"V-NRLF $B Sit, in 1 ^HIS book gives the unprofessional reader a succinct ■*■ notion of the development of classic German philosophy from Kant to E[egel. Technical details are omitted, while the ideas that are significant for the history of culture are emphasized. It shows how German thought took shape in the struggle for German nationality against the Napoleonic menace, and how profoundly that crisis affected the philosophy of morals, of the state, and of history which has since that time penetrated into the common con- sciousness of Germany. Incidentally it makes clear how superficial is the current accounting for the contemporary attitude of intellectual Germany by reference to Nietzsche, etc., since that attitude is shown to have its basis in the older idealistic philosophy. Charles Edward Rugh lflfi7-1958 educaxioi; [ - . Professor of Education I University of California GERMAN PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICS BY JOHN DEWEY Professor of Philosophy in Columbia University NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1915 6*7?/ tone. OB7. Copyright, 1915, BY HENRY HOLT AND .COMPANY THE QUINN A 80DEN CO. PRESS RAHWAY, N. J. PREFACE The will of John Calvin McNair established a Foundation at the University of North Carolina upon which public lectures are to be given from time to time to the members of the University. This book contains three lectures which were given in February of this year upon this Foundation. It is a pleasure to acknowledge the many courtesies enjoyed during my brief stay at Chapel Hill, the seat of the University. J. D. Columbia University, New York City, April, 1915. CONTENTS PAGE I German Philosophy : The Two Worlds 3 II German Moral and Political Phi- losophy 47 III The Germanic Philosophy of History 91 Index 133 GERMAN PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICS GERMAN PHILOSOPHY: THE TWO WORLDS The nature of the influence of general ideas upon practical affairs is a troubled question. Mind dislikes to find itself a pilgrim in an alien world. A discovery that the belief in the influ- ence of thought upon action is an illusion would leave men profoundly saddened with themselves and with the world. Were it not that the doctrine forbids any discovery influencing affairs — since the discovery would be an idea — we should say that the discovery of the wholly ex post facto and idle character of ideas would profoundly influence sub- sequent affairs. The strange thing is that when men had least control over nature and their own affairs, they were most sure of the efficacy of thought. The doctrine that nature does nothing in vain, that it is directed by purpose, was not engrafted by scholasticism upon science ; it formu- lates an instinctive tendency. And if the doctrine 8 4/ 1 ••' " THE TWO WORLDS be fallacious, its pathos has a noble quality. It testifies to the longing of human thought for a world of its own texture. Yet just in the degree in which men, by means of inventions and political arrangements, have found ways of making their thoughts effective, they have come to question whether any thinking is efficacious. Our notions in physical science tend to reduce mind to a bare spectator of a machine-like nature grinding its unrelenting way. The vogue of evolutionary ideas has led many to regard intelligence as a deposit from history, not as a force in its making. We look backward rather than forward ; and when we look forward we seem to see but a further unrolling of a panorama long ago rolled up on a cosmic reel. Even Bergson, who, to a casual reader, ap- pears to reveal vast unexplored vistas of genuinely novel possibilities, turns out, upon careful study, to regard intellect (everything which in the past has gone by the name of observation and reflec- tion) as but an evolutionary deposit whose im- portance is confined to the conservation of a life already achieved, and bids us trust to instinct, or something akin to instinct, for the future: — as if there were hope and consolation in bidding us trust THE TWO WORLDS 5 to that which, in any case, we cannot intelligently direct or control. I do not see that the school of history which finds Bergson mystic and romantic, which prides itself upon its hard-headed and scientific character, comes out at a different place. I refer to the doc- trine of the economic interpretation of history in its extreme form — which, so its adherents tell us, is its only logical form. It is easy to follow them when they tell us that past historians have ig- nored the great part played by economic forces, and that descriptions and explanations have been correspondingly superficial. When one reflects that the great problems of the present day are those attending economic reorganization, one might even take the doctrine as a half-hearted con- fession that historians are really engaged in con- struing the past in terms of the problems and interests of an impending future, instead of re- porting a past in order to discover some mathe- matical curve which future events are bound to describe. But no; our strictly scientific economic interpreters will have it that economic forces pre- sent an inevitable evolution, of which state and church, art and literature, science and philosophy 6 THE TWO WORLDS are by-products. It is useless to suggest that while modern industry has given an immense stim- ulus to scientific inquiry, yet nevertheless the in- dustrial revolution of the eighteenth century comes after the scientific revolution of the seven- teenth. The dogma forbids any connection. But when we note that Marx gave it away that his materialistic interpretation of history was but the Hegelian idealistic dialectic turned upside down, we may grow wary. Is it, after all, history we are dealing with or another philosophy of his- tory? And when we discover that the great im- portance of the doctrine is urged upon us, when we find that we are told that the general recog- nition of its truth helps us out of our present troubles and indicates a path for future effort, we positively take heart. These writers do not seem to mean just what they say. Like the rest of us, they are human, and infected with a belief that ideas, even highly abstract theories, are of efficacy in the conduct of human affairs influencing the history which is yet to be. I have, however, no intention of entering upon this controversy, much less of trying to settle it. THE TWO WORLDS 7 These remarks are but preliminary to a considera- tion of some of the practical affiliations of por- tions of the modern history of philosophical thought with practical social affairs. And if I set forth my own position in the controversy in ques- tion, the statement is frankly a personal one, in- tended to make known the prepossessions with which I approach the discussion of the political bearings of one phase of modern philosophy. I do not believe, then, that pure ideas, or pure thought, ever exercised any influence upon human action. I believe that very much of what has been presented as philosophic reflection is in effect simply an idealization, for the sake of emotional satisfaction, of the brutely given state of affairs, and is not a genuine discovery of the practical influence of ideas. In other words, I believe it to be esthetic in type even when sadly lacking in esthetic form. And I believe it is easy to exag- gerate the practical influence of even »the more vital and genuine ideas of which I am about to speak. But I also believe that there are no such things as pure ideas or pure reason. Every tiving thought represents a gesture made toward the 8 THE TWO WORLDS world, an attitude taken to some practical situa- tion in which we are implicated. Most of these gestures are ephemeral; they reveal the state of him who makes them rather than effect a significant alteration of conditions. But at some times they are congenial to a situation in which men in masses are acting and suffering. They supply a model for the attitudes of others; they condense into a dramatic type of action. They then form what we call the " great " systems of thought. Not all ideas perish with the momentary response. They are voiced and others hear; they are written and others read. Education, formal and informal, em- bodies them not so much in other men's minds as in their permanent dispositions of action. They are in the blood, and afford sustenance to conduct ; they are in the muscles and men strike or retire. Even emotional and esthetic systems may breed a disposition toward the world and take overt effect. The reactions thus engendered are, indeed, superficial as compared with those in which more primitive instincts are embodied. The business of eating and drinking, buying and selling, marry- ing and being given in marriage, making war and peace, gets somehow carried on along with any and THE TWO WORLDS 9 every system of ideas which the world has known. But how, and when and where and for what men do even these things is tremendously affected by the abstract ideas which get into circulation. I take it that I may seem to be engaged in an emphatic urging of the obvious. However it may be with a few specialized schools of men, almost everybody takes it as a matter of course that ideas influence action and help determine the subsequent course of events. Yet there is a purpose in this insistence. Most persons draw the line at a certain kind of general ideas. They are especially prone to regard the ideas which constitute philosophic theories as practically innocuous — as more or less amiable speculations significant at the most for moments of leisure, in moments of relief from pre- occupation with affairs. Above all, men take the particular general ideas which happen to affect their own conduct of life as normal and inevitable. Pray what other ideas would any sensible man have ? They forget the extent to which these ideas originated as parts of a remote and technical theoretical system, which by multitudes of non- reflective channels has infiltrated into their habits 10 THE TWO WORLDS of imagination and behavior. An expert intel- lectual anatomist, my friends, might dissect you and find Platonic and Aristotelian tissues, organs from St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas, Locke and Descartes, in the make-up of the ideas by which you are habitually swayed, and find, indeed, that they and other thinkers of whose names you have never heard constitute a larger part of your mental structure than does the Calvin or Kant, Darwin or Spencer, Hegel or Emerson, Bergson or Browning to whom you yield conscious allegiance. Philosophers themselves are naturally chiefly re- sponsible for the ordinary estimate of their own influence, or lack of influence. They have been taken mostly at their own word as to what they were doing, and what for the most part they have pretended to do is radically different from what they have actually done. They are quite negligible as seers and reporters of ultimate reality, or the essential natures of things. And it is in this aspect that they have mostly fancied seeing them- selves. Their actual office has been quite other. They have told about nature and life and society in terms of collective human desire and aspiration THE TWO WORLDS 11 as these were determined by contemporary dif- ficulties and struggles. I have spoken thus far as if the influence of general ideas upon action were likely to be bene- ficial. It goes against the grain to attribute evil to the workings of intelligence. But we might as well face the dilemma. What is called pure thought, thought freed from the empirical contin- gencies of life, would, even if it existed, be irrel- evant to the guidance of action. For the latter always operates amid the circumstance of contin- gencies. And thinking which is colored by time and place must always be of a mixed quality. In part, it will detect and hold fast to more perma- nent tendencies and arrangements ; in part, it will take the limitations of its own period as neces- sary and universal — even as intrinsically desir- able. The traits which give thinking effectiveness for the good give it also potency for harm. A phys- ical catastrophe, an earthquake or conflagration, acts only where it happens. While its effects en- dure, it passes away. But it is of the nature of ideas to be abstract: that is to say, severed from the circumstances of their origin, and through 12 THE TWO WORLDS embodiment in language capable of operating in remote climes and alien situations. Time heals physical ravages, but it may only accentuate the evils of an intellectual catastrophe — for by no lesser name can we call a systematic intellectual error. To one who is professionally preoccupied with philosophy there is much in its history which is profoundly depressing. He sees ideas which were not only natural but useful in their native time and place, figuring in foreign contexts so as to formulate defects as virtues and to give rational sanction to brute facts, and to oppose alleged eternal truths to progress. He sees move- ments which might have passed away with change of circumstance as casually as they arose, acquire persistence and dignity because thought has taken cognizance of them and given them intellectual names. The witness of history is that to think in general and abstract terms is dangerous; it elevates ideas beyond the situations in which they were born and charges them with we know not what menace for the future. And in the past the danger has been the greater because philosophers have so largely purported to be concerned not with con- temporary problems of living, but with essen- THE TWO WORLDS 13 tial Truth and Reality viewed under the form of eternity. In bringing these general considerations to a close, I face an embarrassment. I must choose some particular period of intellectual history for more concrete illustration of the mutual relation- ship of philosophy and practical social affairs — which latter, for the sake of brevity, I term Politics. One is tempted to choose Plato. For in spite of the mystic and transcendental coloring of his thought, it was he who defined philosophy as the science of the State, or the most complete and organized whole known to man; it is no accident that his chief work is termed the " Republic." In modern times, we are struck by the fact that Eng- lish philosophy from Bacon to John Stuart Mill has been cultivated by men of affairs rather than by professors, and with a direct outlook upon so- cial interests. In France, the great period of phi- losophy, the period of les philosophes, was the time in which were forged the ideas which connect in particular with the French Revolution and in gen- eral with the conceptions which spread so rapidly through the civilized world, of the indefinite per- fectibility of humanity, the rights of man, and the 14 THE TWO WORLDS promotion of a society as wide as humanity, based upon allegiance to reason. Somewhat arbitrarily I have, however, selected some aspects of classic German thought for my illustrative material. Partly, I suppose, because one is piqued by the apparent challenge which its highly technical, professorial and predominantly a priori character offers to the proposition that there is close connection between abstract thought and the tendencies of collective life. More to the point, probably, is the fact that the heroic age of German thought lies almost within the last cen- tury, while the creative period of continental thought lies largely in the eighteenth century, and that of British thought still earlier. It was Taine, the Frenchman, who said that all the leading ideas of the present day were produced in Germany be- tween 1780 and 1830. Above all, the Germans, as we say, have philosophy in their blood. Such phrases generally mean something not about hereditary qualities, but about the social condi- tions under which ideas propagate and circulate. Now Germany is the modern state which pro- vides the greatest facilities for general ideas to take effect through social inculcation. Its sys- THE TWO WORLDS 15 tem of education is adapted to that end. Higher schools and universities in Germany are really, not just nominally, under the control of the state and part of the state life. In spite of freedom of academic instruction when once a teacher is installed in office, the political authorities have always taken a hand, at critical junctures, in determining the selection of teachers in subjects that had a direct bearing upon political policies. Moreover, one of the chief func- tions of the universities is the preparation of future state officials. Legislative activity is dis- tinctly subordinate to that of administration con- ducted by a trained civil service, or, if you please, bureaucracy. Membership in this bureaucracy is dependent upon university training. Philosophy, both directly and indirectly, plays an unusually large role in the training. The faculty of law does not chiefly aim at the preparation of practicing lawyers. Philosophies of jurisprudence are essen- tial parts of the law teaching ; and every one of the classic philosophers took a hand in writing a phi- losophy of Law and of the State. Moreover, in the theological faculties, which are also organic parts of state-controlled institutions, the theology 16 THE TWO WORLDS and higher criticism of Protestant Germany have been developed, and developed also in close con- nection with philosophical systems — like those of Kant, Schleiermacher and Hegel. In short, the educational and administrative agencies of Ger- many provide ready-made channels through which philosophic ideas may flow on their way to prac- tical affairs. Political public opinion hardly exists in Ger- many in the sense in which it obtains in France, Great Britain or this country. So far as it ex- ists, the universities may be said to be its chief organs. They, rather than the newspapers, crystallize it and give it articulate expression. In- stead of expressing surprise at the characteristic utterances of university men with reference to the great war, we should then rather turn to the past history in which the ideas now uttered were gen- erated. In an account of German intellectual history sufficiently extensive we should have to go back at least to Luther. Fortunately, for our pur- poses, what he actually did and taught is not so important as the more recent tradition concerning his peculiarly Germanic status and office. All THE TWO WORLDS 17 peoples are proud of all their great men. Germany is proud of Luther as its greatest national hero. But while most nations are proud of their great men, Germany is proud of itself rather for pro- ducing Luther. It finds him as a Germanic prod- uct quite natural — nay, inevitable. A belief in the universal character of his genius thus nat- urally is converted into a belief of the essentially universal quality of the people who produced him. Heine was not disposed by birth or tempera- ment to overestimate the significance of Luther. But here is what he said: " Luther is not only the greatest but the most German man in our history. . . . He possessed qualities that we seldom see associated — nay, that we usually find in the most hostile antagonism. He was at once a dreamy mystic and a practical man of action. . . . He was both a cold scholastic word-sifter and an inspired God-drunk prophet. . . . He was full of the awful reverence of God, full of self-sacrificing devotion to the Holy Spirit, he could lose himself entirely in pure spirituality. Yet he was fully acquainted with the glories of this earth ; he knew how estimable they are ; it was his lips that uttered the famous maxim — 18 THE TWO WORLDS " ' Who loves not woman, wine and song, Remains a fool his whole life long.' He was a complete man, I might say an absolute man, in whom there was no discord between matter and spirit. To call him a spiritualist would be as erroneous as to call him a sensualist. . . . Eternal praise to the man whom we have to thank for the deliverance of our most precious posses- And again speaking of Luther's work : " Thus was established in Germany spiritual freedom, or as it is called, freedom of thought. Thought became a right and the decisions of rea- son legitimate." The specific correctness of the above is of slight importance as compared with the universality of the tradition which made these ideas peculiarly Germanic, and Luther, therefore, a genuine na- tional hero and type. It is, however, with Kant that I commence. In Protestant Germany his name is almost always associated with that of Luther. That he brought to consciousness the true meaning of the Lutheran THE TWO WORLDS 19 reformation is a commonplace of the German his- torian. One can hardly convey a sense of the unique position he occupies in the German thought of the last two generations. It is not that every philosopher is a Kantian, or that the professed Kantians stick literally to his text. Far from it. But Kant must always be reckoned with. No posi- tion unlike his should be taken up till Kant has been reverently disposed of, and the new position evaluated in his terms. To scoff at him is fair sacrilege. In a genuine sense, he marks the end of the older age. He if the transition to distinc- tively modern thought. One shrinks at the attempt to compress even his leading ideas into an hour. Fortunately for me, few who read my attempt will have sufficient acquaintance with the tomes of Kantian in- terpretation and exposition to appreciate the full enormity of my offense. For I cannot avoid the effort to seize from out his highly technical writ- ings a single idea and to label that his germinal idea. For only in this way can we get a clew to those general ideas with which Germany char- acteristically prefers to connect the aspirations and convictions that animate its deeds. 