THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA IN MEMORY OF Frederick Slate Professor of Physics .-■ Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from Microsoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/comtemillspencerOOwatsrich COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER PUBLISHED BY JAMES MACLEHOSE AND SONS, GLASGOW, publishers to the SlmbersttB. MACMILLAN AND CO., LONDON AND NEW YORK. London, - - Simpkin, Hamilton and Co. Cambridge, - Macmillan and Bowes. Edinburgh, - Douglas and Foulis. MDCCCXCV. COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER AN OUTLINE OF PHILOSOPHY JOHN WATSON, LL.D. PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF QUEEN'S COLLEGE KINGSTON, CANADA, AUTHOR OF " KANT AND HIS ENGLISH CRITICS" GLASGOW JAMES MACLEHOSE & SONS ^publishers to the Shtibersitg NEW YORK: MACMTLLAN & CO. 1895 <(?* K& PREFACE. By the use of a double title I have tried to indicate that my aim in this little work has been at once critical and constructive. The philosophical creed which commends itself to my mind is what in the text I have called In- tellectual Idealism, by which I mean the doctrine that we are capable of knowing Reality as it actually is, and that Reality when so known is absolutely rational. Such a doctrine seems to many to be presumptuous, contrary to the sober spirit of inductive inquiry, and based on an untenable theory of knowledge and conduct. My aim has been to show that these objections rest upon a misunder- standing of the idealistic position, at least as held by such writers as the late Professor T. H. Green and the present Master of Balliol. The general proof of Idealism must consist in showing that, while the determination of Reality by such categories as coexistence, succession, and causality, is capable of vindication so long as it is not regarded as ultimate, it becomes false when affirmed to be final, and that we are compelled at last to characterize existence as purposive and rational. There are various ways of enforcing this view. The method which I have followed here is to attempt to show that the ideas which lie at the basis of Mathematics, Physics, Biology, Psy- VI PREFACE. chology and Ethics, Religion and Art, are related to each other as developing forms or phases of one idea — the idea of self-conscious Reason. But, partly out of respect for their eminence, and partly as a means of orientation both for myself and for the students under my charge (for whom this Outline was originally prepared), I have examined certain views of Comte, Mill, and Spencer — and also, I may add, of Darwin and Kant — which appear to me inadequate. No apology seems needed for the publication at the present time of an Outline of Philosophy. There is no lack of Introductions to Psychology and Ethics, but, so far as I know, there is not in English any book which seeks to give in moderate compass a statement of Phil- osophy as a whole. I am well aware that there is danger in generalities, but there seems to be just now an even greater danger that Philosophy, in the large sense in which it was understood by Plato and Aristotle, should be lost in artificial divisions and in a mass of empirical detail. There is no doubt a vast body of material — biological, psychological, and historical — which will have to be reduced to system some day; but in the meantime there is a certain justification in a work like this, which tries to fix the main outlines of a complete system of philosophy. A teacher naturally prefers his own way of putting things, even when he agrees in general with another, but perhaps the following pages, which contain the substance of lectures delivered by the author to his own students, may be of some use to students and even to teachers in other Universities. Should any of my fellow-teachers think of using this Outline in the class-room, I may mention PREFACE. Vll that in my own practice lecturing is only a part, and perhaps the least important part of the work actually done. So far as practicable, it is my habit to insist upon a first-hand study by the class of the authors I criticise. Every year's experience confirms me in the conviction which I ventured to express some years ago in the Preface to my Selections from Kant, that lectures upon authors who have not been read, have very poor educational results. In preparing this Outline I have been most indebted to Green's Prolegomena to Ethics and the criticism of Mill contained in his Philosophical Works ; to Mr. Caird's Comte and Critical Account of the Philosophy of Kant; and, in a lesser degree, to the late Professor Stanley Jevons' articles on Mill's Logic in the Conte?nporary Review. University of Queen's College, Kingston, Canada, i gth Nov., 1894. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. The Aristotelian and Platonic definitions of philosophy — These de- finitions explained — Why it is better not to define Philosophy as a "science" — Philosophy and the sciences — Mathematics from the point of view of eminent mathematicians like Riemann, Helmholtz, Clifford, and Sylvester — Mathematics as J. S. Mill views it — Explanation of Mitt's view of mathematics — ( I ) Mathe- matics not an exact science — It rests upon definitions — Which rest upon experience — No real lines, circles, etc. — Discrepancy between geometrical definitions and " sensibles " — (2) Mathe- matics not a necessary science — It rests upon induction — No accumulation of instances can warrant a must — Imagination cannot re-present what has not been presented — Experience can never warrant a conclusion wider than itself — Nothing impossible in straight lines enclosing a space, or in 2 + 3 = 6 — Apparent necessity of mathematical propositions therefore explicable on the principle of "inseparable association" — Mill's view may be put in a sentence: "Mathematics is not an exact or necessary science, but states what we have found to hold good within our limited experience, its apparent necessity being due to confusion between a necessity in the nature of things and the subjective necessity of inseparable association " — Mill's view of mathematics will be considered later — (1) The mathematician never thinks of asking Mill's question — Explanation of the mathematician's view — He has no theory of knowledge, and never asks Plato's question — CONTENTS. Mill and all philosophers have asked that question — Hence two questions : {a) What do we know about the number and magni- tude of things? {b) What is the nature of mathematical know- ledge? — (2) The absolute opposition of knowledge and the object of knowledge cannot be maintained — Mill's "round square" means that there is no absolute fixity in the quantitative relations of things — Hence we are forced to inquire into the possibility of knowing existence in its ultimate nature — If real existence cannot be known, real knowledge is impossible — Can we not show that we are capable of knowing reality as it truly is ? — This is genuine humility, though it sounds like arrogance — (3) How mathematics originated — It is not a collection of detached propositions, but an organized system. — Mill is well aware of this, and the first lesson of students is to get at Mill's point of view — Familiar illus- tration of that view — Summary: (1) Mathematics directs its attention to the objects of knowledge, philosophy to the nature of knowledge : (2) mathematics assumes that those objects are absolutely real, while philosophy inquires into the truth or false- hood of that assumption : (3) philosophy admits the internal consistency of mathematics, but refuses to admit without criticism that any of its conclusions are true of things as they are in their ultimate nature — The physical sciences assume that no change ever takes place which is not due to some cause — Illustration (taken from Mill's Logic): "A body is found to assume a crystalline form : what is the cause of the change?" — No sensible man ever did, or ever will, question so obvious a fact — Hume thought it impossible to show that there is any necessary con- nection in nature — Explanation of Hume's view of Causation — (1) Another proof (if any were needed) that there is something in Philosophy — Hume's sceptical doctrine evidently rests upon his peculiar theory of knowledge — Perhaps Locke, Hume, and even Mill may be wrong — (2) Obviously, we cannot tell what is the nature of knowledge without determining at the same time the nature of real existence — Illustration from Shakespeare's Mid- summer Night's Dream — (3) We now see that Philosophy has to examine the principles assumed by such sciences as physics and chemistry — Philosophy admits that, in whatever sense any one of the propositions which sciences contain is true, all the rest are true — Philosophy may (provisionally) be divided into — (1) Philosophy of Nature, (2) Philosophy of Mind, (3) Philosophy of God, 1 CONTENTS. XI CHAPTER II. PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. Explanation of Comte's view of the philosophical doctrine known as the Relativity of Knowledge — His "subjective" and "objective" synthesis — In simple language he means: "Man must be con- tent to gain such a limited knowledge of the world and of human life as will enable him to make use of nature for the perfecting of society" — Comte's own intellectual development is partly explained by his relation to Rousseau and the French Revolution — Sum of Rousseau's teaching: "All the evils of man are due to society, and he can reach perfection only by being freed from all restraint and allowed to follow his natural in- stincts " — Even in the economic region this form of individualism was not justified of its children — What Comte learned from St. Simon — Comte's three stages, theological, metaphysical, positive — Fetichism, Polytheism, and Monotheism — Metaphysic — Physical science — Extract from Cours de Philosophic Positive — What has been given a mere hint of the profound philosophy of Comte — His social philosophy the most valuable part of his system — Formulation of what is (unfortunately) known as Agnosticism — Our question : Is such a doctrine consistent with itself? — Ambiguity in the doctrine as expressed by Comte — (i) It some- times means for him that the only true knowledge is of laws not of causes — Illustration from the first book of the Iliad — How Lewes and Comte deal with Homer— -In his main contention Comte is right ; it is no explanation of a pestilence to say that an offended God sent it in his wrath, or that it is produced by a "poisonous principle" — But Comte does not see that this does not banish religion or even philosophy — (2) Comte also assumes that the human mind is necessarily limited to the knowledge of phenomena, and is conscious of its own limitation — The conceit of knowledge most vigorous in those who have recently learned a few elementary truths — No man ever supposed we have com- plete knowledge (we take the liberty of excluding maniacs) — The question is : Has man a knowledge only of things as to his finite mind they seem to be? — Comte's limitation of knowledge to phenomena implies two mutually exclusive realms ; think out for yourselves what this means ; Comte has not done so — Kant's remark about dogmatism and scepticism worth noting — (a) Are Xll CONTENTS. there two spheres of existence f — Surely that is nonsense — {b) After all a phenomenon is merely an appearance — Plato's 5d£a helps to illustrate Comte — Comte's doctrine implies that there are two distinct kinds of intelligence — This seems to be greater nonsense still : it at once affirms and denies the consciousness of limitation, which is self- contradictory — Comte's doctrine of the relativity of knowledge plausible because knowledge is only in its infancy — But knowledge cannot consist in adding particular to particular — Is any knowledge the apprehension of particulars? — A knowledge of mere particular is a contradiction in terms — Simple illustration from seeing a piece of sugar — We cannot perceive, or even imagine, space as a whole, but we can think it as one — Besides the particular aspect of an object there is always implied a certain universal aspect — Bearing of this simple fact on the doctrine of the relativity of knowledge — Illustration from the law of gravitation (Comte's own instance), - - - -21 CHAPTER III. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. GEOMETRY. Mathematical knowledge is the science of magnitude — It is usually sup- posed to deal with Space and Motion, though we might add Time — In that case we should have three sciences: Geometry, Kinematics, and Chronometry — Our object therefore to inquire whether geo- metry is a real science of nature — We assume space to be of three dimensions only — Mill says that geometry is not a science — (1) Ex- amination of Mitt's view of geometry— 'His view re-stated, but more in detail — Mill here takes it for granted that we have a knowledge of the actual properties of real things : he is not contrasting a reality unknown to us with a reality as we suppose it to be — Kant takes a different view, holding that to an infinite in- telligence the geometrical properties under which objects present themselves to us are seen to be unreal — Mill's view is truer than Kant's — Euclid would have been unable to understand Mill — The mathematician, while aware that points, lines, etc., are not sensible objects, does not suppose that he is dealing with mere fiction of abstraction — What are "real things?" — Mill's answer — Objections to it — (1) Our perception of the CONTENTS. Xlll position and figure of a sensible object is not derived from sensation — Yet Mill must hold that the geometrical properties of bodies are somehow given us in sensation — Perhaps a number of sensations may be so associated as to appear extended — Hume thought so — Illustration of Hume's view from the perception of the edge of a desk — Conclusion : No geometrical property of a sensible object can be derived from any number or variety of sensations, nor from any association of sensations — An "ultimate inexplicability " a mere refuge of the destitute — What is an '"object?" — We shall be helped to an answer by considering how we come to have a perception of the position of a particle of matter — If space were a sphere with a definite boundary we might locate the particle, but space has no boundary that we can perceive — Are there any purely individual particles? — In the perception of objects as in space, their mutual externality is implied — Hence it involves a peculiar intellectual form of con- sciousness — Now we are in a position to estimate the value of Mill's view of geometry — In a sense every one is an un- conscious mathematician — Geometry does not say that the edge of any object is straight — (2) Mill's denial of the accuracy of geometry has no real foundation; but perhaps the propositions of geometry are not universal and necessary — Detailed examina- tion of Mill's view — Conclusion : The nature of our consciousness is such that any experience of the enclosure of a space by two straight lines is an impossible experience— The author's own view, 43 CHAPTER IV. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE {Continued). ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA. Statement of Mill's Theory of Numbers — He has two main objects in view : (a) to show that arithmetic and algebra rest upon induc- tion from sensible observations ; (b) to prove that their supposed accuracy and precision arises from their hypothetical character — (1) Mill does not criticise the a priori view, but it might be put thus : it rests (he says) upon induction from sensible observations — The view of the "nominalists" — Mill objects that Nominalism virtually denies the theory of numbers to be based upon inditction y XIV CONTENTS. and he is right — What, then, has led the nominalist to suppose that there are no general propositions in regard to numbers? — The reason is that in arithmetical and algebraic operations we deal with symbols of sensible objects — "Ten" represents an actual fact of sensible observation — Arithmetic differs in this respect from geometry — (2) Examination of Milt's Theory of Numbers, - 76 CHAPTER V. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE (Continued). THE PHYSICAL SCIENCES. Mill seeks to distinguish the processes by which generalizations of science are reached from various logical processes confounded with them — (1) Induction not the mere registration in language of a given number of individual observations — (2) Certain mathe- matical processes not inductive — (3) Description of a set of observed phenomena not inductive — Mill's definition of an induc- tion — Examination of Mill's definition — Causation — Three kinds of laws of nature — The ground of induction is the law of causation — Definitions of a "cause" — Examination of Mill's definition of a cause as an "invariable" and "unconditional" antecedent — A cause is an unchangeable fact — Distinction drawn by Mill between permanent and changeable causes irrelevant and misleading — This introduces new problem, 86 CHAPTER VI. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE (Continued). BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. Third problem of philosophy of nature — Like Aristotle we commonly distinguish between organic and inorganic beings — The distinction is denied by two sets of thinkers: {a) those who " level down"; [b) those who " level up " — Therefore we must not assume it — Is there a biological knowledge of nature? — Spencer defines life as "the power of continuous adjustment of internal relations to external relations" — Perhaps a better definition is " the principle by which a being maintains its individuality by a continuous adaptation to CONTENTS. XV external conditions " — The individuality of a living being is dependent upon the organization of its parts, as Aristotle saw — Where there is little differentiation of organs, it is hard to say whether there is one being or several — Living beings also produce other individuals of the same general type as themselves — Appar- ently, therefore, we must apply to them a different conception, viz., final cause — Some, however, hold that the theory of develop- ment, as enunciated by Darwin, is incompatible with a teleological explanation of the world — Darwin himself assumes a line of demarcation between organic and inorganic beings — Origin of Species illustrated by Alfred Russell Wallace's instance of the rook and crow — Darwin's view is that species are not immutable — (i) Struggle for existence — (2) Principle of heredity — The doctrine extended to man by Darwin {Descent of Man) — Animals said to exhibit most, if not all, the mental and moral faculties, and even to have the rudiments of religion — Lowest races of man very little superior to higher animals — Darwin's view implies (1) a continuous development of intellectual and moral qualities from lower animals up to savages, and from savages up to civilized man ; (2) that this development may be explained by the law of natural selection — As non-scientific men, we must assume the truth of Darwinism as a scientific theory — The principle of natural selection, as Huxley shows, overthrows the old conception of design as formulated by Paley — But is it inconsistent with a philosophical conception of teleology ? — Darwinism presupposes ( 1 ) that the laws of inorganic nature are inviolable ; (2) that in each living being there is a tendency or impulse to maintain itself and to continue its species ; (3) that the variations in the several parts of the living being are consistent with the impulse to self-maintenance and race-mainten- ance — Do these assumptions not presuppose some form of tele- ology? — Darwin, as an unsophisticated scientific man, was unaware that Paley's conception of design was obsolete — Reasons for maintaining a philosophical teleology— (1) If there were no harmony between an organism and its environment, the organism could not exist at all — (2) If there was no self-maintenance and the tendency to race-maintenance, there would be no "struggle for existence " — (3) The tendency to organization implies purpose of some kind — These considerations do not prove teleology, but may show that it is not absurd, 101 XVI CONTENTS. CHAPTER VII. RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. Re-statement of Darwin's view of man in his relation to the animals — Darwin certainly light in holding that the higher animals dis- play elementary intelligence — What follows ? — Leibnitz saw phil- osophy further than Darwin — Every real thing he holds to be an individual substance or to have a unique existence of its own separating it from all other existence — All existence is discrete — The Atomists made the mistake of supposing that there are real material atoms existing in space, whereas there is no real space (or time) — The "confused" perception of monads — Leibnitz' doctrine suggests how the Darwinian conception must be com- pleted — Tyndall and Haeckel saw this — Darwin really holds two radically different views of the world without knowing it — Tendency of the letter of Darwin to abolish the distinction between intelligence and unintelligence — Rigid application of the theory of natural selection to man yields this result — (a) No freedom of knowledge —(6) Nor can there be any freedom of action — Right and Wrong names for the pleasure of approbation and the pain of disapprobation — Darwin's view implies that mental and moral qualities are free of natural characteristics, received by inheritance and called out by the reaction of the organism on the environment — Natural selection cannot explain the fact of knowledge as it exists in man — Meaning of curiosity, interest, and attention — Knowledge, even as it existed for primi- tive man implied (i) the consciousness of a distinction between the apparent and the real ; (2) the capacity of apprehending the real in virtue of intelligence — Hence the attempt to reduce knowledge to the mere flow of impressions in a subject that passively receives them, makes even the simplest knowledge un- intelligible — But we must be careful not to fall into Descartes' mistake of supposing that there are "innate conceptions" — (1) Suppose the mind to be absolutely separated from all objects, and it has no conceivable nature — Descartes saw this, hence he fell back upon the view that there are certain conceptions which the mind has by its very nature, e.g., that of God — This view untenable — To say, e.g., that a child is a pure potentiality is to use language that has no precise signification — (2) Descartes' other assumption, that there is an apprehension CONTENTS. XV11 by the mind of what is external to it, is equally inadmissible — For him there is (logically) no material world — Proof of this statement — The Cartesian doctrine of the separation of mind and matter therefore leads to the denial of all knowledge — Conclusion : Existence cannot be divided into two antithetical halves — So far as we have knowledge we are freed from any unintelligible force acting externally upon us — Final objection to the principle of natural selection as an explanation of the knowledge of man — (i) Darwin's "selfish tendency or impulse" is neither selfish nor unselfish but non-selfish — The fact is that man, grasping the law of his environment, and grasping the law of his own nature, turns the environment into the means of realizing his inchoate ideal — (2) Darwin's ** social impulses " are neither selfish nor unselfish but super-selfish — For (a) man is by his very nature social (as Aristotle says), and forms part of an organism in which the good of each is bound up with the good of all ; and therefore (b) in submitting himself to the law of reason he gains true freedom, 123 CHAPTER VIII. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. Intelligence and will develop pari passu — Apparent conflict between the idea of man and the idea of the world — Spencer says that every philosophy must assume the absolute distinction of "subject" and "object" — His view explained — The plain man accepts it as palpably true, because he does not understand it — Spencer's problem is : Granting the opposition of subject and object, how does the subject come to have a knowledge, or an apparent knowledge, of the object? — His derivation of "relation of sequence and relation of coexistence" {i.e., of time and space) — Parallelism of "feelings" and nervous, changes — Apparently simple feeling really complex — The subject thus reducible to units of feeling, the object to units of force — Objection : How can the subject apprehend the object? — Spencer answers that we do not know reality in its absolute nature — Hence we can think of matter only in terms of mind, and of mind only in terms of matter — Spencer's five propositions — All five untenable — (1) Examination of the absolute opposition of subject and object — It involves a confusion between {a) the separation and {6) the logical distinction of subject XV111 CONTENTS. and object — A subject conscious only of its own states would never become conscious of an external object — Why the separation of subject and object seems indubitable — (i) The objective world is not dependent upon anybody's knowledge — (2) It existed prior to the subject — Similarly, the subject has different properties from the object — The answer of Philosophical Idealism — {a) The supposed "separation" of the object rests upon an untenable dualism — Inorganic things are not independent of one another — Nor are organic beings — Nor can we find Mind existing inde- pendently—The objective world is therefore self-conscious — {b) Scientific evolutionists deny the identity of subject and object, because the objective world existed before the subject — But (1) this assumes that "subject" must mean this or that individual subject — (2) It really abolishes the subject — The category of "cause" falsely applied to the relation between existence as a whole and its modes — Summary of the idealistic view — Comparison of Scientific Evolutionism and Philosophical Idealism — Self- determination in knowledge — Self-determination in action — Criticism of Spencer's second proposition, that the object is for us a complex of feelings, the subject a complex of movements, - 150 CHAPTER IX. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. IDEA OF DUTY. (1) "Duty" implies an opposition of an ideal world and the actual world — (2) It also implies an opposition between a law of reason and a lazv of inclination — Why the opposition seems absolute — Analysis of desire — The contrast of the ideal and actual self not absolute — Carlyle [saw this — The Stoical conception of "reason" — How far it is true — The abstract idea of duty, and particular duties — No " natural law" in the "spiritual world " — " Renuncia- tion " not the last word of morality — No real opposition between appetite and reason — "Duty" may be defined as " The identifi- cation of the actual self with the ideal self, by a particular determin- ation of it" — Kant holds that "Duty" implies (1) an absolute law — (2) self-determination by this law — His reasons for maintaining that action done from desire is contrary to duty — Objections to the form of Kant's doctrine — His analysis of the " categorical impera- tive " — Distinguishes between (1) duties of imperfect obligation, CONTENTS. XIX and (2) duties of perfect obligation — His three formulae — Desire for pleasure involves (1) a particular object or end, (2) conceived as desirable for me, (3) which is distinguished both from the object and the subject — Kant is therefore wrong in assuming that desire for an object is desire for pleasure — Problem of morality is : What is the distinguishing characteristic of the object we ought to desire — The solution consists in each individual conceiving of himself as a member in a social organism — Historical proof of this — Strength and weakness of Kant's ethical theory, 195 CHAPTER X. MORAL PHILOSOPHY {Continued). IDEA OF FREEDOM. The problem of freedom has the same root as the problem of duty — The solution turns upon our view of "motives" — "Deter- minism" does not explain the transition from desire to action — What a "motive" really is — Meaningless to say that "the strongest motive" leads to action — There is no "liberty of indifference " — Kant's view of freedom — He holds that in willing the law of reason man is free — This would make man irre- sponsible for doing wrong — How the contrast of freedom and necessity arises. THE SUMMUM BONUM. Hedonist view of the summum bonum — Kant distinguishes between (a) the chief good and {b) the complete good — Statement of his doctrine — His "postulate" of immortality— His moral proof of the being of God — Objections to his argument for immortality — His proof of the being of God must be revised, - - - 235 CHAPTER XI. MORAL PHILOSOPHY {Continued). PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHTS. Self-realization is exhibited in the sphere of individual rights — Kantian distinction of the sphere of rights from the sphere of morals — Rights (1) belong to persons, not to things, (2) are held against all other persons, (3) are reciprocal — Rights dis- tinguished by Kant as {a) rights of property, {b) right of con- tract, {c) personal rights — The State based upon an "original XX CONTENTS. contract "—Ultimate form of the State a Republic— All class legislation wrong — Kant's view of penal justice — Basis of Inter- national law — Articles for an everlasting peace — Kant's doctrine of rights repeats his opposition of desire and reason in a new form — (i) His theory of society not self- consistent — It virtually admits that society is the basis of rights — Imperfection of his view of the family and the State — (2) Kant's opposition of law and morality untenable — (3) His view of punishment inadequate — Kant's system of moral virtues — Two ends which we ought to realize : (1) our own perfection, (2) the happiness of others — Distinction of "obligations of right" and "obligations of virtue ' — The three characteristics of duty — Duties to ourselves — Duties to others — Kant wrong in opposing these, - - - - 257 CHAPTER XII. PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. RELIGION. Kant separates Morality from Religion — His interpretation of "Original Sin " — How he treats the Pauline doctrine of Redemption — Kant's conception of evil in advance of the doctrine of the Stoics — But his doctrine must be reinterpreted — He has not got rid of Individualism — No opposition of outer and inner law — Morality not independent of Religion. ART. Art an objective presentation of the ideal — Kant distinguishes between the beautiful and the sublime — An aesthetic judgment rests upon a disinterested contemplation of beauty — The sublime due to the disharmony of the object as perceived and as conceived — Two forms of the sublime : mathematical, or that which is too great in magnitude to be pictured by the imagination ; and dynamical, or the feeling which arises in presence of the forces of nature — Beauty excludes the idea of definite purpose — The products of art a symbol of moral ideas — Value of Kant's conception of beauty — Examination of Kant's affirmations (1) that beauty rests upon feeling; (2) that it involves thought, 282 ERRATUM. Page 76, line 9 from foot, delete "not" after "do.' COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. CHAPTER I. THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. "The feeling of wonder," says Plato in his dialogue the Theaetetus, 1 "is the genuine mark of the philosopher; for philosophy has its origin in wonder; and he was no bad genealogist who said that Iris is the child of Wonder." Those who are destitute of this feeling he calls the "uninitiated," who "will not admit that there is any reality but that which they can take hold of with their hands." Philosophy, in other words, at first exists as an immediate feeling or conviction, that things in their real or ultimate nature are not what at first they seem to be. It looks beyond the shows of things to a reality that is felt to be implied, although it is not yet grasped by the mind as a definite object, the nature of which can be expressed in precise and definite language. We can say, negatively, that reality, as it is behind the veil of sense, is not that which we see with our eyes and grasp with our hands; but at first we cannot apply to it any definite 1 Theaetetus, 155 CD. A 2 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. predicates. Wonder may therefore be said to be a self- contradictory feeling. It denies that what we know is real, and yet it cannot tell us what reality is. We are conscious of our ignorance, and yet we claim to know that we have no knowledge. The man of hard common- sense, the " uninitiated" as Plato would call him, can therefore make out a very good case for his rejection of philosophy as a useless quest for what can never be known. Like Mephistopheles in Goethe's Faust, he prides himself on taking things as they are, and refusing to follow the lead of mere ideas. Plato, on the other hand, finds in the vision of the ideal the true reality. Those who are content with the first or unreflective view of things he likens to men confined within a dark under- ground cave, with a narrow opening towards the light, who see only the shadows of things thrown on the wall as they are carried past the mouth of the cave. In this con- viction of the reality of the invisible and intangible, Plato is at one with those who believe that in art and religion there is revealed something truer than all that we can directly perceive with our senses. Poetry and religion, as well as philosophy, claim that there is a contradiction between what seems and what is, and that true reality can be revealed only to the higher vision. He who is satisfied with the first or unreflective view of things need never hope to know reality as it truly is. There is a divine unrest which compels us to search for the hidden truth of things. As Aristotle says, it is in the effort to be rid of ignorance that men have been led to construct philosophies. The object of philosophy is therefore to search for the first principles of things; to discover, if that be possible, what is as distinguished from what seems THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 3 to be. Hence Aristotle well says that philosophy has to do with existence as it really is. It must be observed, however, that philosophy cannot be defined as the science of reality. For it may be that :he ultimate nature of reality cannot be discovered by man. As a matter of fact there is at the present time an influential class of thinkers who hold that man is so constituted that he never can have a knowledge of ulti- mate reality. Human knowledge, they maintain, never reaches beyond phenomena or appearances. Much may be learned about the nature of phenomena, but nothing about the reality which lies behind phenomena. Carry your investigation to the extreme limits of the phenomenal world; lay bare the laws which govern the minutest and the most distant object accessible to our observation, even when it is aided by the most delicate instruments, and you are as far as ever from the ultimate nature of things. The progress of human knowledge does not enable us to break through the charmed circle within which we are compelled to move, but only serves to bring into bolder relief the great unknowable reality against which the bounded circumference of the known world becomes visible. I hope to show that this doc- trine of the unknowability of ultimate reality cannot be accepted, but manifestly we cannot, in the face of such a denia], assume that reality as it truly is can be known by man. If it can be established that philosophy leads to the knowledge of ultimate reality, we may then define it as the science of first principles ; but, in the meantime, we must be content to say, that it is the search for first principles. To understand all that is implied in this definition we 4 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. must make clear to ourselves the distinction between philosophy and other branches of human knowledge, and especially between philosophy and science. None of the sciences seems to rest on so firm a foundation as the science of mathematics. That 2 + 2 = 4 ; that the straight line between two points is the shortest that can be drawn ; that the interior angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles : such propositions as these are usually assumed to be absolutely true and to admit of no possible exception. The mathematician is therefore accustomed to assume that the propositions of his science are demonstrably true, and that no con- ceivable advance of knowledge can ever upset them. He does not speak with stammering tongue, as Aristotle says of the early Greek philosophers, but announces his results with perfect assurance of their truth. And yet there is a question which mathematics has not raised, and without resolving which the absolute truth of its conclusions cannot be established. It is assumed by the mathematician that the objects which we number and measure could not be of an entirely different nature from what they are for us. When it is said that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points, it is taken for granted that every possible space must be, like ours, of three dimensions and absolutely devoid of curvature. It is further assumed that what is affirmed of lines, triangles, and circles in the abstract is equally true of real lines, triangles, and circles. Now both of these propositions have been denied. It is maintained by such eminent mathematicians as Riemann, Helmholtz, Clifford, and Sylvester, that our space of three dimensions is only one of an infinite number of possible spaces, and that, THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 5 were our experience wider, we should find that our Euclidian geometry is of very limited and partial applica- tion. It is further maintained by so eminent a thinker as John Stuart Mill, that the propositions of arithmetic and geometry are not absolutely true even in their application to the sensible reality which we are capable of knowing. The only source of our knowledge, it is held, is experience. No real knowledge can be obtained from the mere exercise of our own minds. To get at reality at all we must go to experience. But experience can never assure us that what has presented itself to us in a certain way might not possibly appear in an entirely different form. Hence, mathematics, if it is a science at all, must rest upon the facts of experience. Let us see the conclusion to which this doctrine of Mill naturally leads. In the first place, Mill maintains that the supposed exactness and necessity of mathematics is a delusion. (1) Mathematics is not an exact science. What is the foundation of the science of geometry? Plainly the so- called definitions. But upon what do these definitions themselves rest? They cannot be self-evident, because all that a definition can tell us is the meaning attached to certain terms. Definitions are purely verbal, and prove nothing in regard to the reality of that which is defined. I may define a centaur as a being half man and half horse, but it does not follow that a centaur exists in rerum natura. Similarly, I may define a circle as a figure the radii of which are all equal, but it does not follow that a real circle corresponding to my definition actually exists. To determine whether the definitions of geometry are true or false we must have recourse to experience. Now, when 6 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. we go to experience, we find that there are no real things corresponding to our definitions. Where in nature shall we find a point without magnitude, a line that is perfectly straight and without breadth, a circle with all its radii exactly equal, a square with all its angles perfectly right ? An actual sensible point is a surface, a real line is the edge of a sensible object, and such a line is never per- fectly straight; the surface of a thing is always more or less uneven. There is no doubt that geometry deals with real things, but the discrepancy between its definitions and sensible realities shows that it is not dealing with those things as they truly are, but only with a partial aspect of them. We are therefore compelled to conclude that geometry is r not an exact science. (2) Nor is geometry a necessary science. Like other sciences it rests upon induction, or, in other words, it states in a general form what experience has shown us to hold good in a number of particular instances. No accumulation of such instances can warrant us in saying that things must be as our experience has shown them to be. It is true that geometry draws its conclusions from figures that are not directly perceived, but are only represented in imagina- tion. But imagination can never represent what has not been presented beforehand in perception. When I have once perceived two straight lines meet and then diverge, I can imagine them diverging as far as I please, but I can never imagine them as again meeting. It is this peculiarity of our imaginative faculty which explains the apparent necessity of geometrical propositions. We are unable to imagine diverging lines as meeting, however far we may prolong them, because our whole experience contradicts the supposition. We have at one time seen THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 7 two straight lines diverging from a point, and at another time we have seen two straight lines converging, but we have never seen two straight lines at once diverging and converging. The supposition is excluded from the nature of our experience. But it must be carefully observed, that experience can never warrant a conclusion wider than itself. There is nothing impossible in the supposi- tion that two straight lines should enclose a space. The supposition is contrary to our experience, but it cannot be shown to be contradictory of the nature of things. There is nothing contradictory in the notion that 2 + 3 = 6. Were our experience wider we might meet with objects of a different nature from those with which we have come in contact. Hence, in the second place, Mill ex- plains the apparent necessity of mathematical propositions on the principle of inseparable association. All that is meant by the term "inseparable association" is, that two ideas which have always gone together in our experience become so closely united that, having no contrary experi- ence, we cannot conceive of them as separated. Such ideas are those which are combined in a mathematical proposition. Their apparent necessity is merely the sub- jective necessity of uniform association. Ideas that have never been experienced apart we naturally suppose to be inseparable in nature as they are in our experience. An instance of inseparable association we have in the pro- position that two straight lines cannot be thought of as enclosing a space. We cannot say that two straight lines cannot enclose a space, but only that we cannot think of them as enclosing a space. The only reason we have for our affirmation is that we have had no experience of straight lines enclosing a space, which is a very different 8 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. thing from saying that such an experience is impos- sible. The general conclusion, then, is that mathematics is not an exact or necessary science, but merely expresses what we have found to hold good within our limited experience, its apparent necessity being due to the natural confusion between a necessity in the nature of things and the sub- I jective necessity of inseparable association. An examination of Mill's doctrine of mathematics cannot be profitably entered upon at present. In the meantime we may learn from it something about the relations of philosophy and science, (i) The first thing to be noted is, that the question which Mill asks is one which the mathematician as such does not think of asking. The mathematician usually assumes that the conclusions \\ which he reaches are absolutely true, and can be applied J in the numbering and measuring of any object that can 1 ever come within the range of his experience. His assumption, stated generally, is, that we can have a real knowledge of the number and magnitude of things. It is true that a mathematician may be aware that there is a further problem which he has not investigated, but it is at least convenient, and conduces to clearness, if we say that mathematics assumes the possibility of real know- ledge, leaving to philosophy the task of inquiring into the possibility and the conditions of knowledge. The science of mathematics, then, as we may say, puts for- ward no theory in regard to the nature of knowledge. Whether its propositions apply only within the limited range of objects as they appear to man, or hold good of all possible objects, is for the mere mathematician a matter of indifference. The question, What is know- THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 9 ledge? either has never occurred to him, or he sets it aside as irrelevant to his special investigation. He may be said to be in the attitude of the youthful Theaetetus, in the dialogue of Plato to which I have already referred, who, when asked by Socrates, What is Knowledge ? answers that "Knowledge consists of all the things we can learn from Theodorus ; geometry for instance." Mill, on the other hand, and the same thing is true of all philosophers, has become aware that the true meaning of Socrates' question is, What is implied in the act of knowledge? What constitutes knowledge? In seeking to answer this question, Mill is led, like the Greek Pro- tagoras, as represented by Plato, to say that " Knowledge is sensible perception." We may say, then, that mathe- matics seeks to answer the question, What do we know about the number and magnitude of things? while philosophy tries to answer the question, What is the nature of mathematical knowledge? Let us call the first problem scientific and the second philosophic. It would then seem that science directs its attention to the objects of knowledge, philosophy to the nature of knowledge itself. (2) This seems to give us a clear distinction between science and philosophy. But on closer investi- gation we find that" the absolute opposition of knowledge and the object of knowledge is one that cannot be maintained. If Mill is right, we must distinguish between the objects with which mathematics deals, and those objects which lie beyond the range of possible experience, or rather, those objects which perhaps lie beyond that range. For it is held that a time might come when the whole fabric of our present mathematical knowledge would be completely upset. We cannot tell, on Mill's theory, (h IO COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. what a day or an hour might bring forth. Suddenly our experience might completely change its complexion, and diverging lines might be found to enclose a space, parallel lines might meet, squares might appear round, and straight lines curved. " To conceive a round square," says Mill, " would only be to conceive two different sensations as produced in us simultaneously by the same object; and we should probably be as well able to conceive a round square as a hard square, or a heavy square, if it were not that, in our uniform experience, at the instant when a thing begins to be round it ceases to be square, so that the beginning of the one impression is inseparably associated with the departure or cessation of the other." 1 It is here implied that there is no absolute fixity in the quantitative relations of things. Now this means that there are infinite possibilities of experience such as we cannot even imagine with any definiteness. A world in which all our mathematical conceptions were completely reversed is so different from anything we can figure to ourselves, that we can only say, generally, that it would be totally unlike anything of which we have had experi- ence. The question is therefore forced upon us, whether we can admit even the possibility of such a world. So long as we admit its possibility, it is plain that we cannot claim to have any knowledge of things as they truly are. Now this conclusion is so contrary to what mathematics and other sciences are accustomed to assume, that we simply must inquire into the possibility of knowing existence in its ultimate nature. The nature of know- ledge is thus bound up with the nature of existence. If real existence cannot be known, real knowledge is im- 1 Mill's Examination of Hamilton, ch. vi., p. 68. T I I. Xt 77 THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. II possible. Philosophy, therefore, must seek to determine the relations of knowledge and existence. If it could be shown that Mill's theory of knowledge is false, there would be some presumption that his tacit denial of the knowability of real existence is also false. But there is no other way of coming to a satisfactory conclusion on the question, than by entering into a thorough investiga- tion of the relations of knowledge and reality. It is vain to say that we cannot help believing in the reality of knowledge. That is true enough, but many things that men have firmly believed have turned out to be mere prejudices. There is no possible way of satisfying doubt but by facing it. To dismiss a problem without inquiry leaves in the mind an uneasy consciousness that the sceptic may after all be right. Philosophy, just because it seeks to determine the ultimate nature of things, can never be satisfied with anything short of truth that may be verified by the unbiased exercise of reason. Now if we could only show, by an inquiry into the relations of knowledge and existence, that we are capable of knowing reality as it truly is, or, in other words, that in whatever sense mathematics is true of any existence it is true of all possible existence, the sceptical conclusion of Mill would be proved untrue. It cannot be denied that at first sight there seem to be insuperable difficulties in the way of such a proof. To say that man can, so to speak, contemplate existence from the point of view of omniscience seems to be the extreme of presumption. It must be observed, however, that it is not less pre- sumptuous to say that man cannot know things as they really are. For how can any one say that we do not know real existence unless he has some knowledge of I 12 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. what real existence is? Presumptuous or not, philosophy cannot avoid the question : Is the knowledge of real existence possible? Thus the inquiry into the nature of knowledge is necessarily bound up with the inquiry into the nature of existence. (3) We may now see, in some degree, how philosophy is related to the science of mathe- matics. It is the nature of the human mind to pass from one stage of activity to another. The science of mathematics had its origin in the desire to determine with accuracy the number and magnitude of objects in space and time. In a very gradual way more and more perfect methods of measurement have been discovered, until mathematics has now reached the dimensions of a vast body of closely connected propositions. There is no manner of doubt that all those propositions hang closely together, and that to deny any one of them is to deny them all. The science of mathematics, in other words, is not a collection of detached propositions, but an organized system in which every part is connected with and dependent upon every other part. Now you will observe that Mill does not in any way question the coherence of mathematical propositions among themselves. If a mathematician advances a new proposition, it is open to another mathematician to say that it is untrue, on the ground that it is inconsistent with what has been already established, or that there is some flaw in the reasoning by which it is sought to be proved. But this is quite a different class of objection from that which Mill makes when he denies the accuracy and necessity of mathematics. Mill not only grants the internal co- herence and organic unity of the whole body of mathe- matics, but his argument expressly appeals to its internal THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 13 coherence and unity. Geometry, as he points out, is a science only if its definitions are true, because all its other propositions rest upon and presuppose the truth of those definitions. Mill's objection is not to the inner consistency of mathematics, but to its claim to formulate the relations of all possible existence. If it is true at all, all its propositions are true; if it is false at all, all its propositions are false. The truth or falsehood of mathematics is thus established, so to speak, at one stroke. Now, we may learn from this what is the relation of philosophy to mathematics. The mathematician, in Mill's view, is like a man who starts on a journey with no other end in view but to see what objects of interest may be found by the way. Every step he takes brings him in sight of a new object, and he goes on continually adding to what he calls his knowledge. By and by some one suggests that the objects in which he has been so interested, and which he has been at so much pains to observe and systematize, are due to an illusion of his own senses, and have no other reality than for himself and those like himself. This is a new point of view, and one which, once presented, cannot well be dismissed without inquiry. The mathematician may indeed say, that whether the objects on which he has expended so much labour are realities or illusions, it is worth while finding out their nature. Illusions they may be, but there is a wonderful coherence in them. But, granting this, he can never take quite the same view of them as before. His implicit faith in their reality has been shaken. He is doubtful whether they are realities or only appearances. Philosophy, then, does not deny 14 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. the reality of mathematics so far as phenomena are con- cerned, but it raises the question, whether the laws of phenomena are also laws of things as they truly are. Mathematics hands over this latter question to philosophy, and hence by the decision of philosophy its ultimate value must be determined. On the supposition that a single proposition of mathematics holds good of real existence, the whole body of mathematics holds good of it: if a single proposition is true only of apparent existence, the same thing must be said of the science as a whole. We see, then, that the truth of a special science can only mean, prior to the philosophical criticism of its founda- tion, that it is perfectly coherent within itself. Perfectly coherent it may be, however, while yet it rests upon an assumption that has never been justified. It is this assumption that philosophy has to investigate, not the truth of the individual propositions which rest upon it. If philosophy can only show that what mathematics has assumed as self-evident may be justified before the bar of reason, the whole body of mathematics will then rise to the dignity of demonstrated truth. If philosophy fails to justify that assumption, we shall have to conclude that mathematics is at the most merely an account of the relations which we have found to hold good of objects within our limited experience. Whatever conclusion we may reach, this is evident, that philosophy presents us with a problem which we cannot evade without mental unrest and disquiet. We have found then, firstly, that mathematics directs its attention to the objects of knowledge, philosophy to the nature of knowledge itself; secondly, that mathematics assumes that those objects are absolutely real, while philo- THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 15 sophy inquires into the truth or falsehood of that assump- tion ; and, thirdly, that philosophy admits the internal consistency of mathematics, but refuses to admit without criticism that any of its conclusions are true of things as they are in their ultimate nature. Let us now see whether philosophy bears a similar or a different relation to the other special sciences. It will be admitted that those sciences assume that no change ever takes place which is not due to some cause- A body, for instance, is found to assume a crystalline form, and the question at once arises as to the cause of the change. As the change never occurs except in the case of the solidification of a substance from a liquid state, we conclude that such solidification is the cause of the crystal- lization. And even in those instances in which we are unable to assign the cause, we feel quite sure that the event has not occurred without a cause. So much is this the case that, were we to find instances in which crystal- lization occurs when a substance was not previously in a liquid state, we should not think of saying that the change arose without any cause, but only that we had not yet found out the cause. The assumption, therefore, which lies at the foundation of all scientific discovery is that the changes which occur in nature do not occur at random, but are connected together in fixed ways. Given the cause, and the effect must follow. As we have found, however, that Mill denies what seems to be the even stronger necessity of mathematical truth, it is not surpris- ing that the assumed connection of events has also been denied. According to Hume it is impossible to show that there is any necessary connection in nature. The only warrant we can produce for our belief that events could 1 1 6 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. not be connected otherwise than as we have found them to be connected, is the fact that in our experience we have always found them to occur in a certain order. Because heat and flame have presented themselves to- gether in our observation, we naturally come to imagine that the one could not occur without the other. It is true that we have never found flame that was not associated with heat, but that does not entitle us to say that they might not be separated. No number of observations can ever rise to the dignity of a necessary law. There is nothing to show that any two events which have been connected in our experience nine hundred and ninety- nine times, should not on the thousandth time be found to be totally unconnected. The reason why we suppose events to be necessarily connected may be explained by the fact that any two ideas which have frequently occurred together or in close succession are naturally supposed to imply an objective connection of events. It is a law of the human mind to expect the recurrence of that which has frequently occurred. Hence when an impression or idea arises in our mind, we naturally pass to the idea which has been often found associated with it. The con- nection of ideas, however, does not prove any necessary connection of events. The supposed connection of events is in reality the subjective connection of habit. Thus Hume completely inverts the ordinary conception of causality. He attributes the connection to the ob- serving subject, not to the observed object. No event is really connected with another, but the transition from one idea to another frequently associated with it is so easy and natural that we are irresistibly led to THE PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY. 1 7 suppose a real connection where none can be shown to exist. Now (i) the doubt which Hume casts upon the real connection of events, like the similar doubt of the neces- sary truth of mathematics, makes it imperative on us to inquire into the nature of knowledge. The ordinary belief, that all changes are due to something in the nature of things, can no longer be assumed without question. If what we have been wont to regard as a law of things should turn out to be a mere fiction of our own minds, we shall be compelled to alter our whole view of the character of the special sciences. So complete a reversal of our common beliefs cannot be allowed to pass without the severest scrutiny. Hume's sceptical doctrine in regard to causality evidently rests upon his peculiar theory of knowledge. Like his follower Mill, and his master Locke, he holds that what we know of nature must come to us in the form of sensible impressions. It may be, however, that this is a false, or, at least, an imperfect account of the origin of knowledge, and that the denial of the real con- nection of things is incompatible with the nature of know- ledge as properly understood. Be this as it may, a searching inquiry into the nature of knowledge is absol- utely indispensable. The belief in causal connection, which all the special sciences assume without misgiving, must be either confirmed or rejected. Here again, there- fore, we find that, whereas science limits itself to objects, philosophy investigates the nature of knowledge. (2) It lies on the very face of Hume's denial of the real con- nection of objects and events, that we cannot tell what is the nature of knowledge without determining at the same time the nature of real existence. If Hume is B 1 8 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. right, we must suppose that what we call the course of nature is a perfectly arbitrary succession of events. On his view there is no reason why any event might not be followed by any other event, and therefore no reason why at any moment the whole world of objects might not literally " dissolve, And, like an insubstantial pageant faded, Leave not a rack behind." The rays of the sun might suddenly freeze water instead of vaporizing it, and the breath of the north wind set the world on fire. We have no other guarantee of what will be but a fancy of our own, which rests upon a confusion between the customary and the neces- sary. Hume's doctrine is therefore at bottom a denial of all law. There is no limit to the variability of nature but the possible combinations of particular events. What we call laws of nature are merely the accidental juxta- position of events. A theory of knowledge which reduces the apparent connection of events to a "fortuitous con- course" of disconnected particulars is not to be lightly accepted. It compels us to ask whether the world is destitute of internal coherency and system, as Hume would have us believe. Thus the inquiry into the nature of knowledge is once more found to be connected in the closest possible way with the inquiry into the nature of existence as a whole. (3) We may now see that philo- sophy has to examine the principles assumed by such sciences as physics and chemistry, just as it has to examine into the assumed necessity of mathematical truth. Those sciences, taking for granted the principle that every change must have a cause, go on to ask what f THE PROBLEM OF FHJ-fcOSOPHY. 