1 TALKS TO TEACHERS AND STUDENTS By WILLIAM JAMES mm m I m mm .-S. WELL'S, COLUMBUS. O. y v Works by WILLIAM JAMES, M.D., Ph. tt Litt.D., LL.D. ; Correspondent of the Insti- tute of France ; Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University, The Principle! of Psychology. 2 vols. Svo. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1890. Psychology : Briefer Course. 12010. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1892. The Will to Believe, and Other Essays In Popular Philosophy. New York: Long- mans, Green & Co. 1897. Is Life Worth Living ? i8mo. Philadelphia: S. 6. Weston, 1305 Arch Street 1896. Human Immortality : Two Supposed Objec- tions to the Doctrine. i6mo. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1898. The Literary Remains of Henry James. Edited, with an Introduction, by WILLIAM JAMBS. With Portrait. Crown Svo. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1885. TALKS TO TEACHERS AND STUDENTS BY WILLIAM JAMES NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1900 COPYRIGHT, 1899, 1900 BY WILLIAM JAMBS PREFACE. IN 1892 I was asked by the Harvard Corporation to give a few public lectures on psychology to the Cambridge teachers. The talks now printed form the substance of that course, which has since then been delivered at various places to various teacher-audi- ences. I have found by experience that what my hearers seem least to relish is analytical technicality, and what they most care for is concrete practical application. So I have gradually weeded out the former, and left the latter unreduced ; and now, that I have at last written out the lectures, they contain a minimum of what is deemed ' scientific' in psy- chology, and are practical and popular in the ex- treme. Some of my colleagues may possibly shake their heads at this ; but in taking my cue from what has seemed to me to be the feeling of the audiences I be- lieve that I am shaping my book so as to satisfy the more genuine public need. Teachers, of course, will miss the minute divisions, subdivisions, and definitions, the lettered and num- bered headings, the variations of type, and all the 206598O IV PREFACE other mechanical artifices on which they are accus- tomed to prop their minds. But my main desire has been to make them conceive, and, if possible, re- produce sympathetically in their imagination, the mental life of their pupil as the sort of active unity which he himself feels it to be. He doesn't chop himself into distinct processes and compartments ; and it would have frustrated this deeper purpose of my book to make it look, when printed, like a Bae- deker's handbook of travel or a text-book of arithme- tic. So far as books printed like this book force the fluidity of the facts upon the young teacher's atten- tion, so far I am sure they tend to do his intellect a service, even though they may leave unsatisfied a craving (not altogether without its legitimate grounds) for more nomenclature, head-lines, and subdivisions. Readers acquainted with my larger books on Psy- chology will meet much familiar phraseology. In the chapters on habit and memory I have even copied several pages verbatim, but I do not know that apology is needed for such plagiarism as this. The talks to students, which conclude the volume, were written in response to invitations to deliver 1 addresses ' to students at women's colleges. The first one was to the graduating class of the Boston Normal School of Gymnastics. Properly, it contiri- PREFACE T ues the series of talks to teachers. The second and the third address belong together, and continue an- other line of thought. I wish I were able to make the second, ' On a Cer- tain Blindness in Human Beings,' more impressive. It is more than the mere piece of sentimentalism which it may seem to some readers. It connects itself with a definite view of the world and of our moral relations to the same. Those who have done me the honor of reading my volume of philosophic essays will recognize that I mean the pluralistic or individualistic philosophy. According to that philos- ophy, the truth is too great for any one actual mind, even though that mind be dubbed ' the Absolute,' to know the whole of it. The facts and worths of life need many cognizers to take them in. There is no point of view absolutely public and universal. Pri- vate and uncommunicable perceptions always remain over, and the worst of it is that those who look for them from the outside never know where. The practical consequence of such a philosophy is the well-known democratic respect for the sacredness of individuality, is, at any rate, the outward toler- ance of whatever is not itself intolerant. These phrases are so familiar that they sound now rather dead in our ears. Once they had a passionate inner meaning. Such a passionate inner meaning they may Tl PREFACE easily acquire again if the pretension of our nation to inflict its own inner ideals and institutions vi et armis upon Orientals should meet with a resistance as obdurate as so far it has been gallant and spirited. Religiously and philosophically, our ancient national doctrine of live and let live may prove to have a far deeper meaning than our people now seem to imagine it to possess. CAMBRIDGE, MASS., March, 1899. CONTENTS. TALKS TO TEACHERS. PAGE I. PSYCHOLOGY AND THE TEACHING ART . . 3 The American educational organization, 3 What teachers may expect from psychology, 5 Teaching methods must agree with psychology, but cannot be immediately deduced therefrom, 7 The science of teaching and the science of war, 9 The educational uses of psychology denned, 10 The teacher's duty toward child-study, 12. II. THE STREAM OF CONSCIOUSNESS .... 15 Our mental life is a succession of conscious ' fields,' 15 They have a focus and a margin, 18 This description contrasted with the theory of 'ideas,' 20 Wundt's conclusions, 20, note. III. THE CHILD AS A BEHAVING ORGANISM . 22 Mind as pure reason and mind as practical guide, 22 The latter view the more fashionable one to-day, 23 It will be adopted in this work, 24 Why BO? 25 The teacher's function is to train pupils to behavior, 28. IV. EDUCATION AND BEHAVIOR 29 Education defined, 29 Conduct is always its outcome, 30 Different national ideals : Germany and England, 31. Till CONTENTS PAOE V. THE NECESSITY OF REACTIONS .... 33 No impression without expression, 33 Verbal reproduction, 34 Manual training, 35 Pupils should know their ' marks,' 37. VI. NATIVE AND ACQUIRED REACTIONS ... 38 The acquired reactions must be preceded by native ones, 38 Illustration: teaching child to ask instead of snatching, 39 Man has more in- stincts than other rnarpT"al", 43. VII. WHAT THE NATIVE REACTIONS ABE . . 45 Fear and love, 45 Curiosity, 45 Imitation, 48 Emulation, 49 Forbidden by Rousseau, 51 His error, 52 Ambition, pugnacity, and pride. Soft pedagogics and the fighting impulse, 54 Ownership, 55 Its educational uses, 56 Con- structiveness, 58 Manual teaching, 59 Transi- toriness in instincts, 60 Their order of succes- sion, 61. Vin. THE LAWS OF HABIT 64 Good and bad habits, 64 Habit due to plasti- city of organic tissues, 65 The aim of education is to make useful habits automatic, 66 Maxims . relative to habit-forming: 1. Strong initiative, 67 2. No exception, 68 3. Seize first opportunity to act, 69 4. Don't preach, 71 Darwin and poetry: without exercise our capacities decay, 71 The habit of mental and muscular relaxation, 74 Fifth maxim, keep the faculty of effort trained, 75 Sudden conversions compatible with laws of habit, 70 Momentous influence of habits on character, 77. CONTENTS IX FAOB IX. THE ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS 79 A case of habit, 79 The two laws, contiguity and similarity, 80 The teacher has to build up useful systems of association, 83 Habitual asso- ciations determine character, 84 Indetermiaate- ness of our trains of association, 85 We can trace them backward, but not foretell them, 86 Interest deflects, 87 Prepotent parts of the field, 88 In teaching, multiply cues, 89. X. INTEREST 91 The child's native interests, 91 How uninterest- ing things acquire an interest, 94 Rules for the teacher, 95 ' Preparation ' of the mind for the lesson: the pupil must have something to attend with, 97 All later interests are borrowed from original ones, 99. XI. ATTENTION 100 Interest and attention are two aspects of one fact, 100 Voluntary attention comes in beats, 101 Genius and attention, 102 The subject must change to win attention, 103 Mechanical aids, 104 The physiological process, 106 The new in the old is what excites interest, 108 In- terest and effort are compatible, 110 Mind-wan- dering, 112 Not fatal to mental efficiency, 114. XII. MEMORY 116 Due to association, 116 No recall without a cue, 118 Memory is due to brain-plasticity, 119 Native retentiveness, 120- Number of associa- tions may practically be its equivalent, 122 Re- tentiveness is a fixed property of the individual, 123 Memory versus memories, 124 Scientific X CONTEXTS FAOK system as help to memory, 126 Technical mem- ories, 127 Cramming, 129 Elementary memory unimprovable, 130 Utility of verbal memorizing, 131 Measurements of immediate memory, 133 They throw little light, 134 Passion is the im- portant factor in human efficiency, 137 Eye- memory, ear-memory, etc., 137 The rate of forgetting, Ebbinghans's results, 139 Influence of the unreproducible, 142 To remember, one must think and connect, 143. XIII. THE ACQUISITION OF IDEAS 144 Education gives a stock of conceptions, 144 The order of their acquisition, 146 Value of verbal material, 149 Abstractions of different orders : when are they assimilable, 151 False conceptions of children, 152. XIV. APPERCEPTION 155 Often a mystifying idea, 155 The process de- fined, 157 The law of economy, 159 Old- fogyism, 160 How many types of apperception ? 161 New heads of classification must continually be invented, 163 Alteration of the apperceiving mass, 165 Class names are what we work by, 166 Few new fundamental conceptions acquired after twenty-five, 167. XV. THE WILL 169 The word defined, 169 All consciousness tends to action, 170 Ideo-motor action, 171 Inhibi- tion, 172 The process of deliberation, 174 Why so few of our ideas result in acts, 176 The associationist account of the will, 177 A balance of impulses and inhibitions, 178 The CONTENTS XI PAGE over-impulsive and the over-obstructed type, 179 The perfect type, 180 The balky will, 181 What character building consists in, 184 Right action depends on right apperception of the case, 185 Effort of will is effort of attention : the drunkard's dilemma, 187 Vital importance of voluntary attention, 189 Its amount may be in- determinate, 191 Affirmation of free-will, 192 Two types of inhibition, 193 Spinoza on inhibi- tion by a higher good, 194 Conclusion, 195. TALKS TO STUDENTS. I. THE GOSPEL OF RELAXATION 199 II. ON A CERTAIN BLINDNESS IN HUMAN BEINGS 229 III. WHAT MAKES A LIFE SIGNIFICANT? . 265 TALKS TO TEACHERS I. PSYCHOLOGY AND THE TEACHING ART IN the general activity and uprising of ideal in- terests which every one with an eye for fact can discern all about us in American life, there is per- il aps no more promising feature than the fermen- tation which for a dozen years or more has been going on among the teachers. In whatever sphere of education their functions may lie, there is to be seen among them a really inspiring amount of searching of the heart about the highest concerns of their profession. The renovation of nations begins always at the top, among the reflective members of the State, and spreads slowly outward and downward. The teachers of this country, one may say, have its future in their hands. The earnestness which they at present show in striving to enlighten and strengthen themselves is an index of the nation's probabilities of advance in all ideal directions. The outward organization of educa- tion which we have in our United States is per- 4 TALKS TO TEACHERS haps, on the whole, the best organization that exists in any country. The State school systems give a diversity and flexibility, an opportunity for experiment and keenness of competition, nowhere else to be found on such an important scale. The independence of so many of the colleges and uni- versities; the give and take of students and in- structors between them all; their emulation, and their happy organic relations to the lower schools ; the traditions of instruction in them, evolved from the older American recitation-method (and so avoiding on the one hand the pure lecture-sys- tem prevalent in Germany and Scotland, which considers too little the individual student, and yet not involving the sacrifice of the instructor to the individual student, which the English tutorial sys- tem would seem too often to entail), all these things (to say nothing of that coeducation of the sexes in whose benefits so many of us heartily believe), all these things, I say, are most happy features of our scholastic life, and from them the most sanguine auguries may be drawn. Having so favorable an organization, all we need is to impregnate it with geniuses, to get superior men and women working more and more abundantly in it and for it and at it, and in a PSYCHOLOGY AND THE TEACHING ART 5 generation or two America may well lead the education of the world. I must say that I look forward with no little confidence to the day when that shall be an accomplished fact. No one has profited more by the fermentation of which I speak, in pedagogical circles, than we psychologists. The desire of the schoolteachers for a completer professional training, and their aspiration toward the ' professional * spirit in their work, have led them more and more to turn to us for light on fundamental principles. And in these few hours which we are to spend together you look to me, I am sure, for information concerning the mind's operations, which may enable you to labor more easily and effectively in the several schoolrooms over which you preside. Far be it from me to disclaim for psychology all title to such hopes. Psychology ought certainly to give the teacher radical help. And yet I con- fess that, acquainted as I am with the height of some of your expectations, I feel a little anxious lest, at the end of these simple talks of mine, not a few of you may experience some disappointment at the net results. In other words, I am not sure that you may not be indulging fancies that are just a shade exaggerated. That would not be 6 TALKS TO TEACHERS altogether astonishing, for we have been having something like a 4 boom ' in psychology in this country. Laboratories and professorships have been founded, and reviews established. The air has been full of rumors. The editors of educa- tional journals and the arrangers of conventions have had to show themselves enterprising and on a level with the novelties of the day. Some of the professors have not been unwilling to co-operate, and I am not sure even that the publishers have been entirely inert. 