20 THE TWO WORLDS Adventuring without further preface into this field, I find that Kant's decisive contribution is the idea of a dual legislation of reason by which are marked off two distinct realms — that of science and that of morals. Each of these two realms has its own final and authoritative constitution: On one hand, there is the world of sense, the world of phenomena in space and time in which science is at home ; on the other hand, is the supersensible, the noumenal world, the world of moral duty and moral freedom. Every cultivated man is familiar with the con- flict of science and religion, brute fact and ideal purpose, what is and what ought to be, necessity and freedom. In the domain of science causal de- pendence is sovereign; while freedom is lord of moral action. It is the proud boast of those who are Kantian in spirit that Kant discovered laws deep in the very nature of things and of human experience whose recognition puts an end forever to all possibility of conflict. In principle, the discovery is as simple as its application is far-reaching. Both science and moral obligation exist. Analysis shows that each is based upon laws supplied by one and the same THE TWO WORLDS 21 reason (of which, as he is fond of saying, reason is the legislator) ; but laws of such a nature that their respective jurisdictions can never compete. The material for the legislation of reason in the natural world is sense. In this sensible world of space and time, causal necessity reigns : such is the decree of reason itself. Every attempt to find freedom, to locate ideals, to draw support for man's moral aspirations in nature, is predoomed to failure. The effort of reason to do these things is contrary to the very nature of reason itself: it is self-contradictory, suicidal. When one considers the extent in which religion has been bound up with belief in miracles, or de- partures from the order of nature ; when one notes how support for morals has been sought in natural law; how morals have been tied up with man's natural tendencies to seek happiness and with consequences in the way of reward of virtue and punishment of vice ; how history has been explained as a play of moral forces — in short, the extent to which both the grounds and the sanctions for morality have been sought within the time and space world, one realizes the scope of the revolu- tion wrought by Kant, provided his philosophy be 22 THE TWO WORLDS true. Add to this the fact that men in the past have not taken seriously the idea that every exist- ence in space, every event in time, is connected by bonds of causal necessity with other existences and events, and consequently have had no motive for the systematic pursuit of science. How is the late appearance of science in human history to be ac- counted for? How are we to understand the com- paratively slight influence which science still has upon the conduct of life? Men, when they have not consciously looked upon nature as a scene of ca- price, have failed to bring home to themselves that nature is a scene of the legislative activity of rea- son in the material of sense. This fact the Kantian philosophy brings home to man once for all; it brings it home not as a pious wish, nor as a pre- carious hope confirmed empirically here and there by victories won by a Galileo or a Newton, but as an indubitable fact necessary to the existence of any cognitive experience at all. The reign of law in nature is the work of the same reason which proceeds empirically and haltingly to the discov- ery of law here and there. Thus the acceptance of the Kantian philosophy not only frees man at a single stroke from superstition, sentimentalism THE TWO WORLDS 23 and moral and theological romanticism, but gives at the same stroke authorization and stimulation to the detailed efforts of man to wrest from nature her secrets of causal law. What sparse groups of men of natural science had been doing for the three preceding centuries, Kant proclaimed to be the manifestation of the essential constitution of man as a knowing being. For those who accept the Kantian philosophy, it) is accordingly the magna charta of scientific work: the adequate formulation of the constitution which directs and justifies their scientific inquiries. It is a truism to say that among the Germans as nowhere else has developed a positive reverence for science. In what other land does one find in the organic law men- tion of Science, and read in its constitution an express provision that " Science and its teaching are free " ? But this expresses only half of Kant's work. Reason is itself supersensible. Giving law to the material of sense and so constituting nature, it is in itself above sense and nature, as a sovereign is above his subjects. The supersensible world is thus a more congenial field for its legislative activ- ity than the physical world of space and time. 24 THE TWO WORLDS But is any such field open to human experience? Has not Kant himself closed and locked the gates in his assertion that the entire operation of man's knowing powers is confined to the realm of sense in which causal necessity dominates? Yes, as far as knowledge is concerned. No, as far as moral obligation is concerned. The fact of duty, the existence of a categorical command to act thus and so, no matter what the pressure of physical sur- roundings or the incitation of animal inclinations, is as much a fact as the existence of knowledge of the physical world. Such a command cannot proceed from nature. What is cannot introduce man to what ought to be, and thus impose its own opposite upon him. Nature only enmeshes men in its relentless machine-like movement. The very existence of a command in man to act for the sake of what ought to be — no matter what actually is — is thus of itself final proof of the operation of supersensible reason within human experience: not, indeed, within theoretical or cog- nitive experience, but within moral experience. The moral law, the law of obligation, thus pro- ceeds from a source in man above reason. It is token of his membership as a moral being in a THE TWO WORLDS 25 kingdom of absolute ends above nature. But it is also directed to something in man which is equally above nature: it appeals to and demands freedom. Reason is incapable of anything so irra- tional, so self-contradictory, as imposing a law of action to which no faculty of action corre- sponds. The freedom of the moral will is the answer to the unqualified demand of duty. It is not open to man to accept or reject this truth as he may see fit. It is a principle of reason which is involved in every exercise of reason. In denying it in name, man none the less acknowledges it in fact. Only men already sophisticated by vice who are seeking an excuse for their viciousness ever try to deny, even in words, the response which freedom makes to the voice of duty. Since, how- ever, freedom is an absolute stranger to the natural and sensible world, man's possession of moral free- dom is the final sign and seal of his membership in a supersensible world. The existence of an ideal or spiritual realm with its own laws is thus certified to by the fact of man's own citizenship within it. But, once more, this citizenship and this certification are solely moral. Scientific or in- tellectual warrant for it is impossible or self- 26 THE TWO WORLDS contradictory, for science works by the law of causal necessity with respect to what is, igno- rant of any law of freedom referring to what should be. With the doors to the supersensible world now open, it is but a short step to religion. Of the negative traits of true religion we may be sure in advance. It will not be based upon intellectual grounds. Proofs of the existence of God, of the creation of nature, of the existence of an imma- terial soul from the standpoint of knowledge are all of them impossible. They transgress the limits of knowledge, since that is confined to the sensible world of time and space. Neither will true reli- gion be based upon historic facts such as those of Jewish history or the life of Jesus or the author- ity of a historic institution like a church. For all historic facts as such fall within the realm of time which is sensibly conditioned. From the points of view of natural theology and historic religions Kant was greeted by his contemporaries as the " all-shattering." Quite otherwise is it, however, as to moral proofs of religious ideas and ideals. In Kant's own words : " I have found it necessary to deny knowledge of God, freedom and THE TWO WORLDS 27 immortality in order to find a place for faith " — faith being a moral act. Then he proceeds to reinterpret in terms of the sensuous natural principle and the ideal rational principle the main doctrines of Lutheran Prot- estantism. The doctrines of incarnation, original sin, atonement, justification by faith and sanctifi- cation, while baseless literally and historically, are symbols of the dual nature of man, as phenomenal and noumenal. And while Kant scourges ecclesi- astical religions so far as they have relied upon ceremonies and external authority, upon external rewards and punishments, yet he ascribes transi- tional value to them in that they have symbolized ultimate moral truths. Although dogmas are but the external vesture of inner truths, yet it may be good for us " to continue to pay reverence to the outward vesture since that has served to bring to general acceptance a doctrine which really rests upon an authority within the soul of man, and which, therefore, needs no miracle to commend it." It is a precarious undertaking to single out some one thing in German philosophy as of typical importance in understanding German national life. Yet I am committed to the venture. My convic- 28 THE TWO WORLDS tion is that we have its root idea in the doctrine of I Kant concerning the two realms, one outer, phys- ical and necessary, the other inner, ideal and free. To this we must add that, in spite of their sep- arateness and independence, the primacy always lies with the inner. As compared with this, the philosophy of a Nietzsche, to which so many resort at the present time for explanation of what seems to them otherwise inexplicable, is but a superficial and transitory wave of opinion. Surely the chief mark of distinctively German civilization is its combination of self-conscious idealism with unsur- passed technical efficiency and organization in the varied fields of action. If this is not a realization in fact of what is found in Kant, I am totally at loss for a name by which to characterize it. I do not mean that conscious adherence to the philoso- phy of Kant has been the cause of the marvelous advances made in Germany in the natural sciences and in the systematic application of the fruits of intelligence to industry, trade, commerce, military affairs, education, civic administration and indus- trial organization. Such a claim would be absurd. But I do mean, primarily, that Kant detected and formulated the direction in which the German THE TWO WORLDS 29 genius was moving, so that his philosophy is of immense prophetic significance; and, secondarily, that his formulation has furnished a banner and a conscious creed which in solid and definite fashion has intensified and deepened the work actually un- dertaken. In bringing to an imaginative synthesis what might have remained an immense diversity of enterprises, Kantianism has helped formulate a sense of a national mission and destiny. Over and above this, his formulation and its influence aids us to understand why the German conscious- ness has never been swamped by its technical ef- ficiency and devotion, but has remained self- consciously, not to say self-righteously, idealistic. Such a work as Germany has undertaken might well seem calculated to generate attachment to a positivistic or even materialistic philosophy and to a utilitarian ethics. But no; the teaching of Kant had put mechanism forever in its subordinate place at the very time it inculcated devotion to mechanism in its place. Above and beyond as an end, for the sake of which all technical achieve- ments, all promotion of health, wealth and happi- ness, exist, lies the realm of inner freedom, of the SO THE TWO WORLDS ideal and the supersensible. The more the Ger- mans accomplish in the way of material conquest, the more they are conscious of fulfilling an ideal mission; every external conquest affords the greater warrant for dwelling in an inner region where mechanism does not intrude. Thus it turns out that while the Germans have been, to employ a catchword of recent thought, the most technically pragmatic of all peoples in their actual conduct of affairs, there is no people so hostile to the spirit of a pragmatic philosophy. The combination of devotion to mechanism and organization in outward affairs and of loyalty to freedom and consciousness in the inner realm has its obvious attractions. Realized in the common temper of a people it might well seem invincible. Ended is the paralysis of action arising from the split between science and useful achievements on one side and spiritual and ideal aspirations on the other. Each feeds and reinforces the other. Freedom of soul and subordination of action dwell in harmony. Obedience, definite subjection and control, detailed organization is the lesson en- forced by the rule of causal necessity in the outer world of space and time in which action takes THE TWO WORLDS SI place. Unlimited freedom, the heightening of con- sciousness for its own sake, sheer reveling in noble ideals, the law of the inner world. What more can mortal man ask? It would not be difficult, I imagine, to fill the three hours devoted to these lectures with quota- tions from representative German authors to the effect that supreme regard for the inner meaning of things, reverence for inner truth in disregard of external consequences of advantage or disad- vantage, is the distinguishing mark of the German spirit as against, say, the externality of the Latin spirit or the utilitarianism of Anglo-Saxondom. I content myself with one quotation, a quota- tion which also indicates the same inclina- tion to treat historic facts as symbolic of great truths which is found in Kant's treatment of church dogmas. Speaking of the Germanic lan- guages, an historian of German civilization says: " While all other Indo-European languages al- low a wide liberty in placing the accent and make external considerations, such as the quantity of the syllables and euphony, of deciding influence, the Germanic tribes show a remarkable and inten- tional transition to an internal principle of ac- 32 THE TWO WORLDS centuation. ... Of all related peoples the Ger- manic alone puts the accent on the root syllable of the word, that is, on the part that gives it its meaning. There is hardly an ethnological fact extant which gives so much food for thought as this. What leads these people to give up a habit which must have been so old that it had become instinctive, and to evolve out of their own minds a principle which indicates a power of discrimina- tion far in advance of anything we are used to attribute to the lower stages of civilization? Cir- cumstances of which we are not now aware must have compelled them to distinguish the inner es- sence of things from their external form, and must have taught them to appreciate the former as of higher, indeed as of sole, importance. It is this accentuation of the real substance of things, the ever-powerful desire to discover this real substance, and the ever-present impulse to give expression to this inner reality which has become the con- trolling trait of the Germanic soul. Hence the conviction gained by countless unfruitful efforts, that reason alone will never get at the true founda- tion of things ; hence the thoroughness of German science; hence a great many of the qualities that explain Germanic successes and failures; hence, perhaps, a certain stubbornness and obstinacy, the unwillingness to give up a conviction once formed ; hence the tendency to mysticism; hence that con- THE TWO WORLDS 33 tinuous struggle which marks the history of Ger- man art, — the struggle to give to the contents powerful and adequate expression, and to satisfy at the same time the requirements of esthetic ele- gance and beauty, a struggle in which the victory is ever on the side of truth, though it be homely, over beauty of form whenever it appears deceitful ; hence the part played by music as the only ex- pression of those imponderable vibrations of the soul for which language seems to have no words ; hence the faith of the German in his mission among the nations as a bringer of truth, as a recognizer of the real value of things as against the hollow shell of beautiful form, as the doer of right deeds for their own sake and not for any reward beyond the natural outcome of the deed itself." The division established between the outer realm, in which of course acts fall, and the inner realm of consciousness explains what is otherwise so paradoxical to a foreigner in German writings : The constant assertion that Germany brought to the world the conscious recognition of the prin- ciple of freedom coupled with the assertion of the relative incompetency of the German folk en masse for political self-direction. To one sat- urated by the English tradition which identifies 34 THE TWO WORLDS freedom with power to act upon one's ideas, to make one's purposes effective in regulation of public affairs, the combination seems self-con- tradictory. To the German it is natural. Read- ers who have been led by newspaper quotations to regard Bernhardi as preaching simply a gospel of superior force will find in his writings a con- tinual assertion that the German spirit is the spirit of freedom, of complete intellectual self-determina- tion ; that the Germans have " always been the standard bearers of free thought." We find him supporting his teachings not by appeal to Nietzsche, but by the Kantian distinction between the " empirical and rational ego." It is Bernhardi who says : " Two great movements were born from the Ger- man intellectual life, on which, henceforth, all the intellectual and moral progress of mankind must rest: — The Reformation and the critical philoso- phy. The Reformation that broke the intellectual yoke imposed by the Church, which checked all free progress; and the Critique of Pure Reason which put a stop to the caprice of philosophic speculation by defining for the human mind the limitations of its capacities for knowledge, and at the same time pointed out the way in which knowl- THE TWO WORLDS 35 edge is really possible. On this substructure was developed the intellectual life of our time, whose deepest significance consists in the attempt to reconcile the result of free inquiry with the reli- gious needs of the heart, and thus to lay a founda- tion for the harmonious organization of mankind. . . . The German nation not only laid the founda- tions of this great struggle for a harmonious devel- opment of humanity but took the lead in it. We are thus incurring an obligation for the future from which we cannot shrink. We must be pre- pared to be the leader in this campaign which is being fought for the highest stake that has been offered to human efforts. . . . To no nation ex- cept the German has it been given to enjoy in its inner self ■ that which is given to mankind as a whole.' . . . It is this quality which especially fits us for leadership in the intellectual domain and imposes upon us the obligation to maintain that position." * More significant than the words themselves are their occasion and the occupation of the one who utters them. Outside of Germany, cavalry generals who employ philosophy to bring home practical lessons are, I think, rare. Outside of •Bernhardi, "Germany and the Next War," pp. 73-74. Italics not in the original text. 36 THE TWO WORLDS