
 emphasises the " Dualism of the Practical Reason," as the 
 author himself elsewhere calls it. This is more significant 
 than might at first appear, for the problem, as here stated, 
 is a manifest survival from eighteenth century individualism. 
 Referring to this chapter, Professor Sidgwick says, in the 
 Preface to the second edition of the Methods : " I hold with 
 Butler that * Reasonable Self-love and Conscience are the two 
 chief or superior principles in the nature of man,' each of 
 which we are under a ' manifest obligation ' to obey ". 
 
 It might reasonably be held that the dualism in Butler's 
 system is by no means so serious as this would imply, at any 
 rate, if we take into account the logic of his system as a whole ;
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 413 
 
 but Professor Sidgwick does not permit us to mistake his 
 own position- While never suggesting a real doubt as to our 
 complete obligation to do what we believe to be right, he 
 holds that morality must be regarded as only incompletely 
 rationalised, unless it can be shown to be for the agent's 
 individual interest to be moral. Yet even so, his unflinching 
 honesty, which never shows in a more admirable light than 
 here, will not permit him for a moment to juggle with this 
 crux of eighteenth century Ethics. He refers, indeed, to his 
 own argument, which goes to prove that it is ' reasonable ' 
 for one to aim at Good in general, and not merely at one's 
 own individual, selfish good.^ But he does not see fit to 
 pursue this line of argument further, in the present connection. 
 He admits also the reasonableness of the Egoist's demand 
 that it shall be for his ' interest ' to be moral, and, after care- 
 fully pointing out what can, and what cannot, be proved by 
 the conventional appeal to sympathy, etc., he finally comes to 
 the inevitable conclusion that there is no way of demonstrating 
 that, in all cases, it is strictly for the agent's selfish interest 
 to be moral, unless we take into account strictly theological 
 considerations. 
 
 The clearest statement of his conclusion is to be found in 
 the final paragraph of the first edition of the Methods, the gist 
 of which is as follows : " The old immoral paradox, ' that my 
 performance of Social Duty is good not for me but for others,' 
 cannot be completely refuted by empirical arguments : nay, 
 the more we study these arguments the more we are forced 
 to admit, that if we have these alone to rely on, there must 
 be some cases in which the paradox is true. And yet we can- 
 not but admit with Butler, that it is ultimately reasonable 
 to seek one's own happiness. Hence the whole system of our 
 beliefs as to the intrinsic reasonableness of conduct must fall, 
 without a hypothesis unverifiable by experience reconciling 
 the Individual with the Universal Reason, without a belief, in 
 some form or other, that the moral order which we see im- 
 
 ^ See pp. 495 et seq.
 
 414 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 perfectly realised in this actual world is yet actually perfect." ^ 
 In the later editions Professor Sidgwick expresses himself 
 much more guardedly, but to practically the same purpose. 
 And we may add that, given the presuppositions, this appeal 
 to the theological sanction is the only way out of a more or 
 less complete ethical agnosticism. 
 
 The presuppositions, however, all centre about the fatal 
 assumption that the ultimate interest of the individual is 
 something which can be considered apart from that of the 
 society to which he belongs. If a ' sanction ' for morality 
 be demanded from this point of view, Gay's answer is the only 
 possible one, viz., that, since God only can in all cases make 
 us happy or miserable. He only can reconcile duty with interest. 
 And that was what all the so-called ' Theological Utilitarians ' 
 meant by saying that ' complete obligation ' to morality could 
 come only from the Divine Being himself. If we shrink from 
 such a conclusion, it is in no spirit of hostility to theology, 
 much less to the essential teaching of Christianity ; it is merely 
 because the philosophical methodology of the present day will 
 not permit us thus to invoke Divine assistance to extricate 
 us from speculative difficulties which we can avoid by the 
 exercise of our natural reason. 
 
 But it would be very unjust to Professor Sidgwick to allow 
 his own too emphatic statement of the " Dualism of the 
 Practical Reason " to serve as a final commentary upon his 
 system. As a matter of fact, he himself is one of the very 
 moralists who have enabled us to transcend this position, 
 which here he seems to define as his own. Both historically 
 and logically this demand for the reconciliation of duty and 
 interest, in the sense of separate individual interest, which 
 could be effected only by the theological sanction, is in- 
 timately connected with the theory of obligation which Gay 
 once for all perfectly expressed, when he said : " Obligation 
 is the necessity of doing or omitting any action in order to be 
 happy ". 
 
 1 See p. 473.
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 415 
 
 The eighteenth century Intuitionists did not by any means 
 wholly escape confusion regarding the problem as to the rela- 
 tion between duty and interest ; but their characteristic theory 
 of the absolute nature of moral obligation, intuitively appre- 
 hended, did not at all commit them to this Dualism of the 
 Practical Reason, while they were influenced in the contrary 
 direction by their view, that the mere consciousness that an 
 action was right or wrong could in some way become a sufficient 
 motive for performing it or abstaining from it. Professor 
 Sidgwick himself, here, as elsewhere, has much in common 
 with traditional Intuitionism, and could easily have avoided 
 this characteristic crux of eighteenth century Utilitarianism. 
 As we saw in the early part of Chapter xvi., he utterly refuses 
 to reduce the notion of ' ought ' to terms of anything else, as 
 the earlier Utilitarians had done. For him, as much as for 
 any Intuitionist, * ought ' is an irreducible datum of moral 
 consciousness, although he uses the term in a sense rather 
 more abstract than that of ordinary Intuitionism. Moreover, 
 he distinctly holds, in his latest as in his earliest treatment, 
 that, while it may not perhaps properly be maintained that 
 reason, apart from all feeling, can afford the moral motive, it 
 is nevertheless much as if this were the case, since we nearly 
 all desire, more or less strongly, to do what is reasonable 
 merely because it is such. 
 