'The new psychology' has tWs become a term to conjure up portentous ideas ^ t m f Continuity tells us that objects thought of hi the coming wave are such as in some previous experience were next to the objects repre- sented in the wave that is passing away. The vanishing objects were once formerly their neigh- bors in the mind. When you recite the alphabet or your prayers, or when the sight of an object reminds you of its name, or the name reminds you of the object, it is through the law of contiguity that the terms are suggested to the mind. The Law of Similarity says that, when contigu- ity fails to describe what happens, the coming objects will prove to rt'stmLl*' the going objects, even though the two were never experienced together before. In our flights of fancy,' this is frequently the case. If, arresting ourselves in the flow of reverie, we ask the question, " How came we to be think- THE TWO LAWS OP ASSOCIATION 81 ing of just this object now?" we can almost al- ways trace its presence to some previous object which has introduced it to the mind, according to one or the other of these laws. The entire rou- tine of our memorized acquisitions, for example, is a consequence of nothing but the Law of Con- tiguity. The words of a poem, the formulas of trigonometry, the facts of history, the properties of material things, are all known to us as definite systems or groups of objects which cohere hi an order fixed by innumerable iterations, and of which any one part reminds us of the others. In dry and prosaic minds, almost all the mental se- quences flow along these lines of habitual rou- tine repetition and suggestion. In witty, imaginative minds, on the other hand, the routine is broken through with ease at any moment; and one field of mental objects will sug- gest another with which perhaps in the whole his- tory of human thinking it had never once before been coupled. The link here is usually some anal- ogy between the objects successively thought of, an analogy often so subtle that, although we feel it, we can with difficulty analyze its ground; as where, for example, we find something masculine in the color red and something feminine in the 82 TALKS TO TEACHERS color pale blue, or where, of three human beings' characters, one will remind us of a cat, another of a dog, the third perhaps of a cow. Psychologists have of course gone very deeply into the question of what the causes of association may be ; and some of them have tried to show that contiguity and similarity are not two radically diverse laws, but that either presupposes the pres- ence of the other. I myself am disposed to think that the phenomena of association depend on our cerebral constitution, and are not immediate con- sequences of our being rational beings. In other words, when we shall have become disembodied spirits, it may be that our trains of consciousness will follow different laws. These questions are discussed hi the books on psychology, and I hope that some of you will be interested in following them there. But I will, on the present occasion, ignore them entirely; for, as teachers, it is the fact of association that practically concerns you, let its grounds be spiritual or cerebral, or what they may, and let its laws be reducible, or non-reduci- ble, to one. Your pupils, whatever else they are, are at any rate little pieces of associating machin- ery. Their education consists in the organizing THEIR GREAT SCOPE 83 within them of determinate tendencies to associate one thing with another, impressions with conse- quences, these with reactions, those with results, and so on indefinitely. The more copious the associative systems, the completer the individual's adaptations to the world. The teacher can formulate his function to him- self therefore in terms of ' association ' as well as in terms of native and acquired reaction.' It is mainly that of building up useful systems of asso- ciation in the pupil's mind. This description sounds wider than the one I began by giving. But, when one thinks that our trains of associa- tion, whatever they may be, normally issue in ac- quired reactions or behavior, one sees that in a general way the same mass of facts is covered by both formulas. It is astonishing how many mental operations we can explain when we have once grasped the principles of association. The great problem which association undertakes to solve is, Why does just this particular field of consciousness, constituted in this particular way, now appear before my mind ? It may be a field of objects imagined ; it may be of objects remembered or of objects perceived ; it may include an action resolved on. In either case, 84 TALKS TO TEACHERS when the field is analyzed into its parts, those parts can be shown to have proceeded from parts of fields previously before consciousness, in con- sequence of one or other of the laws of association just laid down. Those laws run the mind : inter- est, shifting hither and thither, deflects it ; and attention, as we shall later see, steers it and keeps it from too zigzag a course. To grasp these factors clearly gives one a solid and simple understanding of the psychological machinery. The 'nature,' the 'character,' of an individual means really nothing but the habitual form of his associations. To break up bad associa- tions or wrong ones, to build others in, to guide the associative tendencies into the most fruitful channels, is the educator's principal task. But here, as with all other simple principles, the dif- ficulty lies in the application. Psychology can state the laws : concrete tact arid talent alone can work them to useful results. Meanwhile it is a matter of the commonest expe- rience that our minds may pass from one object to another by various intermediary fields of conscious- ness. The indetenninateness of our paths of asso- ciation in concrete is thus almost as striking a feat- ure of them as the uniformity of their abstract INDETEKMINATENESS OP ASSOCIATIONS 85 form. Start from any idea whatever, and the entire range of your ideas is potentially at your disposal. If we take as the associative starting- point, or cue, some simple word which I pronounce before you, there is no limit to the possible diver- sity of suggestions which it may set up in your minds. Suppose I say * blue,' for example : some of you may think of the blue sky and hot weather from which we now are suffering, then go off on thoughts of summer clothing, or possibly of meteo- rology at large ; others may think of the spectrum and the physiology of color-vision, and glide into X-rays and recent physical speculations; others may think of blue ribbons, or of the blue flowers on a friend's hat, and proceed on lines of personal reminiscence. To others, again, etymology and linguistic thoughts may be suggested; or blue may be * apperceived ' as a synonym for melan- choly, and a train of associates connected with morbid psychology may proceed to unroll them- selves. In the same person, the same word heard at different times will provoke, in consequence of the varying marginal preoccupations, either one of a number of diverse possible associative sequences. Professor Miinsterberg performed this experiment 86 TALKS TO TEACHERS methodically, using the same words four times over, at three-month intervals, as ' cues ' for four different persons who were the subjects of obser- vation. He found almost no constancy in their associations taken at these different times. In short, the entire potential content of one's con- sciousness is accessible from any one of its points. This is why we can never work the laws of asso- ciation forward : starting from the present field as a cue, we can never cipher out in advance just what the person will be thinking of five minutes later. The elements which may become prepo- tent in the process, the parts of each successive field round which the associations shall chiefly turn, the possible bifurcations of suggestion, are so numerous and ambiguous as to be indetermina- ble before the fact. But, although we cannot work the laws of association forward, we can always work them backwards. We cannot say now what we shall find ourselves thinking of five minutes hence ; but, whatever it may be, we shall then be able to trace it through intermediary links of contiguity or similarity to what we are thinking now. What so baffles our prevision is the shifting part played by the margin and focus in fact, by each element by itself of the margin or focus in calling up the next ideas. SOME CUES ARE PREPOTENT 87 For example, I am reciting ' Locksley Hall,' in order to divert my mind from a state of suspense that I am in concerning the will of a relative that is dead. The will still remains hi the mental background as an extremely marginal or ultra- marginal portion of my field of consciousness ; but the poem fairly keeps my attention from it, until I come to the line, " I, the heir of all the ages, in the foremost files of time." The words * I, the heir,' immediately make an electric connection with the marginal thought of the will; that, in turn, makes my heart beat with anticipation of my possible legacy, so that I throw down the book and pace the floor excitedly with visions of my future fortune pouring through my mind- Any portion of the field of consciousness that has more potentialities of emotional excitement than an- other may thus be roused to predominant activ- ity ; and the shifting play of interest now hi one portion, now in another, deflects the currents in all sorts of zigzag ways, the mental activity run- ning hither and thither as the sparks run in burnt-up paper. One more point, and I shall have said as much to you as seems necessary about the process of association. 88 TALKS TO TEACHERS You just saw how a single exciting word may call up its own associates prepotently, and deflect our whole train of thinking from the previous track. The fact is that every portion of the field tends to call up its own associates ; but, if these associates be severally different, there is rivalry, and as soon as one or a few begin to be effective the others seem to get siphoned out, as it were, and left behind. Seldom, however, as in our ex- ample, does the process seem to turn round a single item in the mental field, or even round the entire field that is immediately in the act of pass- ing. It is a matter of constellation, into which portions of fields that are already past especially seem to enter and have their say. Thus, to go back to * Locksley Hall,' each word as I recite it in its due order is suggested not solely by the previous word now expiring on my lips, but it is rather the effect of all the previous words, taken together, of the verse. " Ages," for example, calls up " in the foremost files of time," when preceded by " I, the heir of all the " ; but, when preceded by " for I doubt not through the," - it calls up "one increasing purpose runs." Similarly, if I write on the blackboard the letters ABODE F, . . . they probably suggest to you G H I. . . . THE PUPIL AX ASSOCIATING MACHINE 89 But, if I write A B A D D E F, if they suggest anything, they suggest as their complement EOT or E F I C I E N C Y. The result depending on the total constellation, even though most of the single items be the same. My practical reason for mentioning this law is this, that it follows from it that, in working asso- ciations into your pupils' minds, you must not rely on single cues, but multiply the cues as much as possible. Couple the desired reaction with numer- ous constellations of antecedents, don't always ask the question, for example, in the same way; don't use the same kind of data in numerical problems ; vary your illustrations, etc., as much as you can. When we come to the subject of mem- ory, we shall learn still more about this. So much, then, for the general subject of asso- ciation. In leaving it for other topics (in which, however, we shall abundantly find it involved again), I cannot too strongly urge you to acquire a habit of thinking of your pupils in associative terms. All governors of mankind, from doctors and jail-wardens to demagogues and statesmen, instinctively come so to conceive their charges. If you do the same, thinking of them (however else you may think of them besides) as so many 90 TALKS TO TEACHERS little systems of associating machinery, you will be astonished at the intimacy of insight into their operations and at the practicality of the results which you will gain. We think of our acquain- tances, for example, as characterized by certain ' tendencies.' These tendencies will in almost every instance prove to be tendencies to associa- tion. Certain ideas in them are always followed by certain other ideas, these by certain feelings and impulses to approve or disapprove, assent or decline. If the topic arouse one of those first ideas, the practical outcome can be pretty well foreseen. ' Types of character ' in short are largely types of association. X. INTEREST AT our last meeting I treated of the native ten- dencies of the pupil to react in characteristically definite ways upon different stimuli or exciting circumstances. In fact, I treated of the pupil's in- stincts. Now some situations appeal to special instincts from the very outset, and others fail to do so until the proper connections have been or- ganized in the course of the person's training. We say of the former set of objects or situations that they are interesting in themselves and origi- nally. Of the latter we say that they are natively uninteresting, and that interest in them has first to be acquired. No topic has received more attention from peda- gogical writers than that of interest. It is the natural sequel to the instincts we so lately dis- cussed, and it is therefore well fitted to be the next subject which we take up. Since some objects are natively interesting and hi others interest is artificially acquired, the 92 TALKS TO TEACHERS teacher must know which the natively interesting ones are ; for, as we shall see immediately, other objects can artificially acquire an interest only through first becoming associated with some of these natively interesting things. The native interests of children lie altogether in the sphere of sensation. Novel things to look at or novel sounds to hear, especially when they in- volve the spectacle of action of a violent sort, will always divert the attention from abstract concep- tions of objects verbally taken in. The grimace that Johnny is making, the spitballs that Tommy is ready to throw, the dog-fight in the street, or the distant firebells ringing, these are the rivals with which the teacher's powers of being inter- esting have incessantly to cope. The child will always attend more to what a teacher does than to what the same teacher says. During the per- formance of experiments or while the teacher is drawing on the blackboard, the children are tran- quil and absorbed. I have seen a roomful of col- lege students suddenly become perfectly still, to look at their professor of physics tie a piece of string around a stick which he was going to use in an experiment, but immediately grow restless when he began to explain the experiment. A NATIVELY INTERESTING THINGS 93 lady told me that one day, during a lesson, she was delighted at having captured so completely the attention of one of her young charges. He did not remove his eyes from her face ; but he said to her after the lesson was over, " I looked at you all the time, and your upper jaw did not move once I " That was the only fact that he had taken in. Living things, then, moving things, or things that savor of danger or of blood, that have a dra- matic quality, these are the objects natively in- teresting to childhood, to the exclusion of almost everything else; and the teacher of young chil- dren, until more artificial interests have grown up, will keep in touch with her pupils by constant appeal to such matters as these. Instruction must be carried on objectively, experimentally, anec- dotally. The blackboard-drawing and story-tell- ing must constantly come in. But of course these methods cover only the first steps, and carry one but a little way. Can we now formulate any general principle by which the later and more artificial interests con- nect themselves with these early ones that the child brings with him to the school? Fortunately, we can: there is a very simple law 94 TALKS TO TEACHERS that relates the acquired and the native interests with each other. Any object not interesting in itself may become interesting through becoming associated with an object in which an interest already exists. The two associated objects grow, as it were, together: the interesting portion sheds its quality over the whole ; and thus things not interesting in their own right borrow an interest which becomes as real and as strong as that of any natively interesting thing. The odd circumstance is that the borrowing does not impoverish the source, the objects taken to- gether being more interesting, perhaps, than the originally interesting portion was by itself. This is