Germany, it would be hard to find an audience where an appeal for military preparedness would be reinforced by allusions to the Critique of Pure Reason. Yet only by taking such statements seriously can one understand the temper in which opinion in Germany meets a national crisis. When the philosopher Eucken (who received a Nobel prize for contributing to the idealistic literature of the world) justifies the part taken by Germany in a world war because the Germans alone do not repre- sent a particularistic and nationalistic spirit, but embody the " universalism n of humanity itself, he utters a conviction bred in German thought by the ruling interpretation of German philosophic idealism. By the side of this motif the glorifica- tion of war as a biologic necessity, forced by in- crease of population, is a secondary detail, giving a totally false impression when isolated from its context. The main thing is that Germany, more than any other nation, in a sense alone of all na- tions, embodies the essential principle of humanity : freedom of spirit, combined with thorough and de- tailed work in the outer sphere where reigns causal law, where obedience, discipline and subordina- THE TWO WORLDS 37 tion are the necessities of successful organization. It is perhaps worth while to recall that Kant lived, taught and died in Konigsberg; and that Konigs- berg was the chief city of east Prussia, an island still cut off in his early years from western Prussia, a titular capital for the Prussian kings where they went for their coronations. His life- work in philosophy coincides essentially with the political work of Frederick the Great, the king who combined a regime of freedom of thought and complete religious toleration with the most ex- traordinary display known in history of adminis- trative and military efficiency. Fortunately for our present purposes, Kant, in one of his minor essays, has touched upon this combination and stated its philosophy in terms of his own thought. The essay in question is that entitled " What is the Enlightenment ? " His reply in substance is that it is the coming of age on the part of human- ity: the transition from a state of minority or infancy wherein man does not dare to think freely to that period of majority or maturity in which mankind dares to use its own power of under- standing. The growth of this power of free use of reason is the sole hope of progress in human 38 THE TWO WORLDS affairs. External revolutions which are not the natural expression of an inner or intellectual revo- lution are of little significance. Genuine growth is found in the slow growth of science and philoso- phy and in the gradual diffusion throughout the mass of the discoveries and conclusions of those who are superior in intelligence. True freedom is inner freedom, freedom of thought together with the liberty consequent upon it of teaching and publication. To check this rational freedom " is a sin against the very nature of man, the primary law of which consists in just the advance in ra- tional enlightenment." In contrast with this realm of inner freedom stands that of civil and political action, the prin- ciple of which is obedience or subordination to constituted authority. Kant illustrates the na- ture of the two by the position of a military sub- ordinate who is given an order to execute which his reason tells him is unwise. His sole duty in the realm of practice is to obey — to do his duty. But as a member not of the State but of the king- dom of science, he has the right of free inquiry and publication. Later he might write upon the campaign in which this event took place and THE TWO WORLDS 39 point out, upon intellectual grounds, the mistake involved in the order. No wonder that Kant pro- claims that the age of the enlightenment is the age of Frederick the Great. Yet we should do injustice to Kant if we inferred that he expected this dualism of spheres of action, with its twofold moral law of freedom and obedience, to endure forever. By the exercise of freedom of thought, and by its publication and the education which should make its results permeate the whole state, the habits of a nation will finally become elevated to rationality, and the spread of reason will make it possible for the government to treat men, not as cogs in a machine, but in accord with the dignity of rational creatures. Before leaving this theme, I must point out one aspect of the work of reason thus far passed over. Nature, the sensible world of space and time, is, as a knowable object, constituted by the legisla- tive work of reason, although constituted out of a non-rational sensible stuff. This determining work of reason forms not merely the Idealism of the Kantian philosophy but determines its em- phasis upon the a priori. The functions of reason through which nature is rendered a knowable ob- 40 THE TWO WORLDS ject cannot be derived from experience, for they are necessary to the existence of experience. The details of this a priori apparatus lie far outside our present concern. Suffice it to say that as compared with some of his successors, Kant was an economical soul and got along with only two a priori forms and twelve a priori categories. The mental habitudes generated by attachment to a priori categories cannot however be entirely neg- lected in even such a cursory discussion as the present. If one were to follow the suggestion involved in the lately quoted passage as to the significant symbolism of the place of the accent in German speech, one might discourse upon the deep mean- ing of the Capitalization of Nouns in the written form of the German language, together with the richness of the language in abstract nouns. One might fancy that the dignity of the common noun substantive, expressing as it does the universal or generic, has bred an intellectual deference. One may fancy a whole nation of readers rever- ently bowing their heads at each successively cap- italized word. In such fashion one might arrive at a picture, not without its truth, of what it THE TWO WORLDS 41 means to be devoted to a priori rational princi- ples. A number of times during the course of the world war I have heard someone remark that he would not so much mind what the Germans did if it were not for the reasons assigned in its justification. But to rationalize such a tangled skein as human experience is a difficult task. If one is in possession of antecedent rational con- cepts which are legislative for experience, the task is much simplified. It only remains to subsume each empirical event under its proper category. If the outsider does not see the applicability of the concept to the event, it may be argued that his blindness shows his ineptness for truly uni- versal thinking. He is probably a crass empiric who thinks in terms of material consequences in- stead of upon the basis of antecedent informing principles of reason. Thus it has come about that no moral, social or political question is adequately discussed in Ger- many until the matter in hand has been properly deduced from an exhaustive determination of its fundamental Begriff or Wesen. Or if the material is too obviously empirical to allow of such deduc- 42 THE TWO WORLDS tion, it must at least be placed under its appro- priate rational form. What a convenience, what a resource, nay, what a weapon is the Kantian distinction of a priori rational form and a pos- teriori empirical matter. Le.t the latter be as brutely diversified, as chaotic as you please. There always exists a form of unity under which it may be brought. If the empirical facts are recalcitrant, so much the worse for them. It only shows how empirical they are. To put them under a rational form is but to subdue their irrational opposition to reason, or to invade their lukewarm neutrality. Any violence done them is more than indemnified by the favor of bringing them under the sway of a priori reason, the incarnation of the Absolute on earth. Yet there are certain disadvantages attached to a priori categories. They have a certain rigid- ity, appalling to those who have not learned to identify stiffness with force. Empirical matters are subject to revision. The strongest belief that claims the support of experience is subject to modification when experience testifies against it. But an a priori conception is not open to adverse evidence. There is no court having jurisdiction. THE TWO WORLDS 43 If, then, an unfortunate mortal should happen to be imposed upon so that he was led to regard a prejudice or predilection as an a priori truth, con- trary experience would have a tendency to make him the more obstinate in his belief. History proves what a dangerous thing it has been for men, when they try to impose their will upon other men, to think of themselves as special in- struments and organs of Deity. The danger is equally great when an a priori Reason is substi- tuted for a Divine Providence. Empirically grounded truths do not have a wide scope; they do not inspire such violent loyalty to themselves as ideas supposed to proceed directly from reason itself. But they are discussable; they have a humane and social quality, while truths of pure reason have a paradoxical way, in the end, of es- caping from the arbitrament of reasoning. They evade the logic of experience, only to become, in the phrase of a recent writer, the spoil of a " logic of fanaticism." Weapons forged in the smithy of the Absolute become brutal and cruel when confronted by merely human resistance. The stiffly constrained character of an a priori Reason manifests itself in another way. A cate- 44 THE TWO WORLDS gory of pure reason is suspiciously like a pigeon- hole. An American writer, speaking before the present war, remarked with witty exaggeration that " Germany is a monstrous set of pigeonholes, and every mother's son of a German is pigeoned in his respective hole — tagged, labeled and ticketed. Germany is a huge human check-room, and the government carries the checks in its pocket." John Locke's deepest objection to the older form of the a priori philosophy, the doctrine of innate ideas, was the readiness with which such ideas become strongholds behind which authority shel- ters itself from questioning. And John Morley pointed out long ago the undoubted historic fact that the whole modern liberal social and political movement has allied itself with philosophic em- piricism. It is hard here, as everywhere, to disen- tangle cause and effect. But one can at least say with considerable assurance that a hierarchically ordered and subordered State will feel an affinity for a philosophy of fixed categories, while a flexible democratic society will, in its crude empiricism, exhibit loose ends. There is a story to the effect that the good townspeople of Konigsberg were accustomed to THE TWO WORLDS 45 their watches by the time at which Kant passed upon his walks — so uniform was he. Yielding to the Teutonic temptation to find an inner meaning in the outer event, one may wonder whether Ger- man thought has not since Kant's time set its intellectual and spiritual clocks by the Kantian standard: the separation of the inner and the outer, with its lesson of freedom and idealism in one realm, and of mechanism, efficiency and organ- ization in the other. A German professor of phi- losophy has said that while the Latins live in the present moment, the Germans live in the infinite and ineffable. His accusation (though I am not sure he meant it as such) is not completely justi- fied. But it does seem to be true that the Germans, more readily than other peoples, can withdraw themselves from the exigencies and contingencies of life into a region of Irmerlichkeit which at least seems boundless ; and which can rarely be success- fully uttered save through music, and a frail and tender poetry, sometimes domestic, sometimes lyric, but always full of mysterious charm. But technical ideas, ideas about means and instru- ments, can readily be externalized because the outer world is in truth their abiding home. n GERMAN MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY It is difficult to select sentences from Kant which are intelligible to those not trained in his vocabulary, unless the selection is accompanied by an almost word-by-word commentary. His writ- ings have proved an admirable terrain for the dis- play of German Grundlichkeit. But I venture upon the quotation of one sentence which may serve the purpose of at once recalling the main lesson of the previous lecture and furnishing a transition to the theme of the present hour. " Even if an immeasurable gulf is fixed between the sensible realm of the concept of nature and the supersensible realm of the concept of freedom, so that it is not possible to go from the first to the second (at least by means of the theoretical use of reason) any more than if they were two separate worlds of which the first could have no influence upon the second, — yet the second is 47 48 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY meant to have an influence upon the first. The concept of freedom is meant to actualize in the world of sense the purpose proposed by its laws." ... That is, the relation between the world of space and time where physical causality reigns and the moral world of freedom and duty is not a sym- metrical one. The former cannot intrude into the latter. But it is the very nature of moral legislation that it is meant to influence the world of sense; its object is to realize the purposes of free rational action within the sense world. This fact fixes the chief features of Kant's philosophy of Morals and of the State. It is a claim of the admirers of Kant that he first brought to recognition the true and infinite nature of the principle of Personality. On one side, the individual is homo phenomenon — a part of the scheme of nature, governed by its laws as much as any stone or plant. But in virtue of his citizenship in the kingdom of supersensible Laws and Ends, he is elevated to true universality. He is no longer a mere occurrence. He is a Per- son — one in whom the purpose of Humanity is in- carnate. In English and American writings the MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 49 terms subjective and subjectivism usually carry with them a disparaging color. Quite otherwise is it in German literature. This sets the age of subjectivism, whose commencement, roughly speak- ing, coincides with the influence of Kantian thought, in sharp opposition to the age of individ- ualism, as well as to a prior period of subordina- tion to external authority. Individualism means isolation; it means external relations of human beings with one another and with the world; it looks at things quantitatively, in terms of wholes and parts. Subjectivism means recognition of the principle of free personality: the self as creative, occupied not with an external world which limits it from without, but, through its own self-conscious- ness, finding a world within itself; and having found the universal within itself, setting to work to recreate itself in what had been the external world, and by its own creative expansion in industry, art and politics to transform what had been mere lim- iting material into a work of its own. Free as was Kant from the sentimental, the mystic and the romantic phases of this Subjectivism, we shall do well to bear it in mind in thinking of his ethical theory. Personality means that man as a rational 50 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY being does not receive the end which forms the law of his action from without, whether from Na- ture, the State or from God, but from his own self. Morality is autonomous; man, humanity, is an end in itself. Obedience to the self-imposed law will transform the sensible world (within which falls all social ties so far as they spring from natural instinct desire) into a form appro- priate to universal reason. Thus we may para- phrase the sentence quoted from Kant. The gospel of duty has an invigorating ring. It is easy to present it as the most noble and sub- lime of all moral doctrines. What is more worthy of humanity, what better marks the separation of man from brute, than the will to subordinate selfish desire and individual inclination to the commands of stern and lofty duty ? And if the idea of com- mand (which inevitably goes with the notion of duty) carries a sinister suggestion of legal au- thority, pains and penalties and of subservience to an external authority who issues the commands, Kant seems to have provided a final corrective in insisting that duty is self-imposed. Moral com- mands are imposed by the higher, supranatural self upon the lower empirical self, by the rational MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 51 self upon the self of passions and inclinations. German philosophy is attached to antitheses and their reconciliation in a higher synthesis. The Kantian principle of Duty is a striking case of the reconciliation of the seemingly conflicting ideas of freedom and authority. Unfortunately, however, the balance cannot be maintained in practice. Kant's faithful logic compels him to insist that the concept of duty is empty and formal. It tells men that to do their duty is their supreme law of action, but is silent as to what men's duties specifically are. Kant, moreover, insists, as he is in logic bound to do, that the motive which measures duty is wholly inner ; it is purely a matter of inner consciousness C To admit that consequences can be taken into ac- l count in deciding what duty is in a particular case \ would be to make concessions to the empirical and /sensible world which are fatal to the scheme. The combination of these two features of pure internality and pure formalism leads, in a world where men's acts take place wholly in the external and empirical region, to serious conse- quences. The dangerous character of these consequences I 52 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY may perhaps be best gathered indirectly by means of a quotation. " While the French people in savage revolt against spiritual and secular despotism had broken their chains and proclaimed their rights, another quite different revolution was working in Prussia — the revolution of duty. The assertion of the rights of the individual leads ultimately to indi- vidual irresponsibility and to a repudiation of the State. Immanuel Kant, the founder of the critical philosophy, taught, in opposition to this view, the gospel of moral duty, and Scharnhorst grasped the idea of universal military service. By calling upon which individual to sacrifice property and life for the good of the community, he gave the clearest expression to the idea of the State, and created a sound basis on which the claims to indi- vidual rights might rest." * The sudden jump, by means of only a comma, from the gospel of moral duty to universal mili- tary service is much more logical than the shock which it gives to an American reader would indi- cate. I do not mean, of course, that Kant's teaching was the cause of Prussia's adoption of universal military service and of the thorough- * Bernhardi, " Germany and the Next War," pp. 63-64. MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 53 going subordination of individual happiness and liberty of action to that capitalized entity, the State. But I do mean that when the practical political situation called for universal military service in order to support and expand the exist- ing state, the gospel of a Duty devoid of con- tent naturally lent itself to the consecration and idealization of such specific duties as the existing national order might prescribe. The sense of duty must gets its subject-matter somewhere, and unless subjectivism was to revert to anarchic or romantic individualism (which is hardly in the spirit of obedience to authoritative law) its appro- priate subject-matter lies in the commands of a superior. Concretely what the State commands is the congenial outer filling of a purely inner sense of duty. That the despotism of Frederick the Great and of the Hohenzollerns who remained true to his policy was at least that hitherto un- known thing, an enlightened despotism, made the identification easier. Individuals have at all times, in epochs of stress, offered their supreme sacrifice to their country's good. In Germany this sacri- fice in times of peace as well as of war has been systematically reinforced by an inner mystic sense 54 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY of a Duty elevating men to the plane of the uni- versal and eternal. h In short, the sublime gospel of duty has its de- fects. Outside of the theological and the Kantian moral traditions, men have generally agreed that duties are relative to ends. Not the obligation, but some purpose, some good, which the fulfill- ment of duty realizes, is the principle of morals. The business of reason is to see that the end, the good, for which one acts is a reasonable one — that is to say, as wide and as equitable in its working out as the situation permits. Morals which are based upon consideration of good and evil consequences not only allow, g but imperiously demand the exercise of a discriminating intelli- gence. A gospel of duty separated from empirical purposes and results tends to gag intelligence. It substitutes for the work of reason displayed in a wide and distributed survey of consequences in order to determine where duty lies an inner con- sciousness, empty of content, which clothes with the form of rationality the demands of existing social authorities. A consciousness which is not based upon and checked by consideration of actual results upon human welfare is none MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 55 the less socially irresponsible because labeled Reason. Professor Eucken represents a type of idealistic philosophy which is hardly acceptable to strict Kantians. Yet only where the fundamental Kant- ian ideas were current would such ethical ideas as the following flourish: " When justice is cdnsidered as a mere means of securing man's welfare, and is treated accord- ingly — whether it be the welfare of individuals or of society as a whole makes no essential difference — it loses all its characteristic features. No longer can it compel us to see life from its own standpoint; no longer can it change the existing condition of things; no longer can it sway our hearts with the force of a primitive passion, and oppose to all consideration of consequences an irresistible spiritual compulsion. It degenerates rather into the complaisant servant of utility; it adopts herself to her demands, and in so doing suffers inward annihilation. It can maintain itself only when it comes as a unique revelation of the Spiritual Life within our human world, as a lofty Presence transcending all considerations of ex- pediency." * • Eucken, " The Meaning and Value of Life," translated by Gibson, p. 104. 