3 1822 01164 0430 LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CfLlFORH'* SAN DIEGO U\ JOLLA, CALIFORNIA AN DIEGO 3 1822 01 64 0430 o,r. ^ A^ THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED ^ r^ /^n /^ r^ / Ilrprintcb, foith ^bbitions, from " (ibc Contcm}jorunt licbicb." WJ/jr^ ^^^ Uc^^n'^^ THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED Comprising some Retnarks on Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy and on Mr. J. S. Mill's Examination of that Philosophy By H. L. M^NSEL, b.d. VVAYNFLETE I'ROFESSOR OF MOKAL AND METAPHYSICAL PHILOSOrHV IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD ^%#- ALEXANDER STRAHAN, PUBLISHER LONDON AND NEW YORK 1 866 MUIR AND PATERSON, PKINTEllS, EDINBURGH. PREFACE. The circumstance that the following remarks were originally published as an anonymous article in a Review, will best explain the style in which they are written. Absence from England prevented me from becoming acquainted with Mr, Mill's Examination of Sir William Hamilton s Philosophy till some time after its publication ; and when I was requested to undertake the task of reviewing it, 1 was still ignorant of its contents. On proceeding to fulfil my engagement, I soon VI PREFACE. discovered, not only that the character of the book was very different from what the author's reputation had led me to expect, but also tlmt my task would be one, not merely of criticism, but, in some degree, of self-defence. The remarks on myself, coming from a writer of Mr. Mill's ability and repu- tation, were such as I could not pass over without notice ; while, at the same time, I felt that my principal duty in this instance was the defence of one who was no longer living to defend himself. Under these cir- cumstances, the best course appeared to be, to devote the greater portion of my article to an exposition and vindication of Sir W. Hamilton's teaching ; and, in the additional remarks which it was necessary to make on the more personal part of the controversy, to speak of myself in the third person, as PREFxVCE. Vll I should have spoken of any other writer. The form thus adopted has been retained in the present republication, though the article now a^^pears with the name of its author. My original intention of writing a review of the entire book was necessarily abandoned as soon as I became acquainted with its contents. To liave done justice to the wdiole subject, or to Mr. Mill's treatment of it, would have required a volume nearly as large as his own. I therefore determined to confine myself to the Philosophy of the Conditioned, both as the most original and important portion of Sir W. Hamilton's teaching, and as that which occupies the first place in Mr. Mill's Examination. THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE CONDITIONED. rriHE reader of Plato's Republic will readily recall to mind that wonderful passage at the end of the sixth book, in which the philosopher, under the image of geometrical lines, exhibits the various re- lations of the intelligible to the sensible world ; especially his lofty aspirations with regard to '* that second segment of the in- telligible world, which reason of itself grasps by the power of dialectic, employing hypo- theses, not as principles, but as veritable A 2 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. hypotheses, that is to say, as steps and starting-points, in order that it may ascend as far as the unconditioned (i^^xP'^ '^^^^ awn-o- Qiroii), to the first principle of the universe, and having grasped this, may then hiy hold of the principles next adjacent to it, and so go dov^n to the end, using no sensible aids whatever, but employing abstract forms throughout, and terminating in forms." This quotation is important for our present purpose in two ways. In the first place, it may serve, at the outset of our remarks, to propitiate those plain-spoken English critics who look upon new terms in philosophy with the same suspicion with which Jack Cade regarded •" a noun and a verb, and such abominable words as no Christian ear can endure to hear," by showing that the head and front of our offending, "the Uncondi- The PJiilosopliy of the Conditioned. 3 tioned," is no modern invention of Teutonic barbarism, but sanctioned even by the Attic elegance of a Plato. And in the second place, it contains almost a histoiy in minia- ture of the highest speculations of philo- sophy, both in earlier and in later times, and points out, with a clearness and precision the more valuable because uninfluenced by recent controversies, the exact field on which the philosophies of the Conditioned and the Unconditioned come into collision, and the nature of the problem which they both ap- proach from opposite sides. What is the meaning of this problem, the solution of which Plato proposes as the highest aim of philosophy — '' to ascend to the unconditioned, and thence to deduce the universe of conditioned existence I " The problem has assumed different forms at dif- 4 TJie PJiilosopJiy of the Conditio7ied. ferent times : at present we must content ourselves with stating it in that in wliich it "svill most naturally suggest itself to a student of modem philosophy, and in which it has the most direct bearing on the sub- ject of the present article. All consciousness must in the first instance present itself as a relation between two con- stituent parts, the person who is conscious, and the thing, whatever it may be, of which he is conscious. This contrast has been in- dicated, directly or indirectly, by various names — mind and matter ; person and thing ; subject and object ; or, lastly, in the dis- tinction, most convenient for philosophy, how- ever uncouth in sound, between self and not self— the ego and the non-ego. In order to be conscious at all, I must be conscious of something : consciousness thus presents itself The Philosophy of the Coiiditioned. 5 as the product of two factors, / and somie- thing. The problem of the unconditioned is, briefly stated, to reduce these two factors to one. For it is manifest that, so long as they remain two, we have no unconditioned, but a pair of conditioned existences. If the some- thing of Avhich I am conscious is a separate reality, having qualities and modes of action of its own, and thereby determining, or con- tributing to determine, the form which my consciousness of it shall take, my conscious- ness is thereby conditioned, or partly de- pendent on something beyond itself. It is no matter, in this respect, whether the in- fluence is direct or indirect — whether, for instance, I see a material tree, or only the mental image of a tree. If the nature of the thing in any degree determines the char- 6 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. acter of the imaofe — if tlie visible form of a tree is different from that of a house because the tree itself is different from the house, my consciousness is, however remotely, influenced by something different from itself, the ego by the non-ego. And on the other hand, if I, who am conscious, am a real being, distinct from the things of which I am conscious — if the conscious mind has a constitution and laws of its own by wliich it acts, and if the mode of its consciousness is in any degree determined by those laws, the non-ego is so far conditioned by the ego ; the thing which I see is not seen absolutely and j^9c^r se, but in a form partly dependent uj)on the laws of my vision. The first step towards the reduction of these two factors to one may obviously be made in three different ways. Either the The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 7 eqo may be represented as a mode of the non- ego, or the non-ecjo of the ecjo, or both of a tertium quid, distinct from either. In other words : it may be maintained, Jirst, that matter is the only real existence ; mind and all the phenomena of consciousness being really the result solely of material laws ; the brain, for example, secreting thought as the liver secretes bile ; and the distinct personal existence of which I am apparently conscious being only the result of some such secretion. This is Materialism, which has then to ad- dress itself to the further problem, to reduce the various phenomena of matter to some one absolutely first principle on which every- thing else depends. Or it may be main- tained, secondly, that mind is the only real existence ; the intercourse which we appar- ently have with a material world being really 8 The Philosophy of the Coiiditioncd. the result solely of the laws of our mental constitution. This is Idealism, which again has next to attempt to reduce the various phenomena to some one immaterial principle. Or it may be maintained, tlmxlly, that real existence is to be sought neither in mind as mind nor in matter as matter ; that both classes of phenomena are but equalities or modes of operation of something distinct from both, and on which both alike are dependent. Hence arises a third form of philosophy, which, for want of a better name, we will call Indifferentism, as being a system in which the characteristic dif- ferences of mind and matter are su23j)osed to disappear, being merged in something higher than both. In using the two former of these terms, we are not speaking of Materialism and Ideal- The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 9 ism as they have always actually manifested themselves, but only of the distinguishing principle of these systems when pushed tf> its extreme result. It is quite possible to be a materialist or an idealist with respect to the immediate phenomena of consciousness, without attempting a philosophy of the Un- conditioned at all. But it is also possible, and in itself natural, when such a philosophy is attempted, to attempt it by means of the same method which has approved itself in relation to subordinate inquiries ; to make the relation between the human mind and its objects the type and image of that be- tween the universe and its first principle. And such attempts have actually been made, both on the side of Materialism and on that of Idealism ; and probably would be made oftener, did not counteracting causes fre- I o The Philosophy of the Conditioned. quently hinder the logical development of speculative principles. In modern times, and under Christian in- fluences, these several systems are almost necessarily identified with inquiries concern- ing the existence and nature of God, The influence of Christianity has been indirectly felt, even in speculations prosecuted in ap- parent independence of it ; and the admission of an absolute first principle of all things dis- tinct from God, or the acknowledgment of a God separate from or derived from the first principle of all things, is an absurdity which, since the prevalence of Christianity, has be- come almost impossible, even to antichristian systems of thought. In earlier times, indeed, this union of philosophy with theology was by no means so imperative. A philosophy like that of Greece, which inherited its specu- The Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. 1 1 lations from a poetical theogony, would see no difficulty in attributing to the god or gods of its religious belief a secondary and derived existence, dependent on some higher and more original principle, and in separating that principle itself from all immediate con- nection with religion. It was possible to assume, with the Ionian, a material sub- stance, or, with the Eleatic, an indifferent abstraction, as the first principle of things, without holding that principle to be God, or, as the only alternative, denying the existence of a God ; and thus, as Aristotle"' has ob- served, theologians endeavoured to evade the consequences of their abstract principles, by attributing to the chief good a later and derived existence, as the poets supposed the supreme God to be of younger birth than * Mctafli., xiv. 4. 1 2 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. night and chaos and sea and sky. But to a Christian philosophy, or to a philosophy in any way influenced by Christianity, this method of evasion is no longer possible. If. all conditioned existence is dependent on some one first and unconditioned principle, either that principle must be identified with God, or our philosophical speculations must fall into open and avowed atheism. But at this point the philosophical inquiry comes in contact with another line of thought, suggested by a different class of the facts of consciousness. As a religious and moral being, man is conscious of a relation of a personal character, distinct from any sug- gested by the phenomena of the material world, ^ — a relation to a supreme Personal Being, the object of his religious worship, and the source and judge of his moral obli- The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 3 gations and conduct. To adopt the name of God in an abstract speculation merely as a conventional denomination for the highest link in the chain of thought, and to believe in Him for the practical purposes of worship and obedience, are two very different things ; and for the latter, though not for the former, the conception of God as a Person is indis- pensable. Were man a being of pure in- tellect, the problem of the Unconditioned would be divested of its chief difficulty ; but he is also a being of religious and moral faculties, and these also have a claim to be satisfied by any valid solution of the pro- blem. Hence the question assumes another and a more complex form. How is the one absolute existence, to which pliilosophy aspires, to be identified with the personal God demanded by our religious feelings ? 1 4 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Shall we boldly assume that the problem is already solved, and that the personal God is the very Unconditioned of which we were in search ? This is to beg the question, not to answer it. Our conception of a personal being, derived as it is from the immediate consciousness of our own j)ersonality, seems, on examination, to involve conditions incom- patible with the desired assumption. Per- sonal agency, similar to our own, seems to point to something very different from an absolutely first link in a chain of phenomena. Our actions, if not determined, are at least influenced by motives ; and the motive is a prior link in the chain, and a condition of the action. Our actions, moreover, take place in time ; and time, as we conceive it, cannot be regarded as an absolute blank, but as a condition in which phenomena take place as The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 5 past, present, and future. Every act taking place in time implies something antecedent to itself; and this something, be it what it may, hinders us from regarding the subse- quent act as absolute and unconditioned. Nay, even time itself, apart from the phe- nomena which it implies, has the same char- acter. If an act cannot take place except in time, time is the condition of its taking place. To conceive the unconditioned, as the first link in a chain of conditioned con- sequences, it seems necessary that we should conceive something out of time, yet fol- lowed by time ; standing at the beginning of all duration and succession, having no antecedent, but followed by a series of con- sequents. Philosophical theologians have been con- scious of this difficulty, almost from the 1 6 The PJiilosophy of the Coiiditioiicd. earliest date at wliicli philosophy and Chris- tian theology came in contact with each other. From a number of testimonies of similar import, we select one or two of the most striking. Of the Divine Nature, Gre- gory Nyssen says : " It is neither in place nor in time, but before these and above these in an unspeakable manner, contemplated it- self by itself, through faith alone ; neither measured by ages, nor moving along with times." '" " In the changes of things," says Augustine, ''you will find a past and a future ; in God you will find a present where past and future cannot be." t " Eternity," says Aquinas, '' has no succession, but ex- ists all together." I Among divines of the Church of England, we quote two names * C Eimom., i., p. 98, Ed. Gretser. t In Jomm. Evang., tract, xxxvii. 10. :J: Smnma, pars, i., rpi. x., art. 1. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 7 only, but those of the highest : — " The dura- tion of eternity," says Bishop Pearson, " is completely indivisible and all at once ; so that it is ever present, and excludes the other dijEFerences of time, past and future.""' And Barrow enumerates amono- natural modes of being and operation far above our reach, " God's eternity without succession," coupling it with " His prescience without necessitation of events."! But it is needless to multiply authorities for a doctrine so fami- liar to every student of theology. Thus, then, our two lines of thought have led us to conclusions which, at first sight, appear to be contradictory of each other. To be conceived as unconditioned, God must be conceived as exempt from action in time : * Minor Theol. Works, vol. i., p. 105. + Sermon on the Unsearchableness of God's Judgments. B 1 8 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. to be conceived as a person, if His 2:)ersona- lity resembles ours, He must be conceived as acting in time. Can these two conclusions be reconciled with each other ; and if not, which of them is to be abandoned ? The true answer to this question is, we believe, to be found in a distinction which some recent critics regard with very little favour, — the distinction between Reason and Faith ; between the power of conceiving and that of believing. We cannot, in our present state of knowledge, reconcile these two conclu- sions ; yet we are not required to abandon either. We cannot conceive the manner in which the unconditioned and the personal are united in the Divine Nature ; yet we may believe that, in some manner unknown to us, they are so united. To conceive the union of two attributes in one object of TJie Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 9 thoug"ht, I must be able to conceive them as united, in some particular manner : when this cannot be done, I may nevertheless believe that the union is possible, though I am un- able to conceive how it is possible. The problem is thus represented as one of those Divine mysteries, the character of which is clearly and well described in the language of Leibnitz : — '' II en est de meme des autres mysteres, oil les esprits moderes trou- veront toujours ime explication suffisante pour croire, et jamais autant qii'il en faut pour comprendre. II nous suffit d'un cer- tain ce (/we cest (ri can) mais le comme7it (ttw?) nous passe^ et ne nous est point neces- * Theodicec, Discours de la Confonnite de, la Foi avec la Eaison, § 56. Leibnitz, it will be observed, uses the expression pmir com- prendre, for which, in the preceding remarks, we have substituted to conceive. The change has been made intentionally, on account 20 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. But this distinction involves a further con- sequence. If the mysteries of the Divine Nature are not apprehended by reason as existing in a particular manner (in which case they would be mysteries no longer), but are accepted by faith as existing in some manner unknown to us, it follows that we do not know God as He is in His absolute nature, but only as He is imperfectly repre- of au amliiguity in the former word. Sometimes it is used, as Leibnitz here uses it, to denote an apprehension of the manner in which certain attributes can coexist in an object. But sometimes (to say nothing of other senses) it is used to signify a complete knowledge of an object in all its properties and their consequences, such as it may be questioned whether we have of any object what- ever. This ambiguity, which has been the source of much con- fusion and much captious criticism, is well pointed out by Norris in his Reason and Faith (written in reply to Toland), p. 118, Ed- 1697 : " WHien we say that above reason is when we do not compre- hend or perceive the truth of a thing, this must not be meant of not comprehending the truth in its whole latitude and extent, so tliat as many tmths should be said to be above reason as we cannot The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 2 i sentecl by those qualities in His creatures which are analogous to, but not identical with, His own. If, for example, we had a knowledge of the Divine Personality as it is in itself, we should know it as existing in a certain manner compatible with uncondi- tioned action ; and this knowledge of the manner would at once transform our convic- tion from an act of faith to a conception of thus thoroughly comprehend and pursue througliout all their conse- quences and relations to other truths (for then almost ever3^thing would be above reason), but only of not comprehending the union or connection of those immediate ideas of which the proposition supposed to be above reason consists." Comprehension, as thus explained, answers exactly to the ordinary logical use of the term amccjMon, to denote the combination of two or more attributes in an unity of re^iresentation. In the same sense, M. Peisse, in the preface to his translation of Hamilton's Fragments, p. 98, says, — " Comprendre, c'est voir un terme en rapport avec un aiitre ; c'est voir comnie un ce qui est donne comme multiple." This is exactly the sense in which Hamilton himself uses the word coiiccption. (See Ecid's JVorks, p. 377.) 