(H^> '.\f mmM m. :f,'^1';*-t'^ '' -'l-'i'^Vi: ;A>^|:!.\v,' ;■■;•■., r Digitized by the Internet Archive in 2007 with funding from IVIicrosoft Corporation http://www.archive.org/details/developmentofeurOOsidgrich THE DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY THE DEVELOPMENT OF EUEOPEAN POLITY BY HENRY SIDGWICK I \ AUTHOR OF 'the METHODS OF ETHICS,' 'THE PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY, AND 'the ELEMENTS OF POLITICS' iLontron MACMILLAN AND CO, Limited NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 1903 A II rights resented "T.' -•:■« £l^AL EDITOR'S PEEFACE The book here offered to the public consists of lectures delivered in the University of Cambridge to students of history and of moral sciences. In arranging it for publication I have retained the lecture form, so as to avoid unnecessary changes of phraseology. It had of late years been more and more decidedly the author's view — as he has left on record — that a threefold treatment of politics is desirable for completeness : — first, an exposition analytical and deductive, such as he attempted in his work on the Elements of Politics; secondly, an evolu- tionary study of the development of polity within the historic period in Europe, beginning with the earliest known Grseco- Roman and Teutonic polity, and carried down to the modern state of Europe and its colonies as the last result of political evolution ; thirdly, a comparative study of the con- stitutions of Europe and its colonies in connexion with the history of what may be called the constitution-making century which has just ended. The present book is an attempt at a treatment of political science from the second point of view. A description of its plan and scope will be found in the first lecture. In reading the book it should be borne in mind that it does not deal with theoretical politics as such. The theory of politics is treated in Elements of Politics^ where the work and structure of the modern state are examined, and though the present book is complete in itself, it is intended that, for a full view of the subject, both books should be read. As a matter of fact, Mr. Sidgwick often gave a course of lectures on Political Theory along with the lectures contained in this book — some of his pupils attending both courses. With regard to the third point of view, the comparative study of present constitutions would, as Mr. Sidgwick himself said, to some extent overlap with this book, but only in its later part. It was a favourite idea of his, when he was making plans for the future, that he might reside abroad VI DE VEL OPMENT OF E UROPEAN POLITY for some time in different countries successively in order to learn on the spot, not only what their constitutions were on paper, but what they were in fact — how they actually worked, and what tendencies to development were operating. The scheme was perhaps too ambitious to have had, at Mr. Sidgwick's age, much chance of being carried out by him, but it is a scheme which, if adequately performed, ought to afford much interest and instruction. To return to the present work, it should be observed that in lecturing it was Mr. Sidgwick's practice to write his lectures pretty completely — though occasionally parts were at first only in the form of full notes — and generally to discuss the subject of them afterwards with the members of his class by means of papers and essays and conversation classes. When the next occasion arrived for lecturing on the same subject, he went through the lectures again before delivering them, added the results of further study, endeavoured to remove difficulties or obscurities, and made any other improvements that occurred to him — often changing somewhat the order of treatment. To facilitate this process, he used during the latter part of his life to write, as a rule, on loose sheets of paper, which could be shuffled about, and when too much obscured by erasures and marginal additions, be rewritten — a plan which also made it easy to interpolate additional sheets. When he felt that the matter had become sufficiently mature to be worked up into a book, he would determine its general arrangement and adapt the lectures to it. Finally, in preparing the work for publica- tion he would revise what was written, add new matter, and fill up gaps. It is thus that his Elements of Politics and, I believe, his Methods of Ethics were composed. The present work has not, of course, undergone the later finishing process, and indeed the author was himself doubtful whether it was sufficiently finished for publication. He had been led to give up the idea of publishing so long as he held his professorship, feeling that the time and labour required to make it what he considered an adequately scholarly book could not — owing to arrange- ments in connexion with the teaching and examinations at Cambridge — be given consistently with his duty as Professor of Moral Philosophy. He intended to resign his chair in a year or two, and hoped then to return to this work ; but his illness and death in 1900 cut short his plans. With regard to the publication of the book, he directed me to seek advice from friends competent to judge. I have received much kind advice and assistance from Mr. James Bryce, Mr. A. Y. Dicey, EDITOR'S PREFACE Vli Mr. O. Browning, Mr. T. Thornely, and others, and all whom I have consulted, including my brother, Mr. A. J. Balfour, who read the first half of the book, have recommended publica- tion. The reader will doubtless notice, however, that the treatment is unequal — that some points are more fully dealt with, and in a more finished manner than others. In particular, I have little doubt that the last three lectures would have received further development in the hands of the author had he lived. It is perhaps fortunate, however, that in Elements of Politics there is a good deal said incidentally about present polities, which may be regarded as supplementary to Lectures XXVIII. and XXIX. This is, partly at least, referred to in foot- notes in the appropriate places. With regard to my responsibility as editor, I have through- out, in accordance with the author's expressed desire con- cerning any work of his to be published after his death, made such verbal alterations and corrections of inadvertencies as seemed to be needed, and I have of course added connecting words when the sentences were not fully written out in the manuscript. But in every case where the slightest doubt seemed possible as to what was the sense of the words intended to be read in, I have enclosed those I have added in square brackets. I think it has only happened two or three times in the course of the book. The substance and expres- sion are therefore entirely the author's. As regards arrangement my responsibility is greater, owing partly to the way in which the lectures had been given. Mr. Sidgwick first lectured on the subject, I think, in 1885-86, and from that date he seems to have lectured on it in every year till 1898-99. But the last course — given in the Easter term of 1899 — was a short one of eight lectures, and the previous course had also not been a full course. To adapt the lectures to these short courses the manuscript had been much disarranged, and it was not put into order afterwards ; and the author's habit of altering the sequence of the sheets and con- stantly renumbering them renders the numbering practically useless in most cases. I have therefore had to use my own judgment as to order, and in this part of the work I have re- ceived very material assistance from students' note-books. I had note-books of diff'erent years, and was thus able not only to s6e approximately what the order of treatment had been, but also that in different years it was not the same. Under these circumstances a certain amount of patching together was needed. In doing this I have used entirely the author's manu- Viu DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY script ; but in order to make transitions as smooth as possible I have sometimes allowed myself, when there were different versions of the same thing, to choose one sentence from one and another from another version. I have also occasionally- interpolated passages from portions of the author's manuscript other than what was tied together as the material for this book. In such rearrangement there was, of course, a certain danger of misrepresenting the author's meaning, and of using material intended to be superseded, but I have endeavoured to avoid both dangers. It will be seen from what I have said that I am to a con- siderable extent responsible for the details of arrangement ; and I hope that if the reader should think there are defects of order, or too much iteration of particular points, or other similar defects, he will attribute the fault to the editor, and not to the author. It should be mentioned that the first three lectures and Lecture X. (on Kome) had been put into print by the author for the use of his class. These are arranged as he left them, except that I have interpolated § 6 in Lecture I., this appearing to be the most appropriate place for it. As regards footnotes and Appendix, I am largely responsible for the selection. A good many of the footnotes were, it is true, indicated as such by the author, and some parts of the manuscript tied together as the material of the book, which did not seem to fit in well into the text, have also been introduced as notes ; but other footnotes and most of the notes in the Appendix have been introduced by me from other portions of the manuscript left by the author, because they seemed to me useful in throwing light on the text, or to be in themselves interesting. The distinction between footnotes and Appendix is only that the notes in the latter are either too long to be conveniently introduced as footnotes, or their connexion with the text is somewhat indirect. I have in the course of the book inserted one or two editorial footnotes, but these are, I think, clearly indicated as such, and explain themselves. I should like to be able to give, as the author would have done, a list of the books to which he was most indebted in the composition of this work. But this is unfortunately impossible. I could give a long list of books used and annotated in the course of preparing it, but it would probably be incomplete, and in any case would not represent the degree in which he had made use of them respectively. All I have been able to do is to give, so far as possible, the references to actual quotations or what are very nearly quotations. EDITORS PREFACE ix It remains to thank those who have helped in various ways in the course of the work. I have first to thank Mr. Bryce, Mr. Dicey, Mr. Browning, and Mr. Thornely, and Miss Alice Gardner, Lecturer on History at Newnham College — not only, as already mentioned, for advice, but also for reading the proofs and making criticisms, which, though they could not — as they might in the author's lifetime — modify the substance of what was said, have yet enabled me to remove clerical errors, and, with the help of other parts of the manuscript, to improve some passages and to make some points clearer. And here I should like to mention that the author had shown some of the lectures, in an earlier form, to the late Sir John Seeley, to Mr. P. F. Willert, and to Mr. Stanley Leathes — perhaps to others — and had received criticisms and suggestions from them which he doubtless made use of. Mr. H. G. Dakyns, who had also read some of the lectures before, has greatly helped me, not only by reading the proofs, but by going through some of the manuscript with me. I have to thank Miss E. M. Colman and Mrs. Percy Godber for lending me their notes of the lectures which they attended in 1894-95 and 1895-96 respectively. Miss Gardner, already mentioned, and Miss E. M. Sharpley, Lecturer in Classics at Newnham College, have, besides helping me to correct the proofs, taken much trouble in looking out and verifying references ; and in this Mr. Thornely and Mr. Dakyns have also helped. To Miss Gardner I am further indebted for the Index, and for help with the Table of Contents. Eleanor Mildred Sidgwick. Newnham College, Cambridge, August 1903. - CONTENTS LECTURE I Introductory Survey op the Subject PAGES § 1. The purpose of this book is to treat the history of Political Societies or States from the point of view of inductive Political Science. . . . . . .1-3 § 2. It is concerned with the development as well as the classifica- tion of forms of polity. ..... 3-6 § 3. Analogies between past history and present politics must be used with caution, but the development of the "modem state " of Western Europe and its colonies is connected with ancient Greece and Rome, not only in the way of resem- blance and analogy, but by direct influence ; and to the study of this group, which has developed not only political institutions but constitutions, this book is limited ; though not of course to the exclusion of absolute monarchy. . 6-12 § 4. Differences of race and effects of climate and geographical con- ditions on political development are important. . . 12-15 §5. Outline of the plan of the book. .... 15-20 § 6.., Imitation must be noted as a disturbing cause in the develop- ment of polity, but it only operates where there is a previous tendency towards the form of polity imitated. . . 20-25 § 7. Meaning of " Political Society, " "State" and "Nation." . 25-28 LECTUEE II The Beginnings op Historic Polity § 1. The earliest known polities in Greece, Rome, and Germany have important resemblances, but of the three the stage of the Germans when we first hear of them is earliest and of the Romans latest. ..... 29-32 xi h xii DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY § 2. In the primitive German polity we find an assembly of free- men in arms, a council of chiefs, and sometimes a king ; and a movement is traceable towards kingship. . . 32-34 § 3. The polity of Homeric Greece is more monarchical, though both here and in Rome we find the three elements — king, council, and assembly. ..... 34-42 LECTUKE III The Patriarchal Theory § 1. In this lecture we look backward from the primitive polity to guess how political society originated. This question, so much debated in earlier stages of modern political thought as of practical importance, has now only historic interest. . 43-44 § 2. In historic times new states have been formed by aggrega- tion and by division. But political societies cannot have been formed by division out of non-political. They may have been formed by aggregation — especially voluntary coalescence. ...... 44-46 § 3. Were they then formed by voluntary aggregation of heads of natural families, or by the extension of single families into larger bodies of kindred ? Maine, arguing from ancient law and what is known of primitive societies, holds the latter view, conjecturing that the independent group thus formed out of the partriarchal family was normally governed by the eldest male ascendant representing the common ancestor. . 46-50 § 4. In considering this we answer three questions as follows : — (1) kinship real or supposed may be assumed to have been the bond in the primitive gi-oup ; . . • . ■ 50-51 § 5. but (2) this kinship was not necessarily of the patriarchal type ;....... 51-54 § 6. and (3) even when the patriarchal family was established within the clan, there is no reason to regard the father's power as the original type of political power. Hereditary kingship may, however, have arisen through a combina- tion of the principle of choosing the strongest and wisest, with a tendency to regard a son as the natural successor to the father. ...... 54-56 LECTUEE IV Summary of the Theory of Origin — Transition from Primitive Kingship § 1. The theory of origin arrived at in the last lecture is summed up and further explained. ..... 57-60 CONTENTS xm 2. Before tracing tlie development from the primitive polity in Greece, we may note that we have here many instances to generalise from, but the advantage of this is neutralised by our fragmentary knowledge of most of the Greek states and colonies. In early history, however, Athens and Sparta may be taken as types of states formed by integration and conquest respectively. ..... 60-62 3. Unlike Rome, in Greece the transition from kingship to early oligarchy seems generally to have been peaceful. Monarchical despotism — " tyrannis " — comes in Greece after oligarchy. 62-66 4. The difference between the movement towards kingship in early German history and from it in Greece, is connected with the tendency towards the formation of country- states in the former and city-states in the latter. Concentration in towns arises from (1), economic causes ; (2), the more rapid development of civilisation in towns ; (3) and in Greece from the geographical conditions leading to small independent states, and the protection against aggression afforded in small states by the walled town. The con- centration of life in the town develops the sentiment of the state, while the development of this sentiment fixes the notion of a city community as the highest political development. ...... 66-70 5. The transition from villages to towns was often semi -com- pulsory, and may have been promoted by the ambition of primitive kings. But the development of civilised life in small separate communities deprives kingship of its value as a bond of national unity, and, speaking broadly, political society in Greece passed from primitive kingship to primitive oligarchy, the council becoming the ruling organ. ....... 71-74 LECTURE V Early Oligarchy in the Greek City-State 1. The assembly of the freemen in arms also tends to acquire an oligarchical character from various causes. There are two kinds of oligarchy — that where a minority of rich govern a majority of poor citizens, and that where the whole body of citizens is a minority compared with free non-citizens. It is in this latter sense that Sparta is an oligarchy. . . 75-80 2. This kind of oligarchy resulting, as in Sparta, from conquest is found elsewhere in Greece ; but it may also arise from the citizens by inheritance becoming a minority compared with free immigrants. On the other hand, "integration" — coalescence of small towns as in Athens — would tend to throw power into the hands of a minority inhabiting the central town and able to attend the assembly. . . 80-82 XIV DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY PAGES § 3. Growing inequality of property is an important cause of oligarchy. The landless freeman relieved from fighting at his own charge would lose his place in the assembly. The importance of cavalry in war would also throw power into the hands of the rich. Early oligarchies of this sort were probably "natural oligarchies." . . . 82-85 LECTUEE VI Tyrannis § 1. "Tyrannis" — unlawful despotism — tends to prevail in Greece at two periods. In the first the tyrannus is usually a demagogue who profits by the movement against early oligarchy. In the second he is more often a leader of mercenaries. ...... 86-89 § 2. The movement against early oligarchy is due to oppression by the rich ; to the growth of new wealth outside old families ; to growing luxury and insolence ; to distrust of unwritten law. The codifier and the " aesymnete," or lawful dictator, sometimes avert the crisis. .... 89-90 § 3. There is great inequality of development in Greece, and the early democratic movement occurs in the more advanced parts. ....... 90-93 § 4. Accordingly we find the earlier Tyrannis in commercial and maritime states and in colonies. It is sometimes averted by broadening the basis of oligarchy. . . . 93-95 § 5. Tyrannis pressed more hardly on the rich than the poor, and it often raised the power and prestige of the State, but being always irregular and lawless it was generally condemned. . 95-99 LECTUEE VII Greek Democracy § 1. After the period of the earlier Tyrannis we have a very general drift towards democracy, with lapses to oligarchy. . 100-101 § 2. "We know little of the oligarchies of this period. . . 102-103 § 3. Of democracy we know more from Athens, where the general assembly of the people governed ; the magistrates and council were subordinate and were appointed by lot ; attendance at the assembly was paid ; administration of justice was popular ; the assembly did not itself legislate. . . 103-107 § 4. Aristotle's classification of governments implies a general condemnation of the actual governments in Greek States. . 107-111 § 5. And his condemnation of fully developed democracy is con- firmed by Plato and Isocrates, but they all agree that a bad oligarchy is worse. . . . . .111-113 CONTENTS XV Democracy seems to have tended to personal liberty ; and the corrupt administration of justice at Athens, and the over- burdening of the rich by taxation, is perhaps exaggerated. Democracy was often violent, but some forms of oppression were probably more often talked of than realised. . . 113-119 LECTUEE VIII Ideal States op Aristotle and Plato The Athens of Plato and Aristotle — the fully developed "" democracy of t he fourth c&nturyj^not the developing demo- cracy of the fifth — must be taken as typical. . .120-121 Regarding this as bad, and the ordinary oligarchy as worse, Plato and Aristotle design ideal states not larger than a single city in which the citizens are to be landowners living at leisure, carefully educated and trained for war — husband- men, artisans, and retail traders to be excluded from citizen- ship. Plato would have an elected magistracy and council — Aristotle would give deliberative and judicial functions to the landowning class after they have passed the military age. ....... 121-126 Sparta has evidently served as model for this aristocratic ideal ; but as a practical policy Aristotle recommends a fusion between aristocracy and democracy — constitutional demo- cracy — "politeia." . • . . . 126-129 He does not introduce monarchy of any kind into his balanced constitution. ...... 129-130 LECTUEE IX Greek Federalism Recapitulation of Greek political development. The transitions are largely due to economic and other internal causes, but also to war ; and the need of resisting larger states produces federalism. ...... 131-134 In fact, the time has come for the transition to country-states — by federation as in the Achaean League, or by expansion and absorption as in Rome. It is marked by the word "ethnos" taking the place of "polls." . . . 134-135 There had been federation earlier, but as the importance of cities grew it became more difficult. . . . 135-137 In the revived Achaean League the isolation of the city-state is overcome. The national government is democratic and non-representative, but inevitably tends to a practically representative and aristocratic character. , . . 137-140 XVI DE VELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY LECTUEE X Rome PAGES § 1. Aristotle would have classed republican Rome as a ** politeia," though a strange one with its duality of governing assemblies, its tribunes, and the legislative power of the plebeian assembly — results of the struggle between patricians and plebeians. ...... 141-145 § 2. Though the plebeians triumph the administration remains aristocratic. This is due to the pressure of external struggles ; and to the preponderantly rural character of the assembly ; the plebs want to be secured from misgovern- ment, not to govern. ..... 145-148 § 3. The struggle had been between rich and poor, and between old families and new ; when the leading plebeians are admitted to office they coalesce with patricians into a new nobility ; it is this which governs while Rome is conquering. ...... 148-151 § 4. The conflict between rich and poor is kept in abeyance by distribution of conquered land and establishment of colonice; these form centres from which the language and civilisation spread ; thus by expansion and absorption the city-state grows. But there is no more public land to divide when the century of revolution begins. .... 151-154 § 5. In this revolution what is breaking down is the government of an aristocracy that has always recognised the sovereignty of a popular assembly ; we see not only the degeneration of an oligarchy, but the demoralisation of an undeveloped democracy. ...... 154-156 LECTUEE XI Rome (continued) § 1. Polybius finds in the Roman constitution monarchical besides aristocratic and democratic elements. But the powers of the consuls were far from what Aristotle means by mon- archical, though the proconsuls in the provinces ruled monarchically. ...... 157-159 § 2. The early consuls after the transition from monarchy to republic were more like kings, possessing the judicial func- tions of the praetors and the functions of the censors, and not being limited by the tribunate. The splitting up of executive authority increased the power of the senate. . 159-163 § 3. The transition from republic back to monarchy follows from the unwieldy size of the city-state rendering the form of government inadequate, while yet this size was necessary CONTENTS xvn PAQB3 for physical strength ; and the corresponding change of the - army from a citizen -militia to the legions of particular generals. Order could only be maintained by concentrating the command of the legions in one hand. The primary element of the Imperial authority is proconsular, and republican forms are at first maintained. . . . 163-167 LECTUEE XII Functions of Government and Kelation op Law to Government in Greece and Rome 1. The ancient governments have been said to regulate the lives of individuals more than modern ones ; but apart from Sparta the evidence is against this in Greece, except inter- ference due to the fusion of Church and State and the predominance of war. ..... 168-171 2. Legislation is, on the other hand, more important in the modern view of the functions of government than in the ancient. In the Greek view law was not simply a product of the popular will. ..... 171-176 3. In Rome we can trace the process by which the idea of govern- ment as normally legislative was reached. There was some new legislation in the XII. Tables, . . . 176-178 4. but for several centuries after this, legislation was not the chief means of altering the law. It was modified by inter- pretation in ' ' answers of the learned " and by the over- riding of law by equity through the praetors' edict. By this yt*s gen^mw was reached .... 178-179 5. through the practical needs arising from dealings with foreigners. The more universal character of jus gentium led to its ultimate fusion with the philosophical idea of jus naturale, but they were not completely convertible, par- ticularly as to slavery. ..... 179-183 LECTUEE XIII Transition to Medieval History § 1. Legislation increases under the Empire, and becomes more and more Imperial. Justinian's work symbolises the concentra- tion of legislative power in the emperor. . . . 184-186 § 2. In the slow development of the country-state, to which we now turn, a vague analogy can be traced to the more rapid development of the Greek city-state. . . . 186-190 § 3. But this comparison brings out the much stronger tendency to monarchy in the former. The main cause is the need of a bond of unity ; but the pre-existence of the Roman Empire xvill DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY is another cause, acting by example and tradition and through the lawyers and the Church. . . . 190-194 4. The country-state is complex compared with the city-state. We have to consider in its development the relation between political power and landownership, the growth of towns within the state, the separate organisation of the clergy. . 194-196 5. Another element of complexity is the Holy Roman Empire. . 196-198 6. Broadly speaking, the diverse courses of development come to absolute monarchy in the seventeenth century, and begin from the old Teutonic community. Though as the barbarians gradually prevail over the Roman Empire, the Teutonic kingship grows to meet its task, it does not become strong enough ; in the struggles against disorder and chaos society knits itself together by the feudal system. . . 198-201 LECTUEE XIV Feudal and Semi-Feudal Polity § 1. The tendencies for the relation of lordship and service to prevail over that of citizen to citizen, and for the relation of the individual to land to determine his political position, coalesce into the fusion of personal service and land tenure characteristic of feudalism. But it is the fusion of land- holdership with governmental power that constitutes its prominent political character. .... 202-204 § 2. The result is a scale of ranks in relation to land. The allegi- ance of the vassal to his immediate superior not directly to the king, and the possibility of having feudal relations in two countries, were disruptive forces. At the bottom of the scale the serf had mostly no legal appeal against the justice of his lord. Though feudalism provided a temporary framework for national life, kingship, outside it, represented the undivided power of the state and the source of more equal justice. ...... 204-209 § 3. The Frankish monarchy was the home of feudalism proper, . 209-211 § 4. but its main tendencies are found elsewhere, as may be illus- trated by the case of England. .... 212-214 LECTUEE XV Medieval Theocracy § 1. Re-capitulation. In feudal society, King, Church, and Towns in a sense represented civilisation, but did not always hold together. ....... 215-217 § 2. Theocracy defined. In ancient historic Greece and Rome it did not exist. A separate organisation of the Church is favourable to it. . . . . . . 217-221 CONTENTS XIX 3. Its inheritance of the Jewish law kept the early Christian Church separate from the State ; an attitu4e only partially changed when Christianity became the established religion ^ of the Empire. . . . . . . 221-223 4. The seed of Theocracy thus sown is developed when, in the chaos following thfe fall of the Western Empire, the Church holds together and becomes the one intellectual influence, s Ecclesiastics take part in secular administration and later hold important positions in the feudal hierarchy. When Hildebrand by the celibacy of the clergy has secured their separation from the laity, both political facts and the state ' of thought and feeling tended to the realisation of his dream of a pope forming, instead of king or emperor, the coping-stone of the feudal organisation. . . . 223-227 5. The main movement to theocracy begun by Hildebrand cul- minates under Innocent III. and ends with Boniface VIII. 227-229 6. The quasi-legal arguments urged in support of theocratic claims are not the real grounds on which their force rests. . 229-231 LECTUKE XVI Medieval Cities — General Type 1. Medieval cities are both parts of the nation and partially independent communities. Their organisation and develop- ment is similar throughout Western Europe. They differ from the ancient city-state in the freedom and ultimate power and dignity of mechanic labour, and in the governing class of the nation remaining outside them. They acquire most power where the central government is weakest. . 232-237 2. But England with its strong central government exhibits equally the general type — ultimately a kind of federation of crafts. The town works itself free from the political system of the surrounding country ; the merchants take the lead ; then the crafts rise to equality ; as a last stage an oligarchy of master artisans develops within the crafts. . 237-241 3. Towns obtained independence at different times and in varying degrees in Spain, France, etc. ..... 241-243 LECTUKE XVII Medieval Cities — German 1. Germany having no old Roman civilisation is civilised entirely under early medieval conditions. The Church and the towns are instruments of this, and the towns are a colonising type. ...... 244-247 XX DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY § 2. In development, towns under bishops lead. The towns gradually acquire self-government under councils — at first a " natural oligarchy," but increasingly exclusive. The mercantile oligarchy when developed is confronted by a demos of artisans organised in "crafts." . . . 247-251 § 3. The medieval "crafts" must be directly or indirectly derived from the later Roman artisan corporations. . . 251-253 § 4. The long struggle of the crafts with the mercantile oligarchy is like the Roman struggle between patricians and plebeians. The cities with extensive foreign trade form the bulwark of oligarchy. We have in German as in Greek towns a movement from natural to more exclusive oligarchy through inequality of wealth and then to a more popular constitu- tion ; but the German towns do not fall under Tyrannis. . 253-256 § 6. Many cities remain "Free Imperial Cities" till the end of the eighteenth century, but the democratic movement practically ceases after the fifteenth, and the drift is towards narrowing oligarchy — partly owing to the contagion of monarchical ideas, partly to oligarchic tendencies within the crafts, as in England. .... 256-258 LECTUEE XVIII Medieval Cities — Italian : Lombardt § 1. The industrial character of the cities is less pure in Italy than elsewhere owing to their predominance over feudality. . 259-261 § 2. The peculiar history of Italy leading to its division into two parts separated by the Papal States, accounts for the diverse conditions of different cities and groups of cities. The cities of Southern Italy and Venice develop early — nominally under the Eastern Empire. . . . 261-264 § 3. Venice would probably in any case have developed early like the other maritime cities — Genoa and Pisa. The inland towns of Tuscany develop late, probably owing to its out- lying position. ...... 264-266 § 4. The Lombard cities are first organised to protect them- selves against Huns and Saracens. The industrial element grows, as in Gennany, under the shield of the Church, but gradually shakes itself free and in the twelfth century the towns are governed by "consuls." . . . 266-268 § 5. The independence of the towns is shown by their wars with each other and confirmed by their successful struggle with Frederick Barbarossa. . . . .268-270 § 6. In the meanwhile they struggle with the neighbouring feudal nobles, compel them to submit to their jurisdiction and partly reside in the towns. .... 270-273 § 7. The resulting disorderliness leads to the institution of "Podestas" and ultimately to Tyrannis. The full indus- trial development is thus cut short in the thirteenth century. 273-276 CONTENTS XXI LECTUEE XIX Medieval Cities — Comparison op Italian City-Communities WITH Ancient Greece 1. In North Italy, where the greater part of a continuous territory is divided among cities, these show striking resemblances to Greek city-states. . . . 277-280 2. But the resemblances are qualified by important dissimilarities ; the independence differs in degree ; the factions — Guelf and Ghibelin — in kind ; . . . . . 280-283 3. in Greece we have not the double antithesis between nobles and ^opoZam g'mssi and between the latter and artisans ; . 283-284 4. and the Tyrannis of Greece and Italy differ. . . 284-285 LECTUEE XX Medieval Cities — Florence § 1. The independence of Florence develops late — after the death of the Countess Matilda in 1015, and we soon find it under consuls. ....... 286-287 § 2. To give strength in the struggle with nobles the consuls are superseded — as in Lombardy — by a Podestk, with later a CapitaTU) del Popolo, each having special and general councils. ....... 287-290 § 3. The constitution is further complicated by the organisation of the Guelf party with a share in the government. . .290 § 4. And similarly of the greater Arti (crafts). . . . 290-293 § 5. The preponderance of the Arti is increased in 1282, and again in 1293, when the "ordinances of justice" are instituted against the nobles with a "gonfalonier of justice" to carry them out. ...... 293-295 § 6. The lot is partially introduced into the election to ofiices. . 295-298 § 7. Constitutional struggles lead to the lesser Arti obtaining a share in the government. ..... 298-300 § 8. But oligarchy is renewed by means of the Guelf organisa- tion and the persecution of real or pretended Ghibelins. Hence discontent leading to the revolution of the Ciompi — workers below the organised arti — the high-water mark of the democratic movement. Oligarchy regains power and ultimately the transition to practical monarchy under the Medici has popular support. .... 300-301 xxil DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY LECTUEE XXI Medieval Kepresentative Institutions PAGES § 1. The difference between ancient and modern ideas on taxation may be traced to the way modern polity grew out of feudal conditions. From the monarch's point of view Assemblies of Estates were a means of overcoming difficulties in raising money. ....... 302-303 § 2. The democratic element in the assemblies is due to the development of the towns. The impulse to the formation of assemblies is sometimes from above, sometimes from below — as in Germany, where we see a strong tendency to spontaneous association, which does not however lead to permanent constitutional government. . . . 303-307 § 3. In France the movement is from above, — in its antifeudal policy it is an advantage to the crown to have direct relations with the cities. The want of union between the estates, chiefly concerning taxation, prevented permanent results from efforts at popular control. And the effect is similar in Spain and Scandinavia. . . . 307-310 § 4. In England the effects of insularity, of strong central govern- ment, of nobility not descending to younger sons, produce greater union of classes and exceptional strength of parlia- mentary government. ..... 310-315 LECTUEE XXII Movement to Absolute Monarchy § 1. In the eighteenth century, absolute monarchy might well have been regarded as the final outcome of the long develop- ment of country states. The movements first to and then from it, are from one point of view two stages in one process towards the modern conception of political society. . 316-320 § 2. Modern history may be said to begin in the middle of the seventeenth century, when monarchy finally predominates over other elements in the state, and the coherence of the modern state is substituted for the imperfect order of medieval institutions. ..... 320-323 § 3. In the medieval state every one has rights, but there is no central power strong enough to secure them to him. The triumph of monarchy represents the first approximation to it ; hence patriotic sentiment supports the monarch against anarchical forces. ...... 324-326 § 4. The failure of the medieval assemblies is another aspect of the same thing ; the representatives of classes could not unite to represent the nation. But apart from this the rule of one seemed, both in fact and theory, the simplest mode of attaining unity. ..... 326-329 CONTENTS xxiil LECTUKE XXIII Movement to Absolute Monarchy {corUimoed) PAGBS 1. To influences on the side of monarchy we must add Theology and Roman Law ; though the former was mixed and vary- ing. The ideal of medieval theology was a monarchical organisation under one universal headship, but when this broke down conflicts with secular powers led ecclesiastical writers to lay stress on the doctrine that secular govern- ment rests on consent of the people. Both Catholic and Protestant influences vary with circumstances during the Reformation ; but its consequences, on the whole, favour monarchy, as is seen in Spain and France. . . 330-335 2. Roman law, framed in the Imperial period, is more steadily on the side of monarchy. ..... 335-336 3. There are qualifications to monarchical absoluteness in survivals of abortive medieval parliaments, and in privileges of nobles and lawyers. ...... 336-339 4. Also exceptions due to geographical and other causes. . 339-341 5. In the most important exception — England — Parliament finally triumphs in 1688. .... 341-344 LECTUEE XXIV Political Thought — Hobbes and Locke 1. Political ideas, ideas of government as it ought to be, are largely derived from experience of governments as they are and have been. They are also causes of political change ; and more markedly as civilisation advances. Thus political theories are partly fashioned as instruments for attaining immediate practical results : and this affects their develop- ment. ....... 345-349 2. The establishment, in fact, of political order on a monarchical basis has for its counterpart in thought the doctrines of Hobbes : — that absolute governmental power is necessary for orderly political society. He thinks it had better be monarchical, but this is not necessary to his theory. . 349-352 3. Hobbes assumes an original compact by which individuals in a *' state of nature " bind themselves to obey a government. This they do because the state of nature is miserable through anarchy. Only a compact binding all to unquestioning obedience to a sovereign with unlimited power can be effective. ...... 352-356 4. Locke's theory justifies the act which sealed the failm-e of monarchical absolutism in England. He held that by the original compact power is entrusted to government for certain ends : if the trust is violated the duty of obedience ceases. . . . . , . . . 356-359 XXIV DE VELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY § 5. He diverged from the traditional view in holding that no man has a right to consent to be a slave ; a legitimate govern- ment must be such as men living in natural freedom would reasonably combine to form. If government has recourse to illegal coercion and taxation unconsented to, it violates the ends for which government was instituted. . . 359-363 LECTURE XXV Political Thought : Locke to Montesquieu § 1. Locke's theory, like Hobbes', admits all forms of government. But as Hobbes prefers monarchy, so Locke prefers a govern- ment in which the legislative power is separated from the executive. . . . . . .364-367 § 2. The political thought of the eighteenth century has its focus in France. English thought is languid in the first half of the century ; there is some disappointment at the results of the Glorious Revolution, till Montesquieu sets the English Constitution on a pedestal for the admiration of Europe. . 367-371 § 3. Montesquieu and Rousseau prepared the way for the French Revolution : Montesquieu through the admiration he inspired for the ancient republics as examples of a form of govern- ment demanding a high strain of political virtue. . .371-376 § 4. Also through his admiration for the English constitution as maintaining political liberty — especially by separation of powers legislative, executive and judicial, preventing tyrannic preponderance of any. ..... 375-377 LECTUEE XXVI Political Thought : The Influence op Rousseau § 1. To turn admiration of the Law of Nature as an ideal into a practical ardour for its realisation and to extend it from civil to constitutional relations was in France the work of Rousseau. ...... 378-380 § 2. The manner in which absolute monarchy had grown out of feudalism, and the resulting abuses and inequalities, pre- pared the way for his doctrine. .... 380-384 § 3. He preached nature in contrast with the artificiality and frivolity of society, and he preached the inalienable sovereignty of the people ; but he did not dream of restoring the state of nature in reconstructing society in accordance with the law of nature. . . . 384-390 CONTENTS XXV Of Rousseau's three main points — that (1) men are by nature free and equal, (2) the rights of government depend on a compact, (3) which must be one in which each gives up his will to the will of the whole — (1) belongs to the law of nature of Roman jurists ; (2), connected with this, was generally accepted, (3) is Rousseau's, arrived at by com- bining the lines of thought of Hobbes and Locke. . . 390-392 Rousseau's view is contrasted with that of the Physiocrates, who desired not to reconstruct government but to limit its functions. ...... 392-394 LECTUEE XXVII Development of English Polity since 1688 1. Though French thought had an important share in bringing about the change to constitutional monarchy — or republic, which is not essentially different — in West European polity, the influence of the English constitution is more indisputable. ...... 395-397 2. But its imitators have not always known how different it has been at different stages. ..... 397-402 3. Cabinet government, in which the prime minister is the leader of the party that has the majority in the House of Commons — existed only in germ in the eighteenth century, when the established view was that the ministers were chosen by the monarch. ....... 402-407 4. After the Reform Bill his power of appointing the minister is found to have gone. The eighteenth-century constitution is very like the German constitution. . . . 407-410 LECTURE XXVIII Constitution-making of the Nineteenth Century 1. In Montesquieu's ideal — a representative assembly controlling legislation and taxation and exercising a check on the execu- tive by the necessity of their obtaining supplies, with the reign of law secured by the independence of the judicature and the strict limitation of the power to imprison before trial — we have, summarily stated, the last result of political development in Western Europe ; the type varying between the new English and the German or old English. . . 411-415 2. The English constitution as conceived by Montesquieu, which the founders of the American constitution had before them, differs in important respects from the new English — cabinet government — which has in most cases been adopted in West European states. ...... 415-419 XXVI DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY § 3. In saying the English type has been adopted, minor diflferences are ignored — e.g. in the construction of the second chamber and in the extent of the franchise. . . . 420-422 § 4. But the English judicial system has been largely imitated — notwithstanding differences as to the relation of the execu- tive to the ordinary tribunals. .... 422-425 LECTUKE XXIX Modern Federalism § 1. Recapitulation. Federality of Germany, Austria and Hungary, Sweden and Norway. ..... 426-428 § 2. The development of Swiss polity. .... 428-430 § 3. This was uniquely continuous among other less enduring confederations. ...... 430-432 § 4. A federal state — a whole made up of parts politically approximately equal, with a constitutional division of functions between the governments of the whole and of the parts — ordinarily requires an "extraordinary legisla- ture " for any alteration of the constitution. Hence, though it breaks up more easily than a unitary state, its constitu- tion tends to be unusually stable — as is illustrated by the United States. . . . . . .432-436 § 5. The most important cause of federalism is need of strength in external relations. Commercial considerations are another cause. ....... 436-437 § 6. It may also arise by the establishment of secured local liberties in states previously unitary. .... 437-438 § 7. Partly from this democratic tendency, partly fi'om the tend- ency to "integration" seen throughout history, the extension of federalism seems the most probable of the political prophecies relating to the form of government. . 439 DEVELOPMENT OF EUEOPEAN POLITY LECTUKE I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT § 1. I PURPOSE, in the Lectures that follow, to treat sum- marily an important part of the history of Political Societies, from the point of view of Inductive Political Science, as I conceive it. The full meaning of the term "Political Society " will be unfolded as we proceed : provisionally I mean by it a group of human beings united among them- selves, and separated from other human beings, by the fact that they habitually obey the same government, and thus form a corporate whole, whose life may be distinguished from that of the individuals composing it. Such a society, when it has reached a certain stage of civilisation, is also called a " State," and I shall use this as an alternative term. I regard Government as the essential characteristic of States or Political Societies as such ; and it is as possessing Govern- ment that I shall be concerned with these bodies from first to last. With other characteristics of social man, as we find him in different ages and countries, his languages, his customs, his religions, his science and art, even his economic condition, I shall only be concerned indirectly ; i.e. so far as these other characteristics have an important connection in the way of cause and effect, with what I shall call, for brevity, his "poKty" — meaning by "polity" the structure of the government under which he lives, and its relations to the governed. In saying that I treat of Political Societies from the B 2 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. point of view of " Political Science/' I mean, on the one hand, that I am concerned primarily with polities as they are and have been, and not with polity as it ought to be ; and, on the other hand, that I study them primarily with the view of ascertaining (1) the classes to which they belong, or the general t}^es which they exemplify, and (2) the causes which have led to the prevalence of this or that general type in different regions at different times. I thus distinguish the point of view of Political Science on the one hand from that of the wider and more comprehensive subject which we call Political Philosophy, and on the other hand from that of ordinary political history. On the one hand. Political Science (so treated) does not — as Political Philosophy does — concern itself directly with the right or best form of government, or the form which we should aim at introducing at the particular stage which we have reached in the development of society. We may, indeed, hope to derive from Political Science results of practical utility — I shall presently consider in what way and to what extent — but still its primary business is not political construction, but generalisation from political facts, whether furnished by history or by contemporary observation. So far as our study deals with types of polity, they are types obtained by mere abstraction from the world of reality, not ideal types which it sets before us as models to be aimed at. On the other hand, the distinction between Political Science and ordinary political history lies in the generality of the object of science. What as students of Political Science we are primarily concerned to ascertain, is not the structure or functions of government in any particular historical community, --but the distinctive characteristics of different forms of government in respect of their structure or their functions ; not the particular process of political change in (e.^.) Athens or England, but the general laws or tend- encies of change exemplified by such particular processes. Hence it often happens that the same political facts are studied in very different relations by the historian and by the student of Political Science respectively. The historian I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 3 aims primarily at presenting facts in their chronological v/ order ; but in comparing the political development of \ different parts of the human race, we find — throughout the past as well as at the present time — that they are contem- poraneously at very different stages of development, and may consequently be approximately in the same stage at very wide intervals of time. Political Science, accordingly, aims at bringing together for comparison societies similar in their political characteristics, however widely separated in time. Thus, when, at the outset of our study, we endeavour to form a general conception of the " primitive Indo- Germanic polity," ^ we have to compare what Tacitus tells us of the Germans of his time, not with the contem- poraneous political organisation of Eome, but with the very earliest form of Eoman polity that antiquarian study enables us to discern. § 2. Political Science, then, aims like other sciences at ascertaining relations of resemblance among the objects that it studies ; it seeks to arrange them in classes, or to exhibit them as examples of types. But though classification is an important part of its task, it is not the whole of it ; nor is it, I may say, the most interesting part. What specially interests us in comparing different forms of polity is to ascertain their causes and effects, and especially the order of development according to which one form tends to succeed another. This is, no doubt, a difficult under- taking ; and I could not attempt to perform it, even in a summary and tentative way, in regard to the whole range of political societies historically known to us. But in fact I shall confine myself in the main to a limited portion of the subject, which I select as having a special interest for my readers, both on scientific and on political grounds. What I shall mainly attempt is to exhibit with their dis- tinctive characteristics, to classify according to their most important resemblances, and to link together by the con- ception of continuous development, the principal forms of political society which the history of European civilisation ^ The phrase is Freeman's. 4 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. manifests ; regarding them as stages in the historic process through which political society has passed, and of which the modern state, as we know it, is the outcome. European History, thus treated, acquires what may be called a morphological unity. This is not, of course, the only point of view from which the unity of history might be regarded. The development of civilised society is a very complex fact, which has many elements or aspects ; and there are other elements — e.g. the development of thought or knowledge-^which might fairly claim to be taken as the central and primary fact, round which other developments are to be grouped. Still, the development of organised political society does afford us a central element or strand of social change, in tracing which we are naturally led to conceive as a continuous whole the processes that we are accustomed to separate as " ancient," " medieval," and "modern" history. Now in order to conceive the unity of this process vividly and fully, it is important to link the past with the present — to keep before our minds that " history is past politics, politics present history." And when we thus connect the past with the present, our thoughts are inevitably carried through the present to the future, — especially to the future of the group or system of states of which our own is a member, and which is now manifestly dominant over the greater part of the globe. And thus though, as I have said, the aim of Political Science is not directly practical, we are naturally led to study the past development of political society with more than purely speculative curiosity; we are concerned to ascertain the kind and amount of guid- ance, in reference to the practical problems of our own age, which we may hope to obtain from this study. As I have elsewhere explained,^ I do not think that the historical method is the one to be primarily used in attempting to find reasoned solutions of the problems of practical politics. In the first place. History cannot, I conceive, determine the ultimate end and standard of good and bad, right and ^ Elements of Politics, chap. i. I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 5 wrong, in political institutions ; whether we take this to be general happiness, or as others hold, human well-being interpreted somehow so as to distinguish it from happiness. This ultimate end we cannot get from history ; we bring it with us to history when we judge of the goodness or bad- ness of the past laws and political institutions which history shows us. Secondly, supposing that we are agreed as to the ultimate end at which a statesman should aim, historical inquiry appears to me only useful in a limited and secondary way in determining our choice of means for the attainment of the end; in consequence of the continual process of change and development through which political societies move, which renders the experience of the past — unless it be a comparatively recent past — largely inapplicable to the present needs of the most advanced communities. But, though the history of the past cannot, in my view, be the primary source of our data for deciding the political questions of our own age and country, it is still very important that we should obtain from it such guidance as it can furnish. Firstly, so far as from the study of what has been we can ascertain the laws of political evolution, and thus forecast — even dimly — what is to be, though such forecast cannot determine positively our political ideal, it may determine it negatively by indicating what is not to be aimed at as out of our reach ; we may obtain from it some notion of the limits within which any practicable ideal is confined, the kind of society and circumstances for which the political institutions of the future will have to be adapted. We may also learn, if not with certainty still with consider- able probability, which of the elements and characteristics of our own political society are likely to increase and become more important as the years go on, and which are likely to decrease and become less important. How far any such forecast is scientifically attainable, I do not yet determine ; but it must always be the aim and aspiration of Political Science to attain it as far as possible. Secondly, history may render us a different kind of service in dealing with other societies than our own — whether 6 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. foreign nations or dependencies. For the history of political institutions shows us a variety of forms of political and social organisation, the study of which may enable us to under- stand better the nature and probable behaviour of organisms of the same kind existing contemporaneously ; since human societies, as I have already observed, are co-existing in all different stages of development, and we have actually to deal with communities for whose present political and social condition instructive analogies are to be found in the past condition of societies better known to us. Thus competent judges hold that it might have prevented serious mistakes in our government of India, if the governing statesmen had had before their minds the historical development of land-tenure, as we now conceive it to have taken place in European countries. In this way history, in the ordinary sense, — the study of the past, — furnishes one element of what may be called " Comparative Politics," the other element being supplied by contemporary observation. The two mutually assist and supplement each other, though the task of combining the different sets of data is often difficult. § 3. This leads us to the question that has the greatest practical interest — viz. how far we can find in the past history of polity instructive analogies for our own political condition ? Now, primd facie, if we West Europeans are right in regarding ourselves as in the van of progress, we can only find close analogies of this kind in the recent history of states that form with us a group moving together; e.g. the United States and our own colonies may teach us valuable lessons of experience as to the working of that representative democracy which appears to be our destiny, but which is more completely established there than here. But it is not only in recent history that such analogies have been sought during the long and active political discussion that has taken place, since aspirations after republican liberty and virtue found stirring expression in Europe in the middle of the eighteenth century. From the time of Montesquieu I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 7 and Kousseau, down to the time of Sir Henry Maine, a leading place has been given in such discussions to the consideration of democracy as known to us from Greek and Eoman history. It has been held that a careful study of this previous experi- ence is likely to throw important light on the process of change now going on in the type of political society to which our own State belongs — what we may call the normal State of Western Europe and America. It is commonly agreed that the West European states are at present moving toward democracy; and in considering whether this movement is good or bad, and how we ought to meet the dangers and difficulties involved in it, analogical arguments are con- tinually based on what is known to us from history as to the behaviour of the Demos of Greek city-states, and of Eoman popular assemblies in the latest phase of the Eepublic. I hold that such analogies have to be used with great caution, owing to the important differences between Grseco-Eoman political conditions and those of modern Europe : especially (1) the difference between the direct democracy of a small state where all can meet in one assembly, and the representative democracy of the larger states which are the normal kind in our modern world : (2) the difference introduced by slavery, which, in the most democratic of ancient communities, excluded absolutely from political rights a large portion of the manual labour class : (3) the separa- tion of Church and State, which our modern societies inherit from medieval Europe : and (4) the changed conditions and position of industry in the modern State. Still, making all allowances for these differences, I think that it is interesting and instructive to compare the successive stages in the more rapid development of the city-states of ancient Greece and Italy with the successive stages in the slower development of the " country-state " or " nation-state " of modern Europe.^ For — whatever be the degree of resemblance between the developments — at any rate the careful and systematic per- formance of this comparison gives the right point of view ^ The comparison was suggested many years ago by the German historian Gervinus in his Introduction to the History of the Nine.teenth Century. 8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. for estimating the value of the lessons that will in any case continue to be drawn from ancient history for modern politicians. It need hardly be added that the earlier process is con- nected with the later not merely in the way of resemblance and analogy. The "modern state" — the last result of political civilisation — is a type exemplified almost exclusively by the states of Western Europe, and the colonies that have sprung from them ; and the states of Western Europe are either (1) t*)^ ^ portions of the Roman Empire, broken up by the irruption of the Germans, and reconstituted under the blended in- fluences of Eoman civilisation and the primitive political habits of the German tribes ; or (2) nations originally akin to these conquering tribes, and subsequently drawn within the influences of their political and social development. France, Spain, Italy, are examples of the former ; Germany and Scandinavia of the latter class ; England lies historically between the two, but in tracing the conditions of political development must be classed with the latter.^ Again, the political thought of this whole group of states has been to an important extent influenced by the study of Greek history and the political conceptions and doctrines of Greek thinkers derived from reflection on the phenomena of the Greek city-states. I propose accordingly to confine my attention mainly to the political institutions of the ancient Greeks and Romans, and of Western Europe and its colonies in post-Roman times. And this limitation is less narrow than it seems, if the special aim of Political Science, as above explained, be kept in view. Of course, in the widest sense of the term, political institutions are not peculiar to any one part of the globe, or any one of the different races of men. Though there are societies — groups of gregarious men — in which the " differentiation " into governors and governed is barely per- ^ Although England was long a province of the Roman Empire, which Germany — in the main — was not, still, for reasons that will hereafter appear, the political development of Germany was more influenced by ideas derived from Rome than that of England. I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 9 ceptible, such societies constitute a very insignificant portion of humanity : it is almost universally true that a man is a " political animal " in the sense of being either ruler or ruled, either obeying or constituting a government of some kind. But there is a sense in which higher political develop- ment has originated almost exclusively in, and is still mainly confined to certain portions of the white, or — as some still call it — Caucasian race. They alone have developed, along with the development of their civilisation,^ governing organs of which the members are accustomed " to rule and obey alternately"^ — whether (1) the supreme ruler is merely elected by the citizens for a limited time, and then gives up power and may be formally called to account for his exercise of it, or (2) the supreme rule is in whole or in part exercised collectively by a body of citizens meeting from time to time. In the history of political institutions these forms interest us most, not only as citizens of a modern West- European State, but as students of Political Science : just as the highest forms of life have a special interest for the bio- logist. I shall accordingly confine my attention mainly to the nations who have shown a power of developing them. And among them the most important and conspicuous of those whose history is known to us are certainly the Greeks, Eomans, and West- Europeans. They stand pre-eminent among the civilised portions of humanity as having de- veloped, up to the highest point that their civilisation has yet reached, not only political mstitutions, but coTistitutions and constitutional ideas and theories. We cannot indeed confine our attention to constitutional governments : since we shall continually have presented to us, from almost the beginning to almost the end of the process that we shall be studying, the form of government which is commonly distinguished as " absolute " monarchy. ^ This qualification is required, because we find the rudiments of such an organ, in the form of the "assembly of the nation in arms," in that primitive polity which is not confined to any one race. 2 d.px'^i-v Koi dpx^adai. lo DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Indeed it is noteworthy, that if we take a summary survey of the actual experience of civilised societies in matters of government — extending it as far as we can through time and space — the one which in extent of human beings ruled by it surpasses all the rest is so-called Absolute Monarchy. By the word Absolute it is not, of course, meant that the power of the ruler over the ruled is practi- cally unlimited — that he can deal with his subjects as if they were a troop of cattle. Such a ruler has always been more or less controlled by his fear of the disapprobation of his subjects and his desire of their esteem ; by his fear of the ultima ratio of revolution, which has never been unknown in any political society ; by the influence of religion on his own mind, and his knowledge of its influence on the minds of others. He has been restrained in earlier stages of civilisation by the general recognition which he shares of law or custom as something fixed and unalterable, having a source higher than ordinary human volition ; in later stages by the complexity of the system of law and the machinery of administration in a civilised state, rendering it increasingly difficult for the monarch to effect any change that he desires without causing other grave consequences that he does not desire. What is meant by calling him " absolute " is that there is no established constitutional authority — no human authority that his subjects habitually obey as much as they obey him — which can legitimately resist him or call him to account. It is not difficult to understand why this kind of monarchy should be common. If any government — however complex its structure — were in an ideally good condition, the resolutions and actions of its various parts and organs would be as harmonious and consistent as if they emanated from one rational wOl : and obviously, the simplest method of producing unity and order in the effects of government is by giving the ultimate control in all matters to the will of one man. The effectiveness of such a government, when power is concentrated in the hands of an able man, is shown by many examples of even I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT ii irregular despotism both in ancient and in modern times. No doubt in the great monarchies founded by conquest, the habit of obedience in the conquered is not supported by a sense of the advantages of government, but by a fear of the consequences of resisting. But in the conquering nation the habit of obedience to a single man's will is doubtless strengthened by the perception of its advantage in securing vigour and consistency of action in struggles with other nations. Doubtless many warriors besides the warrior in the Iliad have said in primitive ages, " Many ruling is not good, let there be one ruler." As I have just hinted, we must not suppose that where this form of government has been permanently established the governed have submitted with uniform patience to the evils resulting from this con- centration of power in the hands of an unfit irresponsible individual ; but where they have successfully rebelled against it they have not endeavoured to modify the form of govern- ment : they have merely got rid of one man and put another in his place. In the general history, then, of political institutions it is a peculiar characteristic of certain portions of the white race or races of men, that they have maintained, in advanced stages of civilisation, a different method — at once more artificial and more orderly — of avoiding the evils of arbitrary rule ; while at the same time endeavouring to maintain the unity of resolution and action which is necessary for the efhcient performance of governmental functions. This is what we call the con- stitutional method. Considering the greater complexity which this method, when fully developed, involves, in the current conception of government and the habit of political obedience, we should expect to find its complete development limited to societies which have made some progress in civilisation ; but history further shows that the progress of civilisation, at any rate in its earlier stages, has no general tendency to bring it into use. It has in fact been confined, as I have said, to the white race — until very recently — and mainly. 12 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. though not entirely/ to the Indo- Germanic family of nations : and even within these limits it seems to have required special external conditions for its development. § 4. Some explanation is required of these notions of "race'* and " family of nations." Firstly, in speaking of the " white race," I do not mean to imply that there are four or five original stocks of human beings, distinguishable by colour and other marks, as "white," "brown," "yellow," and "black" races. In the present state of anthropology there is no ground for assuming any such original differences of stocks ; and the physical differences actually existing are more numer- ous and complicated, and shade off into each other more gradually, than the popular nomenclature suggests. And since all varieties of human beings are zoologically of one species — inter-marriage between any two generally producing fertile offspring — the physical differences of race historically presented may be to an indefinite extent referable to crossing of breeds. A special instance of this is perhaps presented by the marked differences we find between the fair whites, prevalent in Northern Europe, and the dark whites prevalent in Southern Europe and parts of Asia ; — as the latter are considered by leading anthropologists to be prob- ably due to a crossing of the fair whites with a darker race. It is to be observed that this distinction cuts across that which Comparative Philology would lead us to draw between Aryan or Indo -Germanic and Semitic nations; and this illustrates another uncertainty in which the application of the notion of " race " is involved, from the difficulty of separating, among the mental characteristics that distinguish average members of different societies, what comes from physical heredity and what from social influence. In con- sequence of this affinities of language are a very imperfect guide to affinities of race. Hence, in speaking of the " Indo - Germanic family of nations," I must not be under- stood to imply that the nations thus grouped together are all physically derived from one stock ; but only that they are ^ The constitution of Semitic Carthage appears to have borne a high repu- tation in Greece in the time of Aristotle, and later. I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 13 connected with one ancient social group by a continuous social life, evidenced by continuity of language and at least partly due to continuity of race. At the same time there are certain broad distinctions of physical race which have remained nearly permanent during the range of history. As Mr. Tylor ^ says, on the wall-paint- ings at Thebes we can distinguish red-brown Egyptians, Ethio- pians like those of the present day, captives from Palestine with the well-known Semitic profile, thick-lipped negroes, and fair-skinned Libyans. And these examples may remind us that civilisation is not a monopoly of the white race, in the widest sense of that term. " At the dawn of history, the leaders of culture were the brown Egyptians, and the Baby- lonians," whose language is not connected with any known language of white nations ; while the yellow Mongoloid Chinese have been "for four thousand years or more a civilised and literary nation." The civilisation that spread round the Mediterranean was not originated by the dark whites — Phoenicians, Greeks, Eomans — but only carried on by them. Still we may perhaps say that higher political civil- isation, the capacity for developing constitutional government in a civilised state, belongs primarily to the white race ; and mainly to branches of the white race which speak an Indo- Germanic language, and therefore show a partial continuity of descent from one single original group. The consideration of race leads us naturally to the consideration of climate and external conditions : since the view that the diversity of the races of men results from a number of separate origins is now antiquated ; this diversity is now generally held to be due to the gradual summation of the effects, direct or indirect, of the action of external con- ditions on the primitive human organism. It is interesting therefore to consider briefly how far climate and external conditions have operated to render certain portions of the white race, or its Indo-Germanic branch, more adapted for higher political development than others. It would certainly seem that temperate climate is favourable to this develop- ■^ Anthropology, chap. i. 14 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. ment ; since in arctic regions the special difficulties of the struggle for existence, and the consequent sparseness of the population, impede the development of civilisation ; while it is an old remark that the inhabitants of hot climates tend to be at once passionate and (except under pressure of physical need) indolent. Thus the sober intelligence, self- control, and sustained energy required for constitutional government has a better chance of being developed in temperate climes ; though, having been developed there, this kind of polity may spread to other regions in which it would not have originated, — like other inventions for the improve- ment of man's estate, originally produced under specially favouring conditions. But climate is not the only external condition that is important in tracing the history of polity. Indeed through- out this history we continually meet striking instances in which the exceptional political development of parts of the human race is clearly due to the exceptional nature or relations of the land which they inhabit. Thus in medieval and modern history I need only mention the names of Venice, Switzerland, Holland, England, to recall undoubted examples of this. A no less important case is Greece. Even a study of Greek history alone suggests strongly that the peculiar configuration of Greece — with mountains that separate tribes and favour independence, and water-ways favouring trade and communication — is specially adapted for the growth of the earlier forms of civilised constitutional govern- ment : and this suggestion is supported by the fact that in other cases, where nature, by large rivers running through fertile plains, has favoured conveyance and communication without favouring independence, and has thus facilitated a transition from barbarism to civilisation, — the civilisation has been developed on a purely monarchical basis. Indeed the very predominance of simple monarchy that we have already noticed in the greater part of the history of civilisa- tion, seems to justify us in attributing the peculiar develop- ment of Greece partly to its special physical conditions. In the great States of Egypt, Babylonia, Assyria, Persia, I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 15 whose history is antecedent to, or contemporaneous with, that of Greece, monarchy is absolute, in the sense above explained : from the time that we have any knowledge of them, the mass of the people have "nothing to do with the government of their country except to obey it," and the subordinate governors have no constitutional right to oppose the will of the monarch. Whenever such opposition takes place, it means revolt and partial disorder. We have, however, now to observe that so far as the evidence of history goes, this is not the primitive political condition : and I shall hereafter try to show that we have no valid reason for regarding it as the condition that naturally arises first when the state develops out of the family. At any rate the earliest polity known to us in the history of the peoples with whom we are to be mainly concerned, appears to be — commonly if not universally — one not merely of greater equality of conditions, and greater individual independence, but also of greater collective control on the part of the fighting -men of the primitive tribe. § 5. It is accordingly with the form of polity which Mr. Freeman calls the "primitive Aryan or Indo- Germanic polity," ^ that I shall commence my sketch of the develop- ment of political institutions in Europe. It is not to be regarded as in any way peculiar to the Aryan or Indo- Germanic race : still I shall only examine it in the forms in which we find it at the outset of the historically known development of the branches of the Indo-Germanic race with which we are specially concerned — Greeks, Eomans, and Germans. I shall trace the resemblance amid differences which we find in comparing the earliest known political institutions of the Germans, with the earliest known political institutions of Greece and Eome. Then, taking my stand on these beginnings of the history of the peoples that most interest us, I shall look backward and endeavour to trace briefly what can be dimly and conjecturally discerned of their 1 I shall try to show later that the word "primitive " is liable to be mis- leading. i6 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. political development in still earlier times, combining anti- quarian speculation with inferences from what we know of these earlier stages of development as exhibited by other portions of society. In this way we shall get as near as — in my opinion — a sober-minded inquirer ought to go to the consideration of the old question of the origin of political society. Then, turning our faces towards the down-flowing stream of time, we shall follow the comparatively rapid evolution of the different forms of government in the city-state which is the leading type of a civilised political community in the most brilliant period of ancient Greece — in contrast to the country-state which is the leading type in modern European history. I shall trace, as far as our imperfect knowledge allows, the movement from the primitive polity — in which we can distinguish a certain division of powers in varying proportions among three elements, a king, a council of sub- ordinate chiefs, and the whole body of free fighting men — to an oligarchical form of government; and shall show briefly how this oligarchy tends to assume various forms in different states, and to pass through various phases. I shall then pass to examine the Tyrannis or unconstitutional despotism which, in the seventh and sixth centuries B.C., tends to prevail for a time in many of the leading states of Greece — partly in consequence of popular movements against the established oligarchy — and the prevalence of which is a special and important feature in the evolution of the city- state, in ancient Greece and medieval Italy alike. I shall then pass to the period best known to us : in which a movement towards fully developed democracy is, on the whole, unmistakable; though this form of government is often temporarily overcome by oligarchy, and towards the close of the period — as the old citizen militia give place to mercenary armies — is increasingly liable to lapse again into unconstitutional despotism. With the aid of Aristotle I shall briefly analyse the general causes that tended to bring into being and preserve one or other of these different forms of government in the Greek city-state : and shall note I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 17 how rare in Aristotle's own view is even an approximation to his ideal government by those best qualified to govern — aristocracy in the true sense ; and how difficult it was even to maintain that moderate constitutional democracy which he recommended as the best practical form of government for the Greek city-states of the latter half of the fourth century B.C. Then I shall note the failure of the Greek towns, in the most brilliant period of their history, to realise a stable federal union ; and shall finally call attention to the remark- able degree of success achieved by federation even under the unfavourable conditions of Macedonian predominance. Then, turning to Eome, I shall note the early character- istics and changes of Eoman political institutions in the light thrown on them by Greek analogies ; and shall analyse the nature and causes of the strangely but successfully com- pacted constitution that emerged from the long conflicts of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. I shall try to explain how a popular assembly constitutionally supreme, and tending in each of its two later forms — as assembly in tribes and assembly in hundreds — to be continually more democratically organ- ised, yet leaves contentedly the practical control of affairs in the hands of an aristocratic senate, while Eome is conquering first Italy and then the world round the Mediterranean. I shall further point out how, while the process of conquest went on, a continual extension of Eoman citizenship, by an elaborate process of expansion and absorption combined, swelled the great city-state into what Aristotle would have regarded as a monstrous overgrowth ; until, under the shock of the war with the Italian allies at the beginning of the first century B.C., it became finally transformed, by the ab- sorption of the Italians en masse, into a country-state mis- represented by a metropolitan mob, and quite inadequately organised for its task of imperial rule. I shall then explain briefly the nature of the transition — painful and sanguinary, but rendered inevitable by expansion and conquest — from repubHc to monarchy, at first partly hidden under republican forms and working through republican institutions ; until the distinction between Eoman citizen and Eoman subject c i8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. has vanished under Caracalla, and, in the hands of Diocletian, the Empire stands forth an unveiled and untempered despotism. Then, surveying from this point the whole antecedent history of Greco -Italian civilisation, I shall examine the development of the general notion of governmental functions — and especially of the relation of Law to Government — both as conceived by ancient thinkers, and as realised in the actual facts of Greco-Eoman polity. Then, gliding across the collapse of the Western Empire, I shall note the changes undergone by the political structure of the old Teutonic community, in its efforts to meet the severe demands made on it by the complex and disorderly conditions of the new semi -barbaric kingdoms formed in the fifth century A.D. I shall show how Teutonic, Imperial, and Christian institutions combined and mingled ; until, in the part of Western Europe where disorder seemed almost tending to dissolution, society gradually reconstructed itself on the scaffolding of partial order which we call the feudal system. I shall show how the Church, strong in its intellectual pre- dominance, and gaining an intenser corporate life from its successful struggle with disintegrating forces within and without, made its great attempt to bring Western Europe under ecclesiastical domination ; and I shall point out how the theocratic type of government — of which Aristotle knows nothing — is thus manifested, for the first time in the historically known part of the process of develop- ment that we are studying. I shall further show how, in the secular sphere, the political importance of the dis- tinction between " city " and " country " grows within the medieval nation as it advances in civilisation; and I shall compare with the city-state of old Greece, based on slavery, the industrial town community of the Middle Ages which reached practical independence in Germany and Italy ; in which mechanic labour rose first to freedom and then to dignity and power. Then I shall show how the growth of the modern nation into completer unity from the imperfect cohesion of the I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 19 feudal system, while it added power and prestige to mon- archy as the source and bond of national unity and order, also produced those assemblies of estates which for a time seem destined to develop into stable organs of constitu- tional government; then we shall have to observe how almost everywhere this fair promise was blighted — chiefly through the insuperable disunion of the different " estates " represented in these assemblies ; until, over the greater part of Western Europe, pure monarchy comes to be established and accepted as the form of government best adapted to an orderly and civilised country-state. We shall also note the exceptional conditions which caused federal and republican institutions to come into being and flourish in the small but important communities of Holland and Switzerland. I purpose at this point to pass, in a brief and summary way, from the region of political fact to that of political thought, and trace down from the Eoman jurists the move- ment of ideas which led toward the close of the eighteenth century to the passionate demand for universal political liberty and equality ; and which — in spite of the reaction which followed the first attempt to realise this demand in France — is yet one essential factor of the great process of change, belonging mainly to the nineteenth century, which has established the modern constitutional state throughout Western Europe. And along with this I shall ask you to contemplate the other essential factor of this great change, — the example of prosperous continuity of constitutional development which England alone among the greater West- European states has been privileged to exhibit. I shall also examine the origin, in the eighteenth century, of the individual- istic theory of the functions of government ; which, in com- bination with an analysis of the natural processes of production, distribution, and exchange of wealth, has formed the characteristically modern body of doctrine commonly known as Political Economy. Then, turning to the Western Continent, I shall briefly characterise the type of polity — varying importantly from the European type — which colonial independence has r 20 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. brought into existence there ; and shall examine the nature and working of the Federal system by which the great English colony in North America has maintained republican order for a century of independent life over a territory larger than Western Europe. Finally, surveying the whole history of European civilisation, I shall consider what forecast may be reasonably made as to its probable future development. It may perhaps be thought that this is a great deal of history to pack into so small a space. But it must be re- membered that we shall not be concerned with the particulars of history as such, but only with the general facts that these exemplify. I do not merely mean that we are not con- cerned with the personal and dramatic element of history — the careers of statesmen and generals, royal marriages and battles — but that for the most part we are not primarily concerned with the political development of any particular community, except as illustrating general causes and tend- encies. What we are concerned with is the general type of political society exemplified by a number of particular societies at a certain stage of development, the chief characteristics of the form and structure of this type, the changes that take place in it, and their causes. § 6. At this point it may be well to consider a disturb- ing cause which it is important to take into account in making any such generalisations as to development, namely, imitation. !For example, in modern Europe we cannot say that modern Parliamentary government, in the form of con- stitutional monarchy, is an independent result of similar tendencies of development in Italy, Belgium, Spain, and the Scandinavian kingdoms, where it is now established; it is obvious to the most superficial student of history that the similarity now existing among the forms of government in these different countries is largely due to imitation, direct or indirect, of England ; and the present English form of government is itself the result of a continuous development of Parliamentary institutions from medieval to modern times which is nearly if not quite unique in European I INTRO D UCTOR V SUR VE Y OF THE SUBJE CT 2 1 history. When with this in our mind we study more ancient periods of history, we cannot but feel that a large allov/ance must be made for direct imitation in considering the probable causes of the prevalence of a particular type of polity at a particular stage of development among states in active mutual communication, as (e.