56 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY * Such writing is capable of arousing emotional reverberations in the breasts of many persons. But they are emotions which, if given headway, smother intelligence, and undermine its responsi- bility for promoting the actual goods of life. If justice loses all its characteristic features when regarded as a means (the word " mere " inserted before " means " speaks volumes ) of the welfare of society as a whole, then there is no objective and responsible criterion for justice at all. A justice which, irrespective of the determination of social well-being, proclaims itself as an irre- sistible spiritual impulsion possessed! of the force of a primitive passion, is nothing but a primitive passion clothed with a spiritual title so that it is protected from having to render an account of itself. During an ordinary course of things, it passes for but an emotional indulgence ; in a time of stress and strain, it exhibits itself as surrender of intelligence to passion. The passage (from Bernhardi) quoted earlier puts the German principle of duty in opposition to the French principle of rights — a favorite con- trast in German thought. Men like Jeremy Ben- tham also found the Revolutionary Rights of Man MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 57 doctrinaire and conducing to tyranny rather than to freedom. These Rights were a priori, like Duty, being derived from the supposed nature or essence of man, instead of being adopted as empirical ex- pedients to further progress and happiness. But the conception of duty is one-sided, expressing command on one side and obedience on the other, while rights are at least reciprocal. Rights are social and sociable in accord with the spirit of French philosophy. Put in a less abstract form than the revolutionary theory stated them, they are things to be discussed and measured. They admit of more and less, of compromise and ad- justment. So also does the characteristic moral contribution of English thought — intelligent self- interest. This is hardly an ultimate idea. But at least it evokes a picture of merchants bargain- ing, while the categorical imperative calls up the drill sergeant. Trafficking ethics, in which each gives up something which he wants toget some- thing which he wants more, is not the noblest kind of morals, but at least it is socially responsible as far as it goes. " Give so that it may be given to you in return " has at least some tendency to bring men together; it promotes agreement. It 58 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY requires deliberation and discussion. This is just what the authoritative voice of a superior will not tolerate; it is the one unforgiveable sin. The morals of bargaining, exchange, the mutual satisfaction of wants may be outlived in some remote future, but up to the present they play an important part in life. To me there is something uncanny in the scorn which German ethics, in behalf of an unsullied moral idealism, pours upon a theory which takes cognizance of practical motives. In a highly esthetic people one might understand the display of contempt. But when an aggressive and commercial nation carries on commerce and war simply from the motive of obedience to duty, there is awakened an unpleasant suspicion of a suppressed " psychic •^ complex." When Nietzsche says, " Man does not desire happiness ; only the Englishman does that," we laugh at the fair hit. But persons who pro- fess no regard for happiness as a test of action have an unfortunate way of living up to their principle by making others wwhappy. I should entertain some suspicion of the complete sincerity of those who profess disregard for their own hap- MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 59 piness, but I should be quite certain of their sin- cerity when it comes to a question of my hap- piness. Within the Kantian philosophy of morals there is an idea which conducts necessarily to a philoso- phy of society and the State. Leibniz was the great German source of the philosophy of the en- lightenment. Harmony was the dominant thought of this philosophy; the harmony of nature with itself and with intelligence ; the harmony of nature with the moral ends of humanity. Although Kant was a true son of the enlightenment, his doctrine of the radically dual nature of the legislation of Rea- son put an end to its complacent optimism. Ac- cording to Kant, morality is in no way a work of nature. It is the achievement of the self-conscious reason of man through conquest of nature. The ideal of a final harmony remains, but it is an ideal to be won through a battle with the natural forces of man. His breach with the enlightenment is nowhere as marked as in his denial that man is by nature good. On the contrary, man is by nature evil — that is, his philosophical rendering of the doctrine of original sin. Not that the passions, appetites and senses are of themselves evil, but they 60 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY tend to usurp the sovereignty of duty as the mo- tivating force of human action. Hence morality is a ceaseless battle to transform all the natural desires of man into willing servants of the law and purpose of reason. Even the kindly and sociable instincts of man, in which so many have sought the basis of both morality and organized society, fall under Kant's condemnation. As natural desires, they aspire to an illegitimate control in man's motives. They are parts of human self-love: the unlawful tendency to make happiness the controlling purpose of ac- tion. The natural relations of man to man are those of an unsocial sociableness. On the one hand, men are forced together by natural ties* Only in social relations can individuals develop their capacities. But no sooner do they come together than disintegrating tendencies set in. Union with his fellows give a stimulus to vanity, avarice and gaining power over others — traits which cannot show in themselves in individuals when they are isolated. This mutual antagonism is, however, more of a force in evolving man from savagery to civilization than are the kindly and sociable instincts. MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 61 " Without these unlovely qualities which set man over against man in strife, individuals would have lived on in perfect harmony, contentment and mutual love, with all their distinctive abilities latent and undeveloped." In short, they would have remained in Rous- seau's paradise of a state of nature, and " perhaps Rousseau was right when he preferred the savage state to the state of civilization pro- vided we leave out of account the last stage to which our species is yet destined to rise." But since the condition of civilization is but an intermediary between the natural state and the truly or rational moral condition to which man is to rise, Rousseau was wrong. " Thanks then be to nature for the unsociable- ness, the spiteful competition of vanity, the in- satiate desires for power and gain." These quotations, selected from Kant's little essay on an " Idea for a Universal History," are precious for understanding two of the most char- acteristic traits of subsequent German thought, the distinctions made between Society and the 62 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY State and between Civilization and Culture. Much of the trouble which has been experienced in re- spect to the recent use of Kultur might have been allayed by a knowledge that Kultur has little in common with the English word " culture " save a likeness in sound. Kultur is sharply antithetical to civilization in its meaning. Civilization is a natural and largely unconscious or involuntary growth. It is, so to speak, a by-product of the needs engendered when people live close together. It is external, in short. Culture, on the other, is deliberate and conscious. It is a fruit not of men's natural motives, but of natural motives which have been transformed by the inner spirit. Kant made the distinction when he said that Rous- seau was not so far wrong in preferring savagery to civilization, since civilization meant simply social decencies and elegancies and outward pro- prieties, while morality, that is, the rule of the end of Reason, is necessary to culture. And the real significance of the term " culture " becomes more obvious when he adds that it involves the slow toil of education of the Inner Life, and that the attainment of culture on the part of an indi- vidual depends upon long effort by the com- MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 63 munity to which he belongs. It is not primarily an individual trait or possession, but a conquest of the community won through devotion to " duty." In recent German literature, Culture has been given even a more sharply technical distinc- tion from Civilization and one which emphasizes even more its collective and nationalistic char- acter. Civilization as external and uncontrolled by self-conscious purpose includes such things as language in its more spontaneous colloquial ex- pression, trade, conventional manners or etiquette, and the police activities of government. Kultwr comprises language used for purposes of higher literature; commerce pursued not as means of enriching individuals but as a condition of the de- velopment of national life; art, philosophy (espe- cially in that untranslatable thing, the " Welt- Anschauung ") ; science, religion, and the activities of the state in the nurture and expansion of the other forms of national genius, that is, its activi- ties in education and the army. The legislation of Bismarck with reference to certain Roman Catholic orders is nicknamed Kultwr-kampf, for it was conceived as embodying a struggle between two radically different philosophies of life, the Ro- 64 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY man, or Italian, and the true Germanic, not simply as a measure of political expediency. Thus it is that a trading and military post like Kiao-Chou is officially spoken of as a " monument of Teu- tonic Kultur." The war now raging is conceived of as an outer manifestation of a great spiritual struggle, in which what is really at stake is the supreme value of the Germanic attitude in phi- losophy, science and social questions generally, the " specifically German habits of feeling and think- ing." Very similar motives are at work in the dis- tinction between society and the State, which is almost a commonplace of German thought. In English and American writings the State is al- most always used to denote society in its more organized aspects, or it may be identified with government as a special agency operating for the collective interests of men in association. But in German literature society is a technical term and means something empirical and, so to speak, ex- ternal ; while the State, if not avowedly something mystic and transcendental, is at least a moral entity, the creation of self-conscious reason operat- ing in behalf of the spiritual and ideal interests MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 65 of its members. Its function is cultural, educa- tive. Even when it intervenes in material interests, as it does in regulating lawsuits, poor laws, pro- tective tariffs, etc., etc., its action has ultimately an ethical significance: its purpose is the further- ing of an ideal community. The same thing is to be said of wars when they are really national wars, and not merely dynastic or accidental. Society is an expression of man's egoistic na- ture; his natural seeking for personal advantage and profit. Its typical manifestation is in com- petitive economic struggle and in the struggle for honor and recognized social status. These have their proper place ; but with respect even to them it is the duty of the State to intervene so that the struggle may contribute to ideal ends which alone are universal. Hence the significance of the force or power of the State. Unlike other forms of force, it has a sort of sacred import, for it represents force consecrated to the assertion and expansion of final goods which are spiritual, moral, rational. These absolute ends can be maintained only in struggle against man's individ- ualistic ends. Conquest through conflict is the law of morals everywhere. 66 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY In Kant we find only the beginnings of this political philosophy. He is still held back by the individualism of the eighteenth century. Every- thing legal and political is conceived by him as external and hence outside the strictly moral realm of inner motivation. Yet he is not content to leave the State and its law as a wholly unmoral matter. The natural motives of man are, according to Kant (evidently following Hobbes), love of power, love of gain, love of glory. These motives are egoistic; they issue in strife — in the war of all against all. While such a state of affairs does not and cannot invade the inner realm of duty, the realm of the moral motive, it evidently pre- sents a regime in which the conquest of the world of sense by the law of reason cannot be effected. Man in his rational or universal capacity must, therefore, will an outward order of harmony in which it is at least possible for acts dictated by rational freedom to get a footing. Such an outer order is the State. Its province is not to promote moral freedom directly — only the moral will can do that. But its business is to hinder the hin- drances to freedom: to establish a social condi- tion of outward order in which truly moral MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 67 acts may gradually evolve a kingdom of human- ity. Thus while the State does not have a directly moral scope of action (since the coer- cion of motive is a moral absurdity), it does have a moral basis and an ultimate moral func- tion. It is the law of reason, " holy and inviolable," which impels man to the institution of the State, not natural sociability, much less considerations of expediency. And so necessary is the State to hu- manity's realization of its moral purpose that there can be no right of revolution. The over- throw and execution of the sovereign (Kant evi- dently had the French Revolution and Louis XVI in mind ) is " an immortal and inexpiable sin like the sin against the Holy Ghost spoken of by theologians, which can never be forgiven in this world or in the next." Kant was enough of a child of the eighteenth century to be cosmopolitan, not nationalistic, in his feeling. Since humanity as a whole, in its universality, alone truly corresponds to the uni- versality of reason, he upheld the ideal of an ulti- mate republican federation of states; he was one of the first to proclaim the possibility of endur- 68 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY ing peace among nations on the basis of such a federated union of mankind. The threatened domination of Europe by Na- poleon following on the wars waged by republican France put an end, however, to cosmopolitanism. Since Germany was the greatest sufferer from these wars, and since it was obvious that the lack of national unity, the division of Germany into a multitude of petty states, was the great source of her weakness; since it was equally obvious that Prussia, the one strong and centralized power among the German states, was the only thing which saved them all from national extinction, subsequent political philosophy in Germany res- cued the idea of the State from the somewhat ambiguous moral position in which Kant had left it. Since a state which is an absolute moral neces- sity and whose actions are nevertheless lacking in inherent moral quality is an anomaly, the doctrine almost calls for a theory which shall make the State the supreme moral entity. Fichte marks the beginning of the transforma- tion; and, in his writings, it is easy to detect a marked difference of attitude toward the national- istic state before and after 1806, when in the battle MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 69 of Jena Germany went down to inglorious defeat. From the time of Fichte, the German philosophy of the State blends with its philosophy of his- tory, so that my reservation of the latter topic for the next section is somewhat arbitrary, and I shall not try rigidly to maintain the division of themes. I have already mentioned the fact that Kant relaxes the separation of the moral realm of free- dom from the sensuous realm of nature sufficiently to assert that the former is meant to influence the latter and finally to subjugate it. By means of the little crack thus introduced into nature, Fichte rewrites the Kantian philosophy. The world of sense must be regarded from the very start as material which the free, rational, moral Ego has created in order to have material for its own ade- quate realization of will. Fichte had a longing for an absolute unity which did not afflict Kant, to whom, save for the concession just referred to, a complete separation of the two operations of legislative reason sufficed. Fichte was also an ardently active soul, whose very temperament as- sured him of the subordination of theoretical knowledge to moral action. It would be as difficult to give, in short space, 70 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY an adequate sketch of Fichte's philosophy as of Kant's. To him, however, reason was the expres- sion of the will, not (as with Kant) the will an application of reason to action. " Im Anfang war die That " is good Fichteanism. While Kant continued the usual significance of the term Reason (with only such modifications as the ra- tionalism of his century had made current), Fichte began the transformation which consummated in later German idealism. If the world of nature and of human relations is an expression of reason, then reason must be the sort of thing, and have the sort of attributes by means of which the world may be construed, no matter how far away this conception of reason takes us from the usual meaning of the term. To Fichte the formula which best described such aspects of the world and of life as he was interested in was effort at self- realization through struggle with difficulties and overcoming opposition. Hence his formula for reason was a Will which, having " posited " itself, then " posited " its antithesis in order, through further action subjugating this opposite, to con- quer its own freedom. The doctrine of the primacy of the Deed, and MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 71 of the Duty to achieve freedom through moral self- assertion against obstacles (which, after all, are there only to further this self-assertion) was one which could, with more or less plausibility, be de- rived from Kant. More to our present point, it was a doctrine which could be preached with noble moral fervor in connection with the difficulties and needs of a divided and conquered Germany. Fichte saw himself as the continuator of the work of Luther and Kant. His final " science of knowl- edge " brought the German people alone of the peoples of the world into the possession of the idea and ideal of absolute freedom. Hence the peculiar destiny of the German scholar and the German State. It was the duty and mission of German science and philosophy to contribute to the cause of the spiritual emancipation of humanity. Kant had already taught that the acts of men were to become gradually permeated by a spirit of ration- ality till there should be an equation of inner freedom of mind and outer freedom of action. Fichte's doctrine demanded an acceleration of the process. Men who have attained to a conscious- ness of the absolute freedom and self -activity must necessarily desire to see around them similar free 72 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY beings. The scholar who is truly a scholar not merely knows, but he knows the nature of knowl- edge — its place and function as a manifestation of the Absolute. Hence he is, in a peculiar sense, the direct manifestation of God in the world — the true priest. And his priestly function consists in bringing other men to recognize moral free- dom in its creative operation. Such is the dignity of education as conducted by those who have attained true philosophic insight. Fichte made a specific application of this idea to his own country and time. The humiliating condition of contemporary Germany was due to the prevalence of egoism, selfishness and particular- ism: to the fact that men had lowered themselves to the plane of sensuous life. The fall was the worse because the Germans, more than any other people, were by nature and history conscious of the ideal and spiritual principle, the principle of freedom, lying at the very basis of all things. The key to the political regeneration of Germany was to be found in a moral and spiritual regen- eration effected by means of education. The key, amid political division, to political unity was to be sought in devotion to moral unity. In this MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 73 spirit Fichte preached his " Addresses to the Ger- man Nation." In this spirit he collaborated in the foundation of the University of Berlin, and zealously promoted all the educational reforms in- troduced by Stein and Humboldt into Prussian life. The conception of the State as an essential moral Being charged with an indispensable moral function lay close to these ideas. Education is the means of the advancement of humanity toward realization of its divine perfection. Education is the work of the State. The syllogism completes itself. But in order that the State may carry on its educational or moral mission it must not only possess organization and commensurate power, but it must also control the conditions which secure the possibility offered to the individuals composing it. To adopt Aristotle's phrase, men must live before they can live nobly. The primary condi- tion of a secure life is that everyone be able to live by his own labor. Without this, moral self- determination is a mockery. The business of the State, outside of its educational mission, is con- cerned with property, and this business means in- suring property to everyone as well as protecting him in what he already possesses. Moreover, prop- 74 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY erty is not mere physical possession. It has a profound moral significance, for it means the sub- jugation of physical things to will. It is a neces- sary part of the realization of moral personality: the conquest of the non-ego by the ego. Since property does not mean mere appropriation, but is a right recognized and validated by society itself, property has a social basis and aim. It is an expression not of individual egotism but of the uni- versal will. Hence it is essential to the very idea of property and of the State that all the members of society have an equal opportunity for prop- erty. Hence it is the duty of the State to secure to its every member the right to work and the reward of his work. The outcome, as expressed in his essay on " The Closed Industrial State," is State Socialism, based on moral and idealistic grounds, not on economic considerations. In order that men may have a real opportunity to develop their moral person- alities, their right to labor and to adequate living, in return for their labor must be assured. This cannot happen in a competitive society. Industry must be completely regulated by the State if these indispensable rights to labor and resulting com- MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 75 fort and security of life as means to moral voli- tion are to be achieved. But a state engaged in unrestricted foreign trade will leave its working- men at the mercy of foreign conditions. It must therefore regulate or even eliminate foreign com- merce so far as is necessary to secure its own citi- zens. The ultimate goal is a universal state as wide as humanity, and a state in which each in- dividual will act freely, without state-secured rights and state-imposed obligations. But before this cosmopolitan and philosophically anarchic condition can be reached, we must pass through a period of the nationalistic closed state. Thus at the end a wide gulf separates Fichte from Kant. The moral individualism of the latter has become an ethical socialism. Only in and by means of a circle of egos or personalities does a human being attain the moral reason and freedom which Kant bestowed upon him as his birthright. Only through the educational activities of the State and its complete regulation of the industrial activities of its members does the potential moral freedom of individuals become an established reality. If I have devoted so much space to Fichte it is not because of his direct influence upon 76 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY affairs or even upon thought. He did not found a school. His system was at once too personal and too formal. Nevertheless, he expressed ideas which, removed from their special context in his system, were taken up into the thought of culti- vated Germany. Heine, speaking of the vogue of systems of thought, says with profound truth that " nations have an instinctive presentiment of what they require to fulfill their mission." And Fichte's thought infiltrated through many crevices. Rodbertus and Lasalle, the socialists, were, for example, profoundly affected by him. When the latter was prosecuted in a criminal suit for his " Programme of Workingmen," his reply was that his programme was a distinctively philo- sophic utterance, and hence protected by the con- stitutional provision for freedom of science and its teaching. And this is his philosophy of the State: " The State is the unity and cooperation of individuals in a moral whole. . . . The ultimate and intrinsic end of the State is, therefore, to further the positive unfolding, the progressive de- velopment of human life. Its function is to work out the true end of man; that is to say, the full MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 77 degree of culture of which human nature is capa- ble." And he quotes with approval the words: " The concept of the State must be broadened so as to make the State the contrivance whereby all human virtue is to be realized to the full." And if he differs from Fichte, it is but in the assertion that since the laboring class is the one to whom the need most directly appeals, it is work- ingmen who must take the lead in the development of the true functions of the State. Pantheism is a philosophic nickname which should be sparingly employed; so also should the term Monism. To call Fichte's system an ethical pantheism and monism is not to say much that is enlightening. But with free interpretation, the designation may be highly significant in refer- ence to the spiritual temper of the Germany of the first part of the nineteenth century. For it gives a key to the presentiment of what Germany needed to fulfill its mission. It is a commonplace of. German historians that its unity and expansion to a great state powerful 78 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY externally, prosperous internally, was wrought, unlike that of any other people, from within out- ward. In Lange's words, " our national develop- ment started from the most ideal and approxi- mated more and more to the real." Hegel and Heine agree that in Germany the French Revo- lution and the Napoleonic career were paralleled by a philosophic revolution and an intellectual empire. You recall the bitter word that, when Napoleon was finally conquered and Europe par- titioned, to Germany was assigned the kingdom of the clouds. But this aerial and tenuous kingdom became a mighty power, working with and in the statesmen of Prussia and the scholars of Germany to found a kingdom on the solid earth. Spiritual and ideal Germany made common cause with realistic and practical Prussia. As says Von Sybel, the historian of the " Founding of the Ger- man Empire " : " Germany had been ruined through its own disintegration and had dragged Prussia with it into the abyss. It was well known that the wild fancies of the Conqueror hovered about the utter annihilation of Prussia; if this should take place, then east as well as west of the Elbe, not only MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 79 political independence, but every trace of a Ger- man spirit, the German language and customs, German art and learning — everything would be wiped out by the foreigners. But this fatal danger was perceived just at the time when every- body had been looking up to Kant and Schiller, had been admiring Faust, the world-embracing masterpiece of Goethe's, and had recognized that Alexander von Humboldt's cosmological studies and Niebuhr's " Roman History " had created a new era in European science and learning. In such intellectual attainments the Germans felt that they were far superior to the vanquisher of the world and his great nation; and so the political interests of Prussia and the salvation of the Ger- man nationality exactly coincided. Schleier- macher's patriotic sermons, Fichte's stirring ad- dresses to the German people, Humboldt's glorious founding of the Berlin University, served to aug- ment the resisting power of Prussia, while Scharnhorst's recruits and militia were devoted to the defense of German honor and German cus- toms. Everyone felt that German nationality was lost if Prussia did not come to its rescue, and that, too, there was no safety possible for Prussia unless all Germany was free. " What a remarkable providence it was that brought together, as in the Middle Ages, on this ancient colonial ground, a throng of the most 80 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY energetic men from all districts of Germany. For neither Stein nor his follower, Hardenberg, nor the generals, Scharnhorst, Bluecher and Gneisenau, nor the authors, Niebuhr, Fichte and K. F. Eichorn, nor many others who might be men- tioned, were born in Prussia; yet because their thoughts centered in Germany, they had become loyal Prussians. The name Germany had been blotted from the political map of Europe, but never had so many hearts thrilled at the thought of being German. " Thus on the most eastern frontier of German life, in the midst of troubles which seemed hope- less, the idea of German unity, which had lain dormant for centuries, now sprang up in a new birth. At first this idea was held exclusively by the great men of the times and remained the in- valuable possession of the cultivated classes; but once started it spread far and wide among the younger generation. . . . But it was easier to de- feat the mighty Napoleon than to bend the Ger- man sentiments of dualism and individualism to the spirit of national unity." What I have called the ethical pantheism and monistic idealism of Fichte (a type of philosophy reigning almost unchallenged in Germany till al- most the middle of the century) was an effective MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 81 weapon in fighting and winning this more difficult battle. In his volume on the " Romantic School in Germany," Brandes quotes from the diary of Hoffman a passage written in 1809. " Seized by a strange fancy at the ball on the 6th, I imagine myself looking at my own Ego through a kaleidoscope. All the forms moving around me are Egos and annoy me by what they do and leave undone." It is a temptation to find in this passage a symbol both of German philosophy and of the temper of Germany at the time. Its outer de- feats, its weakness in the world of action, had developed an exasperated introspection. This outer weakness, coinciding, as Von Sybel points out, with the bloom of Germany in art, philosophy, history, philology and philosophy, made the Ego of Germany the noblest contemporary object of contemplation, yet one surrounded with other national Egos who offended by what they did and what they did not do. Patriotism, national feeling, national consciousness are common enough facts. But nowhere save in Germany, in the ear- lier nineteenth century, have these sentiments and 82 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY impulses been transformed by deliberate nurture into a mystic cult. This was the time when the idea of the Volks-seele, the Volks-geist, was born ; and the idea lost no time in becoming a fact. Not merely poetry was affected by it, but philology, history and jurisprudence. The so-called historic school is its offspring. The science of social psy- chology derives from it at one remove. The soul, however, needed a body, and (quite in accord with German idealism) it formed a body for itself — the German State as a unified Empire. While the idealistic period came first, it is im- portant to bear in mind the kind of idealism it was. At this point the pantheistic allusion be- comes significant. The idealism in question was not an idealism of another world but of this world, and especially of the State. The embodi- ment of the divine and absolute will and ideal is the existing world of nature and of men. Espe- cially is the human ego the authorized and cre- ative agent of absolute purpose. The significance of German philosophy was precisely to make men aware of their nature and destiny as the direct and active representatives of absolute and creative purpose. MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 83 If I again quote Heine, it is because, with his contempt for technical philosophy, he had an inti- mate sense of its human meaning. Of German pantheistic idealism, he wrote in 1833 while it was still in its prime: " God is identical with the world. . . . But he manifests himself most gloriously in man, who feels and thinks at the same time, who is capable of distinguishing his own individuality from ob- jective nature, whose intellect already bears within itself the ideas that present themselves to him in the phenomenal world. In man Deity reaches self-consciousness, and this self-conscious- ness God again reveals through man. But this revelation does not take place in and through individual man, but in and through collective hu- manity . . . which comprehends and represents in idea and in reality the whole God-universe. . . . It is an error to suppose that this religion leads men to indifference. On the contrary, the con- sciousness of his divinity will inspire man with enthusiasm for its manifestation, and from this moment the really noble achievements of true hero- ism glorify the earth." In one respect, Heine was a false prophet. He thought that this philosophy would in the end 84 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY accrue to the profit of the radical, the republican and revolutionary party in Germany. The his- tory of German liberalism is a complicated matter. Suffice it in general to say that the honey the libertarians hived was appropriated in the end by the party of authority. In Heine's assurance that these ideas would in due time issue in action he was profoundly right. His essay closes with burning words, from which I extract the fol- lowing : " It seems to me that a methodical people, such as we, must begin with the reformation, must then occupy ourselves with systems of philosophy, and only after their completion pass to the political revolution. . . . Then will appear Kantians, as little tolerant of piety in the world of deeds as in the world of ideas, who will mercilessly upturn with sword and axe the soil of our European life to extirpate the last remnants of the past. Then will come upon the scene armed Fichteans, whose fanaticism of will is to be restrained neither by fear nor self-interest, for they live in the spirit. . . . Most of all to be feared would be the phi- losophers of nature,* were they actively to min- * He refers to the followers of Schelling, who as matter of fact had little vogue. But his words may not unjustly be transferred to the naturalistic schools, which have since affected German thought. MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 85 gle. . . . For if the hand of the Kantian strikes with strong unerring blow; if the Fichtean cour- ageously defies every danger, since for him danger has in reality no existence; — the Philosopher of Nature will be terrible in that he has allied him- self with the primitive powers of nature, in that he can conjure up the demoniac forces of old German pantheism; and having done so, aroused in him that ancient Germanic eagerness whicR combats for the joy of the combat itself. . . . Smile not at my counsel as at the counsel of a dreamer. . . . The thought precedes the deed as the lightning the thunder. . . . The hour will come. As on the steps of an amphitheater, the nations will group themselves around Germany to witness the terrible combat." In my preoccupation with Heine, I seem to have wandered somewhat from our immediate topic: the connection of the idealistic philosophy with the development and organization of the national state of Germany. But the necessity of the or- ganized State to care for the moral interests of mankind was an inherent part of Fichte's thought. At first, what state was a matter of indifference. In fact his sympathies were largely French and republican. Before Jena, he writes: 86 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY " What is the nation for a truly civilized Chris- tian European ? In a general way, Europe itself. More particularly at any time the State which is at the head of civilization. . . . With this cos- mopolitan sense, we can be tranquil before the vicissitudes and catastrophes of history." In 1807 he writes : " The distinction between Prussia and the rest of Germany is external, arbitrary and fortuitous. The distinction between Germany and the rest of Europe is founded in nature." The seeming gulf between the two ideas is easily bridged. The " Addresses on the Fundamental Features of the Present Age " had taught that the end of humanity on earth is the establishment of a kingdom in which all relations of humanity are determined with freedom or according to Rea- son — according to Reason as conceived by the Fichtean formula. In his " Addresses to the German Nation," in 1807-08, the unique mission of Germany in the establishment of this kingdom is urged as a motive for securing national unity and the overthrow of the conqueror. The Ger- mans are the sole people who recognize the prin- MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 87 ciples of spiritual freedom, of freedom won by action in accord with reason. Faithfulness to this mission will " elevate the German name to that of the most glorious among all the peoples, making this Nation the regenerator, and restorer of the world." He personifies their ancestors speaking to them, and saying : " We in our time saved Germany from the Roman World Empire." But " yours is the greater fortune. You may establish once for all the Kingdom of the Spirit and of Reason, bringing to naught corporeal might as the ruling thing in the world." And this antithesis of the Germanic and the Roman principles has become a commonplace in the German imagination. Moreover, for Germany to win is no selfish gain. It is an advantage to all nations. " The great promise of a kingdom of right reason and truth on earth must not become a vain and empty phantom ; the present iron age is but a transition to a better estate." Hence the concluding words : " There is no middle road : If you sink, so sinks humanity entire with you, with- out hope of future restoration." The premises of the historic syllogism are plain. First, the German Luther who saved for mankind 