 Much more important, however, in the present connection, 
 than this abstract statement, which merely points in the direc- 
 tion of traditional Intuitionism, is Professor Sidgwick's highly 
 significant analysis of desire. The characteristic position of 
 the older Utilitarianism, that only pleasure as such can be 
 desired, and consequently only the agent's own pleasure, he 
 rejects as patently false. In discarding this theory, together 
 with the theory of obligation inseparably connected with it, he 
 really cut loose from the eighteenth century position. He 
 was, indeed, the first Utilitarian to see the real significance 
 of Butler's analysis of desire. And, in spite of minor differ- 
 ences, he agrees with Butler on the essential point. In a 
 passage previously quoted, he says, after remarking that Butler
 
 4i6 History of Utilitarianism. 
 
 has somewhat overstated his case : " But as a matter of fact, 
 it appears to me that throughout the whole scale of my im- 
 pulses, sensual, emotional, and intellectual alike, I can dis- 
 tinguish desires of which the object is something other than 
 my own pleasure "} And a little later he adds : " Our con- 
 scious active impulses are so far from being always directed 
 towards the attainment of pleasure or avoidance of pain for 
 ourselves, that we can find everywhere in consciousness extra- 
 regarding impulses, directed towards something that is not 
 pleasure, nor relief from pain ; and, indeed, a most important 
 part of our pleasure depends upon the existence of such im- 
 pulses ".2 
 
 The logic of all this is plain, at least to ourselves at the 
 present day. Not only is the possibility of an original altru- 
 ism provided for, but the individual moral agent no longer 
 has to be regarded as an isolated centre of desires, whether for 
 the happiness of self or of others. He is rather seen to be an 
 organic part of society, in a sense that carries one far beyond 
 eighteenth century individualism. Butler, indeed, was too 
 often obliged to employ the argunientuni ad hominem, in 
 order to meet the problems and difficulties of individualism 
 in the working out of his system ; but the logic of his system 
 as a whole was clearly in the direction of what we would have 
 to regard as most modern in ethical speculation. And it 
 surely is not too much to say that, in so far as Professor Sidg- 
 wick follows Butler in this all-important analysis of desire, 
 which does so much to transform the problems of Ethics, he 
 also is logically one of the true moderns, in spite of all appar- 
 ent evidence to the contrary. 
 
 It was a notable event in the development of recent ethical 
 theory, when Utilitarianism thus for the first time really took 
 account of Butler's starting-point and method ; and if the result 
 would seem to be the inevitable dissolution of traditional 
 Utilitarianism itself, there is perhaps little ground for regret. 
 Neither J. S. Mill nor Professor Sidgwick were adepts in rigid 
 
 ^ See p. 45. ^ See p. 52,
 
 Henry Sidgwick. 417 
 
 logical consistency ; but the very fact that they could for 
 the time hold together the half-truths of seemingly anti- 
 thetical systems, enabled them to perform a service for the 
 development of systematic Ethics which only the future 
 can duly appreciate. Both were essentially seekers after 
 truth, and not system-makers. In fact, it would be difficult to 
 mention two moralists who have shown more perfect candour 
 in pointing out difficulties of their own systems, of which they 
 were themselves conscious ; and if they helped to lead a 
 succeeding generation to the recognition of truths which they 
 never definitely formulated for themselves, their contribution 
 to Ethics was not the less, but the greater. Few English 
 moralists of the nineteenth century, so recently ended, are 
 deserving of more grateful appreciation than these two emi- 
 nent Utilitarians, who did their work so well that they helped 
 their successors even to transcend the Method of Ethics for 
 which they themselves stood. 
 
 27
 
 INDEX OF NAMES, SUBJECTS, AND WORKS. 
 
 Absolute and Relative Ethics, Spencer, 323 ff,, 351. 
 
 Adaptation to Environment, Spencer's vague conception of complete, 278 ff., 
 
 306 flf. 
 Alciphron ; or, The Mhmte Philosopher (Berkeley, 1732), referred to, 68, 83 n. 
 Amity, the Ethics of, Spencer, 288, 315, 340, 345. 
 Approbation, moral : Gay's explanation of, 74, 75 ; Hume's explanation of, 
 
 loi ff., 106, 108 ; Tucker's view of the teleology of, 156, 157. 
 Association of Ideas: Gay, 74 ff. ; Hartley, 116 ff. ; Tucker, 134 ff. 
 Autobiography (J. S. Mill, 1873), quoted, 193, 195, 197, 198, 202, 211, 243, 262. 
 
 Bacon, referred to, 204, 226. 
 
 Bain, referred to, 193 «., 229. 
 
 Benevolence, the virtue of: Cumberland, 21, 24-27, 48; Shaftesbury, 55; 
 Hutcheson, 59; Hume, 100-102; Hartley, 126; Tucker, 159 ff, ; Paley, 
 173; Bentham, 183; J. S. Mill, 240, 255; Spencer, 280, 283, 316, 326, 
 328, 331, 332, 338, 343» 347-351. 355. 356; Sidgwick, 391 ff. ; Sidgwick's 
 " intuition " of, 398 ff., 405 ff. 
 
 Bentham, 174-190; referred to, i, 72, 81, 97, 112, 148, 154, 164, 165, 166, 167, 
 168, 191, 192, 193, 196, 199, 202, 203,210,211, 214, 227, 262, 273, 320,363, 
 374. 375. 385 ; J- S. Mill's extended criticism of, 204 ff. ; Spencer's criticism 
 of, 270 ff. 
 
 Berkeley, Bishop, 65-69; referred to, 83, 149, 191, 385. 
 
 " Biological view " of morality, Spencer's, 302 ff. 
 
 Boniform Faculty, the: H. More, 11 ff. 
 
 Bowring, J., referred to, 166, 176; quoted, 180. 
 
 Bradley, F. H., referred to, 376 «., 381. 
 
 Brown, J., 83-90 ; referred to, 166, 205. 
 
 Butler, Bishop: referred to, 56, 97, 133, 138, 213, 258, 372, 382, 385, 412, 413, 
 416, 417 ; Sidgwick influenced by, in his theory of desire, 368 ff. 
 
 Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times (Shaftesbury, 171 1), 54 ff. 
 Clarke, Samuel, referred to, 84, 363. 385, 394, 395, 396, 399, 400. 
 Coleridge : criticised by J. S. Mill, 209 ff. ; referred to, 214, 263. 
 Common Sense, the Morality of, exhaustively analysed by Sidgwick, 390 ff.
 
 420 Index. 
 
 Consequences of actions : Cumberland distinguishes sharply between the 
 
 internal, and the external, 39 ff. ; difficulty of predicting the, Berkeley, 67; 
 
 the criterion of morality, Gay, 73 ; not the only criterion, Hartley, 126, 129 ; 
 
 general, not particular, to be computed, Tucker, 148 ff. ; also Paley, 172 ; 
 
 and J. S. Mill, 217; cf. Bentham, 184, i88; Spencer's distinction between 
 
 the "extrinsic" and the "intrinsic," 313 ff. 
 Cudworth, referred to, 4, 8, 10, ii, 17. 
 Cumberland, Bishop, 1-5 1 ; referred to, 67, 68, 69, 73, 78, 79, 80, 82, iii, 157, 
 
 161, 181, 382. 
 
 Data of Ethics, The : Part I. of The Principles of Ethics (Spencer, 1879), 293 ff. ; 
 referred to, 269, 329, 347, 353 ff. 
 
 De cive (Hobbes, 1642), 5 ff. 
 
 De corpore politico (Hobbes, 1650), 6 ff. 
 
 De jure belli et pads (Grotius, 1625), 2 ff. 
 
 De legibus naturae (Cumberland, 1672), 14-51. (See " Cumberland ".) 
 
 De Toqueville, referred to, 213, 263. 
 
 Deontology ; or. The Science of Morality (Bentham, 1834), 175 ff. [See " Ben- 
 tham ".) 
 
 Descartes, referred to, 4, 20, 24, 38. 
 
 Desire, Theory of: J. S. Mill, 256 ff. ; Sidgwick's criticism of Mill's, 367 ; 
 Sidgwick influenced by Butler in his, 368 ff., 416. 
 
 Detail, Method of: J. S. Mill on Bentham's so-called, 205 ff. 
 
 Determinism : Tucker, 144; J. S. Mill, 220 ff. 
 
 Dignity, our sense of: insisted upon by Hutcheson, 61 ff. ; also by Hartley, 122 ; 
 and by J. S. Mill, 251, 252. 
 
 Discourse on the Studies of the University of Cambridge (A. Sedgwick, 1833), 
 criticised by J. S. Mill, 199 ff. 
 
 Distributive, the principles of Ethics regarded by Sidgwick as, rather than as 
 regulative, 407 ff., 410. 
 
 Education, the power of: J. S. Mill's belief in, 237 ff., 252. 
 
 Egoism : in Hobbes, 5 ff. ; regarded by Sidgwick as one of the three Methods of 
 
 Ethics, 373 ff., 380 ; serious difficulties of this view, 382 ff. 
 Enchiridion eihicum (Henry More, 1667), 11- 14. 
 End of action : Gay's distinction between the " particular " and the " ultimate," 
 
 75. (S«e " The Good ".) 
 Enmity, the Ethics of: Spencer, 288, 315, 340, 345. 
 Environment, adaptation to : ambiguity of Spencer's conception of, in Social 
 
 Statics, 278 ff. ; difficulties involved in his later explanations, 306 ff. 
 Essay concerning Hitman Understanding (Locke, 1690), 52 ff. ; referred to, 147. 
 
 (See " Locke ".) 
 Essays on the Characteristics (J. Brown, 1751), 83-go; referred to, 205. 
 Ethical Studies (F. H. Bradley, 1876), referred to, 376 «., 381. 
 Ethics, the possible Methods of: Sidgwick, 372 ff. 
 Ethics of Individual Life, The: Part III. of The Principles of Ethics (Spencer, 
 
 1892), 346 ff.
 
 Index. 42 1 
 
 Ethology, J. S. Mill's proposed science of, 224 ff., 263. 
 
 Evil, the evanescence of : Spencer, 277 ff. 
 
 Evolution : the significance of, for Ethics, 268 ff. ; of conduct, Spencer, 293 ff. ; 
 identified with progress by Spencer, 295, 319; of society, Spencer's view of, 
 315 ff. ; Spencer's Ethics, how far dependent upon the theory of, 318 ff., 
 323, 341 ff., 348, 354, 356. 
 
 Fable of the Bees, The : or, Private Vices Public Benefits (B. Mandeville, 1714). 
 
 referred to, 64, 85. 
 Fouillde, A., referred to, 222. 
 Fowler, T., referred to, 83. 
 
 Fragment on Government, A (Bentham, 1776), 175, 176, 182. 
 Freedom of Wit and Humour, An Essay on the (Shaftesbury, 1709), quoted, 55, 
 
 56. 
 
 Gay, John, 69-83 ; referred to, 27, 90, 91, no, in, 112, 114, 126, 130, 131, 133, 
 
 136, 142, 145, 147, 161, 162, 166, 167, 170, 171, 172, 174, 178, 179, 180, 182, 
 
 189, 201,323, 414. 
 General rules, the necessity of: Berkeley, 67; Tucker, 148, 159; Paley, 172; 
 
 (hardly recognised by) Bentham, 187 ff. ; J. S. Mill, 217, 249 ff. ; Spencer, 
 
 279 ff., 319 ff., 353. 
 Good, The: More, 12, 13 ; Cumberland, 28-35, 49 J Locke, 53 ; Shaftesbury, 57, 
 
 58 ; Hutcheson, 60-62 ; Berkeley, 65 ; Gay, 74, 79 ; Brown, 84, 85 ; Hume, 
 
 100 ff. ; Hartley, i2i ff. ; Tucker, 147 ff. ; Paley, 170 ft'. ; Bentham, 179 ff. ; 
 
 J. S. Mill, 251 ff. ; Spencer, 295 ff., 315, 320,324; Sidgwick, 398 ff., 405, 
 
 408 ff. 
 Green, T. H., referred to, 381. 
 Grotius, 2-4 ; referred to, 11, 27, 36 n. 
 Guizot, referred to, 213, 214, 263. 
 