19 are the partic ular causes whion account for and necessi- tate^ th"e multifarious changes that occur in nature. Philosophy, on the other hand, asks in what sense we can speak of causal connection at all. Thus, while the special sciences are occupied with particular modes of existence, philosophy deals with the relations of these modes to existence as a whole. Should the final result of philosophy be to confirm Hume's view of causality, the assumed unity and systematic connection of nature could only be explained as a disconnected assemblage of objects and events. In any case, it is the task of philosophy to examine into the fundamental principles on which the special sciences are supposed to rest. Philosophy does not, any more than in regard to the propositions of mathematics, deny the inner harmony of the special sciences. It admits that, in whatever sense any one of the propositions which they contain is true, all the rest are true ; but it sets itself to inquire whether any of them has more than a relative value. On the result of this inquiry it depends whether we can, in any proper sense, speak of science at all. We have seen that philosophy bears the same general relation to the other sciences which it bears to mathe- matics, and we may now sum up the results to which we have been brought in three propositions. Firstly, science deals with objects as such, philosophy with the knowledge of objects. Secondly, science assumes that real knowledge is possible, philosophy inquires into the 1 | Ml truth of that assumption. Thirdly, science deals with the relations of objects to one another, philosophy with their relations to existence as a whole. More shortly, science treats of modes of existence, philosophy of 20 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. existence in its completeness. And as existence may roughly be divided into the three great related spheres of Nature, Mind, and God (whatever these may ulti- mately be found to mean), there are three main divisions of philosophy : (i) Philosophy of Nature ; (2) Philosophy of Mind; (3) Philosophy of the Absolute. CHAPTER II. PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. Now, it might seem that, having denned the problem of philosophy, and indicated its three great departments, our next step would be to take up each of those de- partments in turn. But, as we have seen, there are eminent thinkers, who, either expressly or by implication, maintain' that man is by the very nature of his faculties for ever incapable of knowing reality as it ultimately is ; and it is therefore advisable to begin by asking whether this sceptical attitude in regard to the object of philo- sophy has any rational foundation, or whether it does not rather rest upon an untenable assumption. Perhaps the simplest way of approaching this problem will be to examine it in the form in which it is presented by Comte. The fundamental idea which underlies the doctrine of Comte is, that all attempts to obtain an "absolute" view of existence are necessarily futile. This Comte expresses by saying that, while we are capable of a "subjective synthesis " of existence, we are by the necessary limitation of our knowledge incapable of an "objective synthesis." Some explanation of these terms will be necessary. Comte here uses the term "subjective" in the sense of 2 2 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. "limited" or "human"; and with this he contrasts an "objective synthesis," as one in which things would be looked at from the point of view of absolutely complete knowledge. What he contends, therefore, is that man must be content to gain such a limited knowledge of the world and of human life as will enable him to make use of nature, simply for the perfecting of society. Thus Comte would turn our thoughts away from all specula- tions upon the ultimate meaning of existence, and con- centrate them upon the good of humanity. For we find, as he maintains, a tendency to organization in humanity itself, and the aim of the individual is to live a higher life by seeking more and more to make himself instru- mental in advancing the good of the race. This is the main idea in the philosophy of Comte, but it will be profitable to consider more in detail the process by which it is reached. The starting-point in Comte's own intellectual develop- ment was his conviction of the falsehood of pure indi- vidualism, as preached by Rousseau and written in letters of blood on the French Revolution. The sum of Rousseau's teaching was that all the evils of man are due to society, and that he can reach perfection only by being freed from all restraint and allowed to follow his natural instincts. This doctrine of pure individualism was not justified of its children. Freedom from social restraint had not brought liberty but licence. Even in the economic region, the result was a fierce fight of individuals with one another, in which the stronger and more crafty worsted the weaker and less cunning. It was therefore natural that an attempt should be made to find a solution of the problem in a reconstruction of the fabric of society. One of the leaders PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. 23 of this movement was St. Simon, who saw the essential weakness of the gospel according to Jean Jacques Rousseau, and tried to substitute for it a new gospel resting upon a socialistic foundation. The great problem of modern times, he held, was the combination of men with one another as a means of turning nature to the use of all. The physical as well as the intellectual and moral advance- ment of all the members of society ought to be aimed at, and especially the elevation of the poorer and weaker members of society. Liberty he regards not as valuable in itself, but only in so far as it is the means of a better form of social organization. The weakness of St. Simon is that, to secure this higher form of society, he would institute a social despotism that would sacrifice men's free intellectual and moral development in order to make them comfortable. Now Comte, in his youth, was an ardent disciple of St. Simon, and from him he learned two things : (i) he came to see the essential weakness of pure individualism ; and (2) he was led to seek for a solution of the social problem in the idea of society as an organism. The problem as it presented itself to his mind took this form : How can the organization of society be preserved, while yet the individual is not crushed by the despotic rule of the more cultured members of the state ? And his answer was, that by the development of science, which is secured by the individual, and yet is the product not of caprice but of reason, there may be discovered the best means of securing the highest happiness of humanity. The whole history of man is regarded by Comte as the history of association by means of positive science. Man in his primitive state has two opposite tendencies, — the 24 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. tendency to sociality and the tendency to individualism. The social instinct is at first weak, yet its triumph over the personal or selfish instinct is essential to the welfare and even the existence of humanity. Feeling rather than understanding this truth, the first leaders of mankind grasped at a mode of explaining the universe which had at least the merit of strengthening the social bond. Thus arose what Comte calls the theological stage of human development. Nature was supposed to be ruled by a number of supernatural beings. Such a mode of explana- tion was doomed to destruction. As men came to see more and more clearly that the world is governed by law, the gods were removed to a greater and greater distance, — Polytheism arose out of Fetichism, and Monotheism out of Polytheism. What at first seems but the gradual puri- fication of theology is regarded by Comte as really a preparation for its final overthrow. The substitution of a limited for an indefinite number of arbitrary wills, and of one will for a limited number, were but steps in the pro- cess by which all interference of supernatural agents was denied. The work of dethronement was continued by metaphysic. In this stage of development phenomena are explained, not by the arbitrary volitions of divine beings, but by abstract powers or essences, supposed to lie behind phe- nomena. These powers or essences were in reality but the ghosts of the vanished gods ; in other words, the truth of the metaphysical era consisted in its negatio?i of theology, not in any positive reconstruction of its own. The final triumph of metaphysic was in the reduction of the various powers of nature to the one abstraction of nature itself. This is a great advance, but its fundamental weakness is PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. 25 that it still supposes nature to be something lying behind phenomena, and distinct from them. The third stage in the development of humanity is the positive or scientific, in which man has at last come to see that for him the only realities are neither supernatural beings nor metaphysical abstractions, but the laws of the resemblance, the co-existence, and the succession of phe- nomena as these are revealed by positive science. Now, the extreme degree of specialization which the sciences have now reached makes it necessary to reduce them to a system ; in no other way is it possible to turn the vast accumulation of facts to account for the furtherance of human welfare. This done, social benevolence will rest upon the secure foundation of scientific truth. The secret of the universe can be no further read than is necessary for the development of humanity, but man can give unity to his transitory existence by mastering the laws of phenomena, and especially the laws of his own nature and his immediate environment. To this task let him devote all his powers, abandoning for ever the useless and worse than useless task of prying into the unfathom- able mystery of the great universe. In illustration of this hurried sketch of Comte's law of the three stages, I may quote a few passages from the introductory lecture of his Cours de Philosophie Positive. " I believe," says Comte, " that I have discovered the law of development exhibited by the human intelligence in its diverse spheres of activity, — a law which can be shown to rest upon a solid foundation by considerations drawn from the nature of our organization, and which is capable of being verified by a careful scrutiny of the past. The law is this : that each of our main conceptions, each 26 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. branch of knowledge, passes in succession through three distinct stages, — the theological or imaginative stage, the metaphysical or abstract, and the scientific or positive. In other words, the mind of man, by its very nature, em- ploys one after the other, in each of its inquiries, three methods of explanation, the essential character of which is not only different but radically distinct : first, the theo- logical method ; next, the metaphysical ; and lastly, the positive. Hence arise three mutually exclusive types of philosophy, or general systems, in regard to the totality of phenomena. The first yields the necessary starting-point of human intelligence ; the third, its fixed goal ; the second simply serves as a means of transition from the one to the other. " In the theological stage, the human mind seeks to discover the inner nature of things, the first and the final causes of all the effects which strike the senses ; in short, it aims at absolute knowledge, and regards phenomena as due to the direct and continuous activity of supernatural beings, more or less numerous, whose arbitrary interven- tion explains all the apparent anomalies of the universe. " In the metaphysical stage, which is at bottom merely a modification of the theological, for supernatural agents are substituted abstract forces, entities, or personified ab- stractions supposed to be inherent in different classes of things, and to be capable of producing by themselves all the phenomena that we observe. The mode of explana- tion at this stage, therefore, consists in assigning for each class a correspondent entity. "Lastly, in the positive stage, the human mind, recog- nizing the impossibility of gaining absolute conceptions of things, gives up the search after the origin and destiny PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. 27 of the universe and the inner causes of phenomena, and limits itself to the task of finding out, by means of experience combined with reflection and observation, the laws of phenomena, i.e., their invariable relations of similarity and succession. The explanation of facts, re- duced to its simplest terms, is now regarded as simply the connection which subsists between diverse particular phenomena and certain general facts, the number of which is continually reduced with the progress of science. " The theological reaches its greatest perfection when it substitutes the providential action of a single Being for the numerous independent divinities imagined to be at work in primitive times. Similarly, the highest point reached by the metaphysical system consists in con- ceiving, instead of a number of particular entities, a single great entity, called Nature, which is viewed as the sole source of all phenomena. So also, the perfection of the positive system, a perfection towards which it continually tends, but which it is highly probable it will never quite reach, would consist in being able to represent all observed phenomena as particular instances of a single gene ral fact, such as, say, the fa ct of gravitation. " We thus see that the essential character of positive philosophy is to regard all phenomena as subject t o in- variable laws. The aim of all its efforts is the precise discovery of such laws, and the reduction of them to the least possible number. What is called causes — whether these are first causes or final causes — are absolutely inaccessible, and the search for them is a vain search. Everyone knows, in fact, that in positive explanations, even the most perfect, we do not in any way pretend to exhibit the productive causes of phenomena, but only to 28 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. analyze with precision the circumstances of their produc- tion, and to connect them with one another by fixed relations of similarity and succession. " Thus, we say that the general phenomena of the universe are explained^ so far as that is possible, by the Newtonian law of gravitation, because, on the one hand, this theory shows the immense variety of astronomical facts to be the very same fact looked at from different points of view, viz., the constant tendency of all the molecules of matter towards one another in direct pro- portion to their mass, and in inverse proportion to the squares of their distances ; while, on the other hand, this general fact is presented simply as the extension of a phenomenon with which we are all familiar, and which by that very fact we regard as thoroughly known, I mean the weight of bodies at the surface of the earth. But what attraction and weight are in themselves we cannot possibly tell ; such questions do not belong to the domain of positive philosophy, and must be relegated to the imagination of the theologian or the subtlety of the metaphysician." You must not take what has been said as a complete statement of the philosophy of Comte, but only or chiefly of that philosophy on its negative side. Comte's social philosophy, which is the most valuable part of his system, I have purposely passed over as foreign to our present subject. Now here we have a formulation of the main principle of Agnosticism — the unknowability of any reality beyond phenomena and their laws — a principle which is endorsed by many who would not accept his social philosophy. Our question therefore is, whether Comte and all who accept the general agnostic position are PHILOSOPHY OF AUGUSTE COMTE. 29 justified in denying to man all knowledge of the Abso- lute. Is such a doctrine consistent with itself? Is it tenable? Can we limit ourselves in our inquiries to what goes on upon this "bank and shoal of time," shutting our eyes to all that may lie beyond it? We must begin by pointing out an ambiguity in the doctrine of the Relativity of Knowledge, as expressed by Comte, — an ambiguity of which he was not himself clearly conscious, (i) In the first place, the doctrine sometimes means for him that the only true knowledge is of laws, not of causes. "What is called causes," he says in the passage quoted, "whether these are first or final causes, are absolutely inaccessible, and the search for them is a vain search." What Comte has here before his mind mainly is, that theology and metaphysics have, in his estimation, given a wrong explanation of the facts of nature. Homer, e.g., tells us that Apollo [3rj 8e kclt' OvXvfxwoio Kaprjpcov xwo/xevos Krjp, t6£ CbfJ.oi.cnv ^x wpi dfx
., it sets aside for its purpose all other aspects of the real world except its numerical aspect. Hence the science of number never deals with the concrete objects of perception as concrete ; it does not deal with pebbles and boxes as pebbles and boxes, but only with these in so far as they are identical, i.e., as discrete units capable of being discriminated from each other, and therefore of being counted. If the objection is raised, that the science of number must deal with real things or it will be no science, but a mere fiction, the answer is that no science deals with real things in their completeness, but only with real aspects of real things, and that number is therefore a science in the same sense as other sciences. Mill's mistake is in assuming that number must deal either with sensibles or with mere PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — ARITHMETIC. 83 abstractions, whereas it really deals with the sensible as abstract, i.e., with an abstract but real element of existence. If we bear this in mind, we shall have no difficulty in seeing that number does not rest upon induction, in Mill's sense of the word. On his view, we must suppose that we have a number of particular observations of sensible things as numerable, and then infer that all sensible things are numerable. For induction, as he explains it, is the process of inference by which we pass from some to all. If this were a true account of the nature of induc- tion, every general proposition would be based upon a pure assumption, which admits of no possible justification. For how can we legitimately conclude that all possible sensible things are numerable if our data give us only some sensible things ? Mill, therefore, if he were consistent, would limit himself to particular numerical propositions, and deny that there are any true general propositions, i.e., he would take the same view as the nominalists. This may be shown in another way, if we consider his admission that 2 + 1 might make 4 in another planet, for this startling conclusion is just the legitimate inference from his doctrine that all general propositions are in- ferences from particular propositions. Here, in fact, he tacitly admits that beyond those particular propositions we have no right to go, and that general propositions are due merely to the illegitimate extension of particular pro- positions under the influence of association. Mill's doctrine, then, that number rests upon induction from particular propositions cannot be accepted. The true view is, that in the simplest numerical judgment the universal judgment is already implied. For since dis- crimination is presupposed in even the simplest and most 84 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. elementary consciousness as its necessary condition, num- ber is implicit in every act of consciousness. In other words, we can give no explanation of consciousness at all, and therefore no explanation of a particular numerical judgment, unless we admit that every distinguishable element of consciousness is numerable. The numerical relation of things is therefore shown to be absolutely necessary, because without it there would be no conscious- ness at all. It is, in other words, a fixed and unchange- able relation of every possible element of reality that each element is not identical with any other element of reality, i.e., that it must be counted as a unit among other units. In numerical judgments, then, we do not pass from some to all, but in each judgment all is implied. (2) After what has been said, we need not spend much time upon Mill's second point, viz., that the theory of number rests upon a hypothesis which is not strictly true. The hypothesis is, that each unit is the same as every other, whereas it is impossible to find in nature any two units exactly the same. The whole force of this reasoning evidently rests upon the assumption, that the science of number can be a real science only if its judgments are derived from sensible things. But if, as we have main- tained, its aim is to state what holds good of all things only in so far as they are looked at from the point of view of discrete magnitude, the fact that any given object differs in its size or in its weight cannot in any way affect the absoluteness of the science of number. And not only so, but no difference in the size or weight of a particular object could be discerned, unless we presupposed the absoluteness of quantitative relations. We could not possibly tell that one pound or one mile was not equal PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — ARITHMETIC. 85 to another pound or another mile, unless the standard of measurement were absolute. There is therefore no hypothetical element in the mathematical sciences, unless we falsely assume that these sciences formulate the complete nature of things. Viewed as expressing certain unchange- able relations which are presupposed in all our knowledge of real things, mathematics is not a hypothetical but a necessary science. I */ CHAPTER V. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE (Continued). THE PHYSICAL SCIENCES. INDUCTION. We have seen that, according to Mill, mathematics rests upon sensible observation ; and we naturally expect to find him giving the same explanation of the foundation of other sciences. But first of all he seeks to distinguish the in- ductive process by which the generalizations of science are reached from various logical processes which are often confounded with it. In the first place, induction is not the mere registration in language of a given number of individual observations. No single observation, and no number of single observations, is an induction, because here there is no inference from the known to the unknown. f The observation, that the moon shines by the sun's light, no one would call an induction ; nor can there be any induction in the successive observations that Mars, Neptune, Saturn, and the other planets each shine by tfye sun's light. And if we collect all these separate observations in the proposition, that "all the planets shine by the sun's light," we are merely recalling what we already know, not advancing to any new truth. In the second PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 87 place, there are certain mathematical propositions which are improperly called inductions ; as, for instance, the proposition that a straight line cannot meet any section of a cone in more than two points. And, lastly, the description of a set of observed phenomena is not induction. Thus Kepler, after observing a number of the places successively occupied by the planet Mars, found that when joined together they formed an ellipse. The pro- position that Mars described an ellipse was therefore merely the summary of a number of different observations, not the inference to a new truth not contained in those observations; and hence it cannot be called an induction. What, then, is an induction? It is defined by Mill as the process by which we infer that what we know to be true in a particular case or cases will be true in all cases which resemble the former in certain assignable respects. The "resemblance" may be either (a) that of individuals belonging to a class, or {b) that of the same individual at different times ; but, in either of these cases, the essence of the induction consists in making a really "general" proposition, i.e., one which holds good, when we pass from the particular to the universal. Thus, the conclusion that "all men are mortal" is an induction, because we pass from what we know of some men to all men. Similarly, when Kepler inferred that, as the orbit of Mars had hitherto been elliptical, it would always be elliptical, he made a genuine induction. Now, if induction implies in all cases a transition from the particular to the universal, it is naturally asked by what right the transition is made. It is obvious that, in every case of real induction, we tacitly assume that what holds good in the cases observed will hold good 85 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. in all similar cases ; we assume, in other words, that the course of nature is uniform. What, then, is the justifica- tion of that assumption ? Mill answers that it is itself an instance of induction, and by no means one of the most obvious or the earliest. But, before attempting to prove this, he asks what precisely is meant by the "uniformity of nature." (i) It is obvious that by the uniformity of nature it is not meant to exclude infinite diversity. Nobody expects one day to be the mere repetition of the previous day. Yet there is a natural tendency in the human mind to expect that phenomena which have frequently presented themselves in combination will always recur in the same combination. This method of inductio per enutnerationem simplicem is rightly condemned by Bacon. It would be legitimate only if we were certain that we had exhausted all the instances, and such certitude is practically not obtain- able. The truth is that induction to be valid does not depend upon the number of instances observed, but upon something very different. A single instance may be sufficient in one case, a million may not be enough in other cases. (2) If, then, the uniformity of nature does not mean invariability, what is its true meaning? The first thing to observe is that by the uniformity of nature we should understand a number of uniformities. These uniformities, when reduced to their simplest expression, are called laws of nature. Three such laws are these: (1) that air has weight, (2) that pressure on a fluid is propagated equally in all directions, (3) that pressure in one direction, not opposed by equal pressure in the contrary direction, produces motion, which does not cease until equilibrium PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 89 is restored. From these three laws or uniformities the rise of mercury in the Torricellian tube might be predicted. But this is not properly a law of nature, but a result of the three laws of nature mentioned. Every true induction is therefore either a law of nature, or a result of laws of nature ; and the problem of induction is to ascertain the laws of nature, and to follow them into their results. CAUSATION. Now, laws of nature are of three kinds : they are either (a) laws which apply indifferently to synchronous or successive phenomena; (b) laws which hold only of syn- chronous phenomena; or (c) laws which hold only of suc- cessive phenomena, (a) The first sort of laws are those of number, which hold whether the phenomena are syn- chronous or successive. Thus, 2 + 2 = 4, whether we are speaking of two coexistent objects or of two events. (b) The second set of laws are those contained in geometry, which apply only to coexistent objects. (c) The third set of laws are those which express uniformities in the way of succession. It is with these only that we have here to deal. It has already been shown that the laws of number and of geometry are inductions, and the question is as to the inductions which concern the succession of phenomena, or rather the principle which is presupposed in all such inductions. That principle is causation. The ground of induction, so far as successive phenomena are concerned, is the law of causation, which may be thus stated : " Every fact which has a beginning has a cause." What, then, is a "cause"? By a " cause " is to be understood in all cases a phenomenon, i.e., a particular fact or event. Whether 9° COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. there are causes which are not themselves phenomena we shall not inquire. There are certain thinkers (the Cartesians, for example) who hold that, besides physical causes, there are also efficient causes, i.e., causes which, without being themselves events, produce events. But, whether there are such causes or not, at any rate these are not at present in question. In affirming that every event has a cause, we are only affirming that every phe- nomenon in nature is invariably preceded by some other phenomenon. Now, as there are at any given instant many phenomena, each of these is preceded by another phenomenon, and invariably preceded by it. A cause is thus an "invariable antecedent" or "set of antecedents," an effect, an "invari- able consequent." There are many antecedents or sets of antecedents = A, B, C, D, etc., and many consequents = a, f3, y, 8, etc., and each of these is separate and distinct from the others. To find out such antecedents is to perform an induction, so far as the succession of phenomena is concerned. If there were any event which had no such antecedent, no induction could take place. The universality and certainty of the law of causation is therefore the basis of all induction as to successive phenomena. A cause, then, is an antecedent or set of ante- cedents. But it seldom, if ever, happens that there is only one antecedent of a given consequent. In ordinary language one of these antecedents is singled out and called the cause, the others being distinguished as conditions. But the real cause is the whole of the antecedents, i.e., all the conditions without which the consequent would not exist. The reason why one antecedent is specially PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 9 1 selected as the cause, is, that it alone is an event, the others being states, which existed prior to the effect, but did not begin to exist immediately prior to it. It thus seems that a cause is the sum of antecedents without which a given event does not take place, but that of those antecedents the greater number are not themselves events. It has to be added that in considering the sum of conditions, we must take into consideration the negative as well as the positive conditions, i.e., those facts which must be absent if the consequent is to take place. The full definition of cause, therefore, is, "the sum total of the conditions, positive and negative, taken together, upon which the consequent invariably follows." This view of causation does away with the absolute distinction of agent and patient. A stone falls to the earth, and it is said that the earth acts, and the stone is acted upon. But it is just as correct to say that the stone attracts the earth, as that the earth attracts the stone. The distinction between agent and patient is purely verbal, since patients are always agents. All the positive conditions of a phenomenon are agents, in the sense that without the whole of them the consequent could not take place. The cause of anything is "the antecedent which it invariably follows," but it is not "the antecedent which it invariably has followed in our past experience." The sequence must be not only invariable but unconditional. Hence we may define a cause as "the antecedent, or the concurrence of antecedents, on which a phenomenon is invariably and unconditionally consequent." It may be admitted that there are cases in which the cause may not be antecedent to an effect, but simul- 92 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. taneous with it. But this is a matter of minor importance. To avoid the difficulty, a cause may be denned as "the assemblage of phenomena, which occurring, some other phenomenon invariably commences." An effect, at any rate, never precedes a cause, though perhaps it may be simultaneous with it. Among the causes of phenomena some are permanent, i. e., have subsisted ever since the human race has been in existence, and for an indefinite time previous. Such are the sun, the earth, and planets, with their various constituents, air, water, and other substances. We cannot account for the origin of these causes themselves, nor can we tell why they are distributed as they are, or why they are commingled in certain proportions. These permanent causes are sometimes not objects but recurring events, such as the rotation of the earth. But though we cannot trace these causes back to others, all other things or events are the immediate or remote effects of those primeval causes. Hence the state of the whole universe is the consequence of its state at the previous instant, and if any particular state could ever occur a second time all subsequent states would also recur, and history would repeat itself. That this does not happen arises from the fact that no two states of the universe are identical. How far can Mill's account of induction, and especially of that form of induction which consists in the discovery of causes, be accepted? So far as induction is main- tained to be an inference from 'some' to 'all' resting upon resemblance, it is inadequate. Induction always consists in the discovery of identity, not of resemblance. It is of PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 93 course true that in every instance in which an identity has been discovered there must be resemblance, but the induction is not, and cannot be, based upon resemblance. The reason why "all men are mortal" is not that they resemble one another in other ways, and therefore also in the way of "mortality," but because they are identical in the possession of a body which cannot permanently resist the external influences against which it reacts. Certainly, there never is any identity of nature between two things which in no way resemble each other — for no two things can be found which are not similar in certain respects and different in others — but the closest resem- blance will not entitle us to affirm identity, and without identity there is no induction. Is Mill's account of causation more satisfactory than his account of induction? (1) Mill is undoubtedly right in rejecting the concep- tion of a mysterious "power" in one thing to bring another into existence. A body falls to the ground if unsupported, but the earth does not contain within itself any occult "power" by which it draws the stone to itself, nor does the stone contain any occult power of gravitation by which it moves to the earth. The fact is this, that when a body is placed at a certain distance from the earth it begins to move towards the earth at a certain velocity. If it were beyond a certain distance it would not so move. The fact we may state by saying, either that the stone is attracted by the earth, or that the stone falls by its own weight; but the essence of the fact is the motion of the stone under certain fixed con- ditions. Given these conditions and the effect takes place. (2) Mill, however, goes on to say that a "cause" is an 94 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. " invariable antecedent " or " set of antecedents," an effect, an "invariable consequent." Two questions arise here therefore: I. Is a cause an "antecedent"? II. Is it an " invariable " antecedent ? I. (a) At first sight it seems as if every effect were a consequent, seeing that it is an event or change. But it is to be observed that we cannot affirm an event to be a "consequent" merely because it is sequent on some- thing else. No doubt there can be no event that does not imply sequence ; but it is not proved to be a con- sequent merely because it is an event. To call an event a consequent is to imply that its cause is antecedent to it, or existed prior to it. But this assumes that the cause cannot be simultaneous with the effect. Now, in the course of his inquiry, Mill admits that a cause may not be antecedent to its effect, though he says that the point is of little or no importance. Whether it is of import- ance or not, it at least compels us to revise the first definition which Mill gives of cause. We can no longer say that a cause is an "invariable antecedent": we must now say that a cause is that which invariably precedes or accompanies a certain event, an effect that which invariably follows or accompanies its cause. (b) Can we accept this revised definition ? It is obvious that it presupposes a separation between cause and effect, such that each is an independent phenomenon, not depend- ing for its reality upon the causal relation. Whether the phenomenon or sum of phenomena called the cause precedes or accompanies the phenomenon called the effect, the one exists apart from the other. Thus, the formation of water is one phenomenon, and the bringing together of oxygen and hydrogen in the proportion of two to one PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE— PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 95 is another phenomenon or rather sum of phenomena. Here the cause seems to precede the effect. Again, fire is the cause of warmth, but the fire is one phenomenon and the warmth is another, though here the cause and the effect seem to be simultaneous, not successive. If, how- ever, we look more closely, we shall find, I think, that the supposed distinction and independence of cause and effect cannot be maintained. Take the case of the forma- tion of water. It is true that oxygen and hydrogen may exist as separate phenomena, and that as long as they are separate they are distinct from water. But oxygen and hydrogen in their separation are not the cause of water. As Mill himself points out, the cause is the sum total of the conditions. Hence oxygen and hydrogen must be brought together before they can be the cause of the formation of water. When do they become the cause? Only at the moment when the formation of water takes place. Obviously, therefore, the cause is not antecedent to the effect, but must at least be simultaneous with it. But is even this account correct? What has become of the hydrogen and oxygen at the moment when the water is formed? They have ceased to be hydrogen and oxygen, and become water. In other words, the formation of water is precisely the same fact as the union of oxygen and hydrogen j i.e., the cause neither precedes nor accom- panies the effect but is identical with it. Thus in dis- covering the cause of the event we are simply discovering an identical relation. The difference between a cause and an effect is not the difference between one phenomenon and another, but consists in the discovery of the fixed nature of the one single fact or phenomenon. Take the other instance of fire and heat. Nothing 96 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. seems to be more certain than that we have here two distinct phenomena. The fire does not cease to exist because no one feels its heat; the heat does not at once cease when one is out of range of the fire. Thus the cause and the effect seem to be two distinct phenomena, which are only externally related to each other. But here again it must be observed that the fire is not a cause of heat except in so far as heat is actually pro- duced. Not only so, but, as Mill himself tells us, the cause is the sum of conditions without which the effect could not take place. Now among these conditions the sensitive organization of the subject is indispensable. There is no sensation of heat in any but a living being. The cause of heat is thus the excitation of the living organism, under certain physical conditions. But the excitation of the living organism is the sensation of heat, i.e., the cause is simply the effect resolved into its con- stituent elements or conditions. Wherever these con- ditions are present, heat exists; in other words, heat is a fixed relation obtaining between distinguishable phe- nomena. And as there is no meaning in saying that the relation called the cause precedes or accompanies the relation called the effect, the cause neither precedes nor accompanies the effect, but is identical with it. In the same way it might be shown that every instance of causation is the apprehension of a fixed relation. II. If then a cause is identical with an effect, it is plain that we cannot say that a cause invariably precedes, or even that it invariably accompanies, its effect. What then is the meaning of " invariable " ? It can only mean necessary or universal. Hydrogen and oxygen in the proportion of two to one necessarily form water, because PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 97 their union is involved in the unchanging constitution of things. That it is so is a fact, and a fact grasped, not by sensible observation, but by thought. There is no difference in principle between the chemical law, H 2 0, and the geometrical proposition that the interior angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles. The one fact is as necessary as the other. This is virtually admitted by Mill when he tells us that a cause is not only "invariable" but "unconditional"; for "unconditional" can only mean " universal " or admitting of no exception, and therefore belonging to the unchangeable nature of things. A cause, then, is neither an invariable nor an uncon- ditional antecedent, but an unchangeable fact. Mill says that the distinction of agent and patient is purely verbal, since the patient is in all cases an agent, in the sense of being one of the antecedents. It would be more correct to say, that the whole distinction of agent and patient is false. When a stone falls to the earth, neither the stone nor the earth can be regarded as agents. This way of looking at the matter supposes that the stone and the earth have each a separate and independent existence, and that each would be what it is even if the other did not exist. Now, it is of course true that the whole nature of the earth is not exhausted in its relation to the stone, or the whole nature of the stone in its relation to the earth. But when we are seeking for the cause of the fall of the stone, we purposely set aside all the characteristics of the earth and the stone except the fact of the motion of each towards the other. The fact to be explained is therefore purely the approximation of a body of a certain mass to another f 98 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. of a much greater mass, and this fact stated in its pre- cision constitutes the cause. The cause is discovered when it is seen that bodies move towards each other (unless there is some negative or counteracting condition) in proportion to their mass and inversely as the square of their distance. This is a fixed relation, and therefore it applies in all cases. But as it is a relation, there can be no more meaning in calling either of the masses the agent or the patient than in calling either the antecedent of the other. Neither, taken by itself, is a cause or an effect; the cause is the relation between the two masses viewed as unchangeable, and the effect is the same rela- tion viewed as manifested in the particular movement of the one towards the other at a certain rate. This view of causation explains why we do not suppose invariable succession to establish causal connection. If Mill were right in saying that a cause is an "invariable antecedent," all invariable antecedents ought to be causes. But, if a cause is never an antecedent, we at once under- stand why we distinguish invariable succession from causal connection. Night and day have invariably succeeded each other in all human experience, but the one is never supposed to be the cause of the other. The reason is that they are not related as cause and effect, but as distin ct fa cts, each having its own cause. The condi- tions under which night occurs are as unchangeable as those under which day occurs, but they are not identical, and therefore the one is not the cause or the effect of the other. Each involves an identity, but it is a different identity. The last distinction drawn by Mill is between permanent and changeable causes. The sun, the earth, the planets PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — PHYSICAL SCIENCE. 99 are permanent causes, as also the rotation of the earth ; the phenomena of life, on the other hand, could not exist before the origination of living beings. In drawing this distinction Mill has gone entirely beyond the question of causation and has introduced a new problem. All that causation tells us, is, that no event occurs which does not imply fixity of conditions : that wherever the same conditions exist the same event must occur; but it does not tell us that the same conditions have always existed, or will always exist. Thus, if living beings with an organism so differentiated as to have the senses of sight, hearing, taste, smell, and touch exist, the sensations relative to their senses will occur according to fixed laws ; but it by no means follows that such beings have always existed or always will exist. The causes of sensation are therefore not permanent in the sense of continuing through all time : they are only per- manent in the sense that they are always the same when they occur. But the same holds good of what Mill calls permanent causes. No doubt the earth existed prior to the appearance of living beings upon it. But this only means that there were causes which took the form of the relations of material masses to one another, before there were causes which took the form of the relations implied in the sensations of living beings. Whether material masses have always existed the law of causation cannot determine: that is a question which takes us beyond the point of view of causation, and compels us to ask what is the ultimate condition of the existence of any reality. Scientific men are therefore justified in refusing to say whether the material world did or did not begin to be, and limiting themselves to an investigation of the conditions of particular facts, IOO COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. leaving the question of the ultimate explanation of reality to philosophy. The distinction of permanent and non- permanent causes is therefore irrelevant and misleading. Since every cause is on its particular side an event, no cause can be permanent; and as every cause on its universal side is a fixed relation or unchangeable fact, in whatever sense one cause is permanent all are permanent. The totality of causes is thus either the totality of events, or the totality of relations constituting these events, i.e., the system of relations constituting nature as a whole. But what is the ultimate condition of there being such a system or whole we cannot tell without going beyond the conception of causality. CHAPTER VI. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE (Continued). BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. We have now dealt with two of the three philosophical problems that arise in regard to the knowledge of nature : we have inquired into the nature of mathematical and of physical knowledge, and we have found that in both cases alike knowledge rests upon the discovery of certain fixed relations implied in the very constitution of the world as known to us. Our next step is to ask whether our knowledge of nature is exhausted in the apprehension of mathematical and physical relations, or whether there are not certain facts which force us to employ a different conception of things. That there are such facts seems to be implied in the distinction between organic and inorganic beings, between living things and things without life. It is true that this distinction, which to common sense seems to be one of the most obvious and certain, has been denied, and that from two opposite points of view. According to one set of thinkers there is no absolute distinction between organic and inorganic beings, for all the facts of life can be explained in the same way 102 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. as we explain the changes which take place in the material world. If we adopt this view, obviously no conception but that of mechanical causation will be required. Another set of thinkers take exactly the opposite view, maintaining that, instead of saying that organic beings are in no way different in their nature from inorganic beings, we ought to say that inorganic beings are of the same nature as organic: in other words, though there seem to be objects which are entirely destitute of life, this is an illusion : all things are living, and nowhere in the whole world can there be found beings which are inorganic. It is therefore maintained that the conception of mechanical causation is not the only or the highest conception of the world. The distinction between these two sets of thinkers may be expressed by saying that the former "level down," and the latter "level up"; the one class reduce organic beings to the level of inorganic, the other class raise inorganic beings to the level of organic. In the presence of such opposite views, it is obvious that we cannot assume the popular distinction between organic and inorganic beings, but must first deal with the preliminary question, whether such a distinction is justifiable at all. On the other hand, supposing it to be proved that the characteristic phenomena of living beings cannot be explained by the conception of mechanical causation, I do not think that we need encumber ourselves with the question, whether even those things which seem to be inorganic are not in reality organic. Our problem, then, is this. Is there anything in the nature of those beings ordinarily distinguished as living or organic, which compels us to apply to them a conception different from that which we employ in our physical in- PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. IO3 vestigations ; in other words, is there a biological as distinguished from a physical knowledge of nature? or is biology simply a branch of physics ? DEFINITION OF LIFE. If we direct our attention to beings usually distinguished as living, can we state wherein their life consists? Mr. Spencer defines life as "the power of continuous adjustment of internal relations to external relations." This definition is so far true, that it emphasizes one aspect of the living being, viz., that it is perpetually going through changes which do not leave it unaltered, but involve new relations to its environment. Thus the living being in one point of view exhibits a great degree of instability. It is continually changing, and the more complex the being, the greater is the number of changes through which it passes in a given time. Mr. Spencer's definition, however, implies that the living being not only changes, but that there is a series of adjustments to new conditions. The relations of a stone to things external to itself are of a comparatively fixed and unchanging type, and seem to imply nothing more than mechanical and chemical relations. After the lapse of an indefinite time it displays the same essential features as at the first. It is otherwise with the living being, which not only exhibits relations to external circumstances, but presents continually new relations from moment to moment. So far therefore, we may regard Mr. Spencers definition as true. But there is one aspect of life which it does not suffi- ciently accentuate. For not only does the living being dis- play continual adjustment in its relations to its environment, changing as they change, but it preserves its unity through all the changes which it undergoes. External forces are 104 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. perpetually acting upon it, and threatening to destroy its unity, but so long as life continues the being recovers its unity. Thus a living being is a unity in a different sense from that in which we can speak of the unity of a stone. The unity of a stone consists in the fixed un- changing identity of the mechanical forces by which its parts are held together : the unity of the living being is an identity which maintains itself by continuous adaptation to external forces which it cannot avoid. In other words, life implies not only adjustment to external relations, but the persistence of unity or individuality. We may therefore define life as the principle by which a being maintains its individuality by a continuous adaptation to external conditions. Now, the unity or individuality of a living being is dependent upon the organization of its parts. If we break up a stone into parts, each part retains the same pro- perties as it had prior to the separation. A living being, or at least a living being which exhibits a definite organiza- tion, cannot be thus broken up into parts without losing its character as a living being. If a limb is severed from the body, it ceases to display the function which it possessed when it formed part of the body. Hence its function does not belong to it in its isolation from the other parts, but only in its relation to them. And this is true of every part of the living being; in fact, we determine what belongs to the individuality of the being by asking what is incapable of being severed from the whole without losing its characteristic function. A hand cannot grasp, an eye cannot see, an ear cannot hear, the lungs cannot breathe, the heart cannot beat, unless the hand, the eye, the ear, the lungs, the heart, form parts of one individual unity. It is not the mere juxta- PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 105 position of the parts which determines the unity of the living being, but a union so close and intimate that none can be what it is apart from its relation to all the rest. Now, this mutual dependence of parts as regards their functions is what we mean by organization. An organism is a union of parts, but the parts are what they are only in their relations to one another, and hence we say that each part is an organ of the whole. That this conception of an organic unity is the basis of our distinction of a living from a non-living being may be seen from this, that where there is little differentiation of organs, we find it hard to say whether there is one being or several. The lowest form of animal is simply a mass of tissue, with no distinction of head and foot, digestive and nervous system. Such a being we regard as living at all mainly because it has the capacity of assimilating material, and loses this capacity when it dies. But though there is thus in it a certain unity of parts which cooperate in securing an end, the unity is of such an external character that a part will perform the same function as the whole. Such a being may be cut into parts, and the parts still have life. On the other hand, we find that the greater the division of labour between the parts, the closer is the relation by which the parts are bound together in the unity of the whole. Thus the differentiation of the organism is correlative to its integration. This principle is displayed even in beings which have a distinct nervous system. In lower animals, such as the frog, the spinal cord or the lower part of the brain is capable of discharging functions which in higher animals are devolved upon the higher part of the brain. Thus the more truly individual a being is, the 106 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. greater is the complexity of its organs, and the more highly specialized their functions. There is another characteristic which distinguishes living beings from other objects : not only are they organized individuals, with the faculty of self-maintenance by adapta- tion to changing external conditions, but they produce other individuals of the same general type as themselves. Now, if living beings have the power of adaptation to external conditions, and if they exhibit such an organiza- tion of parts as tends to their own maintenance, and the maintenance of their species, it seems as if we were forced to apply to them a different conception from that which was adequate so long as we were viewing the world from the purely physical point of view. For a being which not only passes through changes, but in all its changes realizes the end of self-preservation, cannot, it would seem, be properly understood without the conception of final cause. The conception of causality as employed in the physical sciences does not require us to say more than that there are certain fixed conditions under which all the changes in the world take place. The conception of final cause adds that, in the case of living beings at least, those fixed conditions are of such a nature that they are subservient to an end. Thus the conception of external causation tells us that under certain condi- tions there arises the sensation of light ; the conception of final cause affirms that this sensation of light subserves the preservation of the sentient being for whom it exists. If this is so, we must widen our conception of the world by saying that it not only implies unchanging mathematical relations and unchanging physical relations, but also un- changing biological relations. In other words, not only PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 107 is the world a connected system, but it is an organic system. For, if the living being has the power of per- petuating itself by a continual adaptation to external con- ditions, these conditions must be of such a nature as to admit of such self-adaptation. The world must there- fore be conceived as an organic whole, in which each part is related to all the other parts, i.e., the world must be conceived from a teleological, and not from a mechanical point of view. Accordingly, the physical as well as the mathematical sciences must be regarded as true only in so far as they express what holds good of the world from their limited point of view. Just as there are no separate lines or figures in nature, so there can be no separate objects which are purely mechanical. It may be said, however, and indeed it has been said, that, while the teleological view of the world has much plausibility so long as we suppose living beings to form separate and distinct species, this plausibility vanishes when we find that they have all originated in a purely natural and therefore mechanical way. In other words, it is maintained that the theory of development, as enun- ciated by Darwin, is incompatible with a teleological explanation of the world, and hence we must regard the conception of mechanical causation as the ultimate view of things: We must, therefore, ask whether the theory of development confirms, or casts doubt upon, the con- clusions reached independently of it. THE DARWINIAN THEORY. As stated by Darwin himself, the theory of development assumes that there is a line of demarcation between organic and inorganic beings; and no attempt is made to derive 108 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. the former from the latter. What Darwin maintained in his Origin of Species was, that all living beings have been derived from "one or more primordial forms"; but these "primordial forms" he regarded as themselves living. What Darwin denied was the older biological doctrine that certain animals are clearly distinguishable by pecul- iarities of form, size, colour, etc., and produce offspring that closely resemble their parents, these peculiarities being permanent. Thus, the rook and the crow were regarded as distinct species, because (i) they differ from each other in structure, form, and habits, and because (2) rooks always produce rooks, and crows crows, and they do not interbreed. It was therefore supposed that all existing crows were descended from a single pair of crows, and all the rooks from a single pair of rooks. How the primitive pairs were formed was a " mystery." In opposition to this view, Darwin maintains that " species are not immutable, but that those belonging to what are called the same genera (e.g., the crow and the rook) are lineal descendants of some other and generally extinct species, in the same manner as the acknowledged varieties of any one species are the descendants of that species." There are two fundamental principles which explain how species have originated. In the first place, all living beings multiply in a geometrical progression. In the second place, the offspring differ slightly from the parents, though generally they closely resemble them. (1) Now, it is impossible that all the beings born into the world should live, because there would not be sufficient food to sustain them. Hence arises a struggle for ex- istence, resulting in the extinction, on an average, of as many as survive. They kill one another, they starve PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 109 one another, and the forces of nature carry many of them off. Which of them survive? Naturally, those that are stronger, or swifter, or hardier, or more cunning. "The fittest always survive " — not necessarily the strongest, but those which have some peculiarity that enables them to escape destruction. (2) There is also another principle at work, the principle of heredity or transmission of variations. In the case of plants or domestic animals, we can improve the stock by carefully selecting the best seed and the finest animals. After a time they may have so improved that it is hard to recognize them as identical with the primitive stock. So, in a state of nature, the beings that have some pecul- iarity that gives them a superiority in the struggle for existence, survive ; but when this variation is no longer useful, those individuals that chance to have a new quality or modification more favourable to their continuance will gradually displace the old. It is in this way that new species originate. The general conclusion reached by such considerations is, that all plants and animals have been gradually evolved from "one or more primordial forms." This doctrine, however, is applied not only to plants and the lower animals, but to man. The most superficial examination of man's body shows that it agrees in all essential features with the bodies of other mammalia. " Every detail of structure which is common to the mam- malia as a class is found also in man, while he only differs from them in such ways and degrees as the various species or groups of mammals differ from one another." Now, if it is reasonable to conclude that all mammalia originally descended from some primitive type, are we not compelled IIO COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. to suppose that man also must trace his origin back to that type? Granting that man has originated in the same way as other living beings ; granting, in other words, that as an animal he must be classed with other animals : the question arises whether his mental and moral faculties have also been derived by gradual modification and development from the lower animals. Now, in his Descent of Man, Darwin does not say in express terms that the spiritual nature of man has been derived from the lower animals, "in the same manner and by the action of the same general laws as his physical structure " ; but the whole of his argument tends to that conclusion. "The rudiments of most, if not all the mental and moral faculties of man can be detected in some animals. They exhibit curiosity, imitation, attention, wonder, and memory ; they display kindness to their fellows, pride, contempt, and shame." Some are held to possess a rudimentary language, because they utter several different sounds, each of which has a definite meaning to their fellows or to their young ; others possess the rudiments of arithmetic, because they seem to count and remember up to three, four, or even five. They seem to have some sense of beauty, and certain animals are said to have imagination, because they appear to be disturbed by dreams. Even an approach to religion is said to be exhibited in the deep love and complete submission of a dog to his master. Again, if we compare the lowest races of man with the higher animals, we find that the mental and moral qualities of the former are very little higher than those of the latter. In the lowest savages there is not a dis- tinct moral sense, but merely certain social instincts PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. Ill which develop through circumstances into a moral sense. Those actions which are regarded as contrary to the interests of the tribe excite its disapprobation and are held to be immoral; those actions which as a rule are beneficial to the tribe meet with its approval, and are considered moral. Naturally, the individual has a feeling of satisfaction when he acts so as to gain general approbation, and of discomfort when he does anything contrary to the mind of his tribe. In these feelings orig- inates his consciousness of right and wrong. Conscience arises from the struggle between the desire to do what will benefit oneself and injure others, and the desire to obtain the general approbation of the tribe. The social instincts are thus the foundation of morality. Now, you will observe that in this argument two things are implied : firstly, that there has been a continuous development of intellectual and moral faculties, from the lower animals up to savages, and from savages up to civilized man ; and secondly, that this development may be explained by the same law of natural selection that has been employed to account for the natural descent of man from lower forms of being. It will therefore be well to point out clearly the distinction between these two things. Let us ask, therefore, What is the precise nature and value of the proof that man has descended from the lower animals, granting that proof to be as irresistible as scientific men usually suppose it to be? I do not propose to inquire into the evidence brought forward by Darwin and his followers in support of the natural descent by inheritance of all living beings from one or more primitive forms. Even if I were com- petent to give an authoritative opinion on that question, 112 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. it would not be my place to do it. I shall therefore assume, with the majority of scientific men, that as a matter of fact the old doctrine of the immutability of species is false, and that in the principle of natural selection we have found the true explanation of the phenomena of organized existence. In other words, we must, in my opinion, be prepared to accept the extension of natural law to living beings. On this view, natural selection is in the organic world very much what gravita- tion is in the sphere of the inorganic. What I wish you to consider is, whether, accepting the theory of develop- ment as the only tenable explanation of the characteristics and changes of living beings, we have reached an ultimate explanation, or whether we have only solved a subordinate problem. DARWIN AND PALEY. Now there can be no doubt that the principle of natural selection, as conceived by biologists, is incon- sistent with the conception that any organ or organism has been specially constructed with the design of per- forming a particular function. Paley, in his celebrated argument from design, compares the various organs of a living being to the parts of a watch. Just as the watch is put together by the watchmaker so as to fulfil the purpose of showing the time, so the organs of a living being have been constructed by the supreme Artificer in order to secure its existence and well-being. The same adaptation of means to ends is exhibited, he argues, in such an organ as the eye, which has been constructed with th£ express purpose of enabling the individual to see. This argument therefore rests upon the idea that the PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 113 organs of living beings have been specially designed to subserve a particular purpose. Now, this conception of design is not consistent with the doctrine of natural selection. It assumes that the peculiar adjustment of organisms and organs to external conditions cannot be explained without recourse being had to the hypothesis of an artificer external to them, who specially adapted them to their environment. It assumes, in other words, that in the ordinary operation of natural law there is nothing to account for the peculiar character of living beings. For the whole force of the argument lies in this, that there is nothing in the nature of living beings themselves, or in the action of circumstances upon them, to explain the wonderful adjustment of the one to the other. It is because the operation of natural law does not explain the adaptation of an organism to its environment that recourse is had to the conception of an external designer. Just as the parts of a watch would never come together as they are found in the watch, unless they were brought together and arranged by the watch- maker : so the organs of a living being would never come together spontaneously without the special inter- position of a designing intelligence external to them. But this is exactly what Darwin denies. He refuses indeed to say how the primitive forms from which living beings have descended came to be in existence — whether by " special creation " or by evolution from non-living things — but, in regard to the adaptation of all subsequent beings to external conditions, he maintains that the operation of the law of natural selection explains the facts quite irrespective of any hypothesis of special design. A teleologist like Paley would say that an organism 114 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. exists because it was made for the conditions in which it is found ; the Darwinian, that " an organism exists because, out of many of its kind, it is the only one which has been able to persist in the conditions in which it is found." 1 The ordinary teleologist would say that cats have been made in order to catch mice; the Dar- winian, that cats exist because they catch mice well. The effect of the Darwinian theory therefore is to exclude from the realm of science all explanation by final causes, and to bring the organic world like the inorganic, under the sway of inviolable law. Nor can there be any doubt that in this procedure it is simply following in the lines of the other sciences, which have discarded the hypothesis of the special interposition of supernatural agency, and have sought only to find out the fixed laws according to which phenomena occur. Darwinism, then, seeks to show, firstly, that each living being is fitted for some external conditions, not because it has been externally and artificially constructed for the purpose of living under those conditions, but because it would not have existed at all had it not possessed naturally the organs essential to such existence. Secondly, it explains the existence of all the varieties of living beings, and more particularly the " wonderful development of the highest, by means of the action and reaction between the environment and the simplest organic forms." I do not think that any fruitful results in philosophy are to be obtained by attempting to reinstate the con- ception of external design. Our problem rather is this: granting that the Darwinian theory has made it impossible for us any longer to hold to the idea of the external 1 Huxley's Lay Sermons, p. 302. PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 115 and artificial adaptation of an organized being to a particular end, must we not seek for a new and higher conception of the relation of the various parts of the universe to one another, and more particularly of the various organized beings to their environment? This is, in fact, the special problem of philosophy as distinguished from science. Science is content to start from the assumed independent existence of individual objects, and to treat them as if they were only externally related to one another. This assumption, however, philosophy can- not allow to pass without criticism, but goes on to ask whether there is not a principle of unity which explains the differences of things by showing that they all belong to one intelligible system. In examining the view of Comte, that knowledge is limited to particulars, I tried to show that such a doctrine is inconsistent with the nature of knowable existence. All things that can be observed are related to one another by the fact that they exist in space. We can therefore say, that no sensible object can possibly be known that does not fall within the one world of space. The question therefore arises, whether we are not com- pelled to hold that all living beings in like manner belong to a single system of things, and whether, therefore, we are not forced to return to a teleological conception of the world if we are to bring the theory of development into harmony with the rest of our knowledge. I shall begin by pointing out some of the presup- positions with which the theory starts ; and I shall then inquire whether those presuppositions do not take us beyond the theory, and compel us to regard the universe from a teleological point of view. Il6 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. In the first place, the theory assumes that the laws of inorganic nature are inviolable. The environment, to which living beings must conform on pain of extinction, involves all the ordinary laws of dynamics, physics, and chemistry. Now, these laws rest upon such principles as the indestructibility of matter, the equality of action and reaction, the affinity of elements for each other. The first of these principles affirms that, whatever may be the changes in the sensible properties of things, the quantity of their matter is unchangeable. When a piece of wood is burned, it changes in its sensible properties, but its weight remains the same. So if one body impinges upon another, both alter their position, but the total quantity of energy is the same. Two chemical elements will combine only if they have an affinity for each other, and this affinity is not a mere accident but belongs to the very constitution of the elements. Secondly, the Darwinian theory assumes that in each living being there is a tendency or impulse to maintain itself, and to continue its species. This is implied in the "struggle for existence," which is the main principle of the whole doctrine. Unless living beings possessed the impulse towards self-maintenance, and the impulse to continue their species, there would be no struggle for existence. In the very nature of living beings, there is therefore implied a purposive tendency. It is true that the impulse can only be realized under appropriate external conditions, but external conditions themselves will not account for the facts unless we also presuppose the tendency to self-maintenance and race-maintenance. Thirdly, the theory also assumes that the variations in the several parts of the living being are consistent PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 117 with the impulse to self-maintenance and race-maintenance. For however strong that impulse might be, it would be powerless unless the being by inheritance possessed the organs enabling it to maintain itself under the external conditions in which it is placed. These three assumptions, then, are clearly implied in the doctrine of evolution. If the laws of inorganic nature were not constant, there could be no continuous development of living beings. If living beings had no impulse to self-maintenance, there would be no struggle to live under given external conditions. And, lastly, if there were no law of inheritance by which offspring resembled their parents and yet varied slightly from them, there would be no development of organisms exhibiting an ever more perfect correlation of parts. Now, I think it may be shown that these assumptions, when we ask what is implied in them, compel us to hold that the world is a system, or, in other words, that we cannot explain existence apart from some form of teleology. It is virtually assumed by Darwin that a denial of teleology in the sense in which Paley affirmed it is the same thing as a denial of teleology in any sense. This, however, does not seem to me to follow. On the con- trary, the more clearly we see that no species of living being has been directly formed for a special set of cir- cumstances, the more manifest it becomes that between the inorganic and the organic world there is so close a connection that the one cannot exist without the other. No doubt, if we look at a particular set of circumstances and a particular species of living being, there seems to be no connection except a purely accidental one. Plants that happen to be well armed with spines or hairs may Il8 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. escape being devoured; a much stronger plant without this accidental advantage may perish. If the one species was constructed with hairs to escape destruction, shall we not have to say that in the construction of the other species there was a failure in foresight? At first sight it therefore seems as if there were no adaptation between the environment and the organism except what is acci- dental. If an organism happens to possess a peculiarity that gives it an advantage in the struggle for existence it survives, if not it dies; but the law of inheritance by which the advantageous peculiarity arises seems to have no necessary relation to external conditions, but to be purely accidental. But, when we look more closely, we shall find, I think, that the connection between the organ- ism and the environment cannot be called accidental. For (i) if there were no harmony whatever between an organism and its environment, the organism could not exist at all. Before a being can live, there must be a certain adjustment of the external conditions to the internal ; death, in fact, arises when that adjustment is no longer possible. Even in the case of the beings that do not survive, there is necessarily a certain degree of harmony between them and the conditions in which they are found. The struggle for existence is a struggle to maintain the initial harmony. But, because in some organisms the capacity of adaptation to given conditions is made possible by a peculiar feature not found in others, the harmony of organism and environment is maintained and the being lives and grows. To suppose, therefore, that there is no harmony between living beings and ex- ternal conditions is to suppose that life is impossible; in other words, it is to contradict the fact from which the PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 119 development theory starts. The relation between the inorganic and the organic world is therefore not an accidental relation, but one that is implied in the very existence of the organic world. Now, if this is true, we can no longer oppose the organic to the inorganic world as if they were two inde- pendent spheres of existence, only externally and acci- dentally connected ; we must, on the contrary, regard them as belonging to one system of things. It is not a matter of chance that some living beings are incapable of con- tinuous adjustment to the external conditions, and others succeed in effecting an adjustment : it is a matter of necessity. Were the external conditions totally different from what they are, living beings could not exist : that they do exist is sufficient evidence of an essential harmony between them and the conditions of their exist- ence. What the development theory really proves is, not that the relation of organized beings to their environment is a purely accidental one, but that the adjustment is in the case of many living beings imperfect, and ultimately in all. (2) We have seen that the theory implies in each living being an impulse to maintain itself. If this were absent there would be no struggle for existence. Hence we cannot regard the relation of organic beings to the en- vironment as the mere action of the environment on the organism, but we must add that the tendency to self- maintenance and to race-maintenance is an essential factor in the case. That is to say, living beings are unconsciously purposive in this sense, that their very existence implies a tendency to continue their own exist- ence and the existence of their species. It is true that 120 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. this tendency is in many individuals never realized, on account of an imperfect relation between the organism and the environment; but it is not less true, that while the individual is sacrificed, the tendency to self-main- tenance is actually realized on the whole. Thus, while the world is not fitted for the realization of the impulse to self-maintenance in every individual, it is fitted for the existence and perpetuation of life on the whole. We can no longer hold that each living being, or even each species, has been specially constructed with a view to its existence under certain definite external conditions ; but we can say, that between organic and inorganic things as a whole there is a necessary harmony. This becomes even clearer if we consider — (3) That living beings have not only a tendency to self- maintenance, but a tendency to organization. This tend- ency to organization is explained by Darwin as due to the fact that each organism reproduces itself with slight varia- tions in its offspring, and that those living beings which possess a variation harmonious with the external con- ditions of existence survive, and, reproducing their type with a new variation, give rise to a form of being having a still more perfect capacity of adjustment to the environ- ment. Now, it is true that this mode of explanation is inconsistent with the idea of an external construction of a certain type of organism out of a preexistent material; for, in the living being itself is found the variation which accounts for its adaptation to the environment. But this only shifts the problem, and forces us to ask what is meant by this hereditary tendency to variation. If there were no such tendency, there would be no possibility of development, since that tendency is essential to the PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE — BIOLOGICAL SCIENCE. 121 existence of certain forms, and to the gradual develop- ment of higher forms. While, therefore, the relation of organism and environment is incompatible with the per- petuation of certain forms, it is compatible with others. But what is still more important, it is the very incom- patibility of lower forms with the conditions of existence that explains the development of higher forms. If the simplest and lowest forms of life were better adapted to the environment than the more complex and higher forms, there could have been no evolution of the higher out of the lower. It is just because some beings are less adapted to the environment than others that a perpetual develop- ment of higher forms has taken place. The environment, in other words, is opposed to the continued existence of lower forms of being and harmonious with the con- tinued existence of higher forms. Thus the idea of purpose comes back in another and higher form. It is now seen to be implied in the very nature of existence, not to be something external and arbitrary. The organic forms with the inorganic world a systematic unity in which every part is related to every other. We find, in fact, in the evolution of living beings, the same unifying principle that is at work in the inorganic world, only that in the former the tendency to unity is more clearly manifested than in the latter. The parts of a stone, e.g., seem to be only externally related to one another. Break it up and there is in the stone no tendency to a restoration of the unity that has been destroyed. In the living being, on the contrary, there is a perpetual conflict with external forces, resulting, as we have seen, in the development of ever higher forms of life. Hence it is that, in life, as Kant said, the idea 122 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. of purpose first clearly presents itself. Apart from the tendency to organization and unity, there is no life ; and this tendency, in its widest sweep, is exhibited in the gradual ascent of life from its simplest to its most com- plex forms. The higher a being is, the greater is its power of adaptation, and the more perfect its unity. CHAPTER VII. RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. We find, therefore, that, when it is interpreted from the philosophical point of view, the theory of development leads to the conclusion that organized existence exhibits the continual evolution of living beings towards a more and more perfect form of unity ; in other words, it implies that the form of existence is necessarily ruled by the idea of unity, and is a realization of unity. And this is the same as saying that the world is in no sense a product of chance, but must be conceived from the point of view of immanent teleology. I am well aware that many objections may be raised to this conclusion, and these we shall afterwards have to consider. At present my aim merely is to indicate in general the point of view from which, as I think, the question must be regarded. Assuming, then, that the world is in no sense given over to chance, or, in other words, that it constitutes a systematic unity in which every element is striving towards a definite end, we have next to ask what is the ultimate nature of this unity; we have to ask, in other words, whether the unity of the world implies or does not imply intelligence. It is 124 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. one thing to say that the world is a unity and exhibits in its changes a continual tendency towards a more perfect unity, and it is another thing to say that this unity and tendency to perfection necessarily implies intelligence. It may even be plausibly argued, that as the teleological conception of existence implies absolute fixity in the rela- tions of things, or, in other words, the reign of inviolable law, there is no necessity for the hypothesis of intelligence at all. This is the question which lies at the basis of all philosophy, and we must give our best efforts towards its solution. The only satisfactory answer will consist in the whole system of philosophy, but some preliminary idea of it may be given now. We have seen that Darwin not only traces the physical descent of man down from some primitive form of living being, but he seems to find in the principle of natural selection a sufficient explanation even of his intellectual and moral qualities. The whole tenor of his thought in the Descent of Man is that the great gulf supposed to be fixed between man and the animals cannot be shown to exist. If, therefore, we can explain all the characteristics of the animals by the principle of natural selection, why should we not also explain in the same way all the char- acteristics of man ? Here, then, two main propositions are asserted or implied by Darwin : first, that man as regards mental qualities differs from the animals only in degree, not in kind ; second, that the mental qualities of both man and the animals may be accounted for by the law of natural selection. Let us consider these in order. First. It is asserted or implied that the mental qualities of man are generically identical with those of the animals. RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 25 Darwin brings man and the animals closer together, first, by lifting up the animals, and, second, by lowering man. (a) The higher animals, he contends, exhibit the same kind of intelligence as man. They display, e.g., curiosity, wonder, memory, imagination j some possess a rudimentary mathematics, language, aesthetics, morality, and religion. We must, therefore, correct our preconception that the animals are destitute of intelligence. The facts show that they possess in an elementary form all that has hitherto been supposed to be distinctive of man. (b) On the other hand, we must recognize that man in his lowest stage of development is very little superior in mental qualities to the most developed of the animals. The savage has social instincts which bind him to his fellows, but the same instincts are exhibited by the higher animals. The difference between the highest animal and the savage is no greater, if even so great, as that between the savage and the civilized man. Now, the difference between the civilized man and the savage is only one of degree, and, by parity of reasoning, the difference between the higher animals and the savage must also be one of degree. The general conclusion, then, would seem to be that in the animals is found the same kind of intelligence as in man, just as their organism differs from man's only in its being less developed. There is no break in the con- tinuity of development : the high intelligence of civilized man has come out of the low intelligence of the savage, as the latter has been evolved from the still lower in- telligence of the animals. Man used to be defined as a "rational animal," and it was supposed that "rationality" differentiated, him from the lower animals. This definition 126 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. we must now extend to other beings besides man, and we must say that "all animals are rational." Now, it is not my intention to dispute the facts upon which Darwin bases his view of the essential identity in mental as in bodily powers of man and the animals. There can, I think, be no doubt that the higher animals exhibit qualities that must be regarded as implying an elementary intelligence. Granting this, I propose to show that we must carry back this principle further than Darwin has done. If, in the animals nearest to man, we find traces of a rudimentary intelligence, must we not expect to find in less developed animals traces of an intelligence still more rudimentary; nay, must we not hold that even plants exhibit intelligence in a still more rudimentary form? Nor does it seem possible to stop here. Following out the same line of thought, must we not go still further back, and look for inchoate intelligence even in inorganic things ? This is the direction in which many men of science have recently gone. It is a revival, in a new form, of a doctrine that was advanced in his day by Leibnitz. Perhaps, therefore, it may help to clear the way, if we first consider the Leibnitzian theory of the essential identity of all forms of existence. THE MONADS OF LEIBNITZ. Every real thing is held by Leibnitz to be an individual substance, or, in other words, to have a unique existence of its own, separating it from all other existences. From this point of view, the universe is made up of an infinite number of distinct individuals, which, like crystal spheres, are exclusive of one another and mutually repellent. The universe is therefore a collection of separate individuals, RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 27 not an organic unity, in which each individual is only ideally separable. "There can be nothing real or sub- stantial in the collection, unless the units be substantial." Each is a little world of its own, developing by itself, " as if there were nothing else in existence." This, however, is only one side of the Leibnitzian doctrine. Pushed to its logical extreme it would dissolve the universe into fragments. Each "monad," as Leibnitz calls the individual, is in its existence unrelated to every other. There is no really continuous existence, but only discrete existence. Leibnitz naturally had some difficulty in satisfying himself that material things are separate and distinct. For every material thing is in space, and as such it seems to be infinitely divisible. How then shall we reach an absolute individual, an ultimate atom? If the supposed ultimate atom occupies space, it must be divisible, and therefore it cannot be a real individual. To obtain a real individual atom, it would seem as if we required a space that was itself made up of separate parts, and of such a space we can form no conception whatever. Leibnitz gets over this difficulty by boldly denying that space has a real existence, and consequently by denying that material things are really extended. The ancient Atomists, he says, made the mistake of supposing that there are real material atoms existing in space; and hence they were forced to hold the self- contradictory doctrine that there are real material atoms which have no parts. Real units, then, are not extended at all ; they are individual " monads " having an inde- pendent existence, but not an existence in space. The idea of space is a "confused idea," *>., an idea resting 128 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. upon the first or apparent view of things. At the stage of sensible perception it seems as if real things were in space and were extended; but, when we reflect on the nature of reality, and bring our knowledge to the clearness of thought, we see that real things are not in space. The same thing is true of time : there is no real time, nor are real existences in time. Yet the external world is not a mere illusion : it has its own definite laws, and, what is more, there is a perfect correspondence between the real relations of "monads" to one another, and the connection of phe- nomena in time and space. The law of phenomena is different from the law of real things. Phenomena are connected by the law of efficient causes, monads by the law of final causes. The monads are determined by their own inner nature, not by the action upon them of external causes, but there is a correspondence between the connection of phenomena and the self-determination of monads. The reason of this correspondence is that the activities of the real monads are refracted in passing through the medium of sense; only this refraction always takes place in a fixed way. For example, if I will to raise my arm, the volition proceeds entirely from me : I am self-determined. But, on the other hand, the move- ment of the arm seems to be sufficiently explained by the cerebral movement, which itself is excited by sense-per- ception. I am myself the real cause of the action, but from the point of view of perception the cause is a bodily movement. But why, it may be asked, are monads compelled to represent things in the " confused " form of perception ? If perception is an inadequate view of things, can it be RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 29 said that the monads are determined purely from them- selves? A monad that represented reality as it is would always view things from the point of view of thought; and hence for it there would be no space or time, no extended or temporal world, no efficient causes. In attempting to meet this difficulty, Leibnitz is forced to modify his first unqualified assertion of the absolute self- determination of the monads. All finite monads are indeed determined from within, but each has a certain limit in its own nature to its activity. It is because of this limit that it does not represent the universe to itself as it truly is, but always in a more or less confused form. It presents to itself a picture of the whole world, but a picture blurred and indistinct. But all monads do not represent the world with equal clearness. There is a regular gradation. God, the "monad of monads," whose activity is absolutely unlimited by any passive element, apprehends all things in the clearness of pure thought. Finite spirits like men apprehend the world partly in the light of thought, partly in the confusion of sense. Animals have only sense perception, while plants and inorganic things represent the world in a still more confused way. Observe, however, that on Leibnitz' view the distinction between man and the animal, between the animal and the plant, and between the plant and the mineral, is one of degree not of kind. Wherever there is existence, there is perception. Every monad is an individual, and there is no individual that has not an ideal centre of perception, in which it re- presents all other existence. It is a " living mirror gifted with an internal activity, whereby it represents the whole universe according to its particular point of view, 130 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. and in such a way that its ideal universe has all the regularity of the real one." In this doctrine of Leibnitz we have a suggestion of the manner in which the Darwinian conception of the distinction between the animals and man must be com- pleted. As the animals differ from man only in the degree of their mental qualities, so we must suppose the plant and the mineral to differ in a similar way. This view has been put forward, though with some hesitation, by Tyndall, and Haeckel adopts it without any hesitation. It is pointed out by Tyndall that in the tendency to crystallization of the mineral world we have an anticipation of the organized form of living beings. The whole tend- ency therefore of the Darwinian conception is to deny that there is any fundamental distinction between different orders of existence. The mineral exhibits in an implicit form the same characteristics as are presented in man in an explicit form. We can therefore readily understand why Tyndall says that in matter he discerns the "promise and potency of all kinds and qualities of life." As Darwin denies any generic distinction between man and the animals, so Tyndall would deny any generic distinction between man and the mineral. And the same line of argument is applied by both. As Darwin seeks to show that the higher animals come much nearer to man than is commonly supposed, so Tyndall maintains that in the wonderful symmetry of the crystal we have a close approximation to organized existence. The inference would therefore seem to be, that there is no break in the continuity of. existence, but all existence is of the same fundamental nature. RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 131 If we examine this conception closely, I think we shall find that it really involves two radically different views of the world, which have not been clearly distinguished from each other. The first view is, that there is nothing in the nature of intelligence as found in man that is not contained in lower forms of existence ; in other words, it is implied that intelligence must be reduced to the same level as other modes of existence. The second view is, that all forms of existence imply intelligence, since even in the mineral we find implicitly what in man we find explicitly. The first view levels down, the second levels up. It is one thing to say that all the characteristics of man as an intelligent being can be ex- plained by the operation of the same laws as those which account for the form and movements of inorganic things, and another thing to say that the laws of inorganic nature properly understood are really laws of intelligence. We must therefore inquire which of these opposite views is really held by men like Darwin and Tyndall, and which is true. Now, I think there can be no doubt that the tendency of Darwin's theory of the nature of man is to abolish the distinction between intelligence and non-intelligence. As we have seen, he implies that the mental and moral qualities of man may be explained on the principle of natural selection. Let us see, therefore, what explanation of man's nature must be given in accordance with the theory of natural selection as rigidly applied. The evolution of all forms of life has taken place in this way, that the advantageous peculiarities received by inheritance enable certain forms to survive. But these peculiarities simply come to the individual by natural I32 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. inheritance. No living being can change its inherited qualities. The external conditions are in like manner beyond the control of the individual. Now, whether an individual will survive or not depends upon its power of adaptation to the environment, and this depends en- tirely upon the natural adaptation of its inherited peculi- arities to the circumstances in which it is placed; hence there seems to be in Darwin's theory no place for any spontaneous activity on the part of the individual living being. If therefore, we apply the doctrine of natural selection to man, it seems to make any claim for his freedom, either of intelligence or of action, quite unin- telligible. Man, we are to suppose, inherited from his animal progenitors such qualities as curiosity, wonder, memory, imagination. But these are purely natural tend- encies which the individual can neither make nor unmake; they come to him by inheritance, like his bodily powers, and their direction is determined by the external conditions in which he is placed. Thus the curiosity of primitive man we may suppose to have been excited by something he could not explain, but the feeling itself was due to an inherited tendency, and was called out by the external circumstances. If, therefore, we follow the evolution of man from his primitive to his civilized condition, we shall still find nothing but the reaction of the individual on his environment, — a reaction deter- mined simply by the peculiarities of his inherited disposition. (a) There is on this view no more room for any free activity in knowledge on the part of man than on the part of an unconscious thing. Hydrogen exhibits by its natural constitution an affinity for oxygen, but it would RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 33 be regarded as a pure fiction to endow the hydrogen with any capacity of freely selecting the oxygen as its mate. For, it would be said, hydrogen cannot refuse to unite with oxygen under certain conditions : the union is absolutely determined by the natural characteristics of both. In the same way it must be denied that in man there is any freedom in knowledge ; he can know only that which his inherited disposition fits him to know : to suppose that he could have a different disposition, or react differently under the conditions, is incompatible with the principle of natural selection. {b) Nor can there be any freedom of action. Primitive man inherited certain tendencies from his animal ancestors. Thus, like them, he has a selfish tendency and a social tendency. Which of these shall be predominant will be determined by the interaction between the organism and the environment. The moral sense is developed by the conditions under which man is placed. In virtue of his love of approbation and his fear of punishment — both inherited peculiarities — the savage comes to have a feeling of pain when he follows his selfish desire for his own pleasure. Right and wrong are therefore names for the pleasure of approbation and the pain of disapprobation respectively. But the individual man can no more de- termine which of these shall predominate than he can alter his bodily stature or endow himself with new senses. We must suppose that in the majority of men the love of social approbation is stronger than the love of individual pleasure; because otherwise, the extension and develop- ment of the social bond would be impossible. But this only shows that the inherited disposition and the environ- ment tend on the whole to the evolution of higher 134 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. sociality : it does not show that in the individual there is any free activity. Thus the theory of natural selection, when it is employed to account for the mental and moral qualities of man, leads to the conclusion that there is no freedom either of knowledge or of action. Now, when we clearly see the results which follow from a rigid adherence to the doctrine of natural selection, we cannot help asking whether Darwin has not made a grave mistake in attempting to explain intelligence and morality by a principle which necessarily excludes all freedom either in knowing or in willing. May it not be that natural selection is only a limited or partial explanation, true within its own sphere, but inadequate and untrue when extended to the explana- tion of conscious beings ? In attempting to answer this question, I must begin by reminding you that Darwin at once seeks to approxi- mate the higher animals to man, and to bring man nearer to the higher animals. This he does by saying that in the higher animals are to be found the same characteristics as in man, and that the savage possesses these character- istics in a degree only a little superior to the higher animals. Now, in this contention, it is implied that mental and moral qualities are purely natural characteristics, received by inheritance, and called out by the reaction of the organism on the environment. Darwin, in other words, assumes that the qualities of the animals are due to the influence of natural selection, and, having shown that there is no essential difference between man and the animals in respect of those qualities, he infers that the intelligence of man can be explained in the same way. That is to say, Darwin does not find in the fact RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 35 that the higher animals possess qualities similar to man's, a reason for doubting whether natural selection is an adequate explanation even of them ; but, assuming the explanation to be adequate when applied to the animals, he infers that it must also be adequate when applied to man. I propose to approach the problem from the other side, and to ask whether the principle of natural selection is adequate to the explanation of the facts of intelligence and morality as these exist in man. If we see reason to deny its adequacy as regards man, we shall have reason to doubt whether it is adequate even when applied to the animals. DOES NATURAL SELECTION EXPLAIN KNOWLEDGE? Let us first ask whether natural selection explains the fact of knowledge as it exists in man. Darwin tells us that man inherited from his non-human ancestors such mental characteristics as curiosity, wonder, and memory. What is curiosity? It implies an interest in some object, and a concentration of attention upon it for the purpose of discovering what are its properties. It is further implied in curiosity that the subject believes in the intelligibility of the object. Now interest, attention, belief in the intelligibility of the object, all involve the faculty of distinguishing one object from another by an apprehension of the properties of each; and this again implies that the apprehending subject is capable of separat- ing between himself and the immediate impression that he has from moment to moment. For if, as each im- pression arose, it vanished for ever, it would be impossible for the subject to distinguish one impression from another, and therefore impossible for him to identify an object 136 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER by its peculiar properties. Primitive man was no doubt engaged mainly in a fierce fight for existence, a fight to preserve himself from the destructive influence of the elements and from his natural foes, the lower animals. It was therefore necessary for him to learn to some extent the properties of the elements and the habits of the lower animals. To do this he had to discriminate things by their properties ; to learn the nature of fire, tempest, cold, sunshine, and to find out how the animals might be over- come or captured. But the victory over objects he could achieve only if he had the faculty of grasping the different properties of things. To this end all his energies were directed, and if he made a serious mistake, the forfeit was his life. He had therefore to free himself from the first impressions of the nature of things, by attention, comparison, and discrimination ; that is, he had to separate between his impression of things and their actual nature. Such a faculty of distinguishing between the apparent and the real is the pre-requisite of all knowledge ; and it implies that man was not the sport of the fleeting impression of the moment, but was in some sense its master. His curiosity took the form of an interest in all those properties of things, a comprehension of which was essential to his very existence. Primitive man had no scientific interest in nature; he did not study its phenomena with a view to understanding it for itself. Yet we can readily see in the undeveloped and limited curiosity which he possessed the rudiments of the scientific curiosity of civilized man. For, as I have said, he assumed that what he sought to understand was capable of being under- stood. That is to say, he assumed that in his own intelli- gence could be found the key to the interpretation of RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 37 things. Knowledge, then, even as it existed for primitive man implied (i) the consciousness of a distinction between the apparent and the real, and (2) the capacity of appre- hending the real in virtue of intelligence. It is plain, then, that any attempt to reduce knowledge to the mere flow of impressions in a subject that passively receives them, makes even the simplest knowledge unin- telligible. If consciousness could be described as a mere series of occurrences in the