88 MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY the principle of spiritual freedom against Latin externalism ; then Kant and Fichte, who wrought out the principle into a final philosophy of science, morals and the State; as conclusion, the German nation organized in order to win the world to rec- ognition of the principle, and thereby to establish the rule of freedom and science in humanity as a whole. The Germans are patient; they have a long memory. Ideas produced when Germany was divided and broken were retained and cherished after it became a unified State of supreme military power, and one yielding to no other people in industrial and commercial prosperity. In the grosser sense of the words, Germany has not held that might makes right. But it has been in- structed by a long line of philosophers that it is the business of ideal right to gather might to itself in order that it may cease to be merely ideal. The State represents exactly this incarnation of ideal law and right in effective might. The military arm is part of this moral embodiment. Let senti- mentalists sing the praises of an ideal to which no actual force corresponds. Prussian faith in the reality and enforcement among men of the ideal is of a more solid character. As past history MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 89 is the record of the gradual realization in the Ger- manic State of the divine idea, future history must uphold and expand what has been accom- plished. Diplomacy is the veiled display of law clothed with force in behalf of this realization, and war is its overt manifestation. That war demands self-sacrifice is but the more convincing proof of its profound morality. It is the final seal of devotion to the extension of the kingdom of the Absolute on earth. For the philosophy stands or falls with the con- ception of an Absolute. Whether a philosophy of absolutes is theoretically sound or unsound is none of my present concern. But that philosoph- ical absolutism may be practically as dangerous as matter of fact political absolutism history testi- fies. The situation puts in relief what finally is at issue between a theory which is pinned to a belief in an Absolute beyond history and behind experience, and one which is frankly experimental. For any philosophy which is not consistently ex- perimental will always traffic in absolutes no matter in how disguised a form. In German po- litical philosophy, the traffic is without mask. m THE GERMANIC PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY The unity of the German people longed for and dreamed of after 1807 became an established fact through the war of 1870 with France. It is easy to assign symbolic significance to this fact. Ever since the time of the French Revolution — if not be- fore — German thought has taken shape in conflict with ideas that were characteristically French and in sharp and conscious antithesis to them. Rous- seau's deification of Nature was the occasion for the development of the conception of Culture. His condemnation of science and art as socially corrupting and socially divisive worked across the Rhine to produce the notion that science and art are the forces which moralize and unify hu- manity. The cosmopolitanism of the French En- lightenment was transformed by German thinkers into a self-conscious assertion of nationalism. The abstract Rights of Man of the French Revo- 91 92 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY lution were set in antithesis to the principle of the rights of the citizen secured to him solely by the power of the politically organized nation. The deliberate breach of the revolutionary philosophy with the past, the attempt (foreshadowed in the philosophy of Descartes) to make a tabula rasa of the fortuitous assemblage of traditions and institutions which history offers, in order to sub- stitute a social structure built upon Reason, was envisaged as the fons et origo of all evil. That history is itself incarnate reason; that history is infinitely more rational than the formal abstract- ing and generalizing reason of individuals; that individual mind becomes rational only through the absorption and assimilation of the universal rea- son embodied in historic institutions and historic development, became the articles of faith of the German intellectual creed. It is hardly an exag- geration to say that for almost a century the characteristic philosophy of Germany has been a philosophy of history even when not such in ap- parent form. Yet the meaning of this appeal to history is lost unless we bear in mind that the Enlightenment after all transmitted to Germany, from medieval PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 93 thought, its foundation principle. The appeal was not from reason to experience, but from analytic thought (henceforth condemned to be merely " Un- derstanding " — " Verstand") to an absolute and universal Reason (Vernunft) partially revealed in nature and more adequately manifested in human history as an organic process. Recourse to his- tory was required because not of any empirical lessons it has to teach, nor yet because history be- queathes to us stubborn institutions which must be reckoned with, but because history is the dynamic and evolving realization of immanent reason. The contrast of the German attitude with that of Edmund Burke is instructive. The latter had the same profound hostility to cutting loose from the past. But his objection was not that the past is an embodiment of transcendent reason, but that its institutions are an " inheritance " be- queathed to us from the " collected wisdom " of our forefathers. The continuity of political life centers not about an inner evolving Idea, but about " our hearths, our sepulchers and our al- tars." He has the same suspicion of abstract rights of man. But his appeal is to experience and to practical consequences. Since " circum- 94 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY stances give in reality to every principle its dis- tinguishing color and discriminating effect," there is no soundness in any principle when " it stands stripped of every relation in all the nakedness and solitude of metaphysical abstraction." According to the German view, the English pro- tested because of interference with empirically established rights and privileges; the Germans, because they perceived in the Revolution a radical error as to the nature and work of reason. In point of fact, the Germans never made that break with tradition, political or religious, of which the French Revolution is an emphatic symbol. I have already referred to Kant's disposition to regard church dogmas (of which, as dogmas, he disap- proved) as vehicles of eternal spiritual truths — husks to preserve an inner grain. All of the great German idealists gave further expression to this disposition. To Hegel, for example, the sub- stance of the doctrines of Protestant Christianity is identical with the truths of absolute philosophy, except that in religion they are expressed in a form not adequate to their meaning, the form, namely, of imaginative thought in which most men live. The disposition to philosophize Christianity PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 95 is too widely shown in Germany to be dismissed as a cowardly desire at accommodation with things established. It shows rather an intellectual piety among a people where freedom of thought and conscience had been achieved without a violent political upheaval. Hegel finds that the char- acteristic weakness of Romance thought was an inner split, an inability to reconcile the spiritual and absolute essence of reality with which religion deals with the detailed work of intelligence in science and politics. The Germans, on the con- trary, " were predestined to be the bearers of the Christian principle and to carry out the Idea as the absolutely Rational end." They accomplished this, not by a flight away from the secular world, but by realizing that the Christian principle is in itself that of the unity of the subjective and the objective, the spiritual and the worldly. The " spirit finds the goal of its struggle, its harmony, in that very sphere which it made the object of its resistance, — it finds that secular pursuits are a spiritual occupation " ; — a discovery, surely, which unites simplicity with comprehensiveness and one which does not lead to criticism of the secular pur- suits carried on. Whatever is to be said of this 96 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY as philosophy, it expresses, in a way, the quality of German life and thought. More than other countries, Germany has had the fortune to pre- serve as food for its imaginative life and as emo- tional sanction the great ideas of the past. It has carried over their reinforcement into the pur- suit of science and into politics — into the very things which in other countries, notably in the Latin countries, have been used as weapons of attack upon tradition. Political development tells a somewhat similar tale. The painful transition from feudalism to the modern era was, for the most part, accom- plished recently in Germany, and accomplished under the guidance of established political au- thorities instead of by revolt against them. Under their supervision, and mainly at their ini- tiative, Germany has passed in less than a century to the regime of modern capitalistic competitive enterprise, moderated by the State, out of the do- minion of those local and guild restrictions which so long held economic activity in corporate bonds. The governing powers themselves secured to members of the State what seems, at least to Germans, to be a satisfying degree of po- PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 97 litical freedom. Along with this absence of internal disturbance and revolution, we must put the fact that every step in the development of Germany as a unified political power has been effected by war with some of the neighbors by which it is hemmed in. There stands the unfolding sequence : 1815 (not to go back to Frederick the Great), 1864, 1866, 1870. And the significant thing about these wars is not that external territory was annexed as their consequence, but the rebound of external struggle upon the achieving of in- ternal unity. No wonder the German imagination has been impressed with the idea of an organic evolution from within, which takes the form of a unity achieved through conflict and the conquest of an opposing principle. Such scattering comments as these prove noth- ing. But they suggest why German thought has been peculiarly sensitive to the idea of historic continuity; why it has been prone to seek for an original implicit essence which has progressively unfolded itself in a single development. It would take much more than an hour to give even a super- ficial account of the growth of the historical sci- ences and historic methods of Germany during 98 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY the first half of the eighteenth century. It would involve an account of the creation of philology, and the philological methods which go by the name of higher criticism; of their extension to archeology; of the historic schools of jurispru- dence and political economy, as well as of the ways in which such men as Niebuhr, Mommsen and Ranke remade the methods of studying the past. I can only say here that Germany devel- oped such an effective historical technique that even mediocre men achieved respectable results; and, much more significantly, that when Taine made the remark (quoted earlier) that we owe to the Germany of the half century before 1830 all our distinctively modern ideas, his remarks apply above all to the disciplines concerned with the his- torical development of mankind. The bases of this philosophy are already before us. Even in Kant we find the idea of a single continuous development of humanity, as a progress from a reign of natural instinct to a final freedom won through adherence to the law of reason. Fichte sketched the stages already traversed on this road and located the point at which mankind now stands. In his later writings, the significance PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 99 of history as the realization of the absolute pur- pose is increasingly emphasized. History is the continuous life of a divine Ego by which it realizes in fact what it is in idea or destiny. Its phases are successive stages in the founding of the King- dom of God on earth. It and it only is the revela- tion of the Absolute. Along with this growing deification of history is the increased significance attached to nationalism in general and the Ger- man nation in particular. The State is the con- crete individual interposed between generic hu- manity and particular beings. In his words, the national folk is the channel of divine life as it pours into particular finite human beings. He says: " While cosmopolitanism is the dominant will that the purpose of the existence of humanity be actually realized in humanity, patriotism is the will that this end be first realized in the par- ticular nation to which we ourselves belong, and that this achievement thence spread over the entire Since the State is an organ of divinity, patri- otism is religion. As the Germans are the 100 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY only truly religious people, they alone are truly capable of patriotism. Other peoples are products of external causes ; they have no self-formed Self, but only an acquired self due to general conven- tion. In Germany there is a self which is self- wrought and self-owned. The very fact that Ger- many for centuries has had no external unity proves that its selfhood is metaphysical, not a gift of circumstance. This conception of the German mission has been combined with a kind of anthropological metaphysics which has become the rage in Germany. The Germans alone of all existing European nations are a pure race. They alone have preserved unalloyed the original divine deposit. Language is the expression of the na- tional soul, and only the Germans have kept their native speech in its purity. In like vein, Hegel attributes the inner disharmony characteristic of Romance peoples to the fact that they are of mixed Germanic and Latin blood. A purely arti- ficial cult of race has so flourished in Germany that many social movements — like anti-Semitism — and some of Germany's political ambitions can- not be understood apart from the mystic identi- fication of Race, Culture and the State. In the PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 101 light of actual science, this is so mythological that the remark of an American periodical that race means a number of people reading the same newspapers is sober scientific fact compared with it.* At the beginning of history Fichte placed an " Urvolk." His account of it seems an attempt to rationalize at one stroke the legends of the Golden Age, the Biblical account of man before the Fall and Rousseau's primitive " state of na- ture." The Urvolk lived in a paradise of inno- cence, a paradise without knowledge, labor or art. * Chamberlain, for example, holds that Jesus must have been of Teutonic birth — a perfect logical conclusion from the received philosophy of the State and religion. Quite aware that there is much Slav blood in northern Germany and Romance blood in southern Germany, he explains that while with other peoples crossing produces a mongrel race, the potency of the German blood is such that cross-breeding strengthens it. While at one time he explains the historic strength of the Jew on the ground that he has kept his race pure, another place he allows his indignation at the Jews to lead him to include them among the most mongrel of all peoples. To one thing he remains consistent: By the very essence of race, the Semites represent a metaphysical principle inherently hostile to the grand Germanic principle. It p«rhaps seems absurd to dignify the vagaries of this garrulous writer, but according to all report the volumes in which such expressions occur, "The Foundations of the Nineteenth Century," has had august approval and much vogue. 102 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY The philosophy which demands such a Folk is com- paratively simple. Except as a manifestation of Absolute Reason, humanity could not exist at all. Yet in the first stage of the manifestation, Reason could not have been appropriated by the self- conscious effort of man. It existed without con- sciousness of itself, for it was given, not, like all true self-consciousness, won by morally creative struggle. Rational in substance, in form it was but feeling or instinct. In a sense, all subsequent history is but a return to this primitive condition. But " humanity must make the journey on its own feet ; by its own strength it must bring itself back to that state in which it was once without its own cooperating labor. . . . If humanity does not re- create its own true being, it has no real life." 'While philosophy compels us to assume a Normal People who, by " the mere fact of their existence, without science and art, found themselves in a state of perfectly developed reason," there is no ground for not admitting the existence at the same \ time of " timid and rude earth-born savages." Thus the original state of humanity would have been one of the greatest possible inequality, being divided between the Normal Folk existing as a PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 103 manifestation of Reason and the wild and savage races of barbarism. In his later period of inflamed patriotism this innocuous speculation grew a sting. He had de- termined that the present age — the Europe of the Enlightenment and the French Revolution — is the age of liberation from the external authority in which Reason had presented itself in the second age. Hence it is inherently negative : " an age of absolute indifference toward the Truth, an age of entire and unrestrained licentiousness." But the further evolution of the Divine Idea demands a Folk which has retained the primitive principle of Reason, which may redeem, therefore, the corrupt and rebellious modes of humanity else- where existing. Since the Germans are this saving remnant, they are the Urvolk, the Nor- mal Nation, of the modern period. From this point on, idealization of past Germanic history and appeal to the nation to realize its unique calling by victory over Napoleon blend. The Fichtean scaffolding tumbled, but these ideas persisted. I doubt if it is possible to exag- gerate the extent to which German history has 104 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY been systematically idealized for the last hundred years. Technically speaking, the Romantic move- ment may have passed away and an age of scien- tific history dawned. Actually the detailed facts have been depicted by use of the palette of Ro- manticism. Space permits but one illustration which would be but a literary curiosity were it not fairly typical. Tacitus called his account of the northern barbarians Germania — an unfortu- nate title in view of later developments. The characteristics assigned by him to the German tribes are such as any anthropologist could dupli- cate from any warlike barbaric tribe. Yet over and over again these traits (which Tacitus ideal- ized as Cooper, say, idealized the North American Indian traits) are made the basis of the philo- sophic history of the German people. The Ger- mans, for example, had that psychological ex- perience now known as mana, manitou, tabu, etc. They identified their gods, in Tacitus' phrase, with " that mystery which they perceive by ex- periencing sacred fear." This turns out to be the germinal deposit of spiritual-mindedness which later showed itself in Luther and in the peculiar genius of the Germans for religious experience. PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 105 The following words are from no less an author- ity than Pfleiderer: " Cannot we recognize in this point that truly German characteristic of Iimerlichkeit which scorns to fix for sensuous perception the divine something which makes itself felt in the depths of the sensitive soul, which scorns to drag down the sublime mystery of the unknowable to the vulgar distinctness of earthly things? The fact that the Germans attached but little importance to reli- gious ceremonies accords with this view." To others, this sense of mystery is a prophetic anticipation of the Kantian thing-in-itself. A similar treatment has been accorded to the personal and voluntary bond by which individuals attached themselves to a chieftain. Thus early was marked out the fidelity or loyalty, Treue, which is uniquely Germanic — although some war- like tribes among our Indians carried the system still further. I can allow myself but one more example of the way in which the philosophic so- phistication of history has worked. No historian can be unconscious of the extent to which Eu- \ ropean culture has been genuinely European — I the extent to which it derives itself from a common 106 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY heritage of the ancient world and the extent to which intermixtures and borrowings of culture have gone on ever since. As to Germany, how- ever, these obvious facts have to be accommodated to the doctrine of an original racial deposit stead- ily evolving from within. 4 The method is simple. As respects Germany, ese cultural borrowings and crosses represent the intrinsic universality of its genius. Through this universality, the German spirit finds itself at home everywhere. Consequently, it consciously appropriates and assimilates what other peoples have produced by a kind of blind unconscious in- stinct. Thus it was German thought which re- vealed the truth of Hellenic culture, and rescued essential Christianity from its Romanized petri- faction. The principle of Reason which French enlightenment laid hold of only in its negative and destructive aspect, the German spirit grasped in its positive and constructive form. Shakespeare happened to be born in England, but only the Germans have apprehended him in his spiritual universality so that he is now more his own than he is England's — and so on. But with respect to other peoples, similar borrowings reveal only their PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 107 lack of inner and essential selfhood. While Luther is universal because he is German, Shakespeare is universal because he is not English. I have intimated that Fichte's actual influence was limited. But his basic ideas of the State and of history were absorbed in the philosophy of Hegel, and Hegel for a considerable period abso- lutely dominated German thinking. To set forth the ground principles of his " absolute idealism " would be only to repeat what has already been said. Its chief difference, aside from Hegel's en- cyclopedic knowledge, his greater concrete his- toric interest and his more conservative tempera- ment, is his bottomless scorn for an Idea, an Ab- solute, which merely ought to be and which is only going to be realized after a period of time. " The Actual it the Rational and the Rational t* the Actual " — and the actual means the actuating force and movement of things. It is customary to call him an Idealist. In one sense of much abused terms, he is the greatest reaUst known to phi- losophy. He might be called a Brutalist. In the inquiry Bourdon carried on in Germany a few years ago (published under the title of the " Ger- man Enigma "), he records a conversation with a 108 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY German who deplores the tendency of the Germans to forsake the solid bone of things in behalf of a romantic shadow. As against this he appeals to the realistic sense of Hegel, who, " in opposi- tion to the idealism which had lifted Germany on wings, arrayed and marshaled the maxims of an unflinching realism. He had formulas for the justi- fication of facts whatever they might be. That which is, he would say, is reason realized. And what did he teach? That the hour has sounded for the third act in the drama of humanity, and that the German opportunity is not far off. ... I could show you throughout the nineteenth cen- tury the torrent of political and social ideas which had their source here." I have said that the essential points of the Fichtean philosophy of history were taken up into the Hegelian system. This assimilation involved, however, a rectification of an inconsistency be- tween the earlier and the later moral theories of Fichte. In his earlier ethical writings, em- phasis fell upon conscious moral personality — upon the deliberate identification by the individual will of its career and destiny with the purpose of the Absolute. In his later patriotic philosophy, PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 109 1 he asserts that the organized nation is the channel by which a finite ego acquires moral personality, since the nation alone transmits to individuals the generic principle of God working in humanity. At the same time he appeals to the resolute will and consciously chosen self-sacrifice of individuals to overthrow the enemy and re-establish the Prussian state. When Hegel writes that victory has been obtained, the war of Independence has been suc- cessfully waged. The necessity of emphasizing individual self-assertion had given way to the need of subordinating the individual to the established state in order to check the disintegrating tend- encies of liberalism. Haym has said that Hegel's " Philosophy of Law " had for its task the exhibition as the per- fect work of Absolute Reason up to date of the " practical and political condition existing in Prussia in 1821." This was meant as a hostile attack. But Hegel himself should have been the last to object. With his scorn for an Ideal so impotent that its realization must depend upon the effort of private selves, an Absolute so incon- sequential that it must wait upon the accidents of future time for manifestation, he sticks in politics 110 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY more than elsewhere to the conviction that the actual If the rational. " The task of philosophy is to comprehend that which is, for that which is, is Reason." Alleged philosophies which try to tell what the State should be or even what a state ought in the future to come to be, are idle fan- tasies. Such attempts come too late. Human wisdom is like the bird of Minerva which takes its flight only at the close of day." * It comes, after the issue, to acknowledge what has happened. " The State is the rational in itself and for itself. Its substantial unity is an absolute end in itself. To it belongs supreme right in respect to individ- uals whose first duty is — just to be members of the State." . . . The State " is the absolute real- ity and the individual himself has objective exist- ence, truth and morality only in his capacity as a member oi; the State." It is a commonplace of idealistic theism that nature is a manifestation of God. But Hegel says that nature is only an ex- ternalized, unconscious and so incomplete expres- sion. The State has more, not less, objective real- *Marx said of the historic schools of politics, law and economics that to them, as Jehovah to Moses on Mt. Sinai, the divine showed but its posterior side. PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 111 ity than physical nature, for it is a realization of Absolute spirit in the realm of consciousness. The doctrine presents an extreme form of the idea, not of the divine right of kings, but of the divine right of States. " The march of God in history is the cause of the existence of states; their foundation is the power of reason realizing itself as will. Every state, whatever it be, participates in the divine essence. The State is not the work of human art; only Reason could produce it." The State is God on earth. * His depreciation of the individual as an indi- vidual appears in every theme of his Philosophy of Right and History. At first sight, his theory of great world heroes seems inconsistent with his disregard of individuals. While the morality of most men consists simply in assimilating into their own habits the customs already found in the insti- tutions about them, great men initiate new his- toric epochs. They derive " their purposes and their calling not from the calm regular course of things sanctioned by the existing order, but from a concealed fount, from that inner spirit hidden beneath the surface, which, striking the outer world as a shell, bursts it to pieces." The heroes 112 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY are thus the exception which proves the rule. They are world characters ; while they seem to be seek- ing personal interests they are really acting as organs of a universal will, of God in his further march. In his identification with the Absolute, the world-hero can have but one aim to which " he is devoted regardless of all else. Such men may even treat other great and sacred interests incon- siderately. . . . But so mighty a form must tram- ple down many an innocent flower — crush to pieces many an object in its path." We are not sur- prised to see that Alexander, Caesar and Napoleon are the characters he prefers to cite. One can only regret that he died before his contemplative piety could behold Bismarck. A large part of the intellectual machinery by which Hegel overcame the remnants of individ- ualism found in prior philosophy came from the idea of organic development which had been active in German thought since the time of Herder. In his chief work (" Ideas for a Philosophy of the History of Humanity "), written in the closing decades of the eighteenth century, Herder holds that history is a progressive education of human- ity. This idea, had from Lessing, is combined PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 113 with the idea of Leibniz that change is evolution, by means of an internal force, of powers originally implicit in existence, and with the idea of Spinoza of an all-comprehensive substance. This idea of organic growth was then applied to language, literature and institutions. It soon obtained rein- forcement from the rising science of biology. Long before the days of Darwin or Spencer, the idea of evolution had been a commonplace of Ger- man thought with respect to everything concern- ing the history of humanity. The notion was set in sharp antithesis to the conception of " mak- ing" or manufacturing institutions and constitu- tions, which was treated as one of the fallacies of the French philosophy of the Enlightenment. A combination of this notion of universal organic growth with the technique of prior idealism may fairly be said to have determined Hegel's whole philosophy. While Leibniz and Herder had em- phasized the notion of harmony as an essential factor of the working of organic forces, Hegel took from Fichte the notion of a unity or syn- thesis arrived at by " positing," and overcoming an opposite. Struggle for existence (or realiza- tion) was thus an "organic" part of German 114 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY thinking long before the teaching of Darwin, who, in fact, is usually treated by German writers as giving a rather superficial empirical expression to an idea which they had already grasped in its universal speculative form. It is characteristic of the extent in which Hegel thought in terms of struggle and overcoming that after stating why it was as yet impossible to include the Americas in his philosophy of history, and after saying that in the future the burden of world history will reveal itself there, he surmises that it may take the form of a " contest " between North and South America. No philosopher has ever thought so consistently and so wholly in terms of strife and overcoming as Hegel. When he says the " world history is the world judgment " he means judg- ment in the sense of assize, and judgment as victory of one and defeat of another — victory being the final proof that the world spirit has now passed from one nation to take up its residence in another. To be defeated in a way which causes the nation to take a secondary position among nations is a sign that divine judgment has been passed upon it. When a recent German writer argues that for Germany to surrender any terri- PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 115 tory which it has conquered during the present war would be sacrilegious, since it would be to refuse to acknowledge the workings of God in human history, he speaks quite in the Hegelian vein. Although the phenomenon of nationalism was very recent when Hegel wrote, indeed practically contemporary with his own day, he writes in na- tionalistic terms the entire history of humanity. The State is the Individual of history ; it is to his- tory what a given man is to biography. History gives us the progressive realization or evolution of the Absolute, moving from one National Individual to another. It is law, the universal, which makes the State a State, for law is reason, not as mere subjective reflection, but in its manifestation as supreme over and in particulars. On this account, Hegel's statement that the fundamental principle of history is the progressive realization of free- dom does not mean what an uninstructed English reader would naturally take it to mean. Freedom is always understood in terms of Reason. Its ex- pression in history means that Thought has pro- gressively become conscious of itself; that is, has made itself its own object. Freedom is the conr 116 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY sciousness of freedom. Liberty of action has little to do with it. Obviously it is only in the German idealistic system — particularly in the system of Hegel himself — that this has fully taken place. Meantime, when citizens of a state (especially of the state in which this philosophic insight has been achieved) take the laws of their state as their own ends and motives of action, they attain the best possible substitute for a reason which is its own object. They appropriate as their own personal reason the objective and absolute Reason em- bodied perforce in law and custom. After this detour, we are led back to the fact that the Germans possess the greatest freedom yet attained by humanity, for the Prussian political organization most fully exemplifies Law, or the Universal, organizing under and within itself all particular arrangements of social and personal life. Some other peoples — particularly the Latin — have thought they could make constitutions, or at least that the form of their constitution was a matter of choice. But this is merely setting up the private conceit of individuals against the work of Absolute Reason, and thus marks the disin- tegration of a state rather than its existence. PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 117 Other peoples have tried to found the government on the consent of the governed, unwitting of the fact that it is the government, the specific realiza- tion of Reason, which makes a state out of what is otherwise an anarchic mass of individuals. Other peoples have made a parliament or representative body the essential thing in government; in philo- sophic reality this is only a consultative body, having as its main function communication between classes (which are indispensable to an " organic " state) and the real government. The chief func- tion of parliament is to give the opinion of the social classes an opportunity to feel it is being considered and to enable the real government to take advantage of whatever wisdom may chance to be expressed. Hegel seems quite prophetic when he says: "By virtue of this participation subjec- tive liberty and conceit, with their general opinion, can show themselves palpably efficacious and enjoy the satisfaction of feeling themselves to count for something." Finally, the State becomes wholly and completely an organized Individual only in its external relations, its relations to other states. As his philosophy of history ignores the past in seiz- ing upon the national state as the unit and focus 118 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY of history, so it ignores all future possibility of a genuinely international federation to which iso- lated nationalism shall be subordinated. Bern- hardi writes wholly in the Hegelian sense when he says that to expand the idea of the State into the idea of humanity is a Utopian error, for it would exclude the essential principle of life, struggle. Philosophical justification of war follows inevi- tably from a philosophy of history composed in nationalistic terms. History is the movement, the march of God on earth through time. Only one nation at a time can be the latest and hence the fullest realization of God. The movement of God in history is thus particularly manifest in those changes by which unique place passes from one nation to another. War is the signally visible occurrence of such a flight of the divine spirit in its onward movement. The idea that friendly in- tercourse among all the peoples of the earth is a legitimate aim of human effort is in basic con- tradiction of such a philosophy. War is explicit realization of " dialectic," of the negation by which a higher synthesis of reason is assured. It effectively displays the " irony of the divine Idea." It is to national life what the winds are to the sea, PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 119 " preserving mankind from the corruption en- gendered by immobility." War is the most ef- fective preacher of the vanity of all merely finite interests ; it puts an end to that selfish egoism of the individual by which he would claim his life and his property as his own or as his family's. Inter- national law is not properly law; it expresses simply certain usages which are accepted so long as they do not come into conflict with the purpose of a state — a purpose which always gives the supreme law of national life. Particularly against the absolute right of the " present bearer of the world spirit, the spirits of the other nations are absolutely without right. The latter, just like the nations whose epochs have passed, count no longer in universal history." Since they are al- ready passed over from the standpoint of the divine idea, war can do no more than exhibit the fact that their day has come and gone. World history is the world's judgment seat. For a period Hegelian thought was almost su- preme in Germany. Then its rule passed away almost as rapidly as it had been achieved. After various shiftings, the trend of philosophic thought was definitely " Back to Kant." Kant's greater 120 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY sobriety, the sharp distinction he drew between the realm of phenomena and science and the ideal noumenal world, commended him after the unbridled pretensions of Hegelian absolutism. For more than a generation Hegel was spoken of with almost universal contempt. Nevertheless his ideas, loosed from the technical apparatus with which he surrounded them, persisted. Upon the historical disciplines his influence was peculiarly deep and abiding. He fixed the ideas of Fichte and fastened them together with the pin of evolu- tion. Since his day, histories of philosophy, or religion, or institutions have all been treated as developments through necessary stages of an inner implicit idea or purpose according to an indwelling law. And the idea of a peculiar mission and destiny of German history has lost nothing in the operation. Expressions which a bewildered world has sought since the beginning of the war to ex- plain through the influence of a Darwinian strug- gle for existence and survival of the fittest, or through the influence of a Nietzschean philosophy of power, have their roots in the classic idealistic philosophy culminating in Hegel. Kant still remains the philosopher of Germany. PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 121 The division of life between the world of sense and of mechanism and the world of the supersensible and purpose, the world of necessity and the world of freedom, is more congenial than a complete monism. The attempts of his successors to bridge the gap and set up a wholly unified philosophy failed, historically speaking. But, nevertheless, they contributed an indispensable ingredient to the contemporary German spirit; they helped people the Kantian void of the supersensible with the substantial figures of the State and its His- torical Evolution and Mission. Kant bequeathed to the world an intellect devoted to the congenial task of discovering causal law in external nature, and an inner intuition which, in spite of its sublim- ity, had nothing to look at except the bare form of an empty law of duty. Kant was kept busy in proving the existence of this supernal but empty region. Consequently he was not troubled by being obliged to engage in the unremunerative task of spending his time gazing into a blank void. His successors were not so fortunate. The existence of this ideal realm in which reason, purpose and freedom are one was axiomatic to them ; they could no longer busy themselves with proving its exist- 122 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY ence. Some of them, called the Romanticists, filled it with visions, more or less poetic, which frankly drew their substance from an imagination inflamed by emotional aspiration in revolt at the limita- tions of outward action. Others, called the ideal- istic philosophers, filled in the void, dark because of excess of light, with less ghostly forms of Law and the unfolding in History of Absolute Value and Purpose. The two worlds of Kant were too far away from each other. The later idealistic world constructions crumbled; but their debris supplied material with which to fill in the middle regions between the Kantian worlds of sense and of reason. This, I repeat, is their lasting con- tribution to present German culture. Where Kantianism has not received a filling in from the philosophy of history and the State, it has remained in Germany, as elsewhere, a critique of the methodology of science; its importance has been professional rather than human. In the first lecture we set out with the sug- gestion of an inquiry into the influence of general ideas upon practical affairs, upon those larger PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 123 practical affairs called politics. We appear to have concluded with a conviction that (in the instance before us at least) politics has rather been the controlling factor in the formation of philosophic ideas and in deciding their vogue. Yet we are well within limits when we say that ideas which were evoked in correspondence with concrete social conditions served to articulate and consolidate the latter. Even if we went so far as to say that reigning philosophies simply reflect as in a mirror contemporary social struggles, we should have to add that seeing one's self in a mirror is a definite practical aid in carrying on one's undertaking to its completion. When what a people sees in its intellectual looking glass is its own organization and its own historic evolution as an organic instrument of the accomplishment of an Absolute Will and Law, the articulating and consolidating efficacy of the re- flection is immensely intensified. Outside of Ger- many, the career of the German idealistic phi- losophy has been mainly professional and literary. It has exercised considerable influence upon the teaching of philosophy in France, England and this country. Beyond professorial circles, its in- 124 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY fluence has been considerable in theological direc- tions. Without doubt, it has modulated for many persons the transition from a supernatural to a spiritual religion; it has enabled them to give up historical and miraculous elements as indifferent accretions and to retain the moral substance and emotional values of Christianity. But the Ger- mans are quite right in feeling that only in Ger- many is this form of idealistic thinking both in- digenous and widely applied. A crisis like the present forces upon thoughtful persons a consideration of the value for the gen- eral aims of civilization of a philosophy of the a priori, the Absolute, and of their immanent evo- lution through the medium of an experience which as just experience is only a superficial and negligible vehicle of transcendent Laws and Ends. It forces a consideration of what type of general ideas is available for the articulation and guidance of our own life in case we find ourselves looking upon the present world scene as an a priori and an absolutistic philosophy gone into bankruptcy. In Europe, speaking generally, " Americanism " is a synonym for crude empiricism and a ma- PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 125 tenalistic utilitarianism. It is no part of my pres- ent task to try to show how largely this accusation is due to misunderstanding. It is simpler to inquire how far the charge points to the problem which American life, and therefore philosophy in America, must meet. It is difficult to see how any a priori philosophy, or any systematic absolut- ism, is to get a footing among us, at least beyond narrow and professorial circles. Psychologists talk about learning by the method of trial and error or success. Our social organization com- mits us to this philosophy of life. Our working principle is to try: to find out by trying, and to measure the worth of the ideas and theories tried by the success with which they meet the test of application in practice. Concrete consequences rather than a priori rules supply our guiding prin- ciples. Hegel found it " superficial and absurd to regard as objects of choice " social constitutions ; to him " they were necessary structures in the path of development." To us they are the cumu- lative result of a multitude of daily and ever- renewed choices. That such an experimental philosophy of life means a dangerous experiment goes without say- 126 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY ing. It permits, sooner or later it may require, every alleged sacrosanct principle to submit to ordeal by fire — to trial by service rendered. From the standpoint of a priorism, it is hopelessly anarchic ; it is doomed, a priori, to failure. From its own standpoint, it is itself a theory to be tested by experience. Now experiments are of all kinds, varying from those generated by blind impulse and appetite to those guided by intelligently formed ideas. They are as diverse as the attempt of a savage to get rain by sprinkling water and scat- tering thistledown, and that control of electricity in the laboratory from which issue wireless teleg- raphy and rapid traction. Is it not likely that in this distinction we have the key to the failure or success of the experimental method generalized into a philosophy of life, that is to say, of social matters — the only application which procures complete generalization ? An experimental philosophy differs from em- pirical philosophy as empiricism has been previ- ously formulated. Historical empiricisms have been stated in terms of precedents ; their general- izations have been summaries of what has previ- ously happened. The truth and falsity of these PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 127 generalizations depended then upon the accuracy with which they catalogued, under appropriate heads, a multiplicity of past occurrences. They were perforce lacking in directive power except so far as the future might be a routine repetition of the past. In an experimental philosophy of life, the question of the past, of precedents, of origins, is quite subordinate to prevision, to guidance and control amid future possibilities. Consequences rather than antecedents measure the worth of theories. Any scheme or project may have a fair hearing provided it promise amelioration in the future; and no theory or standard is so sacred that it may be accepted simply on the basis of past performance. But this difference between a radically experi- mental philosophy and an empiristic philosophy only emphasizes the demand for careful and com- prehensive reflection with respect to the ideas which are to be tested in practice. If an a priori philosophy has worked at all in Germany it is be- cause it has been based on an a priori social con- stitution — that is to say, on a state whose organ- ization is such as to determine in advance the main activities of classes of individuals, and to utilize 128 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY their particular activities by linking them up with one another in definite ways. It is a commonplace to say that Germany is a monument to what can be done by means of conscious method and organ- ization. An experimental philosophy of life in order to succeed must not set less store upon methodic and organized intelligence, but more. We must learn from Germany what methodic and . organized work means. But instead of confining intelligence to the technical means of realizing ends which are predetermined by the State (or by something called the historic Evolution of the Idea), intelligence must, with us, devote itself as well to construction of the ends to be acted upon. The method of trial and error or success is likely, if not directed by a trained and informed imagination, to score an undue proportion of fail- ures. There is no possibility of disguising the fact that an experimental philosophy of life means a hit-and-miss philosophy in the end. But it means missing rather than hitting, if the aiming is done in a happy-go-lucky way instead of by bringing to bear all the resources of inquiry upon locating the target, constructing propulsive ma- chinery and figuring out the curve of trajectory. PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 129 That this work is, after all, but hypothetical and tentative till it issue from thought into action does not mean that it might as well be random guesswork; it means that we can do still better next time if we are sufficiently attentive to the causes of success and failure this time. America is too new to afford a foundation for an a priori philosophy; we have not the requisite background of law, institutions and achieved social organization. America is too new to render con- genial to our imagination an evolutionary phi- losophy of the German type. For our history is too obviously future. Our country is too big and too unformed, however, to enable us to trust to an empirical philosophy of muddling along, patching up here and there some old piece of machinery which has broken down by reason of its antiquity. We must have system, con- structive method, springing from a widely in- ventive imagination, a method checked up at each turn by results achieved. We have said long enough that America means opportunity ; we must now begin to ask : Opportunity for what, and how shall the opportunity be achieved ? I can but think that the present European situation forces home 130 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY upon us the need for constructive planning. I can but think that while it gives no reason for supposing that creative power attaches ex officio to general ideas, it does encourage us to believe that a philosophy which should articulate and con- solidate the ideas to which our social practice com- mits us would clarify and guide our future en- deavor. Time permits of but one illustration. The pres- ent situation presents the spectacle of the break- down of the whole philosophy of Nationalism, political, racial and cultural. It is by the acci- dent of position rather than any virtue of our own that we are not sharers in the present demon- stration of failure. We have borrowed the older philosophy of isolated national sovereignty and have lived upon it in a more or less half-hearted way. In our internal constitution we are actu- ally interracial and international. It remains to see whether we have the courage to face this fact and the wisdom to think out the plan of action which it indicates. Arbitration treaties, interna- tional judicial councils, schemes of international disarmament, peace funds and peace movements, are all well in their way. But the situation calls for PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 131 more radical thinking than that which terminates in such proposals. We have to recognize that furtherance of the depth and width of human in- tercourse is the measure of civilization; and we have to apply this fact without as well as within our national life. We must make the accident of our internal composition into an idea, an idea upon which we may conduct our foreign as well as our domestic policy. An international judicial tribunal will break in the end upon the principle of national sovereignty. We have no right to cast stones at any warring nation till we have asked ourselves whether we are willing to forego this principle and to submit af- fairs which limited imagination and sense have led us to consider strictly national to an international legislature. In and of itself, the idea of peace is a negative idea; it is a police idea. There are things more important than keeping one's body whole and one's property intact. Disturbing the peace is bad, not because peace is disturbed, but because the fruitful processes of cooperation in the great experiment of living together are dis- turbed. It is futile to work for the negative end of peace unless we are committed to the positive 132 PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY ideal which it cloaks: Promoting the efficacy of human intercourse irrespective of class, racial, geographical and national limits. Any philosophy which should penetrate and particulate our present social practice would find at work the forces which unify human intercourse. An intelligent and courageous philosophy of practice would devise means by which the operation of these forces would be extended and assured in the future. An American philosophy of history must perforce be a philosophy for its future, a future in which freedom and fullness of human companionship is the aim, and intelligent cooperative experimenta- tion the method. THE END INDEX Absolutism, 89, 112, 115, 124 America, philosophy in, 123- 132 "Americanism," 124 Anti-Semitism, 100-101. A priori, 39-44, 126, 129 Authority, 52-54 Bentham, 56 Bergsori, 4 Bernhardi, 34-35, 52, 118 Bourdon, 107-108 Burke, 93-94 Chamberlain, 101 n. Cosmopolitanism, 67, 75, 85, 99 Culture, 91 Descartes, 92 Despotism enlightened, 53 Dialectic, 70, 118 Duty, 24, 50-57 Education, 14, 72, 73 Empiricism, 41, 43, 126-129 Enlightenment, the, 37-39, 59, 92, 103 Eucken, 36, 55 Evolution, 112 Fichte, 68-80, 85-87 Formalism, 51 Freedom, 18, 25, 30, 33-35, 47, 51, 71, 115. French Revolution, 57, 94, 103 French thought, 52, 91-94, 95, 100 Germania, 104 Germany, 14-16, 28, 29-31, 32- 33, 36, 71, 78-81, 84-85, 88, 91-93, 94-98, 106-107 Haym, 107 Hegel, 94-95, 107-120, 125 Heine, 17, 18, 76, 83, 84-85 Herder, 112 History, 5-6, 59-67, 98-102, 107-119, 121 Hoffman, 81 Idealism, 28, 39, 70, 82, 107, 123, 130 Ideas and action, 3-15, 123- 132 Individualism, 49, 72 Intelligence, 54-56, 126-128 Jena, 68 Kant, 19-40, 47-58, 59-67, 119- 121 Kultur, 62-64 Lange, 78 Lasalle, 77 Law, 20-25, 116 Leibniz, 59, 112 Luther, 16, 27, 71, 87 Marx, 6, 110 n. Militarism, 52 Napoleon, 67, 78-79 Nationalism, 67, 81, 86, 87, 115 Nietzsche, 28, 34, 58 133 134 INDEX Pantheism, 77, 82 Parliaments, 117 Personality, 48 Pfleiderer, 105 Philosophy, 7-18, 123-132 Property, 74 Psychology, Social, 82 Race, 100-101 Religion, 20-21, 26-27, 95 Rights, 52, 57 Romanticism, 81, 104, 122 Rousseau, 61, 91 Schelling, 82 n. Scholar, 72 Science, 21-23, 28 Socialism, 74-75 Social motives, 60-61 Society, 64-65 State, 64-65, 66-67, 73-77, 110- 118 Subjectivism, 49, 81 Supersensible, 23-25 v. Sybel, 78-80 Tacitus, 104 Taine, 14 Universalism of Germany, 36, 106-107 Urvolk, 101-102 Utilitarianism, 57-58 Volk-seele, 82 War, 35-36, 89, 97, 118-120 World-herces, 112 DEWEY AND TUFTS'S ETHICS By John Dewey, Professor in Columbia University, and James H. Tufts, Professor in the University of Chi- cago. (American Science Series.) 618 pp. 8vo. $2.00. G. H. Palmer, Professor in Harvard University; It is a scholarly and stimulating production, the best, I think, for college use that has yet appeared. Indeed, from no other book would a general reader obtain in so brief a compass so wide a view of the moral work of to-day, set forth in so positive, lucid and interesting a fashion. Twenty years ago the book could not have been written, for into it have gone the spoils of all the ethical battles of our time. While I often find myself in dissent from its opinions, I see that whoever wishes to comprehend the deeper social ten- dencies of recent years will do well to study this book, and that he will carry away from his reading as much enjoyment as instruction. Professor Norman Wilde of the University of Minnesota in Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods: If this is not the ideal text -book in ethics for which we have been waiting so many years, it is, at least, a very good substitute for it. Certainly no more valuable fruit of the recent ethical revival has been produced than this, nor one which will itself produce more future good, for it is bound to be but the first of a new type of texts. It marks the end of the abstract, speculative treatises and the beginning of the positive studies of established human values. The moral life is presented as a reality about which there can be no more question tnan about the reality of the physical life, and, indeed, as that in which the latter finds its completion and ex- planation. Theories and systems are strictly subordinated to the facts and are not presented until the facts are clearly given. No student can rise from the study of this book feeling that he has been engaged with questions of purely academic interest. On the contrary, he can not but realize that it is the origin and solution of the problems of his own life with which he is here concerned. Reality is the dominant note of the book. The Outlook : In several respects this work, among the many of its kind appearing in recent years, is eminently valuable, especially for the ample treatment given to ethics in the world of action in civil society, admidst the relations of political, economic, and family life. To trace the growth of morality, and to discover its laws and principles, with a view to their application to present social conditions and problems for progressive moral development, is the proper aim of ethical science as here unfolded. . . . The many ethical questions raised by present economic conditions are treated with admirable fulness and perspicacity. HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY NEW YORK BERGSON'S CREATIVE EVOLUTION Translated from the French by 1>r. Arthur Sffltchett $3.00 net, by mail $3.17 "Bergson's resources in the way of erudition are remark- able, and in the way of expression they are simply phe- nomenal. ... If anything can make hard things easy to follow it is a style like Bergson's. It is a miracle and he a real magician. Open Bergson and new horizons open on every page you read. It tells of reality itself instead of reiterating what dusty-minded professors have written about what other previous professors have thought. Nothing in Bergson is shopworn or at second-hand." — William James. "A distinctive and trenchant piece of dialectic. . . . Than its entrance upon the field as a well-armed and militant philosophy there have been not many more memorable occur- ences in the history of ideas." — Nation. "To bring out in an adequate manner the effect which Bergson's philsophy has on those who are attracted by it let us try to imagine what it would have been like to have lived when Kant produced his 'Critique of Pure Reason.'"— Hibbert Journal "Creative Evolution is destined, I believe, to mark an epoch in the history of modern thought. The work has its root in modern physical science, but it blooms and bears fruit in the spirit to a degree quite unprecedented. . . . Bergson is a new star in the intellectual firmament of our day. He is a philosopher upon whom the spirits of both literature and science have descended. In his great work he touches the materialism of science to finer issues. Prob- ably no other writer of our time has possessed in the same measure the three gifts, the literary, the scientific, and the philosophical. Bergson is a kind of chastened and spirit- ualized Herbert Spencer."— John Burroughs in the Atlantic Monthly. HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY PUBLISHERS NEW YORK BY WALTER LIPPMANN DRIFT AND MASTERY 2nd Printing, $1.50 Net Theodore Roosevelt in The Outlook: "No man who wishes seriously to study our present social, industrial and political life can afford not to read it through and through and to ponder and digest it." William Marion Reedy in The St. Louis Mirror: "When 'A Preface to Polities' was published, I ven- tured the opinion that it was the best book on politics since Walter Bagehot's 'Physics and Politics.' Now he has fol- lowed it with 'Drift and Mastery,' an even more brilliant performance." A PREFACE TO POLITICS 3rd Printing, $1.50 Net The Boston Transcript: " 'A Preface to Politics is its own complete and suffi- cient justification. In many respects it is the ablest brief book of its kind published during the last ten years. It has the supreme virtue of clearness aided by a style that is incisive and compelling." THE STAKES OF DIPLOMACY 4th Printing, cloth, $1.35 Net; paper, 60 cts. Net J. B. Kerfoot in Life: "It is a real joy to find it of the same order as 'A Preface to Politics.' It deals with human nature involved in international human relations impersonally, yet brings significances personally home to us. A book that widens horizons and quickens consciousness." HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY Publishers New York EDUCATION LIBRA** UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY BERKELEY Return to desk from which borrowed. This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. nK C tj 1949 1 3 RECD *AY M973 1 RECD -U AM W87nae 21-100to-9,'47(A5702s16)476 . YB 3021 i M337183 r ft** 1 THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA UBRARY II 1 till b