 Happiness : treatment of, Cumberland, 30-32 ; Gay, 74, 79 ; Brown, 87 ff. ; 
 Hartley, 121 ff. ; Tucker, 137 ft"., 147 ft". ; Paley, 170 ff. ; Bentham, 179 ff., 
 184 ff. ; Spencer, 270 ff. ; general conditions to the greatest, Spencer, 279 
 ff. ; ambiguity of the conception of, according to Spencer, 283 ff., 353 ; 
 general treatment of, Sidgwick, 386 ff. ; the thing ultimately desirable, 
 Sidgwick, 408 ft". {See " Qualitative Distinctions ".) 
 
 Hartley, 113-129; referred to, 73, 82 «., 130, 131, 133, 134, 135, 145, 149, 161, 
 162, 163, 166, 180, 197, 202, 204, 242, 382. 
 
 Hedonistic Calculus : difficulties of the, not mentioned by Cumberland or 
 Gay, 82; referred to by Hartley, 126; emphasised by Tucker, 149 ff. ; 
 Bentham's elaborate treatment of the, 184 ff. ; regarded as impossible by 
 Spencer, 271, 274, 319; considered by Sidgwick, 387, 389. {See " Qualita- 
 tive Distinctions ".) 
 
 History: J. S. Mill's attitude toward the Philosophy of, 211 ff.; Spencer's 
 contempt for, 292, 307 w. 
 
 Hobbes, 4-9; referred to, 15 «., 16, 20, 21, 22, 23, 25, 27, 29, 36, 43, 44, 46, no, 
 in, 154, 161, 171, 363, 378, 382, 383.
 
 422 Index. 
 
 Hume, 91-112; referred to, 70, 73, 78 «., 82 «., 113, 126, 130, 133, 135, 146, 154, 
 
 155. 157. i6i, 183, 189, 254, 382. 
 Hutcheson, 58-63 ; referred to, 54 n., 64, 70, 71, 76, 78, 82, 91, 92, 97, in, 140 
 
 M., 149, 150, 181, 251. 
 
 Immortality, J. S. Mill on, 239 ff. 
 
 Inductions of Ethics : Part II. of The Principles of Ethics (Spencer, 1892), 
 
 345 ff. 
 
 Inheritance of acquired characteristics, Spencer's dependence upon the prin- 
 ciple of, 308 fif., 313. 
 
 Innate Ideas: in More's system, 12; denied by Cumberland, 16; explanation 
 of so-called, by Gay, 76 ; the similar explanation by Tucker, 136 fif., 147 ; 
 Bentham's attitude toward the doctrine of, 178 ff. ; J. S. Mill's different 
 attitude toward the same, 207, 249 ff., 265 ; the doctrine of, not wholly 
 rejected by Spencer at first, 273, 282, 284; Spencer's later attitude toward 
 the same, 310 ff., 346 ; Sidgwick's exhaustive examination of the doctrine 
 of, 389 ff. 
 
 Inquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, An (Hume, 1751), 93 ff. ; relation 
 of the, to the Treatise of Human Nature (Book III.), 93 ff. ; referred to, 70, 
 82 M., 130, 133 w., 154, 161 ff. 
 
 Inquiry concerning Virtue, or Merit, An (Shaftesbury [1699], 171 1), 55 ff. ; re- 
 ferred to, 70. {See " Shaftesbury ".) 
 
 Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue, An (Hutcheson, 
 1725), 58 ff. ; referred to, 70. (See " Hutcheson ".) 
 
 Intuitionism : concessions to, by Spencer in Social Statics, 273, 282, 284; 
 Spencer's later rejection of, 310 ff., 346 ; Sidg\vick's treatment of, 373, 377 ; 
 as a Method of Ethics, 389 ff. ; the weakness of ordinary, 393 ; the truth in, 
 394 ff. ; SidgAvick's conclusions examined and criticised, 401 ff. 
 
 Jurisprudence, the relation between, and Ethics; Bentham, 176. 
 
 Justice: the virtue of, Hume, 103-105; Tucker, 157 ff . ; J. S. Mill, 259 ff. ; 
 Spencer, 280 ff. ; primacy of, according to Spencer, 283 ff., 328 ; evolution 
 of, Spencer, 330 ff. ; origin of the conception of, Spencer, 333 ff. ; Spencer's 
 formula for, 338 ; how dependent upon evolution, 341 ff. ; treated by 
 Spencer practically as an intuition, 343, 355 ; ambiguity of our notions 
 concerning, Sidgwick, 391 ; Sidgu'ick's formula for the " intuition " of, 
 396 ; the very abstract character of same, 403 ff. 
 
 jfustice : Part IV. of The Principles of Ethics (Spencer, 1891), 329-344. 
 
 Kant, referred to, 189, 253, 254, 363, 394, 395, 399. 
 
 Laws of Nature: Grotius, 2-4; Hobbes, 6-9; Cumberland, 15-18, 35-42,49; 
 
 Locke, 53 ; Berkeley, 67, 68 ; not mentioned by Gay, 81 ; nor by Brown, 
 
 89 ; referred to by Paley, 173. 
 Leviathan ; or, The Matter, Form, and Power of a Commonwealth (Hobbes, 165 1), 
 
 5ff.
 
 Index. 423 
 
 Liberty, On (J. S. Mill, 1859), 242 ff., 265. 
 
 Light of Nature, The: pursued by Edward Search (Tucker, 1768-1777), 131- 
 
 164; referred to, 70, 166, 335. 
 Locke, 52-54; referred to, 19M., 78, 132, 133, 138, 146, 147, 199. 
 
 Mandeville, B., referred to, 64, 85. 
 
 Manichjean doctrine, J. S. Mill's attitude toward the, 196, 232 iT., 235. 
 
 Merit, Gay's explanation of, 75. 
 
 Methods of Ethics, The (Sidgwick, 1874), 358-417. {See " Sidgwick ".) 
 
 Methods of Ethics, the three principal, according to Sidgwick, 372 ff. ; criticism 
 of Sidgwick's classification, 376 ff., 381 ff. 
 