one of the most striking proofs of the range of application of the principle of association of ideas in psychology. An idea will infect an- other with its own emotional interest when they have become both associated together into any sort of a mental total. As there is no limit to the various associations into which an interest- ing idea may enter, one sees in how many ways an interest may be derived. You will understand this abstract statement easily if I take the most frequent of concrete ex- amples, the interest which things borrow from HOW IXTEBEST IS ACQUIRED 95 their connection with our own personal welfare. The most natively interesting object to a man is his own personal self and its fortunes. We ac- cordingly see that the moment a thing becomes connected with the fortunes of the self, it forthwith becomes an interesting thing. Lend the child his books, pencils, and other apparatus: then give them to him, make them his own, and notice the new light with which they instantly shine in his eyes. He takes a new kind of care of them alto- gether. In mature life, all the drudgery of a man's business or profession, intolerable hi itself, is shot through with engrossing significance be- cause he knows it to be associated with his per- sonal fortunes. What more deadly uninteresting object can there be than a railroad time-table? Yet where will you find a more interesting object if you are going on a journey, and by its means can find your train ? At such times the time-table will absorb a man's entire attention, its interest being borrowed solely from its relation to his per- sonal life. From all these facts there emerges a\ very simple abstract programme for the teacher to follow in keeping the attention of the child : Begin ivith the line of his native interests, and offer him objects that have some immediate connection with \ 96 TALKS TO TEACHERS these. The kindergarten methods, the objectr teaching routine, the blackboard and manual-train- ing work, all recognize this feature. Schools in which these methods preponderate are schools where discipline is easy, and where the voice of the master claiming order and attention in threat- ening tones need never be heard. Next, step by step, connect with these first objects and experiences the later objects and ideas which you wish to instill. Associate the new with the old in some, natural and telling way, so that the interest, being shed along from point to point, finally suffuses the entire system of objects of thought. This is the abstract statement ; and, abstractly, nothing can be easier to understand. It is in the fulfilment of the rule that the difficulty lies ; for the difference between an interesting and a tedious teacher consists in little more than the inventive- ness by which the one is able to mediate these associations and connections, and in the dulness in discovering such transitions which the other shows. One teacher's mind will fairly coruscate with points of connection between the new lesson and the circumstances of the children's other experi- ence. Anecdotes and reminiscences will abound in her talk ; and the shuttle of interest will shoot SOMETHING TO ATTEND WITH 97 backward and forward, weaving the new and the old together in a lively and entertaining way. Another teacher has no such inventive fertility, and his lesson will always be a dead and heavy thing. This is the psychological meaning of the Herbartian principle of * preparation ' for each lesson, and of correlating the new with the old. It is the psychological meaning of that whole method of concentration in studies of which you have been recently hearing so much. When the geography and English and history and arithmetic simultaneously make cross-references to one an- other, you get an interesting set of processes all along the line. If, then, you wish to insure the interest of your pupils, there is only one way to do it ; and that is to make certain that they have something in their rninds^fo attend^with, when you begin to talk. That something can consist in nothing but a previous lot of ideas already interesting in them- selves, and of such a nature that the incoming novel objects which you present can dovetail into them and form with them some kind of a logically associated or systematic whole. Fortunately, al- most any kind of a connection is sufficient to 98 TALKS TO TEACHERS cany the interest along. What a help is our Philippine war at present in teaching geography ! But before the war you could ask the children if they ate pepper with their eggs, and where they supposed the pepper came from. Or ask them if glass is a stone, and, if not, why not ; and then let them know how stones are formed and glass manu- factured. External links will serve as well as those that are deeper and more logical. But in- terest, once shed upon a subject, is liable to re- main always with that subject. Our acquisitions become in a measure portions of our personal self ; and little by little, as cross-associations multiply and habits of familiarity and practice grow, the entire system of our objects of thought consoli- dates, most of it becoming interesting for some purposes and in some degree. An adult man's interests are almost every one of them intensely artificial : they have slowly been built up. The objects of professional interest are most of them, in their original nature, repulsive ; but by their connection with such natively excit- ing objects as one's personal fortune, one's social responsibilities, and especially by the force of in- veterate habit, they grow to be the only things for which in middle life a man profoundly cares. THE SYSTEM OF OUR INTERESTS 99 But in all these the spread and consolidation have followed nothing but the principles first laid down. If we could recall for a moment our whole individual history, we should see that our pro- fessional ideals and the zeal they inspire are due to nothing but the slow accretion of one mental object to another, traceable backward from point to point till we reach the moment when, in the nursery or in the schoolroom, some little story told, some little object shown, some little opera- tion witnessed, brought the first new object and new interest within our ken by associating it with some one of those primitively there. The interest now suffusing the whole system took its rise in that little event, so insignificant to us now as to be entirely forgotten. As the bees in swarming cling to one another in layers till the few are reached whose feet grapple the bough from which the swarm depends; so with the objects of our thinking, they hang to each other by associated links, but the original source of interest in all of them is the native interest which the earliest one once possessed. XI. ATTENTION WHOEVER treats of interest inevitably treats of attention, for to say that an object is interesting r ^r^.^'*' vs ^*is only another way of saying that it excites atten- tion. But in addition to the attention which any object already interesting or just becoming interesting claims passive attention or sponta- neous attention, we may call it there is a more deliberate attention, voluntary attention or atten- tion with effort, as it is called, which we can give to objects less interesting or uninteresting in theni- ., + selves. The distinction between active and jms- sive attention is made in all books on psychology, and connects itself with the deeper aspects of the topic. From our present purely practical point of view, however, it is not necessary to be intricate ; and passive attention to natively interesting ma- terial requires no further elucidation on this occa- sion. All that we need explicitly to note is that, the more the passive attention is relied on, by keeping the material interesting; and the less the ATTENTION AND GENIUS 101 kind of attention requiring effort is appealed to; the more smoothly and pleasantly the class-room work goes on. I must say a few more words, however, about this latter process of voluntary and deliberate attention. One often hears it said that genius is nothing but a power of sustained attention, and the popu- lar impression probably prevails that men of fo/^~Zi~y genius are remarkable for their voluntary powers ^ctc^CU in this direction. But a little introspective obser- vation will show any one that voluntary attention ' cannot be continuously sustained, that it comes in beats. When we are studying an uninteresting subject, if our mind tends to wander, we have to ^J^ bring back our attention every now and then by ^U, using distinct pulses of effort, which revivify the topic for a moment, the mind then running on for a certain number of seconds or minutes with spon- taneous interest, until again some intercurrent idea captures it and takes it off. Then the proc- esses of volitional recall must be repeated once more. Voluntary attention, in short, is only a momentary affair. The process, whatever it is, exhausts itself in the single act; and, unless the matter is then taken in hand by some trace of interest inherent in the subject, the mind fails to Vfr-w 102 TALKS TO TEACHERS follow it at all. The sustained attention of the : genius, sticking to his subject for hours together, ' is for the most part of the passive sort. The W IL ~ " minds of geniuses are full of copious and original e.iv< .associations. The subject of thought, once started, develops all sorts of fascinating consequences. The attention is led along one of these to another in the most interesting manner, and the attention never once tends to stray away. In a commonplace mind, on the other hand, a JJ&0WVWI subject develops much less numerous associates: it dies out then quickly; and, if the man is to (kA*Jb keep up thinking of it at all, he must bring his attention back to it by a violent wrench. In him, therefore, the faculty of voluntary attention re- ceives abundant opportunity for cultivation in daily life. It is your despised business man, your union man of affairs, (so looked down on by the literary awarders of fame) whose virtue in this regard is likely to be most developed ; for he has to listen to the concerns of so many uninteresting people, and to transact so much drudging detail, that the faculty in question is always kept in training. A genius, on the contrary, is the man in whom you are least likely to find the power of attending to anything insipid or distasteful in CONDITIONS OF VOLUNTARY ATTENTION 103 itself. He breaks his engagements, leaves his letters unanswered, neglects his family duties in- corrigibly, because he is powerless to turn his at- tention down and back from those more interest- ing trains of imagery with which his genius con- stantly occupies his mind. Voluntary attention is thus an essentially in- stantaneous affair. You can claim it, for your purposes in the schoolroom, by commanding it in loud, imperious tones; and you can easily get it ^ in this way. But, unless the subject to which yout*-^ ^ thus recall their attention has inherent power toa^zc^^*-^ interest the pupils, you will have got it for only^ i^f a brief moment ; and their minds will soon be \w* <- f" wandering again. To keep them where you have^*^^**^ called them, you must make the subject too inter- esting for them to wander again. And for that there is one prescription; but the prescription, like all our prescriptions, is abstract, and, to get practical results from it, you must couple it with mother-wit, f The prescription is that the subject must be made to show new aspects of itself; to prompt new ques- tions ; in a word, to change. From an unchanging subject the attention inevitably wanders away. You can test this by the simplest possible case of 104 TALKS TO TEACHERS sensorial attention. Try to attend steadfastly to a dot on the paper or on the wall. You pres- t dL** en ^J nn d that one or the other of two things has happened: either your field of vision has become f ^ >-<~*^^ ~ blurred, so that you now see nothing distinct at all, or else you have involuntarily ceased to look at the dot in question, and are looking at some- thing else. But, if you ask yourself successive questions about the dot, how big it is, how far, of what shape, what shade of color, etc. ; in other words, if you turn it over, if you think of it in T various ways, and along with various kinds of asso- ciates, you can keep your mind on it for a com- paratively long time. This is what the genius does, in whose hands a given topic coruscates and grows. And this is what the teacher must do for every topic if he wishes to avoid too frequent ap- peals to voluntary attention of the coerced sort. In all respects, reliance upon such attention as this is a wasteful method, bringing bad temper and nervous wear and tear as well as imperfect results. The teacher who can get along by keep- ti ing spontaneous interest excited must be regarded u as the teacher with the greatest skill. There is, however, in all schoolroom work a large mass of material that must be dull and un- MECHANICAL AIDS TO ATTENTION 105 exciting, and to which it is impossible in any con- tinuous way to contribute an interest associatively derived. There are, therefore, certain external methods, which every teacher knows, of volun- tarily arousing the attention from time to time and keeping it upon the subject. Mr. Fitch has a lecture on the art of securing attention, and he briefly passes these methods in review; the post- ure must be changed; places can be changed. Questions, after being answered singly, may occa- sionally be answered in concert. Elliptical ques- tions may be asked, the pupil supplying the miss- - ^^ fa* ing word. The teacher must pounce upon the v most listless child and wake him up. The habit *^ * - fZIflr^ of prompt and ready response must be kept Recapitulations, illustrations, examples, novelty order, and ruptures of routine, all these are means for keeping the attention alive and con- tributing a little interest to a dull subject. Above all, the teacher must himself be alive and ready, and must use the contagion of his own example. But, when all is said and done, the fact remains that some teachers have a naturally inspiring pres- ence, and can make their exercises interesting, while others simply cannot. And psychology and general pedagogy here confess their failure, and 106 TALKS TO TEACHERS /c^w.