subject, there could be no knowledge. The successive positions taken up by a moving body may perhaps be so described, but the con- sciousness of man refuses to be expressed in such terms. The moving body is not aware of the successive positions it occupies : man not only has impressions, but he is aware that he has them. To the conscious subject we must therefore attribute much greater complexity than to the unconscious thing. Consciousness always involves the opposition of what seems and what is; or, what is the same thing, it implies that impressions as they occur are only the sign or index of what does not occur. Con- sciousness also involves the capacity on the part of the subject of contrasting the stream of occurrences with the permanent nature of the object. It presupposes, in other words, that the objective world is not a mere series of occurrences, but a fixed system of things, and that the subject is capable of finding out what that system is. Knowledge always consists in grasping things from a uni- versal point of view, i.e., in liberation from accidental impressions and associations. This is the real force of Bacon's contention, that man must come to the study of nature free from all preconceptions. For what this implies is, that only in freeing oneself from the accidental 138 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. impressions of the moment, and putting oneself at the point of view of existence as it actually is, can knowledge be obtained. THE CARTESIAN CONCEPTION OF MIND. What has just been said may also be put in this way, that no knowledge is derivable from mere impressions, but only from impressions that have been brought to the unity of conception. For it is by conception, i.e., by the mental apprehension of the meaning of individual im- pressions when these are viewed by reference to the whole system of things, that we obtain knowledge. We must be careful to observe, however, that we cannot absolutely oppose the conceptions of our own minds to the actual nature of things. Descartes, e.g., maintained that there are certain "innate conceptions," which belong to the mind as it is in itself, while, on the other hand, our particular experiences come to us from without. But if we suppose the mind to supply conceptions purely out of itself, what guarantee can we have that these express the real nature of existence? This whole mode of thought rests upon the supposition, that knowledge is partly obtained by the mind's contemplation of itself, and partly by the mind's passive apprehension of what is without itself. Now, this involves a double misapprehension. In the first place, the mind has no nature when it is separated from all objects actual or possible ; and, in the second place, there is no apprehension by the mind of what is without it. (1) Suppose the mind to be absolutely separated from all objects, and it has no conceivable nature. If we try to think of such a mind, we can only describe it by RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 39 negations : we can say, that it is not extended or mov- able or ponderable : in short, that it has none of the predicates by which we may describe the material world. This was clearly enough perceived by Descartes ; and therefore he went on to say, that mind has none of the attributes of matter, but must be defined as a purely thinking substance. It may be shown, however, that mind in complete isolation from matter cannot be defined even as a thinking substance. For about what is it to think? It cannot be a mind which perceives, because perception is of a world of objects whose properties are those of extension, motion, weight, etc., and, by hypothesis, the mind in itself is a substance that has none of these properties and is entirely removed from all contact with them. And if it cannot perceive, neither can the mind reme?nber or imagine ; for remembrance and imagination presuppose perception. I cannot remember what I have never perceived, nor can I imagine anything that is not a re-arrangement of what has been perceived. In this difficulty Descartes falls back upon the view that there are certain conceptions which the mind has by its very nature, — such conceptions as that of God. But the conception of God or the Infinite is not possible apart from the conception of the Finite. If we think of God we must think of Him as the Being who is the source of all existence, and that is impossible if we have no conscious- ness of any existence. Shall we then say, that although the mind has no conception of any object — whether that object is the world or God — it yet has a conception of itself as a pure thinking activity? But a pure thinking activity which thinks nothing is just as inconceivable as a world beyond consciousness or the Infinite in absolute 140 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. separation from the Finite. For there is no possibility of a thinking activity that thinks on nothing. I can think on space or time or the world or God, but how can I think without thinking on anything? Now, to this pure thought, which is the thought of nothing, Descartes is reduced, because he has removed from thought all that can be an object for it. He has, in other words, reduced the mind to the mere possibility or bare capacity of thinking ; but if the mind is the mere capacity of thinking, how can it think itself? A mere capacity cannot think itself as a capacity : to think is the actual exercise of thought, and in this case there can be no actual exercise of thought, because the mind has been reduced to the mere capacity of thinking, a capacity that can never be realized in actual thinking. Plainly, therefore, on Des- cartes' assumption of the absolute separation of the mind from all reality, we are reduced to the idea of a mere potentiality. Nor are we even entitled to call this supposititious mind the potentiality of thinking. If I say that a child is poten- tially a man, I use language that is perfectly intelligible, because I define the character of the potentiality : what I am saying is, that the child has capacities which, when they are realized take the form of the activities characteristic of a feeling, perceiving, thinking being. But if I say that a child is a pure potentiality, without defining the form that this potentiality will take, I am using language that has no precise signification. Of what is the child the poten- tiality, it is naturally asked? Do you mean that he is potentially a plant, or an animal, or a man? Now, Descartes cannot say that the mind is the potentiality of anything, and therefore his language has no precise sig- RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 141 nification. Such a mind is not definable even as mind, since a pure potentiality, if it could be realized, might exhibit the characteristics which Descartes himself ascribes to matter. (2) Descartes' other assumption, that there is an appre- hension by the mind of what is external to it, is equally inadmissible ; it is, in fact, but the other side of his assumption that the mind is an independent substance. The material world is conceived by Descartes as in all respects the opposite of mind. The mind is a pure unity, whereas extended substance is pure diversity, being "in- finitely self-external or divided into partes extra partes ad infinitum? Being thus separated from each other "by the whole diameter of being," the difficulty arises how the mind can know the external world at all. Descartes is practically compelled to assume that we have such knowledge. We do not, he admits, directly apprehend the objective world, but we have experience of mental states which we must suppose to represent it correctly. In other words, matter exists beyond the mind, but its action upon the mind takes the form of immediate im- pressions, which compel us to infer its existence. Now, it may be shown that this doctrine makes the objective world unintelligible. If I know the material world only through certain mental states of my own, I cannot, on Descartes' premises, attribute these to the object. The impressions of colour, heat, weight, are for me merely my own states. If matter is purely self- external and inert, as Descartes affirms, it is not the subject of states of feeling, such as colour, heat, or weight. Of these I must therefore strip matter. But when these are taken away, matter is no longer definable. A matter 142 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. that has neither colour, nor heat, nor weight, is indis- tinguishable from pure extension. This Descartes himself saw, and hence he held the curious doctrine, that wher- ever there is space there is matter. But space is no more knowable on Cartesian principles than matter, since it exists for us only in the form of our own mental states. We must therefore deny even extension to matter. What remains? Simply the bare idea of something that cannot be further defined. All that we can say of it is, that it is that which is capable of acting on the mind. Now, if we bring together the two sides of the Car- tesian doctrine, we get this result : that Mind is the pure capacity of thinking, and Matter the pure capacity of acting. But we have seen that a mere capacity may be the capacity of anything. Hence there is no recogniz- able distinction between mind and matter. The opposi- tion of subject and object disappears, and leaves us with the idea of pure potentiality, and pure potentiality is no reality, being in fact indistinguishable from pure nothing. Thus the Cartesian doctrine of the separation of mind and matter leads to the denial of all knowledge. I have made this criticism of the Cartesian theory of knowledge in order to show that existence cannot be divided up into two antithetical halves. If the objective world is in its nature entirely foreign to the knowing subject, knowledge is impossible. If man can know only his own subjective states, he is necessarily shut out from all apprehension of objective existence. Now, we have already seen that it is a contradiction in terms to affirm that we know reality to be unknowable. Let us then start from the principle that the objective world is not RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 43 essentially foreign to us, but is something that we can know and understand. If that is true, we must hold that the world is in itself essentially rational, i.e., it forms a connected system of things. Because of its rationality, it can be comprehended by reason. Hence, in every act of knowledge, man finds the world to be partially re- ducible to an intelligible system, and the progress of knowledge will just consist in the gradual extension of the consciousness of systematic unity in the world. But in knowledge man not only finds the world to be rational, but he finds that he is himself rational. It is in virtue of his own intelligence that he is capable of finding the world intelligible. And he cannot learn his own ration- ality apart from the process by which he gains a know- ledge of the objective world. Thus the development of the consciousness of what his own nature essentially is, is at the same time a development of his knowledge of objective reality. In man there is a principle, the principle of rationality, which gives him a mastery over the world, just because in the world that rationality is already implied. The whole process of knowledge may thus be viewed either as the development of man's con- sciousness of the world, or as the development of man's consciousness of himself. Now, if knowledge is of this character, it is plain that, just in so far as we have knowledge we are freed from any unintelligible force acting externally upon us. In so far as primitive man learned the properties of the objective world, he was free from their influence. Having this knowledge he was not subject to nature, but he subjected nature to himself. His environment was not something that acted upon him externally, but something 144 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. that he could comprehend and therefore master. The only external force that acted upon him was the force he had not yet learned to understand. And the develop- ment of man has been a continuous process of mastering the world more and more perfectly. When we learn the meaning of any fact — say, the fact of electricity — it ceases to be something foreign to us; it does not master us, but we master it. The only limit to man's subjection of the world to himself is his ignorance. But even this limit is never absolute, firstly, because, even when some special fact is not yet put in its proper place in the whole in- telligible system of things, we yet are conscious that it can be known ; and, secondly, because our ignorance is never absolute, but always rests upon partial knowledge. We may now see, I think, that the principle of natural selection cannot explain the knowledge of man. That principle assumes that man is incapable of rising above his immediate circumstances. Knowledge is supposed to be the product of the action of the environment upon certain inherited tendencies. But these inherited tendencies we have seen to be but another name for the capacity of grasping the nature of the environment; and this capacity cannot be explained as the mere effect of the environment; on the contrary, it implies a compre- hension of the nature of the environment, and the power of adapting it to himself. We must therefore say, that man's knowledge begins in the partial subjection of external circumstances to his ideal of himself, and that the development of knowledge consists in an ever more complete realization of himself by means of an ever greater mastery of the law of the world. In so far as he knows man is free. We might say, in fact, that the RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 1 45 history of man's knowledge is just the history of his sub- stitution of the higher law of reason for the lower law of natural selection. DOES NATURAL SELECTION EXPLAIN MORALITY? It may be shown by similar reasoning that Darwin's attempt to explain morality by means of natural selection is equally unsuccessful. If we accept his view there is no possible freedom of action, and no distinction between morality and nature. (i) There is no freedom, because the actions of man are determined by the natural im- pulse to pleasure, and that impulse again is due to the action of the environment upon the individual's inherited disposition. (2) Nor is there any moral as distinguished from natural activity; for morality is simply a name for the actions that give more pleasure than pain. Now, I have tried to show that knowledge implies freedom, because it lifts man above the flux of immediate impressions and so liberates him from the tyranny of the sensible. Similarly, it may be shown that in his action, as properly understood, man is free because he is not under the dominion of immediate impulses. Darwin tells us that primitive man inherited from his animal progenitors two opposite tendencies — the tendency to seek his own good and the tendency to seek the good of others ; and which of these shall be predominant will depend upon the environment. Look, first, at the supposed selfish tendency or impulse. This tendency in primitive man, we must suppose, took the form of a struggle for his own existence and for the satisfaction of his natural wants. These wants were mainly food and K 146 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. shelter. Man by his nature as a living being had for these a strong desire, and to get them he was ready to sacrifice all other beings. In particular, he had to struggle with the forces of nature and the lower animals, and individual men had to struggle with one another. Observe, however, that the superiority of man over the lower animals, and of one man over another, arises mainly from the fact that he had a better knowledge of the environment, and by means of this knowledge he could turn it to his own use. He made circumstances the means of satisfying his natural wants. But this adapta- tion of means to ends presupposes in man an idea of the end which he desired to obtain. He desired to secure the satisfaction of his natural desire for food and shelter. In other words, he not only possessed the im- pulse to maintain his life, but he grasped so far the meaning of the impulse. Thus primitive man had a conception of himself as capable of being satisfied. This, indeed, was the necessary condition of a selfish struggle for maintenance at the expense of others. There can be no selfishness where there is no consciousness of self. We thus see, that, just as the knowledge of man implies liberation from the crowd of impressions that are per- petually coming and going, so desire implies liberation from the immediate impulses that arise from time to time. If man were merely the passive recipient of impulses that arise on occasion of external stimuli, he could have no consciousness of himself as a possible subject of satisfaction or dissatisfaction. If primitive man, as Darwin says, had a strong tendency to seek his own good, he must have had the consciousness of his own RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 147 good as distinguished from the good of others. He could not seek for the satisfaction of himself, if he had no idea of himself: he could not seek to satisfy himself at the expense of others, unless he contrasted himself with other selves. What Darwin speaks of as a primitive selfish impulse was not a mere impulse : it was not a mere feeling of the absence of pleasure, but the conscious- ness of self as capable of being satisfied and the effort to obtain that satisfaction at whatever cost to others in the way of their dissatisfaction. Obviously, therefore, we cannot explain the desire for self-preservation as due merely to the excitation of an inherited impulse. The natural appetite for food cannot be called a selfish tend- ency; it becomes selfish only when the individual is conscious of the object of appetite, and when setting that object before his consciousness he seeks to realize it irrespective of the claims of others. It is by learning the meaning of his immediate wants that man learns to satisfy them ; he comes to apprehend their law, and to seek in external nature for the means of their satisfaction. Now, as we have seen in the case of knowledge, to grasp the law of things is to gain a mastery over them, and the only limit to this mastery lies in ignorance of their law. So primitive man, appre- hending the object of his appetites and learning the means by which they could be satisfied, was enabled to satisfy his wants, i.e., to satisfy himself. To speak of such purposive activity as the action of external circum- stances upon an inherited disposition is meaningless : the fact is that man, grasping the law of his environment, and grasping the law of his own nature, turns the environ- ment into the means of realizing his ideal self. He is 148 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCEP. not subject to his impulses, but he subjects his impulses to himself. We may see the same thing if we look at what Darwin calls the social impulses. There is a tendency in man to seek the good of others as well as of himself. If so, he must be capable not only of abstracting from his own immediate impulses, but of putting himself at the point of view of others. Not only does he conceive of himself as a possible subject of satisfaction, but he con- ceives of others in the same way. Thus he rises to the point of view of a community of selves, each of which has a claim to self-satisfaction. What he now contrasts is his own possible self with the possible self of others. And he is capable of foregoing a certain form of self- satisfaction in order that others may obtain a more com- plete self-satisfaction. The savage may seek the good of his tribe even at the risk of losing his life. What does this mean? It means that he has 'risen above the ideal of his own individual self, and grasped the idea of a common good. Darwin would explain this higher con- sciousness by saying that the individual feels pain when he acts contrary to the common opinion of his tribe. But, in the first place, this does not account for the common opinion. If the tribe condemn action that has for its end the good of the individual as opposed to the good of the community, it is because there has arisen before their consciousness the ideal of a self that can find genuine satisfaction only in seeking the good of all. It is therefore implied that selfishness is not the way to obtain the satisfaction of the individual. It is implied, in other words, that man is by his very nature social, RELATIONS OF BIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. 149 and forms part of an organism in which the good of each is bound up with the good of all. And, in the second place, the feeling of dissatisfaction experienced by the individual when he acts contrary to the common opinion rests upon the very same consciousness of a self higher than his merely individual self. It is because he has the same consciousness of a social self as is embodied in common opinion that the individual man is dissatisfied with himself when he has sought for the satisfaction of his own separate self at the expense of others. Thus what Darwin calls the " social impulse " really involves the idea of a community of self-conscious beings, all of whom are selves and can find their own satisfaction only in seeking the good of all. To speak of the environment acting on the individual is to leave out of account all that makes sociality intelligible. For the environment here can only mean the constraining power of that higher consciousness of his true self which is revealed to man in virtue of his reason. Learning that his true nature can be realized only by self-identification with the common weal, the individual man is not externally acted upon by a foreign influence. In submitting himself to the law of reason he is submitting himself to his true self, and such submission is true freedom. CHAPTER VIII. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. SPENCER AND THE SCIENTIFIC EVOLUTIONISTS. We have seen that neither man's knowledge nor his moral consciousness can be explained on the principle of natural selection. To know is to be beyond a mere state of passivity : it is to grasp the meaning of existence in virtue of a principle implied in the very nature of the knowing subject ; to will is to realize an ideal presented to himself by the subject, an ideal which he has just because he is not limited to his immediate impulses but can put himself at a universal point of view. The progress of knowledge consists in an ever fuller comprehension of the meaning of the world ; the progress in morality consists in an ever fuller realization of what in his ideal nature man truly is. And these two sides of man's nature — his intelligence and his will — his consciousness of the world and his consciousness of himself — do not develop inde- pendently of each other; for as man learns to comprehend the meaning of the world he also learns to comprehend himself. Now, there is great danger of losing sight of this truth. When we once see that mind cannot be PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 15 r explained on the supposition that the world acts ex- ternally upon it, we are tempted to say that mind is independent of the world and develops apart from it. Starting from this side of the subject, we seem to find that it can know nothing but its own states. Thus we get into a new difficulty. We have seen that there is an apparent conflict between the idea of the finite and the idea of the infinite. We have also seen that there is an apparent conflict between the idea of the world and the idea of self. We have now to consider the apparent conflict between the idea of self and the idea of the world. To some extent this problem has already been dealt with in what was said of the dualism of Descartes. But it will be profitable to consider it in the form in which it has been presented in our own day. I shall therefore state and examine the doctrine of Mr. Herbert Spencer on this point, a doctrine which has secured a number of adherents. There is one datum of consciousness, Mr. Spencer tells us, that must be assumed by every philosophy, viz., the absolute distinction of subject and object. The world of mind and the world of matter are mutually exclusive j or, as Mr. Spencer puts it, subject and object are "antithetically opposed divisions of the entire assemblage of things." We can analyze our idea of the subject and find out the elements implied in it, and similarly we can reduce our idea of the object to its simplest terms; but there is no possibility of reducing these two ideas further : we cannot identify the subject with the object, or the object with the subject. The distinction of subject and object is "the consciousness of a difference transcending all other differences." 1 This 1 Psychology ; § 62. 152 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. consciousness must be accepted, because its opposite is not only unbelievable but unthinkable. If I say, "The subject is the object," I have framed a proposition that contradicts itself; for the two terms, "subject" and "object," cannot by any effort be brought before con- sciousness in that relation which the proposition asserts between them; in other words, to identify subject and object contradicts the very idea of subject and of object, because the idea of the one is absolutely distinct from the idea of the other. The attempt to think sub- ject as object, or object as subject, is as futile as the attempt to think of a square as round, or to think of a straight line as bent. Now, when a proposition cannot by any possibility be thought, its opposite must be true, i.e. t we must hold the truth of the proposition, " The subject is not identical with the object." Now, there is no doubt that Mr. Spencer, in affirming that subject and object, mind and matter, are absolutely distinct from each other, is affirming what the plain man would accept as palpably true. I perceive that tree before me, but / am not the tree : I am a perceiving, conscious, thinking being, whereas the tree has no per- ception, no consciousness, no thought. The tree, it will be said, has properties that distinguish it toto coelo from me, the subject that perceives it; and therefore the sub- ject is quite distinct in nature from the object. Mr. Spencer can therefore apparently find support for his opposition of subject and object in the ordinary con- sciousness of men. But it is very doubtful if the man of common sense would be willing to follow Mr. Spencer when he goes on to reduce subject and object to their lowest terms. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 153 What is the nature of the object and of the subject? The moment Mr. Spencer proceeds to answer this question, it becomes obvious that his conceptions of object and subject are very different from those ordinarily held. Mr. Spencer, then, starts from the opposition of sub- ject and object, and then he goes on to ask how the subject comes to have a knowledge, or an apparent knowledge, of the object. When we speak of the ob- jective world we are thinking of sensible things in space and time; or, in Mr. Spencer's words, of "relations of sequence and relations of coexistence." How do we get a knowledge of these relations? Mr. Spencer's answer is, that we are conscious of a relation of sequence in every change of consciousness. I may have a series of impressions of sound, and the consciousness of this series gives me the apprehension of the relation of sequence. But I obtain the same apprehension in the consciousness of any series of impressions whatever. Thus, my per- ception of the colour of this desk is given in a succession of impressions of colour; and so also is my apprehension of its hardness and smoothness, its resistance and weight. Primarily, therefore, all our perceptions take the form of a succession of impressions. States of consciousness are serial, not coexistent. Originally, therefore, we have a consciousness only of the relation of sequence, not of the relation of coexistence. How, then, do we advance from the consciousness of sequence to the consciousness of coexistence ? How, out of a succession of impressions, do we obtain the consciousness of what is not successive? Mr. Spencer's answer is, that there are certain sequences of impression that do not occur in a fixed order, but can be taken in any order. The series of impressions 154 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. called sounds come in a certain order, but the series of impressions called colours, or tastes, may appear in a different order. Thus, I can apprehend the colour of this desk either by running my eye along the surface from left to right or from right to left. Thus we come to distinguish between sequences proper, and sequences which are only successive in our apprehension. The former is the consciousness of the relation of sequence, the latter the consciousness of the relation of coexistence. Now, we have many experiences of these two kinds of relation, and hence we form an abstract conception of sequence and an abstract conception of coexistence. The abstract of all sequences is time. The abstract of all coexistence is space. You will observe that Mr. Spencer here assumes that the individual has a direct consciousness only of his own impressions. For him the properties of the object exist only as a series of states in his own mind, and it is out of this series that he constructs the consciousness of coexistence. There is, Mr. Spencer would say, a cor- respondence between the states of the subject and the properties of the object, but not an identity. This correspondence he explains more fully in treating of the relation between mental states or " feelings " and the nervous changes that accompany, but are distinct from, these feelings. The parallelism is set forth with great minuteness. Thus, (a) nervous action occupies appreci- able time, and so also does feeling ; (&) each nervous action leaves a partial incapacity for a like nervous action, so each feeling leaves a partial incapacity for a like feeling j (c) other things being equal, the intensities of feelings vary as the intensities of the correlative nervous PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 55 actions \ (d) the difference between direct and indirect nervous disturbances corresponds to the difference between the vivid feelings we call real and the faint feelings we call ideal. But the parallelism is even closer. We are apt to suppose that the individual sensations and emotions we experience are absolutely simple. But they are not really so. A musical sound, for example, is supposed to be a simple feeling. If equal blows or taps are made one after another at a rate not exceeding some sixteen per second, the effect of each is perceived as a separate noise ; but when the rapidity with which the blows follow one another exceeds this, the noises are no longer identified in separate states of consciousness, and there arises a continuous state of consciousness called a tone. Thus an apparently simple feeling is really composed of various feelings. Now we must suppose, in the same way, that all kinds of feelings are really complex, though apparently simple. Nay, must we not suppose that all feelings are made up of elements that in the last analysis are absolutely identical in their nature? To this prim- ordial element of consciousness a nervous shock of no appreciable duration may be supposed to correspond. You will see from this how far Mr. Spencer has travelled from the point of view of common sense. The mind he conceives as made up of ultimate units of feel- ing, absolutely identical in their nature, just as all nerve action is reducible to simple indistinguishable nervous shocks. The subject, in other words, is in its ultimate nature not the subject that we ordinarily suppose it to be, but a collection of primitive atoms of feeling, just as the object is a collection of primitive units of force. 156 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. Thus the whole complex variety of existence disappears, and what is left is a subject composed of indistinguish- able units of feeling, and an object composed of indis- tinguishable units of force. Mr. Spencer thinks that he has thus proved the in- dependence of subject and object, while he has at the same time established their correspondence. We can reduce the subject to units of feeling, and the object to units of force; but we cannot reduce units of feeling to units of force : this is the " difference transcending all other differences," the distinction "never to be tran- scended while consciousness lasts." There is one diffi- culty, however, in maintaining this absolute dualism of subject and object to which Mr. Spencer himself refers. If the subject is absolutely separated from the object, how does it ever apprehend the nature of the object? As a conscious subject I am aware only of my own feelings ; how then do I know that the object is com- posed of units of force? For me force presents itself simply as a feeling of resistance, and a feeling is separated from a unit of force by the whole diameter of being. No relation of consciousness, as Mr. Spencer admits, " can resemble, or be in any way akin " to the actual relations of things. Hence we must say, that "beyond consciousness" there are "conditions of objective mani- festation which are symbolized by relations as we conceive them." These conditions we cannot know ; yet we are compelled to hold that the distinction of units of feeling and units of motion is a distinction relative to our con- sciousness : it is " one and the same Ultimate Reality, which is manifested to us subjectively and objectively." But while the nature of that which is manifested under PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 157 either form proves to be inscrutable, the order of its manifestations throughout all mental phenomena proves to be the same as the order of its manifestations through- out all material phenomena. Mr. Spencer holds, in short, that we do not know reality in its absolute nature, but we find that it presents itself to us in two parallel forms, which correspond exactly to each other. The develop- ment of the one goes on pari passu with the develop- ment of the other. For example, the nervous system is in the lower animals indefinite and incoherent, but as higher forms emerge there is a gradual advance in integra- tion, complexity, and definiteness. So mind in the lower animals is simple, vague, and incoherent, but when we pass to man, we find that there is a remarkable differentiation and complexity. We must hold, then, on the one hand, that there never is a feeling without a corresponding nerve- movement, or a nerve-movement without a correspond- ing feeling; but, on the other hand, we must maintain that each is but a manifestation of a single reality which to us appears in these two forms. In other words, if we could contemplate reality as it truly is, we should find that in it the distinction of subject and object is abolished; but the character of our intelligence makes it impossible for us to get beyond the absolute dualism of subject and object, because that dualism is the fundamental condition of consciousness itself. Mr. Spencer's conclusion then is, that we cannot know the ultimate nature of mind any more than we can know the ultimate nature of matter. Granted that a feeling in consciousness and a molecular motion are the subjective and objective faces of the same thing; yet "we are incap- able of uniting the two, so as to conceive that reality of 158 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. which they are the opposite faces." Consider how we are forced to present each to our consciousness. What for us is matter ? It is a complex of states of conscious- ness, which have objective counterparts that to us are unknown. What is mind for us? It is a synthesis of many feelings, and of the many changes among them. We infer that all our feelings are probably formed of ultimate units of feeling or mental shocks, but we cannot think of such shocks except as undergone by an actual substance. Now "we can form no notion of a substance of mind that has no attributes, and all such attributes! are abstracted from our experiences of material phenomena.! How can we think of the changes of consciousness except I as caused, and how can we think of any cause except as I some form of motion ? " ' " See then," says Mr. Spencer, " our predicament. We can think of matter only in terms of mind. We can think of mind only in terms of matter. When we have pushed our explorations of the first to the uttermost limit, we are referred to the second for a final answer, and when we have got the final answer of the second, we are referred back to the first for an interpretation of it. We find the value of x in terms of y ; then we find the value of y in terms of x ; and so on we may continue for ever without coming nearer to a solution. The anti- thesis of subject and object, never to be transcended while consciousness lasts, renders impossible all knowledge of that Ultimate Reality in which subject and object are united." The true conclusion is, that "it is one and the same Ultimate Reality which is manifested to us subjectively and objectively." 1 1 Psychology, §§ 272, 273. \ PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 59 Mr. Spencer, then, holds that there is no way of re- ducing mind to matter, or matter to mind. To the same effect Dr. Tyndall tells us that " the passage from the physics of the brain to the corresponding facts of con- sciousness is unthinkable. Granted that a definite thought and a definite molecular action in the brain occur simul- taneously, we do not possess the intellectual organ . . . which would enable us to pass by a process of reasoning from the one to the other. They appear together, but we do not know why." And Professor Huxley says, " I know nothing whatever, and never hope to know any- thing, of the steps by which the passage from molecular movement to states of consciousness is effected." Now, if we accept this absolute dualism of subject and object, mind and matter, we must be prepared to say that we can know nothing of the ultimate nature of reality : our consciousness of self is in irreconcilable antagonism to our consciousness of the world. And this involves no less than a surrender of the special problem of philo- sophy, the problem to find a unity which shall compre- hend and explain all differences. Before committing ourselves to this hopeless view of the problem of know- ledge, we must ask whether the fault may not lie rather in a false theory than in the limited nature of our intelli- gence. The following propositions are maintained by Mr. Spencer : i st. We are conscious of an absolute distinction between subject and object, mind and matter. 2nd. The object is conceivable only as a complex of feelings or mental states; the subject only as a complex of movements. 160 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. 3rd. The ultimate constituents of the subject as known are simple feelings, the ultimate constituents of the object as known are simple movements. 4th. There is an exact correspondence, but no connec- tion, between the feelings of the subject and the movements of the object. 5th. In their real nature subject and object are iden- tical, though we are unable to comprehend that identity. "All which propositions," to apply the famous words of Carlyle, " I must modestly but peremptorily and irre- vocably deny." The ground on which I base that denial may be best understood by an examination of the first of these propositions, on which all the others depend. EXAMINATION OF MR. SPENCER'S OPPOSITION OF SUBJECT AND OBJECT. The fundamental proposition which Mr. Spencer seeks to establish is, that subject and object are for us absolutely exclusive of each other, because their separation is bound up with the very nature of consciousness. By no effort can I think of subject as object, or object as subject. The elimination of this distinction would be at the same time the destruction of consciousness. Now, it may be shown that Mr. Spencer has here con- fused two quite distinct propositions : firstly, that we are conscious of the subject as separate from the object, and, secondly, that we are conscious of the subject as distinguishable from the object. But, so far from these two propositions being identical, they are contradictory the one of the other. The first is false, the second is true; and it is because Mr. Spencer seems to be affirming PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. l6l the second, when in reality his theory compels him to deny it, that he is apt to get credit for making out his case. I shall therefore begin by pointing out the dis- tinction between these opposite propositions. (a) If I say that I am conscious of the subject as separate from the object, I am claiming that I can conceive the subject by itself, without in any way introducing the conception of the object. Now, we saw in considering the dualism of Descartes that this is impossible. Remove from the conception of the subject all relation to an object, and what remains is not the pure subject, but a pure blank. The very meaning of subject is that which is relative to an object. If the subject is not conscious of an object, it cannot be conscious at all, and in the absence of all consciousness the subject has no properties by which it may be thought. Perhaps it may be answered that the object of which the subject is conscious is simply its own state, and that in being conscious of this state it has an object before it, but not the external object. In this case, we shall have to say, that we can think of the subject as conscious of its own states — as conscious of an internal object — without thinking of it as conscious of anything beyond its own states, i.e., any external object. This in fact is what Mr. Spencer does say : he tells us that for the subject the object is always simply its own feelings. We must now suppose the subject with its own states to stand on one side, and the external object with its properties to stand on the other side ; and the contention is, that we can think of the subject as conscious of an internal object, without thinking of an external object at all. Now, a subject conscious only of its own states would l62 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. manifestly never become conscious of any external object. For, if it should ever break through the charmed circle of its own inner life, and get even a glimpse of the object asserted to lie beyond, it would no longer be confined to the internal object, but would have passed over to the external object. Remember, now, that the subject which is so confined to a purely internal life is the human subject. Mr. Spencer must therefore suppose that in his con- sciousness he is absolutely confined to his own internal states, or, in other words, can have no idea of any object other than those states — no idea, that is, of an external object. But if so, the primary datum of consciousness cannot be the absolute distinction of subject from object, by which is meant the absolute distinction of the internal life of the subject from an external reality lying beyond. The primary datum of consciousness must be the con- sciousness simply of self and the states of self. The subject can neither perceive nor imagine anything but his own states, and therefore the supposed opposition of internal subject and external object is for him impossible. The external object has vanished. (b) We have seen then that the consciousness of a separate and independent subject, having no relation to any external object, leads to the denial of all objectivity, i.e., of all reality other than the states of the subject. Let us now see whether the same difficulty besets the proposition, that subject and object are distinguishable but not separable. I can distinguish a centre from a circumference, the one end of a stick from the other, an inside from an outside, the convex and concave sides of a sphere; but can I separate either from the other ? Manifestly not : it is PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 63 impossible to think of a centre without relating it to a circle, of one end apart from the other, an inside without an outside, convex without concave. The question is whether subject and object are not of this nature : dis- tinguishable but not separable. We have already seen the difficulties into which we are driven if we suppose the subject to be separate from the object, and to be aware only of its own states. These difficulties suggest that subject and object are not really separable; but, on the other hand, there seem to be as grave difficulties in the way of accepting the doctrine that they are only ideally, not really separable ; and of these we must take account. That subject and object are absolutely diverse in their nature, and therefore exist in complete independence of each other, seems to be at first sight a simple statement of an undoubted fact. The dualism of subject and object is apparently indubitable, whether we look at the nature of the one or of the other. Look first at the object. (a) If it is said that the object is of the same nature as the subject, it is naturally objected that the object has a nature of its own independently of any knowledge of it by the subject, and independently even of the existence of the subject. (1) The existence and nature of the objective world, it is said, is not dependent upon the knowledge of its nature by any human being. The fire goes out whether I am asleep or awake; visible things are continually undergoing changes that have no dependence upon the apprehension of them by man ; gravitation acts whether I know it to act or not. What knowledge reveals to me is what already exists, not what comes into being only 164 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. when I apprehend it. Were it otherwise, it may be said, things would be continually coming into existence and going out of existence. Nothing, in fact, would exist except at the moment when it was present to somebody's consciousness. And this leads to manifold absurdities. To suppose that the world in which we dwell, and the infinite host of heaven, are continually created and destroyed as they are or are not objects of human con- sciousness is the greatest of all absurdities. It is the dream of men who are so intoxicated with ideas, that they have lost all hold of facts. The theory even implies that there are as many objects as their subjects. For the object of each conscious subject will be distinct. Plainly, therefore, the existence and nature of the object is not dependent upon the knowledge of the subject. (2) Again, the existence of the objective world is in- dependent of the existence of the subject, because it existed prior to the existence of the subject. We know that, long before conscious beings were on the earth, there were other forms of existence. There was a time when our whole solar system was as yet unformed. It was after millions of years that the primitive nebulous matter shaped itself into distinct worlds, and millions of years elapsed before man appeared on the scene. How then can it be denied that the object is independent of the subject? Can any one seriously maintain, that the object cannot exist without the subject, when the object as a matter of fact did exist before there was any subject? (b) The independence of the subject seems to be equally manifest. We say that the subject cannot be of the same nature as the object, 'because its properties are distinct from those of the object. By the object we mean a PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 65 form of existence which is neither conscious nor self- conscious ; by the subject we mean a form of existence which is both. A stone is not conscious of other objects, nor is it conscious of its own properties. It is not aware that it is one of an infinite number of things, partly similar, partly different ; nor does it perceive itself to be hard, figured, coloured, or to have weight. The subject, on the other hand, is conscious of many other forms of existence besides itself, and of its own peculiar character as a knowing and willing being. How, then, can it be said that the subject is of the same essential nature as the object? THE IDEALISTIC VIEW OF THE WORLD. These, then, are some of the objections that may be made to the idealistic view of the universe, which maintains that subject and object are of the same essential nature, and can only be logically distinguished, not really separated. I shall take them up in their order. (a) It is objected that the object is independent of the subject, because it exists and has a nature of its own whether it is known by the subject or not. What is the "subject" here spoken of, which is declared to have no power of affecting the object? Manifestly, the individual human subject — this man or that — the subject that may either know or not know the object. Now, the conception of existence which underlies this objection is that individualistic or dualistic conception which we have seen Mr. Spencer to hold. It sets on the one side a number of individual things in space and time, and, on the other side, it sets a number of individual things each endowed with the faculty of knowledge, and 1 66 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. it maintains that the former are real apart from the latter. The changes of things in space and time go on irrespective of the changes which go on in the knowing subjects that stand apart from them. Now, there is no doubt that we do look at object and subject from this point of view, and for certain purposes it is sufficient. If I wish to observe the properties of gold, I may take a par- ticular piece of gold, and, viewing it as if it were a separate and distinct thing, I may note its properties. Thus the chemist finds that gold has this peculiar property, that it is soluble in aqua regia. On the other hand, I may make the knowing subject an object of observation, and I may observe that the subject in knowing is con- tinually passing from one mental state to another, and that these mental states never occur except when certain changes take place in the sensitive organism. Here, again, I am treating the subject as if he were a separate individual, whose whole nature can be determined simply by observation of the changes through which he passes. It is from this point of view that the external object seems to have a nature of its own, apart from the know- ing subject, which also has a nature of its own. If, therefore, any one should say that the external object is not independent of the subject, the answer seems obvious, that by its very nature as revealed in observa- tion, it manifestly is independent, since it possesses different properties and goes through changes that are in no way dependent upon the properties and the changes of the knowing subject. And the answer is undoubtedly convincing when it is directed against any one who admits the fundamental assumption, that there are individual things, external and internal. If the objective world can PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 167 be properly described as made up of a number of in- dividual things, and if we can similarly speak of a number of individual subjects, it is absurd to say that the former are of the same nature as the latter. Just as an acid differs in its properties from an alkali, so all external objects differ from all knowing subjects in having pro- perties not found in the latter. But the question arises whether either the object or the subject can be correctly described as individual things having properties peculiar to themselves. Is not this conception of existence false, when viewed from the highest point of view, however useful it may be from the point of view of mere observation ? The objective world, from the individualistic point of view, is made up of a number of individual things in space and time, and each of these is supposed to possess properties peculiar to itself. Now, we have already seen that, so far as the existence of objects in space and time is concerned, no object has a property peculiar to itself. The position of anything in space or time is determined by the position of other things. In other words, the existence of one thing is possible only because it is relative to the existence of all other things. There is only one object or world, and what are distinguished as individual objects are merely particular aspects, from which the one object or world may be viewed. And the same thing holds good if we look at the other pro- perties of the objective world. Weight does not belong as a separate property to this or that thing; it is a pro- perty which is constituted by the fact that all the things which we distinguish by their position tend to move towards one another at a certain rate. Similarly, what 1 68 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. we call the chemical properties of sensible things are relations, belonging to things not as individual, but as parts of a single universe. Hydrogen and oxygen are relations between things, not properties attaching to things in their isolation and independence. Speaking of the objective world in the ordinary sense of external reality, i.e. t reality in space and time, we find that it is not made up of separate things, but is a single indivisible unity of which all the supposed separate things are but phases or aspects. Now, it is true that when we have reached the conclusion that there is only one object or world, not a number of individual objects, we have still left opposed to it a number of individual sub- jects, each having a specific existence and nature of its own ; i.e., we have still left an apparently absolute opposi- tion between subject and object. But, if we have found that there are no absolutely individual objects, is it not reasonable to suppose that there are no absolutely in- dividual subjects? So far we have spoken of the objective world as if it comprehended only inorganic existence. But this is mani- festly an arbitrary limitation. For organized beings are not less real than inorganic things, and therefore we must enlarge our conception of the object so as to include those forms of existence that we distinguish as living. Is organized existence, then, of such a character that it can be described as purely individual ? Can we say that there is any plant, or any animal, that lives a life of its own, independently of all relation to other modes of existence? Now, it is at once manifest that we cannot find among living beings any separate and independent individual, PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 69 any more than among non-living things. In the first place, a living being — whether plant or animal — is on one side of its nature plainly a part of the objective world. It has a bodily structure, which displays the same characteristics as other bodies. Thus it is in space and time, it is subject to the laws of dynamics, and it passes through chemical changes. What has been said of individual things as inorganic therefore applies equally to organic things so far as their bodily structure is concerned. That is to say, no living being is an independent individual, but is merely a distinguishable aspect of the one great systematic whole, the object or world. Apart from this whole, it could have no exist- ence. We must therefore widen our conception of the object, and include within it all living beings, so far as these are viewed as having a bodily structure. But can we stop here? Can we say that in their bodily structure living beings belong to the objective world, while as to their characteristics as living, they are independent individuals? Now, there is no doubt that living beings display characteristics not found in non- living beings. They all, as we have seen, exhibit a tendency to maintain themselves and to continue their species. But this tendency can be realized only in so far as they conform to the conditions of their environ- ment. The possibility of maintaining themselves is there- fore possible only in so far as that possibility is implied in the nature of the external world. The living being has a peculiar form of existence, but like other forms it is bound up with the nature of existence as a whole. If it could separate itself from the world, it would cease to be, because the very nature of its existence is, that it I70 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. can realize itself only as part of the world. Now, if we find that living beings cannot be separated from other forms of existence, is it not obvious that we must revise our conception of the objective world, and include within it, not merely inorganic existence, and organic existence as to its bodily structure, but organic existence viewed as organic? In other words, by the "object" we must now designate all modes of existence, whether inorganic or organic. The object is therefore not only a systematic unity of parts, but it is in the strict sense an organic unity, i.e., a unity which implies life. But this means that each individual has a life of its own only in so far as it exhibits within itself the life that is implied in the world as a whole. The life of the individual is thus one phase of the universal life that pulsates through all existence. Change in the smallest degree the laws of any form of existence, and life becomes impossible. Nor can we give any preference to inorganic as distinguished from organic existence ; for organic existence is not less real than inorganic. The only way in which it may plausibly be shown that the objective world is not an organic unity is by attempting to reduce life to the mere play of mechanical forces. But the futility of this attempted reduction has already been shown. The differentiation and development of living beings can be explained only on the supposition that by their very nature they have an impulse to self-maintenance and a tendency to organiz- ation. And this impulse and this tendency they could not possess were its possibility not bound up with the very nature of the world. The world or object is there- fore something more than a system of mechanical forces: PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 171 it is a unity containing within itself the principle of life. From what has been said, it follows that the object must now be conceived to include all modes of existence, organic as well as inorganic. If, therefore, it is still maintained that the object is independent of the sub- ject, this can only mean, that, while all other modes of existence are related to one another in one single system, there is one form of existence which is outside of this system, and belongs to a separate and independent sphere. This mode of existence is mind or consciousness. Now, it must be observed that we do not find mind existing independently of the objective world. Just as there can be no form of life apart from the whole system of external nature, so there can be no form of mind apart from the organism. We find in animals a peculiar faculty, the faculty of feeling, which is not possessed by any other form of being. And we find in man a still higher faculty, the faculty of consciousness. But con- sciousness is not something that exists irrespective of animal sensation. Just as by means of sensation the animal feels within itself a thrill which expresses the nature of what lies beyond its own organism, so in con- sciousness man comes to understand and to interpret the sensations and impulses which, as an animal, he possesses. He not only feels but thinks. Now, if the life of consciousness as it exists in man presupposes the life of sensation and impulse, it is plain that any attempt to isolate the conscious subject from the sensitive subject must result in emptying conscious- ness of all content. For in his sensitive life man expresses the life which pervades and gives meaning to all objective 172 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. existence. To suppose that he can apprehend the nature of existence irrespective of sensation, is to suppose that he can apprehend existence without apprehending it. If in the sensitive life the objective world as a whole is implied, to turn away from sensation is to turn away from the objective world. There is therefore no conscious sub- ject that can be separated from the sensitive subject. And this means that no conscious subject is a separate individual. It is true that by no possibility can con- sciousness be identified with sensation. To suppose such an identification is to overlook what is characteristic of consciousness. But while consciousness cannot be identified with sensation, any more than sensation can be identified with chemical action, it is none the less true that con- sciousness is possible only on presupposition of sensation. The individual subject can have no knowledge of objective existence apart from the changing sensations and impulses which are characteristic of his animal life. And the life of feeling, as we have seen, is made possible by the relations which subsist between the feeling subject and all other modes of existence. To apprehend the mean- ing of feeling is therefore to apprehend the meaning of existence as a whole, /.