LIBRARY THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SANTA BARBARA PRESENTED BY HARRY MCGUIRE SOCIAL THEORY BY G. D. H. COLE FELLOW OF MAGDALEN COLLEGE, OXFORD Author of "Self -Government in Industry," "Labour in the Commonwealth," etc. NEW YORK FREDERICK A. STOKES COMPANY PUBLISHERS Copyright, 1920, by FREDERICK A. STOKES COMPANY Att Rights Reserved CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE I. THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY ... i II. SOME NAMES AND THEIR MEANING . . 25 III. THE PRINCIPLE OF FvrrcjTi'm ... 47 IV. THE FORMS AND MOTIVES OF ASSOCIATION 63 V. THE STATE 81 VI. DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION . . 103 VII. GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION . . . 117 VIII. COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION . . . 128 IX. THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY . 144 X. REGIONALISM AND LOCAL GOVERNMENT . 158 XI. CHURCHES 172 XII. LIBERTY 180 XIII. THE ATROPHY OF INSTITUTIONS . . . 193 XIV. CONCLUSION 201 INDEX 215 SOCIAL THEORY CHAPTER I THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY MEN do not make communities they are born and bred into them. Every individual at his birth is flung into a social environ- ment, and his life's work from infancy is to make the best of that environment for himself and for his fellows. As he grows to fuller consciousness, his environment gradually expands. He becomes aware of the family, contact with which furnishes his first social experience. At the same time, he becomes aware also of a larger world outside the family, a world of wisdom, of things seen from windows and on journeys from home, a world which slowly assumes definite shapes and takes on human characteristics of neighborhood and similarity. As he grows older, the fact of organization in this world becomes apparent, and school, church, club and other social institutions claim him, and assume a part in his life. By the time he reaches manhood, he has drunk in and accepted the fact of the world, his environment, as a complex of individuals and associations, of customs and institutions, of rights 1 2 SOCIAL THEORY and duties, of pleasures, pains, desires, hopes and fears, strivings and attempts to understand all centering round this complex and all raising the more or less insistent question of his place in it, and his relation to it. Of course, this process is widely different in the case of different individuals, types and classes. Hitherto, men have usually been brought far sooner and more completely into contact with an organized social environment than women, whose experi- ence has not been allowed to expand with the same freedom. Again, the opportunities of the rich and of the educated classes for contact with the world without have been far fuller than those of the workers or of the lower middle class. The workers, however, through their Trade Unions, clubs and other societies have shared with the upper classes what is largely denied to the lower middle class the opportunity for free association with a communal object, and the consequent appreciation of the social structure of the world around them. The Trade Union is the working-class equivalent for the upper- class public school and university, which are the scenes not so much of education, as of the social training of a ruling caste. The generality of men and women take their experience of the social scene around them unphilo- sophically. They do not reflect upon it; they merely accept it. But that does not make it any the less a real experience, or any the less a part of their mental equipment. They are born into a complex society, and by a natural process that complex society becomes a part of their lives as THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 3 real a Weltanschauung as any Teutonic philosopher ever imagined. The task which I propose to attempt in this book is that of setting down, as clearly as I can, the social content of this Weltanschauung of the ordinary man, not of course limiting myself to what he sees, but endeavoring to put together the social contents of various experiences, and to make of them, as far as they form one, a coherent and consistent whole. What is the content of our social experience what is the relation between the various fragmentary experiences and contacts of and with individuals, associations and institutions which we come upon in our day-to-day life in Society? What, in short, is the structure of the half -organized and half -con- scious community of which we form a part? Perhaps that last question gives rather too large and inclusive an idea of the purpose which I have in mind. It is not all experience that I mean to deal with, but only social experience. Social Theory is not concerned directly with all the actions of in- dividual men, but mainly with their actions taken in concert through some temporary or permanent organized group, and with the actions of such groups as they affect and react upon the individual. The unorganized, personal conduct of individual men will be always present as the background of our study, though it will only be treated incidentally in relation to its social content. Even with this limitation, the scope which I have taken for this book will seem to many people far too wide. Social Theory, especially under its name of "Political Theory," has often been regarded as 4 SOCIAL THEORY having to do mainly with one particular association, the State, and with its relation to the individual. Recent theory, however, has been moving more and more to the conclusion that this definition of the scope of the subject is wrong, because it is fundamentally untrue to the facts of social ex- perience. I do not mean, of course, to deny that it is possible to write books about, and even to make a distinct and separate study of, the nature of the associ- ation called "The State," and its relation to the indi- vidual. That is, of course, a perfectly legitimate and necessary inquiry. But I do absolutely deny that any study of the relations of State and individual can furnish even the groundwork for a general sur- vey of social experience, and that it, taken by itself, can penetrate to the heart of the question of man's place in Society. It is simply not true that the social relations of which a man is most directly and con- stantly aware are, under normal conditions, his relations with the State ; and it is still less true that these relations furnish the whole, or even the greater part, of his social experience. Society is a very complex thing. Apart from personal and family relations, almost every indi- vidual in it has, from childhood onwards, close con- tacts with many diverse forms of social institution and association. Not only is he a citizen or subject of his State, and of various local governing authori- ties within it: he is also related to the social order through many other voluntary or involuntary associations and institutions. He is, maybe, a worker in a factory, mine or office, a member of a THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 5 church or other religious or irreligious body, a Trade Unionist or member of a professional or trading association, a Cooperator or Allotment Holder or Building or Friendly Society member, he has his club of the Pall Mall, politician or workman's variety, he is a sportsman associated with the fellow-sportsman, a Socialist or a Primrose Leaguer, he has hobbies which cause him to join an associa- tion of persons with the same tastes, or views which cause him to link up with others of the same opinion. Moreover, as a husband and a house or share owner, he is directly in contact with the social institutions of marriage and property, while his whole life is a complex in which social customs and traditions play an immense part. None can escape from constant contact with some of these various social relations, and almost every one is conscious of a widely diver- sified and ceaselessly varying social environment of which he forms, for his fellows, a part. Custom is perhaps strongest among women, and association is certainly strongest among men ; but among women also the growth of association is following hard upon the awakening of a wider social consciousness. This being the character of the social complex, the question at once arises of the right way of surveying it from the theoretic standpoint. The tendency of political theorists has been to survey it under the guidance of the principle of Power or Force, which is also the principle of the Austinian theory of law. Of all the forms of association and institution which I have mentioned, only the State, and, under the State, in a small degree the local authority, obviously possesses in our day coercive 6 SOCIAL THEORY power. The State, therefore, as the "determinate superior," having in its hands not only the majesty of law, but the ultimate weapon of physical com- pulsion, has been singled out and set on a pedestal apart from all other forms of association, and treated as the social institution par excellence, be- side which all other associations are merely cor- porate or quasi-corporate individuals, which the State and the law can only recognize at all by pre- tending that they are individuals, although it is perfectly plain that they are not. Following out this line of thought to its logical conclusion, classical Political Theory has treated the State as the embodiment and representative of the social consciousness, the State's actions as the actions of men in Society, the relations of the State and the individual as the chief, and almost the only, subject-matter of Social Theory. Over against the State and its actions and activities this form of theory has set indiscriminately the whole complex of individuals and other associations and institutions, and has treated all their manifestations as individual actions without vital distinction or difference. "" I believe that this false conception of the subject arises mainly from the conception of human society in terms of Force and Law. It begins at the wrong end, with the coercion which is applied to men in Society, and not with the motives which hold men together in association. TJi^otkfix~way , of .con- ceiving [human Society, first fully developed in Rousseau's Social Contract, is in terms not of Force s or Law, buf_jgfj^ijl. As soon as we view the social scene in this light, THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 7 the whole outlook is at once different. Not only the State, but all the other forms of association in which men join or are joined together for the execution of any social purpose, are seen as ex- pressing and embodying in various manners and degrees .the wills of the individuals who compose them. 'The distinction between Social Theory the theory of social conduct and Ethics the theory of individual conduct is at once seen to be the distinction between simple individual action and associative action, between the direct indi- vidual action of a human being by the simple translation of his will into deed, and the associative action of a number of human beings, or of an individual acting on behalf of a number as agent or representative, through a society or association. / Of course, the act of an individual may be just as "social" in its content and purpose as the act of a society or group. But that is not the point: the vital point is that, viewed in terms of will, the actions of the State appear as of the same nature with the actions of any other association in which men are joined together for a common purpose. The respective spheres of ethical and social theory are thus marked out with sufficient clearness for prac- tical purposes, though a doubtful borderland remains of types of action which can be regarded as either personal or associative, because the element of association, though present in them, is present in so rudimentary a form as not to override the purely individual element. This point, however, does not concern us here ; for it is enough for the present to have made it clear that Social Theory is concerned 8 SOCIAL THEORY primarily, not with the State, but with the whole problem of human assodjjjon that is, of associa- tive will and action. It is, of course, possible to reject will as the basis of human institutions; but the consequences of such a rejection are so extraordinary that nearly all political theorists have recoiled from their direct acceptance. Even those who, like Hobbes, have been most assiduous in founding their conception of actual societies on the basis of Force and Law, have sought to reinforce their position by finding an original basis for social association in will. Hence Hobbes' imaginary original social contract in which men bound themselves together by Will into a society, only to alienate forever for themselves and their posterity the will ^ which alone could make their society legitimate. /As soon as a basis of right, and not of mere fact, is sought for human associa- tion, there is no escape from invoking the principle of human will, except for those who maintain that Kings are Kings forever by Divine Right and Ap- pointment. And even this is only to appeal from the Will of man to an omnipresent and omnipotent Will of God. Every approach to democracy makes the actual and legitimate foundation of Society on the will of its members more manifest. I A theory based on Force and Law may pass for long undetected in an authoritarian Society; but it cannot survive the emergence of democratic or even of aristocratic consciousness^ This is true, not only or mainly because the"wm of the people or of a class begins to exert its influence upon affairs of State; but, still THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 9 more, because, without the sanction of law, other forms of democratic or oligarchal association begin to exercise a power which, within their sphere of operation, threatens to challenge or control the State and to usurp the functions which it has arrogated to itself. Law in the strict sense, law enforceable by courts and police, may remain in the hands of the State; but other bodies, such as a baronial assembly, a Church or a Trade Union, frame regulations and secure their observance, even without the aid of the black cap and the policeman. To the great scandal of authority in our own day, even the policemen form a Trade Union of their own, and aim at becoming, within a narrow sphere, their own legislature, executive, and judiciary. Such a social situation is fatal to Political Theory of the old type. While the political philosophers are holding high argument about the philosophical theory of the State, and the relation to it of the individual, the world around them has become interested in a new set of problems, in the position of voluntary and functional associations in Society, in their relation to national States, and their position as being often international associations, in the multiplicity and possible conflict of loyalties and obligations involved for the indi\idual in simul- taneous membership of several such associations. In short, while the philosophers are still arguing about the State and the individual, the world of creative thought has moved on to the discussion of the functional organization of Society, and the new problems for the individual to which it gives rise. 10 SOCIAL THEORY It is not in the least surprising that, under these conditions, the political theory of the schools has become sterile, and that the new developments have arisen among those whose vital interest has lain neither in philosophy nor in the State, but in the sphere of functional association. Apart from purely psychological developments, there are at present only three live sources of social theory the Church, industry and history. Socially inarticu- late in this country since the enfeebling conflicts of the seventeenth century, the Churches are to-day regaining their voice, if not their hold, upon the people. They are beginning to realize that they, too, are social institutions, and to reclaim their right to spiritual self-government and spiritual freedom from the State. Dr. J. N. Figgis' book, Churches in the Modern State, has proved itself one of the live forces in present-day social theory. A force far more generally diffused, and far more potent in its influence, is that which springs from in- dustrial sources. Bolsheviks, Syndicalists, Marxian Industrialists and Communists not merely claim for proletarian organizations independence of the State ; they threaten to destroy it altogether. Right or wrong, they are a force, and thejr doctrines are a living international influence. /At the same time Guild Socialists, inspired also by industrial and economic conditions, preach the doctrine of democratic self-government in industry and the transformation of the State by the influence of the functional principle. / Their doctrine is far wider than industry, although it springs out of industrial conditions. It amounts in the last analysis to a complete Social Theory to the Social Theory which I am putting forward in this book. Thirdly, there is the source of history, which, as our knowledge of the past grows, reminds us more and more that the factotum State the omnicom- petent, omnivorous, omniscient, omnipresent Sover- eign State in so far as it exists at all outside the brain of megalomaniacs, is a thing of yesterday, and that functional association, which is now growing painfully to a fuller stature, is not a young upstart of our days, but has a pedigree to the full as long and as honorable as that of the State itself and in- deed longer and more honorable. Not only the study of medieval history, but still more the growing knowledge of early human institutions, serves to emphasize the common character of the various forms of human association, the essential reality, based on the common will of men, of associations to which Roman law was prepared to concede only the derivative character of persona ficta. We owe much to Gierke and Maitland in the study of law; for they have enabled us to view it, not as the hand- maid of the Sovereign State, but in its relation to human association as a whole. Our study of Social Theory will begin, then, not with tfie State, or with any other particular form of association, but with association as a whole, and the way in which men act through associations in supplement and complement to their actions as isolated or private individuals. Here, however, we are confronted with an im- mediate difficulty. Is the family to be treated as an association, and therefore as part of the social 12 SOCIAL THEORY fabric of Society as distinguished from the indi- viduals composing it ? Does the study of the family form a part of the study of individual conduct or of social conduct? These are not easy questions to answer. I do not propose to go deeply into the historical character of the family, or to touch at all upon the relations, actual or supposed, between the family and the tribe. I am treating my subject, not his- torically, but purely in relation to the present and the future. I shall therefore say only that, in modern times, the family has changed not only its nature and function, but also its composition, and that in doing so it has become far less a social and far more a purely personal unit. The family to-day only functions as a unit in relation to the personal concerns of a relatively very small group, usually those who are included in a single household or brick-box. The family, in the sense of the clan, including a large group of blood kindred, no longer survives in Western Countries as a social unit. It was, in primitive civilization, distinctly and markedly a social rather than a personal unit; but to-day the social functions of the clan have passed into other hands, and the family remains as a private group largely bereft of social functions except in the getting and upbringing of children. No small exception, truly! But it is an exception largely irrelevant to our present purposes. For, although in a sense the family is the necessary basis of Society, it remains itself, under modern condi- tions, largely external to the social fabric, the scene of purely personal contacts, and least capable of THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 13 organization where it is most performing a social function. Its very character is to be unorganizable, incapable of organized coordination with the world of associations which surrounds it; in short, per- sonal rather than collective, individual rather than associative in its operation. It is itself perhaps the strongest of all human groups, as it is certainly the most permanent ; but, as a human group, it is essen- tially individual, and not the least of its strength lies in the fact that it holds aloof from other groups and remains, to a great extent, isolated in a world of developing interrelation. Its members exercise their civic, industrial and political functions more and more, not through it, but as individuals, and, by the removal of other past functions, the disap- pearance of domestic industry for instance, it is more and more set free to become the sphere of purely personal affections and contacts. In the past, some social theorists have based their whole theory upon the analogy of the family, and have striven to explain all wider phenomena of association and community in its light. 1 Any such explanation seems to-day so obviously misleading that it need not detain us at all. It is, however, important to point out that this is by no means the only cure in which the use of a false analogy has caused social theories to suffer shipwreck. Again and again, social theorists, instead of finding and steadily employing a method and a terminology proper to their subject, have attempted to express the facts and values of Society in terms of some other theory or science. On the analogy of the 1 e.g. Filmer's Patriarcha. 14 SOCIAL THEORY physical sciences they have striven to analyze and explain Society as mechanism, on the analogy of biology they have insisted on regarding it as an organism, on the analogy of mental science or philosophy they have persisted in treating it as a person, sometimes on the religious analogy they have come near to confusing it with a God. These various analogies have very different de- grees of value and disvalue. The mechanical anal- ogy and the organic analogy have been alike defi- nitely harmful, and have led theory seriously astray; for they both invoke a material analogy in what is essentially a mental or spiritual study. The anal- ogies drawn from psychology and mental philosophy are far less harmful, and may be even extremely suggestive, if they are not pushed too far; for though neither Society nor the various associations which it includes are "persons," they approach far more nearly to being persons than to being either mechanical or organic. There are, however, obvious and sufficient reasons why no analogy can carry the study of human Society very far forward. To every distinct human study corresponds its own method and its own terminology, and analogy pushed beyond very restricted limits necessarily engenders confusion. Our object is not to know what Society is like, but to know what and how it is ; and any reference of it to some other body of knowledge defeats the object in view. It is true that the method of social theory bears a close resemblance to the method of ethics and psychology. The two are, indeed, in a very real THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 15 sense, complementary, and only in both groups of knowledge together can we find a full knowledge of community. They must pursue to a great extent the same method, in order to arrive at conclusions which are capable of being collated and correlated. Thus social theory has its social psychology, its descriptive study of the action of men in association, and this is related to social philosophy to some extent, though not wholly in the same way as individual psychol- ogy is related to moral philosophy. 1 How far the parallel holds depends largely upon the sphere assigned to social psychology, which is a young science not yet at all sure of its scope or method. The fact, however, that social and moral theory are complementary, and that, as the final object of both is the human mind in action, they must pursue largely and essentially the same method, is only one reason the more for keeping their terminologies as clearly distinct as possible. For their spheres of operation are distinct, though closely related, and the closeness of their relationship only makes any confusion of terminology the more likely to result in confusion of thought. Thus, if we say that an association is a "person," we are merely obscuring a difference between persons and associations, or rather between personal and associative action, upon which the separate existence of moral and social theory essentially depends. Such a conception may be useful to lawyers whose object is to be able to group persons and associations together for like treatment civilly under the law; but it is clearly inadmissible in social theory. *To this point I must return later. See p. 18. 16 SOCIAL THEORY We must, then, avoid analogies, or at the least avoid allowing our terminology to be influenced at all by analogies, however valuable. We must adopt our own terminology, and make it, as far as possible, clearly distinct from the terminology of any other study. So far, I am fully aware, the ground has not been cleared for the adoption of an easily intelligible and consistent terminology for social theory. This is in part, but only in part, the fault of social theorists, who have not succeeded in denning with sufficient exactitude the scope and the boundaries of their inquiry. It must, however, be recognized that the task is one of peculiar difficulty, both because the words of social theory are words of common use and wont, and therefore peculiarly liable to shift their meaning as conditions change, and still more because conditions do change, and the associations and in- stitutions with which social theory hals to deal change with them, develop new functions, and dis- card old ones, and even alter their fundamental character and internal structure. The "States" of to-day differ widely among themselves, and we should be hard put to it to find a definition which would embrace them all. But the "States" of differ- ent ages differ far more widely, until such common nature as exists among them is almost undiscernible in the mass of transient characteristics which en- compass them at every time. If, then, this book seems to be concerned largely with questions of terminology, that is not my fault. It is hardly possible to fall into any discussion upon an important point of social theory without finding THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 17 sooner or later the discussion tending to resolve itself into a question of words not because only words are at issue, but because it is impossible to get down to the real issues until verbal ambiguities have been removed. We shall be unable to proceed with any analysis and social phenomena, and still more with any explanation of them, until we have de- termined, as far as possible, to use each important name only in a single and definite sense, and until we have agreed what that definite sense is to be. That is why my second chapter deals entirely with questions of terminology. Before, however, we begin the discussion of these vexed questions, it will be well to make as plain as possible the object which this book has in view. The subject-matter of social theory is the action of men in association. That is clear enough. But manifestly this subject-matter can be studied from several different points of view. Apart from purely historical studies, there are at least three main ways besides many subsidiary ways of approach- ing it, and, while each of the resulting bodies of knowledge is useful to each of the others, and each throws a necessary light upon each, their respective interests are clearly distinct and the generalizations or results with which they are concerned are essen- tially different. We must see clearly what is the content of these various studies, if we are to recog- nize and appreciate the scope and the limitations of that study with which alone we are here directly concerned. The first way of approach to social theory lies through the study and comparison of actual social 18 SOCIAL THEORY institutions. Here it often approaches nearly to history ; for the direct material with which it works is to be found in history. The anthropologist or sociologist, studying the institutions of primitive mankind, the constitutional historian, studying the evolution of the State and of the political structure of Society, the jurist, studying the development of law, the ecclesiastical historian, studying the growth and organization of churches all these amass materials from which generalizations can be drawn, and on which more or less scientific principles of human organization can be based. The student of representative institutions a Montesquieu or an Ostrogorski works upon these materials and ar- rives at results which possess an objective value. A "positive science" of institutions is the object of such forms of inquiry. The second way of approach lies through the study, not of institutions in themselves, but of the motives and impulses by which men are moved in their social actions through institutions and associa- tions. At one extreme, this type of theory finds its place in the study of "mob" or "crowd" psychol- ogy, the impulses and ways of action of a barely organized human group. At the other extreme, it studies, from the same standpoint, the psychological aspects of the most complicated and highly devel- oped form of social association, and endeavors, like the psychology of individual conduct, to formulate the general rules which guide the actions of men in association, studying also the diseases of association as individual psychology studies the diseases of personality. Mr. Robert Michels' book on Democ- THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 19 racy and the Organisation of Political Parties is perhaps the best modern example of this form of study in its developed form; but the nucleus of it is to be found in that part of Rousseau's Social Contract which deals with the actions of "govern- ment," and the tendency of all governments to de- generate. 1 There is, of course, much "Social Psychology" which takes for itself a far more roving commission than this. Like psychology as a whole, Social Psychology has often tended, in the hands of its professors, to rely too much on data afforded by the primitive types, and to resolve itself largely into an analysis of instincts. Mr. Graham Wallas' Human Nature in Politics furnished a sort of preface to a more developed sort of Social Psychology, which its author proceeded to follow up, somewhat disap- pointingly, in The Great Society. In America, how- ever, the method of Mr. Wallas is finding followers in plenty, and big developments of this form of social study may be expected from these sources. The third way of approach to social theory is that which Rousseau explicitly set out to attempt in the first two books of his Social Contract. It is no less than the discovery of universal principles of social association of the values, rather than of the facts of sociality. He contrasted his own method sharply with that of Montesquieu in the following passage : "Montesquieu did not intend to treat of the principles of political right; he was content to treat of the positive law of established govern- 1 See Social Contract, bk. iii., especially chap, x. 20 SOCIAL THEORY ments ; and no two studies could be more different than these." 1 Thus, in Rousseau's view, the way of approach which he sought to adopt in discovering the philo- sophic principles of human association was a way which concerned itself not with fact, but with right. It was, in the language of the schools, a normative, and not a positive study. It was thus complemen- tary and parallel to ethical philosophy as the study of individual conduct from the moral standpoint, just as social psychology, the study of associative conduct from the descriptive, analytical and com- parative point of view, corresponds to individual psychology, as the study of individual conduct from the same point of view. Here, however, the parallel breaks down because of the difference of subject matter. In the case of social institutions, there is a third way of study the first of those mentioned above which examines and compares actual in- stitutions and endeavors to reach practical general- izations on this basis. In the case of individual conduct, there is no corresponding third way, unless we consent to regard the study of the human body physiological psychology, physiology proper, and all the other sciences which have to do with the body as in some sense parallel. But to do this is to fall into one of those dangerous analogies against which we have already uttered a warning. Actual institutions may be likened, in a certain sense, to the "body" of the community, as they may be re- 1 Emile, bk. v. The word droit in the French is used in the sense both of "right" (droit politique) and "law" (droit positif). THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 21 garded as, in a certain sense, its mechanism. But strictly speaking, the community has no body and, as Herbert Spencer said, no "common sensor him." Institutions, even if we abstract from the motives which are present in their action, are neither organism nor mechanism. We may, if we will, speak of the "organs of the body social," or of the "machinery of Society," but we must beware of regarding such phrases as more than metaphors, or of basing any conclusions at all upon them. My object in this book is primarily philosophical. I am concerned principally with social theory as the social complement of ethics, with "ought" rather than with "is," with questions of right rather than of fact. But this does not mean that it is desirable or possible to extrude from consideration the other forms of social study which have been mentioned. Social psychology of the type described above offers, in particular, indispensable material for any study of social conduct. The difference is that, in relation to the particular inquiry upon which we are setting out, it forms part, not of the ultimate interest or object before us, but of the material on which we have to work. We must know how associations and institutions actually work, what human motives and distortions of human motive are actually present in them, before we can form any philosophical concep- tion of the principles on which they rest. We there- fore cannot quite say, like Rousseau, "Away with all the facts !" although in our conclusions the facts drop away and only questions of right remain. There is a further danger, not yet directly men- tioned, against which we must be, throughout the 22 SOCIAL THEORY study, always on our guard. It is the more neces- sary to guard against it, because the essential diffi- culties of terminology are always drawing us into it, whether we will or not. We must avoid thinking of either the State or the community as ends in themselves, as self-subsistent and individual realities similar to, or greater than, the persons who are members of them. We must never say that the State desires this, or the community wills that, or the Church is aiming at so and so, without realizing clearly that the only wills that really exist are the wills of the individual human beings who have become members of these bodies. There is no such thing, strictly speaking, as the "will" of an association or institution; there are only the cooperating wills of its members. The chief difficulty here arises from two sources. First, from the fact that the actions of an association seldom if ever reflect the wills of all its members there is practically always a dissentient minority, and very often an apathetic majority. Sec- ondly, from the fact that an association often seems to acquire a sort of momentum which impels it into action without the force of any individual will behind it, or at least causes big actions to be taken on a very small and weak basis of will. Both these facts easily lead us to ascribe a will to the institution itself a will in some sense transcending the wills of its members. Burke's French Revolution arrives at this position by the second route; Bosanquet's Philosophical Theory of the State and much other more or less Hegelian writing by the first. Rous- seau sometimes seems to fall into the same THE FORMS OF SOCIAL THEORY 23 error, though his way of arriving at it is more obscure. This is a question which will have to be discussed much more fully later in this book. Here it need only be said that, even if the belief underlying the view of State or community or association as an "end in itself" were true, it would be none the less important to keep our ways of speaking about such "ends in themselves" clearly distinct from our ways of speaking about individual human beings. Other- wise, only serious confusion can result. Thus, if, like Rousseau, we use the term "General Will" to mean sometimes a will generally diffused among the citizens, and at other times to mean a will whose object is the general good of the citizens, whether it is present in the mind of one or some or all of them, the way is already paved to an illusory recon- ciliation of these two different meanings of terming this "General Will," which begins in either case as somebody's (or everybody's) will, into a will which is neither somebody's nor everybody's, but the will of the State or the community itself. I have spoken so much of terminological difficul- ties and confusions that I fear the reader is already looking forward to the next chapter, which deals entirely with the use of terms, with considerable misgivings. But I hope I have said enough to make it plain that there is no chance of carrying this inquiry satisfactorily through to the end unless we begin by getting as clear as we can the sense in which the names on which it hinges are to be used. We cannot hope to get them quite clear, even to our own minds; and still less can we hope to find any 24 SOCIAL THEORY way of reconciling or making easily comparable the varying terminologies of different writers on our subject. But we must do the best we can, and crave indulgence if our definitions are not fully satis- factory. To that task of clearing the ground for our main inquiry we must now turn. CHAPTER II SOME NAMES AND THEIR MEANING EVERY developed Community may be re- garded as giving rise to an organized Society, within which there exists a vast complex of social customs, institutions and associations, through which the members or citizens express themselves and secure in part the fulfillment of the various purposes which some or all of them have in com- mon. There are in this sentence at least seven words upon the clear definition of which success in our subsequent inquiry largely depends. Community is the broadest and most inclusive of the words which we have to define. By a "Com- munity" I mean a complex of social life, a complex including a number of human beings living together under conditions of social relationship, bound to- gether by a common, however constantly changing, stock of conventions, customs and traditions, and conscious to some extent of common social objects and interests. It will be seen at once that this is a very wide and elastic form of definition under which a wide variety of social groups might be included. It is, indeed, of the essence of community that its definition should be thus elastic; for "community" 25 26 SOCIAL THEORY is essentially a subjective term, and the reality of it consists in the consciousness of it among its mem- bers. Thus a family is, or may be, a community, and any group which is, in a certain degree, self- contained and self-subsistent, is or may be a commu- nity. A medieval University, a monastic brother- hood, a cooperative colony these and many more may possess those elements of social comprehensive- ness which give a right to the title of community. But, if the word is wide and inclusive enough in one aspect, it is essentially limiting in another. In order to be a community, a group must exist for the good life and not merely for the furtherance of some specific and partial purpose. Thus, a cricket club, or a Trade Union, or a political party is not a com- munity, because it is not a self-contained group of complete human beings, but an association formed for the furtherance of a particular interest common to a number of persons who have other interests outside it. A community is thus essentially a social unit or group to which human beings belong, as distinguished from an association with which they are only connected. Yet, despite this wholeness and universality which are of the nature of community, it is not the case that a man can belong to one community only. A community is an inclusive circle of social life; but round many narrow circles of family may be drawn the wider circle of the city, and round many circles of city the yet wider circle of the Province or the Nation, while round all the circles of Nation is drawn the yet wider and more cosmopolitan circle of World civilization itself. No one of these wider NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 27 circles necessarily absorbs the narrower circles within it: they may maintain themselves as real and inclusive centers of social life within the wider communities beyond them. A man is not less a member of his family or a citizen of his city for being an Englishman or a cosmopolitan. Member- ship of two communities may lead, for the indir vidual, to a real conflict of loyalties ; but the reality of the conflict only serves to measure the reality of the communal obligation involved. Our definition does not, of course, enable us to say exactly and in every instance what is a com- munity and what is not. Being a community is a matter of degree, and all communities, being actual, are also necessarily imperfect and incomplete. There may often arise, not merely a dispute, but an actual doubt in the minds of .the persons concerned to what community they belong, as for instance in a border country which hardly knows with which of the peoples it lies between its community of tradi- tion, interest and feeling is the stronger. Again, a province or a town may be merely an administrative area, with no common life or feeling of its own, or it may be a real and inclusive center of social life. Moreover, it may pass by insensible stages from the one condition to the other, as when a depopulated strip of countryside becomes first a formless urban district and then gradually assumes the form and feeling of a town or city, changes and developments in administrative organization usually, but not necessarily, accompanying the change in feeling. There are groups which obviously deserve the name of communities, and groups which obviously do not 28 SOCIAL THEORY deserve it; but there are also countless groups of which it is difficult to say, at any particular moment, whether they deserve the name or not. It is plain, then, that our thing, "a community," does not necessarily involve any particular form of social organization, or indeed any social organiza- tion at all. It is not an institution or a formal asso- ciation, but[a center of feeling, a group felt by its members to be a real and operative unity,! In any community larger than the family, however, this feeling of unity, with its accompanying need for common action, almost necessarily involves con- scious and formal organization. The feeling of unity makes it easy for the members of a commu- nity to associate themselves together for the various purposes which they have in common, and, where the community is free from external hindrances, such association surely arises and is devoted to the execution of these common purposes. Where a com- munity is not free, and an external power hinders or attempts to prevent organization, association still asserts itself, but instead of directing itself to the fulfillment of the various social needs of the group, almost every association is diverted to subserve the task of emancipating the community from external hindrances. This, for instance, is the position in Ireland at the present time. We are concerned in this "study with community as a whole, and with communities of every kind; but our chief interest is necessarily with those larger and more complex communities which have the largest social content and the most diversified social organization. It is, indeed, in relation to these that NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 29 the principal difficulties arise. The simple fact of community is easy enough to appreciate; but in a large and highly developed social group, internal organization, and cross-currents of organization which, assignable to wider communities, overleap the frontiers of the smaller groups and communities within them, often loom so large that the fact of community itself tends to disappear from sight. The desire to counter this tendency is, as we shall see later, one of the principal causes of the facile, but fatal, identification of community with "State" which is so often made by social theorists. "Every developed community," we began by declaring, "may be regarded as giving rise to an organized Society." In the small community of the family this distinction does not to-day, or usually, arise. 1 But for larger communities the distinction is of vital importance. In every such community there is a part of the common life which is definitely and formally organized, regulated by laws and directed by associations formed for social purposes. I mean to use the term Society to denote the com-, plex of organized associations and institutions within the community. I am conscious in this use of giving to the word "Society" a more definite meaning than those with w*hich it is customarily employed. Indeed, the meaning here assigned to it is to a certain extent artificial, but by no means entirely so. We do in fact constantly speak of Society when we wish to 1 It does arise wherever, as in tribal communities, the family becomes a center of organized law-giving or justice, or directs the economic life of its members on a wide enough basis to re- quire formal organization. 80 SOCIAL THEORY denote neither the whole complex of community, nor any particular association or institution, but the sum total of organized social structure which is the resultant of the various associations and insti- tutions within a community. A word is necessary for our purposes to express our sense of that part of the common life which is organized, and the word "Society" seems the best fitted for this purpose. "Society," then, in the sense in which the word is used in this book, is not a complete circle of social life, or a social group of human beings, but a result- ant of the interaction and complementary character of the various functional associations and institu- tions. Its concern is solely with the organized co- operation of human beings, and its development consists not directly in the feeling of community among individuals, but in the better coherence and more Jiarmonious relationship of the various func- tional bodies w'ithin the community. We have seen that a developed community, larger than the family, can hardly exist without institutions and associations; that is, without Society. Society, on the other hand, may exist, if imperfectly, yet in a developed form, without real community, or with only a very slender basis of community. The union of Ireland and Great Britain under a single Parlia- ment, and with a large system of associations and institutions extending to both, is an instance of a Society with but the shadow of a basis of commu- nity. In such a case, as we shall see, the more artifi- cial an association or institution is, or the greater the element of coercion it includes, the more it is in- clined to persist, whereas the more voluntary and NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 31 spontaneous forms of organization find it hard to live under such conditions. The growth of a purely Irish Labor Movement, with a tendency to break away from the British Movement, is an example of this difficulty. Society, as a complex of organizations, cannot stand for, or express, all human life within a com- munity, or the whole life of any single human being. Indeed, it is probably true that what is best and most human in men and women escapes almost entirely from the net of Society, because it is incapable of j being organized. Society is concerned mainly with rights and duties, with deliberate purposes and in- terests. While the community is essentially ~a~\ ^ center of feeling, Society is a center, or rather a group of centers, of deliberation and planning, I concerned far more with means than with ends. It J is, of course, true that an association or an institu- tion can arouse in us and make us attach to it senti- ments of loyalty as well as calculated adherences; but at least the better part of our feelings of love and devotion are put forth in purely personal rela- tionships, or in the narrow but intense community of the family. It is essential that associations and in- stitutions, and even that Society itself, should be able to appeal to our sentiments of loyalty and de- votion, but it would be wrong to desire that these sentiments should be absorbed in them. As long as"!^ human life remains, most of the best things in it will remain outside the bounds and scope of organization, and it will be the chief function of Society so to, organize these parts of human life which respond to organization as to afford the fullest opportunity for 82 SOCIAL THEORY the development of those human experiences and re- lationships to which organization is the cold touch of death. Society, like community, is a matter of degree. It depends not only on the volume and extent of associative and institutional life in the community, but still more on the coherence and cooperative working of the various associations and institutions. Where associative and institutional life is vigorous, but there exist distinct castes and classes, each with its own network of organizations, not cooper- ating but conflicting and hostile, then Society exists indeed, but only in a very low degree. The highest development of Society consists not only in the general diffusion of associations and institutions, over every organizable tract of social life, but also in the harmonious cooperation of all the various bodies, each fulfilling its proper function within Society, in harmony and agreement with the others. We shall be able to appreciate the full implications of this harmony better at a later stage, when we have ex- amined more closely the nature of associations and institutions, and when we have shown in its true light the principle of "function" as their sustaining prin- ciple. n We have so far spoken of associations and insti- tutions uncritically, without any attempt to examine their nature, or to define the sense in which the terms are used. To do this is our next task. We have seen that every developed community includes a network of associations and institutions of the most various kinds, and we have now to explain their character as far as we can. j This is the central difficulty of our subject, and, if this is surmounted, we may fairly hope that much of the rest will be comparatively plain sailing.; Men living together in community are conscious of numerous wants, both material and spiritual. In order to satisfy these wants, they must take action, and accordingly they translate their con- sciousness of wants into will. These wants are of the most diverse character, and require the most diverse means for their satisfaction. In two respects above all, they differ fundamentally one from another, and their differences in these respects present the best starting-point for our examination. Some wants are of a simple character and only require a simple translation into will and action for their fulfillment, or for the demonstration that they cannot be fulfilled. Such wants, being essentially simple and single, do not give rise to any form of organization. But very many wants are complex, and require for their fulfillment not a single act of will or action, but a whole course of action sustained by a continuing purpose. It is in such cases, where the will must be maintained over a whole course of (/ action, that the need 'for organization may arise. The presence of deliberate purpose, however, does not necessarily lead to social organization. The individual has often to present to himself a course of action, and to sustain by a continuing act of will a whole course of action. In such a case he may be said to "organize" his own mind, but organization remains purely personal and within his mind. The position is different when he finds that the purpose before him can only, or can better, be furthered by (7 (7 84 SOCIAL THEORY his acting in common with other individuals and undertaking in common with them a course of action which, he hopes, will lead to the satisfaction of the want of which he is conscious in himself. The mere realization of the need for cooperative action does not, of course, call the cooperation into being, but it is the basis on which cooperation can be built. This consciousness of a want requiring co- operative action for its satisfaction is the basis of association. The wants which may lead to association are themselves of the most diverse kind, and can be class- ified in the most varied ways. The classification that is necessary for our present purpose is, how- ever, clear enough. It is not the "material," but the "social" content of the want with which we are here concerned. In this aspect, the want may be either "several" or "associative." It is, of course, in either case a want of an individual, because only in- dividuals can want anything; but its nature may be such that each individual can enjoy the satis- faction of it by himself, even if imperfectly, whether the other individual secures a like satisfaction or not (these are the wants which I have here called "several"), or it may be such that it can be enjoyed only by the cooperating group as a whole, and not by any individual except in conjunction with other individuals. Of course, if a want is complex in character, and is rather a circle of wants than a single want, it may partake of both natures, and be at once several and associative. Both several and associative wants are fertile of associations; but the permanence and social value NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 35 of the associations which they create differ con- siderably. A mere similarity or coincidence of ob- ject, while it may lead for a time to very close cooperation in pursuit of that object, does not necessarily imply any similarity or coincidence of motive, and still less any real sense of community t 1 T 1 t among those who unite to pursue it. In the absence of profound dissimilarity of motive, it may easily engender a sense of community, and in doing so, may perhaps convert a several into an associative/ want. Thus, a group of farmers may associate purely because each sees in association a prospect of strengthening his economic position; but, having acted together, the group may realize the benefits of associative action, and become inspired with the cooperative principle. Irish agriculture, under the guidance of A. E. and the Irish Homestead, has shown a marked tendency to pass from severalty of wants to associative wants. Wants which are in their nature associative commonly imply a close, constant and continuing cooperation among the persons concerned, both until the object of the association has been secured, and thereafter for its exercise and maintenance. Those who pursue them therefore become far more easily imbued with the spirit of community, and the associations which are created for their fulfillment form a far more vital part of the structure of Society. Almost all the great and important associ- ations which exercise a vital influence on affairs at the present time do so for one of two reasons. Either they exist, or are coming to exist, primarily for the fulfillment of associative wants, or they exercise 36 SOCIAL THEORY influence, despite the severalty of the wants with which they are concerned, by reason of some ex- traneous pull, such as the possession by their mem- bers of vast wealth. In so far as associations are democratic, they can hardly exercise abiding influ- ence unless their purposes are to a considerable ex- tent associative. It is perhaps necessary to illustrate the somewhat bare description given above by a few actual ex- amples. A good instance of pure severalty of aim is to be found in any association which exists simply and solely to represent consumers. A Railway Season-Ticket Holders' Association, for instance, represents persons of the most diverse types, each of whom, broadly speaking, is solely concerned to get railway facilities for himself as cheaply as pos- sible. A commercial or industrial company is another example. In a meeting of shareholders, broadly speaking, each individual is only concerned with the amount of dividend he will secure, and with the expectation of future dividends presented to him by the general position of the company. I do not mean, of course, that any individual acts in such an association purely as season-ticket holder or share- holder, or that his communal instincts and ideas find absolutely no play. That is not the case. But I do mean that the bond of the association itself is purely several, and that the fact of association carries with it no implication that the individuals associated have a common view as to the social position of season tickets or dividends in the com- munity, or a common care for the satisfaction of each other's needs. Only if there is in the asso- NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 37 ciation some other bond besides that of pure sev- eralty will the spirit of community be evoked, and the association take on a communal aspect. This is not to say that associations based on pure severalty may not be useful parts of Society. But, as long as their basis remains purely several, they lack the necessary elements of community which will enable them to link up easily and enter into complementary relationship with the rest of Society. They have their part to play; but it is an isolated and secondary part in the social fabric. How they act to-day we shall see more clearly when we come to consider social theory in its economic aspects. It is indeed in the economic sphere that such asso- ciations mainly, though not exclusively, appear on a large scale. In almost all other spheres, although [j associations based on severalty exist, they attain to importance only when their character of severalty is crossed by an associative want. This very rough and preliminary analysis is sufficient to enable us to proceed to the task of definition. By an "association" I mean any group of persons pursuing a common purpose or system or aggregation of purposes by a course of cooperative action extending beyond a single act, and, for this purpose, agreeing together upon certain methods of procedure, and laying down, in however rudi- mentary a form, rules for common action. At least two things are fundamentally necessary to any asso- ciation a common purpose or purposes and, to a certain extent, rules of common action. The primary condition of all association is a common purpose; for the object of all associations 38 SOCIAL THEORY being the attainment of some end, there can be no association unless the attainment of that end is the purpose of the members. The "end," "object," or "interest," or as I prefer to call it, the "purpose," is the raison d'etre of every association. But, while this is a fundamental point, it is important that it should not be pushed too far. The presence of a common purpose does not imply that it must be fully and consciously apprehended by all or, even in the case of already established associations, a majority of the members. Thus, an association may be constituted by its original founders with a definite purpose; but, in course of time, the con- sciousness of this purpose may become blurred, and the association may survive almost purposelessly, men joining it rather because membership has be- come customary than for the attainment of any end. Some Churches are instances of such atrophied forms of association. Secondly, it must be borne in mind that very many associations have, not a single, clearly definable purpose, but a number of purposes more or less in- timately related one to another. In these cases, while, except in the circumstances contemplated above, each member is as a rule conscious of at least one of the purposes of the association, it does not follow that each member is conscious of, or shares in the desire to forward, each of the pur- poses in view. This may occur, either because a member does not fully appreciate the interrelation of the various purposes, and therefore fails to appreciate the significance of some of them, or be- cause he does really differ from his fellows as to NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 39 some of the purposes contemplated by the associa- tion, while agreeing with him about the rest, and feel- ing the association to be worth while for their sake alone. For example, when a Trade Union or an em- ployers' association combines political and industrial activities, there will be some .who, agreeing with the principal objects of the association and therefore desiring to remain members, will dissent from some of its purposes and methods. The Osborne Judg- ment controversy some years ago, and the recent controversy about the use of "direct action" for political purposes, alike served to force this issue to the front in the case of Trade Unions. It is perhaps unfortunate that it has not been similarly forced to the front in the case of employers' associations. Thirdly, we must remember that associations are sustained by human beings, and are therefore capable of constant development. Changing circum- stances, or a changing appreciation of the same cir- cumstances, may impel the members of an associa- tion to widen or to narrow its objects, or to vary them from time to time. All associations possess a considerable elasticity in this respect, the degree of their elasticity varying largely with the amount of coherence they possess which in turn depends mainly upon the intensity of the communal feeling which inspires them. But there is for every associa- tion a limit of elasticity, and, strained beyond this point by the inclusion of new purposes, the associa- tion will break, and a new one have to be created to fulfill the new purposes. The atrophy of the original purposes causes associations to decay. They may re- new themselves by assuming new purposes; but, if 40 SOCIAL THEORY the change is too big or too violent, they break. Decay or breakage is the fate of every association in the end ; and as, from one cause or the other, asso- ciations disappear, men create new ones to take their place. So~ much for the common purposes which are the moving and sustaining principle of all associations. But, as we saw, there is a secondary characteristic which is essential. Every association must, in some degree, prescribe common rules of action for its members. These rules may be very few and very rudimentary, and -they commonly deal with the conduct of the members only in relation to the purposes of the association, though they often include written or unwritten moral rules of conduct designed to preserve the reputation of the associa- tion, and to act as a sort of elementary guarantee of personal honor. These rules generally include both general rules designed to cover particular cases as they arise, and particular directions issued by the governing body of the association for guidance in particular cases directly. With this aspect of the question we shall have to deal more fully when we consider, in a later chapter, the problems of democracy and representative government. Our definition of the word "association" is clearly very wide indeed. It excludes momentary groups formed, without definite organization, to carry out some single immediate object; but it includes all organized groups possessed of a purpose entailing a course of action. It draws no distinction between groups whose purpose is in some sense political or social or communal, and groups whose purpose is NAMES ANI> THEIR MEANING 41 purely sociable or recreational. It covers a football club or a dining club fully as much as a Church, a Trade Union or a political party. Of course, it makes a great difference to the im- portance of an association, not only how far it is representative of those concerned in its purpose, but also how important its purpose is. But it is imX possible to draw a theoretical line of distinction between associations which are "social" and asso- \j ciations which are only sociable. For some practical J purposes, as for representation upon public bodies, it is no doubt essential to draw such a distinction; but it is necessary to recognize that, however drawn, it cannot be more than empirical. All associations are, in their various manners and degrees, parts of Society. We can now turn to the word which, in the early part of this chapter, was so often used in close con- junction with the word "association." What is an \ institution, and in what sense is the word used in this book? I find the thing for which the word stands difficult to define at all, and impossible to define in any but a largely negative manner. It is not, though it may manifest itself in or through, a group or association, nor has it, strictly speaking, any members. It does, of course, being a social thing, appear in, and operate through, human beings and associations ; but it depends for its institutional status, not upon a particular group of persons who are its members, frame its rules, and seek to effect through it a common purpose, but upon a general / acceptance and recognition by the members of the- community, backed by a sustaining force of custom 42 SOCIAL THEORY or tradition, with or without the sanction of law. It is easily recognizable in some of its principal instances marriage, monogamy, monarchy, peer- age, caste, capitalism and many others belonging to \different ages and civilizations. But, side by side with this use of the word, there is another use of the word "institution" which, while it suits well enough our everyday convenience, may easily be a source of confusion in a theoretical treatment of the question. The word "institution" is often used to denote not only such ideas or re- lations as those instanced above, but also certain actual human groups which are, in the sense in which we have used the word, "associations." Thus Army, Navy, Church and State, to say nothing of less important bodies, are often directly referred to as "institutions." It is important to notice that, in the sense in which we are using the word, Army, Navy, Church and State are not "institutions," but associations > in which institutions may be held to be embodied or / expressed. Thus the Church is an association in which the institution of religion is more or less per- fectly embodied, the State an association more or less perfectly embodying the institution of political government, Army and Navy associations expres- sive of the institution of natural force, and so on. Now, an idea is not an "institution" merely because it is widely or generally held or accepted. It is an "institution" only if, in addition to being so accepted, it is embodied in some external form of social structure or communal custom, either in NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 43 an association or in some actual form of social behavior. We may, then, provisionally define an "institu- tion" as a recognized custom or form of social tradition or idea, manifested in and through human beings either in their personal conduct and relation- ships or through organized groups or associations. Thus, the institution of monarchy is manifested in a king, and the social recognition accorded to him, the institution of peerage in the various peers and their status, the institution of marriage in the vari- ous married persons and their social recognition. In the second group of cases, the position appears to be rather different; for there we first encounter a form of association and then recognize that its social status is due largely to the fact that it embodies an institution. In these cases, we have to study the association directly as an association, and then to study it further in its character as the embodiment of an institution. An institution is, in fact, an idea which is mani- fested concretely in some aspect of social conduct, . and which forms a part of the underlying assump- tions of communal life. This does not make it permanent, or immune from decay or dissolution, though, as we shall see in a later chapter, 1 it does give to it an additional strength and power of survival. It can, however, change or decay. A monarchical Society may become a Republic, if it finds that the monarchical institution has outlived its use. The Guild System was in the Middle Ages 'For a fuller treatment of the whole question, see Chap- ter XIII. 44 SOCIAL THEORY the embodiment of an institution; but the modern Companies which have descended from the Guilds have sunk down to the level of unimportant asso- ciations and have lost all claim to 'institutional status. But, although institutions and their embodiments change, decay and die, it is characteristic of them to possess a greater degree of permanence than belongs to most associations. This relative permanence has both its good and its bad side. It helps to assure to an association or custom, which successfully em- bodies an idea found to be vital to the community, a greater stability than its members or its familiarity alone could assure to it, by giving it a communal sanction and status; but it also tends to cause the survival of associations and customs which have ac- quired an institutional character long after they have ceased to be useful. Our estimate of the advantages and disadvantages of institutions will depend mainly upon our temperament. The temperamental Con- servative (in no party sense) sees in institutions the bulwark of Society: the temperamental innovator sees in them the greatest barrier to progress. We shall use the word "institution" in this book mainly in a rather narrower sense than has been here assigned to it. It will generally be used in con- junction with the word "association" to denote those institutions which are not, or are only in a secondary sense, embodied as associations. When I use it in the wider sense, to include institutions which are also embodied in association, the context will make clear the sense, and I think no confusion will be created. NAMES AND THEIR MEANING 45 There is one further word which we must briefly define before proceeding further. I have spoken repeatedly of custom. Perhaps this word hardly requires definition in the ordinary sense; for its meaning is sufficiently clear. It means no more and no less than a social habit or way of acting, common to the members of a community or social group, or at least widely enough diffused among them over a long enough period of time to have become in some degree taken for granted and acted upon in normal circumstances without any conscious exercise of deliberation. A custom is that which most men do naturally when placed in the appro- priate circumstances. It is as vital to a community to have customs as it is vital to an individual to have instincts; for customs are to the community, as instincts are to the individual mind labor-saving devices born of long use by successive generations. 1 Customs, then, are a vital part of the being of community ; but they do not, as customs, enter into the structure of Society the organized part of the community. They enter into Society only when they become institutions, like marriage, or when their maintenance becomes a purpose to an associa- tion or institution. We shall therefore have little to say of them in this book, not because they are not important, but because, where they appear, they will appear largely under other forms. Before I close this chapter, I must endeavor to clear away a difficulty which may easily have arisen in the reader's mind. I have spoken of the com- 1 Compare Samuel Butler's Life and Habit and Prof. James Ward's Heredity and Memory. 46 SOCIAL THEORY munity as sustaining and of Society as being made up of, associations and institutions, and of the latter as being, in different senses, within Society and within the community. Yet it is manifest that very many associations and institutions are international, and extend far beyond the boundaries of social area clearly recognizable as communities and social com- plexes which are clearly Societies. Does not this present a difficulty ? It will be seen that no difficulty is involved if our original discussion of community is borne in mind. We saw that two or more communities constantly claim the allegiance of a single individual. The family, the city, the nation, the group of closely related nations, the world all these are communities. Every association or institution, however wide- spread, therefore exists within the area of some community. International associations for specific purposes is the forerunner of a closer-knit interna- tional community, and can only exist because, in a rudimentary form, international community is al- ready a fact. Similarly, even international associations are within a Society, however rudimentary. They are the forerunners of a real Society of Nations which will be as necessary an expression of international community as Society within a nation is of national community. Internationally above all, free asso- ciation helps to develop the sense of community on which it is based, and to forward the creation of an international social complex for the expression of that community. CHAPTER III THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION /% LTHOUGH our last chapter was concerned y^primarily with definitions, a number of im- portant conclusions have emerged from it. We have learnt to regard community as a complex of individuals, associations, institutions and customs in varied and multiform relationships; we have learnt to regard Society as a complex of associations and institutions expressing, not the whole of the communal life, but that part of it which is organ- ized ; and we have learnt to see in associations bodies created by the wills of individuals for the expression and fulfillment of purposes which they have in com- mon. We have, in fact, already penetrated the essential and underlying structure of social life. There is, however, at least one point of ultimate principle in relation to which our vision is still fundamentally incomplete. Our method has forced us so far to look at each form of social structure in something like isolation from the others. We have analyzed and defined; but we have not, except in relation to community, as yet made clear the struc- tural principle which makes the complexities of social life into something at least approaching a coherent whole. The underlying principle of com- 47 48 SOCIAL THEORY munity, indeed, is neither more nor less than com- munity itself the sense of unity and social brother- hood which permeates a mass of men and women and makes them, in a real se.nse, one. But we have not seen what is the underlying principle of social organisation, a principle which must be distinct from the principle of community, however dependent upon it. This principle is the principle of Function. Most people know something of those ethical theories which, from the time of Plato onwards, have made "function" their governing principle. In ethics the principle is that each individual should seek not his own self-interest as such, nor his own self -development or self-expression as such, but the fulfillment of his function in the social whole of which he forms a part. His "end" is not to be an isolated or purely personal end, but an end which at once places him in relation to something beyond himself. Pushed to an extreme, this theory may easily result not merely in a denial of all democracy, but in a denial of personality itself as an ultimate or "end" in a glorification and personification of Society in which human values are largely lost, and the personal aspects of life rigidly subordinated to the collective elements. "Function" is eminently unsatisfactory as an ethical principle, that is, as the principle which should determine individual conduct, not because each individual has not, in a very real sense, his function to fulfill, but because he has so many various functions, and because it is just in the - choice of and between functions and in assigning their relative places to the many functions, social and personal, of which we are conscious, that our THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION 49 selfhood appears as a coodinating principle beyond any of them. But the fact that function is not the paramount ethical principle does not mean that it is not the paramount principle of social organization. We have seen that men make, and enter into, associations for the purpose of satisfying common wants, that is, in terms of action, for the execution of common pur- poses. Every such purpose or group of purposes is the basis of the function of the association which has been called into being for its fulfillment. Again, " every institution in Society has an object which has determined the main lines of its growth. The fulfillment of this object is, then, the necessary basis of the function of the institution. Of course, either an association or an institution may be itself complex and have a variety of related purposes or objects, and therefore perhaps a variety of related functions. But as the purpose or object behind an association or institution must be specific and in some degree intelligible in order to have the power to call the association or institution into being, so the functions of all associations and institutions, how- ever they may change and develop, are, in the last resort, also specific. This is the reason why the functional principle is finally applicable to associations and institutions, but not to individuals. ;Every individual is in his nature universal : his actions and courses of action, his purposes and desires, are specific because he makes them so; but he himself is not, and cannot be, made specific, and therefore cannot be expressed in terms of function. This essential difference 50 SOCIAL THEORY makes once more manifest the falsity of the parallel that is often drawn between individuals and as- sociations. An association is not, and cannot be, in any real sense, a "person," because it is specific and functional, and not universal. The individual becomes "functional," or rather "multi-functional," only by limiting himself; the association is func- tional and limited by its very nature. But function is not so much the final cause of each separate association, as the principle under- lying the unity and coherence of associations. We have seen that the value and full development of Society depends not only on the wide prevalence and diffusion of association in the Commonwealth, but also on the successful cooperation and coherence of the various associations. The possibility of this coherence depends upon the fulfillment by each as- sociation of its social function. In so far as the various associations fulfill their respective social purposes, and in so far as these purposes are them- selves complementary and necessary for social well- being, the welter of associations in the community is converted into a coherent Society. In so far as the associations work irrespective of their function in a social whole, or set before themselves purposes which are mutually contradictory and irreconcilable with the good of the whole, the development out of the welter of associations of a coherent Society is thwarted and retarded. It will be observed that a new consideration has been introduced into the argument in the course of the preceding paragraph. In treating function as the characteristic, not of an isolated association, but THE PRINCIPLE OH FUNCTION 51 of an association as a factor in a coherent social whole, or at least a social whole capable of coherence, we have introduced a consideration of value which compels us to scrutinize the purpose of each particu- lar association in the light of its communal value in and for the whole. This consideration is, of course, in no sense novel. The point is clearly stated, although the implications of it are not clearly realized, in Rousseau's Discourse on Political Economy in the following words : 1 "Every political Society is composed of other smaller societies of different kinds, each of which has its interests and rules of conduct; but those societies which everybody perceives, because they have an external and authorized form, are not the only ones which actually exist in the com- munity : all individuals who are united by a com- mon interest compose as many others, temporary or permanent, whose influence is none the less real because it is less apparent, and the proper obser- vation of whose relations is the true knowledge of public morals and manners." Thus, if we view an association as an isolated unit, its object can be only the fulfillment of what- ever purpose or purposes its members have created and maintain it to fulfill. Its will is, in Rousseau's sense, "general" 2 in relation to the members of 1 Rousseau, Political Economy, my (Everyman) edition, P- 253. * The use of the word "general" in this connection must not be understood as contradicting, what was said earlier, that the function of every association is "specific" and not "gen- eral." Its purpose and function remain "specific," whether the will behind it be "general" or "particular." 