-^ * hand things over to the deeper springs of human personality to conduct the task. A brief reference to the physiological theory of the attentive process may serve still further to elucidate these practical remarks, and ' confirm them by showing them from a slightly different point of view. What is the attentive process, psychologically Qjtfj*JU+s*> "-considered? Attention to an object is what takes ^9 /^^jt - place whenever that object most completely oc- cupies the mind. For simplicity's sake suppose the object be an object of sensation, a figure approaching us at a distance on the road. It is far off, barely perceptible, and hardly moving: we do not know with certainty whether it is a man or not. Such an object as this, if carelessly looked at, may hardly catch our attention at all. The opti- cal impression may affect solely the marginal con- sciousness, while the mental focus keeps engaged with rival thuigs. We may indeed not 'see' it till some one points it out. But, if so, how does he point it out? By his finger, and by describing its appearance, by creating a premonitory image of where to look and of what to expect to see. This premonitory image is already an excitement ATTENTION, PHYSIOLOGICALLY CONSIDERED 107 of the same nerve-centres that are to be concerned with the impression. The impression comes, and excites them still further; and now the object en- ters the focus of the field, consciousness being sus- tained both by impression and by preliminary idea. But the maximum of attention to it is not yet reached. Although we see it, we may not care for it; it may suggest nothing important to us; and a rival stream of objects or of thoughts may quickly take our mind away. If, however, our companion defines it in a significant way, arouses hi the mind a set of experiences to be apprehended from it, names it an enemy or as a messenger of important tidings, the residual and marginal ideas now aroused, so far from being its rivals, become its associates and allies. They shoot to- gether into one system with it; they converge upon it; they keep it steadily in focus; the mind attends to it with maximum power. " The attentive process, therefore, at its maximum may be physiologically symbolized by a brain-cell 1 "" played on hi two ways, from without and from' 6 ' within. Incoming currents from the periphery j^*^** arouse it, and collateral currents from the centres^ ' of memory and imagination re-enforce these. In this process the incoming impression is the 108 TALKS TO TEACHERS newer element ; the ideas which re-enforce and sus- ..v.tain it are among the older possessions of the i mind. And the maximui" nf attention may then be said to be found whenever we have a systema- . tic harmony or unification between the novel and the old. It is an odd circumstance that neither the old nor the new, by itself, is interesting: the absolutely old is insipid ; the absolutely new pj 0( ^. makes no appeal at all. The old in the new is - , / -L wna t claims the attention, the old with a slightly f new turn. No one wants to hear a lecture on a AXX y0*~ tr^^*sttAJEti*f lit- iii subject completely disconnected with his previous knowledge, but we all like lectures on subjects of which we know a little already, just as, in the fashions, every year must bring its slight modifi- cation of last year's suit, but an abrupt jump from the fashion of one decade into another would be distasteful to the eye. The genius of the interesting teacher consists ' in sympathetic divination of the sort of material with which the pupil's mind is likely to be already spontaneously engaged, and in the ingenuity which discovers paths of connection from that material to the matters to be newly learned. The principle is easy to grasp, but the accomplishment is difficult in the extreme. And a knowledge of -' INTEREST AND EFFORT ARE COMPATIBLES 109 such psychology as this which I am recalling can no more make a good teacher than a knowledge of the laws of perspective can make a landscape painter of effective skill. A certain doubt may now occur to some of you. A while ago, apropos of the pugnacious instinct, I spoke of our modern pedagogy as being possibly too 'soft.' You may perhaps here face me with my own words, and ask whether the exclusive effort on the teacher's part to keep the pupil's spontaneous interest going, and to avoid the more strenuous path of voluntary attention to repulsive work, does not savor also of sentimen- talism. The greater part of schoolroom work, you say, must, in the nature of things, always be repul- sive. To face uninteresting drudgery is a good part of life's work. Why seek to eliminate it from the schoolroom or minimize the sterner law? A word or two will obviate what might perhaps become a serious misunderstanding here. It is certain that most schoolroom work, till it has become habitual and automatic, is repulsive, and cannot be done without voluntarily jerking back the attention to it every now and then. This is inevitable, let the teacher do what he will. 110 TALKS TO TEACHERS It flows from the inherent nature of the subjects and of the learning mind. The repulsive proc- esses of verbal memorizing, of discovering steps of mathematical identity, and the like, must borrow their interest at first from purely external sources, mainly from the personal interests with which success in mastering them is associated, such as gaming of rank, avoiding punishment, not being beaten by a difficulty and the like. With- out such borrowed interest, the child could not attend to them at all. But in these processes what becomes interesting enough to be attended to is not thereby attended to without effort. Effort always has to go on, derived interest, for the most part, not awakening attention that is easy, however spontaneous it may now have to be called. The interest which the teacher, by his utmost skill, can lend to the subject, proves over Mid over again to be only an interest sufficient to let loose the effort. The teacher, therefore, need ^ never concern himself about inventing occasions ' - where effort must be called into play. Let him still awaken whatever sources of interest in the . . , . , subject he can by stirring up connections between it and the pupil's nature, whether in the line of theoretic curiosity, of personal interest, or of pug-/ INTEREST AND EFFORT ARE COMPATIBLES 111 nacious impulse. The laws of mind will then bring enough pulses of effort into play to keep the pupil exercised in the direction of the subject. There is, in fact, no greater school of effort than the steady struggle to attend to immediately re- pulsive or difficult objects of thought which have grown to interest us through their association as means, with some remote ideal end. The Herbartian doctrine of interest ought not, therefore, in principle to be reproached with ing pedagogy soft. If it do so, it is because it is unintelligently carried on. Do not, then, for the mere sake of discipline, command attention from your pupils in thundering tones. Do not too often beg it from them as a favor, nor claim it as a right, nor try habitually to excite it by preach- ing the importance of the subject. Sometimes, indeed, you must do these things; but, the more you have to do them, the less skilful teacher you will show yourself to be. Elicit interest from within, by the warmth with which you care for the topic yourself, and by following the laws I have laid down. If the topic be highly abstract, show its nature by concrete examples. If it be unfamiliar, trace some point of analogy in it with the known. If _ t 112 TALKS TO TEACHERS it be inhuman, make it figure as part of a story. If it be difficult, couple its acquisition with some prospect of personal gain. Above all things, make sure that it shall run through certain inner changes, since no unvarying object can possibly hold the mental field for long. Let your pupil wander from one aspect to another of your sub- ject, if you do not wish him to wander from it altogether to something else, variety in unity be- ing the secret of all interesting talk and thought. The relation of all these things to the native genius of the instructor is too obvious to need comment again. One more point, and I am done with the subject of , attention. There is unquestionably a great native variety among individuals in the type of their attention. Some of us are naturally scatter- brained, and others follow easily a train of con- nected thoughts without temptation to swerve aside to other subjects. This seems to depend on a difference between individuals in the type of their field of consciousness. In some persons this is highly focalized and concentrated, and the focal ideas predominate in determining association. In others we must suppose the margin to be brighter, CAN M1ND-WANDE1UNG BE CU11ED 113 and to be filled with something like meteoric showers of images, which strike into it at random, displacing the focal ideas, and carrying association in their own direction. Persons of the latter type find their attention wandering every minute, and must bring it back by a voluntary pull. The others sink into a subject of meditation deeply, and, when interrupted, are 'lost' for a moment before they come back to the outer world. The possession of such a steady faculty of at- tention is unquestionably a great boon. Those who have it can work more rapidly, and with less nervous wear and tear. .1 am inclined to think that no one who is without it naturally can by . A~ /r any amount of drill or discipline attain it in a very ' high degree. Its amount is probably a fixed char-J*^*** acteristic of the individual. But I wish to make 'ff a remark here which I shall have occasion to"^J*- v/u ** make again in other connections. It is that no one need deplore unduly the inferiority in himself of any one elementary faculty- This concentrated type of attention is an elementary faculty: it is one of the things that might be ascertained and /* measured by exercises in the laboratory. But, having ascertained it in a number of persons, we ^ ^7 * could never rank them in a scale of actual and *^^*^ 114 TALKS TO TEACHERS practical mental efficiency based on its degrees. The total mental efficiency of a man is the results ant of the working together of all his faculties. He is too complex a being for any one of them to have the casting vote. If any one of them do have the casting vote, it is more likely to be the strength of his desire and passion, the strength of the interest he takes in what is proposed. Con- centration, memory, reasoning power, inventive- ness, excellence of the senses, all are subsidiary to this. No matter how scatter-brained the type of a man's successive fields of consciousness may be, if he really care for a subject, he will return to it incessantly from his incessant wanderings, and first and last do more with it, and get more results from it, than another person whose attention may be more continuous during a given interval, but whose passion for the subject is of a more languid and less permanent sort. Some of the most effi- cient workers I know are of the ultra-scatter- brained type. One friend, who does a prodigious quantity of work, has in fact confessed to me that, if he wants to get ideas on any subject, he sits down to work at something else, his best results coming through his mind-wanderings. This is perhaps an epigrammatic exaggeration on his part ; ATTENTION, CONCLUDED 115 but I seriously think that no one of us need be too much distressed at his own shortcomings in this regard. Our mind may enjoy but little comfort, may be restless and feel confused ; but it may be extremely efficient all the same. XII. MEMORY WE are following a somewhat arbitrary order. Since each and every faculty we possess is either in whole or hi part a resultant of the play of our associations, it would have been as natural, after treating of association, to treat of memory as to treat of interest and attention next. But, since we did take the latter operations first, we must take memory now without farther delay ; for the phenomena of memory are among the simplest and most immediate consequences of the fact that our mind is essentially an associating machine. There is no more pre-eminent example for exhib- iting the fertility of the laws of association as principles of psychological analysis. Memory, moreover, is so important a faculty in the school- room that you are probably waiting with some eagerness to know what psychology has to say about it for your help. In old times, if you asked a person to explain why he came to be remembering at that moment SHALL WE CALL MEMORY A FACULTY 117 some particular incident in his previous life, the only reply he could make was that his soul is endowed with a faculty called memory ; that it is the inalienable function of this faculty to recol- ^ lect ; and that, therefore, he necessarily at moment must have a cognition of that portion (rfjr^^/i the past. This explanation by a 'faculty' is one thing which explanation by association has super- seded altogether. If, by saying we have a faculty of memory, you mean nothing more than the fact that we can remember, nothing more than an*' abstract name for our power inwardly to recall ^ ' the past, there is no harm done : we do have the faculty ; for we unquestionably have such a power. But if, by faculty, you mean a principle of expla- nation of our general power to recall, your psychol- ogy is empty. The associationist psychology, on the other hand, gives an explanation of each par- ticular fact of recollection ; and, in so doing, it also gives an explanation of the general faculty. The 'faculty' of memory is thus no or real ulti- mate explanation ; for it is itself explained as a result of the association of ideas. Nothing is easier than to show you just what I mean by this. Suppose I am silent for a moment, and then say in commanding accents : " Reineni- 118 TALKS TO TEACHERS ber ! Recollect ! " Does your faculty of memory obey the order, and reproduce any definite image from your past? Certainly not. It stands star- ing into vacancy, and asking, "What kind of a thing do you wish me to remember ? " It needs in short, a cue. But, if I say, remember the date of your birth, or remember what you had for breakfast, or remember the succession of notes in the musical scale ; then your faculty of memory im- mediately produces the required result : the ' cue ' determines its vast set of potentialities toward a particular point. And if you now look to see how this happens, you immediately perceive that the /cue is something contiguously associated with the thing recalled. The words, 'date of my birth,' have an ingrained association with a particular number, month, and year ; the words, ' breakfast this morning,' cut off all other lines of recall ex- cept those which lead to coffee and bacon and eggs; the words, 'musical scale,' are inveterate mental neighbors of do, re, mi, fa, sol, la, etc. The laws of association govern, in fact, all the trains of our thinking which are not interrupted by sen- sations breaking on us from -without Whatever appears in the mind must be introduced; and, when introduced, it is as the associate of some- PHYSIOLOGICAL BASIS OP MEMORY 119 ,^r&*t thing already there. This is as true of what you are recollecting as it is of everything else you think of. Reflection will show you that there are peculi- arities in your memory which would be quite whimsical and unaccountable if we were forced to regard them as the product of a purely spir- itual faculty. Were memory such a faculty, granted to us solely for its practical use, vr&^ ought to remember easiest whatever we most needed to remember; and frequency of repeti- tion, recency, and the like, would play no part in the matter. That we should best remember frequent things and recent things, and forget things that are ancient or were experienced only once, could only be regarded as an incomprehen- sible anomaly on such a view. But if we remem- ber because of our associations, and if these are (as the physiological psychologists believe) due to our organized brain-paths, we easily see how the J law of recency and repetition^ jshould prevail. Jj + Paths frequently and recently ploughed are those that lie most open, those which may be expected most easily to lead to results. The laws of our memory, as we find them, therefore are incidents of our associational constitution ; and, when we 120 TALKS TO TEACHERS are emancipated from the flesh, it is conceivable that they may no longer continue to obtain. We may assume, then, that recollection is a resultant of our associative processes, these them- selves in the last analysis being most probably due to the workings of our brain. Descending more particularly into the faculty -*. sr of memory, we have to distinguish between its potential aspect as a magazine or storehouse and vCu*A--C it* actual aspect as recollection now of a particu- lar event. Our memory contains all sorts of items which we do not now recall, but which we may recall, provided a sufficient cue be offered. Botli the general retention and the special recall are explained by association. An educated mem- "ory depends on an organized system of associa- tions^ and its goodness depends on two of their peculiarities : first, on the persistency^ the asso- ciations ; and, second, on their numbej. Let us considereach of these points in turn. First, the persistency of the associations. This gives what may be called the quality of native retentiveness to the individual. If, as I think we are forced to, we consider the brain to be the organic condition by which the vestiges of our THE GIFT OF ORGANIC RETENTIVENESS 121 experience are associated with each