*., to grasp those various aspects under which the one object may be viewed. Unless the conscious subject is capable of such apprehension, he is incapable of knowing reality as it is. But if his conscious life were something entirely apart from his sensitive life, he could know no objective reality. And without such knowledge he could not apprehend himself. Thus to be conscious of himself is to be conscious that he is related to all other modes of existence, and that apart from such relation he could not exist. But if so, he knows PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 73 himself as at once a being who manifests in himself the life of the whole, and a being who is conscious of the life of the whole. From the former point of view, he is a form of the objective world; in other words, the consciousness which presents itself in man is a conscious- ness that belongs to the very nature of existence. For consciousness is not, as we have seen, something that can be separated from other modes of reality, nor is it something that can be reduced to other modes of reality. None the less, it is possible only because the nature of existence as a whole makes it possible. If consciousness were incompatible with the nature of the universe, it could not be : since it is, it must be regarded as a mode, and the highest mode in which existence presents itself. We must therefore revise our view of the nature of objective existence, and say that it includes not only all inorganic and organic things, but that it includes as well all conscious beings. In other words, the consciousness of man is a form and the highest form in which existence appears. The individual man can have no consciousness apart from the one unity which comprehends all existence. But if existence manifests itself as conscious, we must find in the conception of it as conscious its true meaning. The object when properly understood is therefore identical with the subject. If, in other words, the subject as dis- tinguished from the object is that which not only is, but knows itself to be, the object as embracing in its reality the subject must now be defined as that which not only is a systematic unity, but knows itself to be a systematic unity. But this is the same as saying that the objective world properly understood is self-conscious intelligence, or, in ordinary language, is God. 174 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. In this short outline of the proof of intellectual idealism, I have tried to show how, beginning with the first imperfect definition of the object as that which is in space and time, we are forced gradually to widen our definition until we find it embrace all existence. If this proof is at all sound, it follows that there can be no real separation between object and subject. The supposed opposition of subject and object turns out to be simply a distinction in our point of view. When we are looking at the manifestations of intelligence, we speak of the object or world ; when we are thinking of the intelligence which so manifests itself, we speak of the subject; but as the manifestations are those of intelligence, and intelligence is what it manifests, the distinction is no real separation. When, therefore, Mr. Spencer tells us that " the distinction of subject and object" is one "never to be transcended while consciousness lasts," we answer that, so far from this being true, the transcendence of the distinction is necessarily implied in the very nature of consciousness. It is in the apprehension of the object that man apprehends himself; in other words, man learns that all existence is rational, and that he himself is rational, because in his intelligence there is contained the same principle as is implied in all existence. We can now deal very easily with the objection that I have supposed to be raised against the idealist view of existence. It is said that the object must be inde- pendent of the subject because it exists whether the subject knows it or not. Certainly, I answer : the individual subject in coming to the knowledge of the object does not bring the object into existence. No sane man makes any such assertion. But this does not show that the PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. I 75 individual subject could have knowledge, were the object generically different from the subject; on the contrary, it shows that it is by coming to a consciousness of what the object is he has knowledge at all. And this means, as we have seen, that the object properly understood includes the subject, or is intelligence. To grasp the nature of the world is thus to apprehend existence as intelligence, and from the point of view of its intelligible nature : it is to see that existence is not only purposive but rational. (p) The second objection to the identity of subject and object was, that the objective world existed before the subject existed. If there was existence before conscious beings came to be, how can it be denied that the objective world is independent of the subject? This objection is usually urged by scientific evolutionists, who maintain that inorganic things preceded organic, and that living beings without consciousness preceded conscious beings. Now (i) the first thing to observe here is, that this objection rests upon the same individualistic assumption as the former objection. It is taken for granted that to deny the dependence of the inorganic world upon this or that individual subject is to prove its absolute independ- ence. But we have already seen that there is no purely individual subject, no conscious being who is conscious in virtue of something belonging to his own individual existence ; and hence to say that the inorganic world does not depend for its existence upon man, regarded as an individual, by no means proves that the inorganic world can exist by itself. This latter proposition can only be established if it is shown that in the whole realm of 176 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. existence there is nothing that cannot be included in the idea and definition of matter ; in other words, that without going beyond the conception of existence as extended, moving, and exhibiting physical and chemical properties, we can explain not only organized but even conscious existence. Now, it has already been pointed out, that it is impossible to account even for life, and much less for consciousness, without widening our definition of the object so as to include the new characteristics peculiar to life and consciousness ; and hence that the supposition of the separate existence of the inorganic world is an untenable hypothesis. But (2) the objection we are now considering introduces a new difficulty, drawn from the succession in time of the various orders of existence. The inorganic first existed, it is said, and out of it proceeded, by the operation of ordinary mechanical laws, the forms of existence that we call organic; and similarly, the organic existed prior to conscious existence, and gave rise to it j hence, ultimately, all modes of existence have proceeded from matter. This is the line of thought by which Tyndall, for example, tries to show that matter contains in itself " the promise and potency of all kinds of life." Now (a) you will observe that, if this argument is pressed to its consequences, the conclusion must be that conscious- ness is simply a mode of matter. The prior existence of matter, it is held, shows that matter was the cause of life and consciousness. Living beings, who did not yet exist, could not be the cause of their own existence, and hence we must attribute their existence to the only cause that existed, i.e., to matter. If this argument is sound, we must hold that consciousness contains in itself nothing PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 177 that is not due to matter; in other words, we must hold that mind and matter are identical in their nature. But if so, we can no longer maintain that the conscious subject is independent of the object; we must, on the contrary, maintain that the only existence is the object, and that the supposed independence of subject and object, mind and matter, is a conception which a scientific view of the world shows to be false. On TyndalPs own show- ing, therefore, subject and object are irreducible only in the sense that they are supposed to be irreducible by those who have not reached the scientific point of view. It is true that he still maintains that we are unable to conceive of the identification of subject and object; but this can only consistently mean that we are unable to get rid of a deeply rooted preconception. We cannot maintain, both that mind is a product of matter, and that mind is independent of matter : the reasoning by which we establish the former proposition, precludes the possibility of the latter. Thus we find that the very argument by which it is sought to show that the object is independent of the subject leads to the conclusion that there is no such independence. The object is indeed independent of the subject, but only in the sense that there is no subject. We have not established the separation of mind from matter, but abolished mind altogether. I shall try to show that instead of thus reducing mind to matter, we must hold that matter is a form of mind. Inorganic existence, it is said, existed prior to life and consciousness, and therefore life and consciousness are the product of inorganic existence. The assumption here is, that consciousness is related to matter as effect to I78 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. cause. Before we can admit the validity of this assump- tion, we must be certain that the relation between con- sciousness and matter can be conceived as a relation of effect and cause. Now, it is easy to show that the conception of causality here made use of is, at any rate, not the conception that is employed in scientific inquiries. When a scientific man asks what is the cause of the motion of a material body, his aim is to find out the particular conditions which account for this particular event, and the answer that he gives consists in stating those particular conditions. He points out the circum- stances that have to take place before the particular event in question can happen. In all cases the circumstances are some form of motion, because in external things change always takes the form of motion. But when the particular mode of motion assigned as the cause of a particular change has been discovered, nothing has been determined in regard to the nature of existence as a whole; all that has been done is to point out the special relation between two events. The idea of cause and effect, in other words, has a perfectly intelligible meaning when it is employed in explanation of particular events, but it does not follow that it has an intelligible meaning when it is employed to explain existence as a whole. When we pass from the one point of view to the other, we must ask whether we have not changed our conception. Now, if it is said that matter is the cause of life and consciousness, it is plain that by matter cannot here be meant any particular form of material existence. There never is in an effect something essentially different from what is found in the cause. A material body can be called a cause only in this sense, that its motion is the PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 179 condition of a motion in another body. The reason for distinguishing a material body from a living or a con- scious being is, that while the changes in the former are all modes of motion, the changes in the latter are not modes of motion, but modes of life and consciousness. Now, if a material body, or any number of material bodies, is called the cause of life and consciousness, it is assumed that life and consciousness can be explained simply as modes of motion. If, however, the latter are modes of motion, there is no production of life and consciousness by matter, because there is no life or consciousness to be produced. The contradiction, there- fore, to which the conception of matter as the cause of life and consciousness leads is this : If life and con- sciousness are distinct from matter, they cannot be its effects; and, if they are effects of matter, there is no distinction between them and matter. The ordinary con- ception of cause and effect thus breaks down when we try to explain by it the relation between matter on the one hand, and life and consciousness on the other. If we hold that matter has a real existence independently of life and consciousness, we cannot at the same time hold that it is the cause of these. Now the lesson to be learned from this is, that the conception of cause and effect as it is employed in scientific investigation is not adequate as a conception of the relation between existence as a whole and its various modes. We may, if we please, still use the term "cause" to express the relation, but we must give to it a new meaning. Let us see what that meaning is. Prior to the existence of living beings, there existed inorganic things. Did these inorganic things exist as l8o COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. separate individuals, or were they only distinguishable aspects of the one systematic unity? The latter, as we have seen, is the true conception. We have there- fore to conceive of existence prior to the appearance of life, as one single organic whole. But this organic whole had manifested itself only as that which passed through mechanical, physical, and chemical changes. Now, these changes were not related to the whole as effect to cause; they were simply the distinguishable aspects in which the one universe presented itself. These aspects can be viewed as related to one another in the way of cause and effect, but the universe as a whole is not a cause of which all these aspects are effects; or, at least, if we call it a cause, we mean simply that it is a principle of unity manifesting itself in all change. So conceived, cause must now be regarded as self-cause. That is to say, there is nothing outside of the one unity which explains or accounts for it, since beyond it there is nothing : the only cause to which we can assign it is itself. All forms of existence are therefore explained by this unity, but the unity itself is not explained by anything else. Now, take another step. At a certain period life makes its appearance. Whence did this life proceed? It proceeded, the scientific evolutionist tells us, from in- organic nature. "Were not man's origin implicated," says Tyndall, "we should accept without a murmur the derivation of animal life from what we call inorganic nature." This language suggests that life is the pro- duct or effect of that which is without life, i.e., that all the particular living beings which first appeared on the earth were originated by particular inorganic things. The PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. l8l radical imperfection of this view has already been pointed out. No individual thing originates anything ; for every individual is what it is only by reference to the whole system of the universe. What is implied in the origination of life is not that inorganic nature produced life, but that a new form of existence presented itself at a certain period of time in the history of the earth. But this life, although it has for the first time presented itself is not something that has come into being by a power belonging to inorganic things. And no one would be so absurd as to say that it originated from itself. Its origination can be explained only on the supposition that it was implicit in the nature of existence as a whole. Outside of the unity that comprehends all possible existence there is nothing; and therefore life, when it appears, merely manifests in an explicit form what was already wrapped up in the one single existence that is manifested in all modes of existence. But, if this one all-inclusive unity is now seen to involve within itself organic as well as inorganic existence, its nature cannot be comprehended by looking at either apart from the other. It is neither inorganic nor organic, but both. Further, organic existence is of this nature that, while it contains all that is implied in inorganic nature, it also manifests characteristics that are peculiar to itself. The true nature of existence must therefore be defined as organic rather than inorganic; and it is therefore more correct to say, that organic existence has produced inorganic, than that inorganic has produced organic. But both forms of expression are inadequate. For, as no mode of existence originates any other, what we must say is, that in organic existence we have a fuller and 1 82 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. truer expression of the nature of existence as a whole than we have in inorganic existence. Having made this discovery, we can see that in inorganic existence, prior to the rise of life, there was already implied all that subsequently presented itself in organic existence. Thus what is posterior in time is prior in nature : the first is last and the last first. I think you will now see that there is nothing in the fact that life has appeared subsequent to non-living things to show that the former is dependent upon the latter. Since no form of existence can present itself that lies outside the one unity of existence, we are compelled to relate both to that unity, and to find in life, rather than in matter, the true nature of reality. And, if this is so, there can be no difficulty in seeing that it is meaningless to speak of matter as the cause of conscious existence. To argue that consciousness is due to matter is to fall into the old mistake of taking the order of time as identical with the order of nature, and of attributing to individual things a power of origination that belongs only to the single principle manifested in all things. Consciousness appeared later than life. Granted ; but the consciousness which thus appeared could not arise either from the particular forms of existence prior to it, or from itself: its explanation must be found in this, that existence as a whole contained within itself, prior to its manifestation as consciousness, all that so mani- fested itself. There can be no absolute origination in the case of existence as a whole, since outside of that whole there is no reality and no possibility. What is shown by the appearance in the world of conscious beings is not a new existence, but a higher manifestation of PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 83 the one existence that always was and is and shall be. We must therefore say, that inorganic existence, as well as organic existence, when it is properly understood, is a phase, though not the highest phase, of the single self- conscious intelligence in whom and through whom and by whom are all things. For, since nothing is apart from the unalterable nature of the one Being that comprehends all reality, to understand completely the nature of the simplest form of existence — say, a stone^ — is to apprehend it as one of the phases in which the absolute intelligence is manifested. It is this that makes all pursuit of know- ledge sacred. In learning the properties of a simple blade of grass we are partially apprehending the nature of God. SCIENTIFIC EVOLUTIONISM AND PHILOSOPHICAL IDEALISM. These considerations have, I hope, made it plain in what sense idealism maintains that there is no absolute separation of subject and object, mind and matter; that, on the contrary, matter properly understood, is a manifesta- tion of mind. All existence is a manifestation of one supreme all-comprehensive self-consciousness. We may now go on to consider the objection to the identity of subject and object drawn from the character of the subject. It is said that mind must be absolutely independent of matter, because mind is conscious of itself, while matter is not. The idea of the subject thus seems to be exclusive of the idea of the object; or, in Mr. Spencer's language, the distinction is one never to be transcended while con- sciousness lasts. This argument manifestly follows a different line of thought from that which we have just considered. So 184 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. far from maintaining that consciousness must be regarded as a product of matter, it asserts that by no possibility can consciousness be reduced to matter. Matter has no consciousness of itself, whereas every subject is a subject just because of self-consciousness. It is therefore inferred that the conscious subject is independent of the object. Now, it is peculiar that we find this argument for the independence and diverse nature of the subject put for- ward by those who also maintain that life and consciousness are products of inorganic nature. Spencer, Tyndall, Huxley, and others, all maintain that by the one line of argument we are forced to view mind as a mode of matter, and by the other line of argument we are forced to assert that mind cannot be a mode of matter. Their solution of the difficulty is to fall back upon a Power which is neither mind nor matter, but the nature of this Power, they maintain, is absolutely inscrutable to the intellect of man. The self-contradictory character of this solution we have already seen, and hence we must inquire whether we are really forced to maintain that the fact of self- consciousness is inconsistent with the identity of subject and object. When we find the same writer holding that mind is a mode of matter, and that mind is independent of matter, we may be sure that the "fons et origo" of the two discrepant views is to be found in some false assumption common to both. The assumption here is, that each conscious subject, like each material object, is a separate individual whose nature is not in any way relative to the nature of other individuals. In other words, existence is supposed to be made up of a number of individuals, standing opposed to one another as separate and distinct. PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 85 The difference between these individuals is, that some are conscious and some are unconscious; but all alike are what they are in virtue of their own independent existence. The individuality of conscious beings seems to be especially manifest. When I am conscious of myself, I am conscious that I am not to be identified with any other form of existence. I possess, as it has been said, a unique existence and an unsharable conscious- ness, and to deny my individuality is to deny that I am conscious at all. My sensations, my emotions, my thoughts and volitions are mine, and not those of anybody else. I inhabit a world of consciousness that is absolutely impenetrable, and in virtue of this fact I am a self-con- scious subject. My real self is "one and indivisible," different selves are "absolutely and for ever exclusive." Now, in one point of view, this assertion of individuality deserves the strongest commendation. In maintaining that all forms of existence are individual, it brings into prominence an aspect of reality that is lost sight of when all concrete forms of being are resolved into an inscrutable and unintelligible Power. And in particular, it emphasizes the distinction between beings that are self-conscious, and beings that are not self-conscious, implying that in the strict sense of the term the only true individual is the self-conscious subject, which, in all the changes through which it passes, is aware of itself as identical. But, while it is an important truth, that individuality can properly be affirmed only of a being that is self- conscious, it by no means follows that to be self-conscious is to be aware of oneself as a separate individual, having no relation to any other existence. It may easily be shown that the consciousness of individuality is on this i86 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. supposition impossible. If we suppose that in being con- scious of himself, the subject is conscious of nothing else, it is manifest that such a being would have no consciousness even of himself. For all reality would for him be limited to determinations of himself, and therefore he would never contrast with these determinations the determinations of other forms of existence. To be conscious of myself implies that I am conscious of myself as possessing a character which distinguishes me from other modes of being. My individuality is for me the consciousness of what I feel, know, and will. But if I have no consciousness of what is felt, known, and willed by others, I must be in- capable of distinguishing between myself and other selves. It is therefore only in relation and contrast to other selves that I become conscious of what I as an individual am. Assume, therefore, that I am absolutely limited to the consciousness of my own feelings and thoughts and voli- tions, and obviously I should be unaware that others have different feelings, thoughts, and volitions, and therefore unaware of my own peculiar individuality. The conscious- ness of self is therefore relative to the consciousness of other selves. It may be said, however, that while I am no doubt conscious of other selves as having feelings, thoughts, and volitions, yet I am capable of distinguishing these from the feelings, thoughts, and volitions which are peculiarly my own, and that the consciousness of what is mine constitutes my peculiar individuality. And this is true; what I feel, think, and will belongs to me in a sense that nothing else does ; it is mine because it implies a peculiar self-activity on my part. It is the dis- tinguishing characteristic of self-conscious beings that they PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 87 are self-determined. But self-determination is not the same thing as the determination of an exclusive and separate self that has no relation to anything else. This may be shown by a consideration of the two main forms in which self-determination is exhibited, viz., knowledge and action. (1) Knoivledge. — To know is to have the consciousness of what really exists. But if we suppose that in our knowledge we are conscious only of our own states, we shall have no consciousness of any reality. Knowledge therefore implies that we can separate between what seems and what is. If in any case we apprehend what is, we do so in virtue of our own self-activity; but what we apprehend is not an arbitrary product of our activity, but what belongs to the actual nature of reality. To know is thus to exercise conscious activity in the appre- hension of that which has an existence and nature not determined by the activity. In so far as the activity of self-consciousness is exercised in setting aside what is accidental and illusory, we have knowledge. As far as we have knowledge we have transcended our mere indi- viduality and identified ourselves with the universal. Thus we have realized by our self-activity that which is objective. True self-activity consists in identification with the object; and true individuality consists in the con- sciousness that our true self is to be found in such identification. Now, if our knowledge were absolutely complete, we should be absolutely identified with the object. Such absolute identification would not be the destruction of our self-activity, but its perfect realization. We therefore see that absolute individuality would mean the absolute transcendence of the opposition of subject Io5 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. and object. In man, however, this perfect individuality ,is never attained, but remains for him an ideal which, by his self-activity, he is perpetually seeking to realize. If he had no self-activity, he would never get beyond the first opposition of subject and object; if he had complete self-activity, he would absolutely transcend the opposition. In knowledge he is therefore continually abolishing the distinction between subject and object, but it is a dis- tinction which for him is abolished only in idea. Yet in a sense the opposition is already abolished. For, if he had no consciousness of the ultimate unity of subject and object, he would have no consciousness that in his actual knowledge he falls short of his ideal. It is for this reason that a man is aware of himself as having a peculiar individuality which distinguishes him from other men and from God. But this consciousness of his own individuality would be impossible were he not conscious of being beyond it in idea. It is by reference to the standard of complete knowledge as realized in God that a man is conscious of the incompleteness of his own knowledge : it is by reference to the same infinite standard that he pronounces the knowledge of others to be more or less complete than his own. But in all cases the consciousness of one's knowledge, and the conscious- ness of the limited extent of one's knowledge, involves the consciousness, actual or ideal, of the unity of self and not-self. So far is it from being true, that to be con- scious of self is to be conscious of an exclusive self, that the consciousness of self is impossible except as the consciousness of a self that is identical with not-self. (2) Action. — The same thing may be seen in the case of action. To act morally is to determine oneself in PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 189 accordance with the true nature of existence. If I seek my good in what presents itself as good only to me as a separate individual, I shall not realize my true indi- viduality. For, unless I seek my good in what is good absolutely, I shall abandon myself to caprice or to self- will. It is only by willing what is good, absolutely or universally, that I can realize what my true nature fits me to realize. In other words, my self-activity must be determined by the idea of a universal moral law, or it is not a realization of my individuality, because it is con- trary to the true nature of the self. Every moral law is a statement of one of the ways in which the subject may realize what in his ideal nature he is. The consciousness of a moral law is therefore the consciousness of one of the modes in which the subject by his self-activity may identify himself with the object. For the ideal self is capable of being realized only as a self existing in a world that in its ultimate nature is consistent with such realization. If the universe were so constituted that it was inconsistent with the realization of what, in his idea, man is, there would be an absolute antagonism between the self-conscious subject and the object. But such an antagonism is disproved by the fact that in the con- sciousness of the ideal self we already have the promise of the identity of the subject and the object. All moral progress rests upon this idea — upon the idea of an absolute good, which realizes the self because the world exhibits in it a divine purpose. Morality, in other words, is possible at all only if the world is the expression of the divine mind. It is therefore in contrast to the perfect unity of subject and object as conceived to be realized by God, that we become conscious of our own moral 190 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. limitations. In the case of man there always is an opposition between the actual self and the ideal, because man's life is never completely moralized ; but even the consciousness of his moral imperfection would be im- possible were he not conscious of an ideal moral per- fection, and conscious of it as the true nature of the world. Thus, in the practical as in the theoretical consciousness of man, there is implied identification of subject and object. From what has been said you will see that in asserting the identity of subject and object we do not maintain that there is no distinction between beings that are self- conscious and beings that are not self-conscious. What we maintain is, that, as every phase of the world must ultimately be viewed as a manifestation of one self- conscious intelligence, so the true life of man consists in coming to the consciousness of this intelligence and in identifying himself with it. True individuality is self- activity in identifying oneself with the object; and just in so far as a man fails in this he fails in knowledge and in morality. MR. SPENCER'S PSYCHOLOGY. I have dealt thus fully with Mr. Spencer's first pro- position, because it lies at the basis of his whole system. It will not be necessary to consider the other four pro- positions which he maintains, but a few words may be devoted to his second proposition, that the object is for us a complex of feelings, and the subject a complex of move- ments. Let us take each of these assertions by itself. (a) The object is conceivable only as a complex of feelings. My perception of any object is not an appre- PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 191 hension of the object in itself, but only of the impressions which it produces in me. These come in an order of succession, and therefore the perception of coexistent objects is in reality only the consciousness of a reversible order in my impressions as distinguished from an irre- versible order. Now, Mr. Spencer here fails to distinguish between a mere series of feelings and a conceived order of objective reality. He assumes that the occurrence of feelings is the same as the consciousness of their occurrence. But it is easy to show that if the object were reducible to the mere occurrence of feelings, there would be no con- sciousness of their occurrence, and therefore no conscious- ness of an orderly system of things. To be conscious of feelings as related in time is to be beyond mere feelings. This becomes at once evident if we suppose our con- sciousness reduced simply to the occurrence of feelings. Take, e.g., the occurrence of a number of feelings of sound. (1) If there is in the consciousness of such feelings nothing but the feelings themselves, each feeling of sound will exist only so long as it is felt. But the consciousness of a series of feelings cannot be derived from a number of distinct feelings. To have the con- sciousness of a series there must be the consciousness of the one as distinguishable from the other. To simplify the matter, let us suppose that in their content all the feelings are the same. But manifestly we cannot be conscious of feelings as different, unless we are conscious of them as not absolutely identical. In the present case the difference is purely one of time ; if, therefore, we distinguish the one from the other, we must do so on the ground that one precedes and the other follows. 192 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. Now, this distinction of before and after is a distinction of relation, and therefore it involves the consciousness of a relation — the relation of time — between one feeling and another. This capacity of relating one feeling to another cannot be attributed to the feelings themselves, but involves the capacity of grasping time as a unity of dis- tinguishable moments. That is to say, in the conscious- ness of a series of feelings thought is involved. It is for this reason that I become conscious of all feelings as related to one another in the way of time. And time, as the universal form in which all feelings are related, is not a variable element in my experience; it is a fixed or unalterable relation. Here, then, we have one of the simplest forms in which the consciousness of objectivity presents itself. In being conscious of all feelings as related in the way of time, I have apprehended a universal and necessary relation ; and a universal and necessary relation is what we mean by objectivity. You will thus see that it is quite untrue to say that the object is for us a complex of feelings. No number of feelings could ever give us the consciousness of time, and therefore the consciousness of feelings as following in a fixed order in time. The object is not a collection of feelings, but the consciousness of a systematic unity which determines feelings to a fixed order. To be conscious of an object at all, we must have the conception of time as an absolute unity. Hence the conscious subject in the apprehension of his various feelings as successive has already got beyond a series of subjective states, and has grasped these under the objective form of time. (b) The subject, Mr. Spencer says, is conceivable only as a complex of movements. If the mind experiences a PHILOSOPHY OF MIND. 1 93 feeling, this feeling can only be conceived after the manner of a movement in the bodily organism. Thus we are forced to represent the relation of our feelings to one another in terms of the action of one material particle on another. Mr. Spencer indeed denies that this is an adequate view of the nature of mind, but he says it is the only view that makes the fact intelligible to us. Changes of feeling are really different in kind from material movements, but yet we must symbolize the changes of feeling as movements. Now, the difficulty Mr. Spencer has in apprehending the nature of mind is not due to any limitation of our knowledge, but to a false view of the nature of mind. Any attempt to comprehend the nature of consciousness by conceiving of it as made up of separate units of feeling is certain to lead us to suppose that we cannot comprehend mind as it truly is, and have therefore to represent it as it is not. For consciousness is not an assemblage of separate feelings. To suppose it is, leads, as we have seen, to the denial of all consciousness. The dis- tinguishing characteristic of consciousness is, that in all its changing phases it remains identical with itself; what it distinguishes from itself is always a particular aspect of reality, but all aspects of reality are in relation to the one., indivisible self. To speak, therefore, of feelings in terms of nerve-movements is virtually to abolish the dis- tinction between a feeling and a nerve-movement. Now, a feeling as it exists for consciousness is always a particu- lar phase of reality as related by thought to other phases of reality. Apart from consciousness, the feeling has no existence as a known object ; as a known object, it implies the universalizing activity of the one identical subject. But, if prior to the consciousness of the feeling there is no 194 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. known feeling, to speak of a nerve-movement as if it could explain feeling is to assume that a peculiar form of reality can be explained without any reference to that without which it could not exist at all. Consciousness cannot be expressed in terms of motion, because, without supposing consciousness to be distinct from motion, there could be no consciousness at all. In the last two chapters the general character of the moral consciousness of man has been incidentally charac- terized, but it is necessary to consider more carefully the problems which arise in connection with that conscious- ness. The discussion of these problems constitutes Moral as distinguished from Mental Philosophy. CHAPTER IX. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. IDEA OF DUTY. In our ordinary moral consciousness we distinguish be- tween what is and what ought to be, just as in our ordinary theoretical consciousness we distinguish between what seems and what is. We are continually passing upon our- selves or others such judgments as " This ought to be done," "That ought not to be done." In making such judgments we assume that there is right and wrong con- duct, and that action, whether right or wrong, is to be attributed to an agent. In other words, we find in our ordinary consciousness two correlative ideas, — the idea of Duty or moral obligation, and the idea of Freedom or self- activity. These two ideas lie at the basis of all our moral conceptions, and with them Ethics, as the science of conduct, has mainly to deal. We shall deal first with the idea of duty. In the first place, the idea of duty implies an opposition between an ideal or intelligible world and the actual world. This ideal world is conceived as that form of existence which a man is to realize, as distinguished from the form 196 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. of existence that he has realized. In idea man is a mem- ber of the intelligible world, and if he were complete man, he would no longer find any discrepancy between what he ought to be and what he is. But primarily the in- telligible world is not an achievement but a prophecy, not something that man is but something he ought to be. And this is true whether we look at the individual man or at the race. The individual man has an idea of him- self as realizing what he ought to realize, but it presents itself to him as an ideal, because he has not realized it. It is in contrast to this ideal of himself that he becomes conscious of the imperfection of his actual self. If he had no idea of himself as a being that ought to live the ideal life, he would not be aware that "in all things he offends and comes short of the glory of God." The same thing is true of the race. The moral progress of humanity is made possible by an ideal of humanity as it ought to be but is not. There always is in all the strivings of man an ideal man which is set up as the true man, and this ideal is conceived as the real that ought to be, though not the real that is. We can therefore understand why Plato maintained that the ideal is the real. The ideal is the real, not because it is the actual, but because it is what ought to be actual. Man recognizes that his true self is the ideal or moral self, not the self that at any time actually is. Hence, secondly, the idea of duty implies an opposition between a law of reason and a law of natural inclination. The law of reason is recognized as that which expresses the true end or destiny of man, the man as he ought to be ; the law of inclination as that which expresses what man, in so far as he fails to realize the ideal end, actually MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 1 97 is. There is in man an opposition between his desire for the realization of the ideal self, and his desire for the gratification of the lower self, an opposition between the life of spirit and the life of nature. Now, it is of supreme importance to apprehend the true relation of the ideal and the actual self, the life of spirit and the life of nature ; for upon this apprehension mainly depends the character of our ethical theory. The first view of the relation of the natural and the spiritual self which we are inclined to take is that they are absolute opposites. I find within me, it may be said, certain natural impulses, and these incite me to live a life that is in all respects opposed to the life of reason. It is only by rising entirely above my impulses and acting purely from the law of reason that I can be moral. Now, this view manifestly implies that it is possible, on the one hand, to act purely from natural impulse, and, on the other hand, to act purely from reason. But before we can accept such an absolute opposition of Desire and Reason, we must be sure that the opposition exists. Is it then true that man ever does, or ever can, act from mere impulse as distinguished from reason ? What has led to the view that man may act purely from immediate impulse ? It seems to be established by the actual facts of human life. Each of us seems to be an individual object among other objects, possessing by nature certain immediate desires which are brought into play by the stimulation of external things. Thus the immediate appetites of hunger and thirst seem to belong to our animal nature, and to present themselves in our consciousness whether we will or no. These appetites take the form of the feeling of a want, and this feeling 198 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. leads to the impulse to satisfy the want. We find that they can be satisfied by certain acts — the acts of eating and drinking, and, impelled by our natural craving, we perform the acts required. Here, it is said, is an impulse with which nature has endowed us, giving rise to an action. It is not reason that supplies the motive to the action, but an impulse of nature. Our reason may show us the means by which the natural want may be satisfied — it may tell us that hunger can be satisfied only by food, and thirst by drink — but it cannot supply the impulse to act, the motive or active power that produces the action. Nor is it different, it may be said, in the case of the desires that we are accustomed to call higher. Thus man has a benevolent impulse, an impulse to do actions that bring pleasure to others. But, like the appetites of hunger and thirst, that impulse springs up in him because he is by nature endowed with a susceptibility which makes him shrink from pain, and causes him to act so as to prevent others from feeling it. To this the Darwinian would add, that the benevolent impulse has come to man by inheritance from his animal progenitors, and is there- fore as purely natural as the appetite of hunger or of thirst. Let the benevolent impulse be in a man stronger than the selfish impulse, and he will inevitably perform benevolent acts. Now, plausible as this view of natural desire is, I think it may be shown to rest upon an imperfect apprehension of the nature of desire as it exists in man. It is supposed that man knows himself simply as an individual object, possessing like other individual objects certain properties which are revealed in his consciousness, but which are in no way determined as to their nature by his consciousness. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 199 Just as a material thing possesses the tendency to gravitate towards other material things, so man possesses by nature such tendencies to action as hunger, thirst, and benevolence. Accordingly, it is supposed that his consciousness of him- self is simply the consciousness that he exists, and is de- termined now by one impulse, now by another. The immediate impulse is in no way affected by man's con- sciousness of it, for his consciousness only tells him that he is and must be affected by the impulse : " O who can hold a fire in his hand, By thinking on the frosty Caucasus." 1 Thus the consciousness of self seems to be merely the apprehension of a sensitive content, that leaves the content unchanged. From this point of view, the only difference between a merely sensitive and a conscious subject is that the former possesses a certain impulse without being aware of possessing it, while the latter not only has the impulse but knows that he has it. The presence of consciousness, however, seems to leave the impulse just what it was before. If a magnet were to become conscious of its tendency to turn towards the pole, it would be in an analogous con- dition to a self-conscious being that has become aware of itself as having natural impulses. Now this account of the consciousness of self leaves out all that is characteristic of it. We are to suppose that the subject can be conscious of being in a particular state of desire, without being conscious of anything else ; in other words, that the self-conscious subject is aware of himself only in the individual states which in succession occur to him. We must further suppose that the subject can be conscious 1 Richard II r . i. 3. 200 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. of himself as particular without being conscious of himself as universal. But neither of these assumptions can be ad- mitted to be true, (a) If my consciousness of myself as in a particular state of desire — say, desire for food — were the consciousness only of this desire, I should not be able to think of myself as capable of many desires. Tied down to each desire as it arose, I should be continually varying in my desires as from time to time they arose in me, but I should not be aware of this variable character of myself. To be aware of hunger as a desire to which I am subject, I must therefore be able to compare it with the other desires of which I am susceptible. But this means that I am conscious of myself as a being in whom a conflict of desires may take place. For instance, the desire for food may come into conflict with the desire for knowledge. The consciousness of desire thus implies that the subject appears to himself as an object capable of experiencing various desires which may or may not be harmonious with one another, (b) This consciousness leads to another form of consciousness. I cannot be conscious of myself as capable of having a variety of desires, without conceiving of myself as not identical with any one of them, or even with the whole of them taken together. Thus arises the conscious- ness of self as a subject that is opposed to the self as an object with its varying desires. The very consciousness of self as an object lifts the self above its mere objectivity. Hence arises the opposition between myself as a being striving after complete satisfaction and myself as a being experiencing from time to time the satisfaction of particular desires, but never completely satisfied. Self-consciousness thus involves a primary opposition between an ideal self and an actual self. But this oppo- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 201 sition is not absolute. When I have become aware that I have many desires, all of which seek for satisfaction, my action is not determined by any desire as such. I set before my consciousness the idea of myself as seeking satisfaction in different desires, and I select among them that which seems to have the strongest claim to satisfaction under given conditions. It is not the desire that deter- mines my choice, but / who compare the various desires with one another. Having made my choice I will to follow the line of action calculated, or apparently calculated, to secure the end in view. Thus the self-conscious subject is not the passive subject of this or that desire, but he determines himself to follow the object to which a particular desire points. But there is more than this. If I seek for satisfaction in willing the object of a particular desire, I am seeking for satisfaction in that which cannot possibly yield it. For my consciousness of myself is the consciousness of a self that strives after infinite satisfaction. I desire satisfaction not for this side of my nature or for that — not for the present moment only but for all time — and no particular satisfaction can possibly yield complete satisfaction. "Man's unhappiness," says Carlyle, 1 "comes of his Greatness ; it is because there is an Infinite in him, which with all his cunning he cannot quite bury under the Finite. Will the whole Finance Ministers and Upholsterers and Confectioners of modern Europe under- take in joint-stock company, to make one Shoeblack happyt They cannot accomplish it, above an hour or two; for the Shoeblack also has a Soul quite other than his Stomach; and would require, if you consider it, for 1 Sartor Resartus, p. 131. 202 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. his permanent satisfaction and saturation, simply this allotment, no more, and no less : God's infinite Universe altogether to himself, therein to enjoy infinitely, and fill every wish as fast as it rose." Thus arises a division in consciousness between the particular and the universal self. On the one hand, I can realize myself only in willing some particular object ; on the other hand, in willing a particular object I have not gained the satisfac- tion at which I aimed. Here then is the origin of the war of flesh and spirit, the actual and the ideal self. Our self-conscious life seems to be in irreconcilable antagonism with itself. Observe, however, that the antag- onism is now seen to be, not between natural desire impelling us to actions that lie outside of our own will, and reason as setting up an ideal beyond all desire; but it is between that form of self-determination which seeks to realize the self in willing a particular object, and that form of self-determination which seeks to realize the self completely. It is a conflict of the subject with himself, not a conflict between external force and will. Yet the conflict seems to remain. Is there no way of reconciling it? There is one method which has com- mended itself to many moralists, the method of Asceticism. The only way, it is held, in which man can attain the end of his being is by refusing to be influenced in the smallest degree by his desires, i.e., by the satisfactions which seem to be held out to him by willing one side of his nature. For the true nature of man is reason, and reason demands the complete liberation of man from all the passions that enslave him. Thus it was held by the ancient Stoics, as it has been held in modern times by Kant, that morality consists in acting purely from MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 203 the law of reason, as distinguished from the law of desire. This law of reason seemed to the Stoics to be in complete antagonism to the law of desire. Hence they maintained that we can only live the true life of man by being absolutely indifferent to the solicitations of desire ; we must "dwell with ourselves," 1 and treat all the imagined satisfactions of the particular desires as inconsistent with " our being's end and aim." The passions are " unnatural," for man's real nature is not passion but reason. "Follow nature" therefore means, "follow reason." The man who is moved by the desire for wealth is a slave; he becomes free by learning to despise wealth. To be ambitious is to yield to a desire which never can bring satisfaction, but which, on the contrary, must lead to all sorts of dissatis- faction and even to despair ; the wise man holds himself aloof from all the ambitions of ordinary men. The end of life is to reach the state of self-harmony, or complete indifference (drapagia) to the claims of the particular self. Passion as foreign to the true self must be destroyed ; we must as rational beings devote ourselves to the task of expelling this unwelcome guest. Hence morality consists in the negation of passion. The asceticism of the Stoics thus results from their conception of the particular desires as essentially irrational. Accordingly, the morality they teach is purely negative in its character. They tell us, indeed, that we are to live the life of reason; but when we ask wherein the life of reason consists, the answer we get is, that it consists in the annihilation in ourselves of the power over us of all the desires. What is the value of this conception of morality? 