:^r*::V^h-t: lifHli-f! For ive are not children of the bond-woman , but oj the free, E pur se muove. OUTLINES 0' CRITICAL THEORY OF ETHICS BY JOHN DEWEY Professor of Philosophy in the University of Michigari '<^^i ANN ARBOR, MICHIGAN REGISTER PUBLISHING COMPANY Ube 1InIan^ press Copyright, 1891. Register PubliIShing Co.. Ann Arbor, Mich. CONTENTS. Introduction 1-12 PART I.— FUNDAMENTAL ETHICAL NO- TIONS. ChaptePw I.—The Good 13-138 Hedonism 14 Utilitarianism 52 Evolutionary Utilitarianism 67 Kantianism 78 Problem and Solution 95 Realization of Individuality 97 Ethical Postulate 127 Chapter 11.— The Idea of Obligation 139-158 Bain's Theory 140 Spencer's Theory 142 Kant's Theory 147 Its Real Nature 152 Chapter 111.— The Idea of Freedom 158-166 Negative Freedom 158 Potential Freedom 159 Positive Freedom 164 PART IL — THE ETHICAL WORLD. Social Relations 167 Moral Institutions 169 yi PAKT III.— THE MORAL LIFE OF THE INDIVIDUAL. Division of Subject 181 Chapter l. — The Formation and Growth of Ideals 182-211 ' Conscience 182 Conscientiousness 199 Development of Ideals 206 Chapter 11.— The Moral Struggle or the Real- izing of Ideals 211-227 Goodness as Struggle 211 Badness 214 Goodness and Badness 221 Chapter 111— Realized Morality or the Vir- tues 227-233 Cardinal Virtues 231 Conclusion 233-238 PREFACE. Although the following pages have taken shape in connection with class-room work, they are in- tended as an independent contribution to ethical science. It is commonly demanded of such a work that its readers shall have some prefatory hint of its sources and deviations. In accordance with this custom, I may state that for the backbone of the theory here presented — the conception of the will as the expression of ideas, and of social ideas; the notion of an objective ethical world realized in institutions which afford moral ideals, theatre and impetus to the individual; the notion of the moral life as growth in freedom, as the individual finds and conforms to the law of his social placing — for this backbone I am especially indebted to Green's ' Prolegomena to Ethics ', to Mi\ Bradley's ' Ethical Studies ', to Professor Caird's ' Social Philosophy of Comte ' and ' Critical Philosophy of Kant ' (to this latter book in particular my indebtedness is funda- mental), and to Alexander's ' Moral Order and Pro- gress '. Although I have not been able to adopt the stand- point or the method of Mr. Spencer, or of Mr. Leslie Stephen my obligation to the ' Data of Ethics ' and to the ' Science of Ethics ' (especially to the latter) is large. As to the specific forms which give a flesh and blood of its own to this backbone, I may call atten- Vlll tionto the idea of desire as the ideal activity in con- trast with actual possession; to the analysis of indi- viduality into function including capacity and envi- ronment ; to the treatment of the social bearings of science and art (a point concerning which I am indebted to my friend, Mr. Franklin Ford) ; to the statement of an ethical postulate; to the accounts of obligation, of moral rules, and of moral badness. While the book is an analysis, in outline, of the main elements of the theory of ethics rather than a discussion of all possible detailed questions, it will not be found the less fitted, I hope, to give a student an idea of the main methods and problems of contemporary ethics. Other teachers, indeed, may agree that a general outline is better than a blanket- mortgage spread over and forestalling all the activity of the student's mind. I have not been unmindful of the advisability of avoiding in presentation both undue polemic, and undue dogmatism without sufficient reference to the statements of others. I hope the method hit upon, of comparing opposite one-sided views with the aim of discovering a theory apparently more adequate, will help keep the balance. I have quoted freely from the chief modern authorities, hoping that the tastes here given will tempt the reader to the banquet waiting in the authors themselves. The occasional references introduced are not bibliographical, nor intended as exhaustive statements of authorities consulted; they are meant as aids to an intelligent reading on the part of the general student. For this reason they are confined mainly to modern English writings. INTRODUCTION. I. Definition The term ethics is derived from a of Greek word meaning manners, cus- Ethlcs. toms, habits, just as the term morals is derived from a Latin word with a similar mean- ing. This suggests the character of the science as an account of human action. Anthropology, eth- nology, psychology, are also, in their way, accounts of human action. But these latter branches of knowledge simply describe, while the business of/ ethics is to judge. I This does not mean that it belongs to ethics to prescribe what man ought to do; but that its busi- ness is to detect the element of obligation in cop.- duct, to examine conduct to see what gives it its worthy. Anthropology, etc., do not take into account the whole of action, but simply some of its aspects — either external or internal. Ethics deals with conduct in its entirety, with reference, that is, to what makes it conduct, its end, its real meaning. Ethics is the science of conduct, understanding by conduct man's activity in its whole reach. Three of the branches of philosophy may be called normative, implying that they deal with some norm. standard or end, estimating the value of their respect- ive subject-matters as tested by this end. These are Logic, dealing with the end Truth, and the value of intellectual processes with respect to it; Esthetics, dealing with Beaut.y and the value of emotional con- ditions as referred to it; and Ethics, as defined above. But this norm in no case comes from outside the sub- ject-matter; it is the subject-matter considered in its totality. II. Meaning In its widest sense, the term moral or of ethical means nothing more than relating Moral, to conduct; having to do with practice, when we look at conduct or practice from the point of view not of its occurrence, but of its value. Action is something which takes place, and as such it may be described like any objective fact. But action has also relation to an end, and so considered it is moral. The first step in ethics is to fix firmly in mind the idea that the term moral does not mean any special or peculiar kind of conduct, but simply means practice and action, conduct viewed not partially, but in connection with the end which it realizes. It should be noted that the term moral has a wider and a narrower sense. In the wider sense it means action in the moral sphere, as opposed to non-moY^\ and thus includes both good and bad conduct. In the narrower sense it means moral, as opposed to im- moral. See Bradley, Ethical Studies, p. 53, note, for a further meaning. III. Meaning Ethics then has to do with conduct or of action viewed completely, or in relation Conduct. tp_Jts end. But what is conduct? It must be distinguished from action in general; for any process of change, the working of a pump, the growth of a plant, the barking of a dog, may be called action. Conduct implies more than some- thing taking place; it implies purpose, motive, intention; that the agent knows what he is about, that he has something which he is aiming at. All action accomplishes something or brings about results, but conduct has the result in vieiv. It occurs for the sake of producing this result. Con- duct does not simply, like action in general, have a cause, but also a reason, and the reason is present to the mind of the agent. There can be conduct only when there is a being who can propose to him- self, as an end to be reached by himself, something which he regards as worth while. Such a being is a moral agent, and his action, when conscious, is conduct. IV. D vision The main ethical problem is just this: of What is the conduct that really deserves Ethics, the name of conduct, the conduct of which all other kinds of action can be only a per- verted or deflected form ? I Or, since it is the end I which gives action its moral value, what is the true end, summum honum of man ?] Knowing this, we have a standard by which we judge particular •acts.) Those which embody this end are right, others wrong. The question of the Tightness of •conduct is simply a special form of the , question concerning the nature of the end or good. ) IBut the end bears another relation to specific acts. They are not only marked ofP by it as right or wrong, but they have to fulfill it. The end or good decides what should be or 02ight to be. Any act necessary to fulfill the end is a duty. Our second inquiry will be as to the nature of obligation or duty. Then we have to discuss the nature of a being who is capable of action, of manifesting and realizing the end ; capable of right (or wrong ) of obligatory and good action, pi^his will leacj us to discuss the question of Freedom, or Moral Capacity and its Realization. The discussion of these three abstract questions will constitute Part I of our theory ; Part II will take up the various forms and institutions in which the good is objectively realized, the fam- ily, state, etc. ; while Part III will be devoted to an account of the moral experience of the individual. V. The Motive Before taking up the first problem in presented, the nature of the good or Conduct, the end of conduct, it is necessary to analyze somewhat further the various sides and factors of conduct in order to see where the dis- tinctly ethical element is to be found. The ele- ments particularly deserving consideration are (1) / the Motive; (2) the Feelings or Sentiments; (3) Consequences of the Act; (4) Character of Agent. We shall begin with 1. The Motive. The motive of the act is the end aimed at by the agent in performing the act. Thus the motive of Julius Csesar in crossing the Rubicon was the whole series of results which he intended to reach by that act of his. The motive of a person in coming to college is to gain knowl- edge, to prepare himself for a certain profession. The motive is thus identical with the ideal element of the action, the purpose in view. 2. The Feelings or Disposition. Some writers speak of the feelings under which the agent acts as his motive. Thus we may suppose Julius Caesar ' moved ' by the feelings of ambition, of revenge, etc., in crossing the Rubicon. The student may be ' moved ' by curiosity, by vainglory, by emulation, by conscience, in coming to college. It is better, however, to regard the motive as the reason for which the act is performed, and to use the term moving or impelling cause for the feelings in their relation to action. Thus we may imagine a parent asking a child why he struck a playmate, meaning 6 what was the motive of the action. If the child should reply that he struck his playmate because he was angry, this answer would give the moving cause or impelling force of the action, but not its motive. The motive would be the idea of punish- ing this playmate, of getting even with him, of taking something away from him. The motive is the end which he desired to reach by striking and on account of which he struck. This is implied by the fact that the parent would ask, " What made you angry f^^ VI. Moral Bearing It is the feelings which supply of These the impelling force to action. Distinctions. They may be termed, collectively, the natural disposition. The natural disposition in itself has no moral value. This has been well illustrated by Bentham. Principles of Morals and Legislation, pp. 49-55. Bentham here uses the term 'motive' to designate what we have called the moving cause. We may select of the many examples which he gives that of curiosity. We may imagine a boy spinning a top, reading a useful book and letting a wild ox loose in a road. Now curiosity may be the ' motive ' of each of these acts, yet the first act would generally be called morally indifferent, the second good, the third abominable. What we mean by the ' natural ' feelings, then, is the feelings considered in abstraction from activity. Benevolence, as a mere feeling, has no higher moral value than malevolence. But if it is directed upon action it gets a value at once; let the end, the act, be right, and benevolence becomes a name for a moral disposition — a tendency to act in the due way. Nothing is more important than to distinguish between mere sentiments, and feeling as an element in conduct. VII. Relation Do the consequences of an act of have anything to do with its mo- Consequences rality? We may say no, pointing and to the fact that a man who does his Conduct. best we call good, although the consequences of his act may be far from good. We say his purpose in acting was right, and using as he did all the knowledge that he had, he is not to be blamed for its bad consequences. On the other hand, it is evident that we do take into ac- count consequences in estimating the moral value of an act. Suppose, to use one of Bentham's exam- ples, a person were about to shoot an animal but foresaw that in doing so there was a strong proba- bility that he would also wound some bystander. If he shot and the spectator were wounded, should we not hold the agent morally responsible ? Are there not multitudes of intended acts of which we say that we cannot tell whether they are good or bad until we know how they are likely to turn out? The solution of the difficulty is in recognizing the ambiguity of the term ' consequences '. It may mean the whole outcome of the act. When I speak, I set in motion the air, and its vibrations have, in turn, long chains of effects. Whatever I do must have an endless succession of ' consequences ' of which I can know but very little; just so far as, in any act, I am ignorant of the conditions under which it is performed, so far I am ignorant of its consequences. Such consequences are wholly irrelevant morally. They have no more to do with the morality of the act than has the fact that the earth is revolving while the act is taking place. I But we may mean by consequences the foreseen consequences of an act. Just in the degree that any consequence is considered likely to r^ult from an act, just in that degree it gets moral value, for it becomes part of the act itself. The reason that in many cases we cannot judge of the morality of an intended act until we can judge its probable results, is that until we know of these results the action is a mere abstraction, having no content at all. The conceived results constitute the content of 9 the act to be performed. They are not merely rele- vant to its morality, but are its moral quality. The question is whether any consequence is foreseen, conceived, or not. The foreseen, the ideal conse- quences are the end of the act, and as such form the motive. See on Sections 6 and 7, Alexander, Moral Order and Progress, pp. 36-46; on Section 7, Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, pp. 317-323. VIII. Character We have seen that the moral senti- and ments, or the moral disposition (dis- Conduct, tinguished from the feelings as passing emotions), on one side, and the consequences as ideal or conceived (distinguished from the con- sequences that, de facto, result), on the other, both have moral value. If we take the moral feelings, not one by one, but as a whole, as an attitude of the agent toward conduct, as expressing the kind of motives which upon the whole moves him to action, we have character. ■> And just so, if we take the consequences willed, not one by one, but as a whole, as the kind of end which the agent endeav- ors to realize, we have conduct. Character and conduct are, morally, the same thing, looked at first inwardly and then outwardly. Character, except as manifest in conduct, is a barren ideality. Our moral judgments are always severe upon a man 10 who has nothing to show but ' good intentions ' never executed. This is what character comes to, apart fi'om conduct. Our only way of telling the nature of character is the conduct that issues from it. But, on the other hand, conduct is mere outward formalism, excepting as it manifests character. To say that a man's conduct is good, unless it is the manifestation of a good character, is to pass a judgment which is self- contradictory. See Alex;i!j(ler, Op. cit., pp. 4S-50 and }>. 