other, we may suppose that some brains are ' wax to receive and marble to retain.' The slightest impressions made on them abide. Names, dates, prices, an- ecdotes, quotations, are indelibly retained, their several elements fixedly cohering together, so that the individual soon becomes a walking cyclopedia of information. All this may occur with no philo- sophic tendency in the mind, no impulse to weave the materials acquired into anything like a logical system. In the books of anecdotes, and, more re- cently, in the psychology-books, we find recorded instances of monstrosities, as we may call them, of this desultory memory ; and they are often other- wise very stupid men. It is, of course, by no means incompatible with a philosophic mind ; for mental characteristics have infinite capacities for permutation. And, when both memory and phi- losophy combine together in one person, then in- deed we have the highest sort of intellectual efficiency. Your Walter Scotts, your Leibnitzes, your Gladstones, and your Goethes, all your folio copies of mankind, belong to this type. Effi- ciency on a colossal scale would indeed seem to require it. For, although your philosophic or systematic mind without good desultory memory 122 TALKS TO TEACHERS may know how to work out results and recollect where in the books to find them, the time lost in the searching process handicaps the thinker, and gives to the more ready type of individual the economical advantage. The extreme of the contrasted type, the type with associations of small persistency, is found in those who have almost no desultory memory at all. If they are also deficient in logical and sys- tematizing power, we call them simply feeble in- tellects ; and no more need to be said about them here. Their brain-matter, we may imagine, is like a fluid jelly, in which impressions may be easily made, but are soon closed over again, so that the brain reverts to its original indifferent state. But it may occur here, just as in other gelati- nous substances, that an impression will vibrate throughout the brain, and send waves into other parts of it. In cases of this sort, although the immediate impression may fade out quickly, it does modify the cerebral mass; for the paths it makes there may remain, and become so many avenues through which the impression may be re- produced if they ever get excited again. And its liability to reproduction will depend of course upon the variety of these paths and upon the fre- THE SECRET OF A GOOD MEMORY 123 quency with which they are used. Each path is in fact an associated process, the number of these associates becoming thus to a great degree a sub- stitute for the independent tenacity of the original impression. As I have elsewhere written: Each of the associates is a hook to which it hangs, a means to fish it up when sunk below the surface. Together they form a network of attachments by which it is woven into the entire tissue of our thought. The ' secret of a good memory ' is thus the secret of forming diverse and multiple associa- tions with every fact we care to retain. But this-, forming of associations with a fact, what is i but thinking about the fact as much as possible ? Briefly, then, of two men with the same outward experiences, the one who thinks over his experiences most, and weaves them into the most systematic relations with each other, will be the one with the best memory. But, if our ability to recollect a tiling be so largely a matter of its associations with other things which thus becomes its cues, an important pedagogic consequence follows. There can be no improvement of the general or elementary faculty of memory : there can only be improvement of our mem- ory for special systems of associated things; and 124 TALKS TO TEACHERS this latter improvement is due to the way in which the things in question are woven into asso- ciation with each other in the mind. Intricately or profoundly woven, they are held : disconnected, they tend to drop out just in proportion as the native brain retentiveness is poor. And no amount of training, drilling, repeating, and re- citing employed upon the matter of one system of objects, the history-system, for example, will in the least improve either the facility or the durability with which objects belonging to a wholly disparate system the system of facts of chemistry, for instance tend to be retained. That system must be separately worked into the mind by itself, a chemical fact which is thought about in connection with the other chemical facts, tending then to stay, but otherwise easily drop- ping out We have, then, not so much a faculty of mem- \ > ^ A f J ffy as many faculties of memory. We have as mnnv na w* Viavp avsrtama nf iiln. many as we have >O thought of in connection with each other. A given object is held in the memory by the associates it has acquired within its own system exclusively. Learning the facts of another system will in no wise help it to stay in the mind, for the simple MEMORIES RATHER THAN MEMORY 125 reason that it has no * cues ' within that other system. We see examples of this on every hand. Most men have a good memory for facts con- nected with their own pursuits. A college ath- lete, who remains a dunce at his books, may amaze you by his knowledge of the * records ' at various feats and games, and prove himself a walking dictionary of sporting statistics. The reason is that he is constantly going over these things in his mind, and comparing and making series of them. They form for him, not so many odd facts, but a concept-system, so they stick. So the merchant remembers prices, the politician other politicians' speeches and votes, with a copiousness which astonishes outsiders, but which the amount of thinking they bestow on these subjects easily explains. The great memory for facts which a Darwin or a Spencer reveal in their books is not incompati- ble with the possession on their part of a mind with only a middling degree of physiological re- tentiveness. Let a man early in life set himself the task of verifying such a theory as that of evo- lution, and facts will soon cluster and cling to him like grapes to their stem. Their relations to the 120 TALKS TO TEACHERS theory will hold them fast ; and, the more of these the mind is able to discern, the greater the erudi- tion will become. Meanwhile the theorist may have little, if any, desultory memory. Unutiliza- ble facts may be unnoted by him, and forgotten as soon as heard. An ignorance almost as ency- clopedic as his erudition may coexist with the latter, and hide, as it were, within the interstices of its web. Those of you who have had much to do with scholars and savants will readily think of examples of the class of mind I mean. The best possible sort of system into which to weave an object, mentally, is a rational system, or what is called a * science.' Place the thing in its pigeon-hole in a classificatory series; explain it logically by its causes, and deduce from it its necessary effects ; find out of what natural law it is an instance, and you then know it in the best of all possible ways. A * science ' is thus the greatest of labor-saving contrivances. It relieves the memory of an immense number of details, re- placing, as it does, merely contiguous associations by the logical ones of identity, similarity, or anal- ogy. If you know a 'law,' you may discharge your memory of masses of particular instances, for the law will reproduce them for you whenever TECHNICAL MNEMONICS 127 you require them. The law of refraction, for ex- ample : If you know that, you can with a pencil and a bit of paper immediately discern how a con- vex lens, a concave lens, or a prism, must sever- ally alter the appearance of an object. But, if you don't know the general law, you must charge your memory separately with each of the three kinds of effect. f*P Ot*'&* > ** J A 'philosophic' system, in which all things ' .JCZv**" found their rational explanation and were con- -- ^,yV 9 nected together as causes and effects, would be ^*/ the perfect mnemonic system, in which the great- est economy of means would bring about the greatest richness of results. So that, if we have poor desultory memories, we can save ourselves by cultivating the philosophic turn of mind. There are many artificial systems of mnemonics, some public, some sold as secrets. They are all so many devices for training us into certain me-- thodical and stereotyped ways of thinking about the y^^ facts we seek to retain. Even were I competent, **'***' I could not here go into these systems in any de- tail. But a single example, from a popular sys- tem, will show what I mean. I take the number- alphabet, the great mnemonic device for recollect- ing numbers and dates. In this system each digit 128 TALKS TO TEACHERS is represented by a consonant, thus: 1 is t or d; 2, n; 3, m ; 4,r; 5, 1; 6, sh,j, ch, or g ; 7, c, k,g, or g-w ; 8, / or v ; 9, b or ^? ; 0, , ^H>eing for light to be thrown on his real efficiency by measuring any one mental faculty taken apart from its consensus in the working whole. Such k*wv cL* a 11 exercise as this, dealing with incoherent and insipid objects, with no logical connection with each other, or practical significance outside of the 'test,' is an exercise the like of which in real life we are hardly ever called upon to perform. In real life, our memory is always used in the ser- vice of some interest : we remember things which we care for or which are associated with things we care for; and the child who stands at the bot- tom of the scale thus experimentally established might, by dint of the strength of his passion for a subject, and in consequence of the logical asso- ciation into which he weaves the actual materials of his experience, be a very effective memorizer indeed, and do his school-tasks on the whole much better than an immediate parrot who might stand at the top of the scientifically accurate ' list. This preponderance of interest, of passion, in determining the results of a human being's work- ELEMENTARY DEFECTS NOT FATAL 135 ing life, obtains throughout. No elementary measurement, capable of being performed in a laboratory, can throw any efficiency of the"subject ;for the vital thing about him, his emotional and moral energy and dogged- ness, can be measured by no single experiment, and becomes known only by the total results in the long run. A blind man like Huber, with his pas- sion for bees and ants, can observe them through other people's eyes better than these can through their own. A man born with neither arms nor legs, like the late Kavanagh, M. P. and what an icy heart his mother must have had about him in his babyhood, and how ' negative ' would the laboratory-measurements of his motor-functions have been ! can be an adventurous traveller, an equestrian and sportsman, and lead an athletic outdoor life. Mr. Romanes studied the element- ary rate of apperception in a large number of persons by making them read a paragraph as fast as they could take it in, and then immediately write down all they could reproduce of its con- tents. He found astonishing differences in the rapidity, some taking four times as long as others to absorb the paragraph, and the swiftest readers being, as a rule, the best immediate recollectors, 136 TALKS TO TEACHERS too. But not, and this is my point, not the most intellectually capable subjects, as tested by the results of what Mr. Romanes rightly names ' genuine ' intellectual work ; for he tried the ex- periment with several highly distinguished men in science and literature, and most of them turned out to be slow readers. In the light of all such facts one may well be- lieve that the total impression which a perceptive teacher will get of the pupil's condition, as indi- cated by his general temper and manner, by the listlessness or alertness, by the ease or painfulness with which his school work is done, will be of more value than those unreal experimental tests, those pedantic elementary measurements of . fatigue, memory, association, and attention, etc., which are urged upon us as the only basis of a genuinely scientific pedagogy. Such measure- ments can give us useful information only when we combine them with observations made without brass instruments, upon the total demeanor of the measured individual, by teachers with eyes in their heads and common sense, and some feeling for the concrete facts of human nature in their hearts. Depend upon it, no one need be too much cast VAEIOUS TYPES OP IMAGINATION 137 down by the discovery of his deficiency in any ele- mentary faculty of the mind. What tells in life is the whole mind working together, and the de- ficiencies of any one faculty can be compensated by the efforts of the rest. You can be an artist without visual images, a reader without eyes, a mass of erudition with a bad elementary memory. In almost any subject your passion for the subject will save you. If you only care enough for a result, you will almost certainly attain it. If you wish to be rich, you will be rich ; if you wish to be learned, you will be learned ; if you wish to be good, you will be good, Only you must, then, really wish these things, and wish them with ex- clusiveness, and not wish at the same time a hun- dred other incompatible things just as strongly. One of the most important discoveries of the 'scientific' sort that have recently been made in psychology is that of Mr. Galton and others con- cerning the great variations among individuals inVfT** the type of their imagination. Every one is now^xv*, fe^Lt familiar with the fact that human beings vary enormously in the brilliancy, completeness, defi- . niteness, and extent of their visual images. These , are singularly perfect in a large number of indi- viduals, and in a few are so rudimentary as hardly 138 TALKS TO TEACHERS to exist. The same is true of the auditory and motor images, and probably of those of every kind; and the recent discovery of distinct brain- areas for the various orders of sensation would seem to provide a physical basis for such varia- tions and discrepancies. The facts, as I said, are nowadays so popularly known that I need only remind you of their existence. They might seem at first sight of practical importance to the teacher; and, indeed, teachers have been recom- mended to sort their pupils in this way, and treat them as the result falls out. You should inter- rogate them as to their imagery, it is said, or exhibit lists of written words to their eyes, and then sound similar lists in their ears, and see by which channel a child retains most words. Then, in dealing with that child, make your appeals predominantly through that channel. If the class were very small, results of some distinct- ness might doubtless thus be obtained by a pains- taking teacher. But it is obvious that in the usual school-room no such differentiation of appeal is possible ; and the only really useful practical lesson that emerges from this analytic psychology in the conduct of large schools is the lesson al- ready reached in a purely empirical way, that SENSE-IMPRESSIONS SHOULD BE VARIED 139 the teacher ought always to impress the class vr*fa** A * through as many sensible channels as he can. (JL** Talk and write and draw on blackboard, permit -^.