1 Tecum habita et noris, quam sit tibi curia supellex. — Persius. 204 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. (a) Its main value lies in this, that man in his ideal or perfect nature is something more and higher than the particular forms in which he seeks to realize himself. If I try to realize myself completely in devoting myself to the pursuit of wealth, or honour, or knowledge, I am treating myself as if my whole nature were capable of being expressed in each of these desires. Nay, if I try to find satisfaction in the realization of all my particular desires, I equally assume that I can be identified with these, and that if I can only obtain wealth and honour and knowledge I shall have reached complete self- satisfaction. In neither of these ways can the satisfaction that is sought be attained. Suppose that I succeed in satisfying my desire for wealth, I become conscious that I have left unsatisfied my natural desire for honour and knowledge; if I were to obtain the satisfaction of the desire for honour or knowledge, I should leave unsatisfied the desire for wealth. The truth, however, is, that no desire ever can be completely satisfied. The man who seeks to obtain wealth as the means of self-satisfaction never reaches a point where he can say: Now I have obtained all the wealth that I can possibly desire. For the desire has no limit in itself, and therefore no limited object can satisfy it. To suppose, therefore, that any one who makes the satisfaction of all his desires his object can ever attain the satisfaction he seeks, is to suppose that the desire for the infinite can be fed by the finite. The Stoics were therefore right in maintaining that the true end of life cannot be realized by making the objects of particular desires the object aimed at. He who takes the particular as the end will learn by the stern logic of experience MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 205 that he has been seeking to allay his hunger for the infinite by feeding himself on the husks of the finite. It was therefore natural for the Stoics to say : Give up the effort to find satisfaction in the finite, and learn to be indifferent to the allurements of the passions : if you learn the lesson of indifference to the fascinations of desire, you will no longer be the slave of the passions, but the free man of reason. But (b) the difficulty immediately presents itself, that if man must in no case be influenced by the desire for some special form of self-satisfaction, all motive to action seems to be taken away. Reason sets before me the idea of myself as completely satisfied, and this complete satisfaction is not to be found by seeking to secure any definite object. I am not to be actuated by the love of wealth, or honour, or knowledge. In the absence of such motives, how am I to act? Every action must take the form of a volition to realize some particular object. There is no perfectly general action : all action is par- ticular. If I exclude all particular forms of action, nothing remains but the general capacity of acting, and so long as there is nothing but the capacity, there is no realization of the self. Thus the idea of the perfect self remains a mere idea : something that ought to be realized, but which never is realized. Man's actual self and his ideal self remain for ever apart. His duty is to realize the ideal self, but the idea of duty remains a mere idea, because there is no particular line of action that can be followed which does not re-introduce the conception of a particular object to be attained, and so destroy the determination by the abstract idea. How, then, are we to get beyond the abstract idea of 206 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. duty to the consciousness of particular duties ? Obviously, only if the idea of self as infinite or perfect is not in irreconcilable antagonism to the idea of self as finite or particular. We must be prepared to show, in other words, that the law of reason is not the abstract opposite of the law of desire, but is in some sense the same law. Now, observe that the reconciliation of desire and reason cannot be made by saying that the " natural law " of desire must be extended to the " spiritual world." So long as the natural desires are conceived as desires for a particular form of self-satisfaction, so long they must be opposed to the idea of complete self-satisfaction. But the desires are in reality not merely desires for particular satisfactions. To the individual they may seem so, because he has not become aware of what their true meaning is. The man who seeks his satisfaction in the attainment of wealth may have no clear consciousness that the real motive of his action is not the attainment of wealth, but the attainment of self-satisfaction by means of the attainment of wealth. This is implied in the very nature of desire. Why does a man seek wealth ? If he supposed that in attaining it he would only bring to himself dissatisfaction, would he not, instead of seeking it, shun it by all means in his power ? He desires wealth because he conceives of it as the means of securing many forms of satisfaction — food, shelter, comfort, luxuries, social consideration. The real motive which is operative in the search for wealth is the desire for permanent self- satisfaction. Why, then, is self-satisfaction not found in this way ? It is not found because the man has identified his ultimate good with that which is not his ultimate MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 207 good. He has sought for the satisfaction of his ideal self in a self that falls short of the ideal. The opposition which is felt in the contrast of desire and attainment is just the man coming to the consciousness of the dis- crepancy between the ideal as it has actually presented itself to him in his search for wealth, and a higher ideal that was not explicitly before his consciousness. He supposed that he was actuated simply by the desire for satisfaction by means of wealth, when in reality he was blindly seeking for the complete satisfaction of his nature. When he becomes aware of the disharmony between the self-satisfaction he has been seeking and the self-satisfaction that is still unrealized, he comes to the consciousness that there is a higher than his actual self: that the self he has been seeking to realize is not his true self. Thus he awakens to the consciousness of what he ought to be as distinguished from what he is, and he opposes the law of duty to the law of inclination. Now, it is at this point that there is danger of mis- interpreting the meaning of this higher consciousness. In the first consciousness of a higher life, a man is apt to say to himself : " I have been all wrong in seeking my good in such objects as wealth, or honour, or knowledge j henceforth I will give up the search for satisfaction in these, and live only for my higher self." This is a move- ment of the human spirit of which we are continually seeing examples, though it is seldom that we see it in its purity. A man who has passed the greater part of his life in the acquisition of wealth comes to the conscious- ness of a higher law, and, looking back upon his past life, he condemns it as unspiritual. " The pursuit of wealth," he says to himself, " is unworthy of man, and is antagonistic 2o8 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. with my true nature. Henceforth I will lead a higher life." But, as a rule, he does not interpret this thought into action, and surrender the wealth he has acquired ; at the most, he contents himself with giving away a part of it, reserving the largest part for himself. Sometimes we find examples of a much bolder practical idealism. Thus, in the middle ages, we find men like St. Francis, who carry out to its logical issue the principle of renunciation. "All the desires," they say, "are essentially unspiritual, and must be crucified." Hence they devote themselves to a life of poverty, celibacy, and obedience, renouncing for ever all those objects of satisfaction to which men ordinarily devote themselves. In such men we have in its purest form the realization of the negative conception of duty. Can we accept this ideal of life as the highest? Is renunciation the last word of morality? If we consider more particularly the relations of desire and reason, duty and inclination, we shall be forced, I think, to hold that the path of renunciation is not the path that leads to the highest spiritual life. In all his desires, as we have seen, man is unconsciously striving after complete self-realization or self-satisfaction. So long as he seeks for self-satisfaction in a particular object, he is laying up for himself inevitable disappoint- ment. But it does not follow that he is therefore to seek for self-satisfaction in separating himself from all particular interests. To act on this principle is to assume that these interests are necessarily antagonistic to the higher interests of man; it is, in other words, to assume that desire and reason are mutually antagonistic. Now, if we examine carefully any of the special desires, we MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 209 shall find that they are not the opposite of reason, but simply reason in the form of unreason. Desire in its most immediate form appears as appetite, the desire for the satisfaction of the wants of our animal nature. It must, however, be observed that the appetites are not simply animal impulses. If they were merely animal impulses, they would not enter into our conscious life. When I become conscious of an appetite, I become conscious of myself as a being who is capable of seeking for the satisfaction of myself so far as this particular desire. is concerned. What I have before my consciousness is the idea of myself as capable of receiving satisfaction by means of a certain act, the act of eating or drinking. Such desires may take the direct form of a desire for food or drink, or they may take the more complicated form of a desire for the satisfaction of my immediate appetite, together with a repetition of the pleasure that I have experienced in that satisfaction. It is this last form of desire that gives rise to the artificial stimulation of appetite and the various means by which the gratifica- tion may be increased. Having once felt the satisfaction attendant upon the gratification of such wants, I am capable of imagining myself as enjoying it even when the animal appetite is not actually felt. Now, moralists of the ascetic type have no hesitation in rejecting the second form of appetite. Plato, for example, will have no Sicilian cookery in his ideal state : his guardians must live on plain food and discard all dainties of the palate. But most ascetic moralists go still further. Not only must there be no artificial stimulation of the appetites, but even the gratification of the natural de- sires must be negated as far as possible. The wise man 2IO COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. of the Stoics was indifferent to the satisfaction of his appetites. Asceticism, however, is not perfectly consistent with itself. Its principle is that the natural desires should be negated because they are inconsistent with the ideal self of reason. Now, the only way in which a living being can completely get rid of the particular desires which we call the appetites, is by ceasing to live. So long as by eating a man continues to exist, he must be subject to the desire for food, and therefore reason can never absolutely subdue appetite to itself. The negative method of asceticism therefore leads to a practical con- tradiction. The struggle between reason and desire is an ever-renewed fight in which desire must always triumph, because it is bound up with the very existence of the rational subject. Only by one absolute act of self-renuncia- tion, the renunciation of life itself, could the ascetic put an end to the conflict. Now, this self-contradiction in the ascetic conception of morality suggests the question, whether there is any necessary antagonism between appetite and reason. It will be found, on reflection, that the assumed opposition is not really between appetite and reason, but between a self that treats appetite as an absolute end and a self that treats it only as a means. Plato had a glimpse of this when he held that his guardians should eat only the plainest food ; for he did so mainly because he believed that luxurious living is hostile to the high thinking and self-abnegation required in a leader of the people. That is to say, Plato virtually condemns as irrational, not appetite as such, but appetite which assumes an importance inconsistent with the complete develop- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 211 ment of the man. Now, when we look at the matter from this point of view, we see that the opposition supposed by the ascetic to obtain between appetite and reason, really obtains between a higher and lower con- ception of the self. If a man is prepared to sacrifice higher interests to the gratification of his appetites, he acts irrationally, because he substitutes a particular end for a universal. But the immorality of his action does not arise from the fact that he has willed the particular end, but because he has willed it as if it were universal. To realize himself at all, he must will the object indicated by his natural desires ; but the difference between willing the object for itself and willing it for a higher end is spiritually an infinite difference. In the one case he practically affirms that this particular end — this limited self — is universal; in the other case, that this particular end is particular. Or, as we may also put it, in the former case he particularizes the universal; in the latter case, he universalizes the particular. Now, in this uni- versalizing of the particular morality consists. The path to the higher spiritual life cannot be found by negating desire, but by transforming it. Duty does not consist in the destruction of natural inclination, but in subordinating it to the realization of the complete nature of the self. The negative method does not enable the individual to triumph over his appetites, but raises appetite to a bad preeminence. St. Anthony, fasting until he is haunted by spectres of the imagination, gives to appetite an importance that it would not otherwise possess. When, on the other hand, it is recognized that the appetites are means of realizing higher ends, it is seen that their satis- faction is not merely permissible but a duty. It is a 212 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. duty to maintain life, and to maintain it in its highest perfection, because the maintenance of life is essential to the development of the higher self. It is quite true that even the sacrifice of life may be a duty. But it is never a duty unless its maintenance comes into conflict with a higher duty, as when a man betrays his country to save his own life. The same principle which in the one case makes it a duty to maintain life, in the other makes it a duty to sacrifice life : the principle that only in the realization of the ideal self can man realize his real self. We see, then, that duty may be defined as the realiz- ation of the universal through the particular ; or, in other words, the identification of the actual self with the ideal self by a particular determination of it. All false theories neglect one of these aspects. Hedonism neglects the universal or the ideal self. Asceticism neglects the par- ticular or the actual self. The former says that duty is simply determination by the particular, i.e., by immediate desire; the latter affirms that duty is direct identification with the universal. The one does not explain the con- ception of duty at all, since a self that is determined by particular desires has no conception of duty j the other allows for the conception of duty, but does not explain how it can be realized. The truth therefore is, that duty is at once the willing of the universal or law, and the willing of the particular. My duty is to realize my ideal self, but my ideal self is the actual self as willing a par- ticular object which I identify with the law. Thus the law gets a definite content, without ceasing to be a law. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 213 kant's VIEW OF DUTY. These somewhat abstract statements will be better understood if we consider the ethical theory of Kant. For in Kant we find the two sides of morality — the particular and the universal — clearly brought out, although they are not perfectly reconciled. What is meant by duty? asks Kant. To do one's duty is to act independently of any natural inclination for or against the course pursued. We do not say that a man of abundant vital energy acts from a sense of duty when he does from inclination those things that tend to maintain his own life. It is a duty to maintain one's life, but it is not done as a duty when it is maintained because the agent has a natural pleasure in maintaining it. Self-pre- servation is made a duty only if I maintain my life because I ought to do it, not because I desire to do it. Kant maintains, then, that duty implies two things : (1) an absolute law or standard of action; (2) self-deter- mination by this absolute law. In other words, the law and the law alone must be the motive of action. An action is moral quite independently of whether the object aimed at is secured or not. The man who pro- longs his life because he loves it, attains the same object as the man who prolongs his life because it is his duty to do so. On the other hand, there are many men who are actuated by a strong sense of their duty to their fellows, whose benevolent efforts always prove unsuccess- ful, through some lack of those gifts that lead to success. But our estimate of the moral character of such men is not lowered because they are unsuccessful in the accomplishment of the object aimed at; we say that they 214 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. did their duty, and are therefore morally on as high a level as if they had succeeded. It is the motive that makes a man good, not the object sought. There are, then, two absolutely discrepant kinds of motive. In the first place, the motive may be the natural desire for a certain object which appears to me as pleasant. The object, e.g., may be the maintenance of my own life, and the motive may be the natural tendency to seek that object. I desire the object, and, desiring it, I do the acts that tend to secure it. In the second place, the motive may be, not desire for the object, but reverence for the law. Here it is not the object to be attained that constitutes the motive, but my consciousness that I ought to seek to attain it. I have no reverence for the maintenance of life; what I reverence is the law that commands me to maintain my life. When I become conscious that there is an absolute law which has no respect for my inclination either to maintain my life or to get rid of it, I am impressed by the majesty of the law, and I may act out of pure reverence for it. Then my action is moral. My only motive is reverence for the law itself. To do one's duty, then, is to recognize the absolute obligation of the law over every rational being, and to will the law purely because I reverence it. In further enforcing this view, Kant goes on to contend that all action which is done from desire for a certain object is contrary to duty. (i) If our motive is the desire for a certain object — say, the maintenance of life — it is evident that this object must present itself to us as pleasant. The idea of the continuance of one's life affects our susceptibility to pleasure, and because it MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 215 appears as pleasant we desire it. Obviously, therefore, the desire is not something that we can make or unmake. If man were so constituted by nature as to be excited to pain on the presentation of the idea of the continuance of his life, he would desire death instead of life. In point of fact there are cases in which a man is so miserable, that the idea of life appears as painful, and he desires death. Desire is thus determined by the action of the object on the natural susceptibility to pleasure and pain. Having once experienced that a certain object produces pleasure, the individual may formulate for himself a rule of action based upon that experience. Thus he may say: "Seek to maintain life, because it brings pleasure." But this is obviously not an absolute law. If by further experience a man finds that life is not pleasant, he may formulate a new rule of action : " Seek the destruction of life, because it is painful." No absolute law can be based upon desire, because desire is not a fixed principle, but is dependent upon the fluctuations of feeling as determined by chang- ing experience. (2) There are many desires corresponding to the different objects that may be experienced as pleasant. Hence there are many rules of action. But they all agree in this, that they are based upon the desire for pleasure. Nor does it make any difference what the source of the desire may be, whether in the senses or in the intellect. All desires are of the same kind, because all depend upon the susceptibility of the subject for pleasure in the idea of an object. The desire may be a desire for knowledge, but the motive in this case as in others is the pleasure attendant upon the attain- 2l6 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. ment of the object. Now, if this is true, it follows that a life which is ruled by desire is a life that rests upon mere rules of experience. Such a life presents itself to the individual seeking it as happiness ; for by happiness is meant a life of continuous pleasure. (3) Man from his very nature as a finite rational being must desire happiness. For he is necessarily susceptible to the desire for pleasure, and his reason shows him that all his desires are aiming at pleasure. As finite, he must seek for happiness not in himself but in objects without himself. He cannot at first tell, however, what objects his desires aim at; these he must learn from experience, i.e., from a knowledge of their effect upon his peculiar susceptibility. Plainly, therefore, no universal principle of action can be based upon the desire for happiness. We cannot say : Wealth should be sought as a means to happi- ness, because a man may not be susceptible to the desire for wealth. The idea of happiness is merely a name that we apply to all forms of desire for pleasure j it cannot tell us how we are to act in any given case. "Seek happiness" is no guide to conduct. For, when we ask, what then is happiness, no answer can be given except that happiness is what each man from time to time desires ; and, as different men have different desires, and even the same man at different times, happiness cannot be reduced to law. To this Kant adds, that even if all men were susceptible to the same desires, no universal law could be based upon desire, but only a general principle of human action. A law that rests upon the susceptibility to pleasure peculiar to man as a finite being cannot be an absolute law binding upon all rational beings. If, then, there are universal laws of action — laws bind- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 217 ing upon every rational being — they must rest upon the mere idea of duty, not upon desire. An action can be moral only if I am in no way influenced by my desire for an object as pleasurable, but do it purely and solely because it is rational. And it can be rational only if it can be conceived as an act that every rational being is called upon to perform. The test of a moral law is therefore this : Can I view the proposed rule of action as applicable to all, and not simply to myself with my peculiar susceptibilities for certain pleasures ? Is the prin- ciple, in other words, when it is viewed as a rule for all, consistent with itself? If it is, it must be a universal law, since it holds good quite apart from the varying desires of the individual subject ; if it is not, it cannot be a universal law, but, at the most, only a rule of expediency. Kant expresses this idea by saying, that a moral act is one in which we determine ourselves purely by the form of a law, not by its matte?-. Take, for example, the principle, " Respect the property of others." If this means : Respect the property of others, because in this way you will get more pleasure, it is not a law, because some men get more pleasure from dishonesty. But if it means : Respect the property of others, because theft cannot be made a universal principle, and is therefore contrary to reason, we get a universal law. The form in which Kant has stated his doctrine is open to grave objections. (1) He maintains that in acting morally we must be absolutely uninfluenced by desire, because all desire is excited by the idea of pleasure, or, what is the same thing, by the idea of an object as fitted to bring pleasure. 2l8 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. But, if we exclude all objects of desire, how are we to act at all? I am not to act from the desire for wealth, or honour, or knowledge ; what then am I to do ? If there is no definite object to be sought, am I not re- duced to the condition of acting without having the idea of any positive direction that my action is to take ? Kant answers that I can examine different courses of action, and finding out which can be practised by every one, and which cannot be practised by every one, I can set up the former as a law binding upon me because it is the only kind of principle that is consistent with itself. But if I had no desire for any object in particular, how could I get out of the idea of law in general any guide for action, any specific duty? Suppose that I have no desire for life, how is it possible to arrive at the prin- ciple that the maintenance of life is a principle that is consistent with itself? Unless I had the desire for life, the question would never arise, whether it is right or wrong to preserve life. Kant, therefore, must fall back upon desire to get the particular principles from which we are to act. All that he shows is, that, when particular objects of desire are presented before the mind, we can determine which are right by asking whether we can suppose them to be sought by all without contradiction, while others are wrong because we cannot suppose them to be sought by all without contradiction. But if this is so, how can it be said that we act purely from the idea of law? Do we not rather act from the idea of a certain object which is conceived as a law for all? "Act from the idea of law " supplies no principle of action in any given case, unless we fall back upon some object sup- plied by desire. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 2IQ (2) It may be objected that, even if we suppose different courses of action to be suggested by our desires, we cannot tell how we should act in any given case. Kant thinks that certain courses of action can be shown to be wrong because they are incompatible with the very idea of law. Universal stealing, he says, is self-contradictory, because if everyone stole there would be nothing to steal. But the contradiction does not arise from the mere universal- izing of the act, but from attempting to universalize what is self-contradictory before it is universalized. Theft is a contradiction because it recognizes the right of property, but acts contrary to the recognition. Every act of theft is a contradiction of the right of property. The contra- diction does not arise, as Kant supposes, only when theft is universalized, but from the very idea of theft. If there were only one act of theft it would be self-contradictory, that is, the idea of theft presupposes the right of private property. Unless, therefore, we start from the principle, that the right of private property must be recognized as a principle of action, we get no contradiction by supposing theft to be universalized. Suppose, e.g., a community which, resting upon a purely socialistic foundation, does not recognize any right of property; would theft in that case be self-contradictory? It would only be self-contra- dictory in the sense of being impossible ; for where there is no property there can be no theft. Plainly, therefore, we can find a contradiction in the idea of theft only if we assume the absoluteness of private property. But the mere universalizing of an act gives no criterion of action. " Let everyone use what does not belong to him " is the universalized principle of a communistic form of society; "Let no one use what does not belong to him" is the 2 2C COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. universalized principle in a non-communistic form of society. Manifestly, therefore, we can get no criterion of morality by simply universalizing a suggested rule of action. If a rule cannot be shown to be right in itself, it will not be proved right by merely supposing it to be universally acted upon. (3) Another objection to Kant's doctrine that has been made is, that it assumes particular rules of action to be absolute, i.e., to admit of no exception. Now, this leads to all the difficulties of casuistry. If there are a number of rules, each of which admits of no exception, we involve ourselves in self-contradiction. If the command, "Thou shalt not steal," is to be taken as absolute, circumstances may arise in which it comes into collision with the com- mand, " Thou shalt not kill." If in a famine those who have food in store stand upon their right of property, the majority of the people may starve, i.e., in maintaining the right of property, the higher right of life is sacrificed. Now Kant's formal principle, that a rule of action is to be judged as moral by its capability of being universalized, implies that no exception can be allowed to its application ; for, if it is once admitted that the rule is not in all cases such that its violation is a contradiction, the whole principle of determining a moral law by universalizing it goes to the ground. The objections just made must be held as valid against the letter of Kant's ethical theory. But it may be shown that there is in his doctrine a deeper truth which does not find expression in the formal principle of self-consistency. Kant points out that it is one thing to be subject to law, and another thing to act from the consciousness of law. Unless there is a consciousness of law there can be no will. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 22 1 The "mere animal" is subject entirely to the law of its desires, and therefore it has no will. Now, we can con- ceive of a being who in all cases acts in accordance with the laws of reason, i.e., a being whose will is always good, because never deflected from the path of morality by the influence of desire. Man, however, is not a being of that kind. He is capable of being moved to action by natural desire, and therefore there is in his nature a conflict be- tween the law of desire and the law of reason. Hence it is that he presents before himself the law of reason, not as a law that belongs to his very nature, but as a law that he may or may not obey, but which he ought to obey. It is because he may not act from reason, but from desire, that the moral law presents itself to man in the form of an imperative. What, then, is the nature of this imperative? It com- mands categorically or absolutely, i.e., it says that an act must be done because its opposite contradicts the very idea of law. Hence it may be thus expressed : " Act in such a way that, in willing to act, you can will that the maxim of your act should become a universal law." "Act as if by your will the maxim of your act were about to be made into a universal law of nature." Now, we may distinguish between (i) duties of perfect obligation and (2) duties of imperfect obligation. (1) Suppose that a man is tempted to borrow money, under promise to repay, knowing quite well that he cannot fulfil his promise. He asks himself whether the maxim, "Promise what you know you cannot perform," could become a law for all, and he sees at once that if everyone promised without intending to fulfil his promise, nothing would be promised, since no one would believe 2 22 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. another. The universalizing of a false promise thus con- tradicts the very idea of a promise. (2) As an instance of a duty of imperfect obligation, take the case of a man who refuses to help others who are in need. If the maxim, "Give no help to others," is to be regarded as if it were a law of nature, a man must deprive himself of all hope of assistance even when he needs the sympathy of others, and this is a contra- diction. Here we wish a maxim to hold only for ourselves, and not for others ; we affirm that there is a law, only it is not a law for us : and this is an irrational position. Every law is universally applicable. This formula is open to the objections already made. It affords no real criterion of action, and it assumes the principles which it pretends to derive. But Kant has a second formula which comes much nearer the truth. The formula is this : " Always treat humanity, both in your own person, and in the person of others, as an end and never merely as a means." Here Kant has introduced the new idea of man as an end to himself. In the first formula Kant held that we must exclude all motives that imply any relation to an object or end, because such motives are simply forms of natural desire for individual satisfaction ; in the new formula, he admits that we can have a certain end or object in view, only it is not a particular end, but the conception of the self as an end to itself. Each individual is now conceived as a person, i.e., as a being having a will, and therefore as distinct from a thing. But the conception of the individual as an end to himself does not of itself explain how there can be any particular duties. The self is conceived of as a self that MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 223 is opposed to all the particular desires of the self, and therefore it remains abstract. I am to realize myself, but I am to do so independently of all desire ; but, inde- pendently of all desire, there is no particular way in which my self can be realized. Kant, however, has a third formula which comes still nearer the truth : " Act in conformity with the idea that the will of every rational being is a will that lays down universal laws." Here we have the conception of a social community of beings, each of which is at once end and means ; we have, in other words, the idea of humanity as a self- conscious organism. The formula includes the two ideas of (a) universal law and {b) the consciousness of that law as identical with the consciousness of oneself as an end which belongs to one as a rational being. Hence we get the idea that, in obeying the universal law, man is obeying a law that his own reason prescribes. This is the principle of the autonomy of the will, the principle that in submitting to universal law man is submitting to his real self. But while Kant holds that we must conceive ourselves as in idea belonging to the social organism, he will not admit that this is more than an ideal. For man never gets beyond the influence of his particular desires, and therefore he can never realize the ideal. We have now before us the ultimate form in which Kant conceives of morality, and we must ask how far his opposition of the ideal and the real can be maintained. What prevents Kant from holding that the conception of men as members of a social organism is a statement of the actual nature of man? Manifestly, his doctrine 224 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. that men as the subjects of desire contain in their nature an element which prevents them from ever realizing the ideal which reason sets before them. Is it true, then, that desire is of such a nature that it is incompatible with the rational ideal? Kant's view is, that all the desires are desires for pleasure, and that happiness is simply the idea of the subject as having none of his desires for pleasure unsatisfied. Can we admit that every desire is a desire for pleasure? (a) A desire for pleasure is not the same thing as a feeling of pleasure. If I desire the pleasure of music, I am not yet in the condition of experiencing the pleasure. Before I experience it I must therefore set before my consciousness the idea of the pleasure to be experienced from the music. There are here obviously three things involved : Firstly, what is desired is a particular pleasure, the pleasure of music. The desire takes its special character and its power of attraction from the special character of the pleasure conceived. In other words, there is a certain object or end which I set before my consciousness as desirable. Secondly, not only must there be a certain object conceived as desirable, but it is an object con- ceived as desirable for me. Not every one regards music, or, at least, certain kinds of music, as fitted to bring pleasure, but only one who conceives of music as bound up with his own satisfaction. In the desire for pleasure there is therefore implied the distinction of the self desiring from the object desired. Unless the subject distinguished the object desired from himself, there could be no desire for the object, there would merely be an occurrence of a state of pleasure, without any consciousness either of an object as such or a subject as such. Thirdly, the pleasure MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 225 which is desired must be distinguished both from the object and from the subject. If the desire is for pleasure, it must be possible to separate in thought between the object which is to bring the pleasure, and the subject who is to be pleased. Now, it must be observed that all the three elements mentioned are essential to what is called the desire for pleasure. But, if so, obviously it is an imperfect statement of what is involved in desire to say simply that it is a desire for pleasure. If the desire were purely for pleasure, it might arise without any consciousness either of an object in which pleasure is placed, or of a subject to be pleased. But the former is impossible, because pleasure is necessarily not pleasure in general, but a particular kind of pleasure. I desire the pleasure of music, or knowledge, or power, but I never desire pleasure as such. A desire for pleasure in general would lead to nothing, because it would give no direction to my activity. The desire for pleasure there- fore involves the desire for a certain object conceived as pleasurable. Take away the object and you destroy the desire. Equally impossible is the desire for pleasure apart from the idea of the self as the subject to be pleased. For there can be no conception of an object as pleasure- giving, unless the object is conceived as pleasant to the subject desiring it. If the object were not conceived as fitted to bring pleasure to me, it would have no effect upon my activity. I may think of music as an object in which another takes pleasure, but music is not in that case desired by me. What is called the desire for pleasure is therefore in reality the conception of myself as a being whose nature it is to obtain pleasure in a certain object. I must identify myself in thought with the object before 226 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. I can desire it. There is therefore no possibility of realizing myself without realizing the object; and no possibility of feeling myself realized except in the realiza- tion of the object. In other words, what is called the " desire for pleasure " is really the conception on the part of the subject of one of the ways in which by attaining an object, he at the same time has the feeling of a harmony of his individual self with itself and with the world. As Aristotle points out, pleasure is just the feeling of satisfac- tion which accompanies the active realization of the self in relation to external circumstances. If this is a correct analysis of desire, we cannot admit what Kant maintains, that desire for an object is desire for pleasure. It is not desire for pleasure simply as pleasure, but desire for an object conceived of as good because conceived of as a means of realizing the self. In realizing myself in the experience of a certain object I no doubt experience pleasure, but what I am in search of is not the experience of pleasure but the good of which the experienced pleasure is a sign or index. Now, Kant assumes that the realization of the self can take place only if the self sets before itself an end which it wills irrespective of all desire for an object. But (i) there is no end that can be realized apart from desire for an object. Unless some object is desired, the self must remain unrealized, because a self in general is not capable of being realized, and a self that is to be realized must be conceived as realizing itself in some particular way, i.e., as desiring an object. (2) There is no reason to exclude all desire for objects, when we see that desire is just the idea of the self as realizing itself in objects. Such realization must be conceived as pleasurable, be- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 227 cause pleasure is simply the feeling of satisfaction in the realization of oneself. Every realization of the self is its realization in a certain way, i.e., it consists in self-identifi- cation with an object conceived as desirable, and therefore as pleasurable. There is therefore no reason to oppose the law of reason to the law of desire, as if the former absolutely excluded the latter. What reason prescribes is the realization of the self, and, as such realization is impossible apart from the desire for realization in objects, the distinction must lie, not in the presence of an object in the one case, and in its absence in the other, but in the character of the object which is desired. The question of morality therefore takes this form : What is the distinguishing characteristic of the object that we ought to desire ? There are objects that we desire which are not those which we ought to desire : can we state the distinction between what ought and what ought not to be desired? Now, Kant has himself pointed out, that to be moral is to act as if we belonged to a "kingdom of ends"; in other words, each individual must conceive of himself as a member in a social organism. In this conception of the individual as a member of a community the distinctive mark of moral action must be sought. It may, in fact, be shown historically that out of this consciousness of the unity of himself with others the consciousness of morality has sprung j and that the development of the moral con- sciousness has arisen from the ever clearer consciousness of the unity of each with all. At first this consciousness is very imperfectly developed. In purely savage life it takes the form of submission from terror to a superior force. But even in this imperfect 2 28 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. form, there is implied the recognition of a law superior to the caprice of individuals. For, in submitting to one who is superior to himself in courage and contempt of life, the savage recognizes that there is something higher than his merely individual self. Thus there arises some sort of social order. The higher self is still supposed to be embodied in the chief who, by despising the natural desire for life, shows that he has an idea of himself that goes beyond the first immediate promptings of desire. In submitting to his chief the savage thus submits to a higher ideal of himself; for in the chief he finds ex- hibited characteristics that he recognizes as superior to his own. No doubt the form which the moral conscious- ness here takes is inadequate to the idea. The savage recognizes a higher self, but he does not identify himself with it, but conceives of it as something foreign to himself, something which is for him unattainable. And, on the other hand, the chief, while he has a higher ideal of himself and prefers this to the lower self of immediate desire, yet does not recognize that he is acting from a law of reason. The consequence is that, while he acts as a moralizing agent by forcing upon others the con- sciousness of a higher self, he is not himself aware that it is as the embodiment of the higher self that he possesses power and authority. Rather, he views himself as pos- sessing influence over others by his natural superiority. Hence he has no proper sense of the limits of his authority. What he desires is a law for his followers, not because he desires a higher good, but simply because he desires it. His action is therefore largely capricious : what he desires seems to him good, not because it is good, but because he desires it. He does not distinguish between what MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 229 seems good to him, and what is good because it tends to realize a common good. Yet, if the idea of a common good were not unconsciously at work in him, he would have no authority over others. It is because they recog- nize that he is guided by a higher law that they recognize his authority even when he is capricious and irrational. Now, the consciousness of a social good which is at the same time the true good of the individual, a con- sciousness which is implied even in savage life, is the moving principle in the whole evolution of morality. What holds human beings together in society is this idea of a good higher than merely individual good. Every form of social organization rests upon this tacit recogni- tion of a higher good that is realized in the union of oneself with others. Suppose this entirely absent, and the moral consciousness would be impossible. For the moral consciousness always involves the recognition of a higher than individual good, and, because this higher good is partially realized in social laws and institutions, the individual feels himself constrained by his reason to submit to it. It is by reflection upon this good as realized in outward laws and institutions that the in- dividual becomes conscious of moral law. At first, law seems to be externally imposed, but the individual in reflecting upon it recognizes that the real force of the law lies in the fact that it is an expression of his higher self. It is true that in awakening to the consciousness of moral law as deriving its authority from reason, the indi- vidual at first asserts that custom and external law have no authority over him : that the sole authority he can rationally obey is the law of his own reason. But this is only one side of the truth : the other side is, that in 230 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. custom and law there already is realized the law of reason. No doubt society at any time is only a partial realization of the law of reason, and therefore no form of society is final; but it is none the less true that only in so far as morality realizes itself in society can it be realized at all. Now, Kant will not admit that morality is actually realized in the community. He criticizes the community by reference to the ideal of a completely rationalized humanity, and he contends that as this must always be an ideal, the individual is forced to seek for the realiza- tion of himself not in any actual form of the community, but in an intelligible world which exists for him only as an unrealizable ideal. Man is in idea the member of a community, but it is a community that never has been and never will be realized. In one sense this conception of an ideal community shows that Kant is in the grasp of the larger consciousness of human life which has come to men through Christianity. The Greek could find in the actual community of which he was a member a realization of his whole self, because for him the community was no wider than his own little State, or, at the most, than the community of States composing Greece. But with the removal of this artificial restriction through Christianity man became conscious that there was a larger self than the State, viz,, the community of all men in the life of humanity as a whole. It seems therefore as if no form of the community can possibly be adequate to the ideal community. For humanity has a life wider and more enduring than the narrow and evanescent life of a particular people or nation ; and in this all-embracing life the individual can alone find the realization of himself. And as humanity never is com- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 23 1 pletely realized, it seems true to say, that morality points to an ideal that can never be realized. Now, there can be no doubt that, in setting up the idea of humanity as the only adequate form of morality, Kant has partially seized a most important truth. If we take any existing form of the State and compare it with the ideal of humanity, we are compelled to say that it is not completely rational. There are possibilities in humanity that cannot even be clearly imagined, not to say actually realized. It is therefore important to take note of the inadequacy of any existing form of the community to the ideal community. But it must be observed that to be conscious of the incompleteness of existing communities to the perfect community is not to say that morality cannot be realized. Just as knowledge is never complete while yet it is know- ledge, so morality is never perfect while yet it is morality. And just as the idea of completed knowledge is possible only because we already possess knowledge, so the idea of perfect morality is possible only because man is already moral. Had man not already realized in principle the moral ideal he would not be able to contrast the ideal with the actual. Hence we find that the ideal of morality grows and expands with the evolution of the community. The Greek could imagine that in the form of his civic State he had reached finality, and in this he was wrong; but it is none the less true that but for the moralizing influence of the civic community the conception of a higher form of society would have been impossible. In society man learned to comprehend himself. He learned that in devotion to the common good, and in no other way, could he realize himself. Thus he was able to set the social 232 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. ideal against the mere individuality of passion, and in identifying himself with his State he became a moral being. With the Stoics came a perception of the inadequacy of the Greek State to satisfy the ideal man, and therefore the Stoics turned against the existing State, and held that man must be a citizen of the world. In himself he seemed to find a higher ideal than was realized in the community of which he was a member. But this only shows that the community as it existed was not completely rational : it does not show that man can realize himself in isolation. Accordingly, the community must assume a higher form. Morality must no longer be identified with the customs and laws of the narrow civic community, but it must rest upon the wider basis of humanity. This is the principle which is tacitly recognized in all modern forms of the community, however inadequately it may be realized. It is still true that only in identifying himself with a social good can the individual realize himself. And the reason is that in the community the idea of humanity as an organic unity is in process of realization. That the community has not reached its final form only shows that the moral life is the gradual realization of the ideal life. It is not true, therefore, that the ideal of humanity is a mere ideal : it is an ideal that is continually in process of realization. Hence the individual man can find himself, can become moral, only by contributing his share to its realization. He must learn that, to set aside his individual inclinations and make himself an organ of the community is to be moral, and the only way to be moral. He may criticize, and seek to improve the community, but his criticism must rest upon a recognition of the principle that the individual has no right to oppose himself to the community on the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 233 ground of inclination, but only on the ground that the community as it actually is in some ways contradicts the principle of the community, the principle that it is the medium in which the complete realization of man is to be found. No criticism can be of any value that denies the principle of a social good, and seeks to substitute the mere individualism of caprice. We may now see wherein the real opposition of what ought to be with what is consists. It does not consist, as Kant assumes, in a contradiction between desire and reason, as if reason were exclusive of desire. Morality may be said to consist in having rational desires. The individual who desires the good of all is not actuated by a mere desire for pleasure : for the good of all is the true principle of human action. In seeking his good in the universal, a man turns against the desire for the good of himself as an isolated being, but he does not negate all desire. His desires now take the form of a desire for what is rational ; they are spiritualized, not destroyed. Thus he gets positive content for his desires, while yet the content is not mere individual pleasure. In seeking a universal good, man is seeking for that which must be pleasurable, because pleasure is just the feeling of harmony resulting from the willing of what reason determines as good ; but if he seeks for pleasure, instead of good, the pleasure will not be obtained, because he is then attempting to realize himself as a separate individual, i.e. t to realize himself as that which he is not. What is called a life of pleasure always turns out to be a life of pain. And this is really a proof of the higher nature of man, because pain and dissatisfaction with self must result from the dis- harmony between the rational ideal and the irrational 234 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. actual. Morality is not a search for pleasure, but morality is the only true pleasure. Thus we can see how the three elements involved in desire are reconciled. The moral object of desire is the good, i.e., the good of man, not of individual men ; the moral subject of desire is the subject who identifies himself with this moral good ; and moral feeling is the consciousness of harmony enjoyed by the subject who so identifies himself with a universal good. We have seen what is implied in the idea of duty. By duty is properly meant identification with a universal good that is capable of being realized in a community of self-conscious beings. Now, identification with an ideal good is possible only if the conscious subject is capable of such identification. And hence we have now to ask whether the individual man has such a capacity ; in other words, whether he is capable of freedom or self-deter- mination. CHAPTER X. MORAL PHILOSOPHY (Continued). IDEA OF FREEDOM. The problem of human freedom springs from the same root as the problem of duty. In our ordinary judgments we say of ourselves or others, "That ought to be done," 11 That ought not to be done," and we assume in making such judgments that the individual may or may not act in a certain way according as he determines himself, or, in other words, wills, to act. But this first assumption of freedom seems to be thrown into doubt when we begin to consider the springs or motives of human conduct. For it may be argued that no action of man can take place without some motive, something that excites his activity. And what is a motive, it may be asked, but a particular desire excited by the idea of a certain object? But the desire is determined by the natural susceptibility of the individual, and this again is determined quite inde- pendently of the individual. One man is more susceptible