39. From this point of view we are enabled to identify the two senses of motive already discussed — the ideal of action and the moving feelings. Apart from each other they are abstractions. Csesar's motive in crossing the Kubicon may have been ' ambition,' but this was not some bare feeling. It was a feeling of ambition produced in view of the contemplation of a certain end which he wished to reach. So a boy's motive in striking a playmate may be anger, but this means (if the act is any- thing more than one of blind physical reaction) an anger having its conscious cause and aim, and not some abstract feeling of anger in general. The feeling which has its nature made what it is by the conceived end, and the end which has ceased to be a bare abstract conception and become an interest, are all one with each other. Morality is then a matter pertaining to charac- 11 ter — to the feelings and inclinations as transformed by ends of action; and to conduct — to conceived ends transformed into act under the influence of emotions. But what kind of character, of conduct, is right or realizes its true end ? This brings us to our first problem. PART I. FUNDAMENTAL ETHICAL NOTIONS. Chapter I.— THE GOOD. IX. Subdivision We may recognize tliree main of types of theories regarding the good, Theories, of which the first two represent (we shall attempt to show) each respectively one side of the truth, while the third combines the one-sided truths of the other two. Of the first two theories one is^ abstract, because it tends to find the good-in the__ _mere cons equences of conduct ^ aside from chara cter. This is the he donis tic theory, which finds the good to be pleasure. This is either indi- vidualistic or universalistic according as it takes individual or general pleasure to be the good. The second type of t heories attempts to find the go od in the motive of conduct fi ipart f^'^Tn nnnsognanpfta even as -wiH^: it reduces the goodjto conformity to abstract morallaw. The best type of this 14 theory is the Kantian. We shall criticize these theories with a view to developing the factors necessary to a true moral theory. X. Hedonism. According to the strict hedonistic position, the pleasure resulting to the agent from his act is the end of conduct and is therefore the criterion of its morality. The position as usually taken involves, first, that pleasure is psychologically the sole motive to action; and, secondly, that the results of an act in the way of the pain or pleasure it produces are the only tests we have of the rightness of the act. It is said above that these two points are involved in the hedonistic position as usually taken. They are not necessarily involved. Siclgwick. (Methods of Ethics, Bk. I, ch. lY and Bk. ly, ch. I) holds that plea,am:g^js_not_tlie_object pf dft,sir^,OT_jaQtivja,.Qf_ action, huJL^thatJiappiiiess is the_moral_end and criteruin. On the other hand Hodgson (Theory of Practice, Vol. II, ch. II) holds that pleasure m-dy be the motive (in the sense of im- pelling force) but it is never the criterion of conduct. Kant adopts the psychology of hedonism regarding pleasure as the object of desire, but holds that on that very account no object of desire can be the standard of moral conduct. A good statement of strict individualistic hedon- ism is the following from Barratt, Physical Ethics, page 71: "If man aims at pleasure merely by the physical law of action, that pleasure must evidently be ultimately his own, and whether it be or not preceded 15 by phenomena which he calls the pain and pleasure of others, is a question not of principle but of detail, just as the force of a pound weight is unaltered whether it be composed of lead or of feathers, or whether it act directly or through pulleys." XI. The Hedonistic Hedonism holds that pleasure Position is both the natural end and the Sup po rted . proper criterion of action : The following quotation from Bentham (Princi- ples of Morals and Legislation, Works, Vol. 1, p. 1) gives a statement of both these elements. "Mature has placed man under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, [i. e. they are criteria] as well as to determine what we shall do [motives], On the one hand, the standard of right or wrong [crite- rion]; on the other the chain of causes and effects [motives], are fastened to their throne." 1. Pleasure as Criterion. That the tendency of an action to produce pleasure is the standard for judging its moral value is generally held by the hedonists to be so axiomatic as to be beyond argument. See Bain, Moral Science, p. 27. " The ultimate data must be accepted as self-evident: they have no higher authority than that mankind generally are disposed to accept them. . . Now there can be no proof offered for the position that happiness is the proper end of all human pursuits, the criterion of all right conduct. It is an ultimate or final assumption to be tested by reference to the individual judgment of mankind." 8o Bentham, Enquiry I, II, "The principle is not / 16 susceptible of direct proofs for that which is used to prove everything else can not itself be proved; a chain of proofs must have their commencement some- where." Mill, Utilitarianism. (Dissertations and Discussions, pp. 348-349). " The only proof capable of being given that an object is visible is that people actually see it. In like manner the sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable is that people do actually desire it." See Stephen, Science of Ethics, p. 42; Spencer, Data of Ethics, pp. 30-32 and p. 46; Lotze, Practical Philosophy, pp. 18-19; Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 368-369. Hedonism, then, represents the good or the desirable and pleasixre to be two names for the same fact. What indeed can be worth while unless it be either enjoyable in itself or at least a means to enjoyment ? Would theft be considered bad if it resulted in pleasure or truth itself good if its universal effect were pain ? 2. Pleasure as object of desire. It is also urged that psychological analysis shows that pleas- ure is not only the desirable, but also always the desired. Desire for an object is only a short way of saying desire for the pleasure which that object may bring. To want food is to want the pleas- ure it brings; to want scientific ability is to desire to find satisfaction, or attain happiness. Thus it is laid down as a general principle that the inva- riable object of desire, ^nd motive of action is some pleasure to be attained; the action itself and the direct end of action being simply means to pleasure. 17 For a strong statement of this doctrine see Mill, Op. cit., pp. 354-5. "Desiring a thing and finding it pleasant, aversion to it and thinking of it as painful, are phenomena entirely inseparable, or rather two parts of the same phenomenon, — in strictness of lan- guage, two different modes of naming the same psy- chological fact; to think of an object as desirable and to think of it as pleasant are one and the same thing. See also, Bain, Emotions and Will, p. 436, Senses and Intellect, pp. 338-344; Sully, Outlines of Psychology, p. 575, " The inclination or tendency of the active mind towards what is pleasurable and away from what is painful is the essential fact in willing." Also pp. 576- 577. XII, Criticism. Pleasure Notl Taking up the points in reverse the End /order, we shall endeavor to show of Impulse/ first, that the motive of action, in the sense ©i end aimed at, is not pleasure. This point in itself, is, of course, rather psychological than ethical. Taking up then the psychology of pleasure in its connection with will, we shall discuss its relation to impulse, to desire and to motive. It is generally agreed that the raw material of volition is found in some form or other of the im- pulsive or instinctive actions. Such tendencies (e. g., the impulse for food, for drink, for unim- peded motion) clearly precede the reaching of an end, and hence the experience of any pleasure in the end. Our first actions, at least, are not for 2 18 pleasure; on the contrary, there is an activity for some independent end, and this end being reached there is pleasure in an act which has succeeded. This suggests as a possible principle that pleasure is not so much the end of action, as an element in the activity which reaches an end. What Aristotle says of another matter is certainly true of instinct- ive action. "It is not true of every characteristic function that its action is attended with pleasure, except indeed the pleasure of attaining its end J' See Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory, Vol. II, pp. 299-300; Sidgwick, Op. cit., pp. 38-45. XI 11. CriUc'ism— Continued. Pleasure Not ) It may, however, be said that, the End /hile our instinctive actions have of Desire/ another end than pleasure, this is not true of conscious desires — that, indeed, just the difference between instinct and desire is that the former goes blindly to its end, while the latter superimposes the thought of the pleasure to be reached upon the mere instinct. So we have to analyze the nature of desire. A child, led by impulse, has put a piece of sugar into his mouth, just as, under the same circum- stances, he would put a piece of stone into his mouth. But his action results in a state of pleas- ure wholly unforseen by him. Now the next time the child sees the sugar he will not merely have 19 the impulse to put it in his mouth. There will also be the remembrance of the pleasure enjoyed from sugar previously. There is consciousness of sugar as satisfying impulse and hence desire for it. 1. This is a description of an instance of desire. Does it bear us out in the doctrine that pleasure is the object of desire? It is possible that, in an irra- tional animal, the experience of eating food rein- forces the original instinct for it with associated images of pleasure. But even this is very different from a desire for pleasure. It is simply the pri- mordial instinct intensified and rendered more acute by new sensational factors joined to it. In the strict sense, there is still no desire, but only stronger impulse. Wherever there is desire there is not only a feeling of pleasure associated with other feelings (e. g., those of hunger, thirst), but there is the consciousness of an object in ivhich satisfaction is found. The error of the hedonistic psychology is in omitting one's consciousness of an object which satisfies. The hedonists are quite right in holding that the end of desire is not any object external to consciousness, but a condition of consciousness itself. The error begins in elim- inating all objective (that is, active) elements from consciousness, and declaring it to be a mere state of feeling or sensation. The practical conscious- ness, or will, cannot be reduced to mere feeling, 20 any more than the theoretical consciousness, or knowledge, can be so reduced. Even Mill, in its statement of the hedonistic psychology, does not succeed in making the object of desire mere pleasure as a state of feeling. Jt is the ''plea sant thing ^^ and not pleasu re alone which he finds equivalent to the desire. It is true enough that sugar as an external fact does not awaken desire, but it is equally true that a child does not want a passive pleasure. What he wants is his own activity in which he makes the sugar his own. And it should be remembered that the case of sugar is at once a trivial and an exceptional one. Not even children want simply sweat-meats; and the larger the character which finds expression in wants, the more does the direct object of want, the bread, the meat, become a mere element in a larger system of activity. What a man wants is to live, and he wants sweet- meats, amusements, etc., just as he wants substantial — on account of their value in life. Professor James compares the idea that pleasure is the end of desire to saying that " because no steamer can go to sea without incidentally consuming coal, . . . therefore no steamer can go to sea for any other motive than that of coal-consumption." Psychology, Vol. II, p. 558. See the entire passage, pp. 549-559. 