^^^ the pupils to talk, and make them write and draw, t exhibit pictures, plans, and curves, have your dia- grams colored differently in their different parts, etc. ; and out of the whole variety of impressions the individual child will find the most lasting ones for himself. In all primary school work this principle of multiple impressions is well recog- nized, so I need say no more about it here. This principle of multiplying channels and varying associations and appeals is important, not only for teaching pupils to remember, but for teaching them to understand. It runs, in fact, through the whole teaching art. One word about the unconscious and unrepro- ducible part of our acquisitions, and I shall have done with the topic of memory. Professor Ebbinghaus, in a heroic little investi- gation into the laws of memory which he per- formed a dozen or more years ago by the method of learning lists of nonsense syllables, devised a method of measuring the rate of our forgetfulness, which lays bare an important law of the mind. - 7 ^rr-Q. *^*^^ 140 TALKS TO TEACHERS His method was to read over his list until he could repeat it once by heart unhesitatingly. The number of repetitions required for this was a measure of the difficulty of the learning in each particular case. Now, after having once learned a piece hi this way, if we wait five minutes, we find it impossible to repeat it again hi the same unhes- itating manner. We must read it over again to revive some of the syllables, which have already dropped out or got transposed. Ebbinghaus now systematically studied the number of readings- over which were necessary to revive the unhesi- tating recollection of the piece after five minutes, half an hour, an hour, a day, a week, a month, had elapsed. The number of rereadings requir- ed he took to be a measure of the amount of for- getting that had occurred in the elapsed interval. And he found some remarkable facts. The proc- ess of forgetting, namely, is vastly more rapid at first than later on. Thus full half of the piece st-enis to lie forgotten within the first half-hour. two-thirds of it are forgotten at the end of eight ^ -K^- hours, but only four-fifths at the end of a month. He made no trials beyond one month of interval ; but, if we ourselves prolong ideally the curve of remembrance, whose beginning his experiments THE RATE OP FORGETTING 141 thus obtain, it is natural to suppose that, no matter how long a time might elapse, the curve would never descend quite so low as to touch the zero-line. In other words, no matter how long ago we may have learned a poem, and no matter how complete our inability to reproduce it now may be, yet the first learning will still show its lingering effects in the abridgment of the time required for learning it again. In short, Profes- sor Ebbinghaus's experiments show that things which we are quite unable definitely to recall have '< nevertheless impressed themselves, in some way,*^* upon the structure of the mind. We are different . *'Q irn. for having once learned them. The resistances in our systems of brain-paths are altered. Our ap^*"*"^"" prehensions are quickened. Our conclusions from certain premises are probably not just what they would be if those modifications were not there. The latter influence the whole margin of our con- sciousness, even though their products, not being distinctly reproducible, do not directly figure at the focus of the field. The teacher should draw a lesson from these facts. We are all too apt to measure the gains of our pupils by their proficiency in directly repro- ducing in a recitation or an examination such 142 TALKS TO TEACHERS matters as they may have learned, and inarticu- late power in them is something of which we always underestimate the value. The boy who tells us, " I know the answer, but I can't say what it is," we treat as practically identical with him who knows absolutely nothing about the answer at all. But this is a great mistake. It is but a small part of our experience in life that we are ever able articulately to recall. And yet the whole of it has had its influence hi shaping our character and denning our tendencies to judge and act. Although the ready memory is a great blessing to its possessor, the vaguer memory of a subject, of having once had to do with it, of its neighborhood, and of where we may go to recover it again, constitutes in most men and women the chief fruit of their education. This is true even in professional education. The doctor, the lawyer, are seldom able to decide upon a case off-hand. They differ from other men only through the fact tli at they know how to get at the materials for decision in five minutes or half an hour : whereas the layman is unable to get at the materials at all, not knowing in what books and indexes to look or not understanding the technical terms. Be patient, then, and sympathetic with the type THE FORGOTTEN MAY STILL COUNT 143 of mind that cuts a poor figure in It may, in the long examination which life sets us, come out in the end in better shape than the glib and ready reproducer, its passions being deeper, its purposes more worthy, its combining power less commonplace, and its total mental output consequently more important. Such are the chief points which it has seemed ' worth while for me to call to your notice u^dep<%X**^^*Y^ the head of memory. We can sum them up for practical purposes by saying that the art of re- membering is the art of thinking ; and by adding, with Dr. Pick, that, when we wish to fix a new thing in either our own mind or a pupil's, our conscious effort should not be so much to it press and retain it as to connect it with some- thing else already there. The connecting is the thinking; and, if we attend clearly to the con-*"* nection, the connected thing will certainly be likely to remain within recall. I shall next ask you to consider the process by which we acquire new knowledge, the process of 'Apperception,' as it is called, by which we re- ceive and deal with new experiences, and revise our stock of ideas so as to form new or improved conceptions. XIII. THE ACQUISITION OF IDEAS THE images of our past experiences, of what- ever nature they may be, visual or verbal, blurred and dim, vivid and distinct, abstract or concrete, need not be memory images, in the strict sense of the word. That is, they need not rise before the mind in a marginal fringe or context of concomi- tant circumstances, which mean for us their date. They may be mere conceptions, floating pictures of an object, or of its type or class. In this un- dated condition, we call them products of 'im- or 'conception.' Imagination is the commonly used where the object represent- ed is thought of as an individual thing. Concep- **^ tion is the term where we think of it as a type or class. For our present purpose the distinction is not important ; and I will permit myself to use either the word 'conception,' or the still vaguer word ' idea,' to designate the inner objects of con- templation, whether these be individual things, like 'the sun' or 'Julius Caesar,' or classes of THE STOCK OF IDEAS 145 things, like ' animal kingdom,' or, finally, entirely abstract attributes, like 'rationality' or 'rect- itude.' The result of our education is to fill the mind little by little, as experiences accrete, with a stock of such ideas. In the illustration I used at our first meeting, of the child snatching the toy and getting slapped, the vestiges left by the first experi- ence answered to so many ideas which he acquired thereby, ideas that remained with him associ- ated in a certain order, and from the last one of which the child eventually proceeded to act. The sciences of grammar and of logic are little more than attempts methodically to classify all such acquired ideas and to trace certain laws of relation- ship among them. The forms of relation between them, becoming themselves in turn noticed by the mind, are treated as conceptions of a higher and more abstract order, as when we speak of a ' syl- logistic relation' between propositions, or of four quantities making a proportion,' or of the ' incon- sistency ' of two conceptions, or the ' implication ' of one in the other. So you see that the process of education, taken in a large way, may be described as nothing but the process of acquiring ideas or conceptions, -v **U4 , 1$ 'jw**-. 146 TALKS TO TEACHERS the best educated mind being the mind which has the largest stock of them, ready to meet the largest possible variety of the emergencies of life. The lack of education means only the failure to have acquired them, and the consequent liability to be 'floored' and * rattled' in the vicissitudes of experience. In all this process of acquiring conceptions, a certain instinctive order is followed. There is a native tendency to assimilate certain kinds of con- ception at one age, and other kinds of conception at a later age. During the first seven or eight years of childhood the mind is most interested in the sensible properties of material things. Conttructiveness is the instinct most active; and <(U*t o^feL-^ay the incessant hammering and sawing, and dressing and undressing dolls, putting of things together and taking them apart, the child not only trains the muscles to co-ordinate action, but accumulates a store of physical conceptions which are the basis of his knowledge of the material world through life. Object-teaching and manual training wisely extend the sphere of this order of acquisition. Clay, wood, metals, and the vari- ous kinds of tools are made to contribute to the store. A youth brought up with a sufficiently IDEAS OF PHYSICAL THINGS 147 broad basis of this kind is always at home in the world. He stands within the pale. He is ac- quainted with Nature, and Nature in a certain sense is acquainted with him. Whereas the youth brought up alone at home, with no ac- quaintance with anything but the printed page, is always afflicted with a certain remoteness from the material facts of life, and a correlative inse- curity of consciousness which make of him a kind of alien on the earth in which he ought to feel himself perfectly at home. I already said something of this in speaking of the constructive impulse, and I must not re- peat myself. Moreover, you fully realize, I am sure, how important for life, for the moral tone of life, quite apart from definite practical pur- suits, is this sense of readiness for emergencies which a man gains through early familiarity and acquaintance with the world of material things. To have grown up on a farm, to have haunted a carpenter's and blacksmith's shop, to have handled horses and cows and boats and guns, and to have ideas and abilities connected with such objects are an inestimable part of youthful ac- quisition. After adolescence it is rare to be able to get into familiar touch with any of these 148 TALKS TO TEACHERS primitive tilings. The instinctive propensions have faded, and the habits are hard to acquire. Accordingly, one of the best fruits of the * child- study' movement has been to reinstate all these activities to their proper place in a sound system of education. Feed the growing human being, feed him with the sort of experience for which from year to year he shows a natural craving, and he will develop hi adult life a sounder sort of mental tissue, even though he may seem to be * wasting ' a great deal of his growing time, hi the eyes of those for whom the only channels of learning are books and verbally communicated information. It is not till adolescence is reached that the mind grows able to take in the more abstract as- pects of experience, the hidden similarities and distinctions between things, and especially their causal sequences. Rational knowledge of such things as mathematics, mechanics, chemistry, and biology, is now possible; and the acquisition of conceptions of this order form the next phase of education. Later still, not till adolescence is well advanced, does the mind awaken to a systematic interest in abstract human relations moral rela- tions, properly so called, to sociological ideas and to metaphysical abstractions. NATURAL ORDER OF ACQUISITION 149 This general order of sequence is followed tra- ditionally of course in the schoolroom. It is for- eign to my purpose to do more than indicate that general psychological principle of the successive order of awakening of the faculties on which the whole thing rests. I have spoken of it already, apropos of the transitoriness of instincts. Just as many a youth has to go permanently without an adequate stock of conceptions of a certain order, because experiences of that order were not yielded at the time when new curiosity was most acute, so it will conversely happen that many another youth is spoiled for a certain subject of study (although he would have enjoyed it well if led into it at a later age) through having had it thrust upon him so prematurely that disgust was created, and the bloom quite taken off from future trials. I think I have seen college students un- fitted forever for philosophy ' from having taken that study up a year too soon. In all these later studies, verbal material is the vehicle by which the mind thinks. The abstract conceptions of physics and sociology may, it is true, be embodied in visual or other images of phenomena, but they need not be so ; and the truth remains that, after adolescence has begun, 150 TALKS TO TEACHERS "words, words, words," must constitute a large part, and an always larger part as life advances, of what the human being has to learn. This is so even in the natural sciences, so far as these are causal and rational, and not merely confined to description. So I go back to what I said awhile ago apropos of verbal memorizing. The more ac- curately words are learned, the better, if only the teacher make sure that what they signify is also understood. It is the failure of this latter condi- tion, in so much of the old-fashioned recitation, that has caused that reaction against * parrot-like reproduction ' that we are so familiar with to-day. A friend of mine, visiting a school, was asked to examine a young class in geography. Glancing at the book, she said : " Suppose you should dig a hole in the ground, hundreds of feet deep, how should you find it at the bottom, warmer or colder than on top ? " None of the class replying, the teacher said : " I'm sure they know, but I think you don't ask the question quite rightly. Let me try." So, taking the book, she asked : " In what condition is the ulterior of the globe?" and re- ceived the immediate answer from half the class at once : " The interior of the globe is in a condition of igneous fusion ." Better exclusive object-teach- EACH AGE CAN APPREHEND ABSTRACTIONS 151 ing than such verbal recitations as that ; and yet verbal reproduction, intelligently connected with more objective work, must always play a leading, and surely the leading, part in education. Our modern reformers, in their books, write too ex- clusively of the earliest years of the pupil. These lend themselves better to explicit treatment ; and I myself, in dwelling so much upon the native impulses, and object-teaching, and anecdotes, and all that, have paid my tribute to the line of least resistance in describing. Yet away back in childhood we find the beginnings of purely intel- lectual curiosity, and the intelligence of abstract terms. The object-teaching is mainly to launch the pupils, with some concrete conceptions of the facts concerned, upon the more abstract ideas. To hear some authorities on teaching, however, you would suppose that geography not only began, but ended with the school-yard and neighboring hill, that physics was one endless round of repeat- ing the same sort of tedious weighing and meas- uring operation: whereas a very few examples are usually sufficient to set the imagination free on genuine lines, and then what the mind craves is more rapid, general, and abstract treatment. I heard a lady say that she had taken her child to 152 TALKS TO TEACHERS the kindergarten, "but he is so bright that he saw through it immediately." Too many school children ' see ' as immediately * through ' the namby-pamby attempts of the softer pedagogy to lubricate things for them, and make them in- teresting. Even they can enjoy abstractions, pro- vided they be of the proper order ; and it is a poor compliment to their rational appetite to think that anecdotes about little Tommies and little Jennies are the only kind of things their minds can digest. But here, as elsewhere, it is a matter of more or less ; and, hi the last resort, the teacher's own tact is the only thing that can bring out the right effect. The great difficulty with abstractions is that of knowing just what meaning the pupil at- taches to the terms he uses. The words may sound all right, but the meaning remains the child's own secret. So varied forms of words must be insisted on, to bring the secret out. And a strange secret does it often prove. A relative of mine was trying to explain to a little girl what was meant by 'the passive voice': "Suppose that you kill me : you who do the killing are in the active voice, and I, who am killed, am in the passive voice." " But how can you speak if you're killed?" said the child. "Oh, well, AMBIGUITY OF VERBAL ABSTRACTIONS 153 you may suppose that I am not yet quite dead ! " The next day the child was asked, in class, to ex- plain the passive voice, and said, " It's the kind of voice you speak with when you ain't quite dead." In such a case as this the illustration ought to have been more varied. Every one's memory will probably furnish examples of the fantastic mean- ing which their childhood attached to certain verbal statements (in poetry often), and which their elders, not having any reason to suspect, never corrected. I remember being greatly moved emotionally at the age of eight by the ballad of Lord Ullin's Daughter. Yet I thought that the staining of the heather by the blood was the evil chiefly dreaded, and that, when the boatman said, " I'll row you o'er the ferry. It is not for your silver bright, But for your winsome lady," lie was to receive the lady for his pay. Similarly, I recently found that one of my own children was reading (and accepting) a verse of Tennyson's In Memoriam as " Ring out ihefood of rich and poor, Ring in redness to all mankind," and rinding no inward difficulty. 154 TALKS TO TEACHERS The only safeguard against this sort of miscon- ceiving is to insist on varied statement, and to bring the child's conceptions, wherever it be pos- sible, to some sort of practical test. Let us next pass to the subject of Appercep- tion. XIV. APPERCEPTION ' APPERCEPTION ' is a word which cuts a great figure in the pedagogics of the present day. Read, for example, this advertisement of a certain text-book, which I take from an educational journal : - WHAT IS APPERCEPTION ? For an explanation of Apperception see Blank's PSYCHOLOGY, Vol. of the Education Series, just published. The difference between Perception and Apperception is explained for the teacher in the preface to Blank's PSYCHOLOGY. Many teachers are inquiring, " What is the meaning of Apperception in educational psychology ? " Just the book for them is Blank's PSYCHOLOGY in which the idea was first expounded. The most important idea in educational psychology is Apperception. The teacher may find this expounded in Blank's PSY- CHOLOGY. The idea of Apperception is making a revolution in educational methods in Germany. It is explained in Blank's PSYCHOLOGY, Vol. of the Education Series, just published. Blank's PSYCHOLOGY will be mailed prepaid to any address on receipt of $ 1.00. 156 TALKS TO TEACHERS Such an advertisement is in sober earnest a disgrace to all concerned ; and such talk as it indulges-in is the sort of thing I had in view when I said at our first meeting that the teachers were suffering at the present day from a certain industrious mystification on the part of editors and publishers. Perhaps the word ' appercep- tion' flourished in their eyes and ears as it nowadays often is, embodies as much of this mystification as any other single thing. The conscientious young teacher is led to believe that it contains a recondite and portentous secret, by losing the true inwardness of which her whole career may be shattered. And yet, when she turns to the books and reads about it, it seems so trivial and commonplace a matter, meaning nothing more than the manner in which we re- ceive a thing into our minds, that she fears she must have missed the point through the shallow- ness of her intelligence, and goes about thereafter afflicted with a sense either of uncertainty or of stupidity, and in each case remaining mortified at being so inadequate to her mission. Now apperception is an extremely useful word in pedagogics, and offers a convenient name for a process to which every teacher must frequently APPERCEPTION DEFINED 157 refer. But it verily means nothing more than the act of taking a thing into the mind. It corre- sponds to nothing peculiar or elementary in psy- chology, being only one of the innumerable re- sults of the psychological process of association of ideas; and psychology itself can easily dispense with the word, useful as it may be in pedagogics. The gist of the matter is this : Every impression that comes in from without, be it a sentence which we hear, an object of vision, or an effluvium which assails our nose, no sooner enters our conscious- ness than it is drafted off hi some determinate direc- tion or other, making connection with the other materials already there, and finally producing what we call our reaction. The particular connections it strikes into are determined by our past experi- ences and the ' associations ' of the present sort of impression with them. If, for instance, you hear me call out A, B, C, it is ten to one that you will react on the impression by inwardly or out- wardly articulating D, E, F. The impression arouses its old associates ; they go out to meet it ; it is received by them, recognized by the mind as 4 the beginning of the alphabet.' It is the fate of every impression thus to fall into a mind pre- 158 TALKS TO TEACHERS occupied with memories, ideas, and interests, and by these it is taken in. Educated as we already are, we never get an experience that remains for us completely nondescript: it always reminds of something similar in quality, or of some context that might have surrounded it before, and which it now hi some way suggests. This mental escort which the mind supplies is drawn, of course, from the mind's ready-made stock. We conceive the impression hi some definite way. We dispose of it according to our acquired possibilities, be they few or many, hi the way of 'ideas.' This way of taking in the object is the process of ap- perception. The conceptions which meet and assimilate it are called by Herbert the * apperceiv- ing mass.' The apperceived impression is en- gulfed hi this, and the result is a new field of consciousness, of which one part (and often a very small part) comes from the outer world, and another part (sometimes by far the largest) comes from the previous contents of the mind. I think that you see plainly enough now that the process of apperception is what I called it a moment ago, a resultant of the association of ideas. The product is a sort of fusion of the new with the old, hi which it is often impossible to THE LAW OF LEAST DISTURBANCE 159 distinguish the share of the two factors. For example, when we listen to a person speaking or read a page of print, much of what we think we see or hear is supplied from our memory. We overlook misprints, imagining the right letters, though we see the wrong ones ; and how little we actually hear, when we listen to speech, we realize when we go to a foreign theatre ; for there what troubles us is not so much that we cannot under- stand what the actors say as that we cannot hear their words. The fact is that we hear quite as little under similar conditions at home, only our mind, being fuller of English verbal associations, supplies the requisite material for comprehension upon a much slighter auditory hint. In all the apperceptive operations of the mind, a certain general law makes itself felt, the law of economy. In admitting a new body of expe- rience, we instinctively seek to disturb as little as possible our pre-existing stock of ideas. We always try to name a new experience hi some way which will assimilate it to what we already know. We hate anything absolutely new, any- thing without any name, and for which a new name must be forged. So we take the nearest name, even though it be inappropriate. A child 160 TALKS TO TEACHERS will call snow, when he sees it for the first time, sugar or white butterflies. The sail of a boat he calls a curtain ; an egg hi its shell, seen for the first time, he calls a pretty potato ; an orange, a ball; a folding corkscrew, a pair of bad scissors. Caspar Hauser called the first geese he saw horses, and the Polynesians called Captain Cook's horses pigs. Mr. Hooper has written a little book on apperception, to which he gives the title of " A Pot of Green Feathers," that being the name applied to a pot of ferns by a child who had never seen ferns before. In later life this economical tendency to leave the old undisturbed leads to what we know as 'old fogyism.' A new idea or a fact which would entail extensive rearrangement of the pre- vious system of beliefs is always ignored or ex- truded from the mind in case it cannot be sophis- tically reinterpreted so as to tally harmoniously with the system. We have all conducted discus- sions with middle-aged people, overpowered them with our reasons, forced them to admit our con- tention, and a week later found them back as secure and constant in their old opinion as if they had never conversed with us at all. We call UK-MI old fogies ; but there are young fogies, too. Old NUMBERLESS TYPES OF APPERCEPTION 161 fogyism begins at a younger age than we think. I am almost afraid to say so, but I believe that in the majority of human beings it begins at about twenty-five. In some of the books we find the various forms of apperception codified, and their subdivisions numbered and ticketed in tabular form in the way so delightful to the pedagogic eye. In one book which I remember reading there were sixteen dif- ferent types of apperception discriminated from each other. There was associative apperception, subsumptive apperception, assimilative appercep- tion, and others up to sixteen. It is needless to say that this is nothing but an exhibition of the crass artificiality which has always haunted psy- chology, and which perpetuates itself by lingering along, especially in these works which are adver- tised as 'written for the use of teachers.' The flowing life of the mind is sorted into parcels suitable for presentation in the recitation-room, and chopped up into supposed 'processes' with long Greek and Latin names, which in real life have no distinct existence. There is no reason, if we are classing the dif- ferent types of apperception, why we should stop at sixteen rather than sixteen hundred. There 162 TALKS TO TEACHERS are as many types of apperception as there are pos- sible ways in which an incoming experience may be reacted on by an individual mind. A little while ago, at Buffalo, I was the guest of a lady who, a fortnight before, had taken her seven-year- old boy for the first time to Niagara Falls. The child silently glared at the phenomenon until his mother, supposing him struck speechless by its sublimity, said, "Well, my boy, what do you think of it?" to which, "Is that the kind of spray I spray my nose with ? " was the boy's only reply. That was his mode of apperceiving the spectacle. You may claim this as a particular type, and call it by the Greek name of rhinothera- peutical apperception, if you like ; and, if you do, you will hardly be more trivial or artificial than are some of the authors of the books. M. Perez, in one of his books on childhood, gives a good example of the different modes of apper- ception of the same phenomenon which are pos- sible at different stages of individual experience. A dwelling-house took fire, and an infant in the family, witnessing the conflagration from the arms of his nurse, standing outside, expressed nothing but the liveliest delight at its brilliancy. But, when the bell of the fire-engine was heard TOO FEW HEADS OF CLASSIFICATION 163 approaching, the child was thrown by the sound into a paroxysm of fear, strange sounds being, as you know, very alarming to young children. In what opposite ways must the child's parents have apperceived the burning house and the engine re- spectively! The self-same person, according to the line of thought he may be in, or to his emotional mood, will apperceive the same impression quite dif- ferently on different occasions. A medical or en- gineering expert retained on one side of a case will not apperceive the facts in the same way as if the other side had retained him. When people are at loggerheads about the interpretation of a fact, it usually shows that they have too few heads of classification to apperceive by; for, as a gen- eral thing, the fact of such a dispute is enough to show that neither one of their rival interpreta- tions is a perfect fit. Both sides deal with the matter by approximation, squeezing it under the handiest or least disturbing conception: whereas it would, nine times out of ten, be better to en- large their stock of ideas or invent some altogether new title for the phenomenon. Thus, in biology, we used to have interminable discussion as to whether certain single-celled or- 164 TALKS TO TEACHERS ganisms were animals or vegetables, until Haeckel introduced the new apperceptive name of Protista, which ended the disputes. In law courts no tertium quid is recognized between insanity and sanity. . If sane, a man is punished: if insane, acquitted; and it is seldom hard to find two experts who will take opposite views of his case. All the while, nature is more subtle than our doctors. Just as a room is neither dark nor light absolutely, but might be dark for a watch- maker's uses, and yet light enough to eat in or play in, so a man may be sane for some purposes and insane for others, sane enough to be left at large, yet not sane enough to take care of his financial affairs. The word * crank,' which be- came familiar at the time of Guiteau's trial, ful- filled the need of a tertium quid. The foreign terms * de'se'quilibre,' 'hereditary degenerate,' and ' psychopathic ' subject, have arisen in response to the same need. The whole progress of our sciences goes on by the invention of newly forged technical names whereby to designate the newly remarked aspects of phenomena, phenomena which could only be squeezed with violence into the pigeonholes of the earlier stock of conceptions. As time goes THE APPERCEIVING IDEA 165 on, our vocabulary becomes thus ever more and more voluminous, having to keep up with the ever-growing multitude of our stock of apperceiv- ing ideas. In this gradual process of interaction between the new and the old, not only is the new modified and determined by the particular sort of old which apperceives it, but the apperceiving mass, the old itself, is modified by the particular kind of new which it assimilates. Thus, to take the stock German example of the child brought up in a house where there are no tables but square ones, 'table' means for him a thing in which square corners are essential. But, if he goes to a house where there are round tables and still calls them tables, his apperceiving notion * table ' acquires immediately a wider inward content. In this way, our conceptions are constantly dropping characters once supposed essential, and including others once supposed inadmissible. The exten- sion of the notion beast ' to porpoises and whales, of the notion ' organism ' to society, are familiar examples of what I mean. But be our conceptions adequate or inadequate, and be our stock of them large or small, they are all we have to work with. If an educated man is, 166 TALKS TO TEACHERS as I said, a group of organized tendencies to con- duct, what prompts the conduct is in every case the man's conception of the way in which to name and classify the actual emergency. The more adequate the stock of ideas, the more 'able' is the man, the more uniformly appropriate is his be- havior likely to be. When later we take up the subject of the will, we shall see that the essential preliminary to every decision is the finding of the right names under which to class the proposed alternatives of conduct. He who has few names is in so far forth an incompetent deliberator. The names and each name stands for a conception or idea are our instruments for handling our problems and solving our dilemmas. Now, when we think of this, we are too apt to forget an im- portant fact, which is that in most human beings the stock of names and concepts is mostly ac- quired during the years of adolescence and the earliest years of adult life. I probably shocked you a moment ago by saying that most men begin to be old fogies at the age of twenty-five. It is true that a grown-up adult keeps gaining well into middle age a great knowledge of details, and a great acquaintance with individual cases con- nected with his profession or business life. In OLD FOGYISM SETS IN EARLY 167 this sense, his conceptions increase during a very long period ; for his knowledge grows more exten- sive and minute. But the larger categories of conception, the sorts of thing, and wider classes of relation between things, of which we take cog- nizance, are all got into the mind at a compara- tively youthful date. Few men ever do acquaint themselves with the principles of a new science after even twenty-five. If you do not study politi- cal economy in college, it is a thousand to one that its main conceptions will remain unknown to you through life. Similarly with biology, similarly with electricity. What percentage of persons now fifty years old have any definite conception whatever of a dynamo, or how the trolley-cars are made to run? Surely, a small fraction of one per cent. But the boys in colleges are all acquiring these conceptions. There is a sense of infinite potentiality in us all, when young, which makes some of us draw up lists of books we intend to read hereafter, and makes most of us think that we can easily ac- quaint ourselves with all sorts of tilings which we are now neglecting by studying them out hereafter in the intervals of leisure of our business lives. Such good intentions are hardly ever car- 168 TALKS TO TEACHERS ried out. The conceptions acquired before thirty remain usually the only ones we ever gain. Such exceptional cases of perpetually self-renovating youth as Mr. Gladstone's only prove, by the admiration they awaken, the universality of the rule. And it may well solemnize a teacher, and confirm in him a healthy sense of the importance of his mission, to feel how exclusively dependent upon his present ministrations in the way of im- parting conceptions the pupil's future life is prob- ably bound to be. XV. THE WILL SINCE mentality terminates naturally in out- ward conduct, the final chapter in psychology has to be the chapter on the will. But the word ' will ' can be used in a broader and in a narrower sense. In the broader sense, it designates our entire capacity for impulsive and active life, including our instinctive reactions and those forms of behavior that have become secondarily automatic and semi-unconscious through frequent repetition. In the narrower sense, acts of will are such acts only as cannot be inattentively per- formed. A distinct idea of what they are, and a deliberate fiat on the mind's part, must precede their execution7~~ Such acts are often characterized by hesitation, and accompanied by a feeling, altogether peculiar, of resolve, a feeling which may or may not carry with it a further feeling of effort. In my earlier talks, I said so much of our impulsive tendencies that I will restrict myself in what follows to voli- tion hi this narrower sense of the term. 170 TALKS TO TEACHERS ^ VJC>Ci.*Trv *M,tv '** . "_/ H.lio^- r< All our deeds were considered by the early psychologists to be due to a peculiar faculty called the will, without whose fiat action could not occur. Thoughts and impressions, being intrinsi- cally inactive, were supposed to produce conduct only through the intermediation of this superior agent. Until they twitched its coat-tails, so to speak, no outward behavior could occur. This doctrine was long ago exploded by the discovery of the phenomena of reflex action, in which sen- ^ sible impressions, as you know, produce movement immediately and of themselves. The doctrine may also be considered exploded as far as ideas The fact is that there is no sort of consciousness whatever, be it sensation, feeling, or idea, which does not directly and of itself tend to discharge into some motor effect. The motor effect need always be an outward stroke of behavior. It may be only an alteration of the heart-beats or breathing, or a modification in the distribution of blood, such as blushing or turning pale ; or else a secretion of tears, or what not. But, in any case, it is there in some shape when any consciousness is there ; and a belief as fundamental as any in modern psychology is the belief at last attained IDEOMOTOE ACTION 171 that conscious processes of any sort, conscious processes merely as such, must pass over into motion, open or concealed. The least complicated case of this tendency is the case of a mind possessed by only a single idea. If that idea be of an object connected with a native impulse, the impulse will immediately pro- ceed to discharge. If it be the idea of a move- ment, the movement will occur. Such a case of action from a single idea has been distinguished, . from more complex cases by the name of ideo- r J motor* action, meaning action without express decision or effort. Most of the habitual actions to which we are trained are of this ideo-motor ~D ?j* sort. We perceive, for instance, that the door is open, and we rise and shut it; we perceive some raisins in a dish before us, and extend our hand and carry one of them to our mouth without in- terrupting the conversation; or, when lying in bed, we suddenly think that we shall be late for breakfast, and instantly we get up with no par- ticular exertion or resolve. All the ingrained procedures by which life is carried on the man- ners and customs, dressing and undressing, acts of salutation, etc. are executed in this semi-auto- matic way unhesitatingly and efficiently, the very 172 TALKS TO TEACHERS outermost margin of consciousness seeming to be concerned in them, while the focus may be occu- pied with widely different things. But now turn to a more complicated case. Suppose two thoughts to be hi the mind together, of which one, A, taken alone, would discharge itself hi a certain action, but of which the other, B, suggests an action of a different sort, or a consequence of the first action calculated to make us slirink. The psychologists now say that the second idea, B, will probably arrest or inhibit the motor effects of the first idea, A. One word, then, about 'inhibition' in general, to make this particular case more clear. One of the most interesting discoveries of physi- ology was the discovery, made simultaneously hi France and Germany fifty years ago, that nerve currents do not only start muscles into action, but may check action already going on or keep it from occurring as it otherwise might. Nerves of arrest were thus distinguished alongside of motor nerves. The pneumogastric nerve, for example, if stimu- lated, arrests the movements of the heart: the splanchnic nerve arrests those of the intestines, if already begun. But it soon appeared that this THE FUNCTION OF INHIBITION 173 was too narrow a way of looking at the matter, and that arrest is not so much the specific function of certain nerves as a general function which any part of the nervous system may exert upon parts under the appropriate conditions. The higher centres, for example, seem to exert a con- stant inhibitive influence on the excitability of those below. The reflexes of an animal with its hemispheres wholly or hi part removed become exaggerated. You all know that common reflex in dogs, whereby, if you scratch the animal's side, the corresponding hind leg will begin to make scratching movements, usually in the air. Now in dogs with mutilated hemispheres this scratch- ing reflex is so incessant that, as Goltz first de- scribed them, the hair gets all worn off their sides. In idiots, the functions of the hemispheres being largely in abeyance, the lower impulses, not inhibited, as they would be in normal beings, often express themselves in most odious ways. You know also how any higher emotional tendency will quench a lower one. Fear arrests appetite, maternal love annuls fear, respect checks sensuality, and the like ; and in the more subtile manifestations of the moral life, whenever an ideal stirring is suddenly quickened into inten- 174 TALKS TO TEACHERS sity, it is as if the whole scale of values of our motives changed its equilibrium. The force of old temptations vanishes, and what a moment ago was impossible is now not only possible, but easy, because of their inhibition. This has been well called the * expulsive power of the higher emotion.* It is easy to apply this notion of inhibition to the case of our ideational processes. I am lying in bed, for example, and think it is time to get up ; but alongside of this thought there is present to my mind a realization of the extreme coldness of the morning and the pleasantness of the warm bed. In such a situation the motor consequences of the first idea are blocked ; and I may remain for half an hour or more with the two ideas oscillat- ing before me in a kind of deadlock, which is what we call the state of hesitation or delibera- tion. In a case like this the deliberation can be resolved and the decision reached in either of two ways : (1) I may forget for a moment the thermomet- ric conditions, and then the idea of getting up will immediately discharge into act: I shall sud- denly find that I have got up or (2) Still mindful of the freezing temperature, ANY IDEA MAY BE INHIBITORY 175 the thought of the duty of rising may become so pungent that it determines action in spite of in- hibition. In the latter case, I have a sense of energetic moral effort, and consider that I have done a virtuous act. All cases of wilful action properly so called, of choice after hesitation and deliberation, may be conceived after one of these latter patterns. So you see that volition, in the narrower sense, takes place only when there are a number of conflicting systems of ideas, and depends on our having a complex field of consciousness. The interesting thing to note is the extreme delicacy of the inhibi- tive machinery, A strong and urgent motor idea K "~~~ in the focus may be neutralized and made inopera-^ tive by the presence of the very faintest contradic-*~T - tory idea in the margin. For instance, I hold oufr*-^ my forefinger, and with closed eyes try to realize ^k^ *- as vividly as possible that I hold a revolver hi my hand and am pulling the trigger. I can even now fairly feel my finger quivering with the tendency to contract ; and, if it were hitched to a recording apparatus, it would certainly betray its state of tension by registering incipient movements. Yet it does not actually crook, and the movement of pulling the trigger is not performed. Why not? 176 TALKS TO TEACHERS Simply because, all concentrated though I am upon the idea of the movement, I nevertheless also realize the total conditions of the experiment, and in the back of my mind, so to speak, or in its fringe and margin, have the simultaneous idea that the movement is not to take place. The mere presence of that marginal intention, without effort, urgency, or emphasis, or any special rein- forcement from my attention, suffices to the in- hibitive effect And this is why so few of the ideas that flit through our minds do, in point of fact, produce their motor consequences. Life would be a curse and a care for us if every fleeting fancy were to do so. Abstractly, the law of ideo-motor action is true ; but in the concrete our fields of con- sciousness are always so complex that the inhibit- ing margin keeps the centre inoperative most of the time. In all this, you see, I speak as if ideas by their mere presence or absence determined be- havior, and as if between the ideas themselves on the one hand and the conduct on the other there were no room for any third intermediate principle of activity, like that called * the will.' MAN'S CONDUCT AS A RESULTANT 177 If you are struck by the materialistic or fatal- istic doctrines which seem to follow this concep- tion, I beg you to suspend your judgment for a moment, as I shall soon have something more to say about the matter. But, meanwhile yielding one's self to the mechanical conception of the psychophysical organism, nothing is easier than to indulge in a picture of the fatalistic character of human life. Man's conduct appears as mere resultant of all his various impulsions and ' inhibitions. One object, by its presence, makes us act: another object checks our action. Feel- ings aroused and ideas suggested by objects sway us one way and another: emotions complicate the game by their mutual inhibitive effects, the higher abolishing the lower or perhaps being it- self swept away. The life hi all this becomes pru- dential and moral; but the psychologic agents in the drama may be described, you see, as nothing but the 'ideas' themselves, ideas for the whole system of which what we call the ' soul ' or * char- acter ' or will ' of the person is nothing but a collective name. As Hume said, the ideas are themselves the actors, the stage, the theatre, the spectators, and the play. This is the so-called as- sociationist' psychology, brought down to its rad- 178 TALKS TO TEACHERS ical expression: it is useless to ignore its power as a conception. Like all conceptions, when they become clear and lively enough, this conception has a strong tendency to impose itself upon be- lief; and psychologists trained on biological lines usually adopt it as the last word of science on the subject. No one can have an adequate notion of modern psychological theory unless he has at some time apprehended this view in the full force of its simplicity. Let us humor it for a while, for it has advan- tages in the way of exposition. Voluntary action, then, is at all times a resultant of the compounding of our impulsions with our inhi- bitions. From this it immediately follows that there will be two types of will, in one of which impulsions will predominate, in the other inhibitions. We , may speak of them, if you like, as the precipitate ^vxU* ^vxU*i6 and the obstructed will, respectively. When fully pronounced, they are familiar to everybody. The extreme example of the precipitate will is the maniac : his ideas discharge into action so rap- ... , . idly, his associative processes are so extravagantly lively, that inhibitions have no time to arrive, and THE TWO EXTKEME TYPES OF WILL 179 he says and does whatever pops into his head without a moment of hesitation. Certain melancholiacs furnish the extreme ex-< u ample of the over-inhibited type. Their minds ^ u/ *-* t are cramped in a fixed emotion of fear or helpless- ness, their ideas confined to the one thought that for them life is impossible. So they show a con- dition of perfect ' abulia,' or inability to will or act. They cannot change their posture or speech or execute the simplest command. The different races of men show different tem- peraments in this regard. The Southern races'" "**""* are commonly accounted the more impulsive and precipitate : the English race, especially our New^ England branch of it, is supposed to be all sicklied over with repressive forms of self-consciousness, and condemned to express itself through a jungle of scruples and checks. The highest form of character, however, ab- stractly considered, must be full of scruples and inhibitions. But action, in such a character, far from being paralyzed, will succeed in energet- ically keeping on its way, sometimes overpowering the resistances, sometimes steering along the line where they lie thinnest. Just as our extensor muscles act most truly when 180 TALKS TO TEACHERS a simultaneous contraction of the flexors guides and steadies them ; so the mind of him whose fields of consciousness are complex, and who, with the ^ * reasons for the action, sees the reasons against it, and yet, instead of being palsied, acts in the way