to pleasure in the contemplation of a certain object than another. Some are more drawn by pleasures of sense, others by intellectual pleasures, still others by benevolent 236 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. pleasures ; but these differences have a purely natural basis. Nor does it alter the case if we adopt the point of view of the theory of development, and say that the susceptibility of the individual is the result of inheritance. And not only is each kind of pleasure apparently due to natural susceptibility, but the quantity of pleasure is also fixed. Of two men who take pleasure in music, one experiences a greater degree of pleasure than the other. It is in fact the degree of pleasure that determines the strength of a motive. If a pleasure of sense is imagined by one man as more intense than a pleasure of intellect, his action will be determined by the pleasure of sense ; if a pleasure of intellect is imagined as more intense than a pleasure of sense his action will be determined by the pleasure of intellect. But in the one case as in the other the pleasure whose intensive quantity is greater will determine the act. How then can it be said that there is any freedom of will ? There is no possibility of making a pleasure seem greater or less, and therefore no possibility of acting otherwise than we do act. Freedom of will is a dream. To this it has sometimes been answered that freedom of will is a fundamental fact of consciousness. In acting we are conscious that we act freely. It is further maintained that we are even able to act in opposition to the strongest motive. However pleasant an object may seem to be, we can refuse to be determined by it. This may be shown by the fact that there are cases in which two objects seem equally pleasant, and yet we act. Now, if the quantity of pleasure alone determined the will, in such cases we could not act at all. We should be like the ass of Buridanus which was placed between two bundles MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 237 of hay so exactly alike that it starved because there was nothing in either to turn the balance of its desires. But man is of a different texture : in such a case he would decide for one or the other, i.e., he would act without any motive. It is therefore possible to act purely from choice, without being influenced by motives. And this agrees with the fundamental fact of consciousness, the consciousness of our own freedom. We always act freely or from choice. When there are different motives before our minds, we choose that which we prefer. Freedom is the power of choice, the power to act independently of motives. These two opposite theories show that the problem of freedom is bound up with the question of motives. One school affirms that the strongest motive determines the act, the other maintains that action is determined freely without motives. I think we shall find, however, that neither of these views is true, though both contain an element of truth. The first theory is right in maintaining that we act from motives, wrong in denying that we act freely; the second theory is right in maintaining that we act freely, wrong in denying that we act independently of motives. In other words, motives are essential to freedom, freedom essential to motives. To see this we must inquire into the nature of a " motive." Both of these theories assume that a motive is a natural susceptibility to pleasure in the idea of an object, and that the degree of such susceptibility is determined inde- pendently of the subject. The first view infers from this assumed fact that action is the resultant of a conflict of desires, in which the strongest always prevails ; the second view, granting that this would be so if all action were determined by motives, maintains that the subject has 238 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. in himself a power of choice which is independent of motives. We have seen above that in man desire is not a mere susceptibility to pleasure, but the conception of self as capable of satisfaction in a certain object. To be conscious of self is to be beyond all merely external excitation. Nothing can act on the self without the activity of the self. We may see this indirectly by considering what would take place if the desire were merely a natural susceptibility. The self we are to suppose is not self- active, but is the passive recipient of certain impulses. We must suppose, then, that a certain impulse arises from the action of an external stimulus upon the individual. Thus, e.g., when the body requires nourishment, a craving arises of which the subject becomes conscious. But the craving is not due to any activity of the subject. The cause or stimulus is the condition of the body which excites the craving. All that the subject can do is to take note of the craving excited in him by the stimulus. The craving thus becomes a "motive" for the subject, i.e., it acts upon the subject and tends to move him in a certain direction ; in other words, to go through the series of movements by which food is supplied to the body for nourishment. To this it may be objected, that the craving for food does not lead to that series of movements until a volition has taken place, and this volition, it may be said, is an activity of the subject. The subject has to will the move- ments before they can take place. But how, it may be asked, does he come to will the movements? Would any subject will the act of eating if he were not impelled to do so by the natural craving? It is true that the movement must take place before the craving can be MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 239 satisfied, but there would be no movement were there no craving. It is therefore the craving which acts upon or excites the subject to act in a particular way. But, it may again be objected, the craving does not of itself lead to the action ; on the contrary, the subject, feeling the full force of the craving, may yet refuse to give way to it. Now, if the subject can prevent the craving from issuing in action, he must have an activity of his own. A man, e.g., may prefer to starve rather than give way to the crav- ing of hunger, if he can only satisfy his hunger by theft. "Just so," it is answered, "but he does not refrain from eating in such a case without any motive; he does so because he is acted upon by a stronger motive." The motive, in this case, is the desire for a greater pleasure to himself or others. Either he has a stronger desire for the good opinion of others, or of a Supreme Being; or he has a stronger desire for the well-being of others, i.e., for the greater amount of pleasure which will come to others from his abstinence than from his self-indulgence. Thus there is no free activity of the subject, but only an activity determined by the stronger of the two motives. In fact, when there is no competition of motives, there is no possibility of diverse activity. If a man is acted upon by the craving of hunger alone, he will inevitably do the acts by which the craving may be allayed. It is only when different impulses arise in him that a struggle takes place; and the struggle is not between an impulse on the one hand, and a free activity on the other, but between competing impulses. Which way the man shall act will depend upon the impulse which in him is strongest. If the craving for food is stronger than the desire for approbation or for the general good, he will satisfy his 240 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. craving at all hazards ; if the reverse, he will not satisfy it ; but in both cases the strongest motive must prevail. There is no free activity in either case, i.e., no activity that is independent of the motives acting upon the man. Volition, then, is simply the series of movements which issue from the strongest motive. The weak point in this explanation is, that it does not explain how the transition is made from desire to action. On the one hand stands desire ; on the other hand, the series of movements by which desire is expressed ; but how the junction is effected between desire and movement is not explained. This will be obvious if we take the instance already referred to. There arises in a man the desire for food. This means that the conscious subject experiences a feeling of want, and has the idea of the series of movements by which he may satisfy his want — the series of movements, i.e., im- plied in eating. But a feeling of want, so long as it re- mains a feeling, cannot issue in the series of movements required. I may be ever so hungry, but until a volition precedes the movements no action takes place. It may be said that the whole question is whether the desire is strong enough j if it is overpoweringly strong, it will inevitably issue in action. To this it must be answered that a desire as such can never issue in action, however strong it is. All that increase in the intensity of a desire can mean is, that the intensity of the feeling of want grows, and perhaps grows until it becomes the most terrible pain, as in the case of starvation from shipwreck or some other cause. In contrast to this intense pain, there appears before the imagination the most vivid image of the process of eating. But even then the series of MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 241 movements implied in eating does not take place. Hence between every desire and every series of movements there is interposed a volition ; and without volition there is no action. We may now see the mistake into which determinists fall who say that the strongest motive determines the act. By the strongest motive they must mean the most intense desire. That they do mean this is plain from the whole character of the theory. Every desire, it is said, is a desire for pleasure, and a motive is that desire for pleasure which is so strong as to overpower all com- peting desires. A "motive," in other words, is the strongest desire. But we have seen that a desire as such never issues in action, no matter how strong it may be. And there can be no meaning in calling that a "motive" which does not f issue in action, the very meaning of "motive" being that which gives rise to motion. Hence no desire, however strong, can be a motive. We must find the motive in something else than desire, or action would never take place at all. What, then, is a "motive"? In the instance already given we are to suppose the subject to experience the feeling of want which we call hunger, and to have an idea of the act of eating as a means of satisfying the want. Now, the feeling of want as experienced is the consciousness on the part of the subject that his actual condition at the moment is not the condition in which he would like to be. Thus the subject contrasts his actual condition with a condition that as yet exists only as an idea. His desire consists in the feeling of dissatisfaction arising from the opposition between his ideal and his actual condition. But still there is no action. If man were only capable of con- Q 242 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. trasting in thought his actual and his ideal self, he would never act at all. What more is required? It is required that, having the idea of himself as satisfied, so far as this particular desire for satisfaction is concerned, he should also have the idea of a certain action or series of movements as the means of such satisfaction. But even yet there is no action. I may believe that by the act of eating I should satisfy my desire for food, and yet I may not eat. Before I eat I must determine or will to eat, and it is this self-determination or volition that constitutes the motive. Determining to obtain the satisfaction of myself so far as the desire in question is concerned I will the means, and the action follows. Now the satisfaction of myself in this particular way becomes my motive. It is therefore not the desire for satisfaction that constitutes my motive, ]put the willing of the satisfaction. If we now look back to the theory that the strongest motive leads to action, we shall see that it is meaning- less. There was a certain plausibility in saying that the strongest motive prevails, so long as it was supposed that action could proceed from desire. For, if action is the result of a conflict between different desires, the only plausible explanation is, that the desire which has the greatest intensity prevails. It can be known to have the greatest intensity because it prevails, just as of two opposing forces of nature that is strongest which gives rise to the motion of a body. But if desire of itself never issues in action no desire can be a motive, and therefore the strongest desire cannot be a motive. On the other hand, if the motive is the volition, not the desire, there can be no meaning in saying that the MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 243 strongest motive prevails. Every volition prevails. No volition as such is stronger or weaker than another. But, when we have seen that there is no stronger or weaker volition, it is obvious that there is no such dis- tinction as that between a stronger and weaker motive, since the motive is the volition. Every motive is the act of a subject who, believing that he will find satis- faction in a certain action, determines to do it, and therefore wills it. The motive is thus just the self- determination of the subject. And if so, to have a motive is to be free. If there is no motive apart from self-determination or will, freedom is inseparable from motives. The supposition that an act is not due to the subject arises from the assumption, which we have seen to be false, that an act is the result of the pre- ponderance of a certain desire. When we see that a desire, however strong, would never of itself issue in action, we also see that the subject cannot be deter- mined to act from any preponderance of desire, but acts only as he determines himself to act. From this analysis of action we also learn that there can be no "liberty of indifference," i.e., no capacity of acting in opposition to motives. For, if a motive is just one of the modes in which the subject determines him- self, to act contrary to a motive would be to determine himself to act in opposition to his own will, which is absurd. Moreover, if a man could act without any motive, he would be acting from pure caprice, i.e., in opposition to the mode of action of a rational being. We have seen, then, that a motive is never a desire, and hence that to have a motive and to be free are the same thing. The doctrine that denies freedom 244 COMTE, MiLL, AND SPENCER. because man acts from motives, and the doctrine that affirms freedom because man can act without motives, are equally false; the truth being that man is free because he acts from motives. We have now to consider the view of freedom advanced by Kant, which differs from both of those theories. Freedom, according to Kant, is not incompatible with motives, but it is incompatible with all the motives that arise from the natural desires. I am free if I will the moral law, i.e., make duty my sole motive; I am not free if my act springs from a desire for some object which excites my sensibility. The idea of freedom, it is held by Kant, is in the first instance a negative idea, arising as it does from its contrast to the necessity of nature. What do we mean by nature? We mean a system of things in which each is dependent upon something else. Nowhere in nature can we find any object that has a nature of its own. If we take any object in space, we find that all its properties consist in relations to something else. If a change occurs in any body, we find that the change would not have occurred unless the body had been acted upon by some other body. The permanence of a body therefore consists in the permanence of its relations to other bodies. Nothing exists as an independent sub- stance. In fact, a substance not related to anything else would not belong to the system of things that we call nature. Now, the moral consciousness of man seems to de- mand that we should be absolutely independent of circumstances, or, in other words, that we should be determined purely by ourselves. For the moral law MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 245 commands absolutely, refusing to abate its claims in view of circumstances. It says : " No matter what your natural tendencies may be you ought to determine your- self by the inner law of your own being." But the difficulty arises that we seem to be, on the one hand, objects like other objects, and therefore to belong to the system of nature; while, on the other hand, we seem to be subjects, and therefore independent of the system of nature. How can we be both? How can we be at once under the dominion of natural law, and free from natural law? To this Kant answers, that in his moral consciousness man has the idea of himself as under a law of reason, and that in willing this law he is free. When I make the moral law my motive I determine myself by the idea of myself as I really am, and in such determination I am not acted upon by anything external. To make the moral law my motive is to be free, because there is no external com- pulsion in willing what reason shows to be my true self. So far, therefore, as you will observe, Kant recognizes that to be free is to act from a motive. But in limiting freedom to willing the moral law, he manifestly gets into this difficulty, that when a man acts from desire he is not free. Apparently, therefore, we are free to will good actions, but not to will bad actions. And this would seem to imply that we are not responsible for doing wrong, since, when we do wrong, the act is not ours, but flows from the necessity of our nature. The difficulty here referred to is inherent in the ethical doctrine of Kant. It arises from the absolute opposition of desire and reason. What we have to see is that such an opposition is inadmissible. 246 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. A desire, as we have seen, is never in itself a motive : it becomes a motive only when the subject identifies his own good with the object corresponding to the desire. Thus if, having the desire for wealth, I determine to seek my good in the pursuit of wealth, and will the acts necessary to secure it, I make wealth the "motive" of my action. There is, therefore, no proper meaning in saying that when a man acts from desire he is not free. For he never acts from desire as such, but only from the idea of himself as capable of being satisfied by the object of a desire. Now, Kant holds that we are conscious of freedom only in contrast to our determination by natural desire. This would be a correct account of the matter if a natural desire as it exists in our consciousness were simply a fact or occurrence in consciousness, a mere state of feeling excited in us irrespectively of our self-consciousness. But if desire were merely a feeling that presented itself to us — were it simply an event like any other event — we should not be conscious of it as a desire. If I perceive a stone fall, I am conscious of an event, of a certain change as having occurred, but I am not conscious of it as an event which has occurred to me, as a change in my state. But this is what happens when I am conscious of a desire. When I have the craving of hunger, it is for me not simply an event, but an event that affects me: I am conscious of myself as striving in idea towards an object that promises satisfaction to me. We cannot therefore oppose desire to reason as if the former were a mere mechanical occurrence and the latter involved the con- sciousness of self. Desire, being already the consciousness of oneself as capable of being satisfied, involves self- MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 247 consciousness. The idea of satisfaction in the object of a desire is therefore already the possibility of will, and so of freedom. Kant is therefore wrong in contrasting action from desire with action from reason, as external determina- tion to self-determination, necessity to freedom. Every motive, whatever its moral character — whether good or bad — involves freedom, because it involves ^^-determina- tion. Kant, in other words, correctly says that freedom consists in willing the idea of self, but he is wrong in saying that willing the idea of self only takes place when we will the good. To show this clearly we must ask how the contrast of freedom and necessity arises for us. Self-consciousness is primarily the consciousness of self as opposed to the world, and especially to other self- conscious beings. The self appears to be a single indi- vidual, who is conscious of desires that make for his own satisfaction, as distinguished from the satisfaction of others. But this apparent individuality or separateness of the self is a natural illusion; for it is impossible for the individual to find his own satisfaction apart from the world and from other selves. Selfishness is self-contradictory, because it seeks to satisfy the individual self by breaking the bonds which unite all selves ; and hence it is a repeated effort to obtain satisfaction, ending in repeated failure. Here is the point where the opposition of desire and reason presents itself. To act from passion, i.e., from the idea of individual satisfaction, is seen to be to act in contradiction of reason, i.e., to the idea of a universal satisfaction. We may therefore correctly contrast desire and reason, if by this we mean willing a selfish end and willing a universal end. Such a contrast, however, is not identical with the Kantian opposition of desire and reason ; 248 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. for, on Kant's view, desire is a merely natural impulse, reason alone giving the idea of the self. Selfishness involves the idea of self as much as unselfishness ; the difference is that the former seeks to realize the self in what is in- adequate to its true nature, the latter seeks to realize the self in what is adequate to its true nature. We can therefore say that selfishness is irrational, but we cannot say that it is exclusive of reason. Only a rational being can be irrational. Reason involves the possibility of error as well as of truth ; or, more precisely, reason gives man the idea of himself, and makes it possible for him to seek his good in what is inconsistent with that idea, while it also makes it possible for him to seek his good in what is consistent with that idea. The explanation of this anomaly is, that man at first seems to himself to be an individual standing in opposition to others. So appearing, reason tells him to realize this individual self. It is only when in attempting to do so he becomes conscious that he cannot realize himself in selfish ways that he comes to the consciousness of a self-realization through unselfish- ness. In this sense the Fall of Man is necessary to his salvation. Selfishness, in fact, may be called an irrational activity of reason, or a free willing of slavery. Freedom, then, is implied in all man's activity, but freedom can lead to perfect self-realization only when it is exercised in willing the good. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 249 THE SUMMUM BONUM. We have therefore to ask : What is the good ? what is the summum bonum ? The answer of the Hedonist is that the highest good will consist in the greatest possible sum of pleasure. We need not stay to show that this cannot be the highest good : pleasure is no doubt involved in the attainment of the highest good, but the highest good must consist in the perfect realization of self, or, in other words, in perfection of character, not in the experience of pleasure. It will be more profitable to consider the Kantian con- ception of the summum bonum, which attempts to show that man can only attain his " being's end and aim " in so far as the conflicting claims of reason and desire are reconciled. Kant begins by asking what is meant by the summum bonum; and he answers, that it may mean either (a) the chief good, or (b) the co7nplete good. Now, there is no doubt that virtue is man's chief good, since apart from morality man cannot be good at all. But a finite being cannot attain complete good unless he also obtains happi- ness. The complete good therefore involves the com- bination of perfect goodness with perfect happiness. And as men are not good by nature, but can only gradually approximate towards goodness, reason demands that happi- ness should be experienced by each in proportion to his goodness. The first point to be considered is, how happiness is related to virtue. The Stoics and Epicureans hold that virtue and happi- 250 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. ness are identical. According to the former, the virtuous man is the only happy man; according to the latter, the happy man is the only virtuous man. This identification Kant rejects. To be virtuous is not necessarily to be happy, to be happy is not necessarily to be virtuous. A man may be virtuous without being happy, or happy without being virtuous. The problem therefore remains, and at first sight it seems insoluble. If I will the moral law, do I thereby secure happiness ? By no means : to secure happiness I must learn the laws of nature and be able to turn my knowledge to account in furthering my own ends. If, on the other hand, I make happiness my end, my action ceases to be moral. When we look more closely, however, we find that there is an essential difference between the propositions, "Virtue is the necessary consequence of Happiness," and "Happiness is the necessary consequence of Virtue." The former proposition is absolutely false. The man who makes happiness his aim cannot be virtuous, because virtue consists in willing the moral law purely for itself. The latter proposition is not necessarily false. There is a sense in which it may be admitted to be true. We can- not say that by acting virtuously man will secure happi- ness, but it is quite conceivable that virtue should bring happiness, if the world were so arranged as to make happiness follow from virtue. Such a harmony man cannot effect, but it may be effected by a Being who stands to nature in the relation of its Author. The postulate, therefore, of an Author of nature is the only way in which we can conceive of the union of virtue and happiness. MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 25 1 This idea of nature as conceivably harmonizing with the moral life does not show that man can realize the summum bonum. There are two obstacles to such realization. In the first place, man can realize the summum bonum only if he is capable of perfect virtue. To be perfectly virtuous would be to get rid of all immediate desire and act purely from the law of reason. Now, this is impossible, because man cannot get rid of the solicitations of desire, and therefore morality can only be a continual process of subjecting the desires, as they spring up, to the moral law. All that is possible for man is, not the completed harmony of his desires with his reason, but the certain hope of con- tinuous progress in morality, as resting upon the habit of acting virtuously. Now, such a continuity in willing the moral law requires continued existence; and hence the possibility of realizing the chief good requires us to postulate the immortality of man. In no other way can we defend the absolute obligation laid upon us to live the moral life. In this life we can never realize the chief good, and therefore we are tempted to say that man can- not be required to realize it. On the other hand, if we say that in this life a man may become perfectly holy, we fall into " theosophic dreams " of a possible perfection that, with our continual shortcomings, is for us an im- possibility. By the postulate of immortality we avoid both of these fatal alternatives : we do not need to relax the severity of the moral law, because we are capable of continual progress towards perfect holiness : and we do not fall into the dream of an impossible perfection, because we see that morality is an endless progress towards perfection. In the second place, the realization of the summum 252 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. bonum implies the union of virtue and happiness. Sup- posing virtue to be more or less perfectly attained, how can we say that happiness in proportion to virtue must be united with it ? Yet, if it is our duty to seek the highest good, it must be possible that it should be realized. Now, it cannot be realized by us, for though we may will the moral law, we cannot by that volition secure happiness. The union of virtue and happiness is therefore possible only independently of our will. It can be produced only by a Being who is distinct from nature and yet the cause of it. And such a Being must be a cause whose character is in conformity with morality, i.e., a Being who is perfectly rational and perfectly good ; in other words, God. Kant's first postulate is immortality, or endless time, as the condition of the realization of the chief good, i.e., of virtue. The natural desires are in antagonism to the moral law, and as man cannot get rid of them without ceasing to be man, this subjection to the law of reason is a progressus ad infinitum. Now, to this view it may be objected, in the first place, that not even the postu- late of infinite time will account for the realization of virtue on Kant's premisses. For, so long as man is con- ceived to be a subject of desire, so long he is incapable of realizing perfect virtue. The opposition between reason and desire is supposed to be absolute, and therefore no extension of time will destroy it. If, indeed, we supposed Kant to hold that in a future life man would no longer be the subject of desire, we might suppose perfect virtue to be realized. But this he cannot hold, since his argu- ment for immortality rests upon the conflict between desire and reason. We are compelled to postulate MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 253 immortality, because reason demands the realization of perfect virtue, and such realization is impossible because the work of reason in subjecting desire to itself is never complete. We must deny, then, that the postulate of immortality solves the problem of the realization of holi- ness. " Infinite time," as has been said, "is not enough for an impossible task." In the second place, not only can virtue not be com- pletely realized, but it cannot be realized at all. Kant's argument rests upon the absolute opposition of reason and desire; and it is plainly impossible to bring oppo- sites any nearer to each other. On the other hand, if there is no opposition of reason and desire, the whole argument for a progress to infinity falls to the ground. Kant's argument for immortality loses its force because he reasons from the impossibility of morality in a finite time to the possibility of morality in an infinite time. This argument we have seen to be invalid. The nature of a thing is not changed by the mere passing of time. "White is not made any more white," as Aristotle said, in criticizing the eternal ideas of Plato, "by being sup- posed to exist for ever." In other words, unless man can be moral now, he cannot become moral simply if he is supposed to exist for ever. What we must say, therefore, is that every act in which the agent identifies himself with an objective end is a moral act. In Kant's view no progress in morality is possible because morality can never begin. Just as knowledge cannot develop unless there is knowledge, so moral progress can be made only if man can be moral. Now, if man has within him a principle of morality, the argument for immor- 254 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. tality will take a new form. There is no limit, it may be said, to the development of a living principle. If man is capable of knowledge he is capable of growing intellectually until his knowledge " has orbed into the perfect star"; if he is capable of morality he is capable of a progress in morality to which no limits can be set. Thus we may argue, that as man is capable of infinite progress in knowledge and morality — in a word, of infinite self-development — immortality is bound up with the very idea of self-consciousness. To be completely self-conscious would be to know all reality and to have attained to perfect holiness, since perfect self-conscious- ness is possible only in the perfect union of subject and object. In other words, the argument for immortality must be based, not upon what man cannot know or do, but upon what he can know and do. Kant's second postulate of God as the Being who har- monizes virtue and happiness is also open to objection. On the one hand Kant argues that the good lies in the will of man, so that it is realized whether a man attains happiness or not. The martyr sacrifices his happiness absolutely in laying down his life, yet in this sacrifice he realizes the good. There can therefore be no reason for postulating the existence of a Supreme Being, so far as the realization of man's true self is concerned. Happi- ness is, from this point of view, a matter of indiffer- ence. Kant, however, holds that reason rightly demands the union of virtue and happiness. But this union, he maintains, cannot be attained by man; and that for two reasons ; firstly, because nature goes on by a law of its own, a law which does not harmonize with the law of reason; and, secondly, because each man is dependent MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 255 upon others, so that only in a community of perfectly moral beings could happiness be proportionate to virtue, and such a community is an ideal that can never be realized. Kant therefore argues that we must postulate the existence of God, just because in human life happi- ness cannot be united with virtue. They cannot be united, yet reason demands their union, therefore they are united in God. But the argument, to be valid, must take a positive form. That the world is incompatible with the realiza- tion of the highest good cannot be a reason for main- taining the existence of God, but rather a reason for denying it. Only if it can be shown that the world is compatible with the highest good can we argue that exist- ence is a manifestation of God. We must, in other words, show that in the moral life happiness and virtue are combined, and are combined just because " all things work together for good to them that love the Lord." This faith is the source of the religious consciousness, and from it spring all the efforts of men to raise them- selves and others. We must therefore say, not that the impossibility of effecting the union of virtue and happi- ness is the ground of our belief in the existence of God, but, on the contrary, the possibility of such union. The union is effected for the individual in the willing of objective ends that bring satisfaction with them. The man who lives for his family at once wills the good and finds his happiness in realizing it. The reformer wills his country, and in devotion to it he finds his happiness. So in all cases of willing an end that is not selfish. It is true that complete happiness is not obtained. But neither is complete goodness. And it is not too much 256 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. to say, that a man is happy in proportion to his good- ness. Even the martyr in the sacrifice of all lower happiness gains a happiness for which nothing else could compensate. It is, then, the possibility of this union of happiness and goodness in man that entitles us to maintain the perfect union of the two in God. If the world is compatible with the relative harmony of virtue and goodness in us, it already shows itself to be the expression of a Being who is perfectly good. CHAPTER XI. MORAL PHILOSOPHY (Continued). PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHTS. We have seen that the idea of Duty implies the identifi- cation of the subject with a universal end in which the true self may be realized ; and that freedom is the capacity, and the highest good the result, of such self-identification. We have now to consider more particularly the forms in which the subject realizes universal ends. The first and simplest form is in relation to external things and services ; in other words, self-realization is exhibited in the sphere of individual Rights. Kant distinguishes the sphere of Rights from the sphere of Morais in this way, that in the former the will of man is viewed as expressing itself outwardly in acts, while, in the latter, it is viewed only as determined inwardly by motives. The moral law tells us to treat all self-conscious beings as ends, never as means. But here a difficulty arises. When a man acts, his action takes an outer form, and therefore it affects the outer existence of others. If, e.g., R 258 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. a man steals ray property, he interferes with that which is necessary to my existence as a particular being. The problem of jurisprudence is therefore to prevent one man from interfering with the free activity of another, and this cannot be done, consistently with the freedom of each, unless each man voluntarily imposes upon himself the same limit as he imposes upon others. Now, the principle of all free will is to act in conformity with a law that can be universalized. Applying this principle to external action, it would take the form : Impose no limit upon others that you do not impose upon yourself. For example, if others are to respect my property, I must respect theirs ; otherwise the maxim on which I act is not universal. All acts which prevent another from doing the like are self-contradictory. It is therefore in accordance with the law of freedom that such acts should be prevented or annulled. Hence the compulsion of law is quite consistent with freedom. A man is free to will a universal law, but he is not free to will what is merely agreeable to himself. Law, in compelling men to respect the rights of others, does not interfere with freedom, but only with the unreason of particular desires, which is, in fact, the nega- tion- of freedom. Now, in the sphere of Rights, we have nothing to do with the motive from which an action is done, but only with the overt act. If a man respects the rights of pro- perty of others, Law does not ask whether he does so from the fear of punishment, from a desire for the esteem of others, or from regard for the moral law; it is enough that the act conforms to the law. Hence, the aim of law is not to make men act from the highest motives, but to MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 259 prevent them from acting in opposition to the rights of others. A right is thus something purely external. "When it is said that a creditor has the right of exacting pay- ment from his debtor, this does not mean that he can put it to the conscience of the debtor that he ought to pay. It means that a compulsion to pay in such a case can be applied consistently with everyone's freedom, consistently, therefore, with the debtor's own freedom, according to a universal external law. Right and claim to apply compulsion are therefore the same thing." Now, as in law freedom means independence of com- pulsion by another, and the reciprocal limitation of each by the others, the first of rights is equality. No man can demand of me what I cannot demand of him, and I can act towards others as I please so long as I do nothing to prevent them from acting as they please towards me. How is such freedom realized in the outer world? What is meant by a right? Nothing can limit the freedom of one man but the freedom of another, (i) Rights belong only to persons, not to things. Outward things are the means of realizing the will of a person. Hence (2) rights are held by one person as against all others. And -(3) lastly, the relation of persons is recip- rocal. Slavery, e.g., is inconsistent with the principle of rights, because it gives all the rights to one person, with- out recognizing that he is only entitled to rights at all if he respects the rights of all other persons. The basis of all rights, then, is the inviolability of each person. But each person expresses himself in the objects into which he has put his will, and which are inviolable because expressing the will of an inviolable person. Thus arises property, the distinction of mine and thine. To 260 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. interfere with the objects in which each person expresses his will is to interfere with the person himself. Property is not the same thing as physical possession; it is an "intelligible" possession. A thing is mine, not because I hold it, but because my will is expressed in it. (a) The first form, then, of rights is that of jus in rem, or the right of persons over things. Such a right implies other persons while yet it excludes them. It must be recognized, or persons would come into collision with one another. At the same time it does not imply the actual assent of others, and in this it differs from (b) Jus in personam, i.e., personal rights, the rights of one person to an object first possessed by another, or to some service which the other can perform for him. Such a right implies a direct act of transference to the one of that which primarily belongs to the other. This is con- tract. Here the right is established not against all, but against a particular person. In the case of contract for service, the service must be limited in extent and char- acter, otherwise the jus in personam would be equivalent to slavery. (c) Kant adds a third form of rights, jus realiter personate. Here a person becomes not only the subject but the object of a right, i.e., a person is treated as a thing. Kant should evidently have said that such a right contradicts the very idea of free personality on which rights are based. The contradiction arises from the attempt to apply the idea of rights to the family. In marriage the contracting parties acquire right over each other. Each must surrender to the other. Hence poly- gamy and all irregular unions are contrary to the idea of personal rights, because they give to one a right not MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 26 1 granted to the other. Again, children have no rights as against parents, except the right to be supported and educated ; corresponding to which is the right of the parents to govern and direct the child while its powers are immature. So much as to the nature of Private Rights (Jus Pri- vatum, Jus Naturale). But how is the individual to be secured in his rights? There must be a political power, which at once secures each man's rights and excludes him from interfering with the rights of others. There is there- fore required a universal will armed with absolute power. The condition of those who submit to this power is the civil state. Everyone must enter the civil state, because in it alone is there security for rights. "The act whereby a people constitutes itself into a state ... is the original contract by which all members of the people give up their freedom in order to take it up again as members of a commonwealth." The State frees the individual from his particular desires by bringing him under a law of reason. But Kant holds that the State can only take away hin- drances to freedom. The social contract is therefore a contract men are bound to make; and, when made, it can never be broken. A right of revolution is a contra- diction of the very idea of right. Rebellion can never be just, however imperfect the form of the State. To execute the sovereign, as was done in the case of Charles I. and Louis XVI., is a crime against the very idea of justice. At the same time the true or ultimate form of the State is a Republic, and it is obligatory on the sovereign power gradually to bring the State into that form. In the Ideal State the supreme legislative power must be exercised by representatives of the people. This Kant seeks to prove 262 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. as follows. All citizens, as free, equal, and independent, are at once subject and ruler, i.e., they are under a law which they themselves enact. But if so, must not all laws be enacted by all the citizens ? At first Kant seems to say so, but he makes limitations which destroy the force of the admission. (1) There is a distinction between active and passive citizens. Passive citizens include women and children, house servants and day labourers, i.e., all who sell their services. These are only potential citizens, and have no votes until they become actual citizens by gaining a position in which they do not sell their services. (2) There must be a representative system, in which the people do not directly legislate, but elect deputies to do so. The reason is that the legislative must be separated from the executive power. But while the whole people should not legislate, no law should be passed to which the whole people could not give their assent. For ex- ample, a law giving supreme authority to a class is not just. Hence it is wrong to secure such authority to a class by inheritance. But any law that a whole people could possibly accept must be regarded as just, even though at the time the people might not assent to it. Applying this principle, Kant rejects all privileges of birth, all right of inheritance in offices of State, and an established church, especially if it has a fixed creed. So all corporate institutions, for education or charity, are sub- ordinate to the State, and may be abolished at any time and their property seized. The citizens, on the other hand, should have the right of free speech; for all laws must be assumed to be such as the whole people would enact, and therefore the people have the right to show that any law proposed or enacted is contrary to that MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 263 principle. Kant therefore denies Hobbes' principle, that the sovereign has only rights and not duties. It is the duty of the sovereign to enact nothing that is contrary to justice, and to enact everything that is essential to the maintenance of justice. Kant applies this idea of the State to Penal Justice in an unflinching way. Punishment, he holds, must be inflicted without any regard to the happiness either of the criminal or of society, but solely with a view to the main- tenance of justice. Legal penalty {poena forensis) is not like natural penalty {poena naturalis). Vice punishes itself by bringing unhappiness, but the punishment of crime is purely because of the transgression committed. A man is punished because he deserves it; punishment is his own transgression coming back upon himself. Whether punishment is useful is not to the point : for " if justice perish there is no longer any value in the existence of men upon the earth." The principle on which punishment should be inflicted is that of equality. By inflicting evil on another a man affirms that the same amount of evil should be inflicted on himself. Hence the only adequate punishment for murder is death, for nothing is commen- surable with death but death. " Even if a civil society were on the point of being dissolved with the consent of all its members (e.g., if a people dwelling on a desert island had resolved to separate), they would be bound first of all to execute the last murderer in their prisons." Passing now to International Law, we have to ask on what principles it is based. It is based, says Kant, on the same principle as the law of the State. Just as indi- vidual men were bound to combine in a State, so all States are bound to combine in a Universal State. But 264 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. the practical difficulties which stand in the way are so great that we must be content to employ the conception of a Universal State mainly as an ideal. An everlasting peace cannot be realized, but to it a continual approxi- mation may be made, and therefore every State ought to act with a view to its realization. Kant even suggests articles for the future Law of Nations, which he thinks would tend to bring about such a peace, (a) No treaty of peace shall be made with the secret reservation of causes of quarrel, (b) No State shall be transferred by inheritance or gift, (c) No public debts shall be con- tracted with a view to war. (d) No State shall in war make use of means that destroy mutual faith, e.g., breach of capitulation or attempts to make use of treachery among the enemy. But these articles are merely prepara- tory. It is further required that every State should be republican in its constitution, for no other constitution is based on the freedom and equality of all the citizens. It is the great body of the people who suffer from war, not the king or governing aristocracy. Starting from one republic, a federation of States may gradually be secured, with the object of preventing war. In such a league one special article would be to secure the rights of each citizen in the contracting States as a "citizen of the world," i.e., to secure to him freedom to visit and to trade in other countries than his own. Finally, the prin- ciple of all politics is that what is right should be done, not what is practicable. We cannot tell what is practicable, but we can tell what is right. The philoso- pher ought therefore to be called in to assist the statesman, i.e., there should be free discussion of the principles on which States are and ought to be based. Thus in / MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 265 politics, as in morals, we shall learn to make what ought to be our standard. 1 CRITICISM OF KANT'S DOCTRINE OF RIGHTS. Kant's Doctrine of Rights may be said to be a trans- ference to the outward acts of man of that opposition between Desire and Reason, which on his general theory is exhibited in the inner world of the individual's own consciousness. The actions of a man may either flow from a desire for his own personal satisfaction, or they may be consistent with the law of reason. In the former case everything which the man desires he will seek to secure by employing the means necessary. Thus he may desire to possess land, or goods, or the services of others, simply because he regards these as fitted to minister to his individual pleasure. But desire has no limit in itself. If I act purely from a desire for land, I shall take it without any reference to the desires of others. It matters not that another may possess the land, and may equally desire it with me. I care nothing for his desires, but only for my own. If I come into collision with another because we both wish to have the same land, the only way to settle the conflicting claims is that "he should take who has the power, and he should keep who can." " Might is right." Thus the unlimited exercise of desire leads to violence, to the war of all against all, in which the strongest or the most cunning will 1 A fuller statement of Kant's doctrine of Rights will be found in Caird's Critical Accotmt of the Philosophy of Kant, Vol. II., chapter vi., which is so admirable that nothing remained for me to do but to condense it. The same remark applies to the statement of Kant's " System of Moral Duties" given below. 