 Michelet, referred to, 213, 214, 263. 
 
 Mill, James, referred to, 193, 194, 195, 196, 203, 224. 
 
 Mill, J. S., 193-267 ; referred to, 62, 83, 177 »., 190, 269, 297, 360, 361, 366, 367, 
 368, 370, 382, 395, 399, 417. 
 
 Moral Sense, the : Shaftesbury, 56 ff. ; Hutcheson, 58-60, 62 ; supposed indi- 
 cations of, explained by Gay, 76 ; and in a similar way by Tucker, 136 ff., 
 147; Hartley's derivation of, 127 ff. ; existence of, admitted at first by 
 Spencer, 272 ff. ; then reduced to the " instinct of personal rights," 284; 
 tacitly given up in Data of Ethics, 310 ff.,328 ; and explicitly in Inductions 
 of Ethics, 346. 
 
 Moral Sense Ethics, the : regarded as dangerous by certain contemporary 
 theologians, 64 ff. ; Hume's supposed relation to, 92, 98, 112; Spencer's 
 earlier attitude toward, 273, 282 ff. 
 
 Moralists, The : a Philosophical Rhapsody (Shaftesbury, 1709), quoted, 55. 
 
 More, Henry, 11-14. 
 
 Motive, the moral : Cumberland, 25-27, 40 ff., 48 ; Shaftesbury, 55 ff. ; Hutche- 
 son, 59 ff. ; Berkeley, 65 ; Gay, 71 ff., 75, 79 ; Brown, 85 ff. ; Hartley, 119, 
 125, 127; Tucker, 137 ff., 144, 150 ff., 156, 160; treatment of, by Gay, 
 Hume, Hartley, and Tucker compared, 161 ff. ; Paley, 170 ff . ; Bentham, 
 180 ff., 375 ; J. S. Mill, 201, 204, 253 ff., 257, 266 ; Spencer, 321 ff. ; Sidg- 
 wick, 363 ff., 367 ft-., 372. 
 
 Nature : of Things, Cumberland's conception of the, 19, 20, 23, 24 : the state of, 
 Hobbes, 5, 6 ; Shaftesbury's criticism of Hobbes' view of same, 55 : human, 
 Grotius, 2-4 ; Hobbes, 5 ff. ; Cumberland, 20-27 ; Shaftesbury, 55 ff. ; Hume, 
 97 ff. ; J. S. Mill's proposed science of, i.e., Ethology, 223 ff. ; Spencer's 
 earlier conception of, 285 ff. ; his later conception of same, 322 ff. : the 
 order of, not a moral order, J. S. Mill, 231 ff. ; Mill's more consistent posi- 
 tion regarding same, 254 ff., 266. (See " Laws of Nature ".) 
 
 Nature (J. S. Mill, 1874), 228-236, 264. 
 
 Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence : Parts V. and VL of The Prin- 
 ciples of Ethics (Spencer, 1893), 347 ff. ; quoted, 270. 
 
 Negative Beneficence: Spencer, 280 ; relation of, to Justice, 283, 328 ; Spencer's 
 later treatment of, 347 ff.
 
 424 Index. 
 
 Obligation : Cumberland, 37-40 ; Berkeley, 67 ; Gay, 72 ff., 80 ; Brown, 89 ff. ; 
 
 Hume, 109 ff. ; Tucker, 151 ff. ; Bentham, 167 ff., 189; Paley, 170 ff. ; 
 
 evanescence of the feeling of, Spencer, 313 ff. ; the feeling of, not reducible 
 
 to other terms, Sidgwick, 364, 366 ; the problem of, inconsistently treated 
 
 by Sidgwick, 413 ff. 
 Observations on Man, his Frame, his Duty, and his Expectations (Hartley, 1749), 
 
 113-129; referred to, 130, 145, 163. 
 Origin of Species, On the (Darwin, 1859), referred to, 268, 269, 290. 
 
 Paley : 168-174 ; referred to, i, 70, 72, 78, 80, 81, 90, 91, 94 n., 97, 112, 126, 
 148, 154, 163, 165, 166, 167, 175, 180, 183, 184, 189, 191, 199, 209 ; mis- 
 understood at first by J. S. Mill, 200 ff. ; the mistake tacitly corrected 
 later, 205. 
 
 Passive Obedience (Berkeley, 1712), 65 ff. ; referred to, 83, 191. 
 
 Perfection : Cumberland's conception of, 29, 33 ; the significance of, in Shaftes- 
 bury's system, 57 ff. ; in Hutcheson's system, 61 ff. ; in Hartley's system, 
 122 ff. ; in J. S. Mill's system, 248 ff., 251 ff., 265 ; in Spencer's system, 
 274 ff. {See " Perfect Society".) Sidgwick's examination of, as the end 
 of action, 373 ff., 377 ff. 
 
 Perfect Society : the conception of a, regarded by Spencer as the necessary 
 postulate of Scientific Ethics, 274 ff., 278, 288, 323, 327 ; difficulties of this 
 position, 276 ff., 304, 306 ff., 317, 327 ; Spencer's original position re- 
 affirmed, 346. 
 
 " Physical view " of Morality, Spencer's, 300 ff. 
 
 Pleasures : Hartley's account of the genesis of the " intellectual," and pains, 
 118 ff. ; Tucker's account of the genesis of the so-called "higher," by 
 " translation," 140 ff. ; Bentham's arbitrary classification of, 186. (See 
 " Qualitative Distinctions ".) 
 
 Positive Beneficence: Spencer, 280; relation of, to Justice, 283, 328; Spencer's 
 later treatment of, 347 ff. 
 
 Preliminary Dissertation : concerning the Fundamental Principle of Virtue or 
 Morality (Gay, 1731), 69-83; referred to, 85 «., 91, 114, 130, 131, 135, 147, 
 161, 163, 166, 170, 174, 182. {See "Gay".) 
 
 Priestley, J., referred to, 166. 
 
