LOCKE 
 
 By 
 S. ALEXANDER 
 
 M.A., LL.D., PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY AT THE 
 UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER 
 
 LONDON 
 ARCHIBALD CONSTABLE &r CO LTD 
 
 1908 
 
A 
 
PREFATORY NOTE 
 
 I DESIRE to acknowledge my obligations to Prof. 
 Campbell Eraser's books on Locke (especially 
 the introduction to his edition of the Essay), 
 and to Mr. H. R. Fox Bourne's very valuable 
 Life of John Locke (London, 1876). In the 
 concluding chapters I have derived help from 
 Sidgwick's History of Ethics, Stephen's History 
 of English Thought in the Eighteenth Century, 
 and Prof. Ch. Bastide's John Locke : ses theories 
 politiques (Paris, 1906). I am indebted to Prof. 
 G. F. Stout for several useful suggestions. 
 
 S. A. 
 
 280217 
 
CONTENTS 
 
 CHAP. PAGE 
 
 i. LIFE 1 
 
 TI. PHILOSOPHY (THE ESSAY) 24 
 
 in. OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY .... 52 
 
 iv. ETHICS 69 
 
 v. POLITICS .75 
 
 vi. RELIGION ........ 84 
 
 BOOKS WHICH MAY BE CONSULTED 91 
 
LOCKE 
 CHAPTER I 
 
 LIFE 
 
 LOCKE'S life is one of those, not rare in the history 
 of English letters and science, in which the 
 scholar is doubled with the man of the world and 
 of public affairs. His instinct for speculation and 
 his delicate health marked him out for a life of 
 academic retirement; his talent for business and 
 his practical capacity secured him weight in 
 politics, and put within his reach, had he chosen 
 to accept them, important state employments. 
 He combined scholarly seclusion with public in- 
 fluence. In his latest years he held for a time 
 high office as a commissioner of trade; and all 
 his life he was in the background of politics, the 
 trusted adviser of Shaftesbury, of the party who 
 aimed at the establishment of William of Orange, 
 and finally, of Somers and Charles Montague. 
 Though he was always known as a man of eminent 
 parts, his fame as a writer was confined to his last 
 A i 
 
LOCKE 
 
 fifteen years. He himself chose as his profes- 
 sion the more active work of medicine, though 
 he practised it only for a few years in Shaftes- 
 bury's family, and occasionally afterwards. His 
 life was in fact that of a savant, who lived in close 
 relation to the men of science of his time, such 
 as Boyle, Sydenham, and Newton, and who, like 
 Lord Acton in our own day, was at the same time 
 the confidential friend of statesmen. It cannot 
 be doubted that his intellectual and practical 
 interests acted and reacted upon each other. 
 Though not himself the author of great public 
 measures, he took his share in many and he 
 voiced the principles of liberty which inspired 
 them. On the other hand, the devotion to truth 
 which compels him to see things for himself, as 
 they are, within the limits of his vision, is accom- 
 panied in him by a native sagacity and caution, 
 an insight, perhaps acquired in affairs, into the 
 character of men, and a sympathy with the needs 
 of the plain average man, which fitted him to 
 be the exponent of a new method of thinking 
 and to set the tone of thought to the century 
 which succeeded him. More than in the case of 
 most philosophers, Locke's history is varied with 
 incident and involved with the history of the 
 anxious and seminal time in which he lived. 
 
 2 
 
LIFE 
 
 He was born at Wrington, a village in Somerset- \ > 
 shire, on the 29th of August 1632. His father, 
 John Locke, was Clerk to the Justices of the 
 Peace, one of whom Alexander Popham took 
 command of a volunteer regiment of horse raised 
 in the parliamentary cause in 1642. The elder 
 Locke took up arms under him as a captain. He 
 suffered heavily in property by the Civil War. Of 
 his mother the younger John Locke expressed 
 himself in affectionate terms. His father educated 
 him with great care, treating him with rigour as 
 a child, but admitting him to friendship as he 
 grew up, a practice which Locke approves. A 
 letter to his father is preserved which testifies to 
 the tenderness Locke felt for him. Early years 
 are impressionable, and Locke writes in 1661, ' I 
 no sooner perceived myself in the world, but I 
 found myself in a storm which has lasted almost 
 hitherto/ By Popham's offices he was sent, pro- 
 bably in 1646, to Westminster School, then under 
 the government of the famous Dr. Richard Busby, 
 and was there put through an incessant drilling 
 in Greek and Latin, which may have made Locke 
 the good scholar he was, but may also explain the 
 depreciation which he afterwards, in his Thoughts 
 upon Education, expressed for such exercises. 
 From Westminster he proceeded in 1652, as a 
 
 3 
 
LOCKE 
 
 junior student, to Christchurch, Oxford, the Dean 
 of which was then Dr. John Owen, appointed by 
 Cromwell. Owen was also Vice -Chancellor of 
 the University, and he and his Puritan colleagues 
 worked with a will towards redeeming the Univer- 
 sity from the idleness and contempt of learning 
 into which it had fallen. Owen proclaimed and 
 taught the doctrine of toleration a fact not to be 
 forgotten in the life of the future author of the 
 Letters concerning Toleration. Locke did not 
 relish the studies of the place, and regretted that 
 his father had sent him to Oxford. He disliked 
 the public disputations in the schools, which he 
 thought ' invented for wrangling and ostentation, 
 rather than to discover truth.' He regarded his 
 early years at Oxford as wasted, because the only 
 philosophy then known there 'was the peripatetic, 
 perplexed with obscure terms and useless ques- 
 tions/ He spent, we hear, a good part of his first 
 years in the University in reading romances. But 
 he attended the lectures of the mathematicians 
 Wallis and Ward, and was intimate with Pocock, 
 the professor of Arabic. It was, however, the 
 study of Descartes which first ' gave him a relish 
 of philosophical things. He was rejoiced in read- 
 ing them, because, though he very often differed 
 in opinion from this writer, he yet found that 
 
 4 
 
LIFE 
 
 what he said was very intelligible, from whence 
 he was encouraged to think that his not having 
 understood others had possibly not proceeded 
 from a defect in his understanding/ It is not 
 easy to make out the sources of Locke's philo- 
 sophical thought except Descartes, and the Port 
 Royal Logic. Bacon he knew, and also Hobbes 
 (though, he says, not intimately), and he appears 
 to have been influenced by the atomism of 
 Gassendi. Leibniz he knew little, and expressed 
 in later life a low opinion of him. 1 Malebranche 
 he studied and criticised. But we can well believe 
 his own statement that he learned more from 
 intercourse with men than from books. 
 
 Locke became a senior student of Christchurch . 
 in 1659, and the emoluments of that office were, 
 with a small property inherited from his father of 
 about 70 a year, his main source of income till 
 1684, when he was deprived of his studentship. 
 Even when he lived in London, he paid frequent 
 and long visits to Oxford. After the Restoration, 
 a new order of things arose in the University, 
 which Locke welcomed. His bringing up as a 
 Puritan, combined with his disappointment with 
 
 1 The Nouveaux Essais, in which Leibniz expounded and 
 reviewed the Essay, Locke never saw, and indeed, owing to 
 Locke's death, it was not published in Leibniz's lifetime. 
 
 5 
 
LOCKE 
 
 the Puritan rule, may have fostered the bent of 
 his mind towards latitudinarian views of theology, 
 and towards dislike of extreme fanaticism or ' en- 
 thusiasm/ He was appointed to lectureships at 
 Christchurch usually held by clergymen. His 
 father had designed him for the ministry. But 
 Locke declined a tempting offer leading to prefer- 
 ment in the Irish Church, not desiring to commit 
 himself to a profession which he could not divest 
 himself of, supposing that he failed in it. Finally, 
 he decided upon the profession of medicine. He 
 had for some years pursued the study of physical 
 science, and had consorted with Boyle and the 
 other members of the Oxford branch of the Royal 
 Society. Boyle's History of the Air, which Locke 
 edited after Boyle's death, contains observations 
 registered by Locke from 1660 to 1667. He never 
 obtained the doctorate in medicine, and there was 
 some difficulty in securing for him the degree of 
 Bachelor, because he had not attended the regular 
 courses of lectures in medicine. He began practice 
 at Oxford, as an amateur partner of his friend 
 Dr. Thomas. 
 
 In 1665 Locke obtained, in a way which is not 
 clear, the appointment of secretary to Sir Walter 
 Vane, who went to Cleves on a special embassy to 
 the Elector of Brandenburg. Letters to his friend 
 
 6 
 
LIFE 
 
 John Strachey describe with somewhat heavy 
 humour the incidents of his stay there. Locke 
 must have shown his abilities, for, on his return, he 
 was offered an appointment in an embassy to Spain. 
 Though he was plainly much tempted, his good 
 genius saved him from diplomacy for philosophy, 
 and he remained at Oxford practising medicine. 
 
 It was in 1667 that, by an accident arising out of 
 his profession, he became acquainted with Shaftes- 
 bury an event which determined his future life. 
 Shaftesbury (then Lord Ashley) came to Oxford, 
 to drink the waters of the village of Astrop, not 
 far off, which were then much recommended. 
 Owing to some delay in the supply of the waters, 
 Locke, in the absence of Dr. Thomas, waited upon 
 Ashley to explain. The impression the two men 
 left upon each other was such as to lead to a 
 lasting friendship. Locke went to London in 1667 
 at Ashley's invitation, and thenceforth became a 
 member of Ashley's household. He acted as 
 physician to the household, though he also prac- 
 tised to some extent outside. Ashley himself 
 owed his life to an operation performed by Locke. 
 But he was not only the doctor, but was intrusted 
 with intimate private affairs of the family, arrang- 
 ing the marriage of Ashley's son, and becoming 
 thereafter tutor of the little boy who was to be the 
 
LOCKE 
 
 Shaftesbury of the Characteristics and to disown 
 the philosophy of his tutor. More important still, 
 he became Ashley's confidential adviser, though it 
 is not necessary to suppose him privy to all the 
 statesman's political actions. He helped in draw- 
 ing up in 1663 the Fundamental Constitutions for 
 the government of Carolina, of which settlement 
 Ashley was one of the proprietors. A draft of the 
 scheme exists in Locke's handwriting, and whether 
 this scheme is due to him wholly or only in part, 
 its liberal provisions for freedom of religion, if 
 only belief in God is avowed, are in keeping with 
 Locke's opinions. When Shaftesbury became 
 Chancellor in 1672, Locke became secretary of 
 presentations (to benefices), and later, secretary of 
 the recently established Council of Trade and 
 Foreign Plantations (or Colonies), an office which 
 he retained till the Council was dissolved in 1675, 
 though he does not appear to have received the 
 salary due to him. While he was thus occupied 
 in practical affairs, he still carried on his work 
 in medicine, and was allied in friendship with 
 Sydenham, who commends him in no measured 
 terms in the preface to the third edition of his 
 Method of curing Fevers (1676). In 1668, he 
 became a Fellow of the Royal Society. Though 
 he was more than once a member of Council, he 
 
 8 
 
LIFE 
 
 does not, however, seem to have taken any active 
 part in its proceedings. But about this time in a 
 small circle of friends there occurred the famous 
 meeting from which the Essay took its origin. 
 ' Five or six friends,' he says, ' meeting at my 
 chamber, and discoursing on a subject very remote 
 from this, found themselves quickly at a stand by 
 the difficulties that rose on every side. After 
 we had awhile puzzled ourselves without coming 
 nearer resolution of those doubts which perplexed 
 us, it came into my thoughts that we took a 
 wrong course, and that before we set ourselves 
 upon inquiries of that nature, it was necessary to 
 examine our own abilities, and see what objects 
 our understandings were or were not fitted to deal 
 with. This I proposed to the company, who all 
 readily assented, and thereupon it was agreed 
 that this should be our first inquiry. Some hasty 
 and undigested thoughts, on a subject I had never 
 before considered, which I set down against our 
 next meeting gave the first entrance into this 
 discourse/ We know the names of two of his 
 friends, Tyrrell and Thomas, and that the dis- 
 course was about the principles of worship and 
 revealed religion. A short paragraph dated 1671 
 of his common-place book has been preserved, 
 which marks the beginning of Locke's work. 
 
 9 
 
LOCKE 
 
 Relieved of his office in 1675, Locke spent the 
 next four years in rest and travel in France. 
 His chest always was weak, and from this time 
 forward he had constantly to struggle against 
 asthma, for which the smoke-laden air of London 
 in the winter was peculiarly unfavourable. We 
 possess journals of his sojourn in France, which 
 enable us to follow his movements and the obser- 
 vations he made there (e.g. his report on the vine- 
 yards made for Shaftesbury ). Most of his time was 
 spent at Montpellier, the great medical school, and 
 Locke describes the initiation of a young doctor 
 there, in terms which recall the famous passage 
 of Moliere's Malade Imaginaire. Some consider- 
 able time he also spent in Paris, in the society 
 of learned friends. But he returned in 1670 to 
 serve again as adviser to Shaftesbury during the 
 troubled years of the Exclusion Bill and the Whig 
 Plots, in which his movements can only obscurely 
 be traced. Shaftesbury was obliged to escape to 
 Holland in 1681, where he die.d the next year, 
 and Locke, whose political associations brought 
 him into suspicion, thought it prudent to leave 
 England for Holland in 1683, and there h re- 
 mained till after the Revolution, returning in 1689. 
 