2 2 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. reason. If, on the other hand, the only per- sonaHty of which we have a positive know- ledge is our own, and if our own personality can only be conceived as conditioned in time, it follows that the Divine Personality, in so far as it is exempt from conditions, does not resemble the only personality which we di- rectly know, and is not adequately repre- sented by it. This necessitates a confession, which, like the distinction which gives rise to it, has been vehemently condemned by modern critics, but which has been concurred in with singular unanimity by earlier divines of various ages and countries, — the confession that the knowledge which man in this life can have of God is not a knowledge of the Divine Nature as it is in itself, but only of that nature as imperfectly represented through analogous qualities in the creature. TJic Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. 23 Were it not that this doctrine has been fre- quently denounced of late as an heretical novelty, we should hardly have thought it necessary to cite authorities in proof of its antiquity and catholicity. As it is, we will venture to produce a few only out of many, selecting not always the most important, hut those which can be best exhibited verbatim in a short extract. Chrysostom. — De Incompr. Del Natam, Horn. i. 3 : " Tliaf God is everywhere, I know ; and fliat He is wholly everywhere, I know ; but the how, I know not : that He is without begiiming, ungenerated and eternal, I know ; but the how, I knoAV not." Basil. — Ep. ccxxxiv. : " That God is, I knoAv ; l)\it what is His essence I hold to \)Q above reason. How then am I saved ? By faith ; and faith is competent io know that God is, not Avhat He is." Gregory jSTazianzex.- — Orat. xxxiv. : " A theologian among the Greeks [Plato] has said in his philosophy, that to conceive God is difficult, to express Him is impossible. 24 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. . . . J>ut I say that it is impossible to express Him, and more impossible to conceive Him." [Compare Patrick, Wnr/rs, vol. iii., p. 39.] Cyril of Jerusalem. — Catech. vi. 2 : " We declare not "wliat God is, but candidly confess that we know not accu- rately concerning Him. For in those things which concern God, it is great knowledge to confess our ignorance." Augustine. — Enarr. in Psalm. Ixxxv. 8 : " God is ineffable ; Ave more easily say what He is not than what He is." Serm. cccxli. : " I call God just, because in human Avords I find nothing l^etter ; for He is beyond justice. . . . A¥hat then is Avorthily said of God 'i Some one, perhaps, may reply and say, that Hn is Just. But another, Avith better understanding, may say that even this Avord is surpassed by His excellence, and tliat even this is said of Him uiiAvorthily, though it be said fittingly according to human capacity." Cyril of Alexandria. — In Joann. Evavg., 1. ii., c. 5 : " For those things Avliich are spoken concerning it [the DiAdne Mature] are not s})oken as they are in very truth, but as the tongue of man can interpret, and as man can hear; for he Avho sees in an enigma also speaks in an enigma." Damascenus. — De Fide Orthod., i. -i : " That God is, The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 25 is manifest ; but what Ho is in His essence and nature is utterly incomprehensible and unknoAvn." Aquinas. — Summa, pars, i., (pi. xiii., art. 1 : " AVci cannot so name God that the nauie Avhich denotes Him shall express the Divine Essence as it is, in the same Avay as the name num ex2)resses m its signification the essence of man as it is." Ihlr. Hemy More, NnJliin hi micwcosmo spiritiis, niillns in macwcosmo Dens. I do not, of course, mean to assert that all materialists deny or actually disbelieve a God. For, in very many cases, this would be at once an un- merited comjDliment to their reasoning, and an unmerited reproach to their faith." — Lectures, voL i., p. 31.''' * This pai-t of Hamilton's teaching is altogether repudiated by a recent writer, wlio, strangely enough, professes to be his disciple, while rejecting all that is really characteristic of his philosophy. Mr. Herbert Spencer, in his work on First Principles, endeavoui-s to press Sir W. Hamilton into the service of Pantheism and Posi- ti\asm together, by adopting the negative portion only of his philosophy — in which, in common with many other writers, he declares the absolute to be inconceivable by the mere intellect,- — and rejecting the positive portions, in which he most emphatically maintains that the belief in a personal God is imperatively de- manded by the facts of our moral and emotional consciousness. Mr. Spencer regards religion as nothing more than a consciousness of natural facts as being in their ultimate genesis unaccountable — a theory which is simply a combination of the positivist doctrine. 40 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. In the few places in which Hamilton speaks directly as a theologian, his language is in agreement with the general voice of that we know only the relations of phenomena, with the pantheist assumption of the name of God to denote the substance or power which lies beyond phenomena, l&o theory can be more opposed to the philosophy of the conditioned than this. Sir W. Hamilton's fundamental princijile is, that consciousness must be accepted entire, and that the moral and religious feelings, which are the primary source of our belief in a personal God, are in no way invalidated by the merely negative inferences which have deluded men into the assumption of an impersonal absolute ; the latter not lieing legitimate deductions from consciousness rightly interpreted Mr. Spencer, on the other hand, takes these negaiive inferences as the only basis of religion, and abandons Hamilton's great principle of the distinction between knowledge and belief, by quietly drop- ping out of his system the facts of consciousness which make such a distinction necessary. His whole sj'stem is, in fact, a pertinent illustration of Hamilton's remark, that " the phenomena of matter" [and of mind, he might add, treated by materialistic methods], " taken by themselves (you will observe the qualification, taken by themselves), so far from Avarranting any inference to the exist- ence of a God, would, on the contrary, ground even an argument to his negation." Mr. Spencer, like Mr. Mill, denies the freedom of the will ; and this, according to Hamilton, leads by logical conse- quence to Atheism. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 4 1 Catholic theology down to the end of the seventeenth century, some specimens of which have been given on a previous page. Thus he says (Discussio7is, p. 1 5) : " True, therefore, are the declarations of a pious philosophy, — 'A God understood would be no God at all ; ' ' To think that God is, as we can think Him to be, is blasphemy.' The Divinity, in a certain sense, is revealed ; in a certain sense is concealed : He is at once known and unknown. But the last and highest consecration of all true religion must be an altar 'Ayvwa-ro) Oec}. — ' To the unhioivn and unhioivable God."' A little later (p. 20) he says : '' We should not recoil to the opj^osite extreme ; and though man be not identical with the Deity, still is he ^created in the image of God.' It is, indeed, only through an analogy of the human with the 42 The PJiilosophy of tJic Conditioned. Divine nature, that we are percipient and reci23ient of Divinity." In the first of these passages we have an echo of the language of Basil, the two Cyrils, and John Damas- cene, and of our own Hooker and Usher ; w^hile in the second we find the counter truth, intimated by Augustine and other Fathers/" and clearly stated by Aquinas, and which in the last century was elabor- ately expounded in the Divme Analogy of Bishop Browne, — namely, that though * As e.g., by Tertiillian [Adv. Marc, 1. ii., c. 16): " Et haec ergo imago censenda est Dei in liomine, quod eosdein motus et sensus liabeat h^imaiius animi;s quos et Deus, licet non tales quales Deus : pro substantia enim, et status eorum et exitus distant." And by Gregory Nazianzen, Orat. xxxvii. : Qvo/xdaafiev yap ws tj/uv icpLKTOv €K tGjv TjiiiTipuiv TO, Tou Oeou. Aud by Hilary, De Trin., i. 19: " Comparatio enim terrenorum ad Deum nulla est; sed infirmitas nostriB intelligentiffi cogit species quasdam ex inferi- oribus, tanquam superiorum indices quserere ; ut rerum familiarium consuetudine admovente, ex sensus nostri conscientia ad insoliti sensus opinionem educeremur. " The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 43 we know not God in His own nature, yet are we not wholly ignorant of Him, but may attain to an imperfect knowledge of Him through the analogy between human things and Divine. As regards theological results, therefore, there is nothing novel or peculiar in Hamil- ton's teachino' • nor was he one who would have regarded novelty in theology as a re- commendation. The peculiarity of his sys- tem, by which his reputation as a philosopher must ultimately stand or fall, is the manner in which he endeavoured to connect these theological conclusions with psychological principles ; and thus to vindicate on philo- sophical grounds the position which Catholic divines had been compelled to take in the interests of dogmatic truth. That the abso- lute nature of God, as a supertemporal and 44 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. yet personal Being, must be believed in as a fact, though inaccessible to reason as re- gards the manner of its possibility, is a position admitted, almost without exception, by divines who acknowledge the mystery of a personal Absolute — still more by those who acknowledge the yet deeper mystery of a Trinity in Unity. '^ We believe and know," says Bishop Sanderson of the mys- teries of the Christian faith, " and that with fulness of assurance, that all these things are so as they are revealed in the Holy Scriptures, because the mouth of God, who is Truth itself, and cannot lie, hath spoken them ; and our own reason upon this ground teacheth us to submit ourselves and it to tliQ obedience of faith, for the to on, that so it is. But then, for the to ttco?, Nicodemus his question, How can these things he f it is The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. 45 no more possible for our weak understand- ings to comprehend that, than it is for the eyes of bats or owls to look steadfastly upon the body of the sun, when he shineth forth in his greatest strength.'"''' This distinction Hamilton endeavoured to extend from the domain of Christian theology to that of philo- sophical sjDeculation in general ; to show that the unconditioned, as it is suggested in philo- sophy, no less than as it connects itself with revealed religion, is an object of belief, not of positive conception ; and, consequently, that men cannot escape from mystery by rejecting revelation. " Above all," he says, " I am confirmed in my belief by the har- mony between the doctrines of this philo- sophy, and those of revealed truth. . . . For this philosophy is professedly a scientific * Works, voL i., p. 233. 46 The Philosophy of iJic Conditioned. demonstration of the impossibility of that ' wisdom in high matters' which the Apostle prohibits us even to attempt ; and it pro- poses, from the limitation of the human powers, from our impotence to comprehend what, however, we must admit, to show articulately Avliy the ' secret things of God ' cannot but be to man ' j^ast finding out.'"'^ Faith in the inconceivable must thus become the ultimate refuge, even of the pantheist and the atheist, no less than of the Chris- tian ; the difference being, that wliile the last takes his stand on a faith which is in agreement alike with the authority of Scrip- ture and the needs of human nature, the two former are driven to one which is equally opposed to both, as well as to the pretensions of their own philosophy. * Discussions, p. 625. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 47 Deny the Trinity ; deny the Personality of God : there yet remains tliat which no man can deny as the hiw of his own con- sciousness — Tinne. Conditioned existence is existence in time : to attain to a philosophy of the unconditioned, we must rise to the conception of existence out of time. The attempt may be made in two ways, and in two only. Either we may endeavour to conceive an absolutely first moment of time, beyond which is an existence having no dura- tion and no succession ; or we may endeavour to conceive time as an unlimited duration, containing an infinite series of successive antecedents and consequents, each condi- tioned in itself, but forming altogether an unconditioned whole. In other words, we may endeavour, with the Eleatics, to con- ceive pure existence apart and distinct from 48 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. all phenomenal change ; or we may endea- vour, with Heraclitus, to conceive the uni- verse as a system of incessant changes, immu- table only in the law of its own mutability ; for these two systems may be regarded as the type of all subsequent attempts. Both, however, alike aim at an object which is beyond positive conception, and which can be accepted only as something to be believed in spite of its inconceivability. To conceive an existence beyond the first moment of time, and to connect that existence as cause with the subsequent temporal succession of effects, we must conceive time itself as non- existent and then commencing to exist. But when we make the effort to conceive time as non-existent, we find it impossible to do so. Time, as the universal condition of human consciousness, clings round the very TJic Philosophy of I he Conditioned. 49 conception which strives to destroy it, chngs round the language in which we speak of an existence before time. Nor are we more successful when w^e attempt to conceive an infinite regress of time, and an infinite series of dependent existences in time. To say nothing of the direct contradiction involved in the notion of an unconditioned tvhole, — a something completed, — composed of infinite parts — of parts never completed, — even if we abandon the Whole, and with it the Uncon- ditioned, and attempt merely to conceive an infinite succession of conditioned existences — conditioned, absurdly enough, by nothing beyond themselves, — we find, that in order to do so, we must add moment to moment for ever — a process which would require an eternity for its accomplishment.""' Moreover, * See Discussions, p. 29. Of course by this is not meant that D 50 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. the chain of dependent existences in this infinite succession is not, like a mathematical series, composed of abstract and homogeneous 110 duration can be conceived except in a duration e([ually long — that a thousand years, e.g., can only be conceived in a thousand years. A thousand years may be conceived as one unit : infinity cannot ; for an unit is something complete, and therefore limited. What is meant is, that any period of time, however long, is con- ceived as capable of further increase, and therefore as not infinite. An infinite duration can have no time before or after it ; and thus cannot resemble any portion of finite time, however great. AVlien we dream of conceiving an infinite regress of time, says Sir W. Hamilton, ' ' we only deceive ourselves by substituting tlie in- definite for the infinite, than which no two notions can be more opposed." This caution has not been attended to by some later critics. Thus, Dr. Whewell {Tliilosoinliy of Discovery, p. 324) says : " The definition of an infinite number is not tliat it contains all possible unities ; but this — that the progress of numeration, being begun according to a certain law, goes on without limit." This is precisely Descartes' definition, not of the infinite, but of the in- definite. Frincipia, i. 26 : " Nos autem ilia omnia, in quibus sub aliqua consideratione nullum finem poterimus invenire, non (juidem aifirmabimus esse iufinita, sed ut indefinita spectabimus. " An indefinite time is that which is capable of perpetual addition : an infinite time is one so great as to admit of no addition. Surely " no two notions can be more opposed." The PJiilosophy of the Conditioited. 51 units ; it is made up of divers phenomena, of a regressive line of causes, each distinct from the other. Wherever, therefore, I stop in my addition, I do not positively conceive the temis which lie beyond. I apprehend them only as a series of unknown soinethings, of which I may believe that they are, but am unable to say ivliat they are. The cardinal point, then, of Sir W. Hamil- ton's philosophy, expressly announced as such by himself, is the absolute necessity, under any system of philosophy whatever, of ac- knowledging the existence of a sphere of belief beyond the limits of the sphere of thought. '^ The main scope of my specula- tion,""^' he says, " is to show articulately that we must helieve, as actual, much that we are unable (positively) to conceive as even pos- * Letter to Mr. Calderwood. See Lectures, vol. ii., p. 534. 52 The PhilosopJiy of the Coiiditioned. sible." It is, of course, beyond the range of such a speculation, by itself, to enter on an examination of the positive evidences in support of one form of belief rather than another. So far as it aims only at exhibiting an universal law of the human mind, it is of course compatible with all special forms of belief which do not contradict that law ; and none, whatever their pretensions, can really contradict it. Hence the service which such a philosophy can render to the CM'istian reli- gion must necessarily, from the nature of the case, be of an indirect and negative character. It prepares the way for a fair examination of the proper evidences of Christianity, by showing that there is no ground for any a priori prejudice against revelation, as appeal- ing, for the acceptance of its highest truths, to faith rather than to reason : for that this The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 53 appeal is common to all religions and to all philosophies, and cannot therefore be urged against one more than another. So far as certain difficulties are inherent in the consti- tution of the human mind itself, they must necessarily occupy the same position witli respect to all religions alike. To exhibit the nature of these difficulties is a service to true religion ; but it is the service of the pioneer, not of the builder ; it does not prove the religion to be true ; it only clears the ground for the production of the special evidences. Where those evidences are to be found, Sir W. Hamilton has not failed to tell us. If mere intellectual speculations on the nature and origin of the material universe form a common ground in which the theist, the pantheist, and even the atheist, may alike expatiate, the moral and religious feel- 54 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. ings of man — those facts of consciousness which have their direct source in the sense of personahty and free will — plead with over- whelming evidence in behalf of a personal Godj and of man's relation to Him, as a person to a person. We have seen, in a pre- vious quotation, Hamilton's emphatic decla- ration that '■'■ psychological materialism, if carried out fully and fairly to its conclusions, inevitably results in theological atheism." In the same spirit he tells us that " it is only as man is a free intelligence, a moral power, that he is created after the image of God ;" '^ that " with the proof of the moral nature of man, stands or falls the proof of the existence of a Deity;" that "the possibility of morahty depends on the possibility of liberty ;" that "if man be not a free agent, he is not the * Lectures, vol. i. , p. 30. TJie PJiilosophy of tJic Coiiditioned. 55 author of his actions, and has therefore no responsibihty, no moral personality at all ;"'"' and, finally, '' that he who disbelieves the moral agency of man, must, in consistency with that opinion, disbelieve Christianity." t We have thus, in the positive and negative sides of this philosophy, both a reasonable ground of belief and a warning against pre- sumption. By our immediate consciousness of a moral and personal nature, we are led to the belief in a moral and personal God : by our ignorance of the unconditioned, w^e are led to the further belief, that behind that moral and personal manifestation of God there lies concealed a mystery — the mystery of the Absolute and the Infinite ; that our intellectual and moral qualities, though indi- * Lectures, vol. i., p. 33. t Ihid., p. 42. 56 The Philosophy of the Condilioncd. eating the nearest approach to the Divine Perfections which we are capable of conceiv- ing, yet indicate them as analogous, not as identical ; that we may naturally expect to find points where this analogy will fail us, where the function of the Infinite Moral Governor will be distinct from that of the finite moral servant ; and where, conse- quently, we shall be liable to error in judging by human rules of the ways of God, whether manifested in nature or in revelation. Such is the true lesson to be learnt from a philo- sophy which tells us of a God who is " in a certain sense revealed, in a certain sense con- cealed — at once known and unknown." It is not surprising that this philosophy, when compared with that of a critic like Mr. Mill, should stand out in clear and sharp antagonism. Mr. Mill is one of the most The Philosophy of ihe Conditioned. 57 distinguished representatives of that school of Materialism which Sir W. Hamilton de- nounces as virtual Atheism. We do not mean that he consciously adopts the grosser tenets of the materialists. We are not aware that he has ever positively denied the exist- ence of a soul distinct from the body, or maintained that the brain secretes thought as the liver secretes bile. But he is the advocate of a philosophical method which makes the belief in the existence of an imma- terial principle superfluous and incongruous ; he not only acknowledges no such distinction between the phenomena of mind and those of matter as to rec[uire the hypothesis of a free intelligence to account for it ; he not only reo-ards the ascertained laws of coexistence and succession in material phenomena as the type and rule according to which all pheno- 58 The Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. mena whatever — those of internal conscious- ness no less than of external observation — are to be tested ; but he even expressly denies the existence of that free will which Sir W. Hamilton regards as the indispensable condi- tion of all morality and all religion."' Thus, * That this is the real battle-ground between the two philoso- phers is virtually admitted by Mr. Mill himself at the end of his criticism. He says : — " The whole philosophy of Sir W. Hamilton seems to have had its character determined by the requirements of the doctrine of Free-will ; and to that doctrine he clung, because he had persuaded himself that it afibrded the only premises from which human reason could deduce the doctrines of natural religion. I believe that in this persuasion he was thoroughly his own dupe, and that his speculations liave weakened the philosoiihical founda- tion of religion fully as much as they have confinned it." — P. 549. Mr. ^Mill's whole philosophy, on the other hand, is determined by the requirements of the doctrine of Necessity ; and to that doctrine he intrepidly adheres, in utter defiance of consciousness, and some- times of his own consistency. Which of the two philosophers is really "his own dupe," Mr. Mill in believing that morality and religion can exist without free will — that a necessary agent can be responsible for his acts — or Sir W. Hamilton in maintaining the contrary, is a question which the former has by no means satis- factorily settled in his own favour. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 59 instead of recognising in the facts of intelli- gence " an order of existence diametrically in contrast to that displayed to us in the facts of the material universe," "" he regards both classes of facts as of the same kind, and explicable by the same laws ; he abolishes the primary contrast of consciousness between the ego and the non-ego — the j)erson and the thing ; he reduces man to a thing, instead of a person, — to one among the many pheno- mena of the universe, determined by the same laws of invariable antecedence and con- sequence, included under the same fonTiula3 of empirical generalization. He thus makes man the slave, and not the master of nature ; passively carried along in the current of successive phenomena ; unable, by any act of free will, to arrest a single wave in its * Hamilton, Lectures, vol. i., p. 29. 6o The Philosophy of the Conditioned. course, or to divert it from its ordained direction. This diametrical antagonism between the two philosophers is not limited to their first principles, but extends, as might naturally be expected, to every subordinate science of which the immediate object is mental, and not material. Logic, instead of being, as Sir W. Hamilton regards it, an a priori science of the necessary laws of thought, is wath Mr. Mill a science of observation, investigating those operations of the un- derstanding which are subservient to the estimation of evidence.'"' The axioms of Mathematics, which the former philosopher regards, with Kant, as necessary thoughts, based on the a prioid intuitions of sj)ace and time, the latter t declares to be " experimental * Mill's Logic. Introduction, § 7. + Ihid., book ii. 5, § 4. The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 1 truths ; generalizations from observation." Psychology, which with Hamilton is espe- cially the philosophy of man as a free and personal agent, is with Mill the science of " the uniformities of succession ; the laws, whether ultimate or derivative, according to which one mental state succeeds another.'"'' And finally, in the place of Ethics, as the science of the a priori laws of man's moral obligations, we are presented, in Mr. Mill's system, with Ethology, the "science which determines the kind of character produced, in conformity to the general laws of mind, by any set of circumstances, physical and moral." t The contrast betw^een the two philosophers being thus thoroughgoing, it was natural to expect beforehand that an Examination of * Mill's Logic, book vi. 4, § 3. t Ihld., book vi. 5, § 4. 62 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Sir William Ilamiltoris Philosopluj, by Mr, Mill, would contain a sharp and vigorous assault on the principal doctrines of that philosophy. And this expectation has been amply fulfilled. But there was also reason to expect, from the ability and critical power displayed in Mr. Mill's previous writings, that his assault, whether successful or not in overthrowing his enemy, would at least be guided by a clear knowledge of that enemy's position and purposes ; that his dissent would be accompanied by an intelligent apprehen- sion, and an accurate statement, of the doc- trines dissented from. In this expectation, we regret to say, w^e have been disappointed. Not only is Mr. Mill's attack on Hamilton's philosophy, with the exception of some minor details, unsuccessful ; but we are compelled to add, that with regard to the three funda- The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. O3 mental doctrines of that philosophy — the Relativity of Knowledge, the Incognisability of the Absolute and Infinite, and the dis- tinction between Reason and Faith — Mr. Mill has, throughout his criticism, altogether missed the meaning of the theories he is attempting to assail, Tliis is a serious charo-e to brino- ao-ainst a writer of such eminence as Mr. Mill, and one which should not be advanced without ample proof. First, then, of the Relativity of Knowledge. The assertion that all our knowledsfe is relative, — in other words, that we know things only under such conditions as the laws of our cognitive faculties impose upon us, — is a statement which looks at first sigfht like a truism, but which really contains an answer j:o a very important question,— Have 64 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. we reason to believe that the laws of our cognitive faculties impose any conditions at all ? — that the mind in any way reacts on the objects affecting it, so as to produce a result different from that which would be produced were it merely a passive recipient ? " The mind of man," says Bacon, ^' is far from the nature of a clear and equal glass, wherein the beams of things shall reflect according to their true incidence ; nay, it is rather like an enchanted glass, full of super- stition and imposture, if it be not delivered and reduced." Can what Bacon says of the fallacies of the mind be also said of its pro- per cognitions ? Does the mind, by its own action, in any way distort the appearance of the things presented to it ; and if so, how far does the distortion extend, and in what man- ner is it to be rectified ? To trace the course The PJiilosophy of the Co)iditioncd. O5 of this inquiry, from the day when Plato compared the objects perceived by the senses to the shadows thrown by fire on the wall of a cave, to the day when Kant declared that we know only phenomena, not things in themselves, would be to write the history of philosophy. We can only at present call attention to one movement in that history, which was, in effect, a revolution in philo- sophy. The older philosophers in general distinofuished between the senses and the intellect, regarding the former as deceptive and concerned with phenomena alone, the latter as trustworthy and conversant with the realities of things. Hence arose the distinction between the sensible and the intelligible world — between things as per- ceived by sense and things as apprehended by intellect — between Phenomenology and 66 The Pldlosophy of the Conditioned. Ontology. Kant rejected this distinction, holding that the intellect, as well as the sense, imposes its own forms on the things presented to it, and is therefore cognisant only of phenomena, not of things in themselves. The logical result of this position would be the abolition of ontology as a science of things in themselves, and, ci fortiori, of that highest branch of ontology which aims at a knowledge of the Absolute'"' Kar ejo^'/i', of the unconditioned first principle of all things. If the mind, in every act of thought, imposes its own forms on its objects, to think * The term absolute, in the sense of free from relafum, may be used in two applications ; — 1st, To denote the nature of a tiling as it is in itself, as distinguished from its appearance to lis. Here it is used only in a subordinate sense, as meaning out of relation to human knowledge. 2ndly, To denote the nature of a thing as independent of all other things, as -having no relation to any other thing as the condition of its existence. Here it is used in its highest sense, as meaning out of relation to anything else. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 67 is to condition, and the unconditioned is the unthinkable. Such was the logical result of Kant's princi})les, but not the actual result. For Kant, by distinguishing between the Understanding and the Reason, and giving to the latter an indirect yet positive cognition of the Unconditioned as a regulative prin- ciple of thought, prepared the way for the systems of Schelling and Hegel, in which this indirect cognition is converted into a direct one, by investing the reason, thus distinguished as the special faculty of the unconditioned, with a power of intuition emancipated from the conditions of space and time, and even of subject and object, or a power of thought emancipated from the laws of identity and contradiction. The theory of Hamilton is a modification of that of Kant, intended to obviate these 68 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. consequences, and to relieve the Kantian doctrine itself from the inconsistency which gave rise to them. -So long as the reason is regarded as a separate faculty from the understanding, and things in themselves as ideas of the reason, so long the apparent contradictions, which encumber the attempt to conceive the unconditioned, must be re- garded as inherent in the constitution of the reason itself, and as the result of its legiti- mate exercise on its proper objects. This sceptical conclusion Hamilton endeavoured to avoid by rejecting the distinction between the understanding and the reason as separate faculties, regarding the one as the legitimate and positive, the other as the illegitimate and neofative, exercise of one and the same faculty. He thus announces, in opposition to Kant, the fundamental doctrine of the The Philosophy of the Conditioned. O9 Conditioned, as " the distinction between intelligence witliin its legitimate sphere of operation, impeccable, and intelligence beyond that sphere, affording (by abuse) the occasions of error."'" Hamilton, like Kant, maintained that all our cognitions are compounded of two elements, one contributed by the object known, and the other by the mind knowing. But the very conception of a relation implies the existence of thmgs to be related ; and the knowledge of an object, as in relation to our mmd, necessarily implies its existence out of that relation. But as so existinof, it is unknown : we believe that it is ; we know not what it is. How far it resembles, or how far it does not resemble, the object appre- hended by us, we cannot say, for we have no means of comparing the two together. * Discussions, p. 633. 70 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Instead, therefore, of saying with Kant, that reason is subject to an inevitable dekision, by which it mistakes the regulative principles of its own thoughts for the representations of real things, Hamilton would say that the reason, while compelled to believe in the ex- istence of these real things, is not legitimately entitled to make any positive representation of them as of such or such a nature ; and that the contradictions into which it falls when attempting to do so are due to an illegitimate attempt to transcend the proper boundaries of positive thought. This theory does not, in itself, contain any statement of the mode in wiiich we perceive the material world, whether directly by pre- sentation, or indirectly by representative images ; and perhaps it might, without any great violence, be adapted to more than one The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 7 1 of the current hypotheses on this point. But that to which it most easily adjusts itself is that maintained by Hamilton himself under the name of Natural Realism. To speak of perception as a relation between mind and matter, naturally implies the presence of both correlatives ; though each may be modi- fied by its contact with the other. The acid may act on the alkali, and the alkali on the acid, in forming the neutral salt ; but each of the ingredients is as truly present as the other, though each enters into the compound in a modified form. And this is equally the case in perception, even if we suppose various media to intervene between the ultimate object and the j^erceiving mind, — such, e.g., as the rays of light and the sensitive or- ganism in vision, — so long as these media are material,, like the ultimate object itself 72 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Whether the object, properly so called, in vision, be the rays of light in contact with the organ, or the body emitting or reflecting those rays, is indiflerent to the jDresent ques- tion, so long as a material object of some kind or other is supposed to be perceived, and not merely an inmaterial representation of such an object. To speak of our percep- tions as mere modifications of mind produced by an unknown cause, would be like main- taining that the acid is modified by the influence of the alkali Avithout entering into combination with it. Such a view might perhaps be tolerated, in connection with the theory of relativity, by an indulgent interpre- tation of language, but it is certainly not that which the language of the theory most naturally suggests. All this Mr. Mill entirely misapprehends. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 7 3 He quotes a passage from Hamilton's Lec- tures, in which the above theory of Relativity is clearly stated as the mean between the extremes of Idealism and Materialism, and then proceeds to comment as follows : — " The proposition, that our cognitions of objects are only in part dependent on the objects themselves, and in part on elements superadded by our organs or our minds, is not identical, nor prima facie absurd. It cannot, how- ever, warrant the assertion that all our knoAvledge, but only that the part so added, is relative. If oiu' author had gone as far as Kant, and had said that all "which constitutes knowledge is put in by the mind itself, he would have really held, in one of its forms, the doctrine of the relativity of our laioAvledge. But what he does say, far from implying that the whole of our knowledge is relative, distinctly imports that all of it Avliich is real and authentic is the reverse. If any part of what we fancy that we perceive in the objects themselves, originates in the perceivmg organs or in the cognising mind, thus much is purely relative ; but since, by supposition, it does not all so originate, the part that does not is as much absolute 74 The Philosophy of the Conditio7ied. as if it were not liable to be mixed up Avitli these deliisive subjective impressions." — (P. 30.) Mr. Mill, tlierefore, supposes that wliolly relative must mean wliolhj mental ; in other words, that to say that a thing is wholly due to a relation between mind and matter is equivalent to saying that it is wholly due to mind alone. On the contrary, we maintain that Sir W. Hamilton's lanofuaa-e is far more accurate than Mr. Mill's, and that the above theory can with perfect correctness be de- scribed as one of total relativity ; and this from two points of view. First, as opposed to the theory of partial relativity generally held by the pre-Kantian philosophers, ac- cording to which our sensitive cognitions are relative, our intellectual ones absolute. Secondly, as asserting that the object of perception, though composed of elements The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 7 5 partly material, partly mental, yet exhibits both alike in a form modified by their rela- tion to each other. The composition is not a mere mechanical juxtaposition, in which each part, though acting on the other, retains its own characteristics unchanged. It may be rather likened to a chemical fusion, in whicli both elements are present, but each of them is affected by the composition. The material part, therefore, is not " as much absolute as if it were not liable to be mixed up with subjective impressions." But we must hear the continuation of Mr. Mill's criticism : — " The admixture of the relative element not only does not take aAvay the absolute character of the remainder, hut does not even (if our author is right) prevent vis from recognising it. The confusion, according to him, is not inextricable. It is for us to ' analyse and distinguish 76 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. what elemeuls ' in an ' act of knowledge ' are contributed by the object, and what by our organs, or by the uiind. We may neglect to do this, and as far as the mind's share is concerned, we can only do it by the help of pliilosophy ; but it is a task to which, in his opinion, pliilosophy is equal. By thus stripping off such of the elements in our apparent cognitions of tilings as are but cognitions of sometliiiig in us, and consequently relative, we may succeed in luicovering the pure nucleus, the direct intui- tions of tilings in themselves ; as we correct the observed positions of the heavenly bodies by allowing for the error due to the refi'actuig influence of the atmospheric medium, an influence which does not alter the facts, but only our perception of them." Surely Mr. Mill here demands rQuch more of philosophy than Sii" W. Hamilton deems it capable of accomplishing. Why may not Hamilton, like Kant, distinguish between the permanent and necessary, and the variable and contingent — in other words, between the subjective and the objective elements of The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 7 7 consciousness, without therefore obtaining a " direct intuition of thinofs in themselves ? " Why may he not distinguish between space and time as the forms of our sensitive cogni- tions, and the things perceived in space and time, which constitute the matter of the same cognitions, without thereby having an intuition, on the one hand, of pure space and time with nothino- m them, or on the other, of things in themselves out of space and time ? If certain elements are always present in perception, while certain others change with eveiy act, I may surely infer that the one is due to the permanent subject, the other to the variable object, without thereby knowing what each would be if it could be discerned apart from the other. " A direct intuition of things in themselves," according to Kant and Hamilton, is an intuition of things out 78 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. of space and time. Does Mr. Mill suppose that any natural Realist professes to have such an intuition ? The same error of supposing that a doc- trine of relativity is necessarily a doctrine of Idealism, that "matter known only in relation to us " can mean nothing more than " matter known only through the mental impressions of which it is the unknown cause/'''' runs through the whole of Mr, Mill's argument against this portion of Sir W. Hamilton's teaching. That argument, though repeated in various forms, may be briefly summed up * The assumption that these two expressions are or ought to be synonymous is tacitly made by Mr. Mill at the opening of this chapter. He opens it with a passage from the Discussions, in which Hamilton says that the existence of things in themselves is only indirectly revealed to us "through certain qualities related to our fctcultics of knoivlcdgc ;" and then proceeds to show that the author did not hold the doctrine which these phrases "seem to convey in the only siibstantial meaning capable of being attached to them ;" namely, "that we know nothing of objects except their The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 79 in one thesis ; namely, that the doctrine that our knowledofe of matter is whollv relative is incompatible with the distinction, which Hamilton expressly makes, between the primary and secondary qualities of body. The most curious circumstance about this criticism is, that, if not directly borrowed from, it has at least been carefully anticipated by, Hamilton himself Of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, as acknowledged by Descartes and Locke, existence, and the impressions procluced by them upon the human mind." Having thiis quietly assumed that "things in themselves" are identical with "objects," and "relations" with "impressions on the human mind," Mr. Mill bases Iris whole criticism on this tacit iKtitio in'iHciini. He is not aware that though Reid some- times uses the tei'm relative in this inaccurate sense, Hamilton ex- pressly points out the inaccuracy and explains the proper sense. — (See RckVs Worlcs, pp. 313, 322.) 