2. But granting that an ' object ' and a ' pleas- ure ' are both necessary to desire, it may be argued 21 that the ' object ' is ultimately a means to ' pleas- ure.' This expressly raises a question already inci- dentally touched upon: What is the controlling element in desire ? Why is the object thought of as pleasant ? Simply because it is thought of as satisfying want. The hedonists, says Green (Pro- legomena to Ethics, p. 168), make the " mistake of supposing that a desire can be excited by the antic- ipation of its own satisfaction." This is to say, of course, that it exists before it exists, and thus brings itself into being. Green, Op. cit., p. 167, states the matter thus: '' Ordinary motives are interests in the attainment of objects, without which it seems to the man that he cannot satisfy himself, and in the attainment of which, because he has desired them, he will find a cer- tain pleasure, but only because he has previously de- sired them, not because pleasures are the objects des'.red." P>radley says on this same point (Ethical Studies, p. 230): " The difference is between my find- ing my pleasure in an end, and my finding means for the end of my pleasure, and the difference is enor- mous." Consult the entire passage, pp. 226-235. See also Caird, Critical Philosophy of Kant, Vol. II, p. 229. It is the object, then, which controls, and the pleasure is on account of the attaining of the desired object. But even this statement makes more division in desire than actually exists ; for 3. The real object of desire is activity itself. The will takes its rise, as we have seen, in impulse ; in the reaching for something to satisfy some felt 22 lack. Now, in reality, desire adds nothing to impulse excepting consciousness of the impulse. Volitional action does not difPer from impulsive or instinctive, except in bringing to consciousness the nature of the ivant and of the activity necessary to satisfy it. But this makes just the difPerence between ' natural ' or animal activity, and ' moral ' or human activity. To be conscious of the impulse is to elevate it from a blind impelling force to an intended or proposed end; and thus, by bringing it before consciousness, both to extend its range and to idealize it, spiritualize it. To be conscious of an impulse for food means to give up the unreasoned and momentary seizing of it; to consider the rela- tion of things to this want, what will satisfy it best, most easily, etc. The object of desire is not some- thing outside the action; it is an element in the enlarged action. And as we become more and more conscious of impulse for food, we analyze our action into more and more ' objects ' of desire, but these objects never become anything apart from the action itself. They are simply its analyzed and defined content. Man wants activity still, but he knows better what activity means and includes. Thus, when we learn what the activity means, it changes its character. To the animal the activity wanted is simply that of eating the food, of realizing the momentary impulse. To man the 23 activity becomes enlarged to include the satisfaction of a whole life, and not of one life singly, but of the family, etc., connected with the single life. The material well-being of the family becomes one of the objects of desire into which the original impulse has grown. But we misinterpret, when we conceive of this well-being as an external object lying outside the action. It means simply one aspect of the fuller action. By like growing con- sciousness of the meaning of the impulse, produc- tion and exchange of commodities are organized. The impulse for food is extended to include a whole range of commercial activities. It is evident that this growing consciousness of the nature of an impulse, whereby we resolve it into manifold and comprehensive activities, also takes the impulse out of its isolation and brings it into connection with other impulses. We come to have not a series of disconnected impulses, but one all- inclusive activity in which various subordinate ac- tivities (or conscious impulses) are included. Thus, in the previous example, the impulse for food is united with the family impulse, and with the impulse for communication and intercourse with society generally. It is this growing unity with the whole range of man's action that is the * spiritualizing ' of the impulse — the natural and brutal impulse being just that which insists 24 upon itself irrespective of all other wants. The spiritualizing of the impulse is organizing it so that it becoms one factor in action. Thus we lit- erally come to 'eat to live', meaning by life not mere physical existence, but the whole possible sphere of active human relations. 4. Relation of activity to pleasure. We have seen that the ' object ' of desire in itself is a mere abstraction; that the real object is full activity itself. We are always after larger scope of movement, fuller income in order to get larger outgo. The * thing ' is always for the sake of doing ; is a part of the doing. The idea that anything less or other than life (movement, action, and doing), can satisfy man is as ridiculous when compared with the act- ual course of things in history, as it is false psy- chologically. Freedom is what we want, and free- dom means full unimpeded play of interests, that is, of conscious impulses (see Sec. 34 and 51). If the object is a mere abstraction apart from activity, much more is pleasure. Mere pleasure as an object is simply the extreme of passivity, of mere having, as against action or doing. It is possible to make pleasure to some degree the object of desire; this is just what the voluptuary does. But it is a commonplace that the voluptuary always defeats himself. He never gets satisfaction who identifies satisfaction with having pleasures. The reason is 25 •evident enough. Activity is what we want, and since pleasure comes from getting what we want, pleasure comes only with activity. To give up the activity, and attempt to get the pleasure is a contradiction in effect. Hence also the 'hedonistic paradox' — that in order to get pleasure we must aim at something else. There is an interesting reco;2:nition of this in Mill himself, (see his Autobiography, p. 142). And in his Utilitarianism, in discussing^ the feasibility of getting happiness, he shows (pp. 318-319) that the sources of happiness are an intelligent interest in surrounding things— objects of nature, achievements of art, inci- dents of history — and especially an unselfish devotion to others. Which is to say that man does not find sat- isfaction in pleasure as such at all, but only in ob- jective affairs— that is, in complete interpretation, in activity with a wide and full content. Further con- sideration of the end of desire and its relation to pleasure may be found in Green, Op. cit.,pp. 123-132; pp. 163-167. Bradley, Mind, Vol. XIII, p. 1, and Dewey, Psychology, pp. 360-365. XIV. Criticism— Continued. Character It now being admitted that the end and of desire is activity itself in which the Pleasu re. ' object ' and ' pleasure ' are simply fac- tors, what is the moving spring to action? What is it that arouses the mind to the larger activity? Most of the hedonists have confounded the two senses of motive already spoken of, and have held ^that because pleasure is the end of desirop th erefore 26 it is the moving spring of conduct (or more often that because it is the moving spring of conduct it therefore is the end of desire). Mr. Stephen (Science of Ethics, pp. 46-58), although classing himself as a hedonist, has brought out this confusion very clearly. Ordinary hedonism confounds, as he shows, the judgment of what is pleasant — the supposed end — with the pleasant judgment — the moving spring. (See also Bradley, Op. cit., pp. 232-236). It maybe ad- mitted that it is feeling which moves to action, but it is the present feeling which moves. If the feeling aimed at moves, it is only as through anticipation it becomes the present feeling. Now is this present feeling which moves ( 1 ) mere pleas- ure and (2 ) mere feeling at all ? This introduces us to the question of the relation of pleasure (and of feeling in general) to character. 1. If the existing state of consciousness — that which moves — were pure pleasure, why should there be any movement, any act at all ? The feel- ing which moves must be in so far complex: over against the pleasure felt in the anticipation of an end as satisfying, there must be pain felt in the contrasting unsatisfactory present condition. There must be tension between the anticipated or ideal action, and the actual or present (relative) non- action. And it is this tension, in which pain is just 27 as normal an element as pleasure, which moves. Desire is just this tension of an action which satis- fies, and yet is only ideal, against an actual posses- sion which, in contrast with the ideal action, is felt as incomplete action, or lack, and hence as unsatis- factory. 2. The question now comes as to the nature of this tension. We may call it ' feeling,' if we will, and say that feeling is the sole motive power to action. But there is no such thing as feeling at large, and the important thing, morally, is what kind of feeling moves. To take a mere abstraction like ' feeling ' for the source of action is, at root, the fallacy of hedonism. To raise the question, What is it that makes the feeling what it is, is to recognize that the feeling, taken concretely, is char- acter in a certain attitude. Stephen, who has insisted with great force that feeling is the sole 'motive' to action, has yet shown with equal cogency the moral uselessness of such a doctrine, when feeling is left undefined (Op. cit., p. 44). "The love of happiness must express the sole possible motive of Judas Iscariot and his master; it must ex- plain the conduct of Stylites on his column, of Tiberius at Capre^e, of A Kempis in his cell, and of kelson in the cockpit of the Victory. It must be equally good for saints, martyrs, heroes, cowards, debauchees, ascetics,, mystics, cynics, misers, prodigals, men, women, and babes in arms." Surely, this is only to say, in effect, that ' love of happiness ' is a pure bit of scholasticism,, an undefined entitv. 28 In a hedonistic argument (by Stanton Coit,Mind, Vol. XI, p. 349), the fallacy is seen in the following discussion. The story is told of Abraham Lincoln that he once passed an animal in distress by the side of the road, and that, after going by, he finally went back and got him out of the ditch. On being praised for his act, he replied that he did it on his own account, since he kept getting more uncomfort- able as he thought of the animal in distress. From this, it cannot be inferred that love of pleasure is at the basis of moral acts. The mere lumping off of feeling as the spring of conduct overlooks the only important thing morally — the fact that Lincoln felt pain at the thought of the animal unrelieved, and pleasure at the idea of its relief, just be- cause he was a man of compassionate character. It was not the feeling, but the character revealed in, and creative of, the feeling that was the real source of the act. To connect this with our previous account of de- sire (p. 26 ) : the important thing morally is that the nature of the tension between fact and idea — the actual state and the ideal activity — is an expression of character. What kind of activity does it take to satisfy a man? Does riding in a comfortable carriage, and following the course of his own re- flections exhaust his need of action ? or does his full activity require that note be taken of a suffering 29 animal ? It is the kind of character one is (that is, the kind of activity which satisfies and expresses one) which decides what pleasure shall be taken in an anticipated end, what feeling of lack or hin- drance (what pain) there shall be in the given state,^ and hence what the resulting tension, or desire, shall be. It is, therefore, character which moves to conduct. Mere wishing, the mere floating fancy of this or that thing as desirable, is not desire. To iva7it is an active projection of character; really and deeply to want is no surface and passing feeling; it is the stirring of character to its depths. There may be repressed activity; that is not, of itself, desire. There may be an image of larger activity; that is not, of itself, desire. But given the consciousness of a repressed activity in view of the perception of a possible larger action, and a man strives within himself to break his bonds and reach the new satis- faction. This striving within one's self, before the activity becomes overt, is the emotional antecedent of action. But this inward striving or tension, which constitutes desire, is so far from being mere emotion that it is character itself — character as it turns an inward or ideal advance into an outward, or real progress, into action. We may fall back on Aristotle's statement (page 38, of Peters' translation of his ethics): " The pleasure 30 or pain that accompanies an act must be regarded as a test of character. He who abstains from the pleasures of the body and rejoices in his abstinence is temperate, while he who is vexed at having to abstain is still pro- fligate. As Plato tells us, man needs to be so trained from youth up as to take pleasure and pain in the right objects.'' XV. Summary. The truth in hedonism is its convic- tion that the good, the end of man, is not to be found in any outward object, but only in what comes home to man in his own cons cious exp eri- ence. The error is in reducing this experience to mere having, to bare feelings or affections, elimi- nating the element of doing. It is this doing which satisfies man, and it is this which involves as its content (as knowledge of impulse, instead of blind impulse) objective and permanent ends. When Mill speaks of the end of desire as a " satis- fied life," (p. 317 of Utilitarianism) he carries our assent ; but to reduce this satisfied life to feelings of pleasure, and absence of pains, is to destroy the life and hence the satisfaction. As Mill recognizes, a life bounded by the agent's own feelings would be, as of course, a life " centred in his own mis- erable individuality." (Mill, p. 319). Such words have meaning only because they suggest the con- trast with activity in which are comprehended, as * ends ' or ' objects ' (that is, as part of its defined 31 content) things — art, science and industry — and persons (see Sees. 34 and 35). Here too we must 'back to Aristotle.' According to him the end of conduct is eudaimonia, success, wel- fare, satisfied life. But eudaimonia is found not in pleasure, but in the fulfillment of human powers and functions, in which fulfillment, since it is fulfillment pleasure is had. (Ethics, Bk. I, ch. 4-8). We now take up the question whether pleasure is a standard of right action, having finished the discussion concerning it as an end of desire. XVI. Pleasure The line of criticism on this point as the may be stated as follows: Pleasure Standard fails as a standard for the very reason of that it fails as a motive. Pleasure, Conduct, as conceived by the hedonist, is pas- sive, merely agreeable sensations, without any objec- tive and qualitative, (active) character. This being so, there is no permanent, fixed basis to which we may refer acts and by which we may judge them. A standard implies a single comprehensive end which unifies all acts and through connection with which each gets its moral value fixed. Only action can be a standard for acts. To reduce all acts to means to getting a mere state of feeling is the inevi- table consequence of hedonism. So reducing them is to deprive them of any standard of value. An end to serve as standard must be (1) a com- 32 prehensive end for all the acts of an individual, and (2) an end comprehending the activities of various individuals — a common good. 1. The moral end must be that for the sake of which all conduct occurs — the organizing principle of conduct — a totality, a system. If pleasure is the end it is because each detail of conduct gets its placing, its moral value through relation to pleas- ure, through the contribution it makes to pleasure. 2. The moral end must also include the ends of the various agents who make up society. It must be capable of constituting a social system out of the acts of various agents, as well as an individual system out of the various acts of one agent; or, more simply, the moral end must be not only the good for all the particular acts of an individual, but must be a common good — a good which in satis- fying one, satisfies others. Ail ethical theories would claim that the end proposed by them served these two purposes. We shall endeavor to show that the hedonistic theory, the doctrine that the pleasure is the good, is not capable of serving either of them. XVII. Pleasure 1. It does not unify character. In Not a the first place, the hedonistic theory Standard, makes an unreal and impossible sepa- ration between conduct and character. The psy- 33 chology of hedonism comes into conflict with its ethics. According to the former the motive of all action is to secure pleasure or avoid pain. So far as the motive is concerned, on this theory there can be no immoral action at all. That the agent should not be moved by pleasure, and by v^hat, at the time of acting, is the greatest pleasure pos- sible, would be a psychological impossibility. Every motive would be good, or rather there would be no distinction of good or bad pertaining to the motive. The character of the agent, as measured by his motives, could never, under such circum- stances, have any moral quality. To the consequences of action, or the conduct proper, however, the terms good and bad might be applied. Although the agent is moved by pleasura- ble feelings, the result of his action may be painful and thus bad. In a word, on the hedonistic theory, it is only the external consequences of conduct, or conduct divorced from character, to which moral adjectives have any application. Such a separation not only contradicts our experience (see VIII), but inverts the true order of moral judgment. Con- sequences do not enter into the moral estimate at all, except so far as, being foreseen, they are the act in idea. That is, it is only as the consequences are taken up into the motive, and thus related to character, that they are subject to moral judgment. 3 34 Indeed, except so far as action expresses character, it is not conduct, but mere physical sequence, as irrelevant to morality as the change in blood distri- bution, which also is the ' result ' of an action. Hedonism has to rule out at the start the only thing that gives totality to action — the character of the agent, or conduct as the outcome of motives. Furthermore, the ordinary judgment of men, instead of saying that the sole moral motive is to get pleasure, would say that to reduce everything to means for getting pleasure is the very essence of immorality. On the point above, compare Bentham, Op. cit., I, p. 48. " A motive is substantially nothing more than pleasure or pain operating in a certain manner. Isow pleasure is in itself a good: nay, even, setting aside immunity from pain, the only good; pain is in itself an evil, and, indeed, without exception, the only evil; or else the words good and evil have no meaning. And this is alike true of every sort of pain and of every sort of pleasure. It follows, therefore, immediately and incontestably, that there is no such thing as any sort of motive that is in itself a bad one. If motives are good or bad, it is only on account of their effects; good on account of their tendency to produce pleas- ure or avert pain; bad on account of their tendency to produce pain or avert pleasure. Now the case is, that from one and the same motive, and from every kind of motive, may proceed actions that are good, others that are bad and others that are indifferent." Further, on p. 60, Bentham asks: "Is there nothing, then, about a man that can properly be termed good or bad, when on such or such an occasion he suffers himself to be governed by such or such a motive ? Yes, cer- 35 tainly, his disposition. Now disposition is a kind of fictitious entity, feigned for the convenience of dis- course, in order to express what there is supposed to he permanent m 2i man's frame of mind. It is with disposition as with everything else; it will be good or bad according to its effects." The first quotation, it will be noticed, simply states that the motive is in itself always good, while conduct {i, e., consequences) may be good, bad or indifferent. The second quotation seems, however, to pass moral judgment upon charac- ter under the name of disposition. But disposition is judged according to the tendency of a person's actions. A good or bad disposition, here, can mean nothing intrinsic to the person, but only that the person has been observed to act in ways that usually produce pain or pleasure, as the case may be. The term is a * fiction', and is a backhanded way of expressing a somewhat habitual result of a given person's conduct his motive remaining good (or for pleasure) all the time. The agent would never pronounce any such judg- ment upon his own disposition, unless as a sort of suprise that, his motive being 'good,' his actions turn out so * bad ' all the time. At most, the judgment regarding disposition is a sort of label put upon a man by others, a label of "Look out for him, he is dan- gerous," or, " Behold, a helpful man." The moral standard of hedonism does not, then, bear any relation to the character of the agent, does not enable us to judge it, either as a whole or in any specific manifestation. XVIII. It Does Not Give a Pleasure, as the end, Criterion for fails also to throw light Concrete Acts. on the moral value of any specific acts. Its failure in this respect is, 36 indeed, only the other side of that just spoken of. There is no organizing principle, no ' univer- sal ' on the basis of which various acts fall into a system or order. The moral life is left a series of shreds and patches, where each act is torn off, as to its moral value, from every other. Each act is right or wrong, according as it gives pleasure or pain, and independently of any whole of life. There is, indeed, no whole of moral life at all, but only a series of isolated, disconnected acts. Possession, passivity, inere feeling, by its very nature cannot unite — each feeling is itself and that is the end of it. It is action which reduces multiplicity to unity. We cannot say, in the hedonistic theory, that pleas- ure is the end, but pleasures. Each act stands by itself — the only question is: "What pleasure will it give f The settling of this question is the "hedonistic calculus." We must discover the intensity, duration, certainty, degree of nearness of the pleasure likely to arise from the given act, and also its purity, or likelihood of being accompanied by secondary pains and pleasures. Then we are to strike the balance between the respective sums on the pleasure and pain sides, and, according as this balance is one of pleasure or pain, the act is good or evil. Bentham, Op. cit., p, 16, was the first to go into detail as to this method. He has also given certain memoriter verses stating "the points on which the whole fabric of morals and legislation may be seen to rest. Intense, long, certain, speedy, fruitful, pure. Such marks in pleasures and in pains endure, Such pleasures seek, if private be thy end. If it be public, wide let them extend. Such pains avoid whichever be thy vievr. If pains must come, let them extend to fevr." This, however, in its reference to others, states the utilitarian as well as the hedonistic vir^w. Now, it must be remembered that, if pleasure is the end, there is no intrinsic connection between the motive of th6 act, and its result. It is not claimed that there is anything belonging intrins- ically to the motive of the act which makes it result in pleasure or pain. To make such a claim would be to declare the moral quality of the act the cri- terion of the pleasure, instead of pleasure the criterion of the act. The pleasures are external to the act; they are irrelevant and accidental to its quality. There is no ' universal,' no intrinsic bond of connection between the act and its consequences. The consequence is a mere particular state of feel- ing, which, in this instance, the act has happened to bring about. More concretely, this act of truth-telling has in this instance, brought about pleasure. Shall we call it right? Right in this instance, of course; but is it right generally ? Is truth-telling, as such, 38 right, or is it merely that this instance of it hap- pens to be right? Evidently, on the hedonistic basis, we cannot get beyond the latter judgment. Prior to any act, there will be plenty of difficulties in telling whether it, s.^ particular, is right or wrong. The consequences depend not merely on the result intended, but upon a multitude of circumstances outside of the foresight and control of the agent. And there can be only a precarious calculation of possibilities and probabilities — a method which would always favor laxity of conduct in all but the the most conscientious of men, and which would throw the conscientious into uncertainty and per- plexity in the degree of their conscientiousness. "If once the pleas of instinct are to be abolished and replaced by a hedonistic arithmetic, the whole realm of animated nature h^ to be reckoned with in weaving the tissue of moral relations, and the problem becomes infinite and insoluble ".—Martineau, Op. cit.. Vol. II, p. 334. But waive this ; let the particular case be settled. There is still no law, no principle, indeed no presump- tion as to future conduct. The act is not right he- cause it is truth-telling, hnt because, in this instance, cicumstances were such as to throw a balance of pleasure in its favor. This establishes no certainty, no probability as to its next outcome. The result then will depend wholly upon circumstances exist- ing then — circumstances which have no intrinsic 39 relation to the act and which must change from time to time. The hedonist would escape this abolition of all principle, or even rule, by falling back upon -a number of cases — 'past experience' it is called. We have found in a number of cases that a certain procedure has resulted in pleasure, and this result is sufficient to guide us in a vast number of cases which confe up. Says Mill (Op. cit., pp. 332-4): "During the whole past duration of the species, mankind have been learn- ing by experience the tendencies of actions, on which experience all the prudence as well as all the morality of life are dependent Mankind must by this time have acquired positive belief as to the effects of some actions on theirhappiness; and the beliefs which have thus come down are the rules of morality for the multitude, and for the philosopher, until he has suc- ceeded in finding betted. .... Nobody argues that the art of navigation is not founded on astronomy, because sailors cannot wait'to calculate the 'Nautical Almanac'. Being rational creatures, they go to sea with it ready calculated; and all rational creatures go out upon the sea of life with their minds made up on the common questions of right and wrong, as well as on manvof the far more difficult questions of wise and foolish." That we do learn from experience the moral nature of actions is undoubted. The only ques- tion is : if hedonism were true, could we so learn ? Suppose that I were convinced that the results of murder in the past had been generally, or even 40 without exception (though this could not be proved), painful; as long as the act and the result in the way of feeling (pain or pleasure) are conceived as having no intrinsic connection, this would not prove that in the present instance murder will give a sur- plus of pain. I am not thinking of committing mur- der in general, but of murder under certain specific present circumstances. These circumstances may, and, to some extent, must vary from all previous in- stances of murder. How then can I reason from them to it? Or, rather, let me use the previous cases as much as I may, the moral quality of the act I am now to perform must still be judged not from them, but from the circumstances of the pres- ent case. To judge otherwise, is, on hedonistic principles, to be careless, perhaps criminally care- less as to one's conduct. The more convinced a man is of the truth of hedonism and the more conscien- tious he is, the more he is bound not to be guided by previous circumstances, but to form his judg- ment anew concerning the new case. This result flows out of the very nature of the hedonistic ideal. Pleasure is not an activity, but simply a particular feeling, enduring only while it is felt. Moreover, there is in it no principle which connects it intrin- sically with any kind of action. To suppose then that, because ninety- nine cases of murder have re- sulted in pain, the hundredth will, is on a par with 41 reasoning that because ninety-nine days have been frosty, the hundredth will be. Each case, taken as particular, must be decided wholly by itself. There is no continuous moral life, and no system of con- duct. There is only a succession of unlike acts. Mill, in his examiDation of AVhe well, (Diss, and Diss., Vol. Ill, pp. 158-59),tries to establish a general principle, if not a universal law, by arguing that, even in excep- tional cases, the agent is bound to respect the rule, because to act otherwise vrould weaken the rule, and thus lead to its beii^g disregarded in other cases, in which its observance results in pleasure. There are, he says, persons so wicked that their removal from the earth would undoubtedly increase the sum total of happiness. But if persons were to violate the general rule in these cases, it would tend to destroy the rule. "If it were thought allowable for any one to put to death at pleasure any human being whom he believes that the world would be well rid of,— nobody's life would be safe.'' That is to say, if every one were really to act upon and carry out the hedonistic princi- ple, no rule of life would exist. This does very well as a reductio ad ahsurdum of hedonism, or as an argu- ment against adopting hedonism, but it is difficult to see how Mill thought that it established a ' rule ' on a hedonistic basis. Mill's argument comes to saying that if hedonism were uniformly acted upon, it would defeat itself— that is, pleasure would not result. There- fore, in order to get pleasure, we must not act upon the principle of hedonism at all, but follow a general rule. Otherwise put: hedonism gives no general rule, but we must have a general rule to make hedonism works and therefore there is a general rule ! This begging of the question comes out even more plainly as Mill goes 42 on: "If one person may break through the rule on his own judgment, the same liberty cannot be refused to others; and, since no one could rely on the rule's being observed, the rule would cease to exist." All of this is obviously true, but it amounts to saying: " We must have a rule, and this we would not have if we carried out the hedonistic principle in each case; there- fore, we must not carry it out." A principle, that car- ried out destroj^s all rules which pretend to rest upon it, lays itself open to suspicion. Mill assumes the en- tire question in assuming that there is a rule. Grant this, and the necessity of not 'making exceptions,' that is, of not applying the hedonistic standard to each case, on its own merits, follows. But the argu- ment which Mill needs to meet is that hedonism requires us to apply the standard to each case in itself, and that, therefore, there is no rule. Mill simply says —assume the rule, and it follows, etc. See Bradley, Op. cit., pp. 96-101; Green, Bk. TV, Ch. 3; Martineau, Vol. II, pp. 329-334. XIX. The Sum We have been dealing with hedon- andthe ism in its strict form — that which Quality makes a pleasure, considered as to of its intensity, certainty, etc., the end Pleasure of an act. Hedonism in this form as the fails to unify life, and fails, there- Standard, fore, to supply any standard. But the end of conduct is often stated to be the greatest possible sum of pleasnres, thus introducing a cer- tain element of generality. Mill goes further and brings in the idea of quality of pleasure. 43 Regarding the sum of pleasures the following from Sidgwick (Op. cit. p. 382; see also p. 114) gives the hedonistic statement. "The assumption is involved that all pleasures are capable of being compared quali- tatively with one another and with all pains; that every feeling has a certain intensive quality, positive or negative (or perhaps zero) in respect to its desira- bleness and that the quantity may be known, so that each may be w^eighed in ethical scales against any other. This assumption is involved in the very motion of maximum happiness," as the attempt to make " as great as possible a sum of elements not quantitatively commensurable would be a mathematical absurdity." I. Sum of pleasures as the moral end. This, first, taken as criterion, comes into conflict with the, hedonistic psychology of pleasure as the motive of acts; and, secondly, it requires some objective standard by means of which pleasure is to be summed, and is, in so far, a surrender of the whole hedonistic position. 1. If the object of desire is pleasure or a state of feeling which exists only as it is felt, it is im- possible that we should desire a greatest sum of pleasures. We can desire a pleasure and that only. It is not even possible that we should ever desire a continuous series of pleasures. We can desire one pleasure and when that is gone, another, but we can not unify our desires enough to aim at even a sum of pleasures. This is well put by Green (Op. cit. p. 236). " For the feeling of a pleased person, or in relation to his- 44 sense of enjoyment, pleasure cannot form a sum. How- ever numerous the sources of a state of pleasant feel- ing", it is one and is over before another can be enjoyed. It and its successors can V)e added together in thought, but not in enjoyment or in imagination of an enjoyment. If the desire is only for pleasure, i. e., for an enjoyment or feeling of pleasure, we are sim- ply victims of words when we talk of desire for a sum of pleasures, much more when we take the greatest imaginable sum to be the most desirable." See the whole passage, pp. 235-246. 2. But the phrase "sum of pleasures'' undoubt- edly has a meaning — though the fact that it has a meaning shows the untruth of the hedonistic psy- chology. Surrendering this psychology, what shall we say of the maximum possibility of pleasure as the criterion of the morality of acts ? It must be con- ceded that this conception does afford some basis — although a rather slippery one — for the unification of conduct. Each act is considered now not in its isolation merely, but in its connection with other acts, according as its relation to them may increase or decrease the possible sum of future happiness. But this very fact that some universal, or element of relation, albeit a quantitative one, has been intro- duced, arouses this inquiry: Whence do we derive it ? JIow do we get the thought of a sum of pleasure, and of a maximum sum? Only by taking into account the objective conditions upon which pleas- ures depend^ and by judging the pleasures from the 45 standpoint of these objective conditions. When we imagine we are thinking of a sum of pleasures, we are really thinking of that totality of conditions which will come nearest affording ns self-satisfac- tion — we are thinking of a comprehensive and con- tinuous activity whose various parts are adjusted to one another. Because it is complete activity, it is necessarily conceived as giving the greatest possible pleasure, but apart from reference to complete activity and apart from the objects in which this is realized, the phrase ' greatest sum of happiness ' is a mere phrase. Pleasures must be measured by a standard, by a yard stick, before they can be sum- med in thought, and the yard stick we use is the activity in which the pleasure comes. We do not measure conduct by pleasure, but we compare and sum up pleasures on the basis of the objects which occasion them. To add feelings, mere transitory consequences, without first reducing those feelings to a common denominator by their relation to one objective standard, is an impossibility. Pleasure is a sort of sign or symbol of the object which satis- fies, and we may carry on our judgment, if we will, in terms of the sign,without reference to the stand- ard, but to argue as if the sign were the thing, as if the sum of pleasure were the activity, is suicidal. Thus Green says (Op. cit., p. 244): "In truth a man's reference to his own true happiness is a refer-^ 46 ence to the objects which chiefly interest him, and has its controlling power on that account. More strictly, it is a reference to an ideal state of well-being, a state in which he shall be satisfied; but the objects of the marl's chief interests supply the flUing of that ideal state." See the argument as put by Alexander (Moral Order and Progress, pp. 199-200). Alexander has also brought out (Ibid, pp. 207-210) that even if we are going to use a quantitative standard, the idea of a sum is not a very happy one. It is not so much a sum of pleasures we want, as a certain proportionate dis- tribution and combination of pleasures. " To regard the greatest sum of pleasures as the test of conduct, supposing that we could express it in units of pleas- ure, would be like declaring that when you had an atomic weight of 98 you had sulphuric acid. The numerical test would be useless unless we knew what elements were to be combined, and in Avhat pro- portion. Similarly till we know what kinds of activities (and therefore what kinds of pleasures) go with one another to form the end, the greatest sum of pleasures will give us only the equivalent of the end, but will not tell us w^hat the composition of the end is, still less how to get at it; or, to put the matter more simply, when we know what the characters of persons are, and how they are combined in morality, we then estimate the corresponding sum of pleasures." (p. 209.) II. A certain quality of pleasure the end. Some moralists, notably John Stuart Mill, introduce considerations regarding the quality of pleasure into the conception of the end. "It is quite com- patible," says Mill, " with the principle of utility to recognize the fact that some kinds of pleasure 47 are more desirable and more valuable than others." (p. 310.) Is it compatible? Is kind of pleasure the same thing as pleasure? does not strict hedon- ism demand that all kinds of pleasure equally pre- sent as to intensity in consciousness shall be of the same value ? To say otherwise is to give up pleasure as such as the standard and to hold that we have means for discriminating the respective values of pleasures which simply, as feelings, are the same. It is to hold, that is to say, that there is some standard of value external to the pleasures as such, by means of which their moral quality may be judged. In this case, this independent standard is the real moral criterion which we are employing. Hedonism is surrendered. Kant's position on this point seems impregnable. " It is surprising," he says," that men otherwise astute can think it possible to distinguish between higher and lower desires, according as the ideas which are connected with the feeling of pleasure have their ori- gin in the senses or in the understanding; for when we inquire what are the determining grounds of desire, and place them in some expected pleasantness, it is of no consequence whence the idea of this pleasing object is derived, but only how much it pleases The only thing that concerns one, in order to decide choice, is how great, how long continued, how easily obtained and how often repeated, this agreableness is For as to the man who wants money to spend, it is all the same whether the gold was dug out of the moun- tain or washed out of the sand, provided it is every- 48 where accepted at the same value; so the man who cares only for the enjoyment of life does not ask whether the ideas are of the understanding or the senses, but only how much and how great pleasure they will give for the longest time." See also Bradley, Op. cit,, pp. 105-110. When we ask how the diflFerences in quality are established and how we translate this qualitative difference into moral difference, the surrender of pleasure as the standard becomes even more evi- dent. We must know not only the fact of different qualities, but how to decide which is ' higher ' than any other. We must bring the qualities before a tribunal of judgment which applies to them some standard of measurement. In themselves qualities may be different, but they are not higher and lower. What is the tribunal and what is the law of judg- ment? According to Mill the tribunal is the pref- erence of those who are acquainted with both kinds of pleasure. " Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all. or almost all who have experience of both, give a decided preference, irrespective of any feellDo- of moral obli- gation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure." It is an unquestionable fact that such difierences exist. " Few liuinan creatures would con- sent to be changed into any of the lower animals for a promise of the fviilest allowance of a beast's pleasures. No intelligent person would consent to be a fool; no instructed person would be an ignoramus; no person of feeling and conscience would be selfish and base. 49 even though they should be persuaded that the fool, the dunce or the rascal is better satisfied with his lot than they are with theirs It is better to be a human being dissatisfied, than a pig satisfied; better to be a Socrates dissatisfied, than a fool satisfied. And if the fool or the pig are of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the ques- tion. The other party to the comparison knows both sides."— Mill, Op. cit., pp. 311-313. And in an omitted portion Mill says the reason that one of the higher faculty would prefer a suffering which goes along with that higher capacity, to more pleasure on a lower plane, is somethicg of which "the most appropriate appellation is a sense of dignity, which all human beings possess in one form or another." A question immediately arises regarding this standard of preferability. Is it the mere historical fact that some man, who has experienced both, pre- . fers A to B that makes A more desirable? Surely I might say that if that person prefers A, A is more desirable to him, but that I for my part prefer B, and that I do not intend to give up my preference. And why should I, even though thousands of other men happened to prefer A? B is the greater pleasure, none the less, to me, and as a hedonist I must cling to the only standard that I have. The hedonists, in a word, have appealed to feeling, and to feeling they must go for judgment. And feeling exists only as it is felt and only to him who feels it. On the other hand, perhaps it is not the bare act that some men prefer one pleasure to pother 4 50 that makes it more desirable, but something in the character of the men who prefer. And this is what Mill implies. It is a " sense of dignity " belonging to man which makes his judgment of pleasure better than that of animals; it is the human being against the pig, Socrates against the fool, the good man against the rascal. This is the complete surrender of hedonism, and the all but explicit assertion that human character, goodness, wisdom, are the criteria of pleasure, instead of pleasure the criterion of character and goodness. Mill's "sense of dignity," which is to be consid- ered in all estimates of pleasures, is just the sense , of a moral (or active) capacity and destiny belong- ing to man. To refer pleasures to this is to make it the standard, and with this standard the anti- hedonist may well be content, while asking, how- ever, for its further analysis. To sum up our long discussion of pleasure as a criterion of conduct in respect of its unity, we may say: Pleasure, as it actually exists in man, maybe taken as a criterion, although not the really primary one, of action. But this is not hedonism; for pleasure as it exists is something more than pleas- urable feeling; it is qualified through and through by the kind of action which it accompanies, by the kind of objects which the activity comprehends. And thus it is always a secondary criterion. The 51 moment we begin to analyze we must ask what kind of activity, what kind of object it is which the pleasure accompanies and of which it is a sym- bol. We may, if we will, calculate a man's wealth in terms of dollars and cents; but this is only because we can translate the money, the symbol, into goods, the reality. To desire pleasure' instead of an activity of self, is to substitute symbol for fact, and a symbol cut ofP from fact ceases to be a symbol. Pleasure, as the hedonist treats it, mere agreeable feeling without active and thus objective relationships, is wholly an abstrac- tion. Since an abstraction, to make it the end of desire results in self-contradiction; while to make it the standard of conduct is to deprive life of all unity, all system, in a word — of all standard. XX. The Failure of Thus far our examination of Pleasure as a the hedonistic criterion has been Standard devoted to showing that it will to Unify Con- not make a system out of indivi- duct Socially, dual conduct. We have now to recognize the fact that pleasure is not a common good, and therefore fails to give a social unity to conduct — that is, it does not offer an end for which men may cooperate, or a good which reached by one must be shared by another. No argument is needed to show, theoretically, that any proposed . 52 moral criterion must, in order to be valid, harmon- ize the interests and activities of difPerent men, or to show, practically, that the whole tendency of the modern democratic and philanthropic movement has been to discover and realize a good in which men shall share on the basis of an equal principle. It is contended that hedonism fails to satisfy these needs. According to it, the end for each man is his own pleasure. Pleasure is nothing objective in which men may equally participate. It is purely individual in the most exclusive sense of that term. It is a state of feeling and can be enjoyed only while felt, and only by the one who feels it. To set it up for tho ideal of conduct is to turn life into an exclusive and excluding struggle for possession of the means of personal enjoyment; it is to erect into a principle the idea of the war of all against all. No end more thoroughly disintegrating than indi- -vidual agreeable sensation could well be imagined. Says Kant, (pa^e 116 of Abbott's Trans., entitled Kant's Theory of Ethics) on the basis of the desire of happiness " there results a harmony like that which a certain satirical poem depicts as existing between a married couple bent on going to ruin: O, marvellous harmony, what he wishes, she wishes also; or like what is said of the pledge of Francis I to the emperor •Charles V, what my brother Charles wishes that I wish also {mz., Milan)." Almost all modern moralists who take pleas- ure as the end conceive it to be not individual 53 pleasure, but the happiness of all men or even of all sentient creatures. Thus we are brought to the consideration of Utilitarianism. Says Mill (Op. cit., p. 323), " The happiness which forms the Utilitarian standard of what is right in con- duct is not the agent's own happiness, but that of all concerned; as between his own happiness and that of others, Utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly- impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator." And (page 315) the Utilitarian standard is " not the agent's own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether." See also Sidgwick (Op. cit., p. 379), " By Utilitarianism is here meant the ethical theory, first distinctly formulated by Ben- tham, that the conduct which, under any given cir- cumstances is externally or objectively right is that which will produce the greatest amount of happiness on the whole; that is, taking into account all whose happiness is affected by the conduct. It would tend to clearness if we might call this principle, and the method based upon it, by some such name as Uni- versalistic hedonism." As popularly put, the utilita- rian standard is the " greatest happiness of the great- est number." While in its calculation "each is to count for one and only one." {Bentham). And finally Bain (Emotions and Mill, p. 303), " Utility is opposed to the selfish theory, for, as propounded, it always im- plies the good of society generally, and the subordina- tion of individual interests to the general good." XXI. Criticism of The utilitarian theory certainly Utilitarian- does away entirely with one of the ism. two main objections to hedonism — its failure to provide a general, as distinct from a 54 private end. The question which we have to meet, however, is whether this extension of the end from the individual to society is consistent with the fun- damental principles of hedonism. Hoid do we get from individual pleasure to the happiness of all? An intuitional utilitarian, like Sidgwick, has ready an answer which is not open to the empirical utilita- rians, like Bentliam, Mill and Bain, Methods of Eth- ics, Bk. Ill, ch. 13-14, p. 355. "We may obtain the self-evident principle that the good of any one individ- ual is of no more importance, as a part of universal good, than the good of any other. The abstract prin- ciple of the duty of benevolence, sq far as it is cogni- zable by direct intuition" is, "that one is morally bound to regard the good of any other individual as much as one's own" — and page 364, ''the principles, so far as they are immediately known by abstract in- tuition, can only be stated as precepts to seek (1) one's own good on the whole, and (2) the good of any other no less than one's own, in so far as it is no less an ele- ment of universal good." Sidgwick, that is, differs in two important points from most utilitarians. He holds that pleasure is not the sole, or even the usual object of desire. And he holds that we have an imme- diate faculty of rational intuition which informs us that the good of others is as desirable an end of our conductas is our own happiness. Our former arguments against pleasure as the end, bear, of course, equally against this theory, but not the following arguments. Criticisms of this position of Sidgwick's will be found in Green (Op. cit., pp. 406-415); Bradley (Op. cit,, pp. 114-117). The popular answer to the question how we get from individual to general happiness, misses the 55 entire point of the question. This answer simply says that happiness is ^intrinsically desirable'. Let it be so ; but ' happiness ' in this general way is a mere abstraction. Happiness is always a partic- ular condition of one particular person. Whose happiness is desirable and to ivhom f Because my happiness is intrinsically desirable to me, does it follow that your happiness is intrinsically desirable to me ? Indeed, in the hedonistic psychology, is it not nonsense to say that a state of your feeding is desirable to me? Mill's amplified version of the popular answer brings out the ambiguity all the more plainly. He says (Utilitarianism, p. 349), "No reason can be given why the general happi- ness is desirable, except that each person, so far as he believes it to be obtainable, desires his own hap- piness. This, however, being a fact, we have not only all the proof which the case admits of, but all which it is possible to require, that happiness is a good; that each person's happiness is a good to that person; and the general happiness, therefore, a good to the aggregate of all persons." But does it follow that because the happiness of A is an end to A, the happiness of B an end to B, and the happiness of C an end to C, that, therefore, the happiness of B and C is an end to A ? There is obviously no connection between the premises and the supposed conclusion. And there appears to be, ■^ r rrr 56 as Mill puts it, only an account of the ambiguity of his last clause, " the general happiness a good to the aggregate of all persons." The good of A and B and C may be a good to the aggregate (A -}- B + C), but what universalistic hedonism requires is that the aggregate good of A + B + C, be a good to A and to B and to C taken separately — a very different proposition. Mill is guilty of the fallacy known logically as the fallacy of divi- sion — arguing from a collective whole to the dis- tributed units. Because all men want to be happy, it hardly follows that every man wants all to be happy. There is, accordingly, no direct road from -individualistic hedonism — private pleasure — to uni- versalistic — general pleasure. Moreover, if we adopt the usual psychology of hedonism and say that pleasure is the motive of acting, it is abso- lutely absurd to say that general pleasure can be a motive. How can I be moved by the happiness which exists in some one else ? I may feel a pleasure resembling his, and be moved by it, but that is quite a different matter. XXII. Indirect Means Is there any indirect of Identifying method of going from the Private and pleasure of one to the General Pleasure, pleasure of all? Upon the whole, the utilitarians do not claim that there is any 57 natural and immediate connection between the desire for private and for general happiness, but suppose that there are certain means which are instrumental in bringing about an identity. Of these means the sympathetic emotions and the influence of law and of education are the chief. Each of these, moreover, cooperates with the other. 1. Sympathetic and Social Emotions. We are so constituted by nature that we take pleasure in the happiness of others and feel pain in their misery. A proper regard for our own welfare must lead us, therefore, to take an interest in the pleasure of others. Our own feel- ings, moreover, are largely influenced by the feelings of others toward us. If we act in a certain way we shall incur the disapprobation of others, and this, independently of any overt punishment it may lead them to inflict upon us, arouses feelings of shame, of inferiority, of being under the dis- pleasure of others, feelings all of which are de- cidedly painful. The more enlightened our judg- ment, the more we see how our pleasures are bound up in those of others. " The Dictates of Utility" (Bentham, Op. cit., p. 56) are neither more nor less than the dictates of the most extensive and enlightened (that is, well advised) benev- olence," and (p. 18), " The pleasures of benevolence are the pleasures resulting from the view of any pleasures supposed to be possessed by the beings who may be 58 the objects of benev jlence These may also be called the pleasures of good will, the pleasures of sym- pathy, or the pleasures of the benevolent or social affections"; and (p. 144), " What motives (independent of such as legislation and relij^ion may choose to fur- nish) can one man have to consult the happiness of another? .... In answer to this, it cannot but be admitted that the only interests which a man at all times and upon all occasions is sure to find adequate motives for consulting, are his own. Notwithstanding this, there are no occasions in which a man has not some motives for consulting the happiness of other men. In the first place he has, on all occasions, the purely social motive of sympathy and benevolence; in the next place he has, on most occasions, the semi- social motives of love of amity and love of reputa- tion." And so in the Deontology, which, however, was not published by Bentham himself, page 203, " The more enlightened one is, the more one forms the habit of general benevolence, because it is seen that the interests of men combine with each other in more points than they conflict in." 2. Education and Laic. Education, working directly and internally upon the feelings, and government, appealing to them from without through commands and penalties, are con- stantly effecting an increasing identity of self- interest and regard for others. These means supplement the action of sympathy and the more instinctive emotions. They stimulate and even induce a proper interest in the pleasures of others. In governmental law, with its punishments, we have an express instrument for making the pleas- 59 ures of one harmonize with (or at least not conflict with) the pleasures of others. Thus Benthain, after statino: that an enlightened mind perceives the identity of st'lf-interest and that of others (or of egoism and altriiUm, as these interests are now commonly called), goes on (Deontology, p. 201): " The majority do not have sufficient enlighten- ment, nor enough moral feeling so that their character goes beyond the aid of laws, and so the legislator should supplement the frailty of this natural interest, in adding to it an artificial interest more appreciable and more continuous. Thus the government augments and extends the connexion which exists between pru- dence and benevolence." Mill says (Op. cit., p. 323): " To do as you would be done by, and to love your neighbor as yourself, constitute the ideal perfection of utilitarian morality. As the means of making the nearest approach to this ideal, utility would enjoin, first, that laws and social arrangements should place the happiness or the interest of every individual as nearly as possible in harmony with the interest of the whole; and, secondly, that education and opinion, which have so vast a power over human character, should so use that power as to establish in the mind of every individual an indissoluble association between his own happiness and the good of the whole." XXIII. Private Pleasures In criticism of these Indi- an d rect methods of establishing General Welfare, the identity of 'egoism ^ and * altruism,' it may be said: 1. That the supposed relation between the pri- Tate and the general happiness is extrinsic, and 60 hence always accidental and open to exception.. It is not contended that there is any order which morally demands that there be an identity of in- terests. It is simply argued that there are certain physical and psychological forces which operate, as matter of fact, to bring about such a result. Now we may admit, if we like, that such forces exist and that they are capable of accomplishing all that Bentham and Mill claim for them. But all that is established is, at most, a certain state of facts which is interesting as a state of facts, but which has no especial moral bearing. It is not pretended that there is in the very order of things any necessary and intrinsic connection between the happiness of one and of another. Such identity as exists, therefore, must be a mere external result of the action of certain forces. It is accidental. This being the case, how can it constitute the uni- versal ideal of action? Why is it not open for an agent, under exceptional circumstances, to act for his own pleasure, to the exclusion of that of others? We may admit that, upon the whole (or that always, though this is wholly impossible to prove) in past experience, personal pleasure has been best attained by a certain regard for the pleasures of others; but the connection being wholly empirical (that is, of past instances and not of an intrinsic law), we may ask how it can be claimed that the 61 same connection is certain to hold in this new case ? Nor is it probable that any one would claim that the connection between individual pleasure and general pleasure had been so universal and inva- riable in past experience. Intrinsic moral considerations (that is, those based on the very nature of human action) being put aside, a pretty strong case could be made out for the statement that individual happiness is best attained by ignoring the happiness of others. Probably the most that can be established on the other side is that a due prudence dictates that some attention be paid to the pleasures of others, in cal- culating one's own pleasures. And this suggests: 2. That the end is still private pleasure, general pleasure being simply a means. Granting all that the hedonists urge, what their arguments prove is not that the general pleasure is the end of action, but that, private pleasure being the end, regard for the pleasures of others is one of the most efficient means of reaching it. If private pleasure is a selfish end, the end is not less selfish because the road to it happens to bring pleasure to others also. See Koyce, Religious Aspect of Philosophy, pp. 61-74. 3. The use of education and law to bring about this identity, presupposes that we already have the 62 ideal of the identity as something desirable to realize — it takes for granted the very thing to be proved. Why should it occur to men to use the private influence of opinion and education, and the public influences of law and penalty to identify private welfare > with public, unless they were al- ready convinced that general welfare was the end of conduct, the one desirable thing? What the hedonist has to do is to show how, from the end of private happiness, we may get to the end of general happiness. What Bentham and Mill do show is, that if we take general happiness as the end, we may and do use education and law to bring about an identity of personal and general pleasures. This may go undoubted, but the question how we get the general happiness as the end, the good, re- mains unanswered. Nor is this all. The conception of general hap- piness, taken by itself, has all the abstractness, vagueness and uncertainty of that of personal hap- piness, multiplied indefinitely by the greater num- ber of persons introduced. To calculate the effects of actions upon the general happiness — when hap- piness is interpreted as a state of feeling — is an impossibility. And thus it is that when one is speaking of pleasures one is really thinking of wel- fare, or well-being, or satisfied and progressive human lives. Happiness is considered as it would 63 be, if determined by certain active and well defined interests, and thus the hedonistic theory, while con- tradicting itself, gets apparently all the support of an opposed theory. Universalistic hedonism thus, more or less expressly, takes for granted a social order, or community of persons, of which the agent is simply one member like any other. This is the ideal which it proposes to realize. In this way — although at the cost of logical suicide — the ideal gets a content and a definiteness upon which it is possible to base judgments. That this social organization of persons is the ideal which Mill is actually thinking of, rather than any succession of states of agreeable sensation, is evi- dent by his treatment of the whole subject. Mill is quite clear that education and opinion may produce any sort of feeling, as well as truly benevolent motives to actions. For example, in his critique of Whewell, he says, (Op. cit., p. 154): *' All experience shows that the moral feeliDgs are preeminently artificial, and the products of culture; that even when reasonable, they are no more spontaneous than the growth of corn and wine (which are quite as natural), and that the most senseless and pernicious feeling can as easily be raised to the utmost intensity by inculcation, as hemlock and thistles could be reared to luxuriant growth by sowing them instead of wheat." It is certainly implied here that legislation, education and public opinion must have as a presupposed standard the identity of general and private interests or else they may produce any- thing whatever. That is to say, Mill instead of arriv- ing at his result of general happiness simply takes it for granted. 64 This fact and the further fact that he virtually defines happiness through certain objective interests and ends (thus reversing the true hedonistic position) is obvious from the following-, (Millj Op. cit., pp. 343- 347): After again stating that the moral feelings are capable of cultivation in almost any direction, and stating that moral associations that are of artificial construction dissolve through the force of intellectual analysis (c/. his Autobiography, p. 136), and that the as- sociation of pleasure with the feeling of duty would similarly dissolve unless it had a natural basis of sen- timent, he goes on. " But there is this basis of power- ful natural sentiment. This firm foundation is that of the social feelings of mankind; the desire to be in unity with our fellow-creatures. The social state is at once so natural, so necessary, and so habitual to man that except in some unusual circumstances, or by an effort of volu7itxry abstraction he never conceives of himself otherwise tha7i as a member of a body. Any condition, therefore, which is essential to a state of society becomes more and more an inseparable part of every person's conception of the state of things which he is born into, and which is the destiny of a human being." Mill then goes on to describe some of the ways in which the social unity manifests itself and influences the individual's conduct. Then the latter "comes, as though instinctively, to be conscious of himself as a being who of course pays regard to others. The good of others becomes to him a thing naturally and necessarily to be attended to, like any of the phy- sical conditions of our existence. The deeply -rooted conception which every individual even now has of himself as a social being tends to make him feel it as one of his natural wants, that there should be harmony between his feelings and aims and those of his felloyy 65 d'eaUires. This conviction is the ultimate sanction of the greatest happiness morality." It is to be noticed that there is involved in this account three ideas, any one of which involves such a reconstruction of the pleasure theory as to be a surrender of hedonism. 1. There is, in one instance, a natural (or in- trinsic) connection between the end of conduct and the feelings, and not simply an external or artificial bond. This is in the case of the social feelings. In other words, in one case the ideal, that is, happi- ness, is intrinsically, or necessarily connected with a certain kind of conduct, that flowing from the social impulses. This, of course, reverses hedonism for it makes happiness dependent upon a certain kind of conduct, instead of determining the nature of conduct according as it happens to result in pleasure or pain. 2. Man conceives of himself, of his end or of his destiny as a member of a social body, and this conception determines the nature of his wants and aims. That is to say, it is not mere happiness that a man wants, but a certain kind of happiness, that which would satisfy a man who conceived of himself as social, or having ends and interests in common with others. 3. Finally, it is not mere general "happiness" which is the end, at all. It is social unity; " har- 66 mony of feelings and aims," a beneficial condition for one's self in which the benefits of all are included. Instead of the essentially vague idea of states of pleasurable sensation we have the conception of a community of interests and ends, in securing which alone is true happiness to be found. This concep- tion of the moral ideal we regard as essentially true, but it is not hedonism. It gives up wholly the notion that pleasure is the desired, and, since it sets up a standard by which it determines pleas- ure, it gives up equally the notion that pleasure as such is the desirable. In addition to the works already referred to, the following will give fuller ideas of hedonism and util- itarianism: For historical treatment see Sidgwick, History of Ethics; Jodl, Geschichte der Ethik, Vol. II., pp, 432-468; Bain, Moral Science, Historical Men- tion; Guyau, La Morale Anglaise Contemporaine; Wallace, Epicureanism; Pater, Marius, the Epicurean. Paley, Moral and Political Philosophy; Grote, Exam- ination of the Utilitarian Philosophy (especially fair and valuable criticism); Lecky, History of European Morals, Yol. I, ch. 1; Birks, Utilitarianism (hostile); Blackie, Four Phases of Morals: Essay on Utilitar- ianism (hostile); Gizycki, Students' Manual of Ethical Philosophy, (Coit's trans., favorable); Calderwood, Hand-Book of Moral Philosophy (opposed); Laurie, Ethica (e. g., p. 10). " The object of will is not pleas- ure, not yet happiness, but reason-given law— the law of harmony; but this necessiirily ascertained through feeling, and, therefore, through happiness." Wilson and Fowler, Principles of Morals, Yol. I, 67 pp. 98-112; Vol. II, pp. 262-273. Paulsen, System der Ethik, pp. 195-210. XXIV. The Utilitarian Theory There has lately Combined With the been an attempt to Doctrine of Evolution, c o m b i n e utilitarian morality with the theory of evolution. This posi- tion, chiefly as occupied by Herbert Spencer and Leslie Stephen, we shall now examine. Alexander, also, Moral Order and Progress, makes large use of the theory of evolution, but does not attempt to unite it with any form of hedonism. For the combination, at least three decided ad- vantages are claimed over ordinary utilitarianism. 1. It transforms 'Bmpirical rules' into 'rational laws.' The evolutionary hedonists regard pleasure as the good, but hold that the theory of evolution en- ables them to judge of the relation of acts to pleasure much better than the ordinary theory. As Mr. Spencer puts it, the ordinary theory is not sci- entific, because it does not fully recognize the principle of causation as existing between certain acts as causes, and pleasures ( or pains ) as efPects. It undoubtedly recognizes that some acts do result in pain or pleasure, but does not show how or why they so result. By the aid of the theory of evoh tion we can demonstrate that certain acts must be beneficial because furthering evolution, and others painful because retarding it. /> 68 Spencer, Data of Ethics, pp. 5758. *' Morality properly so-called — the science of right conduct — has for its object to determine liow and why certain rules of conduct are detrimental, and certain other rules beneficial. Those good and bad results cannot be acci- dental, but must be necessary consequences of the constitution of things; and I conceive it to be the business of moral science to deduce, from the laws of ^Ufe and the conditions of existence, what kinds of action necessarily tend to produce happiness, and what kinds to produce unhappiness. Having done this, its deductions are to be recognized as laws of conduct; and are to be conformed to irrespective of a direct estimation of happiness or misery The objec- tion which I have to the current utilitarianism is, that it recognizes no more developed form of utility — does not see that it has reached but the initial stage of moral science It is supposed that in future, as now, utility is to be determined only by observation of results; and that there is no possibility of knowing by deduction from fundamental principles what con- duct 7nust be detrimental and what conduct inust be beneficial." Cf. also ch. IX, and Stephen, Science of Ehtics, ch. IX. It is contended, then, that by the use of the evo- lutionary theory, we may substitute certain condi- tions, which in the very nature of things tend to produce happiness, for a calculation, based upon observation of more or less varying cases in the past, of the probable results of the specific action. Thus we get a fixed objective standard and do away with all the objections based upon the uncertainty, vagueness and liability to exceptions, of the ordinary utilitarian morality. Spencer, Op. cit., p. 162: "When alleging that empirical utilitarianism is but introductory to rational utilitarianism I pointed out that the last does not take welfare for its immediate object of pursuit, but takes for its immediate object of pursuit conformity to certain principles Avhich, in the nature of things, causally determine welfare." 2. It reconciles 'intuitionalism' with 'empir- icism.' The theory of evolution not only gives us an objective standard on which happiness neces- sarily depends, and from which we may derive our laws of cenduct, instead of deriving them from ob- servation of particular cases, but it enables us to recognize that there are certain moral ideas now innate or intuitive. The whole human race, the whole animal race, has for an indefinite time been undergoing experiences of what leads to pleasure and of what leads to pain, until finally the results of these experiences have become organized into our very physical and mental make-up. The first point was that we could substitute for consideration of results consideration of the causes which deter- mine these results ; the present point is that so far as we have to use results, we can use those of the race, instead of the short span of the individual's life. Spencer, Op. cit., pp. 123-124. " The experiences of utility organized and consolidated through all past generations of the human race have been producing corresponding nervous modifications, which, by con- 70 tinned transmission and accumulation, have become in us certain faculties of moral intuition — certain emotions corresponding to right and wrong conduct, which have no apparent basis in the individual expe- riences of utility The evolution hypothesis thus enables us to reconcile opposed moral theories The doctrine of innate powers of moral perception become congruous with the utilitarian doctrine, when it is seen that preferences and aversions are rendered organic by inheritance of the effects of pleasurable and painful experiences in progenitors." 3. It reconciles 'egoism' with 'altruism.' As we have seen, the relation of personal pleasure to general happiness presents very serious difficulties to hedouism. It is claimed, however, that the very pro- cess of evolution necessitates a certain identity. The being which survives must be the being which has properly adapted himself to his environment, which is largely social, and there is assurance that the conduct will be adapted to the environment just in the degree in which pleasure is taken in acts which concern the welfare of others. If an agent has no pleasure in such acts he will either not perform them, or perform them only occasionally, and thus will not meet the conditions of surviving. If surrounding conditions demand constantly certain actions, those actions in time must come to be pleas- urable. The conditions of sui'vival demand altru- istic action, and hence such action must become pleasurable to the agent (and in that sense egotistic). 71 " From the laws of life (Spencer Op. cit., p. 205) it must be concluded that unceasing social discipline will so mould human action, that eventually sympa- thetic pleasures will be pursued to the fullest extent advantageous to each and all Though pleasure may be gained by giving pleasure, yet the thought of the sympathetic pleasure to be gained will not occupy consciousness, but only the thought of the pleasure given." XXV. Criticism Regarding the whole foregoing of scheme, it may be said so far as it Evolutionary is true, or suggestive of truth, it is UtilitarlanisiTK not hedonistic. It does not judge actio ns f i - on rmeir effects in the way of pleasure or pain, but it judges pleasures from the basis of an independent standard ' in the nature of things.' It is expressly declared that happiness is not to be so much the end, as the test of conduct, and it is not happiness in general, of every sort and kind, but a certain kind of happiness, happiness condi- tioned by certain modes of activity, that is the test. Spencer's hedonism in its final result hardly comes to more than saying that in the case of a perfect individual in a perfect society, every action what- ever would be accompanied by pleasure, and that, therefore, in such a society, pleasure would be an infallible sign and test of the morality of action — a position which is not denied by any ethical writer "whatever, unless a few extreme ascetics. Such a 72 position simply determines the value of pleasure by an independent criterion, and then goes on to say of pleasure so determined, that it is the test of the morality of action. This may be true, but, true or not, it is not hedonistic. Furthermore, this standard by which the nature of pleasure is determined is itself an ethical (that is, active) standard. We have already seen that Spencer conceives that the modes of producing hap- piness are to be deduced from the " laws of life and the conditions of existence". This might be, of course, a deduction from x>hysical laws and condi- tions. But when we find that the laws and condi- tions which Spencer employs are mainly those of social life, it is difficult to see why he is not employ- ing a strictly ethical standard. To deduce not -gight actions directly from happiness, but the kinds of actions which will produce happiness from a con- sideration of a certain ideal of social relationships seems like a reversal of hedonism; but this is what Mr. Spencer does. XXVI. The Real Mr. Spencer expressly recognizes Criterion that there exists (1) an ideal code of of conduct, formulating the conduct of Evolutionary the completely adapted man in the Ethics. completely evolved society. Such a code is called absolute ethics as distinguished from 73 relative ethics — a code the injunctions of which are alono to be considered " as absolutely right, in con- trast with those that are relatively right or least wrong, and which, as a system of ideal conduct, is to serve as a standard for our guidance in solving, as well as we can, the problems of real conduct " (p. 275 of the Data of Ethics). The ideal code deals, it will be observed, with the behavior of the completely adapted man in a completely evolved society." This ideal as elsewhere stated, is " an ideal social being so constituted that his spontane- ous activities are congruous with the conditions imposed by the social environment formed by other such beings The ultimate man is one in whom there is a correspondence between all the promptings of his nature and all the requirements of his life as carried on in society" (p. 275). Furthermore, "to make the ideal man serve as a standard, he has to be defined in terms of the conditions ivhich his nature fulfill — in terms of the objective requisites which must be met before conduct can be right" (p. 179). " Hence it is manifest that we must consider the ideal man as existing in the ideal social state " (p. 280). Here we have in the most express terms the rec- ognition of a final and permanent standard with reference to which the nature of happiness is deter- mined, and the standard is one of social relation- 74 ships. To be sure it is claimed that the standard is one which results in greatest happiness, but every ethical theory has always claimed that the ideal moral condition would be accompanied by the max- imum possible happiness. 2. The ideal state is defined with reference to the end of evolution. That is, Spencer defines pleasure from an independent standard instead of using pleasure as the standard. This standard is to be got at by considering that idea of "fully evolved conduct " given by the theory of evolution. This fully evolved conduct implies: (i.) GroajUst- possible quantity of life, both in length and breadth; (ii.) Similar maintenance of life in pro- geny; and (iii.) Life in which there is no interfer- ence of actions by one with those of another, and, indeed, life in which the "members of a society give material help in the achievement of ends, thus rendering the " lives of all more complete ". (See Chap. II of Data of Ethics). Furthermore, the " complete life here identified with the ideally moral life " may be otherwise defined as a life of perfect equilibrium (p. 74), or balance of functions (p. 90), and this considered not simply with refer- ence to the individual, but also with reference to the relation of the individual to society. " Com- plete life in a complete society is but another name for complete equilibrium between the co-ordinated 75 activities of each social unit and those of the ag- gregate of units" (p. 74, and the whole of chap. V. See also pp. 169-170 for the position that the end is a society in which each individual has full functions freely exercised in due harmony, and is, p. 100, " the spontaneous exercise of duly pro- portioned faculties " ). 3. Not only is pleasure thus determined by an objective standard of " complete living in a com- plete society " but it is expressly recognized that as things are noiv, pleasure is not a perfect guide to, or even test of action. And this difficulty is thought to be removed by reference to the ideal state in which right action and happiness will fully coincide. The failure of pleasure as a perfect test and guide of right conduct, comes out in at least three cases : — 1. There is the conflict of one set of pleasures with another, or of present happiness with future, one lot having to be surrendered for the sake of another. This is wrong, since pleasure as such is good, and, although a fact at present, exists only on account of the incomplete development of society. When there is "complete adjustment of humanity to the social state there will be recognition of the truth that actions are completely right only when, besides being conducive to future happiness, special 76 and general, they are immediately pleasurable, and that painfulness, not only ultimate but proximate, is the concomitant of actions which are wrong " (p. 29. See for various cases in which "pleasures are not connected with actions which must be per- formed " and for the statement that this difficulty will be removed in an ideal state of society, p. 77; pp. 85-87; pp. 98-99). 2. There is also, at present, a conflict of indi- vidual happiness with social welfare. In the first place, as long as there exist antagonistic societies, the individual is called upon to sacrifice his own happiness to that of others, but " such moralities are, by their definition, shown to belong to incom- plete conduct; not to conduct that is fully evolved" (See pp. 133-137). Furthermore, there will be conflict of claims, and consequent compro- mises between one's own pleasure and that of others (p. 148), until there is a society in which there is " complete living through voluntary co- operation ", this implying negatively that one shall not interfere with another and shall fulfill contracts, and positively that men shall spontaneously help to aid one another lives beyond any specified agree- ment (pp. 146-149). 3. There is, at present, a conflict of obligation with pleasure. Needed activities, in other words, have often to be performed under a pressure, which 77 either lessens the pleasure of the action, or brings pain, the act being performed, however, to avoid a greater pain (so that this point really comes under the first head). But " the remoulding of human nature into fitness for the requirements of social life, must eventually make all needful activities pleasurable, while it makes displeasurable all activities at variance with these requirements'^ (p. 183). "The things now done with dislike, through sense of obligation, will be done then with immediate liking" (p. 84, and p. 186; and pp. 255-256). All the quotations on these various points are simply so many recognitions that pleasure and pain as such are not tests of morality, but that they become so when morality is independently realized. Pleasure is not now a test of conduct, but becomes such a test as fast as activity becomes full and complete ! What is this but to admit (what was claimed in Sec. XIII.) that activity itself is what man wants ; not mere activity, but the activity which belongs to man as man, and which therefore has for its realized content all man's practical relationships. Of Spencer's conception of the ideal as something not now realized, but to be some time or other realized once for all, we have said nothing. But see below^ Sec. 64, and also Alexander.Op. cit., pp. 264-277, and also James, Unitarian Review, Vol. XXII., pp. 212-213. We have attempted, above, to deal with evolu- 78 tionary ethics only in the one point of its supposed connection with pleasure as a standard. Accounts and criticisms of a broader scope will be found in Darwin, Descent of Man; Martineau, Op. cit., Vol. II, pp. 335- 393; Schurman, Ethical Import of Darwmism; Sorley, Ethics of Naturalism, chapters V, and VI; Stephen, Science of Ethics, particularly pp. 31-34; 78-89; 359- 379; Royce, Religious Aspect of Philosophy, pp. 74-85; Everett, Poetry, Comedy and Duty, Essay on the New Ethics; Seth in Mind, Jan. 1889, on Evolution of Mo- rality; Dewey, Andover Review, Vol. VII, p. 570; Hyslop, Ibid., Vol. IX, p. 348. XXVII. Formal Ethics. We come now to the ethical theories which attempt to find the good not only in the will itself, but in the will irrespective of any end to be reached by the will. The typical instance of such theories is the Kantian, and we shall, therefore, make that the basis of our examin- ation. Kant's theory, however, is primarily a theory not of the good, but of the nature of duty, and that makes a statement of his doctrine somewhat more difficult. " The concept of good and evil must not be deter- mined before the moral law (of which it seems as if it must be the foundation), but only after it and by means of it " (Abbott's Trans., p. 154). Separating, as far as we can, his theory of the good from that of duty, we get the following re- sults : 1. Goodness belongs to the will, and to that alone.