 In Holland he made many friends, one of them 
 in particular Van Limborch, the head of the Re- 
 
 10 
 
LIFE 
 
 monstrant (or Arminian) College, to whom he 
 addressed the Epistola de Tolerantia in its Latin 
 form. After some travelling he settled at Utrecht 
 in 1684, where he learned that Charles n. had 
 compelled Fell, the Dean of Christchurch, to 
 deprive him of his Studentship as having behaved 
 'factiously and undutifully to the Government/ 
 He was left now for his support to his small 
 private property and the annuity of 100 which 
 Shaftesbury had provided for him. Not long 
 after, his name was attached to a list of persons 
 whom James n. requested the Dutch Government 
 to hand over on suspicion of being implicated in 
 Monmouth's insurrection, from which Locke had 
 carefully held himself aloof. Locke remained in 
 hiding for some time at Amsterdam and after- 
 wards settled at Cleves under an assumed name. 
 The danger was probably not so great as he feared 
 the Dutch Government would probably not 
 have surrendered him. His friend Pembroke 
 secured him James's pardon and begged him to 
 return. Locke proudly declined the pardon as 
 having been guilty of no crime. But the danger 
 was past, and he was free to consult his own desire 
 for leisure for study and removed to Rotterdam, 
 where he lived in the house of a Quaker friend, 
 Furly, and was in close association with the 
 
 n 
 
LOCKE 
 
 English exiles, more particularly Mordaunt, after- 
 wards Peterborough, and it appears even with 
 William of Orange himself. He followed William 
 to England in 1689. 
 
 With his return to London Locke's appear- 
 ance as an author begins in England. In 1690 
 appeared both the Essay concerning Human 
 Understanding and the Two Treatises of Govern- 
 ment, the latter work anonymously. The Letter , 
 concerning Toleration had appeared in its Latin 
 form (Epistola de Tolerantia) in 1685, but the 
 English translation (by William Popple) appeared ; 
 in London in 1689. This was also anonymous, 
 and great was Locke's anger when he discovered 
 subsequently that his friend Limborch had di- 
 vulged his authorship, even td an intimate friend. 
 It was never acknowledged "by him except in his 
 will. Locke is thus one of the great writers whose 
 writings have appeared in advanced age, for in 
 1689 he was fifty-seven. But the entries in his 
 common-place books and journals show that the 
 Essay was in preparation ever since 1671, and had, 
 as he said, been the subject of interrupted labours 
 during his travels in France. There is evidence 
 that a draft of it was seen by Shaftesbury before 
 1683, but it was finally prepared during his exile 
 in Holland, where he had already published an 
 
 12 
 
LIFE 
 
 abstract of it in his friend Leclerc's Bibliographic 
 Universelle in 1689. Nothing is more interesting 
 than to trace the preparation in Locke's mind for 
 his authentic deliverances, and the papers pre- 
 served to us show rather how early than how late 
 the central ideas of his various doctrines took 
 shape. Of particular interest are writings which 
 the industry of Mr. Fox Bourne has discovered 
 among the Shaftesbury papers, written by Locke 
 at various times and bearing specially on his 
 views of religious liberty. One of these dates from 
 1660: 'Whether the civil magistrate may lawfully 
 impoftfr and determine the use of indifferent things 
 in reference to religious worship ' ; which shows 
 Locke's impatience of the intolerance shown by 
 the Puritans, and the hopes, doorned'to disappoint- 
 ment, which he derived from the accession of 
 Charles n. Another is a paper of * Reflections on 
 the Roman Commonwealth' (written before 1667), 
 in which Numa is praised for his moderation in 
 what he regarded as the requirements of religion. 
 A still more important ' Essay concerning Tolera- 
 tion (1667) ' published in full by Mr. Fox Bourne 
 anticipates almost completely the Letter. It ex- 
 hibits the same desire towards non-interference 
 of the civil power with religion, exposing also the 
 folly of such interference; the same desire for 
 
 13 
 
LOCKE 
 
 a comprehensive religion which should unite all 
 sects in one national church ; the same exception 
 from toleration of atheists and also of sects like 
 the Catholic in so far as they set up another 
 temporal authority against the civil authority of 
 the land. The main outlines of Locke's famous 
 Letter have become part and parcel of our ordi- 
 nary political thinking, and this diminishes our 
 interest in it and perhaps leads us to forget the 
 audacity and originality, which, though the Letter 
 had precedents in previous writers in England and 
 in the practice of Holland, we must still acknow r - 
 ledge in it, and which gave it its influence over 
 the mind of Europe. . All the more value attaches 
 to the earlier writings which enable us to detect 
 the existence of these doctrines in the history of 
 Locke's own mind. 
 
 Locke's years from 1690 to 1704, or at least 
 from 1691, were spent in semi -retirement in 
 Essex, varied by public business in London. He 
 held office under the Crown as Commissioner of 
 Appeals for eleven or twelve years, and in the 
 more important office of a Commissioner of Trade 
 from 1695, in which office he received a salary of 
 1000. He accepted this last office only under 
 pressure. He appears to have been in fact the 
 chief member of the Board, and projected im- 
 
 14 
 
LIFE 
 
 portant work in promotion of Irish linen manu- 
 facture and of reform of the poor laws, though his 
 proposals in these respects were not put into 
 effect. His inability to bear the London winter 
 led to an early resignation which Somers pressed 
 him to reconsider, but he finally withdrew from 
 office in 1700. His influence was, however, not 
 confined to his official work. In the early years 
 of William's reign, letters from Soiners show how 
 much value was set upon his advice. One 
 incident of peculiar interest occurred in 1689, 
 when he was offered the post of ambassador to 
 Frederick i. the Elector of Brandenburg. Again 
 his good genius persuaded him to decline, on the 
 pretext of his weak health, the cold climate, and 
 his inability to support the ' warm drinking ' 
 necessary in those parts for one who was to make 
 himself acceptable. And though he was invited 
 to go to Vienna instead, Locke persisted in his 
 refusal. William showed the value he set upon 
 Locke's services by summoning him urgently at 
 a later date from Essex in the winter, for some 
 purpose not sufficiently made out, but probably 
 again of a diplomatic character; but the summons 
 cost Locke several days of severe illness. During / 
 these later years Locke concerned himself largely j 
 with economic questions. In 1692, he published [ 
 
 15 
 
LOCKE 
 
 anonymously some letters (addressed, Mr. Fox 
 Bourne thinks, to Somers) on c The consequences 
 of the lowering of interest and raising the value of 
 money' which had reference to a proposal that 
 had been made to lower the rate of interest by law, 
 and to the serious problem of the depreciation of 
 the currency which caused Locke great anxiety. 
 When Lowndes, the Secretary to the Treasury, 
 made a proposal in 1695 for raising the value of 
 money, Locke returned to the subject and rendered 
 service to Somers and Montague, who had con- 
 sulted him, in their legislation for reform of the 
 coinage. In this year also some strictures which 
 Locke had written on the Licensing Act (which 
 maintained the censorship of the press) were read 
 in a conference of the two Houses, and helped 
 towards the demolition of the Act. 
 
 Locke's country residence was at Gates, in Essex, 
 where he finally took up his abode in 1691, in the 
 house of Sir Francis Mashain, as soon as he could 
 persuade that gentleman, at whose house Locke 
 had frequently been a visitor, to accept him as a 
 permanent guest upon suitable terms. Masham's 
 wife was the daughter of Cudworth the Cambridge 
 Platonist, with whose family Locke had long been 
 on terms of friendship. Lady Masham devoted 
 herself with unfailing affection to her friend, 
 
 16 
 
LIFE 
 
 whose declining years and fragile health she 
 cheered with her intellectual companionship. 
 Her letter to Leclerc, written after Locke's death, 
 is a principal source of our knowledge of his life. 
 Masham's daughter Esther (his child by a former 
 wife) became a great friend of Locke, and a lively 
 correspondence passed when either was away from 
 home between ' Laudabridis' and 'Joannes/ While 
 at Gates, Locke carried on the greater part of the 
 immense literary work of his later life. The 
 details may be mentioned briefly. A second letter 
 concerning Toleration had appeared in 1690, in 
 answer to a criticism of the first by Jonas Proast, 
 and the long third letter published in 1692, was 
 a rejoinder to Proast's rejoinder. In 1693 Locke 
 published his Thoughts concerning Education, 
 containing the substance of letters written from 
 Holland to his friend Clarke about the education 
 of Clarke's son. Locke used his medical know- 
 ledge with much effect in the earlier part of his 
 treatise. The general body of the work reveals 
 his sagacious care for the growth of character, 
 and his aversion to studies calculated to cul- 
 tivate address, rather than progress in knowledge. 
 In all the methods of education, he looked to 
 their effect upon the pupil's mind. But he put 
 virtue and practical wisdom first and learning 
 B 17 
 
LOCKE 
 
 last. 1 Probably Locke under-rates the value of 
 learning as itself a means of educating character 
 the topic on which it was reserved for Herbart 
 to insist. But his work deserves its place in 
 educational literature for its wisdom and sense 
 of life, and it has the historical importance of 
 having affected the Emile of Eousseau. Locke 
 was engaged continually in modifying the Essay, 
 of which a second edition appeared in 1694, and 
 a much amended fourth edition in 1700. In 
 1695, he published anonymously his Reasonable- 
 ness of Christianity (followed by two ' Vindica- 
 tions ' of it). Stillingfleet, Bishop of Worcester, 
 recognised in the writer of this work the author 
 of the Essay ; and when Toland, the deistical 
 writer, published next year his Christianity not 
 Mysterious, which he professed to found upon 
 Locke's Essay, attacked the Essay itself by way 
 of a defence of the Trinity against Toland and 
 the Unitarians. Locke replied to Stillingfleet's 
 attacks in a series of letters, between 1697 and 
 
 1 R. H. Quick (Educational Reformers], observes that this 
 work should be read in connection with the Conduct of the 
 Understanding, where instead of considering subjects of study 
 from the point of view of their usefulness for a young gentle- 
 man (as in the Thoughts], Locke considers them as means of 
 training, and urges that the value of study is to enable the 
 youth to use his reason for himself hereafter. 
 
 18 
 
LIFE 
 
 1699, which supplemented in certain respects the 
 doctrine of the Essay, and overwhelmed his op- 
 ponent with argument and irony. Of Locke's 
 posthumous writings the most important philo- 
 sophically are a paper on Malebranche and The 
 Conduct of the Understanding. 
 
 Many friends came to see Locke during his re- 
 tirement at Gates, or received visits from him. 
 Among these was Newton, between whom and 
 Locke there subsisted a real affection. Locke 
 took some part in securing for Newton his ap- 
 pointment at the Mint. But Newton was not 
 always easy to deal with. Once, in consequence 
 of prolonged insomnia (due to dozing by the fire 
 in his room), he imagined a grievance against 
 Locke. A reader who remembers the greatness 
 of the two men will find something very touching 
 in the letter in which Newton contritely asks 
 forgiveness for entertaining and expressing an 
 evil opinion of his friend, and in Locke's reply 
 of surprise and generous affection. Another friend 
 of this later time, whom the Essay brought him, 
 was William Molyneux, 'the ingenious gentle- 
 man' of the Essay 'whom I am proud to call 
 my friend/ an Irish patriot before Swift, who 
 introduced the Essay into Trinity College, Dublin, 
 where it was to be read shortly by the young 
 
 19 
 
LOCKE 
 
 Berkeley, and has ever since remained a text- 
 book. Molyneux' discussion of the Essay helped 
 Locke to several amendments, and he visited 
 Locke at Gates. Another new friend was Anthony 
 Collins, a young neighbouring squire, who after- 
 wards wrote one of the best known of the deistical 
 writings. Locke took a warm interest in a rela- 
 tion of his, Peter King, a young lawyer and 
 member of Parliament, who became his sole 
 executor. It was King's descendant, Lord Chan- 
 cellor King, who published in 1829 the Life 
 of John Locke. Still another young friend de- 
 serves mention, Pierre Coste, French tutor to 
 the boy Francis Masham, who wrote of Locke in 
 Bayle's magazine Les Nouvelles de la Rtpublique 
 des Lettres. Locke died on the 28th of October 
 1704, and was buried in the churchyard at High 
 Laver, the parish where he used to attend service. 
 Locke's capacity of friendship, which included 
 love of children and young people, is apparent 
 from his whole history. Lady Masham and Coste 
 have left us a charming and amiable picture of 
 his personality 4 his singular humanity and good 
 breeding, which made him alike conversible with 
 all sorts of people,' and made him lead people to 
 talk of what they understood best; his fondness 
 of raillery and banter, * though rarely if ever, to 
 20 
 
LIFE 
 
 the least offence of any person, but rather to dwell 
 on some very slight fault, or else that which was 
 usually commendable and for their honour to be 
 known ' ; his wit in conversation ; his kindness and 
 charity, which, however, were always directed to 
 encourage industry. 'He was a great lover of 
 economy, and an exact keeper of accounts ' and he 
 was very neat in his dress and habits, without 
 any affectation or singularity. He was quick- 
 tempered and sometimes against unfair assailants 
 he did not conceal his anger, but he was easily 
 appeased. When some one quoted in his hearing 
 some words of Horace, 'Ah/ said Locke, ' I am like 
 Horace in both these things. I love the warmth 
 of the sun, and though I am prone to be angry, 
 my hot temper soon goes down/ 
 