^.) Greek city-states mostly were.^ We must allow a large place for such imitation, even when we have no direct proof of it. At the same time the effect of imitation does not deprive the generalisations, which we obtain by comparing the political institutions of different states, of all substantial value. For from the very fact that a certain form of government spreads by imitation, we may infer that there was a strong tendency in the states adopting it towards a governmental form of this kind : that similar needs or desires of change had come to be predominantly felt, owing to certain general causes, in these different countries, even though the pre- cise form adopted may be due to its having been previ- ously realised in the single state that gives the model for imitation. Thus it is reasonable to suppose that the West European states generally would have moved in the direc- tion of popular government in the nineteenth century, even if the history of England had not had the unique gradual development of representative institutions which has actually distinguished it ; and it is a probable supposition that they would have had a legislature constructed, in whole or in part, on the representative principle, considering the obvious material difficulties of arranging government directly by the people at large in states of the size of France or Spain ; considering also that all the West -European countries except Italy had had — from causes which we shall hereafter investigate — medieval representative assemblies of estates more or less similar to the English Parliament in the Middle Ages. But it would be rash to affirm that had there been no British constitution to imitate, the West 1 Freeman has noticed this disturbing eflFect of imitation in his Comparaiive Politics. 22 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. European states generally would have had two-chambered legislatures. For example, in such a country as France, if the constitution -makers had been influenced by modern ideas, they might easily have thought that a sufficient com- plexity was introduced into the supreme government, by the due separation and balance of legislative executive and judicial powers, without complicating matters further by a two-chambered legislature. Or again, in countries where there had been no such sweeping away of old institutions as occurred in France, there might have been a revival of the medieval division of estates, leading to a threefold or even fourfold division of parliament : as in fact occurred in Sweden where the four estates — nobles, clergy, burghers, and peasants — deliberated for most purposes separately from A.D. 1810 to 1866. Nor again, apart from the influence of the English model, is there any reason to suppose that we should have found, as we do find in several — though not in all — West- European states, the peculiar form of government which Bagehot has called Cabinet government, ix. government in which the supreme executive functions are entrusted to what is really a committee of the legislature, practically dismissable at any time by a majority of the representative assembly, if supported by a majority of the electorate. I may illustrate this view — that imitation, in the de- velopment of political institutions, may be taken to imply a tendency, apart from imitation, to produce something like the type imitated, or at least conditions favourable to its maintenance — by comparing the two leading cases of city- states in Greek history, which afford, one a positive, one a negative example. We all know that in the best known and most brilliant century and a half of Greek history — from the repulse of Persia 480 B.C. to the submission to Macedonia 326 B.C. — Athens and Sparta are the two leading states ; and that, in the struggle between the principles of oligarchy and de- mocracy that was going on during this period in other city- states of Greece, Athens was, speaking broadly, on the side I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 23 of democracy, and Sparta on the side of oligarchy. In fact, Aristotle complains that both these states used their pre- dominant position to establish oligarchies and democracies respectively in other states under their influence, " not out of any consideration for the interests of the states in question, but simply for their own imperial interest." ^ We shall therefore be disposed, in tracing the develop- ment of democracy in the Greek city-states generally, to regard imitation of Athens as a probably important factor, though we do not know enough details to say with any precision how far it operated. But — and this is my negative example — it is clear that there was almost no attempt to imitate Sparta ; for, as we shall see,^ though Sparta was in policy on the side of oligarchy elsewhere, her government was not, in the view of ancient thinkers, one that should be classified as an oligarchy, though it had oligarchical elements. And this is all the more remarkable, because the ideal polity, which the most eminent political thinkers were led to construct by their view of the conditions of human well-being, bore a much closer resemblance to the actual polity of Sparta than to the actual polity of Athens. That is, in the ideal polity of Plato (in his latest work) and of Aristotle the citizens in a strict sense would be a class from which industrial elements were carefully excluded, living on the produce of lands tilled by serfs, and carefully trained for the military function, as was the case in Sparta. But in spite of the prestige of Sparta in the world of fact, and the influence of Plato and Aristotle in the world of thought, almost no tendency is discernible either to imitate the actual Spartan polity, or to realise the ideal state of the philosophers. This is a striking evidence that imitation only takes place when the type imitated is one in harmony with the general tendencies of political development in the states imitating. Still, generally speaking, it remains true that when imitation has been a factor in a general change in the form of polity of a number of states, it is very difficult, if not ^ Pol. VI. (iv.) ii. 18. 2 Lecture v. pp. 76-80. 24 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. impossible, to say how much of the detail of the change has been due to the result of the peculiar development of the polity that serves as the model. Imitation, in short, will not explain everything, but it will explain a good deal. This being so, it is important, in endeavouring to ascertain the laws of political develop- ment, that we should get all the instruction we can from a comparison of analogous cases, in which the similarities that we are able to trace cannot reasonably be attributed to imitation. It is the desire to bring this comparison into due prominence which has in fact determined the ground plan of my book. For the unique course of European history contains within itself several different series of developments of polity, having, as I have already indicated, a certain analogy with each other, and thus affording material for mutual comparison, while to a great extent independent. There is first that between the development of the ancient city-states and the country-states of Western Europe. But the development of Eoman polity is so different in detail from Greek, that a large place cannot be given to direct imitation of Greece in explaining its causes, though this must not be overlooked. "We may, therefore, treat the development of the Greek city-state and the Eoman city - state as almost independent. The develop- ment of the modern country -state thus affords a third series; and we find a fourth, to which I have already referred, in the development of the medieval cities. It may be observed that of these four different series of changing types of polity, three are so closely connected that they form one history in which the later stages are causally connected with the earlier. From the beginnings of Eome to the Eoman Empire, from this to the partially incoherent medieval kingdoms in which the partially independent medieval cities develop, and from these to modern European states, we have a continuous process, in which we cannot find a break except arbitrarily. So far I agree with Freeman as to " ancient " and " modern " history. This is not indeed the case with the history of Greece ; still, the I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 25 history of Greece has had an important influence both on Eoman and on modern history, though its influence, here as in other departments, has been primarily in the region of thought ; it has been exercised by supplying political ideas, and not by handing on actual political institutions and habits. At the same time, it is not for this reason only that the development of the Greek city-state has an indispensable place among the different series of developments of which I have just spoken. It is an essential part of my plan to study the phases through which the type of state I have called " city-state " has shown a tendency to pass. This is the type which, when we concentrate attention on the highest forms of civilised polity, is not only first in order of time, but for reasons which I shall afterwards explain, prior in order of political development. Now if this type is studied at all, it is indispensable to study it in Greece. The develop- ment of Kome is for special reasons unique — it is the one case of a city-state expanding into an imperial country-state ; and the medieval cities are not perfectly independent, even in Italy, where they are most nearly independent. § 7. I have spoken in the summary survey above given, sometimes of " political society " or " state," and sometimes of " nation." Before we proceed further, it will be well to examine more carefully the meaning and relations of these terms. As I have already explained, I generally use " state " and " political society " as convertible terms, except that I con- fine the term " state " to societies that have made a certain advance in political civilisation. But we should observe that the word " state " is sometimes used in a narrower sense, to denote a political society considered as being what jurists call an " artificial person," and as such, having rights and duties distinct from the rights and duties of the indi- viduals comprising it. I shall allow myself, where there is no danger of ambiguity, to use the word in this narrower sense without further explanation : and I think we may define the degree of civilisation which a political society must have reached in order to be properly called a " state," 26 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. partly by this characteristic : — that it must have arrived at a clear consciousness of this fundamental distinction between the rights and obligations of the community in its corporate capacity, and those of the individuals comprising it. In the primitive " tribal " condition of our Germanic ancestors and other uncivilised and semi-civilised peoples, this distinction is still obscure. Further, it belongs to our ordinary ^ conception of a State that the political society so-called should be attached to a particular part of the earth's surface: and should have a generally admitted claim to determine the legal rights and obligations of the persons inhabiting this portion, whether they are members of the society or not. This is so much the case that we sometimes use the word " state " to designate the portion of the earth's surface thus claimed. I have so far treated the " unity " of a state as depend- ing solely on the fact that its members obey a common government. And I do not think that any other bond is essentially implied in the conception of a state. Still, it should be recognised that a political society, whose members have no consciousness of any ties uniting them independently of their obedience to government, can hardly have the cohe- sive force necessary to resist the disorganising shocks and jars which external wars and internal discontents are likely to cause from time to time. If a political society is to be in a stable and satisfactory condition, its members must have — what members of the same state sometimes lack — a consciousness of belonging to one another, of being members of one body, over and above what they derive from the mere fact of being under one government ; and it is only when I conceive them as having this consciousness that I regard the state as being also a "nation." According to the generally accepted ideal of modern political thought a state ought certainly to be also a nation; still we can- not say that the characteristic of being a nation is com- ^ If a political society were to leave its temtory and establish itself in new lands, it might be held to have remained the same State during and after the transition ; but the point would, I think, be doubtful. I INTRODUCTORY SURVEY OF THE SUBJECT 27 monly implied in the current use of the term " state " or " political society." What is commonly implied is merely (1) that the aggregate of human beings thus denoted is united — if in no other way — by the fact of acknowledging permanent obedience to a common government, and having, through the permanence of the relations between govern- ment and governed, a corporate life distinguishable from the lives of its members ; (2) that the government exercises control over a certain portion of the earth's surface ; and (3) that the society has a not inconsiderable number of members, though the number cannot be definitely stated.^ These characteristics are found by analysing our present conception of a state. But if by the aid of the comparative method we retrace the history of political society up the stream of development — assuming that the less developed precedes the more developed — these characteristics seem to become gradually dim and evanescent. Number dwindles : we get back to a clan not easily distinguishable from an enlarged family ; relation to land becomes loose, the clan being a wandering horde of gregarious shepherds or hunters ; the relation of government and governed becomes only faintly discernible. The recognised chief does not make laws ; the horde follows inherited customs, but there is no magistrate who punishes disobedience ; if the chief were to issue commands — at least in time of peace — there is little probability that they would be generally obeyed. Ultimately, we come back to gregarious groups in which nothing that we can call definite headship is to be dis- cerned. Hence arises a certain difficulty in commencing the investigation of the development of political society: since if we try to begin at the beginning, as seems natural, we have to begin in almost utter darkness. If we are right to infer that our own political society has descended by direct filiation from a group of the most ^ Usually the government of a '* state " is understood to be independent of external control ; but we also apply the terra to governed societies that lack this characteristic, being members of a federal union, or dependencies of a dominant state. 28 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. i politically undeveloped type — a question which I do not now consider — a long part of the process of develop- ment must have taken place in prehistoric times. When the light of history first falls upon the societies to which the modern European State can be definitely traced, they have all a distinct and complex political organisation ; any enquiry into the first origin of political society carries us beyond history proper into speculation, conjecture, inference from analogy. It seems to me, therefore, best to begin with the first polity historically known, without assuming it to be original ; then, taking our stand on this, to conjecture what preceded ; and then, by the light of history, to trace the course of subsequent development. LECTUEE II THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY § 1. In the preceding lecture I have explained the method and objects of this course. What we are to study is the process of development leading up to the modern state. The modern state is a constitutional state ; and accordingly, in viewing European history as a process leading up to it, we are concerned primarily with the history of constitutions ; and, having this limited object in view we may, in the main, keep within the history of three branches of the Indo-Germanic group of nations. We may concentrate attention upon (1) Greece, (2) Eome with her empire — especially the western part, — and (3) the Germanic tribes that broke up and trans- formed the Western Empire, and whose political development was in its turn reacted upon and largely modified by the new conditions that their conquest brought about in this trans- formed empire. At the outset it is important to observe that, divergent as are the Knes of development of Greco-Italian and Teutonic civilisation, they yet are not so far apart in their begin- nings. When we compare the earliest forms of political society in Greece, Eome, and Germany, as the best at- tainable evidence shows them, we find — among important differences — a certain agreement in general features. Indeed, according to Freeman, "there is one form of government which, under various modifications, is set before us in the earliest glimpses which we get of the political life of at least all the European members of the Aryan family. This is that of the single king or chief, first ruler in peace, first captain in war, but ruling 29 30 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. not by his own arbitrary will, but with the advice of a council of chiefs eminent for age or birth or personal exploits, and further bringing all matters of special moment for the final approval of the general Assembly of the whole people. ... It is the form of government which we see painted in our first picture of European life in the songs of Homer. ... It is the form of government which tradition sets before us as the earliest form of that ancient Latin con- stitution out of which grew, first the Commonwealth, and then the Empire of Eome. It is no less the form of govern- ment which we see in the first picture of our race drawn for us by the hand of Tacitus, and in the glimpses given us by our own native annals of the first days of our own branch of that race when they made their way into this island in which we dwell." ^ I think that this view contains an important element of truth somewhat overstated ; accordingly, in the present lecture I propose to examine in order the three leading cases on which Freeman's generalisation is based, observing differences as well as resemblances. But in what order shall we examine them ? This question leads me to the first qualification of Freeman's statement that I have to offer: viz. that the different early nations whose political condition we have to compare can- not be assumed to be — when we take the earliest condition historically ascertainable in each case — at corresponding stages of development. I observe that at the close of the sketch of the original Eoman constitution, in Mommsen's 5 th chapter, that historian expressly says that this earliest recognisable political order of the Eoman community — the constitution, as he conceives it to have existed before the reforms of Servius TuUius — is later by an indefinitely long course of political development than the stage which is shown us in the Homeric poems, or in Tacitus's account of the Germans. Accepting this view, we have a striking illustration of that divergence which I before noted between the chronological order of political facts, which ordinary ^ Comparative Politics, Lect. ii., pp. 65, 66. II THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY 31 history follows, and the order of development which political science aims at tracing. From the point of view of political science the Germans of Tacitus {i.e. of the first century A.D.) are to be considered as earlier than the Eomans some six centuries before : nearer the point of departure of the process of development that we are trying to trace. Can we similarly decide between the two remaining cases ? Can we say which is earliest in development, the political institutions of the Greeks as Homer shows them to us, or of the Germans as Tacitus shows them ? Here the pre- liminary objection may occur that the whole comparison is on too uncertain ground. It may be said that such poetic narratives as Homer's cannot furnish evidence of the historic existence of a form of political society or a state of civilisation: for (1) they are not evidence of the character- istics of the age in which the poems were written, since the poet is describing a heroic past ; and (2) they are not trustworthy evidence of the characteristics of that past, since we cannot attribute to the poet antiquarian knowledge. There is some force in the dilemma, especially where the powers, glories, and rewards of heroic personages are concerned. Still I think it would be carrying scepticism too far to doubt that the indications incidentally given of political institutions, social customs, and industrial arts — when they are clearly not introduced to heighten the impressiveness of the story — on the whole ^ show us Greek civilisation as the poet or poets knew it by experience. And if so we may conclude that the Greeks for whom the Homeric poems were composed were on a decidedly higher level of general civilisation than the Germans of Tacitus ; ^ as possessing walled towns, vineyards, and olive-grounds care- fully cultivated, and luxurious palaces for their chiefs ; importing if not producing works of art similar in techniqiie ^ In one or two cases the poet's language suggests that he is consciously describing a practice outgrown, and offensive to the sentiments of his own age ; — e.g. when he describes the sacrifice of twelve Trojan youths on the funeral pyre of Patroclus. 2 The Germans, according to Tacitus, sacrificed prisoners of war, Arinals, L 61. 32 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. to the shield of Achilles ; and, last but not least, producing the poems themselves. Hence we shall not be surprised to find them at a more advanced stage of political development. § 2. Let us begin, then, with the department of facts chronologically latest, the primitive German constitution, on which Tacitus is our chief authority. In the political institutions of German tribes, as described by Tacitus, we can certainly find the three elements of Freeman's Indo- Germanic polity. There is the assembly of freemen in arms, meeting periodically ; there are the principes or chiefs of the smaller districts that make up the territory of the tribe, who administer justice in these districts, usually lead their fighting men in war, and act as a council to prepare the business for the national assembly. And there is, in some tribes, the superior chief or king ; not strictly hereditary, but always chosen from a noble family ; — and we may infer from other evidence that often only members of one family are eligible. But when we compare the accounts of Tacitus with the description of the Germans given by Csesar in his book on Gaul, we are struck with a curious fact, which the ordinary account of this primitive polity as " patriarchal kingship " ^ ignores. In the brief glimpses of German institutions which Caesar shows, we can see no kingship at all in the tribe or civitas. In peace, he tells us, there is no common magistracy : the chiefs of the districts into which the tribe is divided administer justice among their people : a common magistracy is only formed when the tribe is at war. And even in the time of Tacitus, a century and a half later, kingship — permanent headship of the whole tribe — would seem to have been only developed in a certain number of cases. As Dr. Stubbs says, " a very large pro- portion of the tribes dispensed altogether with royalty : the ■state or civitas was a sufficient centre, and the tie of nation- ality a sufficient bond of cohesion." ^ ^ See for instance Bluntschli, Theory o/tJie State, Book vi., chaps, vii. viii. 2 Constitutional History, chap. ii. § 15. II THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY 33 Thus the earliest movement of change traceable in the development of the German polity seems to be a movement towards kingship — meaning by " kingship " permanent head- ship of the tribe, hereditary generally in a family. And subsequent history confirms this: kingship spreads more and more : we see it deliberately introduced where it did not previously exist : we find it normal in the larger bodies that ejffected the conquest of the Eoman Empire ; at length the Saxons and Frisians in their native Germany seem to be the only Germanic nations without it, and the Saxon invaders of England, though they appear on the scene without it, soon adopt it.^ This being so, it seems rash to follow Freeman in regarding a definite threefold distribution of powers as a primitive Indo- Germanic institution and an "inheritance from the time when Greeks, Eomans, and Teutons lived together : " since, as regards the trihe, the earliest evidence shows us an absence of kingship among the Germans in Germany : and there seems to be no ground for assuming a definite triplicity of governmental organs in each of the smaller groups into which the kingless tribe is distributed. In the tribes that have kings there are, no doubt, the three elements clearly distinguishable. But in any case the supreme authority in the Germanic tribe appears from the account of Tacitus to reside in the assembly of free warriors. I may conveniently show this by a quotation^ from Dr. Stubbs's summary of this account, as Dr. Stubbs has certainly no undue bias in favour of a democratic interpretation of the institutions of our ancestors : " Under both systems the central power was wielded by the national assemblies. These were held at fixed times, generally at the new or full moon. There was no distinction of place : all were free, all appeared in arms. Silence was proclaimed by the priests, who had for the time the power of enforcing it. Then the debate was opened by some one who had a personal claim to be heard, the king, or a jprinceps (local chieftain), or ^ Cf. Otto Gierke, Das Deutsche Genossenschaftsreckt, pt, i. § 6. ^ Constituticnial History, chap. ii. § 16. D 34 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. one whose age, nobility, military glory or eloquence entitled him to rise. He took the tone of persuasion, never that of command. Opposition was expressed by loud shouts ; assent by the shaking of spears ; enthusiastic applause by the clash of spear and shield." " Of matters of deliberation the more important were transacted in the full assembly at which all the free men were entitled to be present. But the business was canvassed and arranged by the priThcipes before it was presented for national determination ; and matters of less import and ordinary routine were dispatched in the limited gather- ings of the magistrates." The assembly also "acted as a high court of justice, heard complaints and issued capital sentences ; " and in the time of Tacitus " the magistrates for the administration of justice" in the districts and villages seem to have been elected in it. § 3. When we turn to Homeric Greece, we find that the polity wears a decidedly more monarchical aspect : every tribe appears to have a single head-chief, though, in the Odyssey at least, the same title that is applied to him (" Basileus ") is also used to denote the subordinate chiefs, whom Tacitus calls principes to distinguish them from the rex} Still, among the various chiefs that a Homeric tribe (in the Odyssey) may have, there is normally one highest chief or king, whose office descends ordinarily though not necessarily by inheritance to one of his children. When a suitor says to Telemachus that it belongs to him as heir of his father to be king of Ithaca, Telemachus answers modestly that there are " many other Achsean chiefs " in Ithaca, and that some one of these may hold sway if Odysseus is dead. It seems clear from the tone of this discussion that Telemachus is considered to have a certain claim ; but that the claim may be overruled. ^ Similarly, in the primitive Germanic constitution, the right of the ^ Tac. Germ. 11. In the Iliad the title ^aa-iXevs is never, I believe, expressly applied to any one who is not either head of a 5i]/j.os or son of such a head. This is one of the points in which the political conceptions of the Iliad — or the older portions of it — appear to difter from those of the Odyssey. 2 Od. i. 394. 11 THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY 35 people to elect their king is ordinarily combined with a hereditary claim to be elected, belonging to members of one family. There is, then, in the Homeric tribe a central king normally hereditary, who, like the German king, in time of peace has the function of deciding disputes of right among the tribesmen, and protecting them from violent wrong ; who represents the community in its external relations, receives ambassadors and entertains strangers ; and who in time of war is the normal leader of the host. Along with him the subordinate chiefs or elders form a council like the German priTicipes : — and we may observe that, like the German chiefs, they are in the habit of settling their affairs at a banquet.^ Further, there is no doubt that general assemblies of the people are customarily summoned for the discussion of matters of public importance ; but there is a serious difference of opinion, among authorities of repute, as to the political function of such assemblies. According to Grote^ the Homeric assembly of freemen, and the Homeric council of chiefs, are " exhibited . . . as opportunities for advising the king, and media for promulgating his intentions to the people, rather than as restraints upon his authority . . . the king promulgates his intentions. . . . But in the Homeric agora no division of affirmative or negative voices ever takes place, nor is any formal resolution ever adopted. ... It is an assembly for talk, communication, and discussion to a certain extent by the chiefs . . . but here its ostensible purposes end. . . . The multitude who compose it are listening and acquiescent, not often hesitating, and never refractory." In answer to this it is urged, with undeniable force, by Freeman and by Gladstone, that formal resolu- tions and divisions are refinements that belong to a later stage of political civilisation ; that we do not even ^ Political dinners are very primitive institutions. ' ' De pace ac belle plenimque in conviviis consultant," says Tacitus. "Give the chiefs a dinner" — suggests Nestor to Agamemnon at the crisis caused by Achilles' wrath. 2 History of Greece, Part i. chap. xx. (vol. ii. pp. 90, 92, 97 1st ed.). 36 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. find them in the Germanic assembly of armed freemen, with which the real decision of peace and war, and other important matters clearly rested. " If they disapprove of a proposal," says Tacitus, " they indicate their rejection by murmurs and groans {fremitus) ; if they approve, they clash spears." ^ Now the Homeric Greeks certainly appear to refrain from noisy dissent; but in the Iliad (ix. 29, 50) disapprobation of Agamemnon's proposal finds effective expression in silence, followed by loud applause of a speaker on the opposite side. It is evident that the speakers in the Homeric assembly have the business of persuading, and that persuasive eloquence is most important to them. The assembly, no less than the battlefield, is a place where heroes win glory i^ and even a man poor in presence, if he has the gift of oratory, " shines in the gathering of his people, and as he passes through the town men gaze on him as a god." ^ The assembly therefore is much more than a mere means of announcement ; and where public speaking is an instrument of public policy, there, as Gladstone and Freeman say, is the real essence of liberty. It is evident, again, that the Trojan assembly {II. xviii. 311) is held by the poet to be gravely responsible for applauding the bad advice of Hector, instead of the good counsel of Polydamas ; and the Ithacan assembly {Od. xvL 375) is credited with the power of driving the suitors of Penelope from Ithaca, as a punishment of their plot to slay Telemachus. And, though it is difficult to say how far the king could, in accordance with custom, decide without or even against the advice of council or assembly — since doubtless the distribution of functions among the three organs was uncertain and fluctuating — it is clear that some public acts were not within the limits of his authority. Thus we hear several times * of a domain {refievo^) cut out of public land to be held in severalty by some hero as a reward for conspicuous public service, but it is never said to be assigned by the authority of the king : — for instance, 1 Tac. Germ. 11. ^ Compare {e.g.) 11. i. 490, and iv. 225. 3 Od. viii. 172. ^ See II. vi. 194, ix. 578, xx. 184. II THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY 37 after Bellerophon's exploits in Lycia, the king gives him " half of all the royal honour " ; but it is the Lycians who "mete him a domain fair with vineyards and tilth." 1 I think, therefore, that we might infer from Homer alone that in the earliest discernible form of Greek political society the assembly of freemen held a position bearing some analogy to that of the German Assembly; — though certainly, in the society that Homer describes, the chief appears to be politically more and the common people less than in the Germanic society described by Tacitus. And this general conclusion may be further supported by evidence drawn from post-Homeric Greece ; which illustrates again how, in tracing by means of induction and comparison the general course of political development, we have to neglect chronology. I mean we have to put together as parallel, politi- cal conditions of different states, separated by long intervals of time ; and on the other hand consider the simultaneous conditions of different countries as separated by long inter- vals of development. We must not indeed carry this neglect of chronology too far ; for a people in low develop- ment, living in communication with a more civQised one, is likely to catch by the contact some elements of civilisation, and thus become socially more advanced in some ways than a people at a generally similar stage of development who lived long before them in time. So far, however, as this influence on contemporary civilisation affects the balance of political forces in a primitive society like the one we are considering, it is hardly likely to favour the power of the general assembly of freemen ; since the chiefs, from their ^ II. vi. 195. In the story of Meleager (J7. ix. 578), the offer of a rifxevos is made by "the elders," not by the king; probably the offer would have required ratification by the assembly. It may be observed that the Homeric king's revenue appears to be regarded as public revenue, which he is customarily bound to employ largely for public purposes : thus the chieftains entertained by Agamemnon are said to ' * drink at the public cost." — //. xvii. 249. On the other hand, he has a right to exact from the tribesmen contributions towards any exceptional expense, — such as that entailed by hospitality towards strangers. 38 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. wealth and position, are likely to anticipate the masses in civilisation, and thereby to increase their predominance. This seems to be the case with the kings of Macedonia when it becomes prominent in Greek history : — here, indeed, the royal family claims to belong by race to the more civilised neighbours. When, therefore, in spite of this source of superiority, we learn from the historians of Alexander that the powers of the Macedonian king were constitutionally limited ; that, in particular, capital punish- ment could not be inflicted except with the assent of the army in war, the assembly in peace; when we find that, even under so towering and triumphant a monarch as Alexander, the Macedonian army in Asia retains this right, and actually acquits Macedonians accused before it by Alexander himself, we certainly obtain some confirmation for Freeman's parallel between the primitive political positions of the Teutonic and Greek assemblies of freemen in arms. But the Macedonian constitution is only known to us by vague general statements and inferences from isolated events. More important evidence is furnished by one of the most interesting of the historic constitutions of Greece — the so-called Lycurgean constitution of Sparta. I think we may assume (1) that the Dorian tribes who conquered Peloponnesus were in a more primitive condition, socially and politically, than the people whom they subdued ; and (2) that in the so-called Lycurgean constitution we have, to a great extent, this original condition artificially preserved and rendered uniquely stable. Through a process of change now undiscoverable — which tradition has concentrated and attached to the name of Lycurgus, — the natural primi- tiveness of life and warlike habits of an invading horde were somehow petrified into the artificial simplicity and hardiness and traditional martial art of an elaborately trained caste of soldiers. Now if we take the old Spartan constitution (leaving out the Board of five " ephors " or super- visors, which, as the best authorities agree, was a later addition), we find its main features those of Freeman's primi- 11 THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLIJ Y 39 tive Indo-Germanic polity; and, in particular, in respect of the powers of the assembly, it has a more striking re- semblance to the German polity described by Tacitus than anything we find in Homer. It was the duty of the kings (I abstract from the peculiarity of the dual kingship of Sparta, which need not now detain us) to call the citizens together once a month at least, on the day of the full moon, in a fixed place in the valley of the Eurotas. This assembly, like the Germanic one, is a martial muster of the freemen in arms : decisions of peace and war, treaties, and other important matters of state are laid before it for decision, just as before the Germanic assembly of Tacitus. In neither case does the ordinary freeman take part in debate ; but the assembly has to accept or reject the proposals laid before it ; and even down to the time of Thucydides, as that historian tells us, the decision of a Spartan, as of a Germanic, assembly was expressed by the shout, and not by a formal vote. Putting all the evidence together, I think we may reasonably suppose that the customary distribution of power between chiefs and common freemen varied considerably in different parts of Greece ; and that where more primitive social conditions survived ^ — as in the mountainous region from which the conquering Dorians came — the independence of the common freeman, and the collective power of the assembly of freemen, was greater than in the more civilised parts. In connection with this it is important to notice the military equipment and mode of fighting of the chiefs ; for during almost the whole period of development comprised in ancient history differences in military equip- ment and organisation have an important correspond- ence to political differences. Thus we may assume that wherever Greek chiefs and nobles fought like Homer's heroes from war-chariots, their political superiority to the loosely arranged common herd was decidedly greater than that of the Teutonic chiefs, who marched to battle on foot with their fellow-tribesmen. I do not, however, think it certain that this manner of fighting ever prevailed widely 40 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. among the Greeks in Europe;^ since war -chariots are altogether unsuited to the mountainous country that occupied so large a part of Greece proper. In any case, we may assume that the Dorians won their victories in Peloponnesus mainly by means of the infantry which constituted their principal arm of warfare in historic times : and the military importance thus attaching to the common Dorian freeman would tend to sustain his political position. On the other hand, we may fairly regard the huge walls of great stone blocks, the magnificent graves with gold treasures, and the remains of palaces at Mycenae and Tiryns as evidence that the Greek chieftains in Peloponnesus, before the Dorian invasions, surpassed in dignity and power their counterparts either in the Germany of Tacitus's time, or in the ruder parts of Greece. As regards judicial functions especially, there seems to be a decided divergence between the primitive Germanic polity and the earliest known Greek polity. In the Germanic constitution the function of declaring justice — so far as controversies of right are not settled by private conflict and compromise, or by arbitration — seems to belong essentially to the freemen, assembled either nationally or locally; the function of the king or local chief being to preside at the trial and enforce the decision. But, though in Homeric Greece the judicial decision was given in the Agora among the citizens at large, there is no evidence to show that the freemen generally took any part in the decision in ordinary cases. We may, however, infer from what has been said above of Macedonia, that the assembled freemen had the ultimate decision in capital cases, as seems to have been the case in Eome when the condemned persons appealed : it is on general grounds probable that — in Greece as elsewhere — the primitive gathering of armed men which formed the political assembly was at first the judicial body also, for important matters of criminal justice. Turning to consider briefly the primitive Eoman con- ^ There are traces of its ancient use in Boeotia and Euboea. II THE BEGINNINGS OF HISTORIC POLITY 41 stitution as delineated by Mommsen, we find again the three elements of Freeman's primitive polity definitely and vigor- ously marked. There is, firstly, the king ; ^ secondly, there is the council of " fathers," which has the customary right of giving counsel to the king, and is the ultimate depositary of royal power when the king dies ; thirdly, there is the assembly, having at least three fundamental resemblances with the primitive Teutonic or Spartan assembly. It (1) meets (at least) on fixed days ; (2) its consent has to be obtained for measures of great national importance, e.g. for an offensive war, or for a change in the " common law " or customary rule of civic relations ; (3) the assembly has only to say " yes " or " no " ; no speaking on proposals laid before it is allowed to private citizens. It is to be noted further, that an appeal seems to be customarily granted to the Koman assembly in cases of infliction of capital punishment. I have already observed that the polity thus broadly characterised is not to be regarded as peculiarly Indo- Germanic. Indeed, according to Mr. Spencer,^ we find a similar " form of ruling agency " among " sundry Malayo-Polynesians, among the red men of North America, the Dravidian tribes of the Indian hills, the aborigines of Australia." We are not, however, here concerned with this wider comparison. Mr. Spencer somewhat characteristically adds that "govern- mental organisation could not possibly begin in any other way," for "no controlling force at first exists save that of the aggregate will as manifested in the assembled horde." But before we affirm this necessity it seems desirable to examine a widely accepted theory of the origin of political society which appears to supply us with the controlling force required. I mean the patriarchal theory, ^ There are some striking differences between Roman and Greek kings. The Roman king has no claim to divine descent ; he is nominated either by his predecessor or by an " inteiTcx " appointed by the senate ; but his admini- strative power seems to go beyond that of the heroic king of Greece — in accordance with the greater sternness and orderliness of the Roman character which we find also exhibited in the intensity in private law of the paternal authority. ^ Political Institutions^ ch. v. § 464. 42 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. ii which gives, as the original force of cohesion in primitive political society, the habit of obedience of children to parents continuing as a habit of obedience to the chief who is regarded as father of the clan. This theory I propose to examine in the following lecture. LECTUEE III THE PATKIAECHAL THEORY § 1. Let me briefly sum up the results of the preceding lecture. In the primitive nation as exhibited to us by its earliest records in Greece and Eome, and in the German tribes so far as they have a common permanent head, we find political functions distributed among three differently constituted organs — the king or supreme chief, a council of subordinate chiefs or elders, and the assembly of fully qualified citizens, which is, as I said, a martial muster of the freemen in arms. These three organs are found approximately similar in the different cases which we have compared ; and the distribution of functions among them in any one case has a broad re- semblance to its distribution in any other : — though we note important divergences in detail, and of course must not attribute to societies in this early stage any such precision and definiteness in division of functions as belongs to the constitutions of more civilised peoples. The main business of this course of lectures is to trace the subsequent process of development, through which this polity passes — a process growing clearer as civilisation pro- gresses and our records of past social and political conditions become more precise and trustworthy. But in the present lecture I want to look backward, instead of forward, into an obscurer region, and to see how far we can construct by the aid of conjecture a probable account of the process by which the primitive polity was reached. The question of the origin of society was much debated in earlier stages of modern political thought, being supposed to have a practical importance which no one now 43 44 DE VEL PM ENT OF E UR OPE A N POLITY lec t. attributes to it. Men, finding themselves in an organised society, paying habitual obedience to a certain govern- ment, asked why this obedience was due, and expected to find the answer in some theory as to how it originated : holding that knowledge of the origin of governmental authority would determine the legitimacy of the present claims of rulers to obedience from particular portions of mankind. But this supposition of a connexion between the original source of government and the present duty of obey- ing it, is now generally discarded ; in considering why we obey the established government, we commonly examine the probable effects of obedience and resistance, — comparing the evils of oppression against the evils of breaking up a settled order. So that the controversy between Locke and Filmer as to whether the authority of government was originally derived from the free consent of individuals previously independent, as Locke maintained, or from the natural authority of a father over his children and children's children, as Filmer maintained, has ceased to have any more than a historic interest for us ; it is therefore easy for us to examine the probability of the alternative con- jectures with scientific impartiality. § 2. But before launching ourselves into this dim region of conjecture, it is well to have clearly before our minds such knowledge, bearing on this question of origin, as is attainable from a study of less obscure parts of history. We want to guess how political society originated in prehistoric ages ; to give ourselves the best chance of guessing right, it will be well to have before us the actually known modes of forming new political societies in historic times. Now we find that new states have been formed in historic times sometimes by aggregation and sometimes by division, and in either case sometimes by free consent and sometimes by force. Division has been in historic times a not infrequent cause ; — especially in earlier stages of development, in which the process that later becomes colonisation goes on in the rude form of sending off roving swarms to seek new settlements. But when a new political Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 45 society is formed by division, it is obviously derived from a pre-existing society of the same kind ; division therefore clearly cannot be the mode in which political societies were originally formed out of non-political. The case is otherwise with aggregation, which therefore requires closer attention, x^iggregation by force, or conquest, is a most important cause of new political communities, after a certain stage of civilisation has been reached either by the conquering or the conquered community. But savage tribes at the lowest stages of development, though con- tinually at war, do not coalesce through conquest pure and simple ; the vanquished are exterminated or driven away, not absorbed — at least the captured males are exterminated, the women being perhaps saved for concubinage or domestic work. Thus we have no ground for regarding conquest as a factor in the very earliest formation of political societies : — and indeed it would be difficult to conceive the formation of political societies out of non-political elements taking place in this way. On the other hand, we find in historic times several cases in which a mainly voluntary aggregation has formed a new political whole out of elements that have already a political organisation of a certain kind, though often one less developed. We find this process taking place at the earliest stage of history as well as at the latest. Most frequently, in early stages of development such com- bination takes place with a view to war, and lasts at first only as long as the war lasts. Thus — as I have mentioned — Csesar tells us that in his time the German tribes {civi- tates) had only common chiefs in war time ; in peace, the smaller divisions (which he calls regiones or pagi) had separate chiefs who administered justice and composed differences. And for this condition of things analogies are easily found in all parts of the world. ^ But wars in this stage are often so recurrent and serious that the advantage of union leads to its permanence. The German tribes of which Tacitus speaks appear to have all ^ Cf. Spencer, Political Institutions, § 451, p. 298. 46 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. obtained this completer degree of internal cohesion : and, as we saw, have national assemblies at which the chiefs of the smaller districts are elected. Then, when we pass from the Germans whom Csesar and Tacitus knew to the Germans who overran the decaying empire four centuries later, we find a further progress in the same direction of change. It is not, however, only with a view to war and defence against foreign forces that this "integration," as Spencer calls it, takes place. If communities are similar in language and customs, then, as civilisation brings an increasing con- sciousness of community of nature and sentiment, the mere desire to establish a more perfect order in the internal relations of the aggregating communities may suffice. This appears when we consider exceptional cases in which circumstances rendered foreign war a comparatively rare incident. Thus we find that in Iceland the transition to one community from a group of " Things " with separate chieftains in local proximity was due to disputes between neighbouring chiefs and their clients and uncertainty as to the law, which brought about the " Constitution of Ulfliot," A.D. 930, establishing a central "Thing" or assembly for the whole island — the "Althing" — and a law speaker to speak a single law. / § 3. Voluntary coalescence, then, seems of all the historic modes of formation of new states to be the only one appli- cable in the case of the original formation of a political society out of something that is not already such a society. Accordingly, the most important historical question at issue between Locke's school and their opponents may be stated thus : Were political societies originally formed by voluntary aggregation of heads of natural families, recognising no right of government in any one more than any other prior to the aggregation ? or were they formed by the extension of single families into larger bodies of kindred, accompanied by a recognition of superiority in individuals or families specially representing the original parents ? We may obtain some light on this question by examining Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 47 the internal structure of the earliest political society that history shows us in Greece, Eome, and Germany. I turn, there- fore, to the account that Maine gives of this structure, on the basis of the evidence derived from comparative jurisprudence, and especially from a study of Eoman law. According to Maine, society in primitive times was " in fact, and in the view of the men who composed it ... an aggregation of families," not " a collection of individuals." Ancient law, accordingly, "is so framed as to be adjusted to a system of . . . corporations." It "considers the entities with which it deals, i.e. the patriarchal or family groups, as perpetual and inextinguishable." -^ It is to be noted that these entities, so far as their patriarchal character is recognised in the earliest Eoman law historically known to us, are families in the strictest sense : the " Patria Potestas " of the head of a household extends only to his wife, children, and their descendants. Over them indeed he appears exercising a despotism so absolute that no member of the family besides himself can be said to have had a separate jural existence at all. He was not only absolute owner of the property, including even the acquisitions of his children : but he could chastise and even kill, could sell or transfer by adoption, could marry and divorce any of his children at will. This complete control within the family carried with it a correspondingly extensive responsibility; the paterfamilias was answerable for any damage done by a son ; but he could relieve himself by tendering the person of the offender as a satisfaction for the damage. And while the Eoman father's power during life was thus in its remarkable extent more analogous to that of an independent ruler than to that of a modern parent, we may find a similar analogy in the no less striking limitation of his power over his estate after death. He could not originally leave any of his property by will away from his children ; he could no more decide what was to be done with it after his death than a mon- arch of a modern state can dispose of the country he governs. When, however, we ask what happened after the father's * Anderit Law, chap. v. p. 126. 48 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. death, we find that the evidence suggests two different answers to the question. When we are considering the consequences of the father's death contemplated in the earliest Eoman Law known to us, we must consider the family to break up at the father's death; those of the children, or fatherless grandchildren, who are physically capable of founding families — i.e. males who have attained puberty — becoming independent units ; while the women, if not under the control of husbands, as lacking this capacity, remain subject to the nearest male relative.-^ But an examination of the earliest Eoman law of inheritance leads us to infer an earlier stage of development, at which the family held together instead of breaking up at the father's death. According to Maine ^ the primitive Roman conception of inheritance was " succession to the en- tire legal position of the deceased man." All the archaic phrases in Roman Law relating to inheritance "indicate that what passed from the testator to the heir was the family, that is, the aggregate of ' rights and duties com- bined in the Patria Potestas and growing out of it ; " hence Maine conceives the original will or testament as " a mode of declaring who was to have the chieftainship in succession to the testator." Again the only claims of consanguinity recognised in the primitive law of intestate inheritance (in default of direct heirs) are the claims of " agnates " — kins- men who trace their connection exclusively through males : and this carries us back to a time at which a man after his father's death still belonged, in some important sense, to the same family group as his brothers and even remoter kinsmen. For the exclusion from inheritance of all collaterals who could only trace their connection through females would be inexplicable unless we suppose that women — even when they married after the father's death — ^left the family by marriage in a sense in which men did not leave it. 1 Later, when wills overruled the original rights of kinsmen, unmarried women after their father's death were placed in the protection of guardians appointed by will. 2 Ancient Law, chap. vi. pp. 181, 190, 191. Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 49 Further, we have to observe that in the Eoman Law of the "Twelve Tables," rights of inheritance extended beyond the limits of traceable kinship to the members of the " Gens," or clan, to which the deceased belonged. This leads us to a very important modification of Maine's con- ception of primitive society as an aggregation of families. We find that in Eome, Athens, Sparta alike, — in short wherever we have an accurate knowledge of an ancient community — the families of the original citizens are grouped in larger bodies, which so far resemble families that they are held together by at least the supposition of a common kinship. We may conveniently distinguish these by the Eoman name " Gentes." Such a Gens is called by Maine a fictitious extension of the family.^ Its members, as such, could not definitely trace blood relationship ; but they bore a common name, and regarded each other as descendants or quasi-descendants of a common ancestor ; and they were united by the religious tie of performing sacrificial rites of a quasi-domestic kind, and in early times by a complex bond of mutual rights and obligations, resembling those arising out of distinct kinship. Thus we find the members of an Athenian Gens bound together by mutual rights of succession to property ; reciprocal obligations of help, defence, and redress of injuries ; mutual rights and obligations to intermarry in certain deter- minate cases, especially where there was an orphan daughter or heiress ; and the possession, in some cases, of common property.^ These bonds of union are so strong, that in conceiving the structure of the primitive society in which they were in full force, we are led to regard it as more markedly an aggregation of Gentes than an aggregation of natural families. And it is a not improbable conjecture that this division into gentes was represented in the original political constitution of Eome ; the " patres " who composed the Senate being originally the chiefs of the old patrician Gentes. ^ Similarly Grote (Part 11. chap, x.) speaks of it as an "enlarged and partly factitious brotherhood." '-^ See Grote, Ix. 50 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. The gentes again were grouped both at Eome and Athens into larger unions — " curiae," ^parpiai (brotherhoods) — con- nected by similar though less close bonds ; and these larger groups were grouped again into tribes. If, then, we contemplate the primitive nation as com- posed in the manner described, of an ascending series of groups — the bond of union within the group being the belief or fiction of common descent, represented in and con- firmed by the performance of sacred rites in worship of a common ancestor — the Patriarchal Theory emerges, if I may so say, spontaneously. As Maine says,^ " we can scarcely help conceiving " these groups " as a system of concentric circles which have gradually expanded from the same point." That is, the patriarchal family prospering and holding together, would become the gens ; and similarly the gens prospering would develop into the larger union of the tribe. And though it is only a conjecture, it is, Maine thinks, " no pre- sumptuous conjecture," that the independent group thus formed by development out of the patriarchal family was normally governed by the " eldest male of the oldest line," representing the "common ancestor of all the free kinsmen." ^ § 4. In examining this view, it will be well to distinguish three questions : — 1. Was the tie that bound members of a primitive community together primarily an extension of the family tie, a consciousness of kinship and common descent ? 2. Did the group of supposed kinsmen which constitutes the most elementary political society known to us, grow out of a family formed by the children of a single male parent ? 3. Did the chief of such a group normally exer- cise authority as representative of the parent in this original family ? The first question, I think, may be confidently answered in the affirmative. There can be no doubt that man, in the earliest stage in which history leads us to form a conception of him, existed in groups, of which at least the ideal bond was kinship. We have seen, indeed, that in the case of ^ Ancient Law, ch. v. p. 128, and ch. vii. p. 234. "'^ Early History of Institutions, Lect. in. p. 94. Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 51 the Greeks and Eomans, kinship is not generally trace- able, even by traditionally preserved genealogies, among all the members of any of the groups within groups of which the community — or at least the old stock of citizens — appears to be composed ; it may even be known that foreign elements have been admitted into the union of kinsmen, with or without a ceremony of adoption ; still, this does not prevent the group, as a whole, from being conceived as descended from a common ancestor. Even where the members of the community were known not to be all kins- men, it was only by feigning themselves to be kinsmen that they could regard it as natural and rational to hold together in political union, — the effect of the fiction being doubtless powerfully aided by the admission of the fictitious kinsmen to the domestic worship of the group. We have no evi- dence of any similar fictitious extension of kinship among the primitive Germans ; but when we catch our first glimpse of them in Caesar's narrative, we find them associated in con- sanguineous groups for war, and for the appropriation and cultivation of land. And though in all these cases the con- stitutional importance of these quasi-consanguineous divi- sions appears to be diminishing when the light of history falls on them, there is sufficient evidence to show clearly that the internal union of a primitive political society was conceived after the pattern of a family union ; that its earliest elements are groups similarly framed ; and that each of these communities, when we know them first, appears to be conscious of a wider legendary kinship linking it to neighbouring communities. Though we cannot say that the belief in descent from a common ancestor is required as a " condition 'precedent " for primitive tribes combining ; still here too the idea of kinship as a basis of combination seems so far predominant, that the belief in a common ancestor is apt to grow up after combination. § 5. We may assume, then, that the earliest form of political society was a comparatively small group of persons regarding themselves as kinsmen : and it is possible that in some cases such a society may have been produced by the 52 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. expansion of a single family. But after the evidence which M'Lennan and others have brought forward as to the wide- spread existence among uncivilised men of kinship traced through females only, and marriage customs very difi'erent from the patriarchal, I cannot regard it as even decidedly most probable that any political society which we know historically was actually thus developed. It is at least not improbable that the gregarious group or groups from which it has been derived, with whatever intervening processes of aggregation and division, went through a stage in which kinship through females was alone recognised; and if so, it is at least not improbable that as it emerged into the stage in which the paternal kinship had prevailed as the bond of family union, it was composed of several families which could not definitely trace themselves to a common male ancestor, though under the influence of the newly -predominant idea of kinship through males, they came to believe that they had had such an ancestor. Evidence of this process of change, in the Arabian clans, is given by Eobertson Smith in his book on Ki7iship and Marriage in Early Arabia. Here I ought to observe that Maine, in a later treatise,^ admitted the importance of a good deal of M'Lennan's evidence, and restated his theory in view of this evidence. He admitted it " to be more than probable that, since the appearance of mankind on the earth, an indefinite portion of the race has suffered at different times from a serious inferiority in numbers of women to men." He acknow- ledged that men would be led " to establish institutions in conformity with this proportion between the sexes " ; and that " the tendency of such institutions would be to arrange men and women in groups very unlike those in which, according to . . . the Patriarchal Theory, they were originally combined." And he admitted that it may be "impossible to say what portion of the human race has suffered from this dispropor- tion between the sexes." He still, however, insists " on the ^ Early Law and Custom, ch. viii. pp. 214, 215. This chapter — with which Spencer, in criticising Maine, does not seem to be acquainted — should be read by all who give any attention to the present inquiry. Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 53 Patriarchal Theory as expressing the primitive grouping of mankind " ; considering the phenomena to which M'Lennan drew attention to be a temporary aberration interposed between the original grouping and that later patriarchal family which archaic law shows us. And he skilfully turns the flank — if I may so say — of M'Lennan, by calling in the authority of Darwin, who approaches the matter from the zoological side.^ Darwin argues from what we know of the habits of monkeys, that primitive man — when nearest the monkeys — must be supposed to have lived in marriage relations certainly more resembling the patriarchal family than those to which M'Lennan has drawn attention : " each with a single wife, or if powerful with several, whom he jealously guarded against all other men," and under the influence of " one of the strongest of all instincts, common to all the lower animals, namely, the love of their young offspring." There is even some reason for attributing to him, in some cases, permanent monogamic unions in this earliest jpost-simian condition. Without denying the force of Darwin's reasoning, I think we may observe that, under the influence of the studies of savage life to which M'Lennan and Darwin led him, Maine's Patriarchal Theory, in its final form, has undergone a material change. As you will remember, an essential characteristic of the patriarchal family in Ancient Law is that the patriarch — the oldest living male ascendant — is supposed to bear despotic sway over his gTown-up sons, as well as the women and young children of his household, and the "implicit obedience of rude men to their parent," which this conception involves, is spoken of as a " primary fact." ^ But it is difficult to sup- pose this a primary fact in the patriarchal family that Maine shows us in Early Law and Custom. Of this family he says (p. 198) that it is "more than barbarous, it is extremely savage," (p. 209) that "sexual jealousy, indulged through power, might serve as a definition of " it, " the power of the strong man" is "the principal formative cause" of it (p. 215). ^ See Descent of Man, Part ill. ch. xx. ^ Ancient Law, ch. v. p. 136. 54 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. But in such a group based on sexual jealousy and physical force, what motive is there to make the grown son, in full youthful vigour, submit to the despotic authority of the father ? Maine suggests that it is respect for the paternal wisdom (p. 198), "the strongest and wisest male rules." But though barbarous people often show a more marked respect for the wisdom that normally comes with age than men in a more advanced stage of civilisation, it is attributing more to this sentiment than any evidence will support, if we sup- pose that it would make men submit to despotic control in the teeth of strong animal passions. And nothing that I can learn of monkeys or other animals at all supports this. I learn {e.g?) that among gorillas " but one adult is seen in a band ; when the young male grows up a contest takes place for mastery, and the strongest, by killing and driving out the others, establishes himself as the head of the community." ^ All this seems highly unpatriarchal. In short, granting the " Cyclopean " family, with a single male head ruling despotic- ally over wives and children of tender years, to be as primi- tive a condition of human society as we can conjecturally get back to, I see no ground for regarding the Patriarchal family of Ancient Law as similarly primitive, or for assuming it to have developed immediately out of the Cyclopean family. The two are dissimilar in respect of the very char- acteristic which is most important for our present inquiry into the development of the state — the submission paid by a number of grown men to one. § 6. The controversy thus seems to concentrate itself on the third of the questions above distinguished, — the relation of political to paternal power. According to Maine, the power of the father — or his representative — is a fact so essential to the structure of primitive society, that "kin- ship, as the tie binding communities together, tends to be regarded as the same thing with subjection to a common authority. The notions of power and consan- guinity blend," ^ though " they in nowise supersede one ^ Dr. Savage, as quoted by Darwin, Descent of Man, Part iii. ch. xx. ^ Early History of InstUiUwns, pp. 68, 69. Ill THE PATRIARCHAL THEORY 55 another." Thus in the case of "the smallest group, the family," it is " difficult to say whether the persons com- prised in it are most distinctly regarded as kinsmen, or as servile or semi-servile dependants of the person who was the source of their kinship " ; and this confusion of " kinship with subjection to patriarchal power is observable also in the larger groups into which the family expands. In some cases the tribe can hardly be otherwise described than as the group of men subject to some one chieftain." Now it is probable that wherever primitive chieftainship was strong, this fusion of ideas tended to result. But we have no reason to regard this extent of the chiefly power as a normal condition of the earliest political societies : and even if we suppose a clan developed out of a really patriarchal — not Cyclopean — family, it would not follow that its chief had his power simply because he was conceived, as the eldest ascendant, to " represent " the father of the family which had expanded into the clan. This idea of " representation " seems to me too artificial and refined to have so decisive a force at so early a stage of development. And certainly in the his- torically known cases in later times, to which Maine refers, where groups of kinsmen, developed out of more or less patriarchal families, hold property in common, — though not as independent groups, but as part of a larger state, — we find no such transmission of paternal power. It is true that in most of these cases — e.g. in the Hindoo joint undivided family — the eldest male of the eldest line, if of full mental capacity, is generally placed at the head of affairs. But as Maine ^ admits, he is merely manager, not patriarch ; and " if he is not deemed fit for his duties, a ' worthier ' kinsman is substituted for him by election"; just as the principle of election, at least within the royal family, seems to have been generally accepted in the appointment of the Teutonic king or supreme chief, where such a supreme chief existed. Thus, even where the institution of the family as we con- ceive it, under the rule of the male parent, is firmly estab- lished within the society, we still find the principle of ^ Early History of Institutions, p. 117. 56 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. hi election on the ground of personal efficiency combining with the principle of inheritance in the male line to determine chieftainship. Similarly there is much evidence to show that in such societies personal superiority, physical or mental, or both, is a powerful factor in determining the retention of the chief's office. Thus, in Homeric Greece, Laertes and Peleus have to give up their chieftainship when old age comes on. And we may reasonably suppose that such personal superiority, especially military capacity, was in an indefinite number of cases the origin of new chieftainship. Tacitus tells us that among the Germans the leader in war was chosen for his valour ; and we cannot doubt that this was frequently the case in primitive communities, or that a successful war chief would frequently retain his chieftainship after the war was over. Other superiorities, besides martial valour or skill, have also to be taken into account ; e.g. the supposed possession of peculiar divine favour, or means of influencing the gods — the " medicine -man" of a tribe, as Spencer says, is in a favourable position for rising to chief- tainship. The story of Numa, in early Eoman history, suggests a rise of this kind. On the whole, then, I think we must suppose the process of development by which permanent hereditary kingship came to be established, to have been one in which this principle of selecting the strongest or wisest — wherever vigorous or skilful leadership was felt to be specially necessary — com- bined and conflicted, in various ways, with the tendency to recognise the son as the natural successor to the father, which is likely to have been strong where male descent definitely determined succession to private property. There is no reason to regard the father's power, in the patriarchal family, as the original type of political power ; but doubt- less the firm establishment of the patriarchal type of family contributed importantly to the stability and strength of tribal headship. LECTURE IV SUMMARY OF THEORY OF ORIGIN TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP § 1. In my last Lecture I laid before you the results at which I have arrived, after studying the evidence for and against the Patriarchal Theory of the origin of political society. Briefly summed up they are these : — 1. It is an undeniable and important truth that the political communities of those Indo- Germanic nations with whom we are specially concerned are, in the first stage in which history leads us to conceive them, found to be organised in groups based on real or assumed kinship ; at least the core or nucleus of the community is so organised, though round this nucleus there may be a large accretion of other elements.^ 2. I think, however, that such a community is rather to be regarded as an aggregation of houses or " clans," each in- cluding several families, than an aggregation of families under the despotic control of the eldest male ascendant, as Maine suggests. That is, the divisions between the Gentes, in the earliest state of things that ancient law leads us to conceive, are more marked than the divisions between the families within each Gens. In Germany, and probably in Italy and Greece also, we have to suppose the tribe distributed primi- ^ It must always be recognised that though kinship is the ideal bond, the need or convenience of union, especially for war, is, to an extent not now traceable, the actual bond. And though doubtless in early times the groups that thus become welded into one are mostly kin before the amalgamation — as Rome and Latins — still we must admit an indefinite number of cases in which alien gi'oups were absorbed. This Maine notices, but does not perhaps emphasise enough. 57 58 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. tively in groups of kinsmen, holding and cultivating land largely in common : both in Eome and Athens we see such groups — gentes or r^evr] — based at least on the idea of kin- ship, and internally united by a common worship, a certain degree of obedience to a common chieftain, mutual rights of succession to property, and reciprocal obligations of help in distress, defence and redress in quarrel. These latter ties no doubt were stronger among members of the same family, or near kinsmen within the larger group ; but still they effectively bound together the whole Gens and made the most marked line of division that which separated Gentes. 3. I do not however think that we can regard the chieftainship of the gens as normally derived from the domestic control of the Patriarch of the patriarchal family, transmitted to the eldest son of the eldest line as the family expands into the clan. For I do not think we can assume this patriarchal form of the family to have continuously existed through primitive ages : since M'Lennan and others have shown the widespread existence — in very different races and regions, not excluding Indo-Germans — of either polyandry or the uncertain and transient marriage relations implied in the customary tracing of kinship through females only. And the kind of family which zoological analogies suggest as primeval, — based on sexual jealousy and physi- cal force, with the strongest male ruling and guarding his females and their young — does not help us to explain what specially requires explanation in the organisation of the clan, namely, the obedience of many grown men to one man not physically stronger than they. Even in the cases in which the patriarchal family may have been established, and have then expanded into the clan, it does not seem that the rather artificial and refined idea of " son representing father," is sufficient to explain how hereditary chieftainship becomes established in a group into which this family expands. Especially as in the groups of this kind which we know as parts of States more advanced in civilisation, there is certainly no transmission of quasi -paternal authority IV SUMMARY OF THEORY OF ORIGIN 59 to the man placed at the head of affairs ; he is manager, not patriarch. I admit that the estabhshment of the patriarchal family within the clan — as I conceive it — was doubtless an im- portant factor in rendering chieftainship hereditary. The chief would aim at handing down his position like his property, and it would seem natural to others that he should do this ; if he had a likely son they would acquiesce ; and the chieftainship would become elective within the family — somewhat as we find it in the Irish clans. But it does not in any way follow that the power of the chieftain was a complete continuation of the " patria potestas " : and though we may reasonably conceive the chief of the Gens as manager of whatever property was held in common, we have no reason to conceive him as having absolute control over it, or over the other members of the Gens. This view will I think be confirmed, if we consider more closely what the functions of the chief or king must have been at the earliest stage in the social development of the peoples that we are considering. Apart from the management of common property, and putting any supposed relation to the Divinity out of account, these functions must have been mainly strategic and judicial. The chief has not to legislate : since, in this stage of development, law exists only in the state of custom which no individual or combina- tion of individuals has any definite authority to alter : and what in later times are distinguished as internal executive functions must be supposed to have been very rudimentary in the beginnings of political development. The tribe or clan requires a leader in war, and a judge in peace : — but, as Maine ^ holds, the preserved traces of earliest law and legal ceremony show the judge's ordinary work to have been a kind of arbitration : he has to decide the disputes between families that are voluntarily brought before him, and especially to bring blood-feuds to a peaceful termination. Now it is obvious that very different qualities are required for strategic and judicial functions respectively. ^ Aiicient Law, ch. x. 6o DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. The best judge would ordinarily be an old man, skilled in the customs of the tribe, but he would not be most fit for leader in war. So far, therefore, as chieftainship was determined by efficiency, we should expect the two functions often to fall apart. And in fact, as Mr. Tylor^ says, "in barbarous countries the tribe-chief and the war-chief may be found side by side " : though doubtless, " when the power of the bow and spear once asserts itself, it is apt to grow further." § 2. Leaving these speculations, let us return to the " primitive polity," which, with the qualifications I have given, I think we may accept as giving a general type of government — allowing for large variations in different times and districts — which belongs to the " tribal condition " of Greeks, Eomans, and Germans in the earliest stage in which history throws any light on it. The streams of political development are thus, as I said, tolerably close together at the point to which we trace each back. We have now to follow their divergent courses. But before beginning the development of Greek polity, with which we shall be mainly concerned in this and the five following lectures, I should like to point out a hypo- thetical advantage and an actual disadvantage of study- ing the phenomena of political development in Greece, as compared with studying them in the history of modern states. The advantage is that there are so many more instances to generalise from, if we only knew them. Here I may remind you that we have to think not only of Greece proper ; for Greek immigrants, at an early stage of Greek civilisation, filled the isles of the Aegean including the large island of Crete, and the west coast of Asia Minor, with small independent communities, which became city-states as civilisation went on ; then later Greek colonisation still further extended this type of polity, carrying it up the coasts of the Adriatic and making Southern Italy a " Magna Graecia," spreading over the greater part of Sicily, extending northward to the Crimea, eastward along the coast of the Euxine, southward to Libya, westward even to far Marseilles. 1 See Tylor, Anthropology , ch. xvi. p. 431. IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 6i It is easy to see that there were thus brought into being independent city-states in hundreds, a comparison of whose polities would have afforded a rich field for induction. But, unfortunately, our knowledge of most instances is extremely meagre and fragmentary. The only constitutions that we know with anything like fulness are those of Sparta and Athens. In other cases, I think the best that we can say is that we probably know the general character of the most important constitutional changes ; but in many cases we cannot say even this. Owing to this, I think only a few broad generalisations can be confidently made with regard to the changes in the forms of government of Greek city-states generally. And an important question then arises how far we can generalise from Sparta and Athens taken as types. I think that, as regards early history, we may do this to some extent, taking Sparta as a type of a community formed by superimposing a conquering tribe on a conquered community, the con- querors becoming a ruling class monopolising political rights ; and Attica as a type of a community " integrated " as it passes out of the tribal condition into that of a city-state, without any such traceable effect of conquest. Again, I think we may regard Athens as a representative type to an important extent of Greek democracy in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. ; partly through the influence of natural imitation, in consequence of the leading position rapidly taken by Athens after the expulsion of the tyrants at the end of the sixth century (510 B.C.), and especially after the successful resistance of Athens to the Persian invasions in the first quarter of the fifth century. On the other hand, we have to bear in mind the quasi-metropolitan position of Athens, derived from her maritime empire, which makes her, so far, unlike other cities. The splendour of Athens was largely due to her imperial position ; and the fulness of her political life was at once stimulated by the task of ruling her empire, and financially sustained by the contributions of the subject cities. But, allowing for this, it is, as I remarked before, at any rate probable that the 62 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Greek states that moved towards democracy in the fifth and fourth centuries were powerfully influenced by the example of Athens, and had a tendency to copy her institu- tions. It would, however, be a fundamental mistake to assume similarly that Sparta was a type of Greek oligarchies. The Spartan constitution must be regarded as almost sui generis, and though the Spartans support oligarchies else- where against the drift to democracy, they do not support constitutions of which their own is a type. § 3. Let us now observe the movement as regards the head chieftainship or kingship of the tribe in the early stage of the races we are examining. As the "primitive polity" has a threefold division of functions among king or head chief, subordinate chiefs, and assembly of freemen, it is natural to conceive that the three kinds of government, popularly distinguished in Greek thought of the fifth and fourth centuries B.C. as monarchy, oligarchy or aristocracy, democracy, come from the preponderance at different times of one or other of these elements, and it is natural to suppose that they preponderated successively — one, few, and many ; kingship becoming oppressive and causing a movement against it which threw power into the hands of subordinate chiefs or nobles; and this govern- ment of the few becoming oppressive in its turn, and thus causing a change to more democratic conditions. And this is, in fact, the view of the natural order of constitutions taken by Polybius, the historian of the second century B.C., who saw the establishment of Eoman dominion over Greece, and thus is, among the Greek writers personally interested in free Greece, the one who had his attention specially directed to Eome. He saw the first subjection of Greece by Eome (146 B.C.); and previously to this had lived in exile seventeen years in Italy. Thus — unlike Aristotle, of whose view I shall speak later — his generalisa- tions as to the development of polity are naturally formed on the basis of the experience of Eome, now dominant, as well as of Greece. According to the generalisations of Polybius, polity is to be conceived as passing naturally IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 63 through the following stages : — Monarchy, through the vices to which it tempts, degenerates into tyranny. Then, the luxury and insolent immorality of the tyrant leading to scandal and hatred, there follows aristocracy. This in its turn degenerates into oligarchy as the ruling class takes partly to money-getting, partly to insolent debauchery, and becomes in both ways oppressive. Then, the masses being stirred by this oppression to resistance and retaliation, there follows democracy ; which, when Demos in his turn becomes insolent and lawless, turns to ochlocracy till the people again find their master in a monarch, and the round begins again. Now, as regards the earlier stages, especially the position of the tyrant between the legitimate king and aristocracy, this scheme certainly seems — as Polybius expressly says — to suit the history of Eome. Through all the uncertainties of tradition we seem to discern clearly that the later king- ship in Rome was more masterful and oppressive than the earlier ; and after kings are got rid of they do not come back. The popular memory of hate and aversion that the violent end of the monarchy leaves behind is successfully kept alive by the patricians who succeed to rule ; the word " king," as Mommsen says, seems to have acted on a Roman populace like the word " popery "on an English populace. So long as the Roman state remains really a city-state, there is no more monarchy ; it is not till Rome has expanded into a country-state, with an empire subject to it, that monarchy comes in again, as an apparently indispensable organ for maintaining the coherence of this great structure. And we hear of one or two instances of similarly violent transitions in Greece, one of which, no doubt, specially influ- enced Polybius and probably, taken together with Rome, led him to the generalisation above given. This is the tradition in Achaea — the strip of country in the north of the Peloponnese, which is so obscure in the brilliant period of Greek city-states and becomes so important later, in the third century, as the nucleus of the Achaean League. We find Achaeans at the beginning of Greek history, in Homer, as the common name for Greeks, and Achaeans at the end 64 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. (Achaia in the New Testament), but hardly hear of them in the middle ! Well, Polybius ^ tells us that kingship ended in Achaea, because the people were displeased with the sons of the last king "for ruling not according to law, but despotically," and so changed the government to a demo- cracy (et? hr)^oKpaTiav). What importance is to be attached to this statement as an apparent exception to the general rule that when monarchy was put down oligarchical governments follow, I will consider presently. I now only mention it as an instance of violent transition on account of the tyrannical aggravation of kingly rule. We hear of one or two other instances of similar violent transition.^ But on the whole, though the imperfections of our knowledge render it difficult to speak confidently, we must, I think, regard them as exceptions. Certainly in Athens, Thebes,^ and Argos * the reduction of royal power is represented as peaceful ; and I think we may infer it as having been normally peaceful, or, at any rate, not due to violent reaction against despotism where the government remains in the royal house after the transition to oligarchy. Of this there are several instances known to us. Compare the famous oligarchy of the Bacchiads at Corinth, the Basilids at Ephesus and Erythrae in Asia Minor, the Penthilids at Mitylene in Lesbos, the Aleuads at Larissa in Thessaly ; in all these cases, when life-long monarchy has come to an end, the chief offices of government appear to be still confined to the royal house.^ Contrast with this the expulsion of the Tarquins at Eome. The difference obviously means a comparatively peaceful transition to oligarchy. I think, then, that we may infer from our evidence that the transition to oligarchy in Greece was more often 1 Polyb. Hist. ii. 41. ^ Samos, Plut. Qu. Gr. cli. 57 ; perliaps Megara, Paus. i. ch. xliii. 3 ; and Arcadia, Paus. viii. ch. v. 13, tliough the extent and nature of the power of these "Kings of Arcadia" is very dubious. 3 Paus. IX. ch. V. 16. "* Paus. ii. ch. xix. 2. ^ Using the term royal house in an enlarged sense. The Bacchiads were a large clan of over 200. IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 65 gradual, and without any great shock of revolutionary violence. And, in fact, from the time that we first hear of Greek polity, the old-fashioned monarchy — the monarchy of the primitive polity, with functions limited by law or custom, and customarily shared with council and assembly — this monarchy appears to be gradually declining in relative prestige. We see this decline in Homer, as we pass from the Iliad to the Odyssey ; where, as I have said, it is even marked by the use of the title " Basileus," which in the Iliad is, I think, always appropriated to the head of a demos or his sons ; ^ but when we come to the Odyssey, " basileus " is " chief " rather than king. This is shown early in the poem, in the passage already referred to, where Telemachus says there are many chiefs (ffao-ckrje^) of the Achaeans in Ithaca, though, as afterwards appears, the island has only one city, and its inhabitants form one " demos " with one assembly. And again, when Odysseus in his travels is thrown on the shore of pleasant Scheria, where the noble Phaeacians dwell in what is manifestly represented as an ideal and happy condition, we find, from the statement of the head-chief Alcinous, that there are " twelve glorious chiefs (^acnXrj€<;) who rule among the people, and he is the thirteenth." ^ It is evident that monarchy is moving downwards towards oligarchy.^ Still, though there is comparatively little evidence anywhere in Greece that the transition to oligarchy was due to a movement against an oppressive extension of monarchical power, monarchical despotism has an im- portant place in the development of Greek polity; but it comes after oligarchy, not before it, and is, in all the cases ^ Lecture 11. p. 34. ^ Od. viii. 391. The ^aaiXTJes in Phaeacia are clearly under-kings ruling separate districts, a certain amount of integration having taken place : Kara 87J1J.0V implies this. ^ The transition seems to have been (a) sometimes to a single /SaaiXeiJy generally elective for a year with reduced — chiefly sacrificial — functions (cf. Ar. Pol. iii. 9, 8), and (&) sometimes to boards of ^aa-iXels. Compare Kyme (Plut. Qu. Gr. 2, p. 360), Elis (Cauer^ 253), Mitylene (Cauer^ 428). I do not think the ^acnXaes at Elis were limited, as Gilbert says {Griech. Staatsalt. § 19, p. 100), to priestly functions. F 66 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. actually known to us, irregular, unconstitutional despotism. It will be convenient to call this by the Greek name "Tyrannis." Its nature, causes, and development I shall consider more fully in a later lecture. At present I have only referred to it to make clear the very important differ- ence between the evolution of Greek and Eoman polity respectively ; that, speaking broadly, the place of despotic monarchy is in the Greek order of development, not between the old monarchy restrained by custom and oligarchy, but between oligarchy and democracy. The Tyrannus is not, as at Eome, a primitive monarch using his power oppressively beyond the limits of old law and custom, but an ambitious leader who wrests monarchical power from oppressive oligarchs by the aid of popular support. § 4. We may complete our general view of the manner in which the three lines of development — Greek, Eoman, German — diverge by noticing the striking difference be- tween Greece and Germany. In early German history the movement is, as we have seen, towards kingship. The German tribes appear on the scene, in Caesar, largely without the institution, but it appears to be gradually adopted everywhere ; and when once adopted it has remarkable stability, as it lasts on through medieval and modern history. In Greece, on the other hand, almost the only traceable movement is the other way : between the age of Homer and the earliest period really historical, kingship in Greece proper has in most States changed into a form of oligarchy ; — one of the few exceptions being Sparta, where, as I have said, primitive institutions were artificially preserved ; but even here kings are reduced to little more than hereditary commanders-in-chief. What is the explanation of this ? Partly, no doubt, the Germans are in an earlier stage of development ; partly, however, we have to refer it to the fact that the process of civilisation that was going on in Greece tended towards the development of small compact states ; which ultimately, in the most advanced communities, have a definitely urban character, the ideas of " city " and IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 67 "state" coming to be blended in a single notion. Whereas, when the Germans began gradually to grow more civilised through contact with the Eoman Empire, the idea of a civilised polity with which they thus became familiar was that of a State extending over a large area of territory, includ- ing municipalities as a subordinate element of a coherent political order; and during the centuries of dissolution and reconstruction, in which the conquered and semi-barbarised fragments of the empire were growing into orderly and coherent nations, this idea of a " country-state " governed their development. The important effects of the distinction between town and country, as elements of the modern state, are familiar to us all ; but we do not always reflect on the profound historical significance of the distinction. While the history of civilisation in ancient Europe is the history of a social life that had its focus always in the town, from which " civility " dimly radiated into the country, the history of modern Europe through the Middle Ages and the Eenais- sance shows us this civilisation modified by the habits of a conquering race, who were distinguished by their fondness for country life, and who retained this characteristic long after they had become civilised. Hence it is one of the most essential differences between Greek politics and modern European politics — a difference from which many others flow — that, in the most civilised period of Greek history, at any rate up to the time of the Macedonian predominance, the political ideal of the most highly civilised Greeks was essentially a city-state. A Greek of this period was of course familiar with bar- barian communities, notably the huge Persian monarchy, in which one government ruled over large countries ; but yet he could hardly conceive of a high degree of political organisa- tion being attained by a community whose political life did not centre in a single town.^ He had, indeed, a sentiment ^ Though Sparta was in a certain sense not a town, but an "agglutination of five adjacent villages," it had the political characteristics of a town — common assembly and close intercourse — in a peculiarly high degree. 68 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of nationality extending beyond the limits of his city : he recognised ties that bound him as a Dorian, say, to other Dorians, as a Hellene to other Hellenes ; but these sentiments were usually feeble in comparison with the patriotism that glowed in a good citizen for his own city. They prompted him to combine with other Hellenes in religious ceremonials and celebrations, and to aid them in war against foreign foes, — perhaps to form leagues, designed to be permanent, for military defence ; — but they did not usually dispose him to form such a political union as would involve the sacrifice of the autonomy of his own city. The apparent exceptions to this general statement, though very extensive, are mostly either found among Greeks who are behind the leading states in political and social development, or they are cases of hard fact conflicting with an ideal still cherished. On the one hand, as Freeman says,^ " the robbers of Aetolia, the respectable but obscure townships of the Achaian shore, and some other of the less advanced and less important members of the Hellenic body" — Acar- nanians, Phokians, and others, "possessed, as far back as we can trace their history, some germs of a polity which may fairly entitle them to rank among Federal common- wealths." On the other hand, Greek history shows us many cities, sharing the full stream of Greek civilisation, that submit to the rule of other cities ; but the submission is mostly reluctant, and involves a sense of inferiority. Of civilised Greeks, in the palmy days of Greece, it is generally true that, however conscious an individual may be of wider circles of nationality, his city is the one political whole of which he permanently and strongly feels himself a part ; and though this city may be in fact dependent on Athens or Sparta, its independence is the ideal condition after which he aspires. This view of the political ideal of Greece finds emphatic expression in the writings of the philosophers Plato and Aristotle. However much these two great thinkers may disagree, they agree in taking as an ideal political com- ^ History of Federal Government, chap. ii. p. 16 (2nd edition). IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 69 munity a single city, together with the country required to supply the material needs of its inhabitants ; they cannot conceive a free civilised community, if really well governed, to be organised on a larger scale. We may distinguish different causes that combined to produce this effect. 1. The primary cause of the growth of the town, as dis- tinct from the village, is of course economic ; it consists in the extension of exchange rendering convenient a larger aggregation of persons engaged in trade or manufactures in adjacent buildings. But 2. The opportunities that the town affords for more habitual and varied communication of experience and thought, and for gratification of common sentiments by art, social expansion, and organised ceremonial, tend to make urban civilisation far outstrip rural, especially before the discovery of printing. Thus civilised life seemed to the Greek to be necessarily connected with cities, where there was a market- place for daily meeting, ornamental temples and porticoes, theatres for music or recitation, gymnasia for athletic exer- cises, etc. But all this is only part of the required explanation. Civilisation has all over the world developed in towns ; the peculiarity of Greece is that they were independent towns with vigorous and intense national life. I have, however, already drawn attention to the physical conditions which had at least an important share in causing this independence ; namely the configuration of Greece, which at once separates by land and affords easy means of communication by sea : so that the more advanced Greek tribes acquired a blending of those habits of independence as regards outsiders, of mutual dependence and es'prit de corps within the community, that we find among mountaineers, with the awakened intellect and varied experiences of a seafaring people. 3. Assuming this independence, we may note, as a third important reason for the Greek tendency to associate high political development with urban life, the large amount of protection which the walled town gave against hostile attack. 70 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. This made city life not only more delightful and elevated than village life, but safer. Villagers, if they could not hold their own against an invading enemy in the field, had to fly to trackless mountain coverts, or huddle wretchedly into little strongholds where their normal life could not be carried on ; but city life could go on at Athens during the Peloponnesian war with full and vigorous pulsation — how- ever disagreeable it might be to see the Lacedaemonians cut- ting down one's barley and fruit trees, and to have to turn out on cold nights to do garrison duty.-^ Then, as gradually there formed itself in the Greek mind the conception of the State as the whole of which all the individual citizens were parts, to whose interests the interests of any individual might be legitimately sacrificed, and to whose will, as expressed in its constitution and laws, the wills of all officials from highest to lowest were subordi- nate, — the city came at the same time to be conceived as the necessary outward framew^ork of this inner political order. A larger State seemed to be incapable of furnishing the means for effective performance of civic functions, for how in such a State could the citizens meet in one assembly and receive announcements from one herald " not being a stentor " ? and how could they have the knowledge of each other's characters, necessary for determining questions of justice and distributing offices of state according to desert ? ^ Thus, while the material unity of the town, and the con- centration of life which it causes, assists the development of the conception of the State and the habits and patriotic sentiment attached to it, so, on the other hand, the develop- ment of political life thus inseparably connected with town life, completes and fixes the Greek notion of the city com- munity — i.e. a community inhabiting a district with a city for centre — as the highest and ultimate form of human association. ^ It is to be observed, however, that this walling round of whole large towns only becomes general gradually, e.q.^ even Athens has only its Acropolis fortified under the Pisistratids. 2 Aristotle, Pol. iv. (vii.) iv. IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP Ji § 5. The process of transition from the village to the town, and from small towns to larger, was often, we may note, semi- compulsory, — e.g., it appears so in Athens and in Eome so far as we can dimly discern it through the mists of legend, — and we may conjecture that the process was powerfully pro- moted by the ambition of primitive kings whose dignity and wealth were enhanced by the result. At the same time it is, I think, to this development of civilised life in small separate communities tending to become city-states, that the transition from kingship and the further series of stages through which the political institutions of Greece passed is largely to be attributed. While kingship spreads and develops among the Germanic tribes, during the first few centuries in which they are known to us, largely, it would seem, from the value that it is felt to have as the bond and symbol of national unity, so, on the other hand, the smallness and concentrated residence of the Hellenic communities appears to have rendered the bond superfluous and the symbol unimpressive. This is substantially Grote's -^ explanation of the origin of the oligarchy in Greece. As he says : — when the personal deficiencies of the hereditary king came to be felt, " there was nothing in the circumstances of the community which rendered the maintenance of such a dignity necessary for visible and effective union; in a single city and a small circumjacent community, collective deliberation and general rules, with temporary and responsible, magistrates, were practicable without difficulty." Thus . . . "the inferior chiefs who had originally served as council to the king, found it possible to supersede him and to alternate the functions of administration among themselves ; retaining probably the occasional convocation of the general assembly as it had existed before, and with as little practical efficacy. Such was in substance the character of that mutation which occurred generally throughout the Grecian States, with the exception of Sparta ; kingship was abolished, and an oli- garchy took its place — a council deliberating collectively, ^ See History of Greece, Part ii. chap. ix. 72 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. deciding general matters by the majority of voices, and selecting some individuals of their own body as temporary and accountable administrators. It was always an oligarchy which arose on the defeasance of the heroic kingdom ; the age of democratical movement was yet far distant, and the condition of the people — the general body of freemen — was not immediately altered, either for better or worse, by the revolution." As I have before said,^ I consider that Grote somewhat underrates the importance of the primitive assembly ; and his statement that it was " always an oligarchy " which took the place of the primitive kingship is probably too broad. As we saw just now, Polybius tells us that in the Achaean towns the violent overthrow of the monarchy led at once to democracy ; and it is easy to conceive that in small societies undisturbed by conquest, and out of the main stream of industrial and commercial progress, a comparative equality in wealth and manner of life was maintained among the citizens much longer than elsewhere, so that when the king was superseded what naturally followed was a moderate democracy. I conjecture that this may have been the case in some parts of Arcadia also. But speaking broadly and generally, it is doubtless safe to affirm that when political society passed in Greece out of the stage of primitive king- ship, it passed into that of primitive oligarchy. It is to be noted that the transition took place at very different times in different States. In the time of Thucy- dides there are no kings left in any of the city-states that are in the full current of Hellenic civilisation ; but that historian speaks (I. ch. iii.) of a " king of the Thessalians " in the middle of the fifth century, and we may infer from Herodotus (vii. 149) that Argos had a hereditary king at the time of the Persian war, whereas long before that date the so-called "king" at Athens has dropped to a mere elected member of a board of chief magistrates. In Corinth and Chalcis, the commercial centres which sent out colonies in the latter half of the eighth century, we learn that the 1 Lect. II. pp. 35, 36. IV TRANSITION FROM PRIMITIVE KINGSHIP 73 colonies were sent out by a trading oligarchy. In Athens too the process, according to tradition, had begun before the middle of this century. The process in the case of Athens, where we can trace the change most definitely, appears to have been very gradual. First the monarchical office is shorn of a part of its power by the appointment of a " polemarch " or commander-in-chief distinct from the king; then a third magistrate {ap^oav) is appointed — who ultimately becomes the chief executive official for matters of internal govern- ment — and the kingly office ceases to be hereditary : then the term of office for all three is limited to ten years : then the office of chief magistrate — hitherto confined to the royal house — is thrown open to all the nobles {evTrarpihai) ; finally (683 B.C.) executive functions are divided among nine annual magistrates. Meanwhile it would seem that, as a natural consequence of these changes, the council of elders, that had in earlier times shared the functions of government with the king, gradually increased in power. For when the chief magistracy became elective, the election naturally fell to this body : then, when the term of office became annual, as vacancies in the council were naturally filled by those who had served as magistrates, it is easy to under- stand how this permanent body would tend to become superior in prestige and power to the annual magistrate. When this process of change is complete, we have the oligarchical form of government definitely substituted for the monarchical. The nature and ultimate result of this process of transition doubtless varied much in different communities ; but almost everywhere kingship goes. Probably the change spread from community to community largely by conscious imitation ; when one city had put down its king, its neighbour was moved to do the same ; probably the insolence, oppression, weakness, of some kings, the ability and good government of others, hastened it here, retarded it there ; but the result is too general and uniform not to be attributed mainly to general causes. And I think we may 74 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. iv largely attribute it to the simple conviction that as the unity and order of the gradually more civilised and concentrated community could be maintained without him, the single li^ift-devouring king " had become a superfluous burden. LECTUEE V EAKLY OLIGARCHY IX THE GREEK CITY-STATE In the preceding lecture we were considering the movement towards oligarchy in Greece, and concentrating attention on the relation of nobles to monarch. The nature of the oligarchy that succeeded was, as I have said, different in different cases. In some cases the main powers of govern- ment were retained within the royal family or clan, until the period of Tyrannis arrives. This was the case {e.g.) at Corinth, where we are told that the house of the Bacchids or Bacchiads ruled for ninety years — the last half of the eighth and the first half of the seventh century B.C. ; a yearly magistrate being chosen out of the family to fill the place of the hereditary king. And, as I said before, we hear of similar kingly families exercising oligarchical rule in several other city-states up to the time of Tyrannis. In other cases, so far as our knowledge goes, the power was shared among a group of families when monarchy declined, e.g. Eupatridae at Athens and Hippobotae at Chalcis and Eretria in Euboea. Let us now turn to consider what change, if any, took place as regards the third governmental element in the primitive polity — the assembly of the freemen in arms. There is no reason to suppose that any change in power on this side necessarily accompanied the reduction of monarchy. Here, doubtless, as Homer would suggest, the predominance of the wealthy landowners was complete in many cases before kingship comes to an end : the king was only the coping-stone of an oligarchical structure of society. Still it is easy to understand how the abolition of monarchy would 75 76 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. render the governing families even more decidedly pre- dominant in this assembly, which we may suppose, with Grote, to have been retained with something like its primitive functions. But apart from any change in the relation of king to subordinate chiefs or elders, we may distinguish different causes operating to give this assembly an oligarchical character — causes somewhat different in different classes of states. Before doing this it is needful to clear up a certain amount of vagueness and confusion that attaches to the ordinary notion of oligarchy. Oligarchy is defined by Aristotle as the rule of the rich few: and doubtless in times near Aristotle's the issue between oligarchy and democracy might be broadly stated as the question whether a rich minority should rule or the mass of free citizens. But this is not the only way in which Oligarchy = Eule of a minority might — or did — arise : since the whole body of citizens might be a minority, even a small minority, as compared with non-citizens (even excluding slaves). This double conception of oligarchy^ may be fitly illustrated from the case of the Greek state whose constitution most clearly recalls the features of the earliest known period — Sparta, the champion of oligarchy in Greece. We have in the Spartans a body of professional warriors — Herodotus reckons them at 8000 men at the time of the Persian war, and Aristotle reports a tradition that they were once as many as 10,000 — an invading tribe permanently fixed by conquest in Sparta as owners of the land in certain parts of Laconia and Messenia ; maintaining a singular system of rigorous education, drill, and semi -communistic regulation, with a view to the maintenance of simplicity of life and martial valour and skill. They lived on the produce of lands cultivated by a much larger number of serfs called " Helots " — at the battle of Plataea, in the Persian war, we find seven 1 This double conception of oligarchy is overlooked by Freeman when he treats the three elements of his primitive polity- King "i ( Monarchical elements. Council of chiefs Assembly of free warriors }( Monarchical as simply equal to -| Oligarchical I Democratic V EARL y OLIGARCHY IN THE GREEK CITY-STA TE 77 Helots attending on each Spartan — serfs attached to the soil, but only required to supply a fixed amount of agricultural produce ; and they held in political dependence the person- ally free inhabitants of the rest of the territory, whom we may estimate at more than three times their number. Their original constitution was, as I have before explained,-^ the "primitive polity" but slightly modified. There were two kings — the cause of the duality not ascertainable, but probably due to an early coalescence of communities — whom we may regard as having originally the functions of the Homeric kings : in the period best known to us they were mainly important as hereditary generals; though they retained special religious privileges and conspicuous special honours, and also certain judicial functions. Secondly, there was a senate of elders, composed of men over sixty, elected for life by the assembly of fully qualified citizens — elected by a quaint old fashion of acclama- tion, estimated by officials placed so that they could not see who was acclaimed. Thirdly, there was the general assembly of full citizens over thirty, who had the power of electing senators and high magistrates, and whose assent was required in the rare event of a new law, and for the determination of war and peace, and the ratification of treaties.^ This assembly of full citizens may be assumed to have originally consisted of the descendants of the whole conquering tribe — speaking broadly : but the condition of paying the contribution necessary to provide the common meals — which every Spartan with full civic rights was obliged to share — ex- cluded the very poor: and this exclusion grew more im- portant as time went on. I ought to mention a remarkable restriction in the power of the assembly, said to have been made a century after 1 Lect. II. pp. 38, 39. 2 When Herodotus (vi. 56) tells us that the kings have the "right of making war upon whatever country they please, without hindrance from any other Spartans," I think he must be understood to mean not the right of declaring war, but of determining the course of the campaign after the declaration of war. Or Herodotus may have made a simple mistake : cf. Thuc. I. XX. Cf. also Herodotus, iii. 46 ; v. 64 ; vi. 106. 78 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Lycurgiis, that " in case the people resolved on a wrong course the senate with the rulers should reverse their decision." ^ It has been inferred ^ that this must have re- duced the decision of the assembly to a mere form : but I think it evidently in no way affected their power of refusing assent to what was proposed — 'preventing any proposed change — it only gave an equal power of prevention to the senate. This was the original constitution : but there was pre- sently added a board of Ephors or Supervisors, elected annually in some way which we do not precisely know, but which, Plato says, comes near election by lot. Appointed, it seems, originally for police purposes, and as a check to neglect of duty or misuse of power by other magistrates, these Ephors gradually increased their power and became the supreme executive for domestic affairs, with a considerable amount of control even in war. Their power, in its nature and extent, the secrecy and relentless severity with which it was exercised, and its object — the maintenance of the constitution alike against discontented Spartans and discontented serfs and dependants — has some striking resemblance to that of the Council of Ten at Venice. They could arrest and imprison any Spartan — even magistrates, suspending them from their functions : even the kings were bound to appear before them after being three times summoned ; and they had power of life and death over the serf cultivators and the inhabitants of the dependent towns of Laconia. jN'ow, in modern times, no one seems to have any doubt that the Spartan government is oligarchical or aristocratic (the two terms being used nearly convertibly — not dis- tinguishing as Plato and Aristotle do the " government of men of merit" from the "government of the few rich"). But there is considerable disagreement as to the reason why it is so. Is it (1) because the Spartans are few compared to their many serfs and subjects ? Or is it (2) because the 1 Plut. lAfc. vi. 7. 2 See Spencer, Political Institutions, § 488 ; derived from Grote, Part ir. chap. vi. Grote's view, however, is that which I have given. V EARLY OLIGARCHY IN THE GREEK CITY-STATE 79 Spartans themselves are a many governed by a few? The former answer is not, I think, what a Greek would ordinarily have given. The Greeks regarded the Helots as broadly equivalent to the slaves in other cities, and Aristotle at least in considering the political constitution of Sparta ignores the non-Spartan inhabitants of Laconia altogether. And if we consider merely the internal political relations of the Spartan community, they present rather a doubtful and changing, than a clearly oligarchical character. There may have been a time at which the "real power was in the hands of the senate : " ^ but in Aristotle's time it is clear that the substance of power had passed into the hands of the Board of Supervisors or Ephors. Aristotle speaks, indeed, of the senatorship as a position of great dignity and honour — " prize of merit " — but he does not describe it as having more than judicial functions ; whereas he speaks of the Board of Ephors as "having the decision in the most important matters," and having "very great and despotic power." And though Grote, taking this latter view, calls the Spartan government a " close, unscrupulous, and well -obeyed oligarchy," we may infer from Aristotle that, in the view of Greek political thinkers, the application of the term "oligarchical" to the power of Ephors over Spartans would have seemed at least doubtful. The office of Ephor was open to all full citizens ; the mode of election, not precisely known, was certainly so far democratic that it gave no advantage to wealth and social position (Aristotle complains that it admitted " poor and venal " candidates) ; the Board only held office for a year, and were responsible like other magistrates when they laid it down. Accordingly, Aristotle's view is that when the Ephors became predominant " the polity gradually changed from aristocracy to demo- cracy," ^ i.e. of course so far as rule over fully qualified Spartan citizens is concerned. Hence, so far as Sparta can be properly viewed as clearly and permanently exemplifying the oligarchical principle, — 1 See Bluntschli, Theory of the State, Book vi. chap. xvii. 2 See Aristotle, Politics, 11. ch. ix. : compare also vi. (iv.) ch. ix. 8o DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. and certainly, as Aristotle recognises, Spartan policy was steadily on the side of oligarchy elsewhere in Greece, — it must be on account of the relation of the whole body of the Spartans as a ruling " few " to a very much larger subject population. Erom this point of view the Ephorate may doubtless be regarded as an eminently oligarchical institution — I mean eminently adapted to the maintenance of a ruling minority against revolutions, whether initiated among their subjects or among discontented members of their own body. But it is important clearly to apprehend the difference between the two points of view. If we con- ceive of Sparta as an oligarchy throughout its history, it is not that the free warriors of Sparta lost their share of political power, but that they became practically a governing few in relation to their serf -cultivators and the free inhabitants of the dependent towns of Laconia. It is from this point of view only that Spartan rule is clearly oligarchical, at all periods of its history ; though in later times the reduction of the number of fully qualified citizens,^ through loss of the means required as provision for the regular training, made the fully qualified citizens a minority even of Spartans. § 2. And though the Lycurgean institutions of Sparta were unique, this kind of oligarchy, in which the original assembly of armed freemen of a conquering tribe becomes a " few " among the conquered many, is by no means unique. It is clear, e.g. that the Dorians in Argos entered into a relation to the conquered Achaeans closely similar to that of the Dorians in Sparta ; we have the serf cultivators of the land appropriated by the conquerors — only called Gymnetes instead of Helots — and a similar group of dependent towns or villages, whose inhabitants had civil freedom but no political independence. So again, in the towns of Crete we find a similar threefold structure of society ; Dorian conquerors, serf-cultivators, free but dependent provincials, and in Cretan institutions as in the Spartan, the assent of the assembly of free warriors is required to important measures ; though Aristotle tells us that in his time it had ^ See Appendix, Note A. V EARLY OLIGARCHY IN THE GREEK CITY-STATE 8i no substantial power. And it is at least not improbable that in most other places Dorian conquest led to a some- what similar result at first. In other parts of Greece where the political society historically known to us traces its origin to conquest, the result, so far as our information goes, was — ultimately if not at first — a government entirely in the hands of leading families, or small groups of families. This seems to have been the case in Thessaly, where the power in different cities seems to have been in the hands of noble families tracing their descent from Heracles; also in Thebes, and in Boeotia generally, where all we hear indicates oligarchical rule strictly limited to a hereditary group of landowning families, which seems to narrow in course of time. So among the Dorians we hear of political privileges confined to 180 men in Epidaurus ; and we find a similar limitation in Elis. But it is not only through conquest that this kind of oligarchical position is acquired by the body that represents the aggregate of free warriors of the tribe. For in the Greek city-state generally citizenship depends normally on inheritance ; the children of aliens born within the territory remain normally aliens — they are only admitted to citizen- ship by special favour, except at crises of change.^ Hence any Greek community might easily become, in this sense, oligarchically constituted as it grew from small beginnings into a flourishing city ; the number of free non-citizens attracted by its prosperity exceeding that of citizens thus limited by inheritance. I conceive that oligarchical government may often have resulted in this way in the earliest stages of the history of a colony. The earliest settlers would divide the land they occupied for the most part into equal lots — it having been on this understanding that the original settlers collected together — and as the colony flourished and grew, the de- scendants of these " land shareholders," ^ would keep the ^ In this they differed, of course, from modern Europe, where the children of aliens usually become citizens of the country in which they are born. ^ ydfxopoi, or yeibfxopoL. At Syracuse and Samos they were oligarchical, not at Athens. 82 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. privileges of citizenship to themselves, excluding both their serfs and the trading population that the prosperity of the town gradually attracted : and thus the government would gradually become oligarchical.^ On the other hand where, as in Athens, the city-state that we historically know was formed by "integration" — that is the political coalescence of a number of smaller towns that still continued to have a "separate existence — it seems that this coalescence itself must have tended to throw the share of power originally exercised by the citizens en masse into the hands of the larger proprietors — the men of old family and wealth — who actually took up their abode in the central town. They alone would remain practically citizens in the full political sense, for eVen though the smaller proprietors were not formally excluded from the assemblies, they would seldom be able to attend. Thus, as I conceive, in more than one way, without any formal change in the political position of the old assembly of freemen, a concentration of political power in the hands of a comparatively small minority of the free members of the community might be gradually brought about. § 3. There is, however, a further important cause — trace- able in some cases, and which we may assume to be tolerably widespread — tending to produce an economic condition favour- able to oligarchy, namely, growing inequality of property. There is, I think, sufficient evidence of an indirect kind, to make it probable that in primitive Greece the tenure of land was at first largely collective ; that is, with pasture common, and allotments of land approximately equal, appropriated ^ The Transvaal is an instance in our own time of the develojjment of an oligarchy in this way. I suppose that a process of this kind had taken place at Apollonia on the Ionian sea, and at Thera, where Aristotle [Pol. vi. (iv.) iv. 9 (1290 b)) tells us that there was "a minority of simply free" — not necessarily wealthy — "citizens ruling a majority," the civic honours being "engrossed by the families which claimed a pre-eminent nobility, as having been the original founders of the colonies, although they Avere numerically few and their subjects were many." As I go on to explain, the number of the ruling class would usually tend to be diminished by the loss of land — and consequently of full civic rights — on the part of many of the descendants of the original citizens. V EARLY OLIGARCHY IN THE GREEK CITY-STATE 83 perhaps at first temporarily to ordinary members of the community: larger portions being specially appropriated to chiefs and sometimes to braves who have rendered special service to the community. As regards pasture, the fact that values in early times were measured in cattle seems decisive ; since it is difficult to see how cattle could be a convenient medium of exchange unless pasture was in common. As regards arable land, a change seems to be taking place during the period of com- position of the Homeric poems. In the Iliad, while we read of common arable land, it is noteworthy that none of the terms applied to a rich man imply landownership ; the rich man is either described as a " man of many flocks and herds " or as a " man of much gold " and " much copper." And even in the Odyssey the term applied to a large land- owner, "man of many lots," carries us back to the time when portions of land — doubtless roughly equal — were distributed by lot among heads of families. Again, the old institution of common meals, at Sparta and elsewhere, is probably a survival from collective ownership of land by a group of real or fictitious kinsmen. Even after complete appropriation had come in, we find from Aristotle that there were several states, e.g. Sparta, in which, for some time longer, the buying and selling of the lots of land was either altogether prohibited or discouraged — only permitted under exceptional circumstances. Still, even the division of inheritances in families of varying size would tend to inequality ; and the tendency would operate more rapidly when sale and purchase was permitted. Now we may fairly infer from Solon's constitution — taken in connexion with the analogies of Eome and Germany — that for some time after private property in land had been fully developed civic privileges and burdens remained connected with the ownership of land of a certain value. The landless freeman who had to work as a hired labourer would be relieved of the duty of fighting at his own charge, and would therefore probably lose his place in the assembly of freemen. The political power of large 84 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. landowners would, in any case, tend to increase as their possessions increased. And this increase of power would be specially marked so long as the importance of cavalry was predominant in war; which was the case in early times — not of course equally everywhere, still widely/ The infantry seems to have long remained an unorganised rabble, except at Sparta. Obviously, only the comparatively rich could afford cavalry equipment for themselves and their followers. Thus we understand how, as Aristotle tells us, the first " polity " or constitutional government in Greece, which was formed after the era of the kings, was substantially under the control of the " knights " ^ — landowners who formed troops of cavalry at their own charges. I conceive, however, that the smaller landowners, who would serve as foot-soldiers at their own charges, — called at Athens " land-shareholders " {rfewfiopoL) in distinction to the gentry of old family {evirarpi- Bat) — would retain a place in the assembly of free citizens and the right to take a part in elections, though the offices and the substantial power would be concentrated in the hands of the gentry. This constitution Aristotle does not consider to have been at first oligarchical in the bad sense of the term : i.e. not an oppressive or selfish rule of the few. And, though I do not regard Aristotle as an important authority on a period so early, I think it probable that this was largely true : that these early governments of few may be fairly called " natural oligarchies," meaning that power was left in the hands of the Few, because the Many were not fit for it and did not seem to themselves to be so. I conceive, then, that oligarchical conditions come to predominate not in one simple way, but in a variety of ways ; partly through the concentration of power in the hands of the old council, raised in power by the substitution of an ^ I may observe that as the art of war progressed the preponderance was transferred from the knights to the heavy-armed infantry, and at a later stage again, old-fashioned soldiers were startled to find battles lost and won by light-armed troops : and Aristotle says that the development of this form of warfare gave an important gain to the poorer citizens in civil dissensions. 2 Pol. VI. (IV.) 13. See Appendix, Note B. V EARLY OLIGARCHY IN THE GREEK CITY-STATE 85 annual magistrate or board of magistrates for the hereditary king ; partly through the limitation of the numbers of fully qualified citizens {a) by the exclusion of the conquered in states founded on conquest and of later immigrants in colonies and (&) by the effect of inequality of wealth and of political "integration" combined in states like Attica. Oligarchy is thus established in the states taking the lead in civilisation as early as the eighth century. As I said, in the period of colonisation which begins soon after the middle of the eighth century — in which Corinth and Chalcis in Euboea take a leading part — these commercial states have already passed into the stage of oligarchy. But it begins at different times in different communities and lasts for varying periods. Then in the seventh century the move- ment against oligarchy begins — but in parts of Greece where agricultural industry predominates and conservative habits hold sway, it lasts longer, so far as we know un- disturbed. Frequently, however, in the first stage of the struggle for power between the oligarchs and the masses, the defeat of the oligarchs does not result in the establishment of democratic institutions : Demos in this first stage is unripe for rule. The mass of free citizens have not sufficient diffused intelligence and faculty of combination to grasp collectively the reins of power: these are seized by an ambitious individual who has taken the lead of the move- ment with an eye to his own aggrandisement. Thus we have Tyrannis, a reversion to monarchy, but to monarchy in almost all cases of an irregular unconstitutional kind, universally regarded as a breach of right and established order, even when the monarch governed with mildness and good effect. LECTUKE VI TYRANNIS § 1. I HAVE before spoken of the phenomenon of "Tyrannis" — the tendency, at a certain stage or stages of the develop- ment of Greek polity, for the government to fall into the hands of a single individual, who — in all the particular cases of lifelong despotism historically known to us — obtains power in a violent and irregular way ; and who sometimes succeeds not only in holding it for life, but also in trans- mitting it at his death to some member of his family. This, as I said, is a feature which distinguishes the develop- ment of Greek from that of Eoman polity ; and it is also interesting to the student of Political Science, from the remarkable parallel which we find to it in the political development of the medieval city-community in Italy — to which I shall draw attention later. I use the Greek name " Tyrannis," because, on the one hand, the English word " Tyranny " suggests too decidedly that the Tyrannus used his power in a practically oppressive, arbitrary, and cruel manner. This was often so, but not always, and the Greek word, as used by writers of the fifth and fourth centuries, does not imply it. Thus Aristotle, writing in the last quarter of the fourth century, tells us that there are two methods by which a "Tyrannus" might preserve his power : the repressive, which was the method adopted by the majority, and the conciliatory ; but he imphes that a Tyrannus who governed with mildness or moderation would be none the less a Tyrannus. On the other hand, the word " despot " does not sufficiently suggest the lawless and irregular character of the power. And this is a 86 V ^ or LECT. VI TYRANNIS 87 fundamentally important characteristic, at least down to the time of the Macedonian predominance. The Greek Tyrannis, in almost every case known to us in free Greece, begins in a cowp d'6tat, and remains irregular and lawless. "VYe know of no case in which an independent Greek state ever " ofifers a crown," unless the acceptance of Gelon as king of Syracuse, after the victory over the Carthaginians, is an exception : and even this is not quite clear. In considering the extent and conditions of Tyrannis, we are led to distinguish between an earlier and a later period. The earlier period favourable to Tyrannis begins, so far as we know, in the first half of the seventh century, in Greece proper ; and in this region and in the islands and Asiatic cities (leaving out of account the eastern cities that have fallen under Persian rule) has, speaking broadly, come to an end before the end of the sixth century. It must be understood that it begins and ends at different times in different cities : and that in no particular case is this irregular despotism, even when it becomes hereditary, very long-lived. According to Aristotle the duration of the Tyrannis of Sicyon — a hundred years — is the longest. But the "Age of the Tyrants " in these regions may be taken to be about 6 5 to 5 B.C. Then follows the time of vigorous and brilliant republican life which begins with the Persian wars and lasts till the predominance of Macedonia. This is the period which we chiefly read about when we read Greek history : it is the time when the political conscious- ness of the Greek city-state is at its height, and republican sentiment, whether oligarchical or democratic, is on the whole too strong to admit of a lapse into despotism. In the younger colonies of Sicily and Southern Italy, the period of the earlier Tyrannis begins and ends at a later date. It does not begin till the end of the seventh century, and its most brilliant time in Sicily is the first quarter of the fifth century — not long before the general putting down of Tyranni, 467 B.C. Then what we may distinguish as the later Tyrannis begins soon after 400 B.C. : but, at least until the time 88 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of the Macedonian supremacy, it does not spread to any extent comparable to the earlier. The distinction between the two is not to be pressed too far, as if there were a sharp division between the types belonging to the two periods respectively ; but, speaking broadly, the causes of the two are different. The causes of the earlier Tyrannis belong more to the inner political development of the Greek city-states : it is usually rendered possible — the opportunity is given — by the first imperfect movements towards popular government. The causes of the later Tyrannis appear to lie more outside the general develop- ment of the polity ; political disorder is always a favouring condition, but an important cause is the growing tendency to employ mercenaries. Another kind of cause, which is operating in certain parts at the end of the first as well as in the second period, is the relation of weak states to powerful neighbours. An individual ruler is found by the powerful neighbour to be the most convenient way of governing what is practically a dependency. From this cause, for example, Tyrannis became prevalent in Ionia on the coast of Asia-Minor at the end of the sixth century B.C., — and in Greece generally after the conquest of Persia by Alexander, and before the development of Federalism, as manifested in the growth of the Achaean League, largely brings it to an end. Speaking broadly, we may say then that the earlier Tyrannis occurs before the citizens of Greek city- states have arrived at full political consciousness. The later revives, after the habits of peaceful industry have diminished the ordinary citizen's power and habit of self- defence. And accordingly, as Aristotle explains, the person who becomes Tyrannus is a different type in each case. In the earlier times, before rhetoric was developed, the man who acquired the position of leader of the popular movement was usually a man of military ability ; so that the transition from demagogue to Tyrannus was easy, and the Tyrannus of the first period was for the most part developed out of a demagogue. The later demagogue, on the other hand, was VI ' TYRANNIS 89 ordinarily not a fighting man, and therefore not qualified for a successful cowp d'4tat : and the later Demos, having arrived at political maturity, was generally less easy to deceive. But though more difficult to wheedle it might be coerced ; and the development of the mercenary system of fighting offered dangerous opportunities for coercion by daring adventurers with military ability, especially when faction and bad government had weakened the attachment to constitutional government and the efiective coherence of the community. § 2. The causes of the movement against early oligarchy seem to be : — 1. Oppression of smaller cultivators by men of wealth, partly by encroachments on common rights, as, e.g., in Megara, where Theagenes the tyrant killed the cattle of the rich that were encroaching on common land ;^ partly again — as civilisation goes on — through increasing recourse on the part of the smaller cultivators to the dangerous resource of borrowing from the rich, so that the rich oppress the poor as creditors under the old severe laws against debt — as in Eome later. 2. In commercial towns the growth of new wealth outside the closed group of old families, which raised up a growing force of new claimants for full citizenship.^ 3. The awakenment of mind due to trade and communica- tion ; and concomitant decaying of old simplicity of manners and old moral restraints, leading to more offensive luxury and insolence of the rich.^ To these we may add: 4. Distrust of unwritten law, which gradually came to be used more and more as an instrument of oppression by the rich who administered it. This last, and partly the first, is sometimes met by the introduction of written codes. The seventh century is the period in which the codifier or legislator appears for the 1 Aristot. Pol. VII. (v.) ch. v. 9 (1309 a). - See Appendix, Note C, on Early Oligarchy and Trade. 3 Aristotle {Pol. vii. (v.) x. 19 (1311 b.)) tells us that the Penthalidae were put down at Mitylene in Lesbos, because they went about the streets beating honest citizens with bludgeons. 90 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. first time in history as distinct from legend, as well as the Tyrannus. He appears first in the colonies ; Zaleucus at Locri (about 662 B.C.) is mentioned as the first author of written legislation/ and Charondas of Catana was not much later. In both cases it seems a probable conjecture that the codifier saved the state from Tyrannis. About the same time as Charondas, or earlier, we have Dracon's legislation at Athens, and, a little later, Solon's. The latter, however, did not prevent Tyrannis.^ We do not know how far Zaleucus or Charondas or Dracon had political power entrusted to them. Solon, we know, had, and he accordingly may be classed as an example of the Aesymnete. The Aesymnete was, as Aristotle says,^ a despot or dictator — that is he had unlimited power — but elected according to law ; elected either for life or for a term of years — Solon only for one year — or to do a particular work. The instance Aristotle gives is Pittacus of Mitylene, who was appointed for ten years (590-580 B.C.). Aristotle says that he was the framer of a code, but not of a polity {e^^^ eidijveiv Kal SLKa^eiv), but the magistracies were limited by property qualifications ; and where the people being mainly agricultural were too busy to have many assemblies, and practically too busy to serve on juries, there being no pay- ment for either. Aristotle mentions as an instance of the best kind of democracy the Mantinean. This would long remain purely agricultural, and Herodotus and Polybius'both testify to its high reputation. Here, as Aristotle main- tains, the assembly did not elect to the offices ; this was done by a body elected from all the citizens (tlv^s alperol e/c irdvTuy). What other democracies of this old type there were, we do not know. The language of Polybius suggests that Achaea may have furnished examples of such. I04 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. preceding ten stages no less than six belong to the fifth century. The century opens with the moderate democracy of Cleisthenes ; but the Athenian democracy is not finally delivered from " oligarchical tutelage " ^ by the reforms of Cleisthenes. Indeed it is, I think, a fairly trustworthy historical generalisation that " oligarchical tutelage " — the influence of the minority in any society, who along with wealth inherit culture and traditions of political experience and practice — "oligarchical tutelage" dies hard. And certainly this was so here. The council of Areopagus, according to the writer of the Athenian Constitution, re- covered power — without any formal vote — through its services at the crisis of the Persian war, and held it for seventeen years, till 462 B.C. And that this was pre- ponderantly oligarchical is evident from the attack made on it by Ephialtes and Pericles.^ From that time till the end of the century the movement towards full democracy is rapid, but it is not complete till nearly all the civil magistracies are practically open to all citizens, and the attendance at the council and assembly, as well as in the law courts paid. This final result is begun in the brilliant age of Pericles — to whom the payment of jurymen is due : but the payment for attendance at the assembly is after his time. In short, I repeat the fifth century is a period of continual change, and not till after the brief and infamous interlude of oligarchy at the end of the Peloponnesian war, does the democracy become stable, at the beginning of the fourth century. ^ ^ The phrase is Mr. Wards Fowler's, but the view he takes is different from the above. See his City State of Greece and Rome, p. 161. 2 This council was filled up by the nine chief magistrates for each year. As regards these, too, there was gradual progress. They were elected, not appointed by lot, for twenty-four years after the expulsion of the Tyrants in 512 B.C. ; then, for a period unknown, appointed by lot out of a number previously selected by each of the ten tribes of Cleisthenes ; then, finally, this previous selection was made by lot. When the change took place we do not know ; but we do know that only after 457 B.C. was the archonship open to any but Pentakosiomedimni and Knights — the two highest property- classes ; in 457 it was opened to the third class. But doubtless for some time later the competition was limited by their being unpaid. VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 105 We do not know exactly how far the Athenian institu- tions were representative, but we may infer from Aristotle that the following characteristics were found widely in Greek democracy of the fourth century. There was first an assembly, open to all full citizens of a certain age, actually governing and not merely electing and controlling governors. At Athens, in this supreme governing assembly, which met regularly forty times a year, besides extraordinary assem- blies on emergencies, all the most important governmental decisions, including the management of the whole foreign policy of the state, and the initiation of legislation, were determined ; and any citizen who had done nothing worthy of disfranchisement might speak. We learn from Aristotle that while it was the general characteristic of democracy in the small states of Greece to have as supreme organ of government such a deliberative body to which all citizens were admitted, there were considerable differences in the extent to which this body actually governed. In the most moderate form of democracy its function was to elect the magistrates, examine the accounts, and decide questions of peace, war, and alliance, leaving other matters of administra- tion to the elected magistrates and council. It is clear however, as I have said, that the tendency of development up to his time was towards the more extreme form of democracy, in which the final decision of all important public matters is habitually claimed by this supreme assembly. The powers of the magistrates, and of the governing council (" Boule ") that prepared business for the assembly, were quite subordinated in the Athenian form of democracy. Accordingly the principle that "one man is as good as another " was applied to these offices, in the form of election by lot from among all citizens of blameless life who applied : except in the case of offices for which special qualifications were obviously required, such as military offices and the most important financial ones. To these it would have been too dangerous to apply the lot. That poor men might really be able to take part in the business of government, attendance at the Athenian council lo6 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. was paid, and ultimately at the assembly too; and this seems to have been regarded as necessary for securing the real effectiveness of the democracy. Though it must be borne in mind that the Demos at Athens and elsewhere, having a basis of slavery beneath it, did not include the greater part of that class of manual labourers which tends to preponderate in a democratically governed modern state, still it is evident from the complaints of Aristotle, not to speak of Aristophanes, that it included a mass of persons — small traders, artisans, etc. — whose poverty rendered them incapable of adequate leisure for the effective performance of public functions. Unpaid attendance was liable to be scanty attendance, and then the assembly might fall under the control of the rich and their dependents. Administration of justice was also popular, and was also paid for similar reasons. At Athens, actions were decided by large popular juries of varying size, the normal number — at least for important suits — being 501. There is another important characteristic of Athenian democracy when fully developed. The popular assembly did not itself legislate, or avowedly and regularly allow its decrees to override the law; though this no doubt occurred in fact too often under the influence of popular passion. The actual business of legislation was given to a numerous committee of law-makers (we hear of 1000 and 500) selected from the jurors for the year. This was not, of course, a committee of experts; still, such a body of sworn jurors would work under a much stronger sense of responsibility than the ordinary assembly.^ And the ^ Note the care with which in the fourth century the work of legislation was divided between iKK\7)(ria and vofxod^rai. 1. At the first assembly in each new year the established code was voted on {^mxetpoTovia vbjxwv) — after a debate in which every citizen could propose changes in the law — chapter by chapter. 2. If the vote on any chapter was negatived, vofiodirat taken from the heliasts (jurors) were appointed in the fourth ordinary iKKX-qcia. Mean- while the proposer of a change had to exhibit in public the old law and the proposed ncAv law side by side, by the statues of the Eponymi; and also to give copies of them to the ypafifiareijs, who read them in public at the inter- vening meetings ; and at the fourth the people, of course with a "probouleuma," decided the number of vo/Modirai, the time allowed them, the pay, and named VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 107 sovereign assembly endeavoured to protect itself against illegality in its decrees by rendering the proposer of such a decree liable to a criminal process.^ This protection seems in fact to have been very imperfect ; sovereign Demos did not always observe his self-imposed restraints. It is clear that in speaking of that extreme democracy, which is hardly a constitution at all but a mob-tyranny, Aristotle has the Athens of his own time partly in view. But the elaborate character of the restraints at least shows that the need of excluding mere mob-tyranny was fully recognised in the political consciousness of Athens. § 4, I have now completed a brief sketch, following the order of development, of the chief forms of government in the Greek city-states up to the time of Macedonian pre- dominance, and briefly discussed the causes that tended to bring them into being, and the conditions favourable to their existence, at different stages of development. There is, however, one question of much interest which I have as yet only dealt with in one case — that of Tyrannis — namely, how did these different types work in practice ? How far did they maintain the well-being of the community governed ? Especially we are disposed to ask this with regard to democracy, towards which, as I said, there is a natural drift in the fourth century B.C., just as there is a similar drift now in the West -European states. But this question, owing to the scantiness of our information, is still more difficult to answer satisfactorily than the questions we have been discussing. We may, however, throw some light on it by examining the political views and theories of the eminent thinkers, chiefly of the fourth century, whose writings have come down to us. The most important are the views of Plato and Aristotle ^ ; but I shall also refer to Plato's master, five ffw-fiyopoL to defend the existing law. 3. Then with a probouleuma of the council on each proposal of change, the vofiodirai decided finally whether the law ought to be altered. 1 Compare Lect. XII. pp. 175, 6. 2 We may say, generally, that in tracing the process of the development of the modern State we find the influence of Greek politics on modern primarily io8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Socrates, whose life ends just at the beginning of the fourth century; to Xenophon, Plato's fellow - disciple ; and to Isocrates the rhetorician, whose work shows a certain rivalry and antagonism to that of Plato which Aristotle carries on ; and whose political view, therefore — since he had some claim to be a political thinker as well as a rhetorician — it is all the more interesting to compare with theirs. Both Plato and Aristotle gave much thought to the definition and classification of forms of government. Plato's dialogues present us with two different schemes of classifica- tion : one in the Republic, the other in a later dialogue, the Statesman. From this latter Aristotle's classification is in the main derived; and I will begin with Aristotle's, because, while admitting his great debt to Plato, one cannot doubt that he far surpassed him in the extent of his knowledge of political facts. The classification adopted by Aristotle is a sixfold one. It is based on a double principle of division, so that it may be conceived as a pair of similarly divided triads. He takes the obvious and already current threefold distinction ex- pressed by the terms Monarchy, Aristocracy or Oligarchy, and Democracy : but he combines this with a principle derived from Socrates — which like other characteristic doctrines of that sage was a truism in theory and unhappily somewhat of a paradox in practice — the principle that the in the region of thought or ideas, while Rome is the main ancient source of modern political facts. And in the region of thought Aristotle's Politics has a special interest, as being the manual from which modern thought in its first stage learnt its first lesson in the scientific analysis and classification of political phenomena. This lesson is liable to be misinterpreted if we do not, in studying it, bear in mind that it is framed in view of the variety of con- stitutions actually developed in Greek city-states, and is primarily applicable to these. But if we bear this in mind : if we remember also that it was written just after the close of the period of real independence of Greek city- states — after the battle of Chaeronea, and the Congress of Corinth, and while Alexander was conquering Asia — and if we consider not merely the general scheme of classification, but the particulars and comments with which Aristotle fills it up, it certainly yields the most important insight into the evolution of the city-states — and especially the later stage of this evolution — as judged by a most penetrating and disengaged intellect. VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 109 true ruler is one who seeks to promote not his own interest, but the interest of the ruled. Combining the distinction thus introduced with the older threefold classification, we get three " correct " constitutions in which the governing in- dividual or body is truly governing, in the Socratic sense : — (1) Kingdom = the rule of an individual of pre-eminent merit; (2) Aristocracy = the rule of the persons best quali- fied to rule ; and (3) what he in a special sense calls " Polity " or " Constitutional Government," in which supreme power is in the hands of the majority of citizens, but with a constitution so arranged as to avoid the defects of mob-rule. Parallel to these we have three perverted forms : — (1) Tyrannis =r the selfish rule of one; (2) Oligarchy = the selfish rule of a wealthy minority; (3) Democracy = the selfish rule of the comparatively unpropertied many. The symmetry of the scheme obviously requires that Aristocracy — like Oligarchy, which is the perversion of Aristocracy — should be the government of the Many by the Few. And Plato certainly held that the government by persons properly qualified to govern — the essential meaning of Aristocracy for both him and Aristotle — must be the government of a few. " It is impossible," he says, " that the multitude in a State can attain the political art ; in a city of 1000 men you would hardly find 50 good draught- players, much less 50 experts in statesmanship."^ And Aristotle, in the passage in which he introduces his scheme, gives this as the received view of Aristocracy, i.e. it resembles oligarchy in its numerical relations, though only numerically.^ It is, however, to be observed that after careful discus- sion Aristotle decides ^ that the mass of ordinary citizens, if properly trained, may be collectively wiser than the few, and so collectively better qualified for the highest deliberative or judicial work, though not individually for executive magistracies; accordingly, in constructing his ideal state,* he decides that all the citizens are to share in government 1 Plato, Fol. 292 E. "^ See Nicom. Ethics, viii. ch. x., and Politics^ iii. ch. vii. ^ Pol. III. ch. xi. •* Pol. IV. (VII.) ch. xiv. no DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. when they come to a sufficiently advanced age. But the citizens in Aristotle's ideal polity do not include artisans or traders, or even husbandmen — for mechanical and com- mercial life is ignoble and opposed to virtue, and though agricultural life is not in its nature so demoralising as mechanical or commercial life, it lacks the leisure which is essential to Aristotle's ideal of a citizen. His citizens are accordingly a body of landowners, living at leisure on the produce of their lots of land, which are supposed to be cultivated by slaves or serfs. They are still, therefore, a select minority, compared with the whole number of human beings required by the material needs of the community. Keturning to the sixfold classification, made up, as I said, of a pair of similarly divided triads, how does Aristotle arrange these six forms of government in order of merit. In the first brief draft of his views in his Ethics the scheme is simple and symmetrical; we have to keep the first three in order of arithmetical progression, and to invert this order in the second triad. So that the scale of merit will be Kingship, Aristocracy, Constitutional Government or Constitutional Democracy, Simple or unbalanced Democracy, Oligarchy, Tyrannis or illegitimate Despotism. If one man can be found of such pre-eminent excellence as to deserve sole rule, this is the simplest and best solution of the problem : where there is no such unique individual the functions of government should be entrusted to those best qualified to perform them. But Aristotle's later views modified this order. In the treatise on Politics kingship no longer seems tp him better than aristocracy, and his view of aristocracy has diverged, as I said, from Plato's. Still, of all governments selfish despotism is worst ; and selfish oligarchy is more odious than selfish democracy. The mere aspect of this classification suggests a painful suspicion that its author means to imply a general condemna- VH GREEK DEMOCRACY 1 1 1 tion of the actual governments in Greek city-states ; for he selects to denote the perverted forms the terms which his- torians ordinarily use in classifying the actual governments.^ And his further exposition makes this suspicion a certainty. His definitions of oligarchy and democracy — in his bad sense of the terms — are not merely abstract and formal : they are intended to be definitions of the prevalent political facts. This is clear from the care with which he explains that the essential difference between the two is not merely numerical — as the derivation of oligarchy might suggest — it is rather the distinction between rich and poor. He describes various kinds of each, some worse and some better ; he notes too that a government may be in form democratical but substantially oligarchical ; but he clearly holds that the study of the actual facts of Greek political history in the later period for the most part shows us societies divided into the party of the rich few and the party of the poor many, struggling for mastery with selfish ends ; the ordinary result, whichever wins, involving the oppression of the other party. § 5. And this condemnation of fully-developed democracy is not Aristotle's view only. It is the prevalent view — we may almost say that it is the only view that has come down to us, if we put out of account the speeches of the orators, who, as their business was to persuade Demos, could hardly tell him plainly that he was incompetent and oppressive. Plato's antagonism to democracy is stronger than Aristotle's. ^ In the main Aristotle's classification only systematises distinctions recognised in the ordinary thought of Greece. In a curious discussion which Herodotus (Bk. iii. 80-82) maintains to have taken place among the seven conspirators in Persia, in the course of the conspiracy which ended in bring- ing Darius Hystaspes to the throne, the characteristics of the governments of One, the Few, and the Many are contrasted ; and the profound differences between the true king and the tyrant, and again between the rule of the wise, the really best, and the rule of the wealthy few, were more or less recognised in ordinary language. What remained to complete the systematic six-fold classification was to lay stress on a corresponding distinction between con- stitutional law-abiding rule of the majority, keeping within the limits of moderation and justice, and the more extreme kind of democracy in which the masses systematically oppressed the rich. 112 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Xenophon's undisguised partisanship of Sparta has drawn on him the severe reprobation of Grote. These, however, it may be urged, are all of one school of thought, they share the Socratic influence. But this cannot be said of Isocrates : yet he too, in his political pamphlets, published about the middle of the century in the form of deliberative speeches, speaks no less strongly of the oppressiveness and incompetence of unbridled democracy under the guidance of unprincipled demagogues. These men, he says, " do not merely compromise our national name : they enrich them- selves at our cost by impeachments, indictments, and all the machinery of calumny, and grind us down by oppres- sive taxation. And their incompetence is equal to their rapacity. Under their influence we do not know our own minds for a day ; and, while the penalty for private bribery is death, the most incapable men become our generals by their large bribes to the popular assembly." ^ All this, no doubt, relates to Athens primarily. But the Athenian democracy was, by general agreement, the most brilliant example of Greek democracy, and, as I have said, doubtless a pattern widely followed in the general drift towards democracy. And Isocrates expressly tells us that his condemnation is not confined to Athens. " We are protected," he says, " by the fact that our competitors are no less ill-governed. . . . We save the Thebans and they save us. . . . It would be worth while for either to pay the members of the popular assembly of the other." ^ Of Argos — another state of old prestige that had now long been democratic — Isocrates says elsewhere, " that whenever the Argives get a breathing time from war, they take to killing their most illustrious citizens." ^ I think we may take it as undeniable that whatever merits the full-blown democracy of the fourth century in Greece may have had, it was generally disliked and con- ^ Isocr. (Or. viii.) de Pace. [Not a literal translation, but condensed from diflferent parts of the Oration.] ■2 Isocr. (Or. viii.) de Pace, 171 a, b. 3 Isocr. (Or. v.) Ad Philipp, 92 d. VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 113 demned by the class of thoughtful persons whose utterances go down to posterity. But again, while agreeing that unbridled democracy is bad, our writers all seem to agree that ordinary selfish oligarchy — the government of the rich minority in their own interest — is worse. " A bad democracy," says Isocrates no less than Aristotle, " is a less evil than an oligarchy " : " even our corrupt democracy would seem divine compared with the government of the Thirty Tyrants " : and " if we go through the chief cities of Hellas, we find that they have prospered less under oligarchy than under democracy." ^ It is true that Plato, in the Republic, regards democracy as worse than oligarchy ; he puts forward a theory of natural tendency to degeneration, according to which such a con- stitution as the Spartan — which he places next to his ideal state — tends to degenerate into oligarchy through the corrupting effect of money - getting ; then oligarchy tends to degenerate into democracy, and democracy into Tyrannis. It is an interesting fact that the first theory of political evolution which the history of European thought offers us is a theory of degeneration. And instances might doubtless be quoted from Greek history to exemplify each of these pro* cesses of degeneration ; but the general order of the succes- sion of forms does not correspond to the general facts of that history, in which, as we have seen, the period specially known as the " Age of the Tyrants " comes before that of fully - developed democracy. In any case Plato seems to have given up this order of demerit at the time of writing the Statesman ; here, as I have said, he gives the order of demerit which Aristotle has adopted, " democracy, ohgarchy, Tyrannis." § 6. Plato's justification for assigning these relative posi- tions to democracy and oligarchy in his later scheme is noteworthy. The government of the Many he holds is essentially a weak government ; it is a form of govern- ment under which people are comparatively little governed. As compared with a government both wise and strong, "• Isocr. (Or. vii.) Areopag. 154 b, 152 c. I 114 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. this faineant character of democracy appears to Plato a defect; but as compared with the selfish coercion of oligarchs, it is a relative merit. And certainly we have to note in democracy on the whole, by the testimony of all our witnesses, a remarkable maintenance of liberty in the strict sense of individual liberty — power of doing what one likes, without dangerous disorder. " The tyranny of the majority," which seemed to Tocqueville and Mill so important a danger of the coming democracy of Europe, certainly does not appear as a marked characteristic of the Demos of Athens. On the contrary, democracy leads, Demosthenes tells us, to a general absence of severity (" iravra irpaorepa ") ; ^ a " general freedom of speech " (irappTjaia), says Euripides ; ^ "we go each on his own way, and do not scowl at other people for going theirs," says the Thucydidean Pericles.^ The "very dogs are more impudent than elsewhere," says Plato, " and the donkeys march along with the air of fully-qualified citizens." * "You are not even allowed," says the pseudo-Xenophon (author of a diatribe against the Athenian constitution), " to beat a slave who does not get out of your way in the street." ^ This at least we moderns, whatever our political creed, shall not put down as a point against Demos. When we try to estimate the general happiness of the political and social organisation of the Greco-Italian civilised world, this great fact of slavery is a heavy weight in the pessimistic scale : there is some comfort in the thought that the weight was somewhat lightened by democracy. But, it may be asked, was not the treatment of the rich an exception to this general disposition to make things easy all round ? Were they not oppressed with un- equal taxation by Demos, in his political character, and plundered by iniquitous prosecutions, tried by the same Demos in his judicial character ? Well, we can hardly doubt, as our authorities agree, that both kinds of oppres- 1 Demosth. Androt. 608. ^ Eurip. Hipp. 422 ; Ion, 672. 3 Thuc. II. ch. xxxvii. ^ Plat. Rep. 563 D. ^ On the Government of Athens ^ ch. i. § 10. VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 115 sion went on to some extent. All that can be said on the other side is that there is no sign that it went to such an extent as to scare rich men away from Athens, and inter- fere with its commercial and industrial prosperity. As regards the large popular courts of justice, certainly the character of the forensic speeches that have come down to us from the fourth century tends to give a low idea of their efficacy as instruments for administering justice ; owing to the amount of misrepresentation and irrelevant abuse of the adversary which the advocates exhibit, and their unrestrained licence in appealing to any sort of motive that may influence the judges in their favour. Still, as to the extent of systematic unjust confiscation through these law courts, it is very difficult to form a decided opinion. When Aristophanes describes the informer as going about picking out " fat delinquents and defaulters, pulpy, luscious, plump, and rich," he implies that they were delinquents and defaulters.^ And even when we learn from Lysias that some advocates in prosecutions used to tell the jurymen that if they let off the accused there would not be funds in the treasury to pay them their three obols a day, we must surely suppose that it was a plea against mercy to a guilty defendant, not an open advocacy of spoliation of an inno- cent man. Still, that it should have been said at all is bad enough. So, again, though the occasional corruption and tyrannous misconduct of the office-holders under Demos cannot be doubted, it may reasonably be doubted whether it was in any degree a distinctive feature of democracy. As regards the over-burdening in the way of taxation, it should be borne in mind that the practice of throwing extra burdens on the rich was old, and there is no sign that it was made worse by extreme democracy. If we hear of people ruining themselves by providing choruses and torch- races, there is considerable reason to think that it was generally by spending more than they were legally bounn to spend, from love of display. We hear of a mad " decking his chorus with gold lace, and then going about 1 Ar. Knights, 259. ii6 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. in rags himself " ^ ; but the gold lace was voluntary extra- vagance, not exacted from him by Demos. The burdens in war were heavier and more painfully felt; but no critic suggests that Demos was fond of going to war because he had not to pay for it, — at any rate in the fourth century, when democratic tendencies were most fully developed. Eather the charge is that he could not brace himself up with sufficient steadiness for the burdens in- volved in adequate resistance to Philip of Macedon. At the same time, while giving this qualified defence of Athenian democracy, I should hesitate to extend it to Greek democracy generally. It would be presumptuous to doubt the truth of Aristotle's statement, that revolutions in democracies often occurred " from the intemperate conduct of the demagogues, who force the propertied class to com- bine by instituting malicious prosecutions against indivi- duals, or by inciting the masses against them as a body." ^ He mentions a curious instance at Ehodes, where the trierarchs — the rich men made pecuniarily responsible for the provision of war -ships — were prevented by the demagogues from obtaining the contributions due to them from other citizens ; and so were " compelled, by fear of the lawsuits with which they were threatened by their creditors, to form a conspiracy and abolish the democracy." ^ Similarly, he tells us that at Megara " the demagogues, in order to have an opportunity for confiscation, ejected large numbers of the nobles from the state, until they had swelled the ranks of the exiles to such an extent that they returned home, conquered the democrats in a pitched battle, and established the oligarchy." ^ If this account is accurate, it would certainly seem that the oppression of the rich in Megara was of a very violent and sweeping kind. It may be said that Aristotle is a hostile witness — but his is a mind in which genuine scientific curiosity seems to be always predominant ; and, as regards the violence of democratic factions at Megara, we find a sort of confirmation in Plutarch,^ from whom we learn that at ^ Antiph. ap. A then. p. 103e. ^ p^/^ yjjj^ (y^ y^ 8 ^^_ (^^ xviii. VII GREEK DEMOCRA CY wj Megara — after the ordinary stages of kingship, oligarchy, and tyranny — a period of licentious democracy occurred in the first half of the sixth century B.C. The poor are said to have forced their way into the houses of the rich, ordered lunch and dinner to be served regardless of expense, and also to have passed a formal decree for the restitution of the interest that had been already paid on debts. Probably, as Grote suggests, the difference of race, surviving from the Dorian conquest, rendered the oppression of the mob more violent. The natural result was two successive relapses into oligarchy, neither of which, however, seems to have lasted very long. A similar explanation may be given of the violent character of the democracy of Argos. It is chiefly known to us from the notorious crKyraXta-^jbo^, or " lynching with clubs," by which 1200 of the upper class, suspected of planning an oligarchical revolution, lost their lives, 370 B.C. But that this kind of thing was not isolated may perhaps be inferred from the manner in which Isocrates (346 B.C.) speaks of the dissensions at Argos in the passage already quoted.^ Nevertheless, democracy seems to have been almost unbroken at Argos from before the middle of the fifth century onward : — probably rivalry with Sparta was partly the cause; oligarchs allying themselves with Sparta would have patriotic feeling against them. Generally speaking, violent democracy tended to cause a disturbed condition with sudden lapses into short-lived oligarchy or tyranny. Such oligarchies — if we may generalise from the brief history of the Thirty at Athens, probably rivalled the worst deeds of the worst democracies. One form of spoliation of the rich — which has some interest from its analogy to certain revolutionary aims of our own day — is 77)9 avaSacrfiof; " redistribution of land." Isocrates the orator when speaking of the " usual mis- fortunes of cities," from which an advocate of Sparta claims that Sparta alone is free, mentions among these usual calamities "cancellation of debts" — such as Solon's great 1 P. 112. ii8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. measure at Athens — and " redistribution of land : " ^ and Aristotle also speaks of this as a recognised method of demagogic oppression.^ He does not, however, give any instance ; and Dion Chrysostom, a Greek rhetorician of the Empire, says " we have absolutely no knowledge that such a thing ever occurred." ^ And I have tried in vain to find a historic instance of a redistribution of land carried out as a democratic measure in a peaceable and quasi -legal way, like Solon's cancellation of debt : though of course some- thing of the kind was liable to occur in civil war when one party was violently expelled. However, one can hardly doubt that there must have been other instances of this high-handed piece of democratic oppression : though it was probably more often talked of than realised. I have left to the last one important charge against Greek democracy, based on Athenian history. It is urged that the long struggle which ended in the acceptance of the Macedonian supremacy over Greece generally, showed the fatal short-sightedness and instability of democracy in foreign policy : and that the Athenians might have resisted Philip successfully had they had some other form of government. I do not think it can be denied that there is much foundation for the charge. But if we are comparing Athenian democracy with the other forms of government which we actually find produced under the same general conditions as the Athenian democracy — i.e. in the small town- communities of Greece — the advocates of democracy may fairly rejoin by asking what other of the Hellenic towns showed itself more able to cope with the situation. The warmest admirers of oligarchy will hardly claim this for Sparta. On the whole, I incline to the view that it was not primarily democracy that was tried and found wanting in the contest with Philip : but rather the too exclusive spirit, the too limited patriotism of the Greek city-states, unable to rise to a really effective Pan-hellenism, an equal and stable federation. Later on, when the principle of federation 1 Isocr. (Or. xii.) Panath. § 259. ^ p^i^ y,jj_ (y_) y_ 3 Qr. xxxi. 332. VII GREEK DEMOCRACY 119 is at length developed from the humble beginnings of the hitherto obscure and unpretending Achaean league, and we see how much federation could effect even with Athens standing aloof and Sparta fallen from her high estate ; — we may be almost willing to agree with Aristotle that the Greek race, from its happy blending and balance of qualities, might have conquered the world if it could only have brought itself to live under one government. LECTUEE VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO § 1. In my last lecture, after giving a brief account of the Athenian constitution of the fourth century, I went on to note the uniformly unfavourable opinion expressed as to the working of Greek democracy by Plato, Aristotle, Iso- crates, and Xenophon ; there being, so far as I know, no impartial utterance of importance on the other side — since, as I said, any phrases flattering to Demos, on the part of the orators whose business it was to persuade him, cannot be regarded as evidence. But it has been urged that "Plato, Isocrates, and Aristotle knew Athens only when her best days were past, and when the gifted and animated population of the golden age had been thinned down sadly by war and pestilence," ^ and that the Athenians, being few and depressed by diminution, had naturally let their government go to the dogs. I hardly think this explanation will do. No doubt the population of Attica was diminished ; we hear of 21,000 male citizens of full age at the end of the fourth century as compared to over 30,000 in the latter part of the fifth. The smaller number, however, is certainly large enough to work the institutions of direct democracy.^ And the Athenians were far from being permanently depressed by the ill success of the Peloponnesian war and the con- sequent loss of their maritime empire ; on the contrary, the reader of Greek history of the fourth century is struck by the elasticity with which they recover from this blow and ^ Warde Fowler, The City State of the Greeks and Eomans, p. 153. 2 Cf. Arist. Fol. iv. (vii.) iv. 4 ; ii. vi. 6. 120 LECT. VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO 121 get together a second empire, though no doubt it is never anything like the first. And, as I said, the fourth century is the period of established and fully-developed democracy ; in the fifth we have the process of development. No doubt, we have a time of brilliant prosperity in the great age of Pericles, but according to the ancient authorities, though here the critical step was taken towards the ultimate democracy, there has not yet been time to see the full effect of democratic institutions. This is one reason why the prosperity of this age cannot be regarded as an effect of the type of fully developed democracy. And another reason why the Athenian constitution in the brilliant period of the fifth century cannot be regarded as typical is the very fact that Athens was then pre-eminently an im- perial city : its national income was largely derived from the tribute of other cities ; and the extent of governmental functions — and pay — enjoyed by Athenians was largely due to their imperial position. Keturning to the fourth century, it should be noticed that stasis, faction and civil strife, an evil characteristic of the city-states of Greece generally throughout their history — as we saw it was civil dissension that gave the opportunity for the Tyrannus of the seventh and sixth centuries — is not found in Athens under fully developed democracy. In Athens the period of civil strife was over by the end of the fifth century. During the fourth century factions in Athens, however bitter, do not lead to disorder and violence ; the struggle that we find elsewhere so common between the wealthy with their partisans and Demos — making, as Plato says, two cities in one, each of which constantly exiles the leading part of the other — from this Athens is free. And still its democracy is subject, as we have seen, to the deep decided condemnation of the leading thinkers and writers on politics. § 2. But if the thinkers were agreed in not seeking a remedy for the evils of democracy in the worse evils of oligarchy, what precisely was the remedy that they pro- 122 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. posed ? To this question both Plato and Aristotle give a somewhat complicated answer. They each construct an ideal state, which they admit is not likely to be generally realised ; and each also pro- poses a yis aller, a second-best course, as having more likeli- hood of being practically adopted. And when we compare the two, we find that though the ideal state of Aristotle is very unlike the ideal state of Plato, it has a strong general resemblance to Plato's second-best model of polity ; so that we may put the teachings of the two thinkers together, and trace in them a continuous movement of thought, from political idealism of a very marked kind, very remote from practical politics, towards a more practical and empirical view. The germ of the political ideal common to Plato and Aristotle is found in the fundamental doctrine on which the dialectical teaching of Plato's master, Socrates, was based : that in the work of government, as in private life, the great desideratum is knowledge — knowledge of the true good of man and of the means to its attainment. A man possessed of this knowledge, if called to the function of ruling, would know how to promote the well-being of the ruled, and would know also that his own well-being would be realised in the right performance of this function. Such a man would be potentially a statesman, whether he be appointed or not; and it would be madness if we could find such a man, not to make him ruler, instead of leaving the selection of rulers to the hazard of the lot; on the other hand, without this essential knowledge the votes of all mankind cannot make a statesman. In these simple articles of Socrates' political creed we have the germ out of which the ideal aristocracy of Plato was developed. For in Plato's view this indispensable knowledge can only be possessed by the philosopher : a man must have been trained to contemplate good in the abstract before he can hope to realise it in human life. At the same time, men whose natural gifts qualify them for the long and laborious training which philosophy requires will always be few in VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO 123 the best regulated community, and these few again only philosophers are qualified to select. Hence Plato's most ideal state must necessarily be an aristocracy based on cooptation ; that is, it must be a state in which implicit obedience is paid to a small carefully trained class of philosophers, who recruit their numbers by selecting in youth those whom they deem fit for the training. Of the other classes necessary to the existence of a self- sufficing human community, the only one on whose training Plato bestows serious attention in constructing his ideal state is the fighting class. The state will, of course, also contain husbandmen and artisans, who ought, in his view, to be distinct from the warriors ; but it is only for the warriors that Plato works out an elaborate system of regula- tions. They, with the philosophers, form the guardians or protectors of the whole community. It is not that he regards war as a normal incident of an ideal condition of human society — quite the contrary. But Plato's state, though ideal, is not designed as a Utopia — it is not a fancy-state but a pattern-state ; it is framed in view of the actual conditions of life in Greek city-states, in which it was an imperative condition of national prosperity that the state should be formidable in war. At the same time his — to a modern mind startling — view of the moral superi- ority of the class of warriors as compared with the classes engaged in providing for the material needs of the com- munity, is in harmony with the Greek conception of virtue, in which valour was more prominent than it would be in a modern conception. This, no doubt, is an indirect effect of the political conditions. Accordingly, philosophers and warriors together make up in Plato's ideal view a class of guardians for whom an elaborate system of training, drill, and regulation of life is worked out : a system modelled on that of Sparta, whose polity Plato ranked first among the actual forms of government of Greece, but designed to exclude far more completely the evils of selfish money- getting domesticity. These evils, Plato saw, were not com- pletely excluded at Sparta ; because the Lycurgean system, 124 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. while drilling the men to a hardy and simple regimen, had left the women undrilled ; and though the barrack life and common meals of Sparta severely limited the men's enjoy- ment of wealth, the desire of heaping up riches for wife and family was practically found to render the Spartan only too accessible to the corrupting temptations of avarice. With a view, then, to a more absolute predominance of civic sentiment than Sparta had attained, and with a view, at the same time, to perfection of the breed of citizens, and to the distribution of functions according to fitness, Plato proposed to abolish private property and private families altogether for his class of guardians. This communism is strongly controverted by Aristotle; and the prominence given to this controversy in his treatise on Politics has rather obscured the close and fundamental similarity between Aristotle's political ideal and Plato's second-best state. For Plato himself came to recognise that his communism was not within the range of practical politics ; accordingly, in his " second-best state " — delineated in a dialogue, The Laws, written many years later than The BepuUic — he gives up his communism as regards both marriage and private property. He does not, however, abandon all hope of preventing by legislative interference the fatal division of society into rich and poor, which — as he emphatically tells us in The Eepuhlic — " made two states at war within a single city." ^ He now hopes to prevent this by constituting his citizens a body of landowners, with equal inalienable allotments of land, and strictly prohibited from acquiring movable property to the value of more than four times that of the allotment. The lots are not to be bought or sold, and each man is to leave his lot to his best- beloved son ; his other sons " he shall distribute to such of the citizens as are childless and willing to adopt them." ^ Various other regulations are made to keep the lots equal. Should population be redundant, the magistrates are to keep it down, if possible ; or — if this be found impracticable — as a last resource they are to send out a colony. 1 The Hepublic, ir. 422. '^ The Laws, v. 740. VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO 125 Aristotle criticises this scheme for preventing inequality of property ; but he criticises it not, as a modern might do, because it interferes too much with the natural laws of economic distribution, but because its interference does not go far enough. He considers that the scheme will break down for want of a fixed limit to the number of children in a family; accordingly, he proposes to introduce such a limit in his ideal state. He criticises other points in Plato's second-best state ; but viewing it as a whole we can see more clearly than he did how similar his own political ideal is to it in its broad features. Both Plato and Aristotle agree in regarding the city-state as the final form of highly organised political society. In the view of both the state must not be larger than a single city, with the land required to support it, in order that the citizens may meet in one assembly, not too large for effective deliberation, and may have the mutual knowledge required for a good choice of magistrates, and also required — in the view of the Greek thinkers — for a good administration of justice. Indeed, on this point Aristotle's conception is stricter than Plato's : he criticises Plato's later state, which is designed to have a body of 5000 fighting men, as too large. Both agree in regarding as the statesman's end the realisation in the citizens of the highest attainable degree of human virtue and well-being ; and of this, in the view of both, the highest mode is philosophy, the activity of the intellect in the attainment of knowledge. Both, again, hold that the realisation of virtue in a high degree is only to be expected from a select class of citizens, relieved from the necessity of providing themselves with the means of subsistence, and subjected to an elaborate system of education ; accordingly, in the view of botn, the citizens are conceived as a body of landowners, living at leisure on the produce of their lots of land cultivated by serfs. Both, accordingly, exclude husbandmen, artisans, and retail traders from citizenship. In the view of both the male citizens must in youth be thoroughly trained for war ; and both recognise — Plato in his second-best state no less than 126 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Aristotle — that it is not in human nature for this body of armed citizens to submit to simple subjection to philosophic rulers. Both, accordingly, agree in giving an important share of political power to the military landowning class, but in different ways and degrees. In Plato's scheme they have the right of electing the executive magistracy, and also the deliberative council to which the magistrates are to refer important matters ; to improve the quality of the council so elected he proposes a division of the citizens into four property-classes, and a constitution so framed as prac- tically to increase the electoral power of the higher classes. Aristotle, on the other hand, proposes to give supreme deliberative functions to an assembly of all the citizens — i.e. all the land-owning class — after they have passed the military age ; he also proposes to give judicial functions to these citizens — assembled, I suppose, in large popular juries like those of Athens. The form of government, therefore, in Aristotle's ideal State is materially nearer to democracy than that in Plato's second-best State if we consider only the distribution of power among the citizens ; but this difference will seem to us unimportant as compared with the fact that both agree in limiting citizenship to a class of landowners living at leisure on the produce of the labour of serfs. This leads me to a final point on which they are agreed in principle : namely, as to slavery. Both hold that there must be slaves, but they hold also that the slaves should be human beings naturally adapted for slavery, and that no Hellene should be owned as a slave.^ § 3. This then, in brief, is the aristocratic ideal of the great Socratic thinkers — putting out of account that ideal monarchy, the rule of the man pre-eminent in wisdom and virtue, which has clearly no relation to practical politics in Aristotle's time. Eegarding his aristocracy from a historical ^ In considering the relation of Plato and Aristotle to actual slavery in Greece, we are apt to judge it too exclusively from the modern point of view, and to say summarily that they accepted and defended slavery. We ought also to recognise how much they were iu advance of their age by disapproving slavery of Greeks. VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO 127 point of view, we see clearly that the Spartan institutions have served as a model; and, accordingly, both Plato and Aristotle agree in giving the Spartan polity a high place among actual Greek States ; it belongs to the class of states which Aristotle calls in a wide sense " aristocratic," as distinct from " oligarchical," i. e. states in which the aim of the constitution is to develop and politically reward merit in the citizens. Still, Aristotle does not consider that either his ideal polity, or anything like the Spartan — anything that could be called aristocratic — is to be generally recommended to the actual city-states that he knows. The tendency to democracy in these is recognised by him as too strong to admit of his recommending anything that could be properly called aristocracy for their adoption. What he does recom- mend is what he calls in a special sense " Constitutional Government" (TroXtre/a) — " Constitutional Democracy," per- haps, conveys his idea better to a modern reader ^ — in which men of moderate means hold the balance between the ex- tremes of rich and poor, and a kind of fusion is effected between the opposing principles of oligarchy and democracy. This fusion or balance might be effected in different ways : on certain points it might be expedient to adopt both oligarchical and democratic arrangements in the con- stitution of the balanced state : — e.g. both to fine the rich for not serving on juries, as was customary in oligarchies, and to pay the poor for serving, as was customary in democracies, in order to secure the attendance of both. In other cases the required balance would be best attained by taking a mean between the two systems : — e.g. by making a moderate property qualification, which would admit the majority of free citizens, the condition of membership of the supreme deliberative assembly, instead of a high qualification as in ^ Just as the general term "Constitutional Government," or a "Consti- tution," if applied to European States in the first half of the nineteenth century, would have been naturally understood to mean "Constitutional Monarchy." In the modern case the problem presented to constructors of constitutions was. — given a king, how is his power to be limited and balanced : by the ancient thinker the power of Demos would be naturally assumed in the same way. 128 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. oligarchies. Or, again, a composite method of appointment, partly oligarchical and partly democratical, might be adopted : e.g. the appointments to the executive offices might be partly by suffrage — which the Greeks deemed an essentially oligar- chical or aristocratic mode of appointment — and partly by lot, which they regarded as the essentially democratic method. It was not, of course, to be expected that the adjustment of the balance would be exactly even, or the same in all cases : some constitutional governments would incline more to oligarchy, and some to democracy. But some such mixed constitution, in which neither the rich nor the poor are allowed to have their way unchecked, is what Aristotle recommends as a practicable ideal for the City- States of his age ; but he admits regretfully that its actual realisation is rare. The reasons for this I will give in his own words : — " The reasons why most governments are either demo- cratical or oligarchical are, firstly, that the class of persons of moderate means is generally small in them ; secondly, in consequence of the disturbances and contentions between the commons and the men of property, whichever side gets the better, instead of establishing a government of a broad and equal kind, takes political supremacy as a prize of victory, and sets up either a democracy or an oligarchy." Further, the " two peoples which attain an imperial position in Greece, had regard solely to their own political aims in establishing, the one democracies, and the other oligarchies in the cities under their rule, subordinating the interests of these cities to their own interest. For these reasons the intermediate form of government is either never realised at all, or only seldom and in a few States." ^ This statement represents the amount of truth that I find in the arguments that have been urged by various writers, from Tacitus ^ downwards, against the possibility of a mixed form of government. The experience of Greek history shows that the desired balance is at any rate difficult ^ Politics, VI. (iv.) xi. 16, 18. The **t\vo peoples" are of course the Athenian and the Spartan. ^ Annals, iv. 33^ VIII IDEAL STATES OF ARISTOTLE AND PLATO 129 to maintain ; one or other element tends to preponderate in the fusion and ultimately destroy the balance. To say that such a mixed form is impossible seems to me a hasty generalization ; but the experience of Greece, as summed up by Aristotle, tends to show that it is likely to be rare. And it is evident that the fusion which he thought most widely practicable would incline rather to democracy, — this is why I have translated his term TroKireia " constitutional democracy " : it is a system in which the ultimate control would rest with the majority of the citizens. He evidently thinks it hopeless, in the Greek city-states of his age generally, to prevail on Demos to resign this ultimate con- trol ; but it may be possible to persuade him to submit to checks and balances which may prevent the oppression of the rich few by the poor many. But even this he only hopes to effect in a stable manner in a society in which the class of persons with moderate means, being numerically strong, can be maintained in preponderance.^ § 4. From a modern point of view it seems strange that Aristotle, in his recommendation of a mixed or balanced constitution, appears never to have thought of introducing monarchy as an element in the fusion. The explanation, I conceive, is partly that he did not find among the politicians he knew any man of such unique merit as to render the allotment to him of so large a share of permanent power apparently reasonable ; partly that a real legitimate mon- archy was something not within the range at least of recent Greek experience. We find that Aristotle recognises five kinds of monarchy, besides the illegitimate, usurped, " unnatural " Tyrannis. But (1) one of these — the Spartan — can only be called kingship by courtesy ; the king is little more than a per- petual commander-in-chief; his power in civil affairs is insignificant. (2) Another species, the hereditary despotism that is natural to barbarians, he regards as beyond the pale of discussion for Greece. (3) The old kingship " according ^ Some approximation to Aristotle's ideal appears to have been attained in the third century. K 130 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. viii to law " of heroic times was irrevocably gone ^ ; and (4) the elective perpetual dictatorship ^ which had been instituted in certain States in the first stage of the struggle between the gentry and the masses was also a thing of the past. Finally, (5) the rule of the Individual of Unique Merit, which stands first in the scale of merit in the Aristotelian classification of governments, was a purely ideal conception, in Aristotle's age at least. There was, therefore, no legiti- mate kingship really deserving the name " within the range of practical politics " for Greece in Aristotle's age ; and it is for this reason, I conceive, that it does not occur to him even to consider a fusion of monarchy with oligarchy, or de- mocracy, or both ; for to suggest any balance or compromise with lawless Tyrannis would have been too daring a paradox.^ ^ It is noteworthy that Aristotle does not conceive the polity of heroic times as being a balanced or mixed form of government : — he conceives the king's power as limited by law or custom, but does not regard it as shared with council or assembly. As doubtless his view of this polity was derived from Homer, his authority may be quoted on Grote's side of the controversy discussed in Lecture ii. pp. 35-37 ; but 1 nevertheless take the other side. 2 See Lect. vi. p. 90, I do not know any historical instance of such a dictator {ala-v/xvijTTjs) being elected for life ; but instances were evidently known to Aristotle (see Politics iii. xiv.) ^ There is reason to doubt how far Aristotle really shared the conventional sentiment against Tyrannis ; but at any rate he does not expressly separate himself from it. LECTUKE IX GREEK FEDERALISM § 1. We have now briefly considered the different types of government and transitions in Greece to the end of the fourth century in their evolutionary order ; it being the aim of political science to get types and the general causes of transition from one type to another as clear as possible by comparing instances. First, we examined the "Primitive Polity," to be called monarchy if anything, but where it is interesting to note, in the council of sub-chiefs or elders and the assembly of the freemen in arms, undeveloped organs which become prominent respectively in the stages of ohgarchy and democracy. Then we discussed the transi- tion to primitive oligarchy, of which the most prominent aspect is the reduction of the power of the king, and ultimately the substitution for him of an annual magistracy. The council then becomes the ruling organ ; the assembly was probably preserved, but the landowners of old family predominate in it. We observed different causes tending to give the assembly an oligarchical character, namely, conquest ; growth, especially in colonies, of new populations without political rights ; integration, under the influence of which small landowners and distant tend to drop out of the assembly ; increase of inequalities of wealth and economic servitude of poorer freemen. The next phenomenon con- sidered was Tyrannis — " irregular, unconstitutional reversion to monarchy," probably, as in Athens, with constitutional forms preserved ; and we distinguished the earlier type developed out of the demagogue, and for which the reaction against early oligarchy gave the opportunity, from the later 131 132 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. for which the employment of mercenaries was a favouring condition. We noted that Tyrannis was a prevalent type at certain periods, but not a necessary stage through which Greek states passed. Then, when the earlier Tyrannis has, speaking broadly, disappeared, the brilliant period of Greek history has begun which is generally characterised by a drift towards democracy. We can trace the progress in the democratic direction from stage to stage at Athens, where a stable democratic constitution is finally established at the end of the fifth century, which remains substantially unaltered up to the time of the subjugation under Macedonia. And elsewhere in Greece the same tendency to democracy is seen — though it does not by any means prevail universally. In one or two cases, as far as we know, the oligarchical form of polity maintains itself throughout this period; more often we hear of oscillation between oligarchy and democracy. Also, in the later part of the time, the habit of employing mercenaries gives a new opportunity for tyrannis. Then the Macedonian predominance and empire closes the period of effective independence of the city-states, and we come to the last noteworthy product of the fertile inventiveness of the Greek mind in the department of political construc- tion : the Federal system, of which the remarkable develop- ment in the third century B.C. sheds a gleam of interest — not only for the student of political science, but for the ordinary reader — on the last stage of the history of free Greece, the period intervening between Macedonian predominance and the final absorption of Greece under Eoman rule. In considering the causes of transition from one form of government to another, we have so far directed our attention chiefly — putting conquest aside — to internal causes. Among these, economic causes are very important ; e.g. the growing inequality of wealth tended, as we saw, to alter the primitive polity in an oligarchical direction, making the poor freeman more dependent on the rich : while again the more extensive use of money, leading to X GREEK FEDERALISM 133 borrowing on the part of the smaller cultivators, aggravated this inequality into a felt oppressiveness, and tended both in Greece and Eome to movements against the primitive oligarchy. Also — especially in colonies and commercial cities — the growth of new wealth, outside the privileged classes, was a cause making for change. But, apart from economic causes, one main impulse to change is doubtless derived from the spread of the simple conviction that " one man is as good as another " — those outside the group politically privileged as good as those inside ; a conviction of which the practical effect would be continually strengthened by the openness to new ideas — the weakening of the force of mere custom and habit — which the gradual civilisation and the mutual communica- tion of so many independent communities would cause. This conviction is most obviously effective in the drift to democracy, but we may suppose it operative in earlier stages in a more limited form. For example, where as at Corinth, one or more annual magistrates chosen from the royal house are substituted for the king, we may suppose the opinion to have become prevalent that one man of royal blood is as good as another — and perhaps (as the Irishman in the story said) " a deal better too," since the occasional inefficiency of the hereditary king must have been a frequent argument for change. So again, when the chief magistracy is thrown open to nobles generally, we may suppose the conviction to have prevailed that one landowner of old family is as good as another. But when we speak of the efficiency of the king or government, we have already passed the line separating internal from external relations of the community, since the efficiency of the primitive king was largely estimated with a view to war ; in fact, as we saw, the introduction of a war chief, distinct from the hereditary king, is said to have been the first step in the process of change to oligarchy at Athens. And no doubt more generally, war was sometimes an important factor in producing a change in the form of government, and sometimes, on the other hand, a source of 134 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. stability, when the established government proved itself efficient. We have noted again that the development of the city- state out of the more primitive group of village communities was importantly favoured by the value of the protection of the walled town in war. And finally, the predominance of federalism in the last stages of the history of Greece was chiefly caused by the necessity, after the Macedonian conquest of the Persian empire, of having states larger than the old city-state, to resist Macedonia and the large states formed out of the fragments of Alexander's empire. I may add that the necessity of greater strength for defence in war has been the cause of federalism in medieval and modern Europe as well as in ancient Greece. § 2. The time, in short, had come for the transition from the City-State to the larger political organisations which play the chief part in modern European history — " Country-States " we may call them. There were two modes of transition by which city-states might pass into a country -state really united by patriotic sentiment as distinct from empire: the method of federation on equal terms, and the method of expansion and absorption. The former is that which prevails in this last period of Greek history when the Achaean and Aetolian leagues or federations attract the chief attention of the historian. The latter is that which enabled Eome to become mistress of the civilised world, and which we shall trace in the two following lectures. The scientific interest of this historical transition lies largely in a comparison of the two. Both processes, as I have said, are forms of transition from the distinctively ancient conception, expressed by the term " Polls," to the conception which is most familiar to the modern mind. We naturally think of a " country," not a " city," as the local habitation of a State ; indeed, we easily slide into using the word country in a double and mixed sense, — to mean sometimes a portion of the earth's surface, some- times a political community inhabiting it, sometimes a fusion IX GREEK FEDERALISM 135 of the two. Thus in any appeal to — any effusion of — patriotic sentiment, the characteristics of the particular part of the earth's surface inhabited by the community occupy a prominent place ; to constitute the object of patriotic devotion the imagination seems to require this embodiment. When we think of the " sea-girt isle " of England, " la belle France," or the German " fatherland," we often do not separate the community from the land, but fuse the two in one notion ; and in more than one case this fusion has had the politically important effect of making it seem natural and right that a portion of the earth's surface separated from the rest by marked natural boundaries should be the territory of a single state. And it is curious to note that while this blending of elements in the notion of " country " is so natural to us moderns, that it requires a little effort to distinguish the elements, we find the corresponding fusion in the Greek notion of " polis " difficult and perplexing. I believe that most moderns when they begin to learn Greek feel some wonder that a language so rich in subtle distinctions should use the same word for " city " and " state." Well, it is an interesting evidence of the transition in political thought, as well as political fact, which goes on in the third century B.C., that in Polybius's history of the Achaean League, the word " ethnos " (nation) largely takes the place of the word " polis " ; and the normal constitution of an Hellenic "ethnos" — which has now become the primary object of patriotic sentiment — is a federal constitution. § 3. Federation of a rude kind is characteristic of early history. In fact, we may say that, in Greece as well as in Germany, the largest political society in the tribal condi- tion is normally a very loose federation of sub -tribes or cantons whose political union becomes closer as civilisation goes on. The sub -tribe or canton may also be called a sort of federation of villages. Thence comes the early "integration" — the >> medieval democracy of organised trades and crafts — in the Italian cities. The effective independence of Florence, and of Tuscan cities generally, is, as I said, later in commencement than that of the cities north of the Apennines, owing to the stronger rule of the Marquisate of Tuscany, but it is more enduring. Florence is developing her republican polity and bringing its industrial character into fuller manifestation long after almost all the Lombard cities have fallen under despotic rule. In the course of this develop- ment the constitution becomes extremely complex. The chief causes of the changes seem to be (1) the con- tinually renewed efforts to repress the lawlessness of the nobles by fresh governmental organisations; and (2) the increased and extended representation of the trades or Arti in the government. The former characteristic is, as we have seen, peculiar to the Italian city ; the latter, on the other hand, shows its essential affinity to the general type of medieval city. The independence of Florence may be taken to begin — if it begins at any point of time — in A.D. 1115 after the death of the Countess Matilda, who had governed alone the Marquisate of Tuscany from A.D. 1076. Under her rule the city had had no theoretical self-government; but practi- cally members of the leading families took part in the administration of justice. Matilda herself presided over the 286 LECT. XX MEDIEVAL CITIES — FLORENCE 287 tribunal when able to be present; but in her absence — which political and administrative occupations rendered not infrequent — the decisions were often left to civic judges. Further, in the struggle that was going on between pope and emperor, while the city of Florence along with its feudal superior the Countess embraced the side of the Pope, the feudal nobility around, who conceived themselves oppressed by this feudal superior, were largely on the side of the emperor. Accordingly, the struggle of the cities with the rural nobility — which we followed in the case of the Lombard cities — began in Florence before any formal municipal independence was attained. The transition to independence, therefore, takes place without much of a shock ; the members of the leading families who had carried on the executive government in Matilda's name now carry it on in the name of the city. This government before long comes to consist of twelve persons called Consuls, elected annually two from each of the six quarters of the city. They belonged to the class of leading citizens largely consisting of feudal nobles, but they were assisted by a council of a hundred or more, in which the industrial element was included and doubtless had the predominance. We may assume that it included representatives of the organised trades, afterwards known as the "greater arts," or of some of these; since in the last quarter of the twelfth century we find that the heads of the Arti are considered competent to have a function formally assigned to them in the treaties negotiated by the city ; and we may assume that a long period of thriving organised existence has preceded this political recognition. Indeed, the external policy of Florence appears to be governed from the first by its commercial interests. There was also the Parlamento for great occasions ; but its meeting was mostly a pure form, and as it often met in a piazza of very moderate size or in a church, it is evident that the mass of the citizens had no effective share in governmental decisions. . § 2. So far there is no antagonism between the noble and 2S8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. the industrial elements ; but from a.d. 1129 onwards we read of the destruction of neighbouring castelli and the forcing of the noble owners into the city, which thus increases its feudal element. Then in the latter half of the twelfth century comes the struggle with Frederick Barbarossa, who appoints Podest^s in Florence and other cities ; but this imperial system — never very effective — collapses at the end of the century. Neverthe- less, here as in Lombardy, the peculiar institution of having an annually appointed foreign noble as Podesta or head of the government is introduced, and soon after (a.d. 1212) has superseded the consuls, who seem to be transformed into a sort of privy council of the Podestk The transformation here seems to be due partly to the sense of the superior efficiency of the single governor for the wars with castelli and neighbouring towns which Florence is carrying on during this period ; though the choice of a foreigner seems to show that the same need was felt here as in Lom- bardy of an impartial stranger to repress the lawless- ness of the nobles. At any rate, in the first half of the thirteenth century, feuds break out among the nobles, pre- sently merging in the general Guelf - Ghibelin quarrel. There are Guelf nobles as well as Ghibelin nobles ; but the old families are almost all Ghibelin and the industrial element, the organised Arti, is mainly Guelf. The antagonism of nobles and industrials grows stronger ; and in a.d. 1250 the people give themselves a separate organisation, both military and political, under the headship of a Capitano del Fopolo. The object of the organisation is to repress effectively the lawless violence of the nobles ; the six quarters are divided into companies, twenty in all, each with its standard, so that the people may all form and unite in military order when the Capitano del Fopolo rings the great bell on the "Torre del Leone." The organisation is presently suspended during a tem- porary predominance of the Ghibelins, but it is revived with modifications in A.D.1267. The result is an extremely complicated constitution, because the guiding principle of XX MEDIEVAL CITIES FLORENCE 289 the Florentine movement towards popular government is to leave — in the main — the existing government with ^ important functions, and to superadd a new organisation |' for the better protection of popular interests. Thus we »^ get the following constitution from 1267 onward. There is, first, the Podesta as before — an annually elected foreign noble — with a privy council of 90 and a larger council of 300 ; these councils are composed of nobles and commons combined. But for the ordinary despatch of administrative business there is a body of twelve, called the Twelve Buoni Uomini, two from each of the six quarters ; they are elected from the people, and are advised by a council of 100, also elected from the people. Then there is the Capitano del Popolo who is, like the Podesta, a foreign noble, selected from a Guelf town ; he also has his special and general councils ; he leads the citizen militia, infantry composed of the people in companies, while the Podestk is the chief representative of the republic in foreign affairs, and often the commander-in-chief of the whole army, but more especially of the cavalry, composed almost entirely of nobles and other professional soldiers.^ The Podestk presided over ordinary civil and criminal justice ; while, as I have said, (\ it was the special function of the Capitano del Popolo to ,^ repress crimes of violence committed by the nobles against popolani. The result was that in case of a measure that had to obtain the concurrence of all the deliberative bodies, the process was singularly complicated. A measure proposed by the twelve Buoni Uomini had to be voted (1) by the Council of 100, (2) by the special council of the Capi- tano, (3) by the general council of the Capitano, usually 1 While from a.d. 1250 the predominance of the industrial element in the life of the city becomes stronger and shows itself in the political organisation more and more, on the other hand, the military superiority of the feudal element becomes greater through the improved heavy armour of the cavalry, as was shown in the battle of Montaperti a.d. 1260. From this came the develop- ment of mercenary warfare ; sons even of noble families become commanders of bands of gens d' amies and acquire reputation in the new art of war. This, as I said, is a fruitful source of tyrannis. U 290 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. on one day ; and the next day by (4) the special council of the Podesta, and (5) the general council of the Podestk To avoid intolerable delays the speaking was severely limited, which is perhaps one reason why political oratory seems never to have had a rich development in Florence — or indeed in Italy generally. § 3. But this is not all. The idea of Florentine govern- ment, as so constituted, is not complete unless we take into account the organisation of the dominant Guelf party, and the organisation of the trades, or Arti. As regards the former, there were appointed at this time six Capitani di Parte Ghielfa — as they were after- wards called — also with councils special and general, to administer the funds of the party derived from confiscated property of Ghibelins. They gradually became an organ of regular government for certain purposes — it being assumed that the Guelf party was always to be in power. This intro- duction of party organisation into regular government is a noteworthy feature of the later medieval political constitu- tion which no modern State has yet imitated. For example, in England, from a.d. 1715-1760, it was an established maxim that the Whigs were always to be in power; but the constitution did not in any way recognise the Whig party. I mentioned just now, in speaking of the parties in Florence, that the struggle between Guelfs and Ghibelins did not completely coincide with the struggle between Grandees and People (Grandi and Popolani), though it did in some measure. The old noble families were almost entirely Ghibelin, and the strength of the Guelf party lay in industrial support ; but there were Guelf nobles as well as Ghibelin nobles ; and in fact of the six Capitani di Parte Guelf a three were Grandi and three Popolani. Later they have a palace of their own and, as I said, certain public functions, the chief being the persecution of Ghibelins. This, as we shall see, is a function which afterwards becomes of decisive importance in determining the character of the government. § 4. But the organisation of the trades or Arti is still XX MEDIEVAL CITIES — FLORENCE 291 more important — is, in fact, the pivot on whicli the con- stitution of 1267 turned. And as it is in this organisation, and its representation in the government of the city that the distinctively medieval structure of the city first becomes prominent, I will dwell on it at more length. The origin of the industrial associations, called in Italy Arti, goes back, as we have seen, to the Eoman times ; and doubtless in Florence they were effectively organised at an early period. Probably all that was done in a.d. 1266—1267 was to give legal recognition — and perhaps greater fixity and order — to a constitution which had long been in existence and effective operation: and to give them formally an important, though still subordinate, place in the new governmental structure. The chief governing organs of these trade associations — the Capitudini delle Arti — sat ex-officio in the special or privy council of the Capitano del Popolo, as well as in the general council. The Arti thus recognised were seven — known as Maggiori Arti. One of these, the "judges and notaries," stands apart from the others as not being primd facie commercial : — it is to be observed, however, that the pro- vision of good judges and notaries was considered in Italy to be of great importance for commercial prosperity, for the decision of commercial disputes, the framing, revising, and enforcing of the statutes of the corporation, drawing up contracts, etc. The other six Arti represent the leading branches of foreign trade in Florence. The first place, at this time, belonged to the Arte di Calimala, the trade of refining and dyeing foreign cloth, and the Arte delta Lana, which dealt in home-made cloth. Owing to the original inferiority of Italian wool, and the superiority of Italian taste, the pros- perity of the Calimala came first ; afterwards, as successful efforts were made to improve the raw material in Italy, the manufacture of home-made wool became more important. Along with these two, the Arte del Camlio, bankers and exchangers, held the first rank. Next came the Arte delta Seta, dealers in silk, which grew in importance later. The next, Medici, or " physicians," seems at first sight pro- 292 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. fessional rather than commercial ; but in fact the medici were dealers in drugs as well as medical advice, and along with Speziali, dealers in spices, represented a not unimportant branch of oriental trade. The list is closed by dealers in fur. These associations taken together — more than one of them comprehending several allied branches of industry — come forward as the natural leaders of the industrial popu- lation of the city; and doubtless at this time are so re- garded by the lesser Arti, which, in the course of the next generation, acquire legal organisation, and later, political recognition. The names of these — linen-drapers, shoemakers, smiths, provision -dealers, butchers, vintners, innkeepers, harness -makers, curriers, armourers, locksmiths, masons, carpenters, bakers — sufficiently explain the distinction. The lesser arts are almost exclusively concerned with the internal retail exchange of commodities and services, and have accordingly a restricted sphere of business interests in contrast with the greater arts. These being engaged in commerce extended widely from West to East, became naturally familiar with, and keenly concerned about, the external political relations of the city, which, of course, they directed largely on commercial principles. To give an idea of the organisation of these Arti, I will take the one which at this time held the leading position — the Arte di Calimala. Every six months the heads of ware- houses and shops met and chose electors, who elected four Consoli, who governed the Arte with the aid of a chancellor (camerlingo), a notary who looked after the exact observance of the statutes and often made speeches at the meetings on behalf of the consuls, a special council of twelve, and a somewhat larger general council. The consuls inspected the shops and warehouses, and punished adulteration, bad quality of wares, short measure, and careless book-keeping, with fines, and, as ultimate sanction, exclusion from the Arte} The consuls of the seven greater Arts — called Capitudini ^ They had also consoli abroad to look after the interests of members of the Arte — the institution of consuls in modern states is lineally descended from this. XX MEDIEVAL CITIES FLORENCE 293 delU Arte — are, as I have said, in 1267 formally included in the special or privy council of the Capitano del Fopolo, which indeed is called consiglio speciale e delle capitudini. § 5. It will be seen that in the strangely elaborated con- stitution just described, the nobles have but a small share, and the importance of the heads of the Arti in the councils was doubtless great. In fact, the Arti, greater and lesser, were, for political purposes, the Popolo. But their prepon- derance is markedly increased fifteen years later (a.d. 1282) when the chief executive government is placed in the hands of six Priori, elected for periods of two months, one from each of six greater arts. The seventh, judges and notaries, is omitted as having enough political influence from the nature of their calling; as we saw, the notary is an im- portant official in each Arte. Thus eligibility to the chief executive is made dependent on membership of one of these ^ organised trades ; nobles who wish to be elected have to enrol themselves in one or other of the six Arti. We have now, it seems, an industrial oligarchy formally established. But as yet it is a natural oligarchy ; there does not seem to be as yet any complaint of exclusiveness in the greater Arti. They are the natural leaders of the Popolo ; and all the Arti, greater and lesser, appear in the thirteenth century to be still united against the nobles, somewhat as in England the urban capitalist and the artisan were united against the territorial aristocracy, in the struggle against the Corn Laws in the early part of the nineteenth century. This is shown eleven to thirteen years later — in A.D. 1293-1295 — when the tables are turned still further on the nobles, and the most noble families in Florence are formally made ineligible to the office of Prior. We find that the Priori are then elected by the presidents of twelve Arti and other sapientes et honi viri artifices, members of Arti, drawn from different quarters. Indeed, some of the lesser Arti appear to have taken a prominent part in the popular movement of this date ; and all the twenty-one Arti, greater and lesser together, pledged themselves to main- tain the most remarkable innovation of this time, namely 294 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. the " Ordinances of Justice," directed specially against the nobles. On these I propose to dwell for a moment, as they show in a very striking manner the difficulties with which the Italian cities had to contend in their endeavours to accomplish the elementary task of enforcing the observance of law and civil order on a nobility which all the civilisa- tion attained by the end of the thirteenth century, in the centre of European civilisation, had left essentially barbaric. It is evident that, even in Florence, where the industrial element had a specially full and prosperous development, even after it had enjoyed for nearly thirty years the political pre- dominance secured in 1267 and increased in 1282, in spite of the Podestd,, of the Gapitano del Pojpolo, of all attempts to organise the industrial element in self-defence — in spite of all — the nobles, with their wealth, their prestige, their family ties and dependents, were able to defy the law to an extent intolerable to peaceful citizens, to overawe witnesses, rescue arrested criminals, and thus secure practical impunity for their habitual outrages. To put an end to this the new Ordinances were instituted and a new machinery for enforcing them. The chief features of the Ordinances were: (1) The family tie, which had been a support of lawlessness, was turned into a means of repression. If a member of a noble family — a family that had cavalieri among its members — committed an offence, his relatives were made responsible. It was further established that all Grandi, from the age of fifteen to seventy, had to appear annually before the Podesta, and to give security for good behaviour ; in the case of minor acts of violence, the surety had to pay the fine and recoup himself from the offender's goods. If a jpojpolano should be killed or mortally wounded by a grande, it was the duty of the Podesta to behead the criminal, destroy his houses, and confiscate his goods. (2) But the most startling measure was that adopted to meet the difficulty of getting witnesses to acts of violence to come forward. It was ordained that common rumour, attested by two ^ ^ Afterwards raised to three. XX MEDIEVAL CITIES FLORENCE 295 credible witnesses, should be sufficient to prove a crime against a noble. It would be difficult to defend this ; but the violence of the remedy proves the obstinacy of the disorder. Its application was limited by the proviso that if popolani take part in the quarrels of grandi, these ex- ceptional 'Ordinances are no longer applicable. The new machinery was the appointment of a Gon- falonier of Justice, having at his command a body of 1000 yopolani — afterwards increased to 4000 — bound to appear in arms at the palace of the Signoria when called upon, or in case of uproar. The Gonfalonier has to support the Podesta in executing the ordinances ; or if the Podest^ and the Capitanx) del Popolo neglect their duty, he has to act in their place. The Gonfalonier formed, with the six Priors, the Signoria or chief executive government, and ultimately became its chief member. He was elected annually, and like the Priors, by the presidents of twelve Arti and other Artisans, drawn from the different quarters of the city. Only members of Arti were eligible, and nobles were excluded, even if enrolled in a company. Even these drastic ordinances did not attain their end at once. For half a century the nobles struggle against them ; and, in the feud between " Whites " and " Blacks " at the beginning of the fourteenth century, the nobles seem to be fighting quite in the old style. But the people stick to the Ordinances, so that they must have had some sub- stantial effect ; indeed, in 1338, Pome asks a copy of them from Florence. § 6. Meanwhile, in A.D. 1323, an important change, specially interesting to the student who compares medieval Italian with ancient Greek polities, takes place in the mode of election to magistracies — the partial introduction of the lot. Hitherto the Priori, while changed every two months, had been elected for every six months ; but this was thought to render candidatures, with accompanying intrigues, too frequent, and it was resolved to elect at once all the Priori for forty-two months ahead, i.e. for twenty-one changes, and afterwards determine the succession of the two months' 296 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect, tenures by lot, no one being re-eligible until the whole number was exhausted. This also had the advantage — from a democratic point of view — of practically throwing open the post to a larger number of persons. The office of prior, in fact, would necessarily be held within three and a half years by 126 different persons, which must, one would think, be at any rate a considerable part of the whole number of persons who seemed to their fellow-citizens competent to fill it. And as the same method was extended to all the magistracies — which Sismondi estimates at 136 — it would certainly seem that an office of some sort would be almost a certainty to a respectable Florentine citizen, with leisure for public affairs — for no office was paid, except those held by foreigners. Sismondi adds that " almost all the free cities of Italy hastened to adopt this innovation of the Florentines ; " ^ and says that the practice, in the early part of the nineteenth century, still survived in Lucca, and in the municipalities of Tuscany and of the States of the Church. In contemplating the number of her magistrates, we must bear in mind that Florence had become a large city in the first half of the fourteenth century. Sismondi estimates that in a.d. 1343 it had 150,000 inhabitants. Observe that, though the change in the mode of election thus described is democratic in the sense of opening to a larger number of persons the prospect of office, the persons choosing are still a select few, for the names to be drawn by lot are not elected by the citizens at large. At the same time, elaborate plans were adopted to prevent the exclusion of any really eligible citizen. It may usefully illustrate the character of the fourteenth century polity of Florence, if I follow the chronicler^ in describing the pro- cedure adopted for electing the Priori and Gonfalonieri in 1328, when, after the death of the Duke of Calabria, who had for three years held the " signory " of Florence,^ a serious attempt was made to put the government on as ^ Histoire des Ripuhliques Italiennes, vol. v. ch. xxx. 2 Giov. Villani, lib. x. ch. cviii. ^ I may remark incidentally that nothing shows so strikingly the diflS- XX MEDIEVAL CITIES FLORENCE 297 broad a basis as possible, consistently with keeping the power in the hands of the Guelf party. The plan was as follows: — (1) The Priori, with the addition of two popolani from each quarter of the city, made a selection of the non- noble citizens of the Guelf party, over thirty years of age, qualified for the priorate. (2) The gonfalonieri delle com- pagnie (captains of militia companies), with two popolani added from each company, did the same. But this was not enough ; the party organisation and the industrial organisation had also to assist in the selection, so (3) the capitani of the Guelf party, with their council, also made their list ; and (4) also the cinque ujiciali della mercatanzia (five trade officials), along with two consoli from each of the greater Arts. It is as if in England we had adopted the policy of having the Liberals always in power — as the Whigs were always in power under the two first Georges — and the ministry was chosen by the Cabinet, aided by a committee of the National Liberal Federation and the delegates of the leading trades-unions. When the lists are made out, the final determination of persons eligible for the office of Prior during the next two years is made by secret ballot by a somewhat differently constituted body of persons, namely the Priori, the Twelve Buoni Uomini " with whom they took counsel on important matters," nineteen gonfalonieri delle compagnie, two consoli for each of the twelve greater Arti, and thirty-six persons added by the Priors and Buoni Uomini, six from each of the six quarters of the town. Sixty-eight votes were required for approval. Then the names of these approved persons were put in purses, one purse for each quarter of the town,, from each of which a name was drawn by lot every two months ; each of those whose names were drawn was then Prior for the ensuing two months, subject to the prohibition preventing the same person being Prior within two years, culties under which republican independence was maintained in medieval Italy than that even Florence, its leading defender, should be from time to time obliged to accept temporarily a foreign lord. He was only accepted with careful reservation of the rights of municipal self-government ; still, that he should be accepted at all is a striking fact. 298 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. or two members of the same house holding the office within the same six months, and two brothers, or father and son, within a year. The Gonfalonieri and the Twelve Buoni Uomini were elected from similar lists, and each Art elected its consuls in a similar manner. It is to be observed that at the same time (a.d. 1328) the before-mentioned complicated system of councils was re- duced to two — the council of the popolo, composed of 300 Guelf popolani, and the council of the comune, composed of 250 approved persons, nobles and popolani. The aim was that all the great interests of the state might be somehow represented ; even the nobles having, in the council of the comune, a representation designed to give them sub- stantial protection against class oppression. § 7. But constitutions in these troublous times were brief in duration. The union of feeling between the greater Arts representing the commercial element and the lesser Arts containing the artisan element, has been diminishing ; and the double discord, between grandi and leading popolani on the one side, and the richer popolani and the ordinary artisans on the other, gives the opportunity for Tyrannis — to which the cities north of the Apennines have by this time generally succumbed. When in September 1342 Walter de Brienne, Duke of Athens, made himself temporarily master of the city, it was a combination of the ancient nobility and the lower class of artisans, which, in a disorderly Parlamento, acclaimed him lord of the city for his lifetime. But in the July following all classes united to free Florence from the tyrant. A brief effort was made to maintain this union by giving the nobles a share of the offices, and the ordinances against them were transiently suspended. But the enemy of the human race, as the chronicler puts it,^ stirred up pride and insolence in the nobles ; the people rebelled against their outrages, and forced them out of the chief magistracy ; a brief armed struggle took place, and the nobility succumbed finally (a.d. 1343). As a class, the old nobility never compete 1 G. Villani, lib. xii. ch. xix. XX MEDIEVAL CITIES — FLORENCE 299 again for power. The Ordinances are permanently re- established, but in a more equitable form ; the responsibility of kinsmen for a noble criminal was restricted to his nearest relatives. Also the notion of grande is changed ; a popolano guilty of certain crimes is declared a grande — with his family and kin unless they deliver him up to justice ; on the other hand, a number of old noble families or individuals are as a favour declared popolani by public decree. A similar plan under different names was adopted by other free republics of Tuscany — Siena, Pistoia, Lucca ; and generally in the cities that remain free the nobility is excluded from all the magistracies ; and in more than one a register of nobles is opened as at Florence, on which to inscribe by way of punishment the names of disturbers of the public peace. This is one of the most remarkable in- stitutions which medieval history shows us. To go back to Florence. The old nobility having finally lost power, the question remains how, in an exclusively industrial government, power is to be divided between the plebeian oligarchs and the artisans organised in the lesser crafts. At first, after a.d. 1343, it seems as if the latter would preponderate. Between a.d. 1328 and 1343 — especially in the struggles of a.d. 1342 and 1343 — a great stride has been made towards democracy. As the chron- icler says : " The people, having won its victory over the grandees . . . rose to great position and boldness and, mastery especially the middle class and the smaller artisans." ^ On the whole, the government of the city fell to the executives of the twenty-one Arti. The old division into six districts having become antiquated, the city was now divided into four quarters, and the number of Priori increased from six to eight, two from each quarter, making — with the Gon- falonier of Justice, now regarded as head of the government — an executive of nine ; and it was arranged that three out of the nine should be taken from the lesser Arts. As a matter of fact — as the chronicler goes on to say — the im- mediate result was that they got more than this proportion, ^ G. Villani, lib. xir. ch. xxii. 30O DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. especially as the prohibition against two members of the same family being Prior within six months pressed harder on old families, whose ties of kin were known to remote degrees, than on new people who kept no account of cousin- ship. § 8. But oligarchy, as we have before observed, usually dies hard. When it was found, as we are told, that " mean and ignorant persons obtained the office of prior," ^ a reaction took place towards practical oligarchy, effected in a rather peculiar way. I have described how the predominant Guelf party was organised as a Guelf society with council and captains, and how later its captains con- stitutionally took part in framing the list of eligible citizens from whom magistrates were elected by lot. They had also an officer for the accusation of suspected imperialists ; and under their influence Ghibelins had been practically excluded from office for three-quarters of a century (a,d. 1266— 1343). Soon after the change of 1343, however, it was believed or pretended that a lax selection of eligibles had admitted Ghibelins ; and under cover of zeal against this generally proscribed party, the Guelf society — in which such of the old nobles as were Guelf retained considerable influence, and coalesced with leading ndbili popolani, somewhat as in ancient Eome, to form a new group of oligarchical tendency — contrived to keep power in its hands for twenty years. They got a law passed which rendered every Ghibelin who held office liable to punishment — capital or pecuniary, at the discretion of the magistrates ; while it gave the leaders of the Guelf society the function of " warning " suspected Ghibelins. By this imputation of Ghibelinism they managed, from a.d. 1358-1378, to scare from the offices not only Ghibelins but any person opposed to the governing group. Hence discontent, leading to what is perhaps the most famous revolution of Florence, the revolution of the Ciompi (a.d. 1378), which has a double historical interest — (1) be- cause it is the high-water mark of the democratic movement ^ Hallam, Middle Ages, chap. iii. part ii. p. 429. XX MEDIEVAL CITIES — FLORENCE 301 in Florence, and (2) because here for the first time the move- ment goes beyond the limits of the regularly organised trades or crafts, and temporarily gives a share in govern- ment to a still lower stratum of the people. This stratum consists partly of groups of workers who had not obtained independent incorporation, but were in a dependent re- lation to one or other of the greater arts. For example, the Arte di Lana, which I may perhaps translate by the familiar term " Drapers' Company," had wool-combers, dyers, and weavers in this way dependent on it, but included also unskilled labourers, ciompi. It would take too long to follow the phases of the revolution. It is effected by a combination of the per- secuted Ghibelins real or suspected, the lesser Arts and this lower stratum ; at a certain point the lower stratum gets the bit between its teeth and seems to carry all before it in a rush of popular excitement which reminds one of the 4meutes of the period after A.D. 1789. It temporarily gains the right of furnishing one-third of the executive of nine (the eight Priors and the Gonfalonier of Justice) ; but the wave of sedition dashes further; there is a reaction, and the result is a constitution in which the lesser Arts pre- dominate. But this only lasts for three years ; in a.d. 1382 the nobili popolani regain power — the effective democratic movement is over.^ The minori Arti retain, it is true, one-fourth share of the magistracies ; but they cease to be genuine " craft-guilds " ; rich young men enter them, and they become passive instruments in the hands of a ruling oligarchy of capital. Indeed, fifty years later, the transi- tion by which the republic gradually passes into the practical monarchy of the Medici has popular support, just as the transition at the end of the Eoman republic has. 1 I have dwelt on Florence alone, to give as much clearness as possible to a brief narrative ; but similar temporary triumphs of the democracy of organised but inferior crafts appear in other cities — e.g. Siena— about the same time. LECTUKE XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS § 1. I now pass to describe briefly the origin and decline of the type of polity which tended to prevail in Western Europe in the later Middle Ages, intervening between the feudal or quasi -feudal conditions of the earlier Middle Ages — which, overlooking minor variations, we may take as lasting from the tenth to the thirteenth century — and the predominance of pure monarchy in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. We may call it " monarchy controlled by assemblies of estates," bearing in mind, as an essential characteristic, that these assemblies include, besides nobles and clergy, representatives of the cities. But before I enter on this description, I should like to draw attention to an important difference between ancient and modern political ideas, on which what I have to say will throw light. Aristotle, in the passage already quoted, describing the functions of the deliberative body,^ says nothing about taxation. The function of raising the funds necessary for public objects seems to be regarded by him as so clearly secondary and subordinate that nothing is said about it. On the other hand, in Locke's famous Treatise on Civil Government (a.d. 1690) the question who is to de- termine taxation seems to be even more fundamental than the question who is to determine legislation. Locke is willing to admit that a people may hand over to an absolute monarch the function of making laws, subject only to the vague condition that the laws must be designed for ^ See Lecture xii. p. 174. 302 LECT. XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 303 the good of the people ; but he will not admit that they can ever be held to have similarly handed over to any government the right to "raise taxes on the property of the people, without the consent of the people, given by themselves, or their deputies." -^ And this view — startling as it is from the point of view of recent, no less than of ancient political theory — corresponds to the prominence which the question of finance historically occupies in the constitutional struggles of the seventeenth century. This difference between ancient and modern political ideas is due, I think, to the manner in which modern polity grew gradually out of feudal conditions. In the feudal polity taxation proper has no place ; the king is conceived to defray the expenses of his kingdom from the resources of his domain, and the feudal services, dues, and occasional " aids " rendered by his vassals. Then, as the expenditure of the Crown increases, especially from the superior utility of paid professional soldiers in war, the monarch's need of getting money conflicts with the estab- lished habit among his vassals of paying as a matter of right and duty only fixed rents and dues, or commuta- tions for services. As Hallam says of the King of France, when the period of assemblies begins : " There was one essential privilege which " the monarch, in spite of in- creased power, " could not hope to overturn by force, the immunity from taxation enjoyed by his barons ; " ^ and, we may add, that the security from arbitrary increase of annual payments, given by their charters to the enfranchised towns, could not be simply ignored. From the monarch's point of view, then, the institution of general assemblies was important as a means of overcoming the obstacles thus placed in the way of his finance. § 2. It is fundamentally important that the stage of medieval political development in which assemblies partly representative become important organs of governmental control, was preceded and partly caused by the development 1 Treatise on Civil Government, ch. xi. § 142. 2 Middle Ages, ch. 11. pt. ii. p. 223. 304 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. within the country -state of city -communities with an independence rivalling that of the feudal lords, but in- ternally organised, as we have seen, on principles quite unlike the feudal — essentially industrial — with more or less tendency for some time to a semi-democratic constitution. It is owing to this development that the assemblies when formed are not merely assemblies of nobles — fighters and clergy — but include representatives of the growing industrial element of society ; and it is this inclusion of an industrial element that most definitely marks these assemblies as expressing a new stage in the development of the nation. Tor the feudal element of these assemblies is not novel ; it is only a later form of the assembly of the monarch's immediate vassals which, under the name of " royal court " or " council," is a known and familiar organ of government in the feudal period, though the degree of regularity with which it performs its functions is very various. It repre- sents the council of chiefs in the primitive polity; it is called together to advise the king on questions of peace and war, give important judicial decisions, and regulate the occasional war taxes (" aids ") which in feudal times were almost the only distinctly public form of taxation. If this alone had continued to give advice to the monarch and consent to the laws and the taxes, even if such councils had become more regular, they would merely have continued the struggle between monarchy and oligarchy of which I have already spoken as characterising the earlier Middle Ages. But by the introduction of the cities a more democratic element comes in to the " meetings of estates " which partly aid, partly control monarchy from the end of the thirteenth century onwards. The formation of these assemblies is a sign and ex- pression of the growing coherence of the nation ; this is a statement that may be made about them all. But as to the causes that mainly led to them, it is, I think, difficult to make any statement that is clearly applicable to all cases. Sometimes the impulse to their formation seems to proceed entirely or mainly from above, and to XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 305 be due to considerations of policy, mainly of finance, on the part of the monarch ; sometimes, again, it seems to come from below, and to be a more comprehensive and impressive result of a spontaneous movement of voluntary association among persons and bodies in the same social condition which characterises the later period of the Middle Ages ; often, of course, both causes blend. Now one might perhaps have expected that where the movement that gives deputies of the third estate seats beside barons and prelates comes from below rather than from above, it would be most likely to develop into stable and permanent constitutional government. But the fact is otherwise. It is in Germany that we see the force of spontaneous association working most clearly and im- pressively ; it is {e.g.) in Germany that the famous voluntary leagues of cities are formed — especially the Hanseatic league, a most striking instance of the strength and practical in- dependence given by the spontaneous confederation of elements that individually remain in formal political de- pendence. Taking its rise in the unions formed by German traders in foreign countries — England, Flanders, Scandinavia, Kussia — for the protection of their common interests, and in smaller unions for different objects among the trading cities of Korth Germany, we find at length, in the middle of the fourteenth century, a great union of North German towns, under the name of Ransa, governed by the resolu- tions passed at meetings of the deputies of the several towns, and having for its primary aims the security of the sea and land routes, the settlement by arbitration of disputes between cities that are members of it, and the acquirement and maintenance of trading privileges in foreign lands. In a.d. 1367-1370 it wages war successfully and gloriously against the Scandinavian kingdoms ; and it main- tains a vigorous life for a long subsequent period, controls the internal polity of the cities composing it, and even — when the Eeformation comes — concerns itself with religious interests. And this is only one among several instances of confederation of German cities in the later Middle Ages, X 306 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. after the decline of Imperial power had set in. Nor is it only in the case of cities that this spontaneous tendency to unite for the defence of common interests is exhibited in Germany ; the nobility, especially the lesser nobility, similarly unite in brotherhoods for the defence of their rights and privileges ; the movement even Reached the peasants, though only imperfectly and transiently except in the famous case of the Swiss. Finally, it is especially in Germany that in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries — the period of medieval parliaments — the force of voluntary combination is manifested, uniting nobles and clergy, knights and citizens into more comprehensive unions for protection against the oppression of the princes. Yet in Germany this medieval system of meetings of estates loses force, and even when it survives in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, can offer no effective resistance to the predominant absolutism.-^ In England, on the other hand, where the transition from the medieval to the modern parliament is gradual and unbroken, there is no such spontaneous impulse to association manifested by the cities ; they are at first called in irregularly by the baronage, chiefly it would seem for moral support, and in order to give the barons' struggle with the king a more impressive air of being a national struggle; and they are afterwards summoned regularly, chiefly for the greater convenience of getting money for the financial needs of the king by negotiating with the cities in the aggregate, through their delegates, rather than negotiating with them separately. In Spain, where these assemblies appear earlier, Prescott says that it is now too late to inquire " whether the convocation of the third estate to the national councils proceeded from politic calculation in the sovereign, or was in a manner forced on him by the growing power and importance of the cities." ^ But in France, as in England, it is evident that the im- pulse proceeds primarily from above ; though the assembly 1 See below, Lecture xxiii. p. 336. ^ History of Ferdinand and Isabella (in a footnote to the Introduction). XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 307 thus called into being in France shows before long a dis- position to grasp the reins of power when the monarch's rule appears feeble and unsuccessful. § 3. Before I go on to analyse the exceptional conditions which led to the completer and more successful develop- ments of these medieval representative institutions in England, let us examine — by way of contrast — the case of France ; partly because, when the period of pure monarchy succeeds this generally transient period of representative institutions, it is in France that it appears most splendid and impressive. _ _ . _ We may begin by noting that, as Guizot points out,^ when the tiers-dtat begins to play an important part in the medieval history of France, the independence of the towns is no longer what it was ; as the power of the Crown grows, extensively and intensively — the lawyers aiding it — and with it the internal order and coherence of the realm, the administrative independence, and especially the semi -sovereign powers acquired by some cities, are gradually reduced or abolished as incompatible with the coherent order which is the lawyer's ideal and which is also, so long as it is established by establishing the pre- dominance of the Crown, naturally the aim of the monarch's ambition. This process is going on during a great part of the thirteenth century, though it continues for two centuries more; but it is not till the beginning of the fourteenth century that the representatives of the cities are summoned to form a " third order " in the assembly of the " estates- general," and it is not till the middle of the same century that this third order becomes self-assertive and aggressive. The explanation is, I conceive, that the Crown, though it aimed steadily at stripping the towns of quasi -sovereign powers, was not afraid of them, not in conscious rivalry with them, as it was with feudal nobles and clergy ; and it was an important gain for the Crown, in its general anti-feudal policy, to enter into direct relations with the towns not only in the royal domain, but in the realm at large. ^ Histoire de la Civilisation en France, Lect. xix. 3o8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. In the first meeting of the estates-general in a.d. 1302, the king's object seems to have been primarily to demon- strate that he had the support of his whole kingdom in his contest with the pope. But, as I have said, another very important motive — and on the whole, I think, the most important motive in France as in England, though its importance may not have been recognised at the time — was the desire to get money more easily. The general assembly facilitated the financial arrangements which the king would otherwise have had to make with his vassals individually; he probably expected, as he actually found, that the deputies of the towns would be more easily induced to lend him pecuniary aid, so that their presence along with the feudal nobles would render the whole process of getting money less difficult. But this expedient, however attractive, could not be tried without a certain danger to monarchy ; the danger that the greater opportunity of combination thus given to the representatives would lead them to assume governmental power, and interfere in legis- lation and administration, whenever the monarchy was weak. And this in fact took place in France in a.d. 1357, in the dark hour of disaster after the battle of Poitiers ; when it is to be noted that the movement of reform, or one may say of revolution, is made by the citizens chiefly, led by the representatives of the merchants of Paris. A similar movement — also led by the urban element — was made in A.D. 1413 when the country was torn by the violence of conflicting factions. But the want of union among the different estates — especially between citizens and nobles — sufficed to prevent these spasmodic attempts at popular control from having permanent effects. One cause of this want of union lay in the exemption of the nobles and clergy from the taille or land tax imposed on the non-nobles. The principle was adopted that " the clergy pay with their prayers, the nobility with their swords, and the people with their money " — at any rate so far as the normal burdens of taxation were concerned. The privileged classes being thus in the main XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 309 detached from interest in the financial question discussed with the estates -general, the hourgeoisie were in the long run too weak to struggle singlehanded with the monarchy. The turning-point of this struggle — considering the funda- mental importance of finance — came in a.d. 1439 when the estates consented, or were successfully understood to consent to the taille perydtuelle. The principle that the consent of the estates was necessary to legitimate taxation was not indeed expressly given up ; indeed, it is asserted half a century later in a.d. 1484, and more regular assemblies every two years are demanded. The Crown promises what is asked — and calls no more assemblies but collects the taxes as before ! It would take too long to follow the history of the various assemblies of estates-general, and estates-provincial, in France. They constitute an important and influential organ for the expression of popular wishes, from which the government when wise obtains valuable advice and suggestion. But one may say generally that the want of union among the different classes represented is the main cause that pre- vents the composite assembly from obtaining an important and permanent share of governmental power. This fateful disunion between nobles and commoners was strikingly manifested at the meeting of estates-general in a.d. 1614, when the nobles make formal complaint to the king that an orator of the third estate has compared the three orders — nobles, clergy, and commons — to three brothers of the same family. The third estate only claimed to be a younger brother ; but the nobles would not admit even that degree of fraternity. When the three estates next met in a.d. 1789 — a century and three-quarters later — the youngest brother, as sometimes happens in families, had grown to be the strongest, and he made his strength felt. A similar cause produced similar effects in Spain, where the representation of cities in the national assemblies had been introduced as early as the twelfth century, and where — both in Aragon and in Castile — the control of these assemblies over the Crown appeared for a long time much 310 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. more firmly established and regular than in France, and seemed up to the fifteenth century, to have more prospect of developing into regular, constitutional government. But here too the strength of the monarchy lay in the absence of union among its competitors for power, and the willing- ness of these competitors to accept privileges at the expense of their fellows. Thus the force of the representation of the towns of Castile was weakened by the bold diminution in its numbers which the Crown effected in the fourteenth century, when the number of cities returning deputies was re- duced to eighteen ; at which number it remained with slight variations — the privileged cities resisting any attempt to increase it. Here too the nobility claim that their personal military service exempts them from taxation ; and it is the division thus established between nobles and citizens that makes the transition to absolutism so easy in the sixteenth century. The Parliaments of the Scandinavian kingdoms had a more solid popular structure — including representatives of peasants as well as of nobles and cities ; indeed, Sweden furnishes an instance of effective parliamentary power even in the eighteenth century. Still, we may observe that the cou'p d'etat wliich turns the government of Denmark into a pure monarchy in A.D. 1660 turns on the same separation of financial interest; the burghers are irritated by the refusal of the nobles to be taxed when they reside on their estates, and their irritation, skilfully fanned by the king, pro- duces a popular revolution that has as its result absolute monarchy. § 4. If, then, we ask why in England alone among the larger states of "Western Europe the medieval assemblies of estates have led by a continuous process to modern parlia- mentary government, the main answer, I think, must be that the cause which produced failure elsewhere — the want of union among different sections and classes — was far less operative in England. I do not say that the England of the fifteenth century is free from provincial jealousies or class jealousies, but they have far less effect here than else- XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 311 wliere. Of this I think there were two chief causes : the insularity of England and the strong government of the Norman kings. I incline to believe that insularity, with its marked boundaries, rendered unity of national sentiment easier from its direct effect on the imagination, people outside the island being palpably foreigners. Hence the remark- ably complete-^ — and under the circumstances rapid — fusion between the Norman conquerors and the conquered English. If we may trust the Dialogus de Seaccario, it was practi- cally complete in one and a half centuries. Another perhaps more important effect of insularity lay in the comparatively peaceful conditions it secured, through the long absence of serious fear of invasion. From this cause " militancy," as Mr. Herbert Spencer would say, was less preponderant than on the Continent. There had always been in England, to an important extent, land held on non-military tenure, "free socage," side by side with land held on military tenure ; and through the comparatively peaceful conditions due to insularity, the more peaceful element of the landed proprietary tended to absorb the other. The Crown had to defend its possessions on the Continent, but the duty of serving beyond sea in these wars gradually came to be felt as a burden — knights were glad to escape it by " scutage." But when this transformation of the burden into a pecuniary one has been effected, the pecuniary obligations of knighthood are felt to be oppressive, and we find in the thirteenth century that it has to be imposed compulsorily. Thus the distinction between the military and the non -military element among the smaller landed proprietors naturally tends to be effaced ; and the union of the rural gentry and the city -merchants into a strong and spirited body of " commons " becomes easier. The other important cause of the greater internal cohesion of English society is the predominance and vigour of the monarchy founded by William the Conqueror. Feudalism in a sense was introduced by William, but the main political effects of feudalism — the disintegration of 312 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. governmental power — were carefully excluded. His strong hand and skilful policy prevented the followers with whom he divided the spoil from attaining anything like the independence of French and German feudatories. Thus we saw ^ that in England the principle was maintained, at any rate in theory and form, that direct allegiance to the king was due not only from his immediate vassals, but from the vassals of those vassals. And in liberally dis- tributing the plunder of English land, William took care to give it in a scattered form, so that, as far as possible, no powerful noble should have too great a preponderance in any one region. Except in the counties palatine of Chester and Durham, charged with military defence against the Welsh and Scotch, the administrative system prevented large power from being placed in the hands of any great nobles. Again, effective control over the local administration of justice is maintained in England from the twelfth century by itinerant justices ; and this royal justice by subordinating local customs increases the homogeneity of the people, which, it must be remembered, had been great in pre-Norman times compared to the Continent. From Henry II. on- ward, with inconsiderable exceptions, England has only one common law. And further, when representative in- stitutions begin, there is nothing in England corresponding to "provincial estates," only one parliament. Again, the cohesion of classes in England was aided by the peculiar English view of nobility as a quality which did not descend to younger sons. This seems to be partly due to the fact that the House of Lords ^ — the " great council 1 Lecture xiv. p. 206. 2 Under the influence of feudalism, introduced by William, the IS'ational Council — of which the democratic element had vanished long before the Norman Conquest — was almost insensibly changed from the assembl}'- of the wise men into the king's court of feudal vassals (Stubbs, Select Charters, p. 15) and practically of the greater barons, though all military tenants-in- chief had a constitutional right to attend. Thus, so far as parliamentary development is continuous, it is the House of Lords that represents the old National Council. XXI MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 313 of the realm " — is in use as a normal element of our strong centralised Norman government, in a degree unparalleled in continental states. The Norman king is not afraid of opposition to his measures from his council of lords ; what he does fear is local resistance to them ; and that the assent of the council tends to prevent. Hence the distinction between barons individually summoned to the council and those not summoned becomes more marked in England than elsewhere, and those not summoned blend with the smaller vassals of the Crown ultimately into gentry. Thus we have a strong monarchy, a relatively feeble nobility, and a homogeneous and united people. Hence the nobility, when driven to resist the tyranny of the Crown, is naturally led to strengthen itself by alliance with other classes that feel this oppression.^ And the union is facilitated by the fact that the development of cities in England shows no such struggles between citizens and feudal nobles as we often meet with in continental history. It is to be borne in mind that England was preponderantly an agricultural and pastoral country in this age — but such large towns as there were, mostly depending directly from the king, had not in their history any such memories of long, bitter, violent quarrels with the nobility such as elsewhere tended to pre- vent union. And the vigorous centralised administration, subjecting, as it did, the inhabitants of the smaller towns to the county authorities for various purposes, accustomed the rural and urban elements to common action. Thus the exceptional vigour of the monarchy in the century and a half after the Norman Conquest, co-operating with other causes to produce an exceptional capacity for combination among the elements of English society, is a main cause of the exceptional strength of the Parliament that becomes a regular part of the government at the beginning ^ Thus it was the barons who extorted Magna Carta from Jolin in a.d. 1215. But the barons lean on the people, and Magna Carta is not framed in the interests of an oligarchy in a bad sense. It aims at securing freedom from arbitrary taxation, at least for all free landholders, and from arbitrary imprisonment and punishment for all freemen 314 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of the fourteenth century. Here, as elsewhere, the oppor- tunity of Parliament lies in the financial need of the Crown; but through the firmer cohesion of the representative ele- ments in Parliament ^ the opportunity is used here with more steady resolution than in most other countries ; and before the end of the fourteenth century the weighty prin- ciples are established that new taxation ^ is illegal without the consent of Parliament; that legislation requires the concurrence of the two Houses ; ^ that the Commons may inquire into and claim amendment of the abuses of the administration. It was also established, though less clearly and completely, that the rights and liberties of Englishmen could not be legitimately invaded or altered by any mere command or ordinance of the monarch. These principles strike root deeply in the political con- sciousness of England, so that even when after the Wars of the Eoses the spirit of Parliament temporarily declines and the Crown becomes practically predominant, it does not openly dispute and override the traditional rights of Par- ^ The principle of representation is not to be found in Magna Carta, but, so far as free landholders go, it was gradually introduced, largely, I suppose, with Hallam and Freeman, as a convenient way of obtaining money. It was not indeed for financial reasons that representatives of the cities were first summoned to Parliament by Simon de Montfort in a.d. 1265. Still financial reasons operated to make this regular, and to bring about the first complete representation of three estates in Edward I.'s reign in a.d. 1295 ; soon after which (a.d. 1297) the necessity of the assent of Parliament to the imposition of new taxation is formally acknowledged. At first Parliament has three estates, and knights vote and tax themselves separately from burgesses ; but the clergy cease to attend in the fouiteenth century — preferring to assemble separately in convocation — and knights blend with burgesses. But we may note that in the fifteenth century the electorate becomes less popular — the limitation of "forty-shilling" freeholders in a.d. 1429 disfranchising a con- siderable number. Also in many boroughs the municipal governing body becomes co- optative and usurps the right of electing representatives. This phenomenon is similar to what we have noticed in the more independent city-communities of Germany and Italy. ^ With some doubt as to customs, which becomes very important after- wards, till finally settled by the Long Parliament. ^ At first the usage is that new laws are made *'at the request of the Commons and with the assent of the Lords " ; then gradually the petitions assume the form of complete statutes under the name of bills, it being found that the Crown did not always really grant what was petitioned. XX r MEDIEVAL REPRESENTATIVE INSTITUTIONS 315 liament. The Tudor monarchs have their way, and in certain directions encroach seriously on the traditional rights of Englishmen: but they have their way usually through the complaisance of Parliament, not by violating its constitutional rights. LECTUEE XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY § 1. Earlier in the course/ in comparing broadly the de- velopment of the country -state of Western Europe with that of the city-state of ancient Greece, I drew attention to one strongly- marked difference of this later evolution, when we view it in its strictly political aspect, concentrat- ing our attention on government and its form. This is the permanence of monarchy. Hereditary monarchy lives on through the stages of development, in which, never- theless, we can trace analogies to the different forms of government which succeed one another in the development of the city-state. It lives on through the stage that corre- sponds to that of the early oligarchies — the oligarchies of old families, in the city-states. Even in that period of the Middle Ages in which the "turbulent nobles," as the historians call them, obscure the splendour and reduce the power of the monarchy ; in which we hear of dukes and counts or earls vying in power with the monarchs to whom they pay nominal obedience; they never succeed in destroying, hardly ever desire to destroy the institution of hereditary monarchy. And monarchy lives still, in most European countries, in the democratic period through which we are now passing; when in almost every civilised country at least a large share of legislative power is in the hands of representatives of the people, and in most such countries they have acquired an important amount of control over the administration of current affairs. And thus — as I pointed out — the period of approximately absolute mon- ^ Lecture xiii. p. 188. 316 LECT. XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 317 archy which intervenes between the two, and which is predominant in most important European countries in the latter part of the seventeenth and till near the close of the eighteenth century, this period — though it has perhaps a certain analogy to the earlier age of the tyrants in Greek history — is not a period of irregular and lawless reversion to the rule of one, but of the predominance, gradual or sudden, of one element over others in the old established government. As I said, the main cause of this phenomenon is, in my view, the greater need in a country-state of the unity and concentration of power given by life-long headship, owing to the greater difficulty of maintaining national unity and political order in a people dispersed over so large a space. We see from the history of France and Germany that increase of the power of the leading nobles against the king may tend ultimately, not so much to the formation of a concentrated oligarchical constitution, as to the breaking up of the state into parts ; and to the lawless oppression and disorderly feuds of individual nobles, as contrasted with the organised and quasi-legal oppression of class by class which the early oligarchy in Greece and Eome shows us. Hence so far as a national consciousness is developed in the country, it sustains the monarchy as a necessary bulwark against this disruption, and as civilisation grows, the in- creasing number of persons who wish to live in peaceful legal relations with their neighbours demand the aid of the king, and are prepared to render him their support, against lawlessness and disorder. But though this is the main cause, we also had to take into account the influence of ideas derived from the Eoman Empire, transmitted in various ways — at first through the habits of obedience of the people conquered, then through the dignity and prestige of the ancient title when revived by Charles the Great A.D. 800, then through the influence of the Church — though, as we have seen, this is of a chequered kind ; finally, through the influence of the lawyers. Through the influence of these causes combined, mon- 3i8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. archy holds its own through the various shocks and vicissi- tudes which it encounters during the long process of the Middle Ages and the period of religious strife that followed, and by the beginning of the eighteenth century has ulti- mately prevailed on the whole, though not everywhere. In the ancient oligarchy of Venice, in the modern con- federacies of Holland and Switzerland the republican form of government is maintained. In England since a.d. 1689 the monarchy has to govern face to face with a parliament — representing, in the main, a broad-bottomed oligarchy — whose supremacy in legislation and finance it had finally admitted ; and it only maintains its effective control of administration by the method which polite people call in- fluence, and rude people corruption by places and pensions. In Sweden in the north, after a brief period of practically absolute monarchy, from a.d. 1693-1718, the extravagant strain which had been put on the resources of the nation by the martial adventures of Charles XII. had caused a reaction towards the control of an assembly, which, as in England, was predominantly oligarchical, and which lasted more than fifty years (a.d. 1720-1773); while in the east the Polish nobility had secured their practical independence at once of monarchy and of order, and offered to the con- temporary observer an interesting example of the worst kind of oligarchy known to history. Still, these were all exceptions. Elsewhere in Eomance and Germanic nations alike, in France, Spain, Portugal, the two Sicilies, in Denmark including Norway, in Austria and most of the smaller states in Germany and North Italy into which the Holy Eoman Empire had practically resolved itself, the monarchical form of government is victorious. Accordingly, if in the middle of the eighteenth century an impartial continental observer had retraced briefly the course of European history from the point of view from which I have tried to sketch it in these lectures, he would probably have regarded monarchy of the type called absolute^ ^ I have allowed myself to use this term for brevity though as we shall see it requires qualification (see pp. 336-339). XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 319 as the final form of government to which the long process of formation of orderly country-states had led up ; and by which the task of establishing and maintaining a civilised political order had been, on the whole, successfully accom- plished, after other modes of political construction had failed to realise it. Then just when this monarchy seems most completely established, in the very country where it has been most splendid and triumphant — in France — there begins a move- ment of thought and opinion which gradually generates a passionate demand for liberty, equality and popular government, which first powerfully co-operates in the formation and determination of the destinies of the great federal republic in North America ; then, gaining strength with this success, overthrows the monarchy in France; then further — in spite of the disillusionment caused by the sanguinary disasters that attend this overthrow, and the subsequent lapse into the military despotism of Napoleon, in spite of the reaction in other countries, supported by strong patriotic sentiment, against this aggressive Napoleonic des- potism and its revolutionary antecedents — the movement towards popular government revives, grows, and to a great extent attains its end all over the countries sharing West European civilisation. So that now, after the interval of a century and a half, absolute monarchy, instead of being the normal form of government in a civilised country-state, is commonly regarded as suited only for semi-civilised Eussia, and unworthy of the advanced communities of Western Europe. In this and the following lectures I propose to consider these two movements towards so-called absolute monarchy, and from this to constitutional monarchy or republic. From one point of view — which is the ordinary one — they seem diametrically opposed to each other ; the one, speaking broadly, from liberty to despotism, and the other from despotism to liberty. But this is only from one point of view ; from another point of view they are only two stages in a continuous process tending in one direction, namely, to the 320 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. realisation of the modern conception of political society as contrasted with the medieval conception. For a complete and duly balanced view of the whole process it is necessary to consider it from both points of view. § 2. But here, perhaps, I may instructively digress to answer a simple question suggested by what I have just said — to which, however, it is not easy to give a simple answer. I have spoken of medieval and modern conceptions of political society ; but where, it may be asked, does modern history begin ? It is difficult to answer the question decisively, because the process of change from medieval to modern ideas and facts is gradual and continuous ; and there is a great difference of opinion as to where this date should be fixed. For example, Bluntschli^ fixes it as late as a.d. 1740. From the Eeformation to about 1740, he says, we see in Europe generally the old age and decay of medievalism rather than the youthful characteristics of a modern era ; and it is not till about 1740 that we feel that a new time is coming. And I think there is some truth in this, and that it is only towards the middle of the eighteenth century that the West European monarch completes his change from an overgrown feudal lord to a modern absolute king. For it is noteworthy that, on the one hand, during the feudal and quasi -feudal period, the monarchy, as I have before said, is only half-feudal. On the other hand, relics of the feudal ideas appear to cling to monarchy after it has effectually suppressed feudalism. On the one hand, during the feudal period, the king, while the highest feudal lord, has, at the same time, relations other than feudal to the community as a whole and all its members — relations due to a blending of old German and Eoman imperial ideas — with perhaps a tinge of Asiatic monarchy derived from the Old Testament. On the other hand, when the feudal and quasi-feudal institutions have given way before the growth of the modern State, relics of the feudal confusion between public and private rights still cling round the monarch. He conceives himself to have a sort of ownership of the land ^ Theory of the State, bk. i. chap. v. XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 321 and its inhabitants, and to be something more than an official appointed to promote their well-being. France, for Louis XIV., has become in its entirety the king's domain. When, in a.d. 1710, he has a transient scruple about taxing his subjects, he is reassured by the reflection that he is the real owner of all their property. So again, though states cannot be divided like properties among the children of the ruler, it still seems right that they should be united like properties through marriage. So England gets plagued with Hanover. The idea that a monarch was doing nothing wrong by sending his subjects to fight in quarrels in which they had no interest belongs to the same survival. The change is gradual ; but, speaking broadly, I think we may put it, as Bluntschli puts it, at about the middle of the eighteenth century. It is about then that the leading West European monarchs begin to be generally regarded, and to definitely regard themselves, as public functionaries in whose hands the power of the State is conceived to be concentrated for public ends. Still, I cannot regard this change in ideas and sentiments as so important as Bluntschli regards it; it does not alter the distribution, nor materially affect the ordinary exercise, of political power. Bluntschli's date, then, seems to me eccentrically late. On the other hand, it is rather common to make modern history begin with the fall of Constantinople in a.d. 1453 ; and no doubt the year that saw the substitution of the Turks, as a first-class European power, for the ancient Eoman Empire of the East, and at the same time, through the emigration of Greeks from Constantinople, saw a powerful impulse given to the revival of learning in Western Europe — this is a specially critical year in more than one way. And in fact the beginning of modern history may be properly put at different dates, according to the different points of view taken. But for the purpose of the present course, the date just mentioned seems to me as much too early as Bluntschli's is too late. Monarchy is at this time still struggling with feudality, still hampered by medieval parliamentary insti- Y 322 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. tutions — assemblies of estates. In France, indeed, it is clearly gaining ground, and before the end of the fifteenth century its predominance is temporarily complete. And we observe a marked emergence of effective monarchs, a marked movement towards the predominance of monarchy, at the end of the fifteenth century, in France, England, and Spain alike. But the process is still incomplete. In France the power of the monarchy is reduced again by the struggle of the Eeformation period — in the civil strife that repeatedly breaks out in the latter part of the sixteenth and first part of the seventeenth century we have not merely Protestantism struggling with Catholicism, but also the nobles struggling with the Crown ; the estates-general too again become transiently important. In England the Tudor rule carefully avoids the appearance of absolutism, preserving the formal control of Parliament over legislation. In Spain, too, the parliamentary traditions are still strong ; and it is by skill rather than force that Ferdinand gets his way. Absolut- ism in Spain is not established till Philip 11. (a.d. ISSe- lSQS) ; and in France, the finally decisive work in establish- ing it has to be done in the seventeenth century by the great Eichelieu, and, after him by Mazarin. The final settlement of monarchy as completely victorious was after the struggles of the Fronde. This would bring it to the middle of the seven- teenth century, and this is the time in which, taking Europe as a whole, the most decisive drift in this direction is felt. Thus it is in a.d. 1660, as I said before, that the most dramatic transition to absolutism that European history affords takes place in Denmark. The king overcomes the nobility by the aid of the burghers and the clergy, who are irritated by the refusal of the nobility to bear their due share of taxation ; and in a.d. 1665 he establishes a fundamental law, giving him and his heirs unlimited sovereignty. In Portugal, again, the final meeting of the Cortes — the medieval representative assembly — is in A.D. 1674. And it is in the third quarter of the same century (a.d. 1650—1675) that the process is going on by which, in the rudiments of what is afterwards to be Prussia — in XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 323 Brandenburg, and Cleve, and Preussen — the " Great Elector " is breaking the power of the assemblies of estates and shaking his kingly power free from their financial control, in spite of stubborn resistance, at least in the case of Preussen. Accordingly, I am disposed, from the point of view of our present study, to answer the disputed question, 'Where modern history begins,' by placing its beginning in the middle of the seventeenth century — treating the period of the Kenaissance, and the period of the Eeformation and the religious strife that followed, as constituting a long transi- tion between medieval and modern thought. By the middle of the seventeenth century the treaty of West- phalia (a.d. 1648) has closed the period of religious wars; and then, or not long after, it is clear that in most West European states, monarchy is predominant over elements in the state that have struggled with it. It is decisively predominant over the successors of the great nobles, who in feudal ages had so often rivalled the monarch in power and dignity. It is also finally predominant over the weakened ecclesiastical power of a divided Christendom — that power which, when Western Christendom was united, had put forward such high-reaching claims ; and which, in the great thirteenth century, seemed so near establishing the throne of the vicar of Christ above those of all secular kings and princes, with authority to depose them at its will. It has, to a great extent, absorbed under its rule the cities which had, in various parts of Western Europe, achieved so high a degree of independence. And finally, it has in most cases become completely predominant over those representative assemblies which checked and balanced its power in the centuries of transition, when the West European states were growing out of the disintegration of feudalism, and growing towards the completer unity and order of the modern state. And thus, through the predominance of monarchy, states are finally constituted all over Western Europe, whose internal coherence, unity, and order contrasts strikingly with the divided authority, doubtful cohesion, and imperfect order that characterise medieval institutions. 324 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. § 3. Let US look more closely at the transition. When we compare the political and social relations of man in the Middle Ages either with those that Graeco-Eoman history shows us, or with those of the period that I distinguish as modern, we find them characterised by a singular combination of legality and illegality. They are characterised by formal legality because every one has rights ; this is the great advance that has been made on the civilisation of the ancient republics, with its large class of slaves, legally their masters' chattels ; from the king on his throne to the serf who turns the clod every medieval class has important rights secured by law and custom. But again, the medieval state is characterised by actual illegality, because no one can be adequately sure of getting his rights. When a dispute arises as to rights — which, from their bewildering variety, complexity, and fluctuation, is a highly probable event, — or when they are openly overridden by high-handed aggression, there is no central supreme power in the State which can determine the dispute with absolute decisiveness, and can bring the organised physical force of the community with irresistible weight to crush any openly recalcitrant indi- vidual or group of individuals. Now, a power of this kind is assumed as essential in the generally accepted theory of the modern state. It is, in- deed, implied in the very definition of a political community commonly received. In all modern discussion as to the best manner of determining the appointment, functions, mutual relations of legislative, executive, and judicial organs of government, it is assumed that, whatever difference there may be between different forms of government, there will be some power somewhere that can finally determine what the law is, can get it decisively applied to the settlement of any particular dispute that may arise, and can effectively enforce it. This assumption is not, indeed, completely realised throughout the whole system of West European states ; but though it is not realised completely, it is so approximately. The element of romantic interest which medieval society derives from the fact that individuals and XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 325 classes must be prepared to fight for their own rights if they wish to enjoy them, is, speaking broadly, absent from modern political society in its ordinary condition. It is from this point of view that the transition to absolute monarchy is, when we now look back upon it, seen to be a stage in the direction in which the constitutional monarchy of the nineteenth century is a further stage. The triumph of monarchy represents the first introduction of approximately complete unity and order, by the effective subordination of all other authority in the state to the authority of the monarch. And the fact that this is so is, as I have said, a main part of the explanation why the change comes about. As the slow process of civilisation goes on, the need of more perfect order is keenly felt, and the completer repression of the anarchical resistance of powerful individuals or groups has consequently more and more the support of public opinion. The sentiment of national unity grows, and with it a sense of the importance of making this unity more complete, with a view not only to internal order, but to strength in struggles with foreign nations. Hence, anything that tends to keep up imperium in imperio within the nation, is viewed with aversion and distrust by this patriotic sentiment, which, consequently, gives power- ful support to the monarch in his conflict with all such anarchical forces and tendencies. These forces are various and changeful, and hence the struggle towards completer order on the basis of monarchy is prolonged, and in most cases has marked fluctuations. Monarchy gains ground under a strong king, mostly by slow degrees, and then seems to lose it again under a weak one, some- times with a sudden collapse. Nor is it always the monarch who wins in the struggle — for example, in the Eomano- Germanic Empire. But though the monarch does not him- self triumph, the monarchical form does, in the main, even in Germany, the princes becoming practically monarchs. The monarch, as we have seen, has to struggle in turn with each of the different elements of the nation : sometimes with nobles, sometimes with towns, sometimes with religious 326 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. bodies ; and in each case the struggle takes varying forms in different ages and countries. Sometimes the powerful nobles represent other families of ancient prestige and large domains rivalling the monarch's. Then, when these are brought under, the struggle sometimes recommences — e.g. in the case of France — with the younger branches of the royal family itself, whom the hereditary monarchs have made rich and powerful. In the earlier feudal times the struggle is usually with powerful individual feudatories, then later, when the tendency to combination has grown, it is with leagues and associations of nobles, or perhaps, as in Germany, leagues of towns. So, again, the conflict with ecclesias- tical organisations takes different forms. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries it is a struggle with the one Church of western Christendom, united under a foreign sovereign in Rome who aims at theocratic supremacy. While in the religious dissensions that fill the period immediately preceding the final predominance of monarchy — say, from Luther's attack on indulgences to the peace of Westphalia — it is the frag- ments into which the Church has broken up that threaten to disorganise the political order of Western Europe, as their lines of division cut across those that separate nations. But amid all these vicissitudes and variations, the preponderance of the general tendencies that are carrying monarchy to victory is all the more strikingly manifested. The winds and the waves of civilisation are in its favour, since the growth of monarchical power is practically bound up with the growth of poKtical order. § 4. And the same fact — that monarchy represents the unity of the nation — gives us, when contemplated on its negative side, the answer to the question why the more perfect order that the modern state requires could not at first be established on the constitutional basis that it has actually attained in the nineteenth century. The answer is broadly, as we have seen, that the classes with which the medieval monarch has to reckon in the latter part of the Middle Ages, and whose consent has somehow to be gained if the work of government is to be carried on, — these XXII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 327 classes appear, even when brought together in assemblies of estates, to be usually incapable of attaining such a full and stable union as might gradually have converted re- presentation of classes into representation of the nation. England is an exception — I have tried to explain why and how — but in most cases the representatives of different classes in the medieval assemblies considered in the preceding lecture remain merely and palpably representatives and defenders of sectional interests, which gives them a double weakness in any struggle with the Crown — the weakness arising from mutual disunion, and the weakness arising from the fact that each group of representatives is or appears to be maintaining the interests of a part against the interests of the whole, the privileges of a section against the common interests of the nation. And, as we have already seen, while it is on the side of finance that their opportunity of gaining a share of governmental power arises, it is also on the side of finance that the separation of interests tends to be strongly marked. But even apart from the weakness we have noted in the assemblies which, as we look back, appear in the later medieval period as actual or probable competitors with the Crown for supreme power, it is easy to see why pure monarchy should supply the first form in which the con- ception of supreme power adequate to the maintenance of order actually embodied itself. We have indeed only to apply to this special case the reason given in my first lecture ^ for the general predominance of monarchy, as com- pared with other forms of government, in civilised societies ; namely that it is so much the simplest and most obviously effective mode of attaining the consistency of resolution and action which belongs to our ideal of govern- ment generally, however constructed. To put it in the scholastic manner of the later medieval thinkers : the " unity " which should be characteristic of an ordered state is most easily attained by placing it under the rule of that which is intrinsically and 'per se one. ^ Lecture i. p. 10. 328 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. And this tendency of thought may, I think, be strik- ingly illustrated if we examine the modern doctrine of sovereignty when it first makes its appearance in the history of European political thought. Jean Bodin or Bodinus is the writer to whom is due the first clear and full enunciation of this doctrine, and when we examine his exposition of it in his great treatise De, Repullicd (a.d. 1576),^ we find that while it is theoretically applicable to aristocracy and democracy no less than to monarchy, yet that Bodin himself is, as Sir F. Pollock says, " prone to identify the theoretical sovereign with the actual king in States where a king exists." ^ He holds indeed (as Austin) that in every independent community governed by law there must be a power from which laws proceed and by which they are maintained — since it is idle and chimerical to assume absolutely immutable and irrevocable laws — whether the power resides in one person or in many ; and that this power, being the source of law, must itself be above the law and therefore not legally limited.^ Theoretically, I say, he finds this unlimited power in all governments worthy of the name ; he holds it to be necessary to the very existence of an independent state; in fact, we have in his book the fundamental general con- ception of the modern state put forward in opposition to the medieval ideas. And in classifying actual govern- ments he theoretically intends to be guided entirely by the facts. But practically, when he comes to apply the doctrine to concrete political facts, he has a strong disposition to identify the theoretical sovereign with the reigning monarch if he can, where the facts at all admit of it. In the case of the German Empire of his time, it would be flying palpably in the face of the facts to do this ; he therefore classes the government of the Empire as an aristocracy. But he has no doubt that in France the king has ^ Bodin's book might be regarded as the first onodern systematic work on political science ; but it is better to take it as transitional. ^ History of the Science of Politics, p. 49. ' I,e. not limited by positive laws ; for it did not enter into Bodin's view to deny that sovereigns were limited by the law of nature. xxir MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 329 the unlimited power he attributes to his theoretical sovereign. And as I shall show in a subsequent lecture, almost the same may be said of Hobbes in the next century. His absolutist doctrine is avowedly neutral as between monarchy, aristocracy, and democracy, but its tendency is palpably monarchical. What his general theory demands is absolute power somewhere ; but he prefers to place it in a king. LECTUKE XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY continued § 1. The correspondent movement of facts and ideas which in the last lecture I tried briefly to characterise gives, I think, the main line of causation that leads gradually and with fluctuations, but decisively on the whole, to the pure monarchy of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. But, as I said, we must also take into account the special influence of Christian theology and also that of Eoman law. I have before observed that in both these cases to some extent, but especially in the case of Eoman juris- prudence, we have the indirect influence of the extinct Eoman Empire. Let us examine each of these, taking first the theological influence, which requires careful treatment, because it is really complex, and different elements of it operate in different ways. It is sometimes said that the doctrine of the " divine right of kings," as preached by the clergy on the side of the monarch in {e.g.) the seventeenth century is a medieval doctrine. And this is partially true, but only partially. This doctrine of orthodox seventeenth- century Christianity is doubtless a survival or bequest from the medieval view of the universe and human society ; but it is a survival of which the political effect is entirely altered by the changed condi- tions of its continued existence. A medieval thinker would no doubt hold that legitimate kings reigned by divine right ; but this proposition would no more determine the limits of their regal powers than the scriptural proposition that " the powers that be are ordained of God " would, in the view of a modern orthodox Christian, determine the dis- 330 LECT. XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 331 tribution of governmental functions in the British con- stitution. According to the medieval view, all power, all lordship was ordered by and derived from God ; the state- ment was not more true of, let us say, the King of France than it was of the great nobles who held fiefs under him by hereditary right which he could not diminish or take away. At the same time, it remains true that the medieval thinkers were led by their theology to a decided preference for monarchy ; the best form of government in their view — as is argued in a treatise on the Eule of Princes, attributed to Thomas Aquinas — is that which most closely resembles the government of the whole universe by one supreme God. As Christianity had grown up under a monarchy, the Church's natural conception of political order was mon- archical. Also its claim to control by consecrating the supreme secular governor is more naturally applicable to monarchy ; it is difficult to conceive the consecration or anointment of a Council or Popular Assembly as an im- pressive ceremonial. The Christian ideal, then, was primarily monarchical ; but it is to be observed that this ideal — at least in its earliest and most strictly medieval form — does not lead the thinker to recognise in theory, in his ideal view of Christendom, the absolutely independent sovereignty of the monarchs of the separate nations into which Western Christendom comes gradually to be definitely organised ; it rather led him to aspire after a monarchical organisation uniting the whole Christian world under one headship. Human society, in its ideal condition as con- ceived by the medieval thinker, would constitute not only a universal Church, but a universal secular community (civitas Dei), the Church monarchically organised under one pope, the secular polity under one emperor, wielding re- spectively the " two swords " of the Gospel narrative, by which spiritual and secular government were symbolised. As regards the manner in which, with this essential dualism of two swords and two governments, ecclesiastical and secular, the essential unity of the Christian polity was to be maintained — on this question there was, as we have 332 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. seen, a fundamental controversy running through the whole period of medieval thought, at least since Hildebrand. According to the ecclesiastical party that supported the claims of Innocent III. and Boniface YIII., the unity was to be attained by simple subordination of the secular sword to the spiritual : the pope was appointed by God as supreme arbiter of questions of morals; all questions of politics were questions of morals ; hence the pope — as Boniface claimed — was " seated by God on the throne of justice above all kings and kingdoms." But these claims (which would, if realised, have converted Western Christendom into a thoroughly theocratic polity, which it never actually became even for a time) were disputed by an important section of the medieval thinkers, who interpreted the superior rank of the spiritual government as meaning only the superior importance of the spiritual welfare of mankind with which it was concerned, and not at all as carrying with it a right to overrule secular governors in their own department; and who accordingly found the ideal unity of Christendom in the Divine Head, represented in the spiritual and secular spheres by pope and secular monarch respectively. Then, when the growing weakness of the Empire rendered the idea of a secular unity under the emperor more and more clearly impossible, ecclesiastical writers on politics did not at once give undivided support to monarchy in the separate nations, because their conflicts with the secular power led them to lay stress on the natural — only remotely divine — origin of the state, as contrasted with the directly divine origin of ecclesiastical rule. Indeed, in the later Middle Ages, from the end of the thirteenth century onward, it is the most accepted doctrine that secular government rests on the consent of the people, who have an original right to choose their own form of government ; so that, though the proposition '' that the ruler is the vicegerent of God," is not formally abandoned, it becomes practically insignificant and ceases to give any support to monarchy. Then afterwards, during the period of religious strife, the XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 333 influence of Christianity is mixed and varying. Both Catholics and Protestants, when under Protestant and Catholic governments respectively, have a strong disposition to favour political doctrines tending to subordinate mon- archy to the control of other powers; but after a.d. 1648, when this period is over and the established divisions of Christendom have put an end for ever to the ecclesiastical efforts after a theocratic organisation under the pope, the preponderant influence both of Eeformed and of Catholic Christianity is again decidedly monarchical. We may say that its natural tendency to support order and especially monarchical order has now free play ; so that the orthodox seventeenth-century interpretation of the text, " the powers that be are ordained of God," is that no Christian may law- fully resist a legitimate monarch.^ On the whole, therefore, the Eeformation and its con- sequences are an important factor on the side of monarchy. Even in the most purely Catholic countries, after the century of strife is over, the rivalry of the Pope with the King for secular sovereignty has gone never to return ; the Church finds its best interest in leaning on monarchy and trusting to it for material support while giving it moral support. And in Anglican and Lutheran countries the subserviency of the Church to the Crown is even more marked. The broad tendency of the disruption of Christendom, caused by the Eeformation, to strengthen the secular power is strikingly illustrated in the case of Spain. Spain, in the period succeeding the Eeformation, stands forth as the ^ It may be observed that the early Reformers, Luther, Melancthon, even Calvin, were led — partly by the return to Scripture and early Christianity, as they understood it, partly by reaction from the Anabaptists, etc. — to lay stress on the obedience due to the powers that be, and to keep aloof from revolutionary schemes of government. Speaking generally, moreover, the movement within the Church against papal power, naturally allied itself with the centuries-old struggle between civil and ecclesiastical power. But this alliance is not permanent or universal : indeed in the later wave of reforma- tion, which connects itself not with Luther but with Calvin, we find claims to supremacy of ecclesiastical over civil power which are very like papal claims : but they lack political force, the Reformers having so strong a need of the aid of the secular power. 334 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. great bulwark of Catholic orthodoxy; it is the country in which Catholicism is at once most irresistibly predominant, and most intensely fanatical. It is the country of Ignatius Loyola ; above all, it is the home of the Inquisition ; and though we cannot find any important movement towards Protestantism, or any other form of heretical or schismatic doctrine in Spain at this time, still the Inquisition managed to consume some 6000 human beings in successive " acts of faith," during the reign of Philip II. Here then, if anywhere, one would think the spiritual power of the Papacy might successfully maintain its claim of superiority over the secular power. But in fact it is quite otherwise ; indeed, it is hardly an exaggeration to say that Philip II. is for practical purposes as autocratic in ecclesiastical matters in Spain as Henry VIII. is in England. He holds the patronage of all the cathedral churches in Spain, chooses archbishops, bishops, and abbots, regulates the details of ecclesiastical discipline, and refuses to admit the pope's bulls and despatches when they contravene his policy. The Inquisition is his instrument not the pope's ; it is he who gives it orders ; he names, dismisses, controls the Inquisitors. Indeed, in spite of his religious fanaticism, we find him using it for purely secular purposes when the instruments of his ordinary administration fail ; for example, when his Custom-house officers cannot stop the exportation of horses into France, he pretends to believe that the horses are intended for Protestant armies, and makes the Inquisition therefore forbid their export. The pope complains, but he has to submit ; his spiritual weapons are ineffective ; the king's fanaticism is intense, but it is limited and qualified by a still intenser belief in himself and his sovereign rights. And similarly in the French monarchy of Louis XIV., the Church — though it retains important privileges, vary- ing in different parts of the country — is effectually sub- ordinated to the Crown, to which it gives loyal support. Its most eminent orators give, like some leading representa- tives of the Anglican clergy in England in the seventeenth XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 335 century, the most unqualified adhesion to monarchical ab- solutism in its extremest form. " The prince, the anointed of the Lord," says Bossuet, " is responsible to no man for the orders he gives " ..." no one can say to him why do you do thus "... kings, " you are gods," that is, the orator adds — for the phrase, he feels, verges on idolatry — "your authority has a divine character, you bear on your fore- heads the mark of divinity." ^ § 2. I now turn to the lawyers. Here the influence of Eoman jurisprudence is more steadily on the same side — in favour of monarchy : this influence first becomes im- portant after the great revival of the study of Eoman juris- prudence — first in the University of Bologna — in the twelfth century. For the later and splendid period of ancient Eoman jurisprudence, from which the books that teach medieval students come down, is of course the Imperial period : it is a fundamental doctrine of the jurists whose wisdom they imbibe that all governmental power is con- centrated in the hands of the monarch. Accordingly, in France in particular, where the feudal disintegration of the nation has gone furthest, the corps of lawyers trained in the study of the Eoman jurists bring to the task of serving the king a professional bias for unlimited monarchy : they are determined to regard the French king as inheriting the powers of the Eoman Emperor. This conviction makes them zealous in combating all conflicting claims: and they thus become the important and indispensable instrument for reducing the independence of the great nobles and making the jurisdiction of the monarch effectively supreme through- out the land. And the influence of Eoman law supplies a part of the explanation of the failure of the medieval essays at parlia- mentary government in Germany. As I said in an earlier lecture,^ the tendency to association and federation — not only of individuals with other individuals of the same class to defend class privileges, but of bodies with bodies — is so 1 Bossuet, Politique tirie de VEcriture, Books ill., iv., v. 2 Lecture xxi. pp. 305, 306. 336 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. striking in the social and political history of Germany from the thirteenth century onward — so much more striking than in England — that I should certainly have expected that it would have been more effective than was actually the case in maintaining representative assemblies in the country-states formed by fragments of the Empire when it becomes clear that the Empire could not be maintained as a coherent whole. There is, no doubt, the general cause of disunion among the classes who had resisting power, and this is specially marked perhaps in the Empire owing to the irrevocable collapse of the Imperial power in the later Middle Ages. They confederated but did not blend. The violence too of the internal dissensions in the period of religious strife — say, with intervals, from Luther's revolt to the end of the Thirty Years' War — is doubtless another cause. The exhausted fragments of the nation had a specially strong desire for the order which monarchy offered. But the " reception " of Eoman law is important — the great influence of Eoman law in Germany, due to the German king being Eoman emperor, is one cause. All this becomes the more noteworthy when we re- member that the ideas of the Eoman jurists as to 'man being by nature free and equal ' gave later on an important contribution to the movement of pre-revolutionary thought which ultimately destroys absolute monarchy in Western Europe. § 3. I have now to point out the qualifications and ex- ceptions which we have to bear in mind, in framing this conception of absolute monarchy as a stage in the develop- ment of West European polity. I begin with the qualifica- tions. In the first place, there remain — to a varying extent in the different countries where the Crown is pre- dominant — survivals of what I may call the abortive medieval Parliaments ; which, though they have ceased to threaten a serious competition for power with the Crown, yet exercise a certain check on it ; or, at the lowest, hamper it a little, and keep alive the idea of the people's consent being necessary to taxation. XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 337 Thus in France, though the estates-general have ceased to be convoked after A.D. 1614, estates-provincial still go on in certain parts — Languedoc, Provence, Burgundy, Brittany, and some smaller portions chiefly situated near the extremities of the kingdom. These estates have nominally the function of voting the taxes for these districts. They never oppose an effective resistance to the Crown, but it sometimes cannot get the supplies it wants without a little management, a little corruption, or a little intimidation. In Spain, again, there are similar survivals, and here there is a marked difference in different portions of the kingdom. The Cortes (Parliament) of Castile have been reduced to impotence under Charles V. : but the Cortes of Aragon — where the royal power, in medieval times, had been more jealously limited than in Castile — still retain substantial checks on the monarch's will till near the end of Philip's reign — and in matters of taxation, till long after. Indeed, the Spanish Crown has difficulties with the pro- vincial Cortes of Aragon even so late as the first years of the eighteenth century : till in a.d. 1707 it takes advantage of the suppression of an insurrection to abolish the special rights and privileges of the province ; and it is not till A.D. 1714 that a similar fate befalls the Catalonian con- stitution, after a resistance on the part of the Catalans of great obstinacy and valour. Similarly in the principalities of various size into which the territory of the Empire has all but broken up in Ger- many, the power of the princes continues to be somewhat hampered — to a varying extent in different places — by the survivals of the provincial assemblies of estates ; though the control exercised by these assemblies is nowhere very effective, and diminishes as time goes on. Their share in legislation was in most cases the first to go — the assembly was reduced to a merely consultative function ; and even where the formal constitutional necessity of the assent of the estates to laws was still recognised, every effort was made to get it regarded as a mere formality. The control over taxation, though vigorously attacked, lingered some- z 338 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. what longer : but even here the estates were commonly more concerned to obtain privileges and exemptions for special classes than to make their control over general taxation effective. But secondly, even when the will of the monarch has come to be theoretically irresistible, the West European monarchy is practically limited, not only by traditional law, custom, religion, etc., but by the resisting force of the human instrument through which it has to work : especially the sense of personal dignity of the nobles, the intellectual habits of the lawyers, the esprit de corps of both. This was pointed out about the middle of the eighteenth century by one of the most influential writers of his age on political theory — Montesquieu — who indeed, to mark the distinction, uses the term monarchy with a meaning expressly distin- guished from despotism. I shall examine the general drift of Montesquieu's speculation, as a factor in pre-revolutionary thought, in a subsequent lecture, but what he says on this point I will give in the language of one of the most judicious of our own eighteenth-century historians — Eobertson ^ — at the close of his view of the state of Europe. He says that when the complete predominance of the monarchy was established two things remained which pre- vented the government of France from degenerating into a mere despotism. First, though the nobles of France had lost political power as a body, they retained their personal privi- leges and pre-eminence of rank. They preserved a conscious- ness of elevation above other classes, and exemption from their burdens: a privilege of assuming ensigns indicative of dignity; a right to be treated with a certain degree of deference during peace, and a claim to various distinctions when in the field. Many of these pretension^ were not derived from positive laws : but being defined and ascertained by the maxims of honour and supported by the whole force of a strong sentiment of personal dignity, they practically set ^ Robertson's Charles V. : Introductory View of the State of Europe, § iii. [The two paragraphs that follow are mainly in the words of Robertson but abridged. — Ed.] XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 339 limits to the power of the monarch. An intermediate order was thus placed between the monarch and his subjects, with traditional privileges which he had, on the whole, over- whelmingly strong motives for ifwt violating. The other important barrier to royal caprice — peculiar to France — was the jurisdiction of the Parhments, especially the Parlement of Paris to which the supreme administration of justice was committed. The kings of France, when they first began to assume the legislative power, produced their edicts and ordinances in the Parle- ment of Paris, where they were registered : and this customary function of registration gave the Parlement an opportunity of protesting against an ordinance it dis- approved : which it on occasion effectively used.^ In both these cases the king could overbear the resist- ance by a vigorous exercise of will : but the esprit de corps of both nobles and lawyers was so strong that it gave him considerable trouble to overbear it. § 4. In the greater part of the study in which we have been engaged in this course of lectures, we have been con- cerned at each stage with the comparison of the leading political characteristics of a group of independent or nearly independent communities, subject to somewhat similar con- ditions of life and sharing a common civilisation — Greek city-states, medieval city-communities, medieval and modern country -states — and we have endeavoured to see clearly the general resemblances among the forms of government, and the relations of the government to the governed, in the different members of the group of states, the changes that take place in them and their causes. But it has been my aim, in all such comparisons, to notice differences as ^ The Parlement — originally a national assembly exercising, as ours, judicial among other functions — was specialised to judicial functions by Philip the Fair in a.d. 1302, and lawyers became prominent in it (in the fourteenth century it had 88 lawyers and 12 peers). The great L'H6pital in 1566 (under Charles IX.) introduced serious conditions of age and capacity. Membership, handed down often and always held for life, gave practical independence, and the Parlement became a body in which strong esprit de corps was maintained for good and for evil. 340 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. well as resemblances ; and when I have spoken of a " prevalent " type of government, to be careful to limit and qualify the statement by bringing into clear view the particular instances in which the prevalent type did not prevail. These negative instances are generally of the highest importance in examining the causes or conditions of the prevalence of the type in the positive instances. Accordingly, in the last lecture, while pointing out how pure monarchy tended to predominate in the West European states in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, I was careful to notice the existence of important exceptions to this general result. Let us now look a little closer at the leading ex- ceptions and their causes. Omitting Venice and the German cities — the relics of medieval republican life — and the temporary lapse of Sweden towards oligarchical control after Charles XII., these are England, the Nether- lands, Switzerland, Poland. First let me note that in three of these four cases, the influence of physical conditions is obvious. How the peculiar conditions of English life that specially favoured medieval parliamentary institutions were largely due to the insularity of England I have already shown. How the Alps exceptionally protected the struggles of the Swiss peasants to free themselves from the oppression of their lords, and how the almost amphibious condition — politically speaking — of important parts of the Netherlands, aided by the force of religious enthusiasm, enabled them, in the century of religious strife that followed the Eeformation, to defy successfully the apparently overwhelming military superiority of Spain — these are all familiar historical ob- servations. To these two republican federations I shall recur in my concluding lecture on Federalism ; here I will only briefly note and explain the difference in their perma- nence. In the case of Switzerland, the federal and republican form of government rendered natural by its physical con- ditions and the origin of its independence, is successfully maintained through the eighteenth century. In the case of what we call Holland the same form of government is also XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 341 explained by the conditions of origin, and is also nominally maintained during this period ; but its success here is im- perfect and chequered, and it tends to lapse into practical monarchy — plainly, I think, from the greater dangers of war, to which the low-lying Netherlands are exposed. It is at the crisis of alarm caused by the invasion from France that in A.D. 1672 William III. is proclaimed stadtholder of Hol- land with unlimited powers : and maintains his predomin- ance till his death in 1702. And a similar alarm in 1747 causes the appointment of a hereditary stadtholder of the seven united provinces. Turning to Poland, where we see the ultimate triumph of the turbulent nobility in the struggle with monarchy, we have an interesting negative example of the value of the industrial element, developed in the cities of other West European states : that is, of its value at once to monarchy in its struggle with the feudal or quasi-feudal nobility, and to social life and political order. For the characteristic of Poland, as compared with the more western states generally, is that the nation has not developed an effective industrial class : the trade in the towns is in the hands of foreigners : accordingly the oligarchy triumphs over monarchy and manifests in a striking way the disintegrative, anarchical tendencies of medieval oligarchy. The " liherum veto" by which from A.D. 1650 onwards a single member of the Polish Diet could refuse assent to the resolutions of the entire assembly, is a characteristic expression and symbol of the place of Poland in the development of European oligarchy. § 5. We have to examine carefully the exceptional course of English political development, not merely as Englishmen, but as students of political science, because it is a very important factor in the general history of West European politics. For when the further step comes to be generally taken from pure monarchy to those nine- teenth-century constitutions in which at least a large share of power is given to representative assemblies elected by a widely extended suffrage, it is the result of the peculiar 342 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. course of development in England which to a great extent gives the model followed in this constitution-making. This is all the more remarkable as the ideas of the constitution- making and the sentiments which powerfully impel towards it radiate from France as a focus rather than from England. The period in England in which we see a tendency towards increase of monarchical power, or at least a struggle of monarchy to maintain its predominance, is about two centuries from the accession of Henry VII. to the Eevolu- tion of A.D. 1688. The characteristics of this period I shall pass over very briefly, as its general features are well known, and the details are of subordinate interest in the general study of the development of West European polity. As we all know, after the Wars of the Eoses, the power of the old baronage appears to have suffered a collapse, and Parliament becomes practically more subservient to the Crown than it has been in the two preceding centuries. At the same time, though the Tudors got their way, it was their policy to leave the legislative supremacy of Parliament formally intact, and they respect the jealousy of its traditional privileges which the Houses of Parliament show. The theory of the constitution is not attacked on their part ; the English answer to Knox's dia- tribe against the " monstrous regiment of women " is that the government of England is a mixed and limited monarchy.^ It is not till the later years of Elizabeth — after foreign danger has passed away — that the Commons begin to reassume something like the independence of spirit in criticism of acts of the Crown which Parliament had shown before the Wars of the Eoses. On the other hand, the theory of an " absolute and paramount power inherent in the very nature of the regal office " ^ was spreading, especially among the lawyers, as it was on the Continent ; and it was supported by the Anglican Church, reviving the doctrine of the divine right of kings harmonised with the Law of Nature as being quasi-paternal. 1 Hallam, Cmistitutional History, vol. i. ch. v. ^ Taswell-Langmead, English Constitutional History, p. 490. XXIII MOVEMENT TO ABSOLUTE MONARCHY 343 Then with the accession of the Stuarts, the conflict finally breaks out between monarchical and parliamentary claims to supremacy and is never really at rest till settled in favour of Parliament by the revolution of 1688. The conflict has two distinct elements — political and religious. The new absolutism struggles with old parliamentary re- straints, and Anglicanism struggles with Puritanism and Catholicism ; Anglicanism being always on the side of the Crown, and practically supporting advances in the absolutist direction until the time of James II. The decisive force in the revolution of 1688 is the alienation of Anglicanism from James ; had it not been for this it is perhaps doubtful if even the unbroken traditions of parliamentary supremacy in legislation and taxation would have prevented monarchy from becoming predominant in England as on the Con- tinent. The personal change from Tudors to Stuarts is in this respect providential. The Tudors aim at having their own way — and generally get it — but are politic enough to avoid alarming opposition by advancing claims opposed to English parliamentary traditions. James I. is a pedant and a doctrin- aire, and therefore inclined to advance claims tending to en- large the royal prerogative in theory more than he means actually to maintain.^ This leads to the definite counter- assertion of privileges by the Commons. The errors of Charles I. and James II. were different ; but probably few kings of equal ability and industry have so little understood the art of governing. Speaking broadly, the victory of Parliament — which does not, as one reads the history, seem at all a certainty — depends on its solid support on precedents of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries. But this alone would not suffice without the religious factor ; and it may be doubted whether things would have gone as they did had the religious factor been absent. To the result attained in A.D. 1688 and the subsequent development of English polity I shall recur later. But 1 See his True Law of Free Monarchits (cf. Hallam, Constitutional History, chap. vi.). 344 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. xxiii first I propose, in the next three lectures, to turn from the development of political facts to the development of political ideas, or rather to direct attention to the development of ideas as among the most important political facts. This is I think a necessary part of the subject of political science so far as it deals with the phenomena of civilised societies : and it is a part which grows in importance as civilisation advances. LECTURE XXIV POLITICAL THOUGHT. HOBBES AND LOCKE § 1. In this and the two succeeding lectures I propose to trace very briefly the movement of modern political thought up to the point at which it takes effect in the French Revolution. I will begin by saying a few words on the general relation of political ideas to political facts. By political ideas I mean primarily ideas of what ought to be in a governed community of human beings, so far as government is concerned. Such ideas may relate to (1) the way in which the organs of government ought to be appointed; (2) the powers which they ought to have; (3) the manner in which those powers ought to be exercised over the governed ; (4) the extent and formation of the groups under separate governments — states and nations; (5) the external or international relations of these groups. These questions are all more or less connected : but some- times attention is directed more to one than another; and, in the line of thought which we are to examine together, attention is chiefly concentrated on the first two questions — the principles on which government ought to be con- stituted, and the extent and justification of its rightful authority over the governed. In saying that political ideas are primarily ideas of government as it ought to be, I do not mean that they are not also ideas of governments as they are and have been. In quiet times the government that ought to be is for most persons the government that exists, though they would like 345 346 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. some details changed. And even in revolutionary times, when there are widespread aspirations after something very different from what actually exists, any political ideal that aims at being practical is likely to be modelled on some- thing that is known to exist — or at any rate is believed to have existed — elsewhere. We can often see this clearly even when that ideal is apparently worked out by an abstract a 'priori method. It is striking how experience controls and limits the imagination even of the most idealistic political philosophers. For instance, Plato's Eepublic is a proverbial term for a Utopian constitution of political society : and certainly Plato's communistic scheme of abolishing private property and private families is such as never has been, and we believe never will be, realised. Yet even Plato is so far limited by the actual facts of Greek society that he can only conceive as a political ideal a town-community organised mainly with a view to war — a free community extending over a continent, to which war is a subordinate consideration, it does not enter into his head to imagine. But again : the development of political ideas is in- fluenced in a different way by their connexion with political facts. The ideas are related to the facts of political history not only as effect to cause, but also as cause to effect. The actual conduct of men, whether governors or governed, is to an important extent influenced by their opinions as to what is right and just ; and thus political theories, while partly determined by pre-existing facts, become in their turn political forces operating among others to modify the facts. And hence to an important extent they come to be shaped and fashioned as instruments for the attainment of this practical end. Now the influence thus exercised by theories on facts is very different in amount in different ages and countries, and it is noteworthy that it is decidedly greater in modern and even in medieval European history than in ancient. So far as we can see, the course of Greek history was in no important respect affected by the speculation of Socrates, XXIV POLITICAL THOUGHT 347 Plato, and Aristotle. Socrates and Plato argued for aristo- cracy on philosophical principles, and their views spread among cultivated men : but none the less the drift of political change at Athens tended steadily to democracy ; and, so far as we know, there was never any slightest chance of realising, or any smallest effort made to realise, the political ideals of Plato and Aristotle. Whereas in the history of Europe from A.D. 800 the influence of ideas on facts has in various ways been very marked. Not to speak of minor and more disputable effects, no one can doubt that the theoretical rights of the medieval Eoman Empire (which was, we may almost say, rather more of a theory than a solid fact during the greater part of its existence) contributed largely, as I have said in a previous lecture,^ to force the history of Germany and Italy into such very different lines of development from that of France or Spain: no one can doubt in modern international law the great influence of the theoretical view of the law of nature upon actually accepted rules of international conduct:^ finally, no one can doubt that abstract doctrines as to the rights of man and the sovereignty of the people have been a decisive force in the great movement which from 1789 onward has been suddenly or gradually transforming modern European polity. Thus the succession of political theories and systems is governed by two distinct kinds of causes — internal and ex- ternal — the separation of whose effects is a rather difficult task, though fundamentally important for the student of the history of Political Philosophy. In the first place, we can always trace in this succession the action of internal laws of development; we find that conceptions and prin- ciples at first vague are made more clear and precise by reflection, and inferences which they by implication contain are more explicitly set forth. In this way whatever in- consistencies lurk in the dominant doctrine are made evident, and its unwarranted assumptions are exposed to 1 Lecture xiii. pp. 196-198. 2 Cf. my ElenneTits of Politics, chap. xv. p. 243, 2nd ed. 348 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. view : so that, by the mere forward movement of the human reason, it tends to be overthrown or limited in favour of some opposing theory, which, at first protected by its own comparative indefiniteness, is forced by its triumph into a similar process of development. We have seen in recent times how, e.g. " Liberty " as an object of aspiration at first means both individuals doing what they like, and the majority having their own way : later the opposition and conflict between the two is seen, and democracy pre- sents itself as possibly " coming slavery." ^ But the actual course of this succession is very different from what it would be if political theories remained merely in the study or the lecture-room : since, so far as political doctrines are useful weapons of conflict, they tend to be taken up when they are required for action and largely moulded by the exigencies of conflict. This is strikingly illustrated by the fate during the Middle Ages of a doctrine with which we shall have a good deal to do — the doctrine that the legitimate source of the authority of secular govern- ment is the consent of the governed. This doctrine, through the greater part of the Middle Ages, enjoyed a kind of acceptance among jurists ; for the authority of the em- perors — the supreme secular authority according to the medieval view of the political order of the Christian world — was stated in the Institutes of Justinian to have been transmitted to them by the Eoman people. So long how- ever as Church and State are in harmony, the doctrine remains of antiquarian interest alone : but when popes and emperors fall out, it occurs to zealous partisans of the Papacy that the people can legitimately take back what it has given, and that an " emperor who has broken his com- pact should be turned off like a thievish swineherd." ^ Thus an exact notion of the 'transference of power' becomes of immediate practical interest. The question is raised, Granting the original right of the people to the power now ^ Cf. Mr. Herbert Spencer in The Man versus the State. 2 Manegold von Lauterbach (born a.d. 1060) ainid Giesebrecht Sitzungsber. der hair. Akad. 1868. XXIV HOBBES 349 possessed by monarchs, can it be resumed by the people when once it has been given away ? If so, how and under what conditions ? However these questions are answered the doctrine gains a logical development : the fundamental conception of the transference of sovereign power becomes more exact and precise. And political thought moves towards the elaborate ' social compact ' theory of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. But the manner in which this notion of the social compact is used by leading thinkers in this later period no less strikingly illustrates the influence of fact on thought. For Hobbes uses it as a basis of absolutism, Locke as a basis of limited constitutional government, Kousseau as a basis of the sovereignty of the people. § 2. Let us begin with Hobbes — as indeed modern political thought may be said to begin with him. The establishment, in the region of fact, of political unity and order on a monarchical basis has for its counterpart, in the region of thought, the doctrine of Hobbes. It is his clear, uncompromising enunciation of the modern doctrine of sovereignty which marks in a decided way the transition to modern thought. His view seems to have first taken shape in A.D. 1640, when our great rebellion was impending but had not yet come : but I shall deal with it in the form it assumed in his most famous treatise, the Leviathan, which appeared in 1651 — midway between the execution of the King in 1649, and the execution of the Parliament in 1653. It is not surprising that at such a crisis a philosopher should have a keen, even an exaggerated sensitiveness to the evils of anarchy : and should lay even exaggerated emphasis on the conditions of order. Hobbes, like B^din,^ lays down that in every political community worthy of the name — in every community that enjoys stable political order — there must be vested somewhere, in some body or individual, a power which, being the source of law, cannot be subject to the restraints * Lecture xxiii. p. 328. 350 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of law. That is, it cannot be subject to the restraints of positive law — what we call the laws of the land, laws of human making : for it is and must be the supreme human law -maker in the land, and cannot be bound by its own laws. It is, indeed, subject to that higher moral code — the Law of Nature or Divine and Supreme Eeason — naturally known to every man as a rational being. ]N'o one in Hobbes's time would have dreamt of denying that every one was in some sense bound by the law of nature, and therefore the sovereign must be so bound. But practically in Hobbes's view this law only binds the sovereign before God : for the law of nature requires an interpreter, and the subjects must accept the sovereign's interpretation: it can- not be allowed that each man is to claim a right to judge the sovereign by his private interpretation of the law of nature, and to resist what he judges to be a violation of it — for then the door would be open to hopeless anarchy. Hence :-^ (1) "The sovereign's actions cannot be justly accused by the subject." (2) " Whatsoever the sovereign doth is unpunishable by the subject." (3) " It belongeth of right " to the sovereign to judge and do " what is necessary for the peace and defence of his subjects " ; (4) and to "judge of what doctrines are fit to be taught them." (5) The sovereign has " the whole power of pre- scribing the rules, whereby every man may know, what goods he may enjoy, and what actions he may do, with- out being molested by any of his follow-subjects " ; (6) and " the right of all judicature and decision of contro- versies " ; (7) " and of rewarding and punishing " as he shall judge best ; (8) " and of making war, and peace, as he shall think best " ; (9) " and of choosing all counsellors and ministers"; (10) and "these rights are indivisible" and inalienable. It is to be noted that particular importance is attached to the " control of doctrine " by which Hobbes especially means religious teaching. Nearly half the book is occupied in defending this feature of a Christian Commonwealth — as ^ Leviathan, chap, xviii. XXIV HOBBES 351 Hobbes designed his to be. Throughout the later Middle Ages — from the end of the eleventh century — the West European states had been liable to feel the difficulty of serving two masters, the ecclesiastical and the civil. But this difficulty was temporarily intensified by the disruption of Christendom, and the violent struggle between Protest- ants and Catholics. When Hobbes's views first took shape (a.d. 1640), there had been about a century of civil strife or danger of civil strife in Western Europe, due to religious dissensions. We can understand how to Hobbes the doctrine that sets up " canons against laws and a ghostly authority against the civil," ^ seems one of the worst diseases of a commonwealth : for which it seems to him the only cure to claim for the civil sovereign an inalienable right to be " judge of opinions and doctrines " and prevent the teaching of any not conducive to peace. Hobbes's political creed may be therefore described as Absolutism : but it is not fundamentally or primarily monarchical absolutism. It is governmental absolutism, the theoretical triumph of the principle of Order over all con- flicting principles of political construction. For observe that in Hobbes's cardinal doctrine, it is only necessary to political order that this indisputable and indivisible supreme power, unlimited by law, should exist in some body or in- dividual : he does not affirm it necessary that it should be vested in a monarch : his condition is equally fulfilled if it be vested in a body of nobles or the people en masse. So that his cardinal doctrine is equally applicable to monarchy, oligarchy, and democracy. He holds that the individual in any ordered community ought to acquiesce equally in any established form of government — except so far as the obliga- tion to obedience is overborne by the still more fundamental law of self-preservation — so long as the government is able to protect him but no longer. This last qualification was very important in A.D. 1651; and I may observe that this un- sentimental absolutism, limiting the subject's loyalty by the monarch's power of protection, was not at all to the taste ■^ Leviathan, chap. xxix. 352 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of ordinary loyal partisans of the temporarily dispossessed monarch of England. At the same time, Hobbes's preference for monarchy in the abstract is plainly avowed ; it is not the only legitimate form of government, but it is the best form ; it has more advantages and fewer drawbacks than any other. Also his conviction is clear that if his doctrine of sovereignty is once admitted by Englishmen, if it is admitted that there is an unlimited sovereign somewhere in the British Constitution, no one can doubt that, by our constitutional tradition, the hereditary monarch is that sovereign. A parliament that the monarch has the undoubted right to dissolve is evidently, he thinks, not sovereign in his sense, only an inconvenient practical check on sovereignty and therefore a danger to order. Probably this expresses the ordinary view of the time, as to the application of the notion of sovereignty. At this period of European history, the doctrine of sovereignty un- limited by law as essential to a state, though unmonarchical in theory and essence, was generally monarchical in effect and application. What the bodies contending with mon- archy actually claimed was not to share sovereignty but to limit it. § 3. But to return to Hobbes's main theory: — How does he prove the necessity that he affirms ? How is the individual to be reduced to this complete subserviency to his sovereign ? Here Hobbes's method of establishing his doctrine is not characteristically modern : he employs notions and assump- tions handed down from earlier ages. He assumes that doctrine of government arising from consent of subjects of which I have spoken — the doctrine that political society is normally instituted by a compact, through which indi- viduals living in a " state of nature " form themselves into a community, and bind themselves to obey a government. He argues that it is the paramount interest of each and all such individuals to combine thus to form a stable commonwealth : because the state of nature, being a state of anarchy, is necessarily a state of universal war and misery. And he XXIV HOBBES 353 argues that only a compact binding each and all to un- questioning obedience to a sovereign with unlimited power can really establish a stable commonwealth : any intro- duction of conditions into the compact must open the door to disputes incapable of decisive settlement, and so to anarchy. Here it is important to observe the distinction between the traditional and the original elements in Hobbes's doctrine. That the condition of political society was preceded by the state of nature was a long accepted view, and also that the mutual rights and duties of government and governed depended on some kind of ancient compact between them. But the accepted view was that in the state of nature individuals were bound by the laws of nature or reason : and that normally — allowing for the imperfection of human nature — they might be expected to obey these laws. Man, it was commonly thought, is a rational and social being, distinguished among other animals by his appetite for tranquil association with his fellows, and his tendency to conform to the guidance of reason. Hence, when in a state of nature — not under human government — he normally recognises that he ought to abstain from aggression on his fellows and observe compacts with them. No doubt — being an imperfect creature — he sometimes breaks his compacts and attacks and quarrels with his neighbours : and then no doubt it is inconvenient for the neighbour that there is no government to restore order and he has to fight for his own rights. The state of nature was no doubt — and is now as exhibited in the mutual relations of modern nations — a state in which war occurs and has to be allowed as legitimate : but still war is an exceptional incident, a casual break in men's normal observance of the simple rules prohibiting mutual injury and commanding observance of compact. This was the received view : but all this Hobbes boldly traversed. Man, he said, is naturally a selfish being : his vaunted social inclinations are really desires for benefit or glory to be obtained from others. No doubt he needs the help of others : but this need, if all fear is removed — e.g.. 2 a 354 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. it' his superiority in power is clear — leads him to seek dominion over them rather than equal society with them. Hence the state of nature must be conceived as a state in which men's conflicting desires and consciousness of practical equality of force lead to continual war. They covet each other's goods and attack each other to get them : for fear of such attack they conquer their neighbours for security : and when there is no other motive they make war for glory. Hence even for a reasonable man who finds himself in this state, the desire for peace and for the observance of rules that conduce to the maintenance of peace, must remain a mere aspiration, so long as a commonwealth is not constituted. We cannot reasonably limit the ' right ' or natural liberty of each in this state to possess himself of anything — even of the person of another : for such appro- priation may be the best means of preserving his life ; and reason forbids him to omit the means by which his life may be best preserved. By rendering unreciprocated obedience to moral rules he would simply make himself a prey to others, and it cannot be his duty to do that. In this condition the life of man — in Hobbes's vigorous English — will doubtless be " solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short " : ^ but still this is his natural condition : though naturally he has a paramount need of peace, he is naturally — i.e. apart from the convention establishing political order — incapable of attaining it : his one chance of peace is to agree to obey a government whose right to command he agrees not to question so long as it secures him the supreme blessing of peace. You see the two parts of the view hang together : it is because the ungoverned state is so miserable that govern- ment must be allowed such unlimited power. If you dis- pute this view of the state of nature, Hobbes's answer is forcible ; it has a painful element of truth if only half truth. I will give it in his own words : " In all places, where men have lived by small families, to rob and spoil one another, has been a trade, and so far from being re- ^ Leviathan^ chap. xiii. XXIV HOBBES 355 puted against the Law of Nature, that the greater spoils they gained, the greater was their honour." ^ But, you may say, it is because they are savages. No, says Hobbes, " as small families did then; so now do cities and kingdoms which are but greater families (for their own security) enlarge their dominions, upon all pretences of danger and fear of in- vasion, or assistance that may be given to invaders, en- deavour as much as they can, to subdue, or weaken their neighbours, by open force, and secret arts, for want of other caution, justly; and are remembered for it in after ages with honour." ^ Look, again he says, at " the manner of life, which men that have formerly lived under a peaceful government, use to degenerate into, in a civil war." ^ If you still doubt, says Hobbes to his contemporaries, consider what opinion of his fellows a man's actions even in a governed society imply — " when taking a journey, he arms himself, and seeks to go well accompanied ; when going to sleep, he locks his doors ; when even in his house he locks his chests ; and this when he knows there be laws, and public officers, armed, to revenge all injuries shall be done him." ^ For such a being then, the only compact which could produce stable political order must be one that established somewhere or other — in king, senate, or popular assembly — a power of command absolute, inalienable, indivisible, unlimited ; or strictly limited only by the individual's right of resisting or evading punishment — his right to self- preservation. The doctrine of Hobbes thus represents in an intensely emphatic and one-sided form the general conviction that, as I have said, accompanied the great transition in Western Europe, consummated in the seventeenth century, to the modern state formed on the basis of monarchical absolutism ; — the conviction that for stable political order, there is required in the state a power somewhere, indivis- ibly and indisputably supreme ; and that this end will be best attained by vesting the power in a hereditary monarch. But, as I have explained, his doctrine is primarily and * Leviathan, chap. xvii. "^ Ibid. chap. xiii. 356 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. fundamentally governmental absolutism, and only secondarily and in its application to contemporary facts monarchical absolutism. And it is to be noted that its important effect on subsequent political thought is rather in its former aspect — the doctrine that sovereignty unlimited by law must reside somewhere in every ordered political community is still a widely accepted element of current political theory. As a support of monarchy in the struggle in England Hobbes's doctrine had not much influence : it was equally alien to the Whig sentiment of liberty and the Tory senti- ment of loyalty — as it acknowledged no obligation to a dispossessed monarch — while its uncompromising subordina- tion of Church to State pleased nobody. Still it represents, as I said, in the region of ideas the movement that is carrying the West European polity to the stage of pure monarchy. § 4. But, as we saw, though this period of monarchy which may be roughly called absolute is a normal stage in the development of West European states generally, the course of development of England is different and exceptional : the attempt at monarchical absolutism failed in England. The long conflict between monarchical and parliamentary claims to supremacy suddenly ends in 1688 in a settlement made decisive by the dispossession of the recalcitrant family of Stuart. It is thus finally settled that the English mon- arch's claim to the obedience of Englishmen is strictly subordinate to the rule of law only modifiable by Parliament ; applied by judges only removable by Parliament ; and that the taxation of the people required for governmental expendi- ture can only be determined by the representatives of the people. The general political theory which justified this moment- ous conclusion of the long struggle is found in Locke's Treatise on Civil Government While studying his doctrine it is important to remember that he writes for a people whom a continuous tradition of four centuries has led to regard the co-operation and consent of a Parliament of two houses — a single Parliament for the realm of England — as XXIV LOCKE 357 necessary to the making of laws which Englishmen are bound to obey, and the raising of taxes which Englishmen are bound to pay. And they habitually regard this as a privilege of Eoglishmen, being familiarly acquainted with the different state of things in France. Locke, like Hobbes, starts with the traditional and generally accepted view that the legitimate claim of any government to the obedience of the governed must be normally based on a fundamental compact, by which the members of a political society have, to obtain the advan- tages of government, resigned a portion of the rights which originally belonged to them as independent human beings.-^ But Locke's conception of the terms of the compact is fundamentally different from that of Hobbes. According to Locke, the compact by which individuals form a society, and agree to be bound by the decision of the majority of a society, is entered into for certain definite ends : and when the majority of the society so formed establishes a govern- ment, it must be supposed only to entrust power to this government for the attainment of these ends : and if this trust is violated the duty of obedience to government ceases. This essentially different view of the fundamental com- pact and its results is connected with a view, very different from that of Hobbes, as to the condition in which men naturally are previous to their entrance into a political society. And here we have to observe that Locke's view of this state of nature — though it differs in some important respects from the view which was traditional and ordinarily accepted in this age of thought — is still much nearer to the traditional view^ than the dark picture painted by Hobbes. As I have said, the traditional view was that apart from political society, human beings, distinguished as they are from other animals by the gift of reason, had been bound — and would always be bound — to obey the law of nature, which every man can know by the sincere exercise of the ^ I say, traditional view, cf. e.g. Hooker, Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity , Book I. chap, x. 358 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. reason God has given him. This conception of a law of nature, universally applicable to men as men, of higher origin and higher validity than the mutable positive laws of particular human societies, had been handed down from medieval to modern thought. The medieval thinkers had derived it from Eoman jurisprudence,^ at first chiefly through the channel of ecclesiastical tradition, afterwards through the direct study of Cicero and the great Eoman jurists of the ancient Empire : but in the age after the Eeformation, in the collapse of the real though imperfect regulative in- fluence exercised over Western Europe by the Catholic Church before the Eeformation, the great need felt of some universally acceptable principles of right, independent of ecclesiastical authority, had brought the conception of the law of nature — and with it that of a state of nature prior to political society — into greater prominence. The most important rules of this law so far as it related to adults were negative : summed up in the great rule of abstaining from all personal injury to others, and all interference with their use of the goods of the earth originally common to all. But, as derivative from the duty of abstaining from injury, was the duty of making reparation for injury that had been committed : there was also the important positive duty of fulfilling compacts freely entered into. We must not forget the rights of parents over children — politically important, because, as may be seen from Locke's contro- versial arguments, certain partisans of absolute monarchy made in the seventeenth century a desperate attempt to find a basis for it in the accepted view of the law of nature, by regarding it as developed out of the natural authority of parents over their children. In short, the rules of the Law of Nature were the rules which, according to the old individualistic view of the State, it was the primary duty of the State to enforce. But in the state of nature individuals had to defend their own rights and exact reparation for their own wrongs : therefore, private war, to obtain such reparation, had to be admitted 1 Cf. ante Lecture xii. pp. 181-183. v: VN/VH*RQ Of XXIV LOCKE 359 to be an inevitable incident of the state of nature — though not, as Hobbes paradoxically afi&rmed, its normal condition. This, then, being the now accepted view of the law and state of nature, how was the authority of government to be based on principles of natural right so conceived ? The accepted answer was that there were two such ways : it might be derived from an original consent of the people governed, or it might be based on conquest in a legitimate war. For it seemed that combatants repelling a violent aggression must have a natural right to kill the aggressors : and it seemed that if they must be allowed a right to kill, they must be allowed to inflict the milder penalty of servi- tude. § 5. So far Locke accepts the traditional view of the origin of legitimate government : but at this point he introduces an important change. For you will observe that the doctrine, as I have so far stated it, might be used to justify the most unlimited despotism : if only it was admitted — as was generally held — that every man has a natural right to deliver himself over into slavery. For thus the slavery of a people may result from an originally free consent, or as a deserved penalty for wrongful aggression. And in fact Grotius, in his epoch-making work on International Bight in War and Peace, which appeared in a.d. 1625, does argue that a perpetual despotism may be legitimately estab- lished in either of these ways : — perpetual, since, as he says, " the slavery of a people is naturally perpetual, because the succession of parts does not prevent it from continuing one people." ^ Here Locke's view is widely different. According to him no man has the right to consent to be a slave : for a man has no absolute power over his own life — suicide is not allowed by the law of nature — and therefore " cannot, ^ Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, Book ir. chap. v. § 32. Speaking broadly, the task of modern thought as regards Natural Eight was to apply- to public law ideas and principles which the Roman jurists applied to private. The epoch - makingness of Grotius lies mainly in his application of it to international law. The importance of Locke's work is its application to constitutional law. 36o DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. by compact . . . enslave himself to any one, nor put himself under the absolute . . . power of another, to take away his life, when he pleases." ^ N'or again can the aggression of ancestors justify the enforcement of servitude on their descendants for all time. Indeed, the state of natural independence is not to be regarded as something existing only in the remote past. It is a state out of which each individual must be conceived to pass by his own consent expressly or tacitly given, before government has rights over him : only every one who owns property in a country — and even a temporary resident while he resides and so makes use of its land — must be understood to have consented to obey the government of a country so long as he so owns or uses. And in conceiving the compact by which the govern- ment of a country was originally formed — as we have no direct evidence what it was — we must assume it to be such as men living in natural freedom and independence would reasonably combine to make : and if so, the government that results cannot have an arbitrary and unlimited power. For it cannot be supposed that men would give up their natural freedom and their natural right to punish aggression, except for the end of securing a better preservation of their lives, liberties and estates than they can provide for them- selves. The power of government, in short, is naturally and reasonably limited by the end for which it is instituted : and this end is to remedy the drawbacks of the state of nature. These drawbacks are three. In Locke's words : " First, there wants an established, settled, known law, received and allowed by common consent to be the standard of right and wrong, and the common measure to decide all controversies between them : for though the law of nature be plain and intelligible to all rational creatures ; yet men being biassed by their interest, as well as ignorant for want of study of it, are not apt to allow of it as a law binding to them in the application of it to their particular cases. " Secondly, in the state of nature there wants a known ^ Locke, Treatise on Civil Government^ Book ir. chap. iv. § 23. XXIV LOCKE 361 and indifferent judge, with authority to determine all differ- ences according to the established law : for every one in that state being both judge and executioner of the law of nature, men being partial to themselves, passion and revenge is very apt to carry them too far, and with too much heat in their own cases; as well as negligence, and unconcernedness, make them too remiss in other men's. " Thirdly, in the state of nature there often wants power to back and support the sentence when right, and to give it due execution. They who by any injustice offended, will seldom fail, when they are able, by force to make good their injustice ; such resistance many times makes the punish- ment dangerous, and frequently destructive, to those who attempt it." ^ In short, the state of nature is wanting in these three respects — clear definition of the law ; impartial applica- tion ; completely effective enforcement. These drawbacks make the state of nature certainly unsafe and uneasy — though not the condition of mere perpetual war and misery that Hobbes held it to be — and hence it is reasonable for men to submit to the limitation of their natural rights which government entails, if government will provide a remedy for these drawbacks. But it would be unreason- able for them to submit except on this condition. Hence the power of government must be understood to be limited by the condition that it is to be used in the execution of established known laws, applied by impartial judges : and the further condition that it is not to take the property of the governed without their consent given personally or by deputy. For — and this is an important and original point in Locke — the individual's right of property is not de rived from government or from any compact with other men. It is derived from the natural right of any individual to material things with which he has mixed his labour — provided that his appropriation of them leaves " enough, and as good ... in common for others." ^ The goods of the earth ^ Locke, op. cit. Book 11. chap. ix. §§ 124-126. 2 Op. cit. Book II. chap. v. § 27. 'i i4> 362 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. in the state of nature are by natural right common : but a man's labour in the same state is manifestly his own : and when he has invested the latter in any portion of the former, it becomes by right his own — provided the oppor- Jj^itijpq ^^ nf.l-iPra arft .nniTigpi^irprl^ TJllS right, thCuT"" independent of and prior to the compact from which government springs : accordingly, it cannot be supposed that any reasonable man would give the government he agrees to establisli a right to take his property without his consent. If government does not fulfil these conditions, if it has recourse ^^^^j^^^^^^ oc\(^ro\ pj-t — nn tai (\ a the due enforcement of law — a r^d t^ taxation ) ; ;9 w hich consent has not been given, then it violates the ends for which govern- ment was instituted, and the governed have a right to regard the compact as dissolved. On the other hand, the governed, though they had an original right to choose any form of government they liked, have not a right to change it when once chosen, so long as jit fulfils the conditions of its trust. But when any govern- Iment comes to an end — either naturally, as when a royal I family dies out, or through violation of trust — then the 1 supreme legislative power reverts to the people, to keep or I bestow at its free choice. The people may thus be said to I have inalienably and perpetually a latent sovereignty, but J only latent. One more condition has to be named. The supreme government originally appointed by the people has no right to transfer its power to others. No such transfer has any validity. Now the supreme organ of government is necessarily the organ that makes the laws, not the organ that carries them out : i.e. the legislature — in England the king and the two chambers — , not the executive — the king without the chambers : if, therefore, the legislature is changed from that originally appointed — changed either with its own consent or otherwise — the duty of obedience to it ceases. And the legislature is changed, says Locke,, when a prince who is only one part of the legislature, subverts or suspends the laws laid down by the legislature XXIV LOCKE 363 and requires his own arbitrary commands to be obeyed instead. Also, the legislature is in effect changed when the prince hinders it from assembling in due time or from acting freely : or if by his arbitrary power he alters the electors or ways of election without the consent and contrary to the common interest of the people : or finally, if he delivers the people into subjection to a foreign power. A prince who does these things alters the constitution which his people has agreed to obey : and thereby loses his claim to their obedience. And this, the Whigs claimed, was what James II. had done or sought to do. LECTURE XXV POLITICAL THOUGHT : LOCKE TO MONTESQUIEU § 1. In my last lecture I gave a brief sketch of the views of Hobbes and Locke : Hobbes representing in the region of ideas the movement which is carrying Western Europe from the divided authority and imperfect political order and coherence of the Middle Ages, to the modern state formed on a monarchical basis ; Locke's doctrine corresponding to the exceptional course of events which established con- stitutional instead of absolute monarchy in England ; Hobbes writing at the crisis of the Great Rebellion and supplying a theory of legitimate government which would do equally well for Charles or Cromwell, but would re- pudiate any division of powers ; Locke's book appearing immediately after the Great Revolution of 1688, and giving the theory on which it was defended/ Let us observe the notions common to the two. Both start with the conception of a state of nature, in which adult men are jurally independent, no one having a right to govern any other — whatever he may do by the exercise of force. Both agree in regarding an " original compact " of such originally independent persons as the normal method of establishing a legitimate government. I may add that both recognise also conquest as a source of governmental rights, though Hobbes holds that here too there is a compact between victor and vanquished, while Locke holds that only conquest ^ It gives, of course, rather the doctrine on which the revolution was justi- fied by constitutional theorists than the view with which it was made. 364 LECT. XXV HOBBES AND LOCKE 365 in a just war can establish rightful dominion, and that only over the persons who took part in the war. You will note that the question in all this discussion is a jural one. It is not the question how government came to be, but how it came to be legitimate. Of this compact seemed the normal explanation. Now it might seem that if the rights of government depend on an ancient compact, the problem of determining them is one for the historian. But neither Hobbes nor Locke actually use a historical method, except subordinately for confirmation of their conclusions. Hobbes indeed repudiates it in principle,^ and though Locke is hardly prepared to go so far he does so practically, for he determines what the com- pact must be supposed to have been by considering the ends which reasonable beings in a state of nature must be supposed to have had in view in entering into a compact. Both again apply their opposed doctrines of unlimited and limited powers of government respectively to all forms of government. Hobbes's absolute sovereign may be one, few, or the whole people acting corporately: though he has a prefer- ence for monarchy. Similarly Locke's theory admits all forms of government, if only their exercise of power conforms to his conditions ; the original compact may constitute democracy, oligarchy, monarchy, or any mixed form ; to whichever form may have been selected, obedience will be due so long as it is faithful to its trust and no longer. But as Hobbes has a preference for monarchy, so Locke, on the other hand, regards as preferable a government in which the legislative power is separated from the executive, and is put wholly or mainly into the hands of " divers persons " who make laws as a body which they have afterwards to obey as indi- viduals. It is preferable, because it avoids the temptation to human frailty which is given, when the same persons who have the power of making laws, " have also in their hands the power to execute them, whereby they may exempt them- selves from obedience to the laws they make, and suit the 1 Cf. Leviathan, end of chap. xx. 366 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. law, both in its making, and execution, to their own private advantage." ^ And when this separation is effected, the legislature is naturally and necessarily supreme over the executive : since the organ that carries out the laws must neces- sarily be subordinate to the organ that makes them. It is true that where, as in England, the supreme head of the executive is also a part of the legislature, and so has no legislative superior, there is an admissible sense in which he may be called supreme or sovereign — as in fact he is traditionally called. But it remains true that he is only a part of the really supreme or sovereign portion of the government: and the oaths of allegiance and fealty taken to him are taken to him not as supreme legislator, but as supreme executor of the law made by him jointly with others.^ This is how Locke meets Hobbes's argument that the hereditary monarch has for so many centuries been alone called sovereign in England. The answer is, Where the legislature is distinct from the executive, the legislature must be supreme: and for centuries the monarch in England has only been a part of the legislature. Hence, it was argued, when the monarch subverts or suspends the laws as laid down by Parliament, or alters the election or ways of election to the House of Commons " without the consent, and contrary to the common interest of the people," or hinders Parliament "from assembling in its due time, or from acting freely " : he in effect changes the established legislature. So again, when as head of the executive he sets up his arbitrary will against the laws he is appointed to carry out, or when he " employs the force treasure and ofi&ces of the Society to corrupt the representa- tives and gain them to his purposes," he acts contrary to his trust. In either case his right to the obedience of his subjects is forfeited, and they may legitimately set up a new monarch in his place.^ But how does Locke answer Hobbes's strongest argument Locke, oip. cit. chap. xii. § 143. ^ Qp^ q^^^ chap. xiii. ^ Op, cit. chap. xix. XXV LOCKE 367 that if conditions are thus introduced into the fundamental compact on which government is based, anarchy comes in ? Partly he admits it. Anarchy does come in : the right that the governed have to resist a government that violates its trust is not a right that belongs to the state of political order : it is a reversion to the right of resistance to wrong which belongs to the state of nature. This Locke fully admits ; and with fine rhetorical effectiveness he turns the argument against his opponent. Herein lies, he says, the great heinousness of the crime of a government that violates its trust that they bring in the evils of anarchy.-^ But let us not exaggerate the danger : it is not lightly that a people can be got to face the difficulties and dangers and inevitable evils of a revolution; it is only a grave and persistent violation of trust by their established govern- ment which will make them do this. And indeed, he contends, by establishing a general recognition that the power of government is a trust held under conditions and not an arbitrary power, you really diminish rather than increase the danger of rebellion and anarchy : for you diminish the danger of oppression, and history shows that whatever theories thinkers may lay down, oppression will in fact lead to revolution. § 2. When we pass from the seventeenth to the eighteenth century in tracing the development of political thought in modern Europe, the main interest of the student- begins in England, but before the middle of the eighteenth century passes to France. Even, I think, for a Frenchman who is tracing the chief factors in the movement of thought that led up to the great revolution of 1789, Hobbes and Locke are more important than any French writers of the seventeenth century. And even for Englishmen who are studying the history of political ideas with a special interest in the antecedents of modern England — even they, I think, about the middle of the century must temporarily transfer their main attention from England to France. For in English political thought in the latter half of the eighteenth ^ Op. cit. chap. xix. 368 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. century the most interesting elements may be traced to French influence — influence either positive and directly stimulating, or stimulating indirectly by rousing vehement antagonism.^ In the first half of the century the movement of thought in England is rather languid, but for the careful student it has the interest which sometimes attaches to a dull and stagnant period, intervening between two periods of in- tellectual stress and movement : one can trace in it the fading out of old manners of thought and the nascent efforts to get to new points of view. Locke's view of the fundamental social compact as source and limit of governmental right is widely accepted, but to a great extent with mere conventional acceptance and not with vital grasp. So far as thought is exercised on it, the development it undergoes is in the direction of separating the practical question. How are the duties and rights of government here and now to be determined ? from the historical — or prehistoric — inquiry. On what terms did our ancestors originally consent to obey government ? It was more and more felt — and not only by persons of revolu- tionary tendencies — that the former question ought not to be determined by the result of the latter inquiry. Suppose our ancestors did commit the " grave absurdity " of letting themselves be taxed without their consent : is that any reason why we should for all time submit to the intoler- able consequences of their folly ? N'o, answers ie.g^ a most moderate and sober Professor of Moral Philosophy, Francis Hutcheson, who taught in Glasgow from a.d. 1730 to 1746, we are free from the obligation of such an unreasonable com- pact, and " may insist upon a new model of polity." ^ With this qualification, Locke's views are accepted as orthodox Whig doctrine ; but the interest taken in them is not very keen ; while the opposing doctrine of the divine right of kings, against which Locke's argument was primarily ^ As examples of the latter I may just mention the writings of Burke, our greatest writer of this period. '^ Hutcheson, System of Moral Philosophy, Book iii. chap. v. § 4. XXV BOLINGBROKE 369 directed, though it continued to be preached from pulpits, had ceased altogether to have any serious influence in what I may call the week-day world. Thus it is treated as an antiquated absurdity, too childish for refutation, by Boling- broke, who does the chief political thinking for what Mr. Leslie Stephen styles the "Walpole Era." In the history of Political Philosophy Bolingbroke hardly deserves a place, but the history of political thought or ideas is not exactly the same thing, and in the history of English political ideas he cannot be passed over ; since he was not only the . . . guide, philosopher, and friend ^ of the growing parliamentary opposition to Walpole (a.d. 1725-1741); his ideas not only throw valuable light on the contemporary phase of our constitution ; they lived on after his political career was over, and had considerable effect on the course of English politics. We may trace their effect even in the more profound and limpid political reflections of Hume. Thus in the Dissertation on Parties in which his long opposition to Walpole was summed up, he anticipates Hume in drawing attention to the peculiar position of English parliamentary parties under the first two Hanoverian kings. The Whigs, by the very force of their triumph, had become the party of the court : the Tories had no less inevitably gone into opposition to the reigning monarch. Thus each party found itself driven by circumstances into collision with its original principles. Parties in this condition naturally tend to degenerate into factions : and the consequent evils are impressively driven home by Bolingbroke. To his influence perhaps is partly due the deeply unfavourable view of political parties which prevails in the succeeding generation — in spite of the fact that they are the recog- nised instruments of parliamentary government. I do not know any vigorous defence in English literature of the working of parliamentary party combination, until the fine ^ Pope, Essay on Man, Ep. iv. 2 B 370 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. outburst at the end of Burke's Thoughts on the Present Discontents — nearly thirty years after Walpole's fall. What then was Bolingbroke's political ideal ? A rather vague and superficial one, which I only notice because of the special importance of English constitutional history in the political development of Western Europe. He wants, for the protection of liberty, to maintain the "balance of the constitution " ; and, to this end, he wishes to put an end to the corruption that is threatening the independency of Parliament, by forming a real " country party " in which the distinctions of Whig and Tory are to be obliterated. He does not see — what is evident to the more disengaged and penetrating reflection of Hume — that it is in fact corruption, or at least the influence of the Crown over members by places and pensions, which sustains in the eighteenth century the balance between Crown and Commons. Destroy this influence, and the tendency of the new constitution would inevitably be — as subsequent history has shown — to transfer power from the Crown to ministers appointed by Parliament. Bolingbroke will not see this, he expounds his " Idea of a Patriot king," who is to dispense with corruption, and yet to govern as well as reign, to put an end to the mischief of faction and at the same time maintain the balance of the constitution. The idea was essentially unpractical but it had practical effects : as a Quarterly reviewer says, it " contributed in no small degree to bring about that great revolution which transformed the Toryism of Filmer and Kochester into the Toryism of Johnson and Pitt"^ — substituting as the object of loyal devotion, instead of the king claiming obedience in virtue of divine right, a king demanding and winning it through his patriotic superiority to party, and his steady undivided concern for the true interests of the country. Such was doubtless the ideal which George III. formed at the outset of his reign ; and — though any idea of dispensing with corruption must have soon vanished — it was partly by appealing to the strong body of vague ^ Quarterly Review, vol. cli. (for 1881), p. 343. MONTESQUIEU 371 sentiment existing in the nation in support of this ideal that George III. and the younger Pitt crushed the Whigs in 1783. In tracing the influence of Bolingbroke I have been carried beyond the period in which he lived and wrote. The thought of this period, taken as a whole, seems to me characterised, as I have said, by a feeling of languor after conflict and perhaps some little disappointment at the results of the Glorious Eevolution. The end so vehemently sought has been reached : the reign of law is established and monarchy brought decisively within the control of Parlia- ment in legislation and taxation : the " balance " of the constitution seems tolerably secure. But the pride English- men feel in their balanced constitution is somewhat tem- pered by an uneasy conviction that Parliament actually is a nest of oligarchical factions, brought into precarious and unstable concord with the Crown by corruption. Then in 1748 Montesquieu's Esprit des Lois appears: and Englishmen suddenly find their constitution idealised and set on a pedestal for the admiration of cultivated Europe, as one framed for securing liberty more completely than even the democratic republics of ancient fame. And Montesquieu's subtle, thorough, and highly eulogistic analysis of the English constitution not only directed the attention of foreign observers to it, but led Englishmen themselves both to feel greater pride in it and to take a somewhat new view of its characteristics.^ § 3. We may observe as we pass, just before the middle of the century, from English writers to French — as the tide of pre-revolutionary thought begins to rise — the different ^ The statement of this view most familiar to Englishmen is that found in Blackstone (Book i. chap, ii.), the first volume of whose famous com- mentaries was published in 1765. Blackstone was professionally expounding the laws of England and not any political theory : but in order to meet the taste of cultivated readers and attain the very remarkable success which his exposition achieved, it was necessary that his account of legal details should be rounded off in a setting of political theories : and the material of this was very largely taken from Montesquieu — though, after the fashion of the time, it was taken without acknowledgment. 372 DEVELOPMENT OF EURO RE AN POLITY lect. relation of theory to fact as between the English and French revolutions. Neither Hobbes nor Locke was directly an important cause of political effects ; Hobbes's book anticipated but hardly influenced the reaction from the rebellion ; Locke's work justified a revolution that was over. The French writers prepared the way for one that was to come. Open a French history of political ideas : — I can re- commend Janet's Histoire de la Politique as a work of solid value, though not free from serious errors — open Janet and you will find the Esprit des Lois of Montesquieu, which Janet regards as " undoubtedly the greatest work of the eighteenth century," classed with Eousseau's Contrat Social as forming together the literary source and spring of the revolutionary movement. It is true that an English reader of the former work finds now some difficulty in understanding how it could aid a movement of which the ideal aim was to realise a political order based on eternal, immutable, and universally applicable principles of natural right. For the originality and interest of Montesquieu for us lies largely in the fact that he represents the first great systematic introduction of the historical method into modern jurisprudence and politics : and the historical method, we think, is as hostile to the a priori method of Eousseau, and his assumption of universally applicable principles of political construction, as water is to fire. Hence I am not surprised that Maine ^ regards Montesquieu's influence as opposed to and overborne by Eousseau's. I think this is a misleading view, and that Janet's is much truer : but I am not surprised at Maine's mistake, for in fact Montesquieu's fundamental doctrine is that laws and forms of government cannot properly be judged to be good or bad abstractly and universally, but only historically and relatively. He maintained firstly that in judging of the goodness and badness of particular laws and political institutions, they have to be considered in relation to the form of government of the society in which they are established — a law that is expedient and ^ Ancient Law, chap. iv. XXV MONTESQUIEU 373 good for a monarchy or an aristocracy may be bad for a democracy and vice versa. And he maintained secondly that the goodness of forms of government should be con- sidered not abstractly but in relation to the varying nature, habits, circumstances, of the particular portions of the human race in which these different forms have actually been established. The question whether a people should have a democratic government is one, according to Montes- quieu, which we cannot answer without knowing that people, if I may so say, within and without : its morality may be too feeble to maintain the strain of republican institutions ; or its climate may be so hot that it falls inevitably into despotism. These two main theses, on the relativity of laws to government, and of government to conditions internal and external, are enforced and illustrated with a great wealth of learning, much originality and insight, and even more ingenuity and suggestiveness : and it is easy to understand how the book had a brilliant literary success. But how could it be a source of the revolutionary move- ment ? The explanation is that Montesquieu's historical impartiality is limited, and does not exclude very decided preferences for one form of government over another. He is concerned to point out that the three forms of govern- ment which he recognises as fundamentally distinct in their natures and principles — republic, monarchy, and despotism — are suited to different peoples and require respectively different kinds of laws to keep them going : but he does not therefore stand neutral as regards their principles : on the contrary, the principles as he presents them differ as light, twilight, and darkness. The principle of a republic — the spring of action which it requires to keep it going and which, as long as republican government really flourishes, it maintains in effective operation — is Political Virtue, i.e. patriotism and public spirit and the readiness to perform public duty at any sacrifice of private interest. And this virtue, he says, is more characteristic of the democratic 374 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. republic than of the aristocratic : the latter is indeed more perfect the more it approaches to the former.^ Such virtue is not similarly needed in a monarchy — and by monarchy you are to understand the West European monarchy of his time, of which France was the most splendid example — ; it does not need political virtue as a republic does, and this is fortunate, as it certainly does not foster such virtue and therefore would not have it to draw on in any adequate degree if it did require it. The mainspring by which monarchy works is Honour: the sense of honour of privileged classes — especially nobles and heads of the legal profession — occupying an inter- mediate position between the monarch and the mass of his subjects. This sense of honour is, he says, at once a source of strength to monarchy, as producing a more devoted and energetic obedience on the part of these privileged persons, so long as the monarch respects their traditional privileges and rules ; at the same time it is a source of an elastic resistance, if he tries to override them. I call it elastic resistance, because it is a resistance which the monarch's undisputed authority can overbear at any point on which he concentrates his will : but it is in practice an effective check, and, as I said before,^ constitutes in Montesquieu's view a fundamental distinction between West European monarchy and Oriental despotism, where all are equal in slavery and the mainspring by which government works is pure Fear. Well, you see what Montesquieu's historical impartiality comes to ! It is true that he does not recommend demo- cracy as a practical ideal to his fellow-countrymen : his practical aim is rather to save the French monarchy from the dangerous tendency he sees in it to decline into despotism, and he hopes to do this by laying stress on the value to both monarch and people of the sense of honour of the nobles and esfprit de corps of the lawyers, as at * This subordination of the difference between aristocracy and democracy- is peculiar to Montesquieu. 2 Lecture xxiii. pp. 338, 339. MONTESQUIEU 375 once supplying the monarch with better instruments for governmental work than mere slaves can ever be, and imposing an elastic but real check on his arbitrary caprice. But though Montesquieu does not recommend the demo- cratic republic, he employs his stores of historical knowledge and the whole force of his rhetoric to spread a reasoned admiration of it as the form of government that at once requires and fosters patriotism and public spirit. This idea that republics are pre-eminent in — we may almost say have a monopoly of — political virtue, may be called the main historical element of French revolutionary thought : and perhaps it did as much even as the idea of natural liberty and equality, and the idea of the inalienable and indivisible sovereignty of the people, to rouse the fire of revolutionary ardour. § 4. But this is not Montesquieu's only contribution to the "ideas of 1789," nor is it that which has in the long run been of most effect in the constitution-making to which the revolution of 1789 gave the first impulse. In the long run, it is not the democratic republic of the Graeco-Eoman world which has furnished the pattern for modern popular government : but rather that other constitution which Montesquieu singles out for admiration — the English con- stitution as settled by the revolution of 1688. The importance of Montesquieu's account of the British constitution lies in his clear perception — in spite of his admiration for democratic republics — that a democratic constitution is not necessarily the freest, i.e. not necessarily constructed so as to give the maximum of protection to the reasonable liberty of individuals. He knew, indeed, from history, that a democratic majority might be as tyrannical, in the way of unjust coercion of individuals, as any despot could be. On the other hand, he finds that political liberty is, in a unique and remarkable degree, the aim of the complex arrangements of English constitutional monarchy. If we examine it, he says, we shall find that "liberty appears in it as in a mirror." ^ ^ Esprit des Lois, Book xi. chap. v. 376 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. The fundamental principle in Montesquieu's view on which a government adapted for realising liberty must be constructed is that of separation of the fundamental powers of government, and a balanced distribution of them among different organs, differently appointed bodies or individuals, so that by the natural play of the whole organisation, any tendency to oppression on the part of any one organ of government may be checked by another. Thus he follows Locke in advocating the separation of the legislative from the executive power. The legislature should only have the power of making general laws, not of decreeing any particular act of administration, though it may with ad- vantage control by criticism the acts of the executive. The assent of the head of the executive should be required for laws, — to prevent any undue encroachment of the legislature — but he should not be able to make laws. But he lays down further — a point Locke had not noticed — that the judicial power should be also separated from either of the other two : if the judge was also the legislator, it would be difficult to keep him to the single- minded aim of interpreting established law. If the executive and judicial power were in the same hands, the danger of the combined power being used oppressively to private persons would be great. Moreover, Montesquieu holds that the " terrible power " of awarding punishment for crime should be given, as in England, not to a per- manent magistrate, but to juries drawn from time to time from the people at large ; and he lays stress on the security given by the Habeas Corpus Act in England, by which the power of the executive to imprison citizens before trial is severely limited. Legislation and taxation should be entrusted, as in England, to an assembly chosen by the whole body of really independent citizens divided in local divisions ; but this assembly, again, should be checked by a body of nobles, to prevent oppression of the minority of rich and dis- tinguished persons. It is only by such a constitution as this, a carefully XXV MONTESQUIEU 377 balanced system of mutually checking powers, that we can effectively secure political liberty : — secure that is, that " no one can be either constrained to do what he is not legally bound to do, or prevented from doing anything legally permissible." ^ Montesquieu's ideal therefore — his practi- cable ideal — is the British constitution idealised. This principle of the separation of the three fundamental powers of government forms a distinct and important element of the revolutionary programme. Thus in the famous declaration of rights of November 1789, we find it emphatically stated that " every society, in which . . . the separation of powers is not definitely determined, has really no constitution {rC a point de constitution^ And another clause lays stress on the need of strictly limiting by law the power of the executive to arrest and imprison private citizens. These are Montesquieu's ideas : and his ideas as sup- ported by the example of the British constitution — or perhaps we should rather say the arrangements of the British constitution as explained and interpreted by Montesquieu — have on the whole been a factor second to none in importance in the constitution -making of the century that followed the publication of the Esprit des Lois, Still, in the movement of thought finally summed up in the Declaration of Eights that I have quoted, his influence is quite subordinate to Eousseau's. Indeed, if you want to have expressed in the form of summary resolutions the fundamental doctrines of Eousseau's Contrat Social, you have only to read one after another the earlier clauses of this declaration. ^ Esprit des Lois, Book xi. chap. iv. LECTUKE XXVI POLITICAL THOUGHT : THE INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU §1.1 DREW attention in the last lecture to the double point of view from which we have to regard Montesquieu — a double- ness expressed in the striking contrast between the aspects in which he is presented by Janet and Maine respectively. Janet, commencing his chapter on Montesquieu,^ refers to the series of revolutions through which Erance has passed since 1789, and says, "How can we dismiss these memories from our minds, when we turn our thoughts to the books which have been the first source of all these changes {la premiere origine de tous ces monvements), V Esprit des Lois and le Contrat Social ?" Perhaps in this phrase Janet attributes, or may seem to attribute, too much to the influence of political ideas and literature and too little to the influence of political facts in the causation of the French Kevolution and its consequences. But if we confine ourselves to the influence of ideas — the literary source of the revolu- tionary movement — Janet's statement is as true as so brief a statement can be, and certainly expresses the prevalent French opinion. On the other hand, Maine, in the interesting fourth chapter of Ancient Law, expresses an entirely diiBPerent and apparently conflicting opinion. So far from regarding Montesquieu and Eousseau as co-operating to bring about the Eevolution, he regards them as diametrically opposed. After describing the important part played by jurists in ^ Eistoire de la Politique, vol. ii. Book iv. chap. v. 378 LECT. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 379 French history, the '' enormous advantage " gained by the French kings in their struggle with the nobles and the Church by their alliance with the lawyers, and the strong position they occupied as a privileged order, side by side with the feudal aristocracy, distributed over France in great chartered corporations, — he goes on to describe how they came to reconcile their speculative opinions and in- tellectual bias with their professional interests and habits by what I may call an enthusiastic Platonic love for the Law of Nature. France, he says, was actually subject to the " curse of an anomalous and dissonant jurisprudence " — a diversity and confusion of local laws, in spite of the political and social unity of the nation — "beyond every other country in Europe " : and the lawyers had a keen sense " of those perfections of jurisprudence which consist in simplicity and uniformity." But " they believed, or seemed to believe, that the vices which actually invested French law were ineradicable ; and in practice they often resisted the reformation of abuses with an obstinacy which was not shown by many among their less enlightened countrymen. But there was a way to reconcile these contradictions. They became passionate enthusiasts for Natural Law. The Law of Nature overleapt all provincial and municipal boundaries ; it disregarded all distinctions between noble and burgess, between burgess and peasant ; it gave the most exalted place to lucidity, simplicity, and system ; but it committed its devotees to no specific improvement, and did not directly threaten any venerable or lucrative techni- caHty." ^ It is easy to understand how this fervid admiration for the Law of Nature would aid a revolutionary movement, if ever an ardent and wide-reaching demand for political change became strong enough to overbear the interested conservatism of the legal profession ; and Maine goes on to describe how this flame of revolutionary enthusiasm was spread by Kousseau. But he speaks of Montesquieu's ideas as working entirely, though on the whole ineffectively, in ^ Maine, Ancient Law, p. 85 (3rd ed.). 38o DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. the opposite direction. Montesquieu, he says, " proceeded on that Historical Method hefore which the Law of Nature has never maintained its footing for an instant." Why- then did he not stem the revolutionary movement towards the realisation of the birthright of man ? Because, Maine says, his work " was never allowed time " to put forth its influence on thought, " for the counter-hypothesis which it seemed destined to destroy passed suddenly from the forum to the street," launched by Kousseau, " that remarkable man who, without learning, with few virtues, and with no strength of character, has nevertheless stamped himself ineffaceably on history by the force of a vivid imagination, and by the help of a genuine and burning love for his fellow- men, for which much will always have to be forgiven him." -^ In this conflict of authorities, I have no doubt of the truth of the statements on both sides. The influence of the Esprit des Lois certainly aided the revolutionary movement, as Janet says. At the same time there is no doubt that Montesquieu's ideas are, as Maine observes, essentially opposed to the fundamental assumption of Kousseau that there are immutable and universally applicable rules of Natural Eight, in which alone man can find a legitimate basis for government. To turn the Platonic admiration for the Law of Nature as an ideal into a practical ardour for its realisation, and to extend it from the civil relations, with which alone the lawyers were concerned, to political or constitutional re- lations, was in France the work of Eousseau and his school. At the root of the revolutionary Utopias of the age we find the old time-honoured and accepted propositions of the Law of Nature, 'that all men are naturally free,' and 'that all men are naturally equal ' — only held with a quite novel heat of conviction, and used in a quite novel way as premisses to justify the most startling and far-reaching political demoli- tion and reconstruction. § 2. It is a commonplace that the absolute monarchy in 1 Op. cit, pp. 86, 87. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 381 France had prepared the way for revolution ; but it was not only the absoluteness of the monarchy, it was also the manner in which it had grown out of feudalism. The monarchy, intent on its aim of concentrating all power in its own hands, had gone on the principle of bargaining with the other elements in the old feudal society which might have held it in check. Thus, by taking from the nobility their political and all their most important social functions, it had rendered them largely useless incumbrances; and in order to induce them to acquiesce with a good grace in this political extinction it had left them pecuniary privileges to such an extent as to render them an intolerably expensive in- cumbrance. At the same time, in order to prevent them more effectually from ever taking up an attitude of rivalry or antagonism to the Crown, and gaining influence enough to do this, it had completed the severance of the leading nobility from the social functions naturally devolving on large landed proprietors by forming them into a large and splendid court, on which royal favour descended in the substantial form of gilded showers from the treasury, yet still was hardly lavish enough to make up for the expenditure entailed by the splendour. Politically and administratively the system of Louis XIV. was in many respects a success. The splendour of Versailles seemed at once to represent fitly and to enhance the glory that France gained under his rule. The nobility, on the whole, were fully content with the share they took in this splendour ; and the centralised administration secured to the people generally many advantages — some protection from lawless personal oppression, some diffusion of enlightened procedure, etc. But financially it was fatally weak ; and its financial weakness riveted and aggravated crying social inequalities and misery, which were in some respects all the worse because they were old, legal, consecrated by custom and history. Let us examine in detail these two mutually dependent facts — a radically vicious system of governmental finance, and flagrant social inequality and oppression. We have to 382 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. go back to the fatal time when the course of development of feudal into modern France definitely separated itself from the corresponding course of development in England; when Charles VII. was allowed in a.d. 1439 to establish a tailU 'per'pUuelle, without the consent of the estates - general. Under the feudal system, as we have seen, the king, like any other feudal lord, provided his ordinary expenditure out of the revenues of his domains, while extraordinary expenses were provided for by voted contributions in which different classes naturally took their fair share. But from the time that the shameful bargain was concluded under Charles VII. by which the nobles sacrificed constitutional liberty by allowing the power of the purse to be given up — " letting the people be taxed without their consent, provided only the nobles themselves were exempted " ^ — inequality was established which the utmost efforts of enlightened ministers, Sully, Eichelieu, Colbert, were unable permanently to miti- gate. The taille (from which in feudal times the gentry were exempt, as a compensation for their being bound to military service) became the regular royal tax. Tocqueville describes all the evils that come from this taxing of, "not those most able to pay, but those least able to resist." ^ As I have just said, continual efforts were made to mitigate them, but — the government must have money, and when new direct taxes were imposed, which nominally fell equally on all, the vicious practice of con- ciliating the rich and powerful by mitigations was still kept up. The clergy, organised and having assemblies, obtained avowed remissions, and the nobles in their private capacity obtained remissions in a less regular way. Again, the corvee royale — forced labour at a low salary, originally for roads, but gradually extended to other public works — was main- tained, and made worse owing to the necessities of govern- ment ; while from this, too, the noble and his " gens " were exempted. Throughout the generation preceding the Kevolution we 1 Tocqueville, L'Ancien Regime et la Revolution, Book ii. chap, x. p. 169. 2 Op. cit. Book II. chap. x. p. 171. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 383 see the Government trying more and more to act paternally, but unable to do so from want of money and from this vicious system of taxation.-^ Thus we have a Government needy, financially shifty, legally and illegally oppressive; and landed nobility, landed clergy, exempt from taxation legally and illegally. But to oppressive exemptions we must add oppressive privileges. The peculiarity of the decay of feudalism in France, which rendered it the most appropriate soil for the Eevolution, is that — the general characteristic of feudalism being the blending of government and landed property in an elaborately graduated hierarchy — in Erance in the eighteenth century all share in government had, as I have said, passed from the nobles ; while a whole system of dues and ex- emptions which originally belonged to them qyia adminis- trators, and which could only be justified on this score, remained as sources of profit to individuals who were now no more than " premiers habitants." Of all the special rights of the nobility, "the political part had disappeared; the pecuniary part alone remained and had sometimes been much increased." ^ Thus feudalism, having from a political become a purely civil institution, had become a simple nuisance — especially to peasants who had become proprietors.^ The poor peasant not only saw the rich noble exempt while he was himself burdened with taxation, forced to labour, forced to military service ; he also found himself forced to pay to the same noble in his private capacity a number of oppressive taxes. Had the peasant not been proprietor, he would not have felt many of them. Had he been governed by the seigneur, they would have seemed to him natural incidents of government. As it was, they galled him at ^ See Tocqueville's Ancien EdgtTne, Book 11. chap, x., for other shameless expedients of the Government to obtain money. 2 Op. cit. Book II. chap. i. pp. 60, 62. ^ Peasant proprietors were very numerous. Though the nobles and clergy each owned about one-fifth of the soil of France, the number of proprietors does not seem to have been much increased by the sale of all the estates of the latter and a great part of the former at the Revolution. Cf. Tocqueville, op. cit. Book II. chap. i. p. 58. 384 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. every turn ; while the burden of expenditure imposed on the noble by custom rendered it difficult for him to abandon them. To all this we must add the old feudal right of administering justice — much restricted and decaying, but yet an abuse of real importance, often made a source of pecuniary profit by needy gentry ; and must also note the absenteeism of rich and great proprietors, and the poverty, isolation, and social uselessness of smaller ones, which rendered their rights practically more oppressive than they would otherwise have been. This state of things offered an exceptionally favourable soil for the growth of the sentiment of liberty and equality preached by Kousseau. § 3. There are two main aspects in which the work of Eousseau is commonly regarded by well-informed persons, on each of which it is important to dwell in order to get a full view of the whole of his extraordinary influence. He is regarded (1) as the apostle of Nature, in contrast with the artificiaKty and frivolity of " so-called civilised existence," and (2) as the apostle of the inalienable sovereignty of the people, a doctrine established by giving a new and striking turn to the old doctrine of the social contract. But I think Maine misunderstands the relation between the two aspects. He attributes to Eousseau the belief that a " perfect social order could be evolved from the unassisted considera- tion of the natural state " ; and by the natural state Maine means the original state, previous to the formation of civil society — as no doubt Hobbes and Locke would have meant. He tells us that in Eousseau's view " every transformation of society which would give it a closer resemblance to the world over which the creature of nature reigned, is admirable and worthy to be effected at any apparent cost." "Every law or institution which would misbeseem this imaginary being under these ideal circumstances is to be condemned as having lapsed from an original perfection." ^ N"ow, this view of Eousseau's aims in the Contrat Social is rather widespread ; but though the mistake is — if I may ^ Ancient Law, chap. iv. pp. 88, 89. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 385 use the treacherous word — very " natural," it is very com- plete. It is weak to say that Eousseau does not hold the view that Maine attributes to him : he does not hold any- thing of the kind. Rousseau's work seized hold of the public mind at a time when — according to the almost unanimous agreement of French historical writers — the critical and negative work, of which Voltaire was the leader, was seriously demoral- ising the educated world. It co-operated with and aided the tendency of the political conditions, due to the deliberate policy of the monarchy, to produce a luxurious and frivolous aristocratic society, of which the court was the centre. A wealthy and polite society from which the monarchy had, as we have seen, withdrawn almost all the steadying and ennobling influence exercised by the responsibilities of political power, the performance of serious and important social services to their fellow-men — such a society might yet be partially saved from mere frivolity by strong religious convictions having the support of thoughtful opinion and the prestige of eloquent expositors, as it had in the great days of the seventeenth-century monarchy. But when the hold of Catholic orthodoxy on the minds of most educated persons had been shattered by the unrivalled literary skill of Voltaire ; and the talkers in salons and at dinner-parties talked — to use Berkeley's phrase — " as if atheism was established by law, and religion only tolerated " ; when philosophy, following the new impulse to learn from England, had abandoned Descartes for Locke, and developed Locke's teaching in the direction of materialism and sensa- tionalism in metaphysics, and naked egoism in morals, then the chief intellectual barrier against luxurious frivolity and artificiality was removed. " The feudal aristocracy," says Taine,^ became a " soci^t6 de salon," — absorbed in the life of the salon to an un- paralleled extent, to the subordination of other interests and duties, to the loss not merely of all deep patriotic concern for public affairs, but of all real force and vitality in the 1 Origines de la France contemporaine. L'Ancien Regime. L. 11. ch. i. 2 c 386 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. domestic affections. Intellectual interests, indeed, remain ; the salons follow, with sympathy and applause, the great enterprise of Diderot, d'Alembert, and their colleagues, to instruct mankind ; but the interest in serious topics is only on condition that the serious topics become a means of entertainment, and a source of richness and variety in conversation. So far as they believe in anything, these denizens of the salon believe in progress, progress of the species, progress of the arts and sciences — the spread of what the Germans call "Aufklarung," enlightenment in all directions. But the sole business of good society is to talk about this progress in the intervals of fetes. Ion mots, and badinage, and to employ the superfluous wealth of the nation in talking about it amid the utmost artificiality of costly grace and splendour. It was such a society as this that Eousseau startled, and to a remarkable extent passionately moved, by his preaching of the superiority of the natural life of man to the artificial product of civilisation. The first work that brought him into notice was a prize- essay, which not only won the prize of the Academy at Dijon, but the applause of the metropolis. The question was whether the restoration {i.e. after the Middle Ages) of the sciences and arts has contributed to purify or corrupt manners. But Eousseau — inspired in a manner which, as he describes it, is almost ecstatic with the great theme of the superiority of Nature to Art — looks beyond restoration to the original establishment of sciences and arts, and maintains that rude, natural man, with his happy ignorance, trans- parent manners, and simple virtues, has lost far more than he has gained from the suspicion and treacheries, the arrogance and vanity, the pompous impostures, the useless speculations which the pursuit of knowledge has brought with it, and the vain luxury that has attended progress in the arts. And the thesis was maintained, in various forms and manners, through a series of treatises, in which we ought not to attempt to find complete consistency of view, but in which there certainly appears a unity of tone and sentiment. xxvr INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 387 It is not within the limits of my present task to go further into this side of Eousseau's work ; but, briefly, he is certainly an admirer of the " noble savage " as he existed prior to political society ; and it is natural to suppose that his object in the Contrat Social is to imitate this state of nature as far as possible, and that he thinks this may be perfectly done by the social contract. But, as I say, it is a complete mistake. The mistake is due to the fact that the old profound and inveterate fusion in the word " natural " of the idea of " what originally was " and of " what ought to be " has — to an important extent — disappeared from Eousseau's political ideas, while it still remains in his language. Eousseau's practical aim, in political construction, is to have a constitution in which justice is realised, and he considers that justice can only be realised in a constitution based on the principles of what he still, with others, calls !N'atural Eight {droit Tiaturel), i.e. the principle of which, as Maine says, the dignity and claims were admitted with unqualified eulogy by the pre-revolutionary jurists, not in France only, but in continental Europe generally. But, in the jurist's conception of Natural Jja^w {droit naturel), the prominent and important content of the notion had always been — not the application of the rules, so-called, to a supposed original condition of man, prior to the formation of political societies, but — the universality of their appli- cation to man as man, as contrasted with the restricted application of the laws of any particular political society to the members of that society. And with this, as we have seen, was joined a conception of the permanence and im- mutability of Natural Law, applicable to man as a rational being, and discoverable by abstract reason, as compared with the mutable character of the laws of any particular state. That political and social order should be in harmony with Natural Eight was a common-place; and that by Natural Eight was meant certain external and immutable principles, even Montesquieu had not expressly disputed. This conception of Natural Eight Eousseau maintained : it 388 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. is fundamental in his political reasoning. So far, Maine is doubtless not misleading. The mistake is to suppose that Rousseau regards droit naturel as realised in the original state of man — the state of savage nature which in his Discourse on Inequality ^ he begins by describing : what he calls the " veritable state of nature." On this point Eousseau's language is quite ex- plicit and unmistakable. Original man, in the veritable state of nature, does not live hj jus naturae, droit naturel, because he has no notion of jus or droit at all, — " not the least notion," says Eousseau, " of mine and thine, no true idea of justice ... no vices or virtues . . . unless we use these terms in the sense of qualities conducive to his own conservation." This is almost like Hobbes : but Rousseau considers that Hobbes errs in attributing to original man passions leading to conflict which would not really be found in him in the state of nature. Rousseau's man is a more isolated and self -sufficient being, " without need of his fellows or desire to harm them " ; and hence though he " reasonably attributes to himself a right to all things of which he has need," the danger to other men from this predominance of the impulse to self-preservation was at its minimum — besides which each one's self-love is moderated by pity, which in this primitive condition " takes the place of laws, manners, and virtue." The original state of nature, then, though it is, if not perhaps the happiest, at any rate the freest from inequality, is certainly not a state in which jus naturae is realised. And though in the later state — on the whole the happiest — that Rousseau afterwards describes, in which a certain amount of sociability has begun, he supposes a sort of pro- perty in dwellings — huts of branches and clay — he is careful to represent the respect for this property as due less to a sense of the right of property than a sense of the inex- pediency of trying to appropriate one's neighbour's hut. He tells us that as — in this new situation — domestic affec- tions, arts of manufacture, and especially social life with ^ Discourss^ir VOrigine de V InigaliU parmi Us Homines, XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 389 song and dance, developed, the desire of consideration led to a sense of injury. But the "first rules of justice" do not come in till property is recognised, and property does not come in till the fatal arts of metallurgy and agriculture have produced the great revolution which destroyed this second, happiest state, when families were domestic and social, but independent. It is evident, therefore, that in desiring to construct a political order founded on droit naturel, Eousseau has no notion of even imitating, much less perfectly realising, the vdritable 4tat de nature. That has gone for ever. Natural man had the advantage of independence : in the true state of nature (unlike Hobbes') he has at once no need of others, and no inclination to hurt them : but Eousseau is as far as any man from the wish to transform society in a way which would make it resemble as closely as possible this original condition of independence. This man has lost : his best substitute for it is complete dependence on a general will, of which his own will is merely an element. Indeed, Eousseau is so far from thinking that — to use Maine's words — a "perfect social order could be evolved from the unassisted consideration of the natural state," that he expressly says that no social order can be perfect, just because it is not natural. " Everything that is not in nature has its inconveniences, and civil society more than all else (phisque tout le reste)!' ^ Indeed, I may almost say — paradoxical as it will sound — that Eousseau resembles Hobbes more than any other writer, certainly comes next to Hobbes, in the extent of the difference that he conceives between natural and social man : and hence the resemblance which we find between the social contracts of Eousseau and Hobbes, in spite of the great con- trast between them. With Eousseau as with Hobbes the natural man in his primitive condition was absolutely in- dependent of others : the difference is that with Eousseau he was not at war with others : he had no need of their aid, but neither had he any need of hurting them. But this 1 Du Contrat Social, Book iii. chap. xv. 390 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. independence, he holds, ceased in the very early stages of the process of civilisation ; and " from the moment that one man had need of the help of another, as soon as it was perceived to be profitable for one man to have provisions for two," ^ the equality and happiness of the early state was lost, and mankind went rapidly down into a state of war resembling Hobbes'. But from this there is no restoring them to their original independence, according to Eousseau : to save man from slavery, our only resource lies in a con- tract which places him in complete dependence on others, — complete, though mutual and equal. The individual, in Eousseau's political system, surrenders his own will to the will of the body of which he becomes a member, as com- pletely and unconditionally as he does in Hobbes' system, save in the one point of the revocability of the contract. The natural man is in idea at least annihilated, to live again as the civic man or citizen, the member or part of a corporate whole. § 4. The movement of thought which culminates in the revolutionary doctrine is, as we have seen, merely the last stage of a process which carries us back beyond the begin- ning of modern history. It is an attempt to determine the structure and powers of government on principles of abstract justice ; and the source of these principles is distinctly to be traced back to the " Law of Nature " as conceived and applied by Koman lawyers under the influence of later Greek philosophy. This process of development I will now briefly sum up. The characteristic of the revolutionary doctrine is that it rests on two or three very simple prin- ciples : (1) that men are by nature free and equal; (2) that the rights of government must be based on some com- pact freely entered into by these equal and independent individuals ; (3) that the only compact at once just to the individuals and sufficient for social union is one in which each individual becomes an indivisible part of a body that retains an inalienable right of determining its own internal constitution and legislation — a sovereign people. These are ^ Discours sur VOriginc de l''In4galiU. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 39i the three main points of Eousseau's charter of liberation issued to mankind. And we may briefly give the historical origin of the three thus : (1) belongs to the Law of Nature of the Koman jurists ; by them only conceived as an ideal code for civil relations. It was left for later medieval and modern thought to apply it to constitutional and inter- national relations. (2) is an inference connected with this Law of Nature, conceived as the only law subsisting in a state of nature, prior to political society : and is generally accepted at the outset of modern thought. But the com- pact is very variously conceived : it may be interpreted in favour of order and despotism, as by Hobbes, or in favour of liberty and constitutional government, as by Locke. (3) is Eousseau's ; arrived at by an original combination of the lines of thought of Hobbes and Locke. Kousseau agrees with Locke that the fundamental social compact ought to have for its end and object the better preservation of the person and goods of every individual who enters into it. But whereas Locke holds that this necessarily imposes limits on governmental authority, and especially makes it illegitimate for government to tax the governed without their consent, — Eousseau holds that the only compact which can produce this effect is one which involves, as completely as that of Hobbes, the total surrender of the individual with all his rights to the com- munity, and the complete submission of his will to the governing will that results from the social union. But whereas Hobbes takes the view that this governing will is simply the will of whatever government — whether of one, few, or all — the contracting individuals agree to obey, Eousseau maintains that it must be the will of the whole, the truly general will. The Whole formed by the social union is essentially and permanently and inalienably sove- reign. The different powers of government commonly re- cognised — legislative, executive, etc. — are not properly, he says, parts of sovereignty, but emanations from it : and the sovereign must retain always and inalienably the supreme legislative power. The different so-called forms of govern- 392 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. ment — monarchy, oligarchy, etc. — cannot legitimately be more than forms of executive government ; their business must be to carry out the sovereign people's will. If any one idea, any one principle, can be said to be in itself the intellectual source of the great Ke volution of 1789, it is this principle of the perpetual and inalienable sovereignty of the people. The conditions of the social union being the same for all, no one has any interest in making them onerous for others : hence Rousseau, unlike Locke, places no limit on the absolute power of the whole over its members — except the one very important restriction that the general will must be expressed in general laws that affect all citizens alike. There is no limitation of its legislative competence by pre-existing individual rights : the surrender of the in- dividual to the community is unlimited and complete : but it is conditional on an equal mutual surrender by all others : therefore the will of the sovereign whole must be a truly general will.-^ § 5. It is interesting to contrast this view — that the one thing needful to secure just government is to secure that laws are made by the general will of the whole people, of which all individuals are equal parts, and that this general will is always expressed in general laws : — it is in- teresting to compare this with the opposite view of a school whose influence in 1789 was hardly perceptible, but which cannot be passed over in the history of eighteenth-century political ideas, as their subsequent influence was indirectly very great. I mean the Physiocrates or Eeonomistes — the pre- cursors of Adam Smith and the original authors of the system ^ Observe that in this latest form of the doctrine of a social compact, all ques- tions as to the historical fact of a compact have become irrelevant. The com- pact is transmuted into an ideal conception : it states the relations that ought to exist in a justly ordered State — the relations, on the one hand, between the individuals and the community they form ; on the other hand, between the community and its organs of government. It may be noted that if we want a summary comparison of the idde mere of 1688 with the idee mere of 1789, we cannot have it better than in Locke's Civil Government, chap. xiii. § 149, and Rousseau's Contrat Social, Book i. chap. vi. See Appendix, Note G, as to Rousseau's idea of the general will. XXVI INFLUENCE OF ROUSSEAU 393 of natural liberty or laisser /aire. I am not now concerned with their peculiar theories of production and taxation, but merely with their view of the political order required to realise natural liberty and common good. It was curiously opposite to Eousseau's, though still a part of the general movement, in French thought of the age, towards reorganisa- tion of society in harmony with natural equity — the establishment of a social order which should at once realise the natural rights of individuals and obtain the maximum of utility for the community. While the school of Kousseau held that the essential thing was to alter the basis of the struc- ture of government by establishing the sovereignty of the people, in the view of the economists the important point was, not how government ought to be constituted, but what government ought to do. While Kousseau and his followers had no conception of a need of limiting the scope of legisla- tion, the Physiocrates held that the one duty of government was to get out of its head that it had to make laws. What it had to do was to ascertain and protect from encroachment the simple, eternal, and immutable laws of nature ; to protect the natural freedom of each to labour in the way that seemed to him best, so long as he did not injure others, — abolishing all industrial privileges, restraints, and prohibitions ; and to protect the fruits of his labour. This simple task they seem to have thought could best be performed by an absolute monarch; — at least they were willing, for the most part, to leave the absolute monarchy as it was ; in fact, they opposed that separation of powers which Montesquieu admired in the English constitution as tending to complicate and enfeeble the action of government.^ ^ This fundamental difference of method in aiming at, broadly speaking, the same ultimate end — protection of the individual from oppression — is all the more interesting for us, as it still exists in the popular liberalism of the present day. Civil and constitutional freedom — the one, being left alone by the government, and the other, having control over government — are very different things. They coincide practically as regards the majority of the electoral body, since the majority will prevent government from interfering with them disagreeably, but they may not coincide as regards the minority. For example, a man who likes a glass of beer and to go to the theatre on 394 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. xxvi But the drift against absolutism was too stroug for this school to have much permanent direct influence in France before 1789. A great part of what the Physiocrates urged ^ was undeniably useful and needed: the removal of restrictions and restraints on industrial processes, the release from com- pulsory labour, the suppression of monopolies, etc. If introduced with due care, due regard for expectations and habits formed by a long regime of governmental tutelage, and due compensation for legitimate vested interests that had grown up in connexion with this regime, such reforms might have made it possible to restore order to the embarrassed finances of France. But the attempt made by Turgot, the most eminent member of the school, when he was for a brief space (a.d. 1774-1776) controller -general, conspicuously failed in the necessary care and circumspection : his reforms, pressed on with the uncompromising rigidity of a doctrinaire, alienated public opinion, and brought him into conflict with the parlement, which, being the only traditional constitu- tional check on royal authority, had strong support in the growing popular sentiment for freedom. And when Turgot fell, it was evident that the lead of the movement towards organic change had passed from the Physiocrates, and that the tendency under the influence of Eousseau to seek national prosperity by a renovation of the structure of government, instead of a limitation of its functions, would irresistibly dominate the coming revolution. Sundays may feel personally freer under an absolute government where he is allowed these indulgences, than in a country with universal suffrage, where the majority prevents him. ^ Apart from the unhappy impCt unique. LECTUEE XXVII DEVELOPMENT OF ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1688 § 1. England and France took the leading part, in funda- mentally different ways, in bringing about the last great change in West European polity — the establishment of the form of government which we call " constitutional monarchy" ; the form which now prevails all but universally in Europe outside Eussia, France being not essentially an exception though it might at first sight seem so. France, it is true, is a republic, not a monarchy : but the West European con- stitutional monarchy is not, paradoxical as it may seem, essentially monarchical in the ordinary sense : i.e. a per- manent hereditary king is not essential to it. In many cases — I do not say in all — if the functions performed by the hereditary monarch were transferred to a President elected for a term of years, the difference resulting would certainly not be so fundamental as to lead us to regard it as an essentially different form of government. You will observe that it is this general change in West European polity which I wish to characterise and explain, and not the particular striking phenomenon which we call the French Eevolution. I have had to direct special attention to the movement of pre-revolutionary thought in France : but in doing so I have always had in view its effect in causing the general change in Western Europe, and not its effect in causing a particular series of events in France. If I had been trying to explain the particular phenomenon of the French Eevolution, I should have had to bring into view other causes which I have felt justified 395 396 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. in ignoring. For — as Professor Seeley once impressively expounded in a course of lectures delivered here — " the evil which most visibly and indisputably brought on the French Revolution was the bankruptcy of the French Government. It was in despair of dealing alone with the deficit that the banker Necker determined to strengthen himself by summoning the States-General." And if we go further back and inquire into the causes of this bankruptcy, we must not be content to refer to the radically bad system of finance, the inequalities of taxation, of which I spoke in the last lecture. For these inequalities, though they were partly the cause of the bankruptcy, were not the sole cause. The bankruptcy, as Seeley says, was caused by war : and if we inquire further, we may come to the conclusion that it was caused by the ambition of Louis XIV. ; that it was a con- sequence of the European wars kindled by him, and the position in Europe which his policy gave to France, and which debarred it from the policy of non-intervention which could alone have lightened the financial burdens. But this interesting line of thought I leave to the student of French history. What we are now concerned with are the general types of polity tending to prevail at different stages of the political development of Europe, and the causes of transition from one prevalent type to another ; and from this point of view the bankruptcy of France and its causes become of subordinate interest. I have referred to this now, because I am proposing in this lecture to direct special attention to the facts of English history : and my justification for doing this is, that when we are trying to explain the form of government which, by the end of the third quarter of the nineteenth century, had become all but universal in Western Europe, the state of things in England is certainly a more obvious and indisputable element of the explanation than the state of things in France. I do not say that it is a more important element : if I had thought this, I should not have claimed so much of your attention for the development of political ideas in the eighteenth century. I do regard the overflow of the tide XXVII ENGLISH POLITY SINCE l688 397 of revolutionary thought and feeling — of the .movement in favour of Liberty, Equality, and Sovereignty of the People — from France into the neighbouring countries, where, since the splendid times of Louis XIV., the cultivated world had been accustomed to read French literature, and to look to France as the source of new ideas, new culture, new ways of living, — I do regard this as a factor really second to none in importance as a cause of the general transition. At the same time, this French share of the causation is more obscure, and more difficult precisely to measure : the English share is more clear and unquestionable. For, how- ever much these neighbouring lands were influenced by French thought, they have not tried to imitate any of the peculiar constitutions to which the constructive ingenuity of the French mind, together with the rapidly recurring crises of revolutionary change, has given birth, — neither the constitution of 1791, nor the constitution of the year III., nor the constitution of the year VIIL, nor, returning to the Christian era, the constitution of 1848, nor that of 1870, nor that of 1875. What they have imitated has been obviously and palpably the English constitution, just as in France it was imitated in 1814 and 1830. § 2. To the English constitution, then, I now turn. I must begin by observing that its imitators have not always known what it was or how different it was at different stages : they have not thoroughly grasped the process of change that had gone on in it between the Eevolution of 1688 and the constitution-making period of the nine- teenth century. This imperfect apprehension has continued till very recent times, and even now still lingers in some quarters. Indeed, we may say that there are two forms of misapprehension. Sometimes the nineteenth -century con- stitution is too much assimilated to what really existed in the eighteenth ; sometimes mce versa. To illustrate the first, I may direct attention to Blunt- schli's-^ treatment of the subject. In examining this, we must bear in mind that Bluntschli is a man of wide in- ^ Theory of the State, Book vi. cliaps. xiv.-xvi. (English translation). 398 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. formation as a politician, of liberal aims, and though not a penetrating thinker, he is not a loose or careless one. In his book you have an instructive account, from a modern German point of view, of the movement by which con- stitutional monarchy has become the prevalent type in the West European states. According to Bluntschli, certain "results" were arrived at by the Ee volution of 1688. Absolute monarchy was rejected, and limited or constitu- tional monarchy established, based on principles which the Hanoverian kings, he says, found it difficult to understand, but which — " circumstances being too strong for them " — they could not refuse to recognise ; and in our own day the "royal family" in England has become unreservedly constitutional, while the monarchy has " lost neither respect nor power " thereby, — observe, " not lost power." ^ He then describes briefly how a constitution broadly resembling the English has been — in the nineteenth century — established in the Eomance states (omitting France), in Belgium and Holland, and in Scandinavian and Teutonic countries. I say "broadly resembling the English," because everywhere supreme legislative power is in the hands of the monarch, the representative assembly, and a senate or council, while executive power is in the hands of a king and responsible ministers. But this last phrase leads us to the delicate question, how the executive power is divided between the king and his responsible ministers : and it is here that Bluntschli shows the misapprehension of which I am speaking. Eor he proceeds to contrast "true" and "false" ideas of consti- tutional monarchy ; and in this contrast it is clearly English constitutional monarchy — as much as any other — of which he means to give the " true idea." When he says that it is a "false idea of constitutional monarchy" to suppose that the real power has passed from the king to his ministers, he means that it is a false idea of English constitutional monarchy no less than of any other. When he says that the principle of constitutional monarchy is 1 Op. dU pp. 373, 374. XXVII ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1 688 399 inconsistent with the idea " that the monarch is subordinate to the national representatives or to his ministers, and that he may be compelled by them to express a will other than his own " ^ ; that " constitutional monarchy does not transfer the centre of gravity in the government either to the chambers or to the ministers " ^ ; that the constitutional " monarch has a share in legislation which is usually decisive as regards the substance of a law " ^ ; that the " whole government" — i.e. the whole function of governing within the limits laid down by law — is really and not formally " concentrated in the monarch " * ; he apparently believes all this to be true of English as well as continental specimens. He is, indeed, aware of differences in the extent of limita- tions imposed on the royal rights, and he recognises that the English constitution " imposes more limitations upon the royal rights than have been found tolerable by most of the continental monarchies." ^ But he regards this as merely a difference in degree ; he does not regard it as going so far as to render the propositions above quoted inapplicable to England. Now, so far as Bluntschli — and I have taken him as the representative of a school of thought widely extended in Germany — intended these statements to be true of the facts of English polity when he published his book in 1852, and still more in 1875 when he published the fifth edition, I do not think any duly instructed Englishman will doubt that he was wrong. And he certainly did in part so intend them : but partly, in his talk of " true and false " ideas, he mixes up the question of fact with a question of what ought to be, and partly with a merely verbal question. And as both these kinds of confusion are commonly made in dis- cussing topics of this kind, I will spend a minute or two in making them clear. Partly, Bluntschli argues that if the power of the nominal head of the government is reduced to the point to which the " false ideas " would reduce it, this nominal head should not 1 Oi?. cit. p. 405. 2 Q^^ cn^ p^ 4Qg_ 3 Qp^ ^n^ p^ 408. 4 Op. cit. p. 408. 5 Qp^ cit. p. 407. 400 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. be called a monarch. Well, that is a mere question of words : let us call this form of government — as Tennyson — a " crowned republic " ; the name does not matter, the practical question is whether it is a good thing or not. But again, Bluntschli no doubt means to argue that it is not a good thing : that we shall get better government on the whole if the monarch is allowed to have a will of his own and to carry out his own ideas — within the limits laid down by law and imposed by the need of ministerial co-operation. This, again, is a tenable view as to what ought to be, but it should not be mixed up with a view of what actually exists in England or any other country. At the same time, this mixture is very common when we are considering any point in a constitution which depends not solely or strictly on law, but largely on custom and convention, on the general opinion as to what any member of a government ought to do, and the general approval which would be given to sys- tematic resistance if he tried to do anything else. And that is the case with the division of power between the monarch and his ministers. There is, in fact, a wide difference between the English and the German species of constitutional monarchy. But it is not, in the main, a legal difference : in both types alike every governmental act of the monarch requires the co-operation of a responsible minister : while in England no more than in Germany is there any legal requirement that the prime minister should be the recognised leader of a majority of the house of representatives. The difference is, that if the Queen of England were now (1899) to dismiss Lord Salisbury, as the Emperor William dismissed Bismarck, simply because she did not agree with his policy, her act would meet with almost unanimous disapproval, which would take effect in a refusal of supplies by an over- whelming majority of the House of Commons, and so would rapidly and certainly end in the humiliation and sub- mission of the monarch. This would undoubtedly happen in England : and therefore it would seem absurd in England to say that this practical impossibility of dismissing a prime XXV ir ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1 688 401 minister who has the contidence of the majority of the House of Commons is due to a " false idea " of the functions of a constitutional monarch : and if any one did say this, he would be clearly understood to be expressing an opinion as to conventions and expectations that ought to prevail, not that he supposed to be actually prevalent. But if the case were otherwise — as it doubtless was in Germany when Bluntschli wrote — if opinion were divided as to the proper normal extent of the power left by the constitution to the monarch, any expression by a writer of individual opinion as to what ought to be might have an important effect in modifying the general opinion.. There would thus be a strong temptation to say the " true idea " of constitutional government is so and so, in the hope of aiding in establishing it as the prevalent idea. And, as I before said, I think that some English writers on our history after 1688 have been influenced by the same temptation to which Bluntschli has yielded, but have been led by it in an opposite direction. They seem to have vaguely believed, or at least to have been willing that their readers should believe, that the Victorian phase of English polity, — the system by which the monarch regularly and normally accepts as prime minister the leader of the party that has the majority in the House of Commons, allows him the selection of his colleagues, and allows the Cabinet so formed to determine the action of the Crown in most im- portant matters, — that this system dates from the Eevolution of 1688, or at any rate from the disuse of the royal veto which began in William III.'s reign. This I hold to be a complete mistake. Constitutional monarchy, in the sense in which Locke's treatise aims at establishing it, i.e. in the sense of the undisputed supremacy of law only capable of being modified by King, Lords, and Commons, over the so-called sovereign — this was both aimed at and established in 1688. But the transfer of executive power, of governmental power within these limits, from the king to a set of ministers of whom the head is practically chosen by the parliamentary majority — this was not aimed at, and there was scarcely even 2d 402 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lfxt. a germ of it for some time. There is no manifest sjmiptom of a decline in royal power till about the middle of George II.'s reign, and after this the substantial power of the king revived under G-eorge III. § 3. The Victorian polity is only discoverable in germ in the eighteenth century, and has taken its present shape in the main since the first Eeform Bill. The established eighteenth-century view was that the prime minister, and other ministers, were chosen by the monarch. One or other of them had, no doubt, to keep a majority in the House of Commons ; but that was conceived as a part of the busi- ness on which the Crown employed them. The fact that if they could not do this business they had to go, did not present itself as a restriction on royal power, any more than the fact that a general who cannot maintain military discipline would have to go, under the most absolute mon- arch who wanted his armies to win battles. But it may be said, a minister who has to make and keep a majority must be dependent on the House of Com- mons, and must ultimately be practically chosen by it. !N"ot so, for the fact that he was the minister of the Crown helped him a considerable way towards a majority. Here I may observe that if the effect of 1688 is commonly over- rated, the change that took place after 1660 is — as Seeley points out — underrated.^ The method by which the English ^ Cf. Seeley, Introduction to Political Science, p. 253. [On the outside of this lecture Mr. Sidgwick made the note "Borrowed in part from Seeley ; this must be carefully looked to in case of publication." And it will be found by any one who compares, that from this point onwards the lecture is in fact largely taken from Seeley's Introdicction to Political Science (Lectures iii. and iv. of the second series in the volume), though the writers are by no means in complete agreement. Not only are pieces quoted, but in other passages, not exactly quotations, the ideas and phraseology are used. This book of Sir John Seeley's was published posthumously in 1896, and was prepared for publication by Mr. Sidgwick ; and I believe that it was while he was editing it that the present lecture assumed, broadly speaking, the form it now has. To what extent it would have been altered, had he lived to put these lectures into book form, I cannot of course say. It is interesting to observe that these lectures of Sir John Seeley's were not altogether new to Mr. Sidgwick when he edited them. He had read them previously in manuscript, and there are rather full notes on them XXVII ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1688 403 sovereign deals with Parliament in the eighteenth century- dates from the Eestoration or soon after. Influence became an important factor soon after the Eestoration — influence being a term including all the different means of persuasion which the Crown, partly by its prestige, partly by its wealth and patronage, could exert upon individuals."^ For the permanence of Parliament dates from the Eestoration, and, as Seeley says, " When Parlia- ment became permanent, the Crown had this compensa- tion, that Parliament also came within its reach and so became subject to its influence." ^ Thus conflict between monarchical and parliamentary power in the executive government is, we may say, doubly veiled in the eighteenth century. Parliament preserves all the legal forms of a monarchy exercising, within the law, real executive power and having a share in legislation : but in the background it has the power of the purse and of refusing the Mutiny Act. The king knows this, and does not attempt open fight with Parliament. He lets the veto become obsolete : but in the background he too has a for- midable force — influence. The king retired from view and ceased to be an impressive figure in internal politics : but those who lived in the eighteenth century under these historically unimpressive kings always complain of their having too much power. In the middle of George III.'s reign — nearly a hundred years after the Glorious Eevolution — a resolution was proposed in the House of Commons " that the power of the Crown has increased, is increasing, and ought to be diminished." It is only for a compara- tively brief period in the middle of the eighteenth century that it goes under an eclipse. Let us briefly pass in review the monarchs after 1689. William III. no one regards as merely ceremonial. Anne by among his papers, evidently written for discussion with Seeley, and express- ing points of agreement and disagreement ; and it appears that at the same time Seeley was reading the lectures or some of them which have developed into the present book, and doubtless criticising them. The object apparently was to secure, so far as possible, agreement and harmony of treatment. — Ed.] 1 Cf. Seeley, cyp. cit. p. 261. 2 q^^ ^^^^ p^ 261. 404 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. her own will made and unmade ministers ; her will was a main factor in determining important changes of policy.^ When we come to George I. and George II., it certainly seems as if power had passed to Walpole for a long time ; but so under the French kings, even after Louis XIV., the power often seems concentrated in the hands of ministers. In both cases it is essentially because the king's favour is secured to the minister.^ And this is how the matter is regarded by Walpole's contemporaries. For half a century after 1689 there is no indication that the House of Com- mons even desires to use its control over legislation and taxation to force the monarch to appoint the minister selected by it. A minister supported by a majority of the House of Commons, such as Walpole, is powerful no doubt, but there is no idea that he is " powerful against the sove- reign." ^ The sovereign never tries to dismiss him and fails — there is no trial of strength, — but there is no idea that there is anything to prevent his doing so, except his con- viction that Walpole does his business better than any one else could do it, gets him the money he wants, etc. And granting that the Minister has his way to a great extent, — that may happen in a despotism. No doubt when the coalition against Walpole has grown strong he can no longer do the king's business; he has to be dropped; but this does not imply any new constraint on the king's choice. ''Very far back in our history the Parliament has occa- sionally dictated to " the king " what Ministers he shall not consult." * That is a very different thing from taking the choice out of his hands. 1 Cf. Seeley, o^. cit. p. 274. 2 The parallel between Walpole and e.g. Richelieu or Mazarin is, however, incomplete, in that the latter did not derive their power from any source but the Crown, whereas Walpole derived his partly from his capacity of managing the House of Commons. I think the tendency to parliamentary ministers was established when Parliament became permanent, with the power of the purse. If a king is led to choose his first minister for his capacity of managing Parliament, the step is not great to the position in which he will find it necessary to take the minister whom the leaders of the majority want. « Op. cit p. 276. ^ 0^. cit, p. 276. XXVII ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1 68 8 405 Still, causes tending to make the minister independent of the sovereign did no doubt begin to operate when the Hanoverian kings came in : though I think, with Seeley, that the first clear indications of the growth of this system appeared in the last fifteen years of George II.'s reign. In any case' they are due not to the Eevolution, but to " the working of the very peculiar system of party that came in with the House of Hanover." -^ This is, briefly, the system of having the Whigs always in office, which the Hanoverian kings have to accept until, in the course of time, Toryism runs itself clear of Jacobitism. This practically threw the king into the hands of the Whigs : who could, therefore, by hold- ing together, force their choice on him. Thus the Pelhams were forced on him in 1745 : probably not from any deep- laid "intention of carrying the Eevolution further, and re- ducing to a lower point the power of the Crown." ^ Still it did have this effect : and it appears that George II. " was conscious of a paralysis creeping upon the monarchy. When some one praised the English constitution in his hearing, he said it was . . . not a good one for the king." ^ But when we come to George III., there is a revival. In fact, a note in Bluntschli shows that it is the con- stitution in George III.'s reign that he has in view when he extends his " true idea " of constitutional monarchy even to the English constitution : his mistake is in supposing the Victorian constitution to be practically identical with the Georgian. But English writers often seem to fall into the opposite mistake of representing George III. as strug- gling against the polity established by the Eevolution. George III. has no idea of reviving any of the struggle of James II. : he has no idea of suspending, or dispensing from, or in any way violating or evading the obligation of any law, or of disputing or limiting the legislative power of Parliament. What he struggles against is the new usurpa- tion of the Whig party introduced in 1745, facilitated, as I have said, by the fact that, an important part of the old 1 Seeley, op. dt, p. 278. 2 cf. (yp, dt. pp. 278-281. 3 Op. cit. p. 283. 406 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. royalist party being still actively or passively attached to the Stuarts, George II. could not trust a Tory government. With George III. this inevitable subserviency to the Whigs ceases : and he struggles on the whole successfully against the " new usurpation " by which the Pelhams were forced on George II. As Seeley says, " Throughout his reign you find him steadily insisting . . . that the minister shall be his minister " : and " on the whole he is successful. The disturbed period before 1770 ends in the ministry of Lord North, who is emphatically the king's own minister, and who holds office for twelve years ; the second short period of disturbance ends in the ministry of the younger Pitt, also agreeable to the king, which lasts eighteen years ; and after Pitt's death the other side can only hold office about a year." ^ It is sometimes supposed that Pitt, having the support of the country, was really independent of the Crown ; and that in choosing him the king had in fact put himself under a master. I recommend any one who thinks so to read a paper from which an extract is published by Lord Eose- bery — an unimpeachable authority on such a point. It is " an analysis of the House of Commons, dated May 1, 1788, which has been recently discovered among the papers of one of Pitt's private secretaries. In it the * party of the Crown' is estimated at 185 members. * This party in- cludes all those who would probably support His Majesty's Government under any minister not peculiarly unpopular.' ' The independent or unconnected members of the House ' are calculated at 108; Fox's party at 138; and that of Pitt at 52. Even this unflattering computation is further discounted by the remark that ' of this party, were there a new Parliament and Mr. P. no longer to continue minister, not above twenty would be returned.' " ^ Well, through the powerful influence to which this document gives such striking testimony, " the party that had humiliated his predecessor is held by George III. at arm's length. The • 1 Seeley, o/?. cit. p. 283. 2 Lord Rosebery's Pitt, p. 78. XXV II ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1688 407 party of the Pelhams, directed after the retirement of New- castle by Kockingham and after Eockingham's time by Fox, and known in this reign simply as the Whig party, can only at long intervals during this reign force its way into power, The king will tolerate them for a moment if he sees no alternative, but always under protest. They are not his ministers, and it is his fixed opinion that he has the right to appoint ministers at his pleasure. Accordingly he receives them sullenly, watches them narrowly, and struggles, if he cannot appoint the whole Cabinet, at least to have re- presentatives on it, some Thurlow or EUenborough. And then he waits for his opportunity, which commonly arrives in about a year, dismisses them, and once more chooses a ministry for himself." " Tor about half a century George III. was able to keep our system at this point. But under George IV. and William IV. the " dependence of the minister on Parliament " grows again rapidly. Canning forces himself on George IV., and if it cannot exactly be said that Earl Grey forced him- self on William, it is at least true that the share of the king in his appointment, compared to the share of the people, was as one to a hundred." ^ § 4. After the Eeform Bill in 1834 the power of appointing the minister is found to have gone. " William IV., tired of the Eeform Ministry, seized the opportunity of Lord Althorp being called to the upper house to make, as he said, 'a new arrangement,' dismissed his ministers, and sent for Sir Eobert Peel. Then it appeared how our con- stitution had insensibly altered. The problem proposed to Sir Eobert was insoluble. . . . The House did not dispute the king's right to appoint his own minister, they treated that minister with all due respect ; still when he unfolded his policy to the House it failed to obtain the approbation of the majority." ^ It is interesting to note the details of the struggle. There is no suggestion of refusing the supplies : even a ^ Seeley, op. cit. pp. 283-4. 2 6>p. cit. pp. 284-5. 408 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. motion of Hume's to limit them to three months is dropped : nor is there a motion of want of confidence. What would have happened if Peel had taken the line of confining him- self to executive functions and leaving the Houses to legis- late, we cannot say with certainty, but probably he would have been forced to resign. However, he thought it neces- sary to have a policy, that is, to propose legislative measures, to " offer improvements in civil jurisprudence, reform of ecclesiastical law, the settlement of the tithe question in Ireland, the commutation of tithe in England, the removal of any real abuse in the Church, the redress of the grievances of which the Dissenters have any just ground to complain." He thus took up a position which rendered it necessary for him to resign when the majority would not have his policy. N'ow what precisely was the alteration that had taken place ? Suppose that " a similar appointment had been made in George II. 's reign, ... in what way would the minister have avoided the same fate " ? The answer is that " in the eighteenth century a minister had a majority because he was minister." ^ This was not necessarily by bribery; compare the elder Pitt's speech on the repeal of the Stamp Act — "The gentleman must not tell us that we passed the Act ourselves, and are therefore as much responsible for it as he is. No ! we took it on his credit as minister. ... I wish the House had not this habit : but so it is. Even that chair, Mr. Speaker, looks too often towards St James'." But the influence of places and pensions was a solid support of this " habit." ^ The Houses knew that they were responsible for legislation : and Pitt's is here an advocate's speech. To say, as Seeley does, that ^ Seeley, oj?. clt. p. 285. '■^ Compare Hume, Essay vi., on the Independency of Parliament (published 1742), "The Crown has so many offices at its disposal, that, when assisted by the honest and disinterested part of the house, it will always command the resolutions of the whole so far, at least, as to preserve the antient con- stitution from danger. We may, therefore, give to this influence what name- we please ; we may call it by the invidious appellations of corruption and dependence; but some degree and some kind of it are inseparable from the very nature of the constitution, and necessary to the preservation of our mixed government." Compare also Paley (a.d. 1785). XXVII ENGLISH POLITY SINCE 1688 409 " it had not yet entered the mind of the representatives that they were entrusted with the government of the country" — if in government we include legislation — seems to me a great exaggeration. Still, " they were in the habit of thinking that it was the business of the king to govern the country. When therefore he was pleased through his ministers to explain " that he held certain measures needful for executive government, they considered that they were entitled, as regards their general expediency, to take " them on the king's credit ; only they held them- selves bound to consider these measures as they affected the people, their constituents." ^ And this is very near the relation of the Emperor William to the Eeichstag; an instance which shows that the maintenance of this form of constitutional monarchy does not necessarily depend on corruption, though actually worked by corruption in England in the eighteenth century. In Germany this is not used. But there are other supports besides parliamentary opinion favourable to the king's free choice: — the idea that, owing to the traditions of the monarchy and the loyalty in the army, the king could, if pressed too hard, defy Parliament and win. The future of this species of constitutional monarchy, apparently firm in Germany, struggling in the Scandinavian States, is an interesting speculation ; but prophecy is neither my duty nor my pleasure. Of the change in England we may recognise several causes. Firstly, there had been a gradual decay of royal influence in George III.'s reign, against which the king had struggled with characteristic firmness, but against which, naturally, George IV. was powerless. The Eockingham Whigs had reduced the Crown patronage, and probably the great growth of the nation in wealth and population had diminished the relative importance of the Court.^ " In the crowded, commercial, manufacturing England of George IV.," members of Parliament " ceased to be courtiers." ^ 1 Seeley, op. ciL p. 287. ^ Cf. op. cit. pp. 288-9. 3 Op. cit. p. 289. 410 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. xxvii The growth of the legislative business of Parliament was another cause. Thus, when it had become " the main business of a minister to legislate, to legislate not on the succession to the Crown, or on the Pretender, or on tests and abjuration oaths, or other matters in which the king was interested, but on workhouses and factories, and banks and tariffs and navigation laws, — questions on which " ^ the traditions of the Crown did not dispose it to active inter- vention, — there was a natural tendency for the minister to become the minister of Parliament : to resist which it would have required a monarch quite different from George IV. or even William IV. Again, the personal unpopu- larity and disreputableness of these sons of George III., especially George IV., were a not unimportant factor in dispelling the element of personal loyalty in the " king's friends " of George III.'s reign. And, finally, the movement of ideas, and the absence of any clear perception of the difference between the later polity and the earlier, facili- tated the change. This cannot occur again. If a Hohen- zollern monarch submits to take a parliamentary prime minister, he will know what he is doing. ^ Seeley, oj). cit, p. 290. LECTUEE XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE NINETEENTH CENTURY § 1. In preceding lectures we saw how in the formation of the modern state as we agree in conceiving it — especially in contrast with the medieval state — the first stage was naturally accompanied by the tendency to absolute monarchy which we find in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. It appeared to be essential to the modern notion of the state that there should be somewhere a power capable of making laws, and which, accordingly, being the source of law, could not be bound by any laws : and it was essential to the ideal of the modern state — in a normal and not anarchical condition — that this power should be supreme ; that it should receive the complete obedience of an overwhelming majority of the citizens, and through their obedience be able to bring the organised force of the community to crush any open resistance of individuals or groups. And I pointed out that the easiest way of arriving at a fairly approximate realisation of this ideal was to establish this power on a monarchical basis, concentrating all supreme authority in the hands of one individual ; and that hence we have an important body — both of thinkers and practical men — maintaining from the sixteenth to the eighteenth century that the advantage of order thus obtained, the exclusion of the evils of anarchy, altogether outweighed the admitted drawbacks of absolute monarchy. Nor was the opinion in favour of absolute monarchy necessarily affected by the progress of ideas which, as I previously said, gradually modernised the king from the old 411 412 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. quasi-feudal conception as having a sort of property in the country. Indeed, even on the very eve of the Eevolution in France, in 1787, the keeper of the royal seal affirmed to the judicial body called the Parlement of Paris — "The sovereign power in France resides in the king alone : he is responsible to God alone for the use of it : the right of making laws is in his sole hands independent and indivisible." But the keeper of the royal seal had not moved with his times. In the age of Louis XIV. this proposition expressed the overwhelmingly prevalent opinion. But as time went on, and free criticism was developed in France and diffused its influence over other parts of Europe — criticism first of ecclesiastical and then of secular rule — there was, as we have seen, a strong drift of educated opinion the other way. And though we are not, of course, to suppose that this drift of political thought was the only cause of the revolution which led to a new form of polity — I have noticed the specially financial reasons, due to the manner in which France had grown out of feudalism, which im- portantly co-operated — still, the drift of opinion was, I cannot doubt, a really important factor. It is to be observed that there are two different kinds of defects in absolute monarchy. It is not only a defect that the supreme power of law-making is in the hands of an individual, who may not use it in the interests of the community : it is a further defect that the execution of the laws being under the supreme control of the same person, there is no sufficient guarantee that he will observe even his own laws, if passion or favour urge him to break them. The distinction between the two is important, because, as G. C. Lewis has said, " There is a great difference between deliberate, universal, and avowed, and unpremeditated, par- ticular, and casual rapacity and injustice. Many governments which habitually act towards their subjects in the most op- pressive manner would be ashamed to reduce the maxims by which they are in fact guided into the form of a law, and to publish it to their subjects and the whole civilised world.' ^ ^ Government of Dependencies, Preliminary Inquiry, p. 30. XXVIII CONSTITUTION- MAKING OF THE 19 TH CENTURY 413 Thus, even if the same individual is supreme both in legislation and in the execution of the laws, it would be an important gain to his subjects if he could, at any rate, be relied on to keep his own laws. This leads us to see that, apart from the question of sovereignty, there is an obvious gain in separating legislative from executive and judicial functions in such a way that those who execute the law are as much bound to obey it as those on whom they execute it : and that the question whether they have obeyed it or not may always be brought before impartial judges for decision. And ob- serve, even when sovereignty is placed in the hands of a people — or of an assembly representing the people — this division of functions is no less necessary for the security of minorities. A supreme assembly may be tyrannical no less than an individual : the only sense in which democratic institutions can be strictly called " freer " than a monarchy is that under a monarchy a majority may be oppressed, while under a democracy it can only be a minority.^ The general recognition of these truths in the first part of the century of constitution -making that we have just gone through, was mainly due to Montesquieu. He found, as I have said, this separation of powers realised in a striking degree in the British constitution of his time, and his influence caused the eyes of the world to be fixed on it as a pattern. Briefly stated, the chief feature of Montesquieu's eulogy of the British constitution, was that by giving the three functions of government — legislative, executive, and judicial — to differently constituted organs, and, in the main, separate and independent organs, it secured the liberty of the individual from illegal oppression : while, by making an assembly which was representative of the people an essential constituent of the legislature, it approximately secured that no law was passed, and especially no tax imposed, without the approval of at any rate an important part of the people. In the English constitution of Montesquieu's time, indeed — and for eighty years after the publication of V Esprit 1 Cf. Elements of Politics, chap. xx. § 2. 414 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. de>8 Lois — the principle of representation was very imper- fectly carried out. But suppose this imperfect representa- tion rectified by an extended and properly distributed suffrage, and we get a constitution in which, if the ideal of popular sovereignty is not completely realised, it is at any rate realised to a considerable extent — though in an indirect way — by the control of the representative assembly over legislation and taxation, and the check exercised on the executive government through the necessity of obtaining supplies from that assembly. At the same time, the inde- pendence of the judicature — including the jury — and the strict limitation on the power of the executive to arrest and imprison before trial, secure the reign of law, and the effective protection of the liberty of the individual citizen. Here we have, summarily stated, the last result of political development in the majority of the states of Western Europe. It is a type varying, as I have pointed out, very widely, and realising the ideal just sketched in varying degrees : England and Germany being the two poles within which the variation, speaking broadly, occurs : and it is not confined to the monarchical form : its most essential features being found in the present government of republican France.^ In such a constitution we may say the ideal of Montes- quieu and the ideal of Rousseau are both realised to a con- siderable extent. But I ought to add that Eousseau would have repudiated this view : regarding it as essential that the sovereignty of the people should be directly exercised, and not indirectly through representatives. " The English people," he says, " are only free at the moments of parlia- mentary elections." ^ I mention this because two modern nations, in which democratic ideas have had fullest develop- ment, have taken important steps in the direction of Eousseau's ideal— the United States of America, by con- stitutions limiting ordinary legislation ; Switzerland further, ^ Cf. my Elements of Polities^ chap. xxii. § 5. ^ "Le peuple Anglais pense etre libre, il se trompe fort; il ne Test que durant I'^lection des membres du parlement." — Contrat Social, Bk. iii. ch. xv. XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19TH CENTURY 415 by the Keferendum — reference to all vote-possessing citizens of laws framed by their representatives. These are both Federal States, and for the present I am only concerned with the constitution-making of what may be called Unitary, as distinct from Federal states. I shall not describe it in detail ; that would, in my limits, tend to an unprofitable array of dates and dry summaries. But I may note that France takes the lead, and till the middle of the nineteenth century is at once the most daring in her experi- ments, and the most widely influential on other states — that is, the party of reform and revolution gets its impulse from France. And even after the series of short-lived con- stitutional experiments which belong to the revolutionary crisis, the lapse into military despotism, the reaction in Europe against that despotism, and the restoration — com- pelled by Europe — of the monarchy in France : — after all this France again becomes a leading centre of influence in the region of political ideas, in the second quarter of the century, until, after the second republic (1848) has led to the second empire, a general distrust of the French methods of arriving at the desired union of freedom and order spreads through Western Europe: and the third republic (1870- 1875), founded on disaster, has hitherto been watched with cold curiosity rather than admiring sympathy by neighbouring nations. § 2. The relation of England to the movement has been fundamentally different. As I have said, England supplied the chief pattern for the form of government in which, after struggle and conflict, the change ultimately results, and, as we have had occasion to observe, the English constitution, before it comes to be used as a pattern, has had a place in that movement of ideas of which France is the focus ; be- cause an important factor in this movement is the contrast that certain influential French writers — first Voltaire and then Montesquieu — drew between the liberty that they actually saw in England in the middle of the eighteenth century and the absence of liberty in France. Indeed we may say that — under the influence especially of Montes- 4i6 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. quieu — the British constitution was transmuted from a fact into an idea. But the idea thus formed did not exactly represent the fact at the time ; and, as we saw in the last lecture, was fundamentally unlike what the fact is now ; the ultimate result of our revolution in 1688 was very different from its immediate aim. The ultimate result has come to be the system of what Bagehot calls " Cabinet Government " : in which the ex- ecutive powers are practically in the hands of a committee of the two Houses of Parliament, selected by their head, the prime minister, who, in his turn, is practically determined — in ordinary cases — by the majority of the House of Commons, which can at any time dismiss him and his colleagues, subject to an appeal to the electorate : he is protected from complete subserviency to the House by the power of dissolution. The power of the hereditary monarch and that of the House of Lords are both of a subordinate kind, though not unimportant. The nobility can check legislation through the House of Lords ; but they practically do not claim to resist the House of Commons on the main features of any question on which its opinion is manifestly in stable harmony with the opinion of a decisive majority of the constituencies ; they only claim to enforce delay and re- consideration and an appeal to the electorate. The monarch has a right to know everything, to have everything dis- cussed with him, and by means of this discussion can in- fluence critical decisions ; also he has the important power of dissolving the House of Commons, and ascertaining whether the Cabinet or the majority of the House of Com- mons is really supported by the people ^ ; but the direction of policy is with the prime minister and Cabinet. All this is admitted in current controversy. ^ ["That is, the monarch would not act unconstitutionally by dismissing his ministers, even though they had the confidence of a majority in the representative assembly, and appointing others, who would then dissolve the assembly, in hopes of changing the balance of parties in parliament by a new election." See the author's Elemerds of Politics, chap. xxii. p. 439, 2nd edition. This chapter may be consulted for a further treatment of the subject of this paragraph and of other parts of this lecture. — Ed.] XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19TH CENTURY 417 But, as we saw, this is quite a different form of government from that which the Eevolution of 1688 was intended to bring about : and for a long time the process by which it was gradually being brought about was im- perfectly apprehended even by acute observers. The Ee- volution was intended to make Parliament supreme in legislation : but it was not intended to give a majority of the House of Commons the power of practically nominating the executive, nor even to enable it to force legislation on the monarch, whose assent was still formally necessary to bills. This is evidently the view of Locke, whose work on civil government was, as I said, considered to give the theory of the Eevolution of 1688. The monarch is, for Locke, the real head of the executive, really supreme in administration, and really a member of the complex organ which lays down the laws. Locke's whole point is that he is not supreme in legislation : that his duty is to conform to the law laid down by Parliament : that his suspending or dispensing from such law is a violation of his trust. And if you look at the official account of the rights of the monarch in Blackstone (a.d. 1765), you will see that he is not only supposed to direct foreign affairs by his " sole prerogative of making war and peace, treaties and alliances," but even in domestic affairs, as a constituent part of the legislature, generalissimo of the army, the fountain of justice and honour, the head of the Church, his range of power is very great. The House of Commons is understood by Blackstone to be able to prevent the abuse of these powers by impeachment of ministers : but no reader of Blackstone would dream that the substance of these powers had passed to a committee selected by a chief practically chosen by a majority of that House ; and in fact, as we saw in the last lecture, this change had not been accomplished in Black- stone's time. But what still enabled the monarch to hold the House of Commons balanced was not the power of veto on legislation, which was practically obsolete^, but the influence exercised on members of the House by the 2 E 4l8 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Crown, partly through the survival — especially in the Tory party — of an opinion favourable to real monarchical rule, within the law, but largely through the solid induce- ments of places and pensions. The indispensability of the latter was, as I said, clear to the cool but somewhat cynical observation of Hume, who told the declaimers against corruption that they were attacking the force that maintained the balance of the constitution: and that if corruption were put an end to, the tendency of the English constitution to become a republic must be irresistible.-^ But it was not clear to Montesquieu : the constitution which Montesquieu admires was the constitution officially recognised, not that which was practically working. Its chief merit was supposed to lie in the separation of powers by which the tyrannic preponderance of either, dangerous to individual liberty, was prevented : whereas in Cabinet government, as we now know it, the intimate practical union of legislative and executive functions in a small committee of Parliament, enjoying the confidence of the majority of the House of Commons, is the most marked characteristic. The strong mutual check actually exercised, under the system of Cabinet government, by the legislature on the executive and vice versa, is unlike anything conceived by Montesquieu. This misapprehension is historically important, because it is the British constitution as conceived by Blackstone and Montesquieu which the founders of the American con- stitution had before them, not exactly as a pattern, but as a type of which they might copy the merits while avoiding the defects : and in fact if we compare the American con- stitution with our own at various stages, we see that this result has been to a great extent attained. The American president really has the power of veto,^ which the English king has long only formally retained : the president really does appoint and dismiss his own ministers ; the decisions of the executive are really his decisions and not theirs : and in order that he may not use this power to control the House ' Hume, Essay vi. '^ Liable, however, to be over-ridden by two-thirds of Congress. XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19 TH CENTURY 419 of Eepresentatives or the Senate, his ministers are prevented from sitting in either House. But in the West European states, in which constitutional government is mostly the product of the nineteenth century, it is the later stage of development — Cabinet government — which has in most cases been adopted : though owing to the want of clear distinction between the two, the power of the monarch has been left somewhat indefinite and varying. In fact, as I have said, constitutional monarchy fluctuates between two types broadly corresponding to what Bluntschli calls " true " and " false," but which it seems more impartial to call German and English (or new English, since the German is very like the old English) : one in which the hereditary monarch is really head of the executive, though the consent of the representative assembly is necessary for legislation and taxation ; the other in which the main part of the executive power has passed to a Cabinet presided over by the leader of the party holding a majority in the representative assembly. Observe that, since the difference depends mainly on custom and opinion and not on law, it is not always possible to say to which type a particular polity at a par- ticular time approximates. For if the king's confidence is given to a prime minister who has also the confidence of the country^ and the support of an assured majority in the representative assembly, there is no clear indication on which side power lies. The question is, what would happen if the monarch tried to dismiss the minister ; and that we can only tell when the time comes.^ The point is not whether at any particular time the monarch is a nonentity and the minister all-powerful : for this is often the case in an absolute monarchy under a weak king. The question is, whether if the monarch wished to dismiss the minister he would find him too strong. 1 This was the case with William Pitt (the younger) in George III.'s reign, and with Bismarck in Germany in our own time. 2 Besides, even if this were tried and failed once, it might succeed another time if the opportunity were better taken : thus the balance of power might oscillate. 420 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. § 3. In saying that the English type is the prevalent one, I ignore minor differences which are not unimportant. For instance, there is a difference as to the second chamber, whose continued resistance to legislation approved by the lower house can be overcome in England by the creation of peers, whereas this is not the case in most Continental states. But I do not think that this makes as much practical difference as it might seem to do, since the Continental aristocracies have not much resisting force; the main struggle is between monarchy and democracy. But speaking broadly, what I have called the English type has been practically imitated in Belgium, which has given for more than sixty years a particularly regular and precise example of the working of the English kind of constitutional monarchy: and in Holland also, since 1848, this type has been adopted. Portugal, after a stormy period in the second quarter of the century, with revolutions backward and for- ward, has had since 1852 — as I understand — peaceful parliamentary government, in which the principle that the leader of the parliamentary majority is to be prime minister has been practically accepted : and the Sardinian con- stitution of 1848 — extended between 1860 and 1870 to the rest of Italy — has been also worked on the same prin- ciple. The same may be said, since 1876, of Spain — which, however, has had a remarkably disturbed and unstable political development during the first three-quarters of the nineteenth century. In the Eomance countries generally, then, we have parliamentary government unmistakably prevalent, and in all cases, except France, in a monarchical form : the Parliament being constructed everywhere on the two-chamber system,, though it is the majority in the representative — or the more directly or simply representative — chamber which is under- stood to give the indispensable support to the ministers in power. I say " the representative, or the more directly or simply representative," because in almost all these cases — Italy is the only exception — the members of the senate, or upper XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19 TH CENTURY 421 chamber, are appointed in whole or in part by election. The election takes various forms. In Belgium, for the most part, the senators are chosen by the same electors as elect the primary representative chamber, but only a com- paratively well-to-do minority are eligible. In Spain, where half the senate is elected, the eligibility is also partly determined by income, but it is also necessary that the senator should have fulfilled some one of a number of functions — civil, military, and professional — of which the holding of a university professorship is one. Here, however, the electors to the senate are not the electors to the house of representatives, but electoral bodies which include, along with others, members of provincial councils. In France the election of senators is similarly given to members or delegates of local governing bodies: but eligibility is un- restricted by income. In Holland, too, provincial govern- ments elect, but eligibility is limited to the comparatively wealthy. In Italy the senators are nominated for life. I fear these details may be bewildering, but I have given them to bring out two points : — first, that the imitation of the English model does not extend to the House of Lords except, so far as the Eomance countries are concerned, in the one case of Spain to a partial extent ; secondly, that the schemes of the different nations are very diverse — so diverse that we may perhaps infer that no nation has solved with conspicuous success the problem of constructing a second chamber. Perhaps we may say that there is a tendency to prefer the principle of election by persons themselves elected, especially by elected provincial organs of government. And this principle, in a more decided form, may now be regarded as normally applied in federal legis- latures constructed on the two-chamber plan.^ We find it also — when we turn to the Scandinavian states — in Sweden. In Norway, alone of West European states, the second chamber is elected by and out of the first. But it is noteworthy that in both Sweden and Norway, but specially 1 [The author did not live to see the establishment of the Australian Commonwealth. — Ed. ] 422 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Norway, the separation into two chambers is less complete than elsewheae. Thus in Norway the two bodies are united for the final vote on any law on which they dis- agree ; and in Sweden this method is adopted for preventing a deadlock in financial matters. As regards extent of the franchise, again, the pattern of England has not been followed. England has rather been dragged after the Continental movement than led it; the tendency being almost everywhere in the direction of universal suffrage. § 4. On the other hand, there has been a very important imitation of the judicial system of England. First in the jury. Here, however, a distinction has to be taken between civil and criminal trials. So far as I know, outside the United Kingdom the jury in civil trials has only been adopted in Portugal ; but in criminal trials it has spread to most West European countries as an important element of the securities for freedom, for which, largely, ' constitu- tional ' government has been demanded. Also, in varying forms or degrees, the judicial protec- tion afforded amply in England against encroachments by the executive on the liberty of the individual citizen has been more or less imitated. But here we must note a remarkable difference — even diametrical opposition — in the interpretation of the principle of ' separation of powers ' in different countries, especially England and France, and it is curious that the two opposite views should both arise from a hona fide application of the same principle, and both be in a manner derived from Montesquieu, who was historically the first to draw attention to the fundamental importance of the principle for the security of the private citizen.^ The English interpretation of Montesquieu's principle ^ I may say that Montesquieu's view seems to me quite obscure on the particular point at issue : in fact he does not expressly treat of it in his famous chapter on the British Constitution, Book xi. chap. vi. Also his definitions of 'executive' and 'judicial' are not clear. But his general idea is certainly ' To prevent arbitrary oppression, put the powers of govern- ment in diflferent hands.' XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19 TH CENTURY 423 has always been — ' To secure legal liberty of citizens, let one organ (the legislature) lay down the law, another (the judicature) decide whether an alleged breach of law has been committed, another (the executive) organise and direct the physical force required to secure obedience to the law and do whatever else is needed for carrying the law into effect ; and let adequate independence be secured to all three.' How to secure adequate independence is a difficult matter ; and in particular Montesquieu held that the assent of the executive to new laws must be made necessary in order to prevent the legislature from undue interference with the executive : so, the very ground on which separa- tion is urged requires that separation not to be complete. But as regards the relation of the executive to the judiciary, the application of the principle has to English minds always seemed simple and obvious. The great point being that the executive is to be kept within the limits of the law, the question whether any of its members or subordinates has in any particular case exceeded them should — it seems obvious — not be left to the executive itself to decide. ' No man can be trusted to be an impartial judge in his own cause ' ; hence, the English mind argues, the decision of these questions must be given to an independent judiciary. But the French interpretation is diametrically opposed. As Mr. Dicey says in his chapter on this subject in the Law of the Constitution (Part. ii. chap, xii.), " The expression ' separation of powers ' ... as interpreted by French history, by French legislation, and by the decisions of French tribunals . . . means neither more nor less than the maintenance of the principle that while ordinary judges ought to be irremovable and thus inde- pendent of the executive, the government and its officials ought (whilst acting officially) to be independent of and to a great extent free from the jurisdiction of the ordinary Courts." Montesquieu's doctrine was thus, he continues, "misapplied by the French statesmen of the Eevolution, whose judgment was biassed, at once by knowledge of the inconveniences which had resulted from the interference of the French 424 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. parlements in matters of state, and by the characteristic and traditional desire to increase the force of the central government." The result is " that the relations of the government and its officials towards private citizens are regulated by a whole body of special rules . . . which differ from the laws which govern the relation of one private person towards another." And "the ordinary tribunals have, speaking generally, no concern with any matter of" this so-called "administrative law. Questions of private right as between private citizens and all accusa- tions of crime fall within the jurisdiction of the civil tribunals. . . . But the ordinary judges are incompetent to pronounce judgment on any ... act done by any official, high or low, hona fide in his official character." The private individual must seek redress for a wrong done by an official in the discharge of his official duties from adminis- trative tribunals. Of these Mr. Dicey says, "These so- called ' Courts ' have of comparatively recent times acquired to a certain extent a quasi-judicial character. . . . We must take care, however, not to be deceived by names. The administrative authorities which decide all disputes in regard to matters of administrative law may be called ' tribunals,' and may adopt forms moulded on the procedure of a Court, but they all of them ... are composed of official persons, and, as is implied by the very pleas advanced in defence of withdrawing questions of adminis- trative law from the civil Courts, look upon the disputes brought before them from a governmental point of view, and decide them in a spirit different from the feeling which influences the ordinary judges." Well, you see how differently the French understand the principle of * separation of powers ' from the English. To the English mind it means, * The function of judicially deciding whether a member or subordinate of the executive has kept within the limits of the law must be separated from the executive function.' To the French mind it means * The function of judicially deciding disputes of right between private citizens must be kept apart from XXVIII CONSTITUTION-MAKING OF THE 19TH CENTURY 425 the function of deciding whether members or subordinates of the executive have broken the law ; the latter function must therefore be given to special administrative tribunals.' It certainly seems to me clear that the English inter- pretation is more in harmony with the general drift of Montesquieu's ideas.-^ ^ It does not, of course, follow that there is not anything to be said for the French view on general grounds of expediency, and general principles of political construction, apart from Montesquieu and his ideas. See Mr. Dicey's book, pp. 326-8 (4th ed.), and my Elements of Politics, ch. xxiv. § 8. LECTUKE XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM § 1. In my last two lectures I characterised briefly the history of constitution-making in unitary states, and dis- tinguished the two types between which, we may say, the actual constitutions known by the common name of con- stitutional monarchy lie. In some cases, as in England, what may be called parliamentary government under the forms of constitutional monarchy is established and recognised : in other cases the struggle between this and what may be called constitutional monarchy proper, or simple constitutional monarchy, in which the monarch governs as well as reigns, is still going on : while in Germany the reins of power are still firmly and undis- putedly held by the hereditary monarch. In the single case of France parliamentary government is established in republican, not monarchical, form ; but it cannot be said that the success or stability of this variety of the type is as yet sufficiently clear for us to attribute any attractive force to the variety, or to predict that other West European states are likely to imitate France. The signs of the times seem to indicate that questions of the extension of the functions of government are more likely to engage the main attention of politicians of the coming generation than questions of change in the form of the internal polity. It may, however, have occurred to my hearers, that in the comparison of two types of modern constitutional monarchy as English and German respectively, I over- looked an important distinction between the two countries 426 LECT. XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 427 selected as typical — viz., that the constitution of Germany- is federal, while the constitution of England is not ; England is what for contrast it is convenient to call a "unitary" state. I did not, however, overlook this ; only it was not necessary for my argument to allude to it : because the point on which I had to lay stress — the relation of the monarch to the ministers who discharge executive functions, and to the representative assembly whose consent is necessary for legislation and for the budget — is substantially the same in the German Empire and in the chief states that make it up, especially Prussia; so that it is not materially affected by the division of functions involved in the federal system. Whether William of HohenzoUern acts as German Emperor or as King of Prussia, in either case he appoints his own ministers, and the representative assembly — whether Federal or Prussian — makes no attempt to force on the monarch a prime minister practically selected by the majority of the assembly. At the same time, what I may call the " federality " of Germany — the union of the German states outside Austria into a larger whole for certain purposes, especially foreign affairs and war, while retaining their independence for many important matters of internal and civil legislation and administration — this is a very noteworthy fact when we are considering the total result of political change in Western Europe. It is also to be noted that a somewhat similar but more complicated federality is found in Austria, — complicated owing to a quite peculiar union between Austria and Hungary, superadded to a division of legislative functions between the imperial diet of Austria and local diets of the various provinces or lands making up Austria as distinct from Hungary. So that there are three deliberative bodies for Austrian affairs : (1) a sort of dual body — two delega- tions of equal number chosen respectively by the Austrian and Hungarian Parliaments, who deliberate on the affairs of common interest for Austria and Hungary simultaneously, but ordinarily apart, communicating and occasionally meet- ing ; (2) the imperial diet of Austria ; (3) the local diets 428 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. of Bohemia, Styria, Tyrol, etc. : and there is a correspond- ing division of executive functions. Then, further, in the affairs of Hungary federality is introduced again in a rather peculiar form, resembling that " Irish Home Eule " which it has been proposed to introduce into the United Kingdom — I should perhaps say, resembling not the form of Irish Home Eule which was actually pro- posed here, but the form that is most consistent with the general principles of representative government. That is, in a particular part of the Hungarian kingdom — Croatia — there has been since 1872 a separate Parlia- ment which legislates on a part of those matters that are not regarded as common to the whole of the territories of the Hungarian Crown, the rest of such matters being legislated on in the Hungarian Parliament at Buda- pest, to which Croatia sends deputies ; the Croatian deputies voting in the Hungarian Parliament not on all matters, but only on such matters as are not legislated on separately in the Croatian Parliament. You see what a complicated case this is of the operation of what I have called federality — i,e, of the plan of uniting communities for certain important purposes of government, while they are separate and independent for certain other important purposes. I use these vague terms because, as we shall see, the division of functions is made differently in different cases : but we may say that wherever federality is introduced, the matters assigned to the common govern- ment include the whole or the greater part of the manage- ment of foreign affairs. In the North, in Scandinavia, we have also a dual state formed by Sweden and Norway : though the tie of union here is materially more slender than that which unites Austria and Hungary. § 2. Then, finally, in Switzerland we have the famous historic instance — unique in modern European history — of federality handed down all but unbroken from medieval to modern times. In respect of continuity of development the Swiss federation is to the federal type almost what England XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 429 is to the unitary type. And the medieval growth and development of the Swiss confederation is one of the few stories in later European history which has rivalled in dramatic interest the struggles of Greeks and Eomans against foreign enemies. How, in a.d. 1291, the peasants of Uri, Schwyz, and Unterwalden banded together — not for political independence at first, as they professed to maintain unimpaired their allegiance to the emperor, and even the rights of subordinate feudal lords in their territory — but in a defensive alliance against the oppression of bailiffs or middlemen acting for the feudal lords: how, in 1315, these rustic soldiers routed the feudal army of Leopold of Austria, hurling down stones and trunks of trees on them from the heights of Morgarten : how the triumphant confederacy begins to shake off dependence on feudal lords : how neighbours sought entrance into it till, in 1353, it has become a league of eight states, including the free imperial cities of Bern and Zurich : how, twenty- five years later, the enlarged confederacy is victorious over another Austrian force, led by another Leopold, in the famous battle of Sempach, which practically gets rid for ever of the overlordship of the Hapsburgs : — all this is fixed in the memory of those who read history in the old- fashioned, but not yet antiquated, spirit, in search of people and events to draw out their sympathies. Then, after this "heroic fourteenth century," there follows a century less morally admirable, but no less prosperous : the confederacy makes conquests, and extends its protection over feebler neighbours ; till, after a victorious war with Charles of Bur- gundy (a.d. 1474-1477), its military prowess is established throughout Europe — so that, in the Italian wars that follow, Switzerland is on all sides recognised as the prime source of first-rate mercenary infantry. At the end of the fifteenth century they have become practically independent of the empire, from which they are formally declared free in 1648 — having, early in the sixteenth century, been increased from eight states to thirteen, with subject and protected territories: and having got through the struggles of the 430 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. Eeformation period without breaking up — a striking proof of the strength that federality has by this time acquired. Henceforward until the end of the eighteenth century there is no great change. Meanwhile the Confederation is by no means homo- geneous or democratic in its constitution. Since the middle of the fourteenth century it has been a league of states with very dissimilar polity, partly of rural cantons, but partly of cities — notably Bern, the leading member — in which we find the tendency to narrowing oligarchy which I noticed in the final phase of development of medieval city-polity.-^ The cities despise the country districts attached to them, and especially the civic oligarchy of Bern rules its subject territories harshly : so the French revolutionary movement finds elements that welcome it eagerly, and the old Con- federation falls in 1798. Then, for the first and last time, federality seems lost : the " Helvetic Eepublic, one and indivisible," was proclaimed. But the federal tradition was too strong : in 1802 Bonaparte gives way to it and restores federality in some measure, and in 1814 there is a reaction to something like the previous constitution. Then, in 1848, after a civil war, a new federal polity is formed to an important extent after a new model — the United States of America. For here the resemblance between Switzerland and England ceases. Switzerland does not give the decisive model of federality ; this is given by the United States of America. This leads me to the most important of all the federal states to which European political development has led — the American — important especially from the great size of the territory over which it has been maintained. But of this I will speak more presently. § 3. I have given this sketch of the development of the Swiss polity, not merely on account of the dramatic or romantic interest to which I referred, but because, as I said, Switzerland, like England, is an instance of a uniquely con- tinuous development of one specimen of a type of polity 1 Lectures xvi. pp. 240, 241 ; xvii. pp. 257, 258 ; xx. p. 301. XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 431 from medieval to modern conditions, a number of other specimens of the same kind having failed to persist. For it must not be supposed that the union of the Swiss cantons and cities is an isolated and peculiar phenomenon in its first stage — I mean in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, when the confederates still maintain a full acknowledgment of Imperial supremacy. On the contrary, as I had occasion to point out in a previous lecture,^ con- federations for defence of common rights and interests, by force of arms if necessary, are a common phenomenon in Germany in this period, after the failure of the Holy Eoman Empire to accomplish its task of reducing Germany and Italy to order has become manifest soon after the middle of the thirteenth century. For example, you will remember the great Hanseatic League of North German cities which (a.d. 1367-1370) waged successful war against the Scandinavian kingdoms. As I said, similar, though less famous, leagues of cities are numerous : and not only of cities : the lesser nobility form similar leagues against the encroachments of the greater, and the tendency to combination goes further, and nobles and cities form similar unions. Indeed, so far as medieval representative institutions are due to an impulse from below, as they largely are in Germany, we may regard them as having a federal character in their aims ; — though, in the form of polity in which they ultimately result, this federal character is obscured by the monarchical headship of the country states into which Germany breaks up, while the federal bond which holds these states together in an Empire is increasingly feeble. The Swiss Confederation, then, so far as the cities are concerned, was the reverse of an isolated phenomenon : but this is not the case with the rural cantons. For the most part in Germany the peasants were excluded from the movement of free combination : the survival of the feudal organisation of society kept them down too effectively. The only exceptions besides Switzerland are, like Switzerland, to be explained by the nature of the country : it seems to have 1 Lecture xxi. pp. 305, 306. 432 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. required either the mountains of the Alps, or the sea-coast of Friesland and Ditmarsh, to enable free communities of peasants to develop and combine. But we note that the protection of the sea was less effective than the mountains : the germs of free democracy and federal polity in Friesland fade in the fifteenth century, and Ditmarsh, the other mari- time exception to the general course of things, has ceased to be an exception before the end of the sixteenth century. But the mention of the sea and of Friesland may remind you that I have omitted one European state that for a long time possessed a federal polity, and that in a period of its history which rivals the Swiss in the interest of a dramatic struggle ending in victory and brilliant prosperity. I refer, of course, to Holland — or rather the United Netherlands. I left this out in my survey of European federality, because in the nineteenth century the federality of the Netherlands is not more than a survival : the polity is in the main the ordinary constitutional monarchy, only with somewhat larger powers and higher dignity attached to the local governments of the old United Provinces once sovereign and leagued. I will not therefore trace the formation of their federal polity, and the complicated and varying relations between " Estates-General " — the main federal organ — and the quasi- monarch " Stadtholder "; the latter tending to prevail in the eighteenth century. Nor will I go into the history of the struggle of the United Netherlands. It is more dramatic even than the Swiss, as the Hollanders are less continuously successful : in fact, on land they are palpably inferior to Spain, which is trying to reduce them. They are as mani- festly saved by their relation to the sea as the Swiss by their mountains ; but here again we see that the protection of the sea is less complete : it is clearly the greater danger of war which presses the polity from the form of a federal republic towards that of a limited monarchy. § 4. It is time that we should pass to a closer considera- tion of the notion of federality and the conditions which tend to favour its introduction, and of the distinctive char- acteristics of a federal state. XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 433 I may begin by remarking that much German learning and subtlety has been applied to distinguishing the conception of a " Federal State " {Bundes-Staat) from that of a " Con- federation of States " (Staatenbund). I think that perhaps undue importance has been attached to the aim of getting a clear and sharp distinction. I do not, at any rate, pro- pose to discuss the various possible lines that may be drawn : or determine exactly when communities forming a union designed to be permanent cease to be individually sovereign — especially as federality in Switzerland has a long career before any sovereignty is claimed. It is more important from our point of view to observe that when a federal com- munity is formed by the union of communities previously independent — I shall presently observe that this is not the only way, though it has been the most important way of introducing federality — the union tends to get closer and the conditions more definite and stable as time goes on ; so that the two notions — confederation of states, federal state — represent two stages in the development of federality. Here I will confine myself to the examination of such unions in a comparatively stable condition, to which the term "Federal Statb^" may in a broad sense be applied. I may begin by pointing out that a federal state is only one kind of composite state. As I said in my Elements of Politics} a state including parts that have, from any cause, a high degree of political separateness may be called com- posite ; even if the governments of its parts are controlled regularly by one supreme legislature, so that its constitution still remains formally unitary. If a state thus constituted is under popular government, and its supreme legislature is elected only by, or consists only of, the citizens who reside in a portion of its territory, the other parts of the state are commonly said to be " dependencies " of the portion to which the legislature is formally responsible : and a similar differ- ence may practically exist under other forms of govern- ment, although the formal constitutional rights of the great majority of the inhabitants may be the same throughout 1 Cf. Elements of Politics, cli. xxvi. § 1. 2 F 434 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. the territory of the state. For example, under absolute monarchy, though no part of the state can be formally a dependency of any other part, it may be so practically ; the monarch may choose his leading subordinates exclusively or mainly from a portion of his dominions, and be practi- cally under the exclusive influence of its public opinion. This position of dependence, whether formal or only prac- tical, is calculated to cause discontent : and it is not likely to be permanently acquiesced in by communities habituated to popular government and feeling themselves on a level in civilisation with the dominant community ; unless, indeed, they are very unequal in size, or unless their exclusion from political rights is compensated by economic advan- tages, which, again, will be likely to excite the jealousy of the inhabitants of the dominant portion of the state. Hence, unless one portion of such a composite state is overwhelm- ingly superior in size and strength, there will be a tendency to an approximate equalisation of political privileges among the parts ; and if at the same time there is a general desire to secure the political separateness of the parts as well as their union in the larger whole, there will be a further tendency to demand that the division of functions between the government of the whole and the government of the parts shall be determined by a constitution which the com- mon legislature of the whole is not competent to change — at any rate by the ordinary process of legislation. These, I think, are essential characteristics of the modern idea of a federal state : — a whole made up of parts, with approximate equality of political position among the parts, and a clear and precise as well as balanced and stable constitutional division of governmental functions between the government of the whole and the government of the parts. Historically, however, this latter characteristic is attained late : in the leading instances of historical federa- tions, we find for a long time no such clear and precise constitutional division of powers, although practically the parts retain their independence, while effectively united in a whole. A certain balance of power is therefore more XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 435 essential than clearness and precision in the division of power. But, no doubt, if there is no such clear division there seems an obvious danger of friction and conflict be- tween the governments of the parts and the government of the whole, and a difficulty of maintaining the balance of power which is characteristic of a federal state. In the nineteenth century, therefore, when constitutional ideas are well developed, the maintenance of this division naturally carries with it some distinction between the ordinary central legislature, that makes laws on the matters not reserved to the part-states according to the constitutional division of powers — and the extraordinary legislature, as Austin calls it, that has the power of altering the fundamental con- stitution. This distinction may exist in a unitary state, but it is a natural security of an orderly and harmonious federal constitution. From this comes a curiously mingled result as regards the stability of a federal state. On the one hand, the greater independence of the parts tends to make it less coherent than a unitary state : so that if discord arises the parts break off more easily and smoothly, so to say. This was illustrated by the civil war in North America (1861— 1864). If the United States had been a unitary state, with slavery in one part, there might no doubt have been a civil war : but the rebels could hardly have cut themselves adrift in solid aggregates, in the apparently orderly and business- like way in which the Southern States voted themselves out of the Union one after another, while the Northern States looked on. On the other hand, so long as disorder and disruption are prevented, the constitution tends to be un- usually stable : as again is illustrated by the United States, where the consent of three-fourths of the federated states is required for a change in the constitution — which has practically prevented almost any change for a hundred years, except the momentous change in enfranchising the negroes, due to the civil war. The division of functions between the common govern- ment of the whole and the separate governments of the 436 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. parts naturally varies. The general idea is that the federa- tion is to be a whole for external relations, while each part is to be independent in internal affairs. But (1) this prin- ciple does not settle how matters external to the parts but internal to the whole are to be determined — that is, matters that concern the relations of the parts as, for instance, free trade among them. And (2) some matters prima facie internal to the parts may expediently be left to the government of ,the whole, on account of the mischief or inconvenience that would be caused by want of uniformity. To this class belong {e.g.) the regulation of currency, bankruptcy, patents and generally commercial law, criminal law, etc. Matters belonging to both these classes are to a considerable though varying extent left, in modern federal states, to the common government. § 5. Let us now consider the conditions under which the federal form of polity is suitable and naturally tends to arise. Of these by far the most important — throughout the period of history that we have traced until comparatively recent times, and even now more important than any other — is the need of strength in external relations. Where there are adjacent communities, anxious to preserve a real independence, but afraid of proving too weak in isolation to hold their own with powerful states in their neighbour- hood, a federal union is an obvious resource. This, as we saw, is exemplified by the part played by federalism throughout Greek history: and it is no less exemplified by the various — either abortive or successful — attempts at federal union which appear in later medieval and early modern history. Thus, to refer to instances above given, the league of the " Hanse " towns of Northern Germany was formed to main- tain their commercial interests, and so was the league of the cities of the Ehine ; the more permanent federal union of the Swiss cantons originated in the effort of small peasant com- munities of mountaineers to maintain their independence ; and the union of the provinces of Holland was formed in the terrible heroic struggle against the persecuting XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 437 armies of Spain in the last quarter of the sixteenth century. In all these cases it is clear that nothing but the need of greater strength in external relations would have brought about a union of so durable a kind among the federating communities. Hence the varied efforts of partial federation which distinguish the Eomano-Germanic Empire from the thirteenth century onward are largely due to the weakness of the central government. Even in the more recent case of the United States of America, this motive seems to have been on the whole the decisive one in overcoming the mutual jealousies and love of independence of the originally separate colonies of Eng- land who threw off the yoke of the mother-country. In the case, however, of the United States, though the first federal union was due to the War of Independence, com- mercial considerations seem to have had an important share in bringing about the second and more stable union of 1789. And considerations of this kind are likely to be important in the future, so long as states endeavour by elaborately arranged tariffs to exclude or hamper the competition of foreign producers in their markets : it will generally be an advantage to the aggregate of the members of a large state that they enjoy a comparatively large area of unrestricted trade — assuming that internal trade is unrestricted. When the case of the United States is quoted as an instance of the prosperity derived from protection, it is a fair answer that the United States present the largest area of unre- stricted free trade that the world has yet seen. § 6. I now turn to the aspect of federalism — in which it presents itself as more in harmony with the ideal of modern democracy than a unitary polity — as a means of realising the maximum of liberty compatible with order. The doctrine of popular sovereignty as spread by Eous- seau was cosmopolitan, and the theoretical determination of the limits of the sovereign people, when once Eousseau's idea of direct democracy is abandoned, was left somewhat obscure. So when, immediately after the great crisis of change in France, the revolutionary propaganda was com- 438 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY lect. menced from France as centre, it easily blended with the old desire for national aggrandisement ; and thus the transi- tion from the enthusiastic issue in the name of republican theory of a charter of liberties to Europe, to the Napoleonic efforts to estabHsh France in an imperial position in Europe, was not a sharp or abrupt transition. The movement of " nationality " — as characteristic of the nineteenth century as constitution-making — was as much a reaction against, as a continuation of, the French revolutionary movement : and the clear apprehension of the danger of a "tyranny of the majority" — which Eousseau had overlooked — on which writers like Tocqueville laid stress, drew attention to the important guarantee of liberty furnished by local self- government. There are, no doubt, important considerations on the other side : and it may be observed that they grow stronger, the more highly civilised and densely populated a country be- comes. Average statesmanship must be expected to be less enlightened in local legislatures, and the danger of mis- chievous legislation in the interest of a predominant class is greater — since such predominance has many more chances in one or other of a number of districts than in the whole country. But what I am concerned to point out now is that we have here, as I before noticed, another way — distinct from union of communities previously independent — in which, in modern times, federality has come to be developed : namely by the establishment of secured local liberties, mainly under the influence of the sentiment of nationality, in states that were previously of the unitary type. It may be observed that such states have often had a kind of federality, only obscured by the predominance of the monarchical common government. The formation of states, in the feudal period and that of transition from feudalism, by marriage of hereditary lords with heiresses, naturally tended to this. Austria is a conspicuous surviving instance, but many other states were in this condition, only the decay of medieval representative institutions and the development of monarchical power gradually obliterated federality. XXIX MODERN FEDERALISM 439 § 7. The future of constitutional monarchy I was unwilling to prophesy : but I feel more disposed to predict a develop- ment of federality, partly from the operation of the demo- cratic tendency just noticed, partly from the tendency shown throughout the history of civilisation to form con- tinually larger political societies — as Spencer would say, to "integration" — which seems to accompany the growth of civilisation. This tendency we traced in the early history of the Gr^eco-Italian city-states ; Eome and Athens were obviously formed by the aggregation of elements be- tween which a state of hostility had previously existed. We noticed also that the history of the German tribes showed them gradually combining in larger and larger aggregates. And especially we noticed how, in the third century B.C., after the Greek cities had been for forty years tossed helpless in the strife among the successors of Alex- ander — against whose armies they were, from mere size, unable effectively to contend — the revival and extension of the Achaean league, uniting several important city-states into one body with the old, comparatively insignificant Achaean towns, gave them a brief interval of real independence. We have seen the same tendency in recent times in the formation of Germany and Italy : and we have in North America an impressive example of" a political society main- taining internal peace over a region larger than Western Europe. I therefore think it not beyond the limits of a sober forecast to conjecture that some further integration may take place in the West European states : and if it should take place, it seems probable that the example of America will be followed, and that the new political aggregate will be formed on the basis of a federal polity/ When we turn our gaze from the past to the future, an extension of federalism seems to me the most probable of the political prophecies relative to the form of government. ^ Cf. Elements of Politics, ch. xiv. § 1. APPENDIX Note A — to page 80 DECLINE IN THE NUMBER OF SPARTANS The decline in the number of Spartans is phenomenal. Herodotus (vii. 234) reckons about 8000 Spartans when Thermopylae was fought (480 B.C.); Gilbert (Gh'iechischen StaatsaUerthilmer, vol. i. p. 41, 2nd ed.) calculates that there were hardly more than 1500 in 371 B.C. ; Aristotle, "not even 1000" in say 330-322 B.C.; Plutarch (Ag. 5), only 700 in 243 B.C., of whom 100 only y^v KeKTrffxevoL kol kA-tJ^ov, the rest 6 8' aXXos o^A-o? o.TTopos kol arifios €v rrj TToAet TrapeKadrjTo. On this it is to l3e remarked that (1) the remarkable decline in Spartan population is in the years 480 to 371, and (2) the remarkable decline in fully qualified citizens is in the years 330 to 243, because one may infer from the language of Aristotle that the exclusion on the ground of poverty had not gone very far. If so, the law of Epitadeus cannot be the explanation of (1) unless Epitadeus lived earlier than Plutarch thinks (Ag. 5). I am disposed to agree wdth Curtius (Bk. ii. eh. i.) that citizenship was granted to trained non- citizens — sometimes illegitimate children of Spartans, sometimes fioOaKcs (cf. Phylarch, ap. Ath. vi. 271 e), i.e. Helots or strangers (^evot Twv Tpochijxojv, Xen, Hell. v. iii. 9) brought up and educated with Spartans. I think the numbers were kept up in this way by adoption with the kings' approval. But the mere cessation of this will hardly explain the paucity of Spartans in the Peloponnesian war compared with Thermopylae. Is it possible that the class afterwards called veoSafxAis were confounded by Herodotus with Spartans, and served along with them; and that afterwards the separation was made more strict ? Busolt (Griechischen StaatsaUerthilmer, § 101) attributes the rapid depopulation of Sparta (1) partly to the losses in the con- 441 442 DE VEL OP ME NT OF E UR OPE AN POLITY tinual wars, (2) partly to "das gestorte Familienleben und die tjppigkeit." But (1) from Lyciirgus to the Persian war the Spartans had had as much fighting ; (2) this cause could hardly operate much in the fourth century, according to Busolt's account of its causes and operation, and the great decline is from 480 to 371 B.C. Busolt, however, holds, without, I think, adequate grounds, that there were 6000 Spartans at Mantinea in 418 B.C. {pip. cit. § 98). This would surely make the depopula- tion from B.C. 418 to 371 quite inexplicable. Note B — to page 84 CAVALRY AND OLIGARCHY I think we must take Aristotle's generalisation about " the first polity after the kings being Ik twv tTnreMv" (Pol. vi. (iv.) 13) as having a substantial and general value as a historical generalisa- tion, rather than as being formally and universally true. It may have been true that the iTnreis in many states were coextensive with the members of the general assembly, and that this had some political functions. But in the only case in which we hear definitely of such a constitution — Kyme in Aeolis — it is not the original constitution but an enlargement. There is no reason to suppose that the oligarchy — or group of oligarchies — in Thessaly, which seems to have lasted an indefinite time under the probably slight control of the common king — was an oligarchy of this kind : or that the Thessalian cavalry consisted entirely of persons who had, as such, political rights. In the fourth century Demosthenes (Kar 'Apio-r. 687 and -n-epl Swraf 173) speaks of Menon of Pharsalus joining an army with 200 or 300 " linrevo-L, Treveo-rats ISlols" and I do not see why the cavalry of the fifth century or earlier should not have been largely constituted in this way. Note C — to page 89 EARLY OLIGARCHY AND TRADE There is a danger of antedating the sentiment against traders. I see no adequate evidence that it was felt in the times of early aristocracy or oligarchy. APPENDIX 443 In the Odyssey (i. 180) the character assumed by Athena is that of a "ruler of the oar-loving Taphians" sailing on a mercantile expedition "to Temese to purchase brass, carrying bright iron as his freight." This passage seems to me to have more importance than the expression of contempt for merchants as unathletic in Od. viii. 156. Again Sappho's brother, who appears to have been of good family, carried wine as a mer- chant from Lesbos to Naucratis (Strabo xvii. 808). Solon, again, is not represented as having lost caste by taking to commerce (Plut. Sol. ii.). Certainly in what we hear of the great Euboean cities in the eighth and seventh centuries there is no sign of any such jealousy between commercial and agricultural wealth. After they have been colonising and commercial for nearly a century, under the Hippobotae, Chalcis fights with Eretria in an antique chivalrous manner about a fertile plain. So again in Megara — after more than a century of commercial enterprise, in which Megara has been competing somewhat with Corinth in Sicily and more effectually with Miletus for the trade of the Euxine, and founding successful colonies in both places, especially in the Propontis — we find that about 630 B.C. the disturbance which gives the opportunity for Tyrannis is a quarrel about the en- croachments of the rich on public pasture -land (Ar. Fol. viii. (v.) ch. v.). A century later the jealousy of "new wealth" is bitterly expressed by Theognis, but this is after the Tyrannis : and the bitterness is directed against low-born people, not against traders as such. It is noteworthy that in the disputes between debtors and creditors, of which we catch a glimpse in Athens as leading to the Solonian legislation, and in Megara not long afterwards (Plut. Quaest. Gh^aec. 18), there is no hint that the creditors are a different class from the wealthy landowners of old family : the whole account (Plut. Sol. cf. also 'A^. ttoA.) suggests that it was these apx^it^oirXovTOi — at any rate no less than any nouveaux riches who had acquired land — who oppressed the poor farmer. I agi-ee with Busolt {StaafsaUerthilmer, § 34) that all this conflict was probably, partly at least, due to the change from " Natural- wirthschaft" to " G-eldwirthschaft," when the coining of gold and silver came in about the beginning of the seventh century ; and doubtless one consequence of this was the intrusion of new wealth into the circle of old families — the barter of wealth for birth in marriage which causes the bitter complaint of Theognis that "men take care of race in their horses but not in their wives, and that women are as bad." (Theog. Eleg. 34. This 444 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY indicates, by the way, a somewhat unexpected freedom of matri- monial choice on the part of women in Megara). The changes such as those in the Solonian constitution by which wealth and not old family was made the ground of the fullest political privileges would also be a consequence. We may note that the exclusion of handicrafts and retail trades does not imply exclusion of merchants. For instance, the practice in Thebes (Ar. Fol. vii. (vi.) ch. vii.) that political privileges were only given a7rocrxo/x€j/ots \povov tlvo. rwv /Savavcroyv epyiovf would not, I conceive, apply to large commerce. Note D — to page 94 PRIORITY OF GREEK COLONIES IN CIVILISATION Nothing is more remarkable than the priority of the Greek colonies in civilisation. For instance, philosophy remains for two centuries colonial : it begins and for some time is concentrated in Asia Minor, then the historic interest of it passes, in the main, to Italy and Sicily. It is not till near the middle of the fifth century, in the predominance of Athens after the Persian Vv^ar, that it finds its natural home there. This priority of civilisation is doubtless partly due to greater natural advantages, namely : — (1) fertility of soil, notably in Italy (Magna G-raecia), where, consequently, the wealth and luxury of Sybaris in the sixth century became and remains proverbial ; and (2) greater power of expansion : the natives being in too low a state of civilisation to be formidable — at least for the first two centuries, from 735 B.C., when colonisation mainly begins, to the end of the sixth century. (Afterwards Samnites, Lucanians, Bruttians, become more formidable in war, and restrict the Italic Greeks to the coast). Probably moreover, colonies then, as now, tended to contain a larger proportion of the energy and enterprise of the mother-state : and to start with political institutions free from certain elements of antiquity that impeded progress. Their danger would be that, cut adrift from old political habits, their progress would be rapid, but lead to less stable and satisfactory results. And this seems to be the case — comparing Athens (e.g.) with Syracuse. APPENDIX 445 Note E — to page 183 CONTRADICTION BETWEEN JUS GENTIUM AND JUS NATURAE RESPECTING SLAVERY Slavery, says Florentinus, " is a constitutio of the jus gentium by which a man is subjected to the mastery of another contra naturam " {Dig. i. 5, 4) — " contrary to jus naturae" is said still more explicitly in the Justinian Institutes (i. iii. 2). The placid recognition by the jurists of contrariety between the jus naturae and institutions universal in the actual com- munities which they knew is rather remarkable, considering the strong language in which the Stoics and Cicero and even later jurisconsults affirm the immutable validity of the law of nature, being as they conceive it the law of eternal reason. It was actually a charge brought by Plutarch against the Stoics that they recognised no validity in any positive laws of any states except so far as identical with the true law of nature and reason — and certainly Cicero's phrases about the Law of Nature bear this out. But it is more surprising to find Gains (Dig. vii. 5) saying that an argument of natural right (naturalis ratio) cannot be affected by the audoritas senatus, and that " no consideration of civil right can affect the force of natural right " (Dig. iv. 5, 8) ; and Celsus affirming that " no law can render legitimate what nature forbids" (Dig. 1. 17). Note F — to page 280 GRADUAL RESTRICTION OF THE POWER OF THE DOGE Venice — like Sparta in the earlier evolution of city-states — is interesting to the modern student of politics, because it shows the gradual reduction of monarchical power. For though the Venetian Doge was elective — and not elective in one family — he was, as Sismondi says, (vol. iii. ch. xx.), irremovable, supreme judge, general of all the forces of the state, honoured with ceremonial of something like oriental magnificence, and often authorised to transmit his dignity to his children. Hence the gradual process by which his powers were restricted may be called a process from monarchy to oligarchy. After the first appointment of a Duke or Doge in a.d. 697 there were three Doges and then the dukedom was abolished 446 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY and a yearly presidency tried : but this was found inadequate, and in A.D. 747 the Doge was returned to. During the next three centuries the Doges struggle for heredity but unsuccess- fully. Then, as Sismondi tells us, in A.D. 1032, two counsellors were given him, whose assent was requisite to any governmental action : he was prohibited from sharing his power with a son, and obliged to take counsel, on important occasions, with leading citizens " invited " (jtregadi) to advise him. A hundred and forty years later — without abolishing the general assemblies of the people, which continued to be summoned on important occasions until the fourteenth century — an annual council of 480 citizens was formed, to which were entrusted all the powers not exercised by the Doge, and, jointly with him, the sovereignty of the republic. But in the case of this council, as in other Italian elections, the choice was not directly made by the people. Twelve tribunes — two from each quarter — had each to select forty members of the council, being prohibited from choosing more than four of one family. These tribunes, in the twelfth century, seem to have been elected by the people ; afterwards the election fell into the hands of the council, which then further claimed the right of confirming or rejecting the selection made by the tribunes, before resigning its annual office. Thus in the thirteenth century, the annually elected — apparently representative — council had become a practically co-optative body. The Venetian nobles, however, were kept from the ordinary vj^pi^ of oligarchs, between the Doge on the one hand, and the people on the other : since, in any struggle of physical force with the people, they could count on no advan- tage similar to that possessed by the Lombard nobles when it came to fighting in the plain. Hence, whereas elsewhere in Italian cities the administration of justice against nobles is a matter of such difficulty that it has to be placed in the hands of a single man armed with dangerous power, in Venice, on the contrary, in A.D. 1179, criminal justice is taken away from the Doge, and entrusted to a ^^ quarantia vecchia" composed of forty members of the Great Council. Then in A.D. 1229, the council of pregadi — corresponding to the consiglio di credenza elsewhere — was fixed in number at sixty, and made elective by the Grand Council, to which it became " probouleutic," having for its special charge the supervision of trade and foreign affairs. At the same time were appointed five mrrettori della promissione ducale and three inquisitori del doge defunto. The duty of the latter was to examine complaints of his conduct, and in case of condemnation, to exact reparation from his heirs. The industry of the "correctors of the ducal APPENDIX 447 oath " led to a large collection of promissioni ducali from A.D. 1240 onward, continued during the thirteenth century. The "promise," as Sismondi says, comes to be a resignation of sovereign rights. The Doge promises not only to observe the laws and execute the decrees of the councils, but not to correspond with foreign powers ; not to open letters addressed to him by his subjects, except in the presence of one of his councillors ; to hold no property outside the state of Venice ; not to intervene in any judgment either of right or in fact ; never to try to increase his power in the state ; never to let any of his relations hold from him any office civil, military, or ecclesiastical, within the republic or outside ; never to let a citizen kiss his hand or kneel before him. This list is oddly unlike the retention of show without substance, which usually characterises the transition to oligarchy under monarchical forms. The explanation doubtless is that after all the Venetians did not want the Doge to become a mere ceremonial and symbol. Note G — to page 392 . ROUSSEAU'S VIEW OF THE GENERAL WILL We must distinguish according to Rousseau {Contr at Social, bk. II. chap, iii.) between la volontd de tous — which is a somme de volonUs particulihes and has regard to private interests — and la volontd gSndrale, which concerns only I'interet commun ; but if we strike out of account the mutually neutralising elements in the will of individuals, what remains will be the volont4 gdndrale. The volonU gdndrale alone can legitimately guide the forces of the state according to the end of the institution, which is ce qu'il y a de commun dans les diffdrents inUrets (bk. ll. chap. i.). But for this will to be really general, it must express itself in laws which ohligent ou favmisent Sgalement tous les citoyens, not in privileges or decisions directed to particular cases (bk. ii. chap, iv.). Rousseau's mistake lies (1) in not seeing that the decision of an aggregate must actually be the decision of the majority ; and (2) that a law cannot be certain to affect all equally, unless they are absolutely similar in condition and circumstances. In book IV. chap, i., he explains that in a well-constituted state, in which plusieurs hommes r4unis se considdrent comme un seul corps, legislation is a simple matter : le Men commun se montre partout avec Evidence et ne demande que du bon sens pom- etre apergu. But when les intdrUs particuliers comm^ncent a se faire sentir et les 448 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY petites socUUs a influer sur la grande, the volonU gSndrale is not destroyed or corrupted, but subordinated : elle est toujours constante, inaltdrable et pure, but individuals prefer their private interests to the general. Even the bribed voter has in him unextinguished the volonU g4n6rale; but what he expresses is a volonU particuliere. His vote answers a wrong question — not 'whether it is im- portant to the state,' but ' whether it is important to me and my party,' etc. La hi de Vordre public dans les assembUes est . . . de faire que la volont6 ginirale soit toujours interrogie et qu^elle rdponde toujours. We may remark on this that it seems surprising that Rousseau could think that the end he has in view could be attained by any loi d'ordre public. The real difficulty lies in the opposition between sectional interests. And further it is a psychological error to suppose that the abstract distinction which Rousseau draws between the wlont4 yarticulihre and the volontS g&adrale is actually realised in the minds of individuals. The commoner case is that the individual's perception of the common interest is really perverted by his strong desire of his own. INDEX Achaea, 63, 64, 72, 80, 94 ; Achaean League, 88, 119, 134 seq. Aesymnetes, 90, 130 Aids (feudal), (see Taxation) Alexander, limits to his powers, 38 ; liberator of Ionian cities, 101 America, United States of, 168, 319 ; their constitution, 418 ; federalism of, 430, 435, 437 Anne, Queen, 403 Aragon, 309, 337 Arcadia, 72, 91, 92, 94, 101, 137, 138 Archons at Athens, 73 seq. Areopagus, council of, 104 Argos, 72, 80, 94, 112, 117, 137 Aristocracy, aristocratic ; in Aristotle's classification, 110 ; in ideal states, 123, 126, 127 ; Roman, 151 ; feudal, 205 seq. ; in France before Revolution, 385 seq. (see Oligarchy) Aristophanes, 115 Aristotle ; on Carthage, 12 (note) ; his idea of state as city, 68, 125 ; on oligarchy and democracy in Sparta, 79 seq. ; on Crete, 80 ; on cavalry and oligarchy, 84, 442 ; on tyrannis, 88 ; on Aesymnetes, 90 ; on de- mocracy and on duration of govern- ments, 101 ; on oligarchies, 102 ; on democracies, 105 ; his classification of governments, 107 seq. ; his ideal state, 120 seq.., 347; his practical ideal, 127 seq.; on monarchy, 129 seq., 188 ; his analysis applied to Rome, 142 seq. ; influence on Christian conceptions of government, 230 ; silent on taxation, 302 Arti (see Crafts) Artisans ; Greek, 123, 125 ; medieval (see Crafts) Ashley, Professor, on craft -gilds, 251 seq. Assembly, primitive, 29 seq. ; early Greek, 75, 76, 80 seq. ; Spartan, 77 seq. ; in oligarchies, 102 ; Athenian, payment for attendance iu, 104 ; its functions, etc., 105 ; of Achaean League, 139 ; different kinds in Rome, 143 seq. (see Estates, Parlia- mentary Government) Athens, imitated, 23 ; as a type, 61, 103 ; early changes, 73, 75 ; formed by integration, 82 ; favours demo- cracies, 97, 99 ; constitution of, 103 seq. ; law-making in, 106, 175, 176 ; religion in, 219 seq. Augustus, 166 seq., 184 seq. Austria, 318 ; federation of, 427 seq., 438 "Babylonian captivity," the, 231 Basileus (see Monarchy) Bishops in medieval states, 224, 267 Blackstone, 371 (note) ; 417 seq. Bluntschli, 320 seq., 397 seq., 419 Bodin, 328 Bolingbroke, 369 seq. Boniface VIIL, 227 Boule (see Council) Brienne, Walter de, iu Florence, 298 Buoni Uomini in Florence, 289 seq. Cabinet Government, 401, 416 (see Ministers) Cajsar on early Germans, 32, 45 Capitano del Popool, 288 seq. Castellani in Italy, 270 seq., 288 Castile, 309, 310, 337 Catalonia, 337 Cavalry, 84, 289, 442 Chalcis, a commercial centre, 72, 85 ; Hippobotae in, 75, App, 443 Charles the Great, empire of, 192, 209, 224, 245, 317 Charles VIII. of France, 279 Christianity (see Church) Church in relation to State, 7, 170, 196, 216, 220, 222 seq. ; early Christian, 221 ; its influence in favour of and against monarchy, 193, 330 seq. ; 449 2 G 450 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY relation to cities in Germany, 246 ; in Italy, 261, 267 seq. (see Theocracy) Ciompi, revolution of the, 300 Cities, Greek, 75-141 passim ; medieval in general, 232-243 ; English, 237 seq. ; French, 242, 243, 307 ; Spanish, 241; German, 244-258 ; Lombard,259. 276 ; Italian and Greek compared, 277-285; Tuscan (especially Flor- ence), 286-301 ; their representation in assemblies, 302-315 passim City-State distinguished from Country- State, 66 seq., 134, 148, 186 seq., 194 seq., 278 Cives sine suffragio, 153 Cleisthenes of Athens, 104 Clergy (see Church) Climate as affecting political develop- ment, 13, 14 Code, codifier, 89 seq., 177 Colonies, Greek, 60, 81, 87, 93, 94, App. 444 ; Roman, 151 seq, Comitia curiata, 145; centuriata, 143 seq. Commons, House of (see Parliament) Compact (see Social Compact) Concilium plebis, 144 Constance, Treaty of, 270 Constantine, Emperor, 187, 222 ; dona- tion of, 229 "Constitutional Government" (Polity) in Aristotle's system, 110, 127 seq. ; modern (see Parliamentary Govern- ment) Consuls, Roman, 160 seq. ; medieval municipal, 243, 268, 287 ; of arti,^ 292, 297 Corinth, a commercial and colonising state, 72, 85 ; tyrants of, 96, 97, 133, 138 Cortes (see Estates) Council {Boule) of 500 at Athens, 105 ; of Achaean League, 139 (note) ; of medieval cities, from 232 passim Country-State distinguished from City- State, 66 seq., 134, 148, 186 seq., 194 seq., 278 Crafts and craft -gilds, 238 seq., 250,^ 251 seq., 281, 287, 288, 290 seq., 297,. 299 Crete, constitutions of, 80 seq. Croatia, 428 Crown (see Monarchy) Curiae, the Roman, 50 Cyclopean family, 54 Cypselos of Corinth, 96 Dante, 228 Democracy, democratic ; in Greek States, 62 seq., 100-119, 120 seq,', in Aristotle's ideal state, 126 ; in medieval towns, 240, 253 seq., 260, r- 283, 300 seq. ; in medieval assemblies, 304 ; movement to federalism, 439 (see England, France, etc.) Denmark, feudalism extending to, 211 ; coup d'etat in, 189, 310, 322 Despotism (see Monarchy and Tyranny) Dicey, Mr. A. V., 423 Diocletian, Emperor, 187 Divine right of kings, 368 Dorians, results of their conquest, 81 (see also Sparta) Droit administratif, 4t.^'2. seq. Empire, beginning of, in Rome, 165 seq. ; Roman, 184 seq. ; Eastern, 261 seq. (see Rome; Holy Roman E?npire) England, feudalism in, 206, 211 ; early monarchy in, 212 ; cities in, 237 seq., 306 ; parliamentary develop- ment in, 310 seq., 341 seq. ; nobility of, 312 ; Montesquieu on its con- stitution, 375 seq., 413 ; its consti- tutional development since 1688, 395- 410 ; constitutional type for nine- teenth century, 415 seq. Ephialtes, 104 Ephors in Sparta, 78 seq. Estates, Assemblies of, 302 seq., 337 Ethnos distinguished from polis, 135 Exarch of Ravenna, 262 Executive, in relation to legislative and judical, 171, 376 seq., 413 seq. ; in England, 396 seq. (see Ministers) False Decretals, the, 229 Federalism in Greece, 119, 134 seq. ; modern, 426-439; modem tendencies to, 439 Feudalism, 195, 201, 202-216 ; in re- ^ lation to Assemblies of Estates, 304 ; in England, 311 seq. ; decline of, in France, 383 seq. Filmer, controversy with Locke, 44 Florence, 265 ; polity of, 286-301 n France, municipal development in, 242 ; ^ estates (general and provincial) of, 306 seq., 337 ; part of, in European changes, 395 ; later constitutions of, 397, 415, 438 Franchise, Roman, 147 ; in nineteenth century, 422 Frankish monarchy, 199 seq., 204 (note) Frederick Barbarossa, 270, 288 ^ Freeman, E. A., on primitive polity, 15, 29, 30, 76 (note); on imitation in politics, 21 (note) ; on Homeric polity. INDEX 451 35 ; on Achaean League, 137 stq, ; on city communities, 244, 260 Gelo of Syracuse, 97 Genoa, 264 Gens, the Roman, 49, 57 seg. George I., II., III. (see Monarchy, Hanoverian) Germany, earliest polity, 33 seq., 45, 66, 67; kingdom of, in relation to -Empire, 196 seq. ; cities of, 235 seq., 244-258 ; estates of, 305 seq., 335 ; Roman law in, 335, 336 ; constitu- tion of, compared with English, 400 seq., 419 ; federalism of, 427 Gervinus quoted, 7 (note) ^Ghibelins, 278, 281 seq., 288, 290, 300 Gilds (see Crafts) Gladstone on Homeric polity, 35 . Gonfalonier of Justice in Florence, 295 seq. Gracchi, Tib. and C, 150, 153, 154, 158, 163 Graeco- Roman politics, how differing from modern, 7 Gregory VII. (see Hildebrand) Grote, on Homeric polity, 35 ; on origin of Greek oligarchy, 71 seq. ; on Xenophon, 112 Grotius, 359 •« Guelfs, 278, 281 seq., 288 seq., 297, 300 Guizot on Third Estate, 307 Hadrian, Emperor, 185 - Hanseatic League, 236, 249, 256, 305, 431, 436 seq. Heiots in Sparta, 76 seq., 207 (note) Henry IV., Emperor, 227, 248 Herodotus on number of Spartan war- riors, 76, and App. 441 ; on Spartan kings, 77 (note) ; on Periander and Thrasybulus, 96 ; on democracy of Mantinea, 103 (note) - Hildebrand, 225 seq., 332 Hindoo family, 55 History, its unity, its relation to ulti- mate ends, 4 ; to practical politics, 5, 6 ; as furnishing analogies, 6, 7 Hobbes, 210, 329, 349-367 passim, 389 seq. Holland (United Netherlands), 340, 341 ; federation of, 432 ^ Holy Roman Empire and Romano-Ger- manic Empire, 196 seq., 225, 235, 256, 267, 317, 318, 325, 336, 431 Homer, Homeric ; his descriptions how far historic, 31 , 32 ; polity, 34 seq., 65, 75, 83, 173 Hungary, 427 seq. Hutcheson, 368 Icelandf constitution of, 46 ideal states, 120 seq. Imitation affecting polity, 20 seq. Industry, mechanic (see Cities, Medi- eval) Innocent HI., 227 seq. Integration, Aggregation ; forming poli- ties, 44 seq., 82, 85, 92, 131, 135, 439 Isocrates on democracy, 112, 117, 120 Italy, medieval cities in, 236 seq., 259 seq. ; constitution of, 420, 421 ; unity of, 439 Janet, 372 Jews, their theocracy, 221 Judicature (Judicial, Judge, Jury, Justice) in earliest polities, 40, 59, 173 ; in Athens, 106 ; feudal, 207, 208, 213, 225, 243; in England before and after the Conquest, 212, 214, 312 ; independence of, 376, 413, 414, 422 seq. Jus civile, 180 Jus gentium, 179 seq. ; App. 445 Jus naturale (see Mature, Law of) Justinian, Emperor, 186, 222, ?48 King, kingship (see Monarchy) Kinship (see Patriarchal Theory) Law ; in relation to government, ancient, 168-383 ; Roman, development of, 176-186 ; its influence on monarchy, 192, 335 seq. ; on revolutionary doctrine, 390 ; Roman in Italian cities, 253 Lawyers, in France, 307, 339, 379 Legislative, 171, 376, 410, 413, 417 seq. (and see Law) Libertun veto in Poland, 341 Licinio-Sextian Laws, 143, 149, 161 Locke, 44, 302, 357-369, 391, 417 Lombardy, cities of, 259 seq. London in Middle Ages, 239 Lords, House of, 416 ; not imitated in new constitutions, 421 - Lot, appointments made by, 105, 128, 295 seq. Louis XIV., 189, 321 seq., 334, 381, 396 seq., 412 Lycurgus (see Sparta) Macedonia, its monarchy and assembly, 38 ; supremacy of, 132, 138 2 G 2 452 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY M'Lennan on Primitive Marriage, 52 se?., 58 Madwig, 176 Magistrates, appointment of, in Greek oligarchies, 102 seg. (see Consuls, Executive) Maine, Sir Henry, his Patriarchal Theory, 47 seq. ; Ancient Lmo and Early History of Institutions, 172 seq., 177 seq., 180 seq. ; on Mont- esquieu and Kousseau, 372, 378 seq., 384 seq. Mantinea, democracy of, 103 (note) Marius, C, 165 Matilda, Countess of Tuscany, 286, 287 ^ Medici in Florence, 301 Megalopolis, 92, 138 -Megara, 116, 138, 283 ; App. 443 Milan, 270 seq. Mill, John Stuart, 114 Ministers, relation of, to Crown and Parliament, 401 seq., 416 seq. Modern history, whence dated, 320 seq. Mommsen on original Roman constitu- tion, 30, 41 ; on urban concentration of Rome, 147 (note) ; on Roman offices, 150 Monarchy (kingship, royalty), absolute, defined, 10, why common, 10, 11 ; movement to, in German primitive community, 32, 33 ; in Homeric de- scriptions, 34 seq. ; in early Greece, 62 seq., 72 seq. ; in Aristotle's sys- tem, 110, 129, 130 ; beginning of medieval, 191 ; absolute in Western Europe, 194 ; German in connection with empire, 196 seq. ; feudal, 209 ^ seq. ; in England, 212, 312 seq. ; absolute, movement to, in Europe, 316-344 ; Hanoverian, 369 seq., 404 seq. ; French, 382 seq. ; defects of absolute, 412 Montesquieu, 338, 371 seq., 380 seq., 413 seq. Napoleon, 319 Nation defined, 26, 27 Nature, law of {jus naturale), 180 seq., 328 (note 3), 350, 357 seq., 379 seq. ; Rousseau on, 387 seq. ; App. 445 Nature, state of, according to Hobbes and Locke, 354-361 ; Rousseau on, 388 seq. Nomothetae, 106 Norman kings (see Monarchy in Eng- land) Norway, 318, 421, 428 Numa, King, 56, 220 Oligarchy, early form of government in Greece, 62 seq., 71 ; movement against, 89, 90, 93-95 ; Aristotle's classification of oligarchies, 102 ; in Aristotle's system, 110 ; in German cities, 249, 250, 256, 257 ; in Italian, 270 seq., 283 ; disruptive, feudal, 317 ; in England, etc., 318, 371 ; Greek in relation to cavalry, App. 442 ; and to trade, App. 442, 443 *' Ordinances of Justice " in Florence, 294 seq. Otto, Emperor, 196 seq., 229, 248, 265 Papacy, Pope (see Church, Theocracy) Papal States, States of the Church, 261- 264 - Parlamento in Italian cities, 274, 279, 287 Parlements in France, 339, 394, 424 Parliament (see under Estates and E7igland) Parliamentary government, types of, in nineteenth century, 420 seq. (see also Ministers Patriarchal Theory, the, 43 seq. Patricians in Rome, 143 seq. ; Frankish,^ 262 Periander of Corinth, 96, 97 Pericles, 104, 114 Philip the Fair, 227 Philip II. of Spain, 322, 334 Phratriae at Athens, 50 Physiocrates, 392 seq. Pisa, 264 Pisistratus, 96 Pitt, William, the elder, 408 Pitt, William, the younger, 371, 406 Plato, his idea of the state as city, 68, 125 ; on governments, 107 seq. ; on degeneration of states, 113 seq. ; his ideal state, 120 seq., 169, 346, 347 Plebeians in Rome, 143 seq. Plutarch, 116 Podesta, the, 243, 273, 288 seq. Poland, 341 Palis, 135, QXi^ passim Political Science distinguished from Political Philosophy and Political History, 2 Political Society defined, 1, 25 (see State) Political thought, relation to facts, 345- 349 Polity defined, 1 Polybius on successive forms of govern- ment, 62 seq. ; on overthrow of Achaean monarchy, 72 ; on demo- cracy of Mantinea, 103 (note 2) ; on INDEX 453 Achaean League, 139 (note) ; on Roman constitution, 157 Polycrates of Samos, 96 Praetor y Praetor Peregrinus, 159, 161, 162, 166, 180 (note), 181 Praetorian Edict, 178 seq. Prime Minister (see Ministers) Primitive Polity, 29-42, 60, 62 Priori in Florence, 293 seq. Private war, 208, 214, 237 Proconsul, proconsular, 158, 162, 165, 166 Provinces, Roman, 161 Referendum, 415 Reformation, 323, 333 Responsa prudentium, 185 Revolution, English, of 1688, 343, 356, 364, 401 seq. Revolution, the French, the intel- lectual source of, 392, 394 ; caused by bankruptcy of France, 395 seq. Rhodes, 116, 139 (note) Robertson's Charles V. quoted, 338, 339 Rome, portions of its Empire broken up and reconstituted to form modern states, 8 ; its early constitution, 30, 41 ; early law, 48 seq. ; its polity, 141-167 ; development of law in, 176-186 ; Empire of, 192, 209 seq. and passim ; religion in ancient, 220 ; Roman derivation of craft-gilds, 251 (see also Holy Roman Empire) Rousseau, J. J., 372, 378-394, 414, 438 ; idea of the General Will, App. 447 seq. Salisbury, Council of, 206 Scandinavia, 213 (note), 310, 421 ; federalism of, 428 Schism, the Great, 231 Second Chamber, 420 seq. Seeley, Prof. Sir J., 396, 402 seq. Senate, Roman, 146, 150, 154, 155, 159 seq., 162 seq., 166 Separation of Powers, 376, 377, 413, 422 seq. (and see Executive and Legislative) Serfs (see Slaves) Servius Tullius, 143 Sicyon, tyranny in, 87 Slaves, slavery, serfs, 7, 76, 80, 106, 114, 125, 126, 183, 207, 240, 253, 324, 445 Social compact, 352 seq., 357 seq., 368 seq., 384 seq., 390 seq. Solon, his constitution, 83, 90 Sovereignty according to Hobbes, 350 seq. ; of the people, 392 Spain, municipal development in, 241 ; assemblies in, 306 ; growth of mon- archical power in, 322 ; limitation of monarchy by Cortes, 322, 337 ; dis- ruption of Christendom strengthens monarchy in, 333 ; modern con- stitution, 420, 421 Sparta, its constitution, 38, 76 seq. ; in favour of oligarchies, 97, 99, 100 ; its stability, 117 ; against Achaean League, 138 ; its control over citizens, 169 ; Spartans and Helots compared to feudal lords and vassals, 207 (note) ; note on decline in number of Spartans, App. 441, 442 Spencer, Herbert, on origin of Govern- ment, 41-45 ; on the Medicine Man, 56 Stasis in city-states, 121 State defined, 1, 25-28 ; country and city, 7, 16, 18, 67 seq., 134, 148, 194 ; and Church, 7, 170 States, general (see Estates, assemblies of) Stoics, their influence on Roman law, 181, 390, App. 445 Stubbs, Dr. W., on absence of royalty among early Germans, 32, 33 ; on English feudalism, 206 ; on early English monarchy, 212 ; on papal supremacy, 228 Sulla, L. Cornelius, 161, 165 Sweden, 318, 421, 428 (see Scandi- navia) Switzerland, 340 ; federalism of, 428 seq. Synoikism in Arcadia, etc., 92, 135 Tacitus on early Germans, 30 seq., 45 ; on mixed government, 128 Taille (see Taxation) Taine, 385 Taxation, Taxes ; Greek, 114 ; ancient and modern views on, 302 ; medieval, 205, 303, 304, 308 seq., 314; ab- solute monarchy and, 321, 322, 336, 337; Locke on, 302, 357, 361; Montesquieu and, 376, 413 ; vicious system of, in the Ancien Regime, 381 seq., 396 Teutonic (see German) Thebes, its early oligarchical govern- ment, 81 ; democracy in, 101 Theocracy, medieval, 215 seq. Thessaly, nobles of, 81, 442 Third estate (see Estates) 454 DEVELOPMENT OF EUROPEAN POLITY Thrasybuhis of Miletus, 96 Timocracy, 102 Tocqueville, A. de, 382 seg-. Tories, 370 seg., 405 seq. Towns alien to feudalism, 216, 217 (see Cities, also Germany, Italy, etc.) Tribunes, Tribunate, Roman, 144, 161, 167 Turgot, 394 Twelve Tables, the, 177 seq. Tylor quoted, 13, 60 Tyrannis, the Greek, 16, 85, 86-99,132 ; the medieval Italian, 272, 275, 276, 284, 285 United Netherlands (see Holland) United States (see America) Venice, its Council of Ten compared to Spartan Ephors, 78, 280 ; early development, 238, 264 ; stable oli- garchy of, 280, 340 ; restriction of power of Doge in, App. 445 seq. Walpole, 369 Warde Fowler, 104 (note), 120 Whigs, 370 seq., 405 seq. William II., Emperor of Germany, 409, 427 William III. of England, 403 William IV. of England, 407 Wilson, Woodrow, 168 (note) Xenophon, 108, 112 THE END Printed by R. & R. Clark, Limited, Edinburgh WORKS BY THE LATE Prof. HENRY SIDQWICK THE METHODS OF ETHICS. Sixth Edition. 8vo. 14s. net. OUTLINES OF THE HISTORY OF ETHICS FOR ENGLISH READERS. Crown 8vo. 3s. 6d. THE PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. Third Edition. 8vo. Us. net. THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICS. 8vo. 14s. net. PHILOSOPHY : Its Scope and Relations. An Introductory Course of Lectures. 8vo. 6s. 6d. net. LECTURES ON THE ETHICS OF T. H. GREEN, MR. HERBERT SPENCER, and J. MARTINEAU. 8vo. 8s. 6d. net. MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd., LONDON. MACMILLAN AND CO.'S IMPORTANT NEW WORKS. THE LIFE OF WILLIAM EWART GLADSTONE. By John Morley. With Portraits and other Illustrations. Three vols. 8vo. 42s. net. A VOLUME OF PARAPHRASES AND TRANSLATIONS FROM THE GREEK ANTHOLOGY, etc. By the Earl of Cromer. Crown 8vo. A HISTORY OF MODERN ENGLAND. In Five Volumes. By Herbert W. Paul. Vols. I. and II. 8vo. LECTURES ON THE FRENCH REVOLUTION AND ON GENERAL MODERN HISTORY. By the late Lord Acton. With Portrait. Two vols. 8vo. A HISTORY OF ENGLISH POETRY. By W. J. Coum hope, C.B., M.A., D.Litt., LL.D., late Professor of Poetry in the University of Oxford and Hon. Fellow of New College, Oxford. Vols. III. and IV. 8vo. OLD QUEBEC : The Fortress of New France. By Sir Gilbert Parker, M.P., and Claude G. Bryan. With twenty- five Photogravure Portraits ; ninety -seven full-page and other Illustrations in the text, and five Maps. 8vo. 15s. net. THE LIFE OF LORD DALHOUSIE. By Sir William Lee-Warner, K. C.S.I. With Portraits, Map, and Plans. Two vols. 8vo. THE LIFE OF SIR WILLIAM HENRY FLOWER, F.R.S. Formerly Director of the Natural History Departments of the British Museum. By C. J. Cornish. With Photogravure Portraits. 8vo. THE LIFE OF GIORDANO BRUNO. By J. Lewis McIntyre, M.A., D.Sc, Anderson Lecturer in the University of Aberdeen. With Photogravure Plate. 8vo. 10s. net. CiESAR'S CONQUEST OF GAUL. An Historical Narrative. Being Part I. of the larger work on the same subject. By T. Rice Holmes, Author of A Histm-y of the Indian Mutiny. With a Portrait of Julius Caesar, a large Map of Gaul, and seven Plans. 3vo. A HISTORY OF THE ENGLISH CHURCH. Edited by Dean Stephens and the Rev. W. Hunt, M.A. A Continuous History, based upon a careful study of Original Authorities, and of the best Ancient and Modern Writers. In eight vols. Crown 8vo. With Maps. Each volume is sold separately, and is fu lishcd with its own Index. NEW VOLUMES. Vol. y. The English Church in the Reigns of Elizabeth and Oames I. By the Rev. W. H. Frere. Vol. VI. The English Church from the Accession of Charles I. to the Death of Anne. By the Rev. W. H. Button, B D. MACMILLAN AND CO., Ltd., LONDON. 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. RENEWALS ONLY— TEL. NO. 642-3405 This book is due on the last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recaU. MC'DLD FEB: 6 71 -5PM 7^ 1 ,NTs^8^.^ro?r7|irS2 Uaife1?|^g!K.ni. j ,lDec:R'5St LD 21-100m-12,'43 (8796s) Y.C 89990 Uf ca.^ S5- THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY -rvi ti.