8o The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. whose theory of external perception is identi- cal with that w^liich Mr. Mill would force on Hamilton himself, Hamilton says : '' On the general doctrine, however, of these philoso- phers, both classes of qualities, as know^n, are confessedly only states of our own minds ; and while we have no right from a subjective affection to infer the existence, far less the corresponding character of the existence, of any objective reality, it is evident that their doctrine, if fairly evolved, w^ould result in a dogmatic or in a sceptical negation of the primary no less than of the secondaiy quali- ties of body, as more than appearances in and for us."""' It is astonishing that Mr. Mill, who pounces eagerly on every imaginable instance of Hamilton's inconsistency, should have neglected to notice this, which, if his * lUid's Worlcs, p. 840. The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 8 1 criticism be true, is the most glaring incon- sistency of all. But Hamilton continues : " It is therefore manifest that the fundamental position of a consistent theory of dualistic realism is — that our cognitions of Extension and its modes are not wholly ideal — that although Space be a native, necessary, a priori form of imagina- tion, and so far, therefore, a mere subjective state, that there is, at the same time, com- petent to us, in an immediate perception of external things, the consciousness of a really existent, of a really objective, extended world," Here we have enunciated in one breath, first the subjectivity of space, which is the logical basis of the relative theory of perception ; and secondly, the objectivity of the extended world, which is the logical basis of the distinction between primary and F 82 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. secondary qualities. It is manifest, there- fore, that Hamilton had not, as Mr. Mill supposes, ceased to hold the one theoiy when he adopted the other."' The key to all this is not difficult to find. It is simply that objective existence does not mean existence per se ; and that a pheno- menon does not mean a mere mode of mind- Objective existence is existence as an object, in perception, and therefore in relation ; and a phenomenon may be material, as well as mental. The thing pe^" se may be only the unknown cause of what we directly know ; but what we directly know is something more than our own sensations. In other words, the j^henomenal effect is material as well as the cause, and is, indeed, that from which our primary conceptions of matter are * See Examination, p. 28. The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 83 derived. Matter does not cease to be matter when modified by its contact with mind, as iron does not cease to be iron when smelted and forged. A horseshoe is something very different from a piece of iron ore ; and a man may be acquainted with the foniier without ever havino- seen the latter, or knowino- what it is like. But w^ould Mr. Mill therefore say that the horseshoe is merely a subjective affection of the skill of the smith — that it is not iron modified by the Vv^orkman, but the workman or his art impressed by iron ? If, indeed, Hamilton had said with Locke, that the primary qualities are in the bodies themselves, whether we perceive them or no,''" he would have laid himself open to Mr. Mill's criticism. But he expressly rejects this statement, and contrasts it with the * Essay, ii. 8, § 23. 84 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. more cautious langfuaofe of Descartes, " ut sunt, vel saltern esse possunt."'"' The second- ary qualities are mere affections of conscious- ness, which cannot be conceived as existing except in a conscious subject. The primary qualities are qualities of body, as perceived in relation to the percipient mind, i. e., of the phenomenal body perceived as in space. How far they exist in the real body out of relation to us, Hamilton does not attempt to decide.t They are inseparable from our * Reid's Works, p. 839. + We have been content to argue this question, as Mr. Mill himself argues it, on the supposition that Sir ~W. Hamilton held that we are directly percipient of primary qualities in external bodies. Strictly speaking, however, Hamilton held that the pri- mary qualities are immediately perceived only in our organism as extended, and inferred to exist in extra-organic bodies. The ex- ternal world is immediately apprehended only in its secundo- primary character, as resisting our locomotive energy. But as the organism, in this theory, is a material non-ego equally with the rest of matter, and as to press this distinction would only affect the The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 85 conception of body, which is derived exchi- sively from the phenomenon ; they may or may not be separable from the thing as it is in itself. Under this explanation, it is manifest that the doctrine, that matter as a subject or substratum of attributes is unknown and unknowable, is totally different from that of cosmothetic idealism, with which Mr Mill verbal accuracy, not the substantial justice, of Mr. Mill's criti- cisms, we have preferred to meet liim on the ground he has him- self chosen. The same error, of supposing that " presentationism " is identical -with " noumenalism, " and "phenomenalism" with "re- pi'esentationism, " runs through the whole of Mr. Stirling's recent criticism of Hamilton's theory of perception. It is curious, how- ever, that the very passage {Lectures, i. , p. 146) which Mr. Mill cites as proving that Hamilton, in spite of his professed phe- nomenalism, was an unconscious noumenalist, is employed by Mr. Stirling to prove that, in spite of his professed presentationism, he was an unconscioiis representationist. The two critics tilt at Hamilton from opposite quarters : he has only to stand aside anrl let them run against each other. 86 The PJiilosophy of tJie Conditioned. confounds it f and that a pliilosopher may without inconsistency accept the former and reject the latter. The former, while it holds the material substance to be unknown, does not deny that some of the attributes of matter are perceived immediately as material, though, it may be, modified by contact with mind. The latter maintains that the attri- butes, as well as the substance, are not perceived immediately as material, but medi- ately through the intervention of immaterial representatives. It is also manifest that, in answer to Mr. Mill's question, which of Hamilton's two '^ cardinal doctrines," Rela- tivity or Natural Realism, ^' is to be taken in a non-natural sense,"t we must say, neither. The two doctrines are quite compatible with each other, and neither requires a non-natural * Examination, p. 23. + Examination, p. 20. TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. 87 interpretation to reconcile it to its com- panion. The doctrine of relativity derives its chief practical value from its connection witli the next great doctrine of Hamilton's philosophy, the incognisability of the Absolute and the Infinite. For this doctrine brings Ontology into contact with Theology ; and it is only in relation to theology that ontology acquires a practical importance. With respect to the other two " ideas of the pure reason," as Kant calls them, the human soul and the world, the question, whether we know them as realities or as phenomena, may assist us in dealing with certain metaphysical difficulties, but need not affect our practical conduct. For we have an immediate intuition of the attributes of mind and matter, at least as phenomenal objects, and by these intuitions 88 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. may be tested the accuracy of the conceptions derived from them, sufficiently for all practi- cal purposes. A man will equally avoid walking over a precipice, and is logically as consistent in avoiding it, whether he regard the precipice as a real thing, or as a mere phenomenon. But in the province of theo- logy this is not the case. We have no im- mediate intuition of the Divine attributes, even as phenomena ; we only infer their existence and nature from certain similar attributes of which we are immediately con- scious in ourselves. And hence arises the question. How far does the similarity extend, and to what extent is the accuracy of our conceptions guaranteed by the intuition, not of the object to be conceived, but of some- thing more or less nearly resembling it? But this is not all. Our knowledge of God, ori- The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 89 ginally derived from personal consciousness, receives accession from two other sources — from the external world, as His work ; and from revelation, as His word ; and the conclusions derived from each have to be compared together. Should any discrepancy arise between them, are we at once warranted in rejecting one class of conclusions in favour of the other two, or two in favour of the third ? or are we at liberty to say that our knowledge in respect of all alike is of such an imperfect and indirect character that we are warranted in believing that some recon- ciliation may exist, though our ignorance prevents us from discovering what it is ? Here at least is a practical question of the very highest importance. In the early part of our previous remarks, we have endea- voured to show how this question has been 90 TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. answered by orthodox theologians of various ages, and how Sir W, Hamilton's philosophy supports that answer. We have now to con- sider Mr Mill's chapter of criticisms. It is always unfortunate to make a stumble on the threshold ; and Mr. Mill's opening paragraph makes two. '^ The name of God," he says, " is veiled under two extremely abstract phrases, ' the Infinite and the Abso- lute.' . . . But it is one of the most unquestionable of all logical maxims, that the meaning of the abstract must be sought in the concrete, and not conversely."'"' — Now, in the first jDlace, " the Infinite " and " the Absolute," even in the sense in which they are both predicable of God, are no more names of God than "■ the creature " and " the finite" are names of man. They are the * Examination, p. 32. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 91 names of certain attributes, which further inquiry may, perhaps, show to belong to God and to no other being, but which do not in their signification express this, and do not constitute our primary idea of God, wliich is tliat of a Person. Men may beUeve in an absolute and infinite, without in any proper sense believing in God ; and thousands upon thousands of pious men have prayed to a personal God, who have never heard of the absolute and the infinite, and who would not understand the expressions if they heard them. But, in the second place, '' the abso- lute" and "the infinite," in Sir W. Hamilton's sense of the terms, cannot both be names of God, for the simple reason that they are con- tradictory of each other, and are proposed as alternatives which cannot both be accepted as predicates of the same subject. For Hamil- 92 The P kilos op ky of the Conditioned. ton, whatever Mr. Mill may do, did not fall into tlie absurdity of maintaining that God in some of His attributes is absolute without being infinite, and in others is infinite with- out beino' absolute.'"" o But we have not yet done with this single paragraph. After thus making two errors in his exposition of his opponent's doctrine, Mr. Mill immediately proceeds to a third, in his criticism of it. By following his " most unquestionable of all logical maxims," and substituting the name of God in the place of " the Infinite " and " the Absolute," he ex- actly reverses Sir W. Hamilton's argument, and makes his own attempted refutation of it a glaring ignoratio elenchi. One of the purposes of Hamilton's argu- ment is to show that we have no positive * See Examination, p. 35. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 93 conception of an Infinite Being ; that when we attempt to form such a conception, we do but produce a distorted representation of the finite ; and hence, that our so-called concep- tion of the infinite is not the true infinite. Hence it is not to be wondered at — nay, it is a natural consequence of this doctrine, — that our positive conception of God as a Person cannot be included under this pseudo-concept of the Infinite. Whereas Mr. Mill, by laying down the maxim that the meaning of the abstract must be sought in the concrete, quietly assumes that this pseudo-infinite is a proper predicate of God, to be tested by its applicability to the subject, and that what Hamilton says of tliis infinite cannot be true unless it is also true of God. Of this refuta- tion, Hamilton, were he living, might truly say, as he said of a former criticism on 94 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. another part of his writings, — " This elabo- rate parade of argument is literally answered in two words — Qiii^ duhitavit V But if the substitution of God for the Infinite be thus a perversion of Hamilton's argument, what shall we say to a similar substitution in the case of the Absolute ? Hamilton distinctly tells us that there is one sense of the term absolute in which it is contradictory of the infinite, and therefore is not predicable of God at all. Mr. Mill admits that Hamilton, throughout the greater part of his arguments, employs the term in this sense ; and he then actually proceeds to " test " these arguments " by substituting the concrete, God, for the abstract. Absolute ;" i.e., by substituting God for something which Hamilton defines as contradictory to the nature of God. Can the force of confusion The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 95 go further? Is it possible for perverse criti- cism more utterly, Ave do not say to misre- present, but literally to invert an author's meanino- ? o The source of all these errors, and of a great many more, is simply this. Mr. Mill is aware, from Hamilton's express assertion, that the word absolute may be used in two distinct and even contradictory senses ; but he is wholly unable to see what those senses are, or when Hamilton is usinof the term in the one sense, and when in the other. Let us en- deavour to clear up some of this confusion. Hamilton's article on the Philosophy of the Unconditioned is a criticism, partly of Schelling, pai^tly of Cousin ; and Schelling and Cousin only attempted in a new form, under the influence of the Kantian philo- sophy, to solve the problem with which gG The Philosophy of the Conditioned. philosophy in all ages has attempted to grapple, — the problem of the Unconditioned. " The unconditioned " is a term which, while retaining the same general meaning, admits of various applications, particular or universal. It may be the unconditioned as regards some special relation, or the uncon- ditioned as reofards all relations whatever. Thus there may be the unconditioned in Psychology — the human soul considered as a substance ; the unconditioned in Cosmology — the world considered as a single whole ; the unconditioned in Theology — God in His own nature, as distinguished from His manifesta- tions to us ; or, finally, the unconditioned par excellence — the unconditioned in Onto- logy — the being on which all other being depends. It is of course possible to identify any one of the three first with the last. It The PhilosopJiy of iJic Conditiotied. 97 is possible to adopt a system of Egoism, and to maintain that all phenomena are modes of my mind, and that the substance of my mind is the only real existence. It is possible to adopt a system of Materialism, and to main- tain that all phenomena are modes of matter, and that the material substance of the world is the only real existence. Or it is possible to adopt a system of Pantheism, and to maintain that all phenomena are modes of the Divine existence, and that God is the only reality. But the several notions are in themselves distinct, though one may ulti- mately be predicated of another. The general notion of the Unconditioned is the same in all these cases, and all must finally culminate in the last, the Uncondi- tioned ])ar excellence. The general notion is that of the One as distinguished from the G 98 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Many, the substance from its accidents, the permanent reahty from its variable modifica- tions. Thought, will, sensation, are modes of my existence. What is the / that is one and the same in all ? Extension, figure, resist- ance, are attributes of matter. What is the one substance 'to which these attributes belong ? But the generalisation cannot stop liere. If matter differs from mind, the non- <'(jo from the ego, as one thing from another, there must be some special point of differ- ence, which is the condition of the existence of each in this or tliat particular manner. Unconditioned existence, therefore, in the hig'hest sense of the term, cannot be the existence of tlds as distino-uished from that : it must be existence j^er se, the ground and principle of all conditioned or special exist- ence. This is the Unconditioned, properly The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 99 so called : the unconditioned in Scliellinof's sense, as the indifference of subject and object : and it is against this that Hamilton's arguments are directed. The question is this. Is this Uncondi- tioned a mere abstraction, the product of our own minds ; or can it be conceived as having a real existence per se, and, as such, can it be identified with God as the source of all existence ? Hamilton maintains that it is a mere abstraction, and cannot be so identified ; that, far from being " a name of God," it is a name of nothmg at all. " By abstraction," he says, " we annihilate the object, and by abstraction we annihilate the subject of con- sciousness. But wliat remains ? Nothing." When we attempt to conceive it as a reality, we " hypostatise the zero."'"' * Discussions, p. 21. I oo The Philosophy of the Conditioned. In order to conceive the Unconditioned existing as a tiling, we must conceive it as existing out of relation to everything else. For if nothing beyond itself is necessary as a condition of its existence, it can exist separate from everything else ; and its pure existence as the unconditioned is so separate. It must therefore be conceivable as the sole existence, having no plurality beyond itself; and as simple, having no plurality within itself. For if we cannot conceive it as existing apart from other things, we cannot conceive it as independent of them ; and if we conceive it as a compound of parts, we have further to ask as before, what is the principle of unity which binds these j^arts into one whole ? If there is such a principle, this is the true unconditioned ; if there is no such principle, there is no unconditioned ; for that Avliich The Philosophy of the Conditioned, i o i cannot exist except as a compound is depen- dent for its existence on that of its several constituents. The unconditioned must there- fore be conceived as one, as simple, and as universal. Is such a conception possible, whether in ordinary consciousness, as Cousin says, or in an extraordinary intuition, as Schelling says ? Let us try the former. Consciousness is subject to the law of Time. A phenomenon is presented to us in time, as dependent on some previous phenomenon or thing. I wish to pursue the chain in thought till I arrive at something independent. If I could reach in thouo-ht a beofinninof of time, and discover some first fact with nothing preceding it, I should conceive time as absolute — as com- pleted, — and the unconditioned as the first thing in time, and therefore as completed I02 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. also, for it may be considered by itself, apart from what depends upon it. Or if time be considered as liavino- no beof-inninir, tliouo-lit would still be able to represent to itself that infinity, could it follow out the series of antecedents for ever. But is either of these alternatives possible to thought ? If not, w^e must confess that the unconditioned is incon- ceivable by ordinary consciousness ; and we must found philosophy, with Schelling, on the annihilation of consciousness. But though Hamilton himself distinguishes between the luiconditioned and the absolute, using the former term generall}^, for that which is out of all relation, and the latter specially, for that which is out of all relation as complete and finished, his opponent Cousin uses the latter term in a wider sense, as synonymous with the former, and the injimtc The P/dlosophy of the Conditioned. 103 as coextensive with both. This, however, does not affect the validity of Hamilton's arscument. For if it can be shown that the absolute and the infinite (in Hamilton's sense) are both inconceivable, the unconditioned (or absolute in Cousin's sense), which must be conceived as one or the other, is inconceivable also. Or, conversely, if it can be shown that the unconditioned, the unrelated in general, is inconceivable, it follows that the absolute and the infinite, as both involving the un- related, are inconceivable also. We may now proceed with Mr. Mill's criticism. He says : — "Absolute, in the sense in whicli it stands related to Infinite, means (conformably to its etymology) that which is finished or completed. There are some things of which the iitmost ideal amount is a limited quantity, though a ([uantity never actually reached. . . . We may speak 1 04 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. of absolutely, Imt not oi' iniinitcly, pure water. Tlic purity of water is not a fact of which, whatever degree we suppose attained, there remains a greater beyond. It has an absolute limit : it is capable of being finished or com- plete, in thought, if not in reality." — (P. 34.) This criticism is either incorrect or nildl ad rem. If meant as a statement of Hamilton's use of the term, it is incorrect : absolute, in Hamilton's philosophy, does not mean simply " completed," but " out of relation as com- pleted;" i.e., self-existent in its completeness, and not implying the existence of anything else. If meant in any other sense than Hamilton's, it is irrelevant. Can Mr. Mill really have believed that Schelling thought it necessary to invent an intellectual intuition out of time and out of consciousness, in order to contemplate " an ideal limited quantity," such as the complete purity of water ? Mr. Mill continues : — The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 105 " Though the idea of Absolute is thus contrasted with tliat of Infinite, the one is equally fitted with the other to he predicated of God ; hut not in respect of the same attributes. There is no incorrectness of speech in the plirase Infinite Power : because the notion it expresses is tliat of a Ik'ing Avho has tlie power of doing all things which we know or can conceive, and more. But in speak- ing of knowledge, Absolute is the proper word, and not Infinite. The highest degree of knowledge that can be spoken of with a meaning, only amoimts to knoAving all that there is to be known : when that point is reached, knowledge has attained its utmost limit. So of goodness or justice : they camiot be more than perfect. There are not infinite degrees of right. The will is either entirely right, or ^vrong in different degrees." — (P. 35.) Surely, whatever Divine power can do, Divine knowledge can know as possible to be done. The one, therefore, must be as infinite as the other. And what of Divine goodness? An angel or a glorified saint is absolutely good in Mr. MilFs sense of the term. His io6 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. " will is entirely right." Does Mr. Mill mean to say that there is no difference, even in degree, between the goodness of God and that of one of His creatures ? But, even supposing his statement to be true, how is it relevant to the matter under discussion ? Can Mr. Mill possibly be ignorant that all these attributes are relations ; that the Abso- lute in Hamilton's sense, "the unconditionally limited," is not predicable of God at all ; and that wdien divines and philosophers speak of the absolute nature of God, they mean a nature in wdiich there is no distinction of attributes at all ? Mr. Mill then proceeds to give a summar}^ of Hamilton's arguments against Cousin, preparatory to refuting them. In the course of this sunnnary he says : — " Let me ask, en jjassant, where is the necessity f(ir The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 107 supposing that, if tlic Absolute, or, to speak plainly, it' God, is only kunwn to us in the character of a cause, he must therefore ' exist merely as a cause,' and he merely 'a mean towards an end?' It is surely possilile to maintain that the Deity is known to us only as he who feeds the ravens, witliout supposing that the Divine Intelligence ex- ists solely in order that the ravens may be fed."'" — (P. 42.) (Jn this we would remark, en jxissant^ that this is precisely Hamilton's own doctrine, that the sphere of our belief is more ex- * In a note to this passage, Mr. Mill makes some sarcastic com- ments on an argument of Hamilton's against Cousin's theory that God is necessarily determined to create. "On this hj^pothesis, " says Hamilton, "God, as necessarily determined to pass from abso- lute essence to relative manifestation, is determined to pass either from the better to the worse, or from the worse to the better." Mr. Mill calls this argument " a curiosity of dialectics," and answers, " Perfect wisdom \\-ould have begun to will the new state at the precise moment Avhen it began to be better than the old." Hamil- ton is not speaking of states of things, but of states of the Divine nature, as creative or not creative ; and Mr. Mill's argument, to refute Hamilton, must suppose a time when the new nature of God begins to be better than the old ! Mr. Mill would perhaps have spoken of Hamilton's argument with more respect had he known that it is taken from Plato. 1 08 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. tensive than that of our knowledge. The purport of Hamilton's argument is to show that the Absolute, as conceived by Cousin, is not a true Absolute {Injinito-Ahsolute), and therefore does not represent the real nature of God. His argument is this : " Cousin's Absolute exists merely as a cause : God does not exist merely as a cause : there- fore Cousin's Absolute is not God." Mr. Mill actually mistakes the position which Hamilton is opposing for that which he is maintainino-. Such an error does not lead us to expect much from his subsequent re- futation. His first criticism is a curious specimen of his reading in philosophy. He says : — • " When the True or the Beautiful are spoken of, the phrase is meant to inchide all things whatever that are true, or all things Avhatever that are beautiful. If this The Philosophy of the CoJiditioiied. 1 09 rule is good for otlier abstractions, it is good for tlie Abso- lute. The word is devoid of meaning unless in reference to predicates of some sort. ... If we are told, there- fore, that there is some Being Avho is, or which is, the Absolute, — not something absolute, but the Absolute itself, — the proposition can be understood in no other sense than that the supposed Being possesses in absolute completeness all predicates ; is absolutely good and abso- lutely bad ; absolutely Avise and absolutely stupid ; and so forth."'"— (P. 43.) Plato expressly distinguishes between "the beautiful " and " things that are beautiful/' as the One in contrast to the Many — the Real in contrast to the Apparent, t It is, of course, quite possible that Plato may be * In support of this position, Mr. Mill cites Hegel — " A\Tiat kind of an absolute Being is that which does not contain in itself all that is actual, even evil included ?" We are not concerned to defend Hegel's position ; but he was not quite so absurd as to mean what Jlr. Mill supposes him to have meant. Does not Mr. IVlill know that it was one of Hegel's fundamental positions, that the Divine nature cannot be expressed by a plurality of predicates ? t Bf public, book v., p. 479. 1 1 o The Philosophy of the Conditioned. wrong, and Mr. Mill right ; but the mere fact of their antagonism is sufficient to show that the meaning of " the phrase " need not be what Mr. Mill supposes it must be. In fact, '' the Absolute " in philosophy always has meant the One as distinofuished from the Many, not the One as including the Many. But, as applied to Sir W. Hamilton, Mr. Mill's remarks on " the Absolute," and his subsequent remarks on " the Infinite," not only misrepresent Hamilton's position, but exactly reverse it. Hamilton maintains that the tenns '' absolute " and " infinite " are per- fectly intelligible as abstractions, as much so as " relative " and " finite ;" for " correlatives suggest each other," and the " knowledge of contradictories is one ; " but he denies that a concrete thing or object can be posi- tively conceived as absolute or infinite. Mr. The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned, i i i Mill represents him as only proving that the '* unmeaning abstractions are unknowable," — abstractions which Hamilton does not assert to be unmeaning, and which he regards as knowable in the only sense in which such abstractions can be known, viz., by under- standing- the meaninp- of their names. ""' " Souiethiiig iiilinite," says Mr. Mill, " is a conception which, like most of our complex ideas, contains a negative element, but which contains positive elements also. In- tinite space, for instance ; is there nothing positive in tliat % The negative part of this conception is the absence * This confusion between conceiving a concrete thing and knowing the meaning of abstract terms is as okl as Toland's Christianity nut Mysterious, and, indeed, has its germ, though not its development, in the teaching of his assumed master, Locke. Locke taught that all our knowledge is founded on simple ideas, and that a complex idea is merely an accumulation of simple ones. Hence Toland maintained that no object could be mysterious or inconceivable if the terms in which its several attributes are ex- pressed have ideas corresponding to them. But, in point of fact, no simple idea can be conceived as an object by itself, though the word by which it is signified has a perfectly intelligible meaning. I I 2 The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. of bounds. Tlie positive are, tlie idea of space, and of space greater than any finite space." — (P. 45.) This definition of infinite space is exactly that which Descartes gives us of indefinite extension, — " Ita quia non possumus imagi- nari extensionem tarn magnani, quin intelh- ganius aclhuc majoreni esse posse, dicemus magnitudinem rerum possibiliuni esse inde- fi.nitam." "' So too, Cudworth, — " There appeareth no sufficient ground for tliis posi- tive infinity of space ; we being certain of no I cannot, e. g., conceive whiteness by itself, though I can conceive a white wall, i. e., whiteness in combination with other attributes in a concrete object. To conceive attributes as coexisting, how- ever, we must conceive tliem as coexisting in a certain manner ; for an object of conception is not a mere heap of ideas, but an organized whole, whose constituent ideas exist in a particular combination with and relation to each other. To conceive, therefore, we must not only be able to apprehend each idea separately in the abstract, but also the manner in which they may possibly exist in combina- tion with each other. * Prineipia, i., 26. The Philosophy of the Cofiditioned. 113 more than this, that be the world or any figurative body never so great, it is not impossible but that it might be still greater and greater without end. Which indejinite increasableness of body and space seems to be mistaken for a j^os^Vu'e injinity thereof.'""' And Locke, a philosopher for whom Mr. Mill will probably have more respect than for Descartes or Cudworth, writes more plainly : "To have actually in the mind the idea of a space infinite, is to suppose the mind already passed over, and actually to have a view of all those repeated ideas of space, which an endless repetition can never totally represent to it, — which carries in it a plain contradiction. "t Mr. Mill thus un- wittingly illustrates, in his own person, the * Intdhdual System, ed. Harasoii, vol. iii., p. 131. t Essay, ii., 17, 7. H 1 1 4 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. truth of Hamilton's remark, "If we dream of effecting tliis [conceiving the infinite in time or space], we only deceive ourselves by substituting the indefinite for the infinite, than which no two notions can be more opposed." In fact, Mr. Mill does not seem to be aware that what the mathematician calls iiifinite, the metaphysician calls inde- finite, and that arguments drawn from the mathematical use of the term infinite are wholly irrelevant to the metaphysical. How, indeed, could it be otherwise? Can any man suppose that, when the Divine attributes are spoken of as infinite, it is meant that they are indefinitely increasable ?'"" * One of the ablest mathematicians, and the most persevering Hamiltono-niastix of the day, maintains the applicahility of the metaphysical notion of infinity to mathematical magnitudes ; but witli an assumption which unintentionally vindicates Hamilton's position more fully than could have been done by a professed dis- The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned, i r 5 lii fact, it is the '' concrete reality," the " something infinite," and not tlie mere abstraction of infinity, which is only con- ceivable as a negation. Every " something " that has ever been intuitively present to my consciousness is a something finite. When, therefore, I speak of a '' something infinite," ciple. "I shall assume," says Professor De Morgan, in a paper recently printed among the Traiisactions of the Cambridge Philo- sophical Society, "the notion of infinity and of its reciprocal in- finitesimal : that a line can be conceived infinite, and therefore having points at an infinite distance. Image apart, which we can- not have, it seems to me clear that a line of infinite length, with- out points at an infinite distance, is a contradiction." Now it is easy to sliow, by mere reasoning, without any image, that this assumption is equally a contradiction. For if space is finite, every line in space must be finite also ; and if space is infinite, every point in space must have infinite space beyond it in every direction, and therefore cannot be at the greatest possible distance from another l)oint. Or thus : Any two points in space are the extremities of the line connecting them ; but an infinite line has no extremities ; therefore no two points in space can be connected together by an infinite line. 1 1 6 TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. I mean a sometliino- existino: in a different manner from all the " somethinofs " of wliicli I have had experience in intuition. Thus it is apprehended, not positively, but negatively — not directly by what it is, but indirectly by what it is not. A negative idea is not negative because it is expressed by a nega- tive term, but because it has never been realised in intuition. If infinity, as applied to space, means the same tiling as being greater than any finite space, both concep- tions are equally positive or equally negative. If it does not mean the same thing, then, in conceiving a space greater than any finite space, we do not conceive an infinite space. Mr. Mill's next string of criticisms may be very briefly dismissed. First, Hamilton does not, as Mr. Mill asserts, say that " the Unconditioned is inconceivable, because it The PJdlosophy of tJic Conditioned. 1 1 7 includes both the Infinite and the Absolute, and these are contradictoiy ol one another." His argument is a common disjunctive syl- logism. The unconditioned, if conceivable at all, must be conceived either as the absolute or as the infinite ; neither of these is pos- sible ; therefore the unconditioned is not conceivable at all. Nor, secondly, is Sir W. Hamilton guilty of the " strange confusion of ideas" which Mr. Mill ascribes to him, when he says that the Absolute, as being absolutely One, cannot be known under the conditions of plurality and difference. The absolute, as such, must be out of all relation, and consequently cannot be conceived in the relation of plurality. " The plurality re- quired," says Mr. Mill, " is not within the thing itself, but is made up between itself and other things." It is, in fact, both ; T 1 8 The PhilosopJiy of the Conditioiieel. but even granting Mr. Mill's assumption, what is a " plurality between a thing and other thino-s " but a relation between them ? There is undoubtedly a " strange confusion of ideas " in this paragraph ; but the con- fusion is not on the part of Sir W. Hamilton. '' Again," continues Mr. Mill, " even if we concede that a thing cannot be known at all unless known as plural, does it follow that it cannot be known as plural because it is also One ? Since when have the One and the Many been incompatible things, instead of different aspects of the same thing ? . . . If there is any meaning in the words, must not Absolute Unity be Absolute Plurality likewise?" Mr. Mill's ^' since when?" may be answered in the words of Plato : — ^" Ot;^e)' eijioiye utottov ooKe'i elvai el eJ' airavTU uirocbalveL Ti? Tw ixeTeyeiv tov evo^ kui tuvtu Tavra ttoWu The PJulosophy of the Conditioned, i i 9 T6D liX^Qoix; av fxeTeyeiv aX\ e« o 'Icttiv ei', auro TOVTO TToWu UTrovel^ei, Koi uu tu iroWa (Vj ev, TovTo 'i'i()}] Ouvjuda-ofxai."'"' Here we are ex- pressly told that " absolute unity " cannot be " absolute plurality." Mr. Mill may say that Plato is wrong ; but he will hardly go so far as to say that there is no meaning in his w^ords. In point of fact, however, it is Mr. Mill who is in error, and not Plato. In different relations, no doubt, the same con- crete object may be regarded as one or as many. The same measure is one foot or twelve inches ; the same sum is one shilling or twelve pence ; but it no more follows that " absolute unity must be absolute plurality likewise," than it follows from the above instances that one is equal to twelve. And, thirdly, when Mr. Mill accuses Sir W. * Parmenidcs, p. 129. 120 TJie Philosophy of tJie Conditioned. Hamilton of departing from his own mean- inof of the term absolute, in maintaining- that the Absolute cannot be a Cause, he only shows that he does not himself know what Hamilton's meaning is. " If Absolute/' he says, '^ means finished, perfected, completed, may there not be a finished, perfected, and completed Cause ? " Hamilton's Absolute is that which is "out of relation, as finished, perfect, complete ;" and a Cause, as such, is both in relation and incomplete. It is in relation to its effect ; and it is incomplete without its effect. Finally, when Mr. Mill charges Sir W. Hamilton with maintaining " that extension and fiafure are of the essence of matter, and perceived as such by intui- tion," we must briefly reply that Hamilton does no such thing. He is not sjDeaking of the essence of matter j;er se, but only The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 2 1 of matter as apprehended in relation to us. Mr. Mill concludes this chapter with an attempt to discover the meaning of Hamil- ton's assertion, "to think is to condition." We have already explained what Hamilton meant by this expression ; and we recur to the subject now, only to show the easy manner in which Mr. Mill manages to miss the point of an argument with the clue lying straight before him. '' Did any," he says (of those who say that the Absolute is thinkable), '^ profess to think it in any other manner than by distinguishing it from other things ? " Now this is the very thing which, according to Hamilton, Schelling actually did. Mr. Mill does not attempt to show that Hamilton is wrong in his interpretation of Schelling, nor, if he is right, what were 1 2 2 The PJiilosopJiy of the Conditioned. the reasons which led Schelling to so para- doxical a position : he simply assumes that no man could hold Schellino-'s view, and there is an end of it.'" Hamilton's purpose is to reassert in substance the doctrine which Kant maintained, and which Schelling denied ; and the natural way to ascertain his meaning would he by reference to these two philosophers. But this is not the method of * Mr. Mill does not expressly name Schelling in tins sentence : but lie does so shortly aftenvards ; and his remark is of the same character with the previous one. " Even Schelling," he says, "was not so gratuitously absurd as to deny that the Absolute must be known according to the capacities of that which knows it — though he was forced to invent a special capacity for the pur- pose." But if this capacity is an " invention" of Schelling's, and if he was "forced" to invent it, Hamilton's point is proved. To think, according to all the real operations of thought which con- sciousness makes known to us, is to condition. And the faculty of the unconditioned is an invention of Schelling's, not known to consciousness. In other words : all our real faculties bear witness to the truth of Hamilton's statement ; and the only way of contro- verting it is to invent an imaginary faculty for the purpose. TJic PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. 1 2 3 Mr. Mill, here or elsewhere. He generally endeavours to ascertain Hamilton's meaning by ranging the wide field of possibilities. He tells us what a phrase means in certain authors of whom Hamilton is not thinking, or in reference to certain matters which Hamilton is not discussing ; but he hardly ever attempts to trace the history of Hamil- ton's own view, or the train of thought by which it suggested itself to his mind. And the result of this is, that Mr. Mill's inter- pretations are generally in the potential mood. He wastes a good deal of conjecture in discoverino- what Hamilton mio-ht have meant, when a little attention in the right quarter would have shown what he did mean. The third feature of Hamilton's philosophy which we charged Mr. Mill with misunder- 124 TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. standing, is the distinction between Know- ledge and Belief. In the early part of this article, we endeavoured to explain the true nature of this distinction ; we have now only a very limited space to notice Mr. Mill's criticisms on it. Hamilton, he says, ad- mitted '^ a second source of intellectual con- viction called Belief." Now Belief is not a " source " of any conviction, but the convic- tion itself No man w^ould say that he is convinced of the truth of a proposition because he believes it ; his belief in its truth is the same thino' as his conviction of its truth. Belief, then, is not a source of con- viction, but a conviction having sources of its own. The question is, have we legitimate sources of conviction, distinct from those which constitute Knowledge properly so called ? Now here it should be remembered The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 125 that the distinction is not one invented by Hamilton to meet the exigencies of his own system. He enumerates as many as twenty- two authors, of the most various schools of philosophy, who all acknowledged it before him. Such a concurrence is no slight argument in favour of the reality of the distinction. We do not say that these writers, or Hamilton himself, have always expressed this distinction in the best lan- guage, or applied it in the best manner ; but we say that it is a true distinction, and that it is valid for the principal purpose to wiiich Hamilton applied it. We do not agree with all the details of Hamilton's application. We do not agree with him, though he is supported by very eminent authorities, in classifying our con- viction of axiomatic principles as helief, and I 2 6 The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. not as knowlechje.'"' But this question does not directly bear on Mr, Mill's criticism. The point of that criticism is, that Hamilton, by admitting a belief in the infinite and unrelated, nullifies his own doctrine, that all knowledge is of the finite and relative. Let us see, * Hamilton's distinction is in principle the same as that wliirh we have given in our previous remarks (pp. 18, 19). He says, " A conviction is incomprehensible when there is merely given to us in consciousness — That its object is {on ^an), and when we are unable to comprehend through a higher notion or belief JVhy or Hotv it is {SwTi iart)." — {Rcicl's Works, p. 754.) We Avould distinguish between why and how, between Siort and wws. We. can give no reason why two straight lines cannot enclose a space ; but we can comprehend hoio they cannot. We have only to form the corres- ponding image, to see the manner in which the two attributes <;oexist in one object. But when I say that I believe in the exist- ence of a spu-itual being who sees without eyes, I cannot conceive the manner in which seeing coexists with the absence of the bodily organ of sight. We believe that the true distinction between knowledge and belief may ultimately be referred to the presence ( ir absence of the corresponding intuition ; but to show this in the various instances would require a longer dissertation than our present limits will allow. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 2 7 We may believe that a thing is, without being able to conceive liov) it is. I believe that God is a person, and also tliat He is infinite ; though I cannot conceive how the attributes of personality and infinity exist together. All my knowledge of personality is derived from my consciousness of my own finite personality. I therefore believe in the coexistence of attributes in God, in some manner different from that in which they coexist in me as limiting each other : and thus I believe in the fact, though I am unable to conceive the manner. So, again, Kant brings certain counter arguments, to prove, on the one side, that the world has a beginning in time, and, on the other side, that it has not a beginning. Now suppose I am unable to refute either of these courses of argument, am I therefore compelled to 128 TJic PhilosopJiy of the Conditioned. have no belief at all ? May I not say, I believe, in spite of Kant, tliat the world has a beginning in time, though I am unable to conceive how it can have so begun ? What is this, again, but a belief in an absolute reality beyond the sphere of my relative knowledge ? " I am not now considering," says Mr. Mill, " what it is that, in our author's opinion, we are bound to believe concerning the unknowable." Why, this was the very thing he ought to have considered, before pronouncing the position to be untenable, or to be irreconcilable with something else. Meanwhile, it is instructive to observe that Mr. Mill himself believes, or requires his readers to believe, something concerning the unknown. He does not know, or at any rate he does not tell his readers, what Hamilton The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 129 requires them to believe concerning the unknowable ; but he himself believes, and requires them to believe, that this unknown something is incompatible with the doctrine tliat knowledge is relative. We cannot re- gard this as a very satisfactory mode of refuting Hamilton's thesis/''' * In a subsequent chapter (p. 120), Mr. Mill endeavours to overthrow this distinction between Knowledge and Belief, by means of Hamilton's own theory of Consciousness. Hamilton maintains that we cannot be conscious of a mental operation without being conscious of its object. On this Mr. Mill retorts that if^ as Hamilton admits, we are conscious of a belief in the Infinite and the Absolute, we must be conscious of the Infinite and the Abso- lute themselves ; and such consciousness is Knowledge. The fallacy of this retort is transparent. The immediate object of Belief is a pro2iosition which I hold to be true, not a thiiuj apprehended in an act of conception. I believe in an infinite God ; i. e. , I believe tJiat God is infinite : I believe that the attributes which I ascribe to God exist in Him in an infinite degi-ee. Now, to believe this pro- position, I must, of course, be conscious of its meaning ; but I am not therefore conscious of the Infinite God as an object of concep- tion ; for tliis would require further an apprehension of the manner in which these infinite attributes coexist so as to form one object. The whole argument of this eighth chapter is confused, owing to 1 30 The Philosophy of the Condiiioiied. But if Mr. Mill is unjust towards the distinction between Knowledge and Belief, as held by Sir W. Hamilton, he makes ample amends to the injured theory in the next chapter, by enlarging the province of credibility far beyond any extent which Hamilton would have dreamed of claiming- for it. Conceivability or inconceivablity, he tells us, are usually dependent on association; and it is quite j)ossible that, under other associations, we might be able to conceive, and therefore to believe, anything short of the direct contradiction that the same thing is and is not. It is not in itself incredible that a square may at the same time be Mr. Mill not having distinguished between those passages in which Sir W. Hamilton is merely using an argumentum ad hominem in relation to Eeid, and those in which he is reasoning from general principles. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 3 1 round, that two straight Hnes may enclose a space, or even that two and two may make five/" But whatever concessions Mr, Mill may make on this point, he is at least fully determined that Sir W. Hamilton shall derive no benefit from them ; for he forth- with proceeds to charge Sir William with confusinof three distinct senses of the term conception — a confusion which exists solely in his own imagination, t — and to assert that * In reference to this last paradox, Mr. Mill quotes from Essays by a Barrister: "There is a world in which, whenever two pairs of things are either placed in proximity or are contemplated together, a fifth thing is immediately created and brought within the con- temi^lation of tlie mind engaged in putting two and two together. ... In such a world surely two and two would make five. That is, the result to the mind of contemplating two twos would be to count five. " The answer to this reasoning has been already given by Archdeacon Lee in his Essay on Miracles. The "five" in this case is not the sum of two and two, but of two and tv^o plios the new creature, i.e., of two and two^;Z((s one. + The sense in which Sir W. Hamilton himself uses the word co7ice2)tion is explained in a note to Eeid's JVorks, p. 377 — namely. T32 The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. the Pliilosopliy of the Conditioned is entirely founded on a mistake, inasmuch as infinite space on the one hand, and, on the other, both an absohite minimum and an infinite di- visibiHty of space, are perfectly conceivable. With reofard to the former of these two assertions, Mr. Mill's whole argument is the combination of two or more attributes in a unity of rcprescnla- tion. The second sense which Mr. Mill imagines is simply a mis- take of his own. When Hamilton speaks of being "unable to conceive as possible," he does not mean, as Mr. Mill supposes, physically possible under the law of gravitation or some other law of matter, but mentally possible as a representation or image ; and thus the supposed second sense is identical with the first. The third sense may also be reduced to the first ; for to conceive two attributes as combined in one representation is to form a notion subordinate to those of each attribute separately. We do not say that Sir W. Hamilton has been uniformly accurate in his application of the test of conceivability ; but we say that his inaccuracies, such as they are, do not aff'ect the theory of the conditioned, and that in all the long extracts which Mr. Mill quotes, with footnotes, indi- cating "first sense," " second sense," " third sense, " the author's meaning may be more accurately explained in the first sense only. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 133 vitiated, as we have already shown, by his confusion between infinite and indefinite ; but it is worth while to quote one of his special instances in this chapter, as a speci- men of the kind of reasoning which an eminent writer on losfic can sometimes em- ploy. In reference to Sir W. Hamilton's assertion, that infinite space would require infinite time to conceive it, he says, " Let us try the doctrine upon a complex whole, short of infinite, such as the number 695,788. Sir W. Hamilton would not, I suppose, have maintained that this number is inconceivable. How lonof did he think it would take to p"o over every separate unit of this whole, so as to obtain a perfect knowledge of the exact sum, as different from all other sums, either greater or less ? " It is marvellous that it should not have 134 ^Z^*^' Philosophy of the Conditioned. occurred to Mr. Mill, while he was writing this passage, "How comes this large number to be a ^ whole' at all ; and how comes it that ' this whole,' with all its units, can be written down by means of six digits ?" Simply because of a conventional arrangement, by which a single digit, according to its position, can express, by one mark, tens, hundreds, thousands, &c., of units ; and thus can ex- haust the sum by dealing with its items in large masses. But how can such a process exhaust the infinite ? We should like to know how lonof Mr. Mill thinks it would take to work out the following problem : — " If two figures can represent ten, three a hundred, four a thousand, five ten thousand, &c., find the number of figures required to represent infinity."'" * Precisely the same iniseonception of Hamilton's position occurs The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 135 Infinite divisibility stands or falls with infinite extension. In both cases Mr. Mill confounds infinity with indefiniteness. But with regard to an absolute minimum of space, Mr. Mill's argument requires a separate notice, " It is not denied," he says, " that there is a portion of extension Avhich to tlie naked eye appears an indivisible point ; it has been called by philosophers the minimum visihihi. This minimum we can indefinitely magnify by means of optical instruments, making visible the still smaller parts which compose it. In each successive ex- periment there is still a minimum visihile, anjiihing less than which cannot be discovered with that instrument, but can with one of a liigher power. Suppose, now, that in Professor De Morgan's paper in the Cambridge Transactions, to which we have previously referred. He speaks (p. 13) of the "notion, which runs through many writers, from Descartes to Hamilton, that the mind must be big enough to Jiold all it can con- ceive." This notion is certainly not maintained by Hamilton, nor yet by Descartes in the paragraph quoted by Mr. De Morgan ; nor, as far as we are aware, in any other part of his works. 136 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. as we increase tlie magnifying power of our instruments, anil before we have readied the limit of possible increase, we arrive at a stage at which that which seemed the smallest visible space under a given microscope, does not appear larger under one which, by its mechanical construc- tion, is adapted to magnify more, but still remains appa- rently indivisible. I say, that if this happened, we should believe in a minimum of extension ; or if some a jn'iori metaphysical prejudice prevented us from believing it, we sho'dd at least be enabled to conceive it." — (P. 84.) The natural conclusion of most men under such circumstances would be, that there was some fault in the microscope. But even if this conclusion were rejected, we presume Mr. Mill would allow that, under the supposed circumstances, the exact magnitude of the minimum of extension would be calculable. We have only to measure the minimum visihile, and know what is the magnifying power of our microscope, to determine the The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 3 7 exact dimensions. Suppose, then, that we assign to it some definite magnitude — say the ten biUionth part of an inch, — should we then conclude that it is impossible to con- ceive the twenty billionth part of an inch ? — in other words, that we have arrived at a definite maofnitude which has no conceivable half? Surely this is a somewhat rash con- cession to be made by a writer w^ho has just told us that numbers may be conceived up to infinity ; and therefore, of course, down to infinitesimality. Mr. Mill concludes this chapter with an assertion which, even by itself, is sufficient to show how very little he has attended to or understood the philosophy which he is at- tempting to criticise. " The law of Excluded Middle," he says, "as well as that of Con- tradiction, is common to all phenomena. 138 The Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. But it is a doctrine of our author that these laws are true, and cannot but be known to be true, of Noumena Hkewise. It is not merely Space as cognisable by our senses, but Space as it is in itself, which he affirms must be either of unlimited or of limited extent" (p. 86). At this sentence we fairly stand aghast. " Space as it is in itself ! " the Noumenon Space ! Has Mr. Mill been all this while ''examining" Sir William Hamilton's philosophy, in utter ignorance that the object of that philosophy is the " Conditioned in Time and Space ;" that he accepts Kant's analysis of time and space as formal necessities of thought, but pronounces no opinion whatever as to whether time and space can exist as Noumena or not ? It is the phenomenal space, " space as cognisable by our senses," which Sir W. Hamilton says The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 139 must be either limited or unlimited : con- cerning the Noumenon Space, he does not hazard an opinion whether such a thing exists or not. He says, indeed (and this is probably what has misled Mr. Mill), that the laws of Identity, Contradiction, and Ex- cluded Middle, are laws of things as well as laws of thought ;"' but he says nothing about these laws as predicating infinite or finite extension. On the contrary, he expressly classifies Space under the law^ of Relativity, the violation of which indicates what may exist, but what we are unable to conceive as existing. Briefly, the law of Excluded Middle (to take this instance alone) is a law of things only in its abstract form, " Every- thing must be A or not iV" {extended, if you please, or not extended) ; but in its subordi- * Discussions, p. 603. 1 40 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. iiate form, *' Everything extended must be extended infinitely or finitely/' it is only applicable, and only intended by Hamilton to be applied, to those phenomena which are already given as extended in some degree. We have now examined the first six chap- ters of Mr. Mill's book, containing his remarks on that portion of Sir W. Hamil- ton's philosophy which he justly regards as comprising the most important of the doc- trines which specially belong to Hamilton himself. The next chapter is an episode, in which Mr, Mill turns aside from Sir W. Hamilton to criticise Mr. Mansel's Bampton Lectures. As our limits do not permit us to carry on the argument at present through the remainder of Mr. Mill's remarks on Hamilton himself, we shall conclude our notice with a few words on this chapter, as TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. 141 closing the properly metaphysical portion of Mr. Mill's book, and as affording ample proof that, in this department of philosophy at least, Mr. Mill's- powers of misapprehen- sion do not cease when Sir W. Hamilton is no longer their object. Mr. Mill's method of criticism makes it generally necessary to commence with a statement of the criticised theory as it really is, before proceeding to his exposition of it as it is not. The present instance offers no exception to this rule. Mr. Mansel's argu- ment may be briefly stated as follows. The primary and essential conception of God, imperatively demanded by our moral and religious consciousness, is that of a person. But personality implies intellectual and moral attributes ; and the only direct and immediate knowledg-e which we have of such 142 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. attributes is derived from the testimony of self-consciousness, bearing witness to their existence in a certain manner in ourselves. But when we endeavour to transfer the conception of personality, thus obtained, to the domain of theology, we meet with certain difficulties, which, while they are not suf- ficient to hinder us from helieving in the Divine Personality as a fact, yet hinder us from conceiving the manner of its existence, and prevent us from exhibiting our belief as a philosophical conclusion, proved by irre- fragable reasoning and secured against all objections. These difficulties are occasioned, on the one hand, by the so-called Philosophy of the. Unconditioned, which in all ages has sho^vn a tendency towards Pantheism, and which, in one of its latest and most finished manifestations, announces itself as the ex- The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 143 liibition of God as He is in His eternal nature before creation ; and, on the other hand, by the limitations and conditions to which our own personality is subject, and which, as we have pointed out in tlie earlier part of this article, have, from the very beginning of Christian theology, prevented theologians from accepting the limited per- sonality of man as an exact image and counterpart of the unlimited personality of God. These difficulties Mr. Mansel endea- vours to meet in two ways. On the one side, he maintains, in common with Sir W. Hamilton, that the Philosophy of the Un- conditioned, by reason of its own incon- gruities and self-contradictions, has no claim to be accepted as a competent witness in the matter ; and on the other side, he maintains, in. common with many theologians before 1 44 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. him, that human personality cannot be as- sumed as an exact cojoy of the Divine, but only as that which is most nearly analogous to it among finite things. But these two positions, if admitted, involve a corresponding practical conclusion as regards the criterion of religious truth or falsehood. Were we capable, either, on the one hand, of a clear conception of the Unconditioned, or, on the other, of a direct intuition of the Divine Attributes as objects of consciousness, we might be able to construct, deductively or inductively, an exact science of Theology. As it is, we are compelled to reason by analogy ; and analogy furnishes only pro- babilities, vaiying, it may be, from slight presumptions up to moral certainties, but whose weight, in any given case, can only be determined by comparison with other evi- TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. 145 dences. There are three distinct sources from which we may form a judgment about the ways of God — first, from our own moral and intellectual consciousness, by which we judge d priori of what God ought to do in a given case, by determining what we should think it wise or rio-ht for ourselves to do in a similar case ; secondly, from the constitution and course of nature, from which we may learn by experience what God's providence in certain cases actually is ; and thirdly, from revelation, attested by its proper evi- dences. Where these three agree in their testimony (as in the great majority of cases they do) we have the moral certainty which results from the liarmony of all accessible evidences : where they appear to differ, we have no rio'lit at once to conclude that the second or the third must give way to the K 146 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. first, and not vice versd ; because we have no right to assume that the first alone is in- f'aUible. In the author's own words : " The lesson to be learnt from an examination of the Limits of Religious Thought is not that man's judgments are ivorthless in relation to Divine things, but that they snefallihle: and tlie probability of error in any particular case can never be fairly estimated without giving their full weight to all collateral considera- tions. We are indeed bound to believe that a Revelation given by God can never contain anything that is really unwise or unrighteous ; but we are not always capable of estimating exactly the wisdom or righteousness of par- ticular doctrines or precepts. And we are bound to bear in mind that exact l)/ in ])ro- portion to the strength of the remaining evidence for the Divine origin of a religion, is The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 147 the iDrohahility that we may he mistaken in supposing this or that portion of its contents to he unworthy of God. Taken in con- junction, the two arguments may confirm or correct each other : taken singly and ab- solutely, each may vitiate the result which should follow from their joint application." "'' In criticising the first part of this argument — that which is directed ao'ainst the deductive jDhilosophy of the Unconditioned — Mr. Mill manifests the same Avant of acquaintance wdth its meaning, and with the previous history of the question, which he had before exhibited in his attack on Sir W. Hamilton. He begins by finding fault with the definition of the Absolute, which Mr. Mansel (herein departing, and purposely departing, from Sir W, Hamilton's use of the term) defines as * BamxHon Lectures, p. 156, 4tli edition. 148 The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. "that which exists in and by itself, having no necessary relation to any other Being." On this, Mr. Mill remarks : '' The first words of his definition would serve for the descrip- tion of a Noumenon ; but Mr. Mansel's Absolute is only meant to denote one Being, identified with God, and God is not the only Noumenon." The description of a Nou- menon ! This is almost equal to the discovery of a Noumenon Space. Does Mr. Mill really suppose that all noumena are self- existent % A noumenon (in the sense in which we suppose Mr. Mill to understand the term, for it has different meanings in different philosophies) implies an existence out of relation to the human mind."" But is * strictly speaking, the temi noumenon, as meaning that which can be apprehended only by the intellect, implies a relation to the intellect apprehending it ; and in this sense to voovixevov is opposed l)y Plato to Tb opufievov — the object of intellect to the object cf The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 149 this the same as being out of all relation whatever, as existing '^ in and by itself ? " Does Mr. Mill mean to say that a creature, whether perceived by us or not, has no rela- tion to its Creator ? But Mr. Mill, as we have seen before, is not much at home when he 2:ets amono" ^^noumena." AVe must pro- ceed to his criticism of the second part of the definition, — " having no necessary relation to sight. But as tlie intellect was supposed to take cognisance of things as they are, in opposition to the sensitive perception of things as they appear, the term noiirnenon hecame synonpnous with ihiiig in itself {to ov i:ad' avro). And this meaning is retained in the Kantian philosophy, in which the noumenon is identical with the Ding an sick. But as Kant denied to the human intellect any immediate intuition of things as they are (though such an intuition may be possible to a superhuman intellect), hence the term noumenon in the Kantian philosophy is opposed to all of wliich the human intellect can take positive cognisance. Hamilton, in this respect, agrees with Kant. But neither Kant nor Hamilton, in opposing the thing in itself to the ijhcnomenon, meant to imply that the former is necessarily self-existent, and therefore uncreated. 15'^ The Philosophy of the Conditioned. any other being." Of these words he says, that " they admit of two constructions. The words in their natural sense only mean, capahle of cxiding out of relation to anything else. The argument requires that they should mean incapahle of existing in relation with anything else." And why is this non-natural sense to be forced upon very plain words ? Because, says Mr. Mill, — " In Avliat manner is a possible existence out of all rela- tion, incompatible with tlie notion of a cause 1 Have not causes a possible existence apart from their effects 1 "Would the sun, for example, not exist if there were no earth or planets for it to illuminate 1 INIr. Mansel seems to think that what is capable of existing out of relation, cannot possibly be conceived or known in relation. But this is not so. . . . Freed from this confusion of ideas, Mr. IMan- sel's argument resolves itself into this, — The same Being cannot be thought by us both as Cause and as Absolute, because a Cause as such is not Absolute, and Absolute, as such, is not a Cause ; which is exactly as if he had said The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 5 1 that Newton cannot l)e tliouglit by us Lotli as an Engli.sli- nian and as a matlicniatician, because an Englishman, as such, is not a mallieniatician, nor a mathematician, as such, an Englishman."— (P. i)2.) The '■^ confusion of ideas " is entirely of Mr, Mill's own making, and is owing to his having mutilated the argument before criti- cising it. The argument in its original form consists of two parts ; the first intended to show that the Absolute is not conceived rt.s siicli in being conceived as a Cause ; the second to show that the Absolute cannot be conceived under different asj^ects at different times — first as Absolute, and then as Cause. It was the impossibility of this latter alterna- tive which drove Cousin to the hypothesis of a necessary causation from all eternity. Mr. Mill entirely omits the latter part of the argument, and treats the former part as if it I 5 2 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. were the whole. The part criticised by Mr. Mill is intended to prove exactly what it does prove, and no more ; namely, that a cause as such is not the absolute, and that to know a cause a.s' such is not to know the absolute. We presume Mr. Mill himself will admit that to know Newton as a mathe- matician is not to know him as an Ensflish- man. Whether he can be known separately as both, and whether the Absolute in this respect is a j^arallel case, depends on another consideration, which Mr, Mill has not noticed. The continuation of Mr. Mill's criticism is equally confused. He says : — " The whole of jMr. IMansel's argument for the incon- ceivability of the Infinite and of the Absolute is one long U/noTcdio elencJd. It has been pointed out in a former cliapter that the words Absolute and Infinite have no real meaning, unless we understand liv tliem tliat which is The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 153 absolute or infinite in some given attribute ; as space is called infinite, meaning that it is infinite in extension ; and as God is termed infinite, in the sense of possessing infinite poAver, and absolute in the sense of absolute good- ness or knoAvledge. It has also been shown that Sir W. Hamilton's arguments for the unknowableness of the Un- conditioned do not prove that we cannot know an object Avhich is absolute or infinite in some specific attribute, but (inly that we cannot know an abstraction called ' The Absolute' or ' The Infinite,' Avhich is supposed to have all attributes at once."— (P. 93.) The fallacy of this criticism, as regards Sir W, Hamilton, has been already pointed out : as regards Mr. Mansel, it is still more glaring, inasmuch as that writer expressly states that he uses the term absolute in a different sense from that which Mr. Mill attributes to Sir W. Hamilton. When Mr. Mill charges Mr. Mansel with ^' undertaking to prove the impossibility " of conceiving '^ a 154 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. Being abtiolutely just or ahsoluteli/ wise"'"" (i. c, as he supposes, perfectlij just or wise), he actually forgets that he has just been criticising Mr. Hansel's definition of the Absolute, as something having a possible existence " out of all relation." Will Mr. Mill have the kindness to tell us what he means by goodness and knowledge " out of all relation ;" i.e., a goodness and knowledge related to no object on which they can be exercised ; a goodness which is good to nothing, a knowledge which knows nothing ? Mr. Mill had better be cautious in talking about ig no ratio elencJii. From the Absolute, Mr. Mill proceeds to the Infinite ; and here he commits the same mistake as before, treating a portion of an argument as if it were the whole, and citing * Examination, p. 95. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 5 5 a portion intended to prove one point as if it were intended to prove another. He cites a passage from Mr. Mansel, in which it is said that ^^ tlie Infinite, if it is to be conceived at all, must be conceived as potentially every- thing and actually nothing ; for if there is anything in general which it cannot become, it is thereby limited ; and if there is any- thing in particular which it actually is, it is thereby excluded from being any other thing. But, again, it must also be conceived as actually everything and potentially nothing ; for an unrealised potentiality is likewise a limitation. If the Infinite can be that which it is not, it is by that very possibility marked out as incomplete, and capable of a higher perfection. If it is actually everything, it possesses no characteristic feature by which it can be distinguished from anything else, 156 TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. and discerned as an object of consciousness." On this passage Mr. Mill remarks, " Can a writer be serious who bids us conjure up a concejDtion of something which possesses infi- nitely all conflicting attributes, and because we cannot do this without contradiction, would have us believe that there is a con- tradiction in the idea of infinite goodness or infinite wisdom % " The answer to this criti- cism is very simple. The argument is not employed for the purpose which Mr. Mill supposes. It is employed to show that the metaphysical notion of the absolute-infinite, as the sum, potential or actual, of all possible existence, is inconceivable under the laws of human consciousness ; and thus that the absolutely first existence, related to nothing and limited by nothing, the ens realissirmiHR of the older philosophers, the inire being of The PJiilosopJiy of the Conditioned. 157 the Hegelians, cannot be attained as a start- ing-point from which to deduce all relative and derived existence. How far the empi- rical conception of certain mental attributes, such as goodness or wisdom, derived in the first instance from our ow^n personal con- sciousness, can be positively conceived as ex- tended to infinity, is considered in a separate argument, which Mr. Mill does not notice. Mr. Mill continues, " Instead of ' the In- finite,' substitute ^ an infinitely good Being ' \i. c, substitute what is not intended], and Mr. Mansel's aro^ument reads thus : — 'If there is anything which an infinitely good Being- cannot become^ — if he cannot become bad — that is a limitation, and the goodness cannot be infinite. If there is anything which an infinitely good Being actually is (namely, good), he is excluded from being 158 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. any otlier thing, as being wise or powerful.' " To the first part of this objection we reply by simply asking, " Is becoming bad a ' higher perfection ? ' " To the second part we reply by Mr. Mill's favourite mode of reasoning — a parallel case. A writer asserts that a creature which is a horse is thereby excluded from being a dog ; and that^ in so far as it has the nature of a horse, it has not the nature of a dog. '' What !" exclaims Mr. Mill, " is it not the nature of a dog to have four legs ? and does the man mean to say that a horse has not four legs ?" We ven- ture respectfully to ask Mr. Mill whether he supposes that being wise is being " a thing," and being good is being another "thing ?" But, seriously, it is much to be wished that when a writer like Mr. Mill undertakes to discuss philosophical questions, he should The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 159 acquire some slight acquaintance with tlie history of the questions discussed. Had this been done by our critic in the present case, it might possibly have occurred to him to doubt whether a doctrine supported by philo- sophers of such different schools of thought as Sj^inoza, Malebranche, Wolf, Kant, Schel- ling, could be quite such a piece of trans- parent nonsense as he supposes it to be. All these writers are cited in Mr. Hansel's note, as maintaining the theory that the Absolute is the ens realissimum, or sum of all existence ; and their names might have saved Mr. Mill from the absurdity of sup- posing that by this expression was meant something " absolutely good and absolutely bad ; absolutely wise and absolutely stupid ; and so forth." The real meaning of the expression has been already sufficiently ex- i6o The Philosophy of tlic Conditioned. plained in our earlier remarks. The problem of the Philosophy of the Unconditioned, as sketched by Plato and generally adopted by subsequent philosophers, is, as we have seen, to ascend up to the first principle of all things, and thence to deduce, as from their cause, all dependent and derived existences. The Unconditioned, as the one first principle, nmst necessarily contain in itself, potentially or actually, all that is derived from it, and thus must comprehend, in embryo or in development, the sum of all existence. To reconcile this conclusion with the phenomenal existence of evil and imperfection, is the difficulty with which philosophy has had to struggle ever since j^bilosophy began. The Manichean, by referring evil to an inde- pendent cause, denies the existence of an absolute first principle at all ; the Leib TJie Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. 1 6 1 nitzian, with his hypothesis of the best possible world, virtually sets bounds to the Divine omnipotence : the Pantheist identifies God with all actual existence, and either denies the real existence of evil at all, or merges the distinction between evil and good in some hiofher indifference. All these con- elusions may be alike untenable, but all alike testify to the existence of the problem, and to the vast though unsuccessful efforts which man's reason has made to solve it. The reader may now, perhaps, understand the reason of an assertion which Mr. Mill regards as supremely absurd,— namely, that we must believe in the existence of an abso- lute and infinite Being, though unable to conceive the nature of such a Being, To believe in such a Being, is simply to believe that God made the world : to declare the L i62 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. nature of sucli a Being inconceivable, is simply to say that we do not know how the world was made. If we believe that God made the world, we must believe that there was a time when the world was not, and when God alone existed, out of relation to any other being. But the mode of that sole existence we are unable to conceive, nor in what manner the first act took place by which the absolute and self-existent gave existence to the relative and dependent. ^'' The contradictions," says Mr. Mill, " which Mr. Mansel asserts to be involved in the notions, do not follow from an imperfect mode of apprehending the Infinite and the Absolute, but lie in the definitions of them, in the meaninsr of the words themselves." They do no such thing : the meaning of the words is perfectly intelligible, and is exactly The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 163 what is expressed by their definitions : tlie contradictions arise from the attempt to combine the attributes expressed by the words in one representation with others, so as to form a positive object of consciousness. Where is the incongruity of saying, *' I believe that a being exists possessing certain attributes, though I am unable in my present state of knowledge to conceive the manner of that existence ?" Mr. Mill, at all events, is the last man in the world who has any right to complain of such a distinction — Mr, Mill, who considers it not incredible that in some part of the universe two straight lines may enclose a space, or two and two make five ; though he is compelled to allow that under our present laws of thought, or, if he pleases, of association, we are unable to conceive how these tilings can be. i64 TIlc Philosophy of the Condiiio7icd. It is wearisome work to wade through this mass of misconceptions ; yet we must entreat the reader's j)atience a httle longer, while we say a few words in conclusion on perhaps the greatest misconception of all — though that is bold language to use with regard to Mr, Mill's metaphysics,— at any rate, the one which he expresses in the most vehement lansi-uagfe. Mr, Mansel, as we have said, asserts, as many others have asserted before him, that the relation between the com- municable attributes of God and the corre- sponding attributes of man is one not of identity, but of analogy ; that is to say, that the Divine attributes have the same relation to the Divine nature that the human attri- butes have to human nature. Thus, for example, there is a Divine justice and there is a human justice ; but God is just as the The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 165 Creator and Governor of the world, having unHmited authority over all His creatures and unlimited jurisdiction oyer all their acts ; and man is just in certain special relations, as having authority over some persons and some acts only, so far as is required for the needs of human society. So, again, there is a Divine mercy and there is a human mercy ; but God is merciful in such a manner as is fitting compatibly with the righteous govern- ment of the universe ; and man is merciful in a certain limited range, the exercise of the attribute being guided by considerations affecting the welfare of society or of indi- viduals. Or to take a more general case : Man has in himself a rule of rio-ht and wrong, implying subjection to the authority of a superior (for conscience has authority only as reflecting the law of God) ; while 1 66 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. God has ill Himself a rule of right and wrong, implying no higher authority, and determined absolutely by His own nature. The case is the same when we look at moral attributes, not externally, in their active manifestations, but internally, in their psychological constitution. If we do not attribute to God the same complex mental constitution of reason, passion, and wdll, the same relation to motives and inducements, the same deliberation and choice of alterna- tives, the same temporal succession of facts in consciousness, which we ascribe to man, — it will follow that those psychological rela- tions between reason, will, and desire, which are implied in the conception of human action, cannot represent the Divine excel- lences in themselves, but can only illustrate them by analogies from finite things. And The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 167 if man is liable to error in judging of the conduct of his fellow -men, in j^roportion as he is unable to place himself in their position, or to realise to himself their modes of thought and principles of action — if the child, for instance, is liable to error in judging the actions of the man, — or the savage of the civilised man, — surely there is far more room for error in men's judgment of the ways of God, in proportion as the difference between God and man is greater than the difference between a man and a child. This doctrine elicits from Mr. Mill the fol- lowing extraordinary outburst of rhetoric : — " If, instead of tlie glad tidings that there exists a Being in whom all the excellences which the highest human mind can conceive, exist in a degree inconceivable to us, I am informed that the world is ruled by a being whose 1 68 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. attributes are infinite, but what they are we cannot learn, nor what are the principles of his government, excejjt that ' the liighest human morality which we are capable of con- ceiving ' does not sanction them ; convince me of it, and I will bear my fate as I may. But when I am told that I must believe this, and at the same time call tliis being by the names which express and affirm the liighest hiiman morality, I say in plain terms that I will not. Whatever power such a being may have over me, there is one thing which he shall not do : he shall not compel me to worship him. I -v^dll call no beuig good, who is not Avhat I mean when I a]iply that epithet to my fellow-creatures ; and if such a being can sentence me to hell for not so calling liim, to hell I will go."— (P. 103.) We will not pause to comment on the temper and taste of this declamation ; we will simply ask whether Mr. Mill really supposes the word good to lose all community of mean- ing, when it is applied, as it constantly is, to different persons among our "fellow- creatures," with express reference to their The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 1 69 different duties and different qualifications for performing tlieni ? The duties of a father are not the same as those of a son ; is the word therefore wholly equivocal when we speak of one person as a good father, and another as a good son ? Nay, when we speak gene- rally of a man as good, has not the epithet a tacit reference to human nature and human duties ? and yet is there no community of meaning when the same epithet is applied to other creatures ? 'H aperi] irpo? to epyov TO oiKelov^ — the goodness of any being whatever has relation to the nature and office of that being. We may therefore test Mr. Mill's declamation by a parallel case. A wise and experienced father addresses a young and inexperienced son: *^ My son/' he says, "there may be some of my actions which do not seem to you to be wise or good, or such as 1 70 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. you would do in my place. Remember, however, that your duties are different from mine ; that your knowledge of my duties is very imperfect ; and that there may be things which you cannot now see to be wise and good, l)ut which you may hereafter discover to be so." '^ Father," says the son, " your principles of action are not the same as mine ; the highest morality which I can conceive at present does not sanction them ; and as for believing that you are good in anything of which I do not plainly see the goodness," — We will not repeat Mr. Mill's alternative ; we will only ask whether it is not just possible that there may be as much difference between man and God as there is between a child and his father ? This declamation is followed by a sneer, which is worth quoting, not on its own The PJiilosophy of the Conditioned. 1 7 i account, but as an evidence of the generosity with which Mr. Mill deals with the supposed motives of his antagonists, and of the ac- curacy of his acquaintance with the subject discussed. He says : — " It is worthy of remark, that the douljt whether words api^lied to Gotl liave their lumian signification, is only felt when the words relate to liis moral attributes ; it is never heard of with regard to his power. We are never told that God's omnipotence must not be supposed to mean an infinite degree of the power we know in man and nature, and tliat perhaps it does not mean that he is able to kill us, or consign us to eternal flames. The Divine Power is always interpreted in a completely himian signification ; but the Divine Goodness and Justice must be miderstood to be such only in an imintelligible sense. Is it unfair to surmise that this is because those who speak in the name of God, have need of the human conception of his poAver, since an idea which can overawe and enforce obedience must addi-ess itself to real feelings ; but are content that his goodness should lie conceived only as sometliing incon- ceivable, because they are so often rerpiired to teach doc- 1 7 - The Philosophy of the Conditioned. trines respecting him which cunllict irrccftncihiljly witli all goodness that we can conceive?" — (P. 104.) On the latter part of this paragraph we will not attempt to comment. But as re- gards the former part, we meet Mr. Mill's confident assertion with a direct denial, and take the opportunity of informing him that the conception of infinite Power has sug- gested the same difficulties, and has been discussed by philosophers and theologians in the same manner, as those of infinite Wisdom and infinite Goodness. Has Mr. Mill never heard of such questions as. Whether Omni- potence can reverse the past ?— Whether God can do that which He does not will to do ? — Whether God's perfect foreknowledge is compatible with his own perfect liberty ? — Whether God could have made a better world than the existing one ? Nay, has not TJic Philosophy of the Conditioned. 173 our critic, in this very chapter, been arguing against Mr. Mansel on the question, whether the Absolute can be conceived as a Cause acting in time : and what is this but a form of the question, whether power, when predi- cated of God is exactly the same thing as power when predicated of man ? Or why has it been said that creation ex niliilo — an absolutely first act of causation, is incon- ceivable by us, but from the impossibility of finding in human power an exact type of Divine power ? To attribute discreditable motives to an o|)ponent, even to account for unquestionable facts, is usually considered as an abuse of criticism. What shall we say when the facts are fictitious as well as the motives ? With regard to Mr. Mansel, the only person who is included by name in this accusation, it is " worthy of remark," that the 174 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. earliest mention of the obnoxious theory in his writings occurs in connection with a difficulty relating solely to the conception of infinite power, and not at all to the moral attributes of God.'" Mr. Mill concludes this chapter with another instance of that ignoratio elenchi which has been so abundantly manifested throughout his previous criticisms. His op- ponent, he allows, ''would and does admit that the qualities as conceived by us bear .some likeness to the justice and goodness which belong to God, since man was made in God's image." But he considers that this "semi-concession" ''destroys the whole fabric" of Mr. Mansel's argument. "The Divine goodness," he says, "which is said to be a different thing from human goodness, * See Prolegmne'tut Logica, p. 77 (2nd ed., p. 85.) The PhilosopJiy of tJic Conditioned. 175 but of wliicli tlic liuinan conception of good- ness is some imperfect reflexion or resem- blance, does it agree with what men call goodness in the essence of the quality — in what constitutes it goodness ? If it does, the 'Rationalists' are right; it is not illicit to reason from the one to the other. If not, the divine attribute, whatever else it may be, is not goodness, and ought not to be called by the name." Now the question really at issue is not whether the " Rationalist" argument is licit or illicit, but whether, in its lawful use, it is to be regarded as infallible or fallible. We have already quoted a portion of Mr. Hansel's language on this point ; we will now quote two more passages, which, without any comment, will sufficiently show how utterly Mr. Mill has mistaken the purport of the argu- ment which he has undertaken to examine. 176 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. *' We do not certainly Icnow tlie exact nature and opera- tion of tlie moral attributes of God : we can but infer and conjecture from wliat we know of the moral attributes of man: and the analogy between tlie Finite and the Infinite can never be so perfect as to preclude all possibility of error in the process. But the possibility becomes almost a certainty, when any one human faculty is elevated by itself into an authoritative criterion of religious truth, without regard to those collateral evidences by which its decisions may be modified and corrected." * . . . " Beyond question, every doubt which our reason may suggest in matters of religion is entitled to its due place in the examination of the evidences of religion ; if we Avill treat it as a part only, and not the whole ; if we will not insist on a positive solution of that wliich, it may be, is given us for another purpose than to be solved. It is reasonable to believe that, in matters of belief as well as of practice, God has not thought fit to anniliilate the free will of man, but has permitted specidative difficixlties to exist as the trial and the discipline of sharp and subtle intellects, as He has permitted moral temptations to form the trial and the dis- cipline of strong and eager passions. . . . "We do not * Bampton Lectures, p. 157, Fourth Edition. The Philosophy of the Conditioned. I i doubt that the conditions of our moral trial tend towards good, and not towards evil j that human nature, even iu its faUen state, bears traces of the image of its Maker, and is fitted to be an instrument in His moral government. And we believe this, notwithstanding the existence of pas- sions and appetites which, isolated and imcontroUed, appear to lead in an ojijposite direction. Is it tlien more reasonaT)le to deny that a system of revealed religion, whose unquestionable tendency as a whole is to promote the glory of God and the welfare of mankind, can have 13roceeded from the same Author, merely because we may be unable to detect the same character in some of its minuter features, viewed aj)art from the system to which they belong ?" * Surely this is very different from de- nouncing all reasoning from human goodness to Divine as '^ illicit." To take a parallel case. The manufacture of gunpowder is a dangerous process, and, if carried on without due pre- cautions, is very likely to lead to disastrous * Bamjyton Lectures, p. 166, Fourth Edition. M 178 The Philosophy of the Conditioned, consequences. Surely it is one thing to point out what precautions are necessary, and what evils are to be apprehended from the neglect of them, and another to forbid the manu- facture altogether. Mr. Mill does not seem to see the difference. We have now considered in detail all that part of Mr. Mill's book which is devoted to the examination of Sir W. Hamilton's chief and most characteristic doctrines — those which constitute the Philosophy of the Con- ditioned. The remainder of the work, which deals chiefly with subordinate questions of psychology and logic, contains much from which we widely dissent, but which we cannot at present submit to a special exami- nation. Nor is it necessary, so far as Sir W. Hamilton's reputation is concerned, that we should do so. If the Philosophy of the Con- The Philosophy of the CoJiditioncd. 1 79 ditioned is really nothing better than the mass of crudities and blunders which Mr. Mill supposes it to be, the warmest admirers of Hamilton will do little in his behalf, even should they succeed in vindicating 'some of the minor details of his teaching. If, on the other hand, it can be shown, as we have attempted to show, that Mr. Mill is utterly incapable of dealing with Hamilton's philo- sophy in its higher branches, his readers may be left to judge for themselves whether he is impliicitly to be trusted as regards the lower. In point of fact, they will do Mr. Mill no injustice, if they regard the above specimens as samples of his entire criticism. We gladly except^ as of a far higher order, those chap- ters in which he is content with statinof his own views ; but in the perpetual baiting of Sir W. Hamilton, which occupies the greater i8o TJie Philosophy of tJic Conditioned. part of the volume, we recognise, in general, the same captiousness and the same incompe- tence which we have so often had occasion to point out in the course of our previous re- marks. It is, we confess, an un|)leasant and an invidious task, to pick to pieces, bit by bit, the work of an author of high reputation. But Mr. Mill has chosen to yoX the question on this issue, and he has left those who dissent from him no alternative but to follow his example. He has tasked all the resources of minute criticism to destroy piece- meal the reputation of one who has hitherto borne an honoured name in philosophy : he has no right to complain if the same measure is meted to himself : — " Neque enim lex sequior ulla Quani necis artifices arte perire sua." The Philosophy of tJic Conditmicd. 1 8 1 But it is not so mucli the justice as the necessity of the case which we w^ould plead as our excuse. Mr. Mill's method of criti- cism has reduced the question to a very narrow compass. Either Sir W, Hamilton, instead of being a great philosopher, is the veriest blunderer that ever put pen to paper, or the blunders are Mr. Mill's own. To those who accept the first of these alternatives it must always remain a marvel how Sir W. Hamilton could ever have acquired that reputation which compels even his critic to admit that '■'■ he alone, of our metaphysicians of this and the preceding generation, has acquired, merely as such, an European celebrity;" how he could have been designated by his illustrious opponent, Cousin, as the " greatest critic of our age," or described by the learned Brandis as 1 82 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. "almost unparalleled in the profound know- ledge of ancient and modern philosophy," The marvel may perhaps disappear, should it be the case, as we believe it to be, that the second alternative is the true one. But even in this case, it should be borne in mind that the blow will by no means fall on Mr. Mill with the same weight with which he designed it to fall on the object of his criticism. Sir W. Hamilton had devoted his whole life to the study of metaphysics ; he was probably more deeply read in that study than any of his contemporaries ; and if all liis reading could produce nothing better than the confusion and self-contradic- tion which Mr. Mill imputes to him, the result w^ould be pitiable indeed. Mr, Mill, on the other hand, we strongly susj)ect, despises metaphysics too much to be at the The Philosophy of the Conditioned. 183 pains of studying them at all, and seems to think that a critic is duly equipped for his task with that amount of knowledge which, like Dogberry's reading and writing, " comes by nature." His work has a superficial cleverness which, together with the author's previous reputation, will insure it a certain kind of popularity ; but we venture to pre- dict that its estimation by its readers will be in the inverse ratio to their knowledge of the subject. But Mr. Mill's general reputation rests on grounds quite distinct from his per- formances in metaphysics ; and though we could hardly name one of his writings from whose main principles we do not dissent, there is hardly one which is not better fitted to sustain his character as a thinker than this last, in which the fatal charms of the goddess Necessity seem to have betrayed 184 The Philosophy of the Conditioned. her champion into an unusual excess of polemical zeal, coupled, it nmst be added, with an unusual deficiency of philosophical knowledge. POSTSCRIPT. It was not till after the preceding pages had been sent to press that I became acquainted with a little work recently published under the title of The Battle of the two Philosophies, hy an Inquirer. The author appears to have been a personal pupil of Sir W. Hamilton's, as well as a diligent student of his ^^Titings. At all events, he has " inquired" to some purpose, and obtained a far more intel- ligent knowledge of Hamilton's system than is exhibited by the majority of recent critics. It is gratifying to find many of my remarks confirmed by the concurrent testimony of so competent a witness. The followinsj would have been noticed 1 86 Postscript. in their proper places had 1 been sooner ac(|uainie(l with them. Of the popular confusion between the infinite and the indefinite, noticed above, pp. 50, 112, "An In(j^uirer" ol)serves : — "If we could realise in thought infinite space, that conception would be a perfectly definite one ; but the notion that is here offered us in its place, though it may be real, is certainly not definite ; it is merely the conception of an indefinite ex- tension In truth, when we strive to think of infinite space, the nearest approach we can make to it is this notion of an indefinite space, which Mr. Mill has substituted for it. But these two conceptions are not only verbally, they are really wholly distinct. An indefinite space is a space of the extent of which we tliink vaguely, without knowinif or without thinking where its boundaries are. Infinite space has certainly, and quite distinctly, no boundaries anywhere." — (I'p. 18-20.) On Mr. Mill's strange distinction between the Divine Attributes, as some infinite and others ab- Postscript. 187 solute, tliu author's remarks are substantially in agree- ment with what has been said above on pp. 105-6. "Mr. INIill argues that all the attributes of God cannot be infinite ; Init tliat some, as power, may be infinite ; and some, as goodness and knowledge, must be absolute, because neither can knowledge be more than complete, nor goodness more than per- fect. When we know all there is to be known, he says, knowledge has attained its utmost limit, fjut this is merely begging the whole question. If there be an Infinite Being, He cannot know all there is to be known unless He know Himself; and adequately to know what is infinite is to have in- finite knowledge. The same thing would be true if there could be a Being whose power and dura- tion only were infinite. ' The will,' he adds, ' is either entirely right, or wrong in different degrees: do%\'nwards there are as many gradations as we choose to distinguish ; but upwards there is an ideal limit. Goodness can be imagined complete, — such that there can be no greater goodness beyond it.' . . . But a Being of infinite power and finite goodness Avould not be perfectly good, be- 1 88 Postscript. cause His power M-oukl not Ijo M'liolly, Ijut only in X)art directed by His goodness. Nay, as that which is finite hears no proportion whatever to what is in- finite: as, how^ever great it he ahsohitely, it is still infinitely less than infinity, such a Being would he partly good and yet infinitely evil, which is absurd in reason and impossible in fact." — (Pp. 24, 25.) The following estimate of j\Ir. Mill's merits as a metaphysician coincides with that which, contrary^ to my expectation, I found forced upon myself after a careful examination of his book. — (See above. Pp. 62, 182.) " We cannot but think that Mr. Mill in tliis, his first work in pure metaphysics, has disappointed just expectation. In leaving the fields of practical philosophy, he seems to have left his genius Ijehind him. Even the peculiar 'cunning of his right hand' — even his unexcelled logical power avails him little, so continually does he fail to see distinctly the conception with which he is fencing. . . . As long as he is applying given principles to the solution of practical questions ; as long as he has Postscript. 189 to do with tlic process of an argument, he proves himself a most able instructor and guide. But when he has to grapple with a metaphysical pro- blem, it almost invarial)ly arrives that the central, the metaphysical difficulty, escapes him." — (Pp. 78- 80.) MriR AND PATEESOX, PRIXTEKS, EDIXBURGH. '^'