 If we had not his letters and the testimony of 
 these friends, we could easily guess from the style 
 of his writing and particularly of the Essay what 
 manner of man he was. It suggests a man saga- 
 cious, cautious, skilled in the knowledge of men 
 and regardful above all things of what it concerns 
 man's happiness to know and to be, a foe to ' en- 
 thusiasm/ but of broad spirit and sympathy. He 
 writes leisurely, as if he were talking out of a full 
 mind ; determined to see things clearly ; anxious 
 to make his meaning plain; yet not over-care- 
 21 
 
LOCKE 
 
 ful of precision, but content, as a man of the 
 world, to allow one part of his discourse to supply 
 the qualification of another part. Prolix his style is, 
 exceeding the measure of our less spacious times, 
 and when it is controversial, protracted into tedi- 
 ousness. Its uniform level is diversified here and 
 there by phrases of striking and even pungent wit 
 (' God when he makes the prophet doth not un- 
 make the man'), more often by quiet humour 
 ('every drowsy nod shakes their doctrine who 
 teach that the soul is always thinking ') or irony, 
 which is always courteous (and therefore more 
 effective) except when it is directed against an 
 unworthy criticism. It betrays little imagination, 
 though occasionally there is a touch of tenderness 
 and fancy as in the passage : ' The ideas as well as 
 children of our youth often die before us ; and our 
 minds represent those tombs to which we are 
 approaching ; where though the brass and marble 
 remain, yet the inscriptions are effaced by time 
 and the imagery moulders away ' ; or when he 
 allows himself to consider the possibility of con- 
 tinuous grades of spirits in the world, though 
 there the imagination belongs rather to the 
 thought than to the style. Often there are pas- 
 sages of sustained eloquence like the concluding 
 pages of the Reasonableness of Christianity. But 
 22 
 
LIFE 
 
 its general tone is that of equable common-sense, 
 without emphasis, without enthusiasm, restrained 
 in its judgment, careful of measure, never dull 
 but reflecting evenly from a candid surface, 
 modest when it is most original, because con- 
 cerned with the faithful presentment of things, 
 rather lambent than fiery, an inspired pedes- 
 trianism. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 
 PHILOSOPHY (THE ESSAY) 
 
 NOTHING enables us so well to understand the 
 meaning of a philosophic writer as to know the 
 spirit in which he undertook his inquiries, and it 
 is fortunate for us that the more personal and 
 autobiographical method of writers like Descartes, 
 Locke, and Spinoza (in one of his treatises) and 
 others, admits us into this secret. Locke's spirit 
 is that of criticism. The method of criticism in 
 philosophy is principally associated with the name 
 of Kant, who avowed and described it. It is the 
 ^ method of determining the limits of our know- 
 ledge by an inquiry into the instrument. In this 
 sense Locke has been rightly described as ' the 
 first critical philosopher/Jand different as his pro- 
 cedure was from Kant's, and different as was the 
 outcome of their thinking, their affinity of spirit is 
 profounder than their divergence. The words in 
 which Locke describes, at the opening of the 
 Essay, the occasion of his writing it remind us of 
 the later words of Kant in his preface to the 
 24 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Critique of Pure Reason. 'I thought,' Locke 
 says, ' that the first step towards satisfying several 
 inquiries the mind of man was very apt to run 
 into, was to take a survey of our own understand- 
 ings, examine our own powers, and see to what 
 things they were adapted. Till that was done I 
 suspected we began at the wrong end and in vain 
 sought for satisfaction in a quiet and sure posses- 
 sion of truths that most concerned us, whilst we 
 let loose our thoughts into the vast ocean of being ; 
 as if all that boundless extent were the natural 
 and undoubted possession of our understandings, 
 wherein there was nothing exempt from its de- 
 cision, or that escaped its comprehension. Thus 
 men extending their inquiries beyond their capac- 
 ities, and letting their thoughts wander into those 
 depths where they can find no sure footing, it is 
 no wonder that they raise questions and multiply 
 disputes, which, never coming to any clear resolu- 
 tion, are proper only to continue and increase 
 their doubts, and confirm them at last in perfect 
 scepticism. Whereas were the capacities of our 
 understandings well considered, the extent of our 
 knowledge once discovered and the horizon found 
 which sets the bounds between the enlightened 
 and dark parts of things between what is and 
 what is not comprehensible by us men would 
 
 25 
 
LOCKE 
 
 perhaps with less scruple acquiesce in the avowed 
 ignorance of the one, and employ their thoughts 
 and discourse with more advantage and satisfac- 
 tion in the other.' With Locke the speculative 
 impulse is an out-growth from practical needs. 
 ' Our business here is not to know all things but 
 those which concern our conduct/ He is per- 
 suaded that for two evils to which the mind is 
 liable : scepticism which bids us doubt everything 
 because there are some things which cannot be 
 understood ; and on the other hand extravagant 
 pretensions to knowledge : there is but one cure, 
 to know how much we can know. The Essay is 
 thus a doctrine of the limits of knowledge. 
 
 All its multifarious inquiries converge to this 
 end. The extent of knowledge is indeed the 
 proper subject of only one book, the fourth and 
 last. Knowledge is to Locke the perception of 
 the agreement or disagreement of our ideas, that 
 is to say, of the objects of our understanding. A 
 preliminary survey was therefore necessary of 
 these ideas, and because to him words, the signs 
 of ideas, were an index to the nature of ideas 
 themselves, and the misuse of language was partly 
 provoked by unclearness in our ideas, and partly 
 provoked it, the study of ideas and the study of 
 words are conjoined. These inquiries occupy the 
 
 26 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 major part of the Essay in Books n. and in. [it 
 is a method Locke describes as the 'plain, his- ( 
 torical method/ But history means to him not \ 
 simply or primarily the record of the origin and 
 growth of our ideas, but rather it has the sense in 
 which Bacon and Aristotle used the word before i 
 him, and in which we still speak of Zoology as 
 natural history. The history of our minds means 
 a description of the contents of our mind as we 
 find them, arranging them into sorts, and assign- 
 ing them to their appropriate faculties.) Q^Ee 
 second book of Locke's Essay, which is a survey 
 of ideas, is in fact an inventory of our experience. 
 But Locke does not distinguish the inquiry into 
 the contents of our ideas from the inquiry into 
 their origin, and hence arises one of the chief 
 defects of the Essay. For in analysing our ideas 
 into their simplest elements, which is his prin- 
 cipal object, he implies and even says, that these 
 simple elements exist first and that the more 
 complex ones are constructed out of them. But 
 the ' history ' which may be true as a description 
 and an analysis is not necessarily true as an 
 account of the order of growthj 
 
 Locke's method has sometimes been described 
 as psychological, and it has been made a charge 
 against him as well as against his successors, 
 
 27 
 
LOCKE 
 
 Berkeley and Hume, that they give us psychology 
 instead of philosophy. This charge is founded 
 upon a misunderstanding of the spirit of their 
 work. While they are founders of English 
 psychology, their primary interest is philosophical 
 or metaphysical, and they are only incidentally 
 psychologists. The object of psychology is to 
 describe the process by which the mind acquires 
 its experiences. Necessarily such a classification 
 as Locke gives of these experiences, referring 
 them to the mental capacities by which we 
 acquire them, supplies at the same time the 
 material of a psychology. But Locke's object is 
 to describe the different kinds of objects the mind 
 thinks about; and in fact the processes of ob- 
 servation, perception, willing and the like, which 
 are the subject-matter of psychology (a word 
 which Locke himself does not employ), are for 
 him merely one portion of the contents of human 
 experience, that which he describes as ideas of 
 reflection. 
 
 By ' idea ' (a term which he borrows from Des- 
 cartes) Locke means 'whatever is the object of 
 the understanding, when a man thinks ' or ' what- 
 ever it is which the mind can be employed about 
 in thinking.' It includes thus the simplest 
 experiences like heat, and the most complex like 
 28 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 those of civilisation or mathematical relations ; and 
 not merely experience of things, but of events, 
 whether in the external world, or, like the process 
 of conceiving, in the mind itself; not only ideas 
 of particular things but general or abstract ideas. 
 Careless as Locke's use of language is, there is 
 never any doubt as to his use of this word. 
 Sometimes he describes an idea by reference to 
 the capacity which supplies it an idea of sensa- 
 tion is thus an idea supplied by sense ; sometimes 
 by reference to its contents, as when he speaks of 
 an idea of heat, in other words heat so far as it 
 is experienced. They are objects of mind: they 
 would not be what they are if they were not ex- 
 perienced ; but they are objects still. They are in 
 fact the appearances of things, in so far as these 
 appearances are presented to the mind, or as 
 Locke and his followers more often say 'are in 
 the mind/ Butjhe does not answer, because he 
 does not raise, the question as to what the nature 
 of these ideas is or how they arise. He is content 
 to say that when a hot thing excites the skin and 
 the movement is continued to the brain, it pro- 
 duces in the mind the idea of heat in this case 
 an idea of sensation or perception. He assumes 
 that there is an external thing, and a mind, and 
 that upon suitable occasion the mind apprehends 
 29 
 
LOCKE 
 
 an idea related to the thing. But while these 
 ideas are for Locke appearances of things, they 
 cannot be described as being identical with things 
 in so far as the things appear to us under different 
 aspecT^PThe ideas are not attributes of the things 
 themselves, they are to Locke copies of the things 
 to which they refer. Locke insists that we can 
 only know reality through ideas which are its 
 copies, that ideas or their relations are the proper 
 objects of mind, and in fact his whole effort is to 
 determine just how much, in extent and in kind, 
 these ideas can tell us of the real world which he 
 assumes. The world of ideas constitutes therefore 
 (to neglect certain qualifications to be mentioned 
 hereafter) a body of representations of real thingij 
 But while he thus assumes that the objects of 
 mind are themselves mental in character Locke 
 never describes them in the modern phrase of 
 ' states of consciousness/ He never says (and does 
 not believe) that we know nothing but our own 
 states. He does indeed constantly speak of 
 ideas as being ' in the mind/ and it is easy to find 
 passages which suggest that the ideas are mental 
 .affections. ' The pictures drawn in our minds/ he 
 says, ' of the ideas of memory ' (what we should 
 now call the images of memory) ' are laid in fading 
 colours, and if not sometimes refreshed, vanish 
 30 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 and disappear/ But it is clear that an idea of 
 perception, e.g. the idea of a tree is not an affec- 
 tion of the mind in the same sense as the act of 
 perception itself is. Nor does Locke, who main- 
 tains that mathematical ideas have a reality of 
 their own, mean that a triangle is a mere affec- 
 tion of the mind which vanishes when we cease to 
 think of it. Locke does not in the Essay raise the 
 problem which is involved in this phrase affec- 
 tion or modification of mind a problem which 
 agitated the followers of Descartes; and when 
 he meets it in his posthumous treatise on Male- 
 branche he is impatient of it and pushes it aside. 
 To have the modification of mind involved in 
 seeing the purple colour of a violet (Malebranche 
 called this sensation a ' sentiment ' in distinction 
 from the idea), is the same thing as ' to have the 
 idea of purple in my mind.' To Locke what is 
 important is that ' when we think of a colour or a 
 figure which we did not think of before there is 
 some alteration in the mind/ But how we come 
 to have ideas he cannot explain. ' I see or per- 
 ceive or have ideas when it pleases God that I 
 should, but in a way that I cannot comprehend/ 
 r'The phrase, that ideas are in the mind, cannot 
 ^therefore be pressed it might be replaced by the 
 phrase, ideas are before the mind. The word 'idea/ 
 
LOCKE 
 
 therefore, contains for Locke no theory ; it means 
 simply an_ object of the understanding when we 
 think. Unfortunately he also did not inquire 
 J what was involved in assigning to ideas a twilight 
 existence between the things they represent and 
 the mind which understands them. That he did 
 not do so is a philosophical deffcfjQjput if we are to 
 apprehend his meaning, we must beware of import- 
 ing into his philosophy doctrines that he does not 
 maintain. 
 
 Let us follow Locke in mis inventory of ideas. 
 They may be distinguished, in the first place, 
 according to their 'original/ All our ideas, all 
 the materials of our thought and knowledge, are 
 derived directly or indirectly from experience, and 
 from two sources of it, sensation and reflection. 
 External sensible objects supply us with the one 
 set of ideas, ideas of sensation; our own opera- 
 tions about the ideas got by sensation, when the 
 mind comes to reflect upon these operations, 
 supply us with the other set, the ideas of reflec- 
 tion : such ideas as the acts of perceiving, willing, 
 thinking, feeling. Apart from experience, then, 
 directly or indirectly received, the mind is to 
 Locke a White paper, void of all characters, with- 
 out any ideas, a tabula rasa ; or it is compared to 
 a dark cabinet into which the senses let in light. 
 
 32 
 
 IX 
 
 o 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 That we have no innate ideas, no objects of ex- 
 perience not derived from these two sources, is the! 
 implied doctrine, the subject-matter of Book iTl 
 whose significance may be deferred. Nor does 
 the mind think, except so far as it has ideas 
 before itfwe cannot say with Descartes that 
 because the essence of mind is to think, the mind 
 is always actually thinking. ' Every drowsy nod 
 shakes their doctrine who declare that the mind 
 thinks always.! But, while the mind is passive in 
 respect of tKese two sources of experience, sen- 
 sation and reflection, the mind is also active : 
 it can attend, it can compare, distinguish and 
 abstract. Hence arisesfthe first important classi- 
 fication of ideas into two classes simple and 
 complex ideas. Simple ideas are the ultimate 
 constituents of experience, the uncompounded ap- 
 pearances of things ; complex ideas are the work- 
 manship of the mmcy Simple ideas are either 
 the ideas of the sensible qualities of things de- 
 rived by sensation of all kinds, the ideas of white- 
 ness, heat and the like, or else they are the ideas 
 of the operations of our minds which come to us 
 by reflection, or else they are like pleasure or 
 pain or existence, ideas which convey themselves 
 into the mind by sensation or reflection indiffer- 
 ently, 'by all the ways of sensation and reflec- 
 C 33 
 
LOCKE 
 
 tion.' These simple elements of experience the 
 mind can neither make nor destroy, it can only 
 receive ; had we fewer or more senses we should 
 receive fewer or more such ideas.r Among simple 
 ideas of sensation the most important distinction 
 is that between the ideas of the primary qualities 
 and the ideas of the secondary qualities of bodies 
 a distinction inherited by Locke from Descartes 
 but introduced mto philosoplry, in its modern 
 shape, by Galileo. V Extension, figure, number, 
 motion or rest, solraity, these are qualities which 
 bodies possess no matter what changes they 
 undergo. Pound an almond or melt wax, the 
 colours may change, but some figure and exten- 
 sion they still have. These qualities, then, are 
 powers in bodies themselves, and really in them, 
 whether any one's senses perceive them or no: 
 in virtue of which they produce exactly corre- 
 sponding ideas in us. But secondary qualities, 
 like colour, taste, and smell, which change with 
 varying circumstances, which may vanish for ex- 
 ample with the absence of illumination, or be 
 unfelt by a person who suffers from a cold, or 
 may change in character according to the condi- 
 tion of the percipient, are not qualities in bodies 
 themselves, but are powers which they possess of 
 producing certain ideas in us, in virtue of their 
 
 34 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 internal structure ; that is, in virtue of the primary 
 qualities of the insensible particles of which they 
 are composed, for Locke assumes material bodies 
 to be ultimately atomic in structure. It may be 
 added that there is a third sort of qualities of 
 bodies, powers which they possess to affect .other 
 external bodies, like the power of the sun to melt 
 wax. It is these last which are commonly called 
 powers. The ideas of the secondary qualities are, 
 therefore, in one important respect, unlike those 
 of the primary qualities; they do not resemble 
 anything in the object, though popular thought 
 thinks that bodies are in themselves red or sweet, 
 in the same way as they are extended. 
 \ ^Simple ideas of reflection may be grouped under 
 theTtwo heads of thinking and willing. Sensible 
 objects give us ideas. The acts of the mind, as 
 engaged upon these ideas, give us the ideas of 
 reflection by a kind of inner sense. \ Perception is 
 the simplest operation we can tfius be aware of, 
 for apparently the act of sensation is nothing but 
 bodily motion in the brain ; the simplest idea of 
 sensation is really an idea of perception. Re- 
 tention, discrimination, comparison, abstraction 
 (which puts a limit between man and brutes), 
 are other examples. It is characteristic of Locke's 
 imperfect consideration of what an idea is, that, 
 35 
 
LOCKE 
 
 while strictly speaking, it is only * retention' or 
 'memory' itself that should be an idea of re- 
 fledlion, he yet constantly speaks of remembered 
 objects as ideas of reflection; though, in itself, a 
 remembered person is no more an object of reflec- 
 tion than a perceived person. By doing so he 
 seems to make the inner sense not only a source 
 of ideas of mental operations, but a source of ideas 
 which are not operations at all but in some sense 
 a special mental reduplication of ideas of sensa- 
 tion a doctrine full of fatal significance for sub- 
 sequent thought. 
 
 \ The complex ideas introduce distinctions which 
 present at once more interest and greater diffi- 
 culty r\ They are the voluntary creations of the 
 miiid, which manipulates the materials derived 
 from sensation and reflection; or they might be 
 described as resoluble into these elements to- 
 gether with an active element of construction 
 referable to the mind itself. [^Locke distinguishes 
 three sorts, Modes, Substances, and Relations, of 
 which Modes and Relations stand on an alto- 
 gether different footing from Substances. Modes 
 are complex ideas like jumping, triangle, grati- 
 tude, which are not regarded as self-subsistent 
 but as affections of substances. They are either 
 simple, or mixed, according as their simple con- 
 36 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 stituents are of the same or different sorts. Thus, 
 twelve is a mere repetition of unity ; beauty is re- 
 soluble into the heterogeneous elements of colour, U 
 figure, pleasure, etc. Simple modes are thus 
 variations of one simple idea e.g. the different 
 figures of extension, different sorts of motion, 
 different numbersTj One particularly interesting 
 mode is infinity or immensity, whether of space 
 or duration, which we get by (or is resoluble 
 into) the addition of unit to unit and joining to 
 this the negative idea that the process of addition 
 may be carried on without limit, never coming to 
 an end. Anticipating the more famous discussion 
 of the same problem by Kant,jjjpcke denies in- 
 finity to be a positive idea there is no idea of 
 a positive completed infinite ' you cannot adapt /^ 
 a standing measure to a growing bulk.' The chief V 
 examples of mixed modes (those which are re- 
 soluble into heterogeneous elements) are to be 
 found in moral ideas, e.g. motive, justice. \ It is 
 true that combinations of qualities inTne real 
 world may correspond to these ideas, or even 
 suggest them. But in themselves they are put 
 together arbitrarily by the mind, and the im- 
 portant consequence follows (for these and simple 
 modes as well), that they have no standard ex- 
 ternal to themselves with which they can be com- 
 
 37 
 
LOCKE 
 
 pared: they are their own archetypes, they are 
 their own guarantee of reality, f This same account 
 applies to ideas of Relation, such as relation of 
 king and subject, identity, cause and effect, and 
 the like. All of them ' terminate in simple ideas/ 
 are 'concerned with their simple ideas/ and are 
 products of the mind's activity in considering 
 them, ' so as to carry its view from one to the 
 other/ \Some of the more special sorts of relations, 
 and TrTparticular moral relations, will occupy us 
 later. 
 
 < The ideas of Substances are of a different 
 nature. They, too, are the workmanship of the 
 mind. We find a number of ideas of simple 
 qualities going together in our experience, and we 
 combine these ideas together under a single name, 
 and regard them as belonging to one thing, but 
 we also go on to suppose some support or sub- 
 stratum to the qualities in the thing which pro- 
 duces these simple ideas in us. We do not know 
 what that support is, any more than the Indian 
 philosopher Locke loves to quote, who declared 
 that the world was supported by an elephant, the 
 elephant by a tortoise, and the tortoise by he 
 knew not what. This obscure idea of some 
 support we know not what is the idea we have 
 of substance in general, land ' it is the same every- 
 --*8 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 where.' 1 A particular kind of substance is then 
 nothing but a group of simple ideas, regarded as 
 so supported, and as flowing from the internal 
 constitution of this unknown somewhat. 
 
 The Church, in the person of the Bishop of 
 Worcester, alleged, in alarm for the doctrine of 
 the Trinity, that Locke was almost discarding 
 substance out of the world. Locke could answer 
 easily enough, that so far from discarding it, he 
 had catalogued it, vague as it was, in his in- 
 ventory of experience, and had explained what 
 kind of an idea it was. ^Lpcke might have been 
 more embarrassed if he had been asked to explain 
 how the mind could not only group together 
 simple ideas as the ideas of one thing, but was\ 
 able to invent the new idea of a support however/ 
 indefinite. He was content to note in his in- 
 ventory the. existence of this idea without more 
 narrowly analysing its nature. A 
 
 BulTtwo consequences he'clrew from his account 
 of substance, which are of great importance. The 
 first is, that the idea of a spiritual substance is no 
 less clear than that of a material one. A material 
 substance is the unknown support of sensible 
 qualities ; spiritual substance is the unknown 
 support of the qualities corresponding to the 
 
 1 First letter to the Bishop of Worcester. 
 39 
 
LOCKE 
 
 ideas of reflection.? At the same time, this victori- 
 ous conclusion needs to be qualified. Bodies and 
 souls are alike the unknown supports of attri- 
 butes. But bodies to Locke have a microscopic 
 atomic constitution : a notion familiar to him 
 from the speculations of Gassendi, or indeed from 
 those of Bacon. It is but the coarseness of our 
 senses and of our intelligence which conceals this 
 constitution from us. Spirits more finely endowed 
 than ours, like the angels', may penetrate further 
 than ours into the constitution of bodies. But/in 
 regard to the soul, there is a peculiar obscurity. 
 A substance it is, but we do not know whether it 
 is an immaterial substance, or merely a material 
 substance to which God has attached the power 
 of thinking.^ The first hypothesis may be the 
 more probable, and only those ' whose thoughts 
 are immersed in matter' find it harder to con- 
 ceive a spiritual than a bodily substance. But 
 though God Himself, from whom all proceeds, is 
 certainly an immaterial substance, there is no con- 
 tradiction in the second hypothesis, which holds 
 Him to have added thought to certain systems of 
 senseless matter. ' All the great ends of worship 
 and religion are well enough secured without 
 philosophical proofs of the soul's immateriality.' 
 The identity of the soul, whichever view be 
 40 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 taken of it, consists in the identity of conscious- 
 ness. 
 
 "jfThe second conclusion is of a different nature. 
 A distinction was current in the schools, between 
 the real essence of substances and the nominal 
 essence or definition. Locke spends himself in 
 argument to prove that we know only nominal 
 essences, and that they are the names of sorts of 
 things by which we identify a particular thing as 
 belonging to a class, they are groups of ideas (J 
 connected together by names. They are thus 
 general ideas formed by abstraction. The real 
 essence is ' that real constitution of anything, 
 which is the foundation of the qualities combined 
 in the nominal essence/ it is to him that minute ' 
 microscopic constitution, from which the obvious 
 sensible qualities combined in the definition are 
 supposed to flow. This real essence of things we 
 do not know, because our senses fail to carry us 
 so far. It follows, to anticipate a little, that our 
 knowledge of substances is confined to the abstract 
 collections of ideas which a<re signified by the 
 general names of substances. \ 
 
 Our brief resume of th^cEIef titles in Locke's 
 inventory of experience is not intended to do 
 more than indicate the wealth of detailed descrip- 
 tion which makes the second book of the Essay 
 
LOCKE 
 
 a storehouse of metaphysical and psychological 
 knowledge. Nor does it attempt at all to follow 
 Locke in his survey of words in the third book. 
 But we may conveniently stop for a moment, 
 before passing on to consider Locke's theory of 
 knowledge, in order to review the picture here 
 presented of the ideas which we possess, the 
 objects of our mind when we think. They are 
 all resoluble into two kinds of simple experiences, 
 ideas of sense qualities, and of mental operations. 
 These simple ideas all correspond to the real 
 things, whose existence Locke assumes, and which 
 are supposed to produce them in our minds : they 
 are ' such perceptions as God has fitted us to 
 receive, and given power to external objects (he 
 is speaking of simple ideas of sensation), to pro- 
 duce in us by established laws and ways, suitable 
 to his wisdom and goodness, though incompre- 
 hensible to us.' They are in Locke's language 
 real, adequate, and true. Some of them are exact 
 copies of their originals, others do not resemble 
 them. But they are but the materials of our 
 experience. The finished objects of our experi- 
 ence are our own handiwork. On the one hand, 
 we have a set of objects, of which the chief are 
 mathematical and ethical constructions, which 
 are real and adequate in their own right, self- 
 42 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 contained because not fashioned according to any 
 exemplar beyond them. These objects contain a 
 wealth of properties, which may be drawn from 
 them by demonstration. On the other hand 
 we have substances, whether material things or 
 minds, and these we do not experience in them- 
 selves, but only so far as we receive simple ideas 
 from them. fWe are left then strangely with a 
 twofold reality. There is one reality, which 
 belongs to certain of our ideas, like the mathe- 
 matical ones, because they are wholly of our 
 making. There is another reality of substances 
 which supply us with the ideas that we receive 
 from them ; which are behind the veil of the ap- 
 pearances by which we know them. This reality we 
 know only partially, and cannot thoroughly knowj 
 
 This survey of ideas anticipates the answer to 
 the problem of the limits of knowledge, which it 
 was Locke's main object to solve. I Knowledge, as 
 already explained, is the perceptionoT the agree- 
 ment or disagreement of ideas. Ideas are but 
 the elements of knowledge, we have knowledge 
 when we perceive their connections. What is 
 known is thus ideas in their connection. Accord- 
 ing to Locke, the connection may be one of four 
 kinds. It may be that of identity or diversity, as 
 when we perceive that white is white, and is not 
 
 43 
 
LOCKE 
 
 black; or of relation, e.g. three is greater than 
 two ; or co-existence, e.g. gold is ' fixed/ which 
 means the co-existence of fixedness with the de- 
 fining qualities of gold ; or lastly, there is a fourth 
 kind of agreement or disagreement, ' that of actual 
 real existence agreeing to an idea/ which may be 
 reserved for later explanationj 
 
