i. i> &*~ \ &* THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES THE STUDY OF ETHICS A SYLLABUS BY TJOHN DEWE1Y GEORGE WAHR, PUBLISHER AND BOOKSELLER ANN ARBOR, MICH. , 1897. COPYRIGHT JOHN DEWEY 1894 THB INLAND PRESS, PRINTERS ANN ARBOR Education Library PREFATORY NOTE. The edition of my Outlines of Ethics having been exhausted, I have prepared the following pages, primarily for the use and guidance of my own students. The demand for the for- mer book seems, however, to justify the belief that, amid the prevalence of pathological and moralistic ethics, there is room for a theory which conceives of conduct as the normal and free living of life as it is. The present pages, it may be added, are in no sense a second edition of the previous book. On the contrary, they undertake a thorough psychological examination of the process of active experience, and a derivation from this analysis of the chief ethical types and crises a task, so far as I know, not previously attempted. ERRATA. Page 91, for 'Chapter VI,' read 'Chapter VII.' 973941 CONTENTS. PAGE. Chapter I. The Nature of Ethical Theory 1 Chapter II. The Factors of Moral Conduct 5 Chapter III. A General Analysis of Conduct 13 Chapter IV. The Moral Consciousness 17 Chapter V. Moral Approbation 24 Chapter VI. Reflective Approbation, Conscience 71 Chapter VII. Nature of Obligation 91 Chapter VIII. Freedom and Responsibility 118 Chapter IX. Virtue and the Virtues 132 SYLLABUS-ETHICAL THEORY. CHAPTER I. NATURE OF ETHICAL THEORY. SECTION I. SUBJECT-MATTER OF ETHICS. Subject-matter of ethical theory is judgment concerning the value of conduct. Three stages. (1) Practical encour- agement and discouragement of - certain acts. Reward, and punishment primary forms of such judgments. (Next stage, urging and restraint through speech. (See Plato, Protagoras, 325-26.) (Third stage,) reflective judgment as to reason for V . S such acts. Ethical theory is simply (I) a systematic judgment of value. The way is prepared for this through the fact that primitive judgments relate not to isolated acts, but to habits of action, and to the types of character which are disposed to induce those habits. Necessary spontaneous generalizations. Codes, "cTHfom"ary and legislative. Demand for more systematic generalization arises when, thiough an extension of the area of life, former habits begin to conflict with each other. Illustrated by Athenian life; by Roman; by modern since the Renascence. Ethical theory is thus (2) a critical judgment upon conduct. Not systematic in the sense that it simply catalogues previous judgments, but in the sense that it attempts to reconstruct them 011 the basis of a deeper principle. (See Sec. 2.) It is a matter of indifference whether we say ethical theory attempts to systematize (in the above sense ) judgments about the value of conduct, or attempts to systematize conduct itself. Every act (consciously performed) is a judgment of value: tin; act dene is done because it is thought to be worth while, or valuable. Thus a man's real (as distinct frjm his nominal or 2 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. symbolic) theory of conduct can be told only from his acts. Conversely, every judgment about conduct is itself an act; it marks a practical and not simply a theoretical attitude. That is, it does not lie outside of the matter judged (conduct), but constitutes a part of its development; conduct is different after, and because of the judgment. 111. in education, where the main point is not so much to get certain acts done, as to induce in the child certain ways of valuing acts, from which the performance of the specific deeds will naturally follow. That is, the best education aims to train conscience. Ethical theory is only a more conscious and more generalized phase of conduct. Analogy with place of theory in modern (experi- mental) science. A theory not a fixed or abstract truth, but a standpoint and method for some activity. It is in this (the activity as directed by theory) that the value of the theory comes out and is tested. (See Sec. 3.) References: Definitions of ethics will be found in Murray, Introduction to Ethics, pp. 1-7; Porter, Elements of Moral Science, Introductory; Muirhead, Elements of Ethics, chs. 1 and 2; Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics, Introduction; Bowne, Principles of Ethics, Introduction. SECTION II. RISE OF ETHICAL THEORY. Origin of reflective jnorality was in Greece. Other ethical codes were either customary or else conceived to be absolute emanations from a divine will. The Greek was in the habit oF "discussing questions regarding ends and means of life. This strengthened by growth of democracy. Also by methods of education, which (in Athens) relied upon appeal to individual's own intelligence rather than upon conformity to fixed rule. (Davidson, Aristotle and Greek Education, pp. 11, 70, 86-87.) Development of commerce, and more general social intercourse among the Greeks, with growth of science and art, resulted in Sophist, who undertook to teach virtue and methods and aims of political influence; he also discussed the moral standard, some denying any moral criterion whatever, holding it possible THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 3 to prove arbitrarily an act either right or wrong; others hold- ing the source of moral law to be the superior power of the ruler. Thus they raised, the question whether moral distinc- tionsPexist iij^the nature of things, or simply^-by arbitrary enactment, osS/for convenience find expediency. While the Sophists themselves tended to uus\ver the question in one of the two latter senses, the dramatists (yEschylus and Sophocles) had, amid the disintegration of the lower religious beliefs, attempted to maintain an eternal and intrinsic moral law and ideal. Soc- rates took the latter position, and attempted to uphold it by means of the weapons of the Sophists themselves, i. e., by inquiry and reflection. He attacked the ideas that morality is based upon the will of the stronger, that it rests upon custom, and that it is adequately expressed in the more or less hap- hazard and external conclusions of the poets and ordinary moral teachers of the times. (See Plato, Republic, Books 1-3.) He insisted that the only adequate and sure basis for morality is knowledge of the Good, i. e., true end of life, and * "^*^^^fc^ ~ """ - m J**~ f ability to refer the value of particular acts and aims to this < -"x_, / ^^"^""^i supreme end. He thus became the founder of conscious eth- fa_ ical theory. See Sidgwick, History of Ethics, esp. ch. 2; Grant, Ethics of Aristotle, ch. 2; Paulsen, Ethik, bk. 1, ch. 1; Grote, His- tory of Greece, chs. 57 and 58; Hegel, History of Philosophy (trans, by Haldane), vol. 1; Fairbanks, on Sophocle's Ethics, International Journal of Ethics, vol. 2, 77; and Butcher, As- pects of Greek Genius; Hellenica, essays by Myers and Ab- bott. Consult also histories of philosophy by Erdmaun, Win- del band, and Ueberweg, portions treating of Sophists and Socrates. SECTION III. RELATION OF MORAL THEORY TO PRACTICE. As already said, ethical theory arises from practical needs, and is not simply a judgment about conduct, but a part of con- duct, a practical fact. (See Aristotle, Ethics, Book L, chs. 2 and 3; ch. 6; Book X., ch. 9.) The inference sometimes 4 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. drawn from this is that ethics is not a science but an art. (For two strong statements of this view, see Mill, Logic, Book 6, ch. 12, and Martineau, Essays, vol. 2, pp. 6-9; strong state- ment of contrary view, see Bradley, Logic, pp. 247-249.) We have to ask, therefore, whether ethics is practical in value, because it is, or is not, a science. The former position will be taken . 1. Moral value not equivalent to preaching or moralizing. Truth has its own moral value, all the greater because not deflected to serve some immediate end of exhortation. 2. Current antithesis between science and art not tenable. Science does not teach us to know; it is the knowing; art does not teach us to do, it is the doing. Art of morality is practice of it, not rules laid down. Same of art of dyeing, of mensura- tion, etc. Rules give basis for mechanical routine, not for art. Art is based upon insight into truth, or relations involved. 3. Question whether word 'science' or word 'art' is to be applied to ethics is of very little account. But question is as to whether ethics is to be regarded as helpful to morals because of scientific insight into truth afforded, or because of its formu- lation of precepts for action. In the latter case, it "helps" the moral life, only by depriving it of its freedom. 111. by physiology and hygiene. In former case, helps by freeing it: by making it more significant and effective as knowledge of mechanics helps a bridge builder. Importance of distinction illustrated by moral value of teachings of Jesus: Did he lay down rules for life, or did he give insight into nature of life? That is, is "salvation" conformity to some scheme laid down, or is it the freeing of life reached through knowledge of its real nature and relations? Summary. So far as agent needs rules, or fixed precepts, he does not perform his deeds from full personal preference, and hence is only imperfectly moral: so far as he understands and is personally interested in the acts demanded, he needs no rules. Hence the absurdity of defining ethical theory from the standpoint of rules. Casuistry. Difference between a THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 5 principle aud a rule; former a method for action, latter a pre- scription for it; former experimental, latter fixed; former orders in sense of setting ib order, latter in sense of command- ing. Practical value of moral theory is both destructive and constructive. Negative side always visible first. In ideal, destruction is only the reaction of the construction. So far as two are separated, reform becomes merely sentimental, or else mere fault finding. On practical value of moral theory, see Muirhead, Ele- ments, ch. 3; Lotze, Practical Philosophy, Introduction. Bradley, Ethical Studies, pp. 174-175. Green, Prolegomena t> Ethics, pp. 338-360; Hoeffdiug, Ethik, pp. 1-9; Interna- tional Journal of Ethics, vol. I., No. 2, Art. by Dewey, on Moral Theory and Moral Practice; p. 335, by James on The Moral Philosopher and the Moral Life (a very strong state- ment of the practical character of the moral judgment); vol. 4, p. 160, by Mackenzie, on Moral Science and Moral Life. CHAPTER II. THE FACTORS OF MORAL CONDUCT. THE AGENT AND HIS SPHERE OF ACTION. s SECTION IV. CONDUCT AS REFERRED TO THE AGENT. /No act is a part of conduct except as it is a part of a sys- tem of plans (purposes) and interests. Theory arose (as already seen) when these plans and interests were reflected upon with a view to their unification. Thus (for all European peoples since Socrates) an act must express character if it is to have moral meaning; it must be considered as the outcome of some aim aud interest on -the part of a conscious agent. (Spen- cer, Data of Ethics, ch. I.) The elements involved in such reference of an aet to an agent are: 1. Some knowledge of what he is about; that is, some end in view in doing the act. 2. Some interest in the act; the act is chosen or preferred. The agent not only knows A A ^^^^^^^ 7' / P. L~ . A A ^ ^^\^j^ji^L\. 6 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. vliat he is about as a reasoning automaton might, but the act appeals to him, has value for him. 3. The insight and the interest must be more than momen- tary they must express some stability. The act must proceed from a disposition, an established tendency, to act thus and so. This analysis was begun by Socrates and practically com- pleted by Aristotle. See Xenophon, Memorabilia, III., ch. 9; Plato, Protagoras, esp. pp. 352-359; Apol. 25; and Aristotle, Ethics, Book II., ch. 4. See also Green, Prolegomena, pp. 268-72. The contact of Greek thought with Semitic conceptions" (particularly through Christianity) emphasized the necessary reference of conduct to the agent. It made holiness of will (character, dominating idea and interest) the ideal, rather than the performance of certain acts: (compare idea of justification by faith) and proclaimed the criterion of moral worth to be in the personal attitude, rather than in the particular act. (See, e. g., I. Corinthians, ch. 13.) In its extreme forms, this emphasis made the act almost, indifferent; it was regarded as somehow "external," the ideal and attitude being all-sufficient per se. The contact with the Germanic peoples, with their strong Romanticism, emphasized also the other factor in the analysis namely the insistence upon the agent's own interest in his acts. It asserted the right of the individual to choose his own ends, and the worthlessnesS'(the slavery) of all acts not per- formed because of this personal preference. In its extreme form, this spirit became the demand for unlimited personal enjoyment- not mere sensuous enjoyment, but the right of the individual to realize to the uttermost the emotional value of his own acts. See Green, Works, Vol. III., p. 92; Carlyle, Sartor Resar- tus, Book II., ch. 9 (on the happiness of the shoe-black); Royce, Religious Aspect of Philosophy, pp. 110-126. Seth (editor) Essays in Philosophic Criticism^ Kilpatrick, on Pessi- mism and the religious Consciousness. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 7 SECTION V. REFERENCE OF CONDUCT TO THE SPHERE OF ACTION. la analyzing conduct, it is just as important to consider the situation as the agent. While conduct proceeds from an agent, the agent himself act with reference to the conditions as they present themselves. Conditions (environment) con- stitute action in the following ways: 1. The agent is moulded through education, unconscious I and conscious, into certain habits of thinking and 'feeling as I well as acting. His act, therefore, partakes of the aims and / disposition of his race and time. (See Grote, Plato, vol. I., p./ 249, for a strong statement of this influence). 2. Our acts are controlled by the demands made upon us. These demands include not simply the express requirements of other persons, but the Customary expectations of the family, social circle, trade or profession; the stimuli of surrounding objects, tools, books, &c. ; the range and quality of opportuni- ties afforded. 3. No idea, plan, wish whatever, can pass into action save through the forces of the environment. Unless, then, we mean to confine our definition of conduct entirely lo inner states of consciousness, we must include the scene of action within the definition. But the situation does more than execute the plan; through its acceptance or rejection of it, partial or complete, it p':icts into consciousness, and strengthens or modifies the |)luu. All existing ideals of all practical (i. e., non-senti- mental) agents are the outcome of such a struggle for realiza- tion. HISTORIC. At the outset of reflection, equal emphasis was put into the reference both to the agent and to the situation. Ethics, dealing with conduct in its individual reference, and politics, dealing with it in reference to the scene of action, were not separated. Plato, Republic, II. pp. 368-9, IV. pp. 427-445; Aristotle, Ethics, X., ch. 9; Politics, I., chs. 1 and 2; III., eh. 12. The term ethos meant the disposition or prevailing habit of the community (compare Lat. mos, mores), and it only grad- 8 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. ually shaded over iuto the idea of individual character. The exclusive reference of conduct to the individual came later, and was due, partly, to the influence of Christianity already referred to, and partly to the general disintegration of local customs and interests, consequent upon the growth of the Roman Empire. (See Renan, Hibbert Lectures, 1880.) The result was that the individual was thrown back into himself, the conditions of action seeming indifferent and even hostile to the realization of moral aims. Stoic, Epicurean, and Sceptic all agreed in setting up as their ideal the individual, self- 8ufficient,_tohimself, independent of everything beyond bim- self that is, every thmg beyond his own consciousness (Sedgwick, History of Ethics, pp. 70-73; Windelband, His- tory of Philosophy, pp. 164-170). The identification of the highest ideal with a good capable of realization only through supernatural assistance, and, as to content, only in another world, led in the Middle Ages to considering the present con- ditions of action as indifferent or profane, the state as the realm of force, not moral aims; and there was a corresponding exclusion of objective factors from the theory of conduct. Since the Reformation, however, the tendency has been stead- ily the other way. It has culminated in the present genera- tion through the development of the idea of evolution and of the historical method, on the scientific side; and through the growth of reforming and philanthropic interest on the practical side. The former have shown the immense part played by historic antecedents and by environment, physical and social, in shaping conduct. The latter has revealed that one of the chief obstacles to general and permanent moral reforms is x unfavorable institutions and habits of living. Herder, Philosophy of History Book IX., and Comte, Posi- tive Philosophy Book VI., are important references in the his- torical development of the present point of view. For various ideas on the social nature of ethics, see Alexander, Moral Order and Progress, pp. 5-15, 81-96; Yale Review, vol. L, pp. 301 and 354, Hadley, Ethics as Political Science; Mind, vol. II., THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 9 p. 453, Barratt, Ethics and Politics; vol. VIII., p. 222, Wal- lace, Ethics and Sociology; International Journal of Ethics, vol. III., p. 281, Mackenzie, Ethics and Economics; vol. IV., p. 133, Hibben, Ethics and Jurisprudence; Journal Specu- lative Philosophy, vol. XXII., p. 322, Patten, Economics and Morality. The necessity of including social conditions and relations in the idea of conduct is brought out, from different points of view, in Spencer, Data, ch. 8; Stephen, Science of Ethics, ch. 3; Green, Prolegomena, pp. 191-201; Bradley, Ethical Studies, pp. 148-156. SEC. VI. TWOFOLD FORMULA FOR CONDUCT. We may sum up the foregoing, on its practical side, by 1 saying that in order to secure right conduct we find ourselves I under the necessity of paying equal attention to the agent and to the conditions with reference to which he acts. No amount of external pressure or influence can secure right conduct of an agent, except in so far as it ceases to be external; except, that is, as it is taken up into the purpose and interests of the agent himself. But, on the other hand, there is no way to develop within the individual right plans, and to attach right values to ends, save as these plans reflect the requirements of the situa- tion in which he finds himself. A business situation gives an illustration. The agent, to be successful, must form his plans with reference to his condi- tions state of raw material, transportation facilities, demand in market, and others competing to supply this demand. His purposes, so far as rightly formed, are a synthesis or co-ordi- nation of the prevailing conditions of his scene of action. But this situation is not something hard and fixed, outside of the agent. What the situation is to him depends upon his own capacities his resources, skill, etc. He himself is a part of the conditions to be taken into account. Inferior raw material will yield to an invention which enables him to get more out of it, remoteness from market to his ability to contrive new methods of transportation, &c. In other words, the situation 10 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. is nothing but the complete co-ordiiiation of allhis powers ( abilities) and relations. Thus it is with that larger success in conduct, termed mo- rality. From the standpoint of the individual agent, Conduct is the co-ordinating, or bringing to a unity of aim and interest, the different elements of a complex situation. From the standpoint of the scene of action, Conduct is co-ordinating, in an organized way, the concrete powers, the impulses and habits, of an individual agent. (See Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 97-130.) SEC. VII. MORAL FUNCTIONS. Conduct may be considered as the same consciously that a biological function is unconsciously. It is the nature of every function to include within itself both organ and environment. The act of respiration is a co-ordination of lungs as organ and air as environment. So digestion, locomotion, etc. We are apt at first to identify function with the organ alone, and con- ceive of environment as if it bore a more external relation to it. But the reference to environment is absolute and intrinsic. The organ is the point of initiation for the function, and is more permanent than any particular portion of the environ ment. It is thus of more immediate importance. But it is the environment, comprehended in the exercise of the function, that finally fixes the organ (as food builds up the organism), and thus, indirectly or mediately, the environment is of the most importance. (Compare the mutual dependence of "appreciation^' and " retention." Psychology, p. 149.) It is equally an error then to consider either organ or environment as fixed in itself. Function is not the exercise of a predetermined organ upon an external environment, nor is it the adjustment of an organ to a predetermined environment. The nature of the function determines both the organ and the environment. Two animals in whom the function of nutrition is differently performed have, in virtue of that fact, different environments as well as different organs. Spencer, (Biology, THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 11 Part I., eh. 4; Psychology, Part Il; Ethics, pp. 75-76) has defined life, mind, and conduct as adjustment of inner rela- tions to outer; but the separation involved in calling one "inner" and the other "outer" marks the failure to recognize that function is not a parallelism between organ and environ- ment, but includes and determines both. SEC. VIII. ETHICAL POSTULATE. Interpreted In moral terms, the foregoing means that moral conduct cannot be adequately conceived as the property or per- formance of the agent alone. The agent corresponds to the organ biologically, and is thus, in itself, simply an instrument for exercising certain functions. Its structure, its aims, its interests, are controlled by the ends to be reached, and these ends include the conditions of action as well as the instrument. In other words, we cannot take the agent as final in defining conduct, because we demand a certain structure of the agent. Conversely, we require that the conditions of action be modified so as to permit the exercise of functions, so as to become the means of the realization of ends. The exercise of function itself tends to this transformation of environment. (Illustrated by nutrition, by industry, by valor, etc.) Defining conduct from the standpoint of the action, which includes both agent and his scene of action, we see that The conduct required truly to express an agent is, at the same time, the conduct required to maintain the situation in which he is placed; while, conversely, the conduct that truly meets the situation is that which furthers the agent. The word "truly" in this statement means with reference to the exercise of function. This statement may be termed the ethical postulate. Its analogy with the scientific postulate uuiforruity of nature, reign of law, etc. That is. we demand order in our expfirip.m'p The only proof ot its existence is in the results reached by making the demand. The postulate is verified by being acted upon. The proof is experimental. 12 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. The ethical postulate, iu other words, expresses the fact that moral experience continually demands of every agent that he shape his plans and interests so that they meet the needs of the situation, while it also requires that, through the agent, the situation be so modified as to enable the agent to express him- self freely. See Dewey, Outlines of Ethical Theory, p. 131. The discussion of conduct in relation to the agent consti- tutes psychological ethics: in relation to the conditions of action, social ethics. It must be borne in mind, however, that this distinction is one of point of view taken, not of material involved: the agent, that is, is a social fact as well as a psy- chical fact, and the conditions of action have a psychical as well as a social meaning. It should also be borne in mind throughout the whole dis- cussion that the aim is not to discover the ideal at which all conduct aims, nor the law which it should follow; the aim, once more, is not to find precepts or rules, but to analyze con- duct. The question is concerning the nature of any ideal and the part which it plays in conduct; the conditions which must be met to entitle any fact to the name of law, etc. PAKT II. PSYCHOLOGICAL ETHICS. CHAPTER III. A GENERAL ANALYSIS OF CON- DUCT. SECTION IX. THE NATURE OF IMPULSE. All conduct is at first impulsive. It has no end consciously in view. The self is constantly performing certain acts more or less determined in results, but without distinct consciousness of their significance. The food impulse; following light with eyes; handling; reaching; locomotion; the talking impulse. All activity is impulsive so far as containing new elements so far, that is, as it is not purely habitual. Impulse is not used as synonymous with instinct. The latter is a defined or limited impulse; the physical mechanism for the act is pretty definitely prearranged. In man, there are very few instincts pure and simple, but rather the loose beginnings and ends of very many instincts. Hence the range and variety of human, as compared with animal, actions. Hence also the impossibility of a syste- matic classification of fundamental impulses to action. (Such classifications were frequent in the older psychologies: see also Martineau, Types of Ethical Theory, vol. II., pp. 120-256, esp. p. 246). While the acts which have proved themselves necessary in the previous life of the race have become so organized into the structure of the individual that they now assert themselves spontaneously as appetites and aversions, each of these is so modified by the experiences and circum- stances of the agent that it is meaningless when separated. Such impulses as love of gain, love of fame, etc., are either pure abstractions, there being in the normal man no such thing as love of gain in general, (that is, unmodified by the make-up of his entire experience) or else they represent an 14 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. abstract classification of the various ends to which impulses may be directed. SECTION X. THE EXPRESSION OF IMPULSE AND ITS CON- SEQUENCES. The various impulses of the individual are not a loose bun- dle of tendencies existing side by side. Because they have \ been evolved in relation to the one more inclusive activity of (\inaintaiuing life, they are interconnected. One impulse in its c utterance tends to call up others, and this excitation or stimu- lation is not wholly dependent upon the circumstances of the moment, but follows (within widely variable limits) certain lines. Thus the movement of the eye in following light and of the hand in grasping an object tend to co ordinate, etc. The difference again between the lower animals and man is ^ that in the former this co-ordination is predetermined quite specifically, while in man onrjLJthevery general lines are laid down, thus leaving room for great variation and experimenta- tion implying possibility of new combinations, and thus the performance of new acts almost without limit. The acts, which to the animals are well defined ends, are, in the human structure, freed from their adjustment to predefined ends and made flexible instruments for a large number of different and much more complex ends. The definite co-ordination of acts is thus, with man, not a datum but a, problem. Each impulse in its expression tends to call up other impulses; and it brings into consciousness .other experiences. A child puts forth, by natural impulse, hjs hand towards a bright color; his hand touches it and he gets new experiences feelings of contact; these, in turn, are stimulus to a further act; he puts the thing in his mouth, and gets a taste, etc. In other words, the expression of every impulse stimulates other experiences and these react into the original impulse and modify it This reaction of the induced experiences into the inducing impulse is the psychological basis of moral conduct. In the ani- mals, so far as we can judge, the stimulus and the response THE STUDY OP ETHICS. 15 seem to assume purely serial order, one impulse calling forth its appropriate act, this its proper sequence and so on. The latter acts or experiences do not return into the earlier; they are not referred or reflected back. The animal life is one of association, not of thought or reflection. SECTION XI. WILL, OR THE MEDIATION OF IMPULSE. ^ ** i " This back-reference of an experience to the impulse which induces it, we may term the mediation of impulse. If we sup- pose that the series of experiences used in the previous illus- tration give the experience of an orange, then the next time the same impulse of following light occurs it is modified by all the experiences in which it previously resulted. It is qualitatively different; the image or idea of the pleasant con- tacts and tastes is now a part of the impulse. A child follows a purely natural impulse in making more or less articulate sounds; these sounds, through the response which others make to them (a response as natural as the sequence of contacts upon the following of light with the eye) set up other ex- periences of the child, and these induced experiences mediate the original babbling impulses. He finds that, expressing one impulse, he gets attention when he falls down; by another, food when he is hungry, etc. It is not simply that these results do follow, but that the child becomes conscious that they follow; that is, the results are referred back to the original impulse and enter into its structure in consciousness. It is evident that these mediations, or conscious baclt-refer- ences, constitute the meaning of the impulse they are its significance, its import. The impulse is idealized. The im- pulse mediated, that is given conscious value through the reference into it of the other experiences which will result from its expression, constitutes volition proper. SECTION XII. THE ETHICAL INTERPRETATION OK THIS PRO- CESS. As the primary point to understand, in ethical psychology, is the return of induced experiences into the stimulating im- 16 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. pulse, so the fundamental fallacy to avoid is the separation of impulse and induced experiences. It is too common an error to think of the expression of the impulse as an independent act and of the induced experiences as simply certain external consequences which follow upon the act, but which have nothing intrinsically to do with it which in themselves are indifferent to the act. (See Martineau, Types, vol. II., p. 24.) So we hear of the act and its consequences. In fact, the con- sequences, so far as they refer back, are the act as a moral or conscious (not simply physical) act. Differences of moral value (as we shall see later) depend simply upon the range and thoroughness of this mediation the completeness with which the "consequences" of an act are returned into the structure of the natural impulse. We thus see again the mis- take of the systems which attempt like Martiueau'e to build up ethical theory on the basis of separate natural impulses. Their moral value is in their interactions, not in themselves as independent. (Bentham, Principles of Morals and Legisla- tion, vol. I. of Works, pp. 49-55, brings out this truth very clearly; he uses, however, the term ' motive' to deuote what I call natural impulse, while I shall use the term motive to de- signate the mediated impulse.) The mediation of the impulse through the experiences it excites, may be comparatively organic or comparatively exter- nal. That is, some ' results ' are almost entirely conditioned upon the relation of the impulse expressed to other organs of action as satisfaction from food when hungry, ^burning hand from putting it in fire, etc., while others are due more to cir- cumstances which accompany the act at the time, but which may be absent as a rule as poison may be found in a food usually healthy. But this distinction is not rigid (that is, they are no 'results' absolutely internal and none absolutely external to the act) and does not afford a natural basis for separation of acts into those truly moral, and those morally in- different. A large part of our moral discipline consists pre- cisely in learning how to estimate probabilities to distinguish THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 17 between relatively necessary and relatively accidental results and to mediate the impulse accordingly. Psychologically, the mediation of impulse (a) idealizes the impulse, gives it its value, its significance or place in the whole system of action, and (b) controls, or directs it. The funda- mental ethical categories result from this distinction. The worth of an impulse is, psychologically, the whole set of expe- riences which, presumably, (that is, upon the best judgment available) it will call into being. This, ethically, constitutes the goodness (or badness) of the impulse the satisfaction (or dissatisfaction) which it carries. But the thought of the con- sequences which will follow, their conscious return back into the impulse, modify it check it, increase it, alter it. The impulse to reach, otherwise immediately expressed, is arrested by the nascent consciousness of the paiii of the burn, it is rein- forced by the nascent consciousness of the satisfaction of food the impulse to see is profoundly modified by the response of other experiences when the child learns to read, etc. In this modification, through reaction of anticipated experiences, we have the basis of what, ethically, we term obligation the necessity of modifying any particular expression cTTmpulse by the whole system of which it is one part. Thus we have, on one side, the moral categories of Satis- faction, Good (Summum bonum) Value, and, on the other, those of Duty, Law, Control, Standard, etc. Every concrete act, unites, of course, the two phases; in its complete charac- ter, as affording satisfaction and, at the same time, fulfilling its organic interactions, it is right and the agent which it expresses is free. Thus we have three main sets of ethical ideas; those centering, respectively, about (a) the Value, (b) the Control^ (c) the Freedom of conch CHAPTER IV. THE MORAL CONSCIOUSNESS. SECTION XIII. THE SUBJECT OF THE MORAL JUDGMENT. What is the subject, and what the predicate of the moral judgment? That is, to what do we attach the ideas of good, 18 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. bad, right, wrong, etc., and what is the meaning of these pre- dicates when attached? We begin by asking what it is that has moral meaning; what conditions must be met in order that ethical notions may be applied to any experience? We may sum up what we have already learned as follows: only an act i (and a conscious act) has moral significance; every conscious act, in its lowest terms, is a mediated impulse "mediation" being the reference back to an impulse of the experiences which it is likely to occasion. In this process, as we have seen, the consequences of the impulse cease to be mere external results and come to form the content of the act. We may recognize three degrees of completeness of this mediation. In the most complete reaction, the original or natural impulse is completely transformed; it no longer exists in its first condition; our impulse to locomotion, for example, is entirely made over when the reaction of other experiences into it is completed when we learn to walk; the first babbling impulse is wholly transformed when we learn to talk, etc. This also means that the mediating experiences are completely absorbed into the initiating impulse; the two sides, the imme- diate and the mediate, no longer have any separate existence. This complete reaction we call habit. When the reaction is less organized into the impulse, arid yet is closely connected with it, we have general lines or plans of action; the larger, more continuous and permanent expectations which form the framework, as it were, of our conduct one's occupation, the daily round of acts which, without being fixed habits, yet form the limits within which one's other acts fall. And finally, we have the particular variable acts, where the experiences which express an impulse are so numerous and complex as to be uncertain. In this case, the "consequences" do not organic- ally react of themselves, but we have to " think it over" and calculate as best we may the probable meaning of an act. If acts all came under the first principle, we should be slaves of routine; if they all came under the last, our whole time would be taken up with minute and anxious reflection THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 19 and our deeds would have no effectiveness. As it is, habits are the tools which put at our immediate disposal the results of our former experiences, thus economizing force; our general plans hold us within certain limits and thus keep us from being at the mercy of caprice or the flux of circumstance; while the play of the relatively uncertain elements keeps our life from petrifying and forms an unceasing call to the exercise of the best forethought at command. " Probability is the guide of \ life." It is the tension between the habitual and the more variable factors that constitutes the significance of our conduct morally. Habits, second nature, give us consistency and force; the reflective element keeps us thoughtful. All of the ten- dencies to action, taken together, constitute "capacity" the power of action, whether impulsive, or habitual, or reflective, which an agent has at disposal. If the view so far presented be correct, we may assert that either conduct or character in the subject to which we attach moral predicates. The terms "character" and "conduct" do not refer to different subjects, but to slightly different aspects of the same subject. We say character when we are thinking of the mediated impulses as the source from which all particular acts issue. It does not refer to the bald un- mediated impulses, nor does it refer to fixed unchangeable habits. It designates the way in which impulses (varying of ^ course, in every person) are directed and controlled that is, mediated. The impulses are still there, and just so far as, in their expression, they give rise to new experiences, character v is modified. There is accordingly no force in the objection sometimes made, that to make character the subject to which the adjectives, good and bad, apply, does not allow freedom or the possibility of change. The reaction of the experiences, which the expression of character effects, is sufficient ground for change. Nor is there more force in the objection that to make character the subject of moral predication is to afford an excuse for acts which are bad on the ground of the " good " feeling or disposition from which they proceeded. Character 20 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. includes the style and nature of the ends, the objects by which the individual mediates his impulses, and thus affords suffi- cient basis for taking into account the objective results of acts. We cannot excuse, for example, an act of unregulated benevo- lence on the ground that it proceeds from a good heart or good feeling, when we judge on the basis of character, any more than when we judge on the basis of the results of the act. On the contrary we are only enabled the better to locate the de- fect; the person's character is such that he does not properly mediate his impulses; he is defective on the reflective side; or, again, the nature of the end which that character sets up the following of the immediate impulse of the moment is not such as to be an object of approval. On the other hand, by conduct we do not mean a mere aggregate of particular acts. Conduct is the expression of the mediated impulses. Character, according to its definition (the way of mediating impulses), has no reality apart from the acts in which such impulses must sooner or later issue. It is be- cause acts proceed from character that they are not a mere series of separate things, one after another, but form the or- ganized whole: conduct. In a word, character is the unity. tbjBjijiirit, the idea of conduct,while conduct is the reality, the realized or objective expression of character. The objection sometimes made to taking conduct as the subject of the moral judgment, that conduct is something outward and therefore indifferent, thus has no place. As character is a way of act- ing, conduct is the executed way. We can now deal shortly with a pair of antitheses which are sometimes set up as the proper object of moral judgment, viz. : motive on one side, consequences on the other. Motive is only character in a given instance. Motive is never a bare natural impulse, but is impulse in the light of the conse- quences which may reasonably be supposed to result from act- ing upon it. A mere impulse to anger is not a motive, and in itself is neither good nor bad. It becomes good or bad accord- ing to the nature of the end to which it is attached. Conse- THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 21 quences, on the other hand, are no more a part of conduct than they are of character, save as they are foreseen; save, that is, as there is reason to believe that they will follow a given impulse. But, if there is such reason, the consequences become a part of the conditions which enter into the mediation of impulse a part of character. For theories denying the necessity of mediation by conse- quences see reference previously made to Martineau, and Kant, Theory of Ethics, (translated by Abbotts), p. 28, 44-46, 107- 114, 123. For theories holding to consequences see Bentham, Principles of Morals, and Mill, Autobiography, pp. 49-50, and Utilitarianism, ch. II., (where, however, the doctrine refers not to the consequences alone, but to the exclusion of motive). For a criticism of Martineau, seeSidgwick, Methods of Ethics, Bk. III., ch. 12. For a discussion of the subject, Muirhead, Elements, pp. 55-62, Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics, pp. 4046, Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 36-46, Green, Prolegomena, Bk. IV., ch. 1. SECTION XIV. THE PREDICATE OF THE MORAL JUDGMENT. When shall we call the character, or conduct, good or bad? An impulse, it must be remembered, is a native or spontaneous way in which the self acts. The experiences which are re- ferred back to the impulse are experiences which the self undergoes because of its own nature. The mediation of the impulse thus means a process of self-development. It is the^ process by which the self becomes aware of the meaning, in terms of its own experiences, of one of its own impulses. The impulse, by itself, or in isolation, is a partial or abstract ex- pression of the self. The child who reaches for a light may want the light, but he does not want the burn which is none the less a part of himself, an organic portion of his experience, under the circumstances. So the child may want to talk, but he can hardly be said to want the introduction into new social relations, and into a world of science and literature, which the expression of that impulse brings about. And yet all this is involved in the original impulse. The expression of impulse 22 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. is thus a process of self-realization. The first meaning of an impulse of anger is simply blind reaction, but this reaction has consequences (relations to others, habits established, etc.), which are, from that time on, part of the impulse. This ten- dency to act without thought, to set up hostile relations to others, is now the meaning which the impulse has for the self. Or the blind reaction of anger is against some meanness; it serves to do away with that meanness and to brace the self. >1 These relations differentiate the impulse and bring the self to consciousness in this direction. The completest possible inter- action of an impulse with all other experiences, or the completett possible relation of an impulse to the whole self constitutes the predicate, or moral value, of an act. The -predicate is, there- fore, identical in kind with the subject.* That is, the subject, 'this act,' in the judgment ' this act is right,' is an act medi- ated by reference to the other experiences it occasions its effect upon the self. The predicate 'is right' simply traces out such effects more completely, taking into account, so far as possible, the reaction into the future character of the self, and, in virtue of this reaction, judging>the act. The basis for discriminating bet.wepn "ri^hf," anrj in the judgment is found in the fact that ^sprne acts tend to narrow the self, to introduce friction into it, to weaken its power, amf in various ways to disintegrate it, while oil tend to expand, "invigorate, harmonize, and in general organize the sel The angry act, for example, in the first case given, is bad, because it brings division, friction ? weakness into the self; in the second case, "good," because it unifies the self and gives power. The first effect of every mediation of an impulse is to check or. arrest that impulse. Reflections means postponement; it is delayed action. Through this delay the impulse is brought into connection with other impulses, habits and experiences. *This has important bearings upon the subject of the criterion as we shall see hereafter. Because the predicate and subject are identical in principle, both being the mediation of the impulse, the criterion always lies within, not without, the act. The criterion is nothing but the completest possible view of the act. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 23 Now if a due balance is kept, the result is that the original impulse is harmonized with the self, and, when expressed, it realizes not only its own partial nature but that of the whole self; it becomes the organ through which the whole self finds outlet. The moral criterion for an act proceeding from anger or from benevolence is whether only a part of u the self or the whole character moves outward in the act. The bad act is partial^, the good organic. The good man "eats to live," that is, the satisfaction even of the appetite of hunger is functional to the whole self or life; if we say the man who "lives to eat" is bad, it is because he is sacrificing much of- himself to one partial expression of himself. We see again the impossibility of classifying the impulses into a hierarchy of higher and lower. When an act is right, there is no higher or lower as to the impulse from which it ^T^^w proceeds. The satisfaction of hunger in its place (that is, one which unifies the whole self) is as imperious in its rightness as the noblest act of heroism or the subumesf act\)f self-devotion. The good man, in a word, is his whole self _ in each of his />v-a-j acts; the bad man is a partial (and hence a different) self in *^-*^ his conduct. He is not one person, for he has no unifying principle. (Compare the expressions "dissipated, gone to t^>&^i pieces, shaky, unstable, lacking in integrity, duplicity, devious, indirect, snaky," etc.) This conception of the organic mediation of an impulse as equivalent to Tightness may be expressed in other ways. Aris- totle seems to have meant this by his principle of the "golden mean." (Aristotle, Ethics, Bk. II., chap. 6-9.) While he states it as an arithmetical mean, it is easy to translate what he says into the conception of an active balance in which due regard is had both to the immediate impulse and to the medi- ating consequences; e. g., courage as the mean between fool- hardiness and cowardice, foolhardiuess being undue preponder- ance of impulse, cowardice lack of proper assertion of impulse; moderation is the balance between extravagance (preponder- ance of immediate impulse) and miserliness (preponderance of reflection), and so on. 24 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. Alexander conveys the same idea by calling Tightness a "moving equilibrium." (Moral Order and Progress, pp. 97- 111.) The same idea is also expressed in the conception of " self- realization ," provided this is understood in the sense of ex- pressing the concrete capacity of an individual agent, and not in the sense of filling in the blank scheme of some undefined, purely general self. (Green, Prolegomena to Ethics, pp. 178- 207; Mackenzie, Manual of Ethics, pp. 136-138, and Bradley, Ethical Studies, chap. 6, tend to use the idea in the latter sense. For further criticism see Philosophical Review, vol. II., p. 652, on Self- Realization as Moral Ideal.) CHAPTER V. MORAL APPROBATION, VALUE AND STANDARD. SECTION XV. NATURAL GOOD. The satisfaction which any impulse affords in its expres- sion may be termed its natural value. It is equivalent to what the economists term "value in use" value which is directly enjoyed, but not measured. Such is the satisfaction which accompanies the fulfillment of the appetite of hunger or of thirst, in itself or apart from any consideration of its further bearings. But, as we have seen, the expression of an impulse is always referred back to it, and comes to constitute its meaning or the content of the act. Purely natural good is found therefore only in the original primitive satisfactions of early childhood: it is the state of animal innocence the state of knowing neither good or evil, but simply enjoying suffering good or suffering evil as they come. SECTION XVI. MORAL GOOD. The mediation of the impulse evidently prevents the im- mediate satisfaction of the impulse, and thus replaces natural good by a good which is presented to consciousness. This sat- isfaction mediated in thought, that is, by reflection upon the nature of an impulse in its relation to the self (or the whole system of impulses) is moral satisfaction or moral value. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 25 This process of reflection evidently sets up a standard or criterion for the value of the original impulse. It no longer has worth in itself but simply in its relation to the whole set of desirable experiences which it will occasion. And this means, of course, its tendency to further the other impulses in its in- teraction with them, or to express the self. It may be com- pared with the measured or defined value of the economists, the measurement here also being through interaction or rela- tion (namely, exchange) creating a tension of various impulses against each other, which makes it necessary to estimate the relative importance of each. The mediating process evidently has two sides; there are two standpoints from which it may be considered, and in terms of which it may be stated. As in the operation of exchange there is but one reality, one process, and yet that process will be differently described according as it is the buyer or seller who reports it, so in measurement of moral value, or the refer- ence of an impulse to the whole experience of the self. The process of mediation or measurement is one, and yet our mode of stating it will be different according as we look at it from the standpoint of the inducing impulse or of the impulses and experiences induced. The process, as a whole, is one of ad- justment, of balancing, of co-ordination. But if we identify ourselves in imagination with the impulse, we have first the checking of the impulse, and then, as dammed up, its gradual transformation and reinforcement the condition of desire and its struggle for fulfillment. The impulse, being the thing which makes itself directly felt in consciousness, is taken to be reality: it is the present factor. But as the other impulses stimulated (redintegrated) and their results begin to be present in consciousness, we may identify ourselves with them and tell the story from their side. As induced and derivative, not immediately present (present only as results of the original impulse), they are ideas; yet, as induced, their reflective character is not equivalent to unreal- ity; they make themselves felt by checking the very impulse 26 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. which aroused them. In this aspect, .they are the law, the controlling power of that impulse. They determine in what form, under what conditions of time, place and quality, if may be satisfied. Thus they determine or measure its value; they say to it: You are not what you are alone or in yourself, but your value is what it is in relation to us. In this aspect, the induced experiences (reason, for short) are the standard of measurement for the natural impulse. But the experiences thus reflectively brought forward while they may transform the original impulse, they also reinforce it. They have their own impulsive quality, or urging for ex- pression. Thus they constitute the ideal; what is desired; the reflective good. The gradual self-assertion of desire up to choice or preference, and the gradual formation of an ideal up to resolution or decision, are one and the same process of mediation of impulse described from the two standpoints, un- til they gradually merge in a complete unity the overt act. The whole process is one of discovering and applying the cri- terion, a process of estimating value. In other words, it is a process of testing, of proving, until, in the act, there is ap- probation. SECTION XVII. DEVELOPMENT OF VOLITION FROM SIDE OF IDEA. We begin with a consideration of the process by which the end becomes developed into an act. This end is at first intel- lectual that is, it exists in thought only. It is & proposed end, not an actualized one. It is an aim, a plan, an intention, a purpose all terms expressing its unrealized condition. In its own content it does not differ from any image which may come before the mind. Its relation to the impulse which calls it into being tends, however, to unite its destiny with that of the impulse, and thus confer upon it a practical value. Con- sider a person who has an artistic impulse one towards paint- ing. This impulse cannot find its immediate expression; it calls before the mind (by association or redintegration) images of all circumstances which are relevant to it which seem to be THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 27 involved in its execution.- According to the strength (the insistence and persistence) of the original impulse, the ideas thus aroused will be mere fleeting fancies, vague schemes to be carried out if circumstances favor, or a defined (determined) project. In abnormal cases, hypnotism, "compulsory ideas," etc., we find that every idea suggested to the mind tends to execute itself, or that some idea becomes so dominant that there is no co-ordination between it and others and hence no control. These abnormal cases reveal the normal principle, covered up by complexity of ordinary life the connection of every idea with an impulse. In childhood we see precisely the same thing, save that here the idea is hardly distinguished in consciousness from the impulse. Attention reveals the same principle in its normal and matured form. Attention is an idea or set of ideas so completely bound up with an impulse that they demand realization. The sole difference from the abnormal "compulsory idea" is that in attention the induced ideas are organically connected with the impulse. That is to say, the distinguishing trait of attention is that it arouses the whole set of ideas which are relevant to the impulse, and only those, other ideas as they arise dying out because of their indifference to the realization of the impulse, while all relevant suggestions are maintained. The full development of an ideal, an end, is, then, the same thing on the ethical side that we term reflective attention on the psychological side just as the direct satisfaction of an impulse is equivalent to non-voluntary, or direct, attention. ( See Dewey, Psychology, pp. 121-129, on natural and acquired value; James, Psy., vol. I., pp. 416-124, on passive and volun- tary attention.) Interest is, by general confession 'bound up with attention; we may, therefore, expect to find a similar close connection between ideal and interest in the process of volition. In the discussion of this development, it is convenient to consider separately two phases which are always, as matters of fact, found together. One of these is the formation of the 28 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. intellectual content, the end (what is aimed at, the rational structure of the plan); the other, the connection of this intel- lectual content with the impulse the interest or practical value which attaches to the aim as thought. Before consider- ing them separately, it must again be remarked that while the content of the plan is purely intellectual or rational (abstract, or objective to the self), the fact that it is found worth while to develop the plan (that attention remains fixed) shows that this rational content is not, for a moment, freed from its prac- tical or dynamic value its connection with impulse as the immediately acting self. SECTION XVIII. DEVELOPMENT OF INTENTION OR THE RA- TIONAL CONTENT. An intention is what an agent means to do. It is thus the primary differentia of a volitional from a purely impulse act, showing that the impulsive is mediated. It constitutes reflec- tion, or the control of the impulse by reason. The thought, or what one intends, may be a mere image which passes listlessly through the mind as in the state of buildiug castles in the air; it may be a vague undefined thought of something or other in general a sentiment, what is sometimes termed " meaning well " or having "good intentions," and yet not meaning the particular end which alone is right. When eth- ically justifiable, it signifies giving attention to all the bearings which could be foreseen by an agent who had a proper interest in knowing what he is about. So far, we have unduly simplified the account by ignoring the conflict of aims or the difficulty of coming to a conclu- sion in many cases. The natural satisfaction, that is, the thought of the course which the original impulse would take if left to itself, and the rational, or mediated, satisfaction con- tend in the mind. This is, as we shall see, the basis of the moral struggle, the conflict of desire and duty. Or, the various suggested ends do not harmonize; it is necessary either to bar out some, or else to discover a still more comprehensive aim in which the claims of the conflicting intentions shall be adjusted. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 29 Thus we are brought to deliberation, the more conscious weighing and balancing of values consideration. We are apt to describe this process as if it were a coldly intellectual one. As matter of fact, it is a process of tentative action; we " try on " one or other of the ends, imagining ourselves actually do- ing them, going, indeed, in this make-believe action just as far as we can without actually doing them. In fact, we often find ourselves carried over the line here; the hold which a given impulse gets upon us while we are " trying it on " passes into overt act without our having consciously intended it. Par- ticularly is this the case so far as our character is immature ; there is a temporary relapse into a " compulsory idea." Decision, resolution, the definitely formed plan, is the proper outcome of consideration. This expresses the conclu- sion of the process of conflict among ends, and the emergence of a purpose which, whether through suppression or compre- hension of other ends, now expresses the self. It is the com- pleted self under the given circumstances. The appearance of an ideal in the mind and the final selection, or determination, are simply the beginning and the end of one and the same pro- cess there is no thrusting in of an outside power, of will or attention. The process we are describing is the process of will or attention. This brings us expressly to a statement of the connection of the intention or aim with the self urging on to action impulse. SECTION XIX. DEVELOPMENT OF MOTIVE. The reaction of the intended content into impulse renders the former itself an impulse; the original impulse, now enlarged, goes on to express itself. This identification of the aim with impulse is motive, the rational spring to action. As attention cannot be separated from interest, the forma- tion of a plan cannot be separated from the reaction of that plan into the self. Every end that occurs to the mind awakens a certain amount of interest, or has a certain value attached to it. It is this reaction, the extent to which the thought tends 30 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. to stir the self, to call it out, that measures the motive power of the thought. Abstractly we may distinguish between the conception of the end, which is rational or reflective, and the motive power of this end; actually, we cannot. Whether or not the conceived end remains in consciousness, even as a con- ception, expresses its value to the self. This identity of the evolution of the ideal, on the intellectual side, with the evolu- tion of a determining motive power, on the emotional, both being forms of self-expression, is the key to an understanding of the ethics of motive. The ideal, or end, is the abstract, objective expression, of the self; the acting, or real, self tem- porarily checked as to its overt expression (immediate activ- ity) but deepened and widened in its consciousness of what it is doing in its appreciation of value. The motive is this abstract self completely related, having its value felt, and thus no longer merely objective but subjective as well, and hence pass- ing into act. (See Dewey, Psy., pp. 15-23, and p. 347). If we take the reaction of the content into the other im- pulses of the self, and consider it apart from the reason or purpose of the act, we get the conflict of emotions the stress and strain of feelings, the play of hope and fear, of doubt and expectation, of suspense and adjustment, of tension and grow- ing ease, which is the subjective counterpart of the objective conflict and resolution of ideals already spoken of. (See Dewey, Psychology, XII. The " formal feelings" there de- scribed are the consciousness of the process of mediation of impulse, apart from its content). One of these emotions is so important that it is often identified with volition itself; it therefore demands special attention. It is the consciousness of effort. Effort is the same process, stated in terms of emotion, that we call consideration, or reflection, when stated in terms of rational content. It is the feeling of the division of activity a necessary accompaniment of the period of suspense within which the original activity is arrested, while the iuduced im- pulses which arrest have not yet gained sufficient force to determine the act. It is a period when the impulses are striv- THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 31 ing towards co-ordination and yet, not having reached it, are in tension against each other temporarily oppose each other. Such temporary opposition is evidently necessary in order to secure a balance which will utilize each set to the full, or secure the maximum of energy. It is obvious that if the opposition of one set to the other is imperfect, one or the other will get the preponderance too soon. The result will be an undue suppression of the other set, loss of efficiency and ulti- mate friction. This conflict of impulses which oppose each other in order to reinforce each other is reported in conscious- ness as the feeling of effort, whose distinguishing trait is pre- cisely a peculiar combination of feelings of power and impo- tence, of activity and resistance to activity. SECTION XX. NATURE OF EFFORT ou TENSION. According to this statement, effort is simply the conscious- ness of the critical moment in the development of will; it is not to be identified with the putting forth of will itself. And yet effort is often considered to be will asserting its own power against some resistance outside of itself. What is the origin of this fallacy ? What are its ethical consequences ? According to the theory given in the text, neither one or. , the other of the contending forces is to be identified by itself with will; each represents a normal and a necessary phase of will the mediate and the immediate, the original and the induced, to repeat once more. Moreover their temporary sep- aration and the resistance which one phase of the activity offers to the other is itself a factor of great positive import- ance in the evolution of a truly rational practical conclu- sion, or act. Now, if will proper is not this whole process, but is some one distinct power, some force standing outside the other factors, if therefore these other factors are resistance not in will, but to it, both our psychological statement, and our ethical theory must be radically changed. It is not difficult to detect the source of the error. We necessarily tend, during the struggle, to identify ourselves especially with that phase of the process which is prominent in 32 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. consciousness, and to regard the other phase (although equally an expression of ourselves) as indifferent or even as hostile to ourselves. The more interesting, the more important, is, for the time being, the self; it absorbs consciousness. .Then we fail to notice that the final act, the complete expression of self, is by no means this side alone, but is colored throughout, and is given value, by the other phase of the self. Take a poor person tempted to steal; suppose he has habits, of honesty. Here the self is identified with the thoughts of decency, of self-respect, of reputation, which arise and assert themselves against the direct impulse to take the loaf of bread. The mediating self is the self, and the impulse is a mere intruder, something outside the will, outside the self, and yet somehow coming in to tempt it. Yet the very fact that this impulse is presented as an end, that it becomes the thought of stealing, shows that that end also, so far as entertained, is self. And if the final determination is not to take the bread, this conclusion the completed self, has by no means the significance which the same conclusion (the same outwardly) would have when not the outcome of such a struggle; the self has not simply re- turned to its normal state after having got rid of an intruder. The impulse to steal has become an integral part of the final act not, of course, in its own isolated state, but in its medi- ated relationship.* And if the statement as thus formulated seems strange, stated in another way, namely, that the meeting and overcom- ing of temptation develops character, it seems a mere com- monplace. In other instances, the thought of the original, natural im- pulse will seem the real self, and the induced experiences the invading force; as, for example, when a man starts to fulfill a natural office of friendliness and then is checked by the * The bearing of this upon the question of the relation of good and evil, and the possibility of an absorption of evil into good character, or vice-versa (corruptio optimi, pessima), will come up later. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 33 thought of the unpopularity of the object as likely to affect him if he does the act. In this case, the very fact that these reasons have weight with the man, that the thought of the obloquy holds his mind, shows that that end expresses himself in its measure. And yet, the man feels that his ""true" self demands the negation of this temptation, and so this end is thought of as external, and the final conclusion (which in reality involves the co-operation of both partial selves) is taken as simply the victory of one over the other. So it may be as to the thing physically done, but in meaning, in its moral (or character) value, it involves both. The same apparent dual- ism is found in any exhibition of attention. In one aspect, the self as attending, the group of impulses and habits, which are endeavoring to assert themselves, seems to be the self, and the content attended to, the object, seems to be outside the self. Yet the fact that the content arouses such interest as to maintain the tendency to assimilate the attending "subject" and the "object " attended to, shows that the integrity of the self, its complete assertion, is neither side separately but the co-ordination of the two phases. Of this co-ordination, the very struggle, or tension, is an integral phase necessary in bringing out the full bearing, or importance of both factors. Every one would admit that we do not get adequate conscious- ness of the object of attention until attention has worked itself out; it is just as true that the impulses and habits which press forward to the object have their significance and value brought to consciousness at the same time. The fact that sometimes the self seems to be inducing experience and sometimes the induced, shows the absurdity of setting up & fixed will or self. When the attraction is towards the conceived end, that seems to be self; when that end repels, upon the whole, so that the movement is towards reduction of its value, the self is located in the primary experience. A man's true self in temperance is in the induced experiences; ia courage in the inducing, etc. 84 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. SECTION XXL THEORIES OF ABSTRACT IDEALS. The ethical consequences of identifying will with a power which puts forth effort against or towards something outside of will flow from the interruption thus abruptly introduced into the moral process. The existence of the ideal is rendered inexplicable. It ia reduced (A) to a supernatural visitor from a world above that of ordinary experience. The very word ' ' ideal " suggests to a sophisticated mind something which is remote and unattain- able outside of the natural course of life. If not defined as introduced into the mind from without by a divine power, it is thought of after the analogy of this concept. (See Martineau, Types, vol. II, pp. 73-74; 97-99; 217-218; and Study of Religion, vol. II, pp. 2640, for assertions of the transcendent character of the ideal. ) (B) Recent moralists -have seen the objections -which'attach to putting the origin and formation of the ideal outside of the self. Yet instead of showing^the point, in the normal process of volition (the appearance of the induced experiences which mediate the original tendency to action) at which the distinc- tion arises, they split the self into two selves and attribute the impulses and [appetites to one, the actual urgent self, and the ideal to another self, a " higher" or " rational " or " spiritual " self in general. (1) Kant presents one type of this view. According to him, there is a sensuous, "phenomenal" self, constituted by appetites and impulses; this furnishes the actual material for our volition. Besides this, there is a rational " noumenal " self, which sets up the ideal or goal of effort. (Theory of Ethics, trans, by Abbott, pp. 105-124; 144-147.) (2) Green recognizes the objection to splitting the self so completely, and falls back on the notion of the moral ideal as meaning the-end of the self as a whole, while natural satisfac- tion means the satisfaction of a particular impulse. This might be interpreted in a sense analogous with the theory I have previously advanced, but as matter of fact, Green makes THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 35 the whole self not the complete definition of the natural im- pulse, under the conditions, but something quite distinct from any possible development of the particular impulse as such. See Green, Prolegomena, pp. 160-162, 178-188, 202-204; Works, vol. II., 136-148; 308-309; 329; 336-338. Compare with the following criticisms my article in Philosophical Re- view, vol. I., No. 6. Objections to the absolute or separate ideal may be stated as follows: (a) It makes a dualism, practically unbridgeable, between the moral and the scientific phases of our experience. If any account of the ideal can be given meeting the needs of the case, we should certainly hesitate before accepting a mode of statement introducing ideas which not only do not lie within the scope of scientific method as usually presented, but which emphasize their complete transcendence of scientific categories and results. All the above theories (any theories which set up an independent, fixed ideal) are necessarily metaphysical in a sense which separates metaphysics from science, instead of making it a more complete recognition of scientific methods and data. That moral science introduces a set of ideas which are not brought explicitly to the front in the physical or even the bio- logical sciences, there can be no doubt. But the account which I have given recognizes this distinction without changing it into a break. Physical science deals wholly with the rational, abstract or objective content. That is, it leaves out of account (i) the fact that every object, or law (relation of objects) arises, in actual experience from an inducing impulse, an action of self; (ii) the fact that sooner or later it reacts back into the impulse, and thus has its final meaning in the new significance which it gives to action. In other words, physical science deals simply with the content of mediation, leaving one side the whole process of mediation. In considering, for exam- ple, a flower, it takes account neither of the impulses of seeing, of reaching, touching, smelling, etc., which make the flower 36 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. into an object in consciousness nor yet the additional value, aesthetic and moral, as well as intellectual, which our activity (our character) will have as result of the study. It omits, in a word, both the reason for and the nature of the value which objects have in our experience in relation to the self. While biology is compelled to assume the fact of value as possessed by objects in relation to life (most generally their value in either maintaining or hindering the life of the genus in question), it does not consider^this value as present to the consciousness of the agent. It will describe, for example, the interaction, both favorable and unfavorable, of a race of men and their environment, but it confines itself to results actually accomplished. It puts one side this value as realized in the conscious life of that race, as affording motive and assimilated into character. Yet science, as science, does not deny the fact of further conscious value. It simply concentrates itself upon other aspects of reality the content which gives value independent of why or how it gives it. Neglect is not denial of value; and recognition of value is not denial of science. Ethics com- pletes the analysis of reality experience begun by physical and biological science. It does not introduce a new and opposed set of ideas. (Royce, Spirit of Modern Philosophy, ch. XII., distinguishes between the world of description and the world of appreciation, this distinction being identical in statement with the distinction just made; but he seems to con- ceive of the " physical " world as a fixed thing, as, indeed, a limitation, due to our ''finite nature," instead of the inter- mediate stage in the development of an act: the definition of the conditions of action). The fixed, or absolute ideal, is not only inexplicable, but is presupposed or ready~made. Against such ideals, we may urge: (b) No moral value attaches to their working-out, or for- mation. It may belong to the attitude taken towards them, to their choice or rejection, but nothing more. But, in our actual THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 37 experience, no such separation exists between forming and choosing an end of action. Our moral discipline consists even more in the responsibility put upon us to develop ideals, than in choosing between them when made. The making of plans, working them out into their bearings, etc., is at once a test of character and a factor in building it up. But this is an impossibility if the ideal is something given towards which will is to be directed if it lies outside the normal process of volition. (Thus, Martineau is logical in holding that only intellectual or prudential value attaches to the consideration of consequences. Types, vol. II., pp. 255-256. With a fixed ideal, they must lie outside, be mere means, and moral mean- ing is found simply in the selection of one or other of the ends given ready-made. Deliberation has no intrinsic moral signi- ficance. So Green has to draw a decided line between the estimation of acts, and of character, the former being decided by a consideration of consequences, the latter by a considera- tion of the disposition from which the act proceeds. Moreover the consideration of character, or conscientiousness, he has logically to reduce to a subjective introspection on the part of the agent as to whether " he has been as good as he should have been," not an objective examination of whether his in- terest, or attention, is rightly distributed. Prolegomena, pp. 317-325. On p. 259, Green takes another view of the ideal), (c) The process of choice, of selection between competing ideals, is rendered arbitrary and meaningless. Why should there be two competing ideals at all, one good, the other bad? And, supposing there are, on what grounds do we prefer one to the other ? As to the first question, there appears to be no alternative between saying (with Kant) that there is a fixed dualism in our nature, sense, as inducing to evil, being on one side, reason, as good, on the other; with Green, that the par- ticular impulse* is always and fixedly opposed in its realization, to the demand of our entire nature (Prol. pp. 180-183 ;]206-207; 233-234); or (with Martineau) that there is an original fixed scale of higher and lower in our impulses. But experience 38 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. does not testify to a conflict between ends one labelled, from the start and unalterably, good and the other labelled bad. On the contrary, one becomes good, the other bad, in the pro- cess of competition and deliberation. Moreover our theory accounts for the presence of the two competitors and the relative conflict between them; it is the old story of th,e immediate and the mediating phases of action. It gives positive meaning to the opposition the deepening of consciousness. (See Alex- ander, Moral Order, pp. 297-316, also Int. Journ. Eth., vol. II., p. 409, for an adequate recognition of the fact that the competing ends are made good and bad, by the very process of deliberation and choice; or, as I have previously put it, the process of action is itself one of estimating and constituting value, of proving and approving.) As to the second question, on what grounds does the self choose between the two fixed ideals, there appears no answer save an appeal to arbitrary free-will, the power of choosing between alternatives without any reason for the choice. The problem of freedom will meet us hereafter; at this point, it is sufficient to note that the sole occasion for bringing in a free- dom of the kind just referred to, is that the alternative ends to be chosen are taken as lying outside the development of will. On our theory, the emergence of the ends and the final choice are facts of exactly the same order, being only an earlier and a latter stage, in time, of the definition of an impulse in its re- lation to the self. It may also be noticed, at this point, that the theory opposed to freedom, namely, that of necessitation has its origin in exactly the same assumption that the origin and development of the ends lie outside the self; being con- ceived as foreign forces, it is natural to draw the inference that the strongest force determines the will overlooking the fact that ends have motive power, great or small, only so far as they interest, hold attention that is, express the direction in which the self is already moving. There is still another difficulty as to choice. If one side comes thus labelled bad from the start, why should it ever be THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 39 chosen? Why should the bad recognized as such, offering itself as such, have superior value? The doctrine of original sin is the only logical answer, and Kant is perfectly logical in trying to introduce a philosophical statement of that doctrine. Theory, pp. 339-352. ( Abbott's trans. "Religion within the Bounds simply of Reason.") (d) No basis is afforded for development of moral ideals for positive progress. The ideal is there once for all and it is only a question of greater or less distance from it. The logical conclusion (not that these writers have been logical enough to draw it) is the Pharisaical one since there has been progress, how much better morally must we be than savages, or our primitive ancestors, or " the lower classes," or than any one else whose acts do not rank objectively as high as ours ! On our theory, it is the ideal, as recognition of the objective mean- ing of action, which has progressed; so that there is only addi- tional capacity, and thus additional demand, for mediation. One class of persons, as a class, is, then, morally no better than any other; one period no more virtuous than another. Re- sponsibilities not virtues, increase. The increase, that is, of knowledge of the bearings of an impulse makes care in action morally more imperative, we are no nearer a goal of perfection, but action has more intellectual and aesthetic meaning. (e) From this it follows also that progress in character is purely negative; on the basis of a fixed ideal it consists sim- ply in lessening the gap which separates us from the ideal. The moral life thus becomes a struggle towards something without and beyond, and, in so far, a hopeless and slavish struggle. The ideal never is realized, do what we may. (Kant has to fall back on purely supernatural means to meet this difficulty. Theory, pp. 218-231.) The ideal has no self-exe- cuting, no moving power. It is never of itself a motive. Upon our theory, the very fact that an ideal is present in conscious- ness, is, as far as it goes, its realization; it is the self mov- ing that way; in so far as it modifies conduct, it is directive and effective. A mere ideal, or unrealized ideal, is a contra- 40 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. diction in terms. The ideal is a very present help in time of trouble. (f) The fixed ideal gives no instruction or information as to the particular thing needing to be done. It does not trans- late itself into terms of a concrete, individual act and every act is concrete and individual. In other words, it does not and cannot become a working principle for what has to be done. (See Green, again, Prol. pp. 317-325, for the necessity, on his basis, of a double standard. ) Such ideals are pure luxuries; only the sentimentalist and the pure theorist can afford them. The working man, of busy life, must have an ideal by which he can go in action, one whicli defines specific acts. (Green attempts to meet the need by reference to the past institutions in which the ideal is embodied; cf. Prol. pp. 180; 207-208; 393- 394. But, since such embodiments are, according to him, only apparent, not real, it is difficult to see how this gives the re- quired instruction. Kant attempts to get to the specific act needed by reference to the universal, non-self-contradictory character of the ideal. Of this, more below.) Again, our theory meets this need, because the ideal is nothing but the definition or mediation of the immediately acting, or impul- sive, self. We conclude then, from our examination of abstract ideals, that true ideals are the working hypotheses of action; they are the best comprehension we can get of the value of our acts; their use is that they mark our consciousness of what we are doing, not that they set up remote goals. Ideals are like the stars: we steer by them, not towards them. SECTION XXII. THE HEDONISTIC THEORY OF VALUE. According to the theory advanced, value consists in the V realization or expression of impulse, moral value being the conscious realization of impulse in its relation to the self or system of active experience. The " ideal " is the consciousness of the relationship. The function of the ideal is to give con- tent or meaning to the impulse: it is the impulse stated in THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 41 objective terms. Abstract idealism was criticized on the ground that it made the ideal something at which impulse and activity in general is aimed, and in which therefore it is exhausted. There is another group of theories which also sets up an outside goal for activity, although differing as to the nature of this goal. This group is tho hedonistic (from the Greek, r^ovij pleasure.) It proclaims that pleasure is the end towards which all action is directed that pleasurable feeling (involving the absence of pain) is the Summum Bonum, the supreme good and thus the standard for measur- ing value. Before passing on to its consideration, it may first be con- trasted with abstract idealism. Comparatively, hedonism may be termed empirical idealism. It has an ideal pleasure but this ideal is a state, a passive experience, something which has already been enjoyed;* as against this, the ideal of perfection set up by the other school is attainable only in the remote future at the end of an infinite time according to Kant and Green. The good of one school is reason, that of the other feeling.f The two schools have stood over against each other since the very beginning of ethical speculation. At first, it was the Cynic against the Cyrenaic; then the Stoic against the Epicurean; latterly, the Kantian against the Utilitarian. (See Sidgwick, History of Ethics, pp. 32-33 and 71-88.) Such a continuous opposition is accounted for on the ground not that one is all truth, and the other all error; but on the ground that each school represents the abstraction of one phase of the process of volition. In truth, the process begins and ends in activity; the beginning being impulsive (original or habitual) activity, the end activity whose value has been measured. In this process, reason (the phase selected and set up independently by the abstract idealists) represents the *See note to p. 147 of Murray's Introduction to Ethics; also Mill, Utilitarianism, pp. 348-849; Bain, Moral Science, p. 27. f " Reason is and must be the slave of passion." Hume. See Treatise on Huriian Nature, Book II., Part 3, Sees. 3 and 4. 42 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. transition from the immediate to the mediated activity the consciousness of the relations of the impulse, the objectified impulse, while feeling (the phase abstracted by the empiricists) represents the consciousness of value to the agent as an individual the activity in its subjective existence. Reason is turning the action inside out, seeing it as part of a general order, independeut of the individual's own immediate propen>- ^**"""^"^*^ *^^ *^" """ *" ^"^"^fc^ < ^^^ "~Wt^^fci ^FT**^^^^^*"^*^ sities. Hence the ideas of specfatorV disinterestedr^universal, which associate themselves so easily with reason. Rational content is required to give the individual's feeling substance and real worth. Feeling is turning the action outside in; it is the realization of value terms of the agent's own peculiar character.* Hedonism (as compared with rationalism) fails to see that the nature or content of this value (as distinct from the mere fact of some value) depends upon the mediation of reason; while abstract idealism fails to note that the reduction of self to reason or thought leaves the self in the air, with no indi- vidualized value. Each of them has to disparage the opposite principle, or reduce it to a mere means to its own end. The theory of experimental idealism (as we term the position here taken), because of its recognition of activity as the primary reality is enabled to give both thought and feeling their due. It does not attempt the impossible task of setting up for activity some end, whether a state of feeling or one of perfect reason, outside itself. It is content to note that activity, mov- ing according to its own law and principle, becomes objectively conscious of its value in the ends which its projects (ideals) and subjectively conscious of its value in the emotions which accompany the realizing of these ends. As compared with the facts, then, both ethical rationalism and empiricism take a derived and secondary phase for the whole truth. As compared with each other, rationalism is * Hence Lotze's hedonistic tendencies. See Practical Phil- osophy, pp. 15-20. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 43 right in so far as it asserts that feelings (or pleasure and pain) are mere abstractions apart from the objects (or rational con- tents) which give them their quality, while empiricism is right in asserting that an end which is not felt (that is, app as part of the agent's ownoeing) has no moral validity or ^^- "SECTION XXIII FEELING AS END OR IDEAL. We shall consider pleasure-pain, (1) as end or ideal of action, (2) as motive, and (3) as criterion or measure of value. The contradiction in hedonism meets us at the outset- Pleasure and pain as feelings exist only as they are actually felt, and to the one who feels them. J Because we have one word, we are apt to suppose that there is some one fact or entity corresponding. There are, indeed, pleasures and pains, but no such thing as pleasure in general. Hence we cannot aim at pleasure. It is a pure abstraction. We may aim, however, it will be said, at some particular pleasure, the pleasure of eating an apple, of performing a charitable act, of deceiving an enemy, etc. Even here, how- ever, there is ambiguity, and even self-contradiction in the theory as ordinarily stated. There is confusion of an ideal of pleasure the conception of what constitutes pleasure with pleasure as an ideal. Since pleasure exists only while it is felt, to say that it is aimed at must mean that there is a thought of it formed. Now this thought will either be an I image so distinct that it is itself pleasurable, or it will be aj conception of the objects or ends which afford pleasure or yield* satisfaction. Take any of the instances above given and it will be seen that fchese two alternatives exhaust the possibilities. Neither of them is equivalent to pleasure as an ideal. In the former case, a pleasure is actually felt and no action is called forth aimed at it. In the latter case there is a presentation of the ends whose attainment is regarded as affording satisfaction, and (through redintegration) of a certain amount of accompa- nying pleasure. But neither actually experienced pleasure, 1 nor a consideration of the objects which afford enjoyment is I 44 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. pleasurable feeling as an aim of action. This latter is a psy- chological impossibility. But since the idea has prevailed, not only that pleasure is a possible end of action, but that it is the only end, it must be examined in more detail. The idea is us*ially_j>resented in connection with a theory of desire. (For the notion tBat plea8Ur6"isTEe~6b]ect of desire see: Mill, Utili- tarianism, pp. 354-355; Bain, Emotions and Will, Part II., ch. 8; Senses and Intellect, pp. 338-344; Spencer, Data, pp. 26-44; Sully, Outlines of Psychology, pp. 574589, Human Mind, vol. IL, pp. 196-207; Thompson, System of Psychology, Part IX.; Lotze, Microcosmus, vol. I., pp. 678-706. Most of these ' cover other points in the hedonistic theory besides the relation of pleasure and desire. Stephen, Science of Ethics, pp. 42-57 and 246-263, is noteworthy for the clearness with which he shows the confusion in ordinary hedonism as to the end, while still himself holdirig that pleasure is motive.) SECTION XXIV. HAPPINESS AND DESIRE. It is generally held by hedonists to be self-evident that we desire pleasure, and avoid pain. The doctrine is even tautol- ogy, according to them. Good, pleasure, the desirable, are synonymous terms; evil, pain, that to which we are averse, mean the same experience. Substituting 'happiness' for 'pleasure', 'misery' for ' pain ', we agree unreservedly to this statement, and yet insist that it does not mean that, pleasure is the object of desire, or aim of action. It is true that good (happiness) is the satisfaction, evil the thwarting of desire. This measures, or defines, happiness in terms of desire; desire is the primary fact, happiness its fulfilling, its completion. Hedonism sees the connection, but reverses its* direction. It takes happiness as a fixed fact, and then tries to define desire in terms of happiness as that which aims at it. It is true that happiness is found in the satisfaction of any desire, par- ticularly in the degree of its dominance; happiness^ this \ satisfaction of desire. But hedonism transforms this fact into the notion that somehow pleasure is there as an ideal, and its contemplation arouses desire. As Green says (Prolegomena, THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 45 p. 168), the hedonists make the "mistake of supposing that a desire can be excited by the anticipation of its own satis- faction." This identity of happiness with satisfaction of desire is the reason for substituting 'happiness' for 'pleasure^-, Pleasure anoVpain are often passive and accidental (pathological, Kant terms it. Theory, p. 106). A child goes on the street and . hears pleasant music; he runs and has a painful fall; a man inherits money and finds himself in the possession of new resources; he invests money safely, as he supposes, and finds it swept away by a sudden panic. It is absurd to deny that satis- faction and dissatisfaction, in the way of pleasure and pain, result in all these instances; yet common speech agrees with sound theory iu hoiding that any one or all of them may become parts of either happiness or misery, weal or woe, according to the relation assumed towards them by the dominant desires (that is character) of the individual* (see Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 212-218). SECTION XXV. THE NATURE OF DESIRE. The hedonist, then, gives the following account of desire: ^Afhqjttiflg that the original, or impulsive, activity does not occur for the sake of pleasure, it is held that when pleasure or pain is experienced as a result of action, the image of memory of the feeling occurring afterwar Is arouses a desire for its renewal (if pleasure), or aversion, a movement to escape it (if pain). Concerning this account a question arises. How does this image of inemory happen to occur to the mind? No image or memory can come into the mind directly or of itself; there must be some suggestion, association or exciting stimulus. We may suppose (i) that the object which gave the satisfaction before is seen (as a child, having eaten sugar once, sees it *I do not mean that the words ' pleasure' and ' happiness' are marked off to denote exclusively these two kinds of satisfaction, one comparatively extraneous to character, the other measured by it, but only to insist that there are these two types _pf satisfaction, and that common speech is quite aware Uf lllelP 46 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. again), and this redintegrates the pleasure image. Now (a) this, at most, is an accidental and, morally, unimportant way for desire to originate. A character whose desires were habit- ually aroused in this style would be immature; it would be the sport of caprice and circumstance, with no settled lines of action. This theory presupposes that the mind is, like Micawber, pas- sively waiting for experiences to "turn up." In the child, or in any character so far as morally immature, the relatively accidental recognition of an object may arouse its own isolated line of action. But moral training consists not in perpetuating this mode of actioj^btflTin eliminating it. Asamatte? oTfact, even a child is actually engaged from the outset and all the time in activity. He has his own impulses, or lines of dis- charge, representing the selected outcome of generations of activity. The child's immaturity chiefly consists not in the fact that it is passively dependent upon external excitations, but in the lack of -continuity in the activities set up by the organs themselves. One way of action gives way to another without reference to a general or comprehensive plan. In other words, the impulse is not mediated or rationalized, (b) Even in the child, therefore, the object arouses the desire because of the activity already going on. The child's primary impulse is already there that of eating. The presentation of the object and the representation of the satisfaction previously had in connection with it, simply deflects, or mediates, this activity. This suggests the fundamental fallacy in the old case of the ass evenly balanced between two bundles of hay. It supposes that the desirable quality, the power of inciting activity, resides in the object entirely independent of the activity of the organ- ism. As matter of fact, the animal (and so with man) is already doing something, looking, or moving, this way or that, and so the hypothesis of a purely indeterminate equilibrium is ,absurd it assumes impossible conditions. Pleasure, in other words, is not suggested immediately by the [object, sugar, but by the activity of tasting, which constitutes 'the practical meaning of that object. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 47 This brings us (ii) to the normal case. The pleasure is aroused because the activity already asserting itself, as a habit more or less organized, hits in idea upon the object (that is, the conditions) which will afford it fulfillment. The recognition of the congruity of the object to the activity arouses the pleasure. A hungry child, seeing or thinking of something to eat, experi- ences gratification in the thought; an engineer, trying to express his engineering capacity, thinks of a new machine and experi- ences pleasure, etc.] Instead of the image of pleasure exciting the action, the activity already going on sets up a pleasure by calling into consciousness the conditions (the object) of its satisfaction. J There is no image of a past pleasure once experi- enced or of a future pleasure to be attained ; there is a present pleasurable experience. This brings out the fact that desire, instead of being the beginning of activity caused by a state of feeling, is a stage in its development arising when both the original and the induced activity are in consciousness but have not yet come to a complete agreement, or co-ordination. (It is the same condition as that already noticed as effort.) Desire is not excited or aroused by any end, whether pleasure or any- thing else. It is a phase in the growth of valued, or rational- ized, action. At this stage of development there is more than pleasure ' felt; there is also pain. Pleasure is felt so far as the object (the mediating or induced experience) is present in idea, thus promising future satisfaction. Pain is felt so far as it is pres- ent only in idea, not in act. The actual perception of the sugar is still, in part, merely ideal, so far as the activity is concerned; the activity which is striving to assert itself is not seeing the sugar, but tasting it. So far as the sight promises success, by redintegrating further acts (reaching, etc.), it is pleasurable, the draft the organs of tasting make upon it being honored. But so far as the full activity is still non-existent, there is pain. The very essence of desire is tension, divided activity. The self is divided against itself; activity is partial. So far as it 48 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. goes, it is action, and hence pleasurable; but as partial, it is painf.il. Desire is neither complete activity aiming at a state outside itself, nor a condition of sheer emptiness.* It is con- flicting activity. The man who desires an education in so far as he can "objectify" his desire (that is, present to himself the conditions which will further his self-assertion in that direction), is in so far already acting in the desired direction, and there is satisfaction; but in so far as he is at present acting in ways which must be mediated, or transformed, there is con- flict and dissatisfaction. The pleasure-pain condition of desire reports, in other words, the existing state of action ; it does not initiate it. i In any account of desire, there are thi-pe elements to be / dealt with activity, object of. / ' .MMMlL^MMMMV** f , _ jre (end thought of as satis- 3^**. ^tB^pfc**^***^ / fying), and feeling. According to hedonism, the object awakens / feeling, and the feeling arouses active desire. I have tried to / show above that the feeling is the activity subjectively appre- S ciated; it is equally true, on our theory, that the object is no independent thing, but is the activity presented to intelligence is the content of action, the statement of the conditions involved. The thought of food is the definition, in objective terms, of hunger; a complex set of commercial relations (a plan of business) is the objective definition of the impulse to assert one's self in nature; the conception of conditions of political power the objectifying of its special impulse, etc. ' Object ' and pleasure-pain feeling are thus the correlative phases, ob- jective and subjective, of activity. The fundamental fallacy of both perfectionism and hedon- ism is thus the same. Both assume value as something pre- sented to the self, and awakening and measuring activity. In trutb^yalue is constituted by activity. (An interesting form of the assumption of a fixed system of goods or values (not hedonistic) towards which activity should be directed will be *The double sense of words here is suggestive. Want means both lack and demand; it is dynamic, and still partial. Capacity means both power (actuality) and possibility (ideality). THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 49 found in the International Journal Ethics, vol. II., in an article by Mr. Davidson, entitled "The Ethics of an Eternal Being." All formulae like the one there given (p. 306) reverse the real state of the case. They assume the existence of valuable ends towards which interest, attention, affection are to be directed, forgetting that such ends are simply the objective expression of interest and attention.) Arguments against ^the idea that pleasure is the object of desire will be found in James, Psychology, vol. II., pp. 549 559; Green, Prol., pp. 163-177; Bradley, Ethical Studies, pp. 226-235, and Mind, vol. XIII., p. 1; Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 34-47, Mind, vol. IL, p. 27, and Contemporary Review, 1871, p. 671; Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 186-225; Dewey, Outlines, pp. 17-30; Muirhead, Elements, pp. 92-111; Murray, Introduction, pp. 160-173; Mackenzie, Manual, pp. 89-116. Most of these references deal with the question of motive as well as of end. The criticisms of hedonism advanced above are practically identical with many of those contained in the references. The positive doctrine of desire is, perhaps, more nearly allied to that of Spinoza, according to which desire is a form of fundamental self-assertion. It is not aroused by some 'end', but the 'end' or 'object' is the consciousness of the nature, or content, of self-assertion. See Spinoza, Ethics, Part III., props. 6-9 and def. 1 of the affects. In Part IV., props. 1437, desire seems at times to be defined in terms of "Good", and good at other times in terms of desire as the content of self-realization. The latter is the characteristic doctrine, in any case. See III., p. 9, schol., and p. 39, schol. SECTION XXVI. PLEASURE AND MOTIVE. "*tAy t As already stated, most hedonists confuse the idea of pleasure as object of desire with pleasure as motive. This confusion testifies to a right psychological instinct: that which is an aim of action must also move to action. There must be an identi- fication of the real concrete ideal with the impelling spring to action. Unless the aim or ideal itself becomes a moving force, 50 THE STUDY OF ETHIC8. it is barren and helpless. Unless the moving force becomes itself idealized, unless it is permeated with the object aimed at, it remains mere impulse, blind and irrational. According to hedonism, the ideal and motive may be confused with each other, but they cannot be identified. The thought of pleasure is either simply an abstract conception, coldly intellectual, of the means to getting pleasure, or it is a concrete image of pleas- ure that is, itself a pleasure. In neither case is it a motive. In the former case, it is simply an abstract idea, without prac- tical efficiency; in the latter case, the pleasure is already enjoyed or experienced, and there is no cause for action.* We are in this dilemma in hedonism. If the motive is feeling, it can suggest no intention whatever, and thus cannot move to anything in particular. There is a certain state being experienced, and that ends the story. Or, if there is a definite aim or intention in view, that end will arouse feeling only in the degree in which it expresses activity tendency towards or away. The feeling excited will not be the moving spring, but will indicate or register the extent to which the self is moved. There is no connecting link, on its theory, between aim and motive. We may freely admit, with the hedonist, that bare thought does not induce, is not motive. But before we can infer from this that an ideal is not motive, we must be able to show that an ideal, or aim, is mere thought. On the contrary, it is the induced or mediating activity. The ideal, indeed, is a concep- tion or thought; but as such, as intellectual, it simply gives definiteness and coherency to the content of the induced self. The concrete ideal is always activity asserting itself in another direction from the present, natural, activity. Physiology has, indeed, afforded a complete disproof of any theory which makes a gap between the ideal (or intellect) * Stephen, Science, p. 51, holds that pleasure means persistence in given state, pain change. So also Ward, Psychic Factors of Civilization, p. 54, who goes to the extreme of holding that all desire is pain, while still defining it as representation of pleasure as well as pain (p. 52). THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 51 and overt action. From the side of the expenditure of energy, the sole difference between thought and action is in the exter- nal, or gross, visibility of the discharge. Thinking involves molecular motion, and continued discharge to the muscles and glands. The question of the final passage of idea into act is simply the question of the concentration (unification) of this organic activity in some definite direction. Physiologically, the entire function of thought consists in transforming the vague, diffuse and non-valued (valuable, bu not defined or measured as to value) activity of infancy into definite, co- ordinated and intentional (measured) activity. Upon our view, then, the ideal and motive are both names for self in certain phases of action. If a man kills another intentionally, his ideal, the thought of the removal of the other man, is not something beyond himself there is no way for the thought, even as thought, to come into his mind, save as a projection of himself. That the thought dwells there and becomes an impelling force to action (a motive) is simply the realization, the definite recognition, of the extent to which the self is involved in that ideal, of the extent to which that ideal is the self. The act of reflection is a phase of the act of ful- fillment. We thus come to the question of intention and motive. The hedonist asserts that the motive is always a feeling of j pleasure-pain, the intention is the consequences aimed at.* We assert that both intention and motive are the self in If action, and the sole difference is that motive is intention com- ]j pletely developed, the concrete or unified self. A man wills to kill another. Roughly speaking, intention corresponds to what he wills, motive to why he wills it. His intention is the "foreseen consequences,'' his motive, that which makes him desire them. His intention is the death of another man; his motive varies according as he is seeking revenge, is a soldier in war, or is engaged in defending himself *Mill, "The intention is what the agent wills, tj d/>, the motive, is the feeling that makes him so will to do." 62 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. from an assault. So far all agree. Does the complete separ- ation of intention and motive follow from this account? Intention, as above illustrated, is an abstraction of intel- lectual analysis. No man ever intends merely to kill another. He intends to save his own life, to defend his country, to "get even" with another, to get money, or, maybe, to exhibit his own markmanship. The " killing another" is simply part of the intent, of the whole aim. It is necessary to discover in- tention in the narrower sense in order to determine that one acts in the moral sphere at all, but it is necessary to discover the whole concrete aim before we can find what a man really wills. Now the moment we have the whole aim, we have motive also. To defend self, to get revenge, is what impels a man to act. Or, if on the other hand, we say revenge, ambi- tion, avarice, patriotism is the motive to murder, this sense of motive is a mere sentiment, an abstraction (and hence inca- pable of inducing action), or it means an active attitude towards certain ideals and this is simply the concrete aim. Suppose Napoleon's motive was ambition. Many men are ambitious; why do they not do what he did? If ambjf.inn is a mere feel- ing, it will never induce action at all; it will not define or sug- gest any particular act to be performed. It will remain stuck in its own sentimental, self-absorbed dreaming. A working ambition must translate itself into thought, into the idea of objects, and must be interest in these definite ends or objects; it must be a demand for the reality of certain ideas. It thus includes intention, in the abstract sense of that word, and is intention in its full sense that at which a man really, and not simply incidentally, aims. An objection sometimes made will bring out the point. Suppose a man shoots at game, knowing that a man is near the line of fire; he kills the man. Now, it is urged, his motive clearly implies lack of regard for life, but it cannot be said that he intended to kill the man. Or, from the other side, it may be said that Brutus intended to kill Caesar, and yet the killing of Caesar was not part of his THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 53 motive (Mackenzie, Manual, p. 40). As to the first, the agent did not intend, by itself, to kill the man; yet neither did he intend, merely by itself, to kill the deer. He intended, as a result, a form of satisfaction of which the possible death of a man, as well as of a deer, was a part and this aim, as self- expression, was the impelling force. As to the second instance, Brutus did not intend simply to kilj Caesar; he intended a cer- tain deliverance of his country, or a certain self -advancement, the death of Caesar forming a constituent part of this aim; and in just this same sense the thought of the death of Caesar (which is what I take Mackenzie to mean by the loose phrase "the killing of Caesar") was a part of his motive; he took a positive interest in the thought of Caesar out of the way, an interest which was sufficient to induce him to do the deed. His whole ideal, of which the removal of Caesar was a part, was what moved him. /The identity of the complete intention and the motive^may also be gathered from a consideration of~The circumstances under which we give credit to a man for a good intention even when no act is obvious. We do so only when the agent can point to effort on his part, and to obstacles which prevented execution. If a man says he really intended to do a certain duty but forgot it, we may indeed recognize the intention so far as entertaining the thought is, psychologically, action, but at the same time must recognize that the possibility of forget- ting shows that the matter was not really ' ' on his mind. ' ' That is, we infer from the fact that it did not move him to the fact that it was only half-formed intention. We always, practi- cally, judge intention from act, provided we have sufficient data to enable us to judge intelligibly concerning the act. Sound psychology justifies our condemnation of the man who has "good intentions" but no deeds to show; his action, in revealing himself, reveals his true intent aud gives the lie to his profession. The impossibility of really judging the conduct of others, as maintained by Kant (Theory, pp. 23-24) and by Green 54 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. (Prol., p. 318), is a fiction resulting from separation of motive and intention. There is, of course, always difficulty in deciding what the act is, but so far as we can tell this, we can tell the intention, and knowing the intention executed, can tell in. what kind of ends the man is sufficiently interested to be moved by them to act can estimate his character. This brings us again to the question: Is feeling motive? Yes, and no. Decidedly no, in the sense in which the consistent hedonist must use the term feeling a state of experienced pain or pleasure. Yes, in the sense in which practical life uses the term : An active interest in certain ends, that interest ex- pressing the controlling lines of activity.* ^'I'he distinctions of interest from mere feeling, or passive affections are: (1) Interest is active, projective. t Wetake interest. In- terest is demand, insistence. Whenever we have an interest in any thought, we cherish it, cling to it, endeavor in all ways to realize or fulfill it. (2) Interest implies an object the end, or thought, which claims attention. We are interested in something, while mere feeling begins and ends in itself. In common speech an "in- terest" means the end which dominates activity. (3) Interest (inter-esse) implies the relation which the in- teresting end bears to the controlling lines of action, to char- acter. It expresses the identification of the object with the subject. Mere feeling does not involve this complete interac- tion with character. Because of this difference, mere feeling is of value only while felt, as actually experienced; an interest has value on its own account (as the outworking of character) whether the objective aim included within it is ever externally experienced or not. "It is better to have loved and lost than never to have loved at all." It is better to aim at anything * Common speech often uses feeling to denote impulse. Hoeff- o use feeling in a dynamic sense which and yet pp. 235-236, he makes impulse a \-S\J LLL LL1.\J H OJ-JCC/^H \JM. I't ding, Psychology, seems to use feeling in a dynamic sense which brings it close to impulse, derivation from feeling. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 55 which calls forth the powers of the self than to get the passive enjoyment of any object whatever; the true satisfaction of interest lies in the assertion of its activity and not in the mere results attained. That is, the assertion of self is the result, in comparison with which all other results are insignificant. This is that independence of the moral agent of all the contingencies of life, of which the Stoics made so much. We conclude, then, by saying that the term ' motive ' sim- ply expresses the moving force or interest of a given end or aim, this interest indicating the extent to which the self finds its own character involved in the realization of that end. Confirma- tion, if any further is necessary, is found in the fact that all hedonists, since James Mill, have used their theory of motives to furnish the machinery by which certain ends are made active interests of the individual agent. The subject with which they have really dealt is not the psychology of motive as such, but rather this problem: Given certain ends which are requisite to the welfare of society, how can these ends be rendered motives to the individual? Their answer has been: We must so con- nect, through the instrumentalities of pleasure and pain, these ends with the individual's own welfare that they shall become identified with his conception of himself. In other words, their practical assumption is not that feeling as such is motive, but that feeling may be so used as to make certain aims, otherwise lying outside of the agent and hence indifferent, interests to him. The following references will give the status of the discus- sion of intention and motive from the time of James Mill to the present. James Mill, Analysis of Human Mind, vol. II., chs. 22 and 25; Bentham, Principles, chs. 8 and 10, pp. 71, 92-95, 97-103; Austin, Jurisprudence, vol. I., chs. 18-20; Mill, Utilitarianism, p. 27, note (Eng. ed., not in Am., but quoted in next reference); Green, Prol., pp. 315-325; Inter- national Jour. Eth., vol. IV., pp. 89-94 and 229-238, and references there given. 56 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. SECTION XXVII. PLEASURE AS CRITERION. / We saw that pleasure as feeling could not be ideal, because /every ideal is present as thought, not as feeling; we saw, how- fever, that the ideal, or thought, might awaken present pleas- ;ure, and so the question arose whether this present pleasure L ; might not be impelling motive. We were obliged to deny it, pn the ground that mere feeling ends in itself, or has no dyna- ,' mic power, and because coucrede feeling, as actually expe- rienced, (a) depends upon the activity already going on (in- stead of exciting it), and (b) is colored throughout by the character of the end or idea which defines the activity. We concluded, then, that the pleasure-pain condition is not motive; but registers the interest which a given individual takes at the given time in a given act. This brings us to the question of pleasure as criterion or standard of the worth of action. Giving up the thought that it is either aim or motive, have we not arrived at the concep- tion that it indicates, registers, reports the worth of action, and is thus its test? In the following sense, yes. The satis- faction (interest) whiclia glVeH individual ' lakes in an act measures the worth which that end, as a matter of fact, has to him at that particular moment. But this does not mean that pleasure or pain is the moral criterion. It means that if we know the kind of ends and acts in which a certain agent takes pleasure (instead of passively enjoying it), we know how to estimate his moral character. If he rejoices in temperance, he is temperate; if he grieves at it as an enforced thing, or as merely useful to some further end, he is still partial in that virtue, etc.|/Pleasure does not determine the worth of an actt >bjit the kind of act which affords pleasure determine _worth of an agent.' That is. wtTmeasure the worth of a given experience Of pain or pleasure^by i tference to a Stanford of > character, by reference to the moving ideal which calls"it forth.* *See Plato, Laws, II., pp. 653-4, Aristotle, Ethics, Book II., ch. 8; Laws, II., pp. 659-61, and Aristotle, Ethics, Book X., ch. 5. I am not able to see that much advance has since been made as to the ethical psychology of pleasure and pain. The artistic sense of the Greek who understood that it was a mark alone of a true gentle- man to know how to take (as to when, where and how much) his pleasures and pains, divined the truth. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. But the hedonist himself contends that it to not the pres- ent felt pleasure which measures the value of the act, but the results of the act in the way of pleasures and pains an act is good according as it effects a net balance of pleasure over pain, bad when painful results predominate over pleasures. It is this doctrine which we must discuss. We note that it makes a break between criterion and ideal and motive. Not the same pleasure, or pleasure in the same sense, is criterion that (on their theory) impels to action or that is the desirable end. (a) The motive must be present and individual, the results are distant and, according at least to one school of hedonists,* general, consisting in pleasure or pain to all men, or to all sen- tient creation, (b) According to the hedonist, no one would ever aim at anything but pleasure, but the act may result in pain as well as in pleasure, may bring other pleasures than those aimed at, or may bring none at all. If the criterion and the ideal were the same, every act whatsoever must be right because an unadulterated pleasure. I. Thus to dissever criterion from ideal is to reduce moral experience to a chaos. A person may aim at anything what- soever, may have any end we please to suggest and the char- acter of that end has nothing whatever to do with the morality of his act. The whole process of forming intentions, of defin- ing ideals, of discussing aims, has absolutely no moral value. It is true that Mill (Util., p. 27, note, Eng. Ed.) says "the morality of the action depends entirely upon the intention," but this seems a complete reversal of hedonism. It proclaims that the test of an act is not the pleasures and pains which, as matter of fact, result from it, but whether, in doing the act, the agent aims at bringing pleasure or pain to himself and others (Mill being a 'universal' hedonist). By no conceiv- able stretch of language can this be interpreted as meaning that pleasure is the 'test of morality; it makes the character oE * Termed by Sidgwick, universalistic hedonism, as distinct from individualistic, but commonly called utilitarianism. 58 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. the agent, the sort of result he aims at, the kind of end that moves him, the criterion. Only extended quotation can show how typical this rever- sal is of all modern utilitarianism, though it seems, in the taaiu, to have escaped the critics. The only hedonistic view is that which measures an act, after it has been performed, by its results in pleasures and pains. Every utilitarian has substi- tuted a criterion for the formation of right ideals. It says to an agent: Before you act, consider as thoroughly as possible the results of your actions, the pains and pleasures that are likely to result to all people and animals from them; then, if you decide uppn the act which promises to bring a balance of pleasure, your act is right. See, for example, the "hedon- istic calculus" as explained by Bentham, Principles (p. 16), noting such expressions in the memoriter verses as ' ' such pleasures seek," "such pains avoid," which clearly indicate that he is setting up a standard for the kind of ideals at which men ought to aim. We do not here need to discuss this cri- terion of morality; whether correct or incorrect, it is not hedonistic. It measures conduct not by pleasure and pain, but by the character of the agent as manifested in the end which he attempts to realize or bring into being. It virtually says that the act performed by an agent in a spirit of benevolence (defined as that which aims at giving pleasure to sentient beings) is right. The utilitarian confuses results which do happen with foreseen results moving to action. Yet if he does not make this confusion, he has no alternative but to say that intention, aim, etc., have nothing to do with the morality of an act. As matter of fact, our criterion and ideal must have a common denominator: the worth of an act must be measured by the worth of its intention, or the experiences aimed at. II. Similar confusion results from the divorce of criterion and motive. The test for the morality o'f the agent is made one thing, and the test for the act another, and both concep- tions contradict the view just stated. The motive, being pleas- ure, is, according to the hedonist, always good. (Bentham, THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 59 Principles, p. 48.) "A motive is substantially nothing more than pleasure or pain operating in a certain manner. Now pleasure is in itself a good .... It follows, therefore, imme- diately and incontestably, that there is no such thing as any sort of motive that is in itself a bad one.* If motives are good or bad, it is only on account of their effects." Here the criterion is distinctly stated to reside in the effects of the act. Hence the separation of the morality of the act from that of an agent. The agent, as expressed in motive, may be 'good,' his act 'bad,' or the contrary. Two entirely different sets of considerations decide the respective cases. The Tightness of the act is decided by its actual effects; of the agent by his pre- dominating feelings. It is quite true that other systems beside the hedonistic make such a separation, generally under the names of the * formal' and 'material' Tightness of an act. (For the histor- ical origin of this distinction, see Sidgwick, History, p. 200; its meaning to those who accept it will be found well stated in Bowne, Principles of Ethics, pp. 39-40. The best assertion known to me of the doctrine of the text [the identity of agent and act] is found, of all places, in Brown, Philosophy of Mind, Vol. III., pp. 489 and 499-502.) According to this distinc- tion, formal Tightness pertains to the motive of the agent; it is his will to do the right. But with the best will in the world, the agent may still act contrary to the conditions of well-being, and do something whose consequences are evil (materially wrong). The distinction seems to avoid a real difficulty in our judgment of conduct. But this very avoidance is the chief objection to it. It restates the difficulty in generalized form instead of solving it. It introduces a fundamental dualism into moral experience by making it possible for a good man to * It would seem as if "pain operating in a certain manner" ought logically to be bad. But if Bentham admitted this, being obliged to hold also that pain impels away from further evil, he would be in an obvious dilemma: the motive would be at once bad and good. The same contradiction, of course, is involved in hold- ing, at one and the same time, that pleasure as motive is good, yet that motive is good only by its effects. 60 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. be continually doing bad acts, and for a bad man to express himself constantly in good acts. No amount of criticism can say more than the mere statement of the doctrine says. It tends to reduce good character to mere sentimental well-wish- ing in general, eliminating the objective factor, the kind of ends aimed at, and to reduce good action to mere conducive- ness to external results, eliminating the factor of self-reference, of spontaneous vital self-assertion. As the outcome, we are left with no working criterion for acts. There is no way in which the individual can convince himself in advance of the right thing to be done. The pleas- ures and pains which may result from any act depend so much upon circumstances lying outside both the ken and the charac- ter of the agent, that it is impossible to forsee them, or to get any guidance from their consideration. If we already have a belief that certain lines of action are, upon the whole, right, we may act in the faith (never with the proof) that such lines of conduct will, upon the whole, result in more pleasure than pain; but if we are dependent upon calculation of the painful and pleasurable consequences, in each instance, we shall have an infinite task. On the reference of an act to the self, to the immediate and to the secondary impulses, there is a defining principle, something which set the minimum and maximum limits. But the pleasures and pains which may proceed from an act are so remote from the intrinsic nature of the act that there are no assignable values in the problem; it is indetermin- ate throughout. A wholly consistent hedonist would be in the position of one having the " mania of doubt"; the condition of an agent who cannot start to do anything without thinking that if he does the act, this, that or the other painful conse- quence may follow, and who, consequently, passes his life in self-absorbed, futile worry.* From the standpoint of possible consequences, the position is legitimate; however improbable, such possibilities cannot, with reference to external results, be *See, for example, Amer. Journ. Psy., vol. I., pp. 222 and ff especially p. 238. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 61 disproved. Only the force of inner impulse and the demand of the occasion, the power of self-assertion, carry the normal individual out of such endless reflections into act. The limit must be self-contained. Criticisms upon the hedonistic standard will be found in the following references, some of which duplicate criticisms upon the subject of ideal and motive, but, so far as possible, confined to the subject of criterion: Bradley, Studies, Essay 3; Green, Proleg., pp. 233-255, 361-388 and 399-415; Martin- eau, Types, vol. II:, pp. 308-334; Leckey, History of Euro- pean Morals, pp. 1-75; Grote, Examination of the Utilitarian Philosophy; Birks, Utilitarianism, chs. 1-4; Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 204-211; Murray, Introduction, pp. 167-205; Dewey, Outlines, pp. 31-51. SECTION XXVIII. THE STANDARD OF HAPPINESS. In spite of all said concerning the unworkable character of the hedonistic ideal, motive and criterion, there is little doubt that, in its modern or utilitarian form, it has been, the chief / theoretic instrument of practical reform. Such a paradox I/ demands attention. Its explanation is found, I think, in the /,/ y,v fact that while nominally the utilitarian has been insisting upon ^Jw./r happiness as an ideal and standard, really he has been engaged T (i) in working out an ideal and standard of happiness of a ~ wide, free and, oftenloftv nature; (ii) has insisted tlial eVOlj individual, without respect ofhirlh j^r^accident of fortune, have the freest chance to realize this happiness for himself, and has, (iii) identified happiness with general welfare, or common good, demanding that all the machinery of law and edu- cation blTSmployed to make reference to the general interest a controlling motive with the individual. In all these respects, utilitarianism has been in the forefront of modern political and industrial development. But none of these demands js^in itself,hedonistic; indeed, all are signs" of a more~organic view of the individual and of society than is logically possible to hedonism. It is the advance beyond hedonism which has con- 62 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. stituted the power of the doctrines, while their entanglement in the individualistic psychology of the 18th century (which gave them their hedonistic character), has, in so far, reduced their effectiveness. A brief sketch of the development of modern utilitarianism will at once complete our criticism by showing how hedonism has abandoned its own ground of hap- piness as standard and has set up a standard for happiness, and will enable the criticism to take a more appreciative attitude toward the practical spring and worth of the chief modern writers. In Bentham -(1748-1832), utilitarianism was made the instrument of legal reform in the interest of the whole people and a weapon of attack upon class interest. Great abuses had deflected law and its administration from equal regard to the community interest, and made of it a device by which a few profited at the expense of the many. The abuses were protected in the name of custom and precedent and these, in turn, were consecrated, it seemed to Bentham, by an ethical philosophy which held that right and wrong were inherent characteristics of things, without regard to the end to which they contrib- ute, or their practical serviceableness. Now as against this fview, Bentham testified that every idea and institution must be cross-questioned, and if not able to justify itself by showing its contribution to the happiness of the world, be condemned to pass out of existence. Bentham equally insisted that this justifying end of happiness was public or common, not indi- vidual or belonging to a class. Hence the two war-cries of ^N utilitarianism, "the greatest happiness of the greatest num- ber," and in its computation, "everyone to count for one and for only one." Here we have the standard, which is in prac- tical substance, the well-being of the community as a whole, with equal and impartial reference to the well-being of each member of the community. To a period when the democratic spirit was rising against the survivals, finally become useless, of an aristocratic civilization, such a theory proved a most useful standard and rallying point. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 68 In such_a standard, there is nothing of necessity hedonistic. Happiness is the common name~for' welfare, well-being, a gen- erally satisfactory condition of life. It conveys, of itself, no suggestion concerning what constitutes happiness, and is far enough from identifying itself with the hedonistic notion of a series of states of agreeable sensation. The other side of utilitarianism developed through the need political reformers have, at least practically, of framing a theory of motives Bentham differed ?romearlier utilitarians largely in his appreciation of the necessity of inducing the individual to take sufficient interest in the general welfare to direct his conduct in accordance with its requirements. Pain and pleasure seemed to him just the instruments needed. Especially interested in criminal procedure and prison admin- istration, pain, in the form of punishment, seemed to him to have great possibilities as a motive power when brought to bear, under the direction of a scientific psychological analysis, upon the individual. On the other hand, the growth of com- mercial life, as reflected in current political economy, had brought to consciousness the ties of interest which hold men together in modern society; it had revealed, in the language of the day, how far the self-interest of one coincides with the self- interest of others. Here, pleasure, as personal profit, seemed to be a powerful inducement to men to seek the common weP fare! As happiness, under the influence of the dominant individ- ualistic psychology, was translated into agreeable sensation, so social interest, under the same influences, was interpreted as sheer personal pains and pleasures, abstracted from the objec- tive conditions which, in their relation to the activity of the individual, really determine and measure them. James Mill (1773-1836), who had a knowledge both of current psychology and current political economy denied to Bentham, completed the fusion of these various elements; and bound, seemingly irretrievably, the new standard and ideal of industrial democracy to the analyses of an individualistic psy- 64 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. chology. John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), his son, while con- tinuing the tradition, yet even more than Bentham changed the idea of happiness as a standard unto a standard of happi- ness, defining it still nominally as agreeable sensation, but in reality in terms of the objective conditions which determine it. (A). Bentham and James Mill had dwelt only upon the quantity of pleasure, in the various forms of its intensity, dura- M *^MMHiMiMflM^flff | * ll P' BI " l 'l^ tion, fruitfulness (as to further pleasures) and purity (or free- dom from pain)*. John Stuart Mill insisted that the quality of pleasure must also be taken into account, and that a small amount of a higher quality might, or should, take precedence of a much larger bulk of a lower quality. Now differences of quality in pleasure as to higher and lower evidently imply a standard of measurement. What is it? Mill gives (or at least suggests) two answers: (i) The standard is the prefergnnfi of those who have experienced both. Now of this it may be said thaT such preference only proves that it is preferable to that person or body of persons; but, even if they were unanimous in their judgment, this would not mean that one was higher for me unless I found it so. But a more serious objection is that this puts the standard of pleasure in the character of the person enjoying it, instead of making pleasure the standard of character, and thus contradicts hedonism. This aspect comes explicit when we find(ii) Mill saying that a "sense of dignity," presumably a sense of -the kind of pleasure that is appropriate to a human being to enjoy, comes in to decide as to higher and lower. (Mill, Util., pp. 309-313.) Now when we define a higher pleasure as that (a) which any person, or (b) a person of higher character, prefers, we have obviously referred pleasure to that in the person's char- acter which makes it preferable we have an objective standard. * Criticisms of the conception of greatest sum of pleasures, showing the implied presence of an objective standard, will be found in Green, Proleg., pp. 235-240; Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 207-210; Watson, Journal of Spec. Philos., vol. 10, p. 271. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. ^ (B). As to motive, the question again arises how an individ- ual agent may be induced to prefer the general well being to his own private profit. The previous answer had been: through the influence of punishment, of reward, of education, etc., set- ting up associations in the^mind^of_the agent between his own happiness and that of others. Mill saw clearly that an identi- fication resting only upon association is artificial, and likely to dissolve through the force of intellectual analysis (which hap pened in his own case, leaving him with a feeling of isolation. Autobiog., p. 136), and that there must be some intrinsic con- nection. This is the social unity of mankind; the nature of the individual h-xo t^opQughl^socj^l that he cannot conceive -bipisplf " nthp.rwjse than as a member of a body He, tEere- fore, comes to identify happiness with harmony jvith his fel- fows. ~(Mill, Util. , 343-347. ) Here the social value of the individual is made the criterion of the moral worth of happi- ness. This thoroughly socialized ideal of happiness is the most characteristic feature of Mill's ethics. It is noble, but it is not hedonism. fencer lharks the final stage in the transformation of hap- piness as pleasurable sensation over into the accompaniment of certain Abjective conditions. As John Stuart Mill is signalized by recognition of the dependence of pleasure upon social law and unity, Spencer is signalized by recognition of the depend^ ence of pleasure upon the laws not of society alone, b universe which conditions the life of society and of the indi- *- ,, vidual. (See his criticisms of the older utilitarianism, Data, pp. 56-63, with which compare Stephen's Science of Ethics, 353-379.) According to Spencer, we must "deduce, from the laws of life and the conditions of existence, what kinds of action neces- sarily tend to produce happiness." And to derive perfect moral laws, we must postulate the case of a "completely jidao^ted man in a completely evolved society," defining, therefore, man "in terms of the conditions which his nature fulfills." (See / ((\j\t\ pp. 179, 275, 280 of Data.) Under present conditions, pleas- ( 66 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. ure is not an adequate test of morality; we make it so only by re7ereir<5e~td~Tlre thwighToFthe "complete relation of individual to environment. At preaaak pleasure and Tightness conflict in at least three respects. QJ We have to do things through sense of obligation only, with constraint, dislike and pain. (2) We have to compromise, and surrender present to future -pleasure, while in a 'right' state we would enjoy both. (3) We. have often to sacrifice our own pleasure to that of others. (See Dewey, Outlines, pp. 75-77 and references there given.) Now we do not have to ask concerning the adequacy of Spencer's analysis here. In any case, it is all but the most explicit recognition that pleasure is not of itself a standard, but that certain activities and conditions, defined in objective terms, measure, or are a standard for, pleasure. In a similar maUIief, Stephen practically sets aside happi- ness as a criterion, and substitutes for it conduciveness to the vitality and development of the social organism. The objec- tive conditions have finally encroached more and more upon the "agreeable feeling, "^md_bave made it only a very thin shell upon a very solfdcore. Hoeffding, Ethik, compare also Monist, vol. I., p. 529, on Principle of Welfare, represents the best contemporary effort to develop utilitarianism along the lines of John Stuart Mill, but distinguishing frankly between welfare as social criterion, the motive which actually impels the individual, and the peda- gogical problem of so influencing his motives as to make him interested in the social end. Gizycki, Manual of Ethical Phil- osophy (trans, by Coit) occupies much the same position, but with less clear and thorough analysis. Compare, Mind, vol. XI., p. 324, article by Coit on Ultimate Moral Aim, and Int. Jour. Ethics, vol. I., p. 311, by Gizycki on Final Moral End. A good statement of the best side of utilitarianism is found in the last named Journal, vol. III., p. 90, by Hodder. SECTION XXIX. STANDARD, IDEAL AND MOTIVE. We conclude this phase of the subject by stating what seems to be the true relation of the three. At fll>ot l in *** 1j r "T^"^^ of the child and of the race, the ideal or aim is comparatively THE STUDY OF ETHICS. As the ideal is formed before, and with reference^ to a given act so the criter- erion is applied to a given act after it has been performed. The act is judged at first by its outcome; primitive people carry this to the point of making no distinction between intentional and accidental acts. Even inanimate things, axes, trees, as well as animals, are tried and condemned.* At this stage, fintentjOT or ideal? is also undefined, acts resulting from custom or instilled habit rather than from tension of habit and intent. But with farther development, there is recognized the need of a criterion not simply for acts after~they are performed, but . for the process of forming ends and purposes. As we have seen, the utilitarian, while nominally dealing with the former, really concerns himself with the latter. Now the act is Ju beforehand as well as afterward; the agent asks not simply wEetheT the act is good, u e. , Satisfies impulse, but also whether it is right, i, e , whether the impulse itself meets the require- ments 6f a"certain standard. This change is at the same time obviously a change in the character of the ideal; the ideal is no longer this or that particular act, its generality being sim- ply in the uncTJffscTous, underlying habit, but is the relation of this or that act to a more general aim. The aim becomes com- prehensive, and the particular act simply one form which the permanent aim assumes. The criterion thus comes to be only the generalized ideal, while the ideal is a specific definition of the more general standard. They are related as a foot-rule in the abstract, and this rule translated into the defined length of some portion of space. The original mediation of impulse is through the special consequences related to that special impulse. But as Curious survivals of the early point of view are still found in the procedure of admiralty law, relating to libelling of ships. O. W. Holmes, Jr., Common Law; the same book contains a careful analysis of the legal view of motive, showing that law, in its prac- tice, identities motive not with feeling, but with foreseen conse- quences as inducing to action, and that " malice " is inferred wher- ever the consequences aimed at or assumed are not of a kind a standard character would aim at. 68 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. fi consequences develop, it is seen that they are not one lot of experience isolated from the whole system. It is seen that the consequence chief in importance is that upon the agent's own habits of action, his capacities, tastes, attitude toward life, I ways of forming ends, etc. ; in short, the consequence is the I mediation, not of this or that impulse, but of the entire actual \ self. The mediation of the particular impulse has meaning only in relation to the placing or function of that impulse in the system of activity. The generic standard and ultimate aim expression of self are thus one. (See Sec. XIII.) The act is the subject; but what the act is the predicate is known only by placing the act, in its obvious features, in its right position in the whole activity. If we look at this whole activity as that which the agent is urging towards in every 'act,' it is Ideal; if we look at it as really deciding the nature and value of the 'act,' it is Criterion. The practical application of this conception of criterion may be briefly stated. ( 1 ) . Such a criterion is workable. JTh^ individual always has his criterion with him, because it hjj"- seTfT It is nothing more nor less than the thought of the con- sequences of the act with reference to his own efficiency as an agent in the scene in which he participates. The formulation here is abstract; it must be, because it is not a criterion for action at large, but a criterion for some agent, this or that or the other particular individual, with his own experiences and part to play. Just because it is so absolutely concrete for him, the criterion can be stated at large only in abstract terms. The criterion and its application both exist in terms of the individual's own moral life; it is always putting two and two together; doing the best possible with the material available. Its terras are the given impulse and its bearing in the agent's own life; it is simply a complete view, or judgment, of the intrinsic nature of the act. Only a Criterion which does lie within the range of the self is workable; an outside criterion^ just in the degree of its externality, will nevef^translate into terms of the individual's own needs and powers; it will not THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 69 couuect. The hedonistic criterion of consequences in the way of pleasure and pain has no intimate intrinsic connection with the individual's own habits and aims, and while the rational- istic criterion is the self in name, it is only in name. The self is a blank all-engulfing whole which does not define itself in terms of definite experience. (2). Such a criterion is absolute, yet relative. It is per- manent, yet flexible. It is absolute in the sense of containing all its conditions and terms within itself, it is self as a living actuality. It is relative, in that it is not an abstract rule excluding all difference of circumstauce, but applies to the concrete relations of the case. It is permanent or identical, because self is one in its life and movement; but flexible and variable since the self is one in and through activity and not by its mere static subsistence. (3). Such a criterion excludes all taint of casuistry and Pharisaism. In any standard save the efficiency, the expres- sion, of the agent herself, the criterion is one thing, its appli- cation another. The standard is a rigid something, external to that to which it is applied. As a result, questions always arise as to rules of application, as to possible exceptions, as to varia- tion according to circumstaiiQe. The fatal weakness of encourag- ing the agent to consider how far the rule may or may not apply to this special case comes in. With complete, or organic mediation as criterion, the case and the standard are really one; it is always a question of what the case really is, when looked at not partially, but in the light of the agent as a concrete, effective agent in his vital relationships. Moreover, fixed, external crit- erion encourages fixity of condemnation. A man is condemned because he does not come ifp" to 'this abstract standard entirely independently of his own instinctive tendencies and his own situation. Only when the criterion is defined as we have above defined it, can we judge the agent on his own ground according, to the meaning the act. has for him. The external standard means always a false complacency, a fixed self -congratulation when- ever we conform to the rule. A criterion which is nothing but 70 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. the act completely viewed imposes action by its very nature; it leaves no time nor opportunity for self -directed complacency. The joy is in the action, not in the thought of the self as good enough to do it. Such a criterion, finally, requires acute and objective examination of the conditions of action, as the exter- nal criterion demands continued subjective introspection to see how far along we have got. The latter makes the agent keep his eye on his subjective attitude towards action, instead of simply finding his attitude in the act. So much for the connection between ideal and criterion, and the identity of each with the act organically viewed, or referred to self as self. How as to motive? That again names the organic act from a certain side the side of the interest as the act because expressing the self. It names the extent to which the ideal and criterion are such in deed, and not in name: the extent, that is, to which they are one with action. An ideal which does not move is no part of the self and hence not an ideal or guide to action. A criterion which is not an application of character, an individualized, habitual view of considering conduct, is mere knowledge that other per- sons think well of an act; it is second handed information. A man's ways of judging acts his standard are just as much a part of himself as are the performance of the acts. The judg- ing is one way of acting. The real criterion is the way of estimating action; the value which the self puts upon it, the interest it takes i. e., motive. We have now finished our study of approbation, or the con- scious value attached to action, on the sides both of the good (ideal) and its standard. We have seen that action is itself the process of measuring and defining goods, and that ideal and standard both come into existence as phases of action. We have seen that~goncious^ action 'is the protTess ot appijo- involvmg tfte development OT a general standard of reference and its translation into definite terms. In all this it is implied thai me ace measures the agent, and that the act THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 71 tests the standard as well as the standard the act. It is this implication to which we now pass. CHAPTER VI. SECTION XXX. REFLECTIVE APPROBATION, OR CONSCIENCE. The identity _of agent and act has been our guiding prin- ciple. Because of this identity, we have insisted that impulse, ideal, motive and standard, all express various phases of char- acter. But so far we have overtly considered this identity only on the side of the passing forth of the agent into act, showing that the act is the conclusion of the process of esti- mating value entered upon whenever any impulse is referred to its probable consequences. This also means, as just said, that the act in manifesting character, reveals it makes it a subject of judgment. This reaction of a deed back into the estimation of character, the reflective weighing of character and motive in the light of the acts which express it, constitutes conscience. We measure the act by our controlling standard direct approbation ; we must equally measure our standard by the act as seen in its expression reflective approbation and reprobation, with the involved ideas of merit and guilt. The act from the standpoint of intention, that is the act in consciousness before performance, is an abstraction. The act as done, the deed with its import brought home, the act in consciousness completed, is concrete or individual. The ab- straction, in intention, comes from the fact that character, the organized habits, the relatively permanent ideas, are taken for granted. The agent is consciously concerned only with the objective conditions under which the permanent, assumed ends take their particular shape. A man will measure land well only when he keeps his thought concentrated upon that one fact of measuring, abstracting both from his larger end (selling it, building a house, etc.), and from his largest end self- expression. But this act done, its meaning in terms of his own life, as realized self, must to some degree, appear. Be- 72 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. fore, the act was defined, or measured, in terms of the objective conditions involved in its performance; now, it is measured, or appreciated, in terms of its significance for the self, one's own individuality. It is this fuller value, in its relation to the partial value, that constitutes conscience. It is the return of the ideal,. the motive, the standard, back out of its abstraction into terms of character, of living self. We have first to notice the different sense which attaches to this return in the cases of the good and the bad act respectively. The good man's ideal is the next thing to be done, the step which requires taking. But in so far as the agent is good, the act, no matter how specific, utters his whole self. The definite act and the generic end are one. It harmonizes his powers, reducing his impulses, both primary and induced, to unity. His whole self being in the act, the deed is solid and substan- tial, no matter how trivial the outer occasion. As Aristotle says (Ethics, Book I., ch. x., p. 12), the nobility of the good man shines through ignoble circumstance. The good man always builds better than he knows. Furthermore, the very aim of the good man is itself a unification in thought, as the deed is in act, of the realities of the situation. (See Sec. VI.) His intent lines up, focuses the demands of life. In doing the deed, then, the universe of Reality moves through him as its conscious organ. Hence the sense of the dignity and validity of the act the essence of the religious consciousness. Hence the joy, the feeling of full life, and the peace, the feeling of harmonized force, which accompany the good act. The " moral sense," on the part of the good man, is this realization of himself in his deed, the consciousness of the deed in its organic significance. The moral consciousness is thus one with the consciousness of the act. The joy is in the act itself, not in the goodness of the agent as distinct from the act; the peace is found in doing the deed; it is not an end to be reached by the deed as a means. The moral consciousness is not a distinct thing, apart from the act: it is the act realized in its full meaning. We THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 73 instinctively recognize that there is something unhealthy in over-conscious morality. There is a Pharisaic paradox, as well as a hedonistic one. Asjjleasure can be got on^v by aii^inp at something else, so the consciousness of moral worth, the sense of right doing, can be had only when it is not sought for. And there is a necessary reason for this: the consciousness of good- ness is the consciousness of a completely unified self. If the agent is thinking of his own glory, or credit, or moral worth, or improvement, he is, by that fact, divided; there is the deed to be performed, and the reflex of it into himself. In so far as the latter is the real motive for action, the interest is not in the act as self (or in the acting self), but in the act as means to a state of enjoyment (in the mere getting a certain expe- rience). Attention to the act is, of necessity, partial, for it does not absorb interest. Hence the moral emotion which is the internalizing of complete activity, or attention, is missed. Mackenzie (Manual, p. 164) takes the ground that conscience refers only to wrong doing; that good action is unconscious of itself. That there is no separate consciousness of good action fol- lows, indeed, from the above. But when Mackenzie says (p. 338> sec. ed.) that there is probably no pleasure of conscience proper, since (i) the moral ideal can hardly be attained, and (ii) "if any individual did attain it, he would attain it only by a devotion to objective ends, which would exclude the possibility of any feeling of self-satisfaction," he seems to me to make the moral life abso- lutely meaningless (i) The first assertion sets up our old friend, the 'abstract ideal' (Sec. XXI.), not a working ideal, and brings out a further objection to it. The continual non-attainment must mean continual dissatisfaction. Healthy interest in work for its own sake, the only genuine and self -persisting form of morality, is rendered impossible. Instead, we must have an anxious craving for a remote future and a restless irritation with the present. (Humility means not that what we have done is worthless, but that its present worth is the itse we can make of it; humility is willingness to throw the past achievement into the stream of life, instead of clinging to it as a life preserver. And so aspiration is not a striving for a vaguely higher ideal, but the tense muscle, the full interest in the present deed. It is humility on its positive side, or utilized for the future.) (ii) The second assertion brings out the contradiction in the doctrine of self-realization when self is conceived as remote, or is presupposed as in any way existing outside the definite act. There is no alternative apparently save 74 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. choice of a self-satisfaction which is exclusive and, really, hedon- istic, or a devotion to objective ends which does not mean self- satisfaction in reality, asceticism or self-sacrifice. All this, be- cause it is not seen that devotion to objective ends(z. e., the media- tion of impulse) is self-satisfaction. No theory which sets up a self at large can recognize that the only satisfaction which really satisfies is the interest, the value of the act itself. Only a doctrine which sees self to be specific, defined activity can admit the con- sciousness of satisfaction, or good, as a normal fact, and yet not set it up as a separate (and therefore hedonistic) aim. To it, there is no self save in the conscious act; no consciousness of satisfaction save the interest, the value, of the act itself. This disposes of the "disguised selfishness" theory con- cerning virtue, the argument that the good man gets his satis- faction out of the good act as much as the bad man out of the evil act. Of course he does, and more. But it is a misunder- standing, already dealt with, to suppose this means that he does the act for his satisfaction; he does it as his satisfaction. What makes him a good man is precisely the fact that such acts are his interest, his satisfaction. In the good man, the act measures or exhibits the interest; the self is only in the moving act; in the bad man, the act is done for the sake of a self, an interest, outside the act; it is measured by a fixed self. (A good ethical statement here is Mackenzie, Manual, App. B, IV.; a good psychological statement, James, Psy., vol. I., ch. 10.) SECTION XXXI. MORAL CONDEMNATION. The recognition that an act is evil (moral condemnation or consciousness of guilt) takes quite a different form, though based on the same principle. Were all our acts approved, we should have no moral consciousness distinct in any way from our consciousness of action; but reprobation means a distinct, a reflex, consciousness. We are morally glad in, not for, our deed; but we are sorry for it. The condemning judgment is one which stands, in a sense, outside of the act as well as within it. It holds the act out; looks back upon it and feels its unworthiness as measured by a standard self, up to which the act has not come. This consciousness of division, of act THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 75 and self, value and standard, is the very essence of the troubled conscience. Yet, in principle, the consciousness of evil is the same as consciousness of good; i, e., it is the real- ization of an act in its full meaning, as brought out through doing the deed. But the meaning of the bad act is division; the agent has intended an unreality; his aim, his ideal, has been severed from the conditions of the situation, from the realities of the universe; he has set up a merely subjective end, and thus isolated himself. In so far as the performance of the act reveals the true nature of the act, there is recoil, rebound; the deed kicks. The agent feels his separation. The dissatisfaction of the act performed reveals the unrealty, the split of self. Hence the peculiar dualism in all remorse. The agent at once feels the extremest repugnance at the very thought of the act, would repel it as far from himself as possible, and yet feels that that act was his very self knows, indeed, that he feels this repulsion just because the act was himself. As his, the act holds him, fascinates him, perhaps to the point of morbidness; literature is filled with accounts of this binding, gnawing, insistent character of evil done. As not truly him- self, because unreal and false in its very nature, the agent is repelled, he attempts to thrust out the memory, to drown remorse and deaden conscience; to have "the damned spot out." The contradiction of these two sides of remorse marks the emergence in consciousness of the contradiction in the act itself. No one intends an act save_as good; but the completed act stands forth as most thoroughly not good. The moral condemnation, in other words, is directed essen- tially at the ideal and standard of the act. Not because the agent consciously aimed at evil does he have the guilty con- science, but because the good (ideal) aimed at was of such a kind as to show a character which takes for good that which in the light of enlarged character is seen as evil. Again, guilt is imputed not because the agent already had a standard of good and then fell short of it. On the contrary, the remorse 76 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. is, for the first time, the experieoce of shortcoming. The guilt is imputed because it reveals the previous standard of good. How unworthy my character must have been, how defective myself to have such a conception of value! The evil was radical, not simply in the act; it was in the way the self determined, or measured good, in the way it set up ends as approved. Prior to the act, the agent measures by his exist- ing standard of good, aud does the deed as good; afterward, the deed, in its full content, reveals his own character, and thus measures the standard. It is implied that the very condemnation, the consciousness of evil, means the consciousness of a new standard of a higher good. If the agent is still on the same level as that in which he performed the act, no compunctions arise. The act is still good to him, and he is still good as exhibited in that act. Only because the bad act brings to light a new good in its own bad- ness manifested. The reaction of the deed into character, in other words, brings that character to consciousness; it shows character its own powers and requirements, and thus enables it to pass judgment upon, i. e. t to appreciate, its own unworthiness. Moral condemnation, in fine, if really moral, if itself approvable, is of itself always repentance or the beginning of better things. Only because to some extent the self is moving more organically does it realize the disorganic character of its past efforts. Only the man becom- ing good recognizes evil as evil. From this appears the duty of the agent with reference to his experiences of guilt, or unworthiness. It is not to experi- ence them for themselves, but to get their reaction into char- acter. One is to dwell on his mistakes aud shortcomings just enough to get the meaning, the instruction, the mediation of impulse and habit, which is in them. The more the attention is turned upon the bad act in itself, the more that act becomes a fixed, external thing, a finality; the dwelling upon the fact that one has done a bad act is positively demoralizing save as one gets from it correction and stimulus for the future. It THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 77 simply widens the very division, hardens the very isolation, which is the badness, while the true function of consciousness of division is to enable one to heal the gap. In other words, one lias the same duty regarding his experiences of guilt that he has regarding every other experience, viz., to use them, to make them functional in activity, instead of merely experi- encing them.* It is a common fallacy to suppose that the mere experiencing of painful consequences from bad action has of itself any remedial power. As we noted (Sec. XXIV.), pleasures do not mean satisfaction; here we note that pains do not, of necessity, mean dissatisfaction. The "wicked" man may experience an indefinite mass of pain from his badness, and yet get none the better for it, if it is not reflected back into his character, is not used as a standpoint whence to measure his previous standard of good. And the professionally "good" man may get nothing out of his compunctions, his pangs of conscience. He may even, as a dilettauter, come to enjoy them, relishing them as indications of his sensitive moral nature. This happens when he isolates them, instead of using them as symptoms by which to locate, and correct, his un- worthiness of character. If the foregoing is correct, then ethical writers have tended immensely to exaggerate the distinction between regret and remorse, in holding that the former applies simply to conse- quences, having no moral meaning, while the latter refers to motive and is essentially moral. The true difference is simply one of perspective, of proportion; both relate to a reaction of consequences into motive as used to guide the latter. It is regret when duty demands that we do not dwell much upon the past bad act; when we can get the good of it without much reflection upon the unworthiness of a character which could *The doctrine of 'salvation by grace,' as expressed in the writings of St. Paul, with the immense meaning attached to it- seems to have for its ethical content the first historical conscious- ness, on the part of humanity, that sin, when it becomes a con ciouxness of sin organically referred back to character, means, also a consciousness of a good which can take that evil up into itself and so conquer it, which, in fact, has already begun so to do. 78 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. assume such consequences. It is remorse (normal, not morbid) when in order to get the change of attitude for the future, it is necessary to realize, more radically, how unworthy was the self displayed in an act of such consequences. Regret and remorse stand on the same basis so far as the implication of character is concerned. One no more regrets the death of a friend, caused by himself without shadow of intent or carelessness, than he regrets the earthquake of Lisbon. He may, do infin- itely more than regret it; he may be stunned and haunted by it; but 'regret' is as futile in one case as in the other. It is impossible to give many references to distinctly ethical writers in agreement with the foregoing position. It is the view, in substance, of Emerson, expressed perhaps most definitely in his Essay on Cpmpensation. The view regarding the essential defect of the Puritanic morality, viz. , that it aimed at the moral con- sciousness by itself, has been very forcibly expressed in the various writings of James Hinton, and of William James, Sr. SECTION XXXII. VARIOUS ASPECTS OF CONSCIENCE. Conscience, as used in common speech, is a term as wide as the entire moral consciousness of man. It is absurd, accord- ingly, for theory to attempt to narrow the word to some tech- nical or special meaning. But common speech indicates by the word, at different times, certain typical phases of the moral consciousness, and theory may follow with a description of these typical phases. 1. We hear of a tender, a hardened conscience, the pangs, / pricks, compunctions, pains and joys of conscience. This evi- dently refers to conscience as an emotional fact] the interest of the act as brought home to the agent in terms of his own \ feelings. /2. We hear of the voice of conscience, conscience telling us to do this and that, of an enlightened conscience, of educating conscience, etc. Here we are thinking of the intellectual con- tent of the moral consciousness; moral judgments as a system of truth, of ideals and standards. 3. We also hear of the commands of conscience, of its majesty, its inviolability, that aspect which Kant terms "cate- THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 79 gorical imperative." Here is clearly indicated the authora- tiveness of any act recognized as moral. SECTION XXXIII. CONSCIENCE AS THE MORAL SENTIMENTS. The intellectual aspect of conscience is most conveniently discussed in connection with the question of intuitionalism and empiricism; that of the authority of conscience in connection with obligation. Concerning the emotional side of conscience, it is hardly necessary to do more than gather together the scattered threads of what has already been said. The purport of the theory, as already developed, is that the valuation of an act assumes an objective and a subjective form. The objective is the analysis of the act into its various conditions, its definition or limita- tion the ideal, intention, etc. The subjective is the feeling excited in the individual, by either the contemplation of the act in thought or by its actual execution in deed. The thought, the intention, is not colorless; it represents a projection of the self, and the moral emotion is simply the realization by an individual of the value of the projected act for himself and as an individual. The thought of every act must have, therefore, its own peculiar, qualitative, emotional accompaniment. We are somehow affected toward every plan. Hope, fear, disgust, tedium, love, hate, etc., etc., so far as excited not directly by some object, but the thought of an object as an end to be reached (so far as mediated by ideas of acts) are thus all forms of moral consciousness, on the emotional side. Such feelings are evi- dently no adequate criterion of the act. On the contrary, they depend upon that which needs judgment individual character and vary with (See Sec. XXVII.) The emotions which are usually picked out as peculiarly ethical, correspond to the generalized ideals already spoken of (Sec. XXIX.). When the feared or hoped for end is itself brought into relation with the self as a whole, with organized character, an emotional response appears which is ' moral ' in a definite sense. A person who is susceptible to such reactions 80 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. is the one with tender or acute conscience; it is natural for him to feel the indwelling reference of character as a whole to any special act; if a child, we say his moral nature is easily appealed to. To a considerable extent, this sensativeness to given acts as expressions of the whole character is a natural gift, a temper- amental quality; one person always differs in kind and range of it from every other. This consideration shows how little we can rest in this emotional response as an ultimate fact, or regard, it as an adequate criterion for the distinction between right and wrong.* It is, psychologically, simply one phase of aesthetic susceptibility in general. Like all the other phases, its moral value lies not in itself but in the use to which it is put, the ends to which it is made subservient. A "sensi- tive" conscience may become an ingredient of a bad character, and a somewhat inert one a factor of a good character. The former happens when the sensitiveness leads the individual to taking the easiest way out of moral difficulties, as relieving a beggar simply to quiet the clamor of his own "conscience," or hiding scenes of sin and misery from himself because they pain him so greviously. The latter happens whenever the inertness is changed into the habit of looking every situation squarely in the face as it comes, and deciding it on its own merits, without regard to the merely personal feeling awakened by it. Over pietistic training has almost always tended to make the emotional response of conscience a criterion in itself, instead of recognizing that it is a part of conduct to which the same responsiblity for right use attaches, as to the passion of anger, or the desire for food. So far as responsibility for the emotional side of conscience is concerned, the great need is to insure that emotion take the form of interest that is, satisfaction in the working out of an idea into deed, and not the form of mere feeling, even though it be called "moral feeling." In the main, this is secured just *As some writers, naming it " moral sense," have considered it. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 81 in so far as there is interest in the deed on its own account just as the artist is interested in painting his picture, the chess- player in his game, the engineer in the execution of his drain- age project, etc. It must be remembered that every deflection or defect of interest as to the deed itself, means lack of atten- tion to it, and means diversion of thought in some other direc- tion, and hence, of necessity, something slighted, scrimped or distorted in the act itself. Completeness of action and com- plete possession of consciousness (full interest) by the thought of the act are synouomous terms. In this sense, the moral emotion, or interest, and the artistic interest, are identical.* Both, to be genuine, are interests in adequate, non-slighted execution of ideas; a phrase which, after all, means only undivided, organic, pure interest in the act itself. The artist whose chief interest is in his product, qua, product,f and not as fulfillment of a process (who separates, that is, the thought of the completed house from the steps necessary on his part to complete it, who looks at the making of a statue as a mere means to the objective statue) is, by that very fact, so far short as an artist. He has not sufficient in- terest in his performance to give it the care and attention it demands. A fortiori, any interest which looks beyond the ob- jective result to the reflex of that result into personal profit or credit is partial and must manifest itself in a partial that is", inartistic-execution . * I say ' artistic,' not ' aesthetic.' Artistic interest is interest in. , the execution of an idea; in its assumption of that concrete full- ness of detail which is realization. Aesthetic interest is interest rather in the contemplation of some idea already executed. It is the difference between art as a process to the artist and a work of art to the spectator. The latter may free activity in the beholder and so be artistic in turn; but it may stop in itself, in the mere self-absorbed feeling awakened. All the attacks, worth consider- ing, of moralists upon art as meaning self-indulgence, effiminate- ness, corruption, etc., seem to me to rest on the confusion of artis- tic with aesthetic. f " You look to the result, you want to see some profit of your endeavors: that is why you would never learn to paint, if you lived to be Methusalem." Stevenson, in The Wrecker. 82 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. It is necessary, however, not to be too rigid in our concep- tion of the act; not to attempt to draw lines too narrowly as to just where the act itself begins or leaves off and external con- siderations come in. A man who should write a book for the mere sake of fame would not be, relatively, much of a writer; his aim would not direct him; yet the thought of fame may become fused with the thought of the book and add a deepened touch of interest to his work. A man who should carry on a profession simply for the sake of supporting his family would be partial in his morality, and would reveal his moral disinte- gration by carelessness at some critical juncture. But the identification of his family's welfare with the pursuit of his calling reinforces, by so much, his attention to his business, the fullness with which he gives his whole mind to his duties. In the same way, appeals to personal profit or loss often do not have the selfish (in the bad sense) meaning, which, at first sight, attaches to them. A man's indignation at some cruelty to humanity is often first stirred by some bitter experience of his own. A cynic may contend that all his efforts are now put forth simply because of the personal injury he himself has suffered; as matter of fact, the appeal to his own interest may mean simply an enlargement of himself. The shock has acted as a stimulus to call his attention to matters previously ignored; it has revealed to him his own implication m that which had previously seemed external. So a man may first be awakened to the public's need of improvement of transit facilities, or sanitation, by coming himself to own property in the needy region; but it is, psychologically, .poor taste to assume that of necessity such an one is moved simply by his own advantage. It may again be that his own personal interest serves as a con- necting link in giving a stimulus to attention." This principle gives a basis* for judging concerning the *See, again, James, Psy., vol. I., pp. 317-329, especially pp. 325-327. Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 317-323 is helpful, though he seems to give too personal a definition to interest. The statement " when its worth a man's while to do wrong, the guilt lies as often with others as with himself," may be safely changed, I think, into the statement that whenever there is opposition between principle and interest, there is always a.responsibility upon others to change the conditions which make the individual conceive of himself in the narrow way. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. to \ moral value of rewards and punishments; of appeals to do a deed because of the profit it will bring self, or because it will pleaseparent or friend or God to have the act done. So far as these ends 1611(1 to Gecorae distinct "ends, substituted for the act itself, the latter being reduced to a means, the tendency is .thoroughly immoral. If these appeals are used as stimuli to bring the self to consciousness of itself, to bring home to self the real intrinsic nature of the deed needing to be done, in so far the effect is moral provided always these instrumentalities are the most efficient ones, under the circumstances, in effect- ing this end. Our general principle enables us to deal with the assertion that a pure conscience always is attached to the right "for the sake of the right." Correctly interpreted, this statement is true to the point of truism, but many who insist upon it ap- pear to interpret it so as to make it false theoretically, and dangerously sentimental practically. In reality, to do a thing for the sake of its rightuess means to do it for its own sake; the rightuess is not an end beyond with reference to which the act is a means; it simply names that phase of the end or aim which confers upon it a claim to pass into act. Rightness names the quality of the deed in itself as the fully mediated activity, or expressed self. We may say that 'right' is pri- marily and fundamentally an adverb; we are to act rightly, in a certain way or fashion. It then becomes an adjective; the deed is ' right' when performed in this way. Finally, it is a noun. Rightness simply denominates this quality wherever found. To make it an end in itself is to set up a sheer ab- straction for the moral ideal. The result is the same as when moral approbation, or a satisfied conscience, is made the end. (See p. 75.) The end lying beyond the act, attention to the latter is partial and diverted; the act is only partially, that is, wrongly, done.* The theory avenges itself. * When Green says (Works, vol. II., pp. 335-336) "The highest moral goodness .... issues in acts done for the sake of their goodness .... But it is impossible that an act should be done for the sake of its goodness, unless it has been previously con- templated as good for some other reason than that which consists in its being done for the sake of its goodness," he seems to fall into this error. Of course, acts done earlier as good are done later with a deeper consciousness of what their goodness consists in, but this is quite a different matter. Upon the whole subject, see Bradley, Studies, Essay II. 84 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. Yet there can be no doubt that conflicts arise, times when interest in the act itself and interest in right as guch do not immediately coincide. In times of great temptation, or at periods of change, when it is necessary to do some act so novel that as yet it does not present interest for its own sake, such conflicts occur. We feel that the right in general demands that the act be done, and yet the act, in itself, is decidedly a bore or even repulsive. Or we feel that an act which has all the argument of attractiveness on its side must be foregone simply for the sake of right. Moreover, it is precisely at such junctures that moral fibre is made. Only through such disci- pi ine~Ts~7nnnTOTeT~oTn"eT~tn"an wishy-washy. Only at such per- iods is morality freed from extraneous recommendations, and the self thrown back naked upon itself in its own innate vigor. Do not these facts contradict the theory laid down? The apparent contradiction vanishes the moment we subject the meaning of ' Right ' in general to analysis. The conflict then turns out to be not between interest or self, and moral A law or principle, but between two_ selyfip, between an interest / in the act narrowly viewed, and an interest in the act more / fully realized. My interest as a momentary being, with capa- cities for enjoyment, may be in some self-indulgence; my inter- est in myself as a member of a family is in abstinence; my interest in myself as, abstractly, a person who can procure enjoyment out of possession is in getting the better of my cus- tomer in a bargain; my interest in my self as actively partici- pating in the interchanges of life is in honor and good faith. I In other words, the Right which demands loyalty to itself in spite of the inducements of immediate interest, is not some Rightness at large; is a view of the particular act as express- ing the self wholly and not partially. And in general, when- ever there is talk of a conflict between a lower and a higher self, a material and a spiritual self, and of the necessity of sacrificing one to the other, as identical with sacrificing self- interest to the demands of Law and Right, it will be found hat the lower self, the interest, is a partial, passive, possessing THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 85 self; the higher self, the Right, is not some abstraction, but is the self performing some concrete function, as father, neighbor or citizen. We conclude, then, with the statement that the emotional side of conscience expresses the interest which every working ideal and act have for the self have by their very nature psy- chologically.* SECTION XXXIV. NATURE OR CONSCIENCE AS MORAL KNOWLEDGE.! The intui^yiaj^jeory holds that conscience is a peculiar faculty which gives man, directly and immediately, knowledge of principles, or rules, of right. In attacking the opposed theory of empiricism, it is quite customary, however, for the intuitionalists to shift their ground, and substitute a doctrine of the intrinsic nature of Tightness for a doctrine of immediate knowledge of it. There is no necessary connection between these two standpoints; Tightness may be a quality which be- longs to acts in themselves (and not because of any consider- ations or results extraneous to the acts) and yet it not be known, except through experience, in what this Tightness con- sists. Any relation made known by physical science certainly belongs to mass and energy in their own intrinsic character (if true, at all), but it does not follow that we perceive these relations upon bare inspection of the facts. It takes experience, * While not in all cases discussing the same questions, the standpoint of Alexander seems to be close to that of the previous pages. In addition to reference already given, see Moral Order, pp. 148-160; 181-193; 324-332. See Stephen, Science, pp. 311-339, and 396-417. On " moral sense," Mackenzie, Manual, pp. 49-52 and references there given. Also references in next section An inter- esting though (it appears to me) somewhat abstract view of moral emotions will be found in Laurie, Ethica, chs. 8, 23, 26 and 27. Schmidt, Das Gewissen, contains an interesting account of the historical development of ideas about conscience, from the early Greek and Hebrew period to the present. It includes much more than the emotional side. A further statement of the doctrines of 'higher' and 'lower' selves will be found in Dewey, Outlines, pp. 216-220. A discussion of a point barely alluded to in the foregoing will be found in Sharp, Aesthetic Element in Morality. fThis is to be interpreted as knowledge of right and wrong, not of obligation. To that, a further section is devoted. 86 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. often long and painful, to bring home to us these "intrinsic" qualities; there is every reason to believe the same is the case with the quality of Tightness. It is no more a matter of direct perception, than js the law of gravitation. It will be ioTind upon careful reading most modern intuitionalists that they are really concerned to uphold the real and necessary character of the moral distinctions in themselves, rather than any special theory regarding the way in which these distinctions are made known. A good historical sketch of intuitionalism will be found in Sidgwick, History, pp. 167-2CO. 213-234. The same author gives a theoretical analysis in Methods, Book I. chs-. 8 and 9, and Book III. The following will indicate the positions of some of the modern intuitionalists. Martineau, Types, Book I., Part II., Vol. II., espe- cially pp. 17-64; Calderwood, Moral Philosophy; Maurice, Con- science; Rickaby, Moral Philosophy; Janet, Theory of Morals. A good criticism of ordinary intuitionalism will be found in Porter, Elements of Moral science, ch. X; while in ch. VIII. will be found a theory of reflective intuitionalism. In general the intuitional theory in its older form has been shattered by a series objections which may be summed up as follows: The intuitional theory, instead of saving the neces- sary and objective character of moral distinction, swamps them all in the merely subjective consciousness. An appeal to_ "intuition" as final meapa fo rfif^ty flu appeal jp pjorely indTyidual^pj^monTto the dogmatic deliverance, or the unproved sentiment of this or that man. If we go outside the "intui- tions" of the individual, there is left only an appeal to a vague common-sense, which is often unenlightened, the product of mere custom and prejudice. In general, intuitionalism leads to the consecration of established opinion. It allows every existing creed and institution to resist challenge and reform by the assertion, "I represent an eternal and necessary intui- tion."* * These are, in substance, the trenchant objections of Bentham, Principles, chs. I and II. The objection to intuitions as always inuring practically to the conservative party is as old as Locke, see Essay, Book I. It largely determined Stuart Mill's standpoint. See Autobiography, pp. 273-74. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 87 The development of historical and comparative science and of the doctrine of evolution have dealt the theory hard blows. The former has revealed the great variety of ideas conscien- tiously maintained upon matters of right and wrong in different ages and in different peoples, and also largely accounted for this variety of ideas by showing their relativity to types of social life. The latter theory, as it gains in acceptance, leaves uojroom for belief in any faculty of moral knowledge separate from the whole process of experience, and cuts the ground out from under any storejof_iirf ormation given directly and imme- diately?* The modern standpoint and method in psychology also make it almost impossible to attach any intellegent mean" ing to the thought of a special faculty of knowledge. On strictly ethical ground, the value of such moral intui- tions, if we had them, would be open to grave question. Intuitionalism would take the form of knowledge either (a) that this or that particular act is right, or (b) that certain kinds of action (honesty, chastity, etc.) are right. The former alternative would be useful if the essence of morality were a short cut to doing the exact things which are right. But if we abandon this materialistic ethics, and recognize that the heart of morality is development ofcharacter. a certain spirit and ruejhod in all conduct, such intuitions would much lessen the range of self-expression, and render hard and mechanical what little remains. It would shut out all that growth of character, all that opening up of consciousness and experience of values that comes in the search for and testing of right and wrong; it would leave the individual simply with the sheer, arbitrary decision to abide or not to abide by the right once for all revealed. *The first objection is generally met by intuitionalists by hold- ing that certain ultimate principals are alike, though their 'applica- tion ' varies. This transfers the ground entirely from a question of mode of knowledge to a question of validity of content. In con- nection with the theory of evolution, Spencer's contention that it restores a modified intuitionalism (empirical for the race, intui- tional, by inheritance of consolidated experience, for the individ- ual) is to be noted. Data, pp. 123-124. 88 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. If intuition reveals general principles, then the responsi- bility of the individual is limited simply to their application. More than this, moral principles once for all made known go necessarily with an external ideal and standard. Casuistry the consideration of an act from the standpoint of different rules, in order to see under which one it is to be brought is a necessary outcome. p The term ' intuition' has a popular as well as a philosophi | sense. Examination indicates that the popular sense is really much more philosophical than the one professedly so. In practical life, we mean by intuition the power to seize as a /" , - , la whole, in a single and almost instantaneous survey, a complete gfniTpofjjjpn msjfeinopsr It is the power to read O& at a glance thtffheaning of a given situation. It is opposed not to experi- ence, but to abstract logical reflection. It is the outcome, on / the theoretic side, of habit on the practical side. A custom of I dealing with a certain sort of facts and conditions often gives I an almost incredible facility in coming to an immediate conclu- \ siou. When the quality is largely temperamental, we term it f (or rather the response in action based upon it) ' tact'; devel- oped through experience, it constitutes the 'expert.' The architect sizes up a plan at once, and is prepared to act. The landscape gardener takes in at a look the possibilities of a cer- tain ' lie ' of ground, and sketches its future development, etc. In this practical sense, much of our moral knowledge is | constantly assuming theform ot intuitions. The demand for / quick appreciatioji of conditions for action in general is much M greater than it can be in any one special direction, like carpen- ) try, or treatment of guests. Thus every individual comes to \ have ways of judging action which are practically instinctive.* ' It must also be remembered that the whole experience goes on in terms of the individual self. Both initiating impulse and mediating idea are acts of self. This reference to self always limits the field for reflection, and also makes this field a whole, a self contained unity. That a man should get intimate prac- *See Dewey, Psy., pp. 344-46. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 89 tical acquaintance with self, should come to appreciate quickly his own deepest concerns, that he should form habits so funda- mental that they at once take up a given set of facts into them- selves and thus judge its value all this is matter for no sur- prise.* Two qualifications are to be noted. First, such intui- tions are not an ultimate criterion. They test individual char- acter, because they are functions of it; that is, the kind of judgments immediately passed shows the kind of character engaged in making the judgment. No moral judgment is ever merely intellectual, because it reflects the aims and interests of the judge. These intuitions must, therefore, upon occasion submit themselves to wider judgment, must become conditions of a fuller character. Secondly, strength of moral character demands a continued tension between the reflective and intui- tive sides, as between conscious aim and habit. (See pp. 18- 19. ) The intuitive side means quickness, certainty, and, above all, concreteness and solidity; the reflective side is the demand for continued mediation, for continued reaction of the whole into the part, for enlargement of scope. It means delay, but a delay which permits a wider field to be surveyed; uncer- tainty, but an uncertainty which makes the final making up of one's mind more reasonable. The empirical theory of conscience is that the individual has no immediale knowledge Uf flgntand wrong,. eittTer BH to ' particular acts or general principles, but that such knowledge is the outgrowth of Continued experience. Logically, this is all the empirical theory is reqtttrtm to mean; and i sense, empiricism seems to be true. The theory, however, has no special meaning, until there is a further analysis of what experience is. In general, the saying that " knowledge re- sults from experience" is a meaningless one; the point of interest is always in the question how experience gives birth to knowledge. * Emerson has stated the intuitive character of moral knowl- edge as a result of the individual's own activity more clearly than any moralist. See, for example, his Essay on Self -Reliance. 90 THJfc STUDY OF ETHICS. The f,>rce of this general statement is apparent when we note that historically the ethical empiricist has gone far beyond the harmless statement above made, and insisted that moral knowledge comes from a calculation of the consequences of the act, those consequences lying outside the content of the act itself. In otherwords. the empiricists have, as a rule, been hedonists, and have interpreted their empiricism as meaning tEaFmoral quality is extrinsic to the act, lying in the results of the act in the way of pleasure and pain, not intrinsic to the act itself. Thus the negative side of both intuitionalism and empiri- cism has been their strength. The empiricist has kept up his side by denying that we have immediate knowledge of right; the intuitionalist has sustained his by denying that moral qual- ity is found in considerations alien to the act's own structure. Both have failed in interpreting the positive significance of their own contentions. The failure of empiricism need hardly be re-argued here. The force of the objections already brought against pleasure as standard finally comes back to the idea that pleasure as a result, lies outside the act itself, outside the character of the person willing the act, and, therefore, is acci- dental, externally variable, incapable of being foreseen, tend- ing to produce either undue laxity or undue anxiety in gen- .1, unusable. On the ground of the principles hitherto advanced, experi- ence is precisely the mediation of impulse; the execution of impulse brings it to consciousness, shows the meaning for life as a whole of that ^pfflulae-in particular. By reaching iq a- certain way (that is, in connection with j)ther impulses of ear or eye) we find out what this impulse means, its value, |n terms^ both of the content of the impulse, the object (ball, or Hiot iron or whatever) and in terms of the place which that object occupies in our own sentient experience pleasure or pain. Experience is the revelation of the meanjpg ?f our impulse, of our acting selves. A* such, there must be all the "to 1 consequences in forming aims, and using standards, THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 91 which the most extreme empiricist could urge. But these con- sequences are not extrinsic to the act they are the act un- folded, defined. (See Sec75Ln. Amosi suggestive illustra- fionand formulation of this principle will be found in vol. I., No. 6 of Philosophical Review, article by Jamea) CHAPTER VI-OBLIGATION. SECTION XXXV. THE PSYCHOLOGY OF OBLIGATION. A typical phase of conscience is indicated by such phrases as 'I ought, am bound,' 'it is my duty,' to act thus and so. There is here a consciousness of a double relation. ' I ought to go to ray business today ' means there is an agent on one side, and a certain idea on the other; that -the former owes something to the latter, while the latter imposes a certain nec- essity (a bounden somewhat) on the former (Duty, due, debt; ought, owe.) What is the meaning of this peculiar relation between agent and ideal? This problem becomes clearer when we compare it with the question of the good. In that also, there is a distinction between immediate ageut and ideal; the one being in a condition of lack and effort, and the other ex- pressing satisfaction, and a completed act. But both terms of the relation are in the same line of movement. The immediate self is striving to attain the good; the good is this striving^ satisfied. But in duty, the distinction between present self and ideal seems pushed to the point of dualism. The present self does not want, of itself, it would seem, to realize the ideal; the latter rather presents itself as a demand, an exaction, it' not "S coercion. 11 yiUlHlH Uver agliinst the ageut and utters the *** categorical imperative" (Kant), 'thou shalt,' 'thou ougbtst,' instead of drawing the agent on by its own intrinsic attractive- ness. Were the relation one of sheer compulsion or coercion, how- ever, the problem, in some respects, would be easier to deal with. We could, at least, class it with other exhibitions of brute force; the relation would be simply one case of a superior 92 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. energy overcoming a lesser. But, on the contrary, in spite of all the apparent opposition and resistance between agent and ideal, the consciousness of duty carries with it the sense of a fundamental underlying identity. The sense of obligation is not the sense of a stronger alien force l)e;irinu r \vn ; it is rather the sense that the obligatory act is somehow more truly and definitely one's self than the present self upon which the obli- gation is imposed. 'I ouglit to do this act,' implies that 'this ^ *"***^^^***^^ act' is- really " 1 ; in so far as the idea of the act is felt as merely alien to self, it is felt as irritating, as something to be got rid of, not as authoritatively binding. t We thus have before us, in a descriptive way, the main features of the consciousness of duty. It is a consciousness of the present self in relation to an idea of action, this relation involving (a) a certain opposition and conflict between the two, based on the reluctance of the immediate self to identify itself in action with the idea, and thus realize it, and (b) a consciousness that in reality the ideal is a more adequate ex- pression of the self than is the present agent. The psychology of this relation may be most easily ap- proached by a return to the distinction of self as immediate and mediate. At a given time, there is always a certain body of positive impulse and habit urging forward for complete expression. But this very structure, in its expression, stimu- lates certain other tendencies and activities which are not, on their face, compatible with the prior activities which induced them. It is, for example, upon the basis of certain present activities that a person marries, or, again, engages in a certain profession. The activities corresponding to these latter en- gagements are stimulated by the former, and are, indeed, nec- essary to their normal psychological completion. Neverthe- less, the person has now, as we say, " assumed the obligations" of a new condition or occupation. He cannot possibly con- tinue his former habits unchanged; they must, moreover, not only be modified here and there, in pieces, but must be subor- dinated, readjusted to the new aims. Here we have the psy- THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 93 chical conditions for the feeling of obligation. The old habits tend to assert themselves; they maintain themselves by their own inertia and momentum. Moreover, it is highly important, from the moral standpoint (as well as necessary from the psy- chical) that they should do so. If the habits are entirely , resolved, or disintegrated, there is no efficient instrumentality by which the new aims may realize themselves. The person relapses into a moral pulp. What is wanted is not the destruc- tion of the old habite and debires, bui tneir utilization in new directions. Now, just in the degree in which the habit is defi- nite and efficient, it will resist an immediate and speedy assumption of a new direction. It is, upon the whole, safe to say that only in matters of slight importance, or of weak and unformed character, will the habit slip easily and naturally into new channels, aud become, through its co-ordinations with other habits, -a subordinate factor in a more comprehensive habit. It is of its very nature to continue its self-assertion. And yet the newly aroused tendencies and ideas are organ- ically connected with this habit. They are included within its self-assertion. The expression of the old habit carries within itself the making over of the old habit. The responsibilities of the new profession which demand a surrender of old acts and enjoyments, which acquire a redistribution of time, which impose changes in the direction of attention and interest all this is not a visitor from an outside sphere, but arises from the* former acts and impulses, the former interests and lines of attention. The new which requires the readjustment of the old is necessary to the integrity of the old. Hence the sense of finding self In the duty, the sense of unity, as well as of con- flict and difference. The two sides in their tension give that consciousness of authority and subjection which is the marked phase of the sense of duty. The sense of duty is thus a phenomenon in ^r%frit-rtiit ian{mjqTiW5rem to seek- ing for pleasures. Kant retains the whole substructure of the hedonistic psychology of desire; sees the evils which result ethically from it, and then adds on the top story of reason as an offset. If the discussion already had (pp. 46-50) is of weight, the true course is to make over the theory of desire. 108 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. If, however, impulse and desire are as self-absorbed as Kant declares them to be, we must question the adequacy of the machinery by which Kant makes law a motor. If there is no intrinsic connection between desire and reason, how can the former, even when checked and held in by reason, give rise to the feeling of moral humiliation? This presupposes some moral capacity already in the desires; something capable of recognizing the authority and value of law which is not only the thing to be explained, but also impossible if desire has the purely low and selfish character Kant attributes to it. At most, the desire would simply feel restraint, coercion, and would be correspondingly impatient and desirous of breaking away the reverse of humility.* When Kant changes the negative feeling of humiliation into a positive one of reverence, it simply attributes even more frankly some kind of positive moral capacity to impulse. That the feeling is supposed to originate from reason, emphasizes rather than avoids the djifi- culty. If the moral law can transform itself into feeling; if reason can become an impulse, then feeling and impul_sg_caii*- not be so depraved as Kant has already defined them to be. When Kant says (p. 170), the agent "can never , when he has laid aside self-conceit, of contemplation of the majesty of law, and the soul believes itself elevated in propor- tion as it sees the moral law elevated above it and its frail nature" there is something intrinsically akin to law ascribed to the "frail nature" of the soul. It is simply a round-about way of saying that the "soul" is not so frail after all, if only it be given a chance. Moreover the whole question is begged from the start. It is only in so far as the reason is already itself impulsive or moving that it can check and restrain the sense nature and thus occasion humility. To hold that " whatever diminishes the obstacles to an activity, furthers this activity itself," (p. * It is worth notice that Plato, who has substantially the same dualism between reason and appetite, is obliged to bring- in a third and mediating pewerr-theowitcfl impulses, (spirited ness), to bridge the gulf. THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 109 171) is to admit that reason already possesses an active, self- realizing power, i. e., is impulsive. The further difficulty in the separation of sense and reason may be seen in the utter inability to answer, from Kant's standpoint, the question as to why, in a given case, the moral law does or does not become a motive. I do not mean simply that it can not give a detailed account perhaps no theory can do that. But it cannot point to any method of approaching the question. Failure cannot be due to lack of authoritative presence of the moral reason that is always there. It cannot be due to the mere presence or agency of the sensuous impulses they are always present and always selfishly urgent. There is absolutely no connecting link by which to indicate any ex- planation of why the machinery of humiliation and reverence should get itself adequately into operation in some cases and fail in others. We are thrown back on bare chance. The ideas of approval, blame, responsibility are-made meaningless. All this because the actual concrete unity of individual char- acter is surrendered and the two abstractions of sense and reason substituted. Thus far we have taken Kant purely on his own ground. It may be added that, historically, reverence seems to have no special priority or moral pre-eminence over motives like patriot- ism,, manliness, desire for community esteem and recognition; that when it did appear it took, until the development of spe- cialized technical reflection (like Kant's own), the form not of recognition of superiority of moral law as such over sensuous impulse, but the recognition that the community welfare is higher in its claims than the immediate pleasures and pains of the agent. (See for example, Plato, Laws, 647, 649, 671, on reverence as fear of pain attached to right objects.) If we turn from theoretical analysis to actual life, it is at once evident that to make reverence for duty the sole motive would lead to a Pharisaism which must deny morality to the vast masses of mankind, and jx-nnit it only to a few who luivr attained a cer- tain stage of intellectual abstraction. 110 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. Upon the whole question, positively, it may be said: (1) The truth in Kant's main contention is adequately recognized j in the statement that an action is to be done as duty, that is, \J for its own intrinsic meaning independent of any reflex advan- / tage, but not fgr duty. The latter makes an abstraction of / duty, reduces the act to a mere means, and thus introduces s. division and lessens interest (See pp. 85-87.) (2) The con- sciousness of the opposition between desire and duty, with the correlative feelings of humility and reverence, arises not essen- tially, by the nature of each, but historically that is, when the appearance of a more comprehensive and organic end demands a readjustment of desires, demand that they attach themselves to the new end instead of following their past course. Kant's account, therefore, strengthens our original analysis. The sense of the majesty and inviolability of duty is the con- sciousness of the moving, the functioning self as against a par- tial habit, which in its narrow self-assertion, tends to become isolated and static^ instead of connected and instrumental. The moral feeling of humility is in its essence the continued attitude of not hanging on to attainment for its own sake of recognizing that it has no worth save as changed into power. Reverence is the correlative continued openness of will and interest to new and larger demands (p. 75). They require not the absolute opposition of a higher and lower nature to explain thera^but the relative opposition between differentiation and inter-connection of impulses and habits. Convenient accounts and criticisms of Kant's Ethics will be found in Caird, Critical Philosophy of Kant, vol. II.; Muirhead, Elements, pp. 112-124; Mackenzie, Manual, pp. 55-70. SECTION XXXVII. HEDONISTIC THEORY OF OBLIGATION. The problem of duty for the hedonist assumes the converse aspect from that presented to the Kantian. For the latter, the main difficulty is in showing how the consciousness of law, proclaimed by reason, should come into working relations, THE STUDY OF ETHICS. intellectual and motor, with desire, so great is the assumed oppo- sition. For the hedonist, the difficulty lies in getting enough opposition to desire to subject the latter to authority* or in getting that kind of opposition which should give rise to a feel- ing of duty rather than of coercion. Upon the basis of hed-^ ^ onisiu, it may be said that it is to an agent's profit or advantage L/-^0 or superior jnterest to take such and such a course, but how ^J **4> can it be said to be his duty? Pleasure is the good, and man's natural desire is for pleasure. How can there be any checking of desire, save as another desire, promising more pleasure, pre- sents itself? Such a checking as this has none of the elements of the consciousness of duty. The traditional hedonistic answer has been through the idea of sanction, some foreseen evil attached to the satisfaction of a desire which, in itself, would give pleasure. f The essence of Bain's theory is the transfer within the mind of the agent of a relation, now existing between elements of his own conduct, which originally existed between the agent's conduct and the behavior of others. The ideas of authority (command) and obedience are correlative. The les- son of obedience is taught from the outset of life to every agent. "The child's susceptibility to pleasure and pain is made use of to bring about this obedience, and a mental association is rapidly formed between this obedience and apprehended pain, more or less magnified by fear." The knowledge that punish- ment may be continued until the act is discontinued " leaves on *Bentham felt this difficulty that it wished to banish the very term 'duty' from ethical discussion. \ Besides the authors considered below, this conception has been developed by Paley, Moral Philosophy, in a theological form (virtue is " doing good to mankind, in obedience to the will of God and for the sake of everlasting happiness''); by Austin, Jurispru- dence in jural form; by Bentham, in jural and social form, in his, Principle of Morals and Legislation, and by J. S. Mill, notes on h ? s father's Analysis of the Human Mind, vol. II.. pp. 334-326 and Utilitarianism, ch. V. It should be remarked, however, that Mill's account only touches the question why we judge the con- duct of others from the standpoint of duty; it does not answer the question why a man conceives something as obligatory upon him- self. 112 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. the mind a certain dread and awful impression as connected with forbidden actions." This "dread of offending" is the germ of the consciousness of duty. It is reinforced, first, by the sentiment of love or respect for the person imposing the command which brings in a new dread, "that of giving pain to a beloved object." Then a tertiary factor comes in : " When the young mind is able to take notice of the use and meaning of the prohibitions imposed upon it, and to approve of the end intended by them, a new motive is added on and begirds the action with a three-fold fear." This latter fear is more defi- nitely stated as follows: "If the duty prescribed has been approved of by the mind as protective of the general interests of persons engaging our sympathies, the violation of this on our part affects us with all the pain that we feel from the in- flicting an injury upon those interests." (See Bain, Emotions and Will, pp. 285-87.) Now this sentiment of fear or reverence attached to supe- rior power, "at first formed and cultivated by the relations of actual command and obedience, may come at last to stand upon an independent foundation." The third factor mentioned above s'e'e'llia, Irom isain^ further account, to be not so much a factor as a revolution. When the child appreciates the "reasons for the command, the character of conscience is in- tirely transformed " (E. and W. p. 288.) The form of author- ity and subjection remains, although the authority is no longer imposed from without. Conscience becomes an " ideal resejBr blajice of public authority " (E. and W. p. 264; the references are all to the third ed., London, 1888); " it is an imitation within ourselves of the p)vennnent without, us" (p. '2etff-iti~hjmself through and through. No action is moral (that is, falling in the moral sphere) save as voluntary, and every voluntary act, as the entire foregoing analysis indi- cates, is the self operating, and hence is free. Impulse is self, the developing ideal is self; the reaction ef the ideal as meas- uring and controlling impulse is self. The entire voluntary, process is one of self-expression, of coming to consciousness of self. This intimate and thorough going selfness of the deed constitutes freedom. Ethical writers have distinguished ' formal ' and ' substan- tial ' freedom; and have claimed that only right acts are really free. This claim involves this truth: Every conscious act in free in the sense that it expresses the self; it is psychologically 124 THE STUDY OP ETHICS. free. But is the intention, the purpose, of self, one ' really possible' ? Does it square with the conditions of things, with the laws of the universe? Is it possible for the self to be what it would be? No intention guarantees its own execution. It* execution depends upon the co-operation of reality; it must fit into the forces which really make up the course of events. Now if the self has a solid intention, one which reality itself reinforces, one whose execution is guaranteed by the conditions of the case, the agent is said to be really, as well as formally, free. But if his intention is merely subjective, if it involves objective impossibilities, the attempt at execution involves friction, loss, a negative, or destructive, reaction of deed into self. In such cases, the agent is really (ethically) in bondage. He is self contradictory. He cannot express the self he aims to express. It is not so much a paradox as it seems, to say that only the good can be really willed; that we only seem to will, only go through the motions or form of willing, the bad. This same identity of self and deed is, of course, the basis- of responsibility. We are responsible for our deeds because they are ourselves. Responsibility is a name for the fact that we are, and are something definite and concrete specific indi- viduals. I am myself, I am conscious of myself in my deeds (self-conscious), I am responsible, name not three facts, but one fact. There is a formal and a substantial responsiblity. One is liable, accountable, held responsible for his acts, because they are himself. This is formal responsibility, and may coincide with moral irresponsiblity. Every bad man is (in the sub- stantial sense) irresponsible; he cannot be counted upon in action, he is not certain, reliable, trustworthy. He does not respond to his duties, to his functions. His impulses and habits are not coordinated, and hence do not answer properly to the stimuli, to the demands made. The vicious man is not socially responsible, and one part of his nature does not respond to the whole. Irresponsibility is but another name for his lack of unity, of integrity; being divided within himself, he ia THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 125 unstable, we can never be sure of him, he is not sure of him- self. Yet this is consistent with formal responsibility. He is capable of forseeing consequences, and of having these fore- seen consequenses influence or modify his conduct. The per- son who fails in one respect or other of these factors is insane, imbecile or morally immature and is not responsible. One's conduct calls forth certain reactions from others reactions as natural as those called forth when one comes in contact with a physical force. The individual lives as truly in a social as in a physical environment, and the reaction of the one to his deed is as much an intrinsic organic consequence of the deed as that of the other. If the individual has not properly mediated his habit or impulse, if he acts upon inten- tion which is one sided, the reaction brings out that factor of the deed. In one case, it may be the burn from putting his hand in the fire, the other case the rebuke or punishment for violating or coining short of social functioning. This is no external consequence (see pp. 14-16); it is an organic factor of his deed, formerly hidden, but brought to light through the action. The deed executed brings the agent to a more definite consciousness of himself; the reactions of others in the way of praise or blame are simply phases of the return of the deed into the agent, arousing him to consciousness of certain features hitherto obscure. A person who is not capable of such experiences, of having the consequences of his action react back into himself, and become motives or modify char- acter, is not (even formally) responsible; one who has this capacity is responsible. This capacity for mediation is not the cause, and responsibility the effect; this capacity for mediation is responsibility. But if this power of being influenced by the foreseen conse- quences is a habit we have substantial respousiblity. This is an attainment, a conquest, not an original possession; it is a name for virtue or Tightness of will. Such a man is respon- sible in his acts, not simply liable for them. He does not try to escape himself in his deeds; when they are bad, he does not 126 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. try to escape himself in his deeds; when they are bad, he does not ' lay it off ' on circumstances, but stands up to the reckon- ing, and in the very identification of himself with the evil deed in its consequences gets beyond it. He meets the demands of the situation. He is sufficiently interested in his function adequately to translate it into its rational detail of specific aims, and to carry out these aims to overt conclusion in deeds. Just as to say that a man is truly free is to recog- nize his realization of moral good, so to say that one is truly responsible is to give him the highest commendation for actual faithfulness to duty. SECTION XL. DETERMINIST AND INDETERMINIST THEORIES. We are, however, told that man cannot be responsible unless he is free in another sense; that a man cannot be respon- sible unless at the time when he acted he could equally well have acted otherwise than as he did act, and this without any change of character and motive. We are told that self- blame, remorse, etc., are inexplicable without this freedom of indifference; and that rebuke and punishment from others become meaningless and unjust without such freedom. All arguments to this effect seem to rest upon an ambiguity. Just so far as a man believes that he was forced to act as he did act, he excuses himself and rightly; the act was not him- self at all, it was the external compulsory force that really acted. The condition of responsibility, that the deed be the concrete will or unified self, is absent. The confusion comes in when absence of adequate self-motivation is substituted for absence of external compulsion. 'I might have done other- wise' that consciousness is itself my miserable condition, my blame or remorse, and not simply a condition of it (pp. 77-8); but what it means is not that I might arbitrarily or with no different self have done otherwise, but that the sole reason for my acting as I did lies in myself, is attributable to no external cause. I might have done otherwise had I been a better self, had I been a worthy person had I been one to whom this THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 127 right end adequately appealed, but I was not such an one; I was just such an one as would do this sort of deed, which I now see in all its badness; this is ray blame. The whole problem arises because the objector insists upon carrying the dualism between agent and deed which he li.ra- self makes over into the doctrine of his opponent. He contin- ually says: 'Ah, then, according to your doctrine, the agent at the time he acted could not have done otherwise than as he did; this I call not freedom but necessity.' He has simply imported here his own separation of agent and act. Upon the basis of the theory against which the objection is brought, this sentence must be rendered as follows: 'The man was himself and did act precisely as he acted.'* The entire sting of the proposition vanishes and it becomes a harmless truism. But the content of this truism gives the only basis of responsibility. Everything which lessens or loosens the concrete, specific organic connection of the agent with his act, in just so much relieves the agent from responsi- bility for his act. if the abstract, metaphysical will or self intervenes between the concrete self, the impulses, habits, ends, and the deed, then it and not this concrete individuality must assume the responsibility for the act; it is none of my doing. )ln the desire^tojnagujfy the self, the indeterminists d-iiy the Specific, real self, whiV.h ia in ^fl fthrmiprh action. ^.nil prfwt an abstract, outeide self, re4acing fre^yfp, f/> n 'fif^/Miniify an( j rt-sp >n.<:M!ity \<> a myth. Only a few of the indeterminists carry the argument be- yond an expansion, generally rhetorical and hortatory, of the dependence of self-blame and just punishment upon ability to have acted otherwise. Martineau has attempted a more de- tailed statement (Study of Religion, Book III., ch. II., vol. II., esp. pp. 210-227.) An analysis of this shows that the real origin of the doctrine of indifference is not the need of justify- *The 'determinism,' in other words is a logical determinate- ness, and not an external pre-determmism. See an article in the Monist, vol. III., p. 362, The Superstition of Necessity. 128 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. ing moral responsibility, but a defective psychological analysis of will, making of it an impossible abstraction. Mr. Martineau gives the following case (pp. 213-215.) You suffer from calumny admitting disproof; to make the exculpa- tion would cast a shadow on some one else, or embitter some precious friendship. The impulse to exculpate self is arrested by another impulse, equally natural. Now in the decision of this conflict Martineau claims that the following factors are involved: (1) " The^two-vincompatible springs of action; (2) Your own past, i, e., a c^rtainTormedsyst5fiT~or~habits and dispositions brought from your own previous use of life. The former head comprises the, motives that are offered; the latter the character that has come to be. Do these settle the matter between them? * * * Or, is our account of what is there still incomplete, and must we admit that besides our formed habit or past self, there is also a, present self that has a part to perform in reference to both? * * * In all cases of self-consciousness and self-action there is necessarily this duplication of the ego into the objective, that con- tains the felt and predicated phenomena at which we look, or may look, and the subjective, that apprehends and uses them. It is with the latter that the preferential power and personal causality reside." And further (p. 216): "I submit that no one can sincerely deem himself incapable by nature of controlling his impulses and modifying his acquired character. That he is able to make them the objects of examina- tion, comparison and estimate, places him in a judicial and authori- tative attitude towards them, and would have no meaning if he were not to decide what influence they should have. The casting vote, and verdict upon the offered motives is with him, and not with themselves; he is 'free' to say 'yes' or 'no' to any of their suggestions; they are the conditions of the act; he is its agent. * * * * you do not let yourself sway to and fro with varying fling of the motives upon your character, like a floating log on an advancing and retreating wave; but address yourself to an active handling of their pretensions. * * * * You yourself, as a per- sonal centre of intelligence and causality are at the head of the transaction and determine how it shall go." The passage has been quoted at length because it clearly reveals the process which leads to the fiction of a distinct, deciding self, a self separate from the material estimated, the impulses competing. That process is an unreal abstraction of THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 129 motive on one side, and of character on the other. These abstractions being erected into fixed things, some other power h:i- to be brought in to make up for the omitted elements and to bridge the gulf: Martineau's third factor, or self in which alone selecting power resides. If motive and if character were what Martiueau assumes them to be, certainly something else would be required to get a moral action under way. (1) Consider the matter from the side of ' motive,' and see what an impossible abstraction Mr. Martineau has made. Here is" the impulse to clear one's repute; there the impulse not to hurt the friend's reputation or affection. And these set over against character, and supposed to be acting upon it or acted on by it ! A very moderate amount of reflection will reveal that each impulse is what it is, in intensity,* in intel- lectual significance and in moral weight, as a function of char- acter. The desire to clear my standing cannot even occur to me save as I have certain habits and dispositions. Its very existence is the expression of a certain tendency of character; what it is, whether a mere dislike to be thought ill of, a love of popularity for its own sake, a recognition of the commercial or professional value of good standing, or the need of having everything that concerns one squared and true all this is con- stituted wholly by character; finally, the weight which it has with respect to other 'motives,' the relative value attached to it, the whole process of estimation, etc., is a process of internal development, of revelation of the extent to which character is bound up with, is present in the motive. The mere appear- ance of the 'impulse' is the immediate, hasty, possibly super- ficial moving of character in a given direction; the constitution of its intellectual significance and moral import is the mediated, persistent assertion of self, developing itself in this defined direction. And the completion of the motive is the volition, the deed. * Martineau afterwards recognizes this much (p. 229), but with- out reconstructing his theory of motives at all. They still remain objective, phenomenal, etc., etc. 130 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. (2) Equally fictitious is the assumption of the character as fixed, given or presupposed. One would imagine from Mr. Martineau's account that habit means only mechanical routine, formation is equivalent to fossilization and organization to a static arrest of development. When one reflects that the dif- ference in the dynamic efficiency of amoeba and man is the difference in habits, in structure, in organization, one sees how much truth is likely to be arrived at from this assumption. j-jcJ^*- "-" *i n fili r igid attainment were it only for the reason that every habit is a dependent function of the whole organism, is a member of a system of habits, and must co-ordinate, must stimulate and be stimulated by others must, in a word, be flexible, continually readjusting itself. The development of volition is a continued exhibition, self-revelation of character, just as the formation of motive is one with passage of self into unified activity or deed. We know what we are and what we can be only through what we do. If character were this solid, inert lump that Mar tinea u conceives it, undoubtedly it could not originate an act which is free and responsible. But in reality the whole process of initiating impulse, considering, deliberating, choosing is a movement of character aiming at adequate discovery and exhibition of self. (3) The necessity of the third factor, the deciding self, "is a necessity originated wholly through the failure to recognize the present moving self in 'motive' and 'character.' Tlje defect comes out clearly when we find the problem stated as if it were an alternative between determination of the volition by character and motive, or by the Self, the free will. It is in reality simply a question oTthe resolution of a volition into its definite factors. There is no third thing, a volition, deter- mined by motive; the volition is the completed motive; and just so it is _the exhibited character, the fulfilled self. The introduction of self as a third factor (instead of the recognition that the whole process is one of self-movement) marks the break, due to defective psychological analysis, between char- acter and deed. It is the flagrant symbol of the failure to THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 131 recognize that the' deed is the concrete agent, the self in func- tional (that is, definitive and co-ordinated) activity. The truth of the matter is that Martineau (and so with all the other indetermiuists) simply accepts the adequacy of the necessitarian psychology of volition up to a certain point, accepts its dualistic separation of impulse and motive from self, and then, seeing the ethical insufficiency, help themselves out by bringing in the Deus ex Machina, a Free Will. This is the reason the contests between inde'erminists and determin- ists (in the causational, not logical sense) are so futile and un- ending. Both have the same premises, the product of inade- quate psychological analysis. The only way to 'rescue ' free- dom from the attack of the determinist is not to bring it in as a 'third factor,' but to reconstruct the theory of motive and character to bring out the functional presence of the self in them, and their consequent flexible, dynamic structure. The criticism of the iudeterrainist holds equally, therefore, against the determiuist, that is, the predeterminist. He makes the same abstraction of motive, erecting hunger, love of praise,, modesty, etc., into little entities which pull and haul on a self outside of them. Or, going into a wider field, he talks of the determination of self by heredity and environment. He has the two things, set over against each other, and with only a mechanical connection between them, one of force, just as the indeterminist can get only an arbitrary relation. They both argue then as if it were a question between mechanical causa- tion on one side, and arbitrary interference on the other, forget- ting that both alternatives arise from the unexamined assump- tion of the dualism of self and ideal and motive. The whole controversy vanishes in thin air when we substitute for the determination of volition by circumstances or by Free Will, the determination of Self in volition, in deed its passage into definite, unified activity. The best statement of the determinist position will be found in Bain, Emotions and Will, ch. XI. For indeterininism, see, besides the above reference to Martineau, his Types, vol. II., pp. 34r-8; 132 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. Lotze, Practical Philosophy and James, Unitarian Review, vol. XXII., p. 193: Dilemma of Determinism (James's refutation of Pre- determinism is convincing: but I see nothing in his positive argu- ment for indeterminism which does not fall in with the determin- ateness of action argued for above); Calderwood, Handbook, Part II., chs. 3 and 4. Stephen's Science of Ethics, pp. 274-293, seems to be in unstable equilibrium between predeterminism and deter- minateness. Much the same may be said for Gizycki, Introduc- tion, ch. VI. Green, Prolegomena, Book II., ch. I., would be in sub- stantial agreement with the view above stated were it not for his abstract view of the Self, which compels him to separate self as ideal (future) from character, making the latter fixed, or past only, and thus bringing him to the determination of deed by character and circumstance. Alexander, Moral Order, pp. 336-341, does not seem to me wholly free from the idea of character as static, but brings out more clearly than any other writer that choice, prefer- ence is freedom, and that it is irrational to try to get back of choice as both indeterminist and predeterminist attempt to do. Dr. Ritchie, Ethical Implications of Determinism, Philos. Rev., vol. II. , p. 529, turns the tables neatly against the indeterminist's usual assertion that he alone can ' rescue ' responsibility. (Gizycki is strong here also; Hodgson's statement, quoted in Martineau, Study, II., p. 224, is also excellent). Bradley's Ethical Studies, I., is a thorough-going statement of the identity of freedom and respon- sibility, as they are valued by the popular consciousness, with con- crete Selfhood. Muirhead, Elements, pp. 50-54; and Mackenzie, Manual, pp. 140-150, are in accord with the text, but hardly ade- quate upon the psychological side. CHAPTER IX. VIRTUE AND THE VIRTUES. SECTION XLI. THE Two-FoLD STATEMENT OF VIRTUE. It is implied iu what has already been said that virtue, the active good will, or unified self, may be stated from either of two standpoints; that of freedom or of responsibility. Virtue may be considered either as a case of substantial freedom, of solid, thoroughly unified action, or as a case of substantial re- sponsibility, of flexible, properly adjusted, interaction the adequate intellectual recognition of, and adequate emotional interest iu, the demands of the situation. We have, here, the emphasis, first upon one side, then upon another, of the idea of coordination. Coordination implies the attained order, or- ganization freedom. But as coordination, it implies the THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 133 reciprocal adjustment of the various su&ordinate activities in- volved responsibility. It is because the unity of will is a functional, a dynamic unity, because deed i.-i simply self in full activity, that freedom and responsibility are the correlative phases of virtue. Every organic function is maintained through the cooperation, the working together of a number of organs, and the higher the specialization of the function (the definiteuess of the deed), the more comprehensive the number and scope of reinforcing organs. Freedom, again, names virtue from the standpoint of good, of value; responsibility from the standpoint of duty. To be a free and responsible self at every point, and in every act, is at once the sole law and the sole end of conduct.* This gives the solution of the apparent paradox of virtue. Some writers insist that virtue is not virtue until it is wholly free, or one's very nature, uutil it is spontaneous self-movement from sheer inclination; that every sign of struggle, of effort, of constraint, must be eliminated.f Others hold that it is the essence of virtue to express effort, resistance and conquest; it is, in Kant's expressive words, "the moral disposition warring," in Laurie's, "it is mediation through pain." (Ethica, p. 145.) Now a case can be made out for either of these positions; and this fact would seem to indicate some common ground. This is found, I think, in the fact that both contentions have in view in their conception of virtue the wholeness of the self in the deed, but approach it from different points of view. The first view thinks of the relation of the whole to the part, rein- forcing, completing it; the self so present in the deed that there is no resistance, so that we, as Emerson says, "do by knowledge what the stones do by structure." It is the full- ness of the mediation that is in mind. The second view thinks *The principle, it may be observed, is formal in statement, j because it is so full of detailed content in actuality. fSee Aristotle, Ethics, Book II., ch. III., and still more ex- pressly, Emerson, Spiritual Laws. 134 THE STUDY OF ETHICS. of the readjustment of the original, or isolated, tendency, of the part, involved in its membership in the whole. It thinks of the reconstruction, the readjustment involved in mediation. It is not because there has been no struggle that we identify virtue with full, easy nature, nor is it merely because of strug- gle that we identify virtue with conquest. It is, in both cases, because conquest means struggle brought to an issue. We know well enough that the man to whom virtue is natural has had his own fights, and we reverence him the more 'that he has subdued his own enemies, and not inflicted part of the burden upon us, nor distracted our own efforts by continually calling attention to his. We reverence him because he has turned even his struggle into power. We may assume that the position of maximum ease and aesthetic freedom in the human body is not one of impotence or flabbiness, or even of being asleep; but the maximum exer- tion of all the muscles, the limit being found in the principle of balance. In looking at such a poise, one might praise it as indicating the power of doing maximum work, another as indi- cating that it is not work but play. So, after all, there is no inconsistency in the statement that it is not easy to be virtuous, and that yet we are not virtuous till it is -easy. SECTION XLIT. THE CLASSIFICATION OP VIRTUES. Virtue being the wholeness of self, the full and definite manifestation of agent in act (the adequate mediation of im- pulse), the various virtues will naturally name various phases of this act. The main phases were first hit upon by Plato (Republic) and have since been named the 'cardinal virtues.' These are wisdom (practical judgment), temperance, (self-con- trol), courage and justice. After the psychological analysis now completed, the derivation and significance of the virtues should be obvious. Wisdom, as a virtue, is evidently the habit of considering the bearings and relations of a given act; it is the habit of interpreting and appreciating it in terms of the self, of taking it concretely and seriously, instead of ab- THE STUDY OF ETHICS. 135 stractly; whether the abstraction be of brute irrationality, or of that sentimentality which sometimes constitutes an over- refined culture and sometimes a crude flippancy. It is, in short, the habit of defining impulse in terms of its objective content, a preparation for giving its due function, of attaching it to its proper use. The over-subjective ethics of one-sided individualism, fos- tered by evangelical phases of Protestantism, need a recon- struction upon the basis of Hellenic thought as regards this virtue. The modern ' I have to follow my conviction ' finds substantiality only in the ancient 'wisdom is the guarantee of all virtues.' There is and can be no duty of living up to con- viction till we have some surety as to the rationality of convic- tion; no duty of ' obeying conscience ' till we have taken pains to have an instructed conscience. Moral education requires a shifting of the centre of obligation, locating it less in the mere doing of what seems to be right and more as the habit of searching for what is really right. As mediaeval Catholicism, in its consciousness of the superiority of spirit over matter, is accused of confusing dirt with piety, so modern Evangelical- ism, in its emphasis upon moral emotion and attitude, is open to the charge of encouraging an ignorant sentimentalism at the expense of a truthfulness which is not simply formal truth- telling, but which insists upon knowing what the truth is. The tendency to derogate from the ethical claims of knowl- '<# ~~~^rfy. ' , ' y ~~. of /4K UCLA-ED/PSYCH Library BJ 1571 D52s /L 'Jn>"(A*rC /^L L 005 592 091 2 UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY