ZJ I I -^ ^ Jj I I 5 s S-75^ i UJ f ■'■'\^^^ ^ 6 ^TJlJDNYSOl^ '^a3AINn-3WV -< aWEUNIVERJ//, vvlOS-ANCElfj> ^^•LIBRARYQ^^ ^tilBRAkY6k <rii3DNVsoi^ "^/^aaAiNn-JUV^ ^ojitvd-jo^ ^.!/ojiivd-jo>^ ■4. ^ .^WEUNIVERy/Zi < OS !^ -Tl E o ^'i:^]2DN vvlOS-AN'CElfXx ^OFCALIFO/?^ ^ ft A-. A o 00 '■^/ia^AiNfi^uv^ ^t'Aavaaii^ .^.OF-CAllFOMli. Ixiwi ^llIBRARYO^ CO C3 ^. \ ^>^H!BRARYQ^^ ! =0 ^<!/0JnVD-JO^ ^V.FIJf^lVFRSVA .1' =0 DO 3> "^/^aaAiNfi'^uv .^jOFCAllFO% '^omnw^ .^OFCAlIFO% %. ^l^WEUNIVER%. ^vWSANCElfj> <ri]30NVS01^'^ -1 >■ -< A'rtEUNIVERi'//, "^/^ajAiNa-jwv :^ ^vN'E-LlBRARYd?A, ^^;; :';A '%0dllV3JO^ "YQr >i: k i 13 s ,^WElJNIV£R% o ^lOSANCElfjv ^^.OF-CALI F0% XcOF-CALI f 0% "^/yaaAiNniwv^ ^<?Aavaan-# ^^Aavaaii-i'^ ~n i\V>' '^<:^AiiViiciiii\^' ''-im'M-m-^^ =0 4 '^<!/0JllV3-JO>' • ^jO^" >i M =0 4 .kp < •^P. O ^v^VlOS-ANGafj}> „ ■ ' CO v/^a3AiNn-3Wv ^^OFTAl CD ^^;OF-CAIIFO%, or ! 03 pa 5<i ^ILIBRARYO^ § 1 ir" ^ ^ -^(f/OJIWOJO^ m CQ I i3 o ■^/^a3AiNn]\\v -< to C5 CD (•5 ..S? en .V? .\WEUNIVER5'//) ':^'^ ■^ i ^TiijONYSOl^ ^lOS-ANCElfj}^ o ~ S V 30 =0 'VAa3AiNa'3Wv i) = <c o 3NVS0V^ ^VOSANCElfj> •uiU '^Aa3AINa-3WV ^t-lIBRARYC>/\ e. ^^.[irDADYo, i^ .. >!i < '^il/OJIlVDJO^ CO •Tn ^lOSANCELfj> 55 > -< ^/5ii3AiNil3WV ^ o c ^^.OF-CAIIFO/?^ ^ C3 00 t-n "^Okmrn-i"^ ^,OF-CALIF0% ^v CD >&AHvaan-^^ >~ cc < 03 THE FOUNDATIONS OF BELIEF BEIWG NOTES INTRODUCTORY TO THE STUDY OF THEOLOGY J- THE FOUNDATIONS OF BELIEF BEING NOTES INTRODUCTORY TO THE STUDY OF THEOLOGY BY THE RIGHT HON. ARTHUR JAMES BALFOUR AUTHOR OF "a DEFENCE OF PHILOSOPHIC DOUBT." ETC. ■9 3 > j'» -. V J * 3 O 1 ? O f ■>■»,« *> NEW YORK LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. AND LONDON 1895 All rights reserved Copyright, 1894, by LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. » c c * ♦ , « t «, « « « c • •« t • • • • • • • t.". •' .•. • . • « • . « • • ft « > « • . • • • « First Edition, Febrhary, 1895 Eepkinted March, April, and May, 1895 TROW DrRECTOHV PRINTING AND BOOKBrNDINQ COMPANY NEW YORK NOTE Part II., Chapter II., of the following Essay ap- peared in 1893 in the October number of 'Mind.' Part I., Chapter I., was delivered as a Lecture to the Ethical Society of Cambridge in the spring of 1893, and subsequently appeared in the July number of the ' International Journal of Ethics ' in the pres- ent year. Though published separately, both these chapters were originall}' written for the present vol- ume. The references to ' Philosophic Doubt' which occur from time to time in the Notes, especially at the beginning of Part II., are to the only edition of that book which has as yet been published. It is now out of print, and copies are not easy to procure ; but if I have time to prepare a new edition, care will be taken to prevent any confusion which might arise from a different numbering of the chapters. I desire to acknowledge the kindness of those who have read through the proof-sheets of these Notes and made suggestions upon them. This somewhat ungrateful labour was undertaken by my friends, the Rev. E. S. Talbot, Professor Andrew Scth, the Rev. James Robertson, and last, but very ■VI NOTE far from least, my brother, Mr. G. W. Balfour, M.P., and my brother-in-law, Professor Henry Sidgvvick. None of these gentlemen are, of course, in any way responsible for the views herein advocated, with which some ot them, indeed, by no means agree. I am the more beholden to them for the assistance they have been good enough to render me. A. J. B. Whittingehame, September 1894. CONTENTS PAGE Preliminary . . i PART I SOME CONSEQUENCES OF BELIEF CHAl'lER I. Naturalism and Ethics ii II. Naturallsm and /Esthetic 33 III. Naturalism and Reason 67 IV. Summary and Conclusion of Part I . . . 77 PART 11 some reasons for belief I. The Phm.osoi'hic Basis of Naturalism . . 89 II. IDKALIS.M; AFTER SOME RECENT ENGLISH WRIT- INGS 137 III. Philosophy and Raitonalism . . . .163 i\'. RATioN.\Lisr Okiiiodoxv 182 viii CONTENTS PART III SOME CAUSES OF BELIEF CHAPTER PAGE I. Causes of Experience i93 II. Authority and Reason 202 PART IV suggestions towards a provisional philosophy I. The Groundwork 241 II. Beliefs and Formulas 259 III. Beliefs, Formulas, and Realities. . . . 271 IV. ' Ultimate Scientific Ideas' .... 288 V. Science and Theology 298 VI. Suggestions towards a Provisional Unifica- tion 330 PRELIMINARY As its title imports, the following Essay is intended to serve as an Introduction to the Study of Theol- ogy. The word * Introduction,' however, is ambig- uous ; and in order that the reader may be as little disappointed as possible with the contents of the book, the sense in which I here use it must be first explained. Sometimes, by an Introduction to a sub- ject is meant a brief survey of its leading principles — a first initiation, as it were, into its methods and results. For such a task, however, in the case of Theology I have no qualifications. With the growth of knowledge Theology has enlarged its borders until it has included subjects about which even the most accomplished theologian of past ages did not greatly concern himself. To the Patristic, Dog- matic, and Controversial learning which has always been required, the theologian of to-day must add knowledge at first hand of the complex historical, antiquarian, and critical problems presented by the Old and New Testaments, and of the vast and daily increasing literature which has grown up around them. He must have a sufficient acquaintance with the comparative history of religions; and in addi- tion to all this, he must be competent to deal with 2 PRELIMINARY those scientific and philosophical questions which have a more profound and permanent bearing on Theology even than the results of critical and his- torical scholarship. Whether any single individual is fully compe- tent either to acquire or successfully to manipulate so formidable an apparatus of learning, I do not know. But in any case I am very far indeed from being even among that not inconsiderable number who are qualified to put the reader in the way of profitably cultivating some portion of this vast and always increasing field of research. The following pages, therefore, scarcely claim to deal with the sub- stance of Theology at all. They are in the narrow- est sense of the word an ' introduction ' to it. They deal for the most part with preliminaries ; and it is only towards the end of the volume, where the Intro- duction begins insensibly to merge into that which it is designed to introduce, that purely theological doc- trines are mentioned, except by way of illustration. Although what follows might thus be fitly de- scribed as ' Considerations preliminary to a study of Theology,' I do not think the subjects dealt with are less important on that account. For, in truth, the decisive battles of Theology are fought beyond its frontiers. It is not over purely religious contro- versies that the cause of Religion is lost or won. The judgments we shall form upon its special prob- lems are commonly settled for us by our general mode of looking at the Universe ; and this again, in PRELIMINARY 3 SO far as it is determined by arguments at all, is determined by arguments of so wide a scope that they can seldom be claimed as more nearly con- cerned with Theology than with the philosophy of Science or of Ethics. My object, then, is to recommend a particular way of looking at the World - problems, which, whether we like it or not, we are compelled to face, I wish, if I can, to lead the reader up to a point of view whence the small fragments of the Infinite Whole, of which we are able to obtain a glimpse, may appear to us in their true relative proportions. This is, therefore, no work of ' Apologetics ' in the ordinary sense of that word. Theological doctrines are not taken up in turn and defended from current objections; nor is there any endeavour here made specifically to solve the ' doubts ' or allay the ' diffi- culties ' which in this, as in every other, age perplex the minds of a certain number of religious persons. Yet, as I think that perhaps the greater number of these doubts and difficulties would never even pre- sent themselves in that character were it not for a certain superficiality and one-sidedness in our habit- ual manner of considering the wider problems of belief, I cannot help entertaining the hope that by what is here said the work of the Apologist proper may indirectly be furthered. It is a natural, if not an absolutely necessary consequence of this plan, that the subjects alluded to in the following pages are, as a rule, more secular 4 PRELIMINARY than the title of the book might perhaps at first susfarest, and also that the treatment of some of them has been brief even to meagreness. If the reader is tempted to complain of the extreme con- ciseness with which some topics of the greatest im- portance are touched on, and the apparent irrele- vance with which others have been introduced, 1 hope he will reserve his judgment until he has read to the end, should his patience hold out so long. If he then thinks that the ' particular way of looking at the World-problems ' which this book is intended to recommend is not rendered clearer by any por- tion of what has been written, I shall be open to his criticism ; but not otherwise. What I have tried to do is not to write a monograph, or a series of mono- graphs, upon Theology, but to delineate, and, if possible, to recommend, a certain attitude of mind ; and 1 hope that in carrying out this less ambitious scheme I have put in few touches that were super- fluous and left out none that were necessary. If it be asked, ' For whom is this book intended?' I answer, that it is intended for the general body of readers interested in such subjects rather than for the specialist in Philosophy. I do not, of course, mean that I have either desired or been able to avoid questions which in essence are strictly philo- sophical. Such an attempt would have been wholly absurd. But no knowledge either of the history or the technicalities of Philosophy is assumed in the reader, nor do I believe that there is any train of PRELIMINARY 5 thought here suggested which, if he thinks it worth his while, he will have the least difficulty in follow- ing. He may, and very likely will, find objection both to the substance of my arguments and their form. But I shall be disappointed if, in addition to their other deficiencies, he finds them unintelligible or even obscure.^ There is one more point to be explained before these prefatory remarks are brought to a conclusion. In order that the views here advocated may be seen in the highest relief, it is convenient to exhibit them against the background of some other and contrast- ed system of thought. What system shall that be ? In Germany the philosophies of Kant and his suc- cessors may be (I know not whether they are) matters of such common knowledge that they fit- tingly supply a standard of reference, by the aid of which the relative positions of other and more or less differing systems may be conveniently deter- mined. As to whether this state of things, if it anywhere exists, is desirable or not, I offer no opinion. But I am very sure that it does not at present exist in any English-speaking community, and probably never will, until the ideas of these speculative giants are throughout rethought by Englishmen, and reproduced in a shape which ordinary Englishmen will consent to assimilate. Until this occurs Tran- scendental Idealism must continue to be what it is ' These observations must not be taken as applyinjr to Part II., Cliapter II., which the general reader is recommended to omit. 6 PRELIMINARY now — the intellectual possession of a small minority of philosophical specialists. Philosophy cannot, under existing conditions, become, like Science, ab- solutely international. There is in matters specu- lative, as in matters poetical, a certain amount of natural protection for the home -producer, which commentators and translators seem unable alto- gether to overcome. Though, therefore, I have devoted a chapter to the consideration of Transcendental Idealism as rep- resented in some recent English writings, it is not with overt or tacit reference to that system that I have arranged the material of the following Essay. I have, on the contrary, selected a system with which I am in much less sympathy, but which under many names numbers a formidable following, and is in reality the only system which ultimately profits by any defeats which Theology may sustain, or which may be counted on to flood the spaces from which the tide of Religion has receded. Agnosticism, Positivism, Empiricism, have all been used more or less correctly to describe this scheme of thought ; though in the following pages, for reasons with which it is not necessary to trouble the reader, the term which I shall commonly employ is Naturalism. But whatever the name selected, the thing itself is sufficiently easy to describe. For its leading doctrines are that we may know * phenomena ' ^ and the laws ' I feel that explanation, and perhaps apology, is due for this use of the word ' phenomena.' In its proper sense the term implies, I PRELIMINARY 7 by which they are connected, but nothing more. ' More ' there may or may not be ; but if it exists we can never apprehend it : and whatever the World may be ' in its reality ' (supposing such an expression to be otherwise than meaningless), the World for us, the World with which alone we are concerned, or of which alone we can have any cognisance, is that World which is revealed to us through perception, and which is the subject-matter of the Natural Sciences. Here, and here only, are we on firm ground. Here, and here only, can we discover anything which deserves to be described as Knowledge. Here, and here only, may we profit- suppose, that which appears, as distinguished from something, pre- sumably more real, which does not appear. I neither use it as carry- ing this metaphysical implication, nor do I restrict it to things which appear, or even to things which f^wA/ appear to beings endowed with senses like ours. The ether, for instance, though it is impossible that we should ever know it except by its effects, I should call a phenom- enon. The coagulation of nebular meteors into suns and planets I should call a phenomenon, though nobody may have existed to whom it could appear. I^oughly speaking, things and events, the general subject-matter of Natural Science, is what I endeavour to indicate by a term for which, as thus used, there is, unfortunately, no substitute, however little the meaning which I give to it can be etymologically justified. While I am on the subject of definitions, it may be as well to say that, generally speaking, I distinguish between Philosophy and Meta- physics. To Philosophy I give an cpistcnioloi^ical significance. I regard it as the systematic exposition of our grounds of knowledge. Thus, the philosophy of Religion or the philosophy of Science would mean the theoretic justification of our theological or scientific beliefs, liy Metaphysics, on the other hand, I usually mean the knowledge that we have, or suppo.se ourselves to have, respecting realities which are not phenomenal, e.g. God, and the Soul. 8 PRELIMINARY ably exercise our reason or gather the fruits of Wisdom. Such, in rough outline, is Naturalism. My first task will be the preparatory one of examining certain of its consequences in various departments of hu- man thought and emotion ; and to this in the next four chapters I proceed to devote myself. PART I SOME CONSEQUENCES OF BELIEF CHAPTER I NATURALISM AND ETHICS The two subjects on which the professors of every creed, theological and anti-theological, seem least anxious to differ, are the general substance of the Moral Law, and the character of the sentiments with which it should be regarded. That it is worthy of all reverence ; that it demands our ungrudging submission ; and that we owe it not merely obedience, but love — these are common- places which the preachers of all schools vie with each other in proclaiming. And they are certainly right. Morality is more than a bare code of laws, than a catalogue raisonn^ of things to be done or left undone. Were it otherwise, we must change something more important than the mere customa- ry language of exhortation. The old ideals of the world would have to be uprooted, and no new ones could spring up and flourish in their stead ; the very soil on which they grew would be sterilised, and the phrases in which all that has hitherto been regard- ed as best and noblest in human life has been ex- pressed, nay, the words- 'best' and ' noblest ' them- 12 NATURALISM AND ETHICS selves, would become as foolish and unmeaning as the incantation of a forgotten superstition. This unanimity, familiar though it be, is surely- very remarkable. And it is the more remarkable because the unanimity prevails only as to con- clusions, and is accompanied by the widest diver- gence of opinion with regard to the premises on which these conclusions are supposed to be founded. Nothing but habit could blind us to the strangeness of the fact that the man who believes that morality is based on a priori principles, and the man who believes it to be based on the commands of God, the transcendentalist, the theologian, the mystic, and the evolutionist, should be pretty well at one both as to what morality teaches, and as to the sentiments with which its teaching should be regarded. It is not my business in this place to examine the Philosophy of Morals, or to find an answer to the charge which this suspicious harmony of opinion among various schools of moralists appears to suggest, namely, that in their speculations they have taken current morality for granted, and have squared their proofs to their conclusions, and not their con- clusions to their proofs. I desire now rather to direct the reader's attention to certain questions relating to the origin of ethical systems, not to their justification ; to the natural history of morals, not to its philosophy ; to the place which the moral law occupies in the general chain of causes and effects. NATURALISM AND ETHICS 1 3 not to the nature of its claim on the unquestioning obedience of mankind. 1 am aware, of course, that many persons have been, and are, of opinion that these two sets of questions are not merely related, but identical ; that the validity of a command depends only on the source from which it springs ; and that in the investigation into the character and authority of this source consists the principal busi- ness of the moral philosopher. I am not concerned here to controvert this theory, though, as thus stated, I do not agree with it. It will be sufficient if I lay down two propositions of a much less dubious character: — (i) That, practically, human beings being what they are, no moral code can be effective which does not inspire, in those who are asked to obey it, emotions of reverence ; and (2) that, practically, the capacity of any code to excite this or any other elevated emotion cannot be wholly inde- pendent of the origin from which those who accept that code suppose it to emanate.^ Now what, according to the naturalistic creed, is the origin of the generally accepted, or, indeed, of any other possible, moral law? What position does it occupy in the great web of interdependent phenom- ena by which the knowable * Whole ' is on this hypothesis constituted ? The answer is plain : as ' These are statements, it will be noted, not relating- to ethics proper. They have nothini,'^ to do either with the contents of the moral law or with its validity ; and if we are to class them as be- longing to any special department of knowledge at all, it is to psy- chology or anthropology that they should in strictness be assigned. 14 NATURALISM AND ETHICS life is but a petty episode in the history of the universe; as feeling is an attribute of only a frac- tion of things that live, so moral sentiments and the apprehension of moral rules are found in but an insignificant minority of things that feel. They are not, so to speak, among the necessities of Nature ; no great spaces are marked out for their accommodation; were they to vanish to-morrow, the great machine would move on with no noticeable variation ; the sum of realities would not suffer sensible diminution ; the organic world itself would scarcely mark the change. A few highly developed mammals, and chiefest among these man, would lose instincts and beliefs which have proved of considerable value in the struggle for existence, if not between individuals, at least between tribes and species. But put it at the highest, we can say no more than that there would be a great diminution of human happiness, that civilisation would become difficult or impossible, and that the ' higher ' races might even succumb and disappear. These are considerations which to the 'higher' races themselves may seem not unimportant, how- ever trifling to the universe at large. But let it be noted that every one of these propositions can be asserted with equal or greater assurance of all the bodily appetites, and of many of the vulgarest forms of desire and ambition. On most of the processes, in- deed, by which consciousness and life are maintained in the individual and perpetuated in the race we are NATURALISM AND ETHICS 1$ never consulted ; of their intimate character we are for the most part totally ignorant, and no one is in any case asked to consider them with any other emotion than that of enlightened curiosity. But in the few and simple instances in which our co-opera- tion is required, it is obtained through the stimulus supplied b}' appetite and disgust, pleasure and pain, instinct, reason, and morality ; and it is hard to see, on the naturalistic h3'^pothesis, whence any one of these various natural agents is to derive a dignity or a consideration not shared by all the others, why morality should be put above appetite, or reason above pleasure. It may, perhaps, be replied that the sentiments with which we choose to regard any set of actions or motives do not require special justification, that there is no disputing about this any more than about other questions of * taste,' and that, as a matter of fact, the persons who take a strictly naturalistic view of man and of the universe are often the loudest and not the least sincere in the homage they pay to the ' majesty of the moral law.' This is, no doubt, perfectly true ; but it does not meet the real diffi- culty. I am not contending that sentiments of the kind referred to may not be, and are not, frequently entertained by persons of all shades of philosophical or theological opinion. My point is, that in the case of those holding the naturalistic creed the sentiments and the creed are antagonistic ; and that the more clearly the creed is grasped, the more thoroughly 1 6 NATURALISM AND ETHICS the intellect is saturated with its essential teaching, the more certain are the sentiments thus violently and unnaturally associated with it to languish or to die. For not onl}^ does there seem to be no ground, from the point of view of biology, for drawing a distinction in favour of any of the processes, physio- logical or psychological, by which the individual or the race is benefited ; not only are we bound to consider the coarsest appetites, the most calculating selfishness, and the most devoted heroism, as all sprung from analogous causes and all evolved for similar objects, but we can hardly doubt that the august sentiments which cling to the ideas of duty and sacrifice are nothing better than a device of Nature to trick us into the performance of altruistic actions.^ The working ant expends its life in labour- ing, with more than maternal devotion, for a prog- eny not its own, and, so far as the race of ants is concerned, doubtless it does well. Instinct, the in- herited impulse to follow a certain course with no developed consciousness of its final goal, is here the instrument selected by Nature to attain her ends. But in the case of man, more flexible if less certain methods have to be emplo)'ed. Does conscience, in bidding us to do or to refrain, speak with an authority from which there seems no appeal? Does ' It is scarcely necessary to state that in following the precedent set by Darwin I do not wish to suggest that Biology necessarily is teleological. Naturalism of course cannot be. NATURALISM AND ETHICS 1/ our blood tingle at the narrative of some great deed ? Do courage and self-surrender extort our passionate sympathy, and invite, however vainly, our halting imitation ? Does that which is noble attract even the least noble, and that which is base repel even the basest ? Nay, have the words ' noble ' and ' base ' a meaning for us at all ? If so, it is from no essential and immutable quality in the deeds themselves. It is because, in the struggle for ex- istence, the altruistic virtues are an advantage to the family, the tribe, or the nation, but not always an advantage to the individual ; it is because man comes into the world richly endowed with the inheritance of self-regarding instincts and appetites required by his animal progenitors, but poor indeed in any inbred inclination to the unselfishness neces- sary to the well-being of the society in which he lives ; it is because in no other way can the original impulses be displaced by those of late growth to the degree required by public utility, that Nature, in- different to our happiness, indifferent to our morals, but sedulous of our survival, commends disinterested virtue to our practice by decking it out in all the splendour which the specifically ethical sentiments alone are capable of supplying. Could we imagine the chronological order of the evolutionary process reversed : if courage and abnegation had been the qualities first needed, earliest developed, and there- fore most deeply rooted in the ancestral organism ; while selfishness, cowardice, greediness, and lust l8 NATURALISM AND ETPIICS represented impulses required only at a later stage of physical and intellectual development, doubtless we should find the ' elevated ' emotions which now crystallise round the first set of attributes transferred without alteration or amendment to the second ; the preacher would expend his eloquence in warning us against excessive indulgence in deeds of self- immolation, to which, like the ' worker ' ant, we should be driven by inherited instinct, and in ex- horting us to the performance of actions and the cultivation of habits from which we now, unfortu- nately, find it only too difficult to abstain. Kant, as we all know, compared the Moral Law to the starry heavens, and found them both sublime. It would, on the naturalistic hypothesis, be more appropriate to compare it to the protective blotches on the beetle's back, and to find them both ingenious. But how on this view is the ' beauty of holiness ' to retain its lustre in the minds of those who know so much of its pedigree ? In despite of theories, man- kind — even instructed mankind — may, indeed, long preserve uninjured sentiments which they have learned in their most impressionable 3'ears from those they love best ; but if, while they are being taught the supremacy of conscience and the austere majesty of duty, they are also to be taught that these sentiments and beliefs are merely samples of the complicated contrivances, many of them mean and many of them disgusting, wrought into the physical or into the social organism by the shaping NATURALISM AND ETHICS 1 9 forces of selection and elimination, assuredly much of the efficacy of these moral lessons will be de- stroyed, and the contradiction between ethical senti- ment and naturalistic theory will remain intrusive and perplexing, a constant stumbling-block to those who endeavour to combine in one harmonious creed the bare explanations of Biology and the lofty claims of Ethics.^ II Unfortunately for m)- reader, it is not possible wholly to omit from this section some references to the questionings which cluster round the time-worn debate on Determinism and Free Will ; but my re- marks will be brief, and as little tedious as may be. ' It may perhaps be thought that in this section I have too confi- dently assumed that moraHty, or, more strictly, the moral sentiments (including among these the feeling of authority which attaches to ethical imperatives), are due to the working of natural selection. I have no desire to dogmatise on a subject on which it is the busi- ness of the biologist and anthropologist to pronounce. But it seems difficult to believe that natural selection should not have had the most important share in producing and making permanent things so obviously useful. If the reader prefers to take the op- posite view, and to regard moral sentiments as ' accidental,' he may do so, without on that account being obliged to differ from my general argument. He will then, of course, class moral sentiments with the aesthetic emotions dealt with in the next chapter. Of course 1 make no attempt to trace the causes of the variations on which selective action has worked, nor to distinguish between the moral sentiments, an inclination to or an aptitude for which has been bred into the pJivxical organism of man or some races of men, and those which have been wrought only into the iY^t/a/ organ- ism of the family, the tribe, or the State. 20 NATURALISM AND ETHICS I have nothing here to do with the truth or un- truth of either of the contending theories. It is sufficient to remind the reader that on the naturalis- tic view, at least, free will is an absurdity, and that those who hold that view are bound to believe that every decision at which mankind have arrived, and every consequent action which they have performed, was implicitly determined by the quantity and dis- tribution of the various forms of matter and energy which preceded the birth of the solar system. The fact, no doubt, remains^ that every individual, while balancing between two courses, is under the inevi- table impression that he is at liberty to pursue either, and that it depends upon 'himself and himself alone, 'himself as distinguished from his character, his desires, his surroundings, and his antecedents, which of the offered alternatives he will elect to pursue. I do not know that any explanation has been proposed of what, on the naturalistic hypothe- sis, we must regard as a singular illusion, I vent- ure with some diffidence to suggest, as a theory pro- visionally adequate, perhaps, for scientific purposes, that the phenomenon is due to the same cause as so many other beneficent oddities in the organic world, namely, to natural selection. To an animal with no self-consciousness a sense of freedom would evidently be unnecessary, if not, indeed, absolutely unmeaning. But as soon as self-consciousness is developed, as ' At least, so it seems to me. There are, however, eminent psychologists who differ. NATURALISM AND ETHICS 21 soon as man begins to reflect, however crudely and imperfectly, upon himself and the world in which he lives, then deliberation, volition, and the sense of re- sponsibility become wheels in the ordinary machinery by which species-preserving actions are produced; and as these psychological states would be weakened or neutralised if they were accompanied by the imme- diate consciousness that they were as rigidly deter- mined by their antecedents as any other effects by any other causes, benevolent Nature steps in, and by a process of selective slaughter makes the conscious- ness in such circumstances practically impossible. The spectacle of all mankind suffering under the delusion that in their decision they are free, when, as a matter of fact, they are nothing of the kind, must certainly appear extremely ludicrous to any superior observer, were it possible to conceive, on the naturalistic hypothesis, that such observers should exist ; and the comedy could not be other- wise than greatly relieved and heightened by the performances of the small sect of philosophers who, knowing perfectly as an abstract truth that freedom is an absurdity, yet in moments of balance and deliberation fall into the vulgar error, as if they were savages or idealists. The roots of a superstition so ineradicable must lie deep in the groundwork of our inherited organ- ism, and must, if not now, at least in the first begin- ning of sclf-consciousness, have been essential to the welfare of the race which entertained it. Yet it 22 NATURALISM AND ETHICS may, perhaps, be thought that this requires us to attribute to the dawn of intelligence ideas which are notoriously of late development; and that as the primitive man knew nothing of * invariable sequences ' or 'universal causation,' he could in nowise be em- barrassed in the struggle for existence by recognising that he and his proceedings were as absolutely deter- mined by their antecedents as sticks and stones. It is, of course, true that in any formal or philosophical shape such ideas would be as remote from the intel- ligence of the savage as the differential calculus. But it can, nevertheless, hardly be denied that, in some shape or other, there must be implicitly present to his consciousness the sense of freedom, since his fetichism largely consists in attributing to inanimate objects the spontaneity which he finds in himself ; and it seems equally certain that the sense, I will not say of constraint, but of incvitablcncss, would be as embarrassing to a savage in the act of choice as it would to his more cultivated descendant, and would be not less productive of that moral im- poverishment which, as I proceed briefly to point out. Determinism is calculated to produce.^ • It seems to be regarded as quite simple and natural that this attribution of human spontaneity to inanimate objects should be the first stage in the interpretation of the external world, and that it should be only after the uniformity of material Nature had been con- clusively established by long and laborious experience that the same principles were applied to the inner experience of man himself. But, in truth, unless man in the very earliest stages of his development had believed himself to be free, precisely the opposite order of discovery might have been anticipated. Even now our means of external NATURALISM AND ETHICS 23 And here I am anxious to avoid any appearance of the exaggeration which, as I think, has sometimes characterised discussions upon this subject. I admit that there is nothing in the theory of determinism which need modify the substance of the moral law. That which duty prescribes, or the ' Practical Rea- son ' recommends, is equally prescribed and recom- mended whether our actual decisions are or are not irrevocably bound by a causal chain which reaches back in unbroken retrogression through a limitless past. It may also be admitted that no argument investigation are so imperfect that it is rather a stretch of lan- guage to say that the theory of uniformity is in accordance with experience, much less tiiat it is established by it. On the contrary, the more refined are our experiments, the more elaborate are our precautions, the more difficult it is to obtain results absolutely identi- cal with each other, qualitatively as well as quantitatively. So far, therefore, as mere observation goes, Nature seems to be always aiming at a uniformity which she never quite succeeds in attaining; and though it is no doubt true that the differences are due to errors in the observations and not to errors in Nature, this manifestly cannot be proved by the observations themselves, but only by a theory established independently of the observations, and by which these may be corrected and interpreted. Rut a man's own motives for acting in a particular way at a particular time are simple compared with the complexities of the material world, and to himself at least might be known (one would suppose) with reasonable certainty. Here, then (were it not for the inveterate illusion, old as self- consciousness itself, that at the moment of choice no uniformity of antecedents need insure a uniformity of consequences) would have been the natural starting-point and suggestion of a theory of causa- tion which, as experience ripened and knowledge grew, might have gradually extended itself to the universe at large. Man would, in fact, have had nothing more to do than to apply to the chaotic com- plex of the macrocosm the principles of rigid and unchanging law by which he had discovered the microcDsm to be governed. 24 NATURALISM AND ETHICS against good resolutions or virtuous endeavours can fairly be founded upon necessitarian doctrines". No doubt he who makes either good resolutions or virtuous endeavours does so (on the determinist theory) because he could not do otherwise ; but none the less may these play an important part among the antecedents by which moral actions are ultimately produced. An even stronger admission may, 1 think, be properly made. There is a fatalis- tic temper of mind found in some of the greatest men of action, religious and irreligious, in which the sense that all that happens is fore-ordained does in no way weaken the energy of volition, but only adds a finer temper to the courage. It nevertheless remains the fact that the persistent realisation of the doctrine that voluntary decisions are as com- pletely determined by external and (if you go far enough back) by material conditions as involuntary ones, does really conflict with the sense of personal responsibility, and that with the sense of personal responsibility is bound up the moral will. Nor is this all. It may be a small matter that determinism should render it thoroughly irrational to feel right- eous indignation at the misconduct of other people. It cannot be wholly without importance that it should render it equally irrational to feel righteous indignation at our own. Self-condemnation, repent- ance, remorse, and the whole train of cognate emo- tions, are really so useful for the promotion of virt- ue that it is a pity to find them at a stroke thus NATURALISM AND ETHICS 2$ deprived of all reasonable foundation, and reduced, if they are to survive at all, to the position of ami- able but unintelligent weaknesses. It is clear, more- over, that these emotions, if they are to fall, will not fall alone. What is to become of moral admiration? The virtuous man will, indeed, continue to deserve and to receive admiration of a certain kind — the admiration, namely, which we justly accord to a well-made machine ; but this is a very different senti- ment from that at present evoked by the heroic or the saintly ; and it is, therefore, much to be feared that, at least in the region of the higher feelings, the world will be no great gainer by the effective spread of sound naturalistic doctrine. No doubt this conffict between a creed which claims intellectual assent and emotions which have their root and justification in beliefs which are deliberately rejected, is greatly mitigated by the precious faculty which the human race enjoys of quietly ignoring the logical consequences of its own accepted theories. If the abstract reason by which such theories are contrived always ended in pro- ducing a practice corresponding to them, natural selection would long ago have killed off all those who possessed abstract reason. If a complete accord between practice and speculation were required of us, philosophers would long ago have been eliminated. Nevertheless, the persistent con- flict lietween that which is thought to be true, and that which is felt to be noble and of good 26 NATURALISM AND ETHICS report, not only produces a sense of moral unrest in the individual, but makes it impossible for us to avoid the conclusion that the creed which leads to such results is, somehow, unsuited for ' such beings as we are in such a world as ours.' Ill There is thus an incongruity between the senti- ments subservient to morality, and the naturalistic account of their origin. It remains to inquire whether any better harmony prevails between the demands of the ethical imagination and what Naturalism tells us concerning the final goal of all human endeavour. This is plainly not a question of small or sub- sidiary importance, though it is one which 1 shall make no attempt to treat with anything like com- pleteness. Two only of these ethical demands is it necessary, indeed, that I should here refer to : that which requires the ends prescribed by morality to be consistent ; and that which requires them to be adequate. Can we say that either one or the other is of a kind which the naturalistic theory is able to satisfy ? The first of these questions — that relating to consistency — will no doubt be dealt with in different ways by various schools of moralists ; but by what- ever path they travel, all should arrive at a negative conclusion. Those who hold as I do, that ' reason- NATURALISM AND ETHICS 2^ able self-love* has a legitimate position among ethical ends ; that as a matter of fact it is a virtue wholly incompatible with what is commonly called selfishness ; and that society suffers not from having too much of it, but from having too little, will probably take the view that, until the world under- goes a very remarkable transformation, a complete harmony between 'egoism' and 'altruism,' between the pursuit of the highest happiness for one's self and the highest happiness for other people, can never be provided by a creed which refuses to admit that the deeds done and the character formed in this life can fiow over into another, and there permit a reconciliation and an adjust- ment between the conflicting principles which are not always possible here. To those, again, who hold (as I think, erroneously), both that the 'greatest happiness of the greatest number' is the right end of action, and also that, as a matter of fact, every agent invariably pursues his own, a heaven and a hell, which should make it certain that principle and interest were always in agreement, would seem almost a necessity. Not otherwise, neither by education, public opinion, nor positive law, can there be any assured harmony produced between that which man must do by the constitution of his will, and that which he ought to do according to the promptings of his conscience. On the other hand, it must be acknowledged that those moralists who are of opinion that ' altruistic ' ends alone are 28 NATURALISM AND ETHICS worthy of being described as moral, and that man is not incapable of pursuing them without any self- regarding motives, require no future life to eke out their practical system. But even they would prob- ably not be unwilling to admit, with the rest of the world, that there is something jarring to the moral sense in a comparison between the distribution of happiness and the distribution of virtue, and that no better mitigation of the difficulty has yet been suggested than that which is provided by a system of * rewards and punishments,' impossible in any uni- verse constructed on strictly naturalistic principles. With this bare indication of some of the points which naturally suggest themselves in connection with the first question suggested above, I pass on to the more interesting problem raised by the second : that which is concerned with the cmo/w/ia/ adequa.cy of the ends prescribed by Naturalistic Ethics. And in order to consider this to the best advantagfe I will assume that we are dealing Avith an ethical sys- tem which puts these ends at their highest; which charges them, as it were, to the full with all that, on the naturalistic theory, they are capable of con- taining. Taking, then, as my text no narrow or egoistic scheme, I will suppose that in the per- fection and felicity of the sentient creation we may find the all-inclusive object prescribed by morality for human endeavour. Does this, then, or does it not, supply us with all that is needed to satisfy our ethical imagination ? Does it, or does it not, pro- NATURALISM AND ETHICS 29 vide US with an ideal end, not merely big enough to exhaust our energies, but great enough to satisfy our aspirations ? At first sight the question may seem absurd. The object is admittedly worthy ; it is admittedly beyond our reach. The unwearied efforts of count- less generations, the slow accumulation of inherited experience, may, to those who find themselves able to read optimism into evolution, promise some faint approximation to the millennium at some far distant epoch. How, then, can we, whose own contribution to the great result must be at the best insignificant, at the worst nothing or worse than nothing, presume to think that the prescribed object is less than adequate to our highest emotional requirements? The reason is plain: our ideals are framed, not according to the measure of our performances, but according to the measure of our thoughts ; and our thoughts about the world in which we live tend, under the influence of increasing knowledge, con- stantly to dwarf our estimate of the importance of man, if man be indeed, as Naturalism would have us believe, no more than a phenomenon among phenom- ena, a natural object among other natural objects. For what is man looked at from this point of view ? Time was when his tribe and its fortunes were enough to exhaust the energies and to bound the imagination of the primitive sage.^ The gods' ' The line of ihou.i^'-lu here is idcnlical witii ihat wliicli I pursued in an already published essay on the Religion of Humanity. 1 30 NATURALISM AND ETHICS peculiar care, the central object of an attendant uni- verse, that for which the sun shone and the dew fell, to which the stars in their courses ministered, it drew its origin in the past from divine ancestors, and might by divine favour be destined to an indef- inite existence of success and triumph in the future. These ideas represent no early or rudimentary stage in the human thought, yet have we left them far behind. The family, the tribe, the nation, are no longer enough to absorb our interests. Man — past, present, and future — lays claim to our devo- tion. What, then, can we say of him ? Man, so far as natural science by itself is able to teach us, is no longer the final cause of the universe, the Heav^en- descended heir of all the ages. His very existence is an accident, his story a brief and transitory episode in the life of one of the meanest of the planets. Of the combination of causes which first converted a dead organic compound into the living progenitors of humanity, science, indeed, as yet knows nothing. It is enough that from such begin- nings famine, disease, and mutual slaughter, fit nurses of the future lords of creation, have gradually evolved, after infinite travail, a race with conscience enough to feel that it is vile, and intelligence enough to know that it is insignificant. We survey the past, and see that its history is of blood and tears, of helpless blundering, of wild revolt, of stupid ac- have not hesitated to borrow the phraseology of that essay wherever it seemed convenient. NATURALISM AND ETHICS 3 1 quiescence, of empty aspirations. We sound the future, and learn that after a period, long compared with the individual life, but short indeed compared with the divisions of time open to our investigation, the energies of our system will decay, the glory of the sun will be dimmed, and the earth, tideless and inert, will no longer tolerate the race which has for a moment disturbed its solitude. Man will go down into the pit, and all his thoughts will perish. The uneasy consciousness, which in this obscure corner has for a brief space broken the contented silence of the universe, will be at rest. Matter will know itself no longer. ' Imperishable monuments ' and ' immortal deeds,' death itself, and love stronger than death, will be as though they had never been. Nor will anything that is be better or be worse for all that the labour, genius, devotion, and suffering of man have striven through countless generations to effect. It is no reply to say that the substance of the Moral Law need suffer no change through any modification of our views of man's place in the universe. This may be true, but it is irrelevant. We desire, and desire most passionately when we are most ourselves, to give our service to that which is Universal, and to that which is Abiding. Of what moment is it, then (from this point of view), to be assured of the fixity of the moral law when it and the sentient world, where alone it has any signifi- cance, are alike destined to vanish utterly away within periods trifiing beside those with which the 32 NATURALISM AND ETHICS geologist and the astronomer lightly deal in the course of their habitual speculations ? No doubt to us ordinary men in our ordinary moments considera- tions like these may seem far off and of little mean- ing. In the hurry and bustle of every-day life death itself — the death of the individual — seems shadowy and unreal ; how much more shadowy, how much less real, that remoter but not less certain death which must some day overtake the race ! Yet, after all, it is in moments of reflection that the worth of creeds may best be tested ; it is through moments of reflection that they come into living and effectual contact with our active life. It cannot, therefore, be a matter to us of small moment that, as we learn to survey the material world with a wider vision, as we more clearly measure the true proportions which man and his performances bear to the ordered Whole, our practical ideal gets relatively dwarfed and beggared, till we may well feel inclined to ask whether so transitory and so unimportant an acci- dent in the general scheme of things as the foi'tunes of the human race can any longer satisfy aspirations and emotions nourished upon beliefs in the Ever- lasting and the Divine. CHAPTER II NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC In the last chapter I considered the effects which Naturalism must tend to produce upon the senti- ments associated with Morality. I now proceed to consider the same question in connection with the sentiments known as assthetic ; and as I assumed that the former class were, like other evolutionary utilities, in the main produced by the normal operation of selection, so I now assume that the latter, being (at least in any developed stage) quite useless for the perfection of the individual or species, must be re- garded, upon the naturalistic hypothesis, as mere by- products of the great machinery by which organic life is varied and sustained. It will not, I hope, be supposed that I propose to offer this distinction as a material contribution towards the definition either of ethic or of aesthetic sentiments. This is a ques- tion in which I am in no way interested ; and I am quite prepared to admit that some emotions which in ordinary language would be described as 'moral,' are useless enougli to be included in the class of natural accidents ; and also that this class may, 3 34 NATURALISM AND ^ESTHETIC indeed does, include many emotions which no one following common usage would characterise as assthetic. The fact remains, however, that the capacity for every form of feeling must in the main either be, or not be, the direct result of selection and elimination ; and whereas in the first section of the last chapter I considered the former class, taking moral emotion as their type, so now I propose to offer some observations on the second class, taking: as their type the emotions excited by the Beautiful. Whatever value these Notes may have will not necessarily be affected by any error that I may have made in the apportionment between the two divisions, and the reader may make what redistri- bution he thinks fit, without thereby necessarily in- validating the substance of the conclusions which I offer for his acceptance. I do not, however, anticipate that there will be any serious objection raised from the scientific side to the description of developed assthetic emotion as ' accidental,' in the sense in which that word is here employed. The obstacle I have to deal with in conducting the argument of this chapter is of a different kind. My object is to indicate the conse- quences which flow from a purely naturalistic treat- ment of the theory of the Beautiful ; and I am at once met with the difficulty that, so far as I am aware, no such treatment has ever been attempted on a large scale, and that the fragmentary contributions which have been made to the subject do not meet NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC 35 with general acceptance on the part of scientific in- vestigators themselves. To say that certain capaci- ties for highly complex feeling are not the direct result of natural selection, and were not evolved to aid the race in the struggle for existence, may be a true, but is a purely negative account of the matter, and gives but little help in dealing with the two questions to which an answer is especially required : namely. What are the causes, historical, psychologi- cal, and physiological, which enable us to derive aes- thetic gratification from some objects, and forbid us to derive it from others ? and, Is there any fixed and permanent element in Beauty, any unchanging reali- ty which we perceive in or through beautiful objects, and to which normal aesthetic feelings correspond ? Now, it is clear that on the naturalistic hypothesis the second question cannot be properly dealt with till some sort of answer has been given to the first ; and the answers given to the first seem so unsat- isfactory that they can hardly be regarded as even provisionally adequate. In order to realise the difficulties and, as I think, the shortcomings of existing theories on the sub- ject, let us take the case of Music — by far the most convenient of the Fine Arts for our purpose, part- ly because, unlike Architecture, it serves no very obvious purpose,^ and we are thus absolved from ' I may be permitted to isjnorc Mr. Spencer's suggestion that the function of music is to promote sympathy by improving our modulation in speech. 36 NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC giving any opinion on the relation between beauty and utility ; partly because, unlike Painting and Poetry, it has no external reference, and we are thus absolved from giving any opinion on the relation between beauty and truth. Of the inestimable blessings which these peculiarities carry with them, anyone may judge who has ever got bogged in the barren controversies concerning the Beautiful and the Useful, the Real and the Ideal, which fill so large a space in certain classes of aesthetic literature. Great indeed will he feel the advantages to be of dealing with an Art whose most characteristic utterances have so little to do directly, either with utility or truth. What, then, is the cause of our delight in Music ? It is sometimes hastily said to have originated in the ancestors of man through the action of sexual selection. This is of course impossible. Sexual selection can only work on materials already in existence. Like other forms of selection, it can im- prove, but it cannot create; and the capacity for enjoying music (or noise) on the part of the female, and the capacity for making it on the part of the male, must both have existed in a rudimentary state before matrimonial preferences can have improved either one gift or the other. I do not in any case quite understand how sexual selection is supposed even to improve the capacity for enjoyment. If the taste exist, it can no doubt develop the means re- quired for its gratification; but how can it improve NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC 37 the taste itself? The ieniales ol certain species of spiders, I believe, like to see good dancing. Sexual selection, therefore, no doubt may gradually improve the dancing of the male. The females of many animals are, it seems, fond of particular kinds of noise. Sexual selection may therefore gradually fur- nish the male with the apparatus by which appro- priate noises may be produced. In both cases, however, a pre-existing taste is the cause of the variation, not the variation of the taste ; nor, ex- cept in the case of the advanced arts, which do not flourish at a period when those who successfully practise them have any advantage in the matri- monial struggle, does taste appear to be one of the necessary qualifications of the successful artist. Of course, if violin - playing were an important aid to courtship, sexual selection would tend to develop that musical feeling and discrimination, without which good violin-playing is impossible. But a grasshopper requires no artistic sensibility before it can successfully rub its wing-cases together ; so that Nature is only concerned to provide the an- atomical machinery by which such rubbing may result in a sibilation gratifying to the existing aesthetic sensibilities of the female, but cannot in any way be concerned in developing the artistic side of Ihose sensibilities themselves. Sexual selection, therefore, however well it may be fitted to give an explanation of a large number of animal noises and of the growth of the organs by 38 NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC which they are produced, throws but little light on the origin and development of musical feeling, either in animals or men. And the other explanations I have seen do not seem to me much better. Take, for instance, Mr. Spencer's modification of Rousseau's theory. According to Mr. Spencer, strong emotions are naturally accompanied by muscular exertion, and, among other muscular exertions, by contractions and extensions of ' the muscles of the chest, abdomen, and vocal cords.' The resultant noises recall by association the emotions which gave them birth, and from this primordial coincidence sprang, as we are asked to believe, first cadenced speech, and then music. Now I do not desire to quarrel with the ' primordial coincidence.' My point is, that even if it ever took place, it affords no explanation of any modern feeling for music. Grant that a particular emotion produced a ' contraction of the abdomen,' that the ' contraction of the abdomen ' produced a sound or series of sounds, and that, through this association with the originating emotion, the sound ultimately came to have independent aesthetic value, how are we advanced towards any explanation of the fact that quite different sound-effects now please us, and that the nearer we get to the original noises, the more hideous they appear? How does the ' pri- mordial coincidence ' account for our ancestors lik- ing the tom-tom? And how does the fact that our ancestors liked the tom-tom account for our liking the Ninth Symphony ? NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC 39 The truth is that Mr. Spencer's theory, like all others which endeavour to trace back the pleasure- f^iving qualities of art to some simple and original association, slurs over the real difficulties of the problem. If it is the primitive association which produces the pleasure-giving quality, the further this is left behind by the developing art, the less pleasure should be produced. Of course, if the art is con- tinually fed from other associations and different experiences, if fresh emotional elements are con- stantly added to it capable of being worn and weathered into the fitting soil for an aesthetic har- vest, in that case, no doubt, we may suppose that with each new development its pleasure - giving qualities may be enriched and multiplied. But then, it is to these new elements and to these new experi- ences, not to the ' primordial coincidence,' that we should mainly look for the causal explanation of our assthetic feeling. In the case of music, where are these new elements and experiences to be found ? None can tell us ; few theorists even try. Indeed, the procedure of those who account for music by searching for the primitive association which first in the history of man or of his ancestors conferred assthetic value upon noise, is as if one should explain the Amazon in its flood by point- ing to the rivulet in the far Andes which, as the tributary most distant from its mouth, has the honour of being called its source. This may be allowed to stand as a geographical description, but it is very 40 NATURALISM AND ^ESTHETIC inadequate as a physical explanation. Dry up the rivulet, and the huge river would still flow on, without abatement or diminution. Only its titular origin has been touched; and if we would know the Amazon in its beginnings, and trace back the history of the vast result through all the complex ramifica- tions of its contributory causes, each great confluent must be explored, each of the countless streams enumerated whose gathered waters sweep into the sea four thousand miles across the plain. The imperfection of this mode of procedure will become clear if we compare it with that adopted by the same school of theorists when they endeavour to explain the beauty of landscape. I do not mean to express any assent to their account of the causes of our feelings for scenery ; on the contrary, these accounts seem to me untenable. But though unten- able, they are not on the face of them inadequate. Natural objects — the sky and hills, woods and waters — are spread out before us as they were spread out before our remotest ancestors, and there is no ob- vious absurdity (if the hereditary transmission of acquired qualities be granted) in conceiving them, through the secular experience of mankind, to be- come charged with associations which reappear for us in the vague and massive form of aesthetic pleas- ure. But according to all association theories of music, that which is charged with the raw material of aesthetic pleasure is not the music we wish to have explained, but some primeval howl, or at best the NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC 41 unmusical variations of ordinary speech, and no solution whatever is offered of the paradox that the sounds which give musical delight have no associa- tions, and that the sounds which had associations give no musical delight. It is, perhaps, partly in consequence of these or analogous difBculties, but mainly in consequence of his views on heredity, which preclude him from accepting any theory which involves the transmis- sion of acquired qualities, that Weismann gives an account of the musical sense which is practically equivalent to the denial that any explanation of the pleasure we derive from music is possible at all. For him, the faculties which enable us to appreciate and enjoy music were evolved for entirely differ- ent purposes, and it is a mere accident that, when they come into relation with certain combinations of sound, we obtain through their means aesthetic gratification. Mankind, no doubt, are continually inventing new musical devices, as they are con- tinually inventing new dishes. But as the second process implies an advance in the art of cookery, but no transmitted modification in the human pal- ate, so the former implies musical progress, but no change in the innate capacities of successive genera- tions of listeners.^ ' I have made no allusion to Helmholtz's classic investigations, for these deal chiefly with the physical character of the sounds, or combinations of sound, which give us pleasure, but do not pretend fully to answer the cjuestion 7vliy they give pleasure. 42 NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC II This is, perhaps, a sufficiently striking example of the unsatisfactory condition of scientific £esthetics, and may serve to show how difficult it is to find in the opinions of different authorities a common body of doctrine on which to rest the argument of this chapter. I should imagine, however, both from the speculations to which I have just briefly ad- verted, and from any others with which I am ac- quainted, that no person who is at all in sympathy with the naturalistic view of things would maintain that there anywhere exists an intrinsic and essential quality of beauty, independent of the feelings and the taste of the observer. The very nature, indeed, of the senses principally engaged indicates that on the naturalistic hypothesis they cannot, in most cases, refer to any external and permanent object of beauty. For Naturalism (as commonly held) is deeply com- mitted to the distinction between the primary and the secondary qualities of matter ; the former (exten- sion, solidity, and so forth) being supposed to exist as they are perceived, while the latter (such as sound and colour) are due to the action of the primary qualities upon the sentient organism, and apart from the sen- tient organism have no independent being. Every scene in Nature, therefore, and every work of art, whose beauty consists either directly or indirectly, either presentatively or representatively, in colour or NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC 43 in sound, has, and can have, no more permanent exist- ence than is possessed by that relation between the senses and our material environment which gave them birth, and in the absence of which they perish. If we could perceive the succession of events which constitute a sunset exactly as they occur, as they are (physically, not metaphysically speaking) /// themselves, they would, so far as we can guess, have no aesthetic merit, or even meaning. If we could perform the same operation on a symphony, it would end in a like result. The first would be no more than a special agitation of the ether ; the second would be no more than a special agitation of the air. However much they might excite the curiosity of the physicist or the mathematician, for the artist they could no longer possess either inter- est or significance. It might, however, be said that the Beautiful, although it cannot be called permanent as compared with the general framework of the external world, is, nevertheless, sufficiently permanent for all human purposes, in so far as it depends upon the fixed rela- tions between our senses and their material sur- roundings. Without at present stopping to dispute this, let us consider whether we have any right to suppose that even this degree of ' objectivity ' can be claimed for the quality of beauty. In order to settle the question we can, on the naturalistic hypothesis, appeal, it would seem, to only one authority, namely, the experience of mankind. 44 NATURALISM AND JESTUETIC Does this, then, provide us with any evidence that beauty is more than the name for a miscellaneous flux of endlessly varying causes, possessing no property in common, except that at some place, at some time, and in some person, they have each shown themselves able to evoke the kind of feeling which we choose to describe as aesthetic ? Put thus there seems room for but one answer. The variations of opinion on the subject of beauty are notorious. Discordant pronouncements are made by different races, different ages, different individuals, the same individual at different times. Nor does it seem possible to devise any scheme by which an authoritative verdict can be extracted from this chaos of contradiction. An appeal, indeed, is sometimes made from the opinion of the vulgar to the decision of persons of ' trained sensibility ' ; and there is no doubt that, as a matter of fact, through the action of those who profess to belong to this class, an orthodox tradition has grown up which may seem at first sight almost to provide some faint approximation to the ' objective ' standard of which we are in search. Yet it will be evident on con- sideration that it is not simply on their 'trained sensibility ' that experts rely in forming their opinion. The ordinary critical estimate of a work of art is the result of a highly complicated set of antecedents, and by no means consists in a simple and naked valuation of the ' aesthetic thrill ' which the aforesaid work produces in the critic, now and NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC 45 here. If it were so, .clearly it could not be of any importance to the art critic when and by whom any particular work of art was produced. Problems of age and questions of authorship would be left en- tirely to the historian, and the student of the beau- tiful would, as such, ask himself no question but this : How and why are my esthetic sensibilities affected by this statue, poem, picture, as it is in itself ? or (to put the same thing in a form less open to metaphysical disputation), What would my feelings towards it be if I were totally ignorant of its date, its author, and the circumstances of its production ? As we all know, these are considerations never in practice ignored by the critic. He is preoccu- pied, and rightly preoccupied, by a multitude of questions beyond the mere valuation of the out- standing amount of aesthetic enjoyment which, in the year 1892, any artistic or literary work, taken simpliciter, is, as a matter of fact, capable of produc- ing. He is much concerned with its technical pecul- iarities. He is anxious to do justice to its author, to assign him his true rank among the productive geniuses of his age and country, to make due allow- ance for his ' environment,' for the traditions in which he was nurtured, for the causes which make his creative genius embody itself in one form rather than in another. Never for one instant does the critic forget, or allow his reader to forget, that the real magnitude of the foreshortened object under observation must be estimated by the rules of his- 46 NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC torical perspective. Never does he omit, in dealing with the artistic legacies of bygone times, to take account of any long -accepted opinion which may exist concerning them. He endeavours to make himself the exponent of the 'correct view.' His judgment is, consciously or unconsciously, but not, I think, wrongly, a sort of compromise between that which he would form if he drew solely from his own inner experience, and that which has been formed for him by the accumulated wisdom of his predecessors on the bench. He expounds case- made law. He is partly the creature and partly the creator of a critical tradition ; and we can easily conjecture how devious his course would be, were his orbit not largely controlled by the attraction of received views, if we watch the disastrous fate which so often overtakes him when he pronounces judgment on new works, or on works of which there is no estimate embodied in any literary creed which he thinks it necessary to respect. Voltaire's opinion of Shakespeare does not make one think less of Voltaire, but it throws an interesting light on the genesis of average critical decisions and the normal growth of taste. From these considerations, which might easily be supplemented, it seems plain that the opinions of critical experts represent, not an objective standard, if such a thing there be, but an historical compro- mise. The agreement among them, so far as such a thing is to be found, is not due solely to the fact NATURALISM AND /liSTHETIC 47 that with their own eyes they all see the same things, and therefore say the same things ; it is not wholly the result of a common experience : it arises in no small measure from their sympathetic endeav- ours to see as others have seen, to feel as others have felt, to judge as others have judged. This may be, and I suppose is, the fairest way of compar- ing the merits of deceased artists. But, at the same time, it makes it impossible for us to attach much weight to the assumed consensus of the ages, or to suppose that this, so far as it exists, implies the realit}^ of a standard independent of the varying whims and fancies of individual critics. In truth, however, the consensus of the ages, even about the greatest works of creative genius, is not only in part due to the process of critical manufacture indicated above, but its whole scope and magnitude is ab- surdly exaggerated in the phrases which pass cur- rent on the subject. This is not a question, be it observed, of aesthetic right and wrong, of good taste or bad taste ; it is a question of statistics. We are not here concerned with what the mass of mankind, even of educated mankind, ought to feel, but with what as a matter of fact they do feel, about the works of literature and art which they have inher- ited from the past. And I believe that every im- partial observer will admit that, of the aesthetic emotion actually experienced by any generation, the merest fraction is due to the 'immortal ' productions <jf the generations which have long preceded it. 48 NATURALISM AND ^ESTHETIC Their immortality is largely an immortality of libraries and museums ; they supply material to critics and historians, rather than enjoyment to mankind ; and if it were to be maintained that one music-hall song gives more assthetic pleasure in a night than the most exquisite compositions of Pales- trina in a decade, I know not how the proposition could be refuted. The ancient Norsemen supposed that besides the soul of the dead, which went to the region of de- parted spirits, there survived a ghost, haunting, though not for ever, the scenes of his earthly la- bours. At first vivid and almost lifelike, it slowly waned and faded, until at length it vanished, leav- ing behind it no trace or memory of its spectral presence amidst the throng of living men. So, it seems to me, is the immortality we glibly predicate of departed artists. If they survive at all, it is but a shadowy life they live, moving on through the gradations of slow decay to distant but inevitable death. They can no longer, as heretofore, speak directly to the hearts of their fellow-men, evoking their tears or laughter, and all the pleasures, be they sad or merry, of which imagination holds the secret. Driven from the market-place, they become first the companions of the student, then the victims of the specialist. He who would still hold familiar intercourse with them must train himself to pene- trate the veil which, in ever-thickening folds, con- ceals them from the ordinary gaze ; he must catch NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC 49 the tone of a vanished society, he must move in a circle of alien associations, he must think in a lan- guage not his own. Need we, then, wonder that under such conditions the outfit of a critic is as much intellectual as emotional, or that if from off the complex sentiments with which they regard the ' immortal legacies of the past ' we strip all that is due to interests connected with history, with biog- raphy, W4th critical analyses, with scholarship, and with technique, but a small modicum will, as a rule, remain which can with justice be attributed to pure aesthetic sensibility. Ill I have, however, no intention of implying b}'' the preceding observations that the aesthetic feelings of ' the vulgar ' are less sophisticated than those of the learned. A very cursory examination of * public taste' and its revolutions may suffice to convince anyone of the contrary. And, in the first place, let us ask why every ' public ' has a taste ? And why, at least in Western communities, that taste is so apt to alter? Why, in other words, do communities or sections (jf communities so often feel the same thing at the same time, and so often feel different things at different times? Why is there so mu-ch uniformity, and why is there so much change? These questions are of great interest, although they have not, perhaps, met with all the attention 4 50 NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC they deserve. In these Notes it would not be fitting to attempt to deal with them at length, and I shall only offer observations on two points which seem relevant to the design of the present chapter. The question of Uniformity is best approached at the humbler end of the testhetic scale, in connec- tion, not with art in its narrower and loftier sense, but with dress. Everybody is acquainted, either by observation or by personal experience, with the coercive force of fashion ; but not everybody is aware what an instructive and interesting phenom- enon it presents. Consider the case of bonnets. During the same season all persons belonging, or aspiring to belong, to the same ' public,' if they wear bonnets at all, wear bonnets modelled on the same type. Why do they do this ? If we were asking a similar question, not about bonnets, but about steam- engines, the answer would be plain. People tend at the same date to use the same kind of engine for the same kind of purpose because it is the best avail- able. They change their practice when a better one is invented. But as so used the words ' better' and ' best ' have no application to modern dress. Neither efficiency nor economy, it will at once be admitted, supply the grounds of choice or the motives for variation. If, again, we were asking the question about some great phase of art, we should probably be told that the general acceptance of it by a whole generation was due to some important combination of historic NATURALISM AND .-l^STHETIC 5 1 causes, acting alike on artist and on public. Such causes no doubt exist and have existed ; but the case of fashion proves that uniformity is not produced by them alone, since it will hardly be pretended that there is any widely diffused cause in the social environment, except the coercive operation of fash- ion itself, which should make the bonnets which were thought becoming in 1881 unbecoming in the year 1892. • Again, we might be told that art contains essen- tial principles of self-development, which require one productive phase to succeed another by a kind of inner necessity, and determine not merely that there shall be variation, but what that variation shall be. This also may be, and is, in a certain sense, true. But it can hardly be supposed that we can explain the fashions which prevail in any year by assuming, not merely that the fashions of the previous years were foredoomed to change, but also that, in the na- ture of the case, only one change was possible, that, namely, which actually took place. Such a doctrine would be equivalent to saying that if all the bonnet- wearers were for a space deprived of any knowledge of each other's proceedings (all other things remain- ing the same), they would, on the resumption of their ordinary intercourse, find that they had all inclined towards much the same modification of the type of bonnet prevalent before their separation — a con- clusion which seems to mc, I confess, to be some- what improbable. 52 NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC It may perhaps be hazarded, as a further expla- nation, that this uniformity of practice is indeed a fact, and is really produced by a complex group of causes which we denominate ' fashion,' but that it is a uniformity of practice alone, not of taste or feeling, and has no real relation to any aesthetic problem whatever. This is a question the answer to which can be supplied, I apprehend, by observation alone ; and the answer which observation enables us to give seems to me quite unambiguous. If, as is possi- ble, my readers have but small experience in such matters themselves, let them examine the experi- ences of their acquaintance. They will find, if I mistake not, that by whatever means conformity to a particular pattern may have been brought about, those who conform are not, as a rule, conscious of coercion by an external and arbitrary authority. They do not act under penalty ; they yield no un- willing obedience. On the contrary, their admira- tion for a ' well-dressed person,' qiid well-dressed, is at least as genuine an aesthetic approval as any they are in the habit of expressing for other forms of beauty ; just as their objection to an outworn fash- ion is based on a perfectly genuine sesthetic dislike. They are repelled by the unaccustomed sight, as a reader of discrimination is repelled by turgidity or false pathos. It appears to them ugly, even gro- tesque, and they turn from it Avith an aversion as disinterested, as unperturbed by personal or ' so- ciet}^ ' considerations, as if they were critics contem- NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC 53 plating the production of some pretender in the reirion of Great Art. In truth this tendency in matters assthetic is only a particular case of a general tendency to agreement which plays an even more important part in other departments of human activity. Its operation, beneh- cent doubtless on the whole, may be traced through all social and political life. We owe to it in part that deep-lying likeness in tastes, in opinions, and in habits, without which cohesion among the individ- ual units of a community would be impossible, and which constitutes the unmoved platform on which we tight out our political battles. It is no contemp- tible factor among the forces by which nations are created and religions disseminated and maintained. It is the very breath of life to sects and coteries. Sometimes, no doubt, its results are ludicrous. Sometimes they are unfortunate. Sometimes merely insignificant. Under which of these heads we should class our ever-changing uniformity in dress I will not take upon me to determine. It is sufficient for my present purpose to point out that the aesthetic likings which fashion originates, however trivial, are perfectly genuine ; and that to an origin similar in kind, however different in dignity and permanence, should be traced much of the characteristic quality which gives its special ilavour to the higher artistic sentiments of each successive generation. 54 NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC IV It is, of course, true that this ' tendency to agree- ment,' ^ this principle of drill, cannot itself determine the objects in respect of which the agreement is to take place. It can do much to make every member of a particular ' public ' like the same bonnet, or the same epic, at the same time ; but it cannot deter- mine what that bonnet or that epic is to be. A fashion, as the phrase goes, has to be ' set,' and the persons who set it manifestly do not follow it. What, then, do they follow ? We note the influences that move the flock. What moves the bell-wether? Here again much might conveniently be learnt from an examination of fashion and its changes, for these provide us with a field of research where we are disturbed by no preconceived theories or incon- venient admirations, and where we may dissect our subject with the cold impartiality which befits scientific investigation. The reader, however, may think that enough has been done already by this method ; and I shall accordingly pursue a more general treatment of the subject, premising that in the brief observations which follow no complete ' Of course the ' tendency to agreement ' is not presented to the reader as a simple, undecomposable social force. It is, doubtless, highly complex, one of its most important elements being, I sup- pose, the instinct of uncritical imitation, which is the very basis of all effective education. The line of thought hinted at in this paragraph is pursued much further in the Third Part of this Essay. NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC 55 analysis of the complexity of concrete Nature is attempted, or is, indeed, necessary for my purpose. It will be convenient, in the first place, to dis- tinguish between the mode in which the public who enjoy, and the artists who produce, respectively promote aesthetic change. That the public are often weary and expectant — weary of what is provided for them, and expectant of some good thing to come — will hardly be denied. Yet I do not think they can be usually credited with the conscious demand for a fresh artistic development. For though they often want some new thing, they do not often want a neiv kind of thing; and accordingly it commonly, though not invariably, happens that, when the new thing appears, it is welcomed at first by the few, and only gradually — by the force of fashion and otherwise — conquers the genuine admiration of the many. The artist, on the other hand, is moved in no small measure by a desire that his work should be his own, no pale reflection of another's methods, but an expression of himself in his own language. He will vary for the better if he can, yet, rather than be conscious of repetition, he will vary for the worse ; for vary he must, either in substance or in form, unless he is to be in his own eyes, not a creator, but an imitator; not an artist, but a copyist.^ It will be observed that I am not obliged to ' No doubt it is an echo of this feelincf that makes purchasers invariably prefer a bad orig^inal to the best copy of the best ori.tjinal — a preference which in argument it would be exceedingly difificult to justify. 56 NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC draw the dividing-line between originality and pla- giarism ; to distinguish between the man who is one of a school, and the man who has done no more than merely catch the trick of a master. It is enough that the artist himself draws the distinction, and will never consciously allow himself to sink from the first category into the second. We have here, then, a general cause of change, but not a cause of change in any particular direction, or of any particular amount. These I believe to be determined in part by the relation between the artists and the public for whom they produce, and in part by the condition of the art itself at the time the change occurs. As regards the first, it is commonly said that the artist is the creation of his age, and the discovery of this fact is sometimes thought to be a momentous contribution made by science to the theory of aesthetic evolution. The statement, how- ever, is unfortunately worded. The action of the age is, no doubt, important, but it would be more accurate, I imagine, to describe it as destructive than as creative ; it does not so much produce as select. It is true, of course, that the influence of ' the environment ' in moulding, developing, and stimulating genius within the limits of its original capacity is very great, and may seem, especially in the humbler walks of artistic production, to be all- powerful. But innate and original genius is not the creation of any age. It is a biological accident, the incalculable product of two sets of ancestral ten- NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC 57 dencies ; and what the age does to these biological accidents is not to create them, but to choose from them, to encourage those which are in harmony with its spirit, to crush out and to sterilise the rest. Its action is analogous to that which a plot of ground exercises on the seeds which fall upon it. Some thrive, some languish, some die; and the resulting vegetation is sharply characterised, not because few kinds of seed have there sown themselves, but because few kinds have been allowed to grow up. Without pushing the parallel too far, it may yet serve to illustrate the truth that, as a stained win- dow derives its character and significance from the absorption of a large portion of the rays which endeavour to pass through it, so an age is what it is, not only by reason of what it fosters, but as much, perhaps, by reason of what it destroys. We may con- ceive, then, that from the total but wholly unknown number of men of productive capacity born in any generation, those whose gifts are in harmony with the tastes of their contemporaries will produce their best; those whose gifts are wholly out of harmony will be extinguished, or, which is very nearly the same thing, will produce only for the benefit of the critics in succeeding generations ; while those who occupy an intermediate position will, indeed, produce, but their powers will, consciously or unconsciously, be warped and thwarted, and their creations fall short of what, under happier circumstances, they might have been able to achieve. 58 NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC Here, then, we have a tendency to change aris- ing out of the artist's insistence on originality, and a limitation on change imposed by the character of the age in which he lives. The kind of change will be largely determined by the condition of the art which he is practising. If it be in an early phase, full as yet of undeveloped possibili- ties, then in all probability he will content him- self with improving on his predecessors, without widely deviating from the lines they have laid down. For this is the direction of least resistance : here is no public taste to be formed, here are no great experiments to be tried, here the pioneer's rough work of discovery has already been accom- plished. But if this particular fashion of art has culminated, and be in its decline ; if, that is to say, the artist feels more and more difficulty in express- ing himself through it, without saying worse what his predecessors have said already, then one of three things happens — either originality is perforce sought for in exaggeration ; or a new style is invented ; or artistic creation is abandoned and the field is given up to mere copyists. Which of these events shall happen depends, no doubt, partl}^ on the accident of genius, but it depends, I think, still more on the prevailing taste. If, as has frequently happened, that taste be dominated by the memory of past ideals ; if the little public whom the big public follow are content with nothing that does not conform to certain ancient models, a period of NATURALISM AND -ESTHETIC 59 artistic sterility is inevitable. But if circumstances be more propitious, then art continues to move ; the direction and character of its movement being due partly to the special turn of genius possessed by the artist who succeeds in producing a public taste in harmony with his powers, and partly to the reaction of the taste thus created, or in process of creation, upon the general artistic talent of the community. Even, however, in those periods when the movement of art is most striking, it is dangerous to assume that movement implies progress, if by progress be meant increase in the poiuer to excite cssthetic emotion. It would be rash to assume this even as regards Music, where the movement has been more remarkable, more continuous, and more apparently progressive over a long period of time than in any other art whatever. In music, the artist's desire for originality of expression has been aided generation after generation by the discovery of new methods, new forms, new instruments. From the bare simplicity of the ecclesiastical chant or the village dance to the ordered complexity of the modern score, the art has passed through successive stages of development, in each of which genius has dis- covered devices of harmony, devices of instrumenta- tion, and devices of rhythm which would have been musical paradoxes to preceding generations, and became musical commonplaces to the generations that followed after. Yet, what has been the net 6o NATURALISM AND yESTHETlC gain ? Read through the long catena of critical judgments, from Wagner back (if you please) to Plato, which ever}' age has passed on its own per- formances, and you will find that to each of them its music has been as adequate as ours is to us. It moved them not less deeply, nor did it move them differently ; and compositions which for us have lost their magic, and which we regard as at best but agreeable curiosities, contained for them the secret of all the unpictured beauties which music shows to her worshippers. Surely there is here a great paradox. The history of Literature and Art is tolerably well known to us for many hundreds of years. During that period Poetry and Sculpture and Painting have been subject to the usual mutations of fashion ; there have been seasons of sterility and seasons of plenty ; schools have arisen and decayed ; new nations and languages have been pressed into the service of Art; old nations have fallen out of line. But it is not commonly supposed that at the end of it all Vv^e are much better off than the Greeks of the age of Pericles in respect of the technical dexterity of the artist, or of the resources which he has at his com- mand. During the same period, and measured by the same external standard, the development of Music has been so great that it is not, I think, easy to exag- gerate it. Yet, through all this vast revolution, the position and importance of the art as compared with other arts seems, so far as I can discover, to have NATURALISM AND /ESTHETIC 6 1 suffered no sensible change. It was as great four hundred years before Christ as it is at the present moment. It was as great in the sixteenth, seven- teenth, and eighteenth centuries as it is in the nine- teenth. How, then, can we resist the conclusion that this amazing musical development, produced by the expenditure of so much genius, has added little to the felicity of mankind ; unless, indeed, it so happens that in his particular art a steady level of aesthetic sensation can only be maintained by increasinof doses of cESthetic stimulant. These somewhat desultory observations do not, it must be acknowledged, carry us very far towards that of which we are in search, namely, a theory of aesthetics in harmony with naturalism. Yet, on recapitulation, negative conclusions of some impor- tance will, I think, be seen to follow from them. It is clear, for instance, that those who, like Goethe, long to dwell among * permanent relations,' wherever else they may find them, will at least not find them in or behind the feeling of beauty. Such permanent relations do, indeed, exist, binding in their unchang- ing framework the various forms of energy and matter which make up the physical universe; but it is not the perception oi these which, either in Nature or in art, stirs within us aesthetic emotion — else sIkhiUI \vc find our surest guides to beauty in 62 NATURALISM AND .ESTHETIC an astronomical chart or table of chemical equiva- lents, and nothing would seem to us of less aes- thetic significance than a symphony or a love-song. That which is beautiful is not the object as we know it to be — the vibrating molecule and the un- dulating ether — but the object as we know it not to be — glorious with qualities of colour or of sound. Nor can its beauty be supposed to last any longer than the transient reaction between it and our spe- cial senses, which are assuredly not permanent or important elements in the constitution of the world in which we live. But even within these narrow limits — narrow, I mean, compared with the wide sweep of our scientific vision — there seemed to be no ground for supposing that there is in Nature any standard of beauty to which all human tastes tend to conform, any beauti- ful objects which all normally constituted individuals are moved to admire, any aesthetic judgments which can claim to be universal. The divergence between different tastes is, indeed, not only notorious, but is what we should have expected. As our aesthetic feelings are not due to natural selection, natural se- lection will have no tendency to keep them uni- form and stable. In this respect they differ, as I have said, from ethical sentiments and beliefs. De- viations from sound morality are injurious either to the individual or to the community — those who indulge in them are at a disadvantage in the struggle for existence ; hence, on the naturalistic hypothesis. NATURALISM AND .^iSTHETIC 63 the approximation to identity in the accepted codes of different nations. But there is, fortunately, no natural punishment annexed to bad taste ; and ac- cordingly the variation between tastes has passed into a proverb. Even in those cases where some slender thread of similarity seemed to bind together the tastes of different times or different persons, further con- sideration showed that this was largely due to causes which can by no possibility be connected with any supposed permanent element in beauty. The agreement, for example, between critics, in so far as it exists, is to no small extent an agreement in statement and in analysis, rather than an agree- ment in feeling ; they have the same opinion as to the cooking of the dinner, but they by no means all eat it with the same relish. In few cases, indeed, do their estimates of excellence correspond with the living facts of ccsthetic emotion as shown either in themselves or in anybody else. Their whole pro- cedure, necessary though it may be for the compara- tive estimate of the worth of individual artists, unduly conceals the vast and arbitrary^ changes by which the taste of one generation is divided from that of another. And when we turn from critical tradi- tion to the aesthetic likes and dislikes of men and women ; when we leave the admirations which are professed for the emotions which are felt, we find ' 'Arbitrary,' i.e. not due to any causes which point to the ex- istence of objective beauty. 64 NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC in vast multitudes of cases that these are not con- nected with the object which happens to excite them by any permanent aesthetic bond at all. Their true determining cause is to be sought in fashion, in that * tendency to agreement ' which plays so large, and on the whole so useful, a part in social economy. Nor, in considering the causes which produce the rise and fall of schools, and all the smaller muta- tions in the character of aesthetic production, did we perceive more room for the belief that there is somewhere to be found a permanent element in the beautiful. There is no evidence that these changes constitute stages in any process of gradual approxi- mation to an unchanging standard ; they are not born of any strivings after some ideal archetype ; they do not, like the movements of science, bring us ever nearer to central and immutable truth. On the contrary, though schools are born, mature, and perish, though ancient forms decay, and new ones are continually devised, this restless movement is, so far as science can pronounce, without meaning or purpose, the casual product of the quest after novelty, determined in its course by incalculable forces, by accidents of genius, by accidents of public humour, involving change but not progress, and predestined, perhaps, to end universally, as at many times and in many places it has ended already, in a mood of barren acquiescence in the repetition of ancient models, the very Nirvana of artistic imagi- nation, without desire and without pain. NATURALISM AND ^ESTHETIC 65 And yet the persistent and almost pathetic endeavours of aesthetic theory to show that the beautiful is a necessary and unchanging element in the general scheme of things, if they prove nothing else, may at least convince us that mankind will not easily reconcile themselves to the view which the naturalistic theory of the world would seemingly compel them to accept. We need feel no difficult}-, perhaps, in admitting the full consequences of that theory at the lower end of the sesthetic scale, in the region, for instance, of bonnets and wall-papers. We may tolerate it even when it deals with impor- tant-elements in the highest art, such as the sense of technical excellence, or S3'mpathy with the crafts- man's skill. But when we look back on those too rare moments when feelings stirred in us by some beautiful object not only seem wholly to absorb us, but to raise us to the vision of things far above the ken of bodily sense or discursive reason, we cannot acquiesce in any attempt at explanation which con- fines itself to the bare enumeration of psychological and physiological causes and effects. We cannot willingly assent to a theory which makes a good composer only differ from a good cook in that he deals in more complicated relations, moves in a wider circle of associations, and arouses our feel- ings through a different sense. However little, theref(jrc, we may be prepared to accept any par- ticular scheme of metaphysical aesthetics — and most of these appear to me to be very absurd — we must 5 66 NATURALISM AND ESTHETIC believe that somewhere and for some Being there shines an unchanging splendour of beauty, of which in Nature and in Art we see, each of us from our own standpoint, only passing gleams and stray reflec- tions, whose different aspects we cannot now co- ordinate, whose import we cannot fully comprehend, but which at least is something other than the chance play of subjective sensibility or the far-off echo of ancestral lusts. No such mystical creed can, how- ever, be squeezed out of observation and experi- ment ; Science cannot give it us ; nor can it be forced into any sort of consistency with the Nat- uralistic Theory of the Universe. CHAPTER III NATURALISM AND REASON Among those who accept without substantial modi- fication the naturalistic theory of the universe are some who find a compensation for the general non- rationality of Nature in the fact that, after all, rea- son, human reason, is Nature's final product. If the world is not made by Reason, Reason is at all events made by the world ; and the unthinking in- teraction of causes and effects has at least resulted in a consciousness wherein that interaction may be reflected and understood. This is not Teleology. Indeed it is a doctrine which leaves no room for any belief in design. But in the minds of some who have but imperfectly grasped their own doctrines, it appears capable of partially meeting the senti- mental needs to which teleology gives a fuller satis- faction, inasmuch as reason thus finds an assured place in the scheme of things, and is enabled, after the fashion of the Chinese, in some sort to ennoble its ignoble progenitors. This theory of the non-rational origin of reason, whicli is a necessary coi'ollary of the naf iii-alistic 68 NATURALISM AND REASON scheme, has philosophical consequences of great in- terest, to some of which I have alkided elsewhere,^ and which must occupy our attention in a later chapter of these Notes. In the meanwhile, there are other aspects of the subject which deserve a moment's consideration. From the point of view of organic evolution there is no distinction, I imagine, to be drawn be- tween the development of reason and that of any other faculty, physiological or psychical, by which the interests of the individual or the race are pro- moted. From the humblest form of nervous irri- tability at one end of the scale, to the reasoning capacity of the most advanced races at the other, everything, without exception — sensation, instinct, desire, volition — has been produced, directly or in- directly, by natural causes acting for the most part on strictly utilitarian principles. Convenience, not knowledge, therefore, has been the main end to which this process has tended. ' It was not for pur- poses of research that our senses were evolved,' nor was it in order to penetrate the secrets of the uni- verse that we are endowed with reason. Under these circumstances it is not surprising that the faculties thus laboriously created are but imperfectly fitted to satisfy that speculative curios- ity which is one of the most curious bj^-products of the evolutionary process. The inadequacy of our intellect, indeed, to resolve the questions which it ' Philosophic Doubt, Pt. iii., ch. xiii. NATURALISM AND REASON 69 is capable of asking is acknowledged (at least in words) both by students of science and by students of theology. But they do not seem so much im- pressed with the inadequacy of our senses. Yet, if the current doctrine of evolution be true, we have no choice but to admit that with the great mass of natural fact we are probably brought into no sensi- ble relation at all. I am not referring here merely to the limitations imposed upon such senses as we possess, but to the total absence of an indefinite number of senses which conceivably we might pos- sess, but do not. There are sounds which the ear cannot hear, there are sights which the eye cannot see. But besides all these there must be countless aspects of external Nature of which we have no knowledge; of which, owing to the absence of ap- propriate organs, we can form no conception ; which imagination cannot picture nor language express. Had Voltaire been acquainted with the theory of evolution, he would not have put forward his Mi- cromegas so much as an illustration of a paradox which cannot be disproved, as of a truth which can- not be doubted. For to suppose that a course of development carried out, not with the object of ex- tending knowledge or satisfying curiosity, but solely with that of promoting lite, on an area so insig- nificant as the surface of the earth, between limits of temperature and pressure so narrow, and under general conditions so exceptional, should have end- ed in supplying us with senses even approximately 70 NATURALISM AND REASON adequate to the apprehension of Nature in all her complexities, is to believe in a coincidence more as- tounding than the most audacious novelist has ever employed to cut the knot of some entangled tale. For it must be recollected that the same natural forces which tend to the evolution of organs which are useful tend also to the suppression of organs that are useless. Not only does Nature take no interest in our general education, not only is she quite indifferent to the growth of enlightenment, un- less the enlightenment improve our chances in the struggle for existence, but she positively objects to the very existence of faculties by which these ends might, perhaps, be attained. She regards them as mere hindrances in the only race which she desires to see run ; and not content with refusing directly to create any faculty except for a practical pur- pose, she immediately proceeds to destroy faculties already created when their practical purpose has ceased ; for thus does the eye of the cave-born fish degenerate and the instinct of the domesticated animal decay. Those, then, who are inclined to the opinion that between our organism and its environ- ments there is a correspondence which, from the point of view of general knowledge, is even approx- imately adequate, must hold, in \\\q first place, that samples or suggestions of every sort of natural man- ifestation are to be found in our narrow and limited world ; in the second place, that these samples are of a character which would permit of nervous tissue NATURALISM AND REASON /I being so modified by selection as to respond specifi- cally to their action ; in the third place, that such specific modifications were not only possible, but would have proved useful at the period of evolution during which our senses in their present shape were developed ; and in \\\q fourth place, that these modi- fications would have proved useful enough to make it worth while to use up, for the purpose of produc- ing them, material which might have been, and has been, otherwise employed. All these propositions seem to me improbable, the first two of them incredible.^ It is impossible, ' It may perhaps be said that it is not necessary that we should be specifically affected by each particular kind of energy in order either to discover its existence or to investigate its character. It is enough that among its effects should be some which are cognisable by our actual senses, that it should modify in some way the world we know, that it should intervene perceptibly in that part of the general system to which our organism happens to be immediately connected. This is no doubt true, and our knowledge of electricity and magnetism (among other things) is there to prove it. But let it be noted how slender and how accidental was the clue which led us to the first beginnings, from which all our knowledge of these great phenomena is derived. Directly they can hardly be said to be in relation with our organs of perception at all (notwithstanding the fact that light is now regarded as an electro-magnetic phenomenon) and their indirect relation with them is so slight that probably no amount of mere obser- vation could, in the absence of experiment, have given us a notion of their magnitude or importance. They were not sought for to fill a gap whose existence had been demonstrated by calculation. Their discovery was no inevitable step in the onward march of scientific knowledge. They were stumbled upon by accident ; and few would be bold enough to assert that if, for example, the human race had not happened to possess iron, magnetism would ever have presented itself as a subject requiring investigation at all. 72 NATURALISM AND REASON therefore, to resist the conviction that there must be an indefinite number of aspects of Nature respecting which science never can give us any information, even in our dreams. We must conceive ourselves as feeling our way about this dim corner of the il- limitable world, like children in a darkened room, encompassed by we know not what ; a little better endowed with the machinery of sensation than the protozoon, yet poorly provided indeed as compared with a being, if such a one could be conceived, whose senses were adequate to the infinite variety of material Nature. It is true, no doubt, that we are possessed of reason, and that protozoa are not. But even reason, on the naturalistic theory, occupies no elevated or permanent position in the hierarchy of phenomena. It is not the final result oi a great process, the roof and crown of things. On the con- trary, it is, as I have said, no more than one of many experiments for increasing our chance of survival, and, among these, by no means the most important or the most enduring. II People sometimes talk, indeed, as if it was the difficult and complex work connected with the main- tenance of life that was performed by intellect. But there can be no greater delusion. The management of the humblest organ would be infinitely beyond our mental capacity, were it possible for us to be NATURALISM AND REASON 73 entrusted with it ; and as a matter of fact, it is only in the simplest jobs that discursive reason is per- mitted to have a hand at all ; our tendency to take a different view being merely the self-importance of a child who, because it is allowed to stamp the let- ters, imagines that it conducts the correspondence. The best way of looking at mind on the naturalistic hypothesis is, perhaps, to regard it as an instrument for securing a flexibility of adaptation which instinct alone is not able to attain. Instinct is incompa- rably the better machine in every respect save one. It works more smoothly, with less friction, with far greater precision and accuracy. But it is not adapt- able. Many generations and much slaughter are re- quired to breed it into a race. Once acquired, it can be modified or expelled only by the same harsh and tedious methods. Mind, on the other hand, from the point of view of organic evolution, may be con- sidered as an inherited faculty for self-adjustment; and though, as I have already had occasion to note, the limits within which such adjustment is permit- ted are exceedingly narrow, within those limits it is doubtless exceedingly valuable. But even here one of the principal functions of mind is to create habits by which, when they are fully formed, it is itself supplanted. If the conscious adaptation of means to ends was always necessary in order to perform even those few functions for the first performance of which conscious adaptation was originally required, life would be frittered away in 74 NATURALISM AND REASON doing badly, but with deliberation, some small frac- tion of that which we now do well without any deliberation at all. The formation of habits is, there- fore, as has often been pointed out, a necessary pre- liminary to the ' higher ' uses of mind ; for it, and it alone, sets attention and intelligence free to do work from which they would otherwise be debarred by their absorption in the petty needs of daily exist- ence. But while it is thus plain that the formation of habits is an essential pre-requisitc of mental develop- ment, it would also seem that it constitutes the first step in a process which, if thoroughly success- ful, would end in the destruction, if not of conscious- ness itself, at least of the higher manifestation of consciousness, such as will, attention, and discur- sive reason.^ All these, as we may suppose, will be gradually superseded in an increasing number of departments of human activity by the growth of in- stincts or inherited habits, by which even such adjust- ments between the organism and its surroundings as now seem most dependent on self-conscious mind may be successfully effected. These are prophecies, however, which concern themselves with a very remote future, and for my part I do not ask the reader to regard their fulfil- ment as an inexorable necessity. It is enough if ' Empirical psychologists are not agreed as to whether the ap- parent unconsciousness which accompanies completed habits is real or not. It is unnecessary for the purpose of my argument that this point should be determined. NATURALISM AND REASON 75 they mark with sufficient emphasis the place which Mind, in its higher manifestations, occupies in the scheme of things, as this is presented to us by the naturalistic hypothesis. Mr. Spencer, who pierces the future with a surer gaze than I can make the least pretence to, looks confidently forw^ard to a time when the relation of man to his surroundings will be so happily contrived that the reign of absolute right- eousness will prevail ; conscience, grown unneces- sary, will be dispensed with ; the path of least resistance will be the path of virtue ; and not the ' broad,' but the ' narrow way,' will ' lead to destruc- tion.' These excellent consequences seem to me to flow very smoothly and satisfactorily from his particular doctrine of evolution, combined with his particular doctrine of morals. But I confess that my own personal gratification at the prospect is some- what dimmed by the reflection that the same kind of causes which make conscience superfluous will relieve us from the necessity of intellectual effort, and that by the time we are all perfectly good we shall also be all perfectly idiotic. I know not how it may strike the reader ; but I at least am left sensibly poorer b}' this deposition of Reason from its ancient position as the Ground of all existence, to that of an expedient among other expedients for the maintenance of organic life ; an ex- pedient, moreover, which is temporary in its charac- ter and insignificant in its effects. An irrational Universe which accidentally turns out a few reason- ^6 NATURALISM AND REASON ing animals at one corner of it, as a rich man may experiment at one end of his park with some curious * sport ' accidentally produced among his flocks and herds, is a Universe which we might well despise if we did not ourselves share its degradation. But must we not inevitably share it? Pascal somewhere observes that Man, however feeble, is yet in his very feebleness superior to the blind forces of Nature ; for he knows himself, and they do not. I confess that on the naturalistic hypothesis I see no such superi- ority. If, indeed, there were a Rational Author of Nature, and if in any degree, even the most insig- nificant, we shared His attributes, we might well conceive ourselves as of finer essence and more in- trinsic worth than the material world which we in- habit, immeasurable though it may be. But if we be the creation of that world ; if it made us what we are, and will again unmake us ; how then ? The sense of humour, not the least precious among the gifts with which the clash of atoms has endowed us, should surely prevent us assuming any airs of superiority over other and more powerful members of the same family of ' phenomena,' more permanent and more powerful than ourselves. CHAPTER IV SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I I HAVE now completed my survey of certain opin- ions which naturalism seems to require us to hold respecting- important matters connected with Right- eousness, Beauty, and Reason, The survey has necessarily been concise ; but, concise though it has been, it has, perhaps, sufficiently indicated the inner antagonism which exists between the Naturalistic system and the feelings which the best among man- kind, including many who may be counted as adhe- rents of that system, have hitherto considered as the most valuable possessions of our race. If natural- ism be true, or, rather, if it be the whole truth, then is morality but a bare catalogue of utilitarian pre- cepts; beauty but the chance occasion of a passing pleasure ; reason but the dim passage from one set of unthinking habits to another. All that gives dig- nity to life, all that gives value to effort, shrinks and fades under the pitiless glare of a creed like this ; and even curiosity, the hardiest among the nobler passions of the soul, must languish under the con- viction that neither for this generation nor for any that shall come after it, neither in this life nor in yS SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I another, will the tie be wholly loosened by which reason, not less than appetite, is held in hereditary bondage to the service of our material needs. I am anxious, however, not to overstate my case. It is of course possible, to take for a moment aesthet- ics as our text, that whatever be our views concern- ing- naturalism, we shall still like good poetry and good music, and that we shall not, perhaps, find if we sum up our pleasures at the year's end, that the total satisfaction derived from the contemplation of Art and Nature is very largely diminished by the fact that our philosophy allows us to draw no im- portant distinction between the beauties of a sauce and the beauties of a symphony. Both may con- tinue to afford the man with a good palate and a good ear a considerable amount of satisfaction ; and if all we desire is to find in literature and in art something that will help us either 'to enjoy life or to endure it,' I do not contend that, by any theory of the beautiful, of this we shall wholly be deprived. Nevertheless there is, even so, a loss not lightly to be underrated, a loss that falls alike on him that produces and on him that enjoys. Poets and artists have been wont to consider themselves, and to be considered by others, as prophets and seers, the re- vealers under sensuous forms of hidden mysteries, the symbolic preachers of eternal truths. All this is, of course, on the naturalistic theory, very absurd. They minister, no doubt, with success to some phase, usually a very transitory phase, of public taste ; but SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OP^ PART I 79 they have no mysteries to reveal, and what they tell us, though it may be very agreeable, is seldom true, and never important. This is a conclusion which, howsoever it ma}- accord with sound philosophy, is not likely to prove ver}- stimulating to the artist, nor does it react with less unfortunate effect upon those to whom the artist appeals. Even if their feeling of delight in the beautiful is not marred for them in immediate experience, it must suffer in memory and reflection. For such a feeling carries with it, at its best, an inevitable reference, not less inevitable be- cause it is obscure, to a Reality which is eternal and unchanging ; and we cannot accept without suffer- ing the conviction that in making such a reference we were merely the dupes of our emotions, the vic- tims of a temporary hallucination induced, as it were, by some spiritual drug. But if on the naturalistic hypothesis the senti- ments associated with beauty seem like a poor jest played on us by Nature for no apparent purpose, those that gather round morality are, so to speak, a deliberate fraud perpetrated for a well-defined end. The consciousness of freedom, the sense of respon- sibility, the authority of conscience, the beauty of holiness, the admiration for self-devotion, the sym- pathy with suffering— these and all the train of be- liefs and feelings from which spring noble deeds and generous ambitions are seen to be mere devices for securing to societies, if not to individuals, some competitive advantage in the struggle for existence. 8o SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I They are not worse, but neither are they better than the thousand-and-one appetites and instincts, many of them, as I have said, cruel, and many of them disgusting, created by similar causes in order to carry out through all organic Nature the like un- profitable ends ; and if we think them better, as in our unreflecting moments we arc apt to do, this, on the Naturalistic hypothesis, is only because some delusion of the kind is necessary in order to induce us to perform actions which in themselves can con- tribute nothing to our personal gratification. The inner discord which finds expression in con- clusions like these largely arises, as the reader sees, from a want of balance or proportion between the range of our intellectual vision and the circum- stances of our actual existence. Our capacity for standing outside ourselves and taking stock of the position which we occupy in the universe of things has been enormously and, it would seem, unfort- unately, increased by recent scientific discovery. We have learned too much. We are educated above that position in life in which it has pleased Nature to place us. We can no longer accept it without criticism and without examination. We insist on interrogating that material system which, according to naturalism, is the true author of our being as to whence we come and whither we go, what are the causes which have made us what we are, and what are the purposes which our existence subserves. And it must be confessed that the answers given to SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I 8 1 this question by our oracle are extremely unsatis- factory. We have learned to measure space, and we perceive that our dwelling-place is but a mere point, wandering with its companions, apparently at random, through the wilderness of stars. We have learned to measure time, and we perceive that the life not merely of the individual or of the nation, but of the whole race, is brief, and apparently quite unimportant. We have learned to unravel causes, and we perceive that emotions and aspirations whose very being seems to hang on the existence of realities of which naturalism takes no account, are in their origin contemptible and in their sug- gestion mendacious. To me it appears certain that this clashing be- tween beliefs and feelings must ultimately prove fatal to one or the other. Make what allowance you please for the stupidity of mankind, take the fullest account of their really remarkable power of letting their speculative opinions follow one line of development and their practical ideals another, yet the time must come when reciprocal action will perforce bring opinions and ideals into some kind of agreement and congruity. If, then, naturalism is to hold the field, the feelings and opinions inconsist- ent with naturalism must be foredoomed to suffer change ; and how, when that change sliall come about, it can do otherwise than eat all nobility out of our conception of conduct and all worth out of our conception of life, I am wholly unable to understand. 82 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I I am aware that many persons are in the habit of subjecting these views to an experimental refuta- tion by pointing to a great many excellent people who hold, in more or less purity, the naturalistic creed, but who, nevertheless, offer prominent ex- amples of that habit of mind with which, as I have been endeavouring to show, the naturalistic creed is essentially inconsistent. Naturalism — so runs the argument — co-exists in the case of Messrs. A., B., C, &c., with the most admirable exhibition of un- selfish virtue. If this be so in the case of a hundred individuals, why not in the case of ten thousand? If in the case of ten thousand, why not in the case of humanity at large ? Now, to the facts on which this reasoning proceeds I raise no objection. I de- sire neither to ignore the existence nor to mini- mise the merits of these shining examples of virtue unsupported by religion. But though the facts be true, the reasoning based on them will not bear close examination. Biologists tell us of parasites which live, and can only live, within the bodies of animals more highly organised than they. For them their luckless host has to find food, to digest it, and to convert it into nourishment which they can consume without exertion and assimilate with- out difficulty. Their structure is of the simplest kind. Their host sees for them, so they need no eyes ; he hears for them, so they need no ears ; he works for them and contrives for them, so they need but feeble muscles and an undeveloped ner- SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I 83 voiis system. But are we to conclude from this that for the animal kingdom eyes and ears, powerful limbs and complex nerves, are superfluities? They are superfluities for the parasite only because they have first been necessities for the host, and when the host perishes the parasite, in their absence, is not unlikely to perish also. So it is with those persons who claim to show by their example that naturalism is practically consistent with the maintenance of ethical ideals with which naturalism has no natural affinity. Their spiritual life is parasitic : it is sheltered by convictions which belong, not to them, but to the society of which they form a part ; it is nourished by processes in which they take no share. And when those convictions decay, and those processes come to an end, the alien life which they have maintained can scarce be ex- pected to outlast them. I am not aware that anyone has as yet en- deavoured to construct the catechism of the future, purged of every element drawn from any other source than the naturalistic creed. It is greatly to be desired that this task should be undertaken in an impartial spirit; and as a small contribution to such an object, I offer the following pairs of contrasted propositions, the first members of each pair repre- senting current teaching, the second representing the teachin": which ouarht to be substituted for it if the naturalistic theory be accepted. A. The universe is the creation oi Reason, and 84 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I all things work together towards a reasonable end. B. So far as we are concerned, reason is to be found neither in the beginning of things nor in their end ; and though everything is predetermined, noth- ing- is fore-ordained. A. Creative reason is interfused with infinite love. B. As reason is absent, so also is love. The uni- versal flux is ordered by blind causation alone. A. There is a moral law, immutable, eternal ; in its governance all spirits find their true freedom and their most perfect realisation. Though it be adequate to infinite goodness and infinite intelligence, it may be understood, even by man, sufficiently for his guidance. B. Among the causes by which the course of organic and social development has been blindly determined are pains, pleasures, instincts, appetites, disgusts, religions, moralities, superstitions ; the senti- ment of what is noble and intrinsically worthy ; the sentiment of what is ignoble and intrinsically worth- less. From a purely scientific point of view these all stand on an equality ; all are action -producing causes developed, not to improve, but simply to perpetuate, the species. A. In the possession of reason and in the enjoy- ment of beauty, we in some remote way share the nature of that infinite Personality in Whom we live and move and have our being. SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I 85 B. Reason is but the psychological expression of certain physiological processes in the cerebral hemispheres ; it is no more than an expedient among many expedients by which the individual and the race are preserved ; just as Beauty is no more than the name for such varying and accidental attributes of the material or moral worlds as may happen for the moment to stir our aesthetic feelings. A. Every human soul is of infinite value, eternal, free ; no human being, therefore, is so placed as not to have within his reach, in himself and others, ob- jects adequate to infinite endeavour. B. The individual perishes ; the race itself does not endure. Few can flatter themselves that their conduct has any effect whatever upon its remoter destinies; and of those few, none can say with reasonable assurance that the effect which they are destined to produce is the one which they desire. Even if we were free, therefore, our ignorance would make us helpless ; and it may be almost a con- solation to reflect that our conduct was determined for us by the distribution of unthinking forces in pre-solar asons, and that if we are impotent to fore- see its consequences, we were not less impotent to arrange its causes. The doctrines embodied in the second member of each of these alternatives may be true, or may at least represent the nearest approacii to truth ot which we are at present capable. Into this question I do not yet inquire. But if they are to constitute 86 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSION OF PART I the dogmatic scaffolding by which our educational system is to be supported ; if it is to be in harmony with principles like these that the child is to be taught at its mother's knee, and the young man is to build up the ideals of his life, then, unless I greatly mistake, it will be found that the inner discord which exists, and which must gradually declare itself, be- tween the emotions proper to naturalism and those which have actually grown up under the shadow of traditional convictions, will at no distant date most unpleasantly translate itself into practice. PART II SOME REASONS FOR BELIEF CHAPTER 1 THE nilLOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM So far we have been occupied in weighing certain indirect and collateral consequences which seem likely to flow from a particular theory of the world in which we live. The theory itself was taken for granted. No attempt was made to examine its foundations or to test their strength ; no compari- son between its different parts was instituted for the purpose of determining how far they really con- stituted a coherent and intelligible whole. We accepted it as we found it, turning with averted eyes even from the speculative problems which lay closest to the track of our immediate investigation. This course is not the most logical; and it might appear a more fitting procedure to reserve our con- sideration of the consequences of a system until some conclusion had been arrived at concerning its truth. Such, liowever, is not the ordinary habit of mankind in dealing with problems in which questions of abstract theory and daily practice are closely intertwined ; and even philosophers show a kindly reluctance too closely to examine the claims 90 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM of creeds whose consequences are in strict accord with contemporary sentiment. I have a better rea- son, however, to offer for the order here selected than can be derived from precedent or example, a reason based on the fact that, had I begun these Notes with the discussion on which 1 am about to embark, their whole character would probably have been misunderstood. They would have been re- garded as contributions to philosophical discussion of a kind which would only interest the specialist ; and the general reader, to whom I desire partic- ularly to appeal, would have abandoned their peru- sal in disgust. For I cannot deny, either that I am about to ask him to accompany me in a search after first principles ; or (which is, perhaps, worse) that the search is destined to be ineffectual. He will not only have to occupy himself with argu- ments of a remote and abstract kind, and for a moment to disturb the placid depths of ordinary thought with unaccustomed soundings, but the ar- guments will be to all appearance barren, and the soundings will not find bottom. The full justifi- cation for a procedure seemingly so futile can only be found in the chapters which follow, and in the general drift of the discussion taken as a whole ; but in the meanwhile the reader will be able to appre- ciate my immediate object if he will bear in mind the precise point at which we have arrived. Let him remember, then, that the result of the inquiry instituted into the practical tendencies of THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 91 the naturalistic theory is to show them to be well- nigh intolerable. The theory, no doubt, may for all that be true, since it must candidly be admitted that there is no naturalistic reason for anticipating any pre-established harmony between truth and ex- pediency in the higher regions of speculation. But at least we are called upon to make a very search- ing inquiry before we admit that it is true. We are not here concerned with any mere curiosity of dia- lectics, with the quest for a kind of knowledge which, however interesting to the few, yet bears no fruit for ordinary human use. On the contrary, the issues that have to be decided are practical, if any- thing is practical. They touch at every point the most permanent interests of man, individual and social ; and any procedure is preferable to a com- placent acquiescence in the loss of all the fairest provinces in our spiritual inheritance. This is a fact which has long been perceived by the defenders of all the creeds, philosophical or theological, with which the pretensions of natural- ism are in conflict. You will not open a modern work of apologetics, for instance, without finding in it some endeavour to show that the naturalistic theory is insufficient, and that it requires to be sup- plemented by precisely the very system in whose interests that particular work was written. This, no doubt, is as it should be; and on this plan a great deal of valuable criticism and interesting specula- tion has been produced. It is not, however, exactly 92 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM the plan which can be here pursued, partly because these Notes contain, not a system of theology, but only an introduction to theology ; and partly be- cause I have always found it easier to satisfy my- self of the insufficiency of naturalism than of the absolute sufficiency of any of the schemes by which it has been sought to modify or to complete it. In this chapter, however, I shall follow an easier line of march, the naiure of which the reader will readily understand if he considers the two elements composing the naturalistic creed : the one positive, consisting, broadly speaking, of the teaching con- tained in the general body of the natural sciences ; the other negative, expressed in the doctrine that beyond these limits, wherever they may happen to lie, nothing is, and nothing can be, known. Now, the usual practice with those who dissent from this general view is, as I have said, to choose the sec- ond, or negative, half of it for attack. They tell us, for example, that the knowledge of phenomena given by science carries with it by necessary impli- cation the knowledge of that which is above phe- nomena; or, again, that the moral nature of man points to the reality of ends and principles which cannot be exhausted by any investigation into a merely natural world of causally related objects. Without the least underrating such lines of investi- gation, I purpose here to consider, not the negative, but the positive half of the naturalistic system. I shall leave for the moment unchallenged the state- THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 93 ment that beyond the natural sciences knowledge is impossible ; but I shall venture, instead, to ask a few questions as to the character of the knowledge which is thought to be obtained within those limits. I shall not endeavour to prove that a scheme of merely positive beliefs, admirable, no doubt, as far as it goes, is yet intellectually insufificient unless it be supplemented by a metaphysical or theological appendix. But I shall examine the foundations of the scheme itself; and though such criticisms on it as I shall be able to offer can never be a substitute for the real work of philosophic construction, they would seem to be its fitting preliminary, and one which the succeeding chapters may show to be not without a profit of its own. One great metaphysician has described the sys- tem of another as ' shot out of a pistol,' meaning thereby that it was presented for acceptance with- out introductory proof. The criticism is true not only of the particular theory of the Absolute about which it was first used, but about every system, or almost every system, of belief which has ever passed current among mankind. Some subtle analogy with accepted doctrines, some general harmony with ex- isting sentiments and modes of thought, has not un- commonly been deemed sufficient to justify the most audacious conjectures ; and the history of specula- tion is littered with theories whose authors seem never to have suffered under an}- overmastering need to prove the opinions which they advanced. No 94 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM such overmastering need has, at least, been felt in the case of 'positive knowledge,' and the very cir- cumstance that, alike in its methods and in its results, all men are practically agreed to accept it without demur, has blinded them to the fact that it, too, has been ' shot out of a pistol,' and that, like some more questionable beliefs, it is still waiting for a rational justification. For our too easy acquiescence in this state of things I do not think science is itself to blame. It is no part of its duty to deal with first principles. Its business is to provide us with a theory of Nature ; and it should not be required, in addition, to pro- vide us with a theory of itself. This is a task which properly devolves upon the masters of speculation ; though it is one which, for various reasons, they have not as yet satisfactorily accomplished. I doubt, in- deed, whether any metaphysical philosopher before Kant can be said to have made contributions to this subject which at the present day need be taken into serious account ; and, as I shall endeavour to indicate in the next chapter, Kant's doctrines, even as modi- fied by his successors, do not, so it seems to me, pro- vide a sound basis for an ' epistemology of Nature.' But if in this connection we owe little to the metaphysical philosophers, we owe still less to those in whom we had a better right to trust, namely, the empirical ones. If the former have to some extent neglected the theory of science for theories of the Absolute, the latter have always shown an inclination THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 95 to sacrifice the theory of knowledge itself to theories as to the genesis or growth of knowledge. They have contented themselves with investisfatinir the primitive elements from which have been developed in the race and in the individual the completed consciousness of ourselves and of the world in which we live. They have, therefore, dealt with the origins of what we believe rather than with its justification. They have substituted psychology for philosophy ; they have presented us, in short, with studies in a particular branch or department of science, rather than with an examination into the grounds of science in general. And when perforce they are brought face to face with some of the problems connected with the philosophy of science which most loudly clamour for solution, there is something half-pathetic and half-humorous in their methods of cutting a knot which they are quite unable to untie. Can anything, for example, be more naive than the undisturbed serenity with which Locke, towards the end of his great work, assures his readers that he ' suspects that natural philosophy is not capable of being made a science'; or, as I should prefer to state it, that nat- ural science is not capable ol being made a philoso- phy ? Or can anything be more characteristic than the moral which he draws from this rather surprising admission, name!}, Ihat as we are so little fitted to frame theories about lliis present world, we had bet- ter devote our energies to preparing for the next ? This remarkable display (^f i)hilosophic resignation 96 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM in the father of modern empiricism has been imi- tated, with differences, by a long line of distin- guished successors. Hume, for example, though naturally enough he declined to draw Locke's edify- ing conclusion, did more than anyone else to estab- lish Locke's despairing premise ; and his inferences from it are at least equally singular. Having re- duced our belief in the fundamental principles of sci- entific interpretation to expectations born of habit ; having reduced the world which is to be interpreted to an unrelated series of impressions and ideas ; hav- ing by this double process made experience impossi- ble and turned science into foolishness, he quietly informs us, as the issue of the whole matter, that outside experience and science knowledge is impos- sible, and that all except ' mathematical demonstra- tion ' and 'experimental reasoning' on 'matters of fact ' is sophistr}' and illusion ! 1 think too well of Hume's speculative genius and too ill of his speculative sincerity to doubt that in making this statement he spoke, not as a philoso- pher, but as a man of the world, making formal obeisance to the powers that be. But what he said half ironically, his followers have said with an un- shaken seriousness. Nothing in the history of specu- lation is more astonishing, nothing — if I am to speak my whole mind — is more absurd than the way in which Hume's philosophic progeny — a most distin- guished race — have, in spite of all their differences, yet been able to agree, both that experience is essen- THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 97 tially as Hume described it, and that from such an experience can be rationally extracted anything even in the remotest degree resembling the existing sys- tem of the natural sciences. Like Locke, these p-en- tlemen, or some of them, have, indeed, been assailed by momentary misgivings. It seems occasionally to have occurred to them that if their theory of knowl- edge were adequate, ' experimental reasoning,' as Hume called it, was in a very parlous state ; and that, on the merits, nothing less deserved to be held with a positive conviction than what some of them are wont to describe as 'positive' knowledge. But they have soon thrust away such unwelcome thoughts. The self-satisfied dogmatism which is so convenient, and, indeed, so necessary a habit in the daily routine of life, has resumed its sway. They have forgotten that they were philosophers, and with true practical instincts have reserved their 'ob- stinate questionings ' exclusively for the benefit of opinions from which they were already predisposed to differ. Whether these historic reasons fully account for the comparative neglect of a philosophy of science I will not venture to pronounce. But that the neglect has been real I cannot doubt. Admirable generalisations of the actual methods of scientific research, usually under some such name as ' Induc- tive Logic,' we have no doubt had in abundance. But a lull and systematic attempt, first to enumerate, and tiien to justify, the presuppositions on which all 7 98 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM science finally rests, has, it seems to me, still to be made, and must form no insignificant or secondary portion of the task which philosophy has yet to perform. To some, perhaps to most, it may, indeed, appear as if such a task were one of perverse fu- tility ; not more useful and much less dignified than metaphysical investigations into the nature of the Absolute. However profitless in the opinion of the objector these may be, at least it seems better to strain after the transcendent than to demonstrate the obvious. And science, it may well be thought, is quite sure enough of its ground to be justified in politely bowing out those who thus officiously ten- der it a perfectly superfluous assistance. This is a contention on the merits of which it will only be possible to pronounce after the critical examination into the presuppositions of science which I desiderate has been thoroughly carried out. It may then appear that nothing stands more in need of demonstration than the obvious ; that at the very root of our scientific system of belief lie problems of which no satisfactory solution has hitherto been devised ; and that, so far from its being possible to ignore the difficulties which these involve, no general theory of knowledge has the least chance of being successful which does not explicitly include within the circuit of its criticism, not only the beliefs which seem to us to be dubious, but those also which we hold with the most perfect practical assurance. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 99 So much, at least, I have endeavoured to estab- lish in another work to which reference has been already made.^ And to this I must venture to refer those readers who either wish to see this position elaborately developed, or who arc of opinion that I have in the preceding remarks treated the philosophy of the empirical school with too scant a measure of respect. The very technical discussion, however, which it contains could not, I think, be made inter- esting, or perhaps intelligible, to the majority of those for whom this book is intended, and, even were it otherwise, they could not appropriately be intro- duced into the body of these Notes. Yet, though this is impossible, it ought not, I think, to be quite impossible to convey some general notion of the sort of difficulty with which any empirical theory of science woidd seem to be beset, and this without requiring on the part of the reader any special knowledge of philosophic terminology, or, indeed, any know ledge at all except that of some few very general scientific doctrines. If I coidd succeed, however imperfectly, in such a task, it might be of some slight service even to the reader conversant with cm])irical theories in all their various forms. I'"or though he will, of course, recognise in what folhjws the familiar faces of many old controversies, the circumstance tlial llicy are here approached, not from tlie accustomed side ol the psychology of per- cepti(jn, but Irom that ol ])h)-sics and physiology, ' Cf. l'refat(jry Note. lOO THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM may perhaps give them a freshness they would not otherwise possess. II In order to fix our ideas let us recall, in however rough and incomplete a form, the broad outlines of scientific doctrine as it at present exists, and as it has been developed from that unorganised knowl- edge of a world of objects — animals, mountains, men, planets, trees, water, fire, and so forth — which in some degree or other all mankind possess. These objects science conceives as ordered and mutually related in one unlimited space and one unlimited time ; all in their true reality independent of the presence or absence of any observer, all governed in their be- haviour by rigid and unvarying laws. These are its material ; these it is its business to describe. Their appearance, their inner constitution, their environ- ment, the process of their development, the modes in which they act and are acted upon — such and such-like subjects of inquiry constitute the problems which science has set itself to investigate. The result of its investigations is now embodied in a general, if provisional, view of the (phenomenal) universe which is practically accepted without ques- tion by all instructed persons. According to this view, the world consists essentially of innumerable small particles of definite and unchanging mass, endowed with a variety of mechanical, chemical, and THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM TOT Other qualities, and forming- by their mutual asso- ciation the various bodies which we can handle and see, and many others which we can neither handle nor see. These ponderable particles have their being in a diffused and all-penetrating medium, or ether, of which wc know little, except that it possesses, or behaves as if it possessed, certain mechanical prop- erties of a very remarkable character ; while the whole of this material ^ system, ponderable particles and ether alike, is animated (if the phrase may be permitted me) by a quantity of energy which, though it varies in the manner and place of its manifestation, yet never varies in its total amount. It only remains to add, as a fact of considerable importance to our- selves, though of little apparent importance to the universe at large, that a few of the material particles above alluded to are arranged into living organisms, and that among these organisms are a small minority which have the remarkable power of extracting from the changes which take place in certain of their tissues psychical phenomena of various kinds ; some of which are the reflection, or partial reproduction in perception and in thought, of fragments and ' This ambiguity in the use of the word ' matter ' is apt to be a nuisance in these discussions. The term is sometimes, and quite jjroperly, used only of ponderable matter, and in opposition to ether, ikit when we talk of the ' material universe,' it is absurd to exclude from our meaning the ether, which is the most important part of that universe, or to deny materiality to a substance which behaves as if it were an elastic solid. The context will, I hope, always show in which sense the word is used. I02 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM aspects of that material world to which they owe their being. Secure in this general view of things, the great co-operative work of scientific investigation moves swiftly on. The experimental psychologist, if we are to begin at that end of the scale, measures ' time reactions,' and other equally important mat- ters illustrating the relations of mind and body ; the physiologist endeavours to surprise the secrets of the living organ ; the biologist traces the develop- ment of the individual and the mutations of the species ; the chemist searches out the laws which govern the combination and reactions of atoms and molecules; the astronomer investigates the move- ments and the life -histories of suns and planets; while the physicist explores the inmost mysteries of matter and energy, not unprepared to discover be- hind the invisible particles and the insensible move- ments with which he familiarly deals, explanations of the material universe yet more remote from the unsophisticated perceptions of ordinary mankind. The philosophic reader is of course aware that many of the terms which I have used, and been obliged to use, in this outline of the scientific view of the universe may be, and have been, subjected to philosophic analysis, and often with very curious results. Space, time, matter, energy, cause, quality, idea, perception — all these, to mention no others, are expressions without the aid of which no account could be given of the circle of the sciences ; though THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM IO3 every one of them suggests a multitude of specula- tive problems, of which speculation has not as yet succeeded in giving us the final and decisive solu- tion. These problems, for the most part, however, I put on one side. I take these terms as I find them ; in the sense, that is, which everybody attrib- utes to them until he begins to puzzle himself with too curious inquiries into their precise meaning. No such embarrassing investigations do I wish to impose upon my reader. It shall be agreed be- tween us that the body of doctrine summarised above is, so far as it goes, clear and intelligible; and all I shall now require of him is to look at it from a new point of view, to approach it, as it were, from a different side, to study it with a new intention. In- stead, then, of asking what are the beliefs which science inculcates, let us ask why, in the last resort, we hold them to be true. Instead of inquiring how a thing happens, or what it is, let us inquire how we know that it does thus happen, and why we believe that so in truth it is. Instead of enumerating causes, let us set ourselves to investigate reasons. Ill Now it is at once evident that the very same general body of doctrines, the very same set of prop- ositions about the * natural ' world, arranged ac- cording to the principles suggested by these ques- tions, would fall into a wholly different order from I04 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM that which would be observed if its distribution were governed merely by considerations based upon the convenience of scientific exposition. Indeed, we may say that there are at least four quite dif- ferent orders, theoretically distinguishable, though usually mixed up in practice, in which scientific truth may be expounded. There is, first, the order of discovery. This is governed by no rational prin- ciple, but depends on historic causes, on the acci- dents of individual genius and the romantic chances of experiment and observation. There is, secondly, the rhetorical order, useful enough in its proper place, in which, for example, we proceed from the simple to the difficult, or from the striking to the important, according to the needs of the hearer. There is, thirdly, the scientific order, in which, could we only bring it to perfection, we should pro- ceed from the abstract to the concrete, and from the general law to the particular instance, until the whole world of phenomena was gradually presented to our gaze as a closely woven tissue of causes and effects, infinite in its complexity, incessant in its changes, yet at each moment proclaiming to those who can hear and understand the certain prophecy of its future and the authentic record of its past. Lastly, there is what, according to the terminology here employed, must be called the philosophic or- der, in which the various scientific propositions or dogmas are, or rather should be, arranged as a series of premises and conclusions, starting from THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 105 tliose which are axiomatic, i.e. for which \nooi can be neither i^iven nor required, and moving on through a continuous series of binding inferences, until the whole of knowledge is caught up and ordered in the meshes of this all-inclusive dialectical network. In its perfected shape it is evident that the philosophic series, though it reaches out to the furthest confines of the known, must for each man trace its origin to something which he can regard as axiomatic and self-evident truth. There is no theo- retical escape for any of us from the ultimate * I.' What ' r believe as conclusive must be drawn, by some process which ' I ' accept as cogent, from something which ' I ' am obliged to regard as intrin- sically self-sufficient, beyond the reach of criticism or the need for proof. The philosophic order and the scientific order of statement, therefore, cannot fail to be wholly different. While the scientific or- der may start with the dogmatic enunciation of some great generalisation valid through the whole unmeasured range of the material universe, the philo- sophic order is perforce compelled to find its point of departure in the humble personality of the inquirer. His grounds of belief, not the things believed in, are the subject-matter uf investigation. His reason, or, if you like to have it so, his share of the Univer- sal Reason, but in any case something which is /lis, must sit in judgment, and must try the cause. The rights of this tribunal are inalienable, its authority' I06 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM incapable of delegation ; nor is there any superior court by which the verdict it pronounces can be reversed. If now the question were asked, ' On what sort of premises rests ultimately the scientific theory of the world?' science and empirical philosophy, though they might not agree on the meaning of terms, would agree in answering, * On premises supplied by experience.' It is experience which has given us our first real knowledge of Nature and her laws. It is experience, in the shape of observation and experiment, which has given us the raw material out of which hypothesis and inference have slowly elaborated that richer conception of the material world which constitutes perhaps the chief, and cer- tainly the most characteristic, glory of the modern mind. What, then, is this experience ? or, rather, let us ask (so as to avoid the appearance of trenching on Kantian ground) what are these experiences ? These experiences, the experiences on which are alike founded the practice of the savage and the theories of the man of science, are for the most part observa- tions of material things or objects, and of their be- haviour in the presence of or in relation to each other. These on the empiricalt heory of knowledge, supply the direct information, the immediate data from which all our wider knowledge ultimately draws its sanction. Behind these it is impossible to go ; impossible, but also unnecessary. For as THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM \OJ the ' evidence of the senses ' does not derive its authority from any higher source, so it is useless to dispute its full and indefeasible title to command our assent. According to this view, which is thoroughly in accordance with common-sense, science rests in the main upon the immediate judgments we form about natural objects in the act of seeing, hearing, and handling them. This is the solid, if somewhat narrow, platform which provides us with a foothold whence we may reach u})ward into regions where the ' senses ' convey to us no direct knowledge, where we have to do with laws remote from our personal observation, and with objects which can neither be seen, heard, nor handled. IV But although such a theory seems simple and straightforward enough, in perfect harmony with the habitual sentiments and the universal practice of mankind, it would evidently be rash to rest satisfied with it as a philosophy of science until we had at least heard what science itself has to say upon the subject. What, then, is the account which science gives of these ' immediate judgments of the senses ' ? Has it anything to tell us about their nature, or the mode of their operation ? Without doubt it has ; and its teaching provides a curious, and at first sight an even startling, commentary on the com- mon-sense version of that philosophy of experience I08 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM whose general character has just been indicated above. For whereas common-sense tells us that our ex- perience of objects provides us with a knowledge of their nature which, so far as it goes, is immediate and direct, science informs us that each particular experience is itself but the final link in a long chain of causes and effects, whose beginning is lost amid the complexities of the material world, and whose ending is a change of some sort in the ' mind ' of the percipient. It informs us, further, that among these innumerable causes, the thing 'immediately experienced ' is but one ; and is, moreover, one separated from the 'immediate experience' which it modestly assists in producing by a very large num- ber of intermediate causes which are never experi- enced at all. Take, for example, an ordinary case of vision. What are the causes which ultimately produce the apparently immediate experience of (for example) a green tree standing in the nex;t field ? There are, .first (to go no further back), the vibrations among the particles of the source of light, say the sun. Consequent on them are the ethereal undulations between the sun and the objects seen, namely, the green tree. Then follows the absorption of most of these undulations by the object ; the reflection of the ' green ' residue ; the incidence of a small fraction of these on the lens of the eye ; their arrangement on the retina ; the stimulation of the optic nerve ; and. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM IO9 finally, the molecular change in a certain tract of the cerebral hemispheres by which, in some way or other wholly unknown, through predispositions in part acquired by the individual, but chiefly inherited through countless generations of ancestors, is pro- duced the complex mental fact which we describe by saying that ' we have an immediate experience of a tree about fifty yards off.' Now the experience, the causes and conditions of which I have thus rudely outlined, is typical of all the experiences, without exception, on which is based our knowledge of the material universe. Some of these experiences, no doubt, are incorrect. The 'evidence of the senses,' as the phrase goes, proves now and then to be fallacious. But it is proved to be fallacious by other evidence of precisely the same kind ; and if we take the trouble to trace back far enough our reasons for believing any scientific truth whatever, they alwa3'S end in some 'immediate experience ' or experiences of the type described above. But the comparison thus inevitably suggested be- tween 'immediate experiences' considered as the ultimate basis of all scientific belief, and immediate experience considered as an insignificant and, so to speak, casual product of natural laws, suggests some curious reflections. I do not allude to the difficulty (j| understanding how a mental effect can be pro- duced by a ])hysical cause — how matter can act on mind. The problem I wish to dwell on is of cpiite no THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM a different kind. It is concerned, not with the nat- ure of the laws by which the world is governed, but with their proof. It arises, not out of the difficulty of feeling our way slowly along the causal chain from physical antecedents to mental consequents, but from the difficulty of harmonising this move- ment with the opposite one, whereby we jump by some instantaneous effort of inferential activity from these mental consequents to an immediate conviction as to the reality and character of some of their re- moter physical antecedents. I am * experiencing ' (to revert to our illustration) the tree in the next field. While looking at it I begin to reflect upon the double process I have just described. I remem- ber the long-drawn series of causes, physical and physiological, by which my perception of the object has been produced. I realise that each one of these causes might have been replaced by some other cause without altering the character of the conse- quent perception ; and that if it had been so re- placed, my judgment about the object, though it would have been as confident and as immediate as at present, would have been wrong. Anything, for instance, which would distribute similar green rays on the retina of my eyes in the same pattern as that produced by the tree, or anything which would pro- duce a like irritation of the optic nerve or a like modification of the cerebral tissues, would give me an experience in itself quite indistinguishable from my experience of the tree, although it has the unfort- THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM III unate peculiarity of being wholly incorrect. The same message would be delivered, in the same terms and on the same authority, but it would be false. And though we are quite familiar with the fact that illusions are possible and that mistakes will occur in the simplest observation, yet we can hardly avoid being struck by the incongruity of a scheme of be- lief whose premises are wdiolly derived from wit- nesses admittedly untrustworthy, )^et which is un- able to supply any criterion, other than the evidence of these witnesses themselves, by which the char- acter of their evidence can in any given case be de- termined. The fact that even the most immediate experi- ences carry with them no inherent guarantee of their veracity is, however, by far the smallest of the diffi- culties which emerge from a comparison of the causal movement from object to perception, with the cogni- tive leap through perception to object. For a very slight consideration of the teaching of science as to the nature of the first is sufficient to prove, not merely the possible, but the habitual inaccuracy of the second. In other words, we need only to consider carefully our perceptions regarded as psychological results, in order to see that, regarded as sources of information, they are not merely occasionally inaccurate, but ha- bitually mendacious. We are dealing, recollect, with a theory of science according to which the ultimate stress of scientific proof is thrown wholly upon our immediate experience of objects. But nine-tenths 112 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM of our immediate experiences of objects are visual ; and all visual experiences, without exception, are, according to science, erroneous. As everybody knows, colour is not a property of the thing seen : it is a sensation produced in us by that thing. The thing itself consists of uncoloured particles, which become visible solely in consequence of their power of either producing or reflecting ethereal undula- tions. The degrees of brightness and the qualities of colour perceived in the thing, and in virtue of which alone any visual perception of the thing is possible, are, therefore, according to optics, no part of its reality, but are mere feelings produced in the mind of the percipient by the complex movements of material molecules, possessing mass and exten- sion, but to which it is not only incorrect but un- meaning to attribute either brightness or colour. From the side of science these are truisms. From the side of a theor}^ or philosophy of science, however, they are paradoxes. It was sufficiently embarrassing to discover that the message con- veyed to us by sensible experiences which the ob- server treats as so direct and so certain are, when considered in transit, at one moment nothing but vibrations of imperceptible particles, at another nothing but periodic changes in an unimaginable ether, at a third nothing but unknown, and perhaps unknowable, modifications of nervous tissue ; and that none of these various messengers carry with them any warrant that the judgment in which they THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM II3 finally issue will prove to be true. But what are we to say about these same experiences when we dis- cover, not only that they may be wholly false, but that they are never wholly true? What sort of a system is that which makes haste to discredit its own premises? In what entanglements of contra- diction do we not find ourselves involved by the attempt to rest science upon observations which science itself asserts to be erroneous? By what possible title do we proclaim the same immediate experience to be right when it testifies to the inde- pendent reality of something solid and extended, and to be wrong when it testifies to the indepen- dent reality of something illuminated and coloured? V There is, of course, an answer to all this, simple enough if only it be true. The whole theory, it may be said, on which we have been proceeding is untenable, the undigested product of crude com- mon-sense. The bugbear which frightens us is of our own creation. We have no immediate expe- rience of independent things such as has been gratuitously supposed. What science tells us of the colour element in our visual perceptions, namely, that it is merely a feeling or sensation, is true of every element in every perception. We are di- rectly cognisant of nothing but the mental results of cerebral changes': all else is a matter of infer- 8 114 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM ence; a hypothesis, more or less well established, to account for the existence of the only realities of which we have first-hand experience— namely, the mental results themselves. Now this theory does at first sight undoubtedly appear to harmonise with the general teaching of science on the subject of mental physiology. This teaching, as ordinarily expounded, assumes through- out a material world of objects and a psychical world of feelings and ideas. The latter is in all cases the product of the former. In some cases it may be a copy or partial reflection of the former. In no case is it identified with the former. When, therefore, I am in the act of experiencing a tree in the next field, what on this theory I am really doing is inferring from the fact of my having certain feel- ings the existence of a cause having qualities ade- quate to produce them. It is true that the process of inference is so rapid and habitual that we are un- conscious of performing it. It is also true that the inference is quite differently performed by the nat- ural man in his natural moments and the scientific man in his scientific moments. For, whereas the natural man infers the existence of a material object which in all respects resembles his idea of it, the scientific man knows very well that the material ob- ject only resembles his ideas of it in certain partic- ulars — extension, solidity, and so forth — and that in respect of such attributes as colour and illumi- nation there is no resemblance at all. Nevertheless, THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM II 5 in all cases, whether there be resemblance between them or not, the material fact is a conclusion from the mental fact, with which last alone we can be said to be, so to speak, in any immediate empirical relation. As this theory regarding the sources of our knowledofe of the material world fits in with the habitual language of mental physiology, so also it fits in with the first instincts of speculative analysis. It is, I suppose, one of the earliest discoveries of the metaphj'sically minded youth that he can, if he so wills it, change his point of view, and thereby sud- denly convert what in ordinary moments seem the solid realities of this material universe, into an un- ending pageant of feelings and ideas, moving in long procession across his mental stage, and having from the nature of the case no independent being before they appear, nor retaining any after they vanish. But however plausible be this correction of com- mon-sense, it has its difficulties. In the first place, it involves a complete divorce between the practice of science and its theory. It is all very well to say that the scientific account of mental physiology in general, and of sense-perception in particular, re- quires us to hold that what is immediately expe- rienced are mental facts, and that our knowledge of physical facts is but mediate and inferential. Such a conclusion is quite out of harmony with its own premises, since the propositions on which, as a Il6 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM matter of historical verity, science is ultimately founded are not propositions about states of mind, but about material things. The observations on which are built, for example, our knowledge of anat- omy or our knowledge of chemistry were not, in the opinion of those who originally made them or have since confirmed them, observations of their own feelings, but of objects thought of as wholly independent of the observer. They may have been mistaken. Such observations may be impossible. But, possible or impossible, they were believed to have occurred, and on that belief depends the whole empirical evidence of science as scientific discoverers themselves conceive it. The reader will, I hope, understand that I am not here arguing that the theory of experience now under consideration, the theory, that is, which con- fines the field of immediate experience to our oum states of mind, is inconsistent with science, or even that it supplies an inadequate empirical basis for science. On these points I may have a word to say presently. My present contention simply is, that it is not experience tJius understood which has supplied men of science with their knowledge of the physical universe. They have never suspected that, while they supposed themselves to be perceiving inde- pendent material objects, their qualities and their behaviour, they were in reality perceiving quite an- other set of things, namely, feelings and sensations of a particular kind, grouped in particular ways, THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM II7 and succeeding each other in a particular order. Nor, if this idea had ever occurred to them, would they have admitted that these two classes of things could by any merely verbal manipulation be made the same. So that if this particular account of the nature of experience be accurate, the system of thought represented by science presents the singu- lar spectacle of a creed which is believed in practice for one set of reasons, though in theory it can only be justified by another; and which, through some beneficent accident, turns out to be true, though its origin and each subsequent stage in its gradual development are the product of error and illusion. This is perplexing enough. Yet an even stronger statement would seem to be justified. We must not only say that the experiences on which science is founded have been invariably misinterpreted by those who underwent them, but that, if they had not been so misinterpreted, science as we know it would never have existed. We' have not merely stumbled on the truth in spite of error and illusion, which is odd, but because of error and illusion, which is even odder. For if the scientific observers of Nature had realised from the beginning that all they were observ- ing was their own feelings and ideas, as empirical idealism and mental physiology alike require us to hold, they surely would never have taken the trouble to invent a Nature {i.e. an independently existing system of material things) for no other purpose than to provide a machinery by which the occurrence of Il8 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM feelings and ideas might be adequately accounted for. To go through so much to get so little, to bewilder themselves in the ever-increasing intricacies of this hypothetical wheel -work, to pile world on world and add infinity to infinity, and all for no more important object than to find an explanation for a few fleeting impressions, say of colour or resistance, would, indeed, have seemed to them a most super- fluous labour. Nor is it possible to doubt that this task has been undertaken and partially accomplished only because humanity has been, as for the most part it still is, under the belief not only that there exists a universe possessing the independence which science and common-sense alike postulate, but that it is a universe immediately, if imperfectly, revealed to us in the deliverances of sense-perception. VI We can scarcely deny, then, though the paradox be hard of digestion, that, historically speaking, if the theory we are discussing be true, science owes its being to an erroneous view as to what kind of information it is that our experiences directly convey to us. But a much more important question than the merely historical one remains behind, namely, whether, from the kind of information which our ex- periences do thus directly convey to us, anything at all resembling the scientific theory of Nature can be reasonably extracted. Can our revised conception THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM II9 of the material world really be inferred from our revised conception of the import and limits of ex- perience? Can we by any possible treatment of sensations and feelings legitimately squeeze out of them trustworthy knowledge of the permanent and independent material universe of which, according to science, sensations and feelings are but transient and evanescent effects ? I cannot imagine the process by which such a result may be attained, nor has it been satisfactorily explained to us by any apologist of the empirical theory of knowledge. We may, no doubt, argue that sensations and feelings, like everything else, must have a cause ; that the hypothesis of a material W'Orld suggests such a cause in a form which is agreeable to our natural beliefs ; and that it is a hypothesis we are justified in adopting when we find that it enables us to anticipate the order and char- acter of that stream of perceptions which it is called into existence to explain. But this is a line of argu- ment which really will not bear examination. Every one of the three propositions of which it consists is, if we are to go back to fundamental principles, either disputable or erroneous. The principle of causation cannot be extracted out of a succession of individual experiences, as is implied by the first. The world described by science is not congruous with our natural beliefs, as is alleged by the second. Nor can we legitimately reason back from effect to cause in the manner required by the third. I20 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM A very brief comment will, 1 think, be sufficient to make this clear, and I proceed to offer it on each of the three propositions, taking them, for convenience, in the reverse order, and beginning, therefore, with the third. This in effect declares that as the material world described by science woidd, if it existed, pro- duce sensations and impressions in the very manner in which our experiences assure us that they actual- ly occur, we may assume that such a world exists. But may we ? Even supposing that there was this complete correspondence between theory and fact, which is far, unfortunately, from being at present the case, are we justified in making so bold a logical leap from the known to the unknown ? I doubt it. Recollect that by hypothesis we are strictly im- prisoned, so far as direct experiences are concerned, within the circle of sensations or impressions. It is in this self-centred universe alone, therefore, that we can collect the premises of further knowledge. How can it possibly supply us with any principles of selection by which to decide between the various kinds of cause that may, for anything we know to the contrary, have had a hand in its production ? None of these kinds of cause are open to observa- tion. All must, from the nature of the case, be purely conjectural. Because, therefore, we happen to have thought of one which, with a little goodwill, can be forced into a rude correspondence with the observed facts, shall we, oblivious of the million possible explanations which a superior intelligence THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 121 might be able to devise, proceed to decorate our particular fancy with the title of the ' Real World ' ? If we do so, it is not, as the candid reader will be prepared to admit, because such a conclusion is justified by such premises, but because we are pre- disposed to a conclusion of this kind by those instinctive beliefs which, in unreflective moments, the philosopher shares with the savage. In such moments all men conceive themselves (by hypoth- esis erroneously) as having direct experiences of an independent material universe. When, therefore, science, or philosophers on behalf of science, pro- ceed to infer such a universe from impressions of extension, resistance, and so forth, they find them- selves, so far, in an unnatural and quite illegitimate alliance with common-sense. By procedures which are different, and essentially inconsistent, the two parties have found it possible to reach results which at first sight look very much the same. Immediate intuitions wrongly interpreted come to the aid of mediate inferences illegitimately constructed ; we find ourselves quite prepared to accept the conclu- sions of bad reasoning, because they have a partial though, as I shall now proceed to show, an illusory resemblance to the deliverances of uncriticised ex- perience. This, it will be observed, is the subject dealt with in the second of the three propositions on which I am engaged in commenting. It alleges that the world described by science is congruous with 122 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM our natural beliefs ; a thesis not very important in itself, which I only dwell on now because it affords a convenient text from which to preach the great oddity of the creed which science requires us to adopt respecting the world in which we live. This creed is evidently in its origin an amendment or modification of the natural or instinctive view of things, a compromise to which we are no doubt compelled by considerations of conclusive force, but a compromise, nevertheless, which, if we did not know it to be true, we should certainly find it diffi- cult not to abandon as absurd. For, consider what kind of a world it is in which we are asked to believe — a world which, so far as most people are concerned, can only be at all adequately conceived in terms of the visual sense, but which in its true reality possesses neither of the qualities characteristically associated with the visual sense, namely, illumination and colour. A world which is half like our ideas of it and half unlike them. Like our ideas of it, that is to say, so far as the so-called primary qualities of matter, such as extension and solidity, are concerned ; unlike our ideas of it so far as the so-called secondary qualities, such as warmth and colour, are concerned. A hybrid world, a world of inconsistencies and strange anomalies. A world one-half of which may com- mend itself to the empirical philosopher, and the other half of which may commend itself to the plain man, but which as a whole can commend itself to THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NAIURALISM 123 neither. A world which is rejected by the first be- cause it arbitrarily selects what he regards as modes of sensation, and hypostatises them into permanent realities ; while it is scarcely intelligible to the second, because it takes what he regards as perma- nent realities, and evaporates them into modes of sensation. A world, in short, which seems to harmonise neither with the conclusions of critical empiricism nor with the ' unmistakable evidence of the senses ' ; which outrages the whole psychology of the one, and is in direct contradiction with the other. So far as the leading philosophic empiricists are concerned — and it is only with them that we need deal — the result of these difificulties has been extra- ordinary. They have found it impossible to swal- low this strange universe, consisting partly of microcosms furnished with impressions and ideas which, as such, are of course transient and essenti- ally mental, partly of a macrocosm furnished with material objects whose qualities exactly resemble impressions and ideas, with the embarrassing ex- ception that they are neither transient nor mental. They have, therefore, been compelled by one device or another to sweep the macrocosm as conceived by science altogether out of existence. In the name of experience itself they have destroyed that which professes to be experience systematised. And we are presented with the singular spectacle of thinkers whose claim to our consideration largely consists in 124 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM their uncompromising empiricism playing uncon- scious havoc with the most solid results which em- pirical methods have hitherto attained. I say 'unconscious' havoc, because, no doubt, the truth of this indictment would not be admitted by the majority of those against whom it is directed. Yet there can, I think, be no real question as to its truth. In the case of Hume it will hardly be denied ; and Hume, perhaps, would himself have been the last to deny it. But in the case of John Mill, of Mr. Herbert Spencer,^ and of Professor Huxley, it is an allegation which would certainly be repudiated, though the evidence for it seems to me to lie upon the surface of their speculations. The allegation, be it observed, is this — that while each of these thinkers has recognised the necessity for some independent reality in relation to the ever- moving stream of sensations which constitute our immediate experiences, each of them has rejected the independent reality which is postulated and ex- plained by science, and each of them has substituted for it a private reality of his own. Where the physicist, for example, assumes actual atoms and motions and forces, Mill saw nothing but permanent possibilities of sensation, and Mr. Spencer knows ' It is probably accurate to describe Mr. Spencer as an empiri- cist ; though he has added to the accustomed first principles of em- piricism certain doctrines of his own which, while they do not strengthen his system, make it somewhat difficult to classify. The reader interested in such matters will find most of the relevant points discussed in Philosophic Doubt, chaps, viii., ix., x. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 125 nothing but ' the unknowable.' Without discussing the place which such entities may properly occupy in the general scheme of things, I content myself with observing, what I have elsewhere endeavoured to demonstrate at length, that they cannot occupy the place now filled by material Nature as conceived by science. That which is a ' permanent possibil- ity,' but is nothing more, is permanent only in name. It represents no enduring reality, nothing which persists, nothing which has any being save during the brief intervals when, ceasing to be a mere * possibility,' it blossoms into the actuality of sen- sation. Before sentient beings were, it was not. When they cease to exist, it will vanish away. If they change the character of their sensibility, it will sympathetically vary its nature. How unfit is this unsubstantial shadow of a phrase to take the place now occupied by that material universe, of which we are but fleeting accidents, whose attributes are for the most part absolutely independent of us, whose duration is incalculable ! A different but not a less conclusive criticism may be passed on Mr. Spencer's 'unknowable.' For anything I am here prepared to allege to the con- trary, this may be real enough ; but, unfortunately, it has not the kind of reality imperatively required by science. It is not in space. It is not in time. It possesses neither mass nor extension ; nor is it capable of motion. Its very name implies that it eludes the grasp of thought, and cannot be caught 126 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM up into formulae. Whatever purpose, therefore, such an ' object ' may subserve in the universe of things, it is as useless as a ' permanent possibility ' itself to provide subject-matter for scientific treat- ment. If these be all that truly exist outside the circle of impressions and ideas, then is all science turned to foolishness, and evolution stands confessed as a mere figment of the imagination. Man, or rather * I,' become not merely the centre of the world, but ain the world. Beyond me and my ideas there is cither nothing, or nothing that can be known. The problems about which we disquiet ourselves in vain, the origin of things and the modes of their de- velopment, the inner constitution of matter and its relations to mind, are questionings about nothing, interrogatories shouted into the void. The baseless fabric of the sciences, like the great globe itself, dis- solves at the touch of theories like these, leaving not a wrack behind. Nor does there seem to be any course open to the consistent agnostic, were such a being possible, than to contemplate in patience the long procession of his sensations, without disturbing himself with futile inquiries into what, if anything, may lie beyond. VII There remains but one problem further with which I need trouble the readers of this chapter. It is that raised by the only remaining proposition of THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 1 27 the three with which I promised just now to deal. This asserts, it may be recollected, that the principle of causation and, by parity of reasoning-, any other universal principle of sense-interpretation, may by some process of logical alchemy be extracted, not merely from experience in general,' but even from the experience of a single individual. But who, it may be asked, is unreasonable enough to demand that it should be extracted from the ex- perience of a single individual? What is there in the empirical theory which requires us to impose so arbitrary a limitation upon the sources of our knowl- edge? Have we not behind us the whole experience of the race ? Is it to count for nothing that for num- berless generations mankind has been scrutinisinsf the face of Nature, and storing up for our guidance innumerable observations of the laws which she obeys? Yes, I reply, it is to count for nothing; and for a most simple reason. In making this appeal to the testimony of mankind with regard to the world in which they live, we take for granted that there is such a world, that mankind has had experiences of it, and that, so far as is necessary for our purpose, we know what those experiences have been. But by what right do we take those things for granted ? They are not axiomatic or intuitive truths; they must be proved by something; and that something must, on the empirical theory, be in the last resort experience, and experience alone. But whose cx- ' See PJiilosophic Doubt, cli. i. 128 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM perience ? Plainly it cannot be general experience, for that is the very thing whose reality has to be es- tablished, and whose character is in question. It must, therefore, in every case and for each individual man be his own personal experience. This, and only this, can supply him with evidence for those funda- mental beliefs, without whose guidance it is impos- sible for him either to reconstruct the past or to an- ticipate the future. Consider, for example, the law of causation ; one, but by no means the only one, of those general prin- ciples of interpretation which, as I am contending, are presupposed in any appeal to general experience, and cannot, therefore, be proved by it. If we en- deavour to analyse the reasoning by which we ar- rive at the conviction that any particular event or any number of particular events have occurred out- side the narrow ring of our own immediate percep- tions, we shall find that not a step of this process can we take without assuming that the course of Nature is uniform^ ; or, if not absolutely uniform, at least sufificiently uniform to allow us to argue with tolerable security from effects to causes, or, if need be, from causes to effects, over great intervals of time and space. The whole of what is called his- torical evidence is, in its most essential parts, noth- " The reader will find some observations on the meaning of the phrase, ' Uniformity of Nature,' in the last chapter of this Essay. In this chapter I have assumed (following- empirical usage) that the Uniformity of Nature and the Law of Causation are different ex- pressions for the same thing. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 1 29 ing- more than an argument or series of arguments of this kind. The fact that mankind have given their testimony to the general uniformity of Nature, or, indeed, to anything else, can be established by tlic aid of that principle itself, and b}' it alone ; so that if wc abandon it, we are in a moment deprived of all logical access to the outer world, of all cogni- sance of other minds, of all usufruct of their accu- mulated knowledge, of all share in the intellectual heritage of the race. While if we cling to it (as, to be sure, we must, whether we like it or not), we can do so only on condition that we forego every en- deavour to prove it by the aid of general experience; for such a procedure would be nothing less than to compel what is intended to be the conclusion of our argument to figure also among the most important of its premises. The problem, therefore, is reduced to this : Can we find in our personal experience adequate evi- dence of a law which, like the law of Causation, does, by the very terms in which it is stated, claim universal jurisdiction, as of right, to the utmost verge both of time and space. And surely, to enun- ciate such a question is to suggest the inevitable answer. The sequences familiar to us in the petty round of daily life, the accustomed recurrence of something resembling a former consequent, follow- ing on the heels of something resembling a former antecedent, are sufficient to generate the expecta- tions and the habits by which we endeavour, with 9 I30 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM what success we may, to accommodate our behav- iour to the unyielding requirements of the world around us. But to throw upon experiences such as these ^ the whole burden of fixing our opinions as to the constitution of the universe is quite absurd. It would be absurd in any case. It would be absurd even if all the phenomena of which we have imme- diate knowledge succeeded each other according to some obvious and undeviating order ; for the con- trast between this microscopic range of observation and the gigantic induction which it is sought to rest thereon, would rob the argument of all plausibility. But it is doubly and trebly absurd when we reflect on what our experiences really are. So far are they from indicating, when taken strictly by themselves, the existence of a world where all things small and great follow with the most exquisite regularity and the most minute obedience the biddinsf of unchanof. ing law, that they indicate precisely the reverse. In certain regions of experience, no doubt, orderly se- quence appears to be the rule : day alternates with night, and summer follows upon spring ; the sun moves through the zodiac, and unsupported bodies fall usually, though, to be sure, not always, to the ground. Even of such elementary astronomical and physical facts, however, it could hardly be main- tained that any man would have a right, on the strength of his personal observation alone, confident- ' At least in the absence of any transcendental interpretation of them. See next chapter. THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 131 ly to assert their undeviating regularity. But when we come to the more complex phenomena with which we have to deal, the plain lesson taught by personal observation is not the regularity, but the irregularity, of Nature. A kind of ineffectual at- tempt at uniformity, no doubt, is commonly appar- ent, as of an ill-constructed machine that will run smoothly for a time, and then for no apparent reason begin to jerk and quiver; or of a drunken man who, though he succeeds in keeping to the high-road, yet pursues along it a most wavering and devious course. But of that perfect adjustment, that all-penetrating governance by law, which lies at the root of scientific inference we find not a trace. In many cases sensa- tion follows sensation, and event hurries after event, to all appearances absolutely at random : no ob- served order of succession is ever repeated, nor is it pretended that there is any direct causal connection between the members of the series as they appear one after the other in the consciousness of the indi- vidual. But even when these conditions are reversed, perfect uniformity is never observed. The most careful series of experiments carried out by the most accomplished investigators never show identical re- sults; and as for the general mass of mankind, so far are they from finding, cither in their personal experi- ences or elsewhere, any sufficient reason for accept- ing in its perfected form the principle of Universal Causation, that, as a matter of fact, this doctrine has been steadily ignored by them up to the present hour. 132 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM This apparent irregularity of Nature, obvious enough when we turn our attention to it, escapes our habitual notice, of course, because we invariably attribute the want of observed uniformity to the errors of the observer. And without doubt we do well. But what does this imply ? It implies that we bring to the interpretation of our sense-perception the principle of causation ready made. It implies that we do not believe the world to be governed by immutable law because our experiences appear to be regular ; but that we believe that our experi- ences, in spite of their apparent irregularity, follow some (perhaps) unknown rule because we first be- lieve the world to be governed by immutable law. But this is as much as to say that the principle is not proved by experience, but that experience is un- derstood in the light of the principle. Here, again, empiricism fails us. As in the case of our judgments about particular matters of fact, so also in the case of these other judgments, whose scope is co-exten-.,^ sive with the whole realm of Nature, we find that any endeavour to formulate a rational justification for them based on experience alone breaks down, and, to all appearance, breaks down hopelessly. VIII But even if this reasoning be sound, may the reader exclaim. What is it that we gain by it ? What harvest are we likely to reap from such broadcast THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 1 33 sowing of scepticism as this? What does it profit us to show that a great many truths which every- bod}' believes, and which no abstract specuLations will induce us to doubt, are still waiting for a philo- sophic proof? Fair questions, it must be admitted ; questions, nevertheless, to which I must reserve my full answer until a later stage of our inquiry. Yet even now something may be said, by way of conclu- sion to this chapter, on the relation which these crit- icisms bear to the scheme of thought whose practi- cal consequences we traced out in the first part of these Notes. I begin by admitting that the criticisms them- selves are, from the nature of the case, incomplete. They contain but the concise and even meagre out- line of an argument which is itself but a portion only of the whole case. For want of space, or to avoid unsuitable technicalities, much has been omitted which would have been relevant to the issues raised, and have still further strengthened the position which has been taken up. Yet, though more might have been said, what has been said is, in my opinion, sufficient; and I shall, therefore, not scruple hence- forth to assume that a purely empirical theory of things, a philosophy which depends for its premises in the last resort upon the particulars revealed to us in perceptive experience alone, is one that can- not rationally be accepted. Is this conclusion, then, adverse to Naturalism ? And, if so, must it not tell with equal force against 134 I'lIE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM Science, seeing that it is solely against that part of the naturalistic teaching which is taken over bodily from Science that it appears to be directed ? Of these two questions, 1 answer the first in the affirm- ative, the second in the negative. Doubtless, if empiricism be shattered, it must drag down natural- ism in its fall ; for, after all, naturalism is nothing more than the assertion that empirical methods are valid, and that no others are so. But because any effectual criticism of empiricism is the destruction of naturalism, is it therefore the destruction of sci- ence also ? Surely not. The adherent of natural- ism is an empiricist from necessity ; the man of science, if he be an empiricist, is so only from choice. The latter may, if he please, have no philos- ophy at all, or he may have a different one. He is not obliged, any more than other men, to justify his conclusions by an appeal to first principles ; still less is he obliged to take his first principles from so poor a creed as the one we have been discussing. Science preceded the theory of science, and is independent of it. Science preceded naturalism, and will sur- vive it. Though the convictions involved in our practical conception of the universe are not beyond the reach of theoretic doubts, though we habitually stake our all upon assumptions which we never at- tempt to justify, and which we could not justify if we would, yet is our scientific certitude unshaken ; and if we still strive after some solution of our sceptical difficulties, it is because this is necessary THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM 1 35 for the satisfaction of an intellectual ideal, not be- cause it is required to fortify our confidence either in the familiar teachings of experience or in their utmost scientific expansion. And hence arises my principal complaint against naturalism. With Em- pirical philosophy, considered as a tentative con- tribution to the theor}' of science, I have no desire to pick a quarrel. That it should fail is nothing. Other philosophies have failed. Such is, after all, the common lot. That it should have been con- trived to justify conclusions already accepted is, if a fault at all — which I doubt — at least a most venial one, and one, moreover, which it has committed in the best of philosophic company. That it should derive some moderate degree of imputed credit from the universal acceptance of the scientific be- liefs which it countersigns, may be borne with, though for the real interests of speculative inquiry this has been, I think, a misfortune. But that it should develop into naturalism, and then, on the strength of labours which it has not endured, of victories which it has not won, and of scientific triumphs in which it has no right to share, presume, in despite of its speculative insufficiency, to dictate terms of surrender to ever}^ other system of belief, is altogether intolerable. Who would pay the slight- est attention to naturalism if it did not force itself into the retinue of science, assume her livery, and claim, as a kind of poor relation, in some sort to rep- resent her authority and to speak with her voice ? 136 THE PHILOSOPHIC BASIS OF NATURALISM Of itself it is nothing. It neither ministers to the needs of mankind, nor does it satisfy their reason. And if, in spite of this, its influence has increased, is increasing, and as yet shows no signs of diminution ; if more and more the educated and the half-educated are acquiescing in its pretensions and, however re- luctantly, submitting to its domination, this is, at least in part, because they have not learned to dis- tinguish between the practical and inevitable claims which experience has on their allegiance, and the speculative but quite illusory title by which the em- pirical school have endeavoured to associate natural- ism and science in a kind of joint supremacy over the thoughts and consciences of mankind. CHAPTER II IDEALISM ; AFTER SOME RECENT ENGLISH WRITINGS* The difficulties in the way of an empirical philos- ophy of science, with which we dealt in the last ' The reader who has no familiarity with philosophic literature is advised to omit this chapter. The philosophic reader will, I hope, regard it as provisional. Transcendental Idealism is, if I mistake not, at this moment in rather a singular position in this country. In the land of its birth (as I am informed) it is but little considered. In English-speaking countries it is, within the narrow circle of professed philosophers, perhiips the dominant mood of thought ; while without that circle it is not so much objected to as totally ignored. This anomalous state of things is no doubt due in part to the inherent difficulty of the subject ; but even more, I think, to the fact that the energy of English Idealists has been consumed rather in the production of commentaries on other people's systems than in the expositions of their own. The result of this is that we do not quite know where we are, that we are more or less in a con- dition of expectancy, and that both learners and critics are placed at a disadvantage. Pending the appearance of some original work which shall represent the constructive views of the younger school of thinkers, I have written the following chapter, with reference chiefly to the writings of the late Mr. T. H. Green, which at pres- ent contain the most important exposition, so far as I know, of this phase of English thought. Mr. Bradley's noteworthy work, ' Ap- pearance and Reality,' published some time after this chapter was finished, is written with characteristic independence ; but I know not whether it has yet commanded any large nuasurc of assent from the few who are compc'tent to pronouun- a vcnlicl upon its merits. 138 IDEALISM chapter, largely arise from the conflict which exists between two parts of a system, the scientific half of which requires us to regard experience as an effect of an external and independent world, while the philosophic or epistemological half offers this same experience to us as the sole groundwork and logi- cal foundation on which any knowledge whatever of an external and independent world may be ra- tionally based. These difificulties and the arguments founded on them require to be urged, in the first in- stance, in opposition to those who explicitly hold what I have called the ' naturalistic ' creed ; and then to that general body of educated opinion which, though reluctant to contract its beliefs with- in the narrow circuit of ' naturalism,' yet habitually assumes that there is presented to us in science a body of opinion, certified by reason, solid, certain, and impregnable, to which theology adds, as an edi- fying supplement, a certain number of dogmas, of which the well-disposed assimilate as many, but only as many, as their superior allegiance to * posi- tive ' knowledge will permit them to digest. These two classes, however, by no means exhaust the kinds of opinion with which it is necessary to deal. And in particular there is a metaphysical school, few indeed in numbers, but none the less im- portant in matters speculative, whose general posi- tion is wholly distinct and independent; who would, indeed, not perhaps very widely, dissent from the negative conclusions already reached, but who have IDEALISM 139 their own positive solution of the problem of the universe. In their opinion, all the embarrassments which may be shown to attend on the empirical philosophy are due to the fact that empirical philos- ophers wholly misunderstand the essential nature of that experience on which they profess to found their beliefs. The theory of perception evolved out of Locke, by Berkeley and Hume, which may be traced without radical modification through their modern successors, is, according to the school of which I speak, at the root of all the mischief. Of this theory they make short work. They press to the utmost the sceptical consequences to which it inevitably leads. They show, or profess to show, that it renders not only scientific knowledge, but any knowledge whatever, impossible ; and they of- fer as a substitute a theory of experience, very re- mote indeed from ordinary modes of expression, by which these consequences may, in their judgment, be entirely avoided. The dimensions and character of these Notes ren- der it impossible, even were I adequately equipped for the task, to deal fully with so formidable a sub- ject as Transcendental Idealism, either in its historical or its metaphysical aspect. Remote though it be from ordinary modes of thought, some brief discussion of the theory with which, in some recent English works, it supplies us concerning Nat- ure and God is, however, absolutely necessary ; and I therefore here present the following observa- I40 IDEALISM tions to the philosophic reader with apologies for their brevity, and to the unphilosophic reader with apologies for their length. From what I have already said it is clear that the theory to which Transcendental Idealism may be, from our point of view, considered as a reply, is 7iot the theory of experience which is taken for granted in ordinary scientific statement, but the closely allied ' psychological theory of perception ' evolved by thinkers usually classed rather as philos- ophers than as men of science. The difference is not wholly immaterial, as will appear in the sequel. What, then, is this ' psychological theory of per- ception ' ? Or, rather, where is the weak point in it at which it is open to attack by the transcendental idealists? It lies in the account given by that the- ory of the real. According to this account the ' real ' in external experience, that which, because it is not due to any mental manipulation by the per- cipient, such as abstraction or comparison, may be considered as the experienced fact, is, in ultimate analysis, either a sensation or a group of sensations. These sensations and groups of sensations are sub- jected in the mind to a process of analysis and com- parison. Discrimination is made between those which are unlike. Those which have points of re- semblance are called by a common name. The se- quences and CO -existences which obtain among them are noted ; the laws by which they are bound together are discovered ; and the order in which IDEALISM 141 they may be expected to recur is foreseen and un- derstood. Now, say the idealists, if everything of which ex- ternal reality can be predicated is thus either a sen- sation or the idea of a sensation, if these and these only are ' given ' in experience, ever37thing else, in- cluding relations, being mere fictions of the mind, we are reduced to the absurd position of holding that the real is not only unknown, but is also un- knowable. For a brief examination of the nature of experience is sufficient to prove that an unrelated ' thing ' (be that ' thing ' a sensation or a group of sensations), which is not qualified by its resemblance to other things, its difference from other things, and its connection with other things, is really, so far as we are concerned, no ' thing ' at all. It is not an object of possible experience ; its true character must be for ever hid from us ; or, rather, as char- acter consists simply in relations, it lias no char- acter, nor can it form part of that intelligible world with which alone we have to deal. Ideas of relation are, therefore, required to con- vert the supposed ' real * of external experience into something of which experience can take note. But such ideas themselves are unintelligible, except as the results of the intellectual activity of some ' Self ' or ' I '. They must be somebody's thought, somebody's ideas ; if only for the purpose of mutual compari- son, there must be some bond of union between them other than themselves. Here again, therefore, 142 IDEALISM the psychological analysis of experience breaks down, and it becomes plain that just as the real in external experience is real only in virtue of an in- tellectual element, namely, ideas of relation (cate- gories), through which it was apprehended, so in internal experience ideas and sensations presuppose the existence of an ' I,' or self-conscious unity, which is neither sensation nor idea, which ought not, therefore, on the psychological theory to be con- sidered as having any claim to reality at all, but which, nevertheless, is presupposed in the very pos- sibility of phenomena appearing as elements in a single experience. We are thus apparently left by the idealist theory face to face with a mind (thinking subject) which is the source of relations (categories), and a world which is constituted by relations : with a mind which is conscious of itself, and a world of which that mind may without metaphor be described as the creator. We have, in short, reached the central position of transcendental idealism. But before we proceed to subject the system to any critical observations, let us ask what it is we are supposed to gain by endeav- ouring thus to rctJiink the universe from so unaccus- tomed a point of view. In the first place, then, it is claimed for this theory that it frees us from the scepticism which, in matters scientific as well as in matters theological, follows inevitably upon the psychological doctrine of percep- tion as just explained : a scepticism which not only IDEALISM 143 leaves no room for God and the soul, but destroys the very possibility of framing any general proposi- tion about the ' external ' world, by destroying the possibility of there being any world, ' external ' or otherwise, in which permanent relation shall exist. In the second place, it makes Reason no mere accidental excrescence on a universe of material objects; an element to be added to, or subtracted from, the sum of ' things ' as the blind shock of un- thinking causes may decide. Rather does it make Reason the very essence of all that is or can be : the (immanent) cause of the world - process ; its origin and its goal. In the third place, it professes to establish on a firm foundation the moral freedom of self-conscious agents. That ' Self ' which is the prior condition of there being a natural world cannot be the creature of that W'Orld. It stands above and beyond the sphere of causes and effects ; it is no mere object among other objects, driven along its predestined course by external forces in obedience to alien laws. On the contrary, it is a free, autonomous Spirit, not only bound, but able, to fulfil the moral commands which are but the expression of its own most essential being. II I am reluctant to suggest objections to any theory which promises results so admirable. Yet I cannot think that all the difficulties with which it is sur- 144 IDEALISM rounded have been fairly faced, or, at any rate, fully explained, by those who accept its main principles. Consider, for example, the crucial question of the analysis which reduces all experience to an experience of relations, or, in more technical language, which constitutes the universe out of categories. We ma}' grant without difficulty that the contrasted theory, which proposes to reduce the universe to an unrelated chaos of impressions or sensations, is quite untenable. But must we not also grant that in all experience there is a refractory element which, though it cannot be presented in isolation, nevertheless refuses wholly to merge its being in a network of relations, necessary as these may be to give it ' significance for us as thinking beings ' ? If so, whence does this irreduc- ible element arise ? The mind, we are told, is the source of relation. What is the source of that which is related ? A ' thing-in-itself ' which, by impressing the percipient mind, shall furnish the ' matter ' for which categories provide the ' form,' is a way out of the difficulty (if difficulty there be) which raises more doubts than it solves. The followers of Kant them- selves make haste to point out that this hypothetical cause of that which is ' given ' in experience cannot, since ex hypothesi it lies beyond experience, be known as a cause, or even as existing. Nay, it is not so much unknown and unknowable as indescribable and unin- telligible ; not so much a riddle whose meaning is obscure as mere absence and vacuity of any meaning whatever. Accordingly, from the speculations with IDEALISM 145 which we are here concerned it has been dismissed with ignominy, and it need not, therefore, detain us further. But we do not get rid of the difficulty by getting rid of Kant's solution of it. His dictum still seems to me to remain true, that ' without matter categories are empty.' And, indeed, it is hard to see how it is possible to conceive a universe in which relations shall be all in all, but in which nothing is to be per- mitted for the relations to subsist between. Rela- tions surely imply a something which is related, and if that something is, in the absence of relations, ' nothing for us as thinking beings,' so relations in the absence of that something arc mere symbols emptied of their signification ; they are, in short, an ' illegitimate abstraction.' Those, moreover, who hold that these all-consti- tuting relations are the ' work of the mind ' would seem bound also to hold that this concrete world of ours, down to its minutest detail, must evolve itself a priori out of the movement of * pure thought.' There is no room in it for the * contingent' ; there is no room in it for the ' given ' ; experience itself would seem to be a superfluity. And we are at a loss, there- fore, to understand why that dialectical process which moves, I will not say so convincingly, but at least so smoothly, through the abstract categories of ' being,' ' not-being,' * becoming,' and so forth, should stumble and hesitate when it comes to deal with that world of Natiir<- which is, after all, one of the prinri]ial 10 146 IDEALISM subjects about which we desire information. No explanation which I remember to have seen makes it otherwise than strange that we should, as the ideal- ists claim, be able so thoroughly to identify ourselves with those thoughts of God which are the necessary preliminary to creation, but should so little under- stand creation itself ; that we should out of our unaided mental resources be competent to reproduce the whole ground-plan of the universe, and should yet lose ourselves so hopelessly in the humblest of its ante-rooms. This difficulty at once requires us to ask on what ground it is alleged that these constitutive relations are the ' work of the mind.' It is true, no doubt, that ordinary usage would describe as mental products the more abstract thoughts (categories), such, for example, as ' being,' ' not-being,' ' causation,' ' reci- procity,' &c. But it must be recollected, in the first place, that transcendental idealism does not, as a rule, derive its inspiration from ordinary usage ; and in the second place, that even ordinary usage alters its procedure when it comes to such more concrete cases of relation as, for instance, ' shape ' and ' posi- tion,' which, rightly or wrongly, are always con- sidered as belonging to the 'external' world, and presented by the external world to thought, not cre- ated by thought for itself. Are the transcendental idealists, then, bound by their own most essential principles, in opposition both to their arguments against Kant's * thing-in-itself ' IDEALISM 147 and to the ordinary beliefs of mankind, to invest the thinking ' self ' with this attribute of causal or quasi- causal activity ? It certainly appears to me that they are not. Starting, it will be recollected, from the analysis (criticism) of experience, they arrived at the conclusion that the world of objects exists and has a meaning only for the self-conscious ' I ' (subject), and that the self-conscious ' I ' only knows itself in contrast and in opposition to the world of objects. Each is necessar}' to the other ; in the absence of the other neither has an}^ significance. How, then, can we venture to sa}' of one that the other is its product ? and if we say it of either, must we not in consistency insist on saying it of both ? Thus, though the pres- ence of a self-conscious principle may be necessary to constitute the universe, it cannot be considered as the creator of that universe ; or if it be, then must we acknowledge that precisel}' in the same way and precisely to the same extent is the univei^se the cre- ator of the self-conscious principle. All, therefore, that the transcendental argument requires or even allows us to accept, is a ' manifold ' of relations on the one side, and a bare self-conscious principle of unity on the other, by which that mani- fold becomes intcr-connected in the ' field of a single experience.' We are not permitted, except by a process of abstraction which is purely temporary and provisional, to consider the ' manifold ' apart from the ' unity,' nor the ' unity ' apart from the ' manifold.' The thoughts do not make the thinker, nor the 148 IDEALISM thinker the thoughts ; but together they constitute that Whole or Absolute whose elements, as they are mere no -sense apart from one another, cannot in strictness be even said to contribute separately to- wards the total result. Ill Now let us consider what bearing this conclusion has upon (i) Theology, (2) Ethics, and (3) Science. I. As regards Theology, it might be supposed that at least idealism provided us with a universe which, if not created or controlled by Reason (crea- tion and control implying causal action), may yet properly be said to be throughout infused by Rea- son and to be in necessary harmony with it. But on a closer examination difficulties arise which some- what mar this satisfactory conclusion. In the first place, if theology is to provide us with a ground- work for religion, the God of whom it speaks must be something more than the bare ' principle of unity ' required to give coherence to the multiplicity of Nature. Apart from Nature He is, on the theory we are considering, a mere metaphysical abstraction, the geometrical point through which pass all the threads which make up the web of possible experi- ence : no fitting object, surely, of either love, rever- ence, or devotion. In combination with Nature He is no doubt ' the principle of unity,' and all the ful- ness of concrete reality besides; but ever}' quality IDEALISM 149 with which He is thus associated belongs to that por- tion of the Absolute Whole from which, by hypoth- esis, He distinguishes Himself ; and, were it other- wise, we cannot find in these qualities, compacted, as they are, of good and bad, of noble and base, the Perfect Goodness without which relio:ious feelinirs can never find an adequate object. Thus, neither the combining principle alone, nor the combining principle considered in its union with the multipli- city which it combines, can satisfy the requirements of an effectual theology. Not the first, because it is a barren abstraction ; not the second, because in its all-inclusive universality it holds in suspension, with- out preference and without repulsion, every element alike of the knowable world. Of these none, what- ever be its nature, be it good or bad, base or noble, can be considered as alien to the Absolute : all are necessary, and all are characteristic. Of these two alternatives, I understand that it is the first which is usually adopted by the school of thought with which we are at present concerned. It may therefore be desirable to reiterate that a 'unifying principle' can, as such, have no qualities, moral or otherwise. Lovingkindness, for example, and Equity are attributes which, like all attributes, belong not to the unifying principle, but to the world of objects which it constitutes. They are conceptions which i)elong to the realm of emj)ir- ic.'il ps\( linlogv. Nor can I see any mctlusd l)v which the}' are to be hitched on to the 'pure spirit- ISO IDEALISM ual subject,* as elements making up its essential character. 2. But if this be so, what is the ethical value of that freedom which is attributed by the idealistic theory to the self-conscious ' I ' ? It is true that this ' I ' as conceived by idealism is above all the * cate- gories,' including, of course, the category of causa- tion. It is not in space nor in time. It is subject neither to mutation nor decay. The stress of ma- terial forces touches it not, nor is it in any servitude to chance or circumstance, to inherited tendencies or acquired habits. But all these immunities and privileges it possesses in virtue of its being, not an agent in a world of concrete fact, but a thinking 'subject,' for whom alone, as it is alleged, such a world exists. Its freedom is metaphysical, not moral ; for moral freedom can only have a meaning at all in reference to a being who acts and who wills, and is only of real importance for us in relation to a being who not only acts, but is acted on, who not only wills, but who wills against the opposing influ- ences of temptation. Such freedom cannot, it is plain, be predicated of a mere ' subject,' nor is the freedom proper to a ' subject ' of any worth to man as ' object,' to man as known in experience, to man fighting his way with varying fortunes against the stream of adverse circumstances, in a world made up of causes and effects.^ ' This proposition would, probably, not be widely dissented from by some of the ethical writers of the idealist school. The freedom IDEALISM 151 These observations bring into sufficiently clear relief the difficulty which exists, on the idealistic theory, in bringing together into any sort of intelli- gible association the ' I ' as supreme principle of unity, and the ' I ' of empirical psychology, which which they postulate is not the freedom merely of the pure self-con- scious subject. On the contrary, it is the individual, with all his qualities, passions, and emotions, who in their view possesses free will. But the ethical value of the freedom thus attributed to self- conscious agents seems on further examination to disappear. Man- kind, it seems, are on this theory free, but their freedom does not exclude determinism, but only that form of determinism ivhich consists in external constraint. Their actions are upon this view strictly prescribed by their antecedents, but these antecedents are nothing other than the characters of the agents themselves. Now it may seem at first sight plausible to describe that man as free whose behaviour is due to ' himself ' alone. But without quar- relling over words, it is, I think, plain that, whether it be proper to call him free or not, he at least lacks freedom in the sense in which freedom is necessary in order to constitute responsibility. It is im- possible to say of him that he ' ought,' and therefore he ' can'. For at any given moment of his life his next action is by hypothesis strictly determined. This is also true of every previous moment, until we get back to that point in his life's history at which he can- not, in any intelligible sense of the term, be said to ' have a char- acter at all. Antecedently to this, the causes which have produced him are in no special sense connected with his individuality, but form part of the general complex of phenomena which make up the world. It is evident, therefore, that every act which he performs may be traced to pre-natal, and possibly to purely material, antece- dents, and that, even if it be true that what he does is the outcome of his character, his character itself is the outcome of causes over which he has not, and cannot by any possibility have, the smallest control. Such a theory destroys responsibility, and leaves our ac- tions the inevitable outcome of external conditions not less com- pletely than any doctrine of controlling fate, whether materialistic or theological. 152 IDEALISM has desires and fears, pleasures and pains, faculties and sensibilities ; which was not a little time since, and which a little time hence will be no more. The ' 1 ' as principle of unity is outside time ; it can have, therefore, no history. The ' I ' of experience, which learns and forgets, which suffers and which enjoys, unquestionably has a history. What is the relation between the two? We seem equally precluded from saying that they are the same, and from saying that they are different. We cannot say that they are the same, because they are, after all, divided by the whole chasm which distinguishes 'subject' from * object.' We cannot say they are different, because our feel- ings and our desires seem a not less interesting and important part of ourselves than a mere unifying principle whose functions, after all, are of a purely metaphysical character. We cannot say they are ' two aspects of the same thing,' because there is no virtue in this useful phrase which shall empower it on the one hand to ear-mark a fragment of the world of objects, and say of it, ' this is I,' or, on the other, to take the ' pure subject ' by which the world of objects is constituted, and say of it that it shall be itself an object in that world from which its essential nature requires it to be self-distinguished. But as it thus seems difficult or impossible in- telligibly to unite into a personal whole the ' pure * and the 'empirical' Self, so it is difficult or impossible to conceive the relations between the pure, though limited, self-consciousness which is ' I ' and the uni- IDEALISM 153 versal and eternal Self-consciousness which is God. The iirst has been described as a ' mode ' or ' mani- festation ' of the second. But are we not, in using such language, falling into the kind of error against which, in other connections, the idealists are most careful to warn us? Are we not importing a cate- gory which has its meaning and its use in the world of objects into a transcendental region where it really has neither meaning nor use at all ? Grant, how- ever, for the sake of argument, that it has a meaning; grant that we may legitimately describe one ' pure subject ' as a ' mode ' or ' manifestation ' of another — how is this partial identity to be established ? How can we, who start from the basis of our own limited self-consciousness, rise to the knowledge of that completed and divine self-consciousness of which, according to the theory, we share the essential nat- ure ? The difficulty is evaded but not solved in those statements of the idealist theory which always speak of Thought without specifying ivhosc Thought. It seems to be thus assumed that the thought is God's, and that in rethinking it we share His being. But no such assumption would seem to be justifiable. For the basis, we know, of the whole theory is a ' criticism ' or analysis of the essential elements of experience. But the criticism must, for each of us, be necessarily of his ozvn experience, for of no other experience can he know anything, except indirectly and by way of inference from his own. What, then, 154 IDEALISM is this criticism supposed to establish (say) for me ? Is it that experience depends upon the unification by a self-conscious ' I ' of a world constituted by re- lations? In strictness, No. It can only establish that inj experience depends upon a unification by my self-conscious ' I ' of a world of relations present to uic, and to me alone. To this ' 1,' to this particu- lar ' self-conscious subject,' all other ' I's,' including God, must be objects, constituted like all objects by relations, rendered possible or significant only by their unification in the ' content of a single experi- ence ' — namely, my own. In other words, that which (if it exists at all) is essentially ' subject ' can only be known, or thought of, or spoken about, as ' object.* Surely a ver}^ paradoxical conclusion. It may perhaps be said by way of reply, that in talking of particular ' I's ' and particular experiences we are using language properly applicable only to the ' self ' dealt with by the empirical psychologist, the ' self ' which is not the< subject,' but the ' object,' of experience. I will not dispute about terms; and the relations which exist between the ' pure ego ' and the ' empirical ego ' are, as I have already said, so obscure that it is not always easy to employ a perfectly accurate terminology in endeavouring to deal with them. Yet this much would seem to be certain. If the words ' self,' ' ego,' ' I,' are to be used intelligibly at all, they must mean, whatever else they do or do not mean, a ' somewhat ' which is self- distinguished, not only from every other knowable IDEALISM 155 object, but also from every other possible ' self.' What we are ' in ourselves,' apart from the flux of thoughts and feelings which move in never-ending pageant through the chambers of consciousness, metaphysicians have, indeed, found it hard to say. Some of them have said we are nothing. But if this conclusion be, as I think it is, conformable neither to our instinctive beliefs nor to a sound psychology ; if we are, as I believe, more than a mere series of occurrences, yet it seems equally certain that the very notion of Personality excludes the idea of any one person being a ' mode ' of any other, and forces us to reject from philosophy a supposition which, if it be tolerable at all, can find a place only in mj's- ticism. But the idealistic theory pressed to its furthest conclusions requires of us to reject, as it appears to me, even more than this. We are not only precluded by it from identifying ourselves, even partially, with the Eternal Consciousness : we are also precluded from supposing that either the Eternal Conscious- ness or any other consciousness exists, save only our own. For, as I have already said, the Eternal Con- sciousness, if it is to be known, can only be known on the same conditions as any other object of knowl- edge. It must be constituted by relations; it must form part of the ' content of experience ' of the knower; it must exist as part of the ' multiplicity ' reduced to ' unity ' by his self-consciousness. But to say that it can only be known on these terms, is to 156 IDEALISM say that it cannot be known as it exists ; for if it exists at all, it exists by hypothesis as Eternal Sub- ject, and as such it clearly is not constituted by rela- tions, nor is it either a * possible object of experi- ence,' or ' anything for us as thinking beings.' No consciousness, then, is a possible object of knowledge for any other consciousness : a statement which, on the idealistic theory of knowledge, is equivalent to saying that for any one consciousness all other consciousnesses are less than non-existent. For as that which is ' critically ' shown to be an in- evitable element in experience has thereby conferred on it the highest possible degree of reality, so that which cannot on any terms become an element in experience falls in the scale of reality far below mere not-being, and is reduced, as we have seen, to mere meaningless no-sense. By this kind of reasoning the idealists themselves demonstrate the ' I ' to be necessary; the unrelated object and the thing-in-itself to be impossible. Not less, by this kind of reason- ing, must each one of us severally be driven to the conclusion that in the infinite variety of the universe there is room for but one knowing subject, and that this subject is ' himself.'^ ' Prof. Caird, in his most interesting and suggestive lecture on the Evolution of Religion, puts forward a theory essentially dif- ferent from the one I have just been dealing with. In his view, a multiplicity of objects apprehended by a single self-conscious subject does not suffice to constitute an intelligible universe. The world of objects and the perceiving mind are themselves opposites which re- quire a higher unity to hold them together. This higher unity is IDEALISM 157 IV 3. That the transcendental ' solipsism ' which is the natural outcome of such speculations is not less inconsistent with science, morality, and common- sense than the psychological, or Berkeleian ^ form of the same creed, is obvious. But without attempt- ing further to press idealism to results which, wheth- er legitimate or not, all idealists would agree in God ; so that by the simplest of metaphysical demonstrations Prof. Caird lays deep the foundations of his theology, and proves not only that God exists, but that His Being is philosophically involved in the very simplest of our experiences. I confess, with regret, that this reasoning appears to me incon- clusive. Surely we must think of God as, on the transcendental theory, we think of ourselves ; that is, as a Subject distinguishing itself from, but giving unity to, a world of phenomena. But if such a Subject and such a world cannot be conceived without also postulating some higher unity in which their differences shall vanish and be dissolved, then God Himself would require some yet higher deity to explain His existence. If, in short, a multiplicity of phe- nomena presented to and apprehended by a conscious ' I ' form to- gether an intelligible and self-sufficient whole, then it is hard to see by what logic we are to get beyond the solipsism which, as I have urged in the text, seems to be the necessary outcome of one form, at least, of the transcendental argument. If, on the other hand, subject and object cannot form such an intelligible and self-suffi- cient whole, then it seems impossible to imagine what is the nature (jf that Infinite One in which the multiplicity of things and persons find their ultimate unity. Of such a God we can have no knowl- edge, nor can we say that we are formed in His image, or share His essence. ' Of course I do not mean to suggest that Berkeley was a ' so- lipsist.' (Jn the scientific bearing of psychological idealism, see Philosophic Doubt, chap. ix. 158 IDEALISM repudiating, let me, in conclusion, point out how little assistance this theory is able under any circum- stances to afford us in solving important problems connected with the Philosophy of Science. The psychology of Hume, as we have seen, threw doubt upon the very possibility of legitimately fram- ing general propositions about the world of objects. The observation of isolated and unrelated impres- sions of sense, which is in effect what experience became reduced to under his process of analysis, may generate habits of expectation, but never can justify rational beliefs. The law of universal causa- tion, for example, can never be proved by a mere repetition, however prolonged, of similar sequences, though the repetition may, through the association of ideas, gradually compel us to expect the second term of the sequence whenever the first term comes within the field of our observation. So far Hume as interpreted by the transcendental idealists. Now, how is this difficulty met on the idealistic theory ? Somewhat in this way. These categories or general principles of relation have not, say the idealists, to be collected (so to speak) from individual and separate experiences (as the empirical philoso- phers believe, but as Hume, the chief among empiri- cists, showed to be impossible) ; neither are they, as the a priori philosophers supposed, part of the original furniture of the observing mind, intended by Providence to be applied as occasion arises to the world of experience with which by a beneficent, IDEALISM 159 if unexplained, adaptation they find themselves in a pre-established harmony. On the contrary, they are the ' necessary prius,' the antecedent condition, of there being any experience at all; so that the difficul- ty of subsequently extracting them from experience does not arise. The world of phenomena is in truth their creation ; so that the conformity between the two need not be any subject of surprise. Thus, at one and the same time does idealism vindicate ex- perience and set the scepticism of the empiricist at rest. I doubt, however, whether this solution of the problem will really stand the test of examination. Assuming for the sake of argument that the world is constituted by ' categories,' the old difficulty arises in a new shape when we ask on what principle those categories are in any given case to be applied. For they are admittedly not of universal application ; and, as the idealists themselves are careful to remind us, there is no more fertile source of error than the im- portation of them into a sphere wherein they have no legitimate business. Take, for example, the cate- gory of causation, from a scientific point of view the most important of all. By what right does the existence of this * principle of relation ' enable us to assert that throughout the whole world every event must have a cause, and every cause m ust be invariably succeeded by the same event ? Because we can apply the category, are we, therefore, bound to aj)ply it? Docs any absurdity or contradiction ensue fi-om our l6o IDEALISM supposing that the order of Nature is arbitrary and casual, and that, repeat the antecedent with what accuracy we may, there is no security that the ac- customed consequent will follow? I must confess that I can perceive none. Of course, we should thus be deprived of one of our most useful ' principles of unification ' ; but this would by no means result in the universe resolving- itself into that unthinkable chaos of unrelated atoms which is the idealist bugbear. There are plenty of categories left ; and if the final aim of philosophy be, indeed, to find the Many in One and the One in Many, this end would be as completely, if not as satisfactorily, accomplished by conceiving the world to be presented to the thinking 'subject' in the haphazard multiplicity of unordered succession, as by any more elaborate method. Its various elements lying side by side in one Space and one Time would still be related together in the con- tent of a single experience; they would still form an intelligible whole ; their unification would thus be ef- fectually accomplished without the aid of the higher categories. But it is evident that a universe so con- stituted, though it might not be inconsistent with Phi- losophy, could never be interpreted by Science. As we saw in the earlier portion of this chapter, it is not very easy to understand why, if the universe be constituted by relations, and relations are the work of the mind, the mind should be dependent on experience for finding out anything about the uni- verse. But granting the necessity of experience, it IDEALISM l6l seems as hard to make that experience answer our questions on the idealist as on the empirical hypothe- sis. Neither on the one theory nor on the other does any method exist for extracting general truths out of particular observations, unless .y^'wr general truths are first assumed. On the empirical hypothesis there are no such general truths. Pure empiricism has, there- fore, no claim to be a philosophy. On the idealist hypothesis there appears to be only one general truth applicable to the whole intelligible world — a world which, be it recollected, includes everything in re- spect to which language can be significantly used ; a world which, therefore, includes the negative as well as the positive, the false as well as the true, the im- aginary as well as the real, the impossible as well as the possible. This single all-embracing truth is that the multiplicity of phenomena, whatever belts nature, must always be united, and only exists in virtue of being united, in the experience of a single self-con- scious Subject. But this general proposition, what- ever be its value, cannot, I conceive, effectually guide us in the application of subordinate categories. It supplies us with no method for appl3nng one principle rather than another within the field of experience. It cannot give us information as to what portion of that field, if any, is subject to the law of causation, nor tell us which of our perceptions, if any, may be taken as evidence of the existence of a permanent world of objects such as is iiiii)ti(.(l in all scientific doctrine. Though, therefore, the old questions come upon us II l62 IDEALISM in a new form, clothed, I will not say shrouded, in a new terminology, they come upon us with all the old insistence. They are restated, but they are not solved ; and I am unable, therefore, to find in idealism any escape from the difficulties which, in the region of theology, ethics, and science, empiricism leaves upon our hands.^ ' I have made in this chapter no reference to the idealistic theory of cesthetics. Holding the views I have indicated upon the general import of idealism, such a course seemed unnecessary. But I can- not help thinking that even those who find in that theory a more satisfactory basis for their convictions than I am able to do, must feel that there is something rather forced and arbitrary in the at- tempts that have been made to exhibit the artistic fancies of an insignificant fraction of the human race during avery brief period of its history as essential and important elements in the development and manifestation of the ' Idea.' CHAPTER III PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM Briefly, if not adequately, I have now endeavoured to indicate the weaknesses which seem to me to be inseparable from any empirical theory of the uni- verse, and almost equally to beset the idealistic theory in the form given to it by its most systematic exponents in this country. The reader may perhaps feel tempted to ask whether I propose, in what pur- ports to be an Introduction to Theology, to pass under similar review all the metaphysical systems which have from time to time held sway in the schools, or have affected the general course of specu- lative opinion. He need, however, be under no alarm. My object is strictly practical ; and I have no con- cern with theories, however admirable, which can no longer pretend to any living philosophic power — which have no de facto claims to present us with a reasoned scheme of knowledge, and which can- not prove their importance by actually supplying grounds for the conviction of some fraction, at least, of those by whom these pages may conceivably be read. In saying that this condition is not satisfied by l64 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM the great historic systems which mark with their imperishable ruins the devious course of European thought, I must not be understood as suggesting that on that account these lack either value or interest. All I say is, that their interest is not of a kind which brings them properly within the scope of these Notes. Whatever be the nature or amount of our debt to the great metaphysicians of the past, unless here and now we go to them not merely for stray arguments on this or that question, but for a rea- soned scheme of knowledge which shall include as elements our own actual beliefs, their theories are not, for the purposes of the present discussion, any concern of ours. Now, of how many systems, outside the two that have already been touched on, can this even plausi- bly be asserted ? Run over in memory some of the most important. Men value Plato for his imag- ination, for the genius with which he hazarded solutions of the secular problems which perplex mankind, for the finished art of his dialogue, for the exquisite beauty of his style. But even if it could be said — which it cannot — that he left a system, could it be described as a system which, as such, has any effectual vitality ? It would be difficult, perhaps impossible, to sum up our debts to Aristotle. But assuredly they do not include a tenable theory of the universe. The Stoic scheme of life may still touch our imagination ; but who takes any inter- est in their metaphysics ? Who cares for their Soul PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 165 of the world, the periodic conflagrations, and the recurring cycles of mundane events ? The Neo- Platonists were mystics ; and mysticism is, as I sup- pose, an undying element in human thought. But who is concerned about their hierarchy of beings connecting through infinite gradations the Absolute at one end of the scale with Matter at the other ? These, however, it may be said, were systems belonging to the ancient world ; and mankind have not busied themselves with speculation for these two thousand years and more without making some advance. I agree ; but in the matter of providing us with a philosophy — with a reasoned system of knowledge — has this advance been as yet sub- stantial? If the ancients fail us, do we, indeed, fare much better with the moderns ? Are the meta- physics of Descartes more living than his physics ? Do his two substances or kinds of substance, or the single substance of Spinoza, or the innumerable substances of Leibnitz, satisfy the searcher after truth ? From the modern English form of the em- piricism which dominated the eighteenth century, and the idealism which disputes its suprema^cy in the nineteenth, I have already ventured to express a reasoned dissent. Are we, then, to look to such schemes as Schopenhauer's philosophy of Will, and Hartmann's philosophy of the Unconscious, to supply us with the philosophical metaphysics of which we arc in need ? They have admirers in this country, but hardly convinced adherents. Of l66 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM those who are quite prepared to accept their pes- simism, how many are there who take seriously its metaphysical foundation ? In truth there are but three points of view from which it seems worth while to make ourselves ac- quainted with the growth, culmination, and decay of the various metaphysical dynasties which have successively struggled for supremacy in the world of ideas. The first is purely historical. Thus re- garded, metaphysical systems are simply significant phenomena in the general history of man : symp- toms of his spiritual condition, aids, it may be, to his spiritual growth. The historian of philosophy, as such, is therefore quite unconcerned with the truth or falsehood of the opinions whose evolution he is expounding. His business is merely to ac- count for their existence, to exhibit them in their proper historical setting, and to explain their char- acter and their consequences. But, so considered, I find it difficult to believe that these opinions have been elements of primary importance to the ad- vancement of mankind. All ages, indeed, which have exhibited intellectual vigour have cultivated one or more characteristic systems of metaphysics ; but rarely, as it seems to me, have these systems been in their turn important elements in determin- ing the character of the periods in which they flour- ished. They have been effects rather than causes ; indications of the mood in which, under the special stress of their time and circumstance, the most de- PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 167 tached intellects have faced the eternal problems of humanity ; proofs of the unresting- desire of man- kind to bring their beliefs into harmony with spec- ulative reason. But the beliefs have almost always preceded the speculations ; they have frequently survived them ; and I cannot convince myself that among the just titles to our consideration some- times put forward on behalf of metaphysics we may count her claim to rank as a powerful instrument of progress. No doubt — and here we come to the second point of view alluded to above — the constant dis- cussion of these high problems has not been barren merely because it has not as yet led to their solu- tion. Philosophers have mined for truth in many directions, and the whole field of speculation seems cumbered with the dross and lumber of their aban- doned workings. But though they have not found the ore they sought for, it does not therefore follow that their labours have been wholly vain. It is somethinij to have realised what not to do. It is something to discover the causes of failure, even though we do not attain any positive knowledge of the conditions of success. It is an even more sub- stantial gain to have done something towards dis- engaging the questions which require to be dealt with, and towards creating and perfecting the ter- minology without which they can scarcely be ade- quately stated, much less satisfactorily answered. And there is yet a third point of view from l68 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM which past metaphysical speculations are seen to retain their value, a point of view which may be called (not, I admit, without some little violence to accustomed usage) the cesthctic. Because reasoning occupies so large a place in metaphysical treatises we are apt to forget that, as a rule, these are works of imagination at least as much as of reason. Meta- physicians are poets who deal with the abstract and the super-sensible instead of the concrete and the sensuous. To be sure they arc poets with a differ- ence. Their appropriate and characteristic gifts are not the vivid realisation of that which is given in experience ; their genius does not prolong, as it were, and echo through the remotest regions of feel- ing the shock of some definite emotion ; they create for us no new worlds of things and persons ; nor can it be often said that the product of their la- bours is a thing of beauty. Their style, it must be owned, has not always been their strong point ; and even when it is otherwise, mere graces of presenta- tion arc but unessential accidents of their work. Yet, in spite of all this, they can only be justly es- timated by those who are prepared to apply to them a quasi-aesthetic standard ; some other stand- ard, at all events, than that supplied by purely argumentative comment. It may perhaps be shown that their metaphysical constructions are faulty, that their demonstrations do not convince, that their most permanent dialectical triumphs have fallen to them in the paths of criticism and negation. PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 169 Yet even then the last word will not have been said. For claims to our admiration will still be found in their brilliant intuitions, in the subtlety of their occasional arguments, in their passion for the Universal and the Abiding, in their steadfast faith in the rationality of the world, in the devotion with which they are content to live and move in realms of abstract speculation too far removed from ordi- nary interests to excite the slightest genuine sym- pathy in the breasts even of the cultivated few. If, therefore, we are for a moment tempted, as surely may sometimes happen, to contemplate with re- spectful astonishment some of the arguments which the illustrious authors of the great historic systems have thought good enough to support their case, let it be remembered that for minds in which the critical intellect holds undisputed sway, the crea- tion of any system whatever in the present state of our knowledge is, perhaps, impossible. Only those in whom powers of philosophical criticism are bal- anced, or more than balanced, by powers of meta- physical imagination can be fitted to undertake the task. Though even to them success may be impos- sible, at least the illusion of success is permitted ; and but for them mankind would fall away in hope- less discouragement from its highest intellectual ideal, and speculation would be strangled at its birth. To some, indeed, it may appear as if the loss would not, after all, be great. What use, they may 1 T/O PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM exclaim, can be found for any system which will not stand critical examination? What value has reasoning which does not satisfy the reason ? How can we know that these abstruse investigations sup- ply even a fragmentary contribution towards a final philosophy, until we are able to look back upon them from the perhaps inaccessible vantage ground to be supplied by this final philosophy itself ? To such questionings I do not profess to find a com- pletely satisfactory answer. Yet even those who feel inclined to rate extant speculations at the low- est value will perhaps admit that metaphysics, like art, give us something we could ill afford to spare. Art may not have provided us with any reflection of immortal beauty ; nor metaphysics have brought us into communion with eternal truth. Yet both may have historic value. In speculation, as in art, we find a vivid expression of the changeful mind of man, and the interest of both, perhaps, is at its highest when they most clearly reflect the spirit of the age which gave them birth, when they are most racy of the soil from which they sprung. II To this point I may have to return. But my more immediate business is to bring home to the reader's mind the consequences which may be drawn from the admission — supposing him disposed PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM l/I to make it — that we have at the present time neither a satisfactory S3'stem of metaphysics nor a satisfac- tory theory of science. Many persons, perhaps it would not be too much to say most persons, are prepared contentedly to accept the first of these propositions ; but it is on the truth of the second that I desire to lay at least an equal stress. The first man one meets in the street thinks it quite nat- ural to accept the opinion that sense-experience is the only source of rational conviction ; that every- thing to which it does not testify is untrue, or, if true, falls within the domain, not of knowledge, but of faith. Yet the criticism of knowledge indicated in the two preceding chapters shows how one- sided is such a view. If faith be provisionally de- fined as conviction apart from or in excess of proof, then it is upon faith that the maxims of daily life, not less than the loftiest creeds and the most far- reaching discoveries, must ultimately lean. The ground on which constant habit and inherited pre- dispositions enable us to tread with a step so easy and so assured, is seen on examination to be not less hollow beneath our feet than the dim and unfamiliar regions which lie beyond. Certitude is found to be the child, not of Reason, but of Custom ; and if we are less perplexed about the beliefs on which we are hourly called upon to act than about those which do not touch so closely our obvious and im- mediate needs, it is not because the questions sug- gested by the former arc easier to answer, but be- 1/2 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM cause as a matter of fact we are much less inclined to ask them. Now, if this be true, it is plainly a fact of capi- tal importance. It must revolutionise our whole attitude towards the problems presented to us by science, ethics, and theology. It must destroy the ordinary tests and standards, whereby we measure essential truth. In particular, it requires us to see what is commonly, if rather absurdly, called the conflict between religion and science in a wholly new aspect. We can no longer be content with the simple view, once universally accepted, that when- ever any discrepancy, real or supposed, occurs be- tween the two, science must be rejected as hereti- cal ; nor with the equally simple view, to which the former has long given place, that every theological statement, if unsupported by science, is doubtful ; if inconsistent with science, is false. Opinions like these are evidently tolerable only on the hypothesis that we are in possession of a body of doctrine which is not only itself philosoph- ically established, but to whose canons of proof all other doctrines are bound to conform. But if there is no such body of doctrine, what then ? Are we arbitrarily to erect one department of belief into a law-giver for all the others ? Are we to say that though no scheme of knowledge exists, certain in its first principles, and coherent in its elaborated conclusions, yet that from among the provisional schemes which we are inclined practically to accept PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 1 73 one is to be selected at random, within whose limits, and there alone, the spirit of man may range in con- fident security ? Such a position is speculatively untenable. It involves a use of the Canon of Consistency not justified by any philosophy ; and as it is indefensible in theory, so it is injurious in practice. For, in truth, though the contented acquiescence in inconsistency is the abandonment of the philosophic quest, the de- termination to obtain consistency at all costs has been the prolific parent of many intellectual narrow- nesses and many frigid bigotries. It has shown itself in various shapes ; it has stifled and stunted the free movement of thought in different ages and diverse schools of speculation ; its unhappy effects may be traced in much theology which professes to be orthodox, in much criticism which delights to be heterodox. It is, moreover, the characteristic note of a not inconsiderable class of intelligences who conceive themselves to be specially reasonable be- cause they are constantly employed in reasoning, and who can find no better method of advancing the cause of knowledge than to press to their ex- treme logical conclusions principles of which, per- haps, the best that can be said is that they contain, as it were in solution, some element of truth which no reagents at our command will as yet permit us to isolate. 174 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM III That I am here attacking no imaginary evil will, I think, be evident to any reader who recalls the general trend of educated opinion during the last three centuries. It is, of course, true that in dealing with so vague and loosely outlined an object as 'educated opinion' we must beware of attribut- ing to large masses of men the acceptance of an}- carefully-thought-out or definitely articulated sys- tem. Systems are, and must be, for the few. The majority of mankind are content with a mood or temper of thought, an impulse not fully reasoned out, a habit guiding them to the acceptance and assimilation of some opinions and the rejection of others, which acts almost as automatically as the processes of physical digestion. Behind these half- realised motives, and in closest association with them, may sometimes, no doubt, be found a 'theory of things' which is their logical and explicit expres- sion. But it is certainly not necessary, and perhaps not usual, that this theory should be clearly formu- lated by those who seem to obey it. Nor for our present purpose is there any important distinction to be made between the case of the few who find a reason for their habitual judgments, and that of the many who do not. Keeping this caution in mind, we may consider without risk of misconception an illustration of the PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 175 misuse of the Canon of Consistency provided for us by the theory corresponding to that tendency of thought which has played so large a part in the development of the modern mind, and which is commonly known as Rationalism. Now what is Rationalism ? Some may be disposed to reply that it is the free and unfettered application of human intelligence to the problems of life and of the world ; the unprejudiced examination of every question in the dry light of emancipated reason. This may be a very good account of a particular intellectual ideal ; an ideal which has been sought after at many periods of the world's history, although assuredly it has been attained in none. Usage, however, per- mits and even encourages us to employ the word in a much more restricted sense : as indicating a special form of that reaction against dogmatic the- ology which may be said with sufficient accuracy to have taken its rise in the Renaissance, to have in- creased in force and volume during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, and to have reached its most complete expression in the Naturalism which occupied our attention through the first portion of these Notes. A reaction of some sort was no doubt inevitable. Men found themselves in a world where Literature, Art, and Science were enormous- ly extending the range of human interests ; in which Religion seemed only to be approachable through the languishing controversies which had burnt with so fierce a flame during the sixteenth and seven- 176 PHILOSOPHY AND PvATIOiNALlSM teenth centuries ; in which accepted theological methods had their roots in a very different period of intellectual growth, and were ceasing to be appropriate to the new developments. At such a time there was, undoubtedly, an important and even a necessary work to be done. The mind of man cannot, any more than the body, vary in one direc- tion alone. The whole organism suffers or gains from the change, and every faculty and every limb must be somewhat modified in order successfully to meet the new demands thrown upon it by the altered balance of the remainder. So is it also in matters intellectual. It is hopeless to expect that new truths and new methods of investigation can be acquired without the old truths requiring to be in some respects reconsidered and restated, surveyed under a new aspect, measured, perhaps, by a differ- ent standard. Much had, therefore, to be modified, and something — let us admit it — had to be destroyed. The new system could hardly produce its best results until the refuse left by the old system had been removed ; until the waste products were elimi- nated which, like those of a muscle too long exer- cised, poisoned and clogged the tissues in which they had once played the part of living and effec- tive elements. The world, then, required enlightenment, and the rationalists proceeded after their own fashion to enlighten it. Unfortunately, however, their whole procedure was tainted by an original vice of method PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 177 which made it impossible to carry on the honour- able, if comparatively humble, work of clearance and purification without, at the same time, destroy- ing much that ought properly to have been pre- served. They were not content with protesting against practical abuses, with vindicating the free- dom of science from theological bondage, with criti- cising the defects and explaining the limitations of the somewhat cumbrous and antiquated apparatus of prevalent theological controversy — apparatus, no doubt, much better contrived for dealing with the points on which theologians differ than for defend- ing against a common enemy the points on which theologians are for the uK^st part agreed. These things, no doubt, to the best of their power, they did ; and to the doing of them no objection need be raised. The objection is to the principle on which the things were done. That principle appeared under many disguises, and was called by many names. Sometimes describing itself as Common- sense, sometimes as Science, sometimes as Enlight- enment, with infinite varieties of application and great diversity of doctrine. Rationalism consisted essentially in the application, consciously or uncon- sciously, of one great method to the decision of every controversy, to the moulding of every creed. Did a belief square with a view of the universe based exclusively upon the prevalent mode of inter- preting sense-perception? If so, it might survive. Did it clash with such UKjdc, or lie beyond it? It 12 178 PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM was superstitious ; it was unscientific ; it was ridicu- lous ; in was incredible. Was it neither in harmony with nor antagonistic to such a view, but simply be- side it? It might live on until it became atrophied from lack of use, a mere survival of a dead past. These judgments were not, as a rule, supported by any very profound arguments. Rationalists as such are not philosophers. They are not pantheists nor speculative materialists. They ignore, if they do not despise, metaphysics, and in practice es- chew the search for first principles. But they judge as men of the world, equally reluctant to criticise too closely methods which succeed so admirably in everyday affairs, or to admit that any other methods can possibly be required by men of sense. Of course, a principle so loosely conceived has led at different times and in different stages of knowledge to very different results. Through the greater portion of the world's history the ' ordinary mode of interpreting sense-perception ' has been perfectly consistent with so-called 'supernatural' phenomena. It may become so again. And if dur- ing the rationalising centuries this has not been the case, it is because the interpretation of sense-per- ceptions has during that period been more and more governed by that Naturalistic theory of the world to which it has been steadily gravitating. It is true that the process of eliminating incongruous beliefs has been gradual. The general body of ra- tionalisers have been slow to see and reluctant to PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM 1/9 accept the full consequences of their own princi- ples. The assumption that the kind of ' experience' which efave us natural science was the sole basis of knowledge did not at first, or necessarily, carry with it the further inference that nothing deserved to be called knowledge which did not come within the circle of the natural sciences. But the inference was practically, if not logically, inevitable. Theism, Deism, Design, Soul, Conscience, Morality, Immor- tality, Freedom, Beauty — these and cognate words associated with the memory of great controversies mark tlie points at which rationalists who are not also naturalists have sought to come to terms with the rationalising spirit, or to make a stand against its onward movement. It has been in vain. At some places the fortunes of battle hung long in the balance ; at others the issues may yet seem doubtful. Those who have given up God can still make a fight for conscience ; those who have abandoned moral responsibility may still console themselves with artistic beauty. But, to my think- infif, at least, the strusfo-le can have but one termina- tion. TIabit and education may delay the inevitable conclusion ; they cannot in the end avert it. For these ideas are no native growth of a rationalist epoch, strong in their harmony with contemporary moods of thought. They are the products of a dif- ferent age, survivals from, as some think, a decay- ing system. And howsoever stubbornly they may resist the influences of an alien environment, if this l8o PHILOSOPHY AND RATIONALISM undergoes no change, in the end they must surely perish. Naturalism, then, the naturalism whose practical consequences have already occupied us so long, is nothing more than the result of rationalising meth- ods applied with pitiless consistency to the whole circuit of belief; it is the completed product of ra- tionalism, the final outcome of using the ' current methods of intcrpi-eting sense-perception ' as the universal instrument for determining the nature and fixing the limits of human knowledge. What wealth of spiritual possession this creed requires us to give up I have already explained. What, then, does it promise us in exchange ? It promises us Consistency. Religion may perish at its touch, it may strip Virtue and Beauty of their most precious attributes ; but in exchange it promises us Con- sistency. True, the promise is in any circum- stances but imperfectly kept. This creed, which so arrogantly requires that everything is to be made consistent with it, is not, as we have seen, consistent with itself. The humblest attempts to co-ordinate and to justify the assumptions on which it proceeds with such unquestioning confidence bring to light speculative perplexities and contra- dictions whose very existence seems unsuspected, whose solution is not even attempted. But even were it otherwise we should still be bound to pro- test against the assumption that consistency is a necessity of the intellectual life, to be purchased, if PHILOSOrHY AND RATIONALISM iSl need be, at famine prices. It is a valuable commod- ity, but it may be bought too dear. No doubt a principal function of Reason is to smooth away con- tradictions, to knock off corners, and to fit, as far as may be, each separate belief into its proper place within the framework of one harmonious creed. No doubt, also, it is impossible to regard any theory which lacks self-consistenc}' as either satisfactory or final. But principles going far beyond admissions like these are required to compel us to acquiesce in rationalising methods and naturalistic results, to the destruction of every form of belief with which they do not happen to agree. Before such terms of surrender are accepted, at least the victorious sys- tem must show, not merely that its various parts are consistent with each other, but that the whole is authenticated by Reason. Until this task is accom- plished (and how far at present it is from being ac- complished in the case of naturalism the reader knows) it would be an act of mere blundering Un- reason to set up as the universal standard of belief a theory of things which itself stands in so great need of rational defence, or to make a reckless and unthinking application of the canon of consistency when our knowledge of first principles is so mani- festly defective. CHAPTER IV RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY At this point, however, it may perhaps occur to the reader that I have somewhat too lightly as- sumed that Rationalism is the high-road to Natural- ism. Why, it may be asked, is there any insuper- able difficulty in framing another scheme of belief which shall permanently satisfy the requirements of consistency, and harmonise in its general procedure with the rationalising spirit ? Why are we to as- sume that the extreme type of this mode of thought is the only stable type ? Such doubts would be the more legitimate because there is actually in exis- tence a scheme of great historic importance, and some present interest, by which it has been sought to run Modern Science and Theology together into a single coherent and self-sufficient system of thought, by the simple process of making Science supply all the premises on which theological conclu- sions are afterwards based. If this device be really adequate, no doubt much of what was said in the last chapter, and much that will have to be said in future chapters, becomes superfluous. If 'our ordinary method of interpreting sense-perception,' which gives us Science, is able also to supply us RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY 1 83 with Theology, then at least, whether it be philo- sophically valid or not, the majority of mankind may very well rest content with it until philosophers come to some agreement about a better. If it does not satisfy the philosophic critic, it will probably satisfy everyone else ; and even the philosophic critic need not quarrel with its practical outcome. The system by which these results are thought to be attained pursues the following method. It divides Theology into Natural and Revealed. Nat- ural Theology expounds the theological beliefs which may be arrived at by a consideration of the general course of Nature as this is explained to us by Science. It dwells principally upon the number- less examples of adaptation in the organic world, which apparently display the most marvellous indi- cations of ingenious contrivance, and the nicest ad- justment of means to ends. From facts like these it is inferred that Nature has an intelligent and a powerful Creator. From the further fact that these adjustments and contrivances arc in a large number of cases designed for the interests of beings capable of pleasure and pain, it is inferred that the Creator is not only intelligent and powerful, but also benevo- lent ; and the inquiring mind is then supposed to be sufficiently prepared to consider without prejudice the evidence for there having been a special Revela- tion by which further truths may have been im- parted, not otherwise accessible to our unassisted powers of speculation. 1 84 RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY The evidences of Revealed Religion are not drawn, like those of Natural Religion, from general laws and widely disseminated particulars ; but they profess none the less to be solely based upon facts which, according to the classification I have adhered to throughout these Notes, belong to the scientific order. According to this theory, the logical bur- den of the entire theological structure is thrown upon the evidence for certain events which took place long ago, and principally in a small district to the east of the Mediterranean, the occurrence of which is sought to be proved by the ordinary methods of historical investigation, and by these alone — unless, indeed, we are to regard as an im- portant ally the aforementioned presumption sup- plied by Natural Theology. It is true, of course, that the immediate reason for accepting the beliefs of Revealed Religion is that the religion is revealed. But it is thought to be revealed because it was pro- mulgated by teachers who were inspired ; the teach- ers are thought to have been inspired because they worked miracles; and they are thought to have worked miracles because there is historical evidence of the fact, which it is supposed would be more than sufficient to produce conviction in any unbiassed mind. Now it must be conceded that if this general train of reasoning be assumed to cover the whole ground of ' Christian Evidences,' then, whether it be conclusive or inconclusive, it does at least attain RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY 1 85 the desideratum of connecting Science on the one hand, Religion— ' Natural' and 'Revealed' — on the other, into one single scheme of interconnected prop- ositions. But it attains it by making Theology in form a mere annex or appendix to Science ; a mere footnote to history ; a series of conclusions inferred from data which have been arrived at by precise- ly the same methods as those which enable us to pronounce upon the probability of any other events in the past history of man, or of the world in which he lives. We are no longer dealing with a creed whose real premises lie deep in the nature of things. It is no question of metaphysical specula- tion, moral intuition, or mystical ecstasy with which we are concerned. We are asked to believe the Universe to have been designed by a Deity for the same sort of reason that we believe Canterbury Cathedral to have been designed by an architect ; and to believe in the events narrated in the Gospels for the same sort of reason that we believe in the murder of Thomas a Becket. Now I am not concerned to maintain that these arguments are bad ; on the contrary, my personal opinion is that, as far as they go, they are good. The argument, or perhaps I should say an argu- ment, from design, in some shape or other, will al- ways have value ; while the argument from history must always form a part of the evidence for an}^ historical religion. The first will, in my opinion, survive any inferences from the doctrine of natural 1 86 RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY selection ; the second will survive the consequences of critical assaults. But more than this is desirable; more than this is, indeed, necessary. For however good arguments of this sort are, or may be made, they are not equal by themselves to the task of up- setting so massive an obstacle as developed Natur- alism. They have not, as it were, sufficient intrinsic energy to effect so great a change. They may not be ill directed, but they lack momentum. They may not be technically defective, but they are assuredly practically inadequate. To many this may appear self-evident. Those who doubt it will, I think, be convinced of its truth if they put themselves for a moment in the position of a man trained on the strictest principles of Natu- ralism ; acquainted with the general methods and results of Science ; cognisant of the general course of secular human history, and of the means by which the critic and the scholar have endeavoured to extort the truth from the records of the past. To such a man the growth and decay of great religions, the legends of wonders worked and suffering en- dured by holy men in many ages and in different countries, are familiar facts— to be fitted somehow into his general scheme of knowledge. They are phenomena to be explained by anthropology and sociology, instructive examples of the operation of natural law at a particular stage of human develop- ment — this, and nothing more. Now present to one whose mind has been so RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY 1 8/ prepared and disciplined, first this account of Natu- ral Religion, and then this version of the evidences for Revelation. So far as Natural Religion is con- cerned he will probably content himself with say- ing, that to argue from the universality of causation within the world to the necessity of First Cause outside the world is a process of very doubtful va- lidity : that to argue from the character of the world to the benevolence of its Author is a process more doubtful still : but that, in anv case, we need not disturb ourselves about matters we so little understand, inasmuch as the Deity thus inferred, if He really exists, completed the only task which Natural Religion supposes Him to have undertaken when, in a past immeasurably remote, he set going the machinery of causes and effects, which has ever since been in undisturbed operation, and about which alone we have any real sources of information. Supposing, however, you have induced your Naturalistic philosopher to accept, if only for the sake of argument, this version of Natural Religion, what will he say to your method of extracting the proofs of Revealed Religion from the Gospel his- tory? Explain to him that there is good historic evidence of the usual sort for believing that for one brief interval during the history of the Universe, and in one small corner of this planet, the continu- ous chain of universal causation has been broken ; that in an insignificant country inhabited by an un- important branch of the Semitic peoples events are 1 88 RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY alleged to have taken place which, if they really occurred, at once turn into foolishness the whole theory in the light of which he has been accus- tomed to interpret human experience, and convey to us knowledge which no mere contemplation of the general order of Nature could enable us even dimly to anticipate. What would be his reply? His reply would be, nay, is (for our imaginary in- terlocutor has unnumbered prototypes in the world about us), that questions like these can scarcely be settled by the mere accumulation of historic proofs. Granting all that was asked, and more, perhaps, than ought to be conceded ; granting that the evi- dences for these wonders was far stronger than any that could be produced in favour of the apocryphal miracles which crowd the annals of every people ; granting even that the evidence seemed far more than sufficient to establish any incident, however strange, which does not run counter to the rec- ognised course of Nature ; what then ? We were face to face with a difficulty, no doubt ; but the in- terpretation of the past was necessarily full of dif- ficulties. Conflicts of testimony with antecedent probability, conflicts of different testimonies with each other, were the familiar perplexities of the historic inquirer. In thousands of cases no abso- lutely satisfactory solution could be arrived at. Possibly the Gospel histories were among these. Neither the theory of myths, nor the theory of contemporary fraud, nor the theory of late inven- RATIONALIST ORTHODOXY 1 89 tion, nor any other which the ingenuit}' of critics could devise, might provide a perfect!}' clean-cut explanation of the phenomena. But at least it might be said with confidence that no explanation could be less satisfactory than one which required us, on the strength of three or four ancient docu- ments — at the best written by eye-witnesses of little education and no scientific knowledge, at the worst spurious and of no authority — to remodel and revo- lutionise every principle which governs us with an unquestioned jurisdiction in our judgments on the Universe at large. Thus, slightly modifying Hume, might the dis- ciple of Naturalism reply. And as against the rationalising theologian, is not his answer conclu- sive ? The former has borrowed the premises, the methods, and all the positive conclusions of Nat- uralism. He advances on the same strategic prin- ciples, and from the same base of operations. And though he professes by these means to have over- run a whole continent of alien conclusions with which Naturalism will have nothing to do, can he permanently retain it? Is it not certain that the huge expanse of his theology, attached by so slen- der a tie to the main system of which it is intended to be a dependency, will sooner or later have to be abandoned ; and that the weak and artificial con- nection which has been so ingeniously contrived will snap at the first strain to which it shall be sub- jected by the forces either of criticism or sentiment ? PART III SOME CAUSES OF BELIEF CHAPTER I CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE So far the results at which we have arrived may be not unfairly described as purely negative. In the first part of these Notes I endeavoured to show that Naturalism was practically insufficient. In the first chapter of Part II. I indicated the view that it was speculatively incoherent. The obvious conclusion was therefore drawn, that under these circumstances it was in the highest degree absurd to employ with an unthinking rigour the canon of consistency as if Rationalism, which is Naturalism in embryo, or Naturalism, which is Rationalism developed, placed us in the secure possession of some unerring standard of truth to which all our beliefs must be made to conform. A brief criticism of one theolog- ical scheme, by which it has been sought to avoid the narrownesses of Naturalism without break- ing with Rationalising methods, confirmed the con- clusion that any such procedure is predestined to be ineffectual, and that no mere inferences of the ordinary pattern, based upon ordinar}^ experience, will enable us to break out of the Naturalistic prison-house. 13 194 CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE But if Naturalism by itself be practically insuf- ficient, if no conclusion based on its affirmations will enable us to escape from the cold grasp of its nega- tions, and if, as I think, the contrasted system of Idealism has not as yet got us out of the difificulty, what remedy remains? One such remedy consists in simply setting up side by side with the creed of natural science another and supplementary set of beliefs, which may minister to needs and aspirations which science cannot meet, and may speak amid silences which science is powerless to break. The natural world and the spiritual world, the world which is immediately subject to causation and the world which is immediately subject to God, are, on this view, each of them real, and each of them the objects of real knowledge. But the laws of the natural world are revealed to us by the discoveries of science ; while the laws of the spiritual world are revealed to us through the authority of spiritual intuitions, inspired witnesses, or divinely guided institutions. And the two regions of knowledge lie side by side, contiguous but not connected, like em- pires of different race and language, which own no common jurisdiction nor hold any intercourse with each other, except along a disputed and wavering frontier where no superior power exists to settle their quarrels or determine their respective limits. To thousands of persons this patchwork scheme of belief, though it may be in a form less sharply defined, has, in substance, commended itself; and if CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE 195 and in so far as it really meets their needs I have nothing to say against it, and can hold out small hope of bettering it. It is much more satisfactory as regards its content than Naturalism ; it is not much less philosophical as regards its method ; and it has the practical merit of supplying a rough- and-ready expedient for avoiding the consequences which follow from a premature endeavour to force the general body of belief into the rigid limits of one too narrow system. It has, however, obvious inconveniences. There are many persons, and they are increasing in num- ber, who find it difficult or impossible to acquiesce in this unconsidered division of the * Whole ' of knowledge into two or more unconnected frag- ments. Naturalism may be practically unsatisfac- tory. But at least the positive teaching of Natural- ism has secured general assent ; and it shocks their philosophic instinct for unity to be asked to patch and plaster this accepted creed with a number of heterogeneous propositions drawn from an entirely different source, and on behalf of which no such common agreement can be claimed. What such persons ask for, and rightly, is a philosophy, a scheme of knowledge, which shall give rational unity to an adequate creed. But, as the reader knows, I have it not to give ; nor does it even seem to me that we have any right to Hatter ourselves that wc arc on the verge of discovering some all-reconciling tlicoiy by which each inevitable 196 CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE claim of our complex nature may be harmonised under the supremacy of Reason. Unity, then, if it is to be attained at all, must be sought for, so to speak, at some lower speculative level. We must either pursue the Rationalising and Naturalistic method already criticised, and compel the desired unification of belief by the summary rejection of everything which does not fit into some convenient niche in the scheme of things developed by em- pirical methods out of sense-perception ; or if, either for the reasons given in the earlier chapters of these Notes, or for others, we reject this method, we must turn for assistance towards a new quarter, and apply ourselves to the problem by the aid of some more comprehensive, or at least more manageable, prin- ciple. II To this end let us temporarily divest ourselves of all philosophic preoccupation. Provisionally re- stricting ourselves to the scientific point of view, let us forbear to consider beliefs from the side of proof, and let us survey them for a season from the side of origin only, and in their relation to the causes which gave them birth. Thus considered they are, of course, mere products of natural con- ditions; psychological growths comparable to the flora and fauna of continents or oceans ; objects of which we may say that they are useful or harmful, plentiful or rare, but not, except parenthetically and CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE I97 with a certain irrelevance, that they are true or untrue. How, then, would these beliefs appear to an in- vestigator from another planet who, applying the ordinary methods of science, and in a spirit of de- tached curiosity, should survey them from the out- side, with no other object than to discover the place they occupied in the natural history of the earth and its inhabitants? He would note, I suppose, to begin with, that the vast majority of these beliefs were the short-lived offspring of sense-perception, instinctive judgments on observed matter-of-fact. * The sun is shining,' * there is somebody in the room,' ' I feel tired,' would be examples of this class ; whose members, from the nature of the case, refer imme- diately only to the passing moment, and die as soon as they are born. If now our investigator turned his attention to the causes of these beliefs of perception, he would, of course, discover, in the first place, that, when normal, they were invariably due to the action of external objects upon the organism, and more par- ticularly upon the nervous system, of the percipient; and in the second place, that though these beliefs were thus all due to a certain kind of neural change, the converse of the proposition is by no means true, since, taking the organic world at large, it was by no means the case that neural changes of this kind invariably, or even usually, issued in beliefs of per- ception, or, indeed, in any psychical result whatever. For consider how the case must present itself to 198 CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE our supposed observer. He would see a series of or- ganisms possessed of nervous systems ranging from the most rudimentary type to the most complex. He would observe that the action of the exterior world upon those systems varied, in like manner, from the simple irritation of the nerve-tissue to the multitudinous correspondences and adjustments in- volved in some act of vision by man or one of the higher mammals. And he would conclude, and rightly, that between the upper and the lower mem- bers of the scale there were differences of degree, but not of kind ; and that existing gaps might be conceived as so filled in that each type might melt into the one immediately below it by insensible gra- dations. If, however, he endeavoured to draw up a scale of psychical effects whose degrees should correspond with this scale of physiological causes, two results would make themselves apparent. The first is, that the lower part of the psychical scale would be a blank, because in the case of the simple organisms nervous changes carried with them no mental consequents. The second is, that even when mental consequents do appear, they form no continuous series like their physiological antecedents ; but, on the contrary, those at the top of the scale are found to differ in something more than degree from those which appear lower down. We do not, for example, suppose that protozoa can properly be said to feel, nor that every animal which feels can properly be said to form CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE 199 judgments or to possess immediate beliefs of percep- tion. One conclusion our observer would, I suppose, draw from facts like these is, that while neural sen- sibility to external influences is a widespread bene- fit to organic Nature, the feelings, and still more the beliefs, to which in certain cases it gives rise are relatively insignificant phenomena, useful supple- ments to the purely physiological apparatus, neces- sary, perhaps, to its highest developments, but still, if operative at all,^ rather in the nature of final im- provements to the machinery than of parts essential to its working. A like result would attend his study of the next class of beliefs that might fall under his notice, those, namely, which, though the}^ do not relate to things or events within the field of perception, like those we have just been considering, are yet not less immediate in their character. Memories of the past are examples of this type ; I should be in- clined to add, though I do not propose here to justify my opinion, certain instinctive and, so to speak, automatic expectations about the future or that part of the present which does not come with- in the reach of direct experience. Like the beliefs of perception of which we have been speaking, they would seem to be the psychical side of neu- ral changes which, at least in their simpler forms, need be accompanied by no psychical manifestation. ' See Note on Chapter V., page 312. 200 CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE Physiological co-ordination is sufficient by itself to perform services for the lower animals similar in kind to those which, in the case of man, are use- fully, or even necessarily, supplemented by their beliefs of memory and of expectation. These two classes of belief, relating respectively to the present and the absent, cover the whole ground of what is commonly called experience, and. something more. They include, therefore, at least in rudimentary form, all particulars which, on any theory, are required for scientific induction; and, according to empiricism in its older forms, they supply not this only, but also the whole of the raw material, without any exception, out of which reason must subsequently fashion whatever stock of additional beliefs it is needful for mankind to entertain. Our Imaginary Observer, however, quite indif- ferent to mundane theories as to what ought to produce conviction, and intent only on discovering how convictions are actually produced, would soon find out that there were other influences besides reasoning required to supplement the relatively simple physiological and psychological causes which originate the immediate beliefs of perception, memory, and expectation. These immediate be- liefs belong to man as an individual. They involve no commerce between mind and mind. They might equally exist, and would equally be necessary, if each man stood face to face with material Nature CAUSES OF EXPERIENCE 201 in friendless isolation. But they neither provide, nor by any merely logical extension can be made to provide, the apparatus of beliefs which we find act- ually connected with the higher scientific social and spiritual life of the race. These also are, without doubt, the product of antecedent causes — causes many in number and most diverse in character. They presuppose, to begin with, the beliefs of per- ception, memory, and expectation in their element- ary shape; and they also imply the existence of an organism fitted for their hospitable reception by ages of ancestral preparation. But these condi- tions, though necessary, are clearly not enough ; the appropriate environment has also to be pro- vided. And though I shall not attempt to analyse with the least approach to completeness the ele- ments of which that environment consists, yet it contains one group of causes so important in their collective operation, and yet in popular discourse so often misrepresented, that a detailed notice of it seems desirable. CHAPTER II AUTHORITY AND REASON This group is perhaps best described by the term Authority, a word which by a sharp transition transports us at once into a stormier tract of specu- lation than we have been traversing in the last few pages, though, as my readers may be disposed to think, for that reason, perhaps, among others, a tract more nearly adjacent to theology and the proper subject-matter of these Notes, However this may be, it is, I am afraid, the fact that the dis- cussion on which I am about to enter must bring us face to face with one problem, at least, of which, so far as I am aware, no entirely satisfactory solu- tion has yet been reached ; which certainly I can- not pretend to solve; which can, therefore, for the present only be treated in a manner provisional, and therefore unsatisfactory. Nor are these peren- nial and inherent difficulties the only obstacles we have to contend with. For the subject is, unfort- unately, one familiar to discussion, and, like all topics which have been the occasion of passionate debate, it is one where party watchwords have AUTHORITY AND REASON 203 exercised their perturbing and embittering influ- ence. It would be, perhaps, an exaggeration to assert that the theor}' of authority has been for three cen- turies the main battlefield whereon have met the opposing forces of new thoughts and old. But if so, it is only because, at this point at least, victory is commonly supposed long ago to have declared itself decisively in favour of the new. The very statement that the rival and opponent of authority is reason ^ seems to most persons equivalent to a declaration that the latter must be in the right, and the former in the wrong ; while popular discussion and specula- tion have driven deep the general opinion that au- thority serves no other purpose in the economy of Nature than to supply a refuge for all that is most bigoted and absurd. The current theory by which these views are sup- ported appears to be something of this kind. Every- one has a ' right ' to adopt any opinions he pleases. It is his ' duty,' before exercising this ' right,' criti- cally to sift the reasons by which such opinions may be supported, and so to adjust the degree of his con- victions that they shall accurately correspond with the evidences adduced in their favour. Authority, therefore, has no place among the legitimate causes of belief. If it appears among them, it is as an in- ' It is, perhaps, hardly necessary to note that throughout this chapter I use Reason in its ordinary and popular, not in its tran- scendental, sense. There is no question here of the Logos or Ab- solute Reason. 204 AUTHORITY AND REASON truder, to be jealously hunted down and mercilessly expelled. Reason, and reason only, can be safely permitted to mould the convictions of mankind. By its inward counsels alone should beings who boast that they are rational submit to be controlled. Sentiments like these are among the common- places of political and social philosophy. Yet, looked at scientifically, they seem to me to be, not merely erroneous, but absurd. Suppose for a moment a com- munity of which each member should deliberately set himself to the task of throwing off so far as pos- sible all prejudices due to education ; where each should consider it his duty critically to examine the grounds whereon rest every positive enactment and every moral precept which he has been accustomed to obey ; to dissect all the great loyalties which make social life possible, and all the minor conventions which help to make it easy ; and to weigh out with scrupulous precision the exact degree of assent which in each particular case the results of this proc- ess might seem to justify. To say that such a com- munity, if it acted upon the opinions thus arrived at, would stand but a poor chance in the struggle for existence is to say far too little. It could never even begin to be ; and if by a miracle it was created, it would without doubt immediately resolve itself into its constituent elements. For consider by way of illustration the case of Morality. If the right and the duty of private judgment be universal, it must be both the privilege AUTHORITY AND REASON 20$ and the business of every man to subject the maxims of current morality to a critical examination ; and unless the examination is to be a farce, every man should bring to it a mind as little warped as pos- sible by habit and education, or the unconscious bias of foregone conclusions. Picture, then, the condi- tion of a society in which the successive generations would thus in turn devote their energies to an im- partial criticism of the 'traditional' view. What qualifications, natural or acquired, for such a task we are to attribute to the members of this emanci- pated community I know not. But let us put them at the highest. Let us suppose that every man and woman, or rather every boy and girl (for ought Reason to be ousted from her rights in persons under twenty-one years of age?), is endowed with the aptitude and training required to deal with problems like these. Arm them with the most re- cent methods of criticism, and set them down to the task of estimating with open minds the claims which charity, temperance and honesty, murder, theft and adultery respectively have upon the approval or disapproval of mankind. What the result of such an experiment would be, what wild chaos of opin- ions would result from this fiat of the Uncreating Word, 1 know not. But it might well happen that even before our youthful critics got so far as a re- arrangement of the Ten Commandments, they might find themselves entangled in the preliminary ques- tion whether judgments conveying moral approba- 206 AUTHORITY AND REASON tion and disapprobation were of a kind which rea- sonable beings should be asked to entertain at all ; whether ' right ' and ' wrong ' were words repre- senting anything more permanent and important than certain likes and dislikes which happen to be rather widely disseminated, and more or less arbi- trarily associated with social and legal sanctions. I conceive it to be highly probable that the con- clusions at which on this point they would arrive would be of a purely negative character. The ethi- cal systems competing for acceptance would by their very numbers and variety suggest suspicions as to their character and origin. Here, would our students explain, is a clear presumption to be found on the very face of these moralisings that they were contrived, not in the interests of truth, but in the in- terests of traditional dogma. How else explain the fact, that while there is no great difference of opin- ion as to what things are right or wrong, there is no semblance of agreement as to why they are right or why they are wrong. All authorities concur, for instance, in holding that it is wrong to commit mur- der. But one philosopher tells us that it is wrong because it is inconsistent with the happiness of man- kind, and that to do anything inconsistent with the happiness of mankind is wrong. Another tells us that it is contrary to the dictates of conscience, and that everything which is contrary to the dictates of conscience is wrong. A third tells us that it is against the commandments of God, and that every- AUTHORITY AND REASON 20/ thinsr which is ag-ainst the commandments of God is wrong. A fourth tells me that it leads to the gal- lows, and that, inasmuch as being hanged involves a sensible diminution of personal happiness, creat- ures who, like man, are by nature incapable of doinof otherwise than seek to increase the sum of their personal pleasures and diminish the sum of their personal pains cannot, if they really compre- hend the situation, do anything which may bring their existence to so distressing a termination. Now whence, it would be asked, this curious mixt- ure of agreement and disagreement ? How account for the strange variety exhibited in the premises of these various systems, and the not less strange uni- formity exhibited in their conclusions? Why does not as great a divergence manifest itself in the results arrived at as we undoubtedly find in the methods employed ? How comes it that all these explorers reach the same goal, when their points of departure are so widely dispersed ? Plainly but one plausible method of solving the difficulty exists. The conclusions were in every case determined be- fore the argument began, the goal was in every case settled before the travellers set out. There is here no surrender of belief to the inward guidance of un- fettered reason. Rather is reason coerced to a fore- ordained issue by the external operation of prejudice and education, or by the rougher machinery of social ostracism and legal penalty. The framcrs of ethical systems are either philosopiiers who are unable to 2o8 AUTHORITY AND REASON free themselves from the unfelt bondage of custom- ary opinion, or advocates who find it safer to exer- cise their liberty of speculation in respect to pre- mises about which nobody cares, than in respect to conclusions which might bring them into conflict with the police. So might we imagine the members of our emanci- pated community discussing the principles on which morality is founded. But, in truth, it were a vain task to try and work out in further detail the results of an experiment which, human nature being what it is, can never be seriously attempted. That it can never be seriously attempted is not, be it observed, because it is of so dangerous a character that the community in its wisdom would refuse to embark upon it. This would be a frail protection indeed. Not the danger of the adventure, but its impossi- bility, is our security. To reject all convictions which are not the products of free speculative in- vestigation is, fortunately, an exercise of which hu- manity is in the strictest sense incapable. Some societies and some individuals may show more incli- nation to indulge in it than others. But in no con- dition of society and in no individual will the incli- nation be more than very partially satisfied. Always and everywhere our Imaginary Observer, contem- plating from some external coign of vantage the course of human history, would note the immense, the inevitable, and on the whole the beneficent, part which Authority plays in the production of belief. AUTHORITY AND REASON 209 II This truth finds expression, and at first sight we might feel inclined to say recognition also, in such familiar commonplaces as that every man is the ' product of the society in which he lives,' and that ' it is vain to expect him to rise much above the level of his age.' But aphorisms like these, however use- ful as aids to a correct historical perspective, do not, as ordinarily employed, show any real apprehension of the verity on which I desire to insist. They be- long to a theory which regards these social influ- ences as clogs and hindrances, hampering the free movements of those who might under happier cir- cumstances have struggled successfully towards the truth ; or as perturbing forces which drive mankind from the even orbit marked out for it by reason. Reason, according to this view, is a kind of Ormuzd doing constant battle against the Ahriman of tradi- tion and authority. Its gradual triumph over the opposing powers of darkness is what we mean by Progress. Everything which shall hasten the hour of that triumph is a gain ; and if by some magic stroke we could extirpate, as it were in a moment, every cause of belief which was not also a reason, we should, it appears, be the fortunate authors of a reform in the moral world only to be paralleled by the abolition of pain and disease in the physical. 1 have already indicated some of the grounds which 2IO AUTHORITY AND REASON induce me to form a very different estimate of the part which reason plays in human affairs. Our an- cestors, whose errors we paUiate on account of their environment with a feeling of satisfaction, due partly to our keen appreciation of our own happier position and greater breadth of view, were not to be pitied because they reasoned little and believed much ; nor should we necessarily have any particular cause for self-g:ratulation if it were true that we reasoned more and, it may be, believed less. Not thus has the world been fashioned. But, nevertheless, this identification of reason with all that is good among the causes of belief, and authority with all that is bad, is a delusion so gross and yet so prevalent that a moment's examination into the exaggerations and confusions which lie at the root of it may not be thrown away. The first of these confusions may be dismissed almost in a sentence. It arises out of the tacit as- sumption that reason means right reason. Such an assumption, it need hardly be said, begs half the point at issue. Reason, for purposes of this discus- sion, can no more be made to mean right reason than authority can be made to mean legitimate authority. True, we might accept the first of these definitions, and yet deny that all right belief was the fruit of reason. But we could hardly deny the converse proposition, that reason thus defined must always issue in rig-ht belief. Nor need we be concerned to deny a statement at once so obvious and so barren. AUTHORITY AND REASON 211 The source of error which has next to be noted presents points of much greater interest. Though it be true, as I am contending, that the importance of reason among the causes which produce and main- tain the behefs, customs, and ideals which form the groundwork of Hfe has been much exaggerated, there can yet be no doubt that reason is, or appears to be, the cause over which we have the most direct control, or rather the one which we most readily identify with our own free and personal action. We are acted on by authority. It moulds our ways of thought in spite of ourselves, and usually unknown to ourselves. But when we reason we are the au- thors of the effect produced. We have ourselves set the machine in motion. For its proper working we are ourselves immediately responsible ; so that it is both natural and desirable that we should concen- trate our attention on this particular class of causes, even though we should thus be led unduly to magnify their importance in the general scheme of things. I have somewhere seen it stated that the steam- engine in its primitive form required a boy to work the valve by which steam was admitted to the cylinder. It was his business at the proper period of each stroke to perform this necessary operation by pulling a string ; and though the same object has long since been attained by mechanical methods far simj)ler and more trustworthy, yet I have little doubt that until the advent of that revolutionary 212 AUTHORITY AND REASON youth who so tied the string to one of the moving parts of the engine that his personal supervision was no longer necessary, the boy in office greatly magni- fied his functions, and regarded himself with par- donable pride as the most important, because the only rational, link in the chain of causes and effects by which the energy developed in the furnace was ultimately converted into the motion of the fly- wheel. So do we stand as reasoning beings in the presence of the complex processes, physiological and psychical, out of which are manufactured the convictions necessary to the conduct of life. To the results attained by their co-operation reason makes its slender contribution ; but in order that it may do so effectively, it is beneficently decreed that, pend- ing the evolution of some better device, reason should appear to the reasoner the most admirable and important contrivance in the whole mechanism. The manner in which attention and interest are thus unduly directed towards the operations, vital and social, which are under our direct control, rather than those which we are unable to modify, or can only modify by a very indirect and circuitous procedure, may be illustrated by countless exam- ples. Take one from physiology. Of all the com- plex causes which co-operate for the healthy nour- ishment of the body, no doubt the conscious choice of the most wholesome rather than the less whole- some forms of ordinary food is far from being the most unimportant. Yet, as it is within our immedi- AUTHORITY AND REASON 213 ate competence, we attend to it, moralise about it. and generally make much of it. But no man can by taking thought directly regulate his digestive secre- tions. We never, therefore, think of them at all until they go wrong, and then, unfortunately, to very little purpose. So it is with the body politic. A certain proportion (probably a small one) of the changes and adaptations required by altered sur- roundings can only be effected through the solvent action of criticism and discussion. How such dis- cussion shall be conducted, what are the arguments on either side, how a decision shall be arrived at, and how it shall be carried out, are matters which we seem able to regulate by conscious effort and the deliberate adaptation of means to ends. We thei*e- fore unduly magnify the part they play in the fur- therance of our interests. We perceive that they supply business to the practical politician, raw ma- terial to the political theorist ; and we forget amid the buzzing of debate the multitude of incom- parably more important processes, by whose unde- signed co-operation alone the life and growth of the State is rendered possible. Ill There is, however, a third source of illusion, which well deserves the attentive study of those who, like our Imaginary Observer, are interested in the purely external and scientific investigation of 214 AUTHORITY AND REASON the causes which produce belief. I have already in this chapter made reference to the * spirit of the age ' as one form in which authority most potently manifests itself ; and undoubtedly it is so. Dog- matic education in early years may do much.* The immediate pressure of domestic, social, scientific, ecclesiastical surroundings in the direction of spe- cific beliefs may do even more. But the power of authority is never more subtle and effective than when it produces a psychological * atmosphere ' or ' climate ' favourable to the life of certain modes of belief, unfavourable, and even fatal, to the life of others. Such 'climates ' may be widely diffused, or the reverse. Their range may cover a generation, an epoch, a whole civilisation, or it may be nar- rowed down to a sect, a family, even an individual. And as they may vary infinitely in respect to the extent of their influence, so also they may vary in respect to its intensity and quality. But whatever be their limits and whatever their character, their importance to the conduct of life, social and individ- ual, cannot easily be overstated. Consider, for instance, their effect on great classes of belief with which reasoning, were it only on account of their mass, is quite incompetent to deal. If all credible propositions, all propositions which somebody at some time had been able to be- lieve, were only to be rejected after their claims had ' I may again remind the reader that the word dogmatic as used in these Notes has no special theological reference. AUTHORITY AND REASON 21 5 been impartially tested by a strictly loc^ical inves- tigation, the intellectual machine would be over- burdened, and its movements hopelessly choked by mere excess of material. Even such products as it could turn out would, as I conjecture (for the ex- periment has never been tried), prove but a mot- ley collection, so diverse in design, so incongruous and ill-assorted, that they could scarcely contribute the fitting furniture of a well-ordered mind. What actually happens in the vast majority of cases is something very different. To begin with, external circumstances, mere conditions of time and place, limit the number of opinions about which anything is known, and on which, therefore, it is (so to speak) materially possible that reason can be called upon to pronounce a judgment. But there are internal limitations not less universal and not less necessary. Few indeed are the beliefs, even among those which come under his observation, which any individual for a moment thinks himself called upon seriously to consider with a view to their possible adoption. The residue he summarily disposes of, rejects with- out a hearing, or, rather, treats as if they had not even that privid facie claim to be adjudicated on which formal rejection seems to imply. Now, can this process be described as a rational one ? That it is not the immediate result of reason- ing is, 1 think, evident enough. All would admit, for example, that when the mind is closed against the reception of any truth by ' bigotry ' or * inveterate 2l6 AUTHORITY AND REASON prejudice,' the effectual cause of the victory of error is not so much bad reasoning as something which, in its essential nature, is not reasoning at all. But there is really no ground for drawing a distinction as regards their mode of operation between the ' psychological climates ' which we happen to like and those of which we happen to disapprove. However various their character, all, I take it, work out their results very much in the same kind of way. For good or for evil, in ancient times and in modern, among savage folk and among civilised, it is ever by an identic process that they have sifted and selected the candidates for credence, on which reason has been afterwards called upon to pass judgment ; and that process is one with which ratiocination has little or nothing directly to do. But though these ' psychological climates ' do not work through reasoning, may they not themselves, in many cases, be the products of reasoning? May they not, therefore, be causes of belief which belong, though it be only at the second remove, to the domain of reason rather than that of authority ? To the first of these questions the answer must doubtless be in the affirmative. Reasoning has unquestionably a great deal to do with the production of psychological climates. As ' climates ' are among the causes which produce beliefs, so are beliefs among the causes which produce ' climates,' and all reasoning, therefore, which culminates in belief may be, and indeed must be, at least indirectly concerned in the effects which AUTHORITY AND REASON 21/ belief develops. But are these results rational ? Do they follow, I mean, on reason qua reason ; or are they, like a schoolboy's tears over a proposition of Euclid, consequences of reasoning, but not conclu- sions from it ? In order to answer this question it may be worth while to consider it in the light of an example which I have already used in another connection and under a different aspect. It will be recollected that in a preceding chapter I considered Rationalism, not as a psychological climate, a well-characterised mood of mind, but as an explicit principle of judgment, in which the rationalising temper may for purposes of argument find definite expression. To Rationalism in the first of these senses — to Rationalism, in other words, considered as a form of Authority — I now revert ; taking it as an instance specially suited to our purpose, not only because its meaning is well understood, but because it is found at our own level of intellectual development, and we can therefore study its origin and character with a kind of insight quite impossible when we are dealing with the ' climates ' which govern in so singular a fashion the beliefs of primitive races. These, too, may be, and .1 suppose are, to some extent, the products of reason- ing. But the reasoning appears to us as arbitrary as the resulting 'climates' are repugnant; and though we can note and classify the facts, we can hardly comprehend them with sympathetic under- standing. 2l8 AUTHORITY AND REASON With Rationalism it is different. How the dis- coveries of science, the growth of criticism, and the diffusion of learning should have fostered the ration- alising temper seems intelligible to all, because all, in their different degrees, have been subject to these very influences. Not everyone is a rationalist ; but everyone, educated or uneducated, is prepared to reject without further examination certain kinds of statement which, before the rationalising era set in, would have been accepted without difficulty by the wisest among mankind. Now this modern mood, whether in its qualified or unqualified {i.e. naturalistic) form, is plainly no mere product of non-rational conditions, as the enu- meration I have just given of its most conspicuous causes is sufficient to prove. Natural science and historical criticism have not been built up without a vast expenditure of reasoning, and (though for present purposes this is immaterial) very good reasoning, too. But are Ave on that account to say that the results of the rationalising temper are the work of reason ? Surely not. The rationalist rejects miracles ; and if you force him to a discussion, he may no doubt produce from the ample stores of past controversy plenty of argument in support of his belief. But do not therefore assume that his belief is the result of his argument. The odds are strongly in favour of argument and belief having both grown up undor the fostering influence of his ' psychological climate.' For observe that precisely in the way in which he AUTHORITY AND REASON 219 rejects miracles he also rejects witchcraft. Here there has been no controversy worth mentioning. The general belief in witchcraft has died a natural death, and it has not been worth anybody's while to devise arguments against it. Perhaps there are none. But, whether there be or not, no logical axe was re- quired to cut down a plant which had not the least chance of flourishing in a mental atmosphere so rig- orous and uncongenial as that of rationalism ; and accordingly no logical axe has been provided. The belief in mesmerism, however, supplies in some ways a more instructive case than the belief either in miracles or witchcraft. Like these, it found in rationalism a hostile influence. But, unlike these, it could call in almost at will the assistance of what would now be regarded as ocular demon- stration. For two generations, however, this was found insufficient. For two generations the rational- istic bias proved sufficiently strong to pervert the judgment of the most distinguished observers, and to incapacitate them from accepting what under more favourable circumstances they would have called the ' plain evidence of their senses.' So that we are here presented with the curious spectacle of an intellectual mood or temper, whose origin was largely due to the growth of the experimental sciences, making it impossible for those affected to draw the simplest inference, even from the most conclusive experiments. This is an interesting case of the conflict be- 220 AUTHORITY AND REASON tween authority and reason, because it illustrates the general truth for which I have been contending, with an emphasis that would be impossible if we took as our example some worn-out vesture of thought, threadbare from use, and strange to eyes accustomed to newer fashions. Rationalism, in its turn, may be predestined to suffer a like decay ; but in the meanwhile it forcibly exemplifies the part played by authority in the formation of behefs. If rationalism be regarded as a non-rational effect of reason and a non-rational cause of belief, the same admission will readily be made about all other in- tellectual climates; and that rationalism should be so regarded is now, I trust, plain to the reader. The only results which reason can claim as hers by an exclusive title are of the nature of logical conclusions ; and rationalism is not a logical conclu- sion, but an intellectual temper. The only instru- ments which reason, as such, can employ are argu- ments ; and rationalism is not an argument, but an impulse towards belief, or disbelief. So that, though rationalism, like other ' psychological cli- mates,' is doubtless due, among other causes, to reason, it is not on that account a rational product ; and though in its turn it produces beliefs, it is not on that account a rational cause. AUTHORITY AND REASON 221 IV The most important source of error on this sub- ject remains, however, to be dealt with ; and it arises directly out of that jurisdiction which in matters of belief we can hardly do otherwise than recognise as belonging to Reason by a natural and indefeasible title. No one finds (if my observations in this matter are correct) any serious difficulty in attributing the origin of other people's beliefs, es- pecially if he disagree with them, to causes which are not reasons. That interior assent should be produced in countless cases by custom, education, public opinion, the contagious convictions of coun- trymen, family, party, or Church, seems natural, and even obvious. That but a small number, at least of the most important and fundamental beliefs, are held by persons who could give reasons for them, and that of this small number only an in- considerable fraction are held in consequence of the reasons by which they are nominally supported, may perhaps be admitted with no very great diffi- culty. But it is harder to recognise that this law is not merely, on the whole, beneficial, but that with- out it the business of the world could not possibly be carried on; nor do we allow, without reluctance and a sense of shortcoming, that in our own persons we supply illustrations of its operation quite as strik- ing as any presented to us by the rest of the world. 222 AUTHORITY AND REASON Now this reluctance is not the result of vanity, nor of any fancied immunity from weaknesses com- mon to the rest of mankind. It is, rather, a direct consequence of the view we find ourselves com- pelled to take of the essential character of reason and of our relations to it. Looked at from the out- side, as one among the complex conditions which produce belief, reason appears relatively insignifi- cant and ineffectual ; not only appears so, but vmst be so, if human society is to be made possible. Looked at from the inside, it claims by an inalien- able title to be supreme. Measured by its results it may be little ; measured by its rights it is every, thing. There is no problem it may not investigate, no belief which it may not assail, no principle which it may not test. It cannot, even by its own volun- tary act, deprive itself of universal jurisdiction, as, according to a once fashionable theory, primitive man, on entering the social state, contracted himself out of his natural rights and liberties. On the con- trary, though its claims may be ignored, they can- not be repudiated ; and even those who shrink from the criticism of dogma as a sin, would probably ad- mit that they do so because it is an act forbidden by those they are bound to obey ; do so, that is to say, nominally at least, for a reason which, at any moment, if it should think fit, reason itself may re- verse. Why, under these circumstances, we are moved to regard ourselves as free intelligences, forming AUTHORITY AND REASON 223 our opinions solely in obedience to reason ; why we come to regard reason itself, not only as the sole legitimate source of belief — which, perhaps, it may be — but the sole source of legitimate beliefs — which it assuredly is not, must now, I hope, be tolerably obvious, and needs not to be further emphasised. It is more instructive for our present purpose to consider for a moment certain consequences of this antinomy between the equities of Reason and the expediencies of Authority which rise into promi- nence whenever, under the changing conditions of society, the forces of the latter are being diverted into new and unaccustomed channels. It is true, no doubt, that the full extent and diffi- culty of the problems involved have not commonly been realised by the advocates either of authority or reason, though each has usually had a sufficient sense of the strength of the other's position to in- duce him to borrow from it, even at the cost of some little inconsistency. The supporter of author- ity, for instance, may point out some of the more obvious evils by which any decrease in its influence is usually accompanied : the comminution of sects, the divisions of opinion, the weakened powers of co- operation, the increase of strife, the waste of power. Yet, so far as I am aware, no nation, party, or Church has ever courted controversial disaster by admitting that, if its claims were impartially tried at the bar of Reason, the verdict would go against it. In the same way, those who have most clamor- 224 AUTHORITY AND REASON ously upheld the prerogatives of individual reason have always been forced to recognise by their prac- tice, if not by their theory, that the right of every man to judge on every question for himself is like the right of every man who possesses a balance at his bankers to require its immediate payment in sovereigns. The right may be undoubted ; but it can only be safely enjoyed on condition that too many persons do not take it into their heads to ex- ercise it together. Perhaps, however, the most striking evidence, both of the powers of authority and the rights of reason, may be found in the fact already alluded to, that beliefs which are really the offspring of the first, when challenged, invariably claim to trace their descent from the second, al- though this improvised pedigree may be as imagi- nary as if it were the work of a college of heralds. To be sure, when this contrivance has served its purpose it is usually laid silently aside, while the belief it was intended to support remains quietly in possession, until, in the course of time, some other, and perhaps not less illusory, title has to be devised to meet the pleas of a new claimant. If the reader desires an illustration of this pro- cedure, here is one taken at random from English political history. Among the results of the move- ment which culminated in the Great Rebellion was of necessity a marked diminution in the universal- ity and efficacy of that mixture of feelings and be- liefs which, constitute loyalty to national govern- AUTHORITY AND REASON 22$ ment. Now loyalty, in some shape or other, is necessary for the stability of any form of polity. It is one of the most valuable products of authority, and, whether in any particular case conformable to reason or not, is essentially unreasoning. Its theo- retical basis therefore excites but little interest, and is of very subordinate importance so long as it con- trols the hearts of men with undisputed sway. But as soon as its supremacy is challenged, men begin to cast about anxiously for reasons why it should continue to be obeyed. Thus, to those who lived through the troubles which preceded and accompanied the Great Rebel- lion, it became suddenly apparent that it was above all things necessary to bolster up by argument the creed which authority had been found temporarily insufficient to sustain ; and of the arguments thus called into existence two, both of extraordinary ab- surdity, have become historically famous — that con- tained in Hobbes' ' Leviathan,' and that taught for a period with much vigour by the Anglican clergy under the name of Divine right. These theories may have done their work ; in any case they had their day. It was discovered that, as is the way of abstract arguments dragged in to meet a concrete difficulty, they led logically to a great many conclu- sions much less convenient than the one in whose defence they had been originally invoked. The crisis which called them forth passed gradually away. They were repugnant to the taste of a dif- 15 226 AUTHORITY AND REASON ferent age; 'Leviathan' and 'passive obedience' were handed over to the judgment of the historian. This is an example of how an ancient principle, broadly based though it be on the needs and feel- ings of human nature, may be thought now and again to require external support to enable it to meet some special stress of circumstances. But often the stress is found to be brief ; a few internal alterations meet all the necessities of the case; to a new generation the added buttresses seem useless and unsightly. They are soon demolished, to make way in due time, no doubt, for others as temporary as themselves. Nothing so quickly waxes old as apologetics, unless perhaps, it be criticism. A precisely analogous process commonly goes on in the case of new principles struggling into rec- ognition. As those of older growth are driven by the instincts of self-preservation to call reasoning to their assistance, so these claim the aid of the same ally for purposes of attack and aggression ; and the incongruity between the real causes by which these new beliefs are sustained, and the official reasons by which they are from time to time justified, is often not less glaring in the one case than in the other. Witness the ostentatious futility of the theories — 'rights of man,' and so forth — by the aid of which the modern democratic movement was nursed through its infant maladies. Now these things are true, not alone in politics, but in every field of human activity where authority AUTHORITY AND REASON 22/ and reason co-operate to serve the needs of mankind at large. And thus may we account for the singu- lar fact that in many cases conclusions are more permanent than premises, and that the successive growths of apologetic and critical literature do often not more seriously affect the enduring outline of the beliefs by which they are occasioned than the successive forests of beech and fir determine the shape of the everlasting hills from which they spring. Here, perhaps, I might fitly conclude this por- tion of my task, were it not that one particular mode in which Authority endeavours to call in reasoning to its assistance is so important in itself, and has led to so much confusion both of thought and of lan- guage, that a few paragraphs devoted to its consid- eration may help the reader to a clearer understand- ing of the general subject. Authority, as I have been using the term, is in all cases contrasted with Reason, and stands for that group of non-rational causes, moral, social and educational, which pro- duces its results by psychic processes other than reasoning. But there is a simple operation, a mere turn of phrase, by which many of these non-rational causes can, so to speak, be converted into reasons without seeming at first sight thereby to change their function as channels of Authority ; and so con- 228 AUTHORITY AND REASON venient is this method of bringing these two sources of conviction on to the same plane, so perfectly does it minister to our instinctive desire to produce a reason for every challenged belief, that it is con- stantly resorted to, without apparently any clear idea of its real import, both by those who regard themselves as upholders and those who regard themselves as opponents of Authority in matters of opinion. To say that I believe a statement because I have been taught it, or because my father believed it before me, or because everybody in the village believes it, is to announce what everyday experi- ence informs us is a quite adequate catise of belief — it is not, however, per se, to give a reason for be- lief at all. But such statements can be turned at once into reasons by no process more elaborate than that of explicitly recognising that my teachers, my family, or my neighbours, are truthful per- sons, happy in the possession of adequate means of information — propositions which in their turn, of course, require argumentative support. Such a procedure may, I need hardly say, be quite legiti- mate ; and reasons of this kind are probably the principal ground on which in mature life we ac- cept the great mass of our subordinate scientific and historical convictions. I believe, for instance, that the moon falls in towards the earth with the exact velocity required by the force of gravitation, for no other reason than that I believe in the com- petence and trustworthiness of the persons who AUTHORITY AND REASON 229 have made the necessary calculations and observa- tions. In this case the reason for my belief and the immediate cause of it are identical ; the cause, indeed, is a cause only in virtue of its being first a reason. But in the former case this is not so. Mere early training, paternal authority, or public opinion, were causes of belief before they were reasons; they continued to act as non-rational causes after they became reasons ; and it is not improbable that to the very end they contributed less to the resultant conviction in their capacity as reasons than they did in their capacity as non- rational causes. Now the temptation thus to convert causes into reasons seems under certain circumstances to be almost irresistible, even when it is illegitimate. Au- thority, as such, is from the nature of the case dumb in the presence of argument. It is only by reasoning that reasoning can be answered. It can be, and has often been, thrust silently aside by that instinctive feeling of repulsion which we call prej- udice when w^e happen to disagree with it. But it can only be replied to by its own kind. And so it comes about that whenever any system of belief is . seriously questioned, a method of defence which is almost certain to find favour is to select one of the causes by which the belief has been produced, and forthwith to erect it into a reason why the system should continue to be accepted. Authority, as I have been using the term, is thus converted into 230 AUTHORITY AND REASON ' an authority,' or into ' authorities.' It ceases to be the opposite or correlative of reason. It can no longer be contrasted with reason. It becomes a species of reason, and as a species of reason it must be judged. So judged, it appears to me that two things per- tinent to the present discussion may be said of it. In the first place, it is evidently an argument of im- mense utility and of very wide application. As I have just noted, it is the proximate reason for an enormous^proportion of our beliefs as to matters of fact, past and present, and for that very large body of scientific knowledge which even experts in sci- ence can have no opportunity of personally verify- ing. But, in the second place, it seems not less clear that the argument from ' an authority ' or ' au- thorities ' is almost always useless as a foundation for a system of belief. The deep -lying principles which alone deserve this name may be, and fre- quently are, the product of authority. But the at- tempt to ground them dialectically upon an author- ity can scarcely be attempted, except at the risk of logical disaster. Take as an example the general system of our beliefs about the material universe. The greater number of these are, as we have seen, quite legiti- mately based upon the argument from ' authori- ties ' ; and it is extremely probable that if any at- tack like that contained in the Second Part of these Notes be made upon the foundations of the system, AUTHORITY AND REASON 23 1 an endeavour will be made to extend to them also the support of so useful an ally. The * universal ex- perience,' or the ' general consent of mankind,' will be adduced as an authoritative sanction of certain fundamental presuppositions of physical science; and of these, at least, it will be said, sccurus judical orbis terraruvi. But a very little consideration is sufficient to show that this procedure is illegitimate, and that, as I have pointed out, we can neither know that the verdict of mankind has been given, nor, if it has, that anything can properly be in- ferred from it, unless we first assume the truth of the very principles which that verdict was invoked to establish.' The state of things is not materially different in the case of ethics and theology. There also the argument from 'an authority' or 'authorities' has a legitimate and most important place ; there also there is a constant inclination to extend the use of the argument so as to cover the fundamental portions of the system ; and there also this endeavour, when made, seems predestined to end in a piece of circular reasoning. I can hardly illustrate this statement without mentioning dogma ; though, as the reader will readily understand, I have not the slightest desire to do anything so little relevant to the purposes of this Introduction in order to argue either for or against it. As to the reality of an infallible guide, ' Cf. for a development of this statement, Philosophic Doubt, chap. vii. 232 AUTHORITY AND REASON in whatever shape this has been accepted by various sections of Christians, I have not a word to say. As part of a creed it is quite outside the scope of my inquiry. I have to do with it only if, and in so far as, it is represented, not as part of the thing to be believed, but as one of the fundamental reasons for believing it ; and in that position I think it inad- missible. Merely as an illustration, then, let us consider for a moment the particular case of Papal Infallibility, an example which may be regarded with the greater impartiality as I am not, I suppose, likely to have among the readers of these Notes many by whom it is accepted. If I rightly understand the teaching of the Roman Catholic theologians upon this subject, the following propositions, at least, must be accepted before the doctrine of Infallibility can be regarded as satisfactorily proved or adequately held :— (i) That the words ' Thou art Peter, and upon this rock,' &c., and, again, ' Feed my sheep,' were uttered by Christ ; and that, being so uttered, were of Divine authorship, and cannot fail. (2) That the meaning of these words is— (^) that St. Peter was endowed with a primacy of jurisdiction over the other Apostles; {b) that he was to have a perpetual line of successors, similarly endowed with a primacy of jurisdiction ; ic) that these successors were to be Bishops of Rome ; {d) that the primacy of jurisdiction carries with it the certainty of Divine 'assistance ' ; (r) that though this ' assistance ' does not ensure either the morality, or AUTHORITY AND REASON 233 the wisdom, or the general accuracy of the Pontiff to whom it is given, it does ensure his absoUite inerrancy whenever he shall, ex cathedra, define a doctrine of faith or morals ; (/) that no pronounce- ment can be regarded as ex cathedra unless it relates to some matter already thoroughly sifted and con- sidered by competent divines. Now it is no part of my business to ask how the six sub-heads contained in the second of these prop- ositions can by any legitimate process of exegesis be extracted from the texts mentioned in the first ; nor how, if they be accepted to the full, they can obviate the necessity for the complicated exercise of private judgment required to determine whether any particu- lar decision has or has not been made under the con- ditions necessary to constitute it a pronouncement ex cathedra. These are questions to be discussed between Roman Catholic and non-Roman Catholic controversialists, and with which I have nothing here to do. My point is, that the first proposition alone is so absolutely subversive of any purely naturalistic view of the universe, involves so many fundamental elements of Christianity {e.g. the supernatural char- acter of Christ and the trustworthiness of the first and fourth Gospels, with all that this carries with it), that if it does not require the argument from an infallible authority for its support, it seems hard to understand where the necessity for that argument can come in at any fundamental stage of apologetic demonstration. And that this proposition does not 234 AUTHORITY AND REASON require infallible authority for its support seems plain from the fact that it does itself supply the main ground on which the existence of infallible authority is believed. This is not, and is not intended to be, an objec- tion to the doctrine of Papal Infallibility ; it is not, and is not intended to be, a criticism by means of example directed against other doctrines involving the existence of an unerring guide. But if the reader will attentively consider the matter he will, I think, see that whatever be the truth or the value of such doctrines, they can never be used to supply any fundamental support to the systems of which they form a part without being open to a reply like that which I have supposed in the case of Papal Infalli- bility. Indeed, when we reflect upon the character of the religious books and of the religious organisa- tions through which Christianity has been built up; when we consider the variety in date, in occasion, in authorship, in context, in spiritual development, which mark the first ; the stormy history and the in- evitable division which mark the second ; when we, further, reflect on the astonishing number of the problems, linguistic, critical, metaphysical, and his- torical which must be settled, at least in some pre- liminary fashion, before either the books or the or- ganisations can be supposed entitled by right of rational proof to the position of infallible guides, we can hardly suppose that we were intended to find in these the logical foundations of our system of relig- AUTHORITY AND REASON 235 ioiis beliefs, however important be the part (and can it be exaggerated ?) which they were destined to play in producing, fostering, and directing it. VI Enough has now, perhaps, been said to indicate the relative positions of Reason and Authority in the production of belief. To Reason is largely due the growth of new and the sifting of old knowledge ; the ordering, and in part the discovery, of that vast body of systematised conclusions which constitute so large a portion of scientific, philosophical, ethical, political, and theological learning. To Reason we are in some measure beholden, though not, perhaps, so much as we suppose, for hourly aid in managing so much of the trifling portion of our personal af- fairs entrusted to our care by Nature as we do not happen to have already surrendered to the control of habit. By Reason also is directed, or misdirect- ed, the public policy of communities within the nar- row limits of deviation permitted by accepted cus- tom and tradition. Of its immense indirect conse- quences, of the part it has played in the evolution of human affairs by the disintegration of ancient creeds, by the alteration of the external conditions of human life, by the production of new moods of thought, or, as I have termed them, psychological climates, we can in this connection say nothing. For these are no rational effects of reason ; the 236 AUTHORITY AND REASON causal nexus by which they are bound to reason has no logical aspect; and if reason produces them, as in part it certainly does, it is in a manner indistin- guishable from that in which similar consequences are blindly produced by the distribution of conti- nent and ocean, the varying fertility of different re- gions, and the other material surroundings by which the destinies of the race are modified. When we turn, however, from the conscious work of Reason to that which is unconsciously per- formed for us by Authority, a very different spec- tacle arrests our attention. The effects of the first, prominent as they are through the dignity of their origin, are trifling compared with the all-pervading influences which flow from the second. At every moment of our lives, as individuals, as members of a family, of a party, of a nation, of a Church, of a universal brotherhood, the silent, continuous, unno- ticed influence of Authority moulds our feelings, our aspirations, and, what we are more immediately con- cerned with, our beliefs. It is from Authority that Reason itself draws its most important premises. It is in unloosing or directing the forces of Authority that its most important conclusions find their prin- cipal function. And even in those cases where we may most truly say that our beliefs are the rational product of strictly intellectual processes, we have, in all probability, only got to trace back the thread of our inferences to its beginnings in order to per- ceive that it finally loses itself in some general princi- AUTHORITY AND REASON 237 pie which, describe it as we may, is in fact due to no more defensible origin than the influence of Au- thority. Nor is the comparative pettiness of the role thus played by reasoning in human affairs a matter for regret. Not merely because we are ignorant of the data required for the solution, even of very simple problems in organic and social life, are we called on to acquiesce in an arrangement which, to be sure, we have no power to disturb ; nor yet because these data, did we possess them, are too complex to be dealt with by any rational calculus we possess or are ever likely to acquire ; but because, in addition to these difficulties, reasoning is a force most apt to di- vide and disintegrate ; and though division and dis- integration may often be the necessary preliminaries of social development, still more necessary are the forces which bind and stiffen, without which there would be no society to develop. It is true, no doubt, that we can, without any great expenditure of research, accumulate instances in which Authority has perpetuated error and re- tarded progress; for, unluckily, none of the influ- ences. Reason least of all, by which the history of the race has been moulded have been productive of unmixed good. The springs at which we quench our thirst are always turbid. Yet, if we arc to judge with equity between these rival claimants, we must not forget that it is Authority rather than Reason to which, in the main, we owe, not religion 238 AUTHORITY AND REASON only, but ethics and politics ; that it is Authority which supplies us with essential elements in the premises of science ; that it is Authority rather than Reason which lays deep the foundations of social life ; that it is Authority rather than Reason which cements its superstructure. And though it may seem to savour of paradox, it is yet no exaggeration to say, that if we would find the quality in which we most notably excel the brute creation, we should look for it, not so much in our faculty of convincing and being convinced by the exercise of reasoning, as in our capacity for influencing and being influenced through the action of Authority. PART IV SUGGESTIONS TOWARDS A PROVISIONAL PHILOSOPHY CHAPTER I THE GROUNDWORK We have now considered beliefs, or certain impor- tant classes of them, under three aspects. We have considered them from the point of view of their practical necessity ; from that of their philosophic proof; and from that of their scientific origin. In- quiries relating to the same subject-matter more distinct in their character it would be difficult to conceive. It remains for us to consider whether it is possible to extract from their combined results any general view which may command at least a provisional assent. It is evident, of course, that this general view, if we are fortunate enough to reach it, will not be of the nature of a complete or adequate philosophy. The unification of all belief into an ordered whole, compacted into one coherent structure under the stress of reason, is an ideal which we can never abandon ; but it is also one which, in the present condition of our knowledge, perhaps even of our faculties, we seem incapable of attaining. For the i6 242 THE GROUNDWORK moment we must content ourselves with something less than this. The best system we can hope to construct will suffer from gaps and rents, from loose ends and ragged edges. It does not, however, fol- low from this that it will be without a high degree of value ; and, whether valuable or worthless, it may at least represent the best within our reach. By the best I, of course, mean best in relation to reflective reason. If we have to submit, as I think we must, to an incomplete rationalisation of belief, this ought not to be because in a lit of intellectual despair we are driven to treat reason as an illusion ; nor yet because we have deliberately resolved to transfer our allegiance to irrational or non-rational inclination ; but because reason itself assures us that such a course is, at the lowest, the least irrational one open to us. If we have to find our way over difficult seas and under murky skies without com- pass or chronometer, we need not on that account allow the ship to drive at random. Rather ought we to weigh with the more anxious care every in- dication, be it negative or positive, and from what- ever quarter it may come, which can help us to guess at our position and to lay out the course which it behoves us to steer. Now, the first and most elementary principle which ought to guide us in framing any provisional scheme of unification, is to decline to draw any dis- tinction between different classes of belief where no relevant distinction can as a matter of fact be dis- THE GROUNDWORK 243 covered. To pursue the opposite course would be gratuitously to irrationalise (to coin a convenient word) our scheme from the very start ; to destroy, by a quite arbitrary treatment, any hope of its symmetrical and healthy development. And yet, if there be any value in the criticisms contained in the Second Part of these Notes, this is precisely the mistake into which the advocates of naturalism have invariably blundered. Without any preliminary analysis, nay, without any apparent suspicion that a preliminary analysis was necessary or desirable, they have chosen to assume that scientific beliefs stand not only upon a different, but upon a much more solid, platform than any others ; that scientific standards supply the sole test of truth, and scientific methods the sole instruments of discovery. I will not repeat the arguments which have led me to the conviction that such pretensions have no foundation in reason. The reader is already in pos- session of some of the arguments which are, as it seems to me, fatal to such claims, and it is not nec- essary here to repeat them. What is more to our present purpose is to find out whether, in the ab- sence of philosophic proof, judgments about the phenomenal, and more particularly about the ma- terial, world possess any other characteristics which, in our attempt at a provisional unification of knowl- edge, forbid us to place them on a level with other classes of belief. That there arc differences of some sort no one, I imagine, will attempt to deny. But 244 THE GROUNDWORK are they of a kind which require us either to give any special precedence to science, or to exclude other beliefs altogether from our general scheme ? One peculiarity there is which seems at first sight effectually to distinguish certain scientific be- liefs from any which belong, say, to ethics or the- ology ; a peculiarity which may, perhaps, be best expressed by the word ' inevitableness.' Every- body has, and everybody is obliged to have, some convictions about the world in which he lives — con- victions which in their narrow and particular form (as what I have before called beliefs of perception, memory, and expectation) guide us all, children, savages, and philosophers alike, in the ordinary conduct of day-to-day existence ; which, when gen- eralised and extended, supply us with some of the leading presuppositions on which the whole fabric of science appears logically to depend. No convic- tions quite answering to this description can, I think, be found either in ethics, ^esthetics, or theology. Some kind of morality is, no doubt, required for the stability even of the rudest form of social life. Some sense of beauty, some kind of religion, is, perhaps, to be discovered (though this is disputed) in every human community. But certainly there is noth- ing in either of these great departments of thought quite corresponding to our habitual judgments about the things we see and handle ; judgments which, with reason or without it, all mankind are practically compelled to entertain. THE GROUNDWORK 245 Compare, for example, the central truth of theol- ogy — 'There is a God' — with one of the funda- mental presuppositions of science (itself a general- ised statement of what is given in ordinary judg- ments of perception) — ' There is an independent material world.' I am myself disposed to doubt whether so good a case can be made out for accept- ing the second of these propositions as can be made out for accepting the first. But while it has been found by many, not only possible, but easy, to doubt the existence of God, doubts as to the independent existence of matter have assuredly been confined to the rarest moments of subjective reflection, and have dissolved like summer mists at the first touch of what we are pleased to call reality. Now, what are we to make of this fact ? In the opinion of many persons, perhaps of most, it affords a conclusive ground for elevating science to a dif- ferent plane of certitude from that on which other systems of belief must be content to dwell. The evidence of the senses, as we loosely describe these judgments of perception, is for such person the best of all evidence : it is inevitable, so it is true ; seeing, as the proverb has it, is indeed believing. This somewhat crude view, however, is not one which we can accept. The coercion exercised in the pro- duction of these beliefs is not, as has been already shown, a rational coercion. Even while we submit to it we may judge it ; and in the very act of be- lieving we may be conscious that the strength of 246 THE GROUNDWORK our belief is far in excess of anything which mere reasoning can justify. I am making no complaint of this disparity be- tween belief and its reasons. On the contrary, I have already noted my dissent from the popular view that it is our business to take care that, as far as possible, these two shall in every case be nicely adjusted. It cannot, I contend, be our duty to do that in the name of reason which, if it were done, would bring any kind of rational life to an immedi- ate standstill. And even if we could suppose it to be our duty, it is not one which, as was shown in the last chapter, we are practically competent to perform. If this be true in the case of those be- liefs which owe their origin largely to Authority, or the non-rational action of mind on mind, not less is it true in the case of those elementary judgments which arise out of sense - stimulation. Whether there be an independent material universe or not may be open to philosophic doubt. But that, if it exists, it is expedient that the belief in it should be accepted with a credence which for all practical purposes is immediate and unwavering, admits, I think, of no doubt whatever. If we could suppose a community to be called into being who, in their dealings with the ' external world,' should permit action to wait upon speculation, and require all its metaphysical difficulties to be solved before repos- ing full belief in some such material surroundings as those which we habitually postulate, its members THE GROUNDWORK 24/ would be overwhelmed by a ruin more rapid and more complete than that which, in a preceding chapter, was prophesied for those who should suc- ceed in ousting authority from its natural position among the causes of belief. But supposing this be so, it follows necessaril}', on accepted biological principles,^ that a kind of credulity so essential to the welfare, not merely of the race as a whole, but of every single member of it, will be bred by elimination and selection into its inmost organisation. If we consider what must have happened at that critical moment in the history of organic development, when first conscious judg- ments of sense-perception made themselves felt as important links in the chain connecting nervous irritability with muscular action, is it not plain that any individual in whom such judgments were ha- bitually qualified and enfeebled by even the most legitimate scepticism would incontinently perish, and that those only would survive who possessed, and could presumably transmit to their descend- ants, a stubborn assurance which was beyond the power of reasoning either to fortify or to under- mine? No such process would come to the assistance ot ' At the first glance, the reader may be disposed to think that to bring in science to show why no peculiar certainty should attach to scientific premises is logically inadmissible. But this is not so: though the converse procedure, by which scientific conclusions would be made to establish scientific premises, would, no doubt, involve an argument in a circle. 248 THE GROUNDWORK other faiths, however true, which were the growth of higher and later stages of civilised development. For, in the first place, such faiths are not necessa- rily, nor perhaps at all, an advantage in the struggle for existence. In the second place, even where they are an advantage, it is rather to the community as a whole in its struggles with other communities, than to each particular individual in his struggle with other individuals, or with the inanimate forces of Nature. In the third place, the whole machinery of selection and elimination has been weakened, if not paralysed, by civilisation itself. And, in the fourth place, were it still in full operation, it could not, through the mere absence of time and opportunity, have produced any sensible effect in moulding the organism for the reception of beliefs which, by hypothesis, are the recent acquisition of a small and advanced minority. II We are now in a position to answer the question put a few pages back. What, I then asked, if any, is the import, from our present point of view, of the universality and inevitableness which unquestion- ably attach to certain judgments about the world of phenomena, and to these judgments alone? The answer must be, that these peculiarities have no import. They exist, but they are irrelevant. Faith or assurance, which, if not in excess of reason, is at THE GROUNDWORK 249 least independent of it, seems to be a necessity in every great department of knowledge which touches on action ; and what great department is there which does not? The analysis of sense-experience teaches us that we require it in our ordinary deal- ings with the material world. The most cursory examination into the springs of moral action shows that it is an indispensable supplement to ethical speculation. Theologians are for the most part agreed that without it religion is but the ineffectual profession of a barren creed. The comparative value, however, of these faiths is not to be measured either by their intensity or by the degree of their diffusion. It is true that all men, whatever their speculative opinions, enjoy a practical assurance with regard to what they see and touch. It is also true that few men have an assurance equally strong about matters of which their senses tell them noth- ing immediately; and that many men have on such subjects no assurance at all. But as this is precisely what we should expect if, in the progress of evolu- tion, the need for other faiths has arisen under con- ditions very different from those which produced (Hir innate and long-descended confidence in sense- perception, how can we regard it as a distinction in favour of the latter? We can scarcely reckon uni- versality and necessity as badges of pre-eminence, at the same moment that we recognise them as marks of the elementary and primitive character oi the beliefs to which they give their all-powerful, but 250 THE GROUNDWORK none the less irrational, sanction. The time has passed for believing that the further we go back towards the * state of nature,' the nearer we get to Virtue and to Truth. We cannot, then, extract out of the coercive character of certain unreasoned beliefs any principle of classification which shall help us to the provi- sional philosophy of which we are in search. What such a principle would require us to include in our system of behefs contents us not. What it would require us to exclude we may not willingly part with. And if, dissatisfied with this double defici- ency, we examine more closely into its character and origin, we find, not only that it is without rational justiiication — of which at this stage of our inquiry we have no right to complain — but that the very account which it gives of itself precludes us from finding in it even a temporary place of intel- lectual repose. I do not, be it observed, make it a matter of complaint that those who erect the inevitable judg- ments of sense-perception into a norm or standard of right belief have thereby substituted (however unconsciously) psychological compulsion for ra- tional necessity ; for, as rational necessity does not, so far as I can see, carry us at the best beyond a system of mere ' solipsism,' it must, somehow or other, be supplemented if we are to force an en- trance into any larger and worthier inheritance. My complaint rather is, that having asked us to THE GROUNDWORK 25 I acquiesce in the guidance of non-rational impulse, they should then require us arbitrarily to narrow down the impulses which we may follow to the almost animal instincts lying at the root of our judgments about material phenomena. It is surely better — less repugnant, I mean, to reflective reason — to frame for ourselves some wider scheme which, though it be founded in the last resort upon our needs, shall at least take account of other needs than those we share with our brute progenitors. And here, if not elsewhere, I may claim the sup- port of the most famous masters of speculation. Though they have not, it may be, succeeded in sup- plying us with a satisfactory explanation of the Uni- verse, at least the Universe which they have sought to explain has been something more than a mere collection of hypostatised sense-perceptions, packed side by side in space, and following each other with blind uniformity in time. All the great architects of systems have striven to provide accommodation within their schemes for ideas of wider sweep and richer content ; and whether they desired to support, to modify, or to oppose the popular theolog}' of their day, they have at least given hospitable wel- come to some of its most important conceptions. In the case of such men as Leibnitz, Kant, Hegel, this is obvious enough. It is true, I think, even in such a case as that of Spinoza. Philosophers, in- deed, may find but small satisfaction in his methods or conclusions. They may see but little to admire 252 THE GROUNDWORK in his elaborate but illusory show of quasi-mathe- matical demonstration ; in the Nature which is so unlike the Nature of the physicist that we feel no surprise at its being also called God ; in the God Who is so unlike the God of the theologian that we feel no surprise at His also being called Nature ; in the «/r/crz metaphysic which evolves the universe from definitions; in the freedom which is indistin- guishable from necessity ; in the volition which is indistinguishable from intellect; in the love which is indistinguishable from reasoned acquiescence ; in the universe from which have been expelled pur- pose, morality, beauty, and causation, and which contains, therefore, but scant room for theology, ethics, aesthetics, and science. In the two hundred years and more which have elapsed since the pub- lication of his system, it may be doubted whether two hundred persons have been convinced by his reasoning. Yet he continues to interest the world ; and why ? Not, surely, as a guide through the mazes of metaphysics. Not as a pioneer of ' higher ' criti- cism. Least of all because he was anything so com- monplace as a heretic or an atheist. The true rea- son appears to me to be very different. It is partly, at least, because in despite of his positive teaching he was endowed with a religious imagination which, in however abstract and metaphysical a fashion, illumined the whole profitless bulk of inconclusive demonstration; which enabled him to find in notions most remote from sense-experience the only abiding THE GROUNDWORK 253 realities ; and to convert a purely rational adhesion to the conclusions supposed to flow from the nature of an inactive, impersonal, and unmoral substance, into something not quite Inaptly termed the Love of God. It will, perhaps, be objected that we have no right to claim support from the example of system- makers with whose systems we do not happen to agree. How, it may be asked, can it concern us that Spinoza extracted something like a religion out of his philosophy, if we do not accept his philosophy? Or that Hegel found it impossible to hitch large frag- ments of Christian dogma into the development of the ' Idea,' if we are not convinced by his dialectic? It concerns us, I reply, inasmuch as facts like these furnish fresh confirmation of a truth reached before by another method. The naturalistic creed, which merely systematises and expands the ordinary judg- ments of sense-perception, we found by direct ex- amination to be quite inadequate. We now note that its inadequacy has been commonly assumed by men whose speculative genius is admitted, who have seldom been content to allow that the world of which they had to give an account could be nar- rowed down to the naturalistic pattern. 2 54 THE GROUNDWORK III But a more serious objection to the point of view here adopted remains to be considered. Is not, it will be asked, the whole method followed through- out the course of these Notes intrinsically unsound ? Is it not substantially identical with the attempt, not made now for the first time, to rest superstition upon scepticism, and to frame our creed, not in accordance with the rules of logic, but with the promptings of desire? It begins (may it not be said ?) by discrediting reason ; and having thus guaranteed its results against inconvenient criti- cism,, it proceeds to make the needs of man the measure of ' objective ' reality, to erect his conve- nience into the touchstone of Eternal Truth, and to mete out the Universe on a plan authenticated only by his wishes. Now, on this criticism I have, in the first place, to observe that it errs in assuming, either that the object aimed at in the preceding discussion is to discredit reason, or that as a matter of fact this has been its effect. On the contrary, be the character of our conclusions what it may, they have at least been arrived at by allowing the fullest play to free, rational investigation. If one consequence of this investigation has been to diminish the importance commonly attributed to reason among the causes by which belief is produced, it is by the action of THE GROUNDWORK 255 reason itself that this result has been brought about. If another consequence has been that doubts have been expressed as to the theoretic validity of certain universally accepted beliefs, this is because the right of reason to deal with every province of knowledge, untrammelled by arbitrary restrictions or customary immunities, has been assumed and acted upon. If, in addition to all this, we have been incidentally compelled to admit that as yet we are without a sat- isfactory philosophy, the admission has not been asked for in the interests either of scepticism or of superstition. Reason is not honoured by pretend- ing that she has done what as a matter of fact is still undone; nor need we be driven into a universal license of credulity by recognising that we must for the present put up with some working hypothesis which falls far short of speculative perfection. But, further, is it true to say that, in the absence of reason, we have contentedly accepted mere desire for our guide? No doubt the theory here advocated requires us to take account, not mei-ely of premises and their conclusions, but of needs and their satis- faction. But this is only asking us to do explicitly and on system what on the naturalistic theory is done unconsciously and at random. By the very constitution of our being we seem practically driven to assume a real world in correspondence with our ordinary judgments of perception. A harmony of some kind between our inner selves and the universe of which we f(;rm a part is thus the tacit postulate 2S6 THE GROUNDWORK at the root of every belief we entertain about * phe- nomena ' ; and all that I now contend for is, that a like harmony should provisionally be assumed be- tween that universe and other elements in our nat- ure which are of a later, of a more uncertain, but of no ignobler, growth. Whether this correspondence is best described as that which obtains between a ' need ' and its ' sat- isfaction,' may be open to question. But, at all events, let it be understood that if the relation so described is, on the one side, something different from that between a premise and its conclusion, so, on the other, it is intended to be equally remote from that between a desire and its fulfilment. That it has not the logical validity of the first I have already admitted, or rather asserted. That it has not the casual, wavering, and purely 'subjective ' character of the second is not less true. For the correspond- ence postulated is not between the fleeting fancies of the individual and the immutable verities of an unseen world, but between these characteristics of our nature, which we recognise as that in us which, though not necessarily the strongest, is the highest ; which, though not always the most universal, is nevertheless the best. But because this theory may seem alike remote from familiar forms both of dogmatism and scepti- cism, and because I am on that account the more anxious that no unmerited plausibility should be at- tributed to it through any obscurity in my way of THE GROUNDWORK 257 presenting it, let me draw out, even at the cost of some repetition, a brief catalogue of certain things which may, and of certain other things which may not, be legitimately said concerning it. We may say of it, then, that it furnishes us Avith no adequate philosophy of religion. But we may not say of it that it leaves religion worse, or, indeed, otherwise provided for in this respect than science. We may say of it that it assumes without proof a certain consonance between the ' subjective ' and the ' objective ' ; between what we are moved to believe and what in fact is. We may not say that the presuppositions of science depend upon any more solid, or, indeed, upon any different, founda- tion. We may say of it, if we please, that it gives us a practical, but not a theoretic, assurance of the truths with which it is concerned. But, if so, we must describe in the same technical language our assurance respecting the truths of the material world. We may say of it that it accepts provisionally the theory, based on scientific methods, which traces back the origin of all beliefs to causes which, for the most part, are non-rational, and which carry with them no warranty that they will issue in right opinion. But we may not say of it that the distinc- tion thus drawn between the non-rational causes whicii jjroducc the immediate judgments of sense- perception, and those which produce judgments in '7 258 THE GROUNDWORK the sphere of ethics or theology, imply any superior certitude in the case of the former. We may say of it that it admits judgments of sense-perception to be the most inevitable, but denies them to be the most worthy. We may say of it generally, that as it assumes the Whole, of which we desire a reasoned knowl- edge, to include human consciousness as an element, it refuses to regard any system which, like Natural- ism, leaves large tracts and aspects of that con- sciousness unaccounted for and derelict as other than, to that extent, at least, irrational ; and that it utterly declines to circumscribe the Knowable by frontiers whose delimitation Reason itself assures us can be justified on no rational principle whatso- ever. CHAPTER II BELIEFS AND FORMULAS After these hints towards the formation of a pro- visional philosophy, it may perhaps be convenient, before proceeding to say what remains to be said on the character of the behefs for which it may provide a foundation, to interpolate some observations on the formal side of their historical development, which will not only serve, I hope, to make clearer the general scheme here advocated, but may help to solve certain difficulties which have sometimes been felt in the interpretation of theological and ec- clesiastical history. Assuming, as we do, that Knowledge exists, we can hardly do otherwise than make the further as- sumption that it has grown and must yet further grow. In what manner, then, has that growth been accomplished ? What are the external signs of its successive stages, the marks of its gradual evolution? One, at least, must strike all who have surveyed, even with a careless eye, the course of human specu- lation — I mean the recurring ])rocess by which the explanations or exj)lanalory lormulas in terms of 26o BELIEFS AND FORMULAS which mankind endeavour to comprehend the uni- verse are formed, are shattered, and then in some new shape are formed again. It is not, as we some- times represent it, by the steady addition of tier to tier that the fabric of knowledge uprises from its foundation. It is not by mere accumulation of material, nor even by a plant-like development, that our beliefs grow less inadequate to the truths which they strive to represent. Rather are we like one who is perpetually engaged in altering some ancient dwelling in order to satisfy new-born needs. The ground-plan of it is being perpetually modified. We build here ; we pull down there. One part is kept in repair, another part is suffered to decay. And even those portions of the structure which may in themselves appear quite unchanged, stand in such new relations to the rest, and are put to such differ- ent uses, that they would scarce be recognised by their original designer. Yet even this metaphor is inadequate, and per- haps misleading. We shall more accurately conceive the true history of knowledge if we represent it under the similitude of a plastic body whose shape and size are in constant process of alteration through the operation both of external and of internal forces. The internal forces are those of reason. The external forces correspond to those non-rational causes on whose importance I have already dwelt. Each of these agencies may be supposed to act both by way of destruction and ol addition. B}^ their joint oper- BELIEFS AND FORMULAS 26 1 ation new material is deposited at one point, old material is eroded at another ; and the whole mass, whose balance has been thus disturbed, is constantly changing its configuration and settling towards a new position of equilibrium, which it may approach, but can never quite attain. We must not, however, regard this body of be- liefs as being equally mobile in all its parts. Certain elements in it have the power of conferring on the whole something in the nature of a definite struct- ure. These are known as ' theories,' ' hypotheses,' ' generalisations,' and ' explanatory formulas ' in gen- eral. They represent beliefs by which other beliefs are co-ordinated. They supply the framework in which the rest of knowledge is arranged. Their right construction is the noblest work of reason ; and without their aid reason, if it could be exercised at all, would itself be driven from particular to particu- lar in helpless bewilderment. Now the action and reaction between these for- mulas and their contents is the most salient, and in some respects the most interesting, fact in the his- tory of thought. Called into being, for the most part, to justify, or at least to organise, pre-existing beliefs, they can seldom perform their office without modi- fying part, at least, of their material. While they give precision to what would otherwise be indetei*- minate, and a relative permanence to what would oth- erwise be in a state of flux, they do so at the cost of some occasional violence to the beliefs with which 262 BELIEFS AND FORMULAS they deal. Some of these are distorted to make them fit into their predestined niche. Others, more refractory, are destroyed or ignored. Even in sci- ence, where the beliefs that have to be accounted for have often a native vigour born of the imperious needs of sense-perception, we are sometimes dis- posed to see, not so much what is visible, as what theory informs us ought to be seen. While in the region of assthetic (to take another example), where belief is of feebler growth, the inclination to admire what squares with some current theory of the beau- tiful, rather than with what appeals to any real feel- ing for beauty, is so common that it has ceased even to amuse. But this reaction of formulas on the beliefs which they co-ordinate or explain is but the first stage in the process we are describing. The next is the change, perhaps even the destruction, of the for- mula itself by the victorious forces that it has pre- viously held in check. The plastic body of belief, or some portion of it, under the growing stress of external and internal influences, breaks through, it may be with destructive violence, the barriers by which it was at one time controlled. A new theory has to be formed, a new arrangement of knowl- edge has to be accepted, and under changed con- ditions the same cycle of not unfruitful changes begins again. I do not know that any illustration of this famil- iar process is required, for in truth such examples BELIEFS AND FORMULAS 263 are abundant in every department of Knowledge. As chalk consists of little else but the remains of dead animalcul^e, so the history of thought consists of little else but an accumulation of abandoned ex- planations. In that vast cemetery every thrust of the shovel turns up some bone that once formed part of a living theory ; and the biography of most of these theories would, I think, confirm the general account which I have given of their birth, maturity, and decay. II Now we may well suppose that under existing circumstances death is as necessary in the intellect- ual world as it is in the organic. It may not always result in progress, but without it, doubtless, prog- ress would be impossible ; and if, therefore, the constant substitution of one explanation for another could be effected smoothly, and as it were in silence, without disturbing anything beyond the explana- tions themselves, it need cause in general neither anxiety nor regret. But, unfortunately, in the case of Theology, this is not always the way things hap- pen. There, as elsewhere, theories arise, have their day, and fall ; but there, far more than elsewhere, do these theories in their fall endanger other interests than their own. More than one reason may be given for this difference. To begin with, in Science the beliefs of sense-perception, which, as I have implied, 264 BELIEFS AND FORMULAS are commonly vigorous enough to resist the warp- ing effect of theory, even when the latter is in its full strength, are not imperilled by its decay. They provide a solid nucleus of unalterable conviction, which survives uninjured through all the mutations of intellectual fashion. We do not require the as- sistance of hypotheses to sustain our faith in what we see and hear. Speaking broadl}^ that faith is unalterable and self-sufficient. Theology is less happily situated. There it often happens that when a theory decays, the beliefs to which it refers are infected by a contagious weak- ness. The explanation and the thing explained are mutually dependent. They are animated as it were with a common life, and there is always a danger lest they should be overtaken by a common de- struction. Consider this difference between Science and Theology in the light of the following illustration. The whole instructed world were quite recently agreed that heat was a form of matter. With equal unanimity they now hold that it is a mode of motion. These opinions are not only absolutely inconsistent, but the change from one to the other is revolution- ary, and involves the profoundest modification of our general views of the material world. Yet no one's confidence in the existence of some quality in things by which his sensations of warmth are pro- duced is thereby disturbed ; and we may hold either of these theories, or both of them in turn, or no BELIEFS AND FORMULAS 265 theory at all, without endangering the stability of our scientific faith. Compare with this example drawn from physics one of a very different kind drawn from theology. If there be a spiritual experience to which the his- tory of religion bears witness, it is that of Recon- ciliation with God. If there be an 'objective' cause to which the feeling is confidently referred, it is to be found in the central facts of the Christian story. Now, incommensurable as the subject is with that touched on in the last paragraph, they resemble each other at least in this — that both have been the theme of much speculation, and that the accounts (jf them which have satisfied one generation, to an- other have seemed profitless and empty. But there the likeness ends. In the physical case, the feeling of heat and the inward assurance that it is really connected with some quality in the external body from which we suppose ourselves to derive it, sur- vive every changing speculation as to the nature of that quality and the mode of its operation. In the spiritual case, the sense of Reconciliation connected by the Christian conscience with the life and death (A Christ seems in many cases to be bound up with the explanations of the mystery which from time to time have been hazarded by theological theorists. And as these explanations have fallen out of favour, the truth to be explained has too often been aban- (h^ned also. This is not the place to press the subject fuitlier: 266 BELIEFS AND FORMULAS and I have neither the right in these Notes to as- sume the truth of particular theological doctrines, nor is it my business to attempt to prove them. But this much more 1 may perhaps be allowed to say by way of parenthesis. If the point of view which this Essay is intended to recommend be accepted, the precedent set, in the first of the above examples, by science is the one which ought to be followed by theology. No doubt, when a belief is only accepted as the conclusion of some definite inferential process, with that process it must stand or fall. If, for in- stance, we believe that there is hydrogen in the sun, solely because that conclusion is forced upon us by certain arguments based upon spectroscopic obser- vations, then, if these arguments should ever be dis- credited, the belief in solar hydrogen would, as a necessary consequence, be shaken or destroyed. But in cases where the belief is rather the occasion of an hypothesis than a conclusion from it, the de- struction of the hypothesis may be a reason for de- vising a new one, but is certainly no reason for aban- doning the belief. Nor in science do we ever take any other view. We do not, for example, step over a precipice because we are dissatisfied with all the attempts to account for gravitation. In theology, however, experience does sometimes lean too timidly on theory, and when in the course of time theory decays, it drags down experience in its fall. How many persons are there, for example, who, because they dislike the theories of Atonement propounded. BELIEFS AND FORMULAS 267 say, by Anselm, or by Grotius, or the versions of these which have imbedded themselves in the de- votional literature of Western Europe, feel bound * in reason ' to give up the doctrine itself? Because they cannot compress within the rigid limits of some semi-legal formula a mystery which, unless it were too vast for our full intellectfial comprehen- sion, would surely be too narrow for our spiritual needs, the mystery itself is to be rejected ! Because they cannot contrive to their satisfaction a system of theological jurisprudence which shall include Re- demption as a leading case, Redemption is no longer to be counted among the consolations of mankind ! Ill There is, however, another reason beyond the natural strength of the judgments due to sense-per- ception which tends to make the change or abandon- ment of explanatory formulas a smoother operation in science than it is in theology ; and this reason is to be found in the fact that Religion works, and, to produce its full results, must needs work, through the agency of organised societies. It has, therefore, a social side, and from this its speculative side cannot, I believe, be kept wholly distinct. For al- though feeling is the effectual bond of all societies, these feelings themselves, it would seem, cannot be properly developed without the aid of something which is, or which docs duty as, a reason. They 268 BELIEFS AND FORMULAS require some alien material on which, so to speak, they may be precipitated ; round which they may crystallise and coalesce. In the case of political societies this reason is founded on identity of race, of language, of country, or even of mere material interest. But when the religious society and the political are not, as in primitive times, based on a common ground, the desired reason can scarcely be looked for elsewhere, and, in fact, never is looked for elsewhere, than in the acceptance of com- mon religious formulas. Whence it comes about that these formulas have to fulfil two functions which are not mereJy distinct but incomparable. They are both a statement of theological conclu- sions and the symbols of a corporate unity. They represent at once the endeavour to sj^stematise re- ligious truth and to organise religious associations ; and they are therefore subject to two kinds of influence, and involve two kinds of obligation, which, though seldom distinguished, are never identical, and may sometimes even be opposed. The distinction is a simple one ; but the refusal to recognise it has been prolific in embarrassments, both for those who have assumed the duty of con- triving symbols, and for those on whom has fallen the burden of interpreting them. The rage for de- fining ^ which seized so large a portion of Christen- dom, both Roman and non-Roman, during the Ref- ormation troubles, and the fixed determination to ' Cf. Note at end of next chapter. BELIEFS AND FORMULAS 269 turn the definitions, when made, into impassable barriers between hostile ecclesiastical divisions, are among the most obvious, but not, I think, among the most satisfactory, facts in modern religious his- tory. To the definitions taken simply as well-in- tentioned efforts to make clear that which was ob- scure, and systematic that which was confused, I raise no objections. Of the practical necessity for some formal basis of Christian co-operation I am, as I have said, most firmly convinced. But not every formula which represents even the best theological opinion of its age is therefore fitted to unite men for all time in the furtherance of common religious objects, or in the support of common religious in- stitutions ; and the error committed in this con- nection by the divines of the Reformation, and the counter-Reformation, largely consisted in the mista- ken supposition that symbols and decrees, in whose very elaboration could be read the sure prophec}' of decay, were capable of providing a convenient framework for a perpetual organisation. It is, however, beyond the scope of these Notes to discuss the dangers which the inevitable use of theological formulas as the groundwork of ecclesi- astical co-operation may have upon Christian unity, important and interesting as the subject is. I am properly concerned solely with the other side of the same shield, namely, the dangers with which this inevitable combination of theory and practice may threaten the smooth development of religious 270 BELIEFS AND FORMULAS beliefs — dangers which do not follow in the parallel case of science, where no such combination is to be found. The doctrines of science have not got to be discussed amid the confusion and clamour of the market-place ; they stir neither hate nor love ; the fortunes of no living polity are bound up with them ; nor is there any danger lest they become petrified into party watchwords. Theology is differently situated. There the explanatory formula may be so historically intertwined with the sentiments and traditions of the ecclesiastical organisation ; the heat and pressure of ancient conflicts may have so welded them together, that to modify one and leave the other untouched seems well-nigh impossible. Yet even in such cases it is interesting to note how unexpectedly the most difficult adjustments are sometimes effected ; how, partly by the conscious, and still more by the unconscious, wisdom of man- kind ; by a little kindly forgetfulness ; by a few happy inconsistencies ; by methods which might not always bear the scrutiny of the logician, though they may well be condoned by the philosopher, the changes required by the general movement of belief are made with less friction and at a smaller cost — even to the enlightened — than might, perhaps, ante- cedently have been imagined. CHAPTER III BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES The road which theological thought is thus com- pelled to travel would, however, be rougher even than it is were it not for the fact that large changes and adaptations of belief are possible within the limits of the same unchano^insr formulas. This is a fact to which it has not been necessary hitherto to call the reader's attention. It has been far more convenient, and so far not, I think, misleading, to follow familiar usage, and to assume that identity of statement in- volves identity of belief ; that when persons make the same assertions in good faith they mean the same thinof. But this on closer examination is seen not to be the case. In all branches of knowledge abundant examples are to be discovered of statements which do not fall into the cycle of change described in the last section, which no lapse of time nor growth of learning would apparently require us to revise. But in every case it will, I think, be found that, with the doubtful exception of purely abstract propositions, these statements, themselves unmoved, represent a moving body of belief, varying from (^nc period of 272 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES life to another, from individual to individual, and from generation to generation. Take an example at random. 1 suppose that the world, so long as it thinks it worth while to have an opinion at all upon the subject, will continue to accept without amendment the assertion that Julius Caesar was murdered at Rome in the first century B.C. But, are we therefore to suppose that this proposition must mean the same thing in the mouths of all who use it ? Surely not ? Even if we refuse to take account of the associated sentiments which give a different colour in each man's eyes to the same in- tellectual judgment, we cannot ignore the varying positions which the judgment itself may hold in dif- ferent systems of belief. It is surely absurd to say that a statement about the mode and time of Caesar's death has the same significance for the schoolboy who learns it as a line in a mcvioria tcchnica, and the historian (if such there be) to whom it represents a turning-point in the history of the world. Nor is it possible to deny that any alteration in our views on the nature of Death, or on the nature of Man, must necessarily alter the import of a proposition which asserts of a particular man that he suffered a par- ticular kind of death. This may perhaps seem to be an unprofitable subtlety ; and so, to be sure, in this particular case, it is. But a similar reflection is of obvious impor- tance when we come to consider, for example, such propositions as * there is a God,' or ' there is a world BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 2/3 of material things.' Both these statements might be, and are, accepted by the rudest savage and by the most advanced philosopher. They may, so far as we can tell, continue to be accepted by men in all stages of culture till the last inhabitant of a perishing world is frozen into unconsciousness. Yet plainly the savage and the philosopher use these words in very different meanings. From the tribal deity of early times to the Christian God, or, if you prefer it, the Hegelian Absolute ; from Matter as conceived by primitive man to Matter as it is conceived by the modern physicist, how vast the interval ! The for- mulas are the same, the beliefs are plainly not the same. Nay, so wide arc they apart, that while to those who hold the earlier view the later would be quite meaningless, it may require the highest effort of sympathetic imagination for those whose minds are steeped in the later view to reconstruct, even imperfectly, the substance of the earlier. The civil- ised man cannot fully understand the savage, nor the grown man the child. II Now a question of some interest is suggested by this reflection. Can we, in the face of the wide di- vergence of meaning frequently conveyed by the same formula at different times, assert that what en- dures in such cases is anything more than a mere husk or shell ? Is it more than the mould into which i8 274 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES any metal, base or precious, may be poured at will ? Does identity of expression imply anything- which deserves to be described as community of belief? Are we here dealing with things, or only with words? In order to answer this question we must have some idea, in the first place, of the relation of Lan- guage to Belief, and, in the second place, of the re- lation of Belief to Reality. That the relation be- tween the first of these pairs is of no very precise or definite kind I have already indicated. And the fact is so obvious that it would hardly be worth while to insist on it were it not that Formal Logic and conventional usage both proceed on exactly the opposite supposition. They assume a constant rela- tion between the symbol and the thing symbolised ; and they consider that so long as a word is used (as the phrase is) ' in the same sense,' it corresponds, or ought to correspond, to the same thought. But this is an artificial simplification of the facts ; a conven- tion, most convenient for certain purposes, but sel- dom or never observed when we are expressing opinions about concrete realities. If in the sweat of our brow we can secure that inevitable differences of meaning do not vitiate the particular argument in hand, we have done all that logic requires, and all that lies in us to accomplish. Not only would more be impossible, but more would most certainly be un- desirable. Incessant variation in the uses to which we put the same expression is absolutely necessary if the complexity of the Universe is, even in the BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 275 most imperfect fashion, to find a response in thought. If terms were counters, each purporting always to represent the whole of one unalterable aspect of reality, language would become, not the servant of thought, nor even its ally, but its tyrant. The wealth of our ideas would be limited by the poverty of our vocabulary. Science could not flourish, nor Litera- ture exist. All play of mind, all variety, all devel- opment would perish; and mankind would spend its energies, not in using words, but in endeavouring to define them. It was this logical nightmare which oppressed the intellect of the Middle Ages. The schoolmen have been attacked for not occupying themselves with experimental observation, which, after all, was no particular business of theirs; for indulging in excessive subtleties — surely no great crime in a metaphysician ; and for endeavouring to combine the philosophy and the theology of their day into a coherent whole — an attempt which seems to me to be entirely praiseworthy. A better reason for their not having accomplished the full promise of their genius is to be found in tiie assumption which lies at the root of their interminable deductions, namely, that language is, or can be made, what logic by a convenient convention supposes it to be, and that if it were so made, it would be an instrument better fitted on that account to deal with the infinite vari- ety of the actual world. 276 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES III If language, from the ver)^ nature of the case, hangs thus loosely to the belief which it endeavours to express, how closely does the belief fit to the reality with which it is intended to correspond ? To hear some persons talk one would really suppose that the enlightened portion of mankind, i.e. those who happen to agree with them, were blessed with a precise knowledge respecting large tracts of the Universe. They are ready on small provocation to embody their beliefs, whether scientific or theologi- cal, in a series of dogmatic statements which, as they will tell you, accurately express their own ac- curate opinions, and between which and any differing statements on the same subject is fixed that great gulf which divides for ever the realms of Truth from those of Error. Now I would venture to warn the reader against paying any undue meed of rever- ence to the axiom on which this view essentially de- pends, the axiom, I mean, that ' every belief must be either true or not true.' It is, of course, indisputable. But it is also unimportant ; and it is unimportant for this reason, that if we insist on assigning every be- lief to one or other of these two mutually exclusive classes, it will be found that most, if not all, the posi- tive beliefs which deal with concrete reality — the very beliefs, in short, about which a reasonable man may be expected principally to interest himself— BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 277 would in strictness have to be classed amonjr the ' not true.' I do not say, be it observed, that all propositions about the concrete world must needs be erroneous ; for, as we have seen, every proposi- tion provides the fitting verbal expression for many different beliefs, and of these it may be that one ex- presses the full truth. My contention merely is, that inasmuch as any fragmentary presentation of a con- crete whole must, because it is fragmentary, be therefore erroneous, the full complexity of any true belief about reality will necessarily transcend the comprehension of any finite intelligence. We know only in part, and we therefore know wrongly. But it may perhaps be said that observations like these involve a confusion between the ' not true ' and the ' incomplete.' A belief, as the phrase is, may be ' true so far as it goes,' even though it does not go far enough. It may contain the truth and nothing but the truth, but not the whole truth. Why should it under such circumstances receive so severe a condemnation ? Why is it to be branded, not only as inadequate, but as erroneous? To this I reply that the division of beliefs into the True, the Incom- plete, and the Wholly False may be, and for many purposes is, a very convenient one. But in the first place it is not philosophically accurate, since that which is incomplete is touched throughout with some element of falsity. And in the second place it does not hapi)en to be the division on which we are engaged. We are dealing with the logical contra- 278 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES dictories ' True ' and ' Not True.' And what makes it worth while dealing with them is, that the partic- ular classification of beliefs which thej suggest lies at the root of much needless controversy in all branches of knowledge, and not least in theology ; and that everywhere it has produced some confusion of thought and, it may be, some defect of charity. It is not in human nature that those who start from the assumption that all opinions are either true or not true, should do otherwise than take for granted that their own particular opinions belong to the former category ; and that therefore all inconsistent opinions held by other people must belong to the latter. Now this, in the current affairs of life, and in the ordinary commerce between man and man, is not merely a pardonable but a necessary way of look- ing at things. But it is foolish and even dangerous when we are engaged on the deeper problems of science, metaphysics, or theology ; when we are endeavouring in solitude to take stock of our posi- tion in the presence of the Infinite. However pro- found may be our ignorance of our ignorance, at least we should realise that to describe (when using language strictly) any scheme of belief as wholly false which has even imperfectly met the needs of mankind, is the height of arrogance ; and that to claim for any beliefs which we happen to approve that they are wholly true, is the height of absurdity. Somewhat more, be it observed, is thus required of us than a bare confession of ignorance. The BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 279 least modest of men would admit without difficulty that there are a great many things which he does not understand ; but the most modest may perhaps be willing to suppose that there are some things which he does. Yet outside the relations of abstract propositions (about which I say nothing) this cannot be admitted. Nowhere else — neither in our knowl- edge of ourselves, nor in our knowledge of each other, nor in our knowledge of the material world, nor in our knowledge of God, is there any belief which is more than an approximation, any method which is free from flaw, any result not tainted with error. The simplest intuitions and the remotest speculations fall under the same condemnation. And though the fact is apt to be hidden from us by the unshrinking definitions with which alike in science and theology it is our practice to register attained results, it would, as we have seen, be a serious mistake to suppose that any complete corre- spondence between Belief and Reality was secured by the linguistic precision and the logical impecca- bility of the propositions by which beliefs themselves are conimuuicatcd and recorded. To some persons this train of reflection suggests nothing but sceptical misgiving and intellectual despair. To me it seems, on the other hand, to save us fr(;ni both. What kind of a Universe would that be which we could understand? if it were intel- ligible (by us), would it be credible? If our reason could comprehend it, would it not be too narrow 28o BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES for our needs? ' I believe because it is impossible ' may be a pious paradox. ' I disbelieve because it is simple ' commends itself to me as an axiom. An axiom doubtless to be used with discretion : an axiom which may easily be perverted in the inter- ests of idleness and superstition ; but one, neverthe- less, which contains a valuable truth not always remembered by those who make especial profession of worldly wisdom. IV However this may be, the opinions here advo- cated may help us to solve certain difficulties oc- casionally suggested by current methods of dealing with the relation between Formulas and Beliefs. It has not always, for instance, been found easy to reconcile the immutability claimed for theological doctrines with the movement observed in theologi- cal ideas. Neither of them can readily be aban- doned. The conviction that there are Christian verities which, once secured for the human race, cannot by any lapse of time be rendered obsolete is one which no Church would willingly abandon. Yet the fact that theological thought follows the laws which govern the evolution of all other thought, that it changes from age to, age, largely as regards the relative emphasis given to its various elements, not inconsiderably as regards the substance of those elements themselves, is a fact written legibly across BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 28 1 the pages of ecclesiastical history. How is this apparent contradiction to be accommodated ? Consider another difficulty — one quite of a dif- ferent kind. The common sense of mankind has been shocked at the value occasionally attributed to uniformity of theological profession, when it is perhaps obvious from many of the circumstances of the case that this carries with it no security for uni- formity of inward conviction. There is an unreal- ity, or at least an externality about such professions which, to those who think (rightly enough) that religion, if it is to be of any value, must come from the heart, is apt not unnaturally to be repulsive. Yet, on the other hand, it is but a shallow form of historical criticism which shall attribute this desire for conformity either to mere impatience of ex- pressed differences of opinion (no doubt a powerful and widely distributed motive), or to the perversi- ties of Priestcraft. What, then, is the view which we ought to take of it? Is it good or bad? and, if good, what purpose does it serve ? Now these questions may be answered, I think, at least in i)art, if we keep in mind two distinc- tions on which in tiiis and the preceding chapter I have ventured to insist — the distinctions, I mean, /// tJic first place, between the function of formu- las as the systematic expression of religious doc- trine, and their function as the basis of religious co- operation ; anrl the distinction, /// tlic second place, between the accuracy of any foimuLa and the real 282 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES truth of the various beUefs which it is capable of expressing. Uniformity of profession, for example, to take the last difficulty first, can be regarded as unimportant only by those who forget that, while there is no necessary connection whatever between the causes which conduce to successful co-operation and those which conduce to the attainment of speculative truth, of these two objects the first may, under certain circumstances, be much more important than the second. A Church is something more than a body of more or less qualified persons engaged more or less successfully in the study of theology. It requires a ver}^ different equipment from that which is sufficient for a learned society. Something more is asked of it than independent research. It is an organisation charged with a great practical work. For the successful promotion of this work unity, dis- cipline, and self-devotion are the principal requisites ; and, as in the case of every other such organisation, the most powerful source of these qualities is to be found in the feelings aroused by common memories, common hopes, common loyalties; by professions in which all agree ; by a ceremonial which all share ; by customs and commands which all obey. He, therefore, who would wish to expel such influences either from Church or State, on the ground that they may alter (as alter they most certainly will) the opinions which, in their absence, the members of the community, left to follow at will their own spec- BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 283 Illative devices, would otherwise form, may know something of science or philosophy, but assuredly knows very little of human nature. But it will perhaps be said that co-operation, if it is only to be had on these terms, may easily be bought too dear. So, indeed, it may. The history (^f the Church is unhappily there to prove the fact. But as this is true of religious organisations, so also is it true of every other organisation — national, po- litical, military, what you will — by which the work of the w(^rld is rendered possible. There are circum- stances which may make schism justifiable, as there are circumstances which make treason justifiable, or mutiny justifiable. But without going into the ethics of revolt, without endeavouring to determine the exact degree of error, oppression, or crime on the part of those who stay within the organisation which ma}- render innocent or necessary the secession of those who leave it, it is, in my judgment, perfectly plain that something very different is, or ought to be, involved in the acceptance or rejection of com- mcjn formulas than an announcement to the world of a purely speculative agreement respecting the niceties of doctrinal statement. This view may perhaps be more readily accepted when it is realised that, as I have pointed out, no agreement about theological or any other doctrine insures, or, indeed, is capable of [)roducing, same- ness of belief. We are no more able to believe what other people believe than to feel what other people 284 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES feel. Two friends read together the same descrip- tion of a landscape. Does anyone suppose that it stirs within them precisely the same quality of sen- timent, or evokes precisely the same subtle associa- tions ? And yet, if this be impossible, as it surely is, even in the case of friends attuned, so far as may be, to the same emotional key, how hopeless must it be in the case of an artist and a rustic, an Ancient and a Modern, an Andaman islander and a European ! But if no representation of the splendours of Nature can produce in us any perfect identity of admiration, why expect the definitions of theology or science to produce in us any perfect identity of belief? It may not be. This uniformity of conviction which so many have striven to attain for themselves, and to impose upon their fellows, is an unsubstantial phan- tasm, born of a confusion between language and the thought which language so imperfectly expresses. In this world, at least, we are doomed to differ even in the cases where we most agree. There is, however, consolation to be drawn from the converse statement, which is, I hope, not less true. If there are differences where we most agree, surely also there are agreements where we most differ. I like to think of the human race, from whatever stock its members may have sprung, in whatever age they may be born, whatever creed they may profess, together in the presence of the One Reality, engaged, not wholly in vain, in spelling out some fragments of its message. All share its being ; to BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 285 none are its oracles wholly dumb. And if both in the natural world and in the spiritual the advance- ment we have made on our forefathers be so great that our interpretation seems indefinitely removed from that which primitive man could alone compre- hend, and wherewith he had to be content, it may be, indeed 1 think it is, the case that our approxi- mate guesses are still closer to his than they are to their common (Object, and that far as we seem to have travelled, yet, measured on the celestial scale, our intellectual progress is scarcely to be discerned. so minute is the parallax of Infinite Truth. These observations, however, seem only to ren- der more distant an}^ satisfactory solution of the first of the difficulties propounded above. If knowl- edge must, at the best, be so imperfect ; if agi-ee- ment, real inner agreement, about the object of knowledge can thus never be complete; and if, in addition to this, the histor}' of religious thought is, like all other histor}^ one of change and develop- ment, where and what are those immutable doc- trines which, in the opinion of most theologians, ought to be handed on, a sacred trust, from genera- tion U) generation? The answer to this question is, I think, suggested by the parallel cases of science and ethics. For all these things may be said of Ihcm as well as of tlieology, and they also are the 1 rustees of statements which ought to be preserved unchanged llirnu'^li nil revolutions in scientific and ethical the(jiy. Ol these statements 1 do nol pre- 286 BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES tend to give either a list or a definition. But with- out saying what they are, it is at least permissible, after the discussion in the last chapter, to say what, as a rule, they are not. They are not Explanatory. Rare indeed is it to find explanations of the concrete which, if they endure at all, do not require perpetual patching to keep them in repair. Not among these, but among the statements of things explained, of things that want explanation, yes, and of things that are inexplicable, we must search for the proposi- tions about the real world capable of ministering unchanged for indefinite periods to the uses of Man- kind. Such propositions may record a particular 'fact,' as that ' Cassar is dead.' They may embody an ethical imperative, as that ' Stealing is wrong,' They may convey some great principle, as that the order of Nature is uniform, or that ' God exists.' All these statement, even if accurate (as I assume, for the sake of argument, that they are), will, no doubt, as I have said, have a different import for different persons and for different ages. But this is not only consistent with their value as vehicles for the transmission of truth — it is essential to it. If their meaning could be exhausted by one genera- tion, they would be false for the next. It is because they can be charged with a richer and richer con- tent as our knowledge slowly grows to a fuller har- mony with the Infinite Reality, that they may be counted among the most precious of our inalienable possessions. BELIEFS, FORMULAS, AND REALITIES 28/ NOTE The permanent value which the results of the great ecclesias- tical controversies of the first four centuries have had for Chris- tendom, as compared with that possessed by the more transitory speculations of later ages, illustrates, I think, the suggestion con- tained in the text. For whatever opinion the reader may entertain of the decisions at which the Church arrived on the doctrine of the Trinity, it is at least clear that they were not in the nature of ex- planations. They were, in fact, precisely the reverse. They were the negation of explanations. The various heresies which it com- bated were, broadly speaking, all endeavours to bring the mystery as far as possible into harmony with contemporary speculations, Gnostic, Neo-platonic, or Rationalising, to relieve it from this or that difficulty : in short, to do something towards ' explaining ' it. The Church held that all such explanations or partial explanations inflicted irremediable impoverishment on the idea of the Godhead which was essentially involved in the Christian revelation. They insisted on preserving that idea in all its inexplicable fulness ; and so it has come about that while such simplifications as those of the Arians, for example, are so alien and impossible to modern modes of thought that if they had been incorporated with Christianity they must have destroyed it, the doctrine of Christ's Divinity still gives reality and life to the worship of millions of pious souls, who are wholly ignorant both of the controversy to which they owe its preservation, and of the technicalities which its discussion has in- volved. CHAPTER IV 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' If, as is not unlikely, there are readers who ac- cept unwillingly this profession of all-pervading error in so far as it applies to our scientific knowl- edge — who are disposed to represent Science as a Land of Goshen, bright beneath the unclouded splendours of the midday sun, while Religion lies beyond, wrapped in the impenetrable darkness of the Egyptian plague — I would suggest for their further consideration certain arguments, not drawn like those in the preceding section from the nature of our knowledge in general, nor like those in an earlier portion of this Essay from the deficiencies which may be detected in scientific proof, but based exclusively upon an examination of fundamental scientific ideas considered in themselves. For these ideas possess a quality, exhibited no doubt equally by ideas in other departments of knowledge, which admirably illustrates our ignorance of what we know best, our blindness to what we see most clearly. This quality, indeed, is not very easy to describe in a sentence ; but perhaps it may be provisionally in- dicated by saying that, although these ideas seem 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' 289 quite simple so long as we only have to handle them for the practical purposes of daily life, ye.t, when they are subjected to critical investigation, they appear to crumble under the process ; to lose all precision of outline ; to vanish like the magician in the story, leaving only an elusive mist in the grasp of those who would arrest them. Nothing, for instance, seems simpler than the idea involved in the statement that we are, each of us, situated at any given moment in some par- ticular portion of space, surrounded by a multitude of material things, which are constantly acting upon us and upon each other. A proposition of this kind is merely a generalised form of the judg- ments which we make every minute of our waking lives, about whose meaning we entertain no manner of doubt, which, indeed, provide us with our famil- iar examples of all that is most lucid and most cer- tain. Yet the purport of the sentence which ex- presses it is clear only till it is examined, is certain only till it is questioned; while almost every word in it suggests, and has long suggested, perplexing problems to all who are prepared to consider them. What are ' we ' ? What is space? Can ' wc ' be in space, or is it only our bodies about which an}' such statement can be made ? Wliat is a ' thing '? and, in particular, what is a 'material thing'? What is meant by saying that one ' material thing ' acts u])on another? What is meant by saying that 'material things' act upt»ii 'us'? Here are six 19 290 ' ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS ' questions all directly and obviously arising out of our most familiar acts of judgment Yet, direct and obvious as they are, it is hardly too much to say that they involve all the leading problems of mod- ern philosophy, and that the man who has got an answer to them is the fortunate possessor of a toler- ably complete system of metaphysics. Consider, for example, the simplest of the six questions enumerated above, namely, What is a ' material thing ' ? Nothing could be plainer till you consider it. Nothing can be obscurer when you do. A ' thing ' has qualities — hardness, weight, shape, and so forth. Is it merely the sum of these qualities, or is it something more? If it is merely the sum of its qualities, have these any independent existence ? Nay, is such an independent existence even conceivable ? If it is something more, what is the relation of the ' qualities ' to the ' something more ' ? Again, can we on reflection regard a ' thing ' as an isolated * somewhat,' an entity self- sufficient and potentially solitary? Or must we not rather regard it as being what it is in virtue of its relation to other ' somewhats,' which, again, are what they are in virtue of their relation to it, and to each other ? And if we take, as I think we must, the latter alternative, are we not driven by it into a profitless progression through parts which are unintelligible by themselves, but which yet obsti- nately refuse to coalesce into any fully intelligible whole ? 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' 291 Now, I do not serve up these cold fragments of ancient though unsolved controversies for no better purpose than to weary the reader who is familiar with metaphysical discussion, and to puzzle the reader who is not. I rather desire to direct atten- tion to the universality of a difficulty which many persons seem glad enough to acknowledge when they come across it in Theology, though they ad- mit it only with reluctance in the case of Ethics and Esthetics, and for the most part completely ignore it when they are dealing with our knowledge of ' phenomena.' Yet in this respect, at least, all these branches of knowledge would appear to stand very much upon an equality. In all of them conclusions seem more certain than premises, the superstruct- ure more stable than the foundation. In all of them we move with full assurance and a practical security only among ideas which are relative and dependent. In all of them these ideas, so clear and so sufficient for purposes of everyday thought and action, become confused and but dimly intelligible when examined in the unsparing light of critical analysis. We need not, therefore, be surprised if we find it hard to isolate the permanent element in Beauty, seeing that it eludes us in material objects; that the ground of Moral Law should not be wholl}^ clear, seeing that the ground of Natural Law is so (ob- scure ; that \vc do not adecpiatcly coiii|ii( Iiciid God, seeing that we can give no very salislactory ac- 292 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' count of what we mean by ' a thing.' Yet I think a more profitable lesson is to be learnt from admis- sions like these than the general inadequacy of our existing metaphysic. And it is the more necessary to consider carefully what that lesson is, inasmuch as a very perverted version of it forms the basis of the only modern system of English growth which, professing to provide us with a general philosophy, has received any appreciable amount of popular support. Mr. Spencer's theory admits, nay, insists, that what it calls * ultimate scientific ideas ' are incon- sistent and, to use his own phrase, * unthinkable.' Space, time, matter, motion, force, and so forth, are each in turn shown to involve contradictions which it is beyond our power to solve, and obscurities which it is beyond our power to penetrate ; while the once famous dialectic of Hamilton and Mansel is invoked for the purpose of enforcing the same lesson with regard to the Absolute and the Uncon- ditioned, which those thinkers identified with God, but which Mr. Spencer prefers to describe as the Unknowable. So far, so good. Though the details of the dem- onstration may not be altogether to our liking, I, at least, have no particular quarrel with its gen- eral tenor, which is in obvious harmony with much that I have just been insisting on. But when we have to consider the conclusion which Mr. Spencer contrives to extract from these premises, our differ- 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' 293 ences become irreconcilable. He has proved, or supposes himself to have proved, that the ' ultimate ideas ' of science and the ' ultimate ideas ' of the- ology are alike ' unthinkable.' What is the proper inference to be drawn from these statements ? Why, clearly, that science and theology are so far on an equality that every proposition which con- siderations like these oblige us to assert about the one, we are bound to assert also about the other; and that our general theor}^ of knowledge must take account of the fact that both these great de- partments of it are infected by the same weakness. This, however, is not the inference drawn by Mr. Spencer. The idea that the conclusions of science should be profaned by speculative questionings is to him intolerable. He shrinks from an admission which seems to him to carry universal scepticism in its train. And he has, accordingly, hit upon a device for ' reconcilincr ' the differences between science and religion by which so lamentable a ca- tastrophe may be avoided. His method is a simple one. He divides the verities which have to be be- lieved into those which relate to the Knowable and those which relate t(j the Unknowable. What is kmnvable he ai)propriates, without exception, for science. What is unknowable he abandons, with- out reserve, to religion. With the results of this arbitration both contending parties should, in his opinion, be satisfied. It is true that religion ma}' complain that by this arrangement it is made the 294 ' ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS ' residuary legatee of all that is * unthinkable ' ; but then, it should remember that it obtains in exchange an indefeasible title to all that is ' real.' Science, again, may complain that its activities are confined to the 'relative' and the 'dependent'; but then, it should remember that it has a monopoly of the ' intelligible.' The one possesses all that can be known ; the other, all that seems worth knowing. With so equal a partition of the spoils both dispu- tants should be content. Without contesting the fairness of this curious arrangement, I am compelled to question its valid- ity. Science cannot thus transfer the burden of its own obscurities and contradictions to the shoulders of religion; and Mr. Spencer is only, perhaps, mis- led into supposing such a procedure to be possible by his use of the word ' ultimate.' ' Ultimate ' scien- tific ideas may, in his opinion, be ' unthinkable ' without prejudice to the ' thinkableness' of 'proxi- mate ' scientific ideas. The one may dwell for ever in the penumbra of what he calls ' nascent conscious- ness,' in the dim twilight where religion and science are indistinguishable ; while the other stands out, definite and certain, in the full light of experience and verification. Such a view is not, I think, philo- sophically tenable. As soon as the ' unthinkable- ness ' of ' ultimate ' scientific ideas is speculatively recognised, the fact must react upon our specula- tive attitudes towards 'proximate' scientific ideas. That which in the order of reason is dependent can- 'ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS' 295 not be unaffected by the weaknesses and the ob- scurities of that on which it depends. If the one is unintelHijible, the other can hardly be rationally es- tablished. In order to prove this — if proof be required — we need not travel beyond the ample limits of Mr. Spencer's own philosophy. To be sure he obstinately shuts his ears against speculative doubts respecting the conclusions of science. ' To ask whether science is substantially true is [he observes] much like asking whether the sun gives light.' ^ It is, I admit, very much like it. But then, on Mr. Spencer's principles, docs the sun give light? After due consideration we shall have to admit, I think, that it does not. For it is a statement which, if made intelligently, not only involves the comprehension of matter, space, time, and force, which are, according to Mr. Spencer, all incomprehensible, but there is the further difficulty that, if his system is to be believed, 'what we are conscious of as properties of matter, even down to weight and resistance, are but subjective affections jnoduccd by objective agencies, which are unknown and unknowable.'^ It would seem, therefore, cither that the sun is a ' subjective affection,' in which case it can hardly be said to ' give light ' ; or it is ' un- known ' and ' unkntjwable,' in which case no assertion respecting it can be regarded as supplying us with any very flattering specimen of scientihc certitude. The truth is that Mr. Spencer, like many of his ' First Principles, p. 19. " Principles of Psychology, ii. 493. 296 ' ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS ' predecessors, has impaired the value of his specula- tions by the hesitating- timidity with which he has pursued them. Nobody is required to investigate first principles ; but those who voluntarily undertake the task should not shrink from its results. And if among these we have to count a theoretical scepti- cism about scientific knowledge, we make matters, not better, but worse, by attempting to ignore it. In Mr. Spencer's case this procedure has, among other ill consequences, caused him to miss the moral which at one moment lay ready to his hand. He has had the acuteness to see that our beliefs cannot be limited to the sequences and the co-existences of phenomena ; that the ideas on which science relies, and in terms of which all science has to be expressed, break down under the stress of criticism ; that beyond what we think we know, and in closest relationship with it, lies an infinite field which we do not know, and which with our present faculties we can never know, yet which cannot be ignored without making what we do know unintelligible and meaningless. But he has failed to see whither such speculations must in- evitably lead him. He has failed to see that if the certitudes of science lose themselves in depths of un- fathomable mystery, it may well be that out of these same depths there should emerge the certitudes of religion ; and that if the dependence of the ' know- able' upon the 'unknowable' embarrasses us not in the one case, no reason can be assigned why it should embarrass us in the other. ' ULTIMATE SCIENTIFIC IDEAS ' 297 Mr. Spencer, in sliort, has avoided the error of dividing all reality into a Perceivable which concerns us, and an Unperceivable which, if it exists at all, concerns us not. Agnosticism so understood he ex- plicitly repudiates by his theory, if not by his practice. But he has not seen that, if this simple-minded creed be once abandoned, there is no convenient halting- place till we have swung round to a theory of things which is its precise opposite : a theory which, though it shrinks on its speculative side from no severity of critical analysis, yet on its practical side finds the source of its constructive energy in the deepest needs of man, and thus recognises, alike in science, in ethics, in beauty, in religion, the halting expres- sion of a reality beyond our reach, the half-seen vision of transcendent Truth. CHAPTER V SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY The point of view we have thus reached is obvi- oiisl)^ the precise opposite of that which is adopted by those who either accept the naturalistic view of things in its simplicity, or who agree with natural- ism in taking our knowledge of Nature as the core and substance of their creed, while gladly adding to it such supernatural supplements as are permitted them by the canons of their rationalising philosophy. Of these last there are two varieties. There are those who refuse to add anything to the teaching of science proper, except such theological doctrines as they persuade themselves may be deduced from scientific premises. And there are those who, being less fastidious in the matter of proof, are prepared, tentatively and provisionally, to admit so much of theology as they think their naturalistic premises do not positively contradict. It must, I think, be admitted that the members of these two classes are at some disadvantage com- pared with the naturalistic philosophers proper. To SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 299 be sure, the scheme of belief so confidently propound- ed by the latter is, as we have seen, both incoherent and inadequate. But its incoherence is hid fr(^m them by the inevitableness of its positive teaching; while its inadequacy is covered by the, as yet, un- squandered heritage of sentiments and ideals which has come down to us from other ages inspired by other faiths. On the other hand, as a set-off against this, they may justly claim that their principles, such as they are, have been worked out to their le- gitimate conclusion. They have reached their jour- ney's end, and there they may at least rest, if it is not given them to be thankful. Far different is the fate of those who are reluctantly travelling the road to naturalism, driven thither by a false philosophy honestly entertained. To them each new discovery in geology, morphology, anthropology, or the ' high- er criticism,' arouses as much theological anxiety as it does scientific interest. They are perpetually occupied in the task of ' reconciling,' as the phrase goes, 'religion and science.' This is to them, not an intellectual luxury, but a pressing and overmaster- ing necessity. For their theology exists only on sufTerance. It rules over its hereditary territories as a tributary vassal dependent on the forbearance of some encroaching overlord. Province after province which once acknowledged its sovereignty has been torn from its grasp ; and it depends no longer upon its own action, but upon Ihc uncon- trolled policy of its too powerful neighbour, how 300 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY long it shall preserve a precarious authority over the remainder. Now, my reasons lor entirely dissenting from this melancholy view of the relations between the various departments of belief have been one of the chief themes of these Notes. But it must not on this account be supposed that I intend to deny, either that it is our business to ' reconcile ' all be- liefs, so far as possible, into a self-consistent whole, or that, because a perfectly coherent philosophy cannot as yet be attained, it is, in the meanwhile, a matter of complete indifference how many contra- dictions and obscurities we admit into our provi- sional system. Some contradictions and obscurities there needs must be. That we should not be able completely to harmonise the detached hints and isolated fragments in which alone Reality comes in- to relation with us ; that we should but imperfectly co-ordinate what we so imperfectly comprehend, is what we might expect, and what for the pres- ent we have no choice but to submit to. Yet it will, I think, be found on examination that the discrepancies which exist between different de- partments of belief are less in number and impor- tance than those which exist within the various de- partments themselves ; that the difficulties which science, ethics, or theology have to solve in common are more formidable by far than any which divide them from each other ; and that, in particular, the supposed 'conflict between science and religion,' SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 3OI which occupies so large a space in contemporary literature, is the theme of so much vigorous debate, and seems to so many earnest souls the one question worth resolving, is either concerned for the most part with matters in themselves comparatively tri- fling, or touches interests lying far beyond the limits of pure theology. Of course, it must be remembered that I am now talkinsf of science, not of naturalism. The differ- ences between naturalism and theology are, no doubt, irreconcilable, since naturalism is by defini- tion the negation of all theology. But science must not be dragged into every one of the many quarrels which naturalism has taken upon its shoulders. Science is in no way concerned, for instance, to deny the reality of a world unrevealed to us in sense-per- ception, nor the- existence of a God who, however imperfectly, may be known by those who diligently seek Him. All it says, or ought to say, is that these are matters beyond its jurisdiction; to be tried, therefore, in other courts, and before judges admin- istering different laws. But we may go further. The being of God may be beyond the province of science, and yet it may be from a consideration of the general body of scientific knowledge that philosophy draws some important motives for accepting the doctrine. Any complete survey of the ' proofs of theism ' would, I need not say, be here quite out of place; yet, in order to make clear where 1 ihink the real difficulty 302 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY lies in framing any system which shall include both theology and science, I may be permitted to say enough about theism to show where I think the difficulty does not lie. It does not lie in the doctrine that there is a supernatural or, let us say, a meta- physical ground, on which the whole system of natural phenomena depend ; nor in the attribution to this ground of the quality of reason, or, it may be, of something higher than reason, in which rea- son is, so to speak, included. This belief, with all its inherent obscurities, is, no doubt, necessary to theology, but it is at the same time so far, in my judgment, from being repugnant to science that, without it, the scientific view of the natural world would not be less, but more, beset with difficulties than it is at present. This fact has been in part obscured by certain infelicities in the popular statements of what is known as the ' Argument from Design.' In a famous answer to that argument it has been pointed out that the inference from the adaptation of means to ends, which rightly convinces us in the case of manufactured articles that they are not the result of chance, but are produced by intelligent contrivance, can scarcely be legitimately applied to the case of the universe as a whole. An induction which may be perfectly valid within the circle of phenomena, may be quite meaningless when it is employed to account for the circle itself. You cannot infer a God from the existence of the world as you infer an SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 303 architect from the existence of a house, or a me- chanic from the existence of a watch. Without discussing the merits of this answer at length, so much may, I think, be conceded to it — that it suggests a doubt whether the theologians who thus rely upon an inductive proof of the being of God are not in a position somewhat similar to that of the empirical philosophers who rely upon an inductive proof of the uniformity of Nature. The uniformity of Nature, as I have before ex- plained, cannot be proved by experience, for it is what makes proof from experience possible.' We must bi"ing it, or something like it, to the facts in order to infer anything from them at all. As- sume it, and we shall no doubt find that, broadly speaking and in the rough, what we call the facts conform to it. But this conformity is not inductive proof, and must not be confounded with it. In the same way, I do not contend that, if we start from Nature without God, we shall be logically driven to believe in Him by a mere consideration of the examples of adaptation which it undoubtedly con- tains. It is enough that when we bring this belief with us to the study of phenomena, we can say of ' This phrase has a Kantian rin(? about it ; but I need not say that it is not here used in tlie Kantian sense. The argument is touched on, as the reader may recollect, at the end of Chapter I., Part II. .See, however, below a further discussion as to what the uniformity of Nature means, and as to what may be properly in- ferred from it. 304 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY it, what we have just said of the principle of uni- formity, namely, that, ' broadly speaking and in the rough,' the facts harmonise with it, and that it gives a unity and a coherence to our apprehension of the natural world which it would not otherwise possess. II But the argument from design, in whatever shape it is accepted, is not the only one in favour of theism with which scientific knowledge furnishes us. Nor is it, to my mind, the most important. The argument from design rests upon the world as known. But something also may be inferred from the mere fact that we know — a fact which, like every other, has to be accounted for. And how is it to be accounted for ? I need not repeat again what I have already said about Authority and Rea- son ; for it is evident that, whatever be the part played by reason among the proximate causes of belief, among the ultimate causes it plays, accord- ing to science, no part at all. On the naturalistic hypothesis, the whole premises of knowledge are clearly due to the blind operation of material causes, and in the last resort to these alone. On that hy- pothesis we no more possess free reason than we possess free will. As all our volitions are the in- evitable product of forces which are quite alien to morality, so all our conclusions are the inevitable product of forces which are quite alien to reason. SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 305 As the casual introduction of conscience, or a 'good will,' into the chain of causes which ends in a ' vir- tuous action ' ought not to suggest any idea of merit, so the casual introduction of a little ratiocina- tion as a stray link in the chain of causes which ends in what we are pleased to describe as a ' dem- onstrated conclusion,' ought not to be taken as impl3ing that the conclusion is in harmou}^ with fact. Morality and reason are august names, which give an air of respectability to certain actions and certain arguments ; but it is quite obvious on exam- ination that, if the naturalistic hypothesis be cor- rect, they are but unconscious tools in the hands of their unmoral and non - rational antecedents, and that the real responsibility for all they do lies in the distribution of matter and energy which liaj)[)enccl to prevail far back in the incalculable past. These conclusions are, no doubt, as we saw at the beginning of this Essay, embarrassing enough to Morality. But they are absolutely ruinous to Knowledge. For they require us to accept a sys- tem as rational, one of whose doctrines is that the system itself is the product of causes which have no tendency to truth rather than falsehood, or to false- hood rather than truth. Forget, if you please, that reason itself is the result, like nerves or muscles, of physical antecedents. Assume (a tolerably violent assumption) that in dealing with her premises she obeys only her own laws. Of what value is this autonomy if those premises are sellUd for he r by 20 306 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY purely irrational forces, which she is powerless to control, or even to comprehend? The professor of naturalism rejoicing in the display of his dialectical resources, is like a voyager, pacing at his own pleas- ure up and down the ship's deck, who should sup- pose that his movements had some important share in determining his position on the illimitable ocean. And the parallel would be complete if we can con- ceive such a voyager pointing to the alertness of his step and the vigour of his limbs as auguring well for the successful prosecution of his journey, while assuring you in the very same breath that the vessel, within whose narrow bounds he displays all this meaningless activity, is drifting he knows not whence nor whither, without pilot or captain, at the bidding of shifting winds and incalculable currents. Consider the following propositions, selected from the naturalistic creed or deduced from it :— (i.) My beliefs, in so far as they are the result of reasoning at all, are founded on premises produced in the last resort by the ' collision of atoms.' (ii.) Atoms, having no prejudices in favour of truth, are as likely to turn out wrong premises as right ones ; nay, more likel}^ inasmuch as truth is single and error manifold. (iii.) My premises, therefore, in the first place, and my conclusions in the second, are certainly untrustworthy, and probably false. Their falsity, moreover, is of a kind which cannot be remedied ; since any attempt to correct it must start from SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 307 premises not suffering under the same defect. But no such premises exist. (iv.) Therefore, again, my opinion about the original causes which produced my premises, as it is an inference from them, partakes of their weak- ness ; so that I cannot either securely doubt my own certainties or be certain about my own doubts. This is scepticism indeed ; scepticism which is forced by its own inner nature to be sceptical even about itself; which neither kills belief nor lets it live. But it may perhaps be suggested in reply to this argument, that whatever force it may have against the old-fashioned naturalism, its edge is blunted when turned against the evolutionary ag- nosticism of more recent growth ; since the latter establishes the existence of a machinery which, irra- tional though it be, does really tend gradually, and in the long run, to produce true opinions rather tliaii false. That machinery is, I need not say. Se- lection, '.ind the other forces (if other fcjrces there be) which bring the ' organism ' into more and more perfect harmony with its ' environment.' Some har- mony is necessary — so runs tiie argument — in order that any form of life ma}' be possible; and as life de- velops, the harmony necessarily becomes more and more complete. But since there is no more imj)or- tant form in which this harmony can show itself than Iriitli of belief, which is, indeed, only ant.lliei- name lor the perfect correspondence between belief and fact. Nature, herein acting as a kind of cosmic In- 308 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY quisition, will repress by judicious persecution any lapses from the standard of naturalistic orthodoxy. Sound doctrine will be fostered ; error will be dis- couraged or destroyed ; until at last, by methods which are neither rational themselves nor of rational origin, the cause of reason will be fully vindicated. Arguments like these are, however, quite insuffi- cient to justify the conclusion which is drawn from them. In the first place, they take no account of any causes which were in operation before life ap- peared upon the planet. Until there occurred the unexplained leap from the Inorganic to the Organic, Selection, of course, had no place among the evolu- tionary processes ; while even after that date it was, from the nature of the case, only concerned to foster and perpetuate those chance -borne beliefs which minister to the continuance of the species. But what an utterly inadequate basis for speculation is here ! We are to suppose that powers which were evolved in primitive man and his animal progenitors in order that they might kill with success and marry in security, are on that account fitted to explore the secrets of the universe. We are to suppose that the fundamental beliefs on which these powers of reasoning are to be exercised reflect with sufficient precision remote aspects of reality, though they were produced in the main by physiological processes which date from a stage of development when the onl}' curiosities which had to be satisfied were those of fear and those of hunger. To say that instru- SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 309 ments of research constructed solely for uses like these cannot be expected to supply us with a meta- physic or a theology, is to say far too little. They cannot be expected to give us any general view even of the phenomenal world, or to do more than guide us in comparative safety from the satisfaction of one useful appetite to tlie satisfaction of another. On this theory, therefore, we are again driven back to the same sceptical position in which we found our- selves left by the older forms of the ' positive,' or naturalistic creed. On this theory, as on the other, reason has to recognise that her rights of in(lc[)cn- dcnt judgment and review arc merely titular digni- ties, carrying with them no effective powers ; and that, whatever her pretensions, she is, for the most part, the mere editor and interpreter of the utter- ances of unreason. I do not believe that any escape from these per- plexities is possible, unless we are prepared to bring to the study of the world the presupposition that it was the work of a rational Being, wlio made // intel- ligible, and at the same time made !/s, in however feeble a fashion, able to understand it. This concep- tion does not solve all difficulties ; far from it.^ But, ' According to a once prevalent theory, ' innate ideas ' were true because they were implanted in us by God. According to my way of putting it, there must be a God to justify our confidence in (what used to be called) innate ideas. I have given the arguinent in a form which avoids all discussion as to the nature of the relation between mind and body. Whatever be the mode of describing this which ultimately commends itself to naturalistic psychologists, 3IO SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY at least, it is not on the face of it incoherent. It does not attempt the impossible task of extracting reason from unreason ; nor does it require us to accept among scientific conclusions any which effectually shatter the credibility of scientific premises. Ill Theism, then, whether or not it can in the strict meaning of the word be described as proved by sci- ence, is a principle which science, for a double rea- son, requires for its own completion. The ordered system of phenomena asks for a cause ; our knowl- edge of that system is inexplicable unless we assume for it a rational Author. Under this head, at least, there should be no ' conflict between science and re- ligion.' It is true, of course, that if theism smoothes away some of the dilTficulties which atheism raises, it is not on that account without difficulties of its own. We cannot, for example, form, I will not say any ade- quate, but even any tolerable, idea of the mode in which God is related to, and acts on, the world of phenomena. That He created it, that He sustains it, we are driven to believe. How He created it, how He sustains it, is impossible for us to imagine. But let it be observed that the difficulties which thus arise are no peculiar heritage of theology, or of a the reasoninj^ in the text holds good. Cf. the purely sceptical presentation of the argument contained in Philosophic Doubt, chap. xiii. SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 311 science which accepts among its presuppositions the central truth which theology teaches. Naturalism itself has to face them in a yet more embarrassing- form. For they meet us not only in connection with the doctrine of God, but in connection with the doc- trine of man. Not Divinity alone intervenes in the world of things. Each living soul, in its measure and degree, does the same. Each living soul which acts on its surroundings raises questions analogous to, and in some ways more perplexing than, those suggested by the action of a God immanent in a universe of phenomena. Of course I am aware that, in thus speaking of the connection between man and his material sur- roundings, I am assuming the truth of a theory which some men of science (in this, however, travel- ling a little beyond their province) would most energetically deny. But their denial really only serves to emphasise the extreme difificulty of the problem raised by the relation of the Self to phenom- ena. So hardly pressed are they by these difficul- ties that, in order to evade them, they attempt an impossible act of suicide ; and because the Self refuses to figure as a phenomenon among phenom- ena, or complacently to fit in to a purely scientific view of the world, they set al)out the hopeless task of suppressing it altogether. Enough has already been said on this point to permit me to j)ass it by. I will, therefore, only observe that those who ask us to reject the conviction entertained by each one of 312 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY US, that he does actually and effectually intervene in the material world, may have many grounds of ob- jection to theology, but should certainly not include among them the reproach that it asks us to believe the incredible. But, in truth, without going into the metaphysics of the Self, our previous discussions ^ contain ample ^ Cf. ante. Part II., Chaps. I. and II. It may be worth while reminding the reader of one set of difficuhies to which I have made little reference in the text. Every theory of the relation between Will, or, more strictly, the Willing Self and Matter must come under one of two heads: — (i) Either Will acts on Matter, or (2) it does not. If it does act on Matter, it must be either as Free Will or as Determined Will. If it is as Free Will, it upsets the uniformity of Nature, and our most fundamental scientific conceptions must be recast. If it is as Determined, Will that is to say, if volition be in- terpolated as a necessary link between one set of material move- ments and another, then, indeed, it leaves the uniformity of Nature untouched ; but it violates mechanical principles. According to the mechanical view of the world, the condition of any material sys- tem at one moment is absolutely determined by its condition at the preceding moment. In a world so conceived there is no room for the interpolation even of Determined Will among the causes of ma- terial change. It is mere surplusage. (2.) If the Will does not act on Matter, then we must suppose either that volition belongs to a psychic series running in a parallel stream to the physiological changes of the brain, though neither in- fluenced by it nor influencing it — which is, of course, the ancient theory of pre-established harmony ; or else we must suppose that it is a kind of superfluous consequence of certain physiological changes, produced presumably without the exhaustion of any form of energy, and having no effect whatever, either upon the material world or, I suppose, upon other psychic conditions. This reduces us to automata, and automata of a kind very difficult to find proper accommodation for in a world scientifically conceived. None of these alternatives seem very attractive, but one of them would seem to be inevitable. SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 313 material for showing how impenetrable are the mists which obscure the relation of mind to matter, of things to the perception of things. Neither can be eliminated from our system. Both must perforce form elements in every adequate representation of reality. Yet the philosophic artist has still to arise who shall combine the two into a single picture, without doing serious violence to essential features, either of the one or the other. I am myself, indeed, disposed to doubt whether any concession made by the ' subjective ' to the ' objective,' or by the ' ob- jective ' to the ' subjective,' short of the total de- struction of one or the other, will avail to produce a harmonious scheme. And certainly no discord could be so barren, so unsatisfying, so practically impossible, as a harmony attained at such a cost. We must acquiesce, then, in the existence of an un- solved difficulty. But it is a difificulty which meets us, in an even more intractable form, when we strive to realise the nature of our own relations to the little world in which we move, than when we are dealing with a like problem in respect to the Divine S[)irit, Who is the Ground of all being and the Source of all change. IV But though there should thus be no conflict between theology and science, either as to the exist- ence of God or as to the possibility of His acting on phenomena, it by no means follows that the idea 3!4 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY of God which is suggested by science is compatible with the idea of God which is developed by theology. Identical, of course, they need not be. Theology would be unnecessary if all we are capable of learn- ing about God could be inferred from a study of Nature. Compatible, however, they seemingly must be, if science and religion are to be at one. And yet I know not whether those who are most persuaded that the claims of these two powers are irreconcilable rest their case willingly upon the most striking incongruity between them which can be produced — I mean the existence of misery and the triumphs of wrong. Yet no one is, or, indeed, could be, blind to the difficulty which thence arises. From the world as presented to us by science we might conjecture a God of power and a God of reason ; but we never could infer a God who was wholly loving and wholly just. So that what religion pro- claims aloud to be His most essential attributes are precisely those respecting which the oracles of science are doubtful or are dumb. One reason, I suppose, why this insistent thought does not, so far as my observation goes, supply a favourite weapon of controversial attack, is that ethics is obviously as much interested in the moral attributes of God as theology can ever be (a point to which I shall presently return). But another reason, no doubt, may be found in the fact that the difficulty is one which has been profoundly realised bv relicrious minds ages before organised science can SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 315 be said to have existed ; while, on the other hand, the growth of scientific knowledge has neither in- creased nor diminished the burden of it by a feather- weight. The question, therefore, seems, though not, I think, quite correctly, to be one which is wholly, as it were, within the frontiers of theology, and which theologians may, therefore, be left to deal with as best they may, undisturbed by any argu- ments supplied by science. If this be not in theory strictly true, it is in practice but little wide of the mark. The facts which raise the problem in its acutest form belong, indeed, to that portion of the experience of life which is the common property of science and theology ; but theology is much more deeply concerned in them than science can ever be, and has long faced the unsolved problem which they present. The weight which it has thus borne for all these centuries is not likely now to crush it; and, paradoxical though it seems, it is yet surely true, that what is a theological stumbling-block may also be a religious aid ; and that is in part the thought of 'all creation groaning and travailing in pain to- gether, waiting for redemption,' which creates in man the deepest need for faith in the love of God. I conceive, then, that those who lalk of the 'con- flict between science and religion ' do not, as a rule, refer to the difficulty presented by the existence of 3l6 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY Evil. Where, then, in their opinion, is the point of irreconcilable difference to be found? It will, I sup- pose, at once be replied, in Miracles. But though the answer has in it a measure of truth, though, with- out doubt, it is possible to approach the real kernel of the problem from the side of miracles, I confess this seems to me to be in fact but seldom accom- plished ; while the very term is more suggestive of controversy, wearisome, unprofitable, and unending, than any other in the language. Free Will alone be- ing excepted. Into this Serbonian bog I scarcely dare ask the reader to follow me, though the advent- ure must, I am afraid, be undertaken if the purpose of this chapter is to be accomplished. In the first place, then, it seems to me unfort- unate that the principle of the Uniformity of Nat- ure should so often be dragged into a controversy with which its connection is so dubious and obscure. For what do we mean by saying that Nature is uni- form ? We may mean, perhaps we ought to mean, that (leaving Free Will out of account) the condition of the world at one moment is so connected with its condition at the next, that if we could imagine it brought twice into exactly the same position, its subsequent history would in each case be exactly the same. Now no one, I suppose, imagines that uni- formity in this sense has any quarrel with miracles. If a miracle is a wonder wrought by God to meet the needs arising out of the special circumstances of a particular moment, then, supposing the circum- SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 317 Stances were to recur, as they would if the world were twice to pass through the same phase, the miracle, we cannot doubt, would recur also. It is not possible to suppose that the uniformity of Nat- ure thus broadly interpreted would be marred by Him on Whom Nature depends, and Who is im- manent in all its changes. But it will be replied that the uniformity with which miracles are thus said to be consistent carries with it no important consequences whatever. Its truth or untruth is a matter of equal indifference to the practical man, the man of science, and the phi- losopher. It asserts in reality (it may be said) no more than this, that if history once began repeating itself, it would go on doing so, like a recurring dec- imal. But as history in fact never docs exactly re- peat itself, as the universe never is twice over pre- cisely in the same condition, we should no more be able to judge the future from the past, or to detect the operation of particular laws of Nature in a world where only this kind of theoretic uniformity pre- vailed, than we should under the misrule of chaos and blind chance. There is force in these observations, which are, however, much more embarrassing to the philos- ophy of science than to that of theology. Without doubt all experimental inference, as well as the or- dinary conduct of life, depends on supplementing this general view of the uniformit)^ of Nature with certain working hyi)olhcses which arc not always, 3l8 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY though they ought to be, most carefully distin- guished from it. One of these is, that Nature is not merely uniform as a whole, but is made up of a bundle of smaller uniformities ; or, in other words, that there is a determinate relation, not onl}'- be- tween the successive phases of the whole universe, but between successive phases of certain fragments of it ; which successive phases we commonly de- scribe as ' causes ' and ' effects.' Another of these working hypotheses is, that though the universe as a whole never repeats itself, these isolated fragments of it do. And a third is, that we have means at our disposal whereby these fragments can be accurately divided off from the rest of Nature, and confidently recognised when they recur. Now I doubt whether any one of these three presuppositions — which, be it noted, lie at the very root of the collection of em- pirical maxims which we dignify with the name of inductive logic — can, from the point of view of philos- ophy, be regarded as more than an approximation. It is hard to believe that the concrete Whole of things can be thus cut up into independent portions. It is still harder to believe that any such portion is ever repeated absolutely unaltered ; since its char- acter must surely in part depend upon its relation to all the other portions, which (by hypothesis) are not repeated with it. And it is quite impossible to believe that inductive logic has succeeded by any of its methods in providing a sure criterion for de- termining, when any such portion is apparently re- SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 319 peated, whether all the elements, and not more than all, are again present which on previous occasions did really constitute it a case of ' cause ' and ' effect.' ^ If this seems paradoxical, it is chiefly because we habitually use phraseology which, strictly inter- preted, seems to imply that a ' law of Nature,' as it is called, is a sort of self-subsisting entity, to whose charge is confided some department in the world of phenomena, over which it rules with undisputed swav. Of course this is not so. In the world of phenomena, Reality is exhausted by what is and what happens. Beyond this there is nothing. These 'laws' are merely abstractions devised by us for our own guidance through the complexities of fact. They possess neither independent powers nor actual existence. And if we would use language with per- fect accuracy, we ought, it would seem, either to say that the same cause would always be followed by precisely the same effect, if it recurred — which it never does ; or that, in certain regions of Nature, though only in certain regions, we can detect sub- ordinate uniformities of repetition wdiich, though not exact, enable us without sensible insecurity or error to anticipate the future or reconstruct the past. This hurried glance which I have asked the reader to take into some obscure corners of induc- tive theory is by no means intended to suggest that • See some of these points more fully worked out in Philosophic Doji/'f, Part I., Chap. II. 320 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY it is as easy to believe in a miracle as not ; or even that on other grounds, presently to be referred to, miracles ought not to be regarded as incredible. But it does show, in my judgment, that no profit can yet be extracted from controversies as to the pre- cise relation in which they stand to the Order of the world. Those engaged in these controversies have not uncommonly committed a double error. They have, in the first place, chosen to assume that we have a perfectly clear and generally accepted theory as to what is meant by the Uniformity of Nature, as to what is meant by particular Laws of Nature, as to the relation in which the particular Laws stand to the general Uniformity, and as to the kind of proof by which each is to be established. And, having committed this philosophic error, they proceed to add to it the historical error of crediting primitive theology with a knowledge of this theory, and with a desire to improve upon it. They seem to suppose that apostles and prophets were in the habit of looking at the natural world in its ordinary course, with the eyes of an eighteenth-century deist, as if it were a bundle of uniformities which, once set going, went on for ever automatically repeating themselves; and that their message to mankind con- sisted in announcing the existence of another, or supernatural world, which occasionally upset one or two of these natural uniformities by means of a miracle. No such theory can be extracted from their writings, and no such theory should be read SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY $21 into them ; and this not merely because such an at- tribution is unhistorical, nor yet because there is any ground for doubting the interaction of the ' spiritual ' and the ' natural ' ; but because this ac- count of the 'natural' itself is one which, if inter- preted strictly, seems open to grave philosophical objection, and is certainly deficient in philosophic proof. The real difficulties connected with theological miracles lie elsewhere. Two qualities seem to be of their essence : they must be wonders, and they must be wonders due to the special action of Divine power ; and each of these qualities raises a special problem of its own. That raised by the first is the question of evidence. What amount of evidence, if an}^, is suf- ficient to render a miracle credible? And on this, which is apart from the main track of ni)- argument, I may perhaps content myself with pointing out, that if by evidence is meant, as it usually is, histor- ical testimony, this is not a fixed quantity, the same for every reasonable man, no matter what may be his other opinions. It varies, and must necessaril}- vary, with the general views, the ' psychological climate,* which he brings to its consideration. It is ])()ssible to get twelve plain men to agree on the evi- dence which requires them to bring in a verdict of guilty or not guilty, because they start with a com- mon stock of presuppositions, in the light of which the evidence su])miftcd to them may, without pre- liminary discussion, be interpreted. But when, as 21 322 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY in the case of theological miracles, there is no such common stock, any agreement on a verdict can scarcely be looked for. One of the jury may hold the naturalistic view of the world. To him, of course, the occurrence of a miracle involves the abandonment of the whole philosophy in terms of which he is accustomed to interpret the universe. Argument, custom, prejudice, authority — every con- viction-making machine, rational and non-rational, by which his scheme of belief has been fashioned— conspire to make this vast intellectual revolution difficult. And we need not be surprised that even the most excellent evidence for a few isolated inci- dents is quite insufficient to effect his conversion ; nor that he occasionally shows a disposition to go very extraordinary lengths in contriving historical or critical theories for the purpose of explaining such evidence away. Another may believe in ' verbal inspiration.' To him, the discussion of evidence in the ordinary sense is quite superfluous. Every miracle, whatever its character, whatever the circumstances in which it occurred, whatever its relation, whether essential or accidental, to the general scheme of religion, is to be accepted with equal confidence, provided it be narrated in the works of inspired authors. It is written : it is therefore true. And in the light of this presupposition alone must the results of any merel}' critical or historical discussion be finally judged. SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 323 A third of our supposed jurymen may reject both naturalism and verbal inspiration. He may appraise the evidence alleged in favour of ' Wonders due to the special action of Divine power ' by the light of an altogether different theory of the world and of God's action therein. He may consider re- ligion to be as necessary an element in any adequate scheme of belief as science itself. Every event, therefore, whether wonderful or not, a belief in whose occurrence is involved in that religion, every event by whose disproof the religion would be seri- ously impoverished or altogether destroyed, has be- hind it the whole combined strength of the system to which it belongs. It is not, indeed, believe-^' in- dependently of external evidence, any more than the most ordinary occurrences in history are be- lieved independently of external evidence. But it does not require, as some people appear to sup- pose, the impossible accumulation of proof on proof, of testimonv on testimony, before the presumption asrainst it can be neutralised. For, in truth, no such presumption may exist at all. Strange as the mira- cle must seem, and inharmonious when considered as an alien element in an otherwise naturalistic set- ting, it may assume a character of inevitableness, it may almost proclaim aloud that thus it has occurred, and not otherwise, to those who consider it in its rela- tion, not to the natural world alone, but to the spirit- ual, and to the needs of man as a citizen of both. 324 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY VI Many other varieties of ' psychological climate * might be described ; but what I have said is, perhaps, enough to show how absurd it is to expect any unanimity as to the value of historical evidence until some better agreement has been arrived at respect- ing the presuppositions in the light of which alone such evidence can be estimated. I pass, therefore, to the difficulty raised by the second, and much more fundamental, attribute of theological miracles to which I have adverted, namely, that they are due to the * special action of God.' But this, be it ob- served, is, from a religious point of view, no pecul- iarity of miracles. Few schemes of thought which have any religious flavour about them at all, wholly exclude the idea of what I will venture to call the ' preferential exercise of Divine power,' whatever differences of opinion may exist as to the manner in which it is manifested. There are those who reject miracles but who, at least in those fateful moments when they imaginatively realise their own helpless- ness, will admit what in a certain literature is called a ' special Providence.' There are those who reject the notion of ' special Providence,' but who admit a sort of Divine superintendence over the general course of history. There are those, again, who re- ject in its ordinar)' shape the idea of Divine super- intendence, but who conceive that they can escape SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 325 from philosophic reproach by beating- out the idea yet a little thinner, and admitting that there does exist somewhere a ' Power which makes for right- eousness.' For my own part, I think all these various opinions are equally open to the only form of attack which it is worth while to bring against any one of them. And if we allow, as (supposing religion in any shape to be true) we must allow, that the ' pref- erential action ' of Divine power is possible, nothing is gained by qualifying the admission with all those fanciful limitations and distinctions with which dif- ferent schools of thought have seen fit to encumber it. The admission itself, however, is one which, in whatever shape it may be made, no doubt suggests questions of great difficulty. How can the Divine Being Who is the Ground and Source of everything that is, Who sustains all, directs all, produces all, be connected more closely with one part of that which He has created than with another? If every event be wholly due to Him, how can we say that any single event, such as a miracle, or any tendency of events, such as 'making for righteousness,* is specially His? What room for difference or distinction is there within the circuit of His universal power? Since the relation between His creation and Him is throughout and in every [)articular one of absolute dependence, what meaning can we attach to the metaphor which represents Him as taking part with one fragment of it, or as hostile to another? 326 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY Now it has, in the first place, to be observed that ethics is almost as much concerned in dealing with this difficulty as theology itself. For if we cannot believe in ' preferential action,' neither can we be- lieve in the moral qualities of which ' preferential action ' is the sign ; and with the moral qualities of God is bound up the fate of anything which deserves to be called morality at all, I am not now arguing that ethics cannot exist unsupported by theism. On this theme I have already said something, and shall have to say more. My present contention is, that though history may show plenty of examples in heathendom of ethical theory being far in advance of the recognised religion, it is yet impossible to suppose that morality would not ultimately be de- stroyed by the clearly realised belief in a God Who was either indifferent to good or inclined to evil. For a universe in which all the power was on the side of the Creator, and all the morality on the side of creation, would be one compared with which the universe of naturalism would shine out a paradise indeed. Even the poet has not dared to represent Jupiter torturing Prometheus without the dim fig- ure of Avenging Fate waiting silently in the back- ground. But if the ideas of an immoral Creator governing a world peopled with moral, or even with sentient, creatures, is a speculative nightmare, the case is not materially mended by substituting for an immoral Creator an indifferent one. Once assume a God, and we shall be obHged, sooner or SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 327 later, to introduce harmony into our system by making obedience to His will coincident with the established rules of conduct. We cannot frame our advice to mankind on the hypothesis that to defy Omnipotence is the beginning of wisdom. But if this process of adjustment is to be done consistently with the maintenance of any eternal and absolute distinction between right and wi'ong, then must His will be a 'good will,' and we must suppose Him to look with favour upon some parts of this mixed world of good and evil, and with disfavour upon others. If, on the other hand, this distinction seems to us metaphysically impossible ; if we cannot do otherwise than regard Him as related in precisely the same way to every portion of His creation, look- ing with indifferent eyes upon misery and happiness, truth and error, vice and virtue, then our theology must surely drive us, under whatever disguise, to empty ethics of all ethical significance, and to re- duce virtue to a colourless acquiescence in the Ap- pointed Order. Systems there are which do not shrink from these speculative conclusions. But their authors will, I think, be found rather among those who ap- proach the problem of the world from the side of a particular metaphysic, than those who approach it from the side of science. He who sees in God no more than the Infinite Substance of which the world of phenomena constitutes the accidents, or who requires Him for no <jther purpose than as In- 328 SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY finite Subject, to supply the ' unity ' without which the world of phenomena would be an ' unmeaninp- flux of unconnected particulars,' may naturally sup- pose Him to be equally related to everything, good or bad, that has been, is, or can be. But I do not think that the man of science is similarly situated; for the doctrine of evolution has in this respect made a change in his position which, curiously enough, brings it closer to that occupied in this matter by theology and ethics than it was in the days when ' special creation ' was the fashionable view. I am not contending, be it observed, that evolu- tion strengthens the evidence for theism. My point rather is, that if the existence of God be assumed, evolution does, to a certain extent, harmonise with that belief in His ' preferential action ' which relig- ion and morality alike require us to attribute to Him. For whereas the material and organic world was once supposed to have been created 'all of a piece,' and to show contrivance on the part of its Author merely by the machine-like adjustment of its parts, so now science has adopted an idea which has always been an essential part of the Christian view of the Divine economy, has given to that idea an undreamed-of extension, has applied it to the whole universe of phenomena, organic and inorganic, and has returned it again to theology enriched, strength- ened, and developed. Can we, then, think of evolu- tion in a God-created world without attributing to SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY 329 its Author the notion of purpose slowly worked out ; the striving towards something which is not, but which gradually becomes, and in the fulness of time will be ? Surely not. But, if not, can it be denied that evolution — the evolution, I mean, which takes place in time, the natural evolution of science, as distinguished from the dialectical evolution of metaphysics — does involve something in the nature of that ' preferential action ' which it is so difficult to understand, yet so impossible to abandon? CHAPTER VI SUGGESTIONS TOWARDS A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION But if I confined myself to saying that the belief in a God who is not merely ' substance,' or ' sub- ject,' but is, in Biblical language, ' a living God,' af- fords no ground of quarrel between theology and science, I should much understate my thought. I hold, on the contrary, that some such presupposi- tion is not only tolerated, but is actually required, by science ; that if it be accepted in the case of science, it can hardly be refused in the case of ethics, aesthetics, or theology ; and that if it be thus accepted as a general principle, applicable to the whole circuit of belief, it will be found to provide us with a working solution of some, at least, of the difficulties with which naturalism is incompetent to deal. For what was it that lay at the bottom of those difficulties ? Speaking broadly, it may be described as the perpetual collision, the ineffaceable incon- gruity, between the origin of our beliefs, in so far as these can be revealed to us by science, and the beliefs themselves. This it was that, as I showed A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 33 1 in the first part of this Essay, touched with the frost of scepticism our ideals of conduct and our ideals of beauty. This it was that, as I showed in the Second Part, cut down scientific philosophy to the root. And all the later discussions with which 1 have occupied the attention of the reader serve but to emphasise afresh the inextricable confusion which the naturalistic hypothesis introduces into every department of practice and of speculation, by refusing to allow us to penetrate beyond the phe- nomenal causes by which, in the order of Nature, our beliefs are produced. Review each of these departments in turn, and, in the light of the preceding discussion, compare its position in a theological setting with that which it necessarily occupies in a naturalistic one. Let the case of science be taken first, for it is a crucial one. Here, if anywhere, we might suppose ourselves in- dependent of theology. Here, if anywhere, we might expect to be able to acquiesce without embar- rassment in the negations of naturalism. But when once we have realised the scientific truth that at the root of every rational process lies an irrational one ; that reason, from a scientific point of view, is itself a natural product ; and that the whole mate- rial on which it works is due to causes, physical, physiological, and social, which it neither creates nor controls, we shall (as I showed just now) be driven in mere self-defence to hold that, behind these non-rational forces, and above them, guiding 332 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION them by slow degrees, and, as it were, with diffi- culty, to a rational issue, stands that Supreme Rea- son in whom we must thus believe, if we are to be- lieve in anything. Here, then, we are plunged at once into the middle of theology. The belief in God, the attribu- tion to Him of reason, and of what I have called ' preferential action ' in relation to the world which He has created, all seem forced upon us by the sin- gle assumption that science is not an illusion, and that, with the rest of its teaching, we must accept what it has to say to us about itself as a natural product. At no smaller cost can we reconcile the origins of science with its pretentions, or relieve ourselves of the embarrassments in which we are involved by a naturalistic theory of Nature. But evidently the admission, if once made, cannot stand alone. It is impossible to refuse to ethical beliefs what we have already conceded to scientific beliefs. For the analogy between them is complete. Both are natural products. Neither rank among their re- moter causes any which share their essence. And as it is easy to trace back our scientific beliefs to sources which have about them nothing which is rational, so it is easy to trace back our ethical be- liefs to sources which have about them nothing which is ethical. Both require us, therefore, to seek behind these phenomenal sources for some ultimate ground with which they shall be congruous ; and as we have been moved to postulate a rational God in A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 333 the interests of science, so we can scarcely decline to postulate a moral God in the interests of moral- ity. But, manifestly, those who have gone thus far cannot rest here. If we are to assign a ' providen- tial ' origin to the long and complex train of events which have resulted in the recognition of a moral law, we must embrace within the same theory those sentiments and influences, without which a moi'al law would tend to become a mere catalogue of com- mandments, possessed, it may be, of an undisputed authority, but obtaining on that account but little obedience. This was the point on which I dwelt at length in the first portion of this Essay. I then showed, that if the pedigrees of conscience, of our ethical ideals, of our capacity for admiration, for sympathy, for repentance, for righteous indignation, were finally to lose themselves among the accidental variations on which Selection does its work, it was inconceivable that they should retain their virtue when once the creed of naturalism had thoroughly penetrated and discoloured every mood of thought and belief. But if, deserting naturalism, we regard the evolutionary process issuing in these ethical re- sults as an instrument for carrying out a Divine purpose, the natural history of the higher sentiments is seen under a wholly different light. They may be due, df)ubtless they are in fact due, to the same selective mechanism which produces the most cruel and the most disgusting of Nature's contrivances for 334 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION protecting the species of some loathsome parasite. Between the two cases science cannot, and natural- ism will not, draw any valid distinction. But here theology steps in, and by the conception of design revolutionises our point of view. The most un- lovely germ of instinct or of appetite to which we trace back the origin of all that is most noble and of good report, no longer throws discredit upon its developed offshoots. Rather is it consecrated by them. For if, in the region of Causation, it is wholly by the earlier stages that the later are determined, in the region of Design it is only through the later stages that the earlier can be understood. But if these be the consequences which flow from substituting a theological for a naturalistic inter- pretation of science, of ethics, and of ethical senti- ments, what changes will the same process effect in our conception of gesthetics? Naturalism, as we saw, destroys the possibility of objective beauty — of beauty as a real, persistent quality of objects ; and leaves nothing but feelings of beauty on the one side, and on the other a miscellaneous assortment of objects, called beautiful in their moments of favour, by which, through the chance operation of obscure associations, at some period, and in some persons, these feelings of beauty are aroused. A conclusion of this kind no doubt leaves us chilled and depressed spectators of our own assthetic enthusiasms. And it may be that to put the scientific theory in a theo- logical setting, instead of in a naturalistic one, will A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 335 not wholly remove the unsatisfactory effect which the theory itself may leave upon the mind. And yet it surely does something. If we cannot say that Beauty is in any particular case an * objective ' fact, in the sense in which science requires us to believe that ' mass/ for example, and ' configuration,' are 'objective' facts, we are not precluded on that account from referring our feeling of it to God, nor from supposing that in the thrill of some deep emo- tion we have for an instant caught a far-off reflec- tion of Divine beauty. This is, indeed, my faith ; and in it the differences of taste which divide man- kind lose all their harshness. For we may liken ourselves to the members of some endless proces- sion winding along the borders of a sunlit lake. Towards each individual there will shine along its surface a moving lane of splendour, where the ripples catch and deflect the light in his direction ; while on either hand the waters, which to his neigh- bour's eyes are brilliant in the sun, for him lie dull and undistinguished. So may all possess a like en- joyment of loveliness. So do all owe it to one un- changing Source. And if there be an endless variety in the immediate objects from which we severally derive it, I know not, after all, that this should furnish any matter for regret. 336 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION II And, lastly, we come to theology, denied by naturalism to be a branch of knowledge at all, but whose truth we have been obliged to assume in order to find a basis for the only knowledge which naturalism allows. Those who are prepared to admit that, in dealing with the causes of scientific and ethical belief, the theory which offers least difficulty is that which assumes them to have been ' providentially ' guided, are not likely to raise objections to a similar theory in the case of religion. For here, at least, might we expect preferential Divine intervention, supposing such intervention were anywhere possible. Much more, then, if it be accepted as actual in other regions of belief. And this is, in fact, the ordinary view of mankind. They have almost always claimed for their beliefs about God that they were due to God. The belief in religion has almost always carried with it, in some shape or other, the belief in Inspiration. To this rule there is, no doubt, to be found an apparent exception in what is known as natural re- ligion — natural religion being defined as the religion to which unassisted reason may attain, in contrast to that which can be reached only by the aid of rev- elation. But, for my own part, I object altogether to the theory underlying this distinction. I do not believe that, strictly speaking, there is any such A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 337 thing as ' unassisted reason.' And I am sure that if there be, the conclusions of ' natural religion ' are not among its products. The attentive reader does not require to be told that, according to the views here advocated, every idea involved in such a proposition as that ' There is a moral Creator and Ruler of the world ' (which I may assume, for purposes of illus- tration, to constitute the substance of natural re- ligion) is due to a complex of causes, of which human reason was not the most important; and that this natural religion never would have been heard of, much less have been received with approval, had it not been for that traditional religion of which it vainly supposes itself to be independent. But if this way of considering the matter be ac- cepted ; if we are to apply unaltered, in the case of religious beliefs, the procedure already adopted in the case of scientific, ethical, and aesthetic beliefs, and assume for them a Cause harmonious with their essential nature, we must evidently in so doing trans- cend the common division between ' natural ' and ' supernatural.' We cannot consent to see the 'pref- erential working of Divine power' only in those religious manifestations which refuse to accommo- date themselves to our conception (whatever that may be) of the strictly ' natural ' order of the world ; nor can we deny a Divine origin to those aspects of religious development whicli natural laws seem com- petent to explain. The; familiar distinction, indeed, between ' natural ' and ' supernatural ' coincides 22 338 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION neither with that between natural and spiritual, nor with that between ' preferential action ' and ' non- preferential,' nor with that between ' phenomenal ' and ' noumenal.' It is, perhaps, less important than is sometimes supposed ; and in this particular con- nection, at all events, is, as it seems to me, merel}^ irrelevant and confusing — a burden, not an aid, to religious speculation. For, whatever difference there may be between the growth of theological knowledge and of other knowledere, their resemblances are both numerous and instructive. In both we note that movement has been sometimes so rapid as to be revolutionary, sometimes so slow as to be imperceptible. In both, that it has been sometimes an advance, sometimes a retrogression. In both, that it has been some- times on lines permitting a long, perhaps an indefi- nite, development, sometimes in directions where far- ther progress seems barred for ever. In both, that the higher is, from the point of view of science, largely produced by the lower. In both, that, from the point of view of our provisional philosophy, the lower is only to be explained by the higher. In both, that the final product counts among its causes a vast multitude of physiological, psychological, political, and social antecedents with which it has no direct rational or spiritual affiliation. How, then, can we most completely absorb these facts into our theory of Inspiration? It would, no doubt, be inaccurate to say that inspiration is that, A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 339 seen from its Divine side, which we call discovery when seen from the human side. But it is not, I think, inaccurate to say that every addition to knowl- edge, whether in the individual or the community, whether scientific, ethical, or theological, is due to a co-operation between the human soul which assimi- lates and the Divine power which inspires. Neither acts, or, as far as we can pronounce upon such mat- ters, could act, in independent isolation. For ' un- assisted reason ' is, as I have already said, a fiction : and pure receptivity it is impossible to conceive. Even the emptiest vessel must limit the quantity and determine the configuration of any liquid with which it may be filled. But because this view involves a use of the term 'inspiration' which, ignoring all minor distinctions, extends it to every case in which the production of belief is due to the 'preferential action' of Divine power, it does not, of course, follow that minor dis- tinctions do not exist. All I wish here to insist on is, that the sphere of Divine influence in matters of belief exists as a whole, and may therefore be studied as a whole ; and that, not improbably, to study it as a whole would prove no unprofitable preliminary to any examination into the character of its more im- portant parts. So studied, it becomes evident that Inspiration, if this use of the word is to be allowed, is limited to no age, to no country, to no people. It is required by those who learn not less than by those who teach. 340 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION Wherever an approach has been made to truth, wherever any individual soul has assimilated some old discovery, or has forced the secret of a new one^ there is its co-operation to be discovered. Its work- ings are to be traced not merely in the later devel- opment of beliefs, but far back among their unhon- oured beginnings. Its aid has been granted not merely along the main line of religious progress, but in the side-alleys to which there seems no issue. Are we, for example, to find a full measure of inspi- ration in the highest utterances of Hebrew prophet or psalmist, and to suppose that the primitive relig- ious conceptions common to the Semitic race had in them no touch of the Divine? Hardly, if we also believe that it was these primitive conceptions which the ' Chosen People ' were divinely ordained to pu- rify, to elevate, and to expand until they became fitting elements in a religion adequate to the neces- sities of a world. Are we, again, to deny any meas- ure of inspiration to the ethico-religious teaching of the great Oriental reformers, because there was that in their general systems of doctrine which pre- vented, and still prevents, these from merging as a whole in the main stream of religious advance ? Hardly, unless we are prepared to admit that men may gather grapes from thorns or figs from thistles. These things assuredly are of God ; and whatever be the terms in which we choose to express our faith, let us not give colour to the opinion that His assistance to mankind has been narrowed down to A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 34 1 the sources, however unique, from which we imme- diately, and consciously, draw our own spiritual nourishment. If a preference is shown by any for a more limited conception of the Divine intervention in matters of belief, it must, I suppose, be on one of two grounds. It may, in the first place, arise out of a natural reluctance to force into the same cate- gory the transcendent intuitions of prophet or apostle and the stammering utterances of earlier faiths, clouded as these are by human ignorance and marred by human sin. Things spiritually so far asunder ought not, it ma}^ be thought, by any sys- tem of classification, to be brought together. They belong to separate worlds. They differ not merely infinitely in degree, but absolutely in kind ; and a risk of serious error must arise if the same term is loosely and hastily applied to things which, in their essential nature, lie so far apart. Now, that there may be, or, rather, plainly are, many modes in which belief is assisted by Divine co-operation I have already admitted. That the word ' inspiration ' may, with advantage, be con- fined to one or more of these I do not desire to deny. It is a question of theological phrenology, on which I am not competent to pronounce ; and if I have seized upon the word for the purposes of my argument, it is with no desire to confound any dis- tinction which ought to be preserved, but because there is ntj other term w hich so pointedly expresses 342 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION that Divine element in the formation of beliefs on which it was my business to lay stress. This, if my theory be true, does, after all, exist, howsoever it may be described, to the full extent which I have indicated ; and though the beliefs which it assists in producing differ infinitely from one another in their nearness to absolute truth, the fact is not disguised, nor the honour due to the most spiritually perfect utterances in aught imperilled, by recognising in all some marks of Divine intervention. But, in the second place, it may be objected that inspiration thus broadly conceived is incapable of providing mankind with any satisfactory criterion of religious truth. Since its co-operation can be traced in so much that is imperfect, the mere fact of its co-operation cannot in any particular case be a pro- tection even against gross error. If, therefore, we seek in it not merely a Divinely ordered cause of belief, but also a Divinely ordered ground for believ- ing, there must be some means of marking off those examples of its operation which rightfully command our full intellectual allegiance, from those which are no more than evidences of an influence towards the truth working out its purpose slowly through the ages. This is beyond dispute. Nothing that I have said about inspiration in general as a source of belief affects in any way the character of certain instances of inspiration as an authority for belief. Nor was it intended to do so ; for the problem, or group of A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 343 problems, which would thus have been raised is altogether beside the main course of my argument. They belong, not to an Introduction to Theology, but to theology itself. Whether there is an authority in religious matters of a kind altogether without parallel in scientific or ethical matters; what, if it ex- ists, is its character, and whence come its claims to our obedience, are questions on which theologians have differed, and still differ, and which it is quite beyond my province to decide. For the subject of this Essay is the 'foundations of belief,* and, as I have already indicated,' the kind of authority con- templated by theologians is never ' fundamental,' in the sense in which that word is here used. The deliverances of no organisation, of no individual, of no record, can lie at the roots of belief as reason, whatever they may do as cause. It is always possi- ble to ask whence these claimants to authority derive their credentials, what titles the orsfanisation or the individual possesses to our obedience, whether the records are authentic, and what is their precise im- port. And the mere fact that such questions may be put, and that they can neither be thrust aside as irrelevant nor be answered without elaborate critical and historical discussion, shows clearly enough that we have no business with them here. ' See atite, chapter on Authority and Reason. 344 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION III But although it is evidently beyond the scope of this work to enter upon even an elementary discus- sion of theological method, it seems right that 1 should endeavour, in strict continuation of the argu- ment of this chapter, to say something on the source from which, according to Christianity, any religious authority whatever must ultimately derive its ju- risdiction. What I have so far tried to establish is this — that the great body of our beliefs, scientific, ethical, aesthetic, theological, form a more coherent and satisfactory whole if we consider them in a Theistic setting, than if we consider them in a Nat- uralistic one. The further question, therefore, inevitably suggests itself. Whether we can carry the process a step further, and say that they are more coherent and satisfactory if considered in a Chris- tian setting than in a merely Theistic one? The answer often given is in the negative. It is always assumed by those who do not accept the doctrine of the Incarnation, and it is not uncommonly conceded by those who do, that it constitutes an ad- ditional burden upon faith, a new stumbling-block to reason. And many who are prepared to accom- modate their beliefs to the requirements of (so-called) ' Natural Religion,' shrink from the difhculties and perplexities in which this central mystery of Revealed Religion threatens to involve them. But what are A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 345 these difficulties? Clearly they are not scientific. We are here altogether outside the region where scientific ideas possess any worth, or scientific cate- gories claim any authority. It may be a realm of shadows, of empty dreams, and vain speculations. But whether it be this, or whether it be the abiding- place of the highest Reality, it evidently must be explored by methods other than those provided for us by the accepted canons of experimental research. Even when we are endeavouring to comprehend the relation of our own finite personalities to the material environment with which they are so intimately con- nected, we find, as we have seen, that all familiar modes of explanation break down and become mean- ingless. Yet we certainly exist, and presumably we have bodies. If, then, we cannot devise formulae which shall elucidate the familiar mystery of our daily existence, we need neither be surprised nor embarrassed if the unique mystery of the Christian faith refuses to lend itself to inductive treatment. But though the very uniqueness of the doctrine places it beyond the ordinary range of scientific criticism, the same cannot be said for the historical evidence on which, in part at least, it rests. Here, it will perhaps be urged, wc are on solid and familiar ground. We have only got to ignore the arbitrary distinction between ' sacred ' and * secular,' and apply the well-understood methods of historic criticism to a particular set of ancient records, in order to extract from them all that is necessary to satisfy our curi- 346 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION osity. If they break down under cross-examination, we need trouble ourselves no further about the metaphysical dogmas to which they point. No im- munity or privilege claimed for the subject-matter of belief can extend to the merely human evidence adduced in its support ; and as in the last resort, the historical element in Christianity does evidently rest on human testimony, nothing can be simpler than to subject this to the usual scientific tests, and accept with what equanimity we may any results which they elicit. But, in truth, the question is not so simple as those who make use of arguments like these would have us suppose. ' Historic method * has its limita- tions. It is self-sufficient only within an area which is, indeed, tolerably extensive, but which does not embrace the universe. For, without taking any very deep plunge into the philosophy of historical criti- cism, we may easily perceive that our judgment as to the truth or falsity of any particular historic state- ment depends, partly on our estimate of the writer's trustworthiness, partly on our estimate of his means of information, partly on our estimate of the intrin- sic probability of the facts to which he testifies. But these things are not ' independent variables,' to be measured separately before their results are balanced and summed up. On the contrary, it is manifest that, in many cases, our opinions on the trustworthi- ness and competence of the witnesses is modified by oar opinion as to the inherent likelihood of what A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 34/ they tell us ; and that our opinion as to the inherent likelihood of what they tell us may depend on considerations with respect to which no historical method is able to give us any conclusive informa- tion. In most cases, no doubt, these questions of antecedent probability have to be themselves de- cided solely, or mainly, on historic grounds, and, fail- ing anything more scientific, by a kind of historic instinct. But other cases there are, though they be rare, to whose consideration we must bring larger principles, drawn from a wider theory of the world ; and among these should be counted as first, both in speculative interest and in ethical importance, the early records of Christianity. That this has been done, and, from their own point of view, quite rightly done, by various de- structive schools of New Testament criticism, every- one is aware. Starting from a philosophy which for- bade them to accept much of the substance of the Gospel narrative, they very properly set to work to devise a variety of hypotheses which would account for the fact that the narrative, with all its peculiari- ties, was nevertheless there. Of these hypotheses there are many, and some of them have occasioned an admirable display of erudite ingenuity, fruitful of instruction from every point of view, and for all time. But it is a great, though common, error to describe these learned efforts as examples of the un- biassed application of historic methods to historic documents. It would be more correct to say that 348 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION they are endeavours, by the unstinted employment of an elabolate critical apparatus, to force the testi- mony of existing records into conformity with the- ories on the truth or falsity of which it is for philos- ophy, not history, to pronounce. What view I take of the particular philosophy to which these critics make appeal the reader already knows ; but our immediate concern is not again to discuss the presuppositions with which other people have approached the con- sideration of New Testament history, but to arrive at some conclusion about our own. How, then, ought the general theory of things at which we have arrived to affect our estimate of the antecedent probability of the Christian views of Christ? Or, if such a phrase as 'antecedent proba- bility ' be thought to suggest a much greater nicety of calculation than is at all possible in a case like this, in what temper of mind, in what mood of ex- pectation, ought our provisional philosophy to in- duce us to consider the extant historic evidence for the Christian story ? The reply must, I think, de- pend, as I shair show in a moment, upon the view we take of the ethical import of Christianity ; while its ethical import, again, must depend on the degree to which it ministers to our ethical needs. A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 349 IV Now ethical needs, important though they are, occupy no great space, as a rule, in the works of ethical writers. I do not say this by way of criti- cism ; for I grant that any examination into these needs would have only an indirect bearing on the essential subject-matter of ethical philosophy, since no inquiry into their nature, history, or value would help either to establish the fundamental principles of a moral code or to elaborate its details. But, after all, as I have said before, an assortment of ' categorical imperatives,' however authoritative and complete, supplies but a meagre outfit wherewith to meet the storms and stresses of actual experience. If we are to possess a practical system, which shall not merely tell men what they ought to do, but assist them to do it ; still more, if we are to regard the spiritual quality of the soul as possessing an in- trinsic value not to be wholly measured by the ex- ternal actions to which it gives rise, much more than this will be required. It will not only be necessary to claim the assistance of those ethical aspirations and ideals which are not less effectual for their purpose though nothing corresponding to them should exist, but it will also be necessary, if it be possible, to meet those ethical needs which must work more harm than good unless we can sustain the belief that there is somewhere to be 350 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION found a Reality wherein they can find their satis- faction. These are facts of moral psychology which thus broadly stated, nobody, I think, will be disposed to dispute, although the widest differences of opinion may and do prevail as to the character, number and relative importance of the ethical needs thus called into existence by ethical commands. It is, further, certain, though more difficulty may be felt in ad- mitting it, that these needs can be satisfied in many cases but imperfectly, in some cases not at all, with- out the aid of theology and of theological sanctions. One commonly recognised ethical need, for exam- ple, is for harmony between the interests of the in- dividual and those of the community. In a rude and limited fashion, and for a very narrow circle of ethical commands, this is deliberately provided by the prison and the scaffold, the whole machinery of the criminal law. It is provided, with less delibera- tion, but with greater delicacy of adjustment, and over a wider area of duty, by the operation of pub- lic opinion. But it can be provided, with any ap- proach to theoretical perfection, only by a future life, such as that which is assumed in more than one system of religious belief. Now the question is at once suggested by cases of this kind whether, and, if so, under what limita- tions, we can argue from the existence of an ethical need to the reality of the conditions under which alone it would be satisfied. Can we, for example. A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 35 1 argue from the need for some complete correspond- ence between virtue and felicity, to the reality of another world than this, where such a correspond- ence will be completely effected ? A great ethical philosopher has, in substance, asserted that we can. He held that the reality of the Moral Law implied the reality of a sphere where it could for ever be obeyed, under conditions satisfactory to the ' Practi- cal Reason ' ; and it was thus that he found a place in his system for Freedom, for Immortality, and for God. The metaphysical machinery, indeed, by which Kant endeavoured to secure these results is of a kind which we cannot employ. But we may well ask whether somewhat similar inferences are not iitting portions of the provisional philosophy I am endeav- ouring to recommend ; and, in particular, whether they do not harmonise with the train of thought we have been pursuing in the course of this Chapter. If the reality of scientific and of ethical knowledge forces us to assume the existence of a rational and moral Deity, by whose preferential assistance they have gradually come into existence, must we not suppose that the Power which has thus produced in man the knowledge of right and wrong, and has added to it the faculty of creating ethical ideals, must have provided some satisfaction for the ethical needs which the historical development of the spirit- ual life has gradually called into existence? Manifestly the argument in this shape is one which must be used with caution. To reason purely 352 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION a priori from our general notions concerning the working of Divine Providence to the reality of particular historic events in time, or to the preva- lence of particular conditions of existence through eternity, would imply a knowledge of Divine mat- ters which we certainly do not possess, and which, our faculties remaining what they are, a revelation Irom Heaven could not, I suppose, communicate to us. My contention, at all events, is of a much humbler kind. I confine myself to asking whether, in a universe which, by hypothesis, is under moral governance, there is not a presumption in favour of facts or events which minister, if true, to our highest moral demands ? and whether such a presumption, if it exists, is not sufficient, and more than sufficient, to neutralise the counter- presumption which has uncritically governed so much of the criticism di- rected in recent times against the historic claims of Christianity? For my own part, I cannot doubt that both these questions should be answered in the affirmative ; and if the reader will consider the variety of ways by which Christianity is, in fact, fitted effectually to minister to our ethical needs, I find it hard to believe that he will arrive at any dif- ferent conclusion. A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 353 V I need not say that no complete treatment of this question is contemplated here. Any adequate survey of the relation in which Christianity stands to the moral needs of man would lead us into the very heart of theology, and would require us to consider topics altogether unsuited to these con- troversial pages. Yet it may, perhaps, be found possible to illustrate my meaning without penetrat- ing far into territories usually occupied by theo- logians; while, at the same time, the examples of which I shall make use may serve to show that, among the needs ministered to by Christianity, are some which increase rather than diminish with the growth of knowledge and the progress of science ; and that this Religion is therefore no mere reform, appropriate only to a vanished epoch in the history of culture and civilisation, but a development of theism now more necessary to us than ever. I am aware, of course, that this may seem in strange discord with opinions very commonly held. There are many persons who suppose that, in addi- tion to any metaphysical or scientific objections to Christian doctrines, there has arisen a legitimate feeling of intellectual repulsion to them, directly due to our more extended perception of the magni- 23 354 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION tilde and complexity of the material world. The discovery of Copernicus, it has been said, is the death-blow to Christianity: in other words, the recognition by the human race of the insignificant part which they and their planet play in the cosmic drama renders the Incarnation, as it were, intrinsi- cally incredible. This is not a question of logic, or science, or history. No criticism of documents, no haggling over ' natural ' or ' supernatural,' either creates the difficulty or is able to solve it. For it arises out of what I may almost call an aesthetic sense of disproportion. ' What is man, that Thou art mindful of him ; and the son of man, that Thou visitest him ? ' is a question charged by science with a weight of meaning far beyond what it could have borne for the poet whose lips first uttered it. And those whose studies bring perpetually to their remembrance the immensity of this material world, who know how brief and how utterly im- perceptible is the impress made by organic life in general, and by human life in particular, upon the mighty forces which surround them, find it hard to believe that on so small an occasion this petty satellite of no very important sun has been chosen as the theatre of an event so solitary and so stu- pendous. Reflection, indeed, shows that those who thus argue have manifestly permitted their thoughts about God to be controlled by a singular theory of His relations to man and to the world, based on an A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 355 unbalanced consideration of the vastness of Nature. They have conceived Him as moved by the mass of His own works; as lost in spaces of His own crea- tion. Consciously or unconsciously, they have fallen into the absurdity of supposing that He considers His creatures, as it were, with the eyes of a con- tractor or a politician ; that He measures their value according- to their physical or intellectual im- portance ; and that He sets store by the number of square miles they inhabit or the foot-pounds of energy they are capable of developing. In truth, the inference they should have drawn is of precise- ly the opposite kind. The very sense of the place occupied in the material universe by man the in- telligent animal, creates in man the moral being a new need for Christianity, which, before science measured out the heavens for us, can hardly be said to have existed. Metaphysically speaking, our opinions on the magnitude and complexity of the natural world should, indeed, have no bearing on our conception of God's relation, either to us or to it. Though we supposed the sun to have been created some six thousand years ago, and to be 'about the size of the Peloponnesus,' yet the funda- mental problems concerning time and space, matter and spirit, God and man, would not on that account have to be formally restated. But then, we are not creatures of pure reason; and those who desire the assurance of an intimate and effectual relation with the Divine life, and who look to this for strength 356 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION and consolation, find that the progress of scientific knowledge makes it more and more difficult to ob- tain it by the aid of any merely speculative theism. The feeling of trusting dependence which was easy for the primitive tribes, who regarded themselves as their God's peculiar charge, and supposed Him in some special sense to dwell among them, is not easy for us ; nor does it tend to become easier. We can no longer share their naive anthropomorphism. We search out God with eyes grown old in study- ing Nature, with minds fatigued by centuries of metaphysic, and imaginations glutted with material infinities. It is in vain that we describe Him as im- manent in creation, and refuse to reduce Him to an abstraction, be it deistic or be it pantheistic. The overwhelming force and regularity of the great nat- ural movements dull the sharp impression of an ever-present Personality deeply concerned in our spiritual well-being. He is hidden, not revealed, in the multitude of phenomena, and as our knowledge of phenomena increases. He retreats out of ail real- ised connection with us farther and yet farther into the illimitable unknown. Then it is that, through the aid of Christian doc- trine, we are saved from the distorting influences of our own discoveries. The Incarnation throws the whole scheme of things, as we are too easily apt to represent it to ourselves, into a different and far truer proportion. It abruptly changes the vv^hole scale on which we might be disposed to measure A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 357 the magnitudes of the universe. What we should otherwise think great, we now perceive to be rela- tively small. What we should otherwise think trifling, we now know to be immeasurably impor- tant. And the change is not only morally needed, but is philosophically justified. Speculation by it- self should be sufficient to convince us that, in the sight of a righteous God, material grandeur and moral excellencies are incommensurable quantities ; and that an infinite accumulation of the one cannot compensate for the smallest diminution of the other. Yet I know not whether, as a theistic speculation, this truth could effectually maintain itself against the brute pressure of external Nature. In the world looked at by the light of simple theism, the evi- dences of God's material power lie about us on every side, daily added to by science, universal, overwhelming. The evidences of His moral inter- est have to be anxiously extracted, grain by grain, through the speculative analysis of our moral nature. Mankind, however, are not given to speculative analysis ; and if it be desirable that they should be enabled to obtain an imaginative grasp of this great truth ; if they need to have brought home to them that, in the sight of God, the stability of the heavens is of less importance than the moral growth of a human si)irit, I know not how this end could be more completely attained than by the Christian doc- trine of the Incarnation. A somewhat similar train of thought is suggested 358 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION by the progress of one particular branch of scien- tific investigation. Mankind can never have been ignorant of the dependence of mind on body. The feebleness of infancy, the decay of age, the effects of sickness, fatigue, and pain, are facts too obvious and too insistent ever to have passed unnoticed. But the movement of discovery has prodigiously emphasised our sense of dependence on matter. We now know that it is no loose or variable connection which ties mind to body. There may, indeed, be neural changes which do not issue in consciousness ; but there is no consciousness, so far as accepted observations and experiments can tell us, which is not associated with neural changes. Looked at, therefore, from the outside, from the point of view necessarily adopted by the biologist, the spiritual life seems, as it were, but an intermittent phospho- rescence accompanying the cerebral changes in certain highly organised mammals. And science, through countless channels, with irresistible force drives home to each one of us the lesson that we are severally bound over in perpetual servitude to a body for whose existence and qualities we have no responsibility whatever. As the reader is well aware, views like these will not stand critical examination. Of all creeds, materialism is the one which, looked at from the inside — from the point of view of knowledge and the knowing Self— is least capable of being philo- sophically defended, or even coherently stated. A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 359 Nevertheless, the burden of the body is not, in practice, to be disposed of by any mere process of critical analysis. From birth to death, without pause or respite, it encumbers us on our path. We can never disentangle ourselves from its meshes, nor divide with it the responsibility for our joint performances. Conscience may tell us that we ougJit to control it, and that we can. But science, hinting that, after all, we are but its product and its plaything, receives ominous support from our ex- periences of mankind. Philosophy may assure us that the account of body and mind given by mate- rialism is neither consistent nor intelligible. Yet body remains the most fundamental and all-pervad- ing fact with which mind has got to deal, the one from which it can least easily shake itself free, the one that most complacently lends itself to every theory destructive of high endeavour. Now, what is wanted here is not abstract specu- lation or negative dialectic. These, indeed, may lend us their aid, but they are not very powerful allies in this particular species of warfare. They can assure us, with a well-grounded confidence, that materialism is wrcjng, but they have (as I think) nothing satisfactory to put in its place, and cannot pretend to any theoretic explanation which shall cover all the facts. What we need, then, is some- thing that shall appeal to men of flesh and blood, struggling with the temptations and discourage- ments which ilesh and blood is heir to : confused 6o A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION and baffled by theories of heredity: sure that the physiological view represents at least one aspect of the truth ; not sure how any larger and more con- soling truth can be welded on to it; yet swayed towards the materialist side less, it may be, by materialist reasoning than by the inner confirma- tion which a humiliating experience gives them of their own subjection to the body. What support does the belief in a Deity inef- fably remote from all human conditions bring to men thus hesitating whether they are to count themselves as beasts that perish, or among the Sons of God ? What bridge can be found to span the immeasurable gulf which separates Infinite Spirit from creatures who seem little more than physi- ological accidents? What faith is there, other than the Incarnation, which will enable us to realise that, however far apart, they are not hopelessly divided ? The intellectual perplexities which haunt us in that dim region where mind and matter meet may not be thus allayed. But they who think with me that, though it is a hard thing for us to believe that we are made in the likeness of God, it is yet a very necessary thing, will not be anxious to deny that an efTectual trust in this great truth, a full satisfaction of this ethical need, are among the natural fruits of a Christian theory of the world. One more topic there is, of the same family as those with which we have just been dealing, to which, before concluding, I must briefly direct the A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 36 1 reader's attention. I have already said something about what is known as the ' problem of evil,' and the immemorial difficulty which it throws in the way of a completely coherent theory of the world on a religious or moral basis. I do not suggest now that the doctrine of the Incarnation supplies any philosophic solution of this difficulty. I content myself with pointing out that the difficulty is much less oppressive under the Christian than under any simpler form of Theism ; and that though it may re- tain undiminished whatever speculative force it pos- sesses, its moral grip is loosened, and it no longer parches up the springs of spiritual hope or crushes moral aspiration. For where precisely does the difficulty lie ? It lies in the belief that an all-powerful Deity has chosen out of an infinite, or at least an unknown, number of possibilities to create a world in which pain is a prominent, and apparently an ineradicable, element. His action on this view is, so to speak, gratuitous. He might have done otherwise ; He has done thus. He might have created sentient beings capable of nothing but happiness ; He has in fact created them prone to misery, and subject by their very constitution and circumstances to extreme possibilities of physical pain and mental affliction. How can One of Whom this can be said excite our love? How can He claim our obedience? How can He be a fitting object of praise, reverence, and worship? So runs the familiar argument, accepted 362 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION by some as a permanent element in their melancholy philosophy ; wrung from others as a cry of anguish under the sudden stroke of bitter experience. This reasoning is in essence an explication of what is supposed to be involved in the attribute of Omnipotence ; and the sting of its conclusion lies in the inferred indifference of God to the sufferings of His creatures. There are, therefore, two points at which it may be assailed. We may argue, in the first place, that in dealing with subjects so far above our reach, it is in general the height of philosophic temerity to squeeze out of every predicate the last significant drop it can apparently be forced to yield ; or drive all the arguments it suggests to their ex- treme logical conclusions. And, in particular, it may be urged that it is erroneous, perhaps even unmeaning, to say that the universality of Omnip- otence includes the power to do that which is ir- rational ; and that, without knowing the Whole, we cannot say of any part whether it is rational or not. These are metaphysical considerations which, so long as they are used critically, and not dogmatically, negatively, not positively, seem to me to have force. But there is a second line of attack, on which it is more my business to insist. I have already pointed out that ethics cannot permanently flourish side by side with a creed which represents God as indifferent to pain and sin ; so that, if our provisional philoso- phy is to include morality within its circuit (and A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 363 what harmony of knowledge would that be which did not ?), the conclusions which apparently follow from the co-existence of Omnipotence and of Evil are not to be accepted. Yet this speculative reply is, after all, but a fair-weather argument ; too abstract easily to move mankind at large, too frail for the sup- port, even of a philosopher, in moments of extrem- ity. Of what use is it to those who, under the stress of sorrow, are permitting themselves to doubt the goodness of God, that such doubts must inevitably tend to wither virtue at the root ? No such conclu- sion will frighten them. They have already almost reached it. Of what worth, they cry, is virtue in a world where sufferings like theirs fall alike on the just and on the unjust? For themselves, they know only that they are solitary and abandoned ; victims of a Power too strong for them to control, too callous for them to soften, too far for them to reach, deaf to supplication, blind to pain. Tell them, with certain theologians, that their misfortunes are explained and justified by an hereditary taint ; tell them, with certain philosophers, that, could they understand the world in its completeness, their agony would show itself an element necessary to the harmony of the Whole, and they will think you are mocking them. What- ever be the worth of speculations like these, it is not in the moments when they are most required that they come effectually to our rescue. What is needed is such a living faith in God's relation to Man as shall leave no place for that helpless resentment 364 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION against the appointed Order so apt to I'ise within us at the sight of undeserved pain. And this faith is possessed by those who vividly realise the Christian form of Theism. For they worship One who is no remote contriver of a universe to whose ills He is indifferent. If they suffer, did He not on their account suffer also? If suffering falls not always on the most guilty, was He not innocent? Shall they cry aloud that the world is ill-designed for their convenience, when He for their sakes subjected Himself to its conditions? It is true that beliefs like these do not in any narrow sense resolve our doubts nor provide us with explanations. But they give us something better than many explanations. For they minister, or rather the Reality behind them ministers, to one of our deepest ethical needs : to a need which, far from showing signs of diminution, seems to grow with the growth of civilisation, and to touch us ever more keenly as the hardness of an earlier time dissolves away. Here, then, on the threshold of Christian Theol- ogy, I bring my task to a conclusion. I feel, on looking back over the completed work, even more strongly than I felt during its progress, how hard was the task I have undertaken, and how far beyond my powers successfully to accomplish. For I have aimed at nothing less than to show, within a reason- A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION 365 able compass and in a manner to be understood by all, how, in face of the complex tendencies which sway this strange age of ours, we may best draw to- gether our beliefs into a comprehensive unity which shall possess at least a relative and provisional sta- bility. In so bold an attempt I may well have failed. Yet, whatever be the particular weaknesses and de- fects which mar the success of my endeavours, three or four broad principles emerge from the discussion, the essential importance of which I find it impos- sible to doubt, whatever errors I may have made in their application. 1. It seems beyond question that any system which, with our present knowledge and, it may be, our existing faculties, we are able to construct must suffer from obscurities, from defects of proof, and from incoherences. Narrow it down to bare science — and no one has seriously proposed to re- duce it further — you will still find all three, and in plenty. 2. No unification of belief of the slightest the- oretical value can take place on a purely scien- tific basis — on a basis, I mean, of induction from particular experiences, whether ' external ' or * inter- nal.' 3. No philosophy or theory of knowledge (epis- temology) can be satisfactory which does not find room within it for the quite obvious, but not suffi- ciently considered fact that, so far as empirical science can tell us anything about the matter, most 366 A PROVISIONAL UNIFICATION of the proximate causes of belief, and all its ultimate causes, are non-rational in their character. 4. No unification of beliefs can be practically adequate which does not include ethical beliefs as well as scientific ones; nor which refuses to count among ethical beliefs, not merely those which have immediate reference to moral commands, but those also which make possible moral sentiments, ideals and aspirations, and which satisfy our ethical needs. Any system which, when worked out to its legiti- mate issues, fails to effect this object can afford no permanent habitation for the spirit of man. To enforce, illustrate, and apply these principles has been the main object of the preceding pages. How far I have succeeded in showing that the least incomplete unification open to us must include the fundamental elements of Theology, and of Chris- tian Theology, I leave it for others to deter- mine ; repeating only the conviction, more than once expressed in the body of this Essay, that it is not explanations which survive, but the things which are explained ; not theories, but the things about which we theorise; and that, therefore, no failure on my part can imperil the great truths, be they religious, ethical, or scientific, whose interde- pendence I have endeavoured to establish. THE END , <,/7^ I i^=?t^l SV^r^ •?=> J>-n <rjl3_3NVS01^ '^A><iAINn]WV .^^ University of California SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 305 De Neve Drive - Parking Lot 17 • Box 951388 LOS ANGELES, CALIFORNIA 90095-1388 Return this material to the library from which it was borrowed. c: I.UJ ?. <rjlJDNVS01^ %a3AINn]\V^ ^<!/0dnV3J0-^ ^ojiivdjo-^ !lfj>^ V- a s > -< 1# ^OFCAIIFOfi*^ i; vr ^<:?Aavaani^ C3 .w >- QQ I Univefsily of California, Los Anaetes L 005 492 658 9 "o ^ Virr-fflA mm FC„.. ^ ^OAbvaa ^V^OSAN'CElfX^ -n '—J CO >■ -rr ■V/sa3AIN[l-3V\V UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY -mm %OJI1VDJO-^' AA 000 514 192 4 <rji]ONV-i 01^ CO >■ \< CD .S? V</ C5 t £^ ^(5Aavaaii-^^ ^^Auvyen-^'^'^ ,-\WEUNIV #^ < ^WE-LiWIVER5-/A 2? L '^ 03 ZZ ^^VlOS-ANCflfT^ Ctf % % o S3 J^ CP «4L. <f:?130NVS01^ '^/^JI3AINn-3WV .-^ § 1 CD %dllV] 0/?^ ^.OFCAilFO/?/(A ^i I 1-1^^ ^(^Auvaan-^^"^ ,^MEUNIVER5'/A CO — : ^vWSANCElfj> C- r^ ^- CO S V > u_ -< v/^aBAiNniuv^ n k t I r ^^omu ;Ry/4 ^>;iosAN'CEifr;^ 01^^ '^/sa3AiNa-3WV' CO =o >• -< i? -ssM-UBRARYQr 1 ir^ % ^^^iLIBRARYQ^ >i 1 fr" % < r-n \\sm\y\ ] ex iiiWtllii ^