52 SOCIAL THEORY the association, but "particular" in relation to the community as a whole. The members of an association, as we have seen, can only come together and work together in the association if they have, to a certain extent, a com- mon object or purpose. Clearly, such a purpose may be one that is socially desirable, or it may be one that hardly affects any person outside the association for either good or ill, or it may be defi- nitely anti-social. The mere fact that the associa- tion seeks only the "interest" of its own members (as, if the word "interest" is understood in a wide enough sense, every association, like every individ- ual, must do), is not enough to make it anti-social, or to prevent it from being socially desirable. It is for the good of the community that each group with- in it should keep itself amused, instructed, devel- oped; for these goods of individuals are, so far, clear additions to the common stock of happiness, which can only be the happiness of individuals. An association becomes anti-social not in seeking the good of its own members, but in seeking their good in ways which detract from the good of others. Such detraction only occurs either when one asso- ciation's objects come into conflict with those of an- other, so that both cannot be fully satisfied, or when an association aims at an object which conflicts with the personal objects of some individual, whether a member of the association or not. Wher- ever such a conflict occurs, coherence is impaired, and the complementary working of associations and individuals is made less perfect. The existence of conflict shows that something is wrong; but it does THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION 53 not, of course, show on which side the wrong lies, or how it is distributed between the two. We seem here to be confronted with a difficulty. We cannot accept the objects of each association, just as its members have made them, as making for a coherent Society and a development of the sense of community. It is, indeed, manifest that very many associations, in seeking a partial good for their own members, are acting anti-socially and impairing the coherence of Society as a whole. We , , .... / . . . VA1.TC.A' must, therefore, criticise the value associations in accordance with some "definite standard. The term "function" is in itself, as applied to associations, a reference to such a standard of value; for it places each association in relation, not only to its own members, but to other associa- tions and institutions, that is, to Society, and also to individuals to both the organized and the un- organized parts of social life, that is, to Community. If our first question in relation to any association must be, "What are the purposes which this as- sociation was created and is maintained by its mem- bers to subserve?" we ask that question only in order to be able the better to proceed at once to a second question, "What is the function which this associa- tion can serve in Society and in community?" This does not mean, of course, that it is possible arbitrarily to determine from outside what the func- tion of an association is. The first question is no less essential than, and is essential to, the second. A "function" can only be based upon a purpose. If men have formed an association for one purpose, we cannot properly tell them that its function is to 54 SOCIAL THEORY do something quite different which has never entered into their heads. The fact that the purposes of men in associations change and develop does indeed enable us to some extent to anticipate changes and developments, and to say that an association will find its true function by proceeding along a line of development along which it has already begun to move. But, apart from such intelligent anticipa- tions, we are limited in assigning to any association its function to the purposes which its members have set before themselves in creating and maintaining it. Social purposes are, thus, the raw material of so- cial functions, and social functions are social pur- poses selected and placed in coherent relationship. This selection cannot have a purely scientific basis; for it is a matter of ends as well as means, and de- pends upon individual standards of value and the kind of social life which the individual desires. Thus at this, as at every other fundamental point of social theory, we are driven back upon the individ- ual consciousness and judgment as the basis of all social values. Mr. Colvin of the Morning Post re- gards one kind of social life as finally desirable, and I another. There is a sense in which I believe most firmly that I am right and he is wrong; but social theory cannot reconcile that fundamental difference between us which is a difference of ends, though it may clear away misunderstandings and prevent loose thinking on both sides. Each of us has in his mind, whether we rational- ize and systematize it or not, some conception of the sort of social life which is ultimately desirable. Our conceptions of the functions of particular THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION 55 associations are inevitably formed in the light of our ultimate conception of social value. In laying bare the basis of community it should be possible for men of varying standards and temperaments to agree; but I am fully conscious that in the later chapters of this book I shall inevitably, as I come to deal with more concrete subjects, more and more obtrude my own standards of valuation. I can lay bare the functional basis of association without bringing my temperament into the argument; but as soon as I begin to deal with the actual function of any particular association there will certainly be wigs on the green. That point in the argument, however, we have not yet reached. We must first carry a good deal further our examination of the principle of function in its general application. Function, we have seen, emerges clearly when, and only when, an association is regarded, not in isolation, but in relation to other associations and to individuals, that is, to some ex- tent in relation to a system of associations, a So- ciety, and a system of associations and individuals, a community. Such a system evidently implies a more or less dear demarcation of spheres as between the various functional associations, in order that each may make its proper contribution to the whole without interfering with the others. It is, however, easy, in search of symmetry, to push this point too far. It is essential that the main lines of demarca- tion should be laid down, and, in the case of the more vital forms of association, that they should be most carefully and exactly drawn, wherever possible by experience rather than by arbitrary 56 SOCIAL THEORY "constitution-making"; but in the case of the less vital forms of association, which affect the general structure of Society only in a small degree either for good or for ill, the same exact delimitation of spheres is unnecessary, and even undesirable as de- tracting from the freedom and spontaneity of asso- ciation. We must indeed bear in mind always that asso- ciations are not mere machines, but are capable of growth and development. We must not, therefore, even in the case of the most vital associations, so exactly define their function and sphere of operation for to-day as to prevent them from developing the power to exercise their function of to-morrow. If we do, the result will not be in most cases what we expect. The association will develop in spite of prohibition ; but in developing it may well break the Society which encloses it, or at the least cause vast waste of energy and unnecessary friction. We must remember always that it is of vital importance for a community not to be compelled constantly to make for itself new sets of associations, but rather to de- velop out of old ones the changed forms which are required for the fulfillment of new functions. It is this vital need of community that makes it so im- portant to preserve as far as possible the freedom of association and the greatest spontaneity of asso- ciative action that is consistent with social coherence. There are, of course, risks attaching to this course. If association is left largely free and un- trammeled, many associations, instead of fulfilling their function in the social whole, will concern the'm- selves to a considerable extent in fulfilling even the THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION 57 anti-social purposes of their members, or in doing something which, while it is in itself not anti-social but even socially valuable, falls within the function of some other form of association. There arise in this way two main forms of perversion of function, leading respectively to opposition and to confusion in Society. These two forms of perversion cannot, of course, be kept clearly distinct; for they often appear together in the same association and in the same act. They are, however, theoretically dis- tinct, and we can, at the outset, examine them sepa- rately. Opposition arises, as we have seen, when an association pursues a purpose which, being a pur- pose of its own members, 1 is anti-social in that it not only conflicts with the purposes of other associations or individuals, but with the good of the community. Opposition, then, arises from the pur- suit of anti-social purposes. Strictly speaking, no anti-social purpose can be a part of the function of an association, in the sense in which we are using the term "function." But, as a function is always a complex thing, the element of "opposition" may arise in the course of the pursuit of a socially desirable function. Thus, the production of com- modities for use and the preservation of order are both socially desirable functions; but either of them may be pursued in anti-social ways which give rise to "opposition" and perversion of func- tion. If an association producing commodities for use makes its main object not the production *Or, of course, of an effective majority or effective "con- scious minority" of them. 58 SOCIAL THEORY for use, but the realization of a profit for its mem- bers, perversion of function arises. Commodities are still produced "for use" in a sense; but the function of the association is perverted by the intro- duction of the profit-making purpose. Similarly, if an association whose function is the preservation of order preserves order in the interest of a single class and deals unequal justice to rich and poor, law and order are still partially preserved; but the function of the association is perverted by its par- tiality and the foundations of justice are to some extent undermined. We shall have much more to say of this subject when we come to consider the economic structure of Society and the problem of class-divisions within the community. Confusion arises when two associations attempt to fulfill the same purpose, and when the purpose is such as requires not a multiplicity of doers, but doing on a coordinated plan. Such confusion may be perfectly bona fide and even fortuitous. There are functions which lie on the border-line of two or more associations, but which must be ful- filled by only one if confusion is to be avoided. Again, there are many cases in which two or more associations, whose purposes were originally dis- tinct, develop towards the same object, and become wholly or partly identical in function. Such cases are often dealt with by amalgamation; but failing this or an agreed re-allocation of functions, con- fusion arises. Again, in many cases there is some job which badly needs doing, and two or more groups of men simultaneously conceive the idea of forming an association for the doing of it. Here THE PRINCIPLE OF FUNCTION 59 again amalgamation is often the obvious remedy. Many other cases can easily be brought to mind in which confusion of functions arises even where the purposes of the associations concerned are ad- mitted to be socially desirable or not harmful. Mingled confusion and opposition, involving a double perversion of function, is very frequent. Let us return to our case of the production of com- modities. Under the existing economic order of Society, there is more than one party to such pro- duction. Employers and workers are alike strongly, and separately, organized in economic associations. Very often the employers in a given industry and the workers in that industry are endeavoring to secure the adoption of diametrically opposite policies in relation to the same thing. Their purposes are opposed, and, without entering into the moral factors in the situation, we can see that this often leads to perversion of the function of the association by way both of opposition and of confusion. That is to say, both associations seek to cover to some extent the same field of activity and this leads to confusion, even if their points of view are not fundamentally opposed; but often in addition each advocates a different policy, so that not only confusion, but also actual conflict, results. It is important to notice that perversion of func- tion in one case, especially where the perversion gives rise to actual opposition, frequently leads to, and even necessitates, perversion of function in other cases. If the appropriate organization is not fulfilling a particular function, it may become necessary or desirable for some other organization, 60 SOCIAL THEORY less fitted by its nature for the task, to undertake to fulfill it as best it can. Again, if one association is fulfilling its function in a perverted manner, so as to serve a sectional instead of a general interest, it may be necessary or desirable for some other organization to intervene in order to redress the balance. Current controversies about the use of direct action (i.e. the strike) for political purposes serve to illustrate this point. It is contended by many of the advocates of direct action that the per- version of function on the part of the State makes it necessary for the Trade Unions to act in the indus- trial field in order to counteract the effects of this political perversion. It falls outside the scope of our present inquiry to determine whether this argument is sound or not in any particular case; but it is clear that such cases can and do arise. At the same time, it must always be remembered that perversion of functions is always, in itself, a bad thing, whether it is spontaneous perversion or consequential perversion designed to counteract a perversion which has already taken place. It may be necessary in certain cases; but the mere fact of its necessity is a clear indication that all is not well with Society. When Society is in health, each association fulfills its social function with the mini- mum of perversion. Indeed, when counteracting forms of perversion become necessary on any large scale, they serve as a clear indication that the structure of Society re- quires to be overhauled. Perversion, carried to an extreme, and accompanied by its counteracting forms leads to revolution, followed by a reconstruc- THE PRINCIPLE OP FUNCTION 61 tion of the body social. Such revolution can, of course, be more or less complete; and involve a more or less complete reconstructing and a more or less complete "sweep" of the old social regime. Often, less degrees of perversion and counter-per- version compel a readjustment of social organiza- tion without the need for a general evolution in the body social. The first so-called "revolution" in Russia was rather such a readjustment than a real revolution; but, this proving inadequate, it was followed by the "November Revolution," which was a real revolution involving a fundamental recon- struction of Society. It is impossible to study the forms of functional perversion with any completeness without a fairly thorough examination of the problem of social classes, which has been responsible, at least in recent times, for by far the greatest amount of perversion. It is also Impossible to make the study complete without dealing with the position of organized religion, i.e. Churches, in Society; for religious differences have been, at least in former times, almost equally potent causes of perversion. Both these points, however, must be reserved for later consideration. In this chapter, our object has been merely that of laying bare the functional principle itself, on the basis on which Society, as a complex of associations and institutions, must rest if it is to achieve any degree of coherence or to make possible a real and abiding spirit of commu- nity. Perversion of function, by destroying the co- herence of social organization, not only upsets the balance of Society, but stirs up bad blood between 62 SOCIAL THEORY the members of the community, and thereby impairs that part of the life of the individual which falls outside the sphere of social organization, almost equally with that part which falls within it. Due performance by each association of its social func- tion, on the other hand, not only leads to smooth working and coherence in social organization, but also removes the removable social hindrances to the "good life" of the individual. In short, function is the key not only to "social," but also to com- munal and personal well-being. CHAPTER IV THE FORMS AND MOTIVES OF ASSOCIATION THE time has now come for a more thorough examination of the forms of association which exist in Society, and for some further dis- cussion of the social character of the motives under- lying association. I do not mean that an exhaustive enumeration of the forms of association, or even an exhaustive classification of them, is either possible or desirable still less that the motives behind association can be satisfactorily reduced to a few broad and simple categories. The object of this chapter is essentially tentative. I shall only try to enumerate and classify the main forms of asso- ciation those which possess the greatest degree of social content, and to discuss briefly those dominant social motives which are constantly appearing in many diverse forms of association. Even apart from the limitations of our space and time, there is one fact which would by itself forbid any exhaustive catalogue. Social association is for- ever assuming new forms and discarding old -ones, as new problems emerge for men to deal with, and as men change their attitude towards the problems which confront them. The fountain of association 63 64 SOCIAL THEORY does not run dry, and it is impossible to enumerate all those who come to drink of its waters. More- over, if we could enumerate to-day, our list would be out of date to-morrow ; for new forms of association would have arisen which very possibly would not fit into any classification which we might have de- vised on the basis of our present knowledge. Nevertheless, we can usefully proceed to a classi- fication of a sort. While new forms of association are constantly arising, the essential forms of association only vary over considerable periods. That even the most essential forms do vary, appear and disappear, cannot be denied. There have been many independent communities without a State; yet to most people to-day the State appears to be an essential form of association. The Guilds were an essential form in the Middle Ages; but where are the Guilds to-day? It is true that we have to-day instead of craft Guilds many other forms of eco- nomic associations; but is even economic associa- tion an essential form for all communities? Have there not been communities devoid of distinct eco- nomic organization ? This can only be denied by those who persist, in face of all vital considerations, in regarding the family in certain primitive Societies as primarily and distinctly an economic association. The family in these Societies certainly had eco- nomic, among other, functions; but this is not enough to constitute it as, in its fundamental char- acter, an economic association. We must recognize, then, not only that the forms of association vary constantly from day to day, but also that even the essential forms vary over longer THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 65 periods. Our classification therefore has reference, not to all social situations, but to the social situation of the civilized communities of our own day. Even so it is necessarily imperfect ; for the institutions of revolutionized Russia and Hungary require, in some respects, a new classification, and a revolution else- where in civilized countries may compel a general amendment of the classification which is adopted here. The nearer we approach in this book to the study of actual social organizations, the more limited and inadequate we shall necessarily find our generalizations to become. It will be a part of our object in this chapter, not merely to describe the outstanding forms of association in our own day and generation, but to attempt, to some extent, to discriminate between essential and non-essential forms. This is, of course, a matter of degree, and no definite line can be drawn. There are, however, apart from doubtful cases, certain forms of association which can fitly be described as essential to Society, and certain others which are not essential to Society. It must be made clear at the outset that this discrimination does not imply any moral valuation. All associa- tions must finally be judged and valued by their service to the individuals who are members of the community, and it may well be found that some of the associations which are here classified as non- essential are of transcendent value to the individual. This, however, is not the question with which I am here concerned. It is purely with social essen- tiality that our classification deals. That is to say, a part of my present purpose is to discriminate 66 SOCIAL THEORY between those associations which form an integral part of the organized coherence of Society, from those which, however great their value, are not in this sense integral and essential to organized Society. The meaning and purpose of this discrimination will emerge more clearly at a later stage. We may reasonably expect to find the essential forms of association among those forms which are outstanding, and occur to the mind naturally as typical forms. It does not follow by any means that all outstanding forms are essential: I have only said that essential forms are likely to be out- standing. We must begin, then, with at least a partial classification of outstanding forms. This classification cannot be entirely simple in character; for there are two different principles on which it must be based. We have to consider both (a) the content of the interest which the association sets before itself; and (b) its method of operation in relation to that interest. The first of these principles is of supreme importance in revealing the interrelation in Society of the various forms of association, that is, their specific, functions; the sec- ond is of primary importance in discriminating be- tween essential and non-essential forms. According to the first of these two ways of classi- fication, we have to distinguish between associations according to the content of their various interests. Here the chief forms which emerge at once into view are the political, the vocational and appetitive, the religious, the provident, the philanthropic, the sociable, and the theoretic. There are others; but THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 67 most of the prevalent forms of association fall un- der one or another of these heads. Of some of the more important forms of political association we shall have much more to say in the next chapter, when we deal with the State and kindred forms of association and institution. We must, however, say something of them here. By a political association I mean an association of which the main purpose is to deal with those personal relationships which arise directly out of the fact that men live together in communities, and which require, and are susceptible to, social organization. I freely admit that it is almost impossible to define accurately or clearly the nature and functions of political association, and I must make it plain that nothing that is said in this chapter is intended to prejudge the question, discussed in the next chapter, whether the State, for instance, can be regarded as a purely political association in the sense here given to the word. That is a very big question indeed; but it does not affect the present issue. I am here, and throughout this book, using the term "political" in a definite and limited sense, in which it is contrasted with vocational, religious and other functional terms. A political association, then, is an association of which the purposes and interests are primarily "political" in the sense defined above. The defi- nition includes not only the State qua association, and the various less extensive regional and local authorities operating as political bodies within the geographical area included in a State, but also, as we shall see, in a secondary sense, many other forms 68 SOCIAL THEORY of association which are also "political" in their interest a political party or society or any bodies concerned with the advocacy of any form of political doctrine or policy. Parliament, and the County Borough of Smethwick, in so far as they are asso- ciations, fall, in this classification, under the same heading as the Liberal Party or the Anti- Vaccina- tion League. A vocational association may be defined as an association consisting of persons who are and whose purpose or interest in the association is directly and primarily concerned with the production, distribu- tion or exchange of some commodity, or the render- ing of some service, or with some question or course of action directly subordinate to one or more of these interests. It thus includes the whole range of professional and occupational association, from that of manual workers to that of technicians and ex- perts, and to that of employers and traders and capi- talists. A Trade Union, a professional institute or society, an Employers' Association, a Limited Com- pany, the British Empire Producers' Organization, the British Medical Association, and the National Union of Teachers are all instances of vocational association. It will have been noticed that, in the preliminary list of the main forms of association under this classification, vocational association was specially linked with another form, which, for want of a bet- ter word, I am forced to call appetitive. It must be made clear at once that the word is not used in any bad or derogatory sense. By appetitive associations I mean those bodies whose members' primary con- THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 69 cern in the association is not, as in the case of voca- tional associations, with production or the rendering of service, but with consumption and use, that is, with the securing of a supply on fair terms of the commodities produced and the services rendered by, or under the auspices of, vocational associations. The consumers' Cooperative Movement, the Rail- way Season-Ticket Holders' Association, the Com- mercial Gas Users' Association, and the Parents' National Educational Union are all examples of ap- petitive association. This form, it will readily be seen, is mainly complementary to vocational associa- tion, the two forms corresponding to the double re- lations of buying and selling, demand and supply, re- ceiving and giving. Different schools of social propagandists lay very different stresses upon the relative importance of these two complementary forms of association. It is perhaps necessary barely to notice here a point which will be more fully dealt with in later chapters. There are certain schools of thought which regard the State, and with it the local author- ities, as primarily associations of consumers and users, that is to say as, in our sense, appetitive asso- ciations. Similarly, some schools of Communists regard the Commune as primarily an association of producers and service Tenderers, that is, in our sense, a vocational association. These theories lead directly to different views as to the proper constitution of State or Commune; but, as they do not affect our present classification, consideration of them can be postponed till a later stage. We come next to those forms of association which 70 SOCIAL THEORY can be called religious. These include not only or- ganized Churches and Connections, but also propa- gandist movements which aim at securing a religious object, such as the "Life and Liberty Movement" within the Church of England. As we shall have much more to say of them later, they need not de- tain us here. The next important form of association is the provident, in which a number of persons join to- gether for mutual assistance, whether under a defi- nite scheme of contributions and benefits for certain purposes, or for a less rigid and definite form of mutual help or beneficence. A Friendly Society, or other mutual insurance associations, whether among workers or among capitalists in a particular trade (e.g. shipping), or among teachers or clergymen, or on a basis which takes no account of occupation, falls under this head. Many Insurance Companies are, of course, not provident and mutual, but profit- making concerns, which belong to the sphere of vo- cational organization ; but the great Friendly Socie- ties with their millions of members afford a large- scale example of real provident associations. Trade Unions also are, of course, in their aspect of benefit societies, assignable to this class of association. Closely allied to provident associations in certain respects, though very different from them in others, are the many associations which exist not for the securing of benefits for their own members, but for the conferring of benefits on other people. Charit- able Societies of whatever type, whether they actu- ally confer benefits or merely meddle with other peo- ple's affairs, and associations which deal with moral THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 71 rather than material benefits for others, can be grouped together under this head. Philanthropic will serve for a name for this very mixed class. Next conies what is perhaps the largest of all groups of associations, those of a purely or mainly sociable character. These are found in their pure form in the vast number of football clubs, cricket clubs, athletic associations, whist clubs, dancing clubs, workmen's clubs, "clubmen's" clubs, night clubs, and all the other types of associations devoted purely to objects of sport, recreation and sociability. Mixed forms are also frequently found. Constitu- tional Clubs, Liberal Clubs, Labor Clubs and many others are sociable in character, but are confined to persons holding similar opinions, and partake in some small degree of the nature of political as- sociations. Purely sociable associations often fed- erate with other associations of the same kind; but generally speaking they are, if their federations and tournaments are included, sufficient unto themselves. Except when licensing or gaming laws are under consideration, or some particularly ardent campaign for public morality is in progress, they mix little, as a rule, in the affairs of Society. All the forms of association mentioned above are in a definite sense practical and aim at the taking of certain overt forms of action, whether adminis- trative propagandist, or purely recreative. This is not the case with the only remaining form of asso- ciation with which we shall here concern ourselves, the theoretical form. This includes learned and sci- entific societies of every type, whatever their object of study and discussion. As learning and science 72 SOCIAL THEORY have a definite bearing on many practical affairs, theoretic associations often tend to approximate to one or another of the practical types, or to possess a mixed character. Moreover, vocational associa- tions, especially among technicians concerned with a common body of knowledge, often pursue theoreti- cal as well as practical ends. Many discuss both the economic and other claims of their members and the status of their profession, and also the theoretic aspects of the science which they profess. Again, the close relation between industry and science gives rise to associations, half practical and half theo- retical, concerned with the application of scientific results and methods to industrial problems. The numerous Industrial Research Associations which have sprung up in recent years are examples of this hybrid form. So far we have been following entirely the first of the two principles of classification with which we set out and distinguishing associations accord- ing to the content of their respective interests. We have now to take up our other principle, and to survey associations briefly according to their method of operation.. We saw, in speaking of political, and again of religious, associations, that they in- cluded not only such bodies as States and Churches respectively, but also all manner of other societies, the content of whose purpose was political or re- ligious. Our second principle will make plain the difference between, say, a State and a political party, or the Church of England and the "Life and Liberty Movement" which aims at its regenera- tion. The difference in both those cases is that THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 73 States and Churches are alike mainly administrative, whereas political parties and movements among Churchmen are mainly propagandist. By an administrative association I mean an asso- ciation which is primarily concerned, not with the advocacy of any particular opinion, but with the doing of some particular job, the arranging and conducting of some particular part of the work which has to be done in Society. This work may be done in many different ways and with many varying degrees of success. Thus the State may be governed by the Unionist Party, the Liberal Party, or the Labor Party, or by a Coalition; but the primary concern of the State is not with Tory- ism or Liberalism or Labor, but with the doing of certain definite jobs with the work to be done, and not with the days of doing it. All the forms of association mentioned in our previous classification include administrative asso- ciations, which are indeed primary in every group. Not only States and Churches, but also Trade Unions, Limited Companies, cricket clubs, Friendly Societies, charitable associations, scientific societies, Cooperative Societies and the rest are principally administrative in function, that is to say, they exist not for the spreading of opinion, but for the doing of things. In a very real sense, administra- tive associations are primary, where propagandist associations are only secondary, and it is among the administrative associations that we shall fine the es- sential social associations of which we are in search. Propagandist associations have already been de- fined by inference. They are those associations 74 SOCIAL THEORY which exist not so much for the doing of a par- ticular job, as for advocating that the job should be done in a particular way, that a particular policy or constitution should be adopted by the primary association concerned with the doing of it. Propa- gandist associations are secondary, because they exist, not in order to do things themselves, but to persuade primary associations and individuals into a particular course of action. There is thus a sense in which they aim at their own extinction; for, when their policy is completely adopted, they cease to have a reason for existence, unless they find a new policy or remain in being in order to see that the results already achieved are maintained. They may, as a whole, be very necessary to Society ; .but no particular propagandist association is essential to the structure of Society. Of course, I am not denying that all associations, however propagandist, possess, in a secondary sense, an administrative character, or that most administrative associations also partake, in a similar sense, of the propagandist character. But the dis- tinction none the less holds; for the fact that no association at all can exist without being confronted by internal administrative problems does not make the main purpose of the association administrative. Similarly, the fact that an association engages in certain forms of propagandist activity does not give it a propagandist character. The projected estab- lishment of a Propaganda Department of State would not make the State a mainly propagandist association. We are now in a position to pursue rather further THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 75 our quest of the essential forms of social associa- tion, not necessarily those essential for all time, but those essential in our own day and civilization. It has already been made clear that the term "essen- tial" is not meant simply to imply any moral valua- tion, and that it is purely social essentiality with which we are here concerned. The key to essential- ity is thus the performance of some function which is vital to the coherent working of Society, and with- out which Society would be lop-sided or incomplete. We have seen that no particular propagandist asso- ciation can be regarded as essential in this sense ; for, although propaganda performs a highly desirable function in keeping individuals and associations "up to the scratch," they are not themselves concerned with the direct execution of vital social functions. Propagandist association in general is, no doubt, es- sential; but no particular propagandist association can claim essentiality except under one condition. This condition is the atrophy or perversion of an essential administrative association or institution. Where this occurs, and the administrative body fails to perform its function, propagandist organization may be, for the moment, the only way of recalling it to its function or, failing that, calling a new body into being in its place. The propagandist association is not, and can hardly become, this new body; but it may be temporarily essential as a means. This, however, is only a partial exception to a rule which holds good in general. It is among administrative associations that the essential forms must be sought. But not all such forms of associa- 76 SOCIAL THEORY tion are essential. Society can do without any par- ticular form of sociable association, as it can do without any propagandist association, and although it cannot do without sociable association as a whole. The same applies to provident and philanthropic and also to theoretic associations. Religious association, on the other hand, must probably be regarded as essential to almost every existing Society, because religion as a personal emotion and belief is widely diffused in almost every existing community. The position of religious associations in Society is, how- ever, as we shall see later, peculiar because of their fundamentally and exclusively spiritual function. 1 We are left with the three forms of political, vocational and appetitive association. Each of these must, I think, be regarded as essential. Each deals with a vital aspect of Social organization, with an "interest" vital to the mass of the members of the community, and each is based upon a deep-rooted and vital instinct of association. It is mainly on the right relationship of these three forms of association that the coherent organization of Society depends. I cannot hope to make this point absolutely clear at the present stage; but I believe that it will emerge with increasing clearness in the course of subsequent chapters. Even if we hold that a particular form of associa- tion is essential, this is not by itself enough to es- tablish the essentiality of any single association be- longing to that class. Within each of the essential forms we may expect to find, in any particular stage of social development, certain actual associations 'See Chapter XI. 77 which can be regarded as essential ; but, in order to establish this, it is necessary to consider not only the form of any association in question, but also its particular content and the motives which animate its members in their common action. Not every association which is administrative in character and political in content is sufficiently important to merit the character of essentiality. For this it must have a particular function which is vital enough to sub- stantiate its claim. Thus, the State may be an essential association; but, to take an extreme in- stance, it is by no means clear that the unnatural aggregation which we call a Rural District Council can claim the same privilege. Again, in the voca- tional sphere, it is essential that producers should be organized; but it does not follow that each par- ticular Trade Union or Employers' Association can claim essentiality. The final test of essentiality is practical, and cannot be made by any abstract or scientific procedure. There is, however, one further important test to which associations for essentiality can be subjected. In our preliminary discussion of the nature of as- sociation, 1 we attempted a distinction between dif- ferent types of motive which animate men in asso- ciation. We drew a distinction between "several" and "associative" motives, and discussed in some detail .the bearings of this distinction on the social import of associations. We saw that "associative" wants and motives far more easily engendered a sense of community than "several" wants, and there- fore gave the association animated by them a higher 1 See ante, p. 34. 78 SOCIAL THEORY status and made it, so far, a greater factor in the making of Society. Our subsequent examination of the main forms of association has placed us in a position to appreciate more fully the bearing of this distinction upon social theory, and also to develop it somewhat further. The mere fact that an association is animated mainly by truly "associative" motives and interests is not enough to establish the fact that it is fulfilling a useful function in Society. For the "associative" want which it seeks to fulfill, however "associative" it may be, is so far only a want of the members of the association, and may still be contrary to the general interest of the community. An "associa- tively" motived association, therefore, is not neces- sarily a socially useful association. But as it is the case that there is such a thing as general social well-being, it is clear that the interests of the members of a community do run together more than they clash. The members of a community have, ex hypothesi, a sense of unity and social re- lationship, and, while they often organize in groups which are opposed on particular points, there is a prima facie reason for supposing that, in the ma- jority of cases, where they cooperate on an associa- tive basis for the fulfilling of a want which they can only enjoy in common, the fulfillment of that want is in the general interest. Moreover, as the community can only find an organized expression even so always a partial expression through social associations and institutions, it is clear that asso- ciations based on an associative want must be the main ingredients in the Society. In them, men THE FORMS OF ASSOCIATION 79 learn to cooperate closely and constantly; and close and constant cooperation in the joint fulfillment of a common object, though it is not necessarily to be identified with the fulfillment of a socially useful function, is the chief means by which men can learn how to fulfill such functions. It is not, however, generally possible to discrimi- nate sharply between associations or forms of asso- ciations, and to say that in this association or form the basis is purely "several," and in the other, purely "associative." Almost every association is, as we have seen, a medley of different motives, and is partly "several," and only in part truly "associa- tive." But, in proportion as an association finds and fulfills its function in Society, the "associative" basis tends to become predominant, and the mo- tive of "severalty" sinks into the background. The best instance I can find of this may strike many readers as being highly controversial; but I cite as clearly illustrating my meaning and expressing my own profound belief. A Trade Union used to be defined as "a continuous association of wage-earners for the purpose of maintaining or improving their conditions of employment." Such a definition al- most implies the complete dominance of "severalty" in the motives animating the members of the asso- ciation. But, in our own day, whatever its justifica- tion in the past, this definition has become clearly inadequate; for the increasing tendency of Trade Unionists to claim for their associations not merely better conditions, but a definite place in the control of industry, plainly implies an emergence of truly "associative" motives, and, in my own opinion, rep- 80 SOCIAL THEORY resents a substantial development of Trade Union- ism towards the performance of its proper social function. Be this as it may, it is clear that, as an association changes and develops, it may change its motives as well as its purposes, and may pass from a stage in which "severalty" is predominant to one in which it is mainly actuated by "associative" motives. This is an indication, though it is not a proof, that the association is moving towards the discovery of its true function in Society. This chapter has dealt entirely with the forms and motives of association, and has only once or twice cursorily mentioned the working of institu- tions as distinct from associations. I have made this omission advisedly, not because institutions are not important, but because we have not yet reached the stage at which it is possible to deal adequately with them. This we shall be able to do only when we liave examined successively the political, voca- tional and appetitive (especially the economic), and religious structure of Society, in which institutions mainly appear. Upon this part of our inquiry we can now embark without further delay. CHAPTER V THE STATE WHAT is the State? And what is its function in Society and in the community? These questions appear to us already in a different light from that in which they appear in most books on Social Theory. They are still vital problems; but they are no longer the center of the whole problem of community. The State, however im- portant, is and can be for us no more than the greatest and most permanent association or in- stitution in Society, and its claim even to any such position will have to be carefully con- sidered. We must bear in mind throughout our considera- tion that it is not a question of The State, a sin- gle unique entity existing alone in a circumambient void, but of "States" existing in many different communities at different stages of development, and entering into the most varied relationships one with another. When we speak of "the State," therefore, we are only using a class-name to which we can attach our generalizations as predicates. We are ignoring non-essential differences between one State and another, and concentrating on those essential characteristics which States have in common. 81 82 SOCIAL THEORY This, however, is to give too inclusive and gen- eralized a scope to our treatment of the subject. Although we shall sometimes be referring to char- acteristics common to all States at all times and stages of development, we shall be using in the main for purposes of illustration "the modern State," that is, the States which exist in our own time and stage of civilization. Taking the nature common to these States as our basis, we shall attempt to arrive, from the study of their common nature, at some conception of their true function in the Society of to-day and to-morrow. Further than that we can hardly hope to go; for a new genera- tion and a new degree of social development will inevitably call for a restatement of social theory. Let us begin with a brief summary and analysis of the principal activities of the modern State, that is, of the States which exist in civilized communities in the world of to-day. Here, again, it would, of course, be useful to attempt a complete and ex- haustive enumeration. Nor is it necessary to our purpose, which is only that of securing sufficient ma- terial to work upon in our attempt to discover the State's function in the Society of to-day. As we saw in our discussion of the principle of function, it is far from being the case that every actual activity of the State forms a part of its social function; but it is the case that the function of the State can only be sought among activities which the State does, in some degree, already exercise. In order to discover the function of the State, it is therefore necessary to adopt a double procedure. We have first to ex- amine, and select from, the actual activities of the THE STATE 83 State those which are, prima facie, essential, and we have then to examine the fundamental nature and constitution of the State with a view to determining which of these essential activities can be regarded as belonging to its function. It is a commonplace observation that during the last two generations at least the activities of the State have been undergoing constant and rapid mul- tiplication and expansion. Moreover, it is gener- ally recognized that this expansion has been far more extensive in the economic than in any other sphere. When Locke wrote his Treatises on Civil Government, interpreting in them the ideas and so- cial situation of the English Revolution of 1688-9, it was still easy to regard the function of the State as strictly specific and limited, because its actual activities were in the main specific and limited, and were in process of actual construction. To-day, whatever may be the true function of the State, there is an undeniable temptation to conclude, on the basis of its actual activities, that its functions are practically universal and unlimited. Such a con- clusion, whether it be right or wrong, at least goes with the grain of present-day Society. Yet it may be that Locke was nearer to being right than those social theorists who are ready to conclude, because the State does everything in fact, that its social function is pantopragmatic and universal. To-day, almost every developed State is cease- lessly active in economic affairs. It passes Factory Acts, and other legislation designed to ensure a minimum of protection to the workers engaged in production: it regulates wages and hours: it at- 84 SOCIAL THEORY tempts to provide for and against unemployment: it intervenes, successfully or unsuccessfully, in in- dustrial disputes: it compels employers to provide compensation for accidents, and both employers and workers to contribute to social insurance funds which it administers. On the other hand, it regu- lates to some extent the commercial operations of financiers and employers, restricts or pretends to restrict trusts and profiteering, uses its consular service and special agents to aid foreign trade, en- courages, subsidizes and assists in industrial re- search, enact laws affecting, and enters into many formal and informal relationships with capitalist in- terests and associations. Moreover, more and more it embarks itself upon economic enterprises, con- ducts a Post Office or a railway service, and be- comes the direct employer of vast numbers of its own citizens, incidentally often imposing political and other disqualifications upon them on the ground that they are State employees. To all this industrial and commercial activity of the national State must be added the no less com- plex activities of local authorities acting under the laws enacted by the State municipal and other lo- cal by-laws regulating industry and commerce, and the extending operations of "municipal trading." It will, however, be more convenient to consider the character and activities of local authorities sepa- rately at a later stage, although no clear or hard and fast line can be drawn between a State and a local authority in those cases where "federal," "Do- minion" or even "regionalist" forms of government exist. THE STATE 85 There is a further economic activity of the State which is more and more becoming manifest in our own day. Taxation is, in its origin, merely a method of collecting from individuals that proportion of their incomes which must be diverted from their per- sonal use to meet the necessary expenses of State administration. But, as the activities of the State expand, taxation shows a marked tendency to be- come also a method of redistributing incomes within the community. This new tendency emerges already in systems of graduated taxation; but it becomes the leading principle in those proposals, nowhere yet carried far into effect, which aim at its definite and deliberate use as a means to at least comparative equality of income. 1 Apart from taxation for administrative purposes, the present economic activities of the State are largely of recent growth. This is not to say that the State had not previously engaged in economic action on a large scale, as for instance under what is known as the "Mercantile System." But between the "Mercantile System" and the economic activity of the modern State intervenes in many cases a period of comparative inactivity laissez faire fol- lowing upon the changes caused by the Industrial Revolution. In the Middle Ages, when economic activities were largely in the hands of the Guilds, and in the period of the Industrial Revolution, when they were largely in the hands of competitive capi- 1 The State Bonus Scheme, actively advocated by Mr. Dennis Milner and his colleagues of the State Bonus League, is an advanced example of this tendency. It is a definite proposal for a redistribution by the State, on a basis of equality, of a considerable proportion of the communal income. 86 SOCIAL THEORY talists, the State's intervention in economic matters was, comparatively, very restricted indeed. Extensive as the economic activities of the State are, it will be agreed that they have not yet, in any actual State, reached an essentially central position. This might occur, and would probably occur if the pure Collectivists had their way; but, for the pres- ent, the central position is still occupied by politi- cal and coordinating rather than by economic ac- tivities, although the latter constantly threaten the position of the two former. Our next inquiry must be into the nature of the political activities of the State. The word "political" is one round which a high degree of ambiguity has gathered. It has very va- rious associations, with the n6Xis, or City-State, of the Greeks, with the modern Nation-State, with the whole complex of social action, with purely party and parliamentary activities, and so forth. Here I am using the word in a definite and specific sense. I mean by political activities those activi- ties which are concerned with the social regulation of those personal relationships which arise directly out of the fact that men live together in communi- ties, and which are susceptible to direct social or- ganization. 1 In this, as in many other cases, it is easier and perhaps more illuminating, to illustrate than to de- fine. What, we must ask, are the main types of actual political activity exercised by the State ? Marriage is at once a civil and a religious institu- tion. The State regulates the relations between in- 1 See ante, p. 67, for political association. THE STATE 87 dividuals by enacting laws dealing with marriage and its dissolution, the care of children, the conduct arising out of sexual relationships in all their forms. It makes laws for the prevention and punishment of crime, for the care and treatment of lunatics, the feeble-minded and others who are not in a position to look after themselves. It is vitally concerned with many relationships quite apart from sex crime or abnormality, and constantly lays down rules of convenience and convention for the guidance of men in their mutual relationships. If it covers any con- siderable area or includes any large number of in- habitants, it must recognize or establish local au- thorities similar to itself but with more limited powers, and makes general rules for the guidance of these bodies in their various activities. In fact, it is concerned mainly with personal rights and the means of reconciling them, and with those limita- tions of personal conduct which are essential to the existence of a coordinated system of personal rights. Where classes exist in the community, the State often exercises further political activity in sustain- ing, recognizing, and modifying class privileges and class exclusions. It creates, say, a peerage, and from time to time elevates the latest exalted servant of the public, .or newspaper proprietor, or nouveau riche, to membership of the peerage. It enacts spe- cial privileges for one class or another, or passes special legislature discriminating against a class. In the extreme case, its political activity assumes the form of a class dictatorship. This is the bad side of the State's political activity. 88 SOCIAL THEORY Thirdly, the State of to-day possesses increasingly important activities of coordination. It is largely concerned in adjusting the relations between asso- ciation and association, or institution and institution, or institution and association, or between other as- sociations or institutions and itself. It enacts laws regulating the form and scope of associative ac- tivity, friendly society law, law affecting banks, companies, partnerships, Trade Unions, clubs, as- sociations of any and every sort. In some degree, it regulates all religious associations, and, in some countries, the existence of an Established Church considerably increases the extent of its religious intervention. There is one theory of the State which regards it as primarily a coordinating body, devoted not to any specific functions of its own, but to the coordinating of the various functional associations within Society. 1 I do not claim that this summary of the activities of States is exhaustive or inclusive, nor do I desire to make it so. It can, with one further develop- ment, be made sufficient for our purpose. I have so far dealt almost entirely with the internal activities of "the State," and ignored its external relations, whether with other States, or with anything wholly or partly outside its geographical boundaries. I have done this because "international" or- external activity cannot be regarded as a particular province of State activity, in the same sense as economic, political and coordinating activities. International action arises in relation to each of these provinces of 1 This view has been often expressed in the columns of the New Age, over the signature "National Guildsmen." THE STATE 89 State activity, and has, besides, special problems of its own. Thus the State takes external economic action in the development of foreign trade, external political action in connection, say, with international provisions regarding crime, marriage, naturaliza- tion, and other questions of personal status and con- venience which involve a measure of activity tran- scending State boundaries. In its activity of coordination, it is confronted with the problem of international association, from the Roman Catholic Church to the Socialist International. These forms of external State action may either lead to quarrels and disagreements between States, or they may bind States together and lead towards a sort of super-State, or at least Society or League of States bound together for the performance of specific functions or the exercise of specific activi- ties. Hitherto, the external actions of States have been far more fertile in disagreement than in organ- ized cooperation ; but it does not follow that this will always be the case. Indeed, a proper understand- ing and adjustment of the internal functions of the State will be likely to exercise a profound and benef- icent action upon its relations with other States, and to set it upon the road of organized interna- tional cooperation which other forms of associa- tion are more forward in following than the State has been in the past. A full discussion of the external aspects of State action, however, would be foreign to our present purpose, which is in the main that of disentangling the true functions of the State from the network of its present activities. By what test can we so test 90 SOCIAL THEORY these activities as to make the real nature and func- tion of the State stand out from among them clear and well-defined? The first step in applying our test must be to investigate the State from a dif- ferent point of view, to regard it in the light, not of its activities, but of its structure and composition. We may then hope, by bringing its activities into relation to its structure, to discover its function in the complex of organized Society. How, then, is the State composed? And what is its structural principle? These are not easy ques- tions to answer, because any attempt to answer them is likely to open at once large controversial ques- tions. Moreover, the structure of different States, or of the same State at different times, appears to be essentially different. What is there in com- mon between the structure of a pure despotism, in which a monarch is supposed to possess absolute and unlimited power, and a State in which all power rests, at any rate in theory, upon the consent and active cooperation of the whole body of the people ? It must be noted that the activities of a "des- potic" and of a "democratic" State may be iden- tical, while their structural principles seem to be vi- tally different. But are their structural principles as fundamentally different as they seem? Every despotism which seeks at all to justify its existence seeks to do so on one or another of three princi- ples. Either it claims to be based upon "divine right and appointment" of the ruler, or it claims to be acting in the interests of the ruled, and there- fore in conformity with their real will, or it claims THE STATE 91 to be based upon the actual consent of the ruled, tacit or expressed. With despotisms which do not seek to justify their existence we are not concerned, since in them it is manifest that social obligation, on which the possibility of a coherent Society de- pends, is not present. We are left, then, with three possible justifica- tions of despotism, and it must be admitted that all three finally reduce themselves to a common form the consent, in one form or another, of the ruled. This is clear in the third form of the theory of despotism, which is based on actual consent. In the second form, the consent is not actual, but un- less it is real and justification fails. It depends upon the metaphysical conception of the "real will," different from the actual will and willing always the good. It claims, in fact, to be the consent of the "better selves" of the ruled. The third theory, that of divine right, seems at first sight to have nothing to do with human consent; but if God has willed that a man shall be king, it is clear that the "better selves" of all men have willed this too, and that, if divine right is established, universal consent ought to follow as a matter of course. Any attempt to justify a despotic State therefore brings us back to the same principle as that on which "democratic" States are usually justified the consent of the ruled. It is true that in a despotism this consent cannot, unless the despotic is elected, pass beyond acquiescence, whereas in democracy consent may become, and in real democ- racy must become, active cooperation. Still, a com- 92 SOCIAL THEORY mon ground of principle has been established, and the State, whatever its form of power, is seen to rest on the consent of those who are its citizens, subjects, members or human constituents. If once the principle of consent is established as the basis of the State, it is impossible to set limits to the operation of the principle. If the members consent to despotism, well and good; but as soon as they desire to assume a more active cooperation in the affairs of State, they have clearly a right to do so. The fullest democracy in action is only the logical development of the principle of consent, ex- panded by the application of actual human wills that is, of the will to self-government. If this is so, we can safely take the "democratic State'" as the developed form of "the State," and expect, in laying bare its structure, to lay bare the structure of States in general. The only obstacle in the way of our immediately adopting this course is the metaphysical doctrine of the real "will" a doctrine which we shall again and again encounter as an influence obscuring our attempt to study the character of social organization. If the doctrine of a real will different from any- body's actual will is accepted, all arguments for democracy, that is government by the actual wills of the ruled, go by the board. But so equally do all arguments for everything else; for we are left without means of ascertaining the nature or content of this real will. The content of actual wills we can know up to a point: the content of the real will we cannot know at all. We can only know what we believe to be good, and thereupon, by a THE STATE 93 quite gratuitous assumption, assume our conception of the good to be the content of everybody's real will. Or, if we are not quite sure ourselves that we know all the good, we can stand back astonished at the magnitude of the State and its works, and say that anything so big must be good. Many idealist social theorists have virtually done this, and made of the doctrine of the real will, in its ap- plication to social theory, no more than a colos- sally fraudulent justification of "things as they are." x I shall content myself with leaping rather lightly over this metaphysical obstacle, referring my read- ers to the book of Professor Hobhouse, and reserv- ing the matter for fuller treatment at a later stage. I shall assume, then, that actual wills are real wills, or at least near enough to reality to be going on with, and I shall therefore assume that the basis of the State's structure is to be found in the actual consent of its members. But here we encounter our first real difficulty. Who are the members of the State, and, indeed, can the State be said to have any members? I am using the word "members" because it is the most neutral word I can find. We usually speak of "citizens" or "subjects"; but one of these words has about it the implication of despotism and the other that of the actual exercise of political rights. I therefore avoid them for the present, because I 1 For an excellent onslaught upon some such theories, see The Metaphysical Theory of the State, by L. T. Hobhouse. For an awful example of them, see the writings of Dr. Ber- nard Bosanquet. 94 SOCIAL THEORY want to avoid equally for the present both these implications. The State, as an association, has members, and its members are all the persons ordinarily resident within the area within which the State ordinarily exercises authority. Such persons are members of the State, whether or not they have votes or other political privileges, by virtue merely of their ordi- nary residence within the State area. For the State is, for the dwellers within its area, a compulsory association, and its compulsory character is re- vealed in two ways in its power to compel all per- sons in its area, and in the right of all such per- sons to membership of it. When we say that the State rests upon consent, we mean that it rests upon the consent of an effective proportion of all the dwellers within its area. Membership of the State is, however, an almost barren theory without recognized political rights for without such rights a member can only make his voice heard in time of revolution, when the ordinary procedure of the State is in abeyance. What right, we must ask, does membership of the State give to the recognition of actual political rights? The answer is partly implied in what we have said already of consent as the basis of the State. The members of the State have the right to translate a passive consent into an active coopera- tion by the assumption of political rights. This they habitually do by gradually extending the fran- chise and other political rights to new sections of the population, as these sections become articulate in advancing their claim. The logical completion THE STATE 95 of this development is universal suffrage as the ex- pression of a political articulateness generally dif- fused through all sections of the people. I shall take, then, as the basis of examination of the structure of the State, a State possessing the institution of universal suffrage. What is the struc- tural principle of such a State? Regarded as a whole, it is a compulsory association including all the dwellers within a particular area. Its basis is therefore territorial and inclusive, whereas the basis of a Trade Union is vocational and selective. The essence of the State is to include all sorts of people, without reference to the sort of people they are, the sort of beliefs they hold, or the sort of work they do. I do not mean, of course, that there is not usually a very important element of identity of character, way of life, and even occupation, among the mem- bers of a particular State. This element of identity is strongest in the City-State, and very strong in the State whose area is the area of a Nation. But it is not the essential principle of the State form of grouping. There are States which are not coterm- inous with Nations, and State and Nation are essentially different things. A Nation may be a community, but it cannot be, though it may pos- sess, a State. A Nation is not an association; a State is. The State, then, is an inclusive territorial asso- ciation, ignoring differences between men and com- pulsorily taking in every one who ordinarily dwells within its area. This being its principle, how can we 96 SOCIAL THEORY discover its function? The answer will be found by asking and answering a further question. Why does the State ignore the differences between men and include all sorts and conditions, and what is the sphere of action, or social function, marked out for it by the adoption of this structure? It ignores the differences between men because it is concerned not with their differences, but with their identity, and its function and interest are concerned with men's identity and not with their differences. Objectively stated, this principle takes the following form. The concern of the State, as an association including all sorts and conditions of men, is with those things which concern all sorts and conditions of men, and concern them, broadly speaking, in the same way, that is, in relation to their identity and not to their points of difference. The State exists primarily to deal with those things which affect all its members more or less equally and in the same way. Let us try to see clearly what are the effects of this principle. It excludes from the primary functions of the State from its social function par excellence those spheres of social action which affect different mem- bers of it in different degrees and in various ways. This does not mean that the State must not concern itself with any such spheres of action, but only that they do not form part of its primary function, and may fall within the functions of other forms of as- sociation. We are not concerned as yet so much with limiting the province of the State as with dis- covering what is its undisputed and peculiar sphere of activity. THE STATE 97 Let us look back now to the point from which we set out to our brief account of the existing activi- ties of the State. Which of these activities clearly correspond to the definition we have just given, and are, by their correspondence, clearly marked out as essential activities of the State. We divided the actual activities of the State into three main di- visions economic, political and coordinative. Let us first look at each of these three divisions in gen- eral and as a whole, proceeding to a further analysis of them as we find it to be required. Economic activities for the most part clearly af- fect the various members of the community 1 in dif- ferent degrees and in various ways. For it is here that one of the most easily recognizable and organiz- able differences between man and man comes into play. Coal mining affects the coal miner in quite a different way from that in which it affects the rest of the people, and so through the whole list of trades and vocations. Of course, coal mining does affect not only the miner, but also everybody else; but the point is that it affects the miner in a different manner and degree. Here, however, a difficulty at once arises. Each trade or vocation affects those who follow it in a different way and degree from the way and degree in which it affects others ; but many vital industries and services do also, from another point of view, affect almost everybody in very much the same way. 1 1 use the terms "members of the community" and "mem- bers of the State" indifferently, assuming that the geographi- cal area of the community coincides with that of the State. The argument is not affected. 98 SOCIAL THEORY We must all eat and drink, be clothed, housed and warmed, be tended in sickness and educated in childhood and youth, and our common needs in these and other respects give rise to a common rela- tion, that of consumers or users of the products and service rendered by those who follow the various trades and vocations concerned. It is upon the fact that the Collectivist theory of the State is based. The Collectivists, or State So- cialists, regard the State as an association of con- sumers, and claim for it supremacy in the economic sphere on the ground that consumption, at least in relation to the vital industries and services, is a matter that concerns everybody equally and in the same way. This, however, is to ignore a difference as vital as the identity on which stress is laid. The most that can be claimed for the State in the eco- nomic sphere on account of the identical interest of all the members of the community in consumption is State control of consumption, and not State control of production, in which the interests of different members of the community are vitally different. The economic sphere thus falls at once into two separable parts production and consumption, in one of which all interests tend to be identical, while in the other, production, they tend to be different. Consumption is thus marked off as falling, prima facie, within the sphere of the State, while produc- tion is no less clearly marked off as falling out- side it. We shall have to pursue this question further at a later stage, when we examine directly the eco- nomic structure of Society. There is, however, one THE STATE 99 question, arising immediately out of this distinction, with which we must deal at the present stage. We saw in our summary of State activities that taxation tends to become, and to be regarded as, not merely a means of raising revenue for public purposes, but a means of redistributing the national income. May not this tendency provide the key to the State's function in relation to consumption? If there is one thing in the economic sphere which affects every- body equally and in the same way it is the question of income, on which the nominal amount of con- sumption depends. Closely bound up with this is the question of price, which, in its relation to in- come, determines the real amount of consumption. Income and prices, then, seem to fall clearly within the province of the State, and the determination of them forms an integral part of the State's functions. The State, then, regulates consumption primarily through income and prices. By these means it acts upon the general level and distribution of consump- tion, and not directly upon the consumption of any particular commodity. It is, however, clear that, in the case of many staple commodities and vital services, not only the general level of consuming power, but also the consumption and supply of a particular commodity or service, affects everybody more or less equally and in the same way. Of course, there are many other commodities whose consumption affects only a part of the people, or af- fects different sections in very unequal measure. In such cases the State has no primary function. Hav- ing regulated the general distribution of consum- ing power, it can leave to ad hoc bodies the expres- 100 SOCIAL THEORY sion of the consumers' point of view in relation to such commodities or services. But in the case of the vital commodities and services which, broadly speaking, affect everybody equally and in the same way, there is a prima facie argument for State regulation, and it is clear that regulation must be done either by the State or by some body or bodies reproducing its structure and similarly based upon general suffrage and an in- clusive and non-selective electorate. The question whether the State or some other body or bodies so constituted should assume these functions depends upon the degree in which the combined performance of political functions and of these specialized eco- nomic functions can be undertaken with satisfac- tory results by the same group of elected persons, or whether it is necessary that the same body of electors should choose different persons and repre- sentative bodies for the performance of functions so essentially different and calling for such different capacities and acquirements. 1 The political activities of the State give rise to no such complex problems as its economic activities. Here the only question that arises in most cases is whether a particular sphere of personal relationship ought to be regulated or left unregulated. If it is to be regulated at all, it falls clearly according to our principle within the proper sphere of the State. * This point is more fully developed in Chapter VI., where it is urged that if a person is chosen to "represent" a body of electors, he can only be a real representative if his function is clearly and specifically limited and defined. See also Intro- duction to Self -Government in Industry (edition of 1919). THE STATE 101 For in personal relationship, whether regulation is based on moral principles or on principles of con- venience, the regulation clearly affects, or should affect, and would but for class and economic dis- tinctions affect, every one equally and in the same way. "Political" activities, then, in the sense which we have given to the phrase, belong clearly to the function of the State. What, then, of activities of coordination, such as we described earlier in this chapter? Here a far greater difficulty arises. To entrust the State with the function of coordination would be to entrust it, in many cases, with the task of arbitrating be- tween itself and some other functional association, say, a Church or a Trade Union. But just as no man ought to be the judge of his own case, so ought no association. Therefore, coordination can- not belong to the function of the State ; but neither can it belong to that of any other functional asso- ciation. We should reach the same conclusion if we ignored the argument against making the State judge in its own cause, and attended only to the nature of coordinating activities. For such activi- ties clearly bring in many questions which do not affect everybody equally and in the same way, but affect various groups in essential different ways. Therefore, once more, we must conclude that the function of coordination does not belong to the State. This is a conclusion of far-reaching and funda- mental importance; for if the State is not the co- ordinating authority within the community, neither 102 SOCIAL THEORY is it, in the sense usually attached to the term, "sov- ereign." But the claim to "Sovereignty" is that on which the most exalted pretensions of the State are based. Almost all modern theories of the State attribute to it not merely a superiority to all other forms of association, but an absolute difference in kind, by virtue of which it is supposed to possess, in theory at least, an unlimited authority over every other association and over every individual in the community. If our account of the nature of the State is cor- rect, its functions must be newly defined and lim- ited in terms of its specific functions, and with this definition and limitation its claim to Sovereignty falls utterly to the ground. We cannot, however, so lightly destroy an almost universally held theoreti- cal position, and, in order to make perfectly plain our reasons for denying it, we must at once embark on a discussion of the closely related questions of democracy and representation. We can then return to our study of the State with a better hope of making the argument perfectly clear. CHAPTER VI DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION THERE is in our own day an almost general prejudice in favor of democracy. Almost everybody is a "democrat," and the name of democracy is invoked in support of the most diverse social systems and theories. This general accept- ance of the name of democracy, even by persons who are obviously not in any real sense "demo- crats," is perhaps largely to be explained by the fact that the idea of democracy has become almost in- extricably tangled up with the idea of representative government, or rather with a particular theory of representative government based on a totally false theory of representation. This false theory is that one man can "represent" another or a number of others, and that his will can be treated as the democratic expression of their wills. Stated in this form, the theory admits of only one answer. No man can represent another man, and no man's will can be treated as a sub- stitute for, or representative of, the wills of others. This may look, at first sight, like a complete denial of every form of representative government, and an affirmation of the futility of all elections. 103 104 SOCIAL THEORY It is, however, nothing of the sort; it is not an attack upon, or an attempt to destroy the theoretic basis of, representative government, but an attempt to restate the theory of representation in a truer form. In order that it may be fully understood, we must bring it into relation to the doctrine of function expounded in previous chapters. We have seen that, just as every action of an individual aims at some specific object, so men form and enter associations in pursuit of specific objects which can be best pursued in common by or through an or- ganized group. Every association, then, has a spe- cific object or objects, and it is in pursuit of some or all of these objects that men consent to be mem- bers of the association. Every association which sets before itself any object that is of more than the most rudimentary simplicity finds itself compelled to assign tasks and duties, and with these powers and a share of au- thority, to some of its members in order that the common object may be effectively pursued. It elects, perhaps, a Secretary, a President, a Treasurer and an Executive Committee, and empowers these per- sons to act on behalf of the association in certain definite ways and within certain limits. In the smaller and more localized associations, much of the control of the proceedings of the association may remain in the hands of the general body of the mem- bers ; but as soon as it becomes too large or too dis- persed for a general meeting to transact business, or if the members are too preoccupied with other affairs to make it their constant concern, the detailed regulation of its proceedings passes largely into the DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 105 hands of a comparatively small number of its mem- bers, officers, committee men, delegates or repre- sentatives. In the largest and most complex forms of association, such as the State, the ordinary mem- ber is reduced to a mere voter, and all the direction of actual affairs is done by representatives or mis- representatives. At the best, representative government gives rise to many inconveniences, to what Walt Whitman described as "the never-ending audacity of elected persons," and Rousseau as "the tendency of all government to deteriorate." With these inconveni- ences we shall have to deal at a later stage; but here we are concerned only to make clear the nature of the representative relation as it exists in such associations as we have spoken of above. In the majority of associations, the nature of the relation is clear enough. The elected person of- ficial, committee man, or delegate makes no pre- tension of substituting his personality for those of his constituents, or of representing them except in relation to a quite narrow and clearly defined pur- pose or group of purposes which the association ex- ists to fulfill. There is, then, in these cases, no ques- tion of one man taking the place of many ; for what the representative professes to represent is not the whole will and personalities of his constituents, but merely so much of them as they have put into the association, and as is concerned with the purposes which the association exists to fulfill. This is the character of all true representation. It is impossible to represent human beings as selves or centers of consciousness; it is quite possible to 106 SOCIAL THEORY represent, though with an inevitable element of dis- tortion which must always be recognized, so much of human beings as they themselves put into asso- ciated effort for a specific purpose. True representation, therefore, like true associa- tion, is always specific and functional, and never general and inclusive. What is represented is never man, the individual, but always certain purposes common to groups of individuals. That theory of representative government which is based upon the idea that individuals can be represented as wholes is a false theory, and destruction of personal rights and social well-being. The fact that a man cannot be represented as a man seems so obvious that it is difficult to under- stand how many theories of government and democ- racy have come to be built upon it. Each man is a center of consciousness and reason, a will pos- sessed of the power of self-determination, an ulti- mate reality. How can one such will be made to stand in place of many? How can one man, being himself, be at the same time a number of other people? It would be a miracle if he could; but it is a risky experiment to base our social system upon a hypothetical miracle. Functional representation is open to no such ob- jection. It does not lay claim to any miraculous quality : it does not profess to be able to substitute the will of one man for the wills of many. Its adherents recognize the element of distortion which exists in all representation; but to them this dis- tortion is not a problem, but an inevitable fact. It does not annihilate or detract from the will of any DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 107 individual ; it merely provides a basis whereby, when the individual has made up his mind that a certain object is desirable, he can cooperate with his fellows in taking the course of action necessary for its at- tainment. Of course, I do not intend to convey the idea that there are just so many functions in Society, and that to each corresponds exactly its own functional as- sociation and form of representation. The need of Society for functional association and representa- tion expands and develops as Society becomes larger and more complex. A special form of asso- ciation and representation, at one time unnecessary, may become necessary as the work of Society in- creases in a particular direction. Moreover, in a very small Society, such as the ancient City-State, where the direct participation of the mass of the people in government was possible, functional asso- ciation was only needed in a very limited degree, and it was often possible for the people to choose directly their functional representatives without any intervening stage of functional association. The principle of representation, however, is the same; the representative represents not persons, but defi- nite and particular purposes common to a number of persons. Having made plain our conception of the true na- ture of representation, we can now look more closely at its consequences. In proportion as the pur- poses for which the representative is chosen lose clarity and definiteness, representation passes into misrepresentation, and the representative character of the acts resulting from association disappears. 108 SOCIAL THEORY Thus, misrepresentation is seen at its worst to-day in that professedly omnicompetent "representative" body Parliament and in the Cabinet which is sup- posed to depend upon it. Parliament professes to represent all the citizens in all things, and therefore as a rule represents none of them in anything. It is chosen to deal with anything that may turn up, quite irrespective of the fact that the different things that do turn up require different types of persons to deal with them. It is therefore peculiarly subject to corrupt, and especially to plutocratic, influences, and does everything badly, because it is not chosen to do any definite thing well. This is not the fault of the actual Members of Parliament; they muddle because they are set the impossible task of being good at everything, and representing everybody in relation to every purpose. There can be only one escape from the futility of our present methods of parliamentary government; and that is to find an association and method of representation for each function, and a function for each association and body of representatives. In other words, real democracy is to be found, not in a single omnicompetent representative assembly, but in a system of coordinated functional represen- tative bodies. There is another, and a simpler, line of argument which leads straight to the same conclusion as we have already reached. It is obvious that different people are interested in, and good at doing, different things. It is therefore equally obvious that, if I am a sensible person, I shall desire to choose different people to represent my wishes in relation to different DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 109 things. To ask me to choose one man to represent me in relation to everything is to insult my intelli- gence, and to offer me every inducement to choose some one so colorless that he is unlikely to do any- thing at all because he will at least probably do no great harm, and no great notice will be taken of him. This is how parliamentary elections usually work out at the present time. But, if I am asked to choose a different person to represent my wishes in relation to each of the main groups of social purposes of which I am conscious, I shall do my best to choose in each case the man who is most fitted to represent my views and to carry them into effect. In short, the one method will in- evitably result in government by the incompetent; the other will at least give every chance for compe- tent representatives to be chosen. Democracy, then, must be conceived in the first place as a coordinated system of functional repre- sentation. But, as soon as we introduce the word "democracy," we raise a further question, that of the relation between me and my functional repre- sentative after I have chosen him. In fact, we find ourselves in the thick of the old controversy of "representative versus delegate." Does our revised theory of representation throw any light upon this controversy? Or, in other words, is the question whether the elected person, once he has been elected, should follow his own will or should be instructed as far as possible on every issue by those who have chosen him, to be an- swered in a different way when the theory of repre- sentation is different? I think the theory of repre- 110 SOCIAL THEORY sentation which we adopt must make a considerable difference to our view of the relation of the elected person to his constituents. In the first place, attempts to make the elected person a mere delegate must always break down, whatever the form of representation. There are many issues on which it is not merely undesirable, but impossible, to tie down a delegate by instruc- tions, because unforeseen situations and complica- tions constantly arise. If for no other reason, pure delegation must break down because the delegate is so often waiting for further instructions that nothing gets done, and the best opportunities for action are continually being missed. On the other hand, pure "representation" without instructions or counsel from the electors approaches very nearly to false representation, substituting, even within a restricted sphere, the will of one for the wills of many. Our functional democracy, based on functional associations and representations, provides a way out of this difficulty. It enables us to combine repre- sentation with constant counsel from the con- stituents, and thus makes it possible to abandon the theory of delegation without imperiling democratic control. The chief difficulty of demo- cratic control over the representative in the political sphere to-day is that, as soon as the voters have exercised their votes, their existence as a group lapses until the time when a new election is re- quired. No body or group remains in being to direct upon the elected person a constant stream of counsel and criticism. Consequently, the elected DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 111 person must receive full instructions at the time of election, which produces an intolerable situation as soon as there is any change in the circumstances, or else he must become a pure representa- tive, acting on his own responsibility and conse- quently expressing only his own will and not those of his constituents. This dilemma exists wherever the body of electors does not remain in being and activity as a body throughout the tenure of office of the elected person. Functional democracy, in which representatives emanate from functional associations which have a permanent being, meets this difficulty. It is no longer necessary for the group to instruct its repre- sentative, because it can continue throughout his time of office to criticise and advise him, and be- cause, I would add, it can at any time recall him if it is not satisfied with the way in which he is doing his job. Recall is, in fact, the final safeguard, while criticism and advice are the normal means of keep- ing the representation democratic. In our own day, experience of bad leaders, both in the State and in other forms of association, has bred an almost general distrust of leadership, and a strong desire, especially on the so-called "left wing," to do away with leaders, and substitute direct control by the "rank and file" through delegates duly in- structed how to act and vote. But there is no reason to take the badness of present-day leaders as a sign that the whole idea of leadership should be given up. Certainly, before we adopt any such drastic expedient, all the circumstances ought to be fully explored. But, at the very beginning of SOCIAL THEORY this explanation, the biggest single cause of the collapse of leadership is plainly to be seen. The absence of any true principle of representation in the sphere of the State, the failure that is to "func- tionalize" the State, and to make the political rep- resentative a functional representative, is the main cause of the perversion of political leadership. But the perversion of political leadership is, in its turn, the main cause of the perversion of leadership elsewhere. The Trade Union leader, and many other "functional" leaders, have their eyes fixed upon Parliament, and the thought of Parliament distracts them from their proper work. Moreover, this parliamentary arriere-pensee is an important factor in causing the wrong leaders to be selected, and the wrong candidates to offer themselves for selection. We must preserve leadership without sacrificing democratic control. Leadership is as vital to a democracy as to an aristocracy or a monarchy. And it is as true in a democracy as anywhere else that the good leader must be given a great deal of rope. In a functional democracy, where the elected person is a representative and not a delegate, and where he acts not as a rule upon instructions, but upon criticism and advice, I believe that the good leader will find ample scope, as soon as the distrust which is born of false democracy has had time to wear off. It is true that he will be liable to sum- mary recall ; but who believes that, after the initial mistakes, this power would be too freely exercised ? The risks are all the other way : it is of a too long DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 113 tenure of office by second-rate men that we should be afraid. Functional democracy will give the good leader his first real chance of leading by his merits, with an instructed and active body of constituents behind him. For it must be remembered that not only will the representative be chosen to do a job about which he knows something, but he will be chosen by persons who know something of it too. Truly a revolutionary proposal for a democrat to make! But some one will object, if I have this respect for leaders why do I insist on the right of recall? I do so, because I have even more respect for human wills and personalities, and because I feel that democracy implies far more than the passive consent of the mass of the people in government. Democ- racy implies active, and not merely passive, citizenship, and implies for everybody at least the opportunity to be an active citizen, not only of the State, but of every association with which his personality or circumstances cause him to be concerned. Those who profess to find the bond of Society in the passive consent of the mass of the people fall between two stools. If the mass of the people are necessary to the justification of the social order, they are necessary in the active and not in the passive mood. In other words, if we base our social theory upon the attitude of the mass of the people, we are logically driven to insist that this attitude ought to be as explicit and positive as possible. A well-organized Society is one in which not merely is the administration good, but the wills of 114 SOCIAL THEORY the members of the community are active, and find expression through the various associations and institutions of which Society is made up. It should be the aim of those who strive to direct the course of social organization to promote the fullest partici- pation of everybody in the work of government. This alone is true democracy, and this can only be secured by the fullest development of functional organization. The current theory of representative government is a denial of this principle ; for, having chosen his representative, the ordinary man has, according to that theory, nothing left to do except to let other people govern him. Functional organiza- tion and representation, on the other hand, imply the constant participation of the ordinary man in the conduct of those parts of the structure of Society with which he is directly concerned, and which he has therefore the best chance of understanding. A man may be pardoned for not quite knowing for whom to vote in a parliamentary election, or how to appraise the career of his Member of Parliament, because the Member of Parliament of to-day is elected not for any clearly defined purpose, but in the void, to deal with anything that may chance to turn up. A functional association, on the other hand, is concerned with doing a definite job, and its officers are also concerned with getting that definite job done. The member is connected with the association because its business is his business, and he is therefore able far more intelligently to initiate and criticise action in relation to it than in relation to an omnium gatherum miscalled "politics." Functional organization gives every one the chance DEMOCRACY AND REPRESENTATION 115 of being, in the measure of his competence and in- terest, an active citizen. This does not mean that, in a functional democ- racy, each person will count for one and no person for more than one. That is the cant of false democ- racy. The essence of functional democracy is that a man should count as many times over as there are functions in which he is interested. To count once is to count about nothing in particular: what men want is to count on the particular issues in which they are interested. Instead of "One man, one vote," we must say, "One man as many votes as interests, but only one vote in relation to each in- terest." This restatement of a democratic principle still leaves intact the equal voting power of unequal persons voting on a particular issue. That, too, is democracy, not because equalization of votes can make unequal persons equal, but because the right way for the better man to "pull his weight" is not by casting more votes himself, but by influencing others to vote aright. Democracy involves leader- ship by influence. Before we end this chapter, we must face a very foolish, but very often urged, objection to the whole idea of functional representation. Functional rep- resentation, we are told, is impossible because, in order to make it work, everybody will have to vote so many times over. I fail to see where the objection arises. If a man is not in- terested enough to vote, and cannot be roused to interest enough to make him vote, on, say, a dozen distinct subjects, he waives his right to vote, 116 SOCIAL THEORY , and the result is no less democratic than if he voted blindly and without interest. It is true that the result is not so democratic as it would be if every- body voted with interest and knowledge, but it is far more democratic than it would be if everybody voted without interest or knowledge,. as they tend to do in parliamentary elections. Many and keen voters are best of all; but few and keen voters are next best. A vast and uninstructed electorate voting on a general and undefined issue is the worst of all. Yet that is what we call democracy to-day. CHAPTER VII GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION WE have seen that, as soon as any associa- tion passes beyond the doing of the most simple and elementary acts, it becomes neces- sary for it to have representatives persons en- dowed with the right, within certain limits, to speak and act in the name of the association, to deliberate on its behalf, and to take the steps necessary for carrying out its decisions. The char- acter and complexity of the representative methods adopted vary both with the size and geographical dispersion of the association, and with the com- plexity of the functions which it exists to perform. Thus, as long as it is possible for all the members to meet together and discuss each issue of policy as it arises, representatives, where they are required, will be unlikely to acquire any very great power, and will be mainly engaged in doing the routine work necessary to carry out the decisions of the general meeting. This is the position to-day in those parishes which are governed by a Parish Meet- ing, or in a small local Trade Union or other asso- ciation. At this stage, it will be seen, there may be rudi- 117 118 SOCIAL THEORY mentary officials, permanent or occasional, corre- sponding to the fully developed executive officers of more advanced forms of association, there may be a committee, permanent or occasional, and also of an executive character. But there is as yet no representative legislative assembly, no body of men selected from the association, and legislating or laying down the main lines of policy in the name of all the members. This is a further development, which arises when it becomes impossible or incon- venient for all the members to meet and deliberate together. It is at this stage that the real problem of government arises, and the association creates for itself a representative assembly, entrusted with the task of legislation. This does not mean that the final decision on questions of policy passes altogether and neces- sarily away from the whole body of the members. There remain two ways in which the whole of the members may still keep important decisions in their own hands. They may choose to act through dele- gates rather than representatives, and although they cannot all meet together, the local members may hold meetings in a number of centers to in- struct their delegate, or, in the alternative, to advise their representative, how to vote. Or they may adopt the institution of the referendum, and insist that important issues shall be submitted to a ballot vote of all the members. Both these expedients, however, are extremely clumsy, when it is attempted to apply them to any but the broadest and simplest issues. For, in either case, every question has to be reduced to a simple GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION 119 Aye or No, and the possibility of adjustments, amendments and new situations has to be left out of account. The method of referendum or instruc- tion is, I believe, the right method where the broad- est and simplest issues are concerned; but it offers no help in dealing with the more complex and de- tailed issues which are constantly arising in almost every association. Men are driven, therefore, to the expedient of the representative * legislative assembly for getting the ordinary day-to-day work of the more complex associations efficiently accomplished. In the less complex associations, very often no separate legislative assembly is created, but the Executive Committee acts also as a legislature within the limits which the purposes of the assembly require. The more complex type of association, however, usually creates a separate body for the task of legislation, and calls this body together as required, the Execu- tive Committee remaining in being to carry out its decisions. In the most complex types of associa- tion, such as the State, the legislative assembly, as well as the Executive Committee, tends to become permanent and to remain in almost con- tinuous session. Even Parliament, however, has only very gradually developed this permanent and continuous character. The early Parliaments were occasional bodies. The purpose of this chapter is to investigate more 1 It is necessary to bear in mind, throughout this chapter, the sense attached to the word "representation." It is always functional representation alone that is to be regarded as true representation. 120 SOCIAL THEORY closely than we have yet done the actual ways of operation of representative bodies and persons, in order to see how the will of the members finds expression through their representatives, and also how it is sometimes perverted and twisted in passing through the representatives' intermediary. One of the most illuminating chapters of Rousseau's Social Contract 1 deal with the "tendency of govern- ment to deteriorate." All action through repre- sentatives, he explains, involves to a certain extent the substitution of the wills of the representatives for those of the represented. Moreover, all groups of men, by experience of acting together, tend to develop in some degree a "common will" of their own. Chosen to express the "common will" of those whom they represent, they acquire a "com- mon will" of their own different from that of the represented. We have given in the last chapter our reasons for supposing that the definite limits and purposes of functional representatives make these dangers far less applicable to it than to so-called "repre- sentation" which is general and not functional. This, however, does not mean that, even with func- tional representation, the danger altogether dis- appears. It is, indeed, impossible that it should ever disappear, unless as the result of a miracle which would be also an overwhelming calamity. For the possibility of Society is based on the fact that, By acting together, men do as a rule develop an increasing sense of community. This is the very basis of Society; but it has inevitably its bad, as 1 Social Contract, bk. Hi., chap. x. GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION 121 well as its good, side. For it means that there is a sense of community among thieves as well as among honest men, and among members of com- mittees and representative assemblies as well as among members of groups and associations. It means that, however faithfully the members of a committee may try to fulfill their whole duty to their members, an element of committee loyalty will almost inevitably enter into their actions. They will tend to back one another, whether they are right or wrong, and, when one of them is in danger of not being reflected, the rest will often tend to support him even if they are aware that he is not the best man for the job. They will say one to another: "After all, we can't let down old Jones." It is an easy and a highly popular pastime to gird at this idiosyncrasy of elected persons. But it is useless to abuse men for being clannish; we must rather recognize that the tendency to clannishness is the cement of the social system, and make up our minds to adopt the proper treatment in dealing with it. In the first place, we must always try to make the position of the representative as clear and definite as possible, clearly marking out his powers and functions and sphere of action and re- sponsibility. And secondly, we must always try to provide as a background for the action of the representative, an active and continuously resource- ful organized body of constituents. It is, I believe, the presence of this continuously active constituency that gives to the Soviet system, despite its counter- vailing disadvantages, its peculiar vitality. In short SOCIAL THEORY it is for the body of the members to counteract the tendency to clannishness and even conspiracy on the part of the elected persons by being clannish and alert in pressing forward their own common wills. I have so far spoken of the tendency of bodies of elected persons to substitute their own wills for the wills which they are supposed to represent as if it were a single and indivisible phenomenon. There is, however, an important distinction not so much in kind as in degree. There is the involuntary and often quite unconscious perversion or substitution which arises directly out of the fact that the mem- bers of the representative body are constantly acting and deliberating together; and there is also the conscious and voluntary perversion which may easily develop out of the unconscious perversion unless it is strongly checked by the presence of an active electorate. Cabinet Government is probably the worst instance of such deliberate and conscious perversion, of which the Party System is also an awful, but illuminating, example. 1 Any long con- tinuance of this, aggravated form of perversion proves that there is something 'seriously wrong either with the electorate as a whole or with the form of representation. Its constant presence in the political system of almost every country shows either that the peoples of the world are fundamentally cor- rupt or foolish, or that the generally accepted theory of representative government is radically wrong. 1 See The Party System, by Hilaire Belloc and Cecil Chester- ton, and Democracy and the Organization of Political Parties, by Robert Michels. GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION Perversion, by the substitution of the will of the elected person for the wills he has been chosen to represent, is liable to occur in all types of repre- sentative body, and in all representative officials. We have therefore been able so far to treat repre- sentative institutions together without distinguish- ing for the most part between the various types. The next stage in our argument requires a more careful and detailed examination of the types of repre- sentative institutions with a view to ascertaining their right relationship one to another and to the represented. This brings us at once to a further discussion of the relation between legislative and executive power. Many of the older writers on social science based the greater part of their exposition of the forms of social organization upon the double distinction of legislative and executive power, or upon the triple distinction of legislature, executive and judiciary. I have endeavored elsewhere to show that the dis- tinction between legislature and executive provides no adequate basis for classifying the activities of modern Societies. 1 It may be possible to distin- guish with clearness sufficient for all practical pur- poses between the work of law-making and the work of seeing to the execution of the laws (leaving aside for the moment the judicial aspect) as long as the social situations to be dealt with remain essentially simple and free from technical complications. But in the communities of to-day law-making and law- 1 See Self-Government in Industry, chapter entitled "The Nature of the State." The final section of the same chapter deals with the judiciary. SOCIAL THEORY administering inevitably run together. It is im- possible to draft a law which will meet all the complexities of the case, and consequently our Parlia- ments and other legislative bodies are continually passing laws, many of whose clauses virtually dele- gate the power of legislation to the administrators, by providing that such and such matters may be dealt with by Order in Council or special order, or that the Minister concerned may make Orders and Regulations dealing with such and such a matter provisions which effectively blur the already faint line of division between legislation and administra- tion. In some cases, the legislative body attempts to retaliate and to establish a control over administra- tion through parliamentary questions, interpella- tions, adjournment motions, votes to reduce a salary or a credit, Standing Committees, Select Commit- tees and what not. The honors, however, under the parliamentary system, rest as a rule with the Executive, which steadily and successfully en- croaches upon the sphere of legislation. Nor are these phenomena confined to Cabinets and political assemblies. They appear also in other forms of association. Trade Union Executives try to seize the power of legislation out of the hands of Delegate Meetings ; and Delegate Meetings retaliate by encroaching upon the sphere of administration. Wherever much detailed and complicated business has to be transacted, the line of demarcation between legislature and executive tends to break down. This breakdown has the more far-reaching con- sequences for social theory. Great stress used to be laid on the balance of powers between legis- GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION 125 lature and executive as a safeguard against tyranny and perversion. Whatever value this principle may have had in the past, it has little or none to-day, except as a minor safeguard within each particular association. Those who seek a balance of power in social organization are therefore compelled to seek for a new principle of division. The old theory was an attempt to divide by stages the law was first enacted by the legislature and it then passed on to the succeeding stage of being administered by the executive. If this method of division by stages has broken down, there seems to be only one alter- native open, if we desire to adhere to the principle of balance in any form. That alternative is to divide by function. In earlier chapters of this book I have tried to establish the preeminence of function as the primary principle of social organization. We have now to see what are the consequences of the acceptance of this principle in the sphere of government. Instead of a division based on the stage which an associa- tive act has reached (the stage of law-making or the stage of administration), it gives us a new principle of division according, not to the stage, but to the content and purpose of the act. In other words, the principle of function implies that each functional form of association has and is its own legislature and its own executive. This may seem either a very startling or a very commonplace proposition according to the manner in which it is interpreted. It is commnoplace, if it only means that each association has to frame rules or laws for its own guidance, and to administer the 126 SOCIAL THEORY rules or laws which it has made. It is startling, if it means that the laws of other functional associa- tions have the same binding character and social status as the laws of the State. Nevertheless, it is the startling form of the prop- osition which more nearly expresses what I mean. It flows as a necessary consequence from the denial of State Sovereignty and omnicompetence, and the affirmation of the functional character proper to the State, as to other associations, that the State's ex- clusive claim to the right of legislation goes by the board. It retains, of course, its right to legislate within its function; but this right belongs also to other associations in relation to their numbers and within their respective functions. This does not mean that all forms of functional legislation are equally important, any more than all forms of association are equally important. But it does mean that, in the measure of their importance, all forms of association acquire for their legislative acts a comparable social status. The full implications of this functional division of legislation can only be made apparent at the end of the four following chapters. I must, however, at once try to meet, at least, provisionally, an ob- jection which is almost certainly present already in the reader's mind. If the power of legislation is divided, he will ask, does not this also imply the division of coercive power? Or, in other words, if the State's exclusive right to legislate is challenged, must not the State's exclusive right to use coercion be challenged also? I answer unhesitatingly that it must, and that GOVERNMENT AND LEGISLATION 127 the State's monopoly of coercive power disappears with its loss of Sovereignty and of the monopoly of legislation. But, before we deal finally with the huge problem which is here raised, we must make quite certain that we know what we mean by coercion, and distinguish between various forms and uses of coercive power. CHAPTER VIII COERCION AND COORDINATION WE ended the last chapter with what was vir- tually an interrogation. What is the nature of coercive power in the community, and how, and in what forms, is it exercised ? Every association, by the mere fact of its ex- istence, is endowed with some coercive power, and actually exercises some such power in the course of pursuing its object. This coercive power is not necessarily recognized by the community, and the courts of law sometimes disallow particular exer- cises of it by voluntary associations. Nevertheless it exists, and is freely exercised every day. Very many associations claim the right to fine their mem- bers for breach of the rules, and nearly all claim the final right of expelling a member who offends against the etiquette or rules of the association, or even who, in the opinion of the members, acts con- trary to the interests of the association. Trade Unions and many other kinds of association con- stantly fine and often expel members, and it is very seldom that their right to do so is challenged by the courts in some particular case. Indeed, often the law of the State, so far from disallowing such asso- 128 COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 129 ciational coercion, backs it up and gives it legal sanction, or at least acquiesces in its decisions. This is especially the case in the "self-governing" profes- sions, where the benchers of the Temple, or the Law Society, or the General Medical Council, freely use coercive power with the approval and sanction of the State. Thus, we can find ample instances of coercion by associations other than the State with- out inviting that great coercionist, spiritual and tem- poral, the Church. There is, however, a distinction between three kinds of coercion, which it is important to recognize at the outset. There is one kind of coercion which only affects a man's purse or property, that is coercion by fine. This is freely employed, not only by the State, but by most important types of associ- ation. There is a second kind of coercion which af- fects a man's freedom of action by limiting directly his range of opportunity and self-expression, as, for instance, by disfranchising him or forbidding him to work in a particular factory or occupation. The first is employed by the State and also by other forms of association ; the second occurs when the members of a Trade Union refuse to work with a non-Union- ist, or expel a man from the Union and then refuse to work with him, or when an employers' associa- tion "blacklists" a man, and so prevents him from getting a job. "Sending to Coventry" is a less or- ganized example of this kind of coercion. The third form of coercion is that which directly affects a man's body, by limiting his right of move- ment, interning him, imprisoning him, or, in the last resort, hanging him, or shooting him, or cutting 130 SOCIAL THEORY off his head. In civilized countries and in modern times these forms of diversion are usually, at least in the case of adults, the monopoly of the State. Civilization, however, is often ready to resort to them without calling in the State in its dealings with what are politely called "non-adult" races, and also, in a less degree, in the case of children. The per- sistence of "lynch law" in some parts of the "civil- ized" world is an exception. How are these forms of coercion related to the functional theory of Society which is propounded in this book? Where, in other words, in a func- tionally organized Society, would the power of coer- cion in its various forms reside? It is clearly useless to deny all coercive power to any association which we are prepared to recognize at all as legitimate; for whether we recognize the right to coercion or not, the power will remain and will be used. The most that is possible is to limit the forms of coercion which may be used by any particular functional association, and to reserve the right to the more stringent forms of coercion in the hands of that body which is most fit to exercise it. It is futile to endeavor to prevent an associa- tion which is allowed to make rules, and must make rules if it is to get its work done at all, from using some means to enforce their observance. Even if an association is deprived of the means of coercing its members directly, it will find indirect means of coercing them by placing obstacles in their way or withholding opportunities from them. Moreover, it is impossible altogether to prevent an association which exists to secure a particular object from COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 131 coercing to a certain extent persons not its members who refuse to join it and pursue a contrary object or the same object in a different way. Here, again, the range and forms of coercion can be limited, but the possibility of coercion cannot be altogether abolished. In a functionally organized Society, it seems reasonable to suppose that each functional associa- tion will employ directly the minor forms of coer- cion in relation to its own members, acting within strictly limited powers, and without the right to in- terfere with life or liberty of person. This, how- ever, only drives us back upon a further question. What body in a functionally organized Society will define the limits within which coercion may be em- ployed by the various associations, and itself exer- cise directly the major forms of coercion, if and when they are required? It is not difficult to recognize that this question brings us back to the very point at which we broke off in our discussion of the State. 1 We were there confronted with the question of the body which would, in a functional Society, exercise the powers of coordination at present claimed by the "Sov- ereign State." But clearly coordination and co- ercion go hand in hand. We are now in a position to restate more clearly and fully the reasons which make it impossible to recognize the task of coordination as falling within the true function of the State. The claim on the State's behalf is usually based on the assumption that the State, because it represents and includes 1 See Chapter V. 132 SOCIAL THEORY everybody within its area, is necessarily superior to other associations which only include some of the persons within its area. 1 But in what sense does the State represent and include everybody? If our functional theory of representation is right, it may include everybody, but it does not include the whole of everybody ; it may represent some purposes com- mon to everybody, but it does not represent all the purposes common to everybody. This being so, it can no longer lay claim to Sovereignty on the ground that it represents and includes everybody; for the Sovereign, if there is one, must 'represent and include, as far as possible, the whole of every- body. This it is impossible for any single association to-day, and indeed impossible for any complex of associations to do completely. For there are vast tracts of life which are simply not susceptible to social organization, and the purposes which they include are therefore not capable of being repre- sented at all. This is, however, only a statement in other words of a fact which we have already recog- nized that, as the State is not co-extensive with or- ganized Society, so Society is not co-extensive with community. The principle of coordination which we are seeking cannot therefore be a principle coordinating all life within a given area, but only that part of life which is social and susceptible to social organiza- tion. But it must coordinate the whole of that or- ganizable social life. It cannot therefore be found *The fact that they may also include persons outside the State's area is usually ignored. COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 133 in any one of the various forms of association which we have described; for to each of these forms all the others are external, and no one of them could act as a coordinating agency either between the others or between itself and the rest. We are there- fore reduced to the conclusion that no one among the many forms of functional association can be the coordinating body of which we are in search. A dim perception of this difficulty has led social theorists into a variety of expedients. Some have maintained, like Rousseau, that Sovereignty resides inalienably in the whole body of the people and is incapable of being conferred upon any form of organization at all. But such a view inevitably encounters the difficulty that, although the Sover- eignty of the people is affirmed, no means can be found of making it actual, and all the important exercises of it pass into the hands of governing bodies which thus become virtually sovereign, even while their Sovereignty is being denied. 1 Where this difficulty is recognized as being insuperable, at least in any large Society, the at- tempt is sometimes made to preserve popular Sov- ereignty by the constant use of the referendum. But a mere "Yes or No" vote, without the possibility of discussion or amendment, reduces popular Sover- eignty to a farce except on the broadest issues, and once more the real power passes to the Government, or to whoever draws up the ballot papers and so decides the form of the question to be submitted. None of these mechanical expedients really gets over 1 See my Introduction to Rousseau's Social Contract (Ev- eryman edition), p. xxvi. 134. SOCIAL THEORY the difficulty. The referendum may be the best way of dealing with certain simple issues; but by itself it certainly does not maintain popular Sover- eignty; nor does the addition of the initiative to it make any substantial difference. If neither any single functional association nor the people itself can be the normal coordinating agency in a functionally organized Society, only one possi- bility remains. The coordinating body must be not any single association, but a combination of asso- ciations, a federal body in which some or all of the various functional associations are linked to- gether. It will be remembered that, in the chapter on "The Forms and Motives of Association," some attempt was made to discriminate between essential and non-essential forms of association. It was recognized that any such discrimination could be only approximate, because even the essential forms would tend to vary in different times and places. We did, however, succeed in establishing a working principle of discrimination. "The key to essen- tiality," we saw, "is the performance of some func- tion which is vital to the coherent working of Society, and without which Society would be lop- sided or incomplete." We saw there that, apart from religious association, which we reserved for special treatment, there are at least three forms of association which are to be regarded as generally essential. These are political association and the two forms of "economic" association or rather of association centering round the giving and receiving of services, that is to say, vocational and appetitive COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 135 association. 1 We saw also that the essentiality of these forms of association in general does not suffice to establish the essentiality of any particular association belonging to one of these forms, unless two further conditions are satisfied. The motive which binds men together in the association must be a truly "associative" motive, 2 and the content or function of the particular association, and not merely of its form, must be important enough to warrant its being regarded as "essential" in accord- ance with the criterion stated above. I do not propose to push further in this book the analysis of the essential forms and instances of association. To determine what actual associations are to be regarded as essential at a particular time and for a particular Society is a practical question, and is therefore alien to a work dealing with Social Theory. 3 Here we are concerned only with the general question with the attempt to discover the principle of coordination in a functionally organized Society. This principle has already been made inferentially clear. The coordinating agency can only be a combination, not of all associations, but of all essential associations, a Joint Council or Congress of the supreme bodies representing each of the main functions in Society. Each functional association will see to the execution of its own function, and for the coordination of the activities of the various 1 See Chapter IV., pp. 63 ff. * For the definition of "associative" motive, see pp. 34 ff. * For a discussion on this point, see my Self -Government in Industry, especially the chapter on the State and the introduc- tory chapter prefixed to the edition of 1919. 186 SOCIAL THEORY associations there must be a joint body representa- tive of them. Here a serious objection will almost certainly be encountered. Is not this, it will be asked, merely a very roundabout way of proposing a change in the method of electing the representatives who form the State? It has often been proposed that the prin- ciple of vocational electorates should be partially recognized and incorporated in the constitution side by side with the geographical principle that, for example, the House of Lords should be replaced by a vocational Second Chamber. It will be suggested that, after all our blare of trumpets, this is what our "great change" comes to in the end. This is not so. There are two absolutely vital differences between the theory which I have been putting forward and the proposal to establish a vocational Second Chamber. In the first place, the assumption of the "Voca- tional Chamber" theory is that all forms of legis- lation, no matter what their content, continue to be dealt with by both Chambers and initiated in either. Functional organization, on the other hand, is ex- plicitly designed to enable each functional body to deal with those matters which belong to its function, without interference in its normal operations from any outside body. Thus, purely political questions belong exclusively to the sphere of the State, purely vocational questions to the sphere of vocational as- sociation. It is only when a question affects more than one form of association, that is, affects men in more than one capacity or function, that it is neces- sary to appeal beyond the purely functional body to COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 137 some body on which the various functions are repre- sented. The whole basis of functional organization is designed to enable each functional body to get on with its own job the job which the members know how to do, and by virtue of their common interest in which they have become associated. Secondly, the coordinating or "joint" body which I have in mind is less an administrative or legislative body, though it cannot help partaking in some degree of both these characters, than a court of appeal. It does not in the normal case initiate; it decides. It is not so much a legislature as a con- stitutional judiciary, or democratic Supreme Court of Functional Equity. If this is clear, we can return to the question from which we were led into this discussion. Coercion and coordination, we said, go hand in hand. If the supreme power of coordination rests in the hands of this "joint" body compounded from the essential functional associations, it seems clear that the supreme power of coercion must rest in the same hands. This involves that the judiciary and the whole paraphernalia of law and police must be under the control of the coordinating body. We saw in the last chapter that the functional organization of Society necessarily involves the division of power of legislation, as well as of ad- ministration, along functional lines. It does not, however, involve a similar division of the judiciary. This question, it will be remembered, we reserved for further treatment, our reason being that it could not be dealt with until we came to discuss the questions of coordination and coercion. 138 SOCIAL THEORY The sole possession of a high degree of coercive power, and especially of coercive power of the third kind, which directly affects a man's body, by any single form of functional association, would clearly upset the social balance at which we are aiming, and place the ultimate social power in the hands of that form of association. On the other hand, its possession in an equal degree by each of the essential forms of association would be not only, to say the least of it, inconvenient, and an invitation to the sort of cat-and-dog fight which went on between Church and State in the Middle Ages, but also a denial of the relation of men to association which is postulated as fundamental in this study. We have seen that a man is a member of an association, not with his whole personality, but with that part of it which he puts into the association in pursuance of the common object which is its function. This being so, the association has at the most no right to coerce the individual in his whole personality, but only in that part of it which he has put into the association. The right to the higher forms of coer- cion cannot, then, reside either in any one associa- tion or in all such associations. It must, however, be in the hands of a single body, if only for reasons of convenience; and this body can therefore only be the coordinating body which is a synthesis of the various essential forms of association. Even so, there is a strict limit to the coercive power to which even the coordinating body is entitled. For, as we have seen, the individual puts into Society, that is into social organization, not his whole personality, but only those parts of it COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 139 which can find expression through social organiza- tion. The coercive right of Society as a whole is therefore limited, and there remains a sphere un- touched by social organization in which the indi- vidual retains his freedom from coercion. 1 It fol- lows that Society has no right to put any man to death; for death involves a total cessation of per- sonality on this earth, at any rate. Even with this safeguard, I rather suspect that many readers have been regarding what has been said in this chapter with a good deal of suspicion and dislike. So much talk about coercion, they will say, augurs ill for the sort of Society which requires it. What is wanted, they will urge, is to get away from the whole idea of coercion as the basis of Society ; for it is its coercive character that makes the State such a nasty body. But it is of no use to refuse to talk about a thing because one does not happen to like it. However much one may dislike coercion and seek to reduce its operation in Society to a minimum, it is necessary to provide for its exercise, if only to supply a means for its abolition. For only that body which possesses coercive power is in a position to forego or prohibit its exercise. Having discovered where coercive power must reside in a functional Society, we are now in a posi- tion to give vent to our dislike of it. One of the greatest results which, I believe, would flow from the full recognition of functional organization would be a substantial and immediate reduction in the use of coercion in Society. For coercion is the conse- 1 For a development of this point, see Chapter XII. 140 SOCIAL THEORY quence of social disorder, and the need for it largely comes, not of innate human wickedness, but of men's failure under existing social conditions to find their proper spheres of social service and to recognize clearly their rights and obligations in So- ciety. If we set our social house in order and make it easier for men to recognize their proper sphere of social service, the need for coercion will, I believe, speedily and progressively disappear. 1 Moreover, there is another huge advantage of functional Society over State Sovereignty. The theory of the Sovereign State means that the pigmy, man, is confronted by the leviathan, State, which encircles and absorbs him wholly, or at least claims the absolute right to encircle and absorb him. It claims to "represent" fully all the individuals who are its members, and therefore to be absolutely superior to them and over them, and to come always first. The functional principle destroys any such claim; for its denial that the individual can be "represented" in any complete sense means -that social organization, however vast and complicated it may be, leaves the individual intact and self-sub- sistent, distributing his loyalties and obligations among a number of functional bodies, but not ab- sorbed in any or all of them, because outside the sphere of functional organization there remains always that most vital sphere of individuality whose self-expression is essentially personal and incapable of being organized. The functional principle is, 1 This view appears to be also largely that of Mr. Bertrand Russell, who adopts Guild Socialism as a step towards a non- coercive Society. See his Roads to Freedom. COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 141 above all else, the recognition of the absolute and inalienable personal identity of every individual person. 1 There is one further point with which we must deal before bringing this chapter to an end. In dealing with the nature of the State, we discussed briefly the international aspects of social organiza- tion. We saw that international action, or the ex- ternal actions of a particular Society, have their various functional aspects, in which they fall within the sphere of the various forms of functional asso- ciation. There remain those parts of international or external action which involve more than one function or call for action by Society as a whole. Foremost among these there will no doubt leap to the mind of the reader the control of armed forces the Army, Navy and Air Force. Where, in a functional Society, would the control of these reside? Who would declare war or make peace or treaties and covenants affecting Society as a whole ? Who would represent a functional Society in a League of Nations? The answers to all these questions follow logically from what has already been established. The external use of force and coercion raises similar problems to its internal use, and it is even more manifest in external relations that the right to use it must be concentrated in the hands of a single body. One part of Society cannot be at peace while another 1 For a fuller discussion of this point, see my paper on "Con- flicting Social Obligations" (Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1915-16), and the chapter on "The Organization of Freedom" in my Labor in the Commonwealth. 143 SOCIAL THEORY part is at war; for the claims of war upon the individual citizen are not limited to an eight hours' day, or to the act of voting; they involve for him the risk of death by violence or starvation. No less clearly is it impossible to entrust external force to any single functional association, both because external affairs involve and interest all the essential forms of association, and because force intended for use externally is also available for internal use, and sole control of armed forces would make the association which possessed it the master of Society. We must, therefore, once more conclude that the external, like the internal, means of coercion, must be in the hands of the body which represents the various social functions, and is entrusted with the task of coordination. Here, again, I am dealing with the problem of external force, not because Armies and Navies and wars are nice things, but because, whether they are nice or nasty, the problem which they present has to be faced. I hope with all my heart that they will disappear before the growth of international coop- eration, not only between States, but between all the various forms of functional association. Moreover, I believe that functional association, which has already shown itself far ahead of States in its sense of international solidarity, offers the best hope of a condition of World Society which will make external force unnecessary, and will also persuade everybody, except the incorrigible and disappointed militarists, that it is unnecessary. Here, then, is the answer to our last question Who would represent a functional Society on a COERCION AND CO-ORDINATION 143 League of Nations? The answer is that an inter- national Society, which in embryo a League of Nations is, if it is anything more than a sham, would reproduce in itself the functional structure of the smaller Societies composing it. Inter- national functional association "would undertake, in the wider sphere, the work undertaken in the narrower sphere by national functional organization, and the central coordinating body would reproduce internationally the federal structure of the national coordinating bodies. This, no doubt, assumes a cer- tain homogeneity of structure among the Socie- ties composing the League; but it is at least doubtful whether, without a considerable element of homo- geneity, a League of Nations could possibly work. A perception of this perhaps accounts for the desire of the "Sovereign States," which have just formed a League, to impress upon all candidates for entry the particular structure, economic and political, which they themselves possess. 1 1 This point is further discussed in my Labor in the Com- monwealth, chap. ii. CHAPTER IX THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY THERE will be a certain type of reader who will regard the greater part of this book as beside the point, or at best as a harmless form of theoretical diversion. I am ignoring, he will say, or relegating to a quite secondary position the factor which in reality dominates and determines the whole course of social organization. Political or- ganization, and indeed every essential form of asso- ciative life, is, in his view, the result of economic conditions and of the distribution of economic power in the community, and the changes which occur from time to time in social organization are equally the results of changes in the economic circumstances. In the words of Marx and Engels, "The economic structure of Society is the real basis on which the judicial and political super- structure is raised in short, the mode of produc- tion determines the character of the social, polit- ical, and intellectual life generally." It is necessary for us to take notice of this point of view, and to admit at once the large measure of truth which it possesses, if our exposition of the theoretical basis of Society is to have any vital 144 ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 145 contact with the working of actual Societies. In- deed, we have already, at several stages of our argument, laid stress on the vital importance of the economic factor in influencing and directing the working of other forms of association, as well as the interaction of various economic factors and associa- tions. We have, however, always treated the in- fluence of economic factors upon non-economic forms of association as a form of perversion, lead- ing to a failure of the association so affected to ful- fill its proper function in Society. If the Marxian thesis is right in its entirety, we must abandon this view; for it is folly to regard as "perversion" a phenomenon which flows directly from the nature of Society itself, or to treat as independent forms of association bodies and manifestations which are only the "superstructure" of economic organiza- tion. In fact, we are here faced by a theory which is the complete inversion of the theory of State Sover- eignty which we have already rejected. Having pulled down the State from its pedestal, we are asked to install the economic structure of Society in its place. There is, however, a profound difference in the argument advanced. Although the claim of the State to Sovereignty is sometimes based on the fact that it is the sole repository of armed force, this argument is not very often or very persistently em- ployed ; for it is clear that there is no reason in the nature of the State why it should occupy this position, and also increasingly clear that there exist other forms of "force," such as the strike, which may under favorable conditions successfully 146 SOCIAL THEORY challenge even a monopolist in armed force. The case for State Sovereignty is therefore usually ar- gued not on this basis of fact, but on what is put forward as a basis of right. The State is said to be sovereign, because it represents everybody. The argument that the economic structure of Society is, if I may use the term, "sovereign," is based on quite different grounds. It is not as a rule suggested that economic conditions ought to be the supreme determinant in Society, but only that they are and must be, owing to the operation of forces beyond our control. The advocates of this theory the "materialist" or "economic" con- ception of history are indeed apt to be impatient of "oughts" and rights. They claim that their conception is "scientific," and base it upon the stern laws of necessity and material evolution. Whatever fine theories other people may spin, they continue to proclaim the hard fact that the human race marches upon its belly, and that the economic order of Society determines everything else. Whatever the process of argument, the result ar- rived at is in one respect the same as that arrived at by the advocates of State Sovereignty. Func- tional organization in either case disappears, or appears only as a subordinate form determined by and existing on the sufferance of a single form of organization, which, even if it has a functional basis, is not in its operation confined to any particular function. There is, however, still an ambiguity in the materialist conception. What is meant by the words, "the economic structure of Society"? Do ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 147 they refer to actual associations, such as Trade Unions or capitalist associations, andlo the distri- bution of power among such associations? Or do they, as the final clause of our quotation from Marx and Engels rather seems to suggest, refer to the actual material conditions existing in Society, without regard to the associations which are re- lated to these conditions ? There is no doubt that the direct reference is not to associations but to the material conditions themselves. But it is held that each set of material conditions finds its necessary expression in a set of associations and a form of social organization of its own. Thus, one set of associations corresponded to, and arose out of, the productive conditions of primitive Society; another set was the inevitable result of the productive conditions of the Middle Ages ; and yet another set, under which we are now living, has been called into existence by the great inventions and the development of large-scale production which marked the period of the In- dustrial Revolution. Each set of economic condi- tions changes gradually, with or without a sharp break or upheaval at some point, into the next, and each new set of associations grows and is built up gradually within the old, until the conditions are ripe for it to assert its dominance, and for the obsolete set of associations to be discarded. Thus, within the capitalist system, a new set of associa- tions is being built up which will take the place of Capitalism; but those new associations, Trade Unions and other working-class bodies, are as much 148 SOCIAL THEORY the products of economic conditions as the capitalist system itself. As an analysis of the growth of Capitalism, and of the working of capitalist institutions both in the past and at the present time, this theory is so largely right that the points at which it is wrong are easily overlooked. Yet there are at least two considerable misstatements involved in it, as it is most com- monly expressed. In the first place, it does not prove, as is often contended, that the form of non-economic associa- tions is determined by economic conditions, but only that their actual working and methods of operation are so determined. Thus, when a prom- inent Marxist 1 writes a book to prove that the State as an association is the political expression of Capitalism and will disappear with the overthrow of Capitalism, what he actually does prove is that, while Capitalism exists as the dominant social form, the State will be forced to do the bidding of Capitalism, and will be, in actual fact, the political expression of the dominant economic power of the capitalist classes. What he does not prove is that, with the overthrow of Capitalism, the State will disappear ; or that it will not be able to assume and exercise its true function as soon as the eco- nomic pressure of Capitalism is removed. In other words, his argument does not in any sense disprove our thesis that what occurs under Capitalism is a perversion of the true function of the State, and its use, not as a political instrument of the whole people, but as a secondary economico- *The State: its Origin and Function. By William Paul. ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 149 political instrument by the dominant economic class. Secondly, although the State is in fact largely an "Executive Committee for administering the affairs of the capitalist class," it is not exclusively so. Perversion of function is not carried so far as to obliterate all signs and traces of its real function. Indeed, by examining the actual working of the State, even under capitalist conditions, we have been able to assign to it its essential function in a ration- ally ordered Society. Under any economic system the State will continue to exercise functions which are not economic, and the perversion of its activi- ties by economic causes will not extend continuously to all its doings. It will be seen that the line of argument which I am adopting is an endorsement of a large part of the Marxian case. While I cannot accept the neo- Marxian criticism of the State as universally true, or as touching the State in its real social function, I am accepting its general truth as it applies to the State of to-day. It is the case that the functioning, not only of the State, but also of most other forms of association, including the economic forms them- selves perhaps more than any, is perverted by the influence exercised upon them by economic factors. Nor is the reason for this widespread perversion far to seek. It is embedded in the present economic structure of Society. For, instead of being organ- ized as a coherent whole for the complementary performance of social functions, men are to-day organized in the economic sphere in conflicting groups, each of which is at least as much concerned 150 SOCIAL THEORY with getting the better of the others and diverting to its own use as much as possible of the product of labor as with serving the community by the per- formance of a useful function. Thus the economic sphere of social action has become a battle-ground of contending sections, and these combatants are also irresistibly impelled to widen their battle- front so as to lay waste the tracts of social organiza- tion which lie outside the economic sphere. Thus, trade rivalries lead to wars between nations ; internal industrial dissension leads employers' associations and Trade Unions to seek direct representation in Parliament, and to extend into the political sphere their economic disputes; and finally, the whole people tends to rally to the one standard or the other, and to make Society as a whole a "devas- tated area" of economic conflict and class-war. I am not concerned to insist here on my belief that Labor is in the right, and Capitalism in the wrong in this struggle, but solely to insist that, wherever the right lies, the existence of such an economic conflict in Society is fatal to the due per- formance of its function by each form of social organization. Indeed, this statement can be made more general; for economic conflict is not the only sort of division that can so rend a community asunder as largely to stop the functioning of its various parts. Religious differences, as we shall see later, can produce and have produced the same results, and there is no final reason why some other matter of discord should not produce them if it arouses strong enough feelings in a sufficient part of the population. We may say, then, that ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 151 the existence of a profound social cleavage in regard to the fulfillment of any essential social function is prejudicial, and may be fatal, to the performance of its proper function by each form of social organization. In our own Society at least, and in the larger industrialized communities generally, economic divisions are at the present time the principal ob- stacles to the fulfillment of social functions. Great inequalities of wealth and economic status lead inevitably, under the modern conditions which necessarily favor large-scale combination on both sides, to cleavages in Society that are bound to assume the character of open conflicts. It is therefore useless to expect that the various forms of association will perform their functions properly as long as the conditions which make for such conflicts continue in existence. The only remedy lies in some form of approximate, or comparatively economic equality. It must be made clear that this assertion is not a plea for, or a declaration of faith in, any par- ticular economic system, even if faith in a particular system is implied in much of this book. Compara- tive or approximate economic equality is possible under more than one system, and I am Marxian enough to believe that different systems are re- quired for its attainment under different economic and productive systems. Thus, a generally diffused system of peasant proprietorship, such as Mr. Belloc and his followers have made an undeniably heroic theoretical attempt to adapt to the conditions 152 SOCIAL THEORY of modern industrialized Societies, 1 is certainly a possible approximation to equality for an agrarian Society, and under it such a Society might hope to find its various functional associations doing their jobs with some approximation to propriety. All the various schools of Socialist thought Collectiv- ist, Communist, Guild Socialist, Syndicalist set out to provide a basis for economic equality on the opposite principle, not of the general diffusion and distribution, but of the concentration and social ownership of the means of production. Any of these systems, whatever their other faults, might, given an appropriate set of material conditions as a basis, provide economic equality and thereby make possible the functioning of Society without perversion from economic causes. But without virtual economic equality it is useless to look for the disappearance' or subordination of class-conflict, and therefore useless to expect Society to function aright, either economically or in any other sphere. In granting so much to the "materialists," how- ever, we must be careful to make clear what we do not grant. Although Society does in one sense walk upon its belly, it does not by any means follow either that the things of the belly must always be Society's main concern, or that they will always continue to dominate and determine the other forms of social action. Far from it. The present dominance of economic considerations in Society is based on two things the "struggle for bread" and the "struggle for power." In the struggle for 1 See The Servile State, by Hilaire Belloc, and The Real De- mocracy, by J. E. F. Mann, N. J. Sievers, and R. W. T. Cox. ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 153 bread there are two factors shortage and maldis- tribution to be considered. In so far as pro- ductive power falls short, and there is a real de- ficiency in the supply of commodities to supply real needs, there exists an economic problem which will continue to trouble us whatever social system we may adopt, until we find a remedy in increasing production. But in so far as productive power is adequate, but difficulty arises over the division of the product, i.e. maldistribution, the problem disappears with the realization of economic equality. And with the disappearance of this problem goes also one of the two causes which make the eco- nomic factors dominate the other factors in social organization. The second cause, the "struggle for power," remains. This is not exclusively or in its nature economic; but it manifests itself in the economic sphere in a struggle between economic classes for the control of industry. With the abolition of economic class, and the establishment of unified functional control of industries by all the persons engaged in them, the social struggle for economic power also disappears, and the second cause of the predominance of economic factors is also removed. In other words, democratic functional organization and approximate economic equality are the condi- tions of the removal of the dominance of economic factors in Society. In short, if economic classes and class-conflicts are done away with, the Marxian thesis will no longer hold good, and economic power will no longer be the dominant factor in Society. Economic con- 154- SOCIAL THEORY siderations will lose their unreal and distorted mag- nitude in men's eyes, and will retain their place as one group among others round which the necessary social functions are centered. For the artificial ma- terial valuation of social things, which is forced upon us by the actual structure of present-day Society, it will become possible to substitute a spiritual valua- tion. When once we have got the economic sphere of social action reasonably organized on functional lines, we shall be free to forget about it most of the time, and to interest ourselves in other matters. The economic sphere will not, of course, be any less essential than before ; but it will need less attention. Always associations and institutions, as well as people, need most attention when they are least "themselves." Our preoccupation with econom- ics occurs only because the economic system is diseased. Needless to say, the organization of the "eco- nomic substratum" of Society on functional lines would produce a very different economic organiza- tion from that which exists in Society at the present time. To-day, almost all the economic forms of as- sociation are doubled with counter-association of workers responding to association of employers, often with associations of managers and profession- als trying to steer an awkward course between these persistent Symplegades. All this duplication of asso- ciations is not merely wasteful, but actively perni- cious. It means that energy, which is required for the service of the community, is diverted and per- verted into a conflict which, from the standpoint of the community, produces nothing. ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 155 This it not to condemn those who engage in, or actively stir up, such conflict. The class-divisions and economic inequalities which exist in Society make the conflict not merely inevitable, but the only means to the attainment of better conditions. It has been truly said that there is no instance in his- tory of a dominant economic class giving up its position except under the pressure of a rising economic class which has become stronger than itself. The only end to this process is the abolition of economic classes and the realization of economic equality. The economic structure of Society can only be properly adjusted to the due performance of its function when the elements of conflict, and with them the conflicting forms of economic association, are resolved into a functional unity. This would in- volve the disappearance of some, and the radical reorganization and re-orientation of others, of the existing types of economic association. The em- ployers' association and the Trade Union would alike be out of place as primarily offensive and defensive forms of organization, and the main types of association would find their motive not in defense or offense, but in social service. The personnel of industry would no longer be divided into opposing camps, but united in its common pursuit of its func- tion of the social organization of production. If this chapter seems altogether too general and unsubstantial to be a real analysis or criticism of the economic part of the social structure, that is because I am loth, by plunging into details of pres- 156 SOCIAL THEORY ent-day organization, to overweight this book with controversies which are irrelevant to its central purpose. I am trying to speak in general terms, leaving the application to be made, and the moral to be pointed, by others or in other bodies. I have tHerefore not attempted to describe the present or past or future economic organization of Society, but only to point out where economic conditions and organization do, and do not, affect the structure and working of Society as a whole. Ordinary "political theory" has suffered immeasurably from its ignoring of the economic aspects and structure of the social system, while Marxian theory suffers from its persistent identification of the economic structure with Society as a whole. I have tried to avoid both these mistakes, and at the same time to recognize the vast influence which economic conditions must always have upon the character of social organiza- tion as a whole, and to point out wherein it seems to me this influence would be limited and made definite under a system of economic equality. There are economic arguments and moral argu- ments enough in favor of the adoption of the prin- ciple of equality in the economic sphere. With these arguments I am not here concerned. I have tried only to start the argument for economic equality from the standpoint of social theory and social or- ganization. In conclusion, let me restate this argu- ment in a single sentence. The existence of economic inequality means that each form of association in Society, instead of at- tending to the fulfillment of its own social func- tion, is perverted to serve economic ends, and ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF SOCIETY 157 that thereby the whole balance and coherence of Society are destroyed, and, in the last resort, revo- lution is converted from a menace into a necessity for the restoration of a reasonable social system. CHAPTER X REGIONALISM AND LOCAL GOVERNMENT IN our treatment of the State in earlier chap- ters, we explicitly reserved for later consideration the question of local government. One good reason for adopting this course was that the question of local organization arises not only in relation to the political structure of Society, but also in relation to its economic structure and to the structure of every functional form of association. For us, the problem of local government is not merely a problem of the relations between the State and the "local authorities," but of the whole organization of Society over larger and smaller geographical areas. It is being realized to an increasing extent that the problem of the areas of government and administration is not a purely political question, but also raises at once many economic issues. Thus, it is often made a cause of complaint against the existing areas of local government that they do not correspond to economic requirements. An efficient tramway service needs to serve the areas of several neighboring towns as well as the rural districts between them ; the supply of water and other public utility services could be better administered if the 158 REGIONALISM 159 areas of local government were enlarged; what has grown to be essentially a single city is often divided into several boroughs with their separate administrations; a town or city is constantly faced with the overflow of its suburbs into the areas of surrounding authorities. Similarly, in the purely economic sphere, we have schemes for the regional- ization of the coal-mining industry under big regional trusts. 1 These are only a few instances of the insistence with which the problem of areas is forcing itself upon our consideration at the present time. Here, we are not concerned directly with the solution of these particular difficulties, but with the general problem of the areas of functional administration, and the relations of larger and smaller areas within a given Society. Clearly, the tendency at the present time is for the areas of administration to enlarge themselves continually in response to the growth in the scale of production and to the continual ex- pansion and "running into one another" of the growing towns and urban areas. The case for the preservation of small areas and units of government has been again and again clearly and forcibly stated. It has been pointed out that, as areas grow larger, the direct contact between the representative and the represented tends to dis- appear, and the unreality of representation grows greater and more evident. Rousseau held that 1 For the economic difficulties involved in existing areas of local government, see State and Municipal Enterprise, by S. and B. Webb (Labor Research Department) ; and for re- gionalization of coal mines, see Sir A. Duckham's scheme in the Reports of the Coal Industry Commission. 160 SOCIAL THEORY democracy as only possible in small Societies, because only in small Societies could the people as a whole retain its control over the conduct of affairs. Mr. Penty and the craftsmen, Mr. Chesterton in The Napoleon of Notting Hill, and other and graver authorities, have put the case for the small unit as the human unit which makes possible a spirit of neighborhood and unity which is difficult to attain over larger areas. The followers of Professor Patrick Geddes have infused into their conception of "Town-Planning" the love of the small area. It is, I think, true that, in the long run at least, to allow "local patriotism" and local organization to fall into decay and disrepute is to imperil the whole basis on which Society rests. It is a commonplace at the present time that local feeling is in decay. Indeed, the constant attempts to discover "revivals" of it and to stimulate it into action serve to show how serious the decay is. Even where local feeling remains strong and vigor- ous, as in many parts of Great Britain it does, it has, nevertheless withdrawn itself largely from the sphere of local government, or local economic administration, and concentrated itself round the less organized and unorganized parts of local life sport, for instance, and sociability in general. This is a perilous situation for the community; for, under right conditions, local feeling ought to express itself not only in these largely personal spheres, but also in all the spheres of organized social administration. Regionalism, as I understand it, is primarily an attempt to face this difficulty, and by making local REGIONALISM 161 areas real areas, to restore the influence of local spirit upon the work of social administration. It is an attempt to define areas which are at once units of social feeling and, as far as possible, also areas of economic life, and suitable to serve as units for the work of administration. The chief faults of most of the existing areas are two: their unreality as centers of local feelings, and their inadequacy to the work of administration under modern conditions, in relation not only to local transport and other public utility services, but also to public health, education, and most of the other work of local government. If these two faults admit of a single remedy, so much the better; and clearly the views of the regionalists and of those who think with them in this matter have every claim to be fully considered by a Society which is admittedly sick and ill at ease with its existing areas. But what must strike us at once is the fact that the regionalist proposal may appear in two contrary lights. From one point of view, it appears as a proposal for the drastic enlargement of the present areas of local administration, while from another point of view it appears as a scheme of devolution, or more, designed to reduce the area of administra- tion in respect of many of those matters which are now dealt with centrally by the State. Thus, we see that we cannot treat the problem of areas in isolation from the content of their admin- istration from their powers and the questions with which they are concerned. Under the existing, and indeed under any system, some things will be 162 SOCIAL THEORY administered centrally and some locally. This would be the case also if "regions" were adopted as important units of administration. The problem is thus complex, and involves a combined considera- tion of areas and powers. Before we consider this problem directly, it is necessary to point out that the whole question as- sumes rather a different form in a functionally organized Society from that which it has under the existing conditions of local and central government. For the objection that the representative loses touch with, and cannot be controlled by, those whom he represents in a large area, though it still has force, is far less applicable when the function of the representative is clearly defined than where it is vague or general. A functionally organized Society can therefore maintain its democratic character over a larger area than a Society organized on the pattern of State Sovereignty, or, for that matter, than a Society organized on the basis of Marxian industrialism. If it is inconvenient to restrict the size of an area, it may be possible to preserve democracy by restricting the function, and at the same time increasing the number of repre- sentative bodies in the larger area. Thus, while it might be dangerous to enlarge the areas of local government in industry and politics under existing conditions, I believe that the "region" would be, for many of the most important purposes, the best area of local government in a functionally organized Society. The unit of local government, to be effective, must be at once small enough to be democratically controlled, and a real unit of social REGIONALISM 163 life and feeling. An area which would be too large under a non- functional system might be just the right size for democratic and efficient functional administration. But what of Regionalism as a proposal to sub- stitute, for many purposes, the smaller area of the "region" for the larger area of the State or the national economic organization? I believe that this proposal is largely right because, in most cases, the area x of the present-day States is simply too large for effective or democratic organization of most things under any system, however functional. This does not mean that the present State areas have no reality and no use; but only that many matters which are now administered naturally would be better administered over a smaller area. The larger areas those which are larger than the "region" or "province" seem to be marked out as spheres rather of coordinating activity on most questions than of actual executive direction. If, as I believe, both economic life and social life generally call for "regional" organization and for the centering in the region of the largest measure of actual executive authority, two groups of questions at once arise. First, what is the proper relation of the economic or political "region" to the larger groups of which it forms a part, and to the smaller groups which form part of it? And secondly, is there any principle which can serve as at least a 1 Here and elsewhere I use the word "area," not to denote so many square miles, but a complex involving various considera- tions, including the extent, population, economic and general character of the country, psychology of the inhabitants, etc. 164 SOCIAL THEORY general indication of the respective spheres of the various "sizes" of administrative or governmental unit? The first group of questions at once raises the problem of federalism, decentralization, or some other form of allocation of powers. Broadly speaking, there are in operation in different places three different systems, in addition to all manner of variations upon them, of determining the relations between larger and smaller authorities of the same type within a single Society. First, there is feder- alism in the strict sense, under which all authority is finally vested in the smaller bodies severally, and each of these hands over certain definite powers to the larger body, retaining in its own hands all powers not specifically transferred. Secondly, there is decentralisation or centralisation, in which all power is credited originally to the larger body, which doles out with greater or less generosity such powers as it thinks fit to the smaller bodies. English local government, in so far as it rests upon statute law, belongs to this type. Thirdly, there is the form in which the power is originally divided between the larger and the smaller bodies, special powers being reserved to each. This occurs principally in the case of written constitutions, and especially under systems of Dominion Home Rule in the British Empire. Such intermediate systems are generally worded either in federal terms (as in the case of Australia) or in unitary terms (as in the case of Canada) ; but the wording makes little difference to the result. Such mixed systems really constitute a third type. REGIONALISM 165 In the sphere of political government, in which alone there is evidence enough to go upon, both constitutions originally federal and constitutions originally unitary tend to approximate as the result of experience of present-day conditions to this third, or mixed, type. The reason is obvious. The relation between larger and smaller bodies of the same kind is increasingly denning itself in terms not of powers alone, but of powers in relation to func- tions. It is for the larger body to fulfill certain functions, and for the smaller bodies to fulfill certain others. The question of local and central government is not, in fact, primarily a question between federal- ism and decentralization, but a question of a right allocation of social functions. This is true as regards the ends to be attained and the actual balance to be sought; but it is not true to the same extent of the methods to be used. The methods are, in fact, prescribed by the cir- cumstances. If there exists a large "unitarily" administered area which requires to be broken up for the performance of some of its functions, the method of decentralization will normally be the most convenient method both of breaking it up and of set- ting up new "regional" bodies where they are re- quired. If, on the other hand, it is desired to bind together a number of uncoordinated small bodies into a larger unit, federation is often the easiest in- strument to use, at least in the earlier stages. The method is a matter of temporary expediency, and differing methods are needed in different circum- stances for arriving at the same end. Not so with the end itself. Before we can begin 166 SOCIAL THEORY to think about methods, we must know, as something comparatively fixed and definite, the end to which we desire to attain. We must make up our minds what, for our Society and generation, is the most desirable division of functions between larger and smaller bodies within it, and we must then discover the methods best suited to promote the realization of this object. I believe that, in a functionally organized Society, the great bulk of the administrative work, both politically and economically, will best be done "regionally," that is by political and economic bodies intermediate in extent between the national State and the existing local authorities. 1 Were some such principle adopted, and twenty or thirty such areas brought into administrative existence in England, I believe that the functions which would still be best executed by the big natural unit would be chiefly functions of coordination, apart from a few big groups of questions, both economic and political, in which national uniformity of treatment would continue to be essential. It must be borne in mind that I am speaking here not of a single national body, the State, and of a single local or rather "regional" body in each "region," but of a number of national functional 1 The "region," in the sense in which I use the word, is not so large as the "province" contemplated in most schemes of English "Provincial Home Rule," or in plans for a "New Heptarchy" ; but it is considerably larger than most of the ex- isting areas of local government. I believe England could reasonably be divided into, say, twenty or thirty regions, most of which would be real social units and local feeling, and many of which would be also approximately economic units. REGIONALISM 167 bodies in the national area, and of a number of regional functional bodies in the "region." The problem has its different aspects that of co- ordinating the working of regional economic bodies on the one hand, and that of coordinating regional political bodies on the other. The problem of coordinating political with economic bodies we have already discussed, and our treatment of that subject in Chapter VIII. holds good of the "region" as well as of the national area. If coordination is to be the main function of the national bodies, what is the best method of repre- sentation upon them? There seem to Se, broadly speaking, two possibilities one, the method now adopted for electing Parliaments and many other national bodies, by universal suffrage in geographi- cal constituencies with or without Proportional Rep- resentation, or various other devices for making representation more true or the reverse the other, the method of indirect electing, under which the members of the national bodies are chosen by the bodies of the same kind covering a smaller area, the members of a national assembly by the various regional assemblies of the same kind for example. Where the main duty of a national body is that of coordination within a clearly defined sphere, I am inclined to believe that the second method will be found to be the best. Under a regional system, the direct control of the elector would be over his repre- sentatives on the various functional bodies within the "region," and it would be best for these in turn to control, and where necessary recall, their representa- tives on the various national coordinating bodies. 168 SOCIAL THEORY I do not, however, desire to suggest that this indirect form of election would necessarily apply to every national body. The method of election that is best varies with the function of the body concerned, and, if a national body exercises large powers of direct administration or government, or deals with matters for which there is no corre- sponding regional body, direct election is obviously available as an alternative. It will be seen that, in local as in national affairs, the arguments advanced in this book favor the ad hoc principle. Indeed, they favor it in two ways, by insisting on the need for a clear definition of the function of each representative body, which is the distinguishing mark of an ad hoc authority, and also by insisting on an ad hoc electorate, so that everybody votes for a body in which all are directly concerned, but vocational and other special or selective electorates are adopted in other cases. Provided the functions of the body are clearly de- fined, and the right electorate secured, all the advan- tages lie with the ad hoc body over the omnibus au- thority, which is based upon the fallacious theory of representation which we have already discarded. I have laid stress on the importance of the "region" as an administrative and governmental area for political and economic purposes alike. I do not mean by this to imply that it is always necessary, or possible, to adopt exactly the same area as the unit for all the various social functions. Thus, in a particular part of a country, the limit of social feeling may be so clearly marked as to leave no possible doubt as to the proper boundaries for REGIONALISM 169 a particular political "region." But, while this is so, it may be quite clear that this political "region" will not do for an economic "region," and the economic boundaries may be no less distinctly, but at the same time differently, defined. In such a case, it will be necessary to adopt different areas for the political and the economic region. It is, how- ever, desirable that the areas of administration for the various functions should coincide wherever possible, in order to make easy cooperation between the various functional bodies within a district. The areas ought to coincide wherever possible, and, where they differ, ought to overlap as little as pos- sible. Thus, where they cannot be made to coincide, it may be possible to make the area of two "regions" dealing with one function coincide with the area of one "region" dealing with another. I cannot close this chapter without asserting, with all the vehemence at my command, the vital im- portance to the larger community of the mainte- nance of strong local life and feeling throughout the smaller communities within it. Only if men can learn the social spirit in their daily contact with their neighbors can they hope to be good citizens of the larger community. Cooperation begins at home, and the fact that we often quarrel most fiercely with our nearest friends and neighbors is only a further indication of this truth. For hate, like love, is a thing of the emotions, and it is upon the emotions that the possibility of real human co- operation is based. The local spirit of a commu- nity is the key to its national spirit. The existing local bodies mostly fall between two 170 SOCIAL THEORY stools. They are neither small enough to appeal to the spirit of "neighborliness" nor large enough to form effective units of political or economic admin- istrations, or to appeal to that larger local spirit which characterizes the man of the West Country, or the Lancastrian, or the Yorkshireman. 1 The "region" will be large enough to be efficient and to make this larger appeal. But the smaller appeal will still need to be made, and I believe that the adoption of regional areas would open the way for a revival of very much smaller local areas which, without possessing important administrative func- tions, would act as centers round which the feelings of "neighborliness" could find expression, and also as most valuable organs of criticism through which a fire of praise, blame and advice could be brought to bear upon the representatives on the regional bodies. Such smaller centers of feeling and expres- sion are no less vital to real democracy than the larger bodies upon which, under present conditions, most of the work of administration is bound to fall. It should be noted that, throughout this chapter, the treatment of the question of "regionalism" is theoretical and is not conceived in terms of prac- tical proposals for immediate adoption. I am speaking, not of changes which can readily be introduced into Society as it is at present con- stituted, but of the form which local government might reasonably be expected to assume in a functionally organized Society. At present, Society 1 The County Council is not a unit, but a residuum with the heart cut out of it by the severance of the towns. REGIONALISM 171 is largely a battle-ground of opposing social forces, especially in the economic sphere. This fact in- evitably forces upon associations, and above all upon economic associations, a growing concentration upon both sides; for each tries to roll up bigger battalions with which to confront the big battalions of its adversary. Thus, both capitalist associations and Trade Unions tend to an increasing extent to centralize their activities upon at least a national scale, not because the national area is the best area for most forms of economic administration, but be- cause they are less concerned with efficient service than with sectional or "class" aims, and with their mutual struggle. These conditions, making for cen- tralization, are likely to persist as long as the ex- isting diversion of the community into opposing economic classes continues. It is therefore prob- able that most regionalist proposals, especially in their economic aspects, will only become "practical politics" when the existing class-divisions in indus- try have disappeared. CHAPTER XI CHURCHES IT is impossible, in any study of social theory which professes to be in any sense compre- hensive, not to deal directly with the place of religious associations in Society. The old quarrel of Church and State may belong mainly to the past, and may have ceased, in this country at least, to affect profoundly the whole social order; but the place of Churches in modern Society is by no means settled, and, apart from this controversy, Churches occupy a position of essential importance in the Society of to-day. Not only is the Roman Inter- national still with us: the Church of England and the "Free Churches" of this country have been in our own day centers of important social controversy, and, as we saw in our first chapter, 1 sources from which new conceptions of the functional organiza- tion of Society have flowed. In the past, and especially in the Middle Ages, the controversy between Church and State centered mainly round the question of temporal power a controversy dependent upon the papal claim to a vice-regency of God over all the Societies of Chris- tendom. To-day, the controversy is not in the main *See p. 10. 172 CHURCHES 173 about temporal power, but about the relations which should exist between Church and State in the sphere of spiritual power. Thus, the Estab- lishment, regarded by its adherents as a recognition by the State of the spiritual mission and social function of the Church, is in fact also an instrument of State supremacy over the Church, a means where- by the temporal power of the State, often wielded now by persons who are not Churchmen, takes into its hand the appointment of spiritual leaders. In return for a doubtful gain in status, the Established Church surrenders a precious part of its autonomy a position which only continues because the Es- tablishment now does no particular harm to per- sons who are not Churchmen, while Churchmen cling to it either from a sense that it confers or recognizes status, or from less worthy economic motives. Thus, the growing "Life and Liberty Movement" in the Church of England recognizes to the full the need for spiritual autonomy, but still clings to Establishment, which, under the conditions of to-day, cannot be made consistent with autonomy. In so far as "establishment" is to be regarded as a social recognition of the mission of the "estab- lished" body, it appears to be quite logical where, and as long as, the vast majority of the people owe allegiance to a single Church. It is logical in such circumstances, because the Church cannot concern itself solely with purely "private" concerns, but must also, if it is to have a mission at all, concern itself intimately and constantly with men's social and as- sociative existence. Its rules and precepts of con- duct, if they apply at all, must apply not only to 174. SOCIAL THEORY men's private and personal doings, but also to their social doings and to the doings of the associations of which they are members. No Church which claims to have any influence upon conduct can be merely "other-worldly": indeed, it can only be effectively "other-worldly" in proportion as it occupies itself with the things of this world. This social character of Churches, implicit in their very nature and explicit wherever they have any real hold upon the people, carries with it the right to the recognition of Churches as an integral part of the structure of Society, wherever a considerable proportion of the people is concerned with them. But "establishment" has so far meant the exclu- sive recognition of the social character of a single Church within a single territory, whether or not it is the only Church or the Church which is gener- ally accepted by the people. If, however, the right to recognition depends upon the social character of Churches, that right extends to all Churches which possess this character. The functional principle im- plies the recognition of all Churches on a basis of equality. Here, however, an immediate difficulty confronts us. The social recognition of the Miners' Federa- tion or of the Edinburgh School Board does not preclude the social recognition of the National Union of Railwaymen or the School Board of Dundee. Indeed, it even implies it; for the func- tions of various industries and of various local au- thorities are complementary, and form a basis for cooperation and the creation of joint and federal bodies where they are required for the functioning CHURCHES 175 and social recognition of any particular form of association. Churches, on the other hand, despite attempts at "Reunion All Round" are not pro- fessedly complementary and do not naturally co- here; for almost every one of them professes, and must be taken as believing itself, to be the only true Church. The problem of "recognition," then, is not so simple in the case of Churches as in the case of those forms of association which cohere naturally, because they recognize at once the complementary character of their social functions. What, then, is the right of Churches to recogni- tion to mean in practice in a functionally organized Society? Or, in other words, what is the right relation of Churches in such a Society not merely to the State, but to the various essential forms of association and to the bodies which exist to coordi- nate their work? We cannot hope to answer this question until we have studied more carefully the nature of the Church as a form of human association. As soon as we do this, its essential difference from the other forms of association which we have been mainly considering becomes at once manifest. The "functions" of which we have been speaking throughout this book we have again and again interpreted as meaning "getting something done," that is, producing ma- terial results external to the persons who are mem- bers of the associations. I do not mean that Churches never aim at material results, any more than I mean that political and economic associa- tions have no spiritual aspects, or aim at results 176 SOCIAL THEORY that are merely material. But I do mean that the direct objects of political and economic association are primarily material, whereas the direct objects of Churches are primarily spiritual. This fact can perhaps be stated more clearly in another way. The distinction between political and economic association is that they have different jobs to do, and work upon different subject-matters. But Churches must concern themselves with the subject-matter of both political and economic asso- ciations, as well as with many matters which fall outside their sphere. The distinction between Churches and these other forms of association lies, then, not in the subject-matter with which they deal, but in their different ways of approaching it. They are concerned with producing a material re- sult, and Churches are also concerned in producing this result; but with political and economic associa- tions the result is primary, while with Churches it is secondary and derivative. The primary concern of Churches, as social associations, is to make their conception of the Spirit of God manifest and real upon earth. The appeal, then, of Churches is different, and the form of social power proper to them is different. The power of political and economic associations is a material power, exercisable in the last resort upon the bodies of the members : the power of Churches is or ought to be a spiritual power, exercisable upon the mind and not upon the body. If this is so, it follows that Churches can form no part of the coordinating body in Society, in so far as this body is concerned with material forms of CHURCHES 177 coercion. Material coercion, despite the rack and the stake, is no business of Churches. May the time come when it will cease to be the business of Society in any aspect. Our problem now reappears as a problem of the relation of spiritual to material power. And we arrive at once at the result that these two forms of power possess no organizable relation. If there is to be an organized relation between Churches and the other forms of association of which we have been speaking, it can arise only in two cases, where the Churches are directly concerned with material things and where their other associations are di- rectly concerned with spiritual things. In fact, the proper relation of Churches to politi- cal and economic forms of association is essentially one of cooperation without formal coordination. Churches cannot, without sacrificing their essentially spiritual character, enter into, or become a part of, the coordinating structure of Society dealt with in Chapter VIII. But they can, on many issues, fruit- fully cooperate with other associations. An in- stance is the civil recognition of religious marriages which exist to-day. Cooperation is essential: co- ordination a distortion of the character both of Churches and of the bodies with which the coordi- nation is made. This separation of Church and State is in no sense either an isolation of the Churches or a derogation from their social character. It is not an isolation, because the need for full cooperation remains : it is not a derogation, because it is the very fact that the Church any real Church is a universitas in itself 178 SOCIAL THEORY that makes coordination impossible. Full liberty of religious association and observance is therefore not the sole necessity: full self-government for every Church and complete freedom from interference with its management, appointments, doctrines and spiritual conduct is also implied. Only through such separation can Churches be freed for the at- tainment of the fullest liberty and the proper per- formance of their spiritual function. Political and economic associations must make their laws and Churches theirs. They may differ and even be con- tradictory; but they cannot conflict because they are on different planes, and, where they are con- tradictory, it is for the individual to choose his allegiance. History proves that he will often prefer a material penalty to a spiritual reprobation. Nothing that has been said in this chapter is meant to suggest that the organized Churches pos- sess a monopoly of the spiritual function, or that they are the sole depositories of spiritual wisdom. As in other spheres, the individual is the ultimate depository of spiritual wisdom and unwisdom, and only a part of his "wisdom" is susceptible of organi- zation. The existence of Churches is only one of the objective symbols of the truth that every ma- terial thing and purpose is also spiritual, and their separate existence does not derogate from, but serves to emphasize, the spiritual as well as material character of other associations. As in man, so in Society and in the community, the spiritual and ma- terial "universes" exist side by side, related in a re- lation which, fundamental and necessary as it is, is no easier to explain in the one case than in the other. CHURCHES 179 Much that is spiritual escapes the organizing influ- ence of all the Churches, as much that is material escapes the organizing of political, economic and other primarily material forms of association ; in the spiritual, as in every other sphere, the individual remains as the ultimate reality in which all associa- tion is built, but whom association can never ex- haust or completely express. CHAPTER XII LIBERTY THIS book has throughout dealt mainly with the functions and interrelation of associations within the community, with the nature of as- sociation, and with its various forms and motives, with the problems arising out of the actual work- ing of associations, and so on. In short, it has been mainly a book about organized Society, and has only dealt incidentally and in passing with those aspects of community which fall outside the sphere of organized Society. This, however, does not absolve us from the ne- cessity of dealing, from our own standpoint, with the problem which has presented the greatest dif- ficulty of all to every social theorist the problem of the relation of the individual to Society, and of the place of individual liberty in the community. The problem does not, indeed, assume for us the form which it assumed for Herbert Spencer, the form simply expressed in the phrase "the Man ver- sus the State" ; but neither can we be content with P the simple identification of liberty with law to which some theorists of an opposite school have all too willingly approximated. The question for us is one, first, of the relative spheres of social and individual o 180 LIBERTY 181 action, and secondly, one of the relation of the in- dividual to the various associations of which he is a member, or which claim in Society a jurisdiction which affects his interests. This forces upon us some attempt to define liberty, as it appears in Society and in the community. And here the first thing we have to do is to get clear in our minds a distinction between two senses in which the word is used liberty attaching to the individual qua individual, and liberty attaching to associations and institutions with which the indi- vidual is concerned. This is not the familiar dis- tinction between "civil" and "political," or even "social," liberty as it is ordinarily drawn; for a liberty attaching to the individual qua individual may be political or economic in its content as well as civil. It is a distinction, not in the content of the liberty, but in its form of expression, between the liberty of personal freedom and the liberty of free and self-governing association. It has often been pointed out that, if every in- dividual is left absolutely free and unrestricted, the result, taken as a whole, is not liberty but anarchy. Nominally free, in such circumstances, the individual has really no freedom because he has no security or safeguard, and no certainty of the way in which other people will behave towards him. But it is no less true that, even if a community possesses a complete and all-pervading system of free and self- governing association, the individual is not neces- sarily any more free, because the associations may so trammel his liberty as to leave him no range for free choice or personal self-expression. In other 182 SOCIAL THEORY words, "free" institutions do not necessarily carry with them personal liberty, any more than personal "unrestrainedness" can by itself secure real per- sonal freedom. The two manifestations of liberty are complementary, and neither of them can be complete, or even real, without the other. It will be noticed that in the last paragraph there was not an exact parallel between our two cases. I did not say that, whereas personal "unrestrained- ness" could not guarantee personal freedom, neither could the unrestrained freedom of associations guar- antee the real liberty of associations. In both cases, the end in view was the liberty of the individual; for, in the last resort, the word "liberty" has no meaning except in reference to the individual. We may speak, if we will, of a "free country" or a "free Church" ; but in both cases we mean a freedom which belongs to the individuals who are members of the body or community concerned. Here we are compelled to draw a further distinc- tion. The idea of liberty directly applying to the individual qua individual is a simple idea, and does mean simply "being let alone," with only the quali- fication that this "being let alone" is an abstrac- tion unless and until it is brought into relation to the other kind of liberty, and regarded as comple- mentary with it. But the idea of social liberty, or liberty as attaching directly to associations, is a complex idea, and includes two distinguishable ele- ments. It implies first the freedom of the associa- tion from external dictation in respect of its manner of performing its function, and it implies equally the internal self-government and democratic char- LIBERTY 183 acter of the association itself. Thus, when we speak of a "free State," we mean both a State which is not subject to any other State, and a State which is democratically governed. Personal liberty is thus simple and external; social liberty dual, and both external and internal. This difference arises, of course, from the fact that, qua individual, the individual directly trans- lates his will into deed, without the need for an in- tervening organization, whereas the individual can only act socially through an association or interme- diary, so that the need arises for a second type of social liberty, the equivalent of which is directly guaranteed to us as individuals by our possession of free will. 1 Of social liberty, or the liberty of associations, it is not necessary to add much to what has already been said. The internal liberty of associations con- sists in their democratic character, and in the truly representative character of their forms of govern- ment and administration. Their external liberty consists in their freedom from interference from outside in the performance of their functions. The point which I have thus emphasized twice by the use of italics is of the first importance. The exter- nal liberty of an association consists not in its free- dom from all interference from outside, but in its freedom in relation to its function. Such interfer- ence as is necessary to coordinate its function with 1 It will, of course, be seen that I am here refraining from entering into the oldest ethical controversy in the world. In such an ethical theory as that of Kant, personal freedom of course has its internal character of self-determination as well as the external character of "unrestrainedness." 184 SOCIAL THEORY those of other associations is not a diminution of freedom, and interference arising from a departure by the association from its function is still less so; for the association exists for the performance of its function and for nothing else, and, as soon as it steps outside its function, its rights lapse be- cause it ceases to possess to its members a true rep- resentative relation. 1 Personal liberty also is so simple an idea in itself as to need no detailed separate treatment. It is sim- ply the freedom of the individual to express with- out external hindrance his "personality" his likes and dislikes, desires and aversions, hopes and fears, his sense of right and wrong, beauty and ugliness, and so on. But to treat these two forms of liberty separately leads us nowhere. They acquire a real meaning only when they are brought into relation and when their complementary character is fully revealed. Until that is done they remain abstractions. Let us remember above all that liberty as a whole has a meaning only in relation to the individual. Society and the community itself have no meaning apart from the individuals composing them, and to treat them as "ends in themselves" is to fall into an error which vitiates every conclusion based upon it. When, therefore, we seek to bring personal and social liberty into a complementary relation, what we are all really doing is to seek that relation be- 1 This statement must be taken in connection with the re- marks on "perversion of function" in Chapter III. ; for where perversion in one case causes perversion in another the asso- ciation may acquire a secondary "counter-perversionary" function which upholds its representative relation. LIBERTY 185 tween them which will secure the greatest liberty for all the individuals in a community, both severally and in association. It is not a question of striking a balance between the claims and counter-claims of the individual and of Society, but of determining what amount of organization and what absence of organization will secure to the individual the great- est liberty as the result of a blending of personal and social liberties. First of all, it is necessary to rid ourselves once and for all of the notion that organization is in itself a good thing. It is very easy to fall into the notion that growing complexity is a sign of progress, and that the expanding organization of Society is a sign of the coming of the Cooperative Commonwealth. A constantly growing measure of cooperation among men is no doubt the greatest social need of our day ; but cooperation has its unorganized as well as its organized forms, and certainly the unorgan- ized cooperation of men, based on a sheer feeling of community, is not less valuable than organized co- operation, which may or may not have this feeling of community behind it. It is easier to do most things with organization than without ; but organization is to a great extent only the scaffolding without which we should find the temple of human cooperation too difficult to build. To say this is not to decry organization : it is only to refrain from worshiping it. Organization is a marvelous instrument through which we every day accomplish all manner of achievements which would be inconceivable without it: but it is none the less better to do a thing without organization if we can, 186 SOCIAL THEORY or with the minimum of organization that is neces- sary. For all organization, as we have seen, neces- sarily carries with it an irreducible minimum of distortion of human purpose : it always comes down, to some extent, to letting other people do things for us instead of doing them ourselves, to allow- ing, in some measures, the wills of "representatives" to be substituted for our own wills. Thus while it makes possible in one way a vast expansion of the field of self-expression that is open to the individual, it also in another way distorts that expression and makes it not completely the individual's own. In complex modern communities there are so many things that must be organized that it becomes more than ever important to preserve from organi- zation that sphere in which it adds least to, and is apt to detract most from, our field of self-expres- sion the sphere of personal relationships and per- sonal conduct. Legislation in recent times has tend- ed more and more to encroach upon this sphere, not so much directly as by indirect roads, and especially owing to the operation of economic causes. Those measures of organization and social coercion which trench upon the personal liberty of the individual or of the family are almost all directly traceable to economic causes, and fundamentally, to the existence of economic inequality in the community. They are the repercussions of the maldistribution of property and income upon the personal lives of the poorer sections of the community. Given even an approximate economic equality, there would be no need for them. LIBERTY 187 This is a sign of the manner in which bad organi- zation, or lack of free organization of a particular socfal function, at once causes perversion in other spheres, not only by causing one association to usurp the function of another, but by causing organization to take place, and compulsion to be applied, where personal liberty ought most to be preserved. The first necessity for concrete liberty for the individual lies in proper free functional organization of those things which cannot be done without association. This alone makes it possible to leave untouched those spheres of human action which are spoiled by organization. This argument can be stated more particularly in another way. Economic equality is essential to personal freedom in the sphere of personal and family relations. But free, or democratic, functional organization in the economic sphere is essential to the maintenance of economic equality. Therefore free economic organization is essential to personal liberty in the sphere of personal relations. But the individual will rightly refuse to be content with a personal liberty which is confined to the sphere of personal relations. Such liberty is vital to him ; but it is also vital to him to be personally free in his associative relations, that is, in relation to the associations of which he is a member, or which affect him by their operations. In relation to the associations of which he is a member, he will de- mand social freedom, that is, a right to a full share in their government and control. But this will not suffice for him. In addition to this social freedom which he and his fellows will claim to enjoy in rela- 188 SOCIAL THEORY tion to the associations to which they belong, each of them severally will claim personal liberty in the sense of freedom from being tyrannized over even by an association in whose decisions he has a voice and vote. What safeguard can there be for personal freedom in relation to associations, that is, what safeguard against the tyranny of majorities? It is folly to attempt, as some theorists do, to answer this argument by a blank denial of the pos- sibility of such tyranny. A majority can be just as tyrannical as a minority. A decision does not be- come my personal decision by the fact that it is carried against my vote in an association of which I am a member. There is no "paradox" of self- government in this sense, no social miracle by which my will can be transmuted into its direct opposite by the operation of democracy. It is not my real will to carry out every decision of a majority of an association to which I happen to belong, however silly or wrong I may believe it to be. In most forms of social theory, this problem assumes a false and misleading aspect by being con- fined to my relations to one particular form of association. The State is first assumed to be an alto- gether superior kind of association or super-asso- ciation, quite different from all the other associa- tions to which a man may belong. It is then assumed that he stands in quite a different relation to the State from his relation to any other associa- tion. And, whereas no one in his senses would believe that it is my real will to carry out all the decisions of my cricket club, without questioning, LIBERTY 189 men can be brought to think of the State so as to say : "Theirs not to reason why: Theirs but to do and die." If our analysis of the nature of association and our account of the nature of the State as merely one form of association are correct, it is "theirs to reason why" either in relation to all associations or to none. We may be prepared to stretch more points in favor of accepting a decision of the State than of the cricket club, because we regard the maintenance of the State as more important; but, if we reason at all, we must apply our reason to the decrees of State as well as to those of other associa- tions. A difference of degree may remain; but the difference in kind has disappeared. According, therefore, to the social theory ad- vanced in this book, a man owes not one absolute so- cial loyalty and other subordinate loyalties which must always, in case of need, be overridden by it, but a number of relative and limited loyalties, of varying importance and intensity, but not essentially differing in kind. If this is so, and if the associa- tion to which we owe our ultimate loyalty is not externally determined for us by the character of the association itself, it follows that the choice of ulti- mate loyalty, in a case where loyalties conflict, nec- essarily resides in the individual himself. It is true that the functional Society which we envisage includes in its structure forms of co- ordination and, in the last resort, coercion. Thus, in making his choice of loyalties, the individual can- 190 SOCIAL THEORY not choose without incurring a risk of penalty, and does not escape altogether from the possibility of being coerced. That, however, is not the immedi- ate point which I have in mind, though I shall be dealing with it before this chapter has grown much longer. The immediate point is that of the moral and not of the physical, or coercive, obligation upon the individual, and a great moral victory is won for individual liberty by the successful assertion of the individual's ultimate and unassailable moral right to choose for himself among conflicting social royal- ties. Even if Society punishes him for choosing in a manner contrary to that prescribed by its co- ordinating organization, it has no right to blame him or call him "traitor" merely because his choice is contrary to the social precept. It is his business how he cliooses, even if the consequences are still a sphere for social definition. 1 Moral immunity, however, may seem to afford but cold comfort. What most people will want to know is how the individual would be practically situated if, in a case of conflict of loyalties, his decision ran counter to that of the coordinating organization of Society. I believe that the position of the individual would be greatly more favorable than it is, or can be, under State Sovereignty or any unitary form of Sovereignty, or, in other words, than it can be under any system in which the su- preme social authority is vested in a single body or association. In this case at least, there is "safety in 1 Definition before the event, of course. The objection to the retrospective creation of offenses holds good all the more if this view is accepted. LIBERTY 191 numbers," and hope for the individual in the balance of functional associations in Society. Unitary the- ories of Sovereignty, or the existence in fact of Societies in which one association is supreme, are invitations to tyranny, because they are based upon the inclusion of all the individuals in a single or- ganization. If the Sovereign State is the represen- tative of everybody, the individual is manifestly less than the Sovereign State which claims, by virtue of its superiority, a right to do with and to him what it pleases in the interests of all or the whole, bien entendu. But, under a functional system, each individual is a member of many associations, and each has upon him only a limited claim limited by its so- cial function. The position of the individual as the source and sustaining spirit of every association is therefore clear, and the associations show plainly as only partial expressions and extensions of the will of the individual. They have thus no superiority over him, and their claim is limited to what he surrenders to them for the performance of their functions. Will not a Society based upon these principles be likely to be far less prone to tyranny than any other sort of Society? It must be remembered that the functional character of all its associations will make them far more truly representative, and therefore far more likely to sustain the will to liberty among their members. The best guarantee of personal liberty that can exist is in the existence, in each form of association, of an alert democracy, keenly critical of every attempt of the elected person and 192 SOCIAL THEORY the official to pass beyond his representative func- tion. In a Society made up of a multiplicity of such associations, there would be less reason than in any other that is practically possible for the emer- gence of tyranny and the submergence of personal liberty beneath the weight of social organization. The safeguards are not absolute; but they are as good as we can hope for at present. The func- tional organization of Society contains in itself the guarantee of the recognition of the fact that Society is based upon the individuals, exists in and for the individuals, and can never transcend the wills of the individuals who compose it. CHAPTER XIII THE ATROPHY OF INSTITUTIONS THERE is always a danger attendant upon theo- retical studies of presenting as static and at rest what is essentially dynamic and in mo- tion. This risk is peculiarly great in the domain of social theory; for it is difficult to refrain from hard- ening universal principles, or principles which at least seem to be universal, into precepts, and from claiming the same universality for the precept as for the principle, Utopias are almost always un- satisfactory, because they almost always depict a community from which factors of vital change and development have been eliminated. It is therefore of the first importance that we should remember that neither the human wills which make Societies and communities, nor the ma- terial circumstances upon which these wills work, have any but a relative degree of permanence. Ma- terial circumstances alter, and their alteration com- pels men to adopt new methods of living and work- ing together. And on the other hand, men's desires and aspirations change, and they seek different methods of cooperation from time to time and from place to place, even if the material conditions remain the same. 193 194. SOCIAL THEORY There is, as we have seen, a strong element of artifice about all forms of social organization. As- sociations are designed, more or less deliberately, for the fulfillment of certain purposes. Even cus- toms, which seem the most unconscious things, are for the most part only purposes become ''mechani- cal" by force of long habit. If will is the basis of Society, habit is certainly the cement which holds its structure together. This "force of habit," which is so powerful a factor in the working of Societies, as well as in the unorganized social life of communities, has two con- trasted aspects. It helps men to live together in Societies and communities without pushing their constant disagreements to the point of open con- flict; for men will tolerate calmly an evil (in their eyes) to which they are accustomed, whereas they would fiercely resent and resist its introduction. The influence of habit, thus checking the desire for re- organization and change, causes changes for the most part to take place gradually without any pro- found disturbance of the life of the community, or of the structure of the Society within it. This is the good side of habit, without which the stable existence of Society, and even of the com- munity itself, would be difficult, if not impossible. But habit has another side, and here its operations are by no means an unmixed blessing. It not only offers resistance to changes which would imperil the stability of Society, but often to changes which are necessary for its preservation and development. It not only prevents the primitive destruction of associations or institutions or customs which incur THE ATROPHY OF INSTITUTIONS 195 a temporary unpopularity, but helps to preserve as- sociations or institutions or customs which have lost all social utility, or which are actively retarding the processes of social development. Even an individual, when he "changes his mind," by casting off an old belief, or prejudice, or fruit of bad reasoning, does not usually do so by a quite sudden and simple act of conversion. He ordina- rily passes through a period of doubt, and, if the belief which is being discarded has with it a strong force of custom or habit, he will often continue to act on the old belief until the long process of con- version is absolutely complete, and even after it is complete when his will is not vigilant to prevent him from doing so. Far more is this the case with social changes. Associations, institutions and cus- toms continue apparently in full force, not only while the faith of men in their social utility is passing away, but even long after it has passed away. So strong is the social force of habit, not only upon the individual, but still more upon crowds, organized groups and communities. It is therefore a phenomenon found in almost every community at almost every stage of its de- velopment that, side by side with fully-grown asso- ciations, institutions and customs, and with such as are beginning to grow and to achieve recognition, there exist other associations, institutions and cus- toms which have lost their savor and social utility, or, to use a convenient phrase, have become atro- phied. Moreover, it will often be found that these atrophied social phenomena occupy, at any rate con- ventionally, the highest place in social honor, and 196 SOCIAL THEORY appear on the surface as integral parts of the struc- ture of Society and necessary bonds of commu- nity. Samuel Butler, who has stated far better than any one else the social force and character of habit and "unconscious memory," made, in his Erewhon novels, the best existing study of this phenomenon of atrophy. The "Musical Banks" of Erewhon, whatever their application to our own Society, form the best possible example of an atrophied insti- tution, and the worship of the goddess "Ydgrun" more familiarly known in this country as Mrs. Grundy expresses the power of habit over us which causes such survivals. There are, no doubt, extreme cases; but any one can think of instances in which the social status of a firmly and long-es- tablished institution is out of all proportion to its surviving social utility. This phenomenon of survival of the "shell" when the function has passed from it occurs principally in the case of those social forms which we decided to call "institutions." 1 It will be remembered that we there defined an institution as "an idea which is manifested concretely in some aspect of social conduct, and which forms a part of the underlying assumptions of communal life." We also said that it may be manifested either "in men's personal con- duct or relationships or through organized groups or associations." An institution, then, may be embodied in an as- sociation; but neither are all institutions embodied in associations, nor do all associations embody 1 See Chapter II., pp. 41 ff. THE ATROPHY OF INSTITUTIONS 197 institutions. An institution is a social form, whether it be embodied in an association, or a custom or something else, which has behind it a strong "force of habit" based upon a historic importance of func- tion. There are thus two elements which go to the conferring of institutional status. An idea only acquires the status of an institution by perform- ing over a considerable period of time an essen- tial social function, and thus becoming important to men's habits as well as to their reasons; but, this status once acquired, habit will usually out- last reason, and maintain the institution in being and in enjoyment of status after its function has ceased to exist or be socially important. I have said that an association may embody, or enjoy the status of, an institution, and in the second chapter I instanced States and Churches as examples of this. As we saw in Chapter II., an association is not an institution, but it may become the embodi- ment or social expression of an institution. Strictly speaking, it is not "the State" that is an institu- tion, but social order, of which the State is regarded, on the score of certain 'past services, as the embodi- ment not "the Church," but the Spirit of God on earth, which the Church with its apostolic tradition is regarded as expressing. An institution is always at bottom an idea, a belief or a commandment, and never an actual thing. It attaches itself to things, but it is not identical with things. This difference has to be brought out in order to explain fully how we manage at all to rid ourselves of atrophied institutions, or, as we should now say, atrophied expressions of institutions. Where the 198 SOCIAL THEORY idea or belief itself, that is to say the institution itself becomes atrophied, the force of habit finally dies out, and the institution passes away, perhaps long after the usefulness has been outlived. But where the idea or belief remains vital, but the as- sociation or law or custom in which it is em- bodied ceases, under altered conditions, truly to ex- press it, there, failing the adaptation of the associa- tion, law or custom, the idea which is the real "soul" of the institution transfers itself to some other law or custom, and the old "body" of the institution decays and finally disappears. In this case, too, there is probably a long period during which, though the soul has departed from it, the body of the institution continues apparently to flour- ish, and retains its social status to all outward seem- ing unimpaired. 1 In our treatment of associations, we dwelt on the fact that often, in the history of Societies, the same function passes at different periods from one association to another. Thus, industry passed from the Medieval Guilds to the capitalist employer, and is now passing, at least in part, into the control of the Trade Unions. But some Medieval Guilds still linger on in the atrophied form of Livery Com- panies, and, when Capitalism has ceased to exist, certainly if there is no violent revolution, and prob- ably even if there is, atrophied survivals of capital- ist association will continue in existence. 1 Foreign observers often mistake such atrophied bodies of institutions for the real soul of a people. The pre- revolutionary legend of Russia, as told for example by Mr. Stephen Graham, furnishes a good example. THE ATROPHY OF INSTITUTIONS 199 In the sphere of social organization, it is pro- foundly true that "Each age is a dream that is dying. And one that is coming to birth." For the associations, customs, laws and conven- tions among which we live are a queer mixture of obsolete and obsolescent survivals from the past, with other social forms "in the prime of life," and yet others which are only beginning to assume the true social shape of their maturity. The social prophet is not he who builds Utopias out of his own imagination, but he who can see in these rising as- sociations, in these laws which are "precedents," and in these forming habits the signs of the future, and can rightly say whither they are tending or what social functions they can be made to serve. The soundest part of the Marxian philosophy is that which inculcates the lesson that the structure of a new social order must be built up within the old while it is still in being, and that the face of Society can only be changed when new associations and ways of life have been created within the fabric of the old in readiness to take its place. It is true that this doctrine appears in Marxism coupled with the deadening determinism which viti- ates the whole system. The appearance of the new forms within the old is made to appear as some- thing inevitable, and not as the product of will and effort. Even as we followed Samuel Butler in applying to social theory his doctrine of habit, we may follow him here in applying his doctrine of evolution. Let us be, as he would have said, La- 200 SOCIAL THEORY marckians rather than Darwinians in our theory of social development. We need not deny or mini- mize the vast influence of material conditions in causing social changes and directing the course of social development ; but we can still believe that the creation of new social forms for old, and still more the right direction and utilization of those new so- cial forms which arise out of changing material conditions, is a matter which human wills can in- fluence and which indeed depend essentially upon men's active will to take advantage of their oppor- tunities. CHAPTER XIV CONCLUSION THE foregoing chapters embody an attempt to state, in the smallest possible compass, the essential principles of social organization. Their primary concern has been not with the ac- tual associations which exist in the community, nor with any attempt at classifying the various forms of association, but with the moral and psychologi- cal problems underlying social organization in its actual and possible forms among men and in com- munities like our own. This limitation is neces- sary, because it may be that there are peoples and communities so different from our own that the generalizations which we make for ourselves out of our own experience simply do not apply to them, or apply only with changes so fundamental as to be incalculable by us. In Western Europe, the con- ditions, psychological and material, which under- lie social organization are homogeneous enough to admit of generalizations that possess a real content. But I should hesitate to apply even to Russia gen- eralizations based on West European study and experience, and still less should I venture to apply them to the civilizations of the East. It musi 201 202 SOCIAL THEORY be enough for us if we can make a social theory which will explain our own communities, and help us to bring them, in their structure and function- ing, into a more real harmony with the wills of the men and women of whom they are com- posed. There are many persons, considering themselves as practically-minded, who scorn altogether the sort of social theory with which this book is concerned. In their eyes, social and political practice is a mass of expedients, devised to overcome particular dif- ficulties, and not derivable from any philosophic theory of Society. You can, they hold, usefully classify and arrange for future reference these vari- ous expedients; you can makfc lists of the forms of social organization, and study, by the method of comparison, the actual expedients employed in vari- ous communities. But they hold that it is useless to attempt, from the study of these expedients, to discover universal principles, or to pretend to find in them the working of certain universal ideas of human association. That the actual structure of existing Societies is to a great extent made up of political and so- cial expedients devised, with no theoretic arriere- pensee, to meet particular problems, I most fully agree ; but it has been part of my purpose to show that these expedients, both in their successes and still more in their failures, clearly reveal the work- ing of the universal principles upon which the main stress has been laid. The clash between the actual structure of present-day communities and the gen- eral principles which govern success in social or- CONCLUSION 203 ganization is manifest in every aspect of the com- munal life to-day not only in that organized part of it which we have called Society, but in its reaction upon the unorganized parts of the lives of the men and women who are the members of the community. Society to-day is, indeed, a "big, booming, buzzing confusion," and it will con- tinue to be impossible to clear this confusion away until we realize that its causes lie in our ignora- tion of the most essential conditions of successful association the principles of democratic functional organization and democratic representation accord- ing to function. While we recognize, however, that much of the malaise of communities to-day arises from the fail- ure of their leaders to grasp and apply these funda- mental principles, it is equally essential to under- stand that these principles themselves are not the inventions of the theorist or social philosopher, but are, however imperfectly, at work everywhere around us in Society. Everywhere men's striving to find expression for their social purposes leads them to base their action upon these principles, and everywhere they find themselves thwarted by actual forms of organization which run directly counter to them, either because of the atrophy of a once useful form or because some vested interest has in- terfered so as to cause a perversion or opposition of function among essential forms of association. So- ciety is everywhere the scene of conflict between the spontaneous outbursts of the principle of func- tional democracy and the resistance of established associations and institutions which are either based 204 SOCIAL THEORY upon, or have come to stand for, a perversion of social function. In these circumstances, it is natural that the true principles of social organization usually find their purest expression in the associations of revolt. There is a tendency, in some degree inevitable, of things established and powerful to deteriorate and suffer perversion, and, in any Society, the recall to sanity will largely come from those spontaneous groupings which form themselves in opposition to the groups in power. This tendency would exist even in the most perfectly organized community; but it is greatly intensified in the communities of to-day by the almost complete absence of any func- tional principle 'in tne groups which at present hold the recognized forms of social power. The prom- ise of the Society of to-morrow is in the revolts of to-day. I have tried to make as clear as possible through- out this book that human Society is neither a mech- anism nor an organism. It is not a machine which we can invent and put together at will in the meas- ure of our collective capacity; and still less is it a thing that grows without being made by our wills. We cannot describe .its processes of growth and change in terms of any other body of knowledge, natural or unnatural. It has a method and proc- esses of its own. Thus, a group of men living to- gether in some particular relation within a com- munity needs something. There may be a dozen different ways in which the need can be met. Per- haps no one devises a way of meeting it, and in that case the need goes unsatisfied. Perhaps, on the CONCLUSION 205 other hand, some on r the group as a whole, finds, or stumbles up^n, a way either of creating some new organization to supply the need, or of adapting an existing organization to deal with it. More or less successfully, the necessary steps are taken, and a new social development is inaugurated. This development would not take place without the need being more or less clearly present that is the material or environmental basis of social organiza- tion. But neither would the development take place unless human wills devised a way of meeting the need that is its human or psychological basis. This, however, is only the first stage in the de- velopment. The new, or re-created, organization arises to meet a need ; but it not only more or less perfectly meets the need, but also exerts an influ- ence on the other organizations which exist side by side with it in the community. It has therefore next to find its proper place in the general structure of Society and in the community as a whole. As an actual organization, it presents itself as a fact of which Society has to take account. Here, again, the factor of human will comes into play. There may be a dozen different ways, of varying merit, of assigning to the new organization its place and recognition in Society. Perhaps none of these ways, or a bad way, is adopted. In that case, the new organization acts as a disruptive force in Society, and may, if it is strong enough, end by tearing the social structure asunder, and compelling a funda- mental reconstruction. Or, on the other hand, it may be itself destroyed, even if it is performing a useful function in Society. Perhaps, however, 206 SOCIAL THEORY a reasonable way is found of fitting the new or- ganization into the social structure. In that case, the new organization enters into the structure of Society, and in doing so both modifies Society as a whole and is itself modified. These are the nor- mal and peculiar processes of social development. I am laboring this point in order to make it clear that important social changes are usually inaugu- rated in the parts and not in the whole of Society, and often nearer to its circumference than to its center. It is usually difficult, and often impossible, to foresee in the early stages of such a process as I have described the nature or extent of the social change that is really beginning. The best social prophet and the best constructive statesman are those who have most the power of divining, among the many new movements and associations which are constantly arising and among the old ones which are constantly undergoing modification to suit new needs, those particular organizations which are most likely to effect large changes in the whole struc- ture of Society. This may seem a truism; but it has a moral which is not so generally recognized. "Keep your eye on the new movements and organizations, and always estimate them in accordance less with what they actually are than with what they seem capable of becoming" is the first maxim of social wisdom. Big social changes are seldom, if ever, created or at least maintained, unless the impetus to change has behind it the force of an organized group or asso- ciation based on a vital common need. In the wel- ter of revolution, the power to build a new or- CONCLUSION 207 der will belong to those who have behind them the most coherent form of social organization, the form best fitted among those available to replace the old order and provide for the effective fulfillment of vital social functions. It is the possession by the working-class movements of such strong and pur- poseful forms of organization as Trade Unionism and Cooperation that makes their inheritance of the task of reconstructing Society almost cer- tain. No doubt, it will be said that this conviction of the coming of a new order, called into being largely as a result of the emergence of the new forms of social power which these working-class movements represent, has colored much of the writ- ing contained in this book. Of course it has done so. It is the business of the theorist to interpret in terms of ideas the actual forces and tendencies by which he is surrounded. Any one with the smallest degree of social vision can see that the existing structure of Society is doomed either to ignominious collapse or to radical transformation. Any one ought to be able to see that the social the- ories based upon this structure are bound to share its fate. Theory which is content merely to inter- pret the established order will inevitably misinter- pret ; for the truth about the established order is only visible when that order is confronted with its suc- cessor growing up within itself. Theory ought to get ahead of actual development; for the chief value of theory lies in helping men to act more intelligently in the present by giving them a power to grasp the principles which must go to make the 208 SOCIAL THEORY future. These principles any social principles are, of course, only true upon certain assumptions; and I have not hesitated to make certain assump- tions the basis on which the whole theory of this book is built. What are these assumptions? I assume that the object of social organization is not merely material efficiency, but also essentially the 'fullest self-expression of all the members. I assume that self-expression involves self-govern- ment, and that we ought to aim not merely at giv- ing people votes, but at calling forth their full par- ticipation in the common direction of the affairs of the community. If any one questions these assumptions, there is no way of proving them either true or untrue. If it is contended that men only ask for peace and quietness, and do not want to govern themselves, I answer in the first place that this is not true, and, secondly, that, if it were true, we ought not to acquiesce in such a state of affairs, but to alter it as speedily as possible. In short, it has been assumed throughout this book that human beings have wills, and that they have a right and duty to use those wills to their full capacity in the di- rection of Society. These, I think, are my only as- sumptions. For the rest, the arguments used to prove each point may be sound or they may be unsound. No doubt they are mixed; but my ob- ject has been not to achieve finality or write a definitive book, but to set others to work upon problems which I have only raised. The time for a new and definitive social theory is not yet; but it is high time for our generation to set about lay- CONCLUSION 209 ing the foundations of a theory more responsive to modern development than that which at present holds sway. Orthodox social theory is bankrupt: it neither corresponds to the facts of to-day, nor affords any help in interpreting the tendencies which are shaping a new social order within the old. There are already, in the writings of such men as Mait- land, Figgis, and the Guild Socialists, some of the elements necessary to a new theory; and my main object has been to express what seem to me the essential principles of this theory, certainly not in a final, but, I hope, in an intelligible form, in or- der that, even if they are not accepted, they may at least be criticised and discussed. BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTES THERE is, of course, an immense literature dealing with social and political theory in its various aspects and from different points of view. These notes are not intended to do more than indicate a few of the books which I have found most useful, by way either of attraction or of repulsion, in forming my own view. The list could be indefinitely prolonged. (A.) GENERAL MACIVER, R. M. Community, a Sociological Study. (Mac- millan.) [This is by far the best general book I know. It is especially useful on the nature of community and for the study of associations.] >r ROUSSEAU, J. J. Social Contract and Discourses, edited and translated by G. D. H. Cole. (Dent.) [Rousseau's Social Contract remains by far the greatest and most stimulating study of the basis of social obligation.] BARKER, E. Political Thought from Herbert Spencer to the Present Day. (Williams & Norgate.) [A useful introductory study.] BURNS, C. DELISLEL Political Ideals. (Oxford Uni- versity Press.) [A short study of the historical development of political ideals.] 210 BIBLIOGRAPHY (B.) SPECIAL CHAPTER I v WALLAS, GRAHAM. Human Nature in Politics. (Con- stable.) The Great Society. (Macmillan.) LIPPMANN, WALTER. A Preface to Politics. (Mitchell Kennerley.) BROWN, W. JETHRO. The Principles Underlying Modern Legislation. ( Murray. ) RITCHIE, D. G. Natural Rights. (G. Allen & Unwin.) Darwinism and Politics. (G. Allen & Unwin.) BOSANQUET, BERNARD. The Philosophical Theory of the States. (Macmillan.) ANSON, SIR W. R. The Law and Custom of the Constitu- tion. (Oxford University Press.) DICEY, A. V. The Law of the Constitution. (Macmillan.) POLLOCK, SIR F. History of the Science of Politics. (Macmillan.) JENKS, EDWARD. The State and the Nation. (Dent.) BAGEHOT, WALTER. Physics and Politics. (Kegan Paul.) The English Constitution. (Nelson.) MACDOUG ALL, WILLIAM. Social Psychology. ( Methuen. ) MACDONALD, J. R. Socialism and Society. (Inde- pendent Labor Party.) CHAPTER II MACIVER, Op. cit. CHAPTER III v PLATO. Republic, translated by A. D. Lindsay. (Dent.) BARKER, E. The Political Thought of Plato and Aris- totle. (Methuen.) DE MAEZTU, RAMIRO. Authority, Liberty and Function. (G. Allen & Unwin.) 212 SOCIAL THEORY HOBSON, S. G., and ORAGE, A. R. National Guilds. (Bell.) COLE, G. D. H. Self -Government in Industry. (Bell.) Labor in the Commonwealth. (Headley.) CHAPTER IV MACIVER. Op. cit. V GIERKE, O. Political Theories of the Middle Ages, edited with an Introduction by F. W. Maitland. (Cam- bridge University Press.) CHAPTER V AND CHAPTER VIII LASKI, H. J. Studies in the Problem of Sovereignty. (Oxford University Press.) Authority in the Modern State. (Oxford Univer- sity Press.) BOSANQUET, B. Op. Cit. HOB HOUSE, L. T. The Metaphysical Theory of the State. (G. Allen & Unwin.) PAUL, WILLIAM. The State: its Origin and Function. (Socialist Labor Press.) COLE, G. D. H. Op. cit. BROWN, W. JETHRO. The Austinian Theory of Law. (John Murray.) CHAPTER VI-VII ROUSSEAU. Op. cit. MICH ELS, R. Democracy and the Organisation of Po- litical Parties. BELLOC, HILAIRE, and CHESTERTON, CECIL. The Party y System. (Swift.) MILL, J. S. Representative Government. CHAPTER IX MARX, KARL. Capital. 3 volumes. >/ and ENGELS, F. The Communist Manifesto. BIBLIOGRAPHY PAUL, WILLIAM. Op. cit. HOBSON and ORAGE. Op. cit. COLE. Op. cit. CHAPTER X FAWCETT, C. B. The Natural Divisions of England. (Royal Geographical Society.) The Provinces of England. (Williams & Norgate.) BRUN, CHARLES. Le Regionalisme. CHAPTER XI FIGGIS, J. N. Churches in the Modern State. (Longmans.) ROBERTS, R. The Church in the Commonwealth. (Head- ley.) MARSON, C. L. God's Co-operative Society. (Longmans.) Report of the Archbishops' Committee on Church and State. CHAPTER XII RUSSELL, BERTRAND. Roads to Freedom. (G. Allen & Unwin. ) Principles of Social Reconstruction. (G. Allen & Unwin.) */ MILL, J. S. Liberty. CECIL, LORD HUGH. Liberty and Authority. (Edward Arnold.) CHAPTER XIII "^BUTLER, SAMUEL. Erewhon. (Fifield.) Life and Habit. (Fifield.) WARD, JAMES. Heredity and Memory. (Cambridge Uni- versity Press.) INDEX Action, relation to organiza- tion, 33 Ad hoc organization, 99 f., 168 Administration, 113, 162, See also Government regional, 166 A. E., 35 Air Force, 141 Amalgamation, 58 American social theory, 19 Analogies, use of, 14 Anarchy, 181 Anthropology, 18 Areas, 158 ff. Army, 42, 141, 142 Associations, 5, 7, 9, n, 14, 17, 25, 26, 30, 34, 35-6, 53, Chap. IV., 104, 125, 206 administrative, 72, 74 appetitive, 68-9, 134 f. coercion in, 128 definition of, 32 ff., 37 development of, 56 diseases of, 18 "essential," 65 ff., 74, 75 ff., 134 f. forms of, Chap. IV. government of, 104 ff., 117 ff. motives of, 77 ff. philanthropy, 71 political, 67, 134. See also State and Local Govern- ment propagandist, 73-4 provident, 70 relation to institutions, 196 ff. religious, 70. See also Churches rules of, 40 Associations, sociable, 71 theoretical, 71-72 vocational, 68, 72, 97, 134 f ., 136. See also Trade Unions and Employers' Associations Assumptions, social, 208 Atrophy, social, 38, 39, 43 ff., 75, Chap. XIII., 203 Austinian theory of law, 5, 212 Australia, 164 Balance of Powers, 124-5 Belloc, Hilaire, 122, 151, 152, 212 "Black Lists," 129 Bolshevism, 10, 61 Bosanquet, Bernard, 22, 93, 211 British Empire, 164 Burke, Edmund, 22 Butler, Samuel, 45, 196, 199, 213 Cabinet system, the, 108, 122 Canada, 164 Capitalism, 42, 147 ff., 198 Caste, 42 Catholicism, Roman, 89, 172 Charity organization, 70 Chesterton, Cecil, 122, 212 Chesterton, G. K., 160 Children, 130 Church and State, 138, 172, 177 of England, 172 Churches, 9, 10, 18, 22, 38, 42, 61, 70, 73, 76, 101, 129, Chap. XL as institutions, 197 215 216 SOCIAL THEORY Churches, Free, 172 City, 27 State, 86, 95, 107 Clan, the, 12 Class-dictatorship, 88 discrimination, 87 privilege, 87 war, 150, 152, 155, 171 Classes, economic, 153 social, 87 f . Clubs, 71 Coal Industry Commission, 159 Coercion, case against, 139 ff. Coercive power, 5, 126-7, Chap. VIII., 186, 189 f. Collectivism, 86, 98, 152 Colvin, Ian, 54 Committees, 121 Communism, 10, 69, 152 Community, 22, 97 definition of, 25-6 relation to State, 64 spirit of, 35, 120, 169 Companies, limited, 36, 68, 73 Livery, 43-4, 198 Company law, 88 Conflicting Social Obligations, 141 Consent as basis of society, 91, "3 Conservatism, 44 Consular service, 84 Consumers, organization of, 69, 98 ff . Control of Industry, 153, 198 Cooperative Societies, 73, 207 Coordination, 88, 101, Chap. VIII., 167 f., 176 ff., 183, 189 Corporate bodies, position of, 6 County Councils, 170 Coventry, sending to, 129 Cox. R. W. T., 152 Crowd psychology, 18 Custom, 5, 25, 41, 44, 45, 195 definition of, 45 relation to institutions, 45 Darwinism, 200 Decentralization, 164 Delegate versus representa- tive, 109 ff. Delegation, 118 Democracy, 9, 90, Chap. VI., 160. See also Functional Organization Despotism, 90 Devolution, 161 f. Direct action, 60 Divine Right of Kings, 8, 90 Domestic system in industry, 13 Dominion Government, 84 Duckham, Sir A., 159 Eastern civilization, 201 Economic aspects of society, 37, 59. 64, 72, 98, Chap. IX., 158 power, 144 ff., 153 ff. Efficiency, 208 Elasticity, social, 39 Elected persons, audacity of, 105, 121 Election, indirect, 167 ff. Employers' associations, 59, 68, 77. 150, 154, 171 "End in itself,'' 23 Engels, F., 144, 147, 212 Environment, i, 2, 205 Equality, economic, 151, 153, 156, 186-7 Erewhon, 196, 213 Establishment, the, 173 Ethics, relation to social theory, 7, 14, 20, 49 Europe, Western, 201 Executive power, 123 Factory Acts, 83 Family, u ff., 26, 64 analogy from, 13 Federal Governments, 84 organization, 134 ff ., 164 Figgis, J. N., 10, 209, 213 Filmer, Sir R., 13 Free will, 183 INDEX Friendly Societies, 70, 73 Function, confusion of, 57 ff. in relation to individual, 48-9 opposition of, 57-9 perversion of, 57-9, 60-2, 122 ff., 145, 148, 156, 184, 203 Functional Equity, Court of, 137 ff- organization, 9, 10, Chap. III., 79, 107, 125, 130 ff., 134 ff., 154, 162 ff., 194, 203, 207 Functions, demarcation of, 55 Geddes, Patrick, 160 General Will, 23, 51. See Will as Basis of Society Gierke, Otto, n, 212 Government, Chap. VII. Dominion, 84, 164 federal, 84, 164 Governments, common will of, 120 tendency to deteriorate, 19, 120 Graham, Stephen, 198 Groups, temporary, 40 Grundy, Mrs., 196 Guild Socialism, 10, 140, 152, 209 Guilds, medieval, 43, 64, 85, 198 Habit, 104 ff. Hegel, 22 History, constitutional, 18 ecclesiastical, 18 materialist conception of, 146, 152 relation to social theory, IT f. Hobbes, 8 Hobhouse, L. T., 93, 212 Hungary, 65 Individual, 49-50 relation to society, 4, 5, 62 Individual, unorganizable as- pects of, 31, 139, 160, 179, i8p ff. See also Personal Rights Industrial Revolution, 85, 147 self-government, 10 Innovation, method of social, 204 f., 206 f. Institutions, 25, 30, 44 atrophy of, Chap. XIII. definition of, 41, 43, 196 f. relation to associations, 196 ff. Insurance Companies, 70 mutual, 70 State, 84 "Interests," 52 International social structure, 46, 88 ff., 141 Ireland, 28, 30-1, 35 Joint Council of functional bodies, 135 ff. Judiciary, 123, 137 Kant. 183 Labor in the Commonwealth, 141, 143, 212 Labor legislation, 84 Research Department, 159 Lamarckism, 200 Law, 6, 8, n, 15, 18, 19, 20, 123, 137, 164, 198. See also Lynch Law Roman, n Society, 129 Leadership, in League of Nations, 89, 141, 143 Learned societies, 71-2 Legislation, Chap. VII., 186 commercial, 84 functional, 125 ff. labor, 83-84 Liberty. Chap. XII. See also Personal Rights and In- dividual 218 SOCIAL THEORY Liberty, personal, 184 social, 182 f . "Life and Liberty" movement, 70, 173 Local Government, 5, 67, 77, 84 f., 87, Chap. X. English, 164 Local patriotism, 160, 169 f. Locke, John, 83 Lords, House of, 136 Loyalties, conflict of, 27, 140, 189 Lynch law, 130 Maitland, F. W., n, 209, 212 Majorities, apathetic, 22 tyranny of, 188 f . Mai-distribution, 153, 186 Mann, J. E. F., 152 Marriage, 42, 43, 45, 87 Marx, 144, 145, 147, 212 Marxism, 10, 148, 149, 151, 153, 156, 162, ^199 Materialist conception of his- tory, 146, 152 Mechanical theory of society, 14, 21, 204 Medical Council, General, 129 Mercantile System, 85 Michels, R., 18, 122, 212 Middle Ages, 10, 43, 64, 85, 138, 147. 172 Militarism, 142 Milner, Dennis, 85 Mining, 97, 159 Minorities, conscious, 57 dissentient, 22 Misrepresentation, 107, 108, 159 f. Monarchy, 42, 43 Monogamy, 42 Montesquieu, 18, 19 Manning Post, 54 Motives, "associative," 77, 135 "several," 77 social, 18. Chap. IV. Municipal trading, 84 Musical Banks, 196 Napoleon of Netting Hill, The, 160 Nation, 26, 46, 95 -State, 86, 95 "National Guildsmen," 88 Navy, 42, 141, 142 New Age, 88 "New Heptarchy," 166 Non-adult races, 130 Non-unionism, 129 Officials, 104 ff., 118 Oligarchy, 9 One man one vote, 114-115 Orders in Council, 124 Organic theory of society, 14, 21, 204 Organization, a necessary evil, 185-6 Osborne Judgment, 39 Ostrogorski, 18 "Other-worldliness," 174 Papacy, the, 172 Parliament, 68, 108, 114, 119, 124, 150, 167 Party System, 122 Paul, William, 148. 212 Peasant proprietorship, 151 Peerage, 42, 43 Penty, A. J., 160 Persona ficta, n Personal rights, 87, 101, 131, 139, 181 ff. See also In- dividual and Liberty. "Personality," social, 14, 15 Physiology, 2O Plato, 48, 211 Plutocracy, 108 Police, 137 Union, 9 Political activities, definition of. 86 organization, 168-9. See also State and Local Government. relation to economic, 144 ff., 176 parties, 26, 41, 68, 73 INDEX 219 Political activities, theory, 4, 9, 156 Primitive civilization, 11-12, 1 8, 29, 64, 147 Profits, 58 Proportional Representation, 167 Provincial Home Rule, 166 Psychology, 14 physiological, 20 social, 10, 15, 18, 19, 2O, 21 Public utility services, 158 f . Purposes, individual, 33. See also Wants and Motives social, 25, 33, 38, 52, 53-4. See also Wants and Mo- tives Recall, in, 167 Referendum, 118, 133-4 Regionalism, 85, Chap. X. Religious disputes, 150-1 Representation, Chap. VI., 159 f., 191 functional, 100, 105 ff., 119. See also Functional Or- ganization Representative Government, 18, 103 ff., 114, ii7ff., 123 ff. or delegate, 109 Republics, 43 Research, industrial, 72, 84 "Reunion all round," 175 Revolt as form of progress, 204 Revolution, 60-1, 94, 198, 206 - English, 83 Rights, personal. See Per- sonal political, 94 Rousseau, 6, 19, 20, 21, 22, 23, 51. 105, 120, 133, 210 Rousseau's Emile, 20 Rules, associative, 40 ethical, 40 Russell, Bertrand, 140, 213 Russia, 61, 65, 198, 201 Schools, 2 Science, 13 Second Chamber, vocational, 136 Selection, social, 54 Self-government, case for, 208 Self -Government in Industry, loo, 123, 135, 212 Sex relationships, 86-87 Sievers, N. J., 152 Social content of action, 7 contract, 8 theory, scope of, 3, 7, 8, 17, 202 ff. Social theory, method of, 14 Socialism, international, 89 Society, 25, 66 as mechanism, 14, 21, 204 as organism, 14, 21, 204 as person, 14 -correlation of organiza- tions in, 204 ff. See also Coordination definition of, 29 Sociology, 18 Sovereignty, 10, 102, 126, 133, 140. 143, 145, 162, 190 Soviets, I2i Spencer, Herbert, 21, 180 "State, The." 4, 5, 10, 18, 22, 29, 42, 64, 67, 69, 73, Chap. V, 112. 119, 183, 188 and Individual, 4, 9, Chap. XII. See also Individual and society, 6 as association, 81, 95 as coercive power, 128 ff., 131 ff., 145-6 as compulsory association, 94 as territorial association, 95 bonus scheme, 85 coordinating activities of, 88, 101 ff. economic activities of, 83 ff.. 97 ff- employees, 84 external relations of, 88, 141 f . 220 SOCIAL THEORY "State, The," functions of, m 82 ff., 96 ff., 136 in industry, 84 members of, 93-4 political activities of, 86 ff., 100 f. Socialism. See Collectiv- ism structure of, go ff. States, actual, 16 democratic, 91-2 joint action of, 89. modern, 82 Strikes, 60, 145 Struggle for bread, 152-3 for power, 153 Subjects, 93 Suffrage, universal, 95 Syndicalism, 10, 152 Taxation, 85 Terminology of social theory, 16, 23, Chap. II. Theory, value of, 207 f. Town-planning, 160 Trade Union law, 88 Unions, 2, 9, 26, 39, 41, 59, 60, 68, 70, 73, 77, 79, 95, 101, 124, 128, 147, 150, 155, 171, 198, 207 Tribe, 29 Trusts, 84, 159 Universitas, 177 University, 2, 26 Utopias, 193, 199 Votes, 94, 115-6, 118-9, 208 Wallas, Graham, 19, 211 Wants, "associative," 34, 77 "several," 34, 77 social, 33, 204-5. See also Motives and Purposes War, 141 ff. Ward, James, 45, 213 Webb, S. and B., 159 Whitman, Walt, 105 Will, as basis of society, 6, 7, 8, 22, 103, 193, 200, 204 General, 23, 51 "Will" of association, 22 'real,' 91, 92-3, 188 Women, 2, 5 World community, 26, 142 Ydgrun, 196 THE LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Santa Barbara THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW. JUN131968 Y 50wi-3,'68(H924288)94S2 2 2 JAN 14107 DC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY A 000813704 4