266 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. succeed best. So far as desire is concerned, no indi- vidual has any rights ; because no one recognizes the claims of another, and each seeks to satisfy his own natural desire for what will bring him pleasure. With this activity of natural desire Kant contrasts the activity which proceeds from a law of reason. For reason denies the claims of mere desire, and asserts that each man should be treated as a "person," i.e., as a being who has claims to external things. Reason says that I have no more claim to external things than other persons. If limits are to be set to my naturally unlimited desire for my own satisfaction, I must not only claim a right over things, but I must admit that others have an equal claim over them. Now, things are limited, and therefore no single person can lay claim to all things* The only way therefore in which violence can be brought to an end is by each person limiting himself to those things that belong to him. So long as these limits are observed there can be no disputes and no violence. But here the difficulty arises, that it is always possible for the individual to fall back upon natural desire. Men are quite willing that others should respect their rights, but under the influence of natural desire they are prompted to deny the rights of others. A piece of land belongs to another, but some one who covets it may get possession of it if he is stronger or more cunning than the rightful possessor. Thus the unlimited claim of desire is substituted for the limited claim of reason. Now, anyone who thus sets up his own desire as ultimate can no longer claim to be treated as a rational being. If he is justified in seizing a thing which belongs to another simply because he desires it, another is equally MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 267 justified in seizing what belongs to him, and thus the reign of violence begins over again. To act from desire is thus to appeal to violence, and therefore violence may be employed against him. It is from this point of view that Kant justifies the existence of the State. A power is needed to compel the desires of men to keep within the limits of reason. If men always respected the rights of others, there would be no need for any external force to compel them to do so. But they do not; and hence a power outside of them- selves is required to make them respect the rights of others, and to make others respect their rights. In the outward sphere, therefore, a State Power is necessary to "compel men to be free." And only the State can be invested with such a power, because violence exerted by an individual is merely a new manifestation of desire. For example, in blood-feuds, the motive is not a law of reason, but the desire of revenge. It is therefore justifi- able to force men to enter into society, since society is the condition of each person becoming free. (1) This theory of society is not self-consistent. It holds, on the one hand, that rights belong to individuals irrespective of society, and, on the other hand, that for such rights they are indebted to society. For Kant bases individual rights upon the conception of a person as an abstract or exclusive self. As such an abstract self I can realize myself in independence of other selves. My free- dom consists in this, that there are things in which my will is expressed, and with which no one may interfere. Now, it is no doubt true that the conception of rights as an ideal excludes the interference of others with what is mine. But who is to secure the observance of such 268 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. rights? Obviously, the individual must recognize that the law of reason, and not the law of desire, is to be obeyed, i.e., he must view himself as a member of a community in which the rights of all are bound up with the rights of each. If so, the community is not a matter of accident : it is not a contract into which individuals may or may not enter, but it is a form of association to which they belong, because otherwise they would have no rights. In other words, suppose each man to be only accidentally related to others, and there can be no absolute rights, because no one is bound to combine with others. The individual may say, I prefer to seek my good by myself, i.e., I prefer to find satisfaction for my desires by getting as much as I can for myself. Only if we grant that without society men cannot realize their true self, can it be maintained that no one is justified in separating himself from society. But if society is neces- sary to constitute a right, as distinguished from a mere object of desire, it cannot be said that society is an accidental relation into which men may or may not enter; it is a relation into which they must enter by the very law of their reason. I have rights only as a mem- ber of society, not as a separate individual. If we develop what is implied in Kant's theory, we shall see that he virtually admits society to be essential to the existence of rights. For he maintains that men may force others to enter into society, and that it is an absolute duty to respect the order of society when once it has been formed. On what ground can it be main- tained that men may be compelled to enter into society, unless on the ground that only so can man's true nature be realized? On any other supposition society can have MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 269 power over the individual only because it is stronger than he, i.e., it becomes a mere despotism, interfering with the individual's claim to be free of its regulations. But Kant really implies that the compulsion of society is a compulsion of reason. Men must enter society because in society they get rid of the caprice of their individual desires, which have no limit in themselves. Hence Kant holds that, whether the individual consents or not, the laws imposed by society must be respected ; and this means that society is essential to the very existence of rights, i.e., to the necessary means by which the indivi- dual secures his freedom. This may be seen still more clearly if we consider Kant's theory of jus realiter personate. Take, e.g., the family relation. Kant admits that here the principle on which all other rights are based does not properly apply. An ordinary right can exist only in relation to a thing, i.e., an object which has no personality. No one can possess a right in a person, because that would make the person a mere thing, and deprive him of his personality. This is why slavery is contrary to the idea of rights. The slave has no rights. Now, in the family relation, there are no exclusive rights. Husband and wife give up to each other their independent personality, and have no rights as against each other. What belongs to the one belongs also to the other, so far as the relation applies. Here therefore there are no exclusive rights; in other words, the separate personality of each is negated. Kant says that in this case the surrender of personality is re- ciprocal. No doubt this is true; but if personality is surrendered by each, it must be because there is here a bond higher than that of abstract personality; for other- 270 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. wise the relation would be a violation of freedom. The facts thus force Kant to admit that the true nature of man is here realized only on the supposition that man in his true nature is not an abstract person, but is capable of entering into a relation which is higher than abstract personality. Now the same thing applies to society. The members of a State are not separate individuals who may or may not combine, but their combination is essential to the freedom of each. Each individual is a member in an organism, and realizes himself only as he makes the common good his end. If society is organic, individuals can have no rights apart from society. In other words, the foundation of the claim for rights must lie in this, that the general good can be realized only by assigning to each individual rights with which no other individual may interfere. The ultimate reason for the claim to rights is not that as an individual a man has such a claim, but that the perfection of his nature as a social being demands it. If it could be shown that men would realize a higher perfection in a society in which there were no individual rights, we should have to say that such rights cannot be permitted. The reason for main- taining personal rights is thus a social one. (2) Kant holds that law deals only with overt acts, not at all with the motives from which acts are done. Morality, again, looks only at motives, asking whether the will has been determined purely by the law of reason, and not by desire. What we may seek is a form of the State in which individuals are brought into external har- mony with each other ; but we must not by means of law seek to make men moral. Goodness cannot be produced MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 27 I by the compulsion of society, because, while you may make men conform to the external law of society, you cannot make them good. Goodness is something that can be realized only by each subject for himself. It is certainly the individual's duty to do what he can to bring about a more perfect form of society, and he must also try to further the happiness of others; but he cannot be asked to make them good, because it is not in his power to do so. Thus mankind is conceived as a sum of independent persons. Now, if there are no rights apart from society, we cannot thus separate the moral development of each in- dividual from that of others. It is no doubt plausible to say that the inner life of each is hidden from every one but himself, or, at least, only imperfectly expressed in his outward actions ; and that we can therefore infer nothing in regard to the inner life of others without first experi- encing it in ourselves. It is indeed a mere truism that what we have had no experience of we cannot learn from without. But this inner experience is not separable from outer experience. We have not first a knowledge of oUr own individual states and then refer these by analogy to others. It is only when we have gone beyond our im- mediate feelings that we understand ourselves at all, and the same process enables us to understand others. Nay, it may be said that we first learn to understand ourselves by understanding others. It is through the community of persons that the individual understands himself. If there were no common life, if society were not an expression of morality, the individual would never realize the meaning of his own moral nature. When a man comes to the consciousness that in his own reason 272 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. there is a law of morality, he at first opposes the idea of himself to the community; but had he not been moralized by the community in the first place, such a return upon himself would be impossible. (3) And this leads us to see what is the true meaning of punishment. Kant denies that punishment can be regarded either as preventative or as educational. The sole object of punishment is to vindicate the principle of rights. The criminal affirms the law of his natural desires, and society uses violence to cause his irrational act to recoil on himself. Properly regarded, there is no contradiction between these three theories of punishment. The object of all punishment is to maintain the social unity as against the caprice of individuals. Punishment is therefore pre- ventative in this sense, that, by tending to awaken in men the consciousness that they are all members of one body, it supplies them with an ideal which tends to prevent them from acting as if they were mere individuals. It is also educational, because it tends to awaken the conscious- ness that crime is worthy of punishment. And lastly, it is a vindication of right in the sense that right is the means by which the higher social self may be realized. Observe, however, that punishment is not preventative merely in the sense that it hinders the commission of particular crimes, but in the sense that it affirms the principle which strikes at the root of all crimes. That is to say, the object of punishment is not simply to deter men from crime by the fear of punishment, but to lead them to view crime as irrational. So punishment is edu- cational, not in the sense of making men fear the penalty, but in the sense of making them fear the guilt. And finally, punishment vindicates right, not as the rights of MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 273 individuals, but as the condition of the higher self which is realized in the social organism, We may therefore say that punishment has to do with the moral nature of man, because it seeks to make the individual substitute the rational motive of self-realization by identification with others for the irrational motive of self-realization by separation from others. Thus the two ends of making men moral and making them happy combine in one : for, as morality is identical with real happiness, to secure the one is to secure the other also. SYSTEM OF MORAL VIRTUES. What, then, are the special forms in which man realizes himself? What, in other words, are the specific duties of man? Kant's conception of duties, as distinguished from rights, is that whereas the latter are enforced by society, the former are enforced by the individual upon himself. Law compels men to respect the rights of others, whatever their natural inclination may be; Morality compels a man to respect the moral law which his own reason reveals to him. The opposition is no longer between an external authority and natural inclination, but between natural inclination and the internal authority of reason. No one can compel a man to be moral, because morality consists in free submission of the individual to the moral law. A man may act in accordance with the idea of duty because he is compelled to do so by the pressure of an external authority, but his act is not therefore moral, because it is not done from a moral motive. In morality the motive as well as the action must be in harmony with the law. This is the single principle of duty. But •274 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. this principle takes different forms according to the different ends which are sought to be realized, i.e., we can distinguish various duties by distinguishing the various ends of action which we ought to have. Now, there are two ends which we ought to realize : (i) our own perfection, (2) the happiness of others. (1) By perfection is meant conformity with the moral law. Such conformity is possible only in so far as a man rises above his animal nature and develops the faculties belonging to him as man. Perfection therefore means, firstly, the development of the faculties characteristic of man. But, secondly, perfection implies purity of will, i.e., that virtuous temper of mind in which the moral law is the sole motive and standard of action. Our duty to ourselves, then, is to develop all our faculties and to cultivate purity of will. (2) Our duty to others is to seek their happiness. It is not our duty to seek our own happiness, for that is an end which natural inclination inevitably prompts us to seek. The happiness of others, again, is not what they think to be their happiness, for often they suppose it to consist in what is inconsistent with it. Nor can we seek the perfection of others directly, for perfection can only be secured by the individual himself; still we may indirectly aid men in their efforts after perfection, by avoiding everything that will mislead them into a false view of their perfection. Thus the moral law implies two commands : (1) Do for yourself all that you regard as binding upon others; (2) Do for others all that you would wish them to do for you. We must, however, distinguish between "obligations of right" and "obligations of virtue." There are various MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 275 duties, and one of these may limit the other to a certain extent. Thus the question may arise how far phil- anthropy is to be limited by one's duty to his own family. It is a man's duty to seek both the general good and the good of his family, and no exception can be admitted; but how far he is to seek the one or the other must be determined by particular considerations. There are three characteristics of duty. (1) There is only one ground of each duty. For example, obligation to truthfulness is not the injury done to others by lying, but the moral worthlessness of the liar. (2) The difference between virtue and vice is a differ- ence in kind not in degree. Aristotle is therefore wrong in making virtue a mean between two vices. The virtue of good husbandry is not that more is spent than is done by the avaricious man and less than is done by the prodigal. Prodigality and avarice are vices because their motives are immoral. The prodigal spends his money simply as a means to enjoyment^ the avaricious man saves his money because of the enjoyment which is found in its possession ; good husbandry makes use of wealth simply as a means to higher ends. (3) Our duties are not determined by our capacity, but our capacity by our duties. We must not say, " I have done all that could be expected of me," but, "I have not attained to the perfect standard of humanity." Virtue may be called a " habit," if it is added that it is a "free habit/' or a "habit of acting by the idea of law." Virtue is always advancing, because it is an unattainable ideal : it is always beginning, because the natural desires cannot be got rid of, and therefore we never attain to a perfectly formed state of virtue. If our actions ever 276 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. became merely habitual, they would have no moral character, because there would be no freedom in the choice of maxims of conduct. Kant distinguishes between (1) Duties to ourselves and (2) Duties to others. I. Duties to Ourselves. 1. Negative or Strict. (a) Duties to ourselves as having an animal nature. These correspond to the three natural impulses of (a) self-preservation, (/?) maintenance of the species, (7) main- tenance of the capacity to use one's powers for useful ends, and for the animal enjoyment of life. These are virtues, because man's physical life is a means to his exist- ence as a person. The vices opposed to them are (a) suicide, (/3) unnatural sensual indulgence, (7) inordinate enjoyment of the pleasures of the table. (6) Duties to ourselves as moral beings. There are here also three virtues, (a) truthfulness, (/?) good husbandry, (7) self-respect. The corresponding vices are (a) lying, (/?) avarice, (7) false humility. The liar is "a mere semblance of humanity, and not a true man." Avarice is the slavish subjection of oneself to the goods of fortune. As to false humility, "he who makes himself a worm cannot complain if others trample upon him." As a person, a man is above all price, and ought not to crouch before his fellows, as if he had no self-centred life of his own. Even the slavish fear of Eastern devotees before the divine involves a sacrifice of human dignity. All the duties of man to himself rest upon his being the "born judge of himself." Hence man's first duty is MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 277 to ki know himself," in the sense of finding out what con- science commands. " Descent into the hell of self- knowledge is the only way to the heaven of divine excellence." 2. Positive. These are simply the duties of developing the bodily and mental powers, and above all the duty of cultivating purity of will II. Duties to Others. These are either (a) those which give rise to an obliga- tion on the part of others, or (b) those which do not give rise to an obligation on the part of others. The former are accompanied by the feeling of love, the latter by the feeling of respect. Love and respect ought to be united. We may compare them to a force of attraction and a force of repulsion. " By the principle of mutual love men are called upon to approach each other, by the principle of respect to preserve a certain distance from each other. As mere feelings, love and respect are not duties j the duties are respectively benevolence and reverence for others as persons. (a) The maxim of benevolence rests on the principle that we can wish well to ourselves only on condition that we wish well to others. The duties that fall under it are three : (a) beneficence, (/?) gratitude, (y) sympathy. (b) The duties of reverence for others arise from "the recognition in other men of a worth for which there is no price or equivalent." We must reverence the dignity of humanity even in the degraded and vicious. Hence we must condemn all punishment by mutilations, which 278 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. bring shame on humanity. So we must respect the in- telligence of others, and in correcting their errors bring out the element of truth in that which misled them. The vices opposed to respect for humanity are (a) pride, (/?) evil-speaking, (7) readiness to mock and insult. There are other duties determined by age, sex, or cir- cumstances, but they cannot be determined on general principles. Of these the most important is Friendship. Kant holds that we can further the happiness of others, but not their moral perfection. For, if a man is acted upon by another, he argues, he cannot be determined purely by the moral law, and therefore he cannot be free. Each man must therefore work out his own moral salvation. It is our duty to seek our own perfection and the happiness of others, but it can never be a duty to seek the perfection of others or the happiness of ourselves. Kant, however, so far modifies his first view as to admit that we may individually assist others in the attainment of moral perfection by taking care not to throw tempta- tions in their way which would lead to their having the misery of a bad conscience. In other words, it is each man's own duty to preserve a blameless conscience, and when he does wrong he can blame no one but himself. To say that "the woman tempted me" is to deny one's freedom as a rational being. But, while no one can blame another for his moral guilt, each may blame himself for putting obstacles in the way of another. For human nature is weak, and is too ready to follow the passions. Now, if it is admitted that we may put hindrances in the way of others, it cannot be denied that we may also act so as to help others in their moral life. If a man MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 279 by his bad example tempts others to wrong, may he not also by his good example induce others to do right? Kant thinks that we cannot affect directly the moral life of others, because morality is a personal matter. Morality is no doubt a personal matter, but it is not therefore carried on in isolation. The influence of good or bad example would not be a moral influence, if men were not capable of appropriating what is good or bad for themselves. Men are not exonerated from moral blame because others act immorally, nor do they cease to deserve moral praise because others act morally ; but this does not alter the fact that morality is essentially social. We are moral beings only as we are capable of viewing ourselves as members of a social organism. We usually deter- mine the moral quality of our actions by reference to the standard of the society to which we belong. If it is objected that in that case we are simply acting from custom, the answer is that to view conduct from the social point of view is not necessarily to act from custom. To act merely from custom is to act by reference to an external standard, the basis of which we do not compre- hend. To act from the social point of view, on the other hand, is to judge all actions, our own and others, from the unexpressed principles on which the common social life rests. The consciousness of these principles gradually grows up in us because we gain the conscious- ness of ourselves only in and through our relations to others. It is true that we may at a later stage come to be conscious that the ordinary standard of action em- bodied in the special form of society to which we belong is inadequate ; but the consciousness of this inadequacy would be impossible for us did not society already 280 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. involve rational principles of action. Thus he who has been so far moralized by coming to the consciousness of the principle upon which the family rests, is prepared for the comprehension of the wider principle upon which the State rests, and, ultimately, for the still wider principle upon which humanity rests. Thus, moral freedom is not the freedom of the mere individual, but the freedom which rests upon self-identification with a universal law that first reveals itself to us in a social law. From this point of view we can see that there can be no opposition, such as Kant maintains, between our duty to ourselves and our duty to others. Every duty is at once a duty to ourselves and a duty to others. Thus the duty of furthering one's own physical and moral well- being is at the same time a duty to society, because it is only by doing so that we can become fit members of the social organism. We are to withstand the immediate promptings of desire, but the gratification of these is con- trary at once to our own welfare and the welfare of others. Nor can it be said, as Kant says, that we must give up our own happiness for the good of others and not at all of ourselves. If this were so, the perfect form of society would be one in which each surrendered all that belonged to himself. In such a society, the aim would be to gratify the selfishness of others, not to reach a point in which all selfishness is done away. In point of fact, the attempt to yield up all to the will of another may develop enor- mous selfishness on the part of those to whom the surrender is made. 1 What we ought to seek is to secure the moral 1 It may be worth while referring to the illuminating poetic treat- ment of this idea in Euripides' Alcestis, at least as "transcribed" and interpreted in Browning's noble " Balaustion's Adventure." MORAL PHILOSOPHY. 281 perfection of all, ourselves as well as others ; and this can only be secured by acting from the point of view of a universal good applicable alike to them and to our- selves. Thus only can a higher spirit take possession of every member of the community. CHAPTER XII. PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. RELIGION. Morality ultimately rests upon the consciousness of an ideal good for man which is identical with the good of existence as a whole. In other words, there is no abso- lute good unless it can be shown that man is seeking to realize what is in conformity with the unchangeable nature of God. A rational faith in God is, therefore, at the basis of morality. This is denied by Kant. He maintains that morality is independent of religion, because the reason of man commands him to realize the moral law, even irrespec- tive of the union of virtue and happiness. The idea of morality is its own guarantee, and unless it can be established independently it is impossible to prove the existence of God at all. God is postulated only because on no other supposition can we explain the possibility of the union of virtue and happiness. Kant, however, proceeds to ask how far, in consistency with his own theory, he can accept the fundamental ideas of the Christian religion. And, first of all, he discusses the question of Original Sin. PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 283 The problem, as he puts it, is this : There is in all men a bias to evil ; and this bias seems to be a tendency inherited from our ancestors. But, on the other hand, when we do a wrong action, we attribute the evil to ourselves, and that irrespective of any inherited tendency to evil. How, then, are we to say at once that evil is a natural propensity over which we have no control, and that evil is under our own control, or is done freely? (1) What constitutes the bias to evil? It does not lie in our natural impulses as such. The appetite of hunger, e.g., is in itself neither good nor bad, and for it we are in no way responsible. Nor can we explain the evil bias as due to a loss of the idea of moral obligation ; for, if we had no idea of moral obligation, we should not be responsible for our acts, nor should we even be con- scious of guilt. So far as we view man as a sensuous being, endowed with immediate impulses, we reduce him to the level of the animals. On the other hand, if man's will were absolutely evil, if he were not conscious of himself as under obligation to obey the moral law, his sole motive would be to act contrary to it. Man would act on the principle of Milton's Satan : " Evil, be thou my good " ; he would, in fact, be " neither more nor less than a devil." Now, if the bias to evil does not lie in the natural impulses, nor in the rational nature of man, wherein can it lie ? It can only lie, Kant answers, in this, that man subordinates moral law to happiness, instead of subordinating happiness to moral law. Thus, though the natural impulses are in themselves morally indifferent, they become evil when they are made the motives of action. The bias to evil is thus the tendency in man to disobey the moral law, which his reason prescribes, by seeking 284 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. for his own individual happiness, i.e., for the satisfaction of all his immediate desires. Kant accepts the scriptural doctrine that "there is none righteous, no not one," but he does not admit that the tendency to evil can be explained by referring it to any person but the agent himself. Evil exists for each man only as he himself wills evil. But how are we to explain the fact that every man exhibits this tendency to seek for happiness, instead of making the moral law his sole motive? The tendency undoubtedly exists in man prior to all definite acts of will, and it seems natural to say that the individual must have received the bias not by his own act, but from some external source. This explanation, however, cannot be accepted. If my evil bias comes from another, I am not responsible for it; nothing can be attributed to me but what I freely will. Kant gets over the difficulty in his own peculiar way. Every volition that I exert pro- ceeds from the very centre of my inner being, but I cannot make that inner being an object of my know- ledge. My volitions I must necessarily present to myself as events in time, but in their true nature they are not events in time. Hence a volition is not due to anything but itself; it proceeds from the free activity of the subject. When we do an evil act, we may say that we fall out of the state of innocence into the state of guilt. Every evil act is thus a new fall from innocence : the fall of man is perpetually reenacted. We cannot shift our responsibility for evil to the acts of any one prior to ourselves, because each evil act may be described as an uncaused act, *.*., as an act proceeding straight from our own will. If, however, we ask, Why does man PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 285 will evil, and thus fall or rather plunge into evil? we can find no answer : the origin of evil is inexplicable. The Biblical narration seems to express this when it makes temptation come from an evil spirit. This, however, leaves unexplained how a being who is pure within could be tempted from without, and we must therefore interpret it to mean, not that man is really tempted by an evil spirit, but that the fall from purity is unsearch- able. We see, however, why it is unsearchable ; for to comprehend the origin of evil we should have to con- template the inner nature of man as free from the form of time, and that is impossible from the necessary limita- tion of our knowledge. Similarly, when we read that sin is inherited from our first parents, we must not interpret the statement literally. Our first parents could not sin for us, but only for them- selves. What we must understand is, that we recognize that in his place we should have acted as the first man is represented as acting. And if we cannot comprehend how a free being should fall from innocence into evil, no more can we comprehend how he can turn again from evil to good. We need not, indeed, exclude the idea that some "supernatural cooperation with our will may be needed to remove hindrances, if not to give positive help ; but if such cooperation be possible, we must first make ourselves worthy of it," i.e., we must open our wills to receive it by our own free action. To suppose that we can be made good in any way but by good action, e.g., that a supernatural influence can be got by doing nothing but praying, "which, before an all-seeing Being, is nothing but wishing," is mere superstition. On these principles, we must say that man passes from 286 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. evil to good, or from good to evil, in an instantaneous act. Conversion is an instantaneous act in this sense, that it implies an absolute change in the principle of the will, a change which cannot be better expressed than by calling it a new birth or even a new creation. Still we can only realize this change by a progress from worse to better; and only God, whose intelligence is not limited by the form of time, can perceive as a complete whole what for us is a succession. We can only have a relative confidence in the change of principle within us, but as we find our character grow in stability our confidence will be also increased. The Pauline doctrine of Redemption, like that of the Fall, is reinterpreted by Kant in his own way. As he denied that moral evil can be imputed to any one because of the guilt of another, so he denies that any one can become morally good by the imputation to him of the righteousness of another. Adam's sin cannot become our sin, nor Christ's goodness our goodness. Yet the Pauline idea of redemption points to a truth. The Stoics supposed that our moral warfare is with passion. The Apostle saw that our "warfare is not with flesh and blood, but with principalities and powers," i.e., with evil spirits. The spirit of evil, however, is not external but internal ; it is a principle of evil in the very nature of our own will. And it can be combated only by another spiritual power, viz., by a principle of good. Yet, though evil and good spring from the individual man himself, the principle of good is by St. Paul personified in a way that corresponds to the truth. We never know our own nature as it is behind the veil. We speak of that as an event, which is indeed the source of all events in the way of volition, but which PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 287 in its real nature cannot be called an event at all. Thus the root of all moral evil and good lies hidden in the inner nature of man, though it exhibits itself in a long series of acts. The principle of good being in us, and yet not being produced by ourselves, it may properly be said that it has come down from heaven and taken our nature that it may elevate us, who are by nature evil. Hence it is that we must speak of the willing of good as done for us by another, by one who has realized the ideal of humanity; for God cannot love the world except as ideally realized in the complete moral perfection of humanity. Kant, in short, holds that the righteousness of Christ is imputed to us only in the sense that God takes our imperfect goodness (as springing from the eternal principle of goodness in us) as equivalent to perfect goodness. For though man in this life can only approxi- mate to goodness, yet, if the principle of goodness is at work in him, it will ultimately purge his nature of all evil. Thus, in so far as we are conscious of continued purity of will, we may have a foretaste of the joy which must spring from an unalterable will for the good. "This joy we may fitly represent as an eternal bliss of heaven, secured to us through unity with our divinely human Lord; while its opposite sorrow will appear to us as an endless hell, through identification with the spirit of evil." What, then, is to be said of our past guilt ? How can there be atonement for it? Our present obedience is imperfect, and, even if it were perfect, it could not atone for the past. In willing evil in the past we have, it would seem, taken the principle of evil into our inmost being, and therefore merited infinite punishment. To atone for our past guilt, it may appear that at the moment when 288 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. our will proceeds from the principle of evil to the principle of good, we ought to bear an infinite punishment. Kant meets this difficulty by saying that the change from the corrupt to the good man already involves the sacrifice of self and the acceptance of a long series of the evils of life, merely for the sake of the good. Kant's subjective view of morality prevents him from doing justice to the truth contained in the Pauline doctrine of the Fall. In St. Paul's conception man is not a separate individual whose inner life is incapable of being influenced by others. On the contrary, he conceives of all men as members of one great organism, so that the evil or good of one communicates itself to all the rest. The sin of Adam passes on from generation to generation, and works increasing woe to man j and the Law, while it makes men conscious of the evil power which has taken hold of them, does not enable them to throw it off. On the other hand, Christ is the source of a new regenerative principle, fitted to restore the whole of humanity to more than its original purity. Viewing this new principle as having already realized what it is fitted to realize, St. Paul says that as in Adam all die, so in Christ all are again made alive. Kant, again, denies that either nature, or man, or even God can directly hinder us in our willing of the moral law. He will have no interference with the self-deter- mination of each individual subject. Now, the subject so isolated he conceives of as having no motive but the law of reason, or, in other words, as containing within himself only the principle of good. If so, the willing of evil is not only, as he says, "mysterious," but it PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 289 is a manifest impossibility. For the subject to will evil, he must cease to be what he is. But Kant had too clear an eye for facts to deny that man wills evil, and therefore he goes on to say that man may will evil in so far as he subordinates reason to passion. The moral recovery of man is not, as the Stoics held, a negation of passion, but its subordination to the moral law. Hence evil must, he says, consist in a perversion of the proper relations between reason and desire : it cannot lie either in the natural desires, which in them- selves are neither good nor evil, or in the corruption of reason, which is impossible. But this opposition is false. (a) The desires of man are good or evil according to their object ; (b) reason does not demand the realization of an abstract good, but of a definite good. The moral perversion of man is not to be explained as a war between two separate principles, but as a conflict in the nature of man himself as capable of willing par- ticular or universal ends. The conflict can only come to an end when the consciousness of an abstract law of goodness is transmuted into the consciousness of social relations. Kant, however, has made a step in advance of the Stoics. The Stoics also held morality to be a life according to reason, i.e., a life in which man is in no way under the dominion of passion. But they go further than Kant in maintaining that the moral life consists in the absolute extinction of all the natural desires. The passions, they say, are "unnatural," i.e., they are in absolute contradiction to the rational nature of man. Hence man can only be himself if he expels all the natural desires, and so comes to "harmony'' 290 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. with himself. This doctrine makes the passions some- thing so foreign to the nature of man that the difficulty is to explain how man should ever be under the influence of passion at all. If man is by nature pure reason, how does he come to give way to passion ? Are we not com- pelled to hold that he cannot be pure reason, or, in other words, that passion is his self-surrender to evil? The Stoics, however, simply assume that as a matter of fact natural desire has an influence upon man, and, affirming the passionless life of reason to be the true life, they say that passion must be extruded as a foreign element. Kant, on the other hand, makes an attempt to explain how passion comes into the will of man. Man is by nature a composite being, having both reason and desire. Evil is not the mere determination by desire, but a determination by the will that places desire above reason. The moral recovery of man is therefore not the annihila- tion of desire, but its subordination to reason. This is the compromise by which Kant seeks to harmonize desire and reason. The desire for happiness is reasonable, but not the desire for happiness at the expense of morality ; and in the elevation of happiness over morality he finds the explanation of evil. If we carry out to its consequences the view of Kant that man is by nature at once rational and sensuous, we shall have to transform his doctrine. If the moral end is to bring desire into conformity with reason, we cannot hold that desire is the abstract opposite of reason. There can be no truce between irreconcilable enemies. The true realization of self must be a realization in which the sensuous and the rational aspects of man's life are in harmony with each other. The desires of man are not PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 29 1 impulses, but desires for particular objects which only differ from the universal end of reason in being particular modes in which that end is sought to be realized. The moral division in man's nature does not arise from the conflict of two opposite principles, but from a false ap- plication of the one principle of self-determination. It is the same self that is present in what is called the life of sense and the life of reason. Even a wrong desire is possible only to a being who in his desires is seeking a universal good, a good that will bring harmony to his ideal nature. The great imperfection of Kant's view of the moral life lies in its strong individualism. The moral law he conceives as so absolutely a law of our own being that we can be aided in our moral life neither by God nor man. This view is an exaggeration of the principle of individual liberty, which was the watch-word of the Re- formation. Luther insisted upon the absoluteness of the individual conscience, but he maintained that before God the individual has no freedom. The enlightenment of the eighteenth century denied even this reservation, and thus the individual was left alone with himself. Kant accepted the principle of individualism, but he maintained that the individual is truly himself only as he prescribes for him- self a universal lav/ — the law of his own being. The individual is influenced by others only on the side of his sensuous desires, and even that influence is possible only as his will gives assent to them. In opposition to this view, we must say that the law which man prescribes to himself presupposes objective ends in which the indivi- dual may realize himself. It is true that we cannot be satisfied, in the realization of any particular end, with the 292 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. satisfaction of a particular desire ; but this dissatisfaction arises only from the consciousness that in willing a particular end we have not realized the self. This opposi- tion, however, is transcended when the true meaning of the particular desires is apprehended; for then we find that the particular end may be willed as identical with the universal or good. It is this identification of desire with good that constitutes morality. All particular objects of desire become good in so far as they are the specific forms in which universal good is realized. From this it follows that the moral law is primarily social. Our consciousness of ourselves as moral and spiritual beings is made possible only by our con- sciousness of other selves. The outer law which binds the different members of society together is really an inner law. Man can rise above his immediate desires, just because he can rise above the point of view of his own individual life and live in the life of others. At first, indeed, the law of society appears as an external law based upon authority, and when man comes to the consciousness of law as the inner law of his own being, it is only natural that he should oppose this inner law to the outer law of society. But in reality it is both inner and outer, the law of his own being, and a social law which binds him to others. The important thing is, that he should submit to the law of society, not because society imposes the law, but because he consciously recognizes it to be identical with the realization of himself. The nearest approximation of Kant to the view that man's moral life is essentially social, is contained in his conception of an invisible ethical community. This PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 293 community, as he holds, rests upon the idea of the moral law as realizable because it ought to be realized ; and therefore it seeks to remove the hindrances which prevent men from living the moral life. Until such a community is established, all men are in an ethical state of nature, in which they hinder on all sides the moral advancement of the race. The great power of evil in the world is the envious rivalry of men. In society they corrupt each other, and become each other's worst enemies. They ought, therefore, to combine on the basis of a common submission to the moral law. In this community force cannot be employed, because moral freedom is inconsistent with it. This community can only be imperfectly represented by any outward institution. The nearest approach to it is in the growth of the consciousness of the importance of morality. This conception of an ethical community is not con- sistent with the general principles of Kant. As we have seen, his principles led him to deny that the individual can further the moral life of others. But he so far modifies this view as to say, that men may put temptations in the way of others, and hence that they may combine to remove hindrances to the moral life. In this doctrine Kant is virtually preparing the way for the idea that true freedom is realized in and through social relations. Man is rational, not because he lives an inner life with which no one can interfere, but because no influence upon him is purely external. The influence of others does not really interfere with the freedom of the individual, because such influence becomes a motive only as it is passed through the transmuting medium of self-consciousness. Thus the influence of 294 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. others may be good or bad, not because it forces the individual to act in a certain way, but because the ideal of self cannot be realized by the individual apart, but only through the development of the ideal in society. Kant's fundamental mistake is to view the natural desires as belonging to the individual sensibility which may be acted upon from without. Every natural desire being, on his view, a susceptibility of the individual to be affected by what is external to him, he assumes that to speak of the influence of society is the same thing as to speak of the influence of natural desire as understood in this unspiritual way. It is only another form of the same imperfection that Kant allows of no distinction between morality and religion. Morality is a purely individual matter, and therefore man cannot be aided in his moral life by God any more than by others, or at least only by God, in so far as he himself wills the law of his own reason. Now, if we thus conceive of God as necessarily withdrawn from the inner life of man, we fall back upon a self-determination which is purely individual. The moral law thus becomes a law only for the individual. Man cannot, indeed, being what he is, rid himself of its authority; but, after all, the goal of his efforts may be only the realization of an ideal that does not harmonize with the true nature of things. What he supposes to be moral progress may, from the point of view of God, be moral retrogression. Thus that which constitutes the essential feature in the religious consciousness is lost, or at least becomes problematic. The essence of the religious consciousness is the assurance that in realizing the higher life man is a fellow-worker with God, and that in so realizing himself all things work PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 295 together for good. If man cannot identify himself with God all his strivings are vain efforts to escape from the prison-house of his own limited individuality. If he can- not know God he can know nothing, because all his apparent knowledge must be infected with the illusion of his finitude; if he cannot identify his will with the will of God, his goodness is from the absolute point of view a mere semblance. Hence the consciousness of the moral law cannot be separated from the conscious- ness of God without losing its power and authority. What gives absoluteness both to the individual conscience and to the laws of society is the identity of both with the infinite perfection of God. It is true that neither involves a complete consciousness of all that is implicit in that perfection j but, except in so far as man is conscious that in himself and others the divine is con- tinually being realized, he has no ground for his faith in goodness. Ultimately, therefore, morality rests upon religion. ART. The higher consciousness of man expresses itself not only in Religion but in Art. What in the one takes the form of a personal experience, lifting the individual above the flux of the transitory and reconciling him to himself and to the world, takes in the other the form of an objective presentation of the ideal nature of existence in one or more of its manifold phases. To deal with so important and complex a subject as the Philosophy of Art in anything like an adequate way would require much time and care, and we must be content at present with a short statement and criticism of the aesthetic theory of 296 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. Kant, who, in this as in other branches of philosophy, was the first philosopher of modern times who attempted to treat the subject in a comprehensive way. His doctrine is open to grave objections, but it is full of fertile sugges- tion, and is a distinct advance upon the superficial or inadequate theories of his predecessors. There are, in Kant's view, two objects of Art, the beautiful and the sublime. Beauty is not, as is usually supposed, a quality of the object, but a peculiar feeling of satisfaction which arises in us in the mere contempla- tion of the object. Our aesthetic judgments are therefore entirely independent of practical utility : a flower, for example, will be pronounced beautiful, quite irrespective of its market value. The feeling of satisfaction awakened in us by a beautiful object is quite unique, and must not be confused either with the feeling of pleasure associated with the satisfaction of desire — say, the desire for a fine wine — or with the feeling which is connected with the willing of a good act. For in both of these cases our satisfaction springs from interest in the object as related to ourselves, whereas the feeling of beauty is entirely disinterested, arising as it does from the bare contemplation of the object called beautiful, and in fact it is the only free and disinterested feeling of which man is capable. It follows from this that, as the feeling of beauty is not determined by the peculiar sensuous susceptibility of the individual, we have no hesitation in affirming that all men must find beautiful the object which awakens in us a disinterested feeling of satisfaction. How, then, are we to explain these peculiarities of our aesthetic judgments? — for manifestly a judgment which rests upon feeling, and yet is universal and necessary, urgently demands explana- PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 297 tion. Kant's answer is, that the secret does not lie in the object as such, but in the fact that in contemplating it the subject is conscious of an immediate harmony in the relation of his faculties of knowledge. His intellect and his perception perfectly correspond, and therefore he naturally feels pleasure so long as he remains in the aesthetic mood. Such pleasure is very different from the satisfaction which accompanies the resolute willing of what is binding upon him by the law of his reason. The feeling of beauty comes without effort the moment we contemplate the beautiful object disinterestedly, and it therefore gives us a sort of prophecy of that union of reason and sense which no effort of ours can actually realize. Besides the beautiful we frame aesthetic judgments in regard to the sublime. These judgments agree in their main characteristics with those in regard to beauty, but there are important differences. For one thing, the feeling of sublimity arises in us even when the object as perceived has no definite limits, though it is always conceived as a whole. The feelings themselves are also different in kind, for, whereas the feeling of beauty is direct, the feeling of sublimity involves a momentary check to the vital forces, followed immediately by their more vigorous outflow. The mind is at once attracted and repelled, and the accompanying pleasure is therefore negative rather than positive : it is in fact due to the disharmony between the object perceived and an ideal object existing only for thought. Strictly speaking, therefore, there is no sublimity in nature, but only in ourselves, and in our- selves as rational beings. The sublime has two forms, which may be distinguished as the mathematical and the dynamical. In the first 298 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. place, the feeling of sublimity may be called out by that which is too great in magnitude to be pictured by the imagination. Such an object is the immensity of the starry heavens. Here we have the conception of an absolute whole, while yet the imagination utterly fails to give a complete picture of it. We may imagine world on world, and system stretching into system, but by all our efforts we cannot attain to that completeness of view which is contained in our idea of the whole material universe. It is this inability to give form to our thought which gives rise to the feeling of the sublime. The very failure of imagination awakens in us the con- sciousness of a power within ourselves far transcending sense and imagination. " Thus the feeling of the sublime in nature is a kind of reverence for our own character as rational beings which we transfer to an object of nature." In the second place, we have the feeling of sublimity in the presence of the forces of nature. We are aware of their greatness, and yet we feel that they cannot over- power us. That force we call great which we cannot resist; yet we may be conscious of our powerlessness without being afraid. " The virtuous man fears God, but is not afraid of Him " ; for he knows that if he desired to disobey His commands he would have reason to fear. So we may be conscious that as physical beings we are impotent to resist the tremendous forces of nature, while yet, there is in us a power that nature cannot overcome. The true sublime is therefore within us. The natural man quakes at the storm or the earthquake : the moral man is raised above fear by the consciousness of moral harmony with the will of God. The feeling of the sub- PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 299 lime is less common than the feeling of beauty. It implies considerable culture, and hence the rude and undeveloped find the forces of nature simply terrible. From its very nature the feeling of the sublime is a more direct aid to the moral life of man than the feeling of the beautiful ; for it arises in the contrast of the inner to the outer, and therefore it prepares the way for the higher moral interest. Hence the Jewish religion, which was preeminently the religion of sublimity, was also the religion in which moral ideas were most power- ful. Turning to the artistic representation of the beautiful, we have to remark that beauty excludes the idea of de- finite purpose. The products of art must appear as free from conscious design as if they were products of nature. The beautiful cannot be produced according to rule; it must proceed fresh from the hands of genius. In this gift of genius the true artist is distinguished from his imitators. He gives expression to aesthetic ideas, i.e., ideas of imagination which give occasion for much thought, but to which no definite conception is adequate. Such ideas are the counterpart of the ideas of reason, to which no perception of sense can be adequate. The productive imagination creates out of the world we know a new world, which is constructed on principles that occupy a higher place in our reason. Its products may well be called ideas, because they arise from the effort after something lying beyond the limits of experience, and give an approximate presentation of the ideas of reason; and because no conception of the understanding can be quite adequate to them. " The poet ventures to give sensuous realization to invisible 300 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. things, the realm of the blessed, heaven, hell, eternity, creation ; or, if he represents that which is exemplified in experience, as, e.g., death, envy, love of fame, yet, imitating by imagination the boundlessness of reason, he seeks to give them a complete sensuous realization for which nature furnishes no parallel." As art presents the idea of the supersensible in sen- suous form, its products are a symbol of moral ideas. A symbol is an image which does not adequately present the idea of reason, but only suggests it. The beautiful is the symbol of the morally good, and hence it makes possible the transition from the allurements of sense to a habitual interest in goodness. " When we find a man interested in the beauty of nature, we have reason to believe that there is in him at least a basis for a good moral character." The great value of Kant's conception of beauty lies in the accuracy with which he has noted the seemingly self-contradictory elements contained in our aesthetic judg- ments. He is still, it is true, perplexed by his imperfect analysis of human feeling, as apparently fluctuating and uncertain, but he insists, and rightly insists, that beauty is not "subjective" in the sense of having no basis but the changing states of the sensitive individual. Thus he breaks once for all with that shallow hedonistic aesthetics which had in England its representatives in such writers as Burke and Alison. On the other hand, Kant refuses to accept the doctrine of Baumgarten, itself a distorted application of the philosophy of Leibnitz, that our aesthetic judgments rest upon "a confused conception of perfection," seeing clearly that, except by a liberal interpretation of its PHILOSOPHY OF THE ABSOLUTE. 30 1 spirit, this doctrine must lead to the final extinction of art as but an imperfect and preparatory stage of abstract science. Kant has therefore to reconcile, as best he may, the two aspects of beauty which are essential to its very nature; and hence he affirms with equal emphasis (i) that it rests upon feeling, and (2) that it involves thought. Thus he is led to say that our aesthetic judgments pro- ceed from a disinterested pleasure in the contemplation of beautiful objects, and that they are universal and necessary, while yet no definite conception can be adduced in support of their claim to universality and necessity. He therefore falls back upon the doctrine, that the peculiar character of such judgments can be ex- plained only on the supposition that the consciousness of beauty arises from the harmony with each other of imagination and understanding, and that their universality is due to the identity of all men in these faculties and their consequent agreement in the experience of aesthetic pleasure in the presence of an object which brings their knowing faculties into harmony with each other. Now, if Kant is right, as he certainly is, in saying that in the consciousness of beauty the subject is in harmony with himself, he is not entitled to retain that opposition of the consciousness of self and the consciousness of the object which haunts him like a spectre through the whole of his speculations. Beauty is either a pure illusion, having no foundation in the nature of things, or our aesthetic judgments are "objective" in the most absolute sense. The feeling of harmony with himself which man experiences in the contemplation of beauty must be regarded as the other side of the harmony which under- lies the world as it really is. It is only because Kant is 302 COMTE, MILL, AND SPENCER. not able to get rid of the conviction that nothing can be known^ in the strict sense of that term, which cannot be compressed within the framework of the " scientific " categories of thought, that he still speaks of our aesthetic judgments as if they required an apology because they do not rest upon "definite" conceptions. In point of fact, what Kant calls the " indefiniteness " of the concep- tions involved in such judgments is really their compre- hensiveness. It is just the infinity of the beautiful object, i.e., its power of revealing the whole in the part, that gives rise to the peace and harmony of the whole man, and lifts him above the allurements of sense and the strenuous effort of the struggle after goodness. The only sense in which beauty can be called "subjective" is this: that the divine meaning of the world is revealed through it, but is not completely realized in it. This, however, merely shows that the concrete realization of the idea of the whole, which is the differentia of beauty, still leaves room for that reflective grasp of existence which it is the function of philosophy to supply. Glasgow: printed at the university press by robert maclehose. WORKS BY PROFESSOR WATSON. KANT AND HIS ENGLISH CRITICS. A Comparison of Critical and Empirical Philosophy. 8vo, 7s. 6d. "Decidedly the best exposition of Kant which we have seen in English. We cannot too strongly commend it." — Saturday Review. " C'est l'ceuvre d'un penseur et d'un maitre. . . . Nous avons lu le livre de M. Watson avec un vif inte>6t et une grande sympathie." — Revue Philosophique. THE PHILOSOPHY OF KANT, as contained in Extracts from his own Writings. Selected and Translated by John Watson, LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Queen's College, Kingston, Canada. New Edition. Crown 8vo, 7s. 6d. " Cannot fail soon to recommend itself to all concerned." — Mind. GLASGOW : JAMES MACLEHOSE & SONS, $ub hslurs to tht anibcrsitg. LONDON AND NEW YORK : MACMILLAN & CO. at RK 14 DAY , RFTTT» M ^ 14 DAY USE ^TURN TO >» :y M ^ BORR LOAN DEPT. i— «£C*-LD — — ~^-