 Principles of Ethics, The (Spencer, 1879-1893), 292-352. {See " Data of Ethics," 
 "Inductions of Ethics," "Ethics of Individual Life," "justice," and 
 " Negative Beneficence and Positive Beneficence ".) 
 
 Principles of Morals and Legislation, An Introduction to the (Bentham [1780], 
 1789), 175 ff. ; referred to, 167. {See " Bentham ".) 
 
 Principles of Moral and Political Philosophy, The (Paley, 1785), 168-174; re- 
 ferred to, 70, 175, 180, 191. {See " Paley ".) 
 
 Progress, human : regarded as a necessity by Spencer, 278, 288, 323. {See 
 " Perfect Society ".) 
 
 Prolegomena to Ethics (T. H. Green, 1883), referred to, 381. 
 
 Property, the right to : Cumberland, 44-47 ; Hume, 103 ft'. ; Tucker, 157 ; 
 Paley, 173 ; Spencer, 337 ft"., 344.
 
 Index. 425 
 
 Prudence : regarded by Tucker as the principal virtue, 155 ff. ; Hume's treatment 
 of, 105 ff. ; Bentham's distinction between " self-regarding " and " extra- 
 regarding," 183 ; the importance of, emphasised by Spencer, 280, 346 ff. ; 
 Sidgwick's " intuition " of, 397, 401, 404, 409. 
 
 " Psychological view " of Morality, Spencer's, 309 ft'. 
 
 Punishment, the Utilitarian Theory of, developed by Tucker, 158 ff". 
 
 " Qualitative Distinctions " (between pleasures) : affirmed by Hutcheson, 61 ; 
 not mentioned by Berkeley, 68 ; would have no meaning for Gay, 79 ; 
 inconsistently admitted by Hartley, 122, 129 ; explicitly denied by Tucker, 
 139 ff., 162 ; also by Paley, 170 ; and by Bentham, 179; reaffirmed by J. S. 
 Mill, 251 ff"., 265 ; denied by Sidgwick, 387. 
 
 Reason : " Right," Grotius, 3 ff". ; Hobbes, 6, 9 ; Cudworth, 10 ; More, n ii. ; 
 Cumberland, 22-25 \ morality not founded on, but on sentiment, Hume, 91 
 ff". ; the function of, in the moral life, Sidgwick, 362 ff. ; ambiguity in 
 Sidgwick's use of, 365 ff". ; dualism of the Practical, according to Sidgwick, 
 412 ff". 
 
 Reasonableness of Christianity , The (Locke, 1695), 53. 
 
 Relative and Absolute Ethics, Spencer, 323 ft"., 351. 
 
 Religion, the essence of: Brown, 89 ; J. S. Mill, 240. 
 
 Sanctions: Berkeley's dependence upon theological, 69; Brown's, 89 ff. ; 
 
 Paley's, 171 ; J. S. Mill's view of the true, 255 ff. ; Spencer's treatment of 
 
 the, 309 ff". 
 " Satisfaction " and " Dissatisfaction," Tucker's use of the terms, 134, 138, 
 
 147 ff. 
 Schurman, J. G., quoted, 344. 
 Sedgwick, A., criticised by J. S. Mill, 199 ff. 
 Selby-Bigge, L. A., referred to, 92 n. ; quoted, 98. 
 Self-development: the ideal of, in Shaftesbury's system, 57; J, S. Mill on the 
 
 importance of harmonious, 248 ff., 265 ; Sidgwick on the ideal of, 375 ft"., 
 
 378 ff. 
 Self-interest, the ruling principle : Berkeley, 65 ff. ; Gay, 73 ; Brown, 85 ff". ; 
 
 Tucker, 151 ft". ; Paley, 170 ft". ; Bentham, 180 ff. 
 Self-preservation, the principle of: in Hobbes, 6, 7 ; significance of same in 
 
 Cumberland, 29, 43 ; treated by Sidgwick as one form of Egoism, 378. 
 Self-realisation : relation of Shaftesbury's system to the doctrine of, 57 ; Sidg- 
 wick's criticism of, as a Method of Ethics, 375 ff., 378 ff. 
 Sermons upon Human Nature (Butler, 1726), referred to, 133. (See " Butler ".) 
 Shaftesbury, 54-58 ; referred to, 59, 61, 62, 63, 64, 70, 78, 79, 84, 85, 88, gi, in, 
 
 181, 234. 
 Sidgwick, 358-417 ; quoted, 2, 3, 33, 50 n. ; referred to, 5 n., 10, 13 «., 57 w., 259, 
 
 260 n. 
 Smith, A., criticised by Spencer, 284 ff. 
 
 27*
 
 426 Index. 
 
 Social Statics ; or. The Conditions Essential to Human Happiness Specified, and 
 the First of Them Developed (Spencer, 1^51), 270-291 ; referred to, 150 »., 
 269, 294. 293, 298, 306, 316 ff., 320, 324, 327 ff., 333 ft"., 336, 338 ff., 345, 346, 
 349. 353. 354. 355. 356. 358, 387 ft. 
 
 " Sociological view " of Morality, Spencer's, 315 ft. 
 
 Society, as an organism, Cumberland, 18, 21, 35, h7. (Cf. Shaftesbury, 55 ft.) 
 
 Spaulding, F. E., referred to, 22 «., 33. 
 
 Spencer, 268-357 ; referred to, 259 ;«., 260, 361, 387, 388, 389, 391. 
 
 Spinoza, referred to, 378. 
 
 Stephen, L., referred to, 21, 29, 193 n., 362. 
 
 Sympathy: in Grotius, 3; denied by Hobbes, 5 ff. ; in Cumberland, 21 ft"., 25 ; 
 differently treated by Hume in Treatise {^V.. III.) and in Inquiry, g$ ff. ; 
 Hume's later treatment of, 102, 108; Hartley's derivation of, rig ff. ; his 
 inconsistent treatment of, 129; Tucker's derivation of, 141 ff. ; his treatment 
 of, 154 ; Paley's treatment of, 171 ; Bentham's failure to explain his position 
 regarding, iSr ; regarded as original by J. S. Mill, 201, 256; necessary to 
 explain moral judgments, Spencer, 285 ; development of, Spencer, 322 ff., 
 335 ; Sidgwick follows Butler in his treatment of, 370 ff. 
 
 System, Man part of a : Cumberland, 18, 24, 48 ; Shaftesbury, 55. {See 
 " Evolution of Conduct ".) 
 
 System of Logic, A : Ratiocinative and Inductive [Bk. VI., " On the Logic of 
 the Moral Sciences"] (J. S. Mill, 1843), 214, 219 ft"., 263. 
 
 System of Moral Philosophy, A (Hutcheson, 1755), 58 ft". 
 
 Theism (J. S. Mill, 1874), 228, 260 »., 261 «. 
 
 Theological Utilitarianism : Berkeley, 64 ff. ; Gay, 69 ft". ; Brown, 83 ft". ; Tucker, 
 130 ff. ; Paley, 165 ff. 
 
 Theology, Natural, J. S. Mill's attitude toward, 234 ff. 
 
 Theory of Moral Sentiments, The (A. Smith, 1759), criticised by Spencer, 284 ft". 
 
 " Trains " of ideas, Tucker's account of, 135 ft". 
 
 " Translation," Tucker's theory of, 136 ft"., 140 ff., 159 ff. (Cf. Gay's anticipa- 
 tion of the theory, 76 ff.) 
 
 Treatise concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality, A (Cudworth, 173 1), 10, 
 II. 
 
 Treatise of Human Nature, A (Hume, 1739-40), 93 ft". ; relation of, to Inquiry, 
 94 ; referred to, 70, 82 «., 113, 129, 130, 133 »., 161. 
 
 Tucker, 130-164; referred to, 27, 70, 72, 78, 80, 82, 83, 91, 97, 112, 114, 126, 165, 
 166, 167, 171, 172, 173, 174, 179, 180, 183, 184, 189, 335. 
 
 Utilitarian formula, the : used by Hutcheson, 60 ff. ; not used by Gay, 82 ; 
 Bentham's use of, 180. 
 
 Utilitarianism (J. S. Mill, 1861-63), 249-260, 265 ff. ; referred to, 198, 367, 395. 
 
 Utilitarianism : the term, first used by J. S. Mill, 197 ; the later form of, inaugu- 
 rated by Mill, 209, 212 ; Mill's proof of, 256 ff. ; Sidgwick's criticism of same, 
 395 ff. ; Sidgwick's proof of, 398 ff. ; difficulties involved in same, 404 ff., 
 409 ff. 
 
 Utility of Religion (J. S. Mill, 1874), 236-241, 264.
 
 Index. 427 
 
 Vibrations, Hartley's theory of, 115 ff. 
 
 Virtue : Shaftesbury's conception of, 55 ff. ; practically identified with benevo- 
 lence by Hutcheson, 59 ff. ; Gay's definition of, 71 ; cf. Paley's definition of, 
 170. {^ee " The Good ".) 
 
 Virtues : classification of the, Cumberland, 41 ; Hume, 105 ff. ; Hartley, 121 ff. ; 
 Tucker, 155 ; Paley, 172 n. ; Bentham, 183 ; Spencer, 280 ff., 327, 346 ff. ; 
 " natural " and " artificial," Hume's distinction between, 99 ff. 
 
 Whewell : J. S. Mill's criticism of, 214 ff., 264 ; quoted, 130 «., 175 ; referred 
 
 to, 10, II n., 52 «., 223. 
 Will : Cumberland's theory of the, 22, 25, 41 ; Associationist theory of the. 
 
 Hartley, 115, ng ; Tucker, 133 ff., 137 ff., 143 ff. ; J. S. Mill, 257 ff. {See 
 
 "The Moral Motive " and " Theory of Desire ".) 
 Wollaston, referred to, 84. 
 
 THE ABERDEEN UNIVERSITY PRESS LIMITED.
 
 Cf)e litJtatp of p{)ilo0op6p 
 
 Edited by J. H. MUIRHEAD, M.A., LL.D. 
 
 Professor of Philosophy in the University of Birmingham 
 
 THE LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY is in the first 
 instance a contribution to the History of Thought. 
 While much has been done in England in tracing the course 
 of evolution in nature, history, religion and morality, com- 
 paratively little has been done in tracing the development 
 of Thought upon these and kindred subjects, and yet " the 
 evolution of opinion is part of the whole evolution." 
 
 This Library will deal mainly with Modern Philosophy, 
 partly because Ancient Philosophy has already had a fair 
 share of attention in this country through the labours of 
 Grote, Ferrier, Benn, and others, and through translations 
 from Zeller ; partly because the Library does not profess 
 to give a complete history of thought. 
 
 By the co-operation of different writers in carrying out 
 this plan, it is hoped that a completeness and thorough- 
 ness of treatment otherwise unattainable will be secured. 
 It is believed, also, that from writers mainly English and 
 American fuller consideration of English Philosophy than 
 it has hitherto received from the great German Histories 
 of Philosophy may be looked for. In the departments of 
 Ethics, Economics, and Politics, for instance, the contri- 
 butions of English writers to the common stock of theoretic 
 discussion have been especially valuable, and these subjects 
 will accordingly have special prominence in this undertaking.
 
 THE LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Another feature in the plan of the Library is its arrange- 
 ment according to subjects rather than authors and dates, 
 enabling the writers to follow out and exhibit in a way 
 hitherto unattempted the results of the logical development 
 of particular lines of thought. 
 
 The historical portion of the Library is divided into 
 two sections, of which the first contains works upon the 
 development of particular schools of Philosophy, while 
 the second exhibits the history of theory in particular 
 departments. 
 
 To these have been added, by way of Introduction to 
 the whole Library, (i) an English translation of Erdmann's 
 History of Philosophy, long since recognised in Germany as 
 the best; (2) translations of standard foreign works upon 
 Philosophy. 
 
 J. H. MUIRHEAD, 
 
 General Editor. 
 
 ALREA D Y PUBL I SHED Demy Svo, Cloth 
 
 THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. By Dr. Johann Eduard 
 Erdman.n. 
 
 English Translation. Edited by WiLLlSTON S. Hough, M.Ph., Professor 
 of Mental and Moral Philosophy and Logic in the University of Minnesota. 
 
 Vol. I. ANCIENT AND MEDI/EVAL PHILOSOPHY. 15s. 
 
 [ Third Edition. 
 
 Vol. IL MODERN PHILOSOPHY. 15s. {Fifth Edition. 
 
 Vol. III. MODERN PHILOSOPHY, SINCE HEGEL. 12s. 
 
 [ Third Edition. 
 
 THE HISTORY OF ^ESTHETIC. By Bernard Bosanquet, 
 
 M.A., LL.D., late Fellow of University College, Oxford, los. 6d. net. 
 
 {Third Edition.
 
 THE LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHY 
 THE DEVELOPMENT OF RATIONAL THEOLOGY SINCE 
 
 KANT. By Professor Otto Pfleiderer, of Berlin. los. 6d. net. 
 
 [Third Edition. 
 
 PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICAL ECONOMY IN SOME OF 
 THEIR HISTORICAL RELATIONS. By James Bonar, M.A., LL.D. 
 los. 6d. net. \_SeiOiid Edition. 
 
 APPEARANCE AND REALITY. By F. H. Bradley, M.A., 
 
 Fellow of Merton College, Oxford. 12s. net. {.Second Edition. 
 
 NATURAL RIGHTS. By David G. Ritchie, Professor of Logic 
 and Metaphysics in the University of St. Andrews. los. 6d. net. 
 
 ANALYTIC PSYCHOLOGY. By G. F. Stout, M.A., Fellow of 
 St. John's College, Cambridge, Wilde Reader in Mental Philosophy, Oxford. 
 2 vols. 21s.net. [Third Edition. 
 
 A HISTORY OF ENGLISH UTILITARIANISM. By Ernest 
 
 Albee, Ph.D., Instructor in the Sage School of Philosophy, Cornell University, 
 los. 6d. net. 
 
 CONTEMPORARY PSYCHOLOGY. By Professor Guido Villa, 
 Lecturer on Philosophy in the University of Rome. Authorised Translation. 
 los. 6d. net. 
 
 THOUGHT AND THINGS: a Study of the Development and 
 Meaning of Thought or Genetic Logic. By James Mark Baldwin, 
 Ph.D., Hon. D.Sc. (Oxon.), LL.D. (Glasgow), Professor in the Johns Hopkins 
 University. 
 Vol. L FUNCTIONAL LOGIC; or, Genetic Theory of Knowledge. 
 
 los. 6d. net. 
 Vol. n. EXPERIMENTAL LOGIC, ios.6d.net. 
 Vol. HI. REAL LOGIC. Part L Genetic Epistemology. ios.6d.net. 
 Vol. IV. REAL LOGIC. Part H. (in preparation). 
 
 VALUATION : ITS NATURE AND LAWS. Being an Intro 
 duction to the General Theory of Value. By Wilbur Marshall Urban, Ph.D.. 
 Professor of Philosophy, Trinity College, Hartford, Conn. los. 6d. net. 
 
 ATTENTION. By Prof. W. B. Pillsbury, University of Michigan, 
 los. 6d. net. 
 
 TIME AND FREE WILL. By Prof. Henri Bergson. Translated 
 from the French by F. L. PoGSON, St. John's College, Oxford. los. 6d. net. 
 
 [Second Edition. 
 
 HEGEL'S PHENOMENOLOGY OF MIND. Translated by Prof. 
 J. B. Baillie. 2 vols. 2LS. net. 
 
 MATTER AND MEMORY. By Prof. Henri Bergson. Trans- 
 lated by N. ^L Paul and W. Scott Palmer. 10s. 6d. net. [Second Edition. 
 
 PSYCHOLOGY OF THE RELIGIOUS LIFE. By Prof. G. M. 
 
 Stratton, University of California, los. 6d. net.
 
 PRESS NOTICES OF 
 ERDMANN'S HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 
 
 PALL MALL GAZETTE 
 
 "A splendid monument of patient labour, critical acumen, and 
 admirable methodical treatment." 
 
 Professor JOHN WATSON, in THE WEEK, of Canada 
 
 " It is not nccessarv to speak of the great merits of Erdmanij's 
 History of Philosophy. Its remarkable clearness and comprehensive- 
 ness are well known. . . . The translation is a good, faithful 
 rendering, and in some parts even reaches a high literary level." 
 
 SCOTSMAN 
 
 "... It mu->t prove a valuable and much-needed addition to 
 our philosophical works." 
 
 Professor JOHN DEWEY, in THE AN DOVER REVIEW 
 
 "To the student who wishes, not simply a general idea of the 
 course of philosoph)-, nor a summary of what this and that man has 
 said, but a somewhat detailed knowledge of the evolution of thought, 
 and of what this and the other writer have contributed to it, 
 Erdmann is indispensable ; there is no substitute." 
 
 JOURNAL OF EDUCATION 
 
 " It is a work that is at once compact enough for the ordinary 
 student, and full enough for the reader of literature. ... At once 
 systematic and interesting." 
 
 SPECTA TOR 
 
 " The translation into English of Erdmann's History of Philosophy 
 is an important event in itself, and in the fact that it is the first 
 instalment of an undertaking of great significance for the study 
 of philosophy in this country. Apart, however, from its relation 
 to the Library to which it is to serve as an introduction, the trans- 
 lation of Erdmann's History of Philosophy is something for which the 
 English student ought to be thankful. . . . Such a History, able, 
 competent, trustworthy, we have now in our hands, adequately and 
 worthily rendereJ into our mother-tongue." 
 
 GEORGE ALLEN & COMPANY, LTD., LONDON 
 THE MACMILLAN COMPANY, NEW YORK
 
 •'^•tf 
 
 S,^["ERN REGIONAL 
 
 ^ ^ oorz'''Sfw^^^^^^^^ 
 
 mIK^P'^C/L/TY