 [Knowledge so defined, to be really knowledge, 
 is either directly or indirectly intuitive. Direct 
 intuition is the immediate perception of such 
 agreement or disagreement : it is immediate cer- 
 tainty ' irresistible/ ' like bright sunshine ' ; and 
 on it all certainty of knowledge depends. Indirect 
 intuition is demonstration, where our ideas are 
 brought into relation by the mediation of a third, 
 each step in the demonstration being itself in- 
 tuitive. ( Supposing that there could be innate 
 ideas and principles which the mind brings along 
 with it, their intuitive character would accord- 
 ingly not serve to distinguish them from any 
 other kind of knowledge which is knowledge in 
 the strict sense. But jStiere are three questions 
 which may profitably be asked about knowledge, 
 concerned as it is with ideas. How far does it 
 extend? How far is it real or conformable to 
 things ? How much can it tell us of actual 
 existence? x 
 
 44 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 The answer to the first two questions turns 
 entirely on the difference between ideas of sub- 
 stances and all other ideas. Our senses are not 
 acute enough to tell us of the primary qualities of 
 the minute particles of bodies, nor our intelligence 
 to inform us of the structure composed by these 
 'particles. We can therefore neither know why 
 the body ' produces in us the ideas of certain 
 qualities included in their nominal essence, nor, 
 what is more important, what is the connection 
 between these qualities themselves, and conse- 
 quently between these qualities and other qual- 
 ities which we may discover in them. Further 
 we have to remember, as Locke says in a striking 
 passage, that substances do not stand alone, but 
 are related to one another, and dependent for their 
 qualities on remote causes which may be unper- 
 ceived. ' Separate a piece of gold from all other 
 bodies, and it would lose all its colour and weight 
 and perhaps malleableness too/ 'We see and 
 perceive some of the actions and grosser opera- 
 tions of things here about us, but whence the 
 streams come that keep all these curious machines 
 in motion and repair, how conveyed and modified, 
 is beyond notice and apprehension. . . . Things, 
 however absolute and entire they seem in them- 
 selves, are but retainers to other parts of nature 
 45 
 
LOCKE 
 
 for that which they are most taken notice of 
 by us.' 
 
 It is plain then that] our knowledge cannot 
 extend beyond our ideas, but also that it must fall 
 short of the range of our ideas, whenever we fail 
 to bring our ideas into relation with one another. 
 Thus though we have an idea of matter and of 
 thinking we may never be able to know whether 
 matter thinks.^ fWe are limited in our knowledge 
 of the co-existence of qualities in bodies because 
 we do not know the ultimate constitution of 
 things. We can go little further than our ex- 
 perience. And if this is true of bodies, it is still 
 more true of spirits which are only known in our 
 persons, while we know nothing of other possible 
 spirits in the universe, but can only conjecture. 
 Whereas the extent of our knowledge of mathe- 
 matical and moral relations appears to be inde- 
 finite and inexhaustible! 
 
 rWhen we ask how far our knowledge is real 
 oTfrue how far, that is, it differs from mere im- 
 agination and conforms to things the answer is 
 p. similar. Mathematical and moral knowledge, since 
 these ideas are their own archetypes, is real and 
 true. But our ideas of substances are referred to 
 archetypes existing beyond ideas. Our knowledge 
 of them can only therefore be true 'so far as it is 
 46 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 founded upon experience and sensible observa- 
 tions, i Hence, to state the same thing otherwise, 
 the important result that a definite limit is set to 
 our acquisition of universal knowledge.!"" So far as 
 ideas are abstract their agreement or disagreement 
 will constitute universal knowledge ; wherever 
 therefore, as in mathematics, we have abstract 
 ideas we Can obtain universal knowledge. Now of 
 substances we know only their nominal essences. 
 These are abstract, but we can derive very little 
 further knowledge from them because.as explained, 
 not knowing the constitution of things, we do not 
 know the connection between the qualities which 
 make up the nominal essence. We are then 
 limited to the particular knowledge of substances 
 derived from particular experiences. Such gener- 
 alisations as we can make as to the co-existence 
 of their properties, wanting as they are in adequate 
 foundation, do not amount to more than pro- 
 bability, useful enough for practice, but falling 
 short of science. Thev are not matter of know- 
 ledge but of judgment} Science, which is uni- 
 versal, is thus only possible in the unfolding of 
 an abstract idea, and consequently Locke is ' apt 
 to doubt a science of physical bodies as out of 
 our reach'; our physical knowledge is at best 
 empirical. 
 
 47 
 
LOCKE 
 
 The inadequacy of our knowledge of substances 
 is plainer still if we ask ourselves what are the 
 things of which we are warranted in holding not 
 merely that they are real or true like mathe- 
 matics but that they have actual existence. At 
 first sight it might seem difficult to understand 
 how, if knowledge is the perception of the agree- 
 ment of ideas, we can have knowledge of actual 
 existence at all. For actual existence outside the 
 world of ideas is not itself an idea and cannot be 
 compared with other ideas. But what Locke 
 means is clear enough : it is the undoubted fact 
 that certain ideas come to us with a ' coefficient 
 of reality/ as it has been called, a ' tang ' which 
 distinguishes them from mere ideas or imagina- 
 tions. They carry us beyond the mere idea to 
 something else, which is what we call real exist- 
 ence. There are two such ideas of whose existence 
 we may have certainty: ourselves and God. Of 
 our own existence we have intuitive knowledge ; 
 to doubt it is, in Descartes' language which Locke, 
 accepts, to be assured of it in the very act of 
 doubting. Of God's existence we have demon- 
 strative knowledge. For I myself exist; there 
 must therefore be some real being to account for 
 my beginning to be, and this real being must 
 exist from all eternity (or it too would have had 
 48 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 a beginning and therefore a further cause). More- 
 over this being as the source of all our powers 
 and knowledge must be most powerful and most 
 knowing in a word, it is God. The pungency of 
 my own existence is thus by this argument com- 
 municated through the principle of causality to 
 God. But Locke, though he regards it as an intui- 
 tive truth that nothing can begin to be except it is 
 produced by some real thing, does not ask himself 
 how the idea of causation, gathered according to 
 his own account from the suggestion of connected 
 changes in things, can be extended so as to apply 
 to a cause like God which never can be presented 
 in sensible or reflective experience. 
 
 Of the existence of ourselves and of God we 
 have thus, according to Locke, complete con- 
 viction. When we turn to material things, we 
 find that while we can at pleasure call up or lay 
 by the ideas of memory or fancy, we are passive 
 in respect of external objects. When we look at 
 the sun, we cannot avoid having the idea of light. 
 There must needs be ' some exterior cause which 
 produces these ideas in my mind whether I will 
 or no.' Moreover a present material thing affects 
 us with a certain force or vivacity which distin- 
 guishes it from a mere imagination. It is the 
 difference between seeing the sun by day and think- 
 D 49 
 
LOCKE 
 
 Ing of it by night. To the objector who urges that 
 the fire may be all a dream, Locke never tires of 
 begging him ' to dream this answer ' ; that there 
 is a manifest difference between dreaming of 
 being in the fire and being actually in it, and at 
 any rate the pain of the second experience makes 
 the difference between our weal and woe, and de- 
 termines us practically. Such knowledge Locke 
 calls sensitive knowledge. It is less than intui- 
 tion and is therefore less than knowledge proper, 
 but it is more than mere 'judgment.' Our know- 
 ledge of the nature of sensible things is thus the 
 particular knowledge of our observations of them, 
 and our knowledge of their actual existence is the 
 sensible experience of their presence so long as 
 they are present ; or it may be added, the memory 
 that they were once so sensibly perceived. 
 
 What falls outside the range of knowledge thus 
 described belongs to the sphere of judgment or 
 probability, and it thus includes the greater part 
 of our beliefs and the propositions we make, in 
 particular the greater part of what is thought to 
 constitute physical science. It supplies what is 
 necessary for conduct, where the conviction or 
 intuition necessary for knowledge fails us. Such 
 propositions are attended not by certainty but by 
 assent. The mind puts ideas together, when their 
 So 
 
PHILOSOPHY 
 
 agreement is not perceived, but only presumed. 
 It may do this in respect of matter of fact, either 
 because of conformity to our own observation, or 
 the ground of probability may be the testimony 
 of others. In matters which are not open to the 
 observation of the senses, like the minute con- 
 stitution of things, we rely in our judgments upon 
 analogy. The strength of our assent varies in 
 degree according to various circumstances, the 
 concurrence of testimony, the agreement of testi- 
 mony with experience, the remoteness of the testi- 
 mony and the like. But Locke has supplied no 
 rules by which we may judge 'the relative pro- 
 bability of judgments, such as are offered by 
 ' inductive ' logic. 
 
CHAPTER III 
 
 OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 LIKE other great writers and thinkers, Locke 
 leaves many strands of thought not woven into 
 one perfect tissue ; loose ends are not connected, 
 gaps are left to be filled in the structure. It is 
 not difficult to point out these defects, and his 
 successors were occupied in overcoming them. 
 But it is more helpful to begin by indicating 
 certain features of the Essay which are impres- 
 sive by their fertility of suggestion. 
 
 1. The general character of his method, in 
 reviewing the contents of experience as a means 
 towards indicating the limits of knowledge, follows 
 the habit of the practical man, which begins with 
 certain loose assumptions that, in the course of 
 the inquiry, take on a changed aspect and receive 
 a new signification. Locke's assumption of real 
 substances, to which knowledge conforms in vari- 
 ous degrees, is easy enough to criticise. If the 
 only objects of our minds are ideas, how can 
 things which are not themselves ideas be made 
 52 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 the object of thought, still less be compared with 
 ideas ? The answer is that Locke, insisting on the 
 philosophical doctrine that all the objects of our 
 thought are mental in the sense before defined, 
 is content to assume side by side with these the 
 existence of minds and of material things. But 
 things which at the beginning of the Essay are 
 the mysterious causes of our ideas turn out in 
 the end to be merely the limits of our knowledge. 1 
 Step by step as he proceeds in the inquiry the 
 material thing receives definition. The ideas of 
 the primary qualities are exact copies of the 
 primary qualities themselves, or in other words, 
 in certain vital respects the contents of the real 
 object are the same as those of the representative 
 one. The secondary qualities are still as in the 
 thing entirely unlike their ideas. But even this 
 apparent breach is narrowed. For the ultimate 
 nature of the thing is held to be a structure of 
 particles insensible to us, and were our senses and 
 our intelligence acute enough to know the primary 
 qualities of these particles and the plan of their 
 combination, we should have an exact repre- 
 sentation of the thing. 'The now secondary 
 qualities of bodies would disappear if we could 
 
 1 The same observation is true of Kant, though Kant's result 
 is different. 
 
 53 
 
LOCKE 
 
 discover the primary ones of their minute parts. 
 . . . We should see an admirable texture of parts of 
 a certain size and figure.' 1 The sensible qualities 
 and the gross superficial (macroscopic) primary 
 ones would be replaced by microscopic primary 
 ones. Were this result but attained (and we 
 must add, the connection of things with other 
 things also observed), knowledge would be en- 
 tirely adequate. For though our knowledge 
 would still be of ideas, there would be nothing 
 in the things themselves which would not have 
 its exact counterpart in ideas, except the un- 
 known something which makes the^difference 
 between ideas and actual things. {Ultimately 
 therefore the limit to our knowledge of things 
 is set by our defective sense and intelligence. 
 Though no finite spirit which knows only by 
 ideas could behold reality face to face, reality is 
 in the end something not remote from ideas, for 
 it corresponds to them, and it is but our defi- 
 ciencies which prevent us from knowing it, as far 
 as it can be known at all? Locke declines the 
 question of the real constitution of spirit, whether 
 it is an immaterial substance or a material sub- 
 stance to which is attached the power of thinking. 
 But he speaks of ' thinking and willing as primary 
 
 1 Essay, Book n., ch. xxiii. 11. 
 
 54 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 qualities of spirit.' l Had he asked himself what 
 reason there was for supposing thinking as in the 
 mind to be different from the thinking which we 
 apprehend the idea of thinking he might have 
 seen that his separation of ideas in general from 
 things was needless. 
 
 S'fOne of Locke's cardinal merits is his insist- 
 
 Lav*** 
 
 ence that no mere words shall take the place of 
 a clear description of the contents of our experi- 
 ence, or shall make us think that we have ideas fj 
 which we cannot find in our experience. Books i. 
 to in. are a long descant upon this theme. And 
 it is this which gives point to a famous portion of 
 Locke's theory which we have not yet described, 
 his denial of innate ideas whether in thinking or 
 in moral^ In the abstract which he wrote of the l 
 Essay^fo^ Leclerc's Bibliotheque Universelle he 
 omits this topic which occupies the whole first 
 Book of the Essay, with the remark that it was 
 designed to overcome the prejudices entertained 
 against the belief that the mind was tabula rasa. 
 Readers of the Essay are often provoked with 
 what they think the triviality of Locke's attempted 
 refutation of innate ideas, amounting, they think, 
 to little more than the proof that we do not have 
 these ideas at birth, and that we acquire them 
 
 1 Essay, Book n., ch. xxiii. 30. 
 
 55 
 
LOCKE 
 
 only by experience, after we have acquired other 
 portions of knowledge no less evident. Such 
 innate ideas, it is urged, are not those which Lord 
 Herbert of Cherbury assumed, or Descartes in- 
 tended by his innate ideas, nor are they such as 
 have been intended by others after Locke who, 
 admitting that experience is needed to evoke these 
 principles to explicit operation, have urged that 
 they themselves are implicit in the mind. Now 
 it was just this conception of implicit knowledge 
 which Locke desired to repudiate. 'To imprint 
 anything on the mind without the mind's perceiv- 
 ing it seems to me hardly intelligible/ Whatever 
 is in the mind must be discoverable there, and 
 he thought that the notion of innate principles 
 clouded the issue with words and substituted 
 empty language for the real effort to discover ideas. 
 He did not deny the truth or the self-evidence 
 of these principles, and he even thought them use- 
 ful as a means of avoiding sophistry in controversy. 
 Still less did he maintain that the mind itself 
 though a white paper to the world of objects was 
 itself a passive instrument. But he claimed, and 
 he claimed rightly, that the mind should not be 
 credited with mysterious knowledge, not verifiable 
 as an idea, and his answer is still valid against 
 those who would endow the mind with methods 
 
 56 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESS A Y 
 
 
 of envisaging objects (categories and the like) 
 which it imports into the object itself. It is this 
 consideration, that what is claimed to be a factor 
 in experience must be found there and catalogued 
 in the inventory, which gives its philosophical im- 
 portance to Locke's polemic. And it is therefore 
 not strange, that the attack upon innate ideas 
 should have come to be that part of Locke's teach- 
 ing which the public connected habitually with 
 his name. 
 
 480 far as Locke himself attempted the problem 
 raised by such ' categories ' of thought, and he did v 
 not seriously attempt it, he supplied indications 
 of a better way. He looked, for instance, for the 
 relation of causality, or power, to experience itself, 
 and crude and imperfect as his description of it 
 is, he found it there. I But he added that it is less 
 obviously experienced in the relations of material 
 bodies than in the operation of the mind itself 
 when it wills the direction of its ideas, or controls 
 the movement of its body a just view though 
 misunderstood, and therefore rejected, by Hume. 
 So far, at least, he sought to find for what after- 
 wards were called categories their real counter- 
 parts in his experience. And what he did went 
 but a little way. He never applied the same 
 principle to the better understanding of the 
 
 57 
 
LOCKE 
 
 nature of substance from observation of the con- 
 tinuity of mental operations. Had he carried this 
 line of thought a little further, he might have 
 recognised in the structure of the system of ideas, 
 whether of sense or reflection, certain fundamental 
 ideas which form the skeleton of the structure 
 and have thus a prerogative place in experience.^ 
 3. Locke's declaration that physical science is 
 impossible, because universal knowledge can only 
 be derived from abstract ideas, is notable be- 
 cause it makes mathematics the ideal of scientific 
 thought.\ Compared with mathematics, physics 
 as a collection of empirical knowledge supplies 
 only probability. He stands thus in strong con- 
 trast with those of his successors (like J. S. Mill) 
 who, attempting to put mathematics on an empiri- 
 cal basis, have sought to reduce it to the level of 
 the physical sciences. At the same time Locke's 
 doctrine, that if there is to be physical science 
 at all it must be derived from the investigation 
 of abstract ideas, has been the parent of much 
 similar thought, and it is revived without Locke's 
 pessimism as to physics in a doctrine which at 
 the present time is at any rate highly accredited, 
 that scientific conceptions and truths are con- 
 venient abstractions which happen to be attested 
 and verified by facts, but are themselves merely 
 
 58 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ES8A7 
 
 creations of the mind, which serve as a short- 
 hand or compendious description of physical data. 
 Both Locke's doctrine and its modern counterpart 
 have their characteristic difficulties. Locke held 
 that mathematics, while derived from the con- 
 struction of mind, is no mere analysis of what 
 was contained in certain conceptions, but led to 
 new truths : it discovered not ' trifling ' or ' verbal ' 
 but 'instructive' propositions. But he neither 
 inquired what compulsive force there was in fig- 
 ures or numbers which drove their investigators 
 into fresh discovery, nor how or in what sense 
 these abstract creations could be exemplified in 
 the world of fact. The same difficulties may 
 be objected to the current revival of Locke's 
 doctrine in physical science. 
 
 The last topic naturally leads on to the mention 
 of some of Locke's palpable defects, which not all 
 his cautious efforts to trace the boundaries be- 
 tween the enlightened and the dark parts of 
 things can conceal. But Locke's defects had the 
 
 value of stimulating the thought of his successors 
 
 Out of Locke grew not only Berkeley^and Hume, 
 but indirectly Kant and Reid. Thesejdefects turn 
 upon one or two main points his imperfect con- < 
 nection and imperfect disconnection of the mind 
 and external things, the individualistic character 
 
 59 
 
LOCKE 
 
 of his philosophy, his oversight of the central fact 
 of continuity .3 
 
 ll Hie antithesis between the two kinds of 
 realities, the constructions of the mind and sub- 
 stances, raises at once difficulties which Locke 
 never resolved.X Mathematical figures, to take 
 them as incontestable examples of modes, owe 
 their elements to sense, but their construction to 
 the mind. Now Locke admits that moral ideas, 
 which he places on the same footing as rnathe- 
 nrfatical ideas, may be gathered from observation. 
 This is obviously true of mathematical ideas also. 
 But how can it be more than a coincidence ? \JHe 
 does not explain how mathematical and moral 
 reality can be applicable to sensible reality. ( Modes 
 are, indeed, defined as groups of ideas' regarded 
 not as independent, but as affections of sub- 
 stances. Yet in the sequel, they are treated as 
 real in their own right, and floated off into an 
 atmosphere of their own. At the same time 
 Locke sees, as has just been noticed, that crea- 
 tures as they are of the mind, they constrain us 
 to think about them in certain ways as much as 
 if they were sensible objects. And yet they do 
 this, not because they correspond to anything in 
 the nature of the mind, but because they are 
 triangles or circles or moral ideas. They are as real 
 60 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 as substances, but they have no actual existence, 
 and yet they are exemplified in the world of actual 
 existence. j[t was this problem left unsolved or 
 rather unraised by Locke which Kant attempted 
 (impelled no doubt in part by Locke), when he 
 asked how mathematics can be true of the real 
 world or in the technical phrase how the syn- \) 
 thetic propositions of mathematics are possible. 
 His answer, or at least part of it, was that space 
 and time were brought by the mind itself to 
 experience, f Whatever value can be attached to 
 the solution, it was of the highest importance 
 to raise the problem. Locke would have rejected 
 the solution, but his own conception of mathe- 
 matics and their place in experience prepared 
 the way for it. 
 
 2. Locke's object was to describe the contents 
 of experience, but his method was a mixture of 
 description and assumption, and the severance of 
 ideas from things as the mental copies of them 
 arises from this defect^Had he described without 
 assumption what he found in his mind, he would 
 have discovered nothing but objects of various ^ 
 sorts ; which he might have called ideas to indi- ^ 
 cate their relation to mind. There would have 
 been substances, possibly vaguely apprehended, in 
 which simple qualities inhered, but there would 
 61 
 
LOCKE 
 
 have been no world behind the ideak^ But he 
 
 ( assumed from common thought the existence of 
 
 permanent things independent of our apprehen- 
 
 sions of them, and he maintained with this the 
 philosophical tenet derived from Descartes that 
 the only objects we know must be ideas. The 
 true proposition, that things show themselves to 
 be related to mind in so far as we apprehend 
 them, he converted like his teacher into the pro- 
 position that we do not know things directly but 
 only through mental phantasms, which are not 
 indeed mere affections of mind, but are suspended 
 somewhere betwixt mind and real things, and 
 sometimes dangerousb^jipproach the condition 
 of mental affections, j This is what Hume after- 
 wards described as the philosophical invention of 
 a twofold existence a doctrine fathered by philo- 
 sophy upon common-sense, but which common- 
 sense does jnot entertain, because it has not faced 
 the question/ It is true that Locke himself, as 
 has been insisted, cared little about the problems 
 he had so raised, and that his whole interest lay 
 in knowing how far these ideas could give us 
 knowledge of their exemplars. But subsequent 
 philosophy has employed itself with varying 
 success in ridding itself of the phantasms which 
 Descartes and Locke have conjured up. Locke 
 62 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 himself saw that ideas of primary qualities stood 
 in an intimacy of relation with their archetypes 
 
 which half destroyed their separatenessj It was 
 
 easy for Berkeley to show that there was no reason 
 for preferring them to the ideas of secondary 
 qualities in this respect. And therefore, he denied 
 the existence of sensible things in Locke's sense, 
 denied, that is, the distinction of sensible things 
 from ideas of sensation, ) Reid took a different 
 line, and insisted that our elementary experiences 
 are judgments, that our sensations * suggest' real 
 external things, that is, are the occasions upon 
 which we, according to a natural law, apprehend 
 external things, of which we are therefore directly 
 aware. jHad Locke confined himself to ideas in 
 his <? own sense, he would have recognised (as he 
 does) that we experience both minds and sensible 
 things, as supplied by reflection and sensation 
 respectively ; and that sensible things, while they 
 claim a real existence, are mental in character in 
 so far as they are inter-related with minds in the 
 same universe and affect them. 
 
 3. One vital consequence followed from Locke's 
 conception of ideas. So far as ideas are presented 
 to (or are in the mind), these objects are the 
 peculiar possession of the individual mind which 
 thinks them. On the other hand, so far as they 
 63 
 
LOCKE 
 
 are always regarded as corresponding to some 
 thing, which by God's good pleasure produces 
 them, we tend to forget their individual char- 
 acter. Locke faithfully describes the world as he 
 finds it, but because there is the background of 
 independent real things, we forget that the ideas 
 are relative only to the individual. Locke, in 
 fact, invests his ideas with all the characters that 
 belong to the real world of objects, which are not 
 confined to one man's inspection, but are open to 
 all. Strictly speaking, the ideas belong only to 
 the individual, and Locke is ready to admit that 
 this is so. The common use of language between 
 man and man implies that they give the same 
 names to corresponding ideas, but ' when he re- 
 presents to himself other men's ideas by some of 
 his own, if he consent to give them the same 
 names that other men do, it is still to his own 
 ideas.' 1 But when mental objects are thus indi- 
 vidual, they fail of the universal character which 
 we attribute to the objects of knowledge. To quote 
 the famous example of Kant, there is a great 
 difference between the experience that when I see 
 the sun shine I feel the stone grow warm, and the 
 experience that the sun warms the stone. The 
 second proposition is knowledge, and is the 
 
 1 Essay y Book in., ch. ii. 2. 
 
 6 4 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 common object of all ; the first is part of the con- 
 tents of the mind of an individual, or if we use 
 the word history in Locke's sense, it is part of the 
 life-history of an individual. Strictly speaking, 
 llulowledge, as Locke conceives it, is part of the * 
 life-history of an individual. Such individualism 
 is inevitable, if the objects we know, the ideas, 
 are detached from the objects themselves. /We 
 can no more acquire common knowledge from 
 putting together the life-histories of individuals, 'Q 
 than we could get a state from putting together 
 a number of purely self-seeking agents. It was 
 Kant's ..great merit to have recognised this 
 problem, though it by no means follows that 
 we must Accept his solution of it. ^What we may ~ 
 do is to deny the existence of ideas, as copies of 
 things, and to recognise that we directly appre- 
 hend the things themselves^ 
 
 4. Locke's individualism arose from his sever- 
 ing ideas from things. Had he, describing experi- 
 ence, omitted ideas or omitted things, he need 
 not have been open to this charge. He can only 
 bring mind and mind together by the happy 
 accident that they think alike. But in another 
 important respect he falls short of his own ideal 
 of describing the contents of experience. MHe Q 
 overlooks the fact of continuity. The objects of 
 E 65 
 
LOCKE 
 
 experience are to him fragmentary and discon- 
 nectedA It is not strictly true to say, as has some- 
 times been said, that for him every idea must be 
 gone as soon as apprehended. For ideas may 
 contain the relations of persistence and identity. 
 These relations are themselves part of our world 
 of ideas. What is true is that the connections 
 
 MM. 
 
 between ideas are external to them. Mutualities are 
 grouped together by the mechanical bond of an 
 underlying support or substance. \ Effect follows 
 cause in the external world in empirical succes- 
 sion. Ideas have identity ' when they vary not 
 at all from what they were at that moment 
 wherein we consider their former existence, and 
 to which we compare the present/ i.e. their 
 identity is not individual continuity but like- 
 ness of quality. The same account applies to 
 all the other ' relations ' between ideas which 
 knowledge directly apprehends. For though 
 when the ideas are ' considered together ' their 
 agreement or disagreement is not external but 
 follows from the nature of the ideas, yet the 
 ideas must first be ' considered together ' for their 
 relation to be perceived. Three is known to 
 be greater than two, and wKite different from 
 black as soon as they are compared, but there is 
 nothing, so far as Locke's description goes, in 
 66 
 
OBSERVATIONS ON THE ESSAY 
 
 three or in white, which compels us to compare 
 them with two or with black. It is true that 
 Locke is feeling after the real nature of causality 
 when, as already mentioned, he seeks for it in the 
 experience of our volitions. ButJ,o all intents 
 and purposes, in spite of his urging the inter-re- 
 latedness of things, the world is to him a number * 
 of isolated atoms grouped together in the last 
 resort by the good pleasure of God, as indeed 
 his follower Berkeley explicitly affirmed.; Locke's 
 badinage of Malebranche's opinion tKat 'we see 
 all things in God' is a good illustration of his 
 insensibility to the cardinal fact of continuity. 
 Malebranche had said that ' when we would think 
 of anything in particular, we at first cast our view 
 upon all beings,' meaning that each thing is 
 seen as a fragment or a limitation of the whole 
 vague universe. ' I do not think/ says Locke, 
 ' that my country neighbours, when they first 
 wake in the morning, find it impossible to think 
 of a lame horse they have, till they have run over 
 in their minds " all beings " that are, and then 
 pitch on dapple.' 
 
 The omission of continuity in the description 
 
 of experience is a case of oversight inexplicable 
 
 enough, were it not that description is the most 
 
 difficult of tasks, but shared with Locke by a long 
 
 67 
 
LOCKE 
 
 line of successors. The failure to recognise it led 
 to frank scepticism in Hume, it led in Kant to 
 attempts to overcome the disconnectedness of the 
 world by mechanical inventions like the categories. 
 The oversight was not confined to sensible things ; 
 it applied to the mind also. For the mind as de- 
 scribed by Locke is as disconnected as the qualities 
 of external things. There is nothing but the 
 spiritual substance which supports the group or 
 succession of mental operations. Locke over- 
 looks the fact, as important and as plain to us as 
 thinking or willing itself, that the mind's action 
 is 'sensibly continuous.' It was not till recent 
 years that the face of psychology was changed by 
 substituting the experienced fact of mental con- 
 tinuity for the inherited conception or prejudice 
 that the mind is known only as a series of mental 
 events. 
 
 68 
 
CHAPTER IV 
 
 ETHICS 
 
 LOCKE'S contribution to Ethics in the Essay is 
 short, but it is remarkable. jOood and evil are 
 nothing but 'pleasure and pain or that which 
 occasions pleasure and pain to us/ ' Moral good 
 or evil then is only the conformity or disagree- 
 ment of our voluntary actions to some law where- 
 by good and evil are drawn on us from the will ^ 
 and power of the law-maker ; which good or evil, 
 pleasure or pain, attending our observance or 
 breach of the law, by the decree of the law-maker, 
 is that we call reward and punishment/ Moral 
 good or evil is thus a relation of human actions, 
 which are modes, to other modes which are rules 
 of action. |Locke enumerates three sorts of moral 
 codes, with their enforcements or ' sanctions ' the 
 divine law, ' which is the measure of sin and duty, 
 given by God whether by revelation or the light *\ 
 of nature ' ; the civil law, the measure of crime 
 and innocence ; and the law of opinion, reputation 
 or fashion, which is the measure of virtue or 
 69 
 
LOCKE 
 
 vicei these terms being partly coincident with 
 the divine law, but only so far as the opinion of 
 societies, tribes or clubs of men agrees with that 
 law, which it in a great measure does. When we 
 ask what the contents of the moral law are, Locke 
 offers us a startling doctrine. 'The idea of a 
 Supreme Being infinite in power, goodness and 
 wisdom, whose workmanship we are and on whom 
 we depend; and the idea of ourselves as under- 
 standing rational beings, being such as are clear 
 in us, would, I suppose, if duly considered and 
 pursued afford such foundations of our duty and 
 rules of action as might place morality amongst 
 the sciences capable of demonstration ; wherein I 
 doubt not but from self-evident propositions, by 
 necessary consequences as incontestable as those 
 in mathematics, the measures of right and wrong 
 might be made out.' JThe science which Aristotle 
 regarded as less certain even than physical science 
 Locke puts on the level of mathematics. He gives 
 as illustration two propositions ' as certain as any 
 demonstration in Euclid : ' where there is no pro- 
 perty, there is no injustice ' ; and ' no government 
 allows absolute liberty^jThe complexity of moral 
 ideas and their want of sensible representation are, 
 he thinks, the reasons why as compared with 
 mathematics morality is thought incapable of 
 70 
 
ETHICS 
 
 demonstration. Molyneux urged Locke to publish 
 a treatise of Ethics based on this conception, and 
 Locke seems to have entertained the idea of doing 
 so, which was not however realised. How much 
 he recognised that human reasoning unassisted 
 by religion falls short of what is required by his 
 ideal of Ethics may be seen from a passage of 
 the Reasonableness of Christianity. ' Experience 
 shows that the knowledge of morality by mere 
 natural light (how agreeable soever it be to it) 
 makes but a slow progress and little advance in 
 the world. And the reason of it is not hard to be 
 found in men's necessities, passions, vices and 
 mistaken interests, which turn their thoughts 
 another way; and the designing leaders as well 
 as following herd find it not to their purpose to 
 employ much of their meditations this way. 
 Human reason unassisted failed men in its great 
 and proper business of morality. It never from 
 unquestionable principles made out an entire 
 body of the " law of nature." ' We can only con- 
 jecture what the science would have been. God 
 and His attributes are known to us by demonstra- 
 tion, and ourselves by direct intuition, and, as the 
 sentence just quoted indicates, Locke would pro- 
 bably, as Sidgwick suggests, have demonstrated 
 from man's nature the body of laws which under 
 
LOCKE 
 
 the name of laws of nature he inherited from 
 Grotius and Puffendorf. It is certain that in 
 Locke's view the value of moral laws is not de- 
 rived from the pleasure and pain they bring by 
 way of sanction. He does not even allow with 
 Bentham and his school, the so-called Hedonists, 
 that human action is determined by the prospect 
 of pleasure or pain. On the contrary, he maintains 
 that it is determined by present ' uneasiness ' or 
 desire. Though we all do desire happiness and 
 in the end good is what is productive of pleasure, 
 the laws of morality are not based upon a utili- 
 tarian foundation but follow from the nature of 
 man and his relation to God. 
 
 Y*" 
 
 But ]the same unsolved problem which met us 
 in his treatment of mathematics, how mathe- 
 matical laws can be valid of sensible facts, con- 
 fronts us again in a corresponding form in Ethics. 
 How can propositions, which follow from abstract 
 human nature, be applicable to or true of a world 
 of concrete men ? Moral judgments vary from 
 country to country and from age to age. This 
 was one of Locke's reasons, and a correct one, for 
 denying the innateness of moral principles. But 
 it does not seem to have disturbed his belief in 
 the abstract character of moral laws. Yet it 
 implies either that these varying and conflicting 
 72 
 
ETHICS 
 
 judgments are not moral or else that morality is 
 not abstract. / The greater the difficulty there is 
 in arriving "a<T an abstract conception of human 
 nature or of what God intended man to be, the 
 more it seems we must turn for a basis of moral 
 judgment to considering the actual passions and 
 circumstances of mankind. 
 
 The only other memorable chapter which Locke 
 writes on Ethics, or rather the psychology of 
 Ethics, is the extremely perplexed and perplex- 
 ing discussion of the freedom of the will which 
 he modified considerably in his life-time, and 
 j^rofessed himself dissatisfied with to the end. 
 
 ] Locke denies that we can speak intelligibly of 
 ireedom of the will, since the will is one power 
 and freedom is another. It is the whole man 
 who is free. We are free so far as we can act or 
 forbear action ; yet we are not free to act other- 
 wise than we do ; to maintain that we are would 
 be to declare that a man is not pleased to do 
 what he is pleased to do. (Yet just when Locke 
 appears to be committing himself to determin- 
 
 ism, he declares that true freedom is found in the 
 power we have of suspending judgment before 
 action, and consequently the right improvement 
 of our liberty consists in right consideration, in 
 the government of the passions, in the constant 
 73 
 
LOCKE 
 
 determination of 'prosecuting true felicity/ and 
 ' suspending this prosecution in particular cases, 
 till they have looked before them, and informed 
 themselves whether that particular thing which 
 is then proposed or desired lie in the way to their 
 main end, and make a real part of that which is 
 their greatest good/ 
 
 74 
 
CHAPTER V 
 
 POLITICS 
 
 c THE power of the civil law/ Locke says in the 
 Essay y ' is the force of the commonwealth engaged 
 to protect the lives, liberties and possessions of 
 those who live according to its laws, and has 
 power to take away life, liberty or goods from him 
 who disobeys/ He uses precisely identical terms 
 in defining political power in the second and more 
 famous of the two Treatises of Government which 
 were published in 1690, in the same year as the 
 Essay. Half of what he wrote or designed appears 
 to have been lost, but Locke hopes that the 
 papers which remain 'are sufficient to establish 
 the throne of our great Restorer, our present 
 King William, and make good his title in the 
 consent of the people ; which, being the only one 
 of all lawful governments, he has more fully and 
 clearly than any prince in Christendom ; and to 
 j ustify to the world the people of England, whose 
 love of their just and natural rights, with their 
 resolution to preserve them, saved the nation 
 75 
 
LOCKE 
 
 when it was on the very brink of slavery and 
 ruin/ The first treatise is a destructive criti- 
 cism of Filmer's Patriarcha, a work designed 
 to establish the claims of absolute monarchy as 
 inherited from Adam. Filmer appears to have 
 been so far historical in his method as the 
 Pentateuch, which he took for his authority, gives 
 us a picture of patriarchal society, which at any 
 rate was one form of government. But neither it 
 nor Locke's criticism of it interests us here. 
 
 The second treatise explains the nature of civil 
 society, by tracing its growth from the state of 
 nature or primitive condition of man, conceived 
 in the fashion in which it had come down from 
 the Stoics and Roman lawyers, who identified 
 it with the Age of Gold. It is a state of peace, 
 and is governed, if the term may be allowed, by 
 the law of nature supposed to be given to men by 
 the ' light of nature.' According to this law men 
 are free to dispose of themselves and their pos- 
 sessions as they think fit ; they are equal, and 
 bound in virtue of their equality to mutual bene- 
 volence. Their liberty is no licence; reason 
 teaches men that no one has a right to harm 
 another in his health, liberty or possessions. But 
 as he is bound to preserve himself, so he is to 
 preserve them. In the state of nature every man 
 76 
 
POLITICS 
 
 has a right to punish a transgressor, requiting him 
 as reason and conscience dictate. Two doctrines 
 are of special interest and importance. The right 
 of property belongs to any man, in so far as he 
 takes any part of the common possession, and 
 mixes his labour with it a doctrine fruitful of 
 consequences in subsequent thought. The rights 
 and duty of the parent arise from the weakness 
 of the children, and the necessity of rearing them 
 through infancy; and Locke thinks that the in- 
 stitution of marriage depends on that of the 
 family : it is the fact that a second child may be 
 born before the first is independent of its parents 
 that leads to permanent marriage. 
 
 From the inconveniences of this state of nature 
 civil society arises. For there is no settled law 
 allowed by common consent; the law of nature 
 is indeed plain, but men are biassed by their 
 interest; there is no 'indifferent' judge and no 
 sufficient power of enforcement. Men therefore 
 by consent divest themselves of their natural 
 liberty by uniting into a community c for their 
 comfortable, safe and peaceable living in a secure 
 enjoyment of their properties'; the united body 
 acting through the will of the majority. This is 
 the institution of commonwealth in a contract of 
 citizens with one another. The first result of this 
 77 
 
LOCKE 
 
 compact ' the first and fundamental positive 
 law ' is the establishing of the legislative power, 
 the supreme power to which government is dele- 
 gated in trust. But the law of nature is not 
 abandoned by the individual's surrender of his 
 liberties to the state, but on the contrary, 'its 
 obligations are only in many cases drawn closer, 
 and have by human laws known penalties an- 
 nexed to them, to enforce their observation.' 
 The legislative power receives therefore no arbi- 
 trary authority, but it is limited by the public 
 good of the society. An executive is established 
 for permanent enforcement of the law, but may 
 be removed by the legislative. The prince or 
 monarch holds his commission therefore as a 
 trust conferred on him by the law ; his preroga- 
 tive is but ' the power left in his hands to provide 
 for the public good, in such cases which, depend- 
 ing on unforeseen and uncertain occurrences, cer- 
 tain and unalterable laws could not safely direct/ 
 When the prince abuses or neglects his trust, or 
 when the legislature abuses its trust, the govern- 
 ment is dissolved, and the people can provide for 
 themselves by establishing a new one. 
 
 Locke's conception of civil society and govern- 
 ment is thus completely foreign to that of a 
 theocracy, and is directed against such a concep- 
 78 
 
POLITICS 
 
 tion. He maintained that civil society and the 
 church have entirely different concerns. 'The 
 power of civil government relates only to man's 
 civil interests/ But 'a church I take to be a 
 voluntary society of men joining themselves to- 
 gether, of their own accord, in order to the public 
 worshipping of God, in such a manner as they 
 judge acceptable to Him and effectual to the 
 salvation of their souls/ The whole doctrine of 
 the Letter Concerning Toleration, from which 
 these words are taken, follows from this. The 
 magistrate, as such, has no concern with religion ; 
 he cannot interfere with worship and belief. He 
 can only do so legitimately in so far as religious 
 worship or doctrine brings the members of a 
 church into conflict with the good of the civil 
 society. And it is only so far as this is the case 
 so far, that is, as they may be influenced in 
 their civil relations by obedience to an external 
 authority that Locke denies toleration to Roman 
 Catholics ; and only because to disbelieve in God 
 renders a man unfit for civil life that he excludes 
 Atheists from the benefit of the toleration which 
 he would extend to Mahomedans. 
 
 The effort of Locke's political doctrine (and 
 hence its historical, as distinguished from its philo- 
 sophical, importance) was to ' establish William's 
 
 79 
 
LOCKE 
 
 throne on the consent of the people/ The effort 
 of Hobbes's doctrine of the State in the Leviathan 
 was to justify the divine right of the Stuarts. 
 With Hobbes the state of nature is one of warfare 
 from which the law of nature or reason bids 
 man depart in order to self-preservation, handing 
 over their rights to a man or body of men, the 
 sovereign. The sovereign, with Hobbes, bears the 
 rights of all the members of the society, is the 
 'person' of the commonwealth, and is therefore 
 distinct altogether from Locke's rnqnarch, or prince, 
 whose capacity is only fiduciary. WithXocke, on 
 the other hand, the state of nature is not left 
 behind, but the law of nature which regulated it 
 is continued into civil society and enforces the 
 ideal conditions of the state of nature. Both 
 writers employ the fiction of a social contract, 
 arising out of the supposed state of nature after 
 experience of its inconveniences. Locke pleads 
 that the state of nature may actually still be 
 traced in the relations of princes, and even in 
 certain peoples who act by popular consent. But 
 he says, in answer to those who doubt the genesis 
 of commonwealth from a state of nature, that 
 naturally enough the state of nature eludes our 
 historical search, for 'government is everywhere 
 anterior to records/ and early peoples are actually 
 80 
 
ROLITICS 
 
 found already under paternal government, the 
 head or father of the group being chosen as the 
 fittest to govern. In truth, the picture of the 
 origin of society from a state of nature by an 
 original compact only illustrates the natural 
 tendency to account for society by analysing it 
 into its fundamental elements and then making 
 the historical assumptions that these elements 
 existed before the society itself was created. Ac- 
 cording as the imagination of the writer was more 
 impressed by the Yahoo or the Houyhnhnm in 
 human nature, he described the state of nature as 
 one of war or of benevolence. In Locke this 
 tendency is parallel to that which led him in his 
 philosophy partially to confuse the analysis of 
 complex ideas into their simple elements with the 
 historical statement or fiction that simple ideas 
 precede, and are combined by the mind into, com- 
 plex ideas. 
 
 The fiction of the original compact by consent 
 of the people (a fiction almost unavoidable if 
 abstract theories must be clothed in the language 
 of concrete life) really did attach the belief of 
 Locke, as it did that of Hobbes and of the writers 
 to whom Locke owes most for his political specu- 
 lation, of whom Hooker was the chief. It was 
 shared by the later writer, Rousseau, whom he 
 F 81 
 
LOCKE 
 
 anticipated. /In^ an important respect Locke fell 
 short of Rousseau ; he did not reach that writer's 
 
 ifeh 
 
 conception of the ' general will ' as the sovereign, 
 but contented himself with the consent of the 
 people acting by the ma|<fr,ity, by what Rousseau 
 
 called the ' will of all/ He missed the organic 
 or personal feature in civil society. In this re- 
 spect Hobbes's conception of the sovereign as the 
 ' person ' or bearer of the rights of the common- 
 wealth is superior to Locke's.\ Only once does he 
 approach this conception, ^Een he points to the 
 natural or 'federative' power of a commonwealth, 
 whereby (as in war^it acts as one body against 
 an external nation:|The body politic is, for Locke, 
 an aggregate of consenting individuals; just as in 
 metaphysics the knowledge, which is the common 
 property of all, appears to be the propositions 
 which all happen to make identically. And as in 
 
 ( \ his metaphysics this defect was concealed by his 
 assumption of a world of real existences, which 
 was there for every one to acquire knowledge of 
 through ideas, it was concealed in his political 
 theory by the persistence of the supposed cfbjee- 
 tive and universal ' laws of nature/ from the state 
 of nature into civil society./ 
 
 Locke's doctrine of civil government may be 
 said to have represented the better spirit of the 
 82 
 
POLITICS 
 
 Revolution. But neither that doctrine nor the 
 doctrine of toleration was received with universal 
 or immediate acceptance in England. But they 
 set up the ideal of thinking in matters of civil 
 and religious liberty for the next century. Tolera- 
 tion was introduced in England not at once, nor 
 in the form which Locke demanded as the non- 
 interference of the state in religion, but in the 
 form of indulgence, of removal (and a qualified v 
 one) of the restrictions on dissenters as com- 
 pared with the favoured church. The specula- 
 tive foundations of Locke's political doctrine have 
 given way or have needed repair. But its politi- 
 cal influence was great, and due allowance being 
 made for its speculative defects, it represents not 
 only the ideals of the finer minds of 1688, but in 
 substance the common-sense of our political con- 
 stitution as we have come to understand it. It 
 exercised a most powerful influence through its 
 effect upon Montesquieu. When the terms of the 
 fundamental declaration of American independ- 
 ence were borrowed as they were from Locke's 
 political treatise, Locke rendered a greater service 
 to political liberty than when he drafted or helped 
 to draft the constitutions of Carolina, which ap- 
 pear to have been inoperative. 
 
CHAPTER VI 
 
 RELIGION 
 
 THE concluding chapters of the Essay set forth 
 the boundaries between faith and reason. Assent 
 in Locke's sense varies in its degrees according to 
 the grounds of probability and it is always less 
 than knowledge. But there is ' one sort of pro- 
 positions which challenges the highest degree of 
 assurance, whether or not the thing proposed 
 agrees or disagrees with common experience and 
 the ordinary course of things.' These are the 
 truths of revelation, the assurance of which is 
 faith. While reason is the 'discovery of the 
 certainty or probability of propositions by ob- 
 servation from ideas got by sensation or reflec- 
 tion/ faith is ' the assent to any proposition not 
 thus made out, but upon the credit of the pro- 
 poser as coming from God in some extraordinary 
 manner/ Revelation can indeed give us no new 
 simple ideas which we had not before by sensation 
 or reflection ; and though it may make us know 
 propositions already known through reason it 
 84 
 
RELIGION 
 
 cannot be admitted against the clear evidence 
 of reason. If this is true of direct revelation, 
 still less can revealed truths be accepted merely 
 on the authority of tradition, or of a book, unless 
 reason convinces us that the book itself is in- 1 
 spired. But there are subjects which, not being 
 contrary to reason, are above reason, and these if 
 revealed are matters of faith to which we can give 
 a full assurance, provided always that reason 
 judges whether the revelation is such, and what 
 the words mean in which it is contained. It 
 follows that even when we can judge by our 
 natural powers, 'an evident revelation should 
 determine our assent even against probability/ 
 In the case of miracles when properly attested 
 their very strangeness makes them fitted to pro- 
 duce belief, when, Locke adds in significant words, 
 ' they are suitable to ends aimed at by Him who 
 has power to change the course of nature.' 
 
 Thijs definition of the separate powers of faith 
 and reason, according to which faith 'cannot be 
 afforded to anything but upon good reason' and 
 so cannot be opposite to it, and at the same time 
 is described as an ' assent founded on the highest 
 reason/ makes Locke at once a believer and a 
 rationalist. [All that he does in the Essay to 
 elucidate his doctrine is to 'protest against what 
 85 
 
LOCKE 
 
 he calls enthusiasm, what we should call fanati- 
 cism, upon which he added a chapter in the fourth 
 edition, which admirably illustrates both his 
 breadth and his cautious restraint. 'Revelation 
 is natural reason enlarged,' but enthusiasm, which 
 persuades itself of immediate intercourse with 
 God, without help of reason, but ' from the con- 
 ceits of a warmed or overweening brain/ pretend- 
 ing to an internal light, sins against the supreme 
 arbitration of reason. It takes away reason to 
 make way for revelation and puts out the light 
 of both. 'For God (he adds in a well-known 
 phrase) when He makes the prophet doth not un- 
 make the man/ 
 
 But the real meaning of Locke's blending of 
 faith and rationalism and of the credence which 
 he attaches to miracles, is only adequately seen 
 when we take into account his Reasonableness of 
 Christianity, a book which, besides many tedious 
 pages, contains some of Locke's finest work. Locke 
 determined, he tells us, to put aside all works of 
 divinity and endeavour to discover the message 
 of the New Testament itself as it presented itself 
 to a candid and unbiassed reader. The plainness 
 of the doctrine made him surprised that every- 
 body did not see and embrace it. Though at his 
 first setting out he was ignorant where his search 
 86 
 
RELIGION 
 
 would conduct him, he was impressed by the 
 'wonderful harmony leading to the same points 
 in all the parts of the sacred history of the 
 Gospels.' Two things, and only two things, he 
 found> besides belief in one God, are taught by 
 Jesus and by His apostles as the condition of 
 the new covenant : faith and repentance believ- 
 ing Jesus to be the Messiah, and through this 
 faith adopting a good life. This replaced the 
 Mosaic law of works and the morality of the 
 heathen. All else contained in the Scriptures 
 beyond these fundamental articles, though truths 
 and to be believed by one who knows them, a 
 man may still be ignorant of and yet be saved, or 
 may interpret differently from other men accord- 
 ing to his lights. That there is one God, that Jesus 
 is the Messiah, and that we must live a good 
 life, are enough. The essential reasonableness of 
 Christianity consisted, to Locke, therefore, in its 
 declaration of God's unity, no longer restricted 
 to one people but delivered to all mankind, and 
 its bringing to righteousness through this faith 
 weak men who cannot by reason attain to rules of 
 morality. 'Natural religion in its full extent 
 nowhere had been taken care of by the force of 
 natural reason.' ' Nobody that I know before our 
 Saviour's time ever did or went about to give us 
 87 
 
LOCKE 
 
 a morality . . . which mankind might have re- 
 course to as their unerring rule. Such a law of 
 morality Jesus Christ hath given us in the New 
 Testament, but by the latter of these ways, by 
 revelation.' 
 
 It is plain, therefore, from the spirit of this work 
 (as well as from the little posthumous Discourse 
 on Miracles) that^for Locke not only the belief in 
 Christian revelation but in the miracles by which 
 it was supported depended on the evidence which 
 the revelation supplies of the < ends aimed at by 
 God.' ' The miracles are to be judged by the 
 doctrine, not the doctrine by the miracles.' 1 Their 
 significance to him lies not so much in their con- 
 trariety to ordinary events, as in the light they 
 threw upon the divine nature, which could use 
 them to enforce a system of morality, thoroughly 
 acceptable to the human reason^\ Locke's pro- 
 found belief in the concern which God has for His 
 universe which He creates, and his willingness to 
 base our theoretical conviction of God's existence 
 on a precarious use of the conception of causality, 
 leave as many questions unsolved as they solve. 
 But at least they do not blur the problem by 
 omitting one portion of the data. 
 
 1 From the Journal. See Fox Bourne, vol. i. p. 464 (quoted 
 by Fraser). 
 
 88 
 
RELIGION 
 
 The rationalism of Locke made him the parent 
 of Deism, which neglected the faith which he com- 
 bined with his rationalism. In the controversy over 
 the question whether natural or rational religion 
 could be reconciled with Christianity as a revealed 
 religion supported by miracles, the Deists were 
 those who upheld natural religion and directly 
 and indirectly, with irony more or less concealed, 
 depreciated Christianity. The latitude practised 
 by the orthodox writers made them not always or 
 easily distinguishable from the Deists, one of whom 
 indeed claimed Archbishop Tillotson as the source 
 of Deism. It is not strange, therefore, that though 
 Locke must be reckoned on the side of the ortho- 
 dox, the Deists should have derived their inspira- 
 tion from him. The circumstances have been 
 related which brought Locke into conflict with 
 Stillingfleet. Toland's argument to show that 
 the Gospels contained nothing ' above reason' was 
 based by him on Locke's Essay and repudiated 
 by Locke. Collins who had been an ardent pupil 
 of Locke wrote in his Discourse of Free-thinking 
 one of the deistical books which excited the live- 
 liest controversy. jThe deistical doctrine passed 
 through various phases in England during the first 
 half of the eighteenth century and then died out. 
 But it left its traces in two minds of the first 
 G 89 
 
LOCKE 
 
 order. In England it led to Hume's Essay on 
 Miracles and his Dialogues concerning Natural 
 Religion. Abroad it led to the deism of Voltaire, 
 who left England in 1728 to become the mission- 
 ary in Europe of the philosophy of Newton and 
 Locke. Hume and Voltaire represent (not in 
 religion only) the disintegrating and sceptical 
 tendency, which was one, but only one element 
 in Locke's philosophy. A new construction 
 followed in the latter part of the century, first 
 in Rousseau and then in Kant, 
 
 90 
 

14 DAY USE 
 
 RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BO 
 
 14 DAY USE 
 
 RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED 
 
 LOAN DEPT. 
 
 This book is due on the last date stamped below, or 
 
 on the date to which renewed. 
 Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. 
 
 
 
 flllP 2/t '64 
 
 
 RUu *.H v ^ 
 
 
 REC'D CD 
 
 
 flllR2'fiA ^PM 
 
 
 HUu ^ O*l O r III 
 
 *, 
 
 
 41'^ie'D LD 
 
 
 MAR 13 '65 -10 A 
 
 VI 
 
 
 
 REC'D LD 
 
 
 Ann 1 q >CR -12 PM 
 
 
 HrK 1 / DO ri 
 
 
 
 
YB 23582 
 
 X" 
 
 
 
 * 
 
 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY