Southern Branch of the University of California Los Angeles Form L I \A-08> c-6b-\ ' tne 'a.t date stam ped beloyy SEP 2 5 1933^^ n-8.'oj 24 T H E SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE A RHETORIC FOR HIGH SCHOOLS AND COLLEGES ARNOLD TOMPKINS PK'.FESSOR OF PEDAGOGY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS, AUTHOR OF " PHILOSOPHY OF TEACHING," " PHILOSOPHY OF SCHOOL MANAGEMENT," AND " LITERARY INTERPRETATION " 34? J: Boston, U.S.A., and London GINN & COMPANY, PUBLISHERS Cbe fttbnuram Press 1807 Dec. ie- 1&C l Copyright, 1889 By ARNOLD TOMPKINS Copyright, 1897 By ARNOLD TOMPKINS ALL RIGHTS RESERVED INTRODUCTION. Kl" Man continually speaks or writes, reads or gives audi- ence. Rhetoric deals with all these universal and lifelong processes; hence, its practical importance is obvious and emphatic. This study, however, got its name from the one exercise of speaking — from the Greek rhetor, speaker — because, in the political life of the Greeks, so much depended on the art of public address. If this study should be named now, and after the most effective means of formal communication, the term would come from reading or writing; and it would not matter which, as each presupposes the other. But we care now nothing for the name except to insist, in obedience to the demands of both life and logic, on its extension over all phases of the discourse process. Until quite recently it has been customary to organize this subject under the literal meaning of the word, attaching it to the chair of oratory in college and confining its prac- tical value to those engaged in public address. Thus, as with the Greeks and Romans, it became the hidden art of the few by which fickle masses were to be swayed. But now it is not so much the swaying of masses that is needed as masses who can critically estimate and appreciate the utterances of others. And these utterances are compara- tively seldom made now in the form of public address, but in that of the book, the newspaper, and the magazine. IV INTRODUCTION. Practical life demands the art of discourse in every phase of its process, and the interest of logic as well as life is sub- served by the discussion in unity of all phases of the proc- ess. Guiding truth in any one can be found only in the unity of all. The distinction between speaking and writing, and also between reading and giving audience, is one of form and instrument, and involves no valid principle; and the four processes reduce to two, — the process of interpreting and that of constructing discourse. The principles controlling one of these processes control also the other. In fact, dis- course is grounded in the relation of constructer and inter- preter. He who makes discourse does so in conscious recognition of the process of interpretation, and he who interprets does so in conscious recognition of the process of construction. Discourse without both author and auditor is unthinkable. Hence, to treat one process to the exclusion of the other, as, for instance, to write a book on composition and then one on reading, would not only be bad economy, but would defeat the search for the highest guiding truth in either. It is hoped, therefore, to take care of both phases of the discourse process by a central movement in the proc- ess itself; the relation must take care of the terms related by including them. Holding, then, that the demands of life and logic must finally be the same, this book is formed under the twofold thought (i) that rhetoric is not a study for the special few who may chance to speak from the platform or at the bar, in the senate or in the pulpit, but for the mass of mankind who all need to communicate thought effectively and to interpret with accuracy and appreciation ; that whatever be the vocation or profession of the student, discourse in all phases of its process remains a constant necessity to him, INTRODUCTION. V however variable to his needs other subjects may be ; and (2) that the most practical results follow from holding the obverse phases of the discourse process into the unity of a single discussion, thus giving skill in all phases while reach- ing more deeply for the principle controlling each. If any one phase of discourse study should have promi- nence above another, it is that of literary interpretation. The school does not exist for what it can do for the pupil while he is simply a pupil, but for what it can influence him, by self-direction and self-propulsion, to do for himself after the days of formal tuition. And no opportunity of the teacher is, perhaps, so great as that of influencing the pupil through an appreciation of good literature to read through life to his soul's salvation. Rhetoric must influence strongly in this direction by making the pupil conscious of, and sensi- tive to, the elements of beauty in literary productions. Lit- erature is rapidly gaining its place in the high school course, and everywhere teachers are asking how to make the most of it. It is hoped that the following discussion may aid in the solution. To this end much attention has been given to the principles and practice of literary analysis, which is also theoretically, as well as practically, proper; for beauty, while an essential element in all discourse, is its highest out- come and crowning glory. While urging strongly that rhetoric should bear its fruit — that it should take possession of the pupil's life for the future and not be finished and put on the shelf as having no relation to life — it must not be supposed that the treatment is necessarily unscientific, a mere collection of rules and recipes, such as is generally found in so-called practical and elementary books on the subject. The more closely organ- ized becomes the discourse process in thought, the more efficient becomes the theory in practice. It would be strange VI INTRODUCTION. indeed if theory and practice, science and art, should prove mutually repellant, as so much talk which opposes theory and practice implies. The more perfect one's construction in thought, the more perfect may be his practice under guid- ance of that thought. While art precedes science, it is only through science that art maybe perfected; hence, art is made effective by perfecting the science. Besides, the scientific treatment is the only elementary one. The rule and recipe treatment cannot excuse itself on the plea of making the subject easy. A subject may be shunned successfully, but it cannot be simplified without scientific coordination. If the subject is to be made easy as well as practical, it must be reduced to an organized, coherent body of knowledge. And if this were not true, even the high-school pupil is not a child and must put away child- ish things. Not at all that I should expect or care that he be conscious of scientific experience, but that he should have the experience without reflecting on it. He must see, or see nothing, the relation of unity among the elements of his subject-matter. In studying rhetoric the pupil usually accepts obediently anything and everything in the serial order put down for him; would accept as many more or as many less in any order in which they might be served up. Discourse, real living discourse, is not such a hodge-podge, and the sooner he finds it out the better, both for ease in knowing and power in practice. What is needed is not dodging, but simple, full, concrete, and organic statement. This book is therefore an effort to enable the pupil to see discourse as it unfolds from a single principle, and to prac- tise constructing and interpreting it under that principle. He must become aware that all is determined from within, and not a mere matter of external legislation by some rheto- rician. Experience has proved that so much a high-school INTRODUCTION. Vll pupil can do, and it needs no argument to convince one that such organic grasp of, and specific insight into, the subject is the only economic way to an efficient practice in the con- struction or interpretation of discourse. Whatever the result, such is the earnest conviction which prompts the following treatment, and which accounts for the deviation from the beaten path of rhetorical discussion. *> PREFATORY NOTE. 3637 This book is based on a former publication by the author, under the same title. The former treatment was dominated by a pedagogical motive, which, for the present purpose, required so complete a rewriting that this work can scarcely be called a revision of the former. The spirit of scientific coordination, however, which prompted the old is the ruling spirit in the new, so that I can say now as I did then : — " Whatever the result of the effort, this book has been written under the conviction that a more strictly scientific treatment of discourse is possible than has yet been made, and which would, therefore, yield a higher discipline and a more fruitful application in the art than usually results from discourse study." Much valuable assistance has been received from the leading Rhetorics, and, when of a nature to permit, formal credit has been given in the text. Special credit should be given to C. C. Everett's " Science of Thought " and to Herbert Spencer's " Essay on the Philosophy of Style," the former having direct influence on my treatment of "The Thought in Discourse," and the latter on "The Language in Discourse." ARNOLD TOMPKINS. Department of Pedagogy; University of Illinois. Champaign, Illinois, Feb. 5, 1897. CONTENTS. PAGE INTRODUCTION iii THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE i THE SUBJECT-MATTER BOUNDED .... I THE ORGANIC ELEMENTS 8 THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE 13 EFFICIENT MEANS TO A WORTHY END - "13 CONDITIONS OF EFFECTIVENESS - - - - 19 The Author or the Interpreter Himself - 19 A Sincere Purpose ------ 24 A Definite Purpose - - - - • - 31 THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE 41 the theme 41 the discourse processes .... 53 Description - 61 attributive description - - - - 62 By Attributes of Relation ----- 62 By Means of its Properties - - - - - 70 PARTITIVE DESCRIPTION 75 THE PROCESS ILLUSTRATED 8 1 Construction - - ----- 81 Interpretation ------ 86 Xii CONTENTS. PAGE Narration 93 THE CHANGE AS A WHOLE 96 Purpose --------- 96 Time - - 96 Cause and Effect ------- 97 Likeness and Difference - - ... 97 THE CHANGE IN ITS PARTS 98 THE PROCESS ILLUSTRATED 103 Construction - - - - - - - - 103 Interpretation 106 Exposition 11 1 the content of the theme ii3 Definition - - - - - - - _II 3 Comparison and Contrast - - - - - 117 Exemplification - - - - - - -118 Idealization - ------ 120 THE EXTENT OF THE THEME 1 23 Division - - - - - - - - 124 THE PROCESS ILLUSTRATED 1 28 Construction - - - - - - -128 Definition - 128 Comparison and Contrast - - - -129 Exemplification - - - 130 Division - - 13° Interpretation - 132 Argumentation - 137 the relation of whole and part- - - - i3s Deduction 139 Law of Deductive Inference 140 Induction - - - - - - • - 14 1 Law of Inductive Inference 142 THE RELATION OF CAUSE AND EFFECT - - - I46 A Priori Arguments - - - - - - 148 Law of Inference from Cause - - - 149 A Posteriori Arguments - - • - - - 152 Laws of I nferetice from Effect - - - - 154 CONTENTS. Xlll PAGE GENERAL LAWS OF ARGUMENTATION - - - l6o The Law of Purpose 160 The Law of Unity - - - - - 163 THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE - - - 171 ITS FUNDAMENTAL LAW - - - - - 17 1 QUALITIES REQUIRED BY THE LAW - - - 174 Clearness - - 177 Energy - ...... iyg Elegance 182 CONDITIONS FOR SECURING THE QUALITIES - - 185 Conditions for Securing Clearness - - 185 Conditions for Securing Energy - - 191 Conditions for Securing Elegance - - - 194 THE RHETORICAL QUALITIES SECURED - •- - I96 LANGUAGE AS AN OBJECT OF PERCEPTION - 1 98 Correctness - - - - - - - -199 Distinctness . . . . - - - 199 Brevity - - - 200 Euphony .... - - 202 Harmony ........ 207 Rhythm 211 THE DIRECT RELATION OF LANGUAGE TO THOUGHT 221 ASSOCIATION OF LANGUAGE FORM WITH IDEAS - 222 Eamiliarity - - - - - - -222 Concreteness - - - - 230 Precision ........ 234 ORGANIZATION OF THE IDEAS INTO THOUGHT - 24I Conciseness ----- - 241 The Proper Length of the Sentence - - - 249 The Proper Arrangement of the Sentence - - 255 Unity of Sentence Structure - 262 Unity in the Discourse Structure - 278 THE INDIRECT RELATION OF LANGUAGE TO THOUGHT 284 FIGURES OF SPEECH - ... 289 Figures of Spelling - - ... 290 Figures of Syntax • - 291 XIV CONTENTS. PAGE FIGURES OF THOUGHT 295 Figures of Association ...... 299 Synecdoche ........ 300 Metonymy - ...... 302 Figures of Comparison ...... 304 Expressed Comparison 307 Implied Comparisons - ... 309 Metaphor 309 Allegory 318 Figures of Contrast ...... 323 Expressed Contrast - - - - - - 323 Implied Contrast - - - - - - 325 EXERCISE IN CLASSIFYING AND TESTING FIGURES - 329 CONCLUSION --- - - - 335 UNIVERSAL OUTLINE OF DISCOURSE - 336 UNIVERSAL OUTLINE FOR PRACTICE - - - 337 ANALYSIS OF "THE RAINY DAY" - '33^ THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. The Subject-Matter Bounded. The science of discourse, or rhetoric, is one of a large group of language studies ; some of which are orthography, orthoepy, lexicography, grammar, composi- tion, reading, linguistics, and literature. In a general way these all have the same subject-matter — language ; but each is restricted to a given view or phase of it. Yes, view or phase, since each subject is not re- stricted to a part ; for each study covers the entire extent of language. Either spelling, pronunciation, or definition of words extends to the whole of language. Grammar is the grammar of the whole ; and all lan- guage is composed, and is supposed to be read. Lin- guistics includes the entire organized framework of language as an instrument of expressing thought ; and literature the whole of thought which animates such organized framework. Thus the entire territory of language is claimed by each language study. Rhetoric has no corner which it can call its own ; but must work the whole field over in its own way. What way ? 2 THE SCIENCE OE DISCOURSE. Language divides itself into the very obvious parts, words, sentences, and discourse. These are the lan- guage units ; and it would seem that language studies should be parted off to deal with each separately. And so they are, to a certain extent ; for we have word studies — orthography, orthoepy, and lexicography ; a sentence study — grammar; discourse studies — com- position, reading, rhetoric, and literature. But with- out naming all, we have several more studies than units ; and, what is worse, grammar and discourse studies deal with words and sentences. Any unit is not confined to one study, nor any study to one unit. This appears strange ; for the language studies can do nothing but deal with the language units. Why do they seesaw in this way ? The trouble arises from catching up the wrong language unit ; or rather, from seizing the unity at the wrong point. We are accustomed to think of words as parts which added together make sentences ; sentences as parts which added together make discourse ; and dis- courses as parts which added together make literature. This addition seems most proper; yet words may be added all day long without producing a sentence ; and sentences, without producing discourse. If literature is not produced before discourses are added, there will be none after the addition ; and if there is not a dis- course before sentences are added the addition will avail nothing. The difference between these language units is not primarily nor essentially that of length. If so we should be inclined to ask, How long must a language THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. 3 piece be made before it becomes a sentence or a dis- course ? If two sentences put together make a discourse, then, if addition of sentences be the test, one hundred sentences would make a superb oration, and one thousand an immortal poem. No ; men have made great speeches in single sentences, long or short ; and good sentences, yea, speeches out of single words. You remember this : "We have met the enemy and they are ours " ; and Caesar's famous effort, " Veni, vidi, vici " ; and " Peace, be still." And either " Peace " or " Vici " would have made a first-rate discourse by itself. The point is that these language units are not such with reference to each other, but with reference to what each expresses. They are the true language units ; not because they refer back and forth to each other as whole and part, but because each expresses a unit of consciousness, — a mental act or state. Each faces its own content and not its neighbor. The true parts of language cannot be obtained by cross-section- ing, but by a division between form and content, — between the letter and the spirit. To show the point exactly, suppose you are now, in your first recitation in rhetoric, laughing outright at the idea of beginning so delightful a study ; and the teacher, to restore proper class dignity, exclaims, " Hush ! " Is he using a word, a sentence, or a dis- course ? Look in the dictionary, and you will find it as a word ; grammar declares it to be a sentence ; while rhetoric maintains it to be a discourse, good or bad depending on whether you do what the word expresses. If the language-form "hush" is thought of simply in THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. relation to its idea, its action, it is a word ; if in relation to its thought, its triple unity of subject, predicate, and thinking act, it is a sentence ; if viewed in relation to its effect on the mind, causing to hush, then it is a dis- course — good if it accomplished the purpose ; bad if it further provoked the laughing. In each case it is the same material unit, but it becomes a different language unit as we turn it from an idea to a thought, or to an effect. The unity is not in the mere language form, but in the relation of the form and its spirit. If language were mere form, then the material juncture of parts would decide the question in any case ; but language is the relation of form and content, and the units are to be selected out of this relation. Since the same language form exists in more than one relation at the same time the same form may be classed differently, as attention is fixed on this or that relation. A man may be a governor, a churchman, a father, a mason, a merchant, etc., at the same time and without violence to his unity ; and when our attention is fixed on one of these relations he is a governor, or a father, etc. A language form considered in relation to an idea is called a word, if the parts are fixed ; if movable, a phrase. The very same language form put in relation to the three elements of a thought, subject, predicate, and copula, is classed as a sentence ; and if studied in relation to the change it is to make in the mind addressed, it becomes a discourse. In discourse there is always an auditor, a recipient, in relation to whom the language is to be considered ; but in the study of language as words, phrases, and sentences, the relation THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. 5 is within the language itself, between its outside and its inside. Discourse study does not separate between form and thought ; but holds both in unity to an end which lies beyond them. The primary law of words and sentences is that of correctness ; the form must be the established form for expressing a given idea or thought. But correct forms are not ends in themselves ; they are only means to effective utterance, in supplying the composer with all the possible ways of expression. Rhetoric selects out of the many forms the one which, under the circum- stances, will be most effective. While there are many ways of expressing the same thing, there is but one of them best suited to a specific end under specific conditions. Shakespeare had Macbeth say, when his conscience was stinging him after the murder of Duncan, " Duncan is in his grave ; after life's fitful fever he sleeps well." This can be said in forty ways to the satisfaction of the dictionary and grammar ; but only one is adequate to Shakespeare's purpose. He might have had Macbeth say, " Duncan died recently ; I still live ; but he is better off than I, for he does not suffer so much " ; or " Duncan is dead and buried ; hav- ing passed the tribulations of life, nothing now annoys him, but my conscience hurts me terribly"; and so on without limit. The rules of spelling and syntax may find no fault in all these, but rhetoric would enter its protest, and challenge the right of all but one. If, in the pos- sibilities of language, an expression can be found better than Shakespeare's he must be tried in the court of rhetoric for flagrant violation of the law of his art. 6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. We see at once how delicate and exacting is the art of rhetoric ; yet, in general estimation, one is held much more strictly accountable for violating rules of orthography, orthoepy, or syntax ; perhaps because such mistakes lie on the surface and are the more easily detected, and because it is comparatively easy to avoid the sins of formal language. Man may and should write correctly by habit and reflex action ; but none but the inspired artist can give the happy stroke ; and to apply the rhetorical test requires insight and reflection. Can we not thus account for the excessive amount of time given to the study of formal language as compared with that of living discourse ? We wish to be forewarned and forearmed against violations for which the merest schoolboy may arrest us. Yes, lan- guage ought to be correct, absolutely so ; but correct- ness is not the last word, and perhaps not the best word, which can be said about language. After being searched and quickened by a poem of Tennyson or charmed and convinced by the music and logic of Phillips, how impertinent to suggest that some long and involved sentence slipped in its syntax! Before closing up the boundary of our subject-matter, we must note that rhetoric is not the only discourse study, — that composition and reading fall within the same compass, using reading in the broad sense to include the study of literature. Composition is the art of constructing discourse ; and reading the art of inter- preting it. They are the reverse sides of the discourse process. Rhetoric investigates the principles which control in the process of constructing and interpreting THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. 7 discourse. Both processes are controlled by the same principles : in one case the principles operate in the direction of purpose or effect, through thought out to language ; in the other back from language, through thought, to the purpose or effect of the discourse, — the first as synthesis, the second as analysis. Composi- tion and reading are simply applied rhetoric ; and both subjects must be held together in a common principle throughout our discussion. Discourse is an interesting and profitable topic considered as mere theory, if this be possible ; but its practical value becomes imperative when we consider that we are constantly making or interpreting discourse, — talking, writing, or speaking; or listening or reading. Especially does its value appear in the higher processes of composing and of reading. One cannot write or speak with assurance and effect without a consciousness of guiding laws ; neither can he read with appreciation without a knowl- edge of the rhetorical elements constituting literary discourse. Since composing and reading are but rhetoric in practice, there is but one discourse study, having its two phases of science and art, or theory and practice. Hence rhetoric is not excluded from any part of the territory of discourse, that is, language in its adapta- tion to the purposes of utterance ; only this : rhetoric cannot practice while it is preaching, although it must practice what it is preaching. 8 the science of discourse. The Organic Elements. In getting our fingers firmly around the subject-mat- ter we have necessarily felt of the organic elements. Discourse, in producing an effect on another mind, uses ideas as a means, and language as a medium. We have already noticed that in words and sentences as such, there is the distinction between form and meaning ; and that in discourse this form and mean- ing are not consciously separated, but move together in producing the effect. If words may be defined as language forms expressing ideas, and sentences as lan- guage forms expressing thought, then a discourse may be defined as a language form expressing thought in the process of producing a definite change in some mind addressed. The ideas presented are the direct means to the end, while the language is chiefly means to the ideas, and therefore indirect means to the purpose. Such, then, are the organic elements. Discourse can- not exist without either, nor unless they cooperate in a definite order. In writing a discourse, the author is first prompted by a desire to put another mind in a certain condition ; then he orders his thoughts to that end ; after which he clothes them in language. This order cannot be reversed. Of course the impulse to produce the change is not dropped to work out the matter of the discourse and express it properly ; for all of this workmanship to the end sought must be done under the moving and shaping force of the desire to reach the end. In fact, in the stress of composition the author is not conscious that he uses language, THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. 9 being wholly occupied and moved as the recipient is to be occupied and moved. This explains what was said at the outset ; namely, that a language form has its unity in the fact that it expresses a unity of conscious- ness. The unity of consciousness in discourse is the moving impulse which shapes discourse to its end. While it has three elements, two are absorbed in the other, — in a consciousness of the end to be realized. In reading, the language element comes first, and then the thought appears ; after which the effect is produced. Yet they do not occur ' this way in an order of time but in an order in which each conditions the other. We cannot realize the thought except in and while perceiving the language, and no effect is produced except in and while gaining the thought. So far as time is concerned, language, thought, and effect move abreast as organically one. Language can- not be received before the thought, as its perception consists in conceiving the thought ; and the thought cannot precede the effect, for the effect is in receiving the thought. In reading, one cannot survey the lan- guage throughout, and then go back and review the thought, and finally receive the effect which the dis- course is to stand for. But after a reader has realized the change which the thought and language are adapted to produce in him, then, if he should turn to make a critical estimate of the discourse he surveys it in the order of its composi- tion. In coming upon a strange machine, the observer makes such a survey of it as will indicate to him its purpose, for instance, to sew with. His attention IO THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. now rests on the point at which the sewing is done, and from that point outward he reconstructs the ma- chine in the order of its invention. Thus the reader moves inward to the point that moved the writer, and then, if he make a critical estimate of the discourse, he must move outward with the author in the process of construction. And really in the ordinary process of reading for what the discourse contains, and not for purpose of estimating the discourse, — for instance, as a child would read, — the purpose, the motive, in the discourse first occupies the recipient. The child feels first, last, and all the time the life in what he reads or hears ; he does not know, if able to read with ease, that language is involved in the process. He lives in an immediate consciousness of what moved the writer to utterance. Survey the matter as. we please and we are driven at last to put down as the established order in the dis- course movement, the purpose or motive, the matter, and then the language. At least this is the only order in which a discussion of discourse can move ; no esti- mate or analysis can be made of thought and language until the specific aim is ascertained. But it must be remembered that the separation of elements and the order of discussion is a necessity for the purpose of discussion only; that in the actual discourse itself they move together as a unity of life, thought and language being gathered up and fused in an experience in the writer to be reproduced in the reader. The organic relation of the elements in discourse appears clearly in comparing discourse with other ob- THE ORGANIZING PRINCIPLE. I I jects. Discourse is like all other objects in expressing thought. The tree, the mountain, the sky, the rain- bow, all say something to us when we look upon them. " To him who in the love of nature holds Communion with her visible forms, she speaks A various language." Likewise with the forms of man's creation ; the bridge, the engine, the statue, the cathedral speak a language to him who holds communion with them. But while all objects express thought, all do not exist for that purpose. The street car is the embodi- ment of thought and must express it ; but its work is to carry passengers. A house manifests the thought of the builder ; but its use is to live in. Some objects, however, are not only like discourse in expressing thought but in existing for that very end. The Angelus and the Statue of Liberty exist for the sole purpose of speaking to man. The ship expresses thought incidentally ; the flag that floats over it, on purpose. Thus discourse falls within a large number of things having for their purpose the expression of thought ; it expresses thought to com- municate it, as do all the fine-art forms, architecture, sculpture, painting, and music. But discourse is cut out from all of these by the peculiar form through which its thought is expressed — language. In the other forms of expression there is some natural resemblance or symbolic property ; but language is purely arbitrary, which is both its loss and its gain. If one should express the thought of a house 12 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. by sculpture, drawing, or painting, the resemblance of these forms to the real house would express the thought, without previous preparation on the part of the observer. But if the word house should be pre- sented to one for the first time it would fail to com- municate the idea house ; there is nothing in its nature to do so. Hence we say that it is an arbitrary symbol. Of course printed language, being a degenerate form of picture writing, did in that form naturally express its object ; as perhaps did spoken language at one time. They no doubt lost their natural character and assumed the conventional in the effort of man to express his thought more effectively. Thus the purpose of dis- course has shaped its instrument through the ages, as it immediately shapes it in each particular discourse. Discourse, then, connects itself with every other object in the universe, words and sentences included, in the fact of expressing thought, or having meaning. It lifts itself out of the universe of objects, with the exception of a small group, by the fact of existing for the sole purpose of communicating thought. It now separates itself from the small group by communicating its thought through the arbitrary symbol of language. C Discourse may, therefore, be defined as the expression of \thought in language for the purpose of communication. Thus is bounded the field of our further study, with a guiding map of the territory, purpose in discourse ; thought in discourse ; language or style in discourse. Thus appears the organizing principle of our science ; nam el v, the effective expression of thought in language to a definite, worthy aim. THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. Efficient Means to a Worthy End. Discourse, like any other instrument, must be studied in its adaptation to the end sought ; and is estimated to have merit in proportion to its efficiency as a means to a worthy end. Hence purpose or effect in discourse is the only standard by which it can be measured, as well as the only motive by which it can be produced. Discourse, being a means to an end, stands between two minds, one of which produces the discourse while the other is affected by it. The effect of the discourse in the mind of the reader is the cause of the discourse .in the mind of the writer. While skating produces pleasure, pleasure produces skating ; that is, pleasure in idea produces the skating which brings the pleasure in reality. Pleasure is both cause and effect in the skat- ing. Exercise causes health, but health, in idea, causes the exercise. Speed in locomotion produces the train, and the train produces speed in locomotion. Thus everything man produces, as an engine, a palace, or a poem, moves in a circle from end in idea to end as reality. Likewise a discourse stands between the effect held in idea by the author and the effect produced in the reader or hearer. When one calls to his friend, " See 14 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the rainbow ! " it is because he wishes his friend to have the same rainbow delight which charms himself. This effect held in mind produces the discourse, " See the rainbow"; and this discourse realizes the delight in the one addressed. If one announce that the French President has resigned, it is because he desires the idea which he entertains to be entertained by others. The following lines stand between the heart- break which Tennyson held in mind and the heart- break which he desired to produce in the reader : — " And the stately ships go on To their haven under the hill ; But oh for the touch of a vanished hand, And the sound of a voice that is still ! " Thus a writer or a speaker idealizes an effect desired in another mind, -and under this guidance and impulse constructs the discourse which realizes the effect. The reader or hearer is also striving to make real the same effect. The end of constructing a discourse and of in- terpreting it are in a sense the same, — are to bring the two minds, through discourse, into the same idea, sentiment, or volition. This is suggested by the word interpretation, whose root meaning is to declare be- tween. An interpreter stands between the speaker and the hearer and aids in bringing their minds into unity. With the composer, the effort is to bring the interpreter into a given thought ; and with the inter- preter the effort is to bring himself into the same thought. Discourse is a means to the unity of two minds in the same thought ; which common thought is THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 1 5 the purpose of the discourse both to the author and to the interpreter. Hence discourse has it purpose to the reader or auditor as well as to the writer or speaker. It would be as vain to read as to write without a purpose ; in either case the discourse is used for a purpose. It is possible for the reader to use a discourse for another purpose than that for which the author intended it ; as an instrument designed for one purpose may often be serviceable for another. In fact it is sometimes claimed that a reader cannot know the purpose of an author ; but the reader can know what effect a given discourse produces on himself, and to him this effect is the purpose of the discourse, being that for which he uses the discourse. We attribute as purpose to the author what we find to be the effect of the discourse in ourselves. We should be much surprised to find the practical outcome of a discourse to be one thing, as tested by our experience in reading it, and to learn from the testimony of the author that he had intended something entirely different. But what is worse, it is claimed that in the case of a poet he has no purpose ; that he but sings as the linnet, and speaks in numbers because the numbers come. If the urgency to utter- ance is so strong as to obliterate consciousness of an objective effect, this does not prove that the composi- tion seeks no objective end ; that it has no use either to the author or the interpreter. And if in such cases the spontaneous outbreak adapts the. discourse without the usual course of patient planning, so much the more credit to the inspiration of purpose. l6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Be this as it may, all such self-forgetful frenzy of in- spiration is quite exceptional ; and the ordinary writer must still set up a definite aim to be realized, and use the most diligent care in adapting his discourse to the end set up. If this were not so every discourse would be a chance product, lawless and irresponsible ; quite apart from our ordinary experience of sequence in cause and effect and the adjustment of means to end. When it is claimed that there is no science of literary discourse, it must be assumed that there is no cer- tainty as to the effect produced in different minds ; and no necessary connection between design and ac- complishment. In such uncertainty the speaker be- fore an audience on the Fourth of July, designing to produce an inspiration of patriotism, might instead, by chance, arouse base passions of spoils and anarchy, or the delightful experience of an ocean voyage. The writer of a great poem designing to exalt religious faith might instead produce skepticism and despair, or the joy of moonlight scenery. Milton wrote "Paradise Lost," but to the reader it might happen to be " Para- dise Regained." Now, let any number of people read the "Psalm of Life," the "Barefoot Boy," " Ivanhoe," or the "Nineteenth Psalm," and all will report sub- stantially the same impression ; and the fuller and the more accurate the comprehension of the selection the more nearly will there be confessed unity of effect, and the more pronounced the conviction that the author knew what he was about in the writing. We are often warned of the danger of reading into a discourse more than the writer put into it ; and it is THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 1 7 possible, and sometimes indulged in, to strain after hidden meanings and subtle analogies quite apart from the main line of the author's movement ; yet the real danger lies in not reading out of the discourse the full meaning of the author. Some say that Shakespeare did not intend what people accredit to him ; but if so he must have credit still for a wonderful knack of sue:- gesting to other people what he himself did not think of. Admitting for the exceptional few the habit of outdoing Shakespeare, Goethe, Dante, and the like, yet most need fear only limping behind their leader. In any case the reader must get out of the discourse all there is in it for him ; and an author may well re- ceive full credit, be it for good luck or wise design. If the reader can fairly read the universe out of the writing it is only fair to suppose that the universe somehow got into it by the hand of the writer. How- ever this may be, the reading world will continue to class certain writings as masterpieces on the basis of the breadth and depth of the effect produced ; and the authors of such writings as masters because, by con- scious or unconscious wisdom, they planned and execu- ted them. The highest effect is not always desired, and dis- course is good if it reach the end sought, whether it be the passing information of conversation or the most powerful influence in the field of thought, art, or elo- quence. So that while discourse is judged in effective- ness to the end sought, it cannot be indifferent to the kind of end sought. In the first place, the end must be a worthy one. A discourse may be well adapted 1 8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. to produce a bad effect, which considered merely in its adaptation to the end desired is a good discourse, but a bad one when taken in its entirety. A boot- black can excel a prime minister in saying some things effectively, but might fall far below him in the value of the thing said and the change wrought in the mind addressed. To merit rhetorical consideration a dis- course must have good moral character. But within this scope, the value of the effect produced is the abso- lute standard of rhetorical criticism. Compare the Sermon on the Mount with, " It snowed yesterday, and to-day the sleighing is good." Both are well adapted to the end sought, but differ infinitely in the effect produced. Thus effectiveness may be considered merely as a quality of the means used, or as a quality of the change produced in the mind addressed. It is possible to approve and admire the finished oration and at the same time condemn its effect on the audience. In fact, the efficient and fascinating means may be the very instruments for beguiling unwary auditors into the acceptance of vicious theories and the adoption of an evil course of conduct. The demagogue needs to use more attractive and, in a sense, more effective means than does a statesman. But rhetorical laws must hold discourse responsible for more than mere efficiency to an indifferent or evil result. The effi- ciency of a discourse is measured by its real value to the mind addressed. If the tendency is evil, the greater the effectiveness the worse for the discourse. Hence effectiveness is measured both by the qua) THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 19 ity and the quantity of the change produced in the mind of the recipient. At least rhetorical skill which conflicts with ethical laws is to be reprobated rather than praised. Vile literature deserves no considera- tion from the rhetorician, further than a public scourg- ing from an outraged moral sense. Discourse, by efficient means, must seriously and honestly seek a worthy aim — must seek to produce a change in the mind addressed for the good of that mind. Hence effectiveness, announced at the outset as the ultimate law of discourse, when properly limited becomes an efficiency which includes the end, and as the law now stands it requires that discourse be an efficient means to a worthy end. It is not only a question of saying the thing well, but whether the thing said is worth saying and what degree of worth can it claim. Before dismissing this topic it would be well for the student, by way of further illustration and emphasis, to compare the value of a wide variety of discourses from the recent conversation and current newspaper topic to the sermon, the poem, and the political J oration. Conditions of Effectiveness. From the foregoing the prime condition of effective- ness is obvious at once as, — The Author or the Interpreter Himself. — No one can write beyond himself, — produce an effect deeper, truer, and more potent than his own life. The com- pass and power of a writer limit absolutely the com- 20 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. pass and power of the writing. To prepare to speak and write with influence involves the whole problem of character and culture, as Ouintilian well under- stood in relation to the orator ; for in his " Institutes of Oratory" he treats comprehensively the whole sub- ject of education, emphasizing continually that the orator is first a wise and virtuous man. As he keeps the man back of the orator, so must the man be kept back of effective speech of whatever purpose. Wealth of knowledge and conviction of duty are vastly more essential to purposes of effective utterance than are laws of syntax and rhetoric. One cannot become a journalist by studying rules of editorial style and journ- alism. This can be accomplished only by a long course of training to alert and comprehensive thought, and to the power of a quick application of a sound political and social philosophy to everyday life. It is charac- ter, wisdom, and wealth of life, and not homiletics, which fit for pulpit eloquence. The study of poetics cannot supply the inspiration and inner grasp of things necessary to poetic construction. Skill in speaking and writing come riot by application of rhetorical devices, but by a full, active, and versatile life. The metaphor is a good rhetorical instrument, but it must be born in the writing and not made and applied to it. In the stress of composition and in the exigency of the moment the figure springs forth winged for its flight and charged with its message. Weighty and forcible utterance cannot be gotten at from the outside, but spring from the weight and force of the life which makes the utterance. The THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 21 whole character and life are necessary to each fit word and sentence ; and to that finer rhetorical, stamp which gives them currency as universal as life. Milton said that for him to write an epic poem required that he make his life an epic poem. Not out of rhetorical maxims but out of the heart the mouth speaketh. The student must, therefore, not come to the task of seeking skill in discourse with any hope of reaching it by specific and short-cut methods ; but by that profound and universal preparation which takes care of all the issues of life. Often the young man with a meagre education, but with ambition for a literary career, seeks a special course in rhetoric and literature, expecting to be shown the knack of successful writing and speaking ; just as the illiterate novice in elocution seeks the tricks and finishing touches for pronounc- ing literary masterpieces by attendance on a school of oratory ; or as a barren soul vainly hopes, by a knowledge of notes and practice of nimble touches on the key-board, to compose symphonies and conduct orchestras. What is really needed is a deep, an all-sided culture. Mathematics, science, history, and the wealth of the world's literature must store the life and illumine the soul for any special literary task which the writer may undertake. Rhetorical study has its special function ; but that excessive faith in its precepts which leads to neglect of universal culture as the true source of rhetorical power will defeat the true aim of rhetoric itself. Quintilian says that Cicero " frequently de- clares that he owed less to the schools of the rhetori- 22 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. cians than to the gardens of the Academy." Let the pupil but consider how much and what kind of preparation it required to write one of Swing's or Beecher's sermons, Lincoln's Gettysburg Speech, Washington's Farewell Address, Lowell's " Vision of Sir Launfal," or Wordsworth's " Ode on the Intima- tions of Immortality." Out of what rhetoric did these come ? They embody the culture and tension of the age, rather than the age's rhetorical maxims. Yes, " The orator is the good man skilled in speaking "; and skill itself is the man's speaking. In further descrip- tion of the orator Ouintilian speaks of him as "a man who, being possessed of the highest natural genius, stores his mind thoroughly with the most valuable kinds of knowledge ; a man sent by the gods to do honor to the world, and such as no preceding age has known ; a man in every way eminent and excel- lent, a thinker of the best thoughts and a speaker of the best words." No one can be a speaker of the best words who is not a thinker of the best thoughts. And just as discourse of worthy effect can spring only from a soul of wealth and worth, so it can be adequately interpreted and appreciated by the same general qualifications. The art of literary criticism, i.e. the art of estimating rather than fault-finding, is not the application of specific rules to a production, but the reception of its effect into the life of the critic, and its ideal reproduction from the standpoint and basis of life from which it was produced, with the added experience of its value. The problem is, how the production arises out of and returns to life, and THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 23 the consequent value of the process. Since the critic must speak to the value of the selection he must have the refinement and compass of life to reexperience the author's life embodied in the selection. The small critic can do no better than to attack details here and there, with this or that rhetorical weapon which he has learned to apply under the name of criticism ; but such is not the process of that discourse-inter- pretation which brings the value of the production home to the reader. Hence it is evident that all that has been said touching the prime condition of effect- ive discourse applies equally to the author and to the interpreter. Of course there is a difference in the capacity required for the details of execution in the two cases ; but the fundamental basis of operation in life is the same in each. Discourse cannot be effective without the adequate reception of its mes- sage, any more than without the adequate presentation of that message. Effective discourse implies some one susceptible to the effect. The writer demands qualified readers as strongly as the reader demands qualified writers. It must not be supposed that this general require- ment of culture on the part of both reader and writer makes discourse unnecessary, by rendering the writer unable to advance the interests of the reader. The help comes to the reader through the writer's ad- vanced position in the particular thought and sen- timent of the discourse under construction. In a particular case, the writer must keep in advance of his reader. He may have to raise himself to the full 24 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. height of his ability to do so ; or he may need, as when addressing the immature in thought, to lower himself within their reach ; but in all cases he must keep in advance on the particular line of his investiga- tion, and more elevated in any sentiment he would arouse. In fact the greater the inequality between the reader and the writer in any particular selection of discourse the better, so long as vain or wasteful effort is not required in the process of interpretation. There has grown up a sentimental prejudice against difficult books, giving preference to those which may be perused in the relaxed mood of the hammock. Real reading requires energy ; and the best books are those which challenge effort, and merit frequent and prolonged study. Yet the original proposition holds, that man, born into the world of literature, to receive the most of it, needs the most varied and thorough culture. As with the writer, the greater the reader's breadth and depth of culture the more effective does discourse become. Coming now to the task of a particular composition, with volume and force of life in general, the author must be moved in each production by A Sincere Purpose. — We have already observed that the effect in the mind addressed is the true cause of the discourse ; and sincerity of purpose re- quires that the effect to be produced in the mind addressed for the good of that mind be the sole impulse to the utterance. The motive must be un- alloyed with any feeling of self ; as when one is THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 25 moved to speak by a desire to appear before an audience, to display learning and power of language, to excel another speaker, or to call forth popular applause. The assumption is, from the very nature of discourse, that the purpose is the effect in the mind of the hearer, for the benefit of the hearer. The moment the reader or hearer feels that the author is making the discourse with reference to himself, the discourse at once loses its power. For this reason the pronoun I should be used warily and sparingly. It is bad taste for a speaker to play a part in illustrative incidents and stories, when his own personality is not essential to the illustration. He should not state, for instance, that he while visiting Rome found the Coliseum in such and such condition, assuming that the point of in- terest with his audience is not the condition of the Coliseum, but the fact that the speaker has traveled and has seen Rome and the Coliseum. He must not thrust himself in between his audience and the object he describes. This does not prevent a speaker or writer from presenting his own experience when that is the topic called for ; but the temptation to get into the foreground of the discussion must be silenced. It is a safe rule for the composer to keep himself out of the discourse altogether, assuming that the audience are interested only in the topic under discussion and not in him. Should he himself become the interesting topic, as when a famous man is called upon to give an account of himself, the case is different ; for then he is the theme of the discourse. But those who need to 26 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. guard themselves most are least apt to be called upon for self-explanation. Instead of uttering the thought for the mind ad- dressed, as the law of purpose requires, consciously or unconsciously, the language and the thought are frequently deformed into affectation of style, than which nothing is more offensive to good taste and to good morals. " Affectation creates caricatures of beauty ; these repel taste as they repel good sense. That cast of character which leads a young man to wear long hair and to part it in the middle often appears in literature in a straining after the feminine qualities of style when no beauty of thought underlies and demands them. This nauseates short-haired men and lends reason to their prejudice against the genuine because of the counterfeit elegance." 1 A natural style cannot be produced without an ab- sorbing interest in the aim of the discourse. Pretense will unconsciously leave its mark in some undue atten- tion to the details of style. Phelps quotes the follow- ing illustration of this offense from a speech of the elder Josiah Ouincy, delivered in the American Con- gress to secure the repeal of the embargo on our com- merce laid by Great Britain in the War of 1812: — An embargo liberty was never cradled in Massachusetts. Our liberty was not so much a mountain as a sea nymph. She was as free as air. She could swim or she could run. The ocean was her cradle. Our fathers met her as she came like a goddess of beauty from the waves. They caught her as she was sporting on the beach. They courted her as she was spreading her nets on the rocks. 1 Phelps. THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 2J Phelps comments on the above thus : " In this strain the orator proceeds. Mark now the quality of this style as related to the professed aim of the whole speech. What was that aim ? The ships of the mer- chants of Boston and Salem and Newburyport and New London and New York were rotting in their harbors. The aim of the legislation advocated by Mr. Quincy was to remove the embargo, and send those ships to sea. Was his mind intent on that in the pas- sage here quoted ? Did this passage assist that aim, or could it naturally do so ? Not at all. The para- graph is vivacious ; its metaphors are novel ; its diction is compact and clear ; it is a specimen of what passed in those days for fine oratory. But it was quite too fine for the sober and rather rough work which the orator had before him. His interest just then, all the enthusiasm of his mind in the business, was expended on the embellishment of his style. He was thinking of it as a work of art. He was speaking to Harvard College and its environs, not to the Southern Con- gressmen whom it was his business to win over to the commercial interest of New England. If his own for- tunes had been embarked in one of these rotting ships, and he was intent with his whole soul on saving it by a vote of the Congress, he would have found some- thing to say more to the purpose than courting sea nymphs on the rocks." The practical object of the discourse should hold everything in control from beginning to end. What is known as natural eloquence arises from the speaker's being caught up by the inspiration, the power of an 28 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. aim. An intense aim is creative ; the result a natural growth, not mechanical contriving. Thought and lan- guage grow to and fit the striving soul within. Hence, sincerity is the secret of naturalness, the greatest charm of discourse. Thus always must the composer be controlled by the genuine impulse of the effect to be produced. The message to be delivered must be the all-absorbing con- sciousness in the delivery. One is not in condition to speak or write till he has an idea which disturbs him into utterance. The urgency of the idea — the end, the effect, the purpose — must be the informing power which orders and organizes every element of thought, and gives harmony and color to every feature of style. Every discourse, like a plant or an animal, is the prod- uct of a vital force ; and it cannot take the form of life by external carpentry. Composition is not prima- rily a putting together ; but the outgoing of a unitary impulse which divides itself into a multiplicity of ideas, thoughts, and language forms in the process of reach- ing unity again in the mind addressed. It begins and ends in unity. One cannot learn to compose by putting words together into sentences, and sentences together into paragraphs, and paragraphs together into discourse. The impelling idea creates and determines the elements and forms needed for its realization in the mind of the reader or hearer. Hence the most searching standard of criticism which can be applied to any discourse is whether it is pro- duced under the full and undivided impulse of the idea for which the discourse purports to stand. For instance, THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 20, al other standards for criticising a popular lecturer are rendered useless when it is observed that he is conscious of beautiful similes, superb gestures, of the fact that he is the lecturer of the evening, etc. Then nothing is to be expected of him but a performance, which is always disposed of by the single criticism that it is hollow and purposeless. Self-consciousness in some form, replac- ing the consciousness of the message, is a general source of weakness in all kinds of stage performers. There are plenty of exceptions to this ; but it is true to such an extent that lecture committees often avoid the employment of professionals, seeking those who are earnestly engaged in solving life's problems and in elevat- ing humanity. Efficient service comes, not from those who seem to think it a nice thing to speak in public from the stage and compose pieces for that purpose, but from those who are earnest seekers after living truth, and who are called and sent to the platform to say what needs to be said to fallen humanity. It is not strange that revolutionary and antislavery times produced or- ators. It was the rugged, earnest business in hand that made Patrick Henry and Wendell Phillips speak with tongues of fire. The secret of Moody's success lies not in any external elocution — for he has none of it — but in his simple, direct, and earnest effort to help his brother man. It is said that after Bishop Simpson had finished a sermon in Memorial Hall, London, a professor of elocution was asked by a friend what he thought of the Bishop's elocution. "Elocution," he re- plied, "that man doesn't need elocution; he's got the Holy Ghost." 30 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. This remark of the elocutionist suggests the applica- tion of the standard of genuine motive to his own art. In this there is decidedly too much reliance on ex- ternals ; and not enough, we may say, on the "Holy Ghost." Usually his choice selection is that which enables him to display his art ; and this is not the selec- tion which of itself produces the deepest and truest effect, but one which requires action, gesticulation, grimaces, contortions, and the full diapason of the vocal cords. For this purpose, the gravedigger's scene in Hamlet is much to be preferred to Portia's tribute to mercy ; and yet the latter has in it far more potency for good — more of genuine effect on the hearer; but we are most frequently favored with the former, because, perhaps, the reciter can best impress himself, if not the greater truth, upon the audience. The selection is to display his art ; not his art the selection. And such, again, is a reversal of means and end in discourse ; for what was presumably written to be a means to an end in the hearer, is used as a means to an end in the reciter. The true elocutionist understands this, and seeks artistic delivery through the merit and inspi- ration of what he delivers. His impelling motive is to make the thought and spirit of the selection go for all they are worth, not for his sake, but for their own. The musician's art is tested likewise. And thus it is in all fine-art and literary criticism ; the first standard to apply is that of a genuine motive in the production. In tracing the history of literature the student may thus part off productions into two great classes, differing more or less in the fundamental THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 3 1 requirement of discourse. Chaucer will be found to be hearty, genuine, sincere, — "so genuine that he need not ask whether he were genuine or no, so sincere as quite to forget his own sincerity." Lowell again pays Chaucer a great tribute when he says, "With Chaucer it is al- ways the thing itself and not the description of it that is the main object." Passing to Spenser, the accom- plished gentleman and scholar, a peculiar form of insincerity may be detected in his "Faery Queen." Spenser at heart was a poet, filled with fine emotions and beautiful imagery ; but in his day writings that did not carry on their face a distinct moral purpose were supposed to be idle and useless. Spenser yielded to this and tried to expound a system of ethics in a poem ; whereas, if he had been true to his own instincts and impulses his Faery Queen would have had living interest to the general reader, and not merely historic value to the antiquary. Pope said that Shakespeare did not write correctly ; and avowed his own purpose to be that of correct writing. He thus became conscious of his style and not his message ; while Shakespeare searched the heart, seemingly unconscious of his art ; yet in the mere matter of style he far excelled all the critical school which followed him, and which made style the conscious object of direct concern. Thus in all literary study, the student must make his first, most general, and most fundamental estimate in terms of the motive creating the selection. A Definite Purpose. — It has already been incident- ally stated that a composer must have, besides a sincere and worthy aim, a definite one. He must set before 32 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. himself just what he is to accomplish, and then keep the eye single to that end. And so, too, must the recip- ient come to a definite experience of the effect pro- duced ; not be satisfied with a blurred or vague general sense of what the discourse means. With the composer a definite and firm seizing of the end is absolutely essen- tial to direct and forcible movement to that end ; and unless the interpreter realize definitely and firmly what has been presented, he has missed so far the object of interpretation. Preparatory to any formal exercise the composer must test himself by such questions as : Just what end do I wish to accomplish? Exactly what impression do I wish to leave? or, Just what action do I wish to prompt? When a high-school pupil makes a choice of his graduating theme, he must be examined as to the ground of his choice. Should he choose, "Every Cloud has a Silvery Lining," or "Over the Alps lies Italy," he may find that he has been caught by something that sounds well, and that he really has no definite idea, sentiment, or conviction moving him to speech. If he does not settle this important matter at the outset he may be forced to learn as he proceeds that his "silvery lining" is only a thin film after all; and that his Italy, which lies beyond the Alps, is sure enough beyond the Alps, but what of that ? If he ex- pects to awaken only the bit of sentiment of "silvery lining" and " over the Alps," he can do no better than to announce his title on the program and retire. Like- wise the value to the interpreter must be tested by an effort to state precisely how he is affected by the selection. THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 33 The composer cannot state precisely the end sought till all the circumstances under which the effect is to be produced are known. Discourse will sometimes have to be adapted to the special experience of trades, pro- fessions, and social surroundings. Farmers, mechanics, merchants, lawyers, and teachers are each interested in and prepared to receive a special class of ideas, which would make no appeal to others. And under such limiting conditions the composer is restricted to aims in harmony with the special interests of the class addressed. But a still more widely controlling factor is the stage of mental development to be addressed. The writer may have to address children and the immature in thought, who can appreciate only the pictures of ob- jects, and these only when expressed in the simplest language ; or he may have to address those who can form classes of things and desire to find relations among objects ; or, still higher, he may have to address those who are able to search for the unity of all things, — the connection of things into a universe. That is, he may have to form popular discourse, scientific dis- course, or philosophic discourse. The composer must always mark the grade of minds addressed, and adjust himself to their experience. The farther he is removed from the grade of life addressed, the more difficult is it to make the required adaptation ; and this is impossible when he has to adapt to those above himself, — the composer can descend, but not as- cend. But adjusting to those of lower capacity is not so easily done as would appear. The difficulty of writ- 34 THE SCIENXE OF DISCOURSE. ing for children is clearly recognized ; and it arises from the distance to which the writer is necessarily removed from the experience addressed. As a rule, a philosopher cannot address a popular audience effectively. To do so he must be a pliable and skillful rhetorician, which means that he has the art of adaptation. But aside from the variable factors which limit and define the end according to circumstances, there is an invariable factor to be counted on in all audiences and under all circumstances, and which determines funda- mentally the aim and adaptation in discourse. This factor is the different powers of the mind to be affected — the intellect, the sensibility, and the will. To make any definite effect on the mind is to affect prominently one or another of these powers. This fact defines the end, making it threefold more definite than the mere idea of addressing the mind ; and gives rise to the three great classes of discourse, Prose, or didactic discourse ; Oratory, or persuasive discourse; Poetry, or literary discourse. Prose, or didactic discourse, seeks to inform the in- tellect, — to communicate to it knowledge for its own sake. This process involves the sensibility and the will, as the mind must be stimulated by desire to re- ceive the truth, and the will must make effort to appropriate it ; yet the end is the knowledge gained, and the other activities are only means thereto. Thus prose discourse is discourse adapted to the logical end of truth. It seeks to bring the mind into a knowledge of the objective world of fact ; to develop a knowl- THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 35 edge of things as they exist. Whatever the form, the discourse is didactic when it is adapted to inform the intellect as an end. Oratory, or persuasive discourse, seeks some end, through action, beyond the knowledge and feeling by which the action is stimulated. With oratory the object is not to bring the mind into conformity with the world, but to stimulate to reaction against the world, — to bring the world into conformity to some idea which the mind itself sets up. While prose seeks to give a knowledge of things as they are, oratory strives, through influencing the will, to make things what they ought to be. For instance, the composer may seek to give a knowledge of the state or of society as they at present exist ; or he may strive to give such knowledge and arouse such sentiments as will prompt to effort to make them what they should be. A writer may desire to give a knowledge of slavery for the sake of the knowl- edge ; or he may, through such knowledge, prompt to action against some form of oppression, as was once done against slavery. Railroads as they are, are not what they should be; and feeling the desirability of making them so, one may speak to prompt action to that end. In so doing, he would form an oration. An oration is based in the emotions, for these are the motives to action. No appeal can be made to the will directly. People will not choose to act by simply being asked to do so. The proper motives to action must be aroused, through the presentation of thought to the intellect. Hence, while it was stated that dis- course affects the intellect, the sensibility, and the 36 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. will, the direct effect is confined to the intellect and the sensibility ; the sensibility being addressed as means to some end reached through action, or for its own sake. Poetry, or literary discourse, awakens emotions for their own sake, and not to serve as motives to action. One may contemplate a waterfall or a landscape and find his reward in the contemplation. Hearing the song of a bird or viewing a gorgeous sunset, is justified by the emotions awakened. In all such cases the mind feels that the object is what it ought to be — that it is perfect. Poetry presents the object as if there were no collision between its ideal and its real nature. Such a view of an object awakens the esthetic emotions, rather than those emotions which prompt to effort, such as the feelings of injustice and oppression wielded by Pat- rick Henry to arouse the colonists to resist the mother country. Let it be emphasized that the distinction here drawn between the kinds of discourse is that of adaptation to an end and not that of form. Popularly speaking, an oration is something spoken, and poetry is that which is written in verse. But an oration is still an oration when printed, and a poem is still a poem when changed to the prose form, as often happens in the process of translation. A poem delivered orally does not become an oration ; and an argument for states' rights put in verse is at best only doggerel poetry. Note the fol- lowing stanzas, from a so-called poem on the discovery of America, "designed to convey instruction to the young " : — THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 37 " Till near the sixteenth century, To Europe was unknown This great land of America, So populous since grown. The people then believed the world To be so very small That Europe, Asia, Africa Were with some islands all." While this is written in verse, it cannot be called poetry in any fundamental sense, but readily falls under prose, because it is an effort to teach facts touching the discovery of America. In all cases the form is incidental to the spirit. By the spiritual standard Irv- ing's " Sketch Book " is a collection of poems ; and this view is justified by the dictionary and the encyclopae- dia ; while Whittier's war poems, designed to arouse the people against slavery, are oratorical, because they seek to change the existing order of things. Shakespeare and the Psalmist are poets in spite of the fact that they did not write in verse. When it is said that an expres- sion is poetic, the soul of the expression is hinted at, and not its form. It is true that the highest tension of feeling naturally seeks rhythmical expression ; yet all good prose is more or less rhythmical ; every oration should be musical. Undoubtedly discourse may be classified on the basis of form into prose and poetry, and this will be done at the proper place — in discuss- ing the language of discourse ; but here we are con- cerned with discourse in its entire spirit and compass. Every one is conscious of using language to each of 38 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the three ends above described. And these ends are fundamental, controlling, as we shall see, the organiza- tion of both the thought and the style of discourse. These kinds of discourse shade imperceptibly into each other ; and frequently a discourse defies exact classification. But this should not discourage us, for such is true everywhere. The dividing line between plants and animals has never been found ; yet we rec- ognize the working value of such a distinction. Every- where in the world of thought things blend and flow ; and we must not hope to draw lines of thought more sharply than they are found in things. It matters not that we are baffled in classifying a given piece of dis- course ; for this fact shows the nature of the discourse, and this is what is really sought. Classification is not an end, but a means. If it be found that a discourse is equally well adapted to each of the three ends, let it be so ; for this is its unique and fundamental fact, — the fact that regulates all further procedure in its study. Such a discovery might be a criticism on the discourse, but not a reflection on the critic. As a rule, however, the classification is readily made, for the types of each class are distinct and numerous. Classify, on the basis of purpose, the following : — " The founder of rhetoric as an art was Corax of Syracuse (c. 466 15. c). In 466 Thrasybulus, the despot of Syracuse, was overthrown, and a democracy was established. One of the im- mediate consequences was a mass of litigation on claims to prop- erty, urged by democratic exiles who had been dispossessed by Thrasybulus, Hiero, or Gelo. If, twenty years after the Crom- wellian settlement of Ireland, an opportunity had been afforded to aggrieved persons for contesting every possession taken under THE PURPOSE IN DISCOURSE. 39 that settlement in the ten counties, such persons being required to plead by their own mouths, the demand for an " art " of forensic rhetoric in Ireland would have been similar to that which existed in Sicily at the moment when Corax appeared. If we would un- derstand the history of Greek rhetoric before Aristotle, we must always remember these circumstances of its origin. The new "art" was primarily intended to help the plain citizen who had to speak before a court of law." "It is estimated that from seventy-five to a hundred thousand wives and children of these soldiers are now held in slavery. It is a burning shame to this country. . . . Wasting diseases, weary marches, and bloody battles are now decimating our armies. The country needs soldiers, must have soldiers. Let the Senate, then, act now. Let us hasten the enactment of this beneficent measure, inspired by patriotism and hallowed by justice and hu- manity, so that, ere merry Christmas shall come, the intelligence shall be flashed over the land to cheer the hearts of the nation's defenders and arouse the manhood of the bondman, that, on the forehead of the soldier's wife and the soldier's child no man can write ' Slave.' " " Oh, there is an enduring tenderness in the love of a mother to her son that transcends all other affections of the heart. It is neither to be chilled by selfishness, nor daunted by danger, nor weakened by worthlessness, nor stifled by ingratitude. She will sacrifice every comfort to his convenience ; she will surrender every pleas- ure to his enjoyment ; she will glory in his fame, and exult in his prosperity ; and if misfortune overtake him, he will be the dearer to her from misfortune ; and if disgrace settle upon his name, she will still love and cherish him in spite of his disgrace ; and if all the world beside cast him off, she will be all the world to him." Which of the foregoing confronts an actual with an ideal condition of things, for the purpose of changing the ideal into the actual ? Which presents simply an ideal for the mere sake of the joy awakened by con- 4-0 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. templating the ideal ? Which presents a fact for its merely intellectual value ? Which of the fore- going confines the attention to one aspect of the sub- ject, and which to two aspects ? In what respect are all of these alike, and in what respect is each peculiar ? Select many other examples, and classify them by applying the foregoing questions. And for further emphasis select some piece of land and pre- sent it, first, to give a clear notion of it ; second, to persuade some one to buy it or to improve it ; third, to awaken the feeling of beauty. To each of the three ends, how should a steam-engine be presented ? forest trees ? charity? the school ? the solar system ? rhetoric? THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. The Theme. To whatever end discourse is adapted, thought is presented as the means, through language as the medium. Hence, we are here concerned, not with the nature of thought, but with its adaptation to the ends of utterance, — with thought in the process of affecting the mind addressed. The same subject-matter may be used for different purposes, but in each case it must be differently organized. In logic thought is considered in its own nature, and organized about some center of its own ; while in discourse thought must be or- ganized to the requirements of the end sought, and in obedience to the conditions under which it is sought. The history of Greece might be so compacted and organized as to satisfy the sternest laws of logic ; but such an organization would not serve to instruct im- mature minds, nor to produce emotional or volitional effects. The nature of the theme determines the logi- cal organization; the particular end sought, and the conditions under which it is sought, the rhetorical organization. The latter may be identical with the former, — in fact, for some purposes it must be so ; but in most cases a modification is made by the laws imposed from without. 4 2 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Therefore, thought in discourse is studied in the process of producing an effect on some mind addressed, and its organization varies in obedience to the differ- ent effects to be produced, and the circumstances and conditions under which the effect is to be pro- duced. To give instruction, the battle of Gettysburg should be organized in one way ; to arouse poetic emotions, it must be organized differently, and still differently to move the will. And each of these must be changed in a marked degree in adapting from a lower to a higher phase of mental development. A still further modification is required when the end is sought under the limitations of some particular time, or place, or .peculiar circumstances, or to minds of special experience. An address to citizens would not be adapted to the soldiers who were engaged in the battle, and what would be suitable for the Southern soldier would not be suitable for the Northern soldier. The poet and the astronomer do not present the same facts about the sun, the moon, and the stars. A didactic discourse on religion or ethics requires the selection of quite different phases and elements from that required in arousing people to religious and ethical conduct. The poet dare not give the mathematical position, form, and size of a landscape, but the surveyor must do so. To use the rainbow as a subject of instruction would require its analysis into the laws of light, but to awaken esthetic feelings the attention must be directed to other aspects, and if it is used to guide conduct in some specific way, still other views must be taken. Lowell, in saying of the dandelion : — THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 43 " Dear common flower that grow'st beside the way, Fringing the dusty road with harmless gold," does not select the same points that are given in the botany. The instructor in zoology would not say of the bird singing that he ..." lets his illumined being o'errun With the deluge of summer he receives." Thus always the subject considered must be plastic to the purpose. Thought in discourse is peculiar in being considered, not in itself, as in logic, but as a means to an end, and is, therefore, organized, not only by its own laws, but also by the laws of the mind in which the effect is to be produced. From the side of mind we have already deduced the fundamental law of discourse as that of Purpose, and we are now brought to the highest law from the side of thought ; namely, that of Unity of process to the end sought. If instruc- tion is to be given, the ideas must cooperate to that end ; if the will is to be moved, all the feelings aroused must prompt in that direction ; if the esthetic feelings are to be stimulated, there must be no discordant note. The thought must have unity in moving the mind to the end sought. Such is the supreme requirement which the purpose makes upon the thought. This thought unity is called the Theme of discourse. In every discourse there must be one idea which sums up the whole, and within which all the parts are organ- ized. Whether a discourse is a single sentence, a para- graph, or an entire book, there must be one all-inclusive 44 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. thought. The Declaration of Independence is a com- plex document, but it is designed to express a single truth, — the right of the American Colonies to free- dom. Many things are said in " Little Lord Faunt- leroy," but they are all included in the idea that kind- ness begets kindness. All the diversity of imagery and sentiment in the "Vision of Sir Launfal " have their unity in the feeling of true charity. No matter how elaborate the exposition, if it have organic unity, it must revolve about, or within, a single idea. Hence the theme is the total significance of the discourse. After purpose, a clear conception of the theme is the first requirement of the composer or the inter- preter. Reading or hearing a discourse is largely the art of grasping into unity the various elements and phases of thought as they are presented ; as the art of composition consists chiefly in giving wealth and diversity of life to some theme constantly kept in unity. Hence the very great value, in reading and literary work, of being required to state the one idea for which the given discourse stands. For practical purposes discourse has been quite thoroughly read when the reader can state its theme ; not its title, for this is quite generally not its theme, and per- haps always too indefinite to answer the requirement of interpretation. The required definiteness will be given to the theme by stating it in the form of a proposition, — by answering the question, What one thing can be affirmed by the reading of this selection ? Or, if a composer, What one thing do I wish to affirm vby writing on this theme ? THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 45 It will be observed that the composer and the in- terpreter move in reverse order in relation to the elements of the theme. The interpreter seizes the elements and features first, and progressively unifies them into the theme. The composer first grasps the theme, and then proceeds to analyze it into its elements, after which the elements are given the organic unity of the whole. The critic will take one step beyond the ordinary reader ; for, after ascertain- ing the theme from the elements, he will reconstruct the discourse from the standpoint of the author — from the theme to its elements. But the first, and for ^general purposes the last, movement in reading is the construction of the theme out of the elements pre- sented. Hence, to interpret with efficiency one must keep the imagination and the judgment intently active relating into one idea all the others. The difference between readers is great ; and it lies chiefly in the power of organizing details into unity. One tries to hold everything, and remembers nothing ; while another organizes the elements into unity as he proceeds, and reaches with certainty the one thought which holds for him all the others. As no habit of reading is so valuable as that of resting the attention on the main issue as it unfolds itself in the process of interpretation, so nothing steadies the nerve of the writer through the compli- cated details of his subject-matter like a firm grip on the organic unity of his theme. After the inspiration of a worthy purpose, a firm grasp of the theme is next of prime importance. In fact there is little distinction 46 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. between them ; for seizing a theme firmly and vividly is itself an inspiration to utterance. One cannot wield a subject till it becomes a part of his life, and is reenforced by his whole life. At this point the subject is transmuted into motive to utterance. Therefore when a composer chooses a theme by which to accomplish a certain end, his first concern is to so bring the theme into his life that it becomes the impelling force in speech. No merely external posting tip on a subject will meet the requirement ; the speaker or writer must be able to give original con- struction to the theme by the initiative force of his own life. Unless the theme be thoroughly possessed it cannot be wielded with precision and force to the end proposed ; it cannot be adapted and given organic unity under a dominant purpose. One staggering under the weight of his theme cannot move nimbly to varying ends, nor adjust the matter delicately to varying conditions. The theme will burden him, and constrain him to the same movement under all circumstances. Thus burdened he cannot move with that masterly progress through the subject, and with that harmony and proportion of treatment which gives symmetry and organic beauty to the whole. Here again it appears that the primary condition of effective speech is the man himself ; for the theme on which he discourses must have been fully assimilated to his own life --must be his life. Unity in discourse cannot be secured by patching things together in a mechanical and external way ; it must arise from a unitary life impulse which orders and organizes every- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 47 thing to a supreme end. This principle is well illustrated in the practice of writing books. For in- stance, one decides to write a grammar, and not having mastered language by an intimate experience with it through its prolonged use and study, places before him the grammars already written ; and by a careful reading and comparison rewords the matter in new phrases and outlines. This is the best he can do, if his wealth of experience with the language itself does not move him to construct from an inward resource. In one case there is mechanism ; in the other, organic life. One may easily write a history of the United States by averaging and paraphrasing many texts on that subject ; but to produce a living history the United States must have so found its way into the writer that he can construct originally. None but an original work can be well written, — not one that an- nounces truth before undiscovered, for in this sense originality is a vain striving ; but one written by the self-assertive thought of the writer, — one actively and not passively determined. Everything is original to the man who makes it his own, — to the one who can originate it and reproduce it. Originality in this sense conditions all effective writing. When the theme so takes possession of the writer as to speak through him as its mouthpiece something will be said clearly and forcibly to the purpose. This firm holding of the theme by the composer requires first that the theme be definitely bounded. To this end it should be stated in as many definite ways as possible, and the boundary lines between it 48 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. and all adjacent territory of thought should be pre- cisely run by means of comparison and contrast. The " fingers of the mind " must be placed well and firmly around it, as a condition to wielding it to any definite end. After the theme as a whole has been grasped it must be inwardly explored and all its phases, and its elements selected out and organized into the theme as a whole. Whatever wealth of life there is in the theme must be taken possession of by the composer. The law of unity implies variety ; there can be no unity without difference, and the greater the variety the richer the unity, so long as unity is main- tained. The more complex any work of man, so long as the complexity is in obvious unity, the greater the power of art displayed. One of the greatest feats of composition is shown by Shakespeare's dramas, which display great profusion of life in unity. Many scenes move abreast without confusion, and in a way to sweep the diapason of human life. A great volume of life is gradually wrought up to the most intense climax, and then as gradually relieved in the peace and joy that follow the storm cloud. The chief labor of the composer is to give distinct feature and wealth of variety to the object of his discussion. The greater the diversity held in unity in an organism the higher the life of that organism. The egg passes into the diversity of the chick, and thus assumes greater unity and life force ; and so must a theme, by the mind's brooding on it, grow into diversity and higher unity, and thus become a living and active force in the world of speech. Every composer will THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 49 recall the fact that the greatest stress under which he labors is that of giving organic life to his subject ; and the striking weakness of compositions such as those prepared for high-school graduating exercises, is the lack of varied and conspicuous features given to the theme treated. Bare mathematical unity may be maintained; it may be a unit without variety, — a globe without air, land, or water, without valley, plateau, or mountain, without lake, river, or water- fall, — a monotonous surface, without height or depth, day or night, winter or summer. Thus while empha- sizing the unity of the theme, there is implied a wealth of diversity in the unity, and that the greater the diversity the stronger the unity. In fact the law might well be stated as diversity in unity. While emphasizing wealth of diversity, the law does not require all the elements of the theme to be pre- sented ; but only those necessary to the purpose under the circumstances. All elements which do not further the purpose must be strictly rejected ; but every element which will further the purpose must be included. To whatever end the subject may be presented, many elements and phases of the subject have to be rejected ; and the composer must often practice self-denial in withholding what he finds inter- esting to himself, yet irrelevant to his purpose. He may desire to give his theme unity and completeness in itself, but he must yield to the unity of the theme in relation to the proposed end. But while unity does not require all the attributes of the theme, yet care must be taken to emphasize 50 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the all which are necessary to produce the desired effect. Again, the necessity for the complete mastery of the theme appears. The composer has ample resources only through knowing all the possibilities of the theme. He cannot make the theme go for all it is worth to the auditor without knowing the wealth of thought which it contains. He must be able to dwell on it with cumulative power till the end is realized ; and this he cannot do without an all-sided view, and without having explored its inner constitution. The cumulative force in his movement is by the wealth of material which he is able to present. The composer is most conscious of the effort to expand and amplify. His greatest strain is that of pushing out his theme here and there in its varied and distinct features till it takes possession of the mind addressed. The mind must have time to grow into a new state. It is a great art to be able to hold the theme close to the mind long enough for its full reaction upon the theme, even though old elements have to be repeated ; yet in this case they would assume new aspects and relations. The time factor is most easily secured when the speaker or writer has a wealth of views and materials provided. The unity requires the action of the theme on the mind in ways varied and continuous till the mind grows into the state desired. Shakespeare, in bringing his audience up to the climax, illustrates this principle admirably. His wealth of invention enables him to hold the auditor in one movement for a great length of time. But care is needed, in seeking to gain time, to keep up a feeling of progress. The purpose THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 5 1 is defeated as soon as there is a feeling of delay. The auditor must feel that the thought is being developed as rapidly as possible ; and the only way to secure this feeling and gain the necessary time is to have the mind of the author in rich and varied touch with the subject being considered. But the effective movement to a mental change by means of a theme does not depend wholly on the selec- tion and number of phases and elements of the theme, but finally on the DietJiod of their presentation. In discourse the elements are seldom, if ever, pre- sented in the order in which they logically cohere; but in the order in which they can most easily be appro- priated by the recipient. The discourse order is the chronological rather than the logical order; the point needed by the mind first is not necessarily of first im- portance to the subject. To instruct children in the Civil War would require first its picture and moving panorama of events; but these logically follow the cause and the moving spirit of the war. The child must begin with the objective and picturable aspects; and it may be that these are all he can receive at the time. The different grades of ability addressed require different arrangements of subject-matter. Popular, scientific, and philosophic discourse employ different methods of presenting the same subject-matter. And the elements arranged for the purpose of instruction are not properly arranged for volitional or emotional ends. The orator does not use materials in the same order as does the poet ; and when audiences and cir- cumstances vary the arrangement varies with them. 52 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. In general, the discourse must move freely and smoothly onward. There must be no hitching back and forth; the thought must grow by easy and imper- ceptible gradations from point to point. Not that it must move in a straight line, — for rather there should be rise and fall, a rhythmical flow, for thought and feel- ing obey the universal law of rhythmical motion, — but that there must be no lunging ahead, or returning to pick up pieces left by the wayside. No one feature gives a discourse more power than a steady onward movement to the end set up. All hesitancy and eddy- ing about of the thought are prime sources of weakness. The points made must have a distinct and orderly suc- cession, or the receiving mind will be baffled in its effort to organize the material presented, and miss the object for which the discourse stands. We have seen that interpretation is primarily the process of bringing into unity the elements as rapidly as they are pre- sented, and nothing can assist the interpreting mind so much as the orderly arrangement of elements in their presentation. In order that a composer master a theme in its unity and diversity, so that he may wield it with precision and effect, and in order that one may interpret with appreciation and profit, the various ways in which a theme is organized must be traced out. The different methods of theme organization give rise to clearly defined discourse processes. the thought in discourse. 53 The Discourse Processes. Since themes are unities of elements, it follows that the two primary movements of thought in the prepara- tion and the presentation of any theme for any purpose are those of analysis and synthesis. The elements of the theme must first be discerned, and then integrated into the whole. Or better, perhaps, three steps may be distinguished : First, seizing the theme in its vague unity; second, analyzing the theme into its elements; third, organizing the elements into the theme, giving a definite organic whole instead of the vague one grasped at the outset. This analysis and synthesis takes definite character from the kinds of unities which constitute the theme, — from the kinds of relations which bind the parts into unity. The parts of an engine are bound together in co- operation to the end for which the engine is designed. The parts of a tree are parts in working together to carry on the life process of the tree as a whole. The parts of the human body contribute to one life process, and are not parts except in and through the whole; and the whole is not a whole except in and through the parts. The government is composed of parts working together to secure the ends of justice. The earth, the solar system, the universe have parts bound together in cooperation. Such a unit is called an organic unit. The lowest form of it, or the form in which it seems to vanish, is the unit whose parts have spatial unity, as in the case of a stone or a pile of material. Here the 54 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. parts are in touch, and bound together by physical force; yet in this case the parts cooperate to make the whole. In some of the other cases named, parts were separated in space, and the unity consists in functional cooperation rather than in spatial wholeness. But in both cases the wholes are bounded in space, and both have parts whose connection makes the whole; both are called individual objects. Gladstone is an individ- ual ; and so is the British nation, and for the same reason. The police force of a city is an individual police force, because the parts work together to keep order, as do the parts of one policeman. The reasons given for calling Jupiter an individual apply equally well to the solar system as an individual. Let it not be understood, therefore, that a theme to be individual must consist of parts touching in space ; yet every in- dividual, though it be a mental act or state, must be figured to the mind as bounded in space. Hence, such themes must first be presented to the imagination as pictured wholes; after which their deeper thought unity may be penetrated. Further guidance for presenting the individual is obtained from noting that each individual has parts which coexist in space and parts which succeed each other in time — space wholes and time wholes. The parts of this tree exist together now, but considering the life of this tree as a whole, in its growth from the seed, it has parts succeeding each other: as, first the sprout and then the shoot appearing above ground, then the shrub, etc. A battle may be caught up in one view at a given moment, as having coexisting parts THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 55 in space; but it is also a moving panorama, having parts in distinct succession. A complete view of the earth brings before the mind its successive stages of development, and also its parts as they at present work together side by side. Thus every individual is a space whole or a time whole — a simultaneous whole or a successive whole. While it requires both views of an individual to complete its organization, the two views cannot be taken at the same time. This will become evident by an attempt to think of an object as fixed and as chang- ing: at the same time. Since this is true, two distinct discourse processes arise in treating the individual. The process presenting the individual as a space, or coexisting, whole is called Description; the process presenting the individual as a time, or successive, whole is called Narration. Themes have quite a different kind of unity from the organic unity above described. A sewing-machine has its origin in an idea which creates all other sewing-ma- chines, and may create them infinitely, so far as the pos- sibility of the idea is concerned. All sewing-machines have their unity in the one originating idea, or type. The idea as an outgoing energy produces all sewing- machines, and thus gives unity to all. When one says simply ''sewing-machine" or "the sewing-machine" he is naming the type, or idea, which brings forth the individual sewing-machines. To think any given sew- ing-machine requires it to be viewed in connection with the common idea of all sewing-machines. A certain activity produces a triangle — an activity which goes 56 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. out and comes back to the place of starting by two pointed turns. This activity produces all triangles, and can produce them infinitely. All are one in this activity, and this is the essence of each one. The mind cannot grasp any one triangle without seizing upon the activity which produces triangles in general. Triangles may vary infinitely, but they are all alike in being produced by an activity returning to the place of starting by two pointed turns. There is an idea, a nature, a potency which produces oak trees, and which may produce them without limit. All trees formed under the impulse of this idea are one in that idea; and the study of each oak requires it to be viewed in connection with the all-producing idea. When we speak of the nature of anything we have reference to its producing idea; for the word nature means that which is about to appear. The nature of man is the energy, the potency which persists in producing men as distinguished from other objects. The nature of an Indian is the fixed idea or type which determines all individual Indians. Such a unit is called a class unit, or concept, as dis- tinguished from the organic unit. The class unit does not mean simply the common productive idea of a number of individuals, but the unity of the individuals in and through the idea. The parts of this unit are the individuals which spring from the same originating source. It differs from the organic unit, not in parts, but in the way the parts are unified. Thinking of the French people as a nation, as individuals working to- gether for a common good, we have an individual — THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 57 a nation ; but thinking of them as being Frenchmen, as having a common genesis, we have a class unit. In each case it is the same subject-matter, — the same whole and the same parts, — but in the former the parts are unified through cooperation, while in the latter through a common nature. Each triangle has sides which work together to make a triangle, but these sides have common nature, being produced by the same kind of movement, which makes the class units called sides. And so with the angles ; they help to form the triangle, but the same activity produces each ; by the former they are organized, and by the latter classified. Triangles might be placed together to form some figure, and would thus help one another to make the whole ; but the same parts, triangles, may be formed into a class by conceiving them in unity with the idea producing each and all. Thus the dis- tinction between the organic unit and the class unit is not that between different parts nor different wholes, but in the manner in which the parts are bound into wholes. It might be well to observe, however, that the class whole cannot be bounded in space, as can the organic whole ; hence it is not a space whole. This follows from the fact that the producing energy, the idea, the type, can create individuals infinitely. After making any conceivable number of engines from the idea engine, the idea remains as productive as ever. Hence the imagination is not required to bound the class unit, as it is required to do with the organic unit. As the organic unit has two aspects, so has the class unit. Class unity consists, as we have seen, in the 58 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. relation of the parts, the individuals, to the one princi- ple which produces the parts. The unity is that of the individuals with the general creating them. This unity can be taken as it exists at a given time, simply as a fixed thing, somewhat as the individual is viewed in description ; or the unity may be thought of in the process of being established under the influence of the active principle, somewhat as the individual is viewed in narration. Ocean currents may be considered as they are, — the individual currents as in unity with a physical principle which constitutes them what they are ; or the physical principle may be viewed in the active production of them, or, through them, of other phenomena. The distinction is simply that between individuals as already existing in the unity of a com- mon nature and individuals in the process of being produced by a common nature or of producing other individuals. From the side of mind, it is the distinction between concept and judgment. The concept is the grasping of the unity existing among individuals, while the judgment is the process of establishing in thought the unity between the subject and predicate of thought ; which interpreted means the unity between the indi- vidual and the general. When the subject and predi- cate of a judgment become identified the judgment vanishes into a new concept, and the desired unity is established, and may be taken in the future without affirming and arguing. However the matter may be turned the unity appears as that between the individual and the general, either THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 59 as fixed, as a fact, or in the process of becoming. The first kind of unity is set forth by the process of Expo- sition ; the second, by the process of Argumentation. These processes are distinct, because, as in the case of description and narration, unity cannot be viewed as established and in the process of being established at the same time. The four discourse processes are alike in that each deals with individual objects ; but they differ in that description deals with individual objects as fixed, as spatial wholes, as they stand organized at a given time ; narration, with individuals as changing in time, as time wholes, as organized wholes progressive in time ; exposition, with individuals as in fixed unity with a common productive energy ; argumentation, with individuals in the active process of unity under a general principle. In all cases the purpose is to pre- sent the theme in unity, and the different processes are only so many phases of a movement to that end, — phases depending on the kind of unity inherent in the subject-matter itself. All of the processes may be required in the same discourse, but the character of the discourse as a whole is determined by the kind of unity which the discourse seeks ultimately to estab- lish. The relation of the processes is not that of higher and lower, or that of simplicity and complexity, but that of the view taken of the subject-matter. For different purposes the same theme may be presented under one or the other of the different processes. Hence, the three ends of discourse are realized by four processes, and to the three kinds of discourse on 60 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the basis of the effect produced must be added the four kinds of discourse on the basis of the process by which the effect is produced. These processes, based on the nature of the theme, move forward under the law of purpose. It thus appears that the processes of discourse are controlled by two factors : (i) the rela- tions which constitute the theme, and (2) the laws im- posed by the mind addressed. These factors must now guide us in the detailed consideration of the dis- course processes. DESCRIPTION. Description is the process by which one mind presents to another, through language, an individual as consti- tuted of coexisting elements. If the real object or its picture could be presented to the eye, its attributes and parts would appear in their unity at once, — at least in their spatial unity. But by the limitation of language, when the several ideas are presented in discourse they must follow each other in an order of time. In this respect language is inferior to painting. Painting, which employs figures and colors in space, presents attributes and parts as they coexist ; thus freeing the mind from the neces- sity of unifying the constituent ideas, so far as the superficial unity is concerned. But in expressing the inner meaning of the object, as interpreted by the judgment and penetrative imagination, language has more than a compensating advantage. While it is possible to paint or to sculpture all parts of the human body, the functional relation of each to life, as inter- preted by the judgment, can be expressed in language only. Painting can express only the outer unity of an object, while language can express the inner unity of thought. The two facts — namely, that the object to be described consists of coexisting elements, and that, by the necessities of language, these elements must be presented in succession — make the law of unity in de- scription difficult to obey. The law requires the object 62 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. to be so presented that the interpreter will readily and correctly organize it into the unity it was before broken in the process of presentation. The first step in description is that of presenting the theme as a whole by means of its attributes. Attributive Description. The theme as a whole is presented by means of its attributes, and this process may be called attributive description. Any means by which this object is known not to be that is an attribute. Since attri- butes do not mutually exclude each other as do parts, they always distinguish objects as wholes. The odor, flavor, weight, and form of the orange are interfused throughout, and occupy the same space ; while the peel, pulp, and seeds must occupy different spaces. An object is first distinguished from other objects by its relations to them ; and the first step in this phase of description is to present the theme By Attributes of Relation. — This method presents the object under the relation of Purpose and Means, Cause and Effect, Time and Place, and Likeness and Difference. The use of each of these attributes involves some object other than the one under consideration. To think of the purpose of an object or of the object as means carries the thought directly to something be- yond the immediate object of thought. To think of the cause or the effect of anything involves more than the single thing. A second object is required THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 63 to locate anything in space or time ; and likeness or difference is clearly inconceivable without two objects. 1. Purpose is the highest distinguishing mark of an object ; and to state the purpose to which an object is means is to make the most comprehensive description of it possible by the use of a single term. Purpose calls the object into being, and unifies its other attri- butes and its parts. These are what they are because of the object's purpose, or end which it fills. There- fore purpose is the most fundamental truth, the most pervasive fact, that can be given in the description of an object. All thought would be thwarted without the ideas of design and adaptation. One cannot speak intelligently about a book, a bridge, a plant, an animal, or the earth, without employing in some form these conceptions. The whole question before us in this discussion of discourse is that of its construction or of its interpretation under the law of adaptation and design. In any field of labor man has only to design and adapt. All things are organized under ends sought ; and there is always assumed a supreme end which organizes all, — "one far-off divine event, To which the whole creation moves." And again : — " I see in part That all as in some piece of art, Is toil cooperant to an end." We should expect, therefore, the relation of purpose and means to permeate and control every description ; and yet one not accustomed to note the fact will be 64 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. surprised at the frequency and variety of terms used in a description to express this relation. They are not confined to those of direct expression, such as purpose, adaptation, aim, object, design, intent, motive, destination, in order to, the "be all and the end all," and the like ; but are found lurking in disguises of many forms, as in this : — "And what is so rare as a day in June ? Then, if ever, come perfect days ; Then heaven tries the earth if it be in tune, And over it softly her warm ear lays." The three expressions, "rare," "perfect," and "in tune," express the adaptation of the day to its life- giving purpose. A day is perfect in proportion as it nourishes life, for that is its purpose. To say that a day is rare is to say that it is exceptionally well fitted to the end of life. The earth is in tune when it can produce the song of life. Lowell's whole description of the day in June brings out in varied ways this one idea. And when he describes the mountain by saying, — " With our faint heart the mountain strives," he expresses, in the word "strives," the fact that the mountain seeks to influence our lives for the better. Note the same relation expressed in the following lines from the Spanish by Longfellow, describing the brook : — 41 Laugh of the mountain ! lyre of bird and tree ! Pomp of the meadow ! mirror of the morn I " THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 6$ This relation has two forms, — one in which the object is considered in adaptation to an end ; and the other in which the object itself is conceived as the purposer. This latter phase is known as descrip- tion by personification. Note its use in the following exquisite bit from Lowell's description of the brook, in " The Vision of Sir Launfal " : — " Down swept the chill wind from the mountain peak, From the snow five thousand summers old ; On open wold and hill-top bleak It had gathered all the cold, And whirled it like sleet on the wanderer's cheek ; It carried a shiver everywhere From the unleafed boughs and pastures bare ; The little brook heard it and built a roof 'Neath which he could house him winter-proof ; All night by the white stars' frosty gleams He groined his arches and matched his beams ; Slender and clear were his crystal spars As the lashes of light that trim the stars." In the description of the June day, occurring in the same poem as the foregoing, the author presents it as being adapted to a purpose ; but the wind and the brook are presented as purposing. 2. After an object has been purposed a cause must operate to produce it ; and when produced it acts and reacts on other objects, manifesting itself in effects. The relation of cause and effect produces changes in objects, and is more prominently employed in narration ; yet it is essential to description. In giving a full conception of the Andes Mountains it is necessary to state the force that upheaved them, and 66 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. their effects on climate, vegetable and animal life, and on the industries of man. The relation of cause and effect is the leading means of presenting a mental state. To bring a particular mental state fully into consciousness, it is necessary to present the conditions which produced the state ; and these may be further strengthened by giving the conduct of the person under the in- fluence of the state. To describe a state of fear is to present some object that produced the state ; as a tornado whirling aloft the ruined houses of a city, with the effect of the fear in the wild gesticulations and screams of the fleeing inhabitants. Longfellow, in describing his sadness in " The Day is Done," gives the cause of his condition in the falling darkness and the light gleaming through the rain and the mist, and also the effect in the fact that he is driven to seek relief. Under the same relation a person's physical appear- ance may be described to suggest his spiritual attri- butes, since the latter, to a certain extent, are causes to the former as effects. Chaucer, in the Prologue to the "Canterbury Tales," introduces the spiritual quali- ties of each character by means of his physical attri- butes. And thus Irving, in "The Legend of Sleepy Hollow," brings out the spiritual Ichabod Crane by means of the physical Ichabod. Physical objects are frequently presented, and in some of their phases can be presented only, by giving their effects on the observer. To speak of an object as awful, terrible, stupendous, sublime, picturesque, THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 6? grotesque, or beautiful is to present the object by means of the effect produced on the observer. Irving talks of sober and melancholy days, mournful magnifi- cence, gloomy remains, a picture of glory, amazing height, noiseless reverence, disastrous story, awful harmony, thrilling thunders, solemn concords ; and in so doing speaks in terms of the effect produced. 3. Relation in time is not so prominently used in description as in narration ; yet its use frequently facilitates the presentation of other attributes. Stat- ing the time of the day and of the year at which a landscape is observed is necessary in order to bring the picture briefly and fully before the mind. This relation has great power of suggestiveness. To in- troduce the description of a shipwreck by, " It was midnight on the waters," both arouses a vague sense of fear, which the fuller description is to make clear and strong, and fills the imagination at once with a general conception of the whole. To state that a man is old carries with it gray hairs, dim eyes, feeble voice, palsied limbs, and clouded memory. To know that a church has stood for a hundred years implies more than can be told in pages of descriptive detail. The location of an object in space corresponds to its location in time. A material object cannot be conceived without relation to other objects in space ; and the parts of an object can be conceived only in spatial relations to each other. And spiritual objects, such as mental activities and states, are figured under spatial relations. In treating one's moral character his virtues are placed side by side as if they had 68 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. spatial qualities. Thus space seems to be a universal form which the mind imposes on all objects in order to think them. The mind itself is figured under spatial relations ; as, large and small, high and low, few-sided and many-sided, and the like ; and character is spoken of as straight or crooked, erect or prostrate, etc. 4. The relation of Likeness and Difference gives rise to a distinct process of description called Com- parison and Contrast. All objects are known by means of likenesses and differences. An object can- not be grasped as an object were it not both alike and different from other objects. To bring these like- nesses and differences into consciousness is one of the most effective means at the composer's command of presenting the elements of an object effectively. Generally the process employs a well-known object as a means of presenting the one under consideration. It has been seen that the chief weakness of a verbal description is the limitation of language which pre- vents the writer or speaker from flashing all parts of the object on the mind at once. The more nearly this can be done, the better. Comparison and contrast is a most powerful means to this end. Often a detailed process of thought and a tediousness of ex- pression may be avoided by comparing and contrast- ing the object under discussion with some well-known object. This is not merely brevity in language, which comes from substituting a known object for words ; it econo- mizes the thought processes. Without requiring the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 69 mind to trace the action of a valve in the heart, attention may be called to the action of a valve in a pump, if the latter be familiar to the audience. A strange fruit may be put before the mind at once, by comparing it to an apple, if it is essentially like an apple ; and thus save weariness of details in both language and thought. To refer a strange animal to its species saves a volume of descriptive detail and a useless repetition of thought processes. This implied comparison presents the essential characteristics of the object ; and if the special marks of the individual are required, a few points of contrast will fill the out- line. Of two objects equally well known, comparison and contrast is a strong means of presenting both at the same time. Often a vivid and sufficient descrip- tion may be made by presenting an object by its extreme opposite. Whether comparison or contrast shall be the leading method depends on whether likenesses or differences are assumed to be most prominent in the object. If two objects are supposed to be different, then it is most effective to present them in their likenesses ; and if they are assumed to be alike then the presenta- tion of differences will fix best the individuality of each. But usually likenesses and differences should be carried along together. In doing this the two methods should be kept distinct. A point of likeness may be given, and then a corresponding point of dif- ference, thus carrying the likenesses and differences in parallel lines. Or all the likenesses may be given by themselves, and then the differences by themselves. JO THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. The purpose being to abbreviate thought and language processes, the object chosen with which to compare the theme must (i) be a familiar object, and must (2) have the greatest number of points common to the theme. To select an object less familiar than the theme, or points of comparison that need explanation themselves, is to defeat the purpose of the comparison. In order that the object may have the greatest number of points common to the theme, it must not be chosen from a class more comprehensive than necessary. The comparison of a horse with a reptile would violate this law. Both belong to vertebrates, but it would be better to choose from mammals, as the bat ; better still to choose from quadrupeds, as the lion ; and still better to choose from the ungulata, as the ox. After presenting an object as a whole by means of its distinct relations to some other object, one other step in attributive description remains; namely, that of presenting the object By Means of its Properties. — Properties are attri- butes which inhere in the nature of the object. They determine it from within, while relations determine it from without. Properties are of two kinds, Primary and Secondary. 1. Primary qualities are essential to the existence of the object, and are involved in every conception of it. To think them away is to destroy all thought of the object. They fall into two general classes, Exten- sion and Resistance. a. Extension, which may be called the mathematical quality, gives rise to the two subordinate attributes of THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. J\ Form and Size ; the first resulting from the kind of extension, the second from the degree of extension. These relations unify the other attributes to the senses, as purpose does to thought. The weight, color, taste, and odor coincide within the same form and limit. These attributes give the empty form of the object, which the other attributes fill out. Position, form, and size are, after purpose, most commonly used to distinguish objects. They even serve to distinguish spiritual objects in a figurative sense. We speak of a large-minded man; of a man "four square to all the winds that blow " ; of a straight man ; of a right and a wrong headed man ; of men superior and inferior ; of high-minded men ; of men above or below a certain plane of conduct, etc. b. The other class of primary qualities, the different forms of resistance, add to the idea of a mere extended form that of a power which resists, either as an active or passive force. A resisting, as well as an extended, something is essential to our notion of an object, whether it be a conception of a material or a spiritual object. The general attribute of passive resistance manifests itself in particular objects as hard, soft, firm, fluid, tough, brittle, rigid, flexible, rough, smooth, light, heavy, compressible, incompressible, elastic, non-elastic, etc. — the physical properties of matter, as the others were the mathematical. It is obvious that these attributes are given primarily by the muscular sense, the lowest sense giving the most fundamental quality. This sense, through these primary qualities of resistance, brings us into a knowledge of external existence. 72 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. While the spatial relations condition the existence of matter as such, these are the inner forces which de- termine and distinguish all objects as objects. They are not determined from without, but are themselves the shaping and conditioning forces. These forces reveal themselves only in reaction against a force within ourselves, and with them we begin our struggle with the outer world. These physical attributes, which are manifested in the struggle with the material world, are the ones attributed to spirit in its struggle in the moral world, such as firm, rigid, resisting, flexible, stern, unyielding, stable, resolute, strong, lenient, persistent, austere, rigorous, etc. More important than passive resistance is the active outgoing of the object to en- counter the world about it, reaching its most significant form in self-activity and will. Objects reveal their true nature in action, and for this reason attributes of action must be employed in description. The river flows, the bird sings, the mind thinks; this is their nature. A man's character is always described by giving his actions. While the actions are fleeting, they point to some permanent quality from which they arise. In fact attributes of action often signify only the power to act; as when we say that a bird sings. This does not mean that it is in the active process of singing, but only that it has the power to sing. A spiritual object can be described only through attributes of action. The primary attribute of mind is activity. We infer its nature from its acts. A man's specific acts and utterances are the key to his inner life. To show that patriotism was one of the traits of THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 73 Washington's life, is to bring before the mind what he said and did. When the novelist or dramatist creates a character, he causes the character to reveal himself in speech and action. The writer endows him with some life principle at the outset, and then contrives occasions and opportunities for him to say and do what is in keeping with a man thus endowed. After the character has once in him the breath of life, a real controlling principle, he passes from under the control of his creator, doing those things which it is fitting for one thus constituted to do. The delineator has only to watch how his hero conducts himself under all the circumstances of life. " People think an author makes his characters and moves them at his will, like so many jumping-jacks, controlled by hidden strings. If that were so each character would be a repetition of the author himself, and nobody would read the book. An author's characters are beyond his control ; they do as they please, and if anybody thinks the men of Drum- tochty are to be easily handled he does not know them." 1 Biography, in setting forth the growth of character, is a most efficient means to character description. This in process is narration ; yet the narration, if the purpose be to arrive at the essential elements of the man's life as a completed product, is subordinate to the process of description. This, too, gives the best opportunity for showing the reaction of the environment on the character. While the individual moulds his age he is moulded by it. His traits and habits are partially accounted for in the life from which he sprang. 1 Ian Maclaren. 74 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 2. The secondary attributes are less essential to the object. They are felt to be affections of the senses rather than qualities of the object. Sound is felt to be subjective, while firmness, given by the muscular sense, is felt to be in the object. The muscular sense gives an objective, resisting something, which as cause pro- duces a subjective effect on the sense of touch, taste, smell, hearing, and sight, giving rise to the various tactile sensations, tastes, odors, sounds, and colors. These senses cannot reveal to us the objective world, unless the sense of sight be an exception, cooperating with the muscular sense to give externality and form. With this exception, these secondary attributes produce their effect on the senses through an active condition of the body to which the attributes belong. The object to be tasted or smelt must be in a state of disso- lution, and to be heard, in a state of motion. Sight and touch are more nearly like the muscular sense, in that they present the body in its normal condition; yet here light is conveyed to the eye through the vibrations of the particles of the body, and the same is true of some form of tactile sensations. These attributes are secondary only in the sense that they are less essential to the existence of the object. If the basis were the effect on the mind, the order would seem reversed; for sight and hearing stand first, in that they minister to the wants of the soul, while taste and smell minister to the wants of the body; and the other attributes to the wants of the object. Thus the muscular sense stands at one extreme of the sense scale, giving that which is of first importance THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 75 to the object; and hearing and sight at the other, giving that which is of first importance to the mind. The terms used to name secondary physical qualities are freely used metaphorically to name spiritual quali- ties, as was found to be the case in primary qualities. In fact, all words descriptive of spiritual objects origi- nally signified physical attributes. Those that seem now to be applied literally, as calm, candid, pure, sincere, bright, dull, etc., have simply lost their physi- cal analogy by constant use. It thus appears that a copious vocabulary of words expressing physical quali- ties is essential to the description of spiritual objects. The presentation of an object as a whole under the relation of substance and attribute prepares the way for its presentation under the relation of whole and part. This process is called Partition, or Partitive Description. Whether it be a physical or a mental object, it can- not be conceived without parts. It must at least have a top and a bottom, a right and a left side, a beginning and an end, an inside and an outside. Whole and part are correlative, for neither can be conceived without the other. Thus grasping a whole is the grasping of attributes and parts. Without both of these ideas not even a start can be made in the description of an object; and a description can involve nothing else than the presentation of attributes and parts. Parts, as we have seen, differ from attributes in be- ing mutually exclusive. Each part must occupy a space ?6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. of its own, and each part taken by itself constitutes a new individual. The old individual from which the new is derived is but a part of a larger whole. This fact further distinguishes parts from attributes, since an attribute cannot exist or be thought of as an attri- bute apart from the object to which it belongs. Each part has the same distinguishing attributes as the whole, and must be presented as if it itself were a whole, with the further step of unifying the parts in the whole. The attributes given of the parts must, therefore, be such as will unify them in the whole. What this means has already been largely indicated under the discussion of the organic unit as distin- guished from the class unity. The parts in the lowest phase of the organic unit are simply aggregated in space. In this, mere position is the unifying attribute; an object appears as a whole to the senses or to the im- agination. It is a mere external unity, and the whole is simply the sum of its parts. The parts cooperate simply by addition, as people collected make a multi- tude or a mass, or as a number of oranges make a pile of oranges. If the oranges were built into a pyramid they would then cooperate a little more definitely to form the whole; and other attributes of each individual besides mere aggregation must be given. Now it is not simply the fact of being together, but of being together in a specified way. And rising still higher in the scale of organic unity, as in the tree or a school in which the parts actively cooperate, still other and more complex attributes of each part are involved in showing the unity of each part with the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. fj whole. This requires always a statement of the function of the part, together with the attributes of the part which adapt it to its function. But in all cases such attributes of a part must be given as make it a member of the whole. If the whole is a mere aggregate, it is necessary to give only the position of each part with reference to the whole; but. if there is active cooperation, the attributes which adapt the part in the cooperation must be given. Thus parts, as wholes, are presented through attributes, but only by means of those attributes which bind them into the unity of the whole. The law of unity in Partition requires that the parts be so presented that the receiving mind may readily and correctly organize them into the whole. This can be done only i. When the farts are made on the same basis of division. In dividing an individual there is choice of bases, permitted by the nature of the object, and determined by the purpose of the description. It may serve the purpose best to follow some accidental basis, as the order in which the parts appear to the eye, or the relative position in space. Such obvious and superficial bases are always used in the lower order of description — descriptions in which the sensuous phases of the object are made prominent. The more scientific the description the more fundamental the basis. This is a question of adaptation to a purpose. On the basis of separation in space, the child readily divides the human body into head, trunk, and limbs. 78 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. This is the best basis for the child, but the physiologist would insist on a basis more intimately connected with life processes. The ordinary description of a landscape would require the mention of such parts as appear at different places, or as occur at different moments of time. But for geographical purposes, the basis must have some -fundamental relation to life. Every change in the basis gives a new set of parts. Not only does this law require the basis to be chosen which is best adapted to the purpose of the writing, but it requires that all the parts be determined on the same basis. If a writer should present a tree as composed of roots, bark, trunk, woody substance, branches, and pith; or the human body as composed of flesh, blood, nerves, muscular tissue, vital organs, adipose tissue, bones, and the mechanical system, using two or more bases of division, utter confusion would arise in the mind of the interpreter. The division should be such as could be made of the actual object. The tree can be actually parted into root, trunk, and branches, and each part put in a different place. So with bark, woody sub- stance, and pith. But if one should attempt to make an actual division of the tree on both bases at once, he would have a practical illustration of what the law of unity means in requiring the division to be made on the same basis. And further, the mind can organize the parts into unity readily 2. When the parts are named in the order determined by the basis. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 79 If ignorant of a tree, as the recipient in a description is supposed to be, to present the parts as roots, leaves, trunk, and branches would cause the mind to form an object wholly different from the one to be described. The basis of partition used determines the order of presenting the parts. It is not necessarily an order of nearness in space or succession in time. It may be an order of functional relation. When the basis of division is that of space, the parts must be named in spatial order. When the basis of division is the order of observation in time, the parts must be named in the order of occurrence. When the basis is some deter- mining principle, the parts must be named in their functional relation, without regard to their position or succession. Thus the parts of the eyeball may be named from without inward, or from within outward, following an order in space; or following the operation of the law of optics, there would be an entirely differ- ent method of procedure, — as first, the retina; second, the crystalline lens, with the parts about it which aid in refracting light; then those parts which regulate the light, followed by those which adjust and protect the image-forming parts. But after the proper basis is selected and adhered to, and the parts given in the order determined by the basis, the object cannot be readily and correctly unified except 3. When all the parts which determine the basis are named. To present a tree as composed of trunk, branches, and leaves, or a flower as composed of calyx, corolla, and 80 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. pistil, is to present the mind with an incomplete unit, and therefore a violation of the general law of unity. Thus the basis being determined by the purpose, if all such parts as the basis gives be presented in the order of their relation as determined by the basis, the mind will the most readily and correctly organize them into the unity they were in before their separa- tion in the process of presentation. The process of description may now be presented in one view by the following outline, which forms a general scheme for all descriptions. Not that a de- scription conforms to the outline, but every description moves within the outline as modified in adaptation to the end sought. The object to be described, — I. As a whole, by means of its attributes. 1. By means of relations. a. Purpose and means. b. Cause and effect. c. Time and space. d. Likeness and difference. 2. By means of properties. a. Primary. (i) Extension — form and size. (2) Resistance — passive and active. b. Secondary — color, sound, odor, taste, and touch. II. As made up of parts. 1. Analysis into parts by the laws of partition. 2. Synthesis of parts by the foregoing attributes. the thought in discourse. 8 1 The Process Illustrated. Construction. — Suppose we choose for our theme a particular human eye. i. The primary law requires that we fix at the out- set a definite aim. Let this be to instruct. More specifically, let it be to produce a full and accurate knowledge of the object chosen, — not a mere picture or general conception of it. This presupposes on the part of the hearer or reader a mind so fully developed that there need be but little concern about adapting to its method of thought, with the exception that the person addressed is supposed to have but a vague knowledge of the object. His knowledge of the eye, in the case assumed, is not sufficient to warrant a strictly logical method of procedure. 2. That the law of unity may be followed, the next step is a statement of the unifying idea. The purpose being to instruct under the conditions named, the uni- fying idea is found in the intellectual relations of the object. The aim stated above requires us to choose the highest bond of union, which is that of the purpose of the eye. 3. The third step is to present this eye as a whole by means of its attributes, under the laws of selection, completeness, and method. The attributes selected, their number, and their arrangement are determined by the purpose of the description already fixed, and also by the unifying idea chosen for the eye itself. The attributes must be united into the whole by showing how each adapts the eye to its purpose. 82 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 4. The fourth step is the presentation of the parts of the eye, as they adapt it to its purpose. This involves two steps : — a. The basis on which the eye is to be divided must first be selected. This has already been determined by the unifying idea chosen for the eye, — namely, that of its purpose. The parts given must be made on their fundamental relation to the whole. The purpose of this eye is to form an image so as to produce the sensation of vision. The relation of the parts to this purpose must determine the parts selected, and the completeness and method of their presentation. b. The second step is the organization of the parts into the whole out of which they have just been made. This requires that the attributes of each part must be given according to the laws for presenting the attri- butes of the whole, — that is, that all those attributes be selected which adapt each part to its use in the object, and that they be presented according to the general law of presenting attributes of a whole. For the purpose of testing our description by the laws, the matter may be formulated as in the following outline. For the sake of brevity, much is omitted which can readily be supplied. Only two parts are given, leaving the others to be filled out by these ex- amples. The outline, however, is sufficiently full and accurate to illustrate what an outline of this eye should be, and what is better than a full description for test- ing the organization of the matter under the laws of thought. Purpose — an organ of vision. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 83 I. Attributes of the whole adapting to the purpose. 1 . Position — In cavity of orbit in upper front part of head ; thus securing (1) range of vision, and (2) protection. 2. Form — spherical; thus securing (1) ease of adjust- ment, and (2) firmness. 3. Size — about one inch in diameter. (Why?) 4. Firm and hard, to maintain the proper adjustment of parts. II. Parts of the whole which adapt to the purpose. 1. The outer coat of the eye. a. Sclerotic coat. (1) Purpose — to give form and protection, and to furnish means of attachment for the muscles. (2) Attributes adapting to its purpose : (a) Position — external posterior part, thus enclosing the other organs and admit- ting light in front. (b) Form — a hollow sphere, with an ante- rior opening to admit light, and a posterior one for the optic nerve. (c) Size — five sixths of globe, as required by openings named ; and one twenty- fifth of an inch thick in posterior part, but thinner in middle portion. (d) Dense, hard, firm, and fibrous, to pre- serve form, support inner parts, and to furnish attachments for the muscles. (e) White and smooth on outer surface, ex- cept at point of insertion of muscles ; inner surface brown and grooved. b. Cornea. (1) Purpose — (a) with sclerotic coat, protect ; (b) but while protecting must transmit light ; (c) incidental to its other functions, to re- fract light. 84 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. (2) Attributes adapting to its purpose. («) Position — front part of eye continuous with sclerotic coat. (Why ?) (£) Form —circular, and concavo-convex. (Why ?) (c) Size — one sixth of outer surface of eye, one thirtieth of an inch in thickness. (Why ?) (</) Hard, dense, fibrous, unyielding. (Why?) (^) Transparent, to admit light. c. Choroid coat, and ciliary processes. (Fill out as above.) d. Retina. (Fill out as above.) e. Aqueous humor, crystalline lens, and vitreous humor. (Fill out as above.) 2. The inner parts of the eye. (Treat as the outer coat is treated above.) After filling out the remainder of this outline, it should be tested systematically by all the preceding laws. For example, under the law of method, the reason for presenting the attributes and parts in the order as outlined should be given. The parts are not presented in a strictly logical order, for the retina and not the sclerotic coat is the functional center of the eye. And that the work of the retina may be done, refracting media are required ; and these again call to their aid the light-regulating parts ; and the whole of the image-forming parts require protecting outer coats. The retina is most immediate to the purpose of the eye ; and each part, in the order last named, is removed in that order one degree further from the immediate purpose of the eye. Such an order would be the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 85 strictly logical order of presentation, but this would not be the easiest order for the mind's movement under the circumstances specified at the outset. A strictly logical order is from within outward, but the mind assumed to be addressed in this case requires the reverse procedure, — a procedure in the order of observation, which would be first an observation of the external coat of the eye, when, removing the external coat, the next coat would be examined, and so on till the retina is reached. This may be called the chrono- logical, as over against the logical, order. This illus- trates clearly how the two factors, mind and object, determine the method of procedure. The other laws should be tested as above. The end sought in the preceding example is that of instruction. Suppose the end be changed to that "of moving the will ; for instance, to induce to proper care of the eye ; what change would be made in the fore- going outline, in respect to selection, completeness, and method of presenting attributes and parts, — changes in obedience to the new end, and the new unity set up ? With this in view let the outline be rewritten. Now rewrite the outline for the purpose of making a poetic description. For further illustration choose an autumn scene, and make an outline of it for the purpose of mere in- struction. Now change the purpose to that of arous- ing a sense of melancholy. The unifying idea will now be this particular feeling. The attributes, ob- jects, and relations chosen must be such as to contrib- ute to this effect, — must be unified in this effect, 86 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. with which the more fundamental attributes of position, form, size, etc., may have little to do. Sober colors and melancholy sounds fill the requirement under selection ; and these, with the dull objects enumerated, are presented in the order of their power to excite the desired emotion, without regard to their logical relation. The precision, rigidity, and fullness of the preceding examples would here violate every law of discourse. If the writer desire to move the will, the means of securing unity through selection, completeness, and method are further changed. Then he must select as many and such points as will have power to control the choice, and present them in such an order as will progressively influence to action. In order to stir the feelings to the point of action, the writer may have to delay the movement with otherwise unimportant and minute details. His skill will be measured by his power to hold the mind in contemplation of exciting details and stimulating circumstances. Thus, with every change in the purpose of the de- scription, there must be a change in the means of secur- ing unity through selection, completeness, and method. Purpose in the intellect, in the sensibility, in the will requires, respectively, unity in thought, unity in emo- tion, unity in volition; and in each case, the law of unity makes a different demand on the kind, number, and arrangement of attributes and parts. Interpretation. — Suppose the " stronghold" (a coun- try home), in " The Legend of Sleepy Hollow," be selected for analysis. The selection must first be perused to find the purpose of the author, or the effect THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 87 which the selection produces on the reader. This is the reverse of construction, for in this the attributes and parts selected must first be observed in order to infer the purpose. This step having been taken, we are ready to organize the description under the pur- pose and principle of unity discovered, which may be shown as follows : — I. Purpose. — To touch the emotions for their own sake, spe- cifically, pleasure in contemplating physical comfort and security. II. Unity. — The scene in its attributes and parts must be so presented as to stimulate this particular emotion. III. The Scene as the author presents it. Purpose of Scene. — Physical security and comfort, given by the author in the word " stronghold," as if a defence against an enemy. This word is the key-note to the selection. 1. Attributes of the whole, adapting to the purpose. a. Spatial relations. (1) Position — on bank of the Hudson. (Rela- tion to purpose and unity ?) (2) Form — a recess, "a nook," a nest-like place. (Relation to purpose and unity?) (3) Size — small. (Relation to purpose and unity ?) b. Qualities. (1) Sheltered. (Relation to purpose and unity?) (2) Fertile. (Relation to purpose and unity?) (3) Green. (Relation to purpose and unity ?) 2. Parts with their attributes which adapt to the purpose. a. The broad branching elm making shade ; spring of softest and sweetest water; sparkling rivulet; bub- bling brook. Each object with its attribute sug- gesting comfort and pleasure. 88 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. b. The barnyard — the barn, large and bursting with treasures ; constant sound of flail ; lively swallows and martins, and pigeons enjoying sunshine; un- wieldy porkers; troops of pigs; squadrons of snowy geese; fleets of ducks; regiments of turkeys; guinea fowls ; chickens. An abundance of objects with attributes contributing to comforts of life. c. The house — spacious ; piazza closed in bad weather, under which flails, harness, utensils of husbandry, spinning-wheel and churn, and benches for sum- mer use ; the hall with resplendent pewter, huge bag of wool, quantity of linsey-woolsey, ears of corn, festoons of apples, peaches, and peppers ; the parlor with claw-footed chairs, mahogany tables ; irons, shovels and tongs, glistening through asparagus tops ; mock oranges and conch shells ; strings of bird's eggs, a great ostrich egg ; an open cupboard displaying immense treasures of silver and china — taste added to comfort — refined abundance. Purpose and unity are here well carried out, since, — i. Those attributes of the whole, and those parts, with such attributes of each part as cause a solid sense of comfort in living, are always chosen, thus obeying the law of selection. 2. Enough of such attributes and parts are given to produce a highly wrought feeling of the kind sought, thus obeying the law of completeness. 3. The elements are presented in the order of effec- tiveness ; and also, in the natural order of observation. (1) The general background of the whole, producing a vague sense of comfort ; and, also, that upon which the eye viewing the scene would first rest ; (2) the spring 4- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 89 and the tree being less essential to physical comfort than what follows, but prominent to the eye encom- passing the scene ; (3) the barnyard, the raw material of comfort in abundance ; (4) the house in which com- fort is realized, and also neatness and good taste are manifested. Thus the law of method is followed. Exercises. — Skill in description comes from much and varied practice under the laws above set forth. And thus too will come a fuller realization of the theory for its own sake. In the following exercises, whether of construction or interpretation, let always the exact effect to be produced, and the conditions under which it is to be produced, be first stated. This must be followed by a statement of the unifying principle, after which the secondary laws are to be systematically applied. Let it be noted in each case also that while the law of completeness must be obeyed, a descrip- tion consistent with the purpose must be as brief as possible. I. Analyze the following brief descriptions: — 1. "A mild, meek, calm, little man." 2. "A rough-looking, sunburnt, soiled-shirted, odd, middle-aged little man." 3. " A mosquito — a horrid, pungent, satanic little particle." 4. " Randall — round-shouldered, bulky, ill-hung devil, with a pale, sallow skin, black beard, and a sort of grin upon his face." 5. "The blue jay, that noisy coxcomb, in his gay, light-blue coat and white underclothes, screaming and chattering, nodding and bobbing and bowing and pretending to be on good terms with every songster of the grove." 6. " It was a fine autumnal day, the sky was clear and serene, and nature wore that rich and golden livery which we always 90 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. associate with the idea of abundance. The forests had put on their sober brown and yellow, while some trees of the tenderer kind had been nipped by the frosts into brilliant dyes of orange, purple, and scarlet. Streaming files of wild ducks began to make their appearance high in the air; the bark of the squirrel might be heard from the grove of beech and hickory trees, and the pensive whistle of the quail at intervals from the neighboring stubble, fields." 7. " He was tall, but exceedingly lank, with narrow shoulders, long arms and legs, hands that dangled a mile out of his sleeves, feet that might have served for shovels, and his whole frame most loosely hung together. His head was small, and flat at top, with huge ears, large green glassy eyes, and a long snipe nose, so that it looked like a weather-cock perched upon his spindle neck, to tell which way the wind blew. To see him striding along the profile of a hill on a windy day with his clothes bagging and fluttering about him, one might have mistaken him for the genius of famine descending upon earth, or some scarecrow eloped from a cornfield." 8. " Brussels, a city, capital of Belgium, on the river Senne, 27 miles S. of Antwerp; pop. (with suburbs) 391,000, or about two thirds as large as Brooklyn, N. Y. It is the most important city of Belgium, and one of the finest in Europe. It was once sur- rounded by walls, but they have been made into broad boulevards, lined with double rows of shade trees. Brussels is noted for splendid public buildings, palaces, and churches, and its libraries, museums, galleries, botanical gardens, and observatory. It is also famous for the manufacture of Brussels lace, and for fine linens, damasks, jewelry, porcelain, and glass." 9. " Up from the meadows rich with corn, Clear in the cool September morn, The clustered spires of Frederick stand Green-walled by the hills of Maryland. Round about them orchards sweep, Apple and peach tree fruited deep, Fair as the garden of the Lord To the eyes of the famished rebel horde." THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 91 II. Select and analyze other examples which flash quickly but vividly beautiful or picturesque objects on the mind. In the daily reading mark descriptions of exceptional merit. III. Practice, orally and in writing, impressing viv- idly but quickly, pictures of objects, having fixed in mind the purpose and the conditions. Analyze the examples thus made. IV. Present the following by merely analyzing each into its parts, having first decided on the purpose and the basis of division. 1. A heart. 2. A door. 3. A watch. 4. A thermometer. 5. An apple. 6. A house. 7. A ship. 8. A steam-engine. 9. A human body. 10. A bird. 11. Greece. 12. South America. 13. A landscape. 14. A school. 15. A literary society. 16. A legislature. 17. Select and present many objects quickly, as they appear at once to the eye. V. Present the following by comparison and con- trast, assuming sometimes one of the pairs to be known and used as a means of presenting the other which is the theme, and sometimes assume both to be equally well known. Sometimes also present all the likenesses first, and then the differences, and some- times present likenesses and differences alternately. 1. An orange and an apple. 2. The Mississippi and the Amazon rivers. 3. Chicago and New York. 4. The earth and Jupiter. 5. South America and Africa. 6. Demosthenes and Cic- ero. 7. Washington and Lincoln. 8. Grant and Napoleon. 9. The government of England and that of the United States. 10. The civilization of ancient Greece and that of the United States at present. 92 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. VI. In a more elaborate way, having chosen a definite purpose and specified definite conditions, de- scribe the following objects and analyze the following descriptions, making outlines as that given for the eyeball and the " Stronghold." i . A lead pencil. 2. A penknife. 3. An apple. 4. An orange. 5. A heart. 6. An umbrella. 7. A river. 8. A mountain. 9. A ship. 10. A steam-engine. n. A real landscape. 12. A scene suggested by a picture. 13. An imaginary scene. 14. The village of Grand Pre", in "Evangeline." 15. A scene from " Snow Bound." 16. An invented scene to illustrate private life in some locality. 1 7. An invented scene of sublimity and gran- deur. 18. An invented scene of the picturesque. 19. An invented scene of simple beauty. 20. Lowell's description of the brook in " The Vision of Sir Launfal." 21. Johnson's description of the Happy Valley in " Rasselas." 22. Mark Twain's description of the Coyote. NARRATION. Narration is the process by which one mind presents to another, through language, an individual as changing in time — as having successive attributes and parts. Narration and description are alike in that both deal with individuals; they differ in that narration presents the individual as it exists at successive moments of time, while description presents the individual as it exists at a single moment of time. Both processes present the same object, but each presents it under different relations. Description presents it as a whole with its attributes and parts coexisting, fixed in their relation to each other and the whole — the statical relation; while narration presents the object as a whole with its attributes and parts changing in time under some force — the dynamical relation. Narration is truer to the object, for it is the nature of things to change. Every object, in " fulfilling its own nature, passes out from its own nature." Hence, the process of narration brings us more closely into the real nature of the object — into the moving force which is its life and being. A striking contrast between narration and descrip- tion is found in the relation of each to language. It was observed in description that words succeed each other in time, while the attributes and parts of the object coexist; and that language is not so well adapted 94 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. as painting or sculpture to present the outer unity of a fixed object. But this is reversed in narration, for words follow in order of time as do events; and thus in narration language has an advantage over painting and sculpture, corresponding to the advantage which these have over language in description. Narration and description are alike in their primary laws. While the leading conception in description is that of a fixed unit, in narration it is that of a changing unit. Yet the object must still be presented as a unit, and the law of unity prevails in narration as in descrip- tion. The unity is found in the changes of the theme, and the problem is to present the changes so that they will be unified in the object narrated. When the object is presented for its own sake, the law of unity is found in the necessary relations involved in the change; but when the object is presented to please or to move the will the changes must be unified in their effects to those ends. Thus purpose and unity, controlling the thought relations under which the theme is presented, are the primary laws in narration, as they are in description. While the object is changing, it still has coexisting attributes and parts, and these must be held in mind while the object is viewed as changing. There can be no conception of a changing unit without involving the conception of the unit as fixed at successive moments in the process of change. The object, at any mo- ment, must consist of such attributes and parts as were given in description. At this moment the growing orange consists of a given form, size, flavor, odor, and THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 95 parts; and without conceiving these as coexisting it is impossible to think the next change it may undergo. An object cannot be presented in the act of change. The change is inferred from a comparison of the object at a given moment with itself at a succeeding or a pre- ceding moment. It is presented to the mind at a given moment by a process of description, and then at the succeeding moment by the same process. It thus appears that description is an essential part of the process of narration. But so intent is the mind on the changes which the object is undergoing, that the descriptive phase of narration is carried on uncon- sciously and informally; and it does not necessarily rise to the rank of a subordinate process. In most narrations, however, there are prominent descriptive parts, many of which are of great length. In the story of one's travels, a description of the scenery may con- stitute the larger part; yet the story is narration, for the scenery is given to present the changes in the traveler's experience. "Childe Harold," as a whole, is a narration, while it is chiefly composed of descriptive parts. In the narration of a battle, it is necessary to state how things appear to the eye before the onset. Irving' s story, " The Widow and Her Son," is neces- sarily interspersed with distinct descriptive parts. This element is so prominent in some narrations that it requires a second thought to decide to which class the discourse belongs. This cannot be decided by the relative amount of space given to description ; but only by ascertaining whether the writer intended to leave the impression of a fixed or of a changing object. g6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. The first step in narration is that of presenting The Change as a Whole. It has already been observed that the conception of change in an object is the fundamental conception in narration. The idea of the change as a whole involves the following conceptions; and the presenta- tion of these conceptions is the first step in the narration of an object. Purpose. — A conception of change involves the idea of end, or purpose, which the change is to accomplish. Purpose, prompting and guiding every movement, is both the beginning and the end of every movement. The need of a reaper is felt, and this prompts the purpose to satisfy the need through an invention. This purpose institutes a series of changes in the object to meet the need which prompted to the purpose. Hence, it may be said that purpose is the moving force in a series of changes, and that in narration, as in de- scription, it is the most fundamental thought relation. Because it determines and explains every change, it is usually the first relation presented. Even when there is no conscious purpose we understand that there is some force moving to an end, in which the moving force is satisfied. Time. — A conception of change involves also the idea of time, as a conception of attributes and parts in the fixed object involves the idea of space. A change cannot take place except in time, and cannot be pre- sented to the mind without its time relations. There- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 97 fore time, answering the questions when and how long, is one of the fundamental thought relations in narration. Time is necessary not only to explain the relation of each event to every other in a series, but also to ex- plain the entire change with reference to other events. An event in history may be accounted for by its rela- tion in time to preceding or succeeding events. In fact, it cannot be explained without this relation. The relations of preceding, succeeding, and during, one or all, are absolutely essential to the explanation of an event. Cause and Effect. — The changes in objects are produced by causes ; and the changes themselves pro- duce effects. Every conception of a change involves the idea of cause and effect. To think the manufac- ture of a lead pencil, the growth of a tree, the devel- opment of character, or the progress of civil liberty, requires, as an element in the conception, the forces operative in each case to produce the changes, and also the results produced. Therefore the ideas of cause and effect must be employed in the narration of an object. Likeness and Difference. — Every conception of a change involves a comparison and contrast of the object with itself at a preceding or a succeeding moment. This relation is not only essential to the conception of a change, but it is used, as in descrip- tion, to facilitate the thought processes under all the other relations. Well-known events may be used to explain events under discussion. This not only shortens the narrative process, but it deepens the 98 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. impression. For this reason two events equally well known may be compared and contrasted with great advantage. Changes may be compared under all the foregoing relations — purpose, time, cause, and effect ; and also the parts. Which relation shall be selected to be thus presented is determined by the purpose of the narration as a whole. Whether two battles be compared as to purpose, time, cause, effect, or parts, is determined when it is decided whether the purpose is to instruct, — and what the grade of instruction, — whether to excite the emotions, or to stimulate to action. The law of purpose and unity requires such relations to be chosen in the comparison and con- trast as will best accomplish the end sought in the narration. The second step in narration is that of presenting The Change in its Parts. The parts in narration are the changes which con- stitute the change as a whole. They fill out the time whole, as the parts in space fill out the space whole in description. This is the most prominent relation in narration. Changes thrust themselves on the at- tention. They may be seen and heard, in most cases, while the other relations reveal themselves only to thought. It is easy to picture the panorama of events in a battle ; but the causes, results, and purposes can be ascertained only by reflection. It is more difficult to obey the law of unity in parti- tive narration than in partitive description, from the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 99 fact that time is a continuous quantity, while a space object is discrete. Hence, the divisions in time are more or less arbitrary, while in space objects nature makes the divisions. The shifting of a dividing line in time one hundred years in history will often do no violence to the purpose of the narration. Because there are no distinct separations in time, which the mind requires for convenience in thinking, an artificial system is adopted ; and the divisions of time by the calendar, satisfying in the sharpness of its boundaries, stand ready made to cut events into parts of definite and convenient length. But whether this arbitrary exact- ness or some inner moving principle be adopted as the basis, will be determined by the purpose of the narra- tion. If the history of England be narrated to show the course of civil freedom, the law of purpose would be violated in choosing the reigns of kings as the basis of separation. This is a proper basis if, instead of their inner life, the external phase of the movement is desired. For common purposes of narration, the external separation of events by some accidental accompaniment, as the above, is desirable and proper; but for the highest purpose, those phases which mark the progress of the moving principle in the realization of itself must be chosen as the basis. In such a move- ment there are no definite boundaries, and to make the arbitrary distinction of date or king control the presentation is to do violence to the purpose. The picturesque phases of things may well mark the divi- sions of a child's history ; but in tracing for the mature the movement towards spiritual freedom, the IOO THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. division must be made on the basis of the relation of occurrences to that end. Not only is the law of unity difficult to obey because the parts are vaguely and indefinitely marked, — because all are as unfixed and restless as the waves of the sea, — but because the changes are infi- nitely complex ; and yet all must be seen as organic parts of one complex whole. When there is but a single line of events in the movement the law of unity presents but little difficulty. The difficulty arises when there is a complex series of events to be ex- hibited in their interrelations, — " when concurring streams of events have to be exhibited as contempo- raneous in order to show their actual relations." In carrying up each line to unite it into the general movement, some events will necessarily be named after those before which they occurred. In the Revolutionary War, a series of events were happening in the South parallel with another series in the North ; and both were parts of the same movement. Both series cannot be narrated at once ; yet that they are parallel must ever be kept before the mind, together with the purpose and cause-and-effect relations of each to the other. Especially difficult is the narration of a conflict. The narrator must be careful not to shift carelessly from one party to the other. The movement is in neither party, but in the conflict between the two. To stand above this conflict and hold steadily the attention on both parties at the same time in the movement is the requirement of unity. To this end the narrator may have to locate the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. IOI attention in one party, as in the aggressive one, and hold it there while drawing the other party into the movement. If the attention needs to be shifted, it must be done so that the reader or hearer will be aware of the change. The law of unity further requires that the changes in the theme be presented in the order of their occur- rence — in the chronological order. Sometimes it may be desirable to violate the actual order of events. Irving introduces the reader to the funeral of the " Pride of the Village," and then narrates her life. Thus also in "The Widow and Her Son." This method serves as a kind of introduction to enlist the reader's interest in what is to follow. But in such cases the writer really follows a chronological order ; for he presents the events in the order of learning them. It is a common fault, especially in ex tempore narra- tion, to reverse the order of events, even when there is only a single line ; thus making it necessary to correct by retracing. The movement should be con- stantly forward ; otherwise the mind of the interpre- ter is kept on a strain readjusting the parts. But when there is a large complex whole, with lines run- ning parallel, yet related to each other, to obey the law of unity requires a conscious effort on the part of the writer. If language permitted all the lines to be carried along together, there would be no more diffi- culty than there is in narrating a single line of events. But this cannot be done, and the only question is, How far shall each be followed up before another is 102 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. begun, and how can their parallelism be indicated ? Each line may be carried through, and then all related into the whole; or one line may be followed out for a short distance, and then dropped to take up another, fixing the relations as the parts progress. Which is better the circumstances will determine. In either case the reliance must be in a firm grasp on the rela- tion of the parts to each other and to the whole ; so that whatever course is pursued, the unifying idea may be held constantly and steadily before the mind. The foregoing thought movement constitutes a uni- versal outline for the process of narration. The. object to be narrated: — I. As a whole under the relations of i. Purpose. 2. Time and place. 3. Cause and effect. 4. Likeness and difference. II. As composed of parts. 1. Analysis into parts by the laws of partition. 2. Each part presented under the relations of the whole. To narrate an object is to set it forth under these relations. Which of them to choose, and the order and completeness with which they shall be presented are determined by the purpose and the conditions under which the effect is to be produced. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. IO3 The Process Illustrated. Construction. — Suppose we are to construct a narra- tion on the subject, " The Stamp Act." 1. First applying the law of purpose, let it be deter- mined to give definite instruction ; not simply popular information, but accurate, systematic knowledge of the subject, — the scientific grade of narration. Only so far here, hov/ever, as necessary to illustrate the process. 2. The law of unity requires the process to be bounded, and the unifying idea determined upon. The time, the place, or the means to the changes might be selected, but our purpose requires the most funda- mental unifying idea, — namely, that of the purpose of the changes. This must be followed by the relations of time, place, cause and effect. These define the process as a whole, as conditioned by the determining purpose. 3. Next, the parts of the whole must be given as determined by the relation of the changes to the pur- pose. The parts must be the changes in the one change which the purpose manifests in the progress of its realization. 4. Lastly, the parts must be shown in their organic relation to the whole change. This will involve for each part the thought relations under which the whole process was viewed. Formulating for the purpose of testing the process it stands thus : — 104 TH E SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. i. Purpose of the Stamp Act. — To secure a revenue from the colonists ; to make the colonists help pay the expenses of the government of England because it had helped them fight against other nations. 2. Time — spring of 1 765. 3. Place — British Parliament. 4. Cause. a. Desire to establish the right of taxing the colonists. b. Knowledge of the disposition of the colonists to resist any attempt to collect a tax in the ordinary way. 5. Effect. a. On the part of the Americans. (1) Made them want representation in the parlia- ment. (2) Aroused indignation because they were not given representation. (3) Colonists refused to use the stamps. (4) Expressed their indignation in many ways. b. On the part of the British. (1) Were compelled to repeal the act. (2) They sought other ways of taxing the colonists. 6. Parts. a. The discussion of the plan of taxation. ( 1 ) The necessity of the revenue from the colonists. (2) The belief that the colonists should be taxed without the consent of their legislatures. (3) The advantages of putting the tax in the form of stamps. (a) The ease and certainty of its collection. (b) The difficulties of resisting its collection. (c) The low price of the stamps. b. The passage of the act. (1 ) Time ; (2) place; (3) effect. c. Enforcing the act. ( 1 ) Time. (2) Place. (3) Effect, (a) In America ; (b) in England. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. IO5 It will be readily observed that the course pursued is true to the purpose of writing stated at the outset. If the points were amplified, as they should be in a regular treatment of the subject, the reader would gain accurate, systematic knowledge of the subject. The intellect would be informed, rather than the emotions aroused or the will moved. Unity is secured by choosing the adequate unifying idea of purpose. This gives a definite current to the movement at the outset. Unity is further secured by giving the space and time boundaries of the whole. Unity is further secured by presenting the changes in the order of their occurrence, and by organizing each change into the whole. The relations of the whole define the whole, and the subordinate parts are shown in their subordinate relations. Unity in this case is difficult to maintain, for there are parallel, co- ordinate movements, also, coordinate purposes, times, places, causes, and results. This difficulty is always found in narrating a conflict. Each of the parallel movements must be kept distinct from the others, and due notice must be given when the attention is to be transferred from one to the other of the coordinate relations or parts. Purpose and unity are obeyed by giving all the changes in the series. How far to carry out the changes into minute detail can be determined only by a more specific statement of the purpose and the conditions. Let the purpose in the above example be changed from instruction to emotional experience, and the use 106 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. of the material given in the outline would vary greatly from the above. The unifying idea would then be found in the emotions, and logical coherence would be largely disregarded. The thought relations would be left incomplete, the matter would be presented in the progressive order of its power over the emotions, exciting incidents would take the place of cause and effect, and completeness would be given to features now only touched upon. Interpretation. — Let the selection be " The Miller and His Son," in " Aesop's Fables." i. The purpose of the selection must first be ascer- tained. By a perusal of the selection it will be readily found that this purpose is to move the will, - — to cause the reader not to shape his conduct to suit the whims of other people. At first thought it may appear that the author intended only to instruct, — to teach the truth that he who tries to please everybody pleases nobody, and besides, loses something himself. But every one knew this before, and the full concrete form in which he presents an already well-known truth makes it clear that he wishes to impress a lesson to the end of resolution and action. 2. The example by which the writer sought to ac- complish his purpose is the mind of the miller. This he presents as changing ; hence he accomplishes his purpose by means of narration, but by the narrating of a fictitious event. The unity of the theme must be found in the changing mind of the miller. The other changes, as the mounting and alighting of the son and father, and the attempt to carry the donkey, are subor- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 107 dinate and external to the internal changes which ex- hibit the theme. The real changes are spiritual ; hence this belongs to the class of spiritual narrations. The attention in reading must rest in the series of spiritual changes, and if the writer obey the law of unity he must hold the attention to the spiritual series. This narration may be tested by casting it in the following form : — I. The changes as a whole. 1 . Purpose (in the miller) — to please those addressing him. 2. Place — on the road to market. This furnishes op- portunity for the causes of the changes. 3. Time — while going to market. This furnishes an- other opportunity for the change. 4. Cause — the miller's desire to please everybody. 5. Effect — pleases nobody and loses his donkey. II. The parts of the change. 1. The miller decides that his son ride. a. Purpose — to please the girls addressing him. b. Cause — a knowledge of what the girls thought. 2. The miller decides to walk and that his son ride. a. Purpose — to please the old man addressing him. b. Cause — a knowledge of what the old man thought. 3. The miller decides that both shall ride. a. Purpose — to please several who sympathized. b. Cause — a knowledge of what the sympathizers thought. 4. The miller decides that he and his son carry the donkey. a. Purpose — to please another group of sympa- thizers. b. Cause — a knowledge of what the group thought. IOS THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. This outline shows at once that unity is maintained, in that everything is subordinated to the one change in the miller's mind. And this, too, obeys the law of pur- pose, for it is the impression of these changes, with their results, by which the author seeks his purpose. The law of unity would have been violated in this if the physical changes had been made prominent, or if there had been a confusion of the two lines of changes. The author has kept the physical changes subordinate, since he presents them as mere signs, or effects, in the mind of the miller. In making the analysis, it would not have been true to the selection if there had been given as the first happening the mounting of the boy, etc., or the other external series on the part of those addressing the miller. In the analysis of every selection, there must be found and stated in clue form its unity of thought. Unity is further secured in first presenting the op- portunity for causes to produce the changes ; and then having purpose, cause and effect, and parts follow in their necessary order. This the anaylsis, if true, will properly set forth. Unity to the end sought further requires that enough changes be presented to accomplish the pur- pose, — enough to show that the miller would change to please anybody. The changes are invented, and the question for the writer was, How many are needed to produce the desired effect on the reader ? Four changes are presented. First, the change caused by the girls, who sympathized with the son ; second, that made by the old men, who appreciated THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. IO9 respect for old age ; third, the change caused by a miscellaneous group, whose sympathy is touched by the effort of the son to keep up ; and fourth, that caused by the townsmen, whose feelings were touched by the overburdened beast. What each caused the miller to do was that which led to some extreme, and called forth rebuke from the next group met. Being moved to change by such diverse classes of people and for such contradictory reasons makes it absolutely certain that the miller would change to please any one for no other reason than to please him. Note also that each decision of the miller was more foolish than the preceding. This continually increases the strength of the impression ; otherwise the last point would be useless, and the law of unity broken. Exercises. — I. Treat the following themes as wholes, either by construction or by analysis, as the case may require : — I. The Civil War. 2. Paul Revere's ride. 3. The Boston Tea Party. 4. Johnson's " Rasselas." 5. The battle of Bala- klava. 6. The history of the United States. 7. The Norman Conquest. 8. The World's Fair. 9. The conquest of Mexico. 10. The Lisbon earthquake. II. Treat the following by partition, being careful to note whether the basis chosen is in harmony with the purpose, and whether the law of unity is main- tained in the partitions made on the basis chosen: — 1. The manufacture of a pen. 2. The writing of an essay. 3. Whittier's " Snow Bound." 4. Longfellow's " Keramos." 5. The history of slavery in the United States. 6. The American Revolution. 7. England's acquisition of territory in the United IIO THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. States. 8. The formation of the earth. 9. The building of a ship. Also, Longfellow's "Building of the Ship." 10. The making of steel. III. Set forth briefly the following by comparison and contrast : — 1. The settlement of the Jamestown and Plymouth colonies. 2. The construction of the Pacific Railroad and the Suez Canal. 3. The election of the President of the United States and of France. 4. The manufacture of cotton and of silk goods. 5. The growth of a plant and an animal. 6. The history of the English and the American governments. 7. The writing of a discourse and build- ing of a house. IV. In a more complete and systematic way, defin- ing the purpose and testing by the law of unity, con- struct narrations, or analyze those already constructed, in the following themes. Make outlines : — 1. The circulation of the blood. 2. The "History of a Mouth- ful of Bread." 3. The story of an iceberg : (a) to instruct, (b) to touch the emotions. 4. The campaign of Burgoyne. 5. " The Wreck of the Hesperus," by Longfellow. 6. " King Vol- mer and Elsie," by Whittier. 7. The life of Franklin. 8. The changes of the seasons : (a) to instruct, (b) to excite the feeling, (c) to move the will. 9. A grape from the seed to a raisin. 10. Political freedom in England and America. 11. A story in- vented from a picture, to awaken pleasurable emotions. 12. A story invented to move the will. 13. The story of " Feathertop," by Hawthorne. 14. The process of learning the science and the art of narration. 15. "The Legend of Sleepy Hollow," by Irving. 16. The great Spanish Armada. 17. The story of a drop of water from its change into vapor in the ocean to its re- turn, — first to give instruction, and then to address the feelings. icS. The Sepoy rebellion. 19. The decay of Feudalism. 20. Shakespeare's " Hamlet." 21. Holmes' " One-Hoss Shay." EXPOSITION. Exposition is the process by zvliich one mind presents to another, through language, a general idea. The preceding processes hold the attention to par- ticular individuals, but exposition directs the attention to the unity of individuals through their common na- ture — their general idea. A description or a narra- tion of individuals may be made for the purpose of presenting their common element, and this is exposi- tion. But so long as the thought is organized in the individuals as such, the process is description or narra- tion. In the first case they become subordinate pro- cesses of exposition. Exposition may also be a subor- dinate process in description and narration. Whenever there is to be described a complex object, as the earth, it is necessary to treat the classes of objects on the earth; and this is exposition. In narrating the history of the United States, there must be an exposition of the classes of colonies that were established. But a description or a narration may be made without expo- sition, while an exposition cannot be made without in- volving, in some way, description or narration. It has already been shown that the theme in exposi- tion is a unit, a whole, consisting of parts; as is the case in description and narration. The whole is the number of individuals which the common idea, or gen- erative activity, binds together, or brings into existence. 112 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. As we have seen, a certain specified energy in a given form of activity produces individual triangles. The number of triangles thus produced form the whole, and the individual triangles are the parts. The producing activity, the common nature, of the individuals is called the content of the class, or general notion ; while the number of individuals thus produced and thus uni- fied is called the extent of the class, or general notion. Thus the content of a general idea is the sum of attri- butes common to a number of individuals, whose sum forms the extent of the idea. The content of the class quadruped is the sum of the attributes, sensation, vol- untary motion, vertebral structure, peculiar nervous and circulatory system, quadrupedal, etc., including whatever else may be found in each animal of that class. The number of animals containing this sum of common attributes forms the extent of the class quadruped. The mind, in thinking the content of a class, must at the same time think the individuals in which the content finds its concrete being, — must think the extent of the class. The content of a class determines its extent. One bears an inverse ratio to the other. If the class ani- mal has for its content the sum of the two attributes sensation and voluntary motion, and a third attribute be added, say warm-blooded, thus increasing the con- tent, the extent is decreased by having to drop from the idea animal the cold-blooded animals. With each addition of a new attribute to the content, there is a subtraction from its extent, — a subtraction of the number not having the attribute added. Continuing THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I 1 3 a this process the richest content would be reached in the least extent, which is the individual. The content thus determines the class whole or the class unity, and the first step in exposition corresponds to that in de- scription and narration, — namely, the presentation of the theme as a whole by means of its attributive content. The Content of the Theme. The content of a general idea consists of two rela- tions — the universal and the particular, or its like- nesses to and its differences from other ideas. If we take from this particular book all the attri- butes it has in common with other books, or in com- mon with any other class of objects, we have destroyed our thought of the book. If we should take from the class book all the attributes common to books only, our thought of book is likewise destroyed. Again, if we should take from this particular book all the attri- butes peculiar to it, or from the class book all the attributes peculiar to it as a class, we have destroyed our thought of this book and the class book. Thus every object or idea has its being in the union of the two relations of particular and universal. Therefore, exposition, in presenting the content of a class, or general idea, must do so through these two relations. These two relations are formally presented by the pro- cess of Defitiition. — Definition is the process of presenting to another mind the content of a class by a statement of the universal and the particular truth of that class. 114 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. The universal truth is presented in definition by re- ferring the class to be defined to the known larger class of which it is a part. Whenever an object or a class is said to be in a larger class, however small the larger class, a connection is established with the uni- verse. To say that a noun is a substantive is to say that it is the arbitrary expression of an object, and to say this is to say that it is the arbitrary expression of an idea, which further implies that it at least is the expression of an idea. Now this last fact is true of every object in the universe. All express thought. Nothing can be correctly defined without connecting it with the sun, moon, and stars, and the definitions which have power to the student are those in which he can feel his way back to, is conscious of, the universal element. This reference of an idea to a larger whole is only a concise and an abbreviate form of giving the universal. Otherwise the universal elements would have to be enumerated. It follows from what has been said that the larger class to which reference is made must be a known class, and such as will give the clearest and fullest no- tion of the class defined. Reference is made to the known class to abbreviate the process ; but if this class need explanation, the purpose is defeated. For the same reason, the class to which reference is made should have the greatest content, and therefore the least extent of any class to which reference can be made. Reference is made to the larger class to save enumerating and explaining common attributes of the class defined ; and the greater the number found in the THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I I 5 larger class, the greater is the economy. For instance, in defining a pronoun it may be referred to the class words or to the smaller class substantives. The choice will be determined first by which is better known ; second, by which has the greater content. If the substantive has been previously defined, it must be selected, because it contains one more attribute in common with the pronoun than does the class words. In saying that a pronoun is a word is saying only that it expresses an idea ; but in saying that it is a substantive is saying that it expresses an idea of an object. There is no exception to the rule that the class de- fined must be referred to a larger class ; yet nothing is more common than for statements which look like defi- nitions to lack this quality : as, " A preposition shows relation." Not what a thing shows, how it looks, or what it does, but what it is, must be the form of every definition; what are its connections with the universal truth out of which it springs. The universal truth having been presented, the truth which gives to the class its particular, separate being must follow. This truth consists of the sum of the particular, but common, attributes of the indi- viduals in the class to be defined. It will be readily seen that these common attributes which bind the in- dividuals into a class are also those which separate the class- defined from the whole to which it is referred. If these common attributes had been found in the larger class, they would have been exhausted in the reference to that class. So that the attributes here to Il6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. be given both unite the individuals of the class and separate them from all other individuals. Summing up, we have the following rule for making a definition: — First, present the universal nature of the class by referring it to the smallest known class of which it is a part. Second, present the particular nature of the class by stating the common, essential attributes which bind the individuals together, and which, at the same time, distinguish the class from the whole of which it is a part. Definition being a statement of unity among indi- viduals, the law of unity here is exacting, and its vio- lation can be definitely detected. This law requires that, in defining, none but common attributes be given. If an attribute be given which belongs only to a part of the class, two classes are presented instead of one. For instance, " A verb is a word that expresses action, state, or being." Action does not belong to all verbs, neither does state or being. If all the verbs of the language be taken and placed before us in groups as the foregoing definitions require, there would be three distinct groups. The attributes named in the definition should belong to each and every verb in the language, but to no other part of speech. When it is said that a verb expresses action, state, or being, other parts of speech are included, for other parts of speech may include the same ideas. But if it be said that a verb is a word that asserts, all other words are excluded. By giving an attribute which extends be- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. WJ yond the theme defined the theme is not unified in itself, but is unified in a larger whole, which should already have been done in giving its universal attri- bute by reference to some larger whole. A definition must unify the theme both in itself and with a larger whole. The former is done by specifying the attribute, or attributes, which unify the theme in itself. And in doing this the mark given must extend through all members of the class defined, but not to a single other object. The definition must be neither too narrow nor too broad. The ultimate test of every definition is whether it unify the theme defined, — unify it both in itself and with a larger whole. Since this double unity of the class is through its likenesses to and its differences from other classes, the class as a whole is also presented by means of Comparison and Contrast. — This is a double process of uniting the parts of the class into the whole, and of uniting the class with a larger whole. This process either follows and explains definition, or precedes and prepares the way for the definition. In the order of learning, comparison and contrast precedes definition. Classes can be formed in the mind only by comparing and contrasting the individuals which are to compose it. Comparison and contrast is the initiative process in classification. By it, the likenesses and differences are sifted out, and thus the mind arrives at the unity of the class in itself, and its unity through common attributes with larger wholes. The law of unity in comparison and contrast re- quires the choice of only such attributes of the objects Il8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. compared and contrasted as will exhibit the common attributes of all the individuals of the class. This law would be violated if in comparing and contrasting verbs with prepositions, verbs should be contrasted with pre- positions in the fact that some verbs express attributes, while prepositions do not. This violates unity because the verb is thus divided into two classes, and only one part contrasted with prepositions. There would be the same violation of unity in saying that verbs and adverbs are alike in that both express attributes, since only one class of verbs do so. Therefore, whenever two classes are to be compared, the attributes chosen, in respect to which the comparison is made, must be common to all the individuals of the class in which they are found. It has already been suggested that description and narration are subordinate processes of exposition. They aid definition and comparison and contrast in present- ing the content of the class. In this service description and narration present only such attributes of the indi- vidual as are common to the class to which the individual belongs. To this extent in exposition these processes are modified, and when thus modified are called Exemplification. - -Exemplification is the process of exposition by which the content of a class is presented through one or more individuals of the class. The class steamship may be presented by describ- ing the "Great Eastern"; suspension bridges, by the suspension bridge across the Niagara River; patriotism, by a particular example of the virtue in Lincoln ; the class triangle, by a particular triangle. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 119 This is the point of confluence of description and narration with exposition, and at this point it is some- times difficult to distinguish between them. When describing the eyeball, the purpose may be to present only what is true of the class, as is the case in a work on anatomy. Such is exposition by exemplification, and not a description of the individual for the sake of the individual. The process may seem identical with that of the description of the capitol at Washington, but in the first case the process, while it may hold the atten- tion to some particular eyeball, the end sought is knowledge of the class, for only that which is general is given in the particular ; while in the second case, the capitol, with all its peculiar attributes, is presented for its own sake. The capitol is not given as an ex- ample of anything, but is itself the thing given. Exemplification is the most common form of exposi- tion, because it has the advantage of presenting the general and the abstract in the concrete. Much that is usually classed under description and narration is exposition under the guise of these other processes. The novelist seems to be telling the story of a par- ticular character, but he is always expounding general truth. Shakespeare narrates the events in Shylock's conduct only to expound the profoundest law of life. Hawthorne's story, "The Bosom Serpent," is to set forth the universal effect of egoism in the human heart. When Aesop tells the story of " The Fox and the Grapes," he is revealing the universal nature of man. When a particular Australian is described we may expect to learn of an unfamiliar race, but a de- 120 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. scription of the President of the United States would probably have for its purpose a knowledge of the Presi- dent. Thus exemplification presents real or fictitious ex- amples. The fictitious example is made necessary from the fact that no real example is adequate to the ideal content to be presented. The real content or nature of a thing or person is hampered in the thing or person, and to present the real thing or person would necessarily fail to present the ideal and poten- tial nature of the class to be expounded. The real world of individual objects does not adequately reveal the world striving to manifest itself through the indi- vidual objects. This thought introduces another and the last process of setting forth the extent of a general idea, — namely, that of Idealization. — Idealization is the process by which an individual object is made adequate to an ideal con- tent or is harmonized with a universal content. We thus arrive at the peculiar phase of exposition which presents ideal truth as contrasted with matter-of-fact truth. The creative imagination now takes the place of the logical judgment, converting the real into the ideal, thus gratifying man's craving for the perfect, out of which arises poetic truth as distinguished from scientific truth. The poet's truth is created by the imagination from what is shadowed forth imperfectly in the real. The imagination in its passion for the perfect penetrates the object, and satisfies itself by adding, subtracting, and rearranging the elements until it contemplates the perfect, thus realizing the truest THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 121 truth. Let no one be disturbed by the statement that fiction is truer than truth, i.e. matter-of-fact truth. Let it be emphasized that the only thing fictitious in fiction or poetry is the individual in which the universal truth is embodied, and that in this process the content or meaning becomes more real because there is a closer approach to the essential truth. Poetic truth is not to be considered airy, fanciful, and unreal, while scientific truth is solid and substantial. Hence the poet idealizes to give his theme greater reality, intensity, and power. First he does this by omissions. For instance, patriotism, an emotion suitable for poetic purposes, when found in the indi- vidual, has elements which conflict with our idea of patriotism. To idealize is to omit them, and thus form a truer and a more pleasing idea. Love, a choice theme of the poet, does not receive a truthful, in the sense of true to the real, handling; whatever sensuous elements are found in the individual are omitted or toned down. The real pleasures of life have their alloy, but the poet strips them of their disenchanting element and we revel in the full fruition. We hold the poet responsible for high ideals: his power as a poet is largely measured by his power to idealize. Each of the emotions may have an element which clashes with our ideal of that emotion, as in the case of love with its gross and carnal element. Some poets use the carnal side, but in doing so sin against the laws of poetry and fine art in general. Each of the emotions arises by degrees out of the instinctive sen- suous emotions, and carries to some degree the lower 122 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. elements along with it. Friendship, in its earliest form, is instinctive and self-interested, and arises by degrees toward the ideal of a pure spiritualized virtue. The poet must give each emotion freedom from disen- chanting elements, that it may find a response from the reader's craving for the ideal. Not only by omissions does the imagination of the poet form the ideal, but by additions also. "Excep- tional states of elation " are made the rule, and what only has a momentary existence in fact is filled out and given a permanent place in the mind. The poet has the license of exaggeration, and may exalt the emo- tion to the highest power of imaginative conception. Circumstances may put limits to the exaggeration; it must not be carried to the degree of offensiveness, for it would then be opposed to poetic effect. The exag- gerations in the fictions of fairyland and mediaeval romance are pushed to the limit of the powers of the imagination without offending proprieties of taste; for they are understood to be indulgences of the imagina- tion, — freedom of the imagination, — sportful moods trampling down the laws of existence for the pleasure of its own free activity. When traits of a people are to be idealized, truth must be respected; but in the idealizing of the spiritual emotions, such as love, friendship, spiritual joy, philanthropy, or duty, no danger is likely to come from the strongest effort of the imagination. The evil passions may be idealized as well as the virtuous emotions, but in this case the poet adds insult to injury, unless done by way of con- trast. Any degree of idealization here is more offen- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 23 sive than the actual, either because it produces a stronger stimulant or because it renders more decep- tive by a goodly appearance the evil communicated. The laws of morality take care of this offense. The true poet needs only to guard himself against creating ideals which stimulate expectation which cannot be realized. It is dangerous to create ideals out of all relation to actual life to which we are chained, so that one breaks with his conditions and desperately and lawlessly strives to realize the unattainable. Ideals which are to inspire and to guide must not create despair or stimulate to the reckless methods of hope- less attainment. The overstimulation of expectation is only less dangerous than false ideals of life. Another form of dangerous exaggeration is that of making amiable and desirable certain weaknesses of human nature. The imagination selects and recombines elements into new wholes, thus adapting to the requirements of taste. As the parts of various landscapes may be brought by the painter into one more beautiful than any from which parts were selected, so the poet may select from various characters the most perfect ele- ments and recombine them into one more perfect than those out of which it was formed. In this way ideal characters are formed. The Extent of the Theme. As we have seen, the extent of a general notion is correlative to its content; either implies the other. The content, or germinant idea, must pass out into 124 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the diversity of individuals, while the individuals, to be members of a class, must inhere in the unity of a single principle. It is only a difference of emphasis. One emphasizes the unity and the other the diversity of the theme being considered. In one the thought moves from the individuals to their unity, in the other the thought moves from the unity to the individuals. Classes may be divided continually into classes of decreasing extent until the individual is reached, thus moving out from the unified conception of the whole, as given by the foregoing processes, to the complete diversity of the individuals which compose the class. The greater this variety the richer the concept. As the leading process of presenting the content of a class is definition, so the leading process of present- ing the extent of a class is Division. — This corresponds to the process of par- tition in description and narration, inasmuch as it pre- sents the parts of the whole. Ultimately the parts of a class arc the individuals which compose it; but divi- sion does not present the individuals as such, but the species and subspecies in classes, until the individual is arrived at. Thus division is like partition in that it presents the parts of the theme; it differs from parti- tion in that it presents the parts of the class, while partition presents the parts of the individual. They are further alike in that both are not merely processes of separation; both processes must bind the parts into the unity of the whole. Each part must, in both cases, be unified in the process of separation. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 125 The nature of the process requires the same unify- ing idea for each of the smaller classes into which the larger class is divided. It is unifying the individ- uals on a content less general than the whole class which makes the divisions of the class. Hence the basis on which the class is divided is also the basis on which each subclass is united. It is impossible to unite each subclass on a different basis, as well as im- possible to make the separation on different bases. For instance, let the class apples be given for subdi- vision. The individuals of one subclass cannot be bound together on the basis of color, those of another on the basis of size, and those of another on the basis of taste, etc. Let the effort be made with the actual apples, and it will readily be perceived why it cannot be clone in thought. But the class may be separated and the subclasses united on the one basis of color, or of taste, etc. Hence the law of unity in division requires that the same basis for separating the class and for uniting the individuals in each subclass be used. This main- tains the double unity of the whole and of each part. This law would be violated in dividing man into men, women, white, brown, black, savage, and civilized. It may be necessary to divide the class first on one basis and then on another. This may be done by notifying the reader of the change of basis, — as, on the basis of sex, man is divided into men and women ; on the basis of color, into white, brown, and black; and on the basis of culture, into savage, half-civilized, and civilized. But each division on the new basis destroys the division on 126 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the preceding basis. Trie mind cannot conceive the race as divided into men and women, and at the same time into white, brown, and black. The second divi- sion necessarily unmakes the first. This, however, does not violate the law of unity, for by stating the change in the basis, the mind is notified to destroy its old division. Thus, without violating the law of unity, the class may be divided on as many bases as the pur- pose may require. Divisions on different bases give variety and wealth to the concept. What basis to choose, and whether one or more, is determined by the purpose of the exposition. For political purposes, the states should be divided on one basis, for agricultural purposes on another, for ethnological purposes on still another. For some purposes, as that of definite, scientific instruction, the basis should be an essential attribute of the class ; but for giving popular information or for emotional purposes, the basis might have to be chosen from superficial and sensuous aspects of the theme. Comparison and contrast, and exemplification, aid division in setting forth extent as they do definition in setting forth content. The subclasses must be sepa- rated by differences and the individuals in each sub- class united by likenesses. Comparison and contrast is the formal process of doing this. The basis of di- vision determines the point of view from which to determine the likenesses and the differences. Thus, too, are the attributes of the individual to be given in exemplification determined. After the division is made and followed by compari- son and contrast, and exemplification, the way is pre- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 127 pared for a new definition, for each subclass becomes a new whole, — a whole just as the first class in the process is a whole, yet a part of a larger whole. Thus the process of exposition is an ever-recurring circle, which may be begun at any point and which will return to the point of beginning. The process may begin with definition and be followed up by comparison and contrast, and exemplification, until the class as a whole is clearly bounded and connected with some larger class. But examples may come first; these be- ing described or narrated, comparison and contrast pre- pares the way for definition. This latter process is the order of learning — the chronological order, while the former process is the logical order. Which shall be the method of procedure must be determined by the purpose of the exposition and the condition of the mind addressed. After one or the other of the forego- ing movements has been made, division will come next in order. Yet division may precede, reserving defini- tion for each of the subclasses. Definition must always follow division. Besides, exemplification, and comparison and contrast may precede, and prepare the way for, division, instead of following it. In fact, all processes move together until by necessity of formula- tion they must be thrown in a circle. It must be noted, however, that the movement is always back and forth from the individuals to the common principle which constitutes the individuals. This is the unity sought, and the foregoing describes the necessary movement of the mind in relating the two, — in seeing diversity in unity and unity in diversity. Neither can 128 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. be seen without the other. When the emphasis is on one the mind moves in one direction, and when on the other it moves in the other direction. We may now formulate the movement in exposition thus: — The General Notion to be Expounded. I. The content presented. 1. By definition. 2. By comparison and contrast. 3. By exemplification. 4. By idealization. II. The extent presented. 1. By division. 2. Each part treated as " I." The Process Illustrated. Construction. — Given the theme " Attributive Words." 1 . Let the purpose be to give instruction — defi- nite, scientific knowledge of the theme. 2. The unity of the individuals in the class is found in the content of the class, and this is set forth by definition, comparison and contrast, and exemplification. Definition. — Attributives are words which express attributes. The universal nature of attributives, that they express ideas, is given by referring them to the already known class, words. Thus the first law of defi- nition, which requires that the universal nature of the class to be defined be presented by its reference to the whole of which it is a part, is obeyed. Let it be ob- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 29 served that this is the smallest class to which it can be referred. To refer attributives to objects would be a violation of the law of unity, since attributives are more closely unified with a smaller known class. The particular nature of the class is given by stating what is expressed — attributes. This mark of attribu- tives uniting with the mark which connects attribu- tives with words forms the content of the class attributives. The first part of the definition — refer- ence to the whole — presents the idea of a symbol ex- pressing an idea; the second adds to the first the kind of idea — attributive. Symbols expressing attributive ideas is the full content. Unity is secured by the choice of one common attri- bute, instead of choosing two or three, some including one part of the class and some another. Suppose it had been said that attributives are words that modify nouns or verbs, and are used as predicates. While this is true, it is not a definition, for it does not present the nature of the class under discussion. It is not es- sential to the nature of attributives that they modify nouns; if so, all attributives would have to do so, which they do not do. Thus with the other two marks given. Besides, instead of unifying the parts of the class, it distributes them, thus violating the law of unity. Comparison and Contrast. — This class can be com- pared and contrasted with only two others — substan- tives and relatives, for these, with attributives, consti- tute the whole class called words. Attributives are like substantives and relatives in that they express ideas; they differ from substantives I30 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. in that substantives express objects, while attributives express attributes ; they differ from relatives in that relatives express relation, while attributives express attributes. In this comparison and contrast, the same mark of distinction is kept before the mind as presented in the definition, thus maintaining the unity of the whole, and further impressing the content of the class. Let it be observed that this process in its double form emphasizes both phases of the content — the universal in the comparison, the particular in the contrast. Exemplification. — In the sentence, " A timely sug- gestion was very kindly received," " timely," " kindly," and "was received" are attributives; each of them ex- presses an attribute. To call attention to the fact that "timely" expresses an attribute of an object, that " kindly " expresses an attribute of an attribute, and that " was received " expresses an attribute of an ob- ject and also asserts, would be to violate the law of unity, for it breaks the class by giving marks that be- long to different parts of it. None but the mark in each word which belongs to the class as a whole should be given. Under other conditions of instruction the order of employing the three foregoing processes might have been reversed. First, several words of this class might have been observed and described, then com- pared and contrasted, and then the contrast thus de- termined presented in a formal definition. Division. — Next the content of the class must be presented by the process of division. This must be THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I 3 I done so as to bind the parts together in the unity already established, - - that is, the unity of the class must be preserved in the process of division. The purpose being to give scientific knowledge of this subject, the basis of division must be the most fundamental attribute of the class. This, as stated by the definition, is expression. If there are subclasses they must be made on the basis of expression, if classes differing in this respect can be found. If not, some lower basis must be used. Observing many attributive words, some will be found which express attributes of objects, others which express attributes of attributes, and still others which express attributes and also assert the attribute. While attributives are united in what they express, they are separated by some special phase of that ex- pression. Thus there are three classes of attributives: (i) those which express attributes of objects, called adjectives ; (2) those expressing attributes of attri- butes, called adverbs ; (3) those expressing attributes and which assert, called attributive verbs. The unity of the class is here maintained (1) through the selection and use of one essential basis of division ; (2) through the giving of parts in the order of their relation, the attributive verb being farther removed from the adjective than is the adverb ; (3) through the enumeration of all the parts which the basis determines. This, followed with a treatment of each subclass as the whole was treated, completes the exposition of the class attributives. 132 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. However elaborate the exposition, the above, sim- ple as it is, presents its universal forms and laws. Whether the student is constructing the science of the adjective or of the animal kingdom, the process is the same. Interpretation. - — Suppose Whittier's " Maud Mul- ler " be selected for interpretation. 1. The selection must be read carefully to ascertain the purpose of the author, for his purpose pervades and controls everything that follows. The purpose in this is to touch the emotions — specifically, the uni- versal regret of the human heart, expressed in the words : — " For of all sad words of tongue or pen, The saddest are these : ' It might have been.' " 2. The theme, which sums up the unity of the whole, is the emotion of regret. The theme is general, not particular. He wishes to express the regret in every individual. Hence the process is that of exposition. The author does not proceed by the scientific pre- cision of logical definition and division. His purpose not only does not require this, but would be defeated if he should thus proceed. He follows the more con- crete method of exemplification. He chooses two examples from the class to be pre- sented — Maud and the Judge. This choice enables him to emphasize the extent of his theme, and yet pre- sent the extent in its unity; for he has chosen from the extremes of life, and represents each as passing over to find happiness in the conditions of the other. If THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 133 such regret is experienced by the extremes of life, it will the more certainly be found in the intermediate grades. This regret arose from a remembered vision of better things than had been attained. In this case, each dreams of happiness in the condition of the other. To give to this vague longing of each for the condition of the other specific point and poetic interest, each is represented as desiring to wed the other — to become one with the other. This desired union that each may secure his happiness in the condition of the other is a logical necessity of the situation. Thus the author does not simply present the extremes of life in order to carry with them the intermediate grades, but that he may express a phase of the general truth, namely, that each individual imagines happiness in the extreme of life farthest removed from himself, and if each could lose his identity in the other, happiness would follow. The bright dreams of each of the extremes not having been realized, and regret following from the contrast of the after life with the dream of youth, show the universality of regret arising from a contrast of the ideal with the real. The exemplification is carried on by the process of narration. The poem appears to be a narration, yet the narration is subordinate to the generalization, which modifies the narration to the end of exposition. The changes selected and the method and complete- ness of their presentation are determined by the gen- eral truth which the changes are to exemplify. a. The first change is the longing and the anticipa- tion of each for the condition of the other. To pro- 134 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. duce this in the Judge, Maud is pictured in beauty, health, and joy, with the background of the poetry of haymaking. This further serves to make it seem un- wise for Maud to long for better things. To produce this feeling in Maud, the far-off town, with its seeming busy life, and the Judge with his wealth and life of luxury, are brought before her. This serves to make it seem unwise in the Judge to long for better things. The vague longing in each takes the form of a definite wish of each to wed the other. b. The second change is the feeling of regret on the part of each arising from the contrast of their real life in later years with their former dreams of what life might be. In this narration each change is essential to illus- trate the theme. Only two are given, — joy in antici- pation, and regret in retrospection. To have chosen any other changes in their lives would have violated the law of unity, they having nothing to do with the purpose. Unity requires the changes in each to be given simultaneously, since they so happen. But lan- guage will not permit this. Instead of tracing each line of changes through separately, unity is better maintained by giving the longing of one and then of the other, and the regret of one and then of the other. And since each is the object the other longs for, and since the regret of each is produced by a remembered dream of the other, unity is as perfectly maintained as if the changes could be related in parallel lines. Exercises. — I. Construct, analyze, and test defini- tions of the following: — THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 135 I. A sentence. 2. A table. 3. A house. 4. A church. 5. A school. 6. A plant. 7. An animal. 8. A preposition. 9. A phrase. 10. A factor. 11. A state. 12. A river. 13. A pyra- mid. 14. Rhetoric. 15. Discourse. 16. Prose. 17. Poetry. 18. Oratory. 19. Description. 20. Partition. 21. Purpose in discourse. 22. Unity in discourse. 23. Method in discourse. 24. Completeness in discourse. 25. Definition. II. Compare and contrast the following: — 1. The adjective and the adverb. 2. The sentence and dis- course. 3. Poems and orations. 4. Monarchic and Democratic governments. 5. The Northern and Southern colonies of America. 6. The horse and the ox. 7. Plants and animals. 8. Steamships and railway trains. 9. Waves and ocean currents. 10. Planets and satellites. 11. Pyramids and cones. 12. Spoken and written language. 13. High schools and colleges. 14. Politeness and justice. 15. Professions and occupations. 16. Vocations and avocations. III. Exemplify the following : — 1. Exemplification. 2. Politeness. 3. Patriotism. 4. Treason. 5. Design in nature, using the heart. 6. Egyptian art, using the Great Pyramid. 7. Roman manners and customs, by a descrip- tion of an imaginary family. 8. What general truth does the story of the Prodigal Son exemplify ? The parable of the Sower ? 9. Point out in text-books and in literature many examples of ex- emplification. IV. Treat the following themes by the process of division : — 1. Rivers. 2. Winds. 3. Ships. 4. Firearms. 5. Books. 6. Orators. 7. Ministers. 8. Teachers. 9. Religions. 10. Governments. 11. Languages. 12. Arts. 13. The senses. 14. Schools. 15. Sentences. 16. Parts of speech. 17. Activities of the mind. 18. The pupils in your school. 19. Money. 20. Commerce. 21. Man. 22. Nations. 23. Select and test by the laws examples of division found in text-books. 136 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. V. Write complete expositions of the following or analyze those already constructed. Note what proc- esses are employed, and whether the law of unity is obeyed. 1. The noun — either a construction or a criticism of the ex- position in some text-book. 2. The planets — construction or analysis. 3. A criticism of this chapter by the laws developed in it. 4. Friendship, as found in the " Merchant of Venice " or in " The Courtship of Miles Standish." 5. Grammar, as treated by some particular text. 6. Orations. ARGUMENTATION. Argumentation is the process by which one mind pre- sents to another the connection between some concrete individual fact and the general principle which deter- mines that fact. We have already seen that a general idea or force or principle produces individual objects, and that ex- position presents the unity of individuals in the gen- eral. Argumentation seeks to establish the unity which exposition assumes. To expound ocean cur- rents is to exhibit a connection between the individual currents and a common nature or principle which gen- erates them, when such connection is supposed to be established and unquestioned. But to argue touching the same subject-matter is to strive to establish such connection. In all argumentation a relation of unity is under question. Hence, while in exposition the starting-point is a concept, in argumentation the start- ing-point is a judgment. A judgment is the decision of the mind in regard to the unity between some particular object and a gen- eral truth. The relation of a general idea to some concrete reality, affirmed or denied as actual, is the world's battle ground of thought and arms. To say " a beautiful landscape " or " developing man " presents a general conception which challenges neither denial nor support. But if it be said, The landscape is beautiful I38 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. or Man has developed from a monkey, we have at once entered the arena. The moment we establish a relation and make an assertion, we become personally responsible. The tree, the planets, government, com- merce, are not ours ; we may only think them. But the relations we establish are our relations; we our- selves give the sanction of our thought and identify our lives with the relation established. For this rea- son argumentation enters so largely into the affairs of men. In social, industrial, or political life, man regu- lates his conduct by the relation of truth to things, and this relation each establishes and asserts for himself, and thus brings himself into harmony or conflict with others, accordingly as his assertions agree or disagree with those of his fellowmen. The most obvious relation involved in argumenta- tion is the same as that in the other processes, namely, — The Relation of Whole and Part. Argumentation strives for the unity of the individ- ual and the general, and thus unites the part in the whole. In arguing the mind moves from the whole to the part or from the part to the whole, accordingly as the one or the other is the known term of relation. One may know the general laws of planetary motion, and from this may reason to some new fact concerning an individual planet; or knowing some fact about one or more of the planets may reason to some new truth about planets taken as a whole. Either from a knowl- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 39 edge of the whole class a knowledge of a part is gained, or from a knowledge of a part of a class a knowledge of the whole is gained. Thus on the basis of direction of movement arguments are divided into two classes, deduction and induction. Deduction. — As the word indicates, deduction is the downward way of knowing, as induction is the upward way. Deductive argument- descends from general principles to particular facts. Some known truth of the whole class is carried down to increase a knowledge of the individuals of the class. The known term is the whole, and a knowledge of the part is sought. This process brings the part into further unity with the whole — makes a more complete iden- tification. The truth of the whole is united with the part through an intermediate whole, — a whole which in- cludes the part and which is included in the larger whole. All reasoning is the unification of two ideas through a third. To judge is to connect two ideas directly; to reason is to connect two ideas indirectly through a third. An act of judgment is expressed by a proposition; but an act of reasoning is expressed by a syllogism which means a " reckoning all together." The deductive syllogism stands thus: — All apples grow on trees; This is an apple; Therefore, it grew on a tree. This syllogism connects this apple with things grow- ing on trees, through the intermediate whole, apples. I4O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Apples contain the attribute, growing on trees, and also contain this apple. Since growing on trees and this apple are both found in all apples, then growing on trees must be found in this apple or this apple must be found among things growing on trees. This sug- gests the Law of Deductive Inference. — Conviction is carried by deduction through the axiom that whatever is com- mon to the individuals of the whole class must be found in each part of the class. It is impossible to believe that all horses have four feet and at the same time be- lieve that there is a horse which has not four feet. The law is that if the whole and the part are united in an intermediate term, one may be affirmed of the other; if not so united, the affirmation cannot be made. If one term is included and the other excluded from the intermediate term, then one may be affirmed not to be the other. If both are excluded from the interme- diate term, no affirmation can be made. Thus reasoning by deduction is largely a matter of imaging the terms in relation to the term through which they are to be united. For instance, using the syllogism before given, image all things growing on trees ; now image all apples, and this image will be found to fall within the first one. Next image this apple; it will fall in the second group. Now, since this apple appears in the second group and the second group falls within the first, there can be no mistake as to this apple's falling within the first ; and this apple can confidently be said to belong among things growing upon trees. But suppose this syllogism be tested: — THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I4I All apples grow on trees; This fruit grows on trees ; Therefore, this fruit is an apple. As before, picture all things growing on trees, and within these things picture all apples. Now picture also this fruit among things growing on trees. While both apples and this fruit are among things growing on trees, this fruit need not be pictured as among apples. It may fall outside of apples and yet be in- side of those things which grow upon trees, as cherries, peaches, etc. It cannot be affirmed, therefore, that this fruit is or is not an apple, and the syllogism proves to be false. Thus fallacies are readily detected by noting whether the major and the minor terms are united in a middle term. A shortened form of the syllogism is used, called enthymeme, meaning to keep in mind, one of the judg- ments not being expressed. Thus, this apple grew on a tree because all apples grow on trees. The en- thymeme is commonly used, it being expanded into a syllogism only for the purpose of testing the argu- ment. Induction. — While deduction moves from whole to part, or from principle to fact, induction moves from part to whole, or from fact to principle. Some apples are observed growing on trees, and it is inferred that all apples grow on trees. No one has observed all apples growing on trees, yet that they do so grow is a firm belief, and this belief came from observing compari- tively a very few cases of apples growing on trees. One may believe that all crows are black from having 142 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. observed only one, and having tasted one orange a notion is formed as to how oranges taste. Thus induction ends with the general principles from which deduction begins. If induction has not estab- lished sound principles, deduction lias no assurance of safe conclusions. A well-formed deductive syllogism admits of no doubt in its conclusion, provided the premises are well established. Because of the con- vincing force of the syllogism in itself, the mind is too often satisfied without raising a question as to its foun- dation in the premises. Deduction cannot increase the certainty of truth beyond the warrant of the induction on which it rests. At best, it can only be said that what it affirms is true provided something else is true. The ignoring of well-established premises and relying on the precision and strength of the deductive syllo- gism is a leading source of fallacy in argumentation. The two movements of induction and deduction are but the two arcs of a circle, which begin in the indi- vidual object and, moving out to the general, return to the individual. Law of Inductive Inference. — Conviction through induction is based on the belief that what is essential to the part must be common to the whole. This is based on our faith that nature is an organic^ ^systematic whole. If this faith were removed, all induction would be impossible. To carry on an argument by induction is to present such matter and in such a way as to make the strongest appeal to this faith. A single act of deduction permits no further discus- sion, but a single act of induction may create only a THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 43 probability. What the single act lacks in convincing power must be made good by the repetition of induc- tive acts. At first thought this would seem a very unsatisfactory process of reasoning, but there comes a point in the accumulation of examples at which the feeling of probability becomes certainty. The number of examples given may range from one to complete enumeration. Other things equal, the certainty in- creases with the increase of the number to the point of complete enumeration, wherr "absolute certainty is reached. If it be observed that each state has a public school system, then it is absolutely certain that all states have such a system. But this is generalization, and not induction proper; the unknown being reached by the logical judgment rather than by the faith of reason. Induction proper does not reach demonstra- tion. If each state except one had been examined and found to have a school system, it is still possible to think that that one has no such system. But at this point induction ceases, for if the last one had been examined there could be no room for the exercise of inductive faith. Induction is to do service when an examination of all the individuals is impracticable or impossible. i. Induction from one example is called analogy. An object or a class which resembles a known object in some respects will be expected to resemble it in others. The more complete the resemblance observed, the greater the assurance that they will resemble in the point under question. If it be known that a piece of chalk is light, white, brittle, and can be used to make 144 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. a mark, on seeing a second object having the first three marks, the presence of the fourth mark in the second object would be inferred. If, in this case, the sec- ond object resembled the first in only two respects, as lightness and brittleness, the tendency, if any, to make the inference would be much weaker. To argue by analogy is to present as many points of resemblance as possible between the known and the unknown terms of comparison. The number of attributes, however, is not the safest basis of inference. Much more depends on the causal connection in the points of resemblance. If a strange animal were found to have a peculiar structure of the skeleton, it would be safer to infer that all of the class had the same structure than to infer that all of the class had the same color as the specimen examined, even if they resembled in many other superficial points. In arguing by analogy the points of comparison must be shown to be essential to the object. When this cannot be done, the mere accumulation of the number of points of resemblance must be resorted to. If it is to be proved, by its analogy to the earth, that Jupiter is inhabited, the accumulation of all the points of resemblance would have weight; but to show that Jupiter is like the earth in those points that condition human life, would be far more convincing. 2. The lowest phase of induction proper is based on the force of accumulated examples. The first orange observed being yellow does not justify the assertion that all oranges are yellow. But by repeated observa- tions, the mind confidently extends this attribute to all THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I45 oranges, and does so without perceiving any necessary connection between the color and the orange. We believe only on the ground that if there had been oranges of other colors we should have chanced upon them. As the number increases, probability grows into certainty. Not that this ever becomes the certainty of demonstration, for the opposite of what is affirmed may always be conceived ; but the mind rests satisfied in its conclusion. As in the lowest phase of analogy the force of the argument is in the number of points of re- semblance, so in the lowest phase of induction the con- vincing power is in the mere number of examples. The highest phase of induction seeks a causal con- nection as the basis of inference. The more funda- mental the attributes observed, the fewer the examples needed. It is sometimes impossible to discover an essential relation of the attribute under question to the object in which it is found; as, why an orange is yellow. In such cases there is no appeal from the mere force of accumulated examples. But in most cases arguing by induction consists in pointing out the essential relation of the property under discussion to the others in the examples produced. When the manner of the working of a cause is obvious, there is little difficulty in the process; as, in the rain wetting the ground. We see in the nature of rain why this effect is produced, and have no hesitancy in saying that rain will always pro- duce this effect. The relation the valves sustain to the function of the heart is easily determined, and that all hearts have such parts is confidently inferred. But the manner of the working of a cause cannot in all I46 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. cases be detected; as, the cause for a tree's growing more rapidly in one kind of soil than in another. We may not be able to see how two objects are connected, but to know that they are necessarily connected is safe ground for induction. The difficulty is in deciding that there is really a cause and effect relation. Especially is this true in complex phenomena, for in this case the essential is entangled with the accidental. For the methods of testing the presence of this relation, see Mill's "Logic," pages 278-291. This introduces us to the real basis of all argu- mentation, namely, — The Relation of Cause and Effect. The primary reason for asserting a relation between two objects is not that of whole and part, but that of the causal connection in the objects themselves. We have seen that a general idea or force produces an individual, and that it is this connection which argu- mentation seeks to establish. All argumentation rests at bottom on the connection of a productive energy in the phenomena produced. To prove that a certain word is a noun is to prove that it arises under the same mental impulse which produces other words classed as nouns. To prove that the free coinage of silver would improve the condition of the country is to find in free coinage a causal energy which would produce the effect affirmed. In establishing such causal connection all the thought relations previously discussed are involved; THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I47 for the causal connection appears from the connection of the objects that the judgment connects, which nature is disclosed by the discourse processes already discussed. Therefore, all the preceding processes may be involved as subordinate processes in argumentation. The greater part of an argument may consist of one or more of the subordinate processes. To prove that a railroad through a certain part of the country would be profitable might require an elaborate description of the country through which the road would pass and of the parts to be connected. To prove that the hanging of John Brown was, or was not, good for the country would require a narration of the preceding and the succeeding events. To prove whether sponges are animals would require an exposition of both the general ideas, sponges and animals. All the attributes in an object which bring it into real connection with another are involved in giving the reasons for connecting them in a proposition ; hence, the constant employment of the other processes in argumentation. But argumen- tation pays the debt in becoming a subordinate process in each of the other processes. In a description of the earth, it may be necessary to prove that it is round; or in narrating a course of events, it may be necessary to prove that something happened, or why it happened; or in expounding the idea man, it may be necessary to prove that he has certain qualities. But an argument is something more than the explana- tion of the subject and predicate of a proposition. It must show why one is affirmed of the other — must present their causal connection. In doing this the 148 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. argument must start from the cause to establish its effect, or from the effect to establish its cause. This fact gives rise to two kinds of arguments, based on the relation of cause and effect. The argu- ment which moves from the cause to the effect is called an a priori argument, or an argument from antecedent probability; the argument which moves from effect to cause is called an a posteriori argument, or an argu- ment from experience. A Priori Arguments. — The a priori arguments are arguments from cause to effect, explaining either what has happened or what will likely happen. Thus we may prove that with the increase of popular education there will be a decrease in crime; education having in itself a nature, a force, a cause, such as to produce this as an effect. That a certain candidate will be elected may be predicted from his high character or from the principles which he embodies. That prosperous times are, or are not, produced by a change in governmental administration is to be proved by determining whether there is in the nature of the case a sufficient causae. Tourgee urges, in his " Appeal to Caesar," that there will arise trouble with the South from the cause now present — the rapid multiplication of the negro popula- tion. The guilt or innocence of an accused person may be largely established by the a priori argument. It is difficult to convict a person whose character is such as to furnish no antecedent probability for the crime alleged. If the man accused of murder is shown to have hated the murdered man intensely, and would gain great riches by committing the crime, there THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 49 would be strong motive to the deed. This, how- ever, would not prove his guilt, but would show why- he may have committed the murder. To give such evidence its greatest force, it must be shown that there is nothing in the accused person's character to oppose the free action of the motive, as fear of the law or high moral character. Laiv of Inference from Cause. — Whenever there is a known cause, its full effect must be inferred, provided there are no hindrances. When there are hindrances, the effect is decreased in proportion to the hindrance to the point of prevention. The degree of probability depends on the strength of the cause after the hin- drance is overcome. To prove the absence of cause or that the cause is neutralized by opposing forces is to destroy all probability whatever. If a man has no motive to theft or is confined so that the act would be impossible, he would not be charged with such a crime. Physical causes are more certain to be followed by their effects than moral causes. The warmth of the sun and the moisture in spring will clothe the earth in verdure; but whether a nation at enmity against another will bring war is not so certain. In the realm of volition, so many and so complex are the motives, and so many of them hidden from view to all except the person choosing, that the connection of cause and effect cannot be ascertained with certainty. If all mo- tives could be taken -into account, the resulting effect in action could be as certainly inferred as the effect of a cause in the physical world. The uncertainty of pre- I 50 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. vision in history arises from the fact that the forces are so diffused and complex that their result is difficult to estimate ; besides, there are many latent forces in human character which must be left out of the account altogether. A common fallacy in argumentation under the law of inference from cause is the assumption that one of two or more effects which may seem to have equal connection with the cause is the effect which is to follow. Which of these effects will follow is the very point in question. Or, of two or more causes which may equally well account for the effect, one is assumed as the cause. Which of these is the real cause is to be proved by the argument. This fallacy is called "beg- ging the question." One writer may urge the system of landholding as the cause of the discontent of the country, while another finds the cause in foreign immi- gration, and a third is sure that railroad monopolies are responsible. Each assumes one cause, and finding that it tends in the desired direction, expects his readers to infer it to be the sole cause, while other causes may be shown to bear with equal force; and all of them, or some cause fundamental enough to include all the minor causes, might be a better basis of infer- ence than any one presented. Another form of this fallacy is the assumption that one circumstance is the cause of another, when it is only a concomitant. Sta- tistics are presented to prove that illiteracy is the cause of crime; while both illiteracy and crime may be common effects of the low character of the persons enumerated in the statistics. People do not read, and THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I 5 I it is observed that they have no libraries, and the second fact is thought to explain the first. Yet the absence of reading and the library may be con- comitant facts of a common cause; as, hard manual labor, sensual indulgence, sluggish state of mind, etc. A fruitful source of such fallacies as the above is the prejudice of the one who makes the argument. To a greater extent than one is consciCus will he select from probable causes the one which he desires to be the cause. The heart has arguments which the head knows not of. A bad motive is generally assumed to explain the actions of those to whom we are opposed; and good motives to explain the actions of those with whom we agree. No candidate for office expects just inferences from the opposite party. Even the philan- thropist, in carrying out some benevolent enterprise, is gratuitously supplied with selfish motives. When many good reasons will readily account for an action, the mind is too often determined in its choice, not by the careful estimate of the relation of cause and effect, but by the wish that a certain motive be the cause. The President may favor or veto a certain measure, and his course be explainable by a desire for the general good or for some selfish gain. Party affiliations will cause one party to praise him for his disinterested loyalty and justice, while with the other party preju- dice finds in the position taken nothing but selfishness or cowardice. When the advantages of either free trade or protective tariff are to be proved against the other, many beneficial effects are assumed that could as easily be explained by other conditions, and 152 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. which would be so explained if the case had not been prejudged — prejudiced — by the desires. The caution needed here is that in estimating an argument the pre- judices of the writer or speaker be taken into account; and that, in making an argument, those assumptions which prejudice intrudes be excluded. The remedy for this fallacy is to love truth more and victory less. The man who wishes to be really, not apparently, suc- cessful in debate must come to the question with an earnest desire to find the real relation of cause and effect involved, solely for the sake of the truth. A debating club in which a question is discussed for the sake of victory is not conducive to that attitude of mind necessary to effective argument. The hypocrisy of the judgment in its pretense of reasons blinds to the real reasons when engaged in an actual contest for truth. Much of the so-called drill in debating is only a drill in fluency of words and deftness in manipulat- ing fallacies. A Posteriori Arguments. — These are arguments from effect to cause, explaining why something is or why something has happened. The effect is known, and the cause which produced it is sought. In the a priori arguments known causes point to unknown future events or to some known effect which the known cause explains; while in the a posteriori argu- ments the effect is known and the cause sought. Inference of cause from effect is based on the differ- ent thought relations involved in thinking. The whole may be inferred from the part; the substance from the attribute, or the attribute from the substance; from THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 53 likenesses, other likenesses, or from differences, other differences; from effect, its adequate cause; from adap- tation may be inferred purpose. From the presence of the whole of a steam engine certain parts may be safely inferred ; or with a part of it present, the whole will be suggested. The attribute yellow being present in a distant field, some substance, as wheat or clay, will be suggested; and the substance, wheatfield, will suggest some accompanying attribute. Likeness in color, form, texture, and parts of two kinds of fruits will suggest likeness as to flavor and odor; and differ- ences in the first respect named will suggest differences in the second. From the moving train, the steam as an adequate cause of the motion may be inferred. From the adaptation of an anchor to grapple in the bed of the ocean, the inference is readily made that some one designed it. But in all these cases the inference is based on the relation of cause and effect. The adapta- tion in the anchor is caused by its purpose; that in the nature of the fruits which caused them to be alike in certain respects will cause them to be alike in other respects; that which usually conditions or causes the presence of the yellow color under the conditions observed is still the cause; and whatever there is in the nature of the engine to necessitate the relation of whole and part is permanent in causing that re- lation. The so-called signs and resemblances, so often spoken of in argumentation, are only other names for effects. The tolling of a bell is a sign that some one has died; but it is a sign of this because it is an effect 154 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. resulting from death. A weapon in possession of the accused man is a sign that he is a murderer; but it is a sign because the carrying of such a weapon is an effect produced by the intention of killing some one. The bridge is a sign that men have labored, for it is an effect produced by such a cause. Two objects resemble each other in certain respects, and reasoning by re- semblance, some unknown attribute of the one will be like some known attribute of the other. Yet this is reasoning from a known effect to a cause, for it is a belief that whatever caused the similarity in the points observed will cause it in the point with reference to which the inference is made. Signs and points of re- semblance are always effects of which the cause is to be inferred. Laws of Inference from Effect. - - The degree of force in the a posteriori argument varies with the cer- tainty of the causal relation on which the inference is based. This depends on (i) the number and com- plexity of the causes which may produce the effect, and (2) the efficiency and reality of the cause. 1. A cause may be inferred from an effect with certainty when the effect is such that only one cause can produce it. We may argue conclusively that the oak is produced from an acorn; that steam is caused by heat ; that the burned house has been on fire ; there being no other cause for each phenomenon. The train is moving, and steam may be inferred as the cause; but not conclusively, for there may be other forces moving it, as men, horses, electricity, gravity, etc. When there are many causes, either of which or THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 155 a combination of which may produce the effect, the inference becomes less certain as the number and com- plexity increase. As a rule, the number and complexity of causes increase in passing from the physical to the spiritual world. Especially is it difficult to assign causes to social phenomena, so manifold and subtile are the moving forces. And nowhere are fallacies more common. 2. In an argument from resemblance a cause may be inferred with certainty when the resemblances are essential. On the ground that Caesar was selfish and a tyrant, it might safely be inferred that another ruler who was selfish was also a tyrant, there being a causal relation between selfishness and tyranny. Glass is transparent and brittle; but it does not follow that be- cause water is transparent it is also brittle, there being no essential relation between transparency and brittle- ness. In such cases the burden of proof consists in showing that the rjo_LQls.-of--resemblance are so related to the nature of the object that they are constant marks of it. This may be done by establishing directly a causal relation, as in the case of selfishness and tyranny; or by an accumulation of examples till the uniformity establishes a belief in a constant cause. Attributes and objects are so often accidental ac- companiments of each other without causal relation that arguments from example are fruitful sources of fallacies. The immature and the untrained mind, in their tendency to hasty conclusions, generally infer a causal relation where there is only an accidental existence; as, — 156 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Some intemperate man lives to a great age; there- fore, intemperance is conducive to longevity. It rained on Monday and the two succeeding days of the week; therefore, when it rains on Monday it will rain three days in the week. A great man smokes; there- fore, smoking is manly. Byron was licentious and a great poet ; therefore, licentiousness is favorable to poetic inspiration. A man who believes the doctrines of a certain church is immoral; therefore, the. doc- trines of that church tend to produce immorality. This kind of argument is much used by the sophist. The demagogue finds it an effective means of carrying conviction to the minds of unthinking people. By means of it, he accounts for the dull or the flourishing condition of the times; the high or the low price of crops and merchandise; the scarcity or the abundance of productions; the demand for labor or the difficulty with which it is obtained; and gives the credit or the blame, as suits his purpose, to the party in power, when the coexistence of the facts may be purely acci- dental. To prove the value of a classical over a scien- tific etkrcation, or vice versa, some eminent scholar is instanced who has pursued one of these courses; while his eminence may be accounted for by a large number of causes; as, natural endowment, more thor- ough discipline on account of superior teachers, social opportunities, combined effect of various studies, etc. The proof would be absolutely convincing if the same person could be the subject of each course, for then the conditions would be identical; or, if many examples under similar conditions from each course could be THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 157 furnished. Through every phase of life, reasoning by example is a fruitful source of error in the lower order of thinkers, and hence an effective means of deception in the hands of the unprincipled. Arguments from example may be either invented or real. An argument against the majority determining the laws which govern a city might be made by invent- ing the example of a majority determining the best method of performing a difficult surgical operation, rather than leaving the case to one skillful surgeon. The argument derives its force from the fact that knowledge and skill bear the same relation to the making of laws that they do to surgery. The example taken must be true to experience, else it has no con- vincing power. Every one knows the relation between knowledge and skill, and a successful operation in sur- gery. If a fictitious city had been presented as having been ruled disastrously by the majority, the example could have had no force whatever, because the ex- ample assumes the fact to be proved. The invented examples in the allegory, the fable, the parable, are used to make a general truth clear, and not as argu- ments to establish it. A prominent form of argument from effect to cause is that of testimony. The fact in the mind of the wit- ness is produced by the cause sought, and the conviction is produced through the belief that the witness will speak the truth rather than a falsehood. In such proof there can be only a probability of the fact testified to because all men do not always speak the truth. The degree of probability depends on 158 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. f (1) the power, and (2) the desire of the witness to speak the truth. 1. There is a wide difference as to the value of the testimony of two witnesses equally honest. One may have powers of observation which enable him to see an object or an occurrence more distinctly, clearly, and fully than another, or superior powers of inference, that he may interpret correctly what he sees, or greater skill in expressing what he sees, that others may receive the correct impression of the matter under question. Two persons seldom see and report things exactly alike, however much they may desire to be true. The impression made on the mind by the senses are the same; the divergence begins with the facts ob- served. Hence, in cases of proof by testimony, the witness is confined to a statement of what the senses report. But this is only a question of degree, for un- conscious inferences are a part of almost every act of sense perception. When the witness reports that he heard a certain object or that he saw an object of a given form, size, and at a given distance, he reports more than the senses give. In all the acquired sense-perceptions, that which is literally given by the senses and that given by the judgment cannot be sepa- rated, except by a conscious process of analysis. The conscious element is the act of sense-perception, and not the act of inference. Therefore, statements of the truth gained by acquired sense-perceptions are taken in testimony as matters of fact rather than as matters of inference or of opinion. The one shades off into the other so gradually that no definite boundary can be fixed. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. I 59 Therefore, it would seem that too much emphasis is often placed on the difference between statements of facts and statements of opinion. Practically, a matter of fact must be limited to an individual concrete object, while a matter of opinion consists of a general truth. 2. The convincing power of a witness not only de- pends on his power to comprehend the truth accurately and fully, and to state it clearly, but also upon his desire to state the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth. Even when the witness has no special prejudice in the case under trial, his narrow-minded- ness, his general prejudices, his confirmed habit of taking partial views of questions, seriously invalidate his testimony. If the witness has some personal interest involved in the trial, it is expected, in the weakness of human nature, that he will consciously or unconsciously color the facts and opinions to accord with his own interests. But if the witness testifies against his own interest, the testimony has greater value than if he were without bias; for in so doing he proves his adherence to truth. Thus it is when a can- didate for office testifies to the high character of his opponent; a man in business recommends the methods of his competitor; one who disbelieves in evolution assents to facts and conclusions which tend to sup- port that theory; or one friend bears witness against another in favor of a common enemy. The value of a witness depends on his knowledge and veracity, as explained in the foregoing. If his charac- ter is sufficiently high, a single witness will establish the truth under question. Other things equal, the *>*"*- ML, l60 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. greater the number of witnesses, the more effective is the testimony produced ; but one competent witness, as a physician testifying to some point of practice in medi- cine, would carry conviction against any number of illiterate and non-professional men. One able and honorable statesman is more competent to bear wit- ness on the value of a measure for general good than the mass of voters who may be called upon to testify at the ballot. Whatever the character, the number of witnesses has great force when, without the opportu- nity for collusion, they bear concurrent testimony. In this case their agreement could not be accounted for on any other ground than the truth of what they say. Authority is a kind of effect from which valuable arguments may be produced. It differs from testi- mony in that testimony respects a matter of fact, while authority, a matter of opinion. In authority we accept the conclusions others have reached after an investiga- tion of the question at issue. This is often the most forcible proof that can be produced, for the conclusions may be of an expert, or many such, involving a wider investigation of facts than would be possible for the immediate occasion. In law, opinions delivered by courts of justice are taken as unquestioned proof in cases which the opinion covers. General Laws of Argumentation. The Law of Purpose. - The practical value of an argument is not measured by its absolute logic, but by the progress from one mental condition to another, THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. l6l made in the mind of those addressed. Such progress may require the closest logical articulation of the sub- ject-matter; as, when the purpose is to present the logic of the subject for its own sake. In this case those addressed are supposed to be seeking the reason involved in the question for the sake of that reason. The mind desires the whys and the wherefores of things, and it appeals to argumentation to gratify this desire. In this case the argument has no end beyond the logic of the argument itself; hence, the logical con- tinuity in the argument measures the progress desired in the mind addressed. The arguments in geometry are of this class. It is possible to argue questions of free trade and protective tariff in the same spirit; that is, not as an advocate who has an ulterior end, but as one investigating truth for truth's sake. In such cases the mind addressed is supposed to be in search of the truth, and needs no rhetorical device to stimu- late it to active appropriation. Such arguments are supposed to fall outside the subject of rhetoric into that of logic; yet the strictest logical argument must form the basis of adaptation to minds in other con- ditions than that above described; just as the logical arrangement of subject-matter in description, narration, and exposition forms the basis of adaptation to the various conditions and changes to be produced by those processes of discourse. The rhetorical argument is called into exercise in the stress and art of producing volition and action; espe- cially when the mind is indifferent or hostile to the truth advocated. The will must be moved under one 1 62 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. or the other of three mental conditions, which must be taken into account as modifying factors of the logi- cal argument ; that is, the mind is open to instruction and disposed to the line of action when the truth is perceived, indifferent to a knowledge of duty and the line of action proposed, or actively opposed to the truth and measure proposed. When the mind is in the third condition named, a counter argument arises, and the two arguments con- stitute a debate. This fact modifies the procedure in the individual arguments, in the fact that the burden of proof rests on him who affirms, and that the pre- sumption of truth is in favor of the one who denies. In courts of law the one who charges another with guilt must prove the fact of guilt; the one who denies the charge has only to offset the argument. In consid- ering the case, the judge and the jury assume innocence until guilt is established. Likewise, a presumption of truth holds in favor of certain opinions, customs, and institutions which an argument seeks to change, since they are supposed to have been established for good reasons. This presumption has such weight in many cases as to support opinions, customs, and institutions long after the reasons that gave them birth have passed away. The one who argues to maintain established things has the sanction of ages on his side, and it requires all the patience and enthusiasm of a bold reformer to overcome precedents and usages. He who has presumption in his favor should not assume the burden of proof unnecessarily; for the one on whom the burden of proof rests must overcome all the proba- THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 63 bilities which gave rise to the presumption. It is much easier to offset an argument to prove crime than to assume the burden of proof and try to estab- lish innocence. The formal debate is not the most promising way of arriving at truth; and, therefore, not the most effective process of discourse. It is apt to weaken sincerity of purpose, in that it prompts stubborn adhesion to one- sided truth, and perverts the argument to personal victory as against a disinterested and universal good. The Law of Unity. — It has already been observed that the very nature of an argument is to establish the unity between the general principle and the individual fact which the principle determines. The different processes of argument are only so many forms of doing this; rather, all the processes taken together is one complex movement to this end; they are all organically one in the process of argument, and are all necessary to establish fully the desired connection. The a pos- teriori argument must support the probability raised by the a priori argument; and deduction must test the conclusions of induction which furnish the deductive premise. And further, the former pair of arguments must be carried on by means of the latter; induction and deduction are the means of establishing the causal connection sought by the a priori and a posteriori argu- ments. So that argumentation is a unified organic movement having various phases and parts. But such is only the logical unity inherent in the argument itself. The argument must have unity, not only in itself considered, but in relation to the mind 1 64 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. addressed, — must have rhetorical as well as logical unity. Everything must progressively tend to estab- lish belief in the truth asserted, and this is subject to other conditions than those imposed by the laws of thought alone; namely, by the capacity, beliefs, and prejudices of those in whom the new belief is to be established. The argument, to have unity, must be presented from the standpoint of the audience's present knowledge, interests, and desires. The most closely unified and logical argument in itself considered may have no unity with the mind addressed. A pro- gressive argument toward belief is the law of rhetorical unity in argumentative discourse. This law requires that no matter be chosen which does not bear on the proposition to be proved. Irrele- vant matter is often introduced to divert the attention from the real point at issue, or to ensnare by the belief that proof has been offered when there has been none. This certainly would be an effective rhetorical device if rhetoric did not have to square itself by ethical standards. Rhetorical art must not resort to logical fallacies. This law also requires that such proof shall be offered as can be grasped by the capacity of the hearer, and such as will assimilate readily with already exist- ing beliefs. The most valid proof that a youth should be obedient to his parents might completely lack unity with him, because of his incapacity to comprehend the ground of the argument. An effort to convert one from a belief in monarchy to a belief in democracy, although perfectly unified and logical in itself, would THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 1 65 have no effect in the monarchist's mind unless such argument should take its rise from the monarchist's present beliefs. Due regard must be had in this case, also, to the selection of proofs that will not antagonize by arousing inveterate prejudices. That the mind may yield itself to the line of proof, the argument must be conciliatory. When the mind is indifferent or opposed to the proposition to be argued, some preparatory statements must be made by way of arousing interest in the ques- tion or to conciliate the opposition. When the mind addressed is opposed, the first step of the speaker is to put himself in sympathy with the opposition. It may be necessary for the speaker to veil his purpose, even to the suppression of the proposition to be proved. The beginning of Mark Antony's oration is a fine example of this. On this point A. S. Hill has the following : — " We have already seen how important it is that a reasoner should himself, at the outset, clearly under- stand the- proposition he is to maintain; but it by no means follows that he should hasten to announce the proposition to those whom he would convince of its truth. His first object should be to secure their favor- able attention. " Now, to engage attention at all, it is desirable to appear to be saying something new. If then the prop- osition is a truism to the persons addressed, it will usually be judicious to awaken their attention by be- ginning with what is novel in the proof. Regarded from a new point of view, approached by a new path, 1 66 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the old conclusion will acquire a fresh interest, except, indeed, for those unfortunate persons whose minds are accessible to nothing but commonplace, and for whom, therefore, even a novelty must be presented in a com- monplace dress. " If the proposition, whether well known to the persons addressed or not, is likely to awaken their hostility, it should not be announced till steps have been taken to procure for it a favorable reception. Often the best course to this end is to state at the out- set the question at issue, but not espouse either side until after the arguments for each have been canvassed. It may also be possible to secure assent to general principles from which the conclusion can be logically deduced. In pursuing this course, the reasoner seems to invite his readers or hearers to join him in an inquiry for truth. This inquiry results, if it be suc- cessful, not so much in convincing them as in leading them to convince themselves of the justness of the conclusion, if he is successful in inducing them to give some weight to reasons which they would not have considered at all, had they known to what conclusions they led. " Another method of disarming hostility is for a speaker to establish pleasant relations with the audi- ence by adverting to opinions (irrelevant ones it may be) which they hold in common with him, before pro- ceeding to points of difference." Under ordinary circumstances, the proposition should be stated as soon as favorable attention is gained and before proofs have been examined. A clear statement THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. 167 of the point at issue is essential to unity in the discus- sion; for the mind cannot follow the bearing of the proofs unless the point on which they bear is known. It would be useless to attempt to prove that Massa- chusetts contributed more to civilization in America than did Virginia unless it be made clear what meaning is put into the term civilization. By the explanation of the meaning attached to the terms of the propo- sition, and to the proposition as a whole, arguments are often rendered unnecessary. Debates sometimes run to great length and are carried on with great vehemence only to discover at last that the opponents hold substantially the same views. Hence, an exposi- tion of the proposition may be the first step in the argument. Whether or not the proposition is an- nounced and explained at the outset, a clear concep- tion of it is the first step in the preparation of the argument. The arrangement of the parts of the argument has much to do with its effectiveness. The law is that they should be so arranged that they will be cumulative in their effect. Each argument in its place should be such as to permit no rebound ; at least, from any posi- tion which had been gained by the preceding argument. From this view it may be inferred the weakest argu- ment should come first, and that the others follow in the order of strength. Yet the law of unity may not permit this; for sometimes a strong argument is needed at the outset to gain confidence in the line of argument. "The Nestorian arrangement of troops, with the weak- est in the middle, suggests an advantageous order of 1 68 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. arrangement. It avoids anti-climax, and at the same time opens the discussion with a strong argument. An inverse recapitulation of the arguments also obvi- ates the effect of anti-climax, when in the original order the weakest comes last. A mere mention of the weak arguments at the beginning, with the statement that you do not rely upon them or mean to use them, may often prove effective." * Exercises. — I. By the suggestions on page 140-1, test the following syllogisms from Jevons' " Primer of Logic." In doing so, train the imagination to image quickly the relations of the three terms involved; and from the relation of the major and minor to the middle, or connecting, term decide what may and what may not be affirmed: — 1. All English silver coins are coined at Tower Hill ; All sixpences are English coins ; Therefore, all sixpences are coined at Tower Hill. 2. All electors pay rates ; No paupers pay rates ; Therefore, no paupers are electors. 3. All animals consume oxygen ; Some animals are flesh-eating ; Therefore, some animals consume oxygen. 4. Some animals are flesh-eating ; Some animals have two stomachs ; Therefore, flesh-eating animals have two stomachs. 5. Brittle substances are not fit for coining ; Some metals are brittle substances : Therefore, no metals are fit for coining. ID. J. Hill. THE THOUGHT IN DISCOURSE. l6g 6. Every city contains a cathedral ; Liverpool does not contain a cathedral ; Therefore, Liverpool is not a city. 7. All minerals are raised from mines ; All coals are raised from mines ; Therefore, all coals are minerals. II. I. Make several illustrations of induction. Analyze them. 2. Select several illustrations of induction. Ana- lyze them. 3. Select a theme and write an argument by anal- ogy. Show that the reasoning in Butler's " Analogy " is by analogy. III. Prove either the positive or the negative of the following by the a priori method : — 1. Free trade, or protection, is conducive to the general good. 2. Intemperance leads to misery. 3. Education lessens crime. 4. Faith in God is conducive to morality. 5. Games of chance are hurtful to morals. 6. Railroads threading the United States north and south would have prevented the Civil War. 7. Intellectual education tends to morality. 8. Science promotes Christianity. 9. The study of history is a more efficient means of culture than the study of Latin. IV. Prove either the positive or the negative of the following by the a posteriori method : — - 1. A prohibitory liquor law decreases drunkenness and crime. 2. Massachusetts has been a greater civilizing force in America than has Virginia. 3. Wealth is favorable to morality. I70 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 4. Popularity is not a sure index to true worth. 5. The Crusades were beneficial to civilization. 6. The exile of the Acadians was not justifiable 7. Longfellow was a greater poet than Chaucer. 8. America has produced better orators than Greece. 9. Argumentation is a more common process of discourse than exposition. V. In a more complete way, using all the methods of argument necessary to the purpose, treat the follow- ing ; first having decided upon the exact state of mind supposed to be addressed, and whether the argument is to instruct, move to action, or rouse esthetic pleasure: — 1. The English language is a more perfect means of communi- cation than the Latin. 2. Capital punishment is, or is never, justifiable. 3. The relation between the North and the South are such as to warrant the continuance of peace and harmony. 4. Morality is essential to a high state of civilization. 5. The multiplication of religious sects has been favorable to Christianity. 6. The state should compel the education of children within its jurisdiction. 7. The state should support a university. 8. "Truth crushed to earth shall rise again. The eternal years of God are hers." 9. The banishment of Roger Williams was, or was not, justifi- able. 10. Should the right of suffrage be extended to women? i 1. Analyze Burke's speech on American Taxation. 12. Analyze Webster's reply to Hayne. 13. Analyze the argument of the Little Cottage Girl, in Words- worth's " We are Seven " ; or the argument in Tennyson's " Two Voices,'' or in " In Memoriam." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. Its Fundamental Law. The first phase of discourse study is the purpose for which thought is uttered; the second, the thought as a means of securing the end sought; the third, the language conveying the thought to the mind in which the effect is to be produced. This chapter is, there- fore, a language study, but a language study in a restricted sense. A complete study of language requires it to be viewed from two opposite directions : the one as an organized means of communication, the other as organized in the process of communication. The first discusses the origin, the development, and the present structure of language as such, or language in itself; the second, language in living unity with thought, bearing its message to accomplish the end for which the thought in any given case is communicated. This is not a difference in the extent of the view taken, but a difference in the phase on which the attention rests. In both cases language is viewed in its entire extent, but not in its entire content. From this side we see the whole as a body of thought symbol, empty of con- tent, except in so far as necessary to explain the sym- bol; on that side, the whole as the living body of thought manifesting the soul of an author to the soul of the reader or hearer. In the one, thought is used I72 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. to explain the language symbol — thought the means, language the end; in the other, language is used to convey 'thought — language the means, thought the end: that is, language considered in the process of communicating thought. In order to make thought a means to gain a knowl- edge of language as an end, there is required a con- scious process of separation between the language form and the content. This conscious separation of form and content, in order to discern how language is adjusted to thought, is the characteristic feature of all true grammatical study. But language in discourse is necessarily viewed in 'living unity with the thought which it communicates. Neither the composer nor the interpreter is conscious of the relation of language to thought. Language and thought grow into one in the process of communication; and the words be- come so tinged and flushed with the life of thought that language itself includes, not merely language sym- bols as shown by grammatical dissection, but whatever life the thought imparts to them. Language as a means of expression includes the life, the richness, the fullness, and the power with which words are charged by the mind, stimulated and exalted into new and un- usual conceptions of the matter under consideration. When we speak of one's clearness, charm, and vigor of language, we include not merely choice of words and structure of sentences, but a certain illumination of the subject by the mind, — the grace and delicacy of its conceptions, and the striking forms and imagery with which it clothes its thought to make it effective. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 73 Hence, it is not correctness of language form in rela- tion to thought, but effectiveness in securing the end sought which constitutes the rhetorical quality of language. That quality of language which makes it effective is called Style. As usually defined, style is the peculiar manner in which an individual author ex- presses himself. If this is style no science can be made of it; for then there are as many styles as speakers and writers. That individuality of an author which one readily detects in reading a new selection from a familiar author, and which constitutes a part of his charm, is for that author only, and can no more be explained and utilized by another than can the author's peculiar voice, bearing, and facial expression. What- ever the individual peculiarities of the writing, whether it be Tennysonian or Johnsonian, it must have those common properties which make language effective. Style, as here to be understood, is the common, essen- tial, and fundamental quality of language which adapts it to the ends for which language is uttered, — which makes it an instrument to the effective communication of thought. Hence, the fundamental law of language in discourse, which is the organizing principle throughout the fol- lowing discussion, may be formulated as follows: — That language,- or style, is best which communicates thought most effectively to the end sought by the dis- course. 174 the science of discourse. Qualities Required by the Law. Language must be adapted to the three ends of discourse; hence there must be three qualities of lan- guage, one quality adapting it to communicate thought to the intellect, one to present thought to the end of volition, and one to the end of esthetic pleasure. Since thought is presented in each case, there is one fundamental quality of style growing out of the rela- tion of language to thought in the process of language interpretation; namely, Clearness, or Perspicuity. This is the fundamental quality of all discourse, whatever its purpose, and the only quality uniformly required when the purpose is to instruct. But if the author seek to move the will or to impress the thought, he must add to Clearness, Energy ; and if to please or to touch the emotions for their own sake, he must add to Clearness, Elegance. The language of prose should be clear; of oratory, energetic; of poetry, elegant. Each should be clear as a condition of delivering the thought to the intellect; but oratory, to impress the truth, to stimu- late the indifferent, to convince the perverse, must be full of vigor and power; and poetry, to please the taste, must have beauty of conception and expression. In addition, therefore, to the fact that language must be clear in order to deliver its truth to the intellect, under some circumstances, it is required also to stimulate the energies of the mind to appropriate the truth presented, to enjoy it, or to live in obedience thereto. Thus style has not only its indifferent phase of passive transmission, but its active phase of stimulation. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 75 While Clearness is the characteristic quality of prose, it may be necessary to stimulate it with beauty and force of diction and conception in order to dispose the mind to receive the truth, and that the truth may be impressed upon it. To instruct those of mature age and those who are active seekers of truth requires only the utmost Clearness; but to instruct children or those who are indifferent to the truth which the author wishes to convey requires a degree of Elegance in style to interest the attention, and a degree of Energy to impress the thought presented. Hence, Elegance and Energy do not belong exclusively to poetry and oratory. Elegance and Energy in prose, as in oratory, are a means. In poetry, Elegance is an end. The style constitutes the poem. Prose takes upon itself the qualities of poetry and oratory when it adds to its ordi- nary work of instruction that of influencing the mind to appropriate the instruction given. Prose influences to instruct; while oratory instructs to influence. To influence, however, is not the characteristic func- tion of prose, and Elegance and Energy are not the characteristic qualities of its language. Prose and poetry communicate truth and beauty for all time, and assume eager minds in search of them. There- fore, the language is not required to bear the burden of conveying thought or pleasing the taste, and at the same time of stimulating the reader or hearer. The scientist and the poet cast their books to the public, knowing that those will read who find there what the mind and the heart crave. The book of prose or poetry determines the reader; the audience determines the I76 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. oration. Given the audience with a definite change of will to be produced, and the orator assumes the aggres- sive. He cannot wait till they, desiring to change their opinion or conduct, search out motives to influ- ence themselves. This would remove the necessity for the oration. His thought and language cannot be passive, but must be energized to stir the indifferent, sluggish, or perverse wills to some definite course of action. While all these qualities of language are essential, under certain conditions, to each kind of discourse, yet, beyond a given degree, they are incompatible. Prose may gain such beauty and force of expression as to defeat perspicuity. Clearness, accuracy, and force of statement may be carried so far as to defeat poetic beauty; and the terse vigor essential to the oration is inconsistent with prosaic clearness or poetic finish. Each kind of production must be characterized by its own quality of language, or its identity will be lost and its purpose defeated. If it be necessary to infuse the clearness of prose with the life of poetry and oratory, it must be so tempered that the intellect will be stimu- lated only to seize the truth, not so as to be absorbed in the beauties of conception. Here, Clearness must prevail over Elegance and Energy. While poetry is marked by Elegance, yet Clearness and Energy are essential. That accuracy and fullness which are best adapted to the expression of thought are inconsistent with the finer workmanship of poetry; and so is the rigid tension of forcible utterance in oratory. The orator with due care must present his thoughts clearly THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 77 and elegantly; yet strength must be secured, even if the strokes be rough and sinewy. Thus effectiveness, the law of language in discourse, requires language to be clear, energetic, or elegant, accordingly as the purpose is to instruct, to move the will, or to gratify the taste. Clearness. — Clearness, then, is that quality of lan- guage which adapts it to instruct or to communicate thought to the intellect, whether in prose, oratory, or poetry. This quality is essential in prose. If mind could communicate directly with mind, the communication would be perfect, for nothing would be lost in the process. But language is necessarily an impediment. The receiving mind must not only think the speaker's or the writer's thought, but must, at the same time, interpret the medium through which the thought is transmitted. This divides the attention between the thought and the language, — the thought, which the author wishes the reader or hearer to attend to with all his energy that he may fully realize the con- tent, and the language, which the writer or speaker uses only as a means of causing him to think the content. Since the receiving mind has only a given amount of energy, so far as the attention is required to the medium of communication it is withdrawn from the thought to be conveyed. Hence, the chief problem of language in discourse is to reduce to the minimum the effort of the mind in the interpretation of the medium. The medium must be so transparent that the interpreting mind will not be conscious of its pres- iy8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ence, but will feel itself in immediate communication with the mind of the writer or speaker. While lan- guage necessarily requires some attention, it may be so perfect that the interpreter is unconscious of it ; so far, at least, as not to have a double consciousness in gain- ing the thought. In learning a foreign language, the student at first is conscious only of language form, and does not read. Later, he begins to interpret the thought of discourse, but realizes feebly the content, being painfully conscious of the language medium. Finally, after many years of study, when the language has passed into identity with thought, the student reads with only a consciousness of the thought and spirit of the author. Not that language and thought are identical, but that the mind in seeing the language immediately grasps the thought without a second act of attention. Effectiveness in communicating the thought has already been given as the fundamental law of language. The preceding prepares for the statement of the fun- damental law of effectiveness in terms of the law of Clearness. That language is most effective which) to the reader or hearer, is identical with the thought. Or, that language is most effective which requires the least possible amount of attention from the reader or hearer. Whatever be the end sought, whether instruction, pleasure, or volition, Clearness must be found in every word and in every sentence of every prose discourse, poem, or oration ; for if the author is not to be under- stood it were as well that he remain silent. Clearness THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 79 has been denned as that quality of expression by virtue of which it communicates the contained thought with- out diverting the attention from the thought to the symbol of thought. That language is clearest which requires the least attention in the process of its inter- pretation. A truly transparent medium through which reader and hearer meet without interruption, mind to mind with writer or speaker, is the standard of perspi- cuity in the expression of thought. Clearness is not a quality that can belong to language as such; it becomes a quality only when organized by thought in adaptation to a stated purpose to be accom- plished under given conditions. It is, therefore, a relative, not an absolute quality; a rhetorical rather than a grammatical quality. Language can be said to be clear or obscure only for those to whom it is addressed. Language must be as clear as the subject- matter permits and as the capacity of those addressed requires. The same language will not be clear to the man and to the child, to the literate and to the illiter- ate. That the reader does not understand what he reads may not, however, be the fault of the expression ; the difficulty may be in the thought itself. The ex- pression may be clear to those to whom such thought is addressed. Assuming that the matter is adapted to the level of the experience of the given audience, the expression should be such as to enable that audience to realize without effort, so far as the expression is concerned, the matter presented. Energy. — Energy is that quality of style which im- presses the matter of discourse. l80 THE SCTENCE OF DISCOURSE. Energy is an active, clearness a passive quality. So far as the medium is concerned, clearness permits the reader to gain the thought without effort. Clearness assumes an eager mind seeking the truth, — a mind already stored with the necessary stimulus for acquisi- tion. Energy has for its purpose the stimulation of mental activity; either to impress the truth on the intellect when the purpose is to instruct, or to excite the sensibilities when the purpose is to please as an end, or when it is desired to affect an action of the will. Hence, the quality of style now to be considered is common to all classes of discourse. But while it is secondary in prose and poetry, it is a primary quality in oratory. Prose and poetry may assume a mind active in seeking the truth or the pleasure communi- cated; but in the oration, the hearer is not already choosing in the line proposed. This would remove the condition which gave rise to the oration; and this condition requires Energy as the primary quality of style. That Energy is necessary in prose is obvious from the fact that a truth may be expressed clearly to the intellect, yet so feebly that it makes no lodgment in the mind addressed. Such a statement may often be infused with sufficient life and force to imbed the thought effectively. That is, the truth is not only expressed but impressed by the quality of the statement itself. When Lowell wishes not only to express but to impress the fact that a large number of authors be- gin their career with promise and even notoriety, but that only a few of this number have an enduring fame, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. l8l he says: " Many a light, hailed by too careless observ- ers as a fixed star, has proved to be only a short-lived lantern at the tail of a newspaper kite." The same author, in speaking of the influence of Swift's humor on Carlyle, after it had filtered through Richter, says: " Unhappily, the bit of mother from Swift's vinegar barrel had strength to sour all the rest." These are not examples of clearness, for this could have been secured by ordinary language. They are not elegant, for they do not appeal to the taste. The purpose be- ing to instruct, the secured energy is not to move the will. When Chaucer, in speaking of the Clerk's horse, says, " As lene was his horse as is a rake," he did not express the truth more clearly nor more elegantly than he might otherwise have done, but he forcibly impressed the image of that horse. When we are told that a certain pastor was so faithful that he watched over his flock while they slept, we receive the plain truth that he preached sleep-producing sermons with multiplied power and lasting effect. Fortunate is that writer who not only can express his truth clearly, but can impress it by the power of the statement in which it is expressed. When emotions are presented, either to the end of esthetic pleasure or to new resolution, they must be made to have their full power in the mind addressed. If pity is the theme, the object awakening it must be made to stir the heart to its depths with that emotion; when grief is to be experienced, the feeling must be made as intense as the purpose requires and the truth permits. With reference to the effective handling of 1 82 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the emotion, we often speak of passages of literature as having great power. Such are well illustrated in many of Tennyson's poems; as, " Break, Break, Break," "Enoch Arden," " The May Queen," "Ode on the Death of the Duke of Wellington." Thus Energy, in whatever kind of discourse, has reference to the power with which the end is reached, — to whatever the writer adds to clearness of expres- sion to carry the matter with strength, force, or vigor to the end sought. Elegance. — Elegance is tliat quality of expression which adapts the discourse to please. It is the essen- tial quality in literary composition; but in prose, Ele- gance is subordinate to Clearness, being permissable only to stimulate and open the mind to receive the thought expressed; while in oratory, Elegance serves to charm and win assent to propositions of duty and action. As Clearness, while the characteristic quality of prose, is essential to poetry and oratory, so Ele- gance, while the characteristic quality of poetry, is essential, under certain conditions, to prose and to oratory. A degree of Elegance may be said to be essential to all prose and to all oratory. At least, the style of these must be in good taste to the degree of having nothing disagreeable or offensive in them. The elements of style thus mutually condition each other. Clearness economizes the intellectual effort of inter- pretation; Elegance economizes the energies of the mind in the feelings, or by exhilarating the faculties enables them to do the work with greater ease. Thus not only to the degree of avoiding offense, but THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 83 to that of giving buoyancy to the faculties, Elegance is required in all discourse, and truth presented in the oration is often most deeply impressed by being clothed in forms of beauty. In Clearness, the laws of style are deduced from the necessary intellectual acts of language interpretation. In Elegance we are to deduce the laws wholly from an appeal to the sensibilities; and to them as the sense of the beautiful. Elegance appeals to the esthetic sense, and its laws must be determined by the general laws of beauty. Here style, in the highest form of Elegance, becomes the end of expression; not style as mere language, but the complete embodiment of the thought. It is not the purpose for the attention to rest in the mere matter communicated, as in prose; but the attention is diverted to the conception of the matter; the emotions are enlisted by it. The method, not the matter, is the chief concern of the writer and the source of interest to the reader. This does not mean that Elegance arises from mere external work- manship; but rather that the matter itself becomes a part of the method —becomes one with the expres- sion. Matter and form coalesce into a new and living product, which- as a whole pleases the taste. Thus, while style is subordinate to the end of thought and volition in prose and in oratory, in poetry it becomes an end in itself, existing in and for itself, as does any other beautiful object. An object is said to be beautiful when it is felt that the idea, or energy, which it manifests has its free- dom. A moving train is beautiful when it is felt that 1 84 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the energy which moves it is not in bondage to the train, — when the energy manifests itself with ease and freedom. When the observer is conscious, through the purring, straining, and slipping of wheels, that the energy is straining to move the train, he pronounces it ugly. The electric car is felt to be beautiful because it seems to be the free manifestation of its own inner life; while a car drawn by external force seems to be helpless and in bondage to its own nature, and hence felt to be ugly. A column is beautiful — well propor- tioned — when it supports its weight without effort, — when not so small that it seems in a strain to support weight above it, or when not so large that it has to support unnecessary weight in itself ; that is, when it is free in relation to the end it accomplishes. A tree is beautiful when the energy which creates it has fully and freely manifested itself. If the tree is lopped and twisted so that the creative energy suffers opposition and violence, the tree is felt to be ugly. Thus beauty is the manifestation of free, creative energy. Language is beautiful, therefore, when it gives free- dom to the energy which produces it ; and this in the twofold respect of its being the product of a physical force and of the idea which calls it forth. Such lan- guage causes esthetic pleasure in the process of inter- pretation. Clearness and Energy are also beautiful. One cannot help admiring perfectly transparent lan- guage, and this is because of the sense of freedom felt in coming directly in touch with the idea. Obscure language is necessarily ugly because it awakens a sense of bondage. Energetic language is felt to be THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 85 beautiful because tbe purpose of the speaker or writer is fully and freely realized. The reader cannot help rejoicing in the effective expression of a thought. In reading a good style of writing one often exclaims, That's the way to say it! because it brings to the reader an idealized sense of his own freedom of effort in giving his expression to thought. To put the case differently, every one has an abiding sense of bondage in expressing his thought so that it may produce the desired effect. When the reader reads an effective style of writing, his sense of bond- age is removed in a sense of freedom of expression awakened by the style. A writer may wish to arouse a feeling of sadness or of charity or of philanthropy, and his whole effort must be expended in producing the desired effect. When the language is fully ade- quate to the desired end, the reader rejoices in the idealized freedom of expression awakened in the proc- ess of interpretation. Thus in one sense Elegance is only the bloom of Clearness and Energy. It cannot be added to lan- guage; it is intrinsic and organic, and consists in what- ever awakens the sense of language freedom. Conditions for Securing the Qualities. Conditions for Securing Clearness. — Thought cannot be clearly embodied in language by any mere study of diction as such. Perspicuity of expression has its foundation in perspicuity of thought. The style grows out of the thought. The relation is an organic, a 1 86 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. vital one. Style is not mechanism; it is organism. It is built from the inside out, by the vital force which urges to expression. Thought is the soul; expression, the incarnate form, vitalized and moulded, not by ex- ternal pressure, but by the inner impulse of thought. True, Clearness depends on the right use of words and forms in which thought is embodied; but this must be ordered from within and not from without. Clearness of thought, therefore, with all that this implies of accurate discipline and thorough furnishing of the mind, is the general primary condition to clear- ness of expression. He who would seek this quality of style must subject himself to whatever discipline will secure power of distinct conception and clear insight, and the habit of methodical, thorough, and complete mental activity; to whatever will multiply the resources of his mind and increase the scope of his mental vision. Confused and obscure thinking cannot result in other than confused and obscure language, and only clearness of thinking can clothe itself in clearness of expression. It must not be understood that because the writer thinks clearly that he will necessarily write clearly. He is yet under the limi- tations of the laws of expression, to which he must render conscious obedience. There may be clear think- ing without clear expression, but not clear expression without clear thinking. It is here intended to empha- size only the fundamental importance of a mind trained to realize distinctly, vividly, and thoroughly, whatever it wishes to body forth in language form; and that to cultivate a perspicuous style implies not only the study THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 87 of the laws of expression, but a thorough culture of all the powers of the mind. Accordingly, a student who wishes to form a good style must not expect too much from direct means, but must rely chiefly on what- ever quickens intellectual life into thorough work. And not only is there needed thorough intellectual, but thorough moral habit as well. The attitude of the mind toward the truth to be presented may determine whether the truth be made obscure or obvious. If truth be presented in the interest of passion or preju- dice, it necessarily becomes partial, distorted, and blurred, and the phraseology can only disguise the truth which it should express. An earnest desire to present the truth for its own sake is the only impulse that can force the writer into obvious expression. Truth, sincerity, and simplicity in the writer are always transferred, consciously or unconsciously, to the writing, and the expression becomes true, simple, direct, and plain. Even when one writes with only a degree of self-consciousness, not yielding himself wholly to the thing he has to say, the unnatural fit of the expression to the thought betrays his insin- cerity, and impedes the reader. Whenever there is found a stilted, unnatural, pompous, high-sounding style as the garb of plain truth, it comes from the fact that the writer concerns himself more with the way in which he says it than with what he says. He wishes you to understand, not what he says, so much as that he is saying it, and saying it well. This desire to cultivate a style for its own sake leads to servile imitation of literary models. These should be used to 1 88 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. perfect one's expression; but to use them to form ex- pressions for the sake of the expression means hypoc- risy in the writer and weakness and obscurity in the writing. Let us, therefore, put down, in style as in morals, sincerity as the first desideratum. The general conditions of perspicuity, honesty and discipline, prepare for the more immediate conditions and special limitations of the writer's or the speaker's actual work of construction. In the first place, he must put himself under the limitations of a specific end, which his particular dis- course is to effect, and the means by which he is to reach the proposed end. The preceding chapters on Purpose and Thought have dealt with the ends and means with a view to effective expression. Since it is the province of rhetoric to treat of the effective utter- ance of thought, it must not omit the conditions to that end. It was stated in the chapter on Purpose that the first act of the mind in the construction of a discourse is the fixing of a definite aim. It now remains only to insist that a definite conception of the end, whether to instruct the intellect, please the emotions, or stimu- late to resolution, and of the specific character of each of these to be reached, is absolutely essential to Clear- ness. The end determines and organizes the means; and nothing less than a definite, vivid apprehension of the end can bring to bear suitable matter or embody it in intelligible forms. The end gives form to the composition, and the form must be clear in relation to that end. What is clear for one purpose may not be so for another. A thought presented clearly enough for THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 89 poetical purposes may be obscure for intellectual pur- poses; and matter presented clearly as individuals to the imagination may not be clear for purposes of thought. A definite aim rejects irrelevant ideas, puts in order confused ones, determines the right word and turn of phrase, and gives method, precision, and accuracy to all the movements of the mind. Without this special con- dition, it is impossible to give unity and symmetry to the theme — both essential to an easy and a correct understanding of the matter presented. After the writer has defined to himself the purpose and the special condition in the mind addressed under which the purpose is to be realized, a thorough mastery of the thought by means of which the purpose is to be realized is the last condition to clear expression. This is to be mastered under the relations and laws presented in the several chapters under thought — De- scription, Narration, Exposition, and Argumentation. To attempt to put in language what has not been clearly thought is the most prevalent source of ob- scurity. The first requirement under this head is that of a definite conception of the theme. The exact object, event, or thought must be so clearly apprehended as not only to give order and unity to the parts, and the mind free and easy movement in their arrangement, but that the mind may be so stimulated that it will clothe its thought in living forms. The theme should be studied till it becomes a part of the writer's being, and strives for utterance. Sidney Smith, in a criticism of Dr. Samuel Parr (quoted by Phelps), says: "He never seems hurried by his subject into obvious Ian- I9O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. guage." And Phelps continues (speaking in reference to sermons): "This hits the mark of defect in many sermons. A preacher's subject, if he have one and has so mastered it as to have clear thought upon it, will force him into an obvious style. He cannot help it if the subject fall within the range of the hearer's compre- hension. He must speak the plain truth, as we call it, like a plain man talking to plain men." It is well to remember, then, that in order to have perspicuity the subject should be so definitely bounded and clearly conceived that the writer or speaker will be " hurried by his subject into obvious language." This thorough mastery of the theme essential to " obvious " expression includes its analysis and syn- thesis by means of all the relations involved in thinking it. This will require at the outset a classification of the theme — whether individual or general; and if indi- vidual, whether fixed or changing; if general, whether in itself considered or applied to test truth. After the classification of the theme follows its mastery under all the relations which define and constitute it. Such a mastery alone can secure for that particular theme that definite, accurate, methodical, complete, and or- ganic thought essential to the clear and truthful pre- sentation to the mind of another. We are led to observe again the unity of the three phases of discourse, — purpose, thought, language. Purpose is limited by the nature of thought and lan- guage; thought conditioned by the purpose and the means of its expression; and language conditioned by both purpose and thought. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 191 Conditions for Securing Energy. - - 1 . Energy springs immediately from the desires and the will of the speaker. The force with which the speaker is urged on to the end he seeks measures the strength of his utterance. If he has truth which he wishes to commu- nicate, or if he feels deeply some soul-stirring senti- ment, or is restless under some ethical impulse, he will, without thought of his style, express himself with vigor and power. Truth which will not stay unsaid will be said forcibly. The more earnest the desire to plant a truth in another mind, for the sake of the other mind, the more strength will the speaker impart to the means he uses. Weakness is the most noticeable fea- ture of one's style who is not really in earnest. Energy in oratory requires of the speaker, more than anything else, a strong ethical impulse. Especially here does Energy spring from the desires and the will. The strength of these are the measure of the strength of the expression. So fundamental is this condition that often the speaker, without elegant or even correct expression, is thoroughly effective. Energy rests in the will's resolution to go forth and execute what the desires prompt. Much depends, however, on the de- sires which prompt to expression. A man's action is under the same law of energy as his style; but energy of action may result from special interests and private ends, while only the most disinterested and highest moral sentiment can impel to forcible utterance. Says Bascom : "The speaker who pursues private ends must either appeal to selfish impulses, which make a poor appearance, or he must go out of the range of his own I92 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. desires in finding the means of persuasion, and thus lose much of the zeal and energy with which the topic ought to be urged; or he must disguise and misrepre- sent the motives of action, and involve himself in all the tortuous, perplexing paths of evil. Those desires, therefore, which are fitted to infuse life into oratory, to inspire and impassion poetry even, must have breadth, philanthropy, and virtue in them, or they cannot address common interests or enkindle common feelings. The great ideas of justice, the public weal, liberty, and virtue must fully penetrate the mind, arouse the heart, and furnish the desires those objects fitted to call forth and nourish speech. According to the intensity of the desire with which common ends, the interest of public and private well-being, are pur- sued will be the energy of discourse. Virtue must rely chiefly on persuasion, and has ever at hand the means and also the motives to employ it. That training which deepens and strengthens virtuous desires and brings the will under its steady government gives to the man, in its most reliable form, all the working power of his nature, impresses all his words with his own life, his own energy." x A definite conception of the immediate end and of the relation of means to that end are essential to Energy. The discipline in thoroughness and accuracy and directness of thought, insisted on under Clearness, are equally important here. "While feeling impels, it cannot take the place of clear, explicit guidance. Nothing but a definite aim can arouse and concentrate 1 Bascom's "Philosophy of Rhetoric." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 93 the mind; and nothing but a full knowledge of the thought to be presented and faculties trained to wield thought with rapidity, precision, and power can warrant a high degree of energy." 1 << Discourse which has an object — a palpable object, an object incessantly pres- ent to the speaker's thought, to which he hastens on for the hearer's sake — is sure in some degree to be energetic discourse." 2 2. The immediate condition for securing Energy is Clearness and Elegance. Obscure thought cannot be presented with force ; and without a certain degree of Elegance, the mind will not readily receive the truth presented. But when Elegance rises to esthetic ends, Energy is sacrificed. Much feeling and interest may be thus aroused, but of no avail to the purpose. "The imagination has free scope, the heart is feasted, but the will is not nerved. The emasculated oration does the work of the novel. This error of discourse arises from the vanity of the speaker, and nourishes the indo- lence of all parties. It becomes fatal according to the greatness and urgency of the end proposed. It is, therefore, in pulpit oratory especially, the most inex- cusable of faults." Elegance must subordinate itself to the purpose of the speaker. If it does not submit itself to the purpose and to the theme, it ceases to be elegant ; for an object not nicely adjusted to its end cannot be beautiful. Oratory must be in earnest ; and being so prevents all indulgence of poetic taste, all display of workmanship, all reveling in poetic delights. 1 Bascom's " Philosophy of Rhetoric." 2 Phelps' " English Style." 194 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Conditions for Securing Elegance. — i . The first in order is culture on the part of the writer. As Clear- ness of style is conditioned by clearness of thinking, so Elegance is conditioned by richness and delicacy of feeling and beauty of conception. Rules of Elegance will avail little with a coarse and uncultivated writer. Longfellow is distinctively artistic in discourse, because, to a naturally refined soul and delicate taste, he added all the refinement of a rich and varied culture. Exces- sive faith in short processes, without the patience to wait the fruit of legitimate labor, often leads the youth to seek literary accomplishment by some special course in language training. Again, it must be insisted that style is not something externally formed, but the natu- ral growth of an inner impulse. The style of the man is the quality of the mind manifesting itself in external form ; and the form will necessarily assume the deli- cacy, grace, and color of the soul from which it receives its vitality. No painting can add to the cheek the crimson flush of life ; no mechanism can give to the artist's material the charm of life and beauty. " Noth- ing mounts into the region of art without undergoing some transformation, receiving buoyancy and color from the mind that wings it for its flight." Elegance results from the infused life and character of the artist. Accordingly, he who aspires to artistic merit in style or to the fullest appreciation of the beautiful in dis- course must discipline and enlighten the mind; purify, refine, and intensify the emotions, by the most thor- ough culture of which he is susceptible. Whatever, therefore, cultivates the taste, giving grace, buoyancy, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 195 and delicacy of movement to the mind ; whatever makes the emotions sensitive and diversified ; what- ever gives the emotional chords tone, intensity, and harmony is an indispensable part of the composer's schooling in the art of elegant writing, and no less essential to appreciative reading. So much does Ele- gance depend on the quality of the mind that rules for securing it are almost worthless. Rules may do much toward securing Clearness, but Elegance is too diffused and volatile to be formulated. 2. The more immediate condition of Elegance is Clearness. In Elegance the language still remains a means of communicating the thought ; and imperfect adaptation to that end, as with any other instrument, clashes with the pleasant emotion of the beautiful. The obscure is necessarily the ugly. Clear expression gives perfect freedom to the idea which seeks to develop itself in an external form ; and such freedom is of the nature of beauty. Wherever there seems to be a struggle of the idea, the essence, the soul within an object, to free itself, we have the sense of the false and ugly. Expression which cramps the idea — obscure expression — is, therefore, inelegant. Tautology is not simply obscurity ; it is deformity. A series of long sentences means not only exhausted faculties in grasp- ing the ideas, but offended sense of harmony. Bun- gling work offends the taste, but that expression which so perfectly bodies forth the idea as to seem to be one with it is essentially elegant. This does not mean that Clearness can rise to the plane of positive pleas- ure ; it is only the negative side of beauty in expres- I96 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. sion, having rather the absence of offensive elements than positive sources of pleasure. The Rhetorical Qualities Secured. With such preparation as the preceding, — in general, through honesty and discipline ; in particular, some definite, specific aim fixed upon, and a thorough mas- tery of the thought which is to serve as a means to the end, — the writer comes to the immediate process of putting his thoughts in language. This process is controlled by the process of interpre- tation, for it is in this process that language appears clear, becomes impressive, and appeals to the taste. The process of giving the thought and that of receiv- ing it are opposite in method ; the first being by a process of analysis, the second by a process of syn- thesis. Before beginning to embody his thought, the writer must grasp his matter as an organic whole, in which act he analyzes and presents part by part in the light of the whole. But the reader receives part by part, and constructs the whole as he proceeds. The writer sees the whole from the beginning ; the reader not till the end. The reader begins where the writer quits — with individual ideas. But the writer must be conscious of the interpreting process of the reader ; else the writer cannot economize and stimulate the mental energies in that process. The first thing the writer needs to know, therefore, is the mental process of interpreting the language of discourse. Only such knowledge can enable the writer to move with ease THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 1 97 and self-assurance ; because it brings, instead of the bondage of dead arbitrary rules of style, the freedom of the reason that underlies them. All rules of style are based on laws of discourse interpretation — on the necessary activity of the mind in realizing thought from language. Yet they are too often studied as the arbitrary, abstract dicta of the rhetorician, and in such cases are of questionable utility. We are told that a short word is better than a long one ; that a Saxon word is better than a foreign one ; yet to follow these rules rather than the principles underlying them would frequently lead to serious error, and thus impede rather than help the writer. Language interpretation involves the activity of all the faculties, — sense-perception, memory, imagination, judgment, and reason; and also feeling and volition. The specific forms of these activities through which language becomes clear, strong, and beautiful is deter- mined by the nature of the language to be interpreted. This nature has a threefold aspect : — First, language may be viewed as a material thing, without reference to its content. As such it must be apprehended through sense-perception. The body, or vehicle, of thought must be matter of observation before it can have significance ; and this through the eye and ear, and most prominently the latter. Through this act of sense-perception certain language qualities are conducive to clearness, energy, or elegance; and frequently of all at once. Second, but language would not be language without expressing thought. And first it bears a direct rela- I98 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. tion to thought, which relation is twofold. There is the direct back-and-forth relation of words and phrases to the ideas expressed, and also the relation of the language parts to the organization of the ideas in the thought. This twofold direct relation of language to thought requires certain specific forms of interpreting activities — of memory, imagination, and judgment. It is in and through these activities that the writer makes his language efficient — clear, forcible, and beautiful. Third, language not only bears a direct relation to the thought in discourse, but also an indirect rela- tion. The thing directly expressed is a means, or language, for expressing something else. When Lowell speaks of opening the portals of the future with the blood-rusted key of the past, the objects presented by the words "portals" and "blood-rusted key" are not the objects of consideration, but only a more effective statement than could be secured by direct language. This indirect relation of language to thought requires peculiar interpreting activities, chiefly in the form of the creative imagination and the intuitive reason. The direct relation of language form to thought constitutes literal language ; while the indirect relation constitutes figurative language. Through figurative language, in addressing the creative power of the mind, language reaches its highest power of efficiency. LANGUAGE AS AN OBJECT OF PERCEPTION. Language as a mere object of perception must be such as not to arrest the attention in an act of sense- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. I99 perception, and, with this negative mark, it may be such as to impress the thought or please the taste. The composer must take full advantage of these acts of sense-perception in order to secure the three phases of effective utterance. To this end his language must be (i) Correct, (2) Distinct, (3) Brief, (4) Euphonious, (5) Harmonious, and (6) Rhythmical. Correctness. — Misspelled words, not only by diver- sion of attention through the eye, but by the train of thought they suggest, are distracting. For the same reason typographical errors should be avoided. The correct pronunciation of a word attracts no attention ; at least, should not. In fact, the test of a speaker's pronunciation is that an educated audience do not notice how the words are pronounced. Any affectation or seeming effort to be correct is distract- ing to the hearer. Economy of effort in the process of interpretation is the reason for a uniform standard of pronunciation, as set forth in the dictionary. Ideas which now pass freely from mind to mind would be clogged in their passage by a multiplicity of strange forms for the same meaning. Accordingly, the speaker who aspires to effective utterance should see to it that he has a faultless pronunciation. Distinctness. — It requires an extra amount of effort to perceive a word that is not clearly written in itself or made to stand out distinctly from others. This may not be a question of style, for it lies beyond the control of the writer ; but if the printed discourse is to have its full effect, the size and clearness of the t'H- S . - .uul th. . a .-.■•.•.■ •• must '•. - • . . . minimum the . - .■ to . thf wvtds. - '. . • words should be dist h . '\ enu". • s . • > the w .- . •• \ It is that q f which if we . to > to the miud and . . e the tv.v >•• from stu> guish and se e . i the e .-. . - .- . • the » • . sei w '••'■• the) .. . ' l< . . . . . ' when thf \\ 9 -■ lot ■•-■ '. * . • &uffr ■. •• u ith I - eceh @ full) the ee bis i been « asted •■• $< -. the wea ds insl ..■ « i • .••-. •' i the hat the mind bed - - it. Often m well chosen we i so the sense ■• '•••.-. \ innd, This b es thf \ . « effort simp!) \ • eq\ •• .• a pi cm ess ■■• anal) syllabi • - distinguish it from < . words which it close!) resembles When, however, onf s s the • >i §e\ era! &h< ifs, thf use ••' thf ' ••• . woi d ctconom] >- tention Short the i -■■ . and e thus nied b\ a sense ol freedom and her. ->••• illei • slmplei thf Insti ument THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 201 which does a given piece of work, the greater our admiration for it. Passing to the sentence we find the thought en- veloped in a form which must be perceived part by- part. Whatever is unnecessary in this form occasions a waste of effort on the part of the recipient of the thought. The compression of the bulk without lessen- ing the weight of the content enables the composer to send the message with such precision and effect that the hearer is unconscious of effort to receive it. Just as words with the fewest letters and syllables reserve the full energy of the mind for the appropriation of the idea, so a sentence with the fewest words for a given thought does not divert the power of the mind into the channel of sense-perception, which should be reserved for the full realization of thought. Therefore, the sentence, for the sake of clearness, should contain the fewest words consistent with the other require- ments of sentential structure. And as secondary qualities energy and elegance are secured through such brevity. As in words and sentences, so in discourse taken as a whole ; the shorter in proportion to the content the greater is the economy of sense-perception. The com- poser's problem is to compress the bulk without dimin- ishing the weight. Lowell says that Shakespeare squeezes meaning into a phrase with an hydraulic press. This should be the composer's effort in the entire dis- course. This, however, is limited by the strength of the interpreter to appropriate concentrated food. Yet one must not speak an infinite deal of nothing which 202 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. requires the interpreter to search as if for a grain of wheat in a bushel of chaff, and which if found would scarcely be worth the search. Discourse which is especially offensive in this respect is called bombast, the remedy' for which lies beyond cautions in the use of language ; for an inflated style can be remedied only by removing the inflation of the writer. Eup ho ny.-- Euphony — literally sound and well — is that quality of a word which makes it pleasant to the ear. Strictly speaking, euphonious sounds are free sounds, — sounds made when nothing obstructs the emerging column of breath. Hence, euphony is more closely allied to elegance than to clearness or energy. All words difficult to speak are rough, harsh, and un- pleasant to the ear. This property belongs strictly to oral words ; yet by association, the written word sug- gests the sensation of its sound, and thus becomes a diverting and unpleasant element. Euphony depends on (i) the choice of the word and (2) on the way it is spoken. 1 . The pleasant sounds include the vowels and the liquid consonants /, m, n, r ; and the unpleasant sounds are especially the gutterals g and x and the sibilants s and s. This classification depends on the degree of freedom in the emergence of the sound, which strictly followed would not put letters in classes, but would mark each letter as differing from every other in respect to the beauty of its sound. Suppose that in the emergence of the column of breath every obstruction be removed as fully as possible, there will be produced the most THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2C»3 beautiful sound in language — long Italian a ; the first sound in every language. By slightly closing the mouth horizontally the modified as and «?'s and i's are produced, which are less beautiful because there is a sense of obstruction in the sound. By closing the mouth partially laterally the sound of o and kindred sounds are produced. The consonants are produced by completely shutting off the column of breath, and are ugly because their sound is obstructed. In the liquid consonants there is still an easy flow of the breath ; hence, liquid sounds. The different sounds in the alphabet are produced by different kinds and degrees of obstruction, and there is a constant increas- ing of bondage of sound from the long Italian a to the gutterals and sibilants. The chief fault in English is its hissing s and z sound, represented by five letters, — c before e and i ; s, z, x(= ks), and / before ion ; as, cessation, science, Xerxes, exactly. When all the individual sounds are pleasant only the right proportion of vowels and consonants will secure euphony. An excess of liquids or vowels is not euphonious ; as, " Tho' oft the ear the open vowels tire." Harshness is produced by the union of too many consonants; as, form'dst, splutters, stretched, church, smoothedst, inextricableness, excogitation, twitches, sarcastical. Long words accented on the first syllable, as per- fectness, peremptorily, disciplinary, expiatory, are diffi- cult to utter and unpleasant to hear. Euphony is violated in words in which a syllable is immediately repeated; as, holily, lowlily, wilily. Vowels coming 204 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. together in the middle of a word or between two words, as hiatus, idea, idea of, you unto, produce an unpleas- ant effect. The same consonant ending one word and beginning the next, as, his son, keep people looking, is not euphonious. The repetition of the same word causes an unpleasant sensation; as, Whatever is, is right, How it was was not explained, He perceives that that sentence is not euphonious. It is obvious here, as in all the preceding, that the utterance is made with difficulty ; hence, the lack of beauty. Words impress the idea by means of the sound which they signify. Such words are called Onomato- poetic ; as, buzz, crackle, hiss, crash, rub-a-dub-dub. Hawthorne describes the rain thus: — - " All day long, and for a week together, the rain was drip-drip- dripping and splash-splash-splashing from the eaves into the tubs beneath the spouts." Milton, in describing the opening of hell's gate, uses this kind of energy with good effect: — " On a sudden open fly With impetuous coil, and jarring sound, The infernal doors ; and on their hinges grate Harsh thunder." Words not imitative, but whose sound is suggestive of the feeling to be expressed are impressive, as may be observed in the closing lines of each stanza of Poe's "Raven," which repeatedly employ the long sound of <?asa fitting sound for the refrain of sadness: — " Then this ebon bird beguiling my sad fancy into smiling, By the grave and stern decorum of the countenance it wore, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 205 'Though thy crest be shorn and shaven, thou,' I said, 'art sure no craven; Ghastly, grim, and ancient Raven, wandering from the nightly shore, Tell me what thy lordly name is on the Night's Plutonian shore ? ' Quoth the Raven, ' Nevermore.' " The same art of impression is employed effectively in the following stanza from Tennyson's " Ode on the Death of the Duke of Wellington ": — " Lead out the pageant ; sad and slow, As fits an universal woe, Let the long, long procession go, And let the sorrowing crowd about it grow, And let the mournful martial music blow; The last great Englishman is low." Words which prolong emphasis, as " nevermore," favor energy. Words whose magnitude of sound are suggestive of the magnitude of the idea lend force to expression. When an important truth is pushed to the end of the sentence to give it prominence, a full, round cadence is essential to its emphasis. Words that require energy of utterance contribute to energy of impression, as may be observed by con- trasting the following: bent, bended; burnt, burned; spelt, spelled. 2. Not only the selection of a word, but the manner of uttering it is subject to the law of euphony. The word most euphonious in itself may be pronounced dis- agreeably, and the harsh ones may be softened by a pleasant voice. A pure, pleasant tone is indispensable 206 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. to him who would communicate thought orally. The most musical composition is often marred or obscured by a shrill or husky voice. Some speakers have the offensive habit of giving prominence to rough sounds, especially the hissing sound of s or z, while euphony requires that these be slurred and prominence given to the full, round, musical tones. It must not be supposed that a euphonious word which will exactly fit the idea to be expressed can always be found. The sound must not interfere with the sense. Of two words otherwise equal, the pleas- ant sounding one should be chosen ; and here the obli- gation to euphony ends, except what aid pronunciation can bring. These oral qualities, except to a certain extent in euphony, are under the control, not of the writer, but of the reader or speaker. At this point the art of oral expression arises out of the science of discourse. Elocution which has for its purpose the effective oral delivery of thought is only a pushing out into a more complete form and fixing in habit of speech the princi- ples of oral expression which here begin to rise to the surface. Not only are individual discourses, but languages are marked by their difference in euphony. The most euphonious languages are Greek and Latin, and the modern languages derived from the Latin, Italian, Portugese, Spanish, and French. Teutonic languages are harsh. In respect to euphony, the English lan- guage is intermediate, having a mixture of both Teu- tonic and Latin elements. Byron's exaggeration of THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 20"J the rough quality of the English well illustrates and emphasizes the truth of its harshness : — " Our harsh, northern, whistling, grunting gutteral, Which we 're obliged to hiss, and spit, and splutter all." Here Byron makes good use of the sound to impress the sense. His statement is perfectly transparent and admirably forcible. Harmony. — The eye and the ear follow words in their succession. The succession of form to the eye produces no effect different in kind from that produced in observing single words. The accumulated effect by the addition of words is an appreciable quantity, and can only be reduced as stated above. But the succes- sion of sounds to the ear produces an effect different in kind from the effect of the individual sounds — an effect depending wholly on the character of the succes- sion. The sounds themselves may be smooth and pleasant, yet the total effect be jarring and unpleas- ant ; and when unpleasant, the sound becomes an ob- struction to the thought instead of its perfect vehicle. That quality of the sentence by which the energies of the mind are not wasted because of the character of the succession of sounds is called Harmony. Harmony is the adjustment of the sounds of words to each other in their successions so that they will fall smoothly and pleasantly on the ear. Or, harmony is that structure of the sentence which permits its utter- ance with the natural rise and fall of the breath, i.e., when it permits free utterance. Harmony as a means of clearness need not reach the degree of positive 208 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. pleasure as in music and poetry, but only the degree which secures the absence of its opposite — negative harmony. Harmonious sounds stimulate the faculties to appropriate the truth, while inharmonious sounds repel from such appropriation. Unless one write poetry of pronounce an oration, he seldom thinks of construct- ing his discourse with reference to the sound. But harmony is not a matter of elegance or energy only. The experience of every one has convinced him that the smooth onflowing of the sentence which sets well to the ear is an essential condition to ease of interpreta- tion. This results chiefly from the clearness given to the medium; but the stimulation of the pleasant sound to the faculties, when not so great as to enlist the attention, enables them to do their work with greater ease and more thoroughly. This energizing power of language over the mind belongs to force of expression rather than to clearness. Unpleasant combination of words cannot always be avoided without obscuring the sense. While sound must not be ignored, it must never be allowed to modify or obscure the meaning. The more rigid requirements of exact truth and genuine sentiment must check any temptation to use words merely to round out a musical period. No definite rules on the subject of harmony can be prescribed. The reliance must be in the ear made susceptible by training to harmonious discourse. Some general suggestions, however, may be helpful. As in words ease of pronunciation is the test of euphony, so in sentences, ease and agreeableness to the THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2CX) organs of speech is the test of harmony. It is, there- fore, essential to harmony that the parts of the sentence be so arranged that the connection between them will fall at the proper intervals to make the breathing easy and natural. The following sentence from Tillotson, quoted by Blair, illustrates the lack of harmony arising from the number and distributions of the rests: — " This discourse concerning the easiness of God's commands, does, all along, suppose and acknowledge the difficulties of the first upon a religious course ; except only in those persons who have had the happiness to be trained up to religion by the easy and insensible degrees of a pious and virtuous education." Concerning this sentence, Blair says: " Here there is no harmony; nay, there is some degree of harshness and unpleasantness; owing principally to this, that there is, properly, no more than one pause or rest in the sentence, falling betwixt the two members into which it is divided, each of which is so long as to occasion a considerable stretch of the breath in pro- nouncing it." The following paragraph from the same author con- tains a sentence which, with the comments upon it, makes clear the distinction between the harmonious and the inharmonious sentence: — " But, God be thanked, his pride is greater than his ignorance, and what he wants in knowledge, he supplies by sufficiency. When he has looked about him, as far as he can, he concludes there is no more to be seen ; when he is at the end of his line, he is at the bottom of the ocean; when he has shot his best, he is sure none ever did, or ever can, shoot better, or beyond it. His own measure he holds to be the certain measure of truth; and his own knowledge of what is possible in nature." 2IO THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE " Here everything is at once, easy to the breath, and grateful to the ear ; and, it is this sort of flowing meas- ure, this regular and proportional division of the mem- bers of his sentence which renders Sir William Temple's style always agreeable. I must observe at the same time, that a sentence with too many rests, and these placed at intervals too apparently measured and regu- lar, is apt to savour of affectation." The parts separated by pauses should have harmoni- ous proportion; not only rests at easy intervals, but variety in quality and length of parts; yet, with all, unity of flow in the sound, — the fuller swell of sound alternating with subsidence, each merging gradually into the other in an undulation of pleasant proportion. The longest and most sonorous member should be put last, and the others arranged according to the principle of climax. This sentence from Irving illustrates well the proper division into members, and how the sound may increase to a full and harmonious close: — " But the sorrows of the poor, who have no outer appliances to soothe, — the sorrows of the aged, with whom life at best is but a wintry day, and who can look for no after-growth of joy, — the sorrows of a widow, aged, solitary, destitute, mourning over an only son, the last solace of her years; these are indeed sorrows that make us feel the impotency of consolation." The weakening of the sound at the close by gradu- ally shortening the members and closing with a short word is both inharmonious in sound and feeble in thought. This may be illustrated by reversing the order in the foregoing sentence. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 211 Harmony in discourse requires not only variety and unity of movement in the single sentences, but also variety and unity in their succession. If the conditions of harmony are all met in a sentence, a repetition of the same arrangement in each succeeding sentence becomes monotonous and offensive. Sen- tences constructed on a similar plan should never follow one another. Short sentences and long ones should be intermixed. It may be necessary to violate har- mony in the single sentence to secure harmony when connected with others. Monotony is incompatible with harmony. Variety, with the suggestion of unity by the easy, uninterrupted movement of voice, is the secret, the soul of harmony. The strained, monotonous humdrum of a speaker or reader, even when the sen- tences in themselves and in their arrangement favor harmony, often prevents the effective delivery of thought. Modulation in the discourse as a whole, like modulation in the sentence, is an essential condition to effective delivery. RhytJim. — We now arrive at what is strictly known as poetic form — measured, musical utterance. There maybe poetry in spirit and thought — in essence — without metrical form, yet the most intense poetic spirit naturally clothes itself in musical utterance. The rhythmical sound itself may, as in music, symbolize the emotion, without the necessity of articulate speech; but aside from this the sound itself is so pleasing as to become an end in itself. Thus at this point the sense qualities of language arise out of the servitude to thought — - realize their freedom from thought, and 212 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. take their place wholly in the realm of the beautiful. The sound still serves to convey the thought, but it here thrusts itself on the attention as a pleasing, sen- suous element to the ear. Of so much value is this element of beauty that the poet has license to constrain the sense for the sake of the sound. In fact, metric utterance is so much of bondage to thought as not to be admissible when the thought is expressed for its own sake. The chief fact about poetic form is that of Rhythm. This has reference to a certain flowing, wave-like move- ment of voice, which, to a certain extent, obscures the stiff requirements of articulate speech. This wave-like movement is highly complex, and is divided into parts within parts. The simplest element in this movement is the syllable. This enters into elementary combina- tions with other syllables; this new combination into still more complex combinations ; and so on till the stanza or the poem is reached. The simplest order of rhythm consists of one strong and one or more weak impulses of the voice. One move- ment of the voice from the stress to the remission or from the remission to the stress is called a Foot. A Foot is a single compound movement of the voice. The strong impulse of the voice which falls on a certain syllable is called the Rhythm-accent. The syllable not only receives more stress but more time in its pro- nunciation. In Latin and Greek, the Rhythm-accent falls on a long syllable; hence, the rhythm in these lan- guages is said to be based on quantity. English rhythm is said to be based on accent ; but in giving the accent, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 21 3 more time is required in its pronunciation, so that the two are inseparable. The syllable that is accented in prose is used for the Rhythm-accent, thus speaking the sense of the word and at the same time securing the music of the verse. A single compound movement of the voice never extends over more than three syllables. Accordingly, afoot will always consist of either one, two, or three syl- lables, giving one accented and one or two unaccented syllables to each foot. The accent may fall on either syllable in the foot — first, second, or third. Falling on the last, we have, if two syllables, the Iam- bic foot; if three syllables, the Anapaestic foot. Fall- ing on the first, we have, if two syllables, the Trochaic foot; if three syllables, the Dactylic foot. When the middle of the three syllables is accented, the foot is called the Amphibrach. The following are examples of each in the order named above: — i . The mel' an chol' y days' are come', the sad' dest of the year'. 2. There 's a smile' on the fruit', and a smile' on the flower'. 3. Tell' me not' in mourn' ful num'bers. 4. Wist' ful ly wan' der ing o' ver the wa'ters, she Sought' for the land' of the bless' ed. 5. The wa'ters are flash' ing, The white' hail is dash' ing. Seldom will the verse be made up of the same kind of feet. Yet one kind must prevail, and this one gives character to the verse. There is great gain in substi- tuting a foot for the regular one, for thus variety is secured. There is, however, a limit to such substitu- 214 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. tion. Two accented syllables or three unaccented syllables should not occur together, because such an arrangement prevents free, easy movement of the voice. One accented syllable cannot be pronounced after an- other accented syllable without a pause, thus causing a jerking movement and an unpleasant sensation. Hence, a foot accented on the last syllable, an Iambus or an Anapaest, should not be followed by a foot accented on the first syllable, a Trochee or a Dactyl. And since three unaccented syllables standing together interfere with rhythmical effect, an Anapaest must not follow a Trochee; neither an Iambus, an Amphibrach, or an Anapaest follow an Amphibrach. At the beginning or at the end of a line, more freedom of substitution is permitted. A Trochee may begin a line of Iambic feet, since nothing precedes the accented syllable and only two unaccented syllables are brought together. The end feet, not standing between other feet, make possible a great variety of combinations not permitted within the line. The principle stated is a safe guide. Two accented syllables or three unaccented syllables stand- ing together cannot be pronounced with rhythmic move- ment of voice. Within this limit the poet has all possible freedom, and the highest rhythmical beauty is attained by variety in the kinds of feet. One kind of foot, however, must characterize the verse; and the variety must be secured by substituting for the regular feet others that will not interfere with the free onflow- ing of the voice. It will be observed that the substituted feet are pro- nounced in the same time as those for which they are THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 21 5 substituted, thus giving variety in the rate of utterance as well as in the quality. The so-called Monosyllabic foot occupies the same time as the other feet of the stanza in which it occurs. This gives, when required, a slow and stately movement, as if borne down with grief or by dignity of sentiment, as in the first line of this: — " Break, break, break, On the cold, grey stones, O sea; And I would that my tongue could utter The thoughts that arise in me." The poet has great power of adjustment in the move- ment of the verse to adapt it to the sentiment he wishes to express. This may be pointed out in the examples at the close of this topic, and the method of securing the suitable movement explained. It will be interest- ing to note, also, what kind of foot is most commonly employed, and which is seldom met with. The simplest order of Rhythm has been stated to be that of the foot. These feet are again grouped into higher orders of Rhythm --grouped by the sense into phrases, making convenient stages of rest for the voice, and marked by what is known as the Caesural pause; or grouped by Alliterative rhythm or by some Emphatic word. This second order of groups is again grouped in the line or the verse, marked by some nat- ural pause required by the sense or by ease of utter- ance or by Rhyme. Only the last grouping of the elementary rhythmical movement need here be noted. A Verse is the coordination of several elementary rhythmical movements into one compound movement, 2l6 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. bearing a definite relation in number to the primary movement. The verse is characterized, therefore, by the number of its primary movements. A verse con- sisting of one foot is called a Monometer; of two feet, Dimeter; of three feet, Trimeter; of four feet, Tetram- eter; of five feet, Pentameter; of six feet, Hexameter. The number of feet in the verse may vary in the poem, but there is a prevailing number which gives character to the poem. As already stated, the grouping into feet is sometimes indicated by Rhyme, giving rise to the distinction of Rhyming verse and Blank verse. Rhyme is the recur- rence of the same sound at the close of each of two or more lines. These sounds must not be identical throughout, but only so from the accented syllable to the close. When the accented vowel and the sound or sounds which follow are identical, the rhyme is said to be perfect; provided the sounds which precede the accented vowel are different. Thus dreary rhymes perfectly with weary; day with pay ; and tenderly with slenderly. In the imperfect rhyme, the sounds, which in the perfect rhyme are identical, differ; yet they are sufficiently alike to suggest similarity, as poor and door; wrong and tongue; afternoon and love-tune. Rhymes are also single, double, and triple, illustrated respectively in day and pay ; dreary and zveary; tenderly and slenderly. Rhymes are further classified on the basis of their manner of succession. Some are succes- sive, some alternate, and some occur at variously con- trived intervals; yet usually with a regularity which becomes the more beautiful in proportion as it breaks THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2\J the constraint of obvious regular recurrence, and dis- plays ingenuity on the part of the writer. Verses are coordinated into the larger and more com- plex group of rhythmical units, called Stanzas. A stanza is a group of any number of verses, and is named from the number of verses it contains. A grouping of stan- zas into a poem constitutes the most complex rhyth- mical unit. Another phase of rhythm should not be overlooked, for it has great poetic charm; and that is, what is known as rhythmical fullness. This is the formal characteristic feature of Hebrew poetry, and is illustrated by almost any verse from the Psalms; as, "The heavens declare the glory of God; and the firmament showeth His handiwork." In this it will be observed that the last half is a restatement of the meaning of the first. It is a kind of swinging movement of thought. This is a marked source of beauty in both Tennyson and Long- fellow. Note it in these: — 1. "Comrades, leave me here a little, while as yet 'tis early morn; Leave me here, and when you want me, sound upon the bugle horn." 2. " The day is cold, and dark, and dreary; It rains, and the wind is never weary; The vine still clings to the mouldering wall, But at every gust the dead leaves fall, And the day is dark and dreary." Still another form of rhythm is Alliteration, which is the repetition of a sound at the beginning of two or 2l8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. more successive words; as, "Apt alliteration's artful aid." The following examples illustrate its nature and value to style : — " That would his rightful ravine rend away." " With hideous horror both together smiffht And souce (strike) so sore, that they the heavens affray : The wise soothsayer, seeing so sad sight." " Friendless, homeless, hopeless, they wandered from city to city ; From the cold lakes of the North to sultry Southern savannas." " A pilgrim wanting a pin or a pistol, a cucumber or a camel, a house or a horse, a loan or a lentil, a date or a dragoman, a melon or a man, a dove or a donkey, has only to inquire at the Joppa Gate." There should be such variety in all the points of the poetic form as not to suggest constraint on the part of the writer or the spirit within the writing. There should be variety in the kinds and the number of feet, and in their arrangement ; in the kinds and succession of rhymes; and in the number and kinds of verses in the stanzas. There must seem to be no constraint to set form, but the greatest variety within the limit of rhythmical movement. The theme itself demands such variety. The varying sentiment sometimes re- quires a quick, sprightly movement, and sometimes the slow, heavy tread of the stately march. Let the following be tested and explained in all the points of poetic form, noting carefully the means of securing variety and adaptation to the varying senti- ment : — THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2\() 1. " Half a league, half a league, Half a league onward All in the Valley of Death Rode the six hundred." 2. " Build me straight, O worthy Master, Staunch and strong, a goodly vessel, That shall laugh at all disaster, And with wave and whirlwind wrestle." 3. " There's a dance of leaves in that aspen bower, There 's a titter of winds in that beechen tree, There 's a smile on the fruit, and a smile on the flower, And a laugh from the brook that runs to the sea." 4. " So live that when thy summons comes to join The innumerable caravan, which moves To that mysterious realm, where each shall take His chamber in the silent halls of death, Thou go not, like the quarry-slave at night, Scourged to his dungeon, but, sustained and soothed By an unfaltering trust, approach thy grave, Like one who wraps the drapery of his couch About him, and lies down to pleasant dreams." 5. " I saw him once before, As he passed by the door, And again The pavement stones resound, As he totters o'er the ground, With his cane." 6. " A little lowly heritage it was, Down in a dale, hard by a forest's side, Far from resort of people, that did pass In travel to and fro ; a little wide There was an holy chapel edified, 220 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Wherein the hermit duly went to say His holy things each morn and eventide ; Thereby a crystal stream did gently play, Which from a sacred fountain welled forth alway." 7. " And what is so rare as a day in June? Then, if ever, come perfect days : Then Heaven tries the earth if it be in tune, And over it softly her warm ear lays. Whether we look, or whether we listen, We hear life murmur, or see it glisten ; Every clod feels a stir of might, An instinct within it that reaches and towers, And groping blindly above it for light, Climbs to a soul in grass and flowers." 8. " I wooed the blue-eyed maid Yielding, yet half afraid, And in the forest's shade Our vows we plighted. Under its loosened vest Fluttered her little breast, Like birds within their nest, By the hawk frighted." 9. " Fear death ? — to feel the fog in my throat, The mist in my face, When the snows begin and the blasts denote I am nearing the place, The power of the night, the press of the storm, The post of the foe, Where he stands, the Arch Fear in a visible form ? Yet the strong man must go ; For the journey is done and the summit attained, And the barriers fall, Though a battle 's to fight ere the guerdon be gained, The reward of it all." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 22 1 10. " Many a morning on the moorland did we hear the copses ring, And her whisper throng'd my pulses with the fullness of the spring." ii. "Ye who believe in affection, that hopes and endures and is patient, Ye who believe in the beauty and strength of woman's devotion, List to the mournful tradition still sung by the pines of the forest ; List to a Tale of Love in Acadie, home of the happy." THE DIRECT RELATION OF LANGUAGE TO THOUGHT. As already observed, this phase of language has two aspects : one that of the direct back-and-forth relation of expression to idea, and the other the relation of the language to the organization of the ideas into a thought whole. Thus there are two phases in the process of interpreting language under the present heading: one that of gathering the material of thought from the vehicle of thought, and the other that of organizing the material gathered into a thought whole. Of course all the interpreting acts move simultaneously; but logi- cally they are conditioned in the order named. Ob- serving the language form conditions the gathering of the ideas which constitute the material of the discourse; which material must be gathered before it can be organized. Yet these acts move simultaneously through the discourse. Thus we are brought next to the discussion of the language qualities which make language effective through the association of language form with ideas. 222 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ASSOCIATION OF LANGUAGE FORM WITH IDEAS. Language form is associated with ideas by three acts: that of the memory, of the imagination, and of the judgment. The memory associates the word with the idea; the imagination realizes the idea in imagery; and the judgment decides from the context as to the fitting idea. These acts require, respec- tively, language to be Familiar, Concrete, and Precise. Familiarity. - - Economy of memory in the act of interpretation requires the use of words that, in the process of interpretation, have passed into identity in consciousness with the idea which they express. These consist of such words as have become familiar by their intimate association with the experience of life. Unfamiliar words may be inferred from the con- text, but this requires extra labor from the reader. The mind of the reader should pass directly and un- consciously to the content of the word. One strange word in a sentence renders useless all the others, puzzling not only the memory in trying to call up its meaning but also the imagination and judgment in their effort to organize the ideas. The vocabulary with which anyone is familiar differs from that used by any other, and is small when com- pared with the whole vocabulary in general use. The writer or speaker cannot adapt his words to the special limitation of each individual addressed, but must as- sume familiarity with the words in current use. In addressing a special audience, special adaptation can be made; but in addressing the general public, he is at THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 223 liberty to use only words that are at present used every- where by intelligent and educated writers. That quality of a word which gives it a right to usage in the language is called Purity. Purity in an English discourse means that there are no words in it that have not the sanction of contemporary literary usage. A vio- lation of Purity is called a Barbarism; and the word in which the violation occurs might be called a Barbarian, because it is outside the kingdom of English. A Bar- barism may be committed by using a word from either of the two following classes: (i) those not in the lan- guage at present — Barbarism in Time; (2) those not in general use over the territory in which the language is spoken — - Barbarism in Place. 1. Barbarisms in Time are of two classes: (a) those that have passed partly or wholly out of use — rare and obsolete words; {b) new words which have gained only a partial currency in the language. Language has life and growth. A word is born; it flourishes; it dies. Language is constantly absorbing and assimilating new elements and casting off the worn out and useless. Growth of ideas is constantly render- ing old words useless and new ones necessary. The greater the vital activity, the larger the class of new words that have gained only a partial hold upon the language, and of old words that are dropping out because rarely used. These transitional words constitute the two classes in which Barbarisms in Time may be committed. a. Obsolete words are those which, having a good standing in one age, are no longer used, because the ideas themselves have no place in men's thoughts, or 224 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. because superseded by some fitter expression. Through this process, the author of one age becomes unintelli- gible to the readers of the next. This is not only because the words themselves have ceased to be used, but because the grammatical forms have become obso- lete; as, en, the plural ending used by Chaucer and contemporary writers. Words are sometimes obsolete in only some of their meanings, as in the word scant- ling (not plentiful, small). Almost any page of the older English writers or of the dictionary will furnish abun- dant illustrations of all varieties of obsolete and obso- lescent words. The following may suffice: eke, wist, twain, scarce-fire, sickerness, silentiary, tumultuate, revoke (to recollect), revile (reproach), erst, yea, verily, choures, veyne, beholden, afeared, obleeged, withouten, otherwhere, ycleped, whilom. The use of obsolete words is allowable in poetry and in certain kinds of fiction. When fiction attempts to present an earlier age, the words of that age, though not used at present, are a means of giving verisimilitude to the story. b. The growth of new words is more rapid than one would suspect. What is a barbarism in one age is pure English in the next. Every year a multitude of cant phrases, slang and colloquial expressions, and ephemeral words spring up to meet some temporary purpose, and then die, unless it happen, which is seldom, that one of them can survive on the ground of real need. Every one has observed the phenomenon of a word coming into life, struggling for existence, and giving way under some fitter form of expression, or making good its own THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2Z$ claim to a place in the language. Says Genung: " The wretched word enthuse seems to be fighting for a place in standard usage, and as yet no one can tell what the sequel will be; at present it is a word to be shunned. A few years ago the word telegram was new and much talked of; but it filled a needed place in the language and soon came to be used by all. The invention of the telephone brought with it the suggestion of a corre- sponding word ' telephem ' ; but it is doubtful whether this will ever become current." The writer is not prohibited from the use of new words, for some one must use them, even coin them. He needs only to be cautioned in coining and using them. Since language was made for man, and not man for language, an author has a right to coin words when some new juncture of thought has no fitting form of expression already. But the ordinary writer will seldom meet with such a juncture, and may well leave to com- manding genius the coining of such circulating media as the race needs. The only rule is to beware of new words. " Be not the first by whom the new are tried." The law of purity simply forbids the use of vulgar sub- stitutes for good expressions already in current use. The following given by A. S. Hill are good examples of the class to be avoided: — " He availed of, instead of availed himself of an opportunity; how does he like? for like it; how do you like ? for like them; a steal for a theft; Lord Salisbury's wander through Europe; the case was referred; he deeded me the land; the skatorial phenome- non; Speaker Randall's retiraey; clothes Iaundried at short notice; walkist, agriculturist, educationalist, speculatist, and the like; B suicided yesterday; the house was burglarized; since the issuance 226 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. (for issue) of the President's order; the conferment of a degree; his letter of declinature; cablegram, reportorial, managerial, con- fliction (for conflict); in course (for of course); tasty (for taste- ful); he was fatigued by the difficult climb; L was extradited; dispeace; informational; to juxtapose. Firstly, illy, are used for first, ill, in apparent ignorance of the fact that, being adverbs already, they do not require the adverbial termination ly. On yesterday, come around (for come round, in the sense of revive or recover), are similar errors." 2. Barbarisms in Place are of two classes: (a) those words not belonging to the territory in which the lan- guage is spoken — foreign words; (b) those belonging only to a part of the territory in which the language is spoken — provincial words. No abuse of language is more prominent than bar- barisms in foreign and provincial words. The illiterate class are more given to the latter; but the former is most frequently committed by persons of literary at- tainments. In a few pages of a literary work these are found : a madam and a felo-do-se ; the principle of esse quani videri; the rule of shunning tanquam scopulum and insolent verbum; malaprop picturesqneness; tcmpora; mutantura; their beaux esprits ; the metier of a profes- sional talker; during the bravnras and tours de force of the great musical arts; etc. The following are less offensive because more frequently used: They have reached the ne plus ultra, — He is subject to ennui, — He is a connoisseur in art, — She belongs to the elite, — The entertainment went off with e'clat, — She made her de'but last evening. These are offensive to good taste and are violations of the law of economy in style. All foreign expressions THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 227 which have not become naturalized in our language should be shunned. While foreign words, after they have become a part of our language, are good English, yet such must not be sought out when the more simple, homely, native word stands ready to do service. Often there is an offensive affectation displayed in seeking out words of foreign origin, especially from the Latin, when the short, simple, Saxon word would carry the idea more directly and forcibly to the head and the heart. After the foreign words are naturalized, it is not a question of native or foreign origin, but of effec- tiveness in conveying the idea. In guarding against the false taste which gives a preference for them, we must be careful not to form a prejudice against words of classical origin. " Seek to use both Saxon and Classical derivatives for what they are worth, and be not anxious to discard either." Technical terms are not considered a part of the language, and should not be used except in addressing the class to which such words belong. In writings in- tended for some particular department of thought or industry, the terms peculiar to the class addressed are the most effective that can be selected; but they must be discarded when such subjects are treated in general literature, although with great loss in directness and precision. Provincial words include those that are merely col- loquial — employed in common conversation; and slang, the low, vulgar colloquialisms of some especial class in society. Some words that are proper in conversation are improper in formal, continued speech. Unfortu- 228 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. natcly slang needs no illustration. There are times when it seems the most compact, spirited way of saying a thing, and it may serve some immediate necessity, and in some cases find a permanent place in the lan- guage; but as a rule it is offensive, and indicates a poverty of words that would make the user blush if he were conscious of his necessity. Within the limit of purity there is ground for a further choice. Economy of memory not only requires the use of pure words, but of these such as will be most familiar to those addressed. Some words, on account of early association, have passed into identity with the idea; and in such cases the idea follows the word with- out effort. Others are in a state of transition; and still others exhaust the attention because the association is new. Mark the difference of force between these: fire, conflagration; pay, remunerate; did, performed; hang, suspend; little, diminutive; see, witness; burned, consumed; answer, rejoinder; died, deceased. The more economical words are usually Saxon, but they are not more economical because they are Saxon; it is because they have become a part of our mental life through early, constant, and long association. This is why Saxon words go " strongest and straightest to men's heads and hearts." A Latin word is as expres- sive as a Saxon word if it be brief, familiar, and well charged with meaning. Saxon words are the original words in the language, and denote the names of things known to our ancestors, and to all classes of people. In accounting for the greater economy secured by the use of Saxon words, Herbert Spencer says: "The most THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 229 important of them is early association. A child's vocab- ulary is almost wholly Saxon. He says, I have, not I possess; I wish, not I desire; he does not reflect, he thinks; he does not beg for amusement, but for play; he calls things nice or nasty, not pleasant or disagree- able. The synonyms which he learns in after years never become so closely, so organically connected with the ideas signified as do these original words used in childhood, and hence the association remains less strong. But in what does a strong association between a word and an idea differ from a weak one ? Simply in the greater ease and rapidity of the suggestive action. It can be in nothing else. Both of two words, if they be strictly synonyms, eventually call up the same image. The expression — It is acid, must in the end give rise to the same thought as — It is sour; but because the term acid was learnt later in life, and has not been so often followed by the thought symbolized, it does not so readily arouse the thought as the term sour. If we remember how slowly and with what labour the appro- priate ideas follow unfamiliar words in another lan- guage, and how increasing familiarity with such words brings greater rapidity and ease of comprehension, and if we consider that the same process must have gone on with the words of our mother tongue from childhood upwards, we shall clearly see that the earliest learnt and oftenest used words will, other things equal, call up images with less loss of time and energy than their later learnt synonyms." The most familiar words are usually the shortest and simplest, and economize not only memory in the asso- 23O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ciative act, but also perception in the presentative act. Thus the word pay has two economical values over the word remunerate. Short, simple, and familiar words are indispensable to a clear style. While all the foregoing discussion is made in terms of clearness, that is, in terms of economy of attention, it is quite obvious that perfectly transparent language is beautiful. Language which obstructs the movement of the mind toward the meaning cannot be beautiful language, for it awakens the sense of bondage. Also the most familiar word is the most energetic, through the fact that no energy is wasted in the inter- preting act. But the positive phase of energy under this head consists in the use of such expressions as will, while expressing the idea required, suggest emo- tions to arouse the mind into active reception. The mind may be kept aglow with emotions awakened by ideas skillfully selected along the train of thought. Some ideas have so long been associated with life and its interests, with its weal and its woe, with its trials and triumphs, — have become so deeply rooted in senti- ment and conviction that they carry with them a com- plex volume of rich and varied emotion. The mere reference to these in passing enriches the thought and stimulates the mind through the associations of memory to a fuller reception and realization of the matter pre- sented. The orator instinctively draws such ideas into the current of his thought. Concrctcness.- -The mind must represent to itself the idea expressed. Even when general or abstract ideas are expressed, the mind represents to itself the individ- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 23 I uals of the class, or the concrete objects in which the abstract as an attribute is found. When an abstract or general term is used, the mind conceives the con- crete and specific to which the general and abstract belong. Words are translated into thoughts through images; and this requires an effort beyond that of merely recalling the meaning of words. When the concrete and specific can be directly named instead of the abstract and general, the mind is relieved from the necessity of choosing from its store of concrete and specific ideas those which may represent the general or embody the abstract. In the expression, " Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow," a general truth concerning all plants is implied ; and with what economy as compared with, "Consider plants, how they grow! " In the last statement the mind is necessarily busy with figuring to itself this or that type of plant, and finally choosing one or holding a great number vaguely in mind. But in the first, the mind is put at ease with a definite species, without losing anything of the general truth expressed. For the writer's purpose, the lily has all the attributes of the class. If an individual could have been mentioned here, the gain would have been still greater. Abstract objects are made from attributes, and have no objective existence except in connection with objects as their subjects. If the mind searches for honesty, it finds not honesty, but an honest man. If, therefore, instead of naming the abstract truth, thus requiring the mind to busy itself with its concrete embodiment, the concrete be named, the labor of transforming the 232 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. abstract into the concrete is avoided; just as in the preceding case the labor is avoided of transforming the general idea into the individuals of which it is composed. Spencer says, we should avoid such sentences as this: — " In proportion as the manners, customs, and amusements of a nation are cruel and barbarous, the regulations of their penal code will be severe." And in place of it we should write: — " In proportion as men delight in battles, bull-fights, and com- bats of gladiators, will they punish by hanging, burning, and the rack." The second sentence loses nothing of the abstract truth expressed in the first, but is an immense saving of the recipient's effort to realize the abstract thought presented. How much does Emerson gain for the reader in ease of interpretation in these concrete state- ments of abstract truths: — "Wealth has its source in the rudest strokes of spade and axe." — " Coal makes Canada as warm as Calcutta." — " Will man content himself with a hut and a handful of dried peas? " — " No matter whether lie makes shoes or statues or laws." — "A dollar in a university is worth more than a dollar in a jail." — "His bones ache with the day's labor he has earned." Such expression gives the composer, also, an oppor- tunity to present a strong and impressive idea instead of a weak one; and thus concrete expression is more forcible, not only because it reserves the energy of the mind for the idea conveyed, but because it stimulates the mind to activity in appropriating the idea. In THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 233 this way, too, the mind may be kept moving through pleasing, as well as stimulating, imagery; as when Tennyson says : — " Were this not well, to bide mine hour, Tho' watching from a ruined tower How grows the day of human power." Certainly the picture of the tower stimulates and delights the mind in the process of interpretation. The highest effect in the beauty of style cannot be secured except there be free use of fresh and glowing imagery. The literary writer dare not speak in abstract terms. The incidental imagery in discourse may be so rich and varied as to become an end in itself, and thus largely, if not wholly, justify the discourse without rela- tion to the theme presented. Just as the music of language may be its own excuse for being, without considering the sense of the selection, as in the case of Poe's " Bells," so concrete expression may rise through charming imagery into more than mere economy of interpretation, and become an esthetic object in itself. But for whatever purpose, a style rich in imagery is a means to effective utterance. The more fully the writer can put his abstract thought in imagery, the more effective will be his presentation. The chief difference between speakers in addressing popular audiences lies chiefly in their power to throw their thought into pleasing and expressive imagery. On one side this is a necessity, for most minds think in the sensuous forms of the imagination. But the point here to be emphasized is the stimulation of the faculties by means of pleasing sensuous forms. 234 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. There is still another element of efficiency in con- crete language. The imagination delights in its own free activity, and this is stimulated by suggestive imagery. The beautiful part of the painting is not the part directly seen, but the part beyond the jutting headland or far down the dim vista. The picture is most pleasing which gives only hints, leaving the imagination the pleasure of its own free activity. The pattern of carpet or wall paper that constrains the mind to definite figures soon wearies the observer; it permits no freedom. Whether a reader return again and again to a selection with increased delight, is not so much determined by what is strictly given as by what is indirectly suggested. The permanence of a piece of literature depends largely upon its power of suggestion to the imagination. Precision. — A word usually expresses several ideas. The one intended to be expressed in any given case must be ascertained through inference by the judgment, based on the relation to accompanying ideas. The word compass standing alone may express equally well any one of a dozen ideas; but standing in discourse, it is limited to one of this number; and the judgment must, by the accompanying words, infer which idea the author intends to express. When the writer uses a word which expresses an idea that does not harmonize with the context, the judgment must perform unneces- sary labor in selecting the true idea, and also in organ- izing the thought as a whole. There is no way to avoid the constant activity of the judgment in realizing the idea expressed by a word in discourse; yet care must THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 235 be taken to avoid unnecessary labor, by selecting the exact word for the idea in the mind of the writer. The quality of the word which economizes the judgment is called Precision. Precision — literally to cut off — is that quality of a word by which it expresses " no more, no less, and no other" than the idea which the writer intended to con- vey. It is a synonym for exactness — the exact fit of the word to the idea. If the word does not express accurately the idea intended, the recipient must labor to gain that idea. If it should be said, " Virtue alone makes us happy," meaning that nothing else can do it, we should miss the meaning of the writer or waste effort to find it. Or, if it should be said, " Virtue only makes us happy," meaning that virtue by itself is suf- ficient to do so, the idea would be falsely conveyed. If the host should say to his guest, " Do not be in a hurry to depart," the guest should think that he was requested not to be excited to leave so quickly, when perhaps it was only intended to request him not to leave so soon — not to hasten. In this case too much is expressed, and the judgment, taking into account the circum- stances, makes the correction, but this costs effort. The term hasten would express too little, if it was intended to express not only rapid movement, but, with it, a disturbed state of mind causing abrupt and irregu- lar movement. Sometimes the writer, by confounding two words which resemble in form, commits the awk- ward blunder of missing the idea entirely; as, when the writer closes his letter with, "Yours respectively." The connection in which the word is used will generally 236 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. prevent a misconception; but to require a reader to make out the correct meaning for himself is to impose on him labor that belongs to the writer. Precision is secured by using words in their proper sense, or with propriety. Whatever the derivation or history of words, they must be used with their current meaning — with the exact meaning stamped upon them by the masters of expression. While in general a knowledge of the derivation and history of a word is essential to its intelligent and accurate use, yet because of the capricious changes in the language, the present application of a large number of words seems to have no connection with their radical meaning. Often two words from the same root and having nearly the same sound have widely different meanings; as, respectively and respectfully. At one time it would have been a compliment to have spoken of a " painful sermon." A clerk is no longer a clergyman. We build a house rather than edify it. This divergence in meaning of words from the same radical often leads to the expression of a different idea from the one intended. If one should speak of the observation of the Fourth of July — confounding the word with observance — the hearer would be puzzled as to the method of the performance. Yet the words are radically so near alike that we can say, The man observes the landscape, or, the Fourth of July. The words falseness and falsehood are both derived from the word false, yet falseness can be applied only to per- sons, while falsehood is affirmed of statements. Words having the same radical signification are called Paro- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 237 nyms. These include also words that have the same sound but different meaning. Sometimes ludicrous blunders are made by not distinguishing between words that have the same or nearly the same sound; as, when it was said that " She was as headstrong as an allegory on the banks of the Nile." Precision is secured chiefly by the discriminating use of synonyms. Synonyms are words which, while expressing shades of difference, have substantially the same meaning. They are not referable to the same root, as are paronyms, but are distinct classes of words derived from different sources. The English language, composed of elements from so many different languages, is rich in synonyms. While synonyms, by the various shades of meaning they express with substantially the same idea, are a means to exact expression, yet because their likeness is more prominent than their difference, they are a source of inaccuracy. If synonyms are to be a means of accuracy to the composer, he must discrim- inate between their meanings, and apply them with a consciousness of their difference. Hence, the distinc- tion between synonymous expressions becomes an im- portant study for him who would write with precision. There must be a constant use of the dictionary and a book of synonyms in testing the exactness of the word selected. The writer should not fall into the slovenly habit of thinking that the word is not quite right, but nearly enough so. If he would cultivate accuracy he must constantly seek to say precisely what his thought requires. The interest of truth demands this, for there is no way in which a statement is made to diverge from 238 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the truth more frequently than by the careless use of synonymous expressions. The turn of thought which depends on the choice of a particular word may be the most significant distinction expressed. It is not only important to discriminate among syno- nyms in order to choose the fit word, but that, in the elaboration of an idea, it may be presented under its different phases; and yet, in the repetition of the idea, the same word need not be chosen. The reiteration of the same idea in the same term is clumsy and monoto- nous; and there is a constant effort to find words that, in the repetition of the idea, will preserve substantially the same meaning. There is no need more constantly felt by the writer than that of many expressions for the same thing. " Not that several forms of expression are in every case to be employed; this, of course, is a matter that must be determined by the occasion. But it often happens that if the writer has not thought broadly and deeply enough to have more than one expression for his idea, the one that he has will be meager. The one apt word is very generally the result of long cogitation and debate between alternative locu- tions. Recognizing this fact, eminent writers have often cultivated as a private discipline the habit of putting things in many different ways, ringing changes in expression, softening and strengthening, formalizing and colloquializing, condensing and expanding, making severely accurate and making freely loose. Such a habit is untold value as means of familiarizing the literary workman with his tools." Thus while synonyms are employed in their different THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 239 shades of meaning to denote delicacy and precision, used for their likeness they secure freedom and flexibility. It should not be forgotten that the choice of a pre- cise word is conditioned by a clearly defined idea; and that to the careful study of synonyms as a means of securing accuracy in expression must be added discipline in forming clear, distinct, and vivid conceptions. Vague and definite ideas cannot clothe themselves in close- fitting words. Whatever trains the mind to bound ideas accurately and to conceive them clearly makes possible the choice of an exact word. And, further- more, the mind, impressed with a sense of accuracy in the idea itself, will be sensitive to the form in which it is put — will instinctively light upon the right word. As introductory to the habit of observing synonyms, let the likenesses and unlikenesses be stated in the following groups, and each applied in its distinction: — Invent, discover; abhor, detest; haste, hurry; alone, only; clear, distinct; calm, peace, tranquillity; custom, habit; equivocal, am- biguous; avow, acknowledge, confess; industrious, laborious, dili- gent; in, into; two, couple; proud r vain; faculty, capacity; bonds, fetters; abdicate, desert; character, reputation; occasion, oppor- tunity; sick, ill; pity, sympathy; stay, remain; jealousy, envy; tolerate, permit; lack, want, need; candid, open, sincere; cautious, wary, circumspect; combination, cabal, plot, conspiracy; shall, will. Distinguish, also, between the following paronyms : - Expect, suspect; healthy, healthful; sensuous, sensual; construe, construct; predict, predicate; contemptible, contemptuous; neglect, negligence; ingenious, ingenuous; subtle, subtile; artist, artisan; womanly, womanish; emigrant, immigrant; human, humane; benevolence, beneficence, 24O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. The purpose has been not to catalogue the precepts of diction, but to illustrate the basis of all precepts in the fundamental principle of the interpreting process. Arbitrary rules confuse, discourage, and enslave; while principles give freedom, guide, inspire confidence, and command respect. With these principles fixed, the student's knowledge will crystallize about them through the necessity of his experience with language, both in construction and interpretation. Whatever the treat- ment, it could not take the place of such experience. With the principle of diction in words to guide, the student who aspires to clearness of expression must hope to secure it by constantly realizing the principles in himself as he reads, writes, or speaks. Especially must he observe the usage of the best writers. The dictionary and book of synonyms, while helpful in their way, cannot take the place of the diligent study of words as they are organized in the life of discourse. The dictionary cannot impart to words the life and delicacy that come from the touch of an author. " Words are the vehicle not only of thought but of sentiment and emotion ; but this they can be only as interwoven with other words. Thus alone can they get beyond the merely intellectual side of language, and from its defined meanings provided for its often far more vital undefined associations. No fineness of usage can be acquired from the dictionary alone ; the grace and power, the subtilities and flexibilities of words, are seen fully only as they are fitted together, in actual literature, by the masters of expression." Without such intimate acquaintance with the best literary usage, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 24I without a large, pure, literary vocabulary to choose from, the principles of choice will be of little avail ; and without principles of choice the composer could not consciously wield the words at his command. ORGANIZATION OF THE IDEAS INTO THOUGHT. The primary language quality required to facilitate this process is that of unity ; and the prominent activity is that of the judgment, which acts, however, upon the constant activity of the memory and the imagination. The memory must hold the materials gathered till the judgment can organize them ; and the imagination must represent in images the thought whole presented. The first requirement under the general law of lan- guage unity is that there be no unnecessary material presented for organization. Such material requires useless effort in the organizing process ; and many times it becomes so burdensome as to defeat, in a large measure, the purpose of the discourse. Hence, the law of unity requires of language first, — Conciseness. — Only the words essential to the full and accurate expression of the thought should be used. The proper number can be only relatively determined. Immature minds require fuller expression than mature; an oral statement may need fuller expression than a written one; a familiar thought needs only to be sug- gested, while the features of an unfamiliar one must be brought out by a great number of words. Thus the proper number of words is determined by a great 242 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. many considerations. It is perhaps a greater error to use too few words than too many; yet the use of too many is the more common error, and so serious as to demand careful attention. It has already been noted that an unnecessary word prevents clearness by the useless burden put upon sense-perception. Still greater is the burden imposed on memory; for there is not only the unnecessary act of associating the word with its idea, but the memory is required to carry the useless idea, only to puzzle the imagination and judgment in their effort to organize it in with the other ideas. Thus, too many words inter- fere with all the interpreting acts, but chiefly with memory. The general fault of wordiness is called Verbosity. Verbosity arises generally from either a diffused or confused mode of thinking, or the desire to seem to be saying more than the concise expression would con- vey. It has its origin, therefore, in the condition of clearness, stated at the outset; namely, in moral habit and in discipline of mind. The lack of precision in the expression is the natural result of a lack in the precision of thought, or of regard for the truth ex- pressed. Verbosity is an overgrowth of words from an untamed thought, nourished by the care of expres- sion for the sake of expression as distinct from thought. Says Phelps: " Diffuseness, repetition, bombast, result inevitably from the study of expression as distinct from thought." When there is no self-consciousness in- volved, the excessive care for expression as something in itself is a leading source of looseness in style; THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 243 Those who expect to cultivate conciseness in style need hope for little from the mere study of language. Verbosity is often so diffused throughout the expres- sion that it cannot be located in any definite form of language. So far as the different ways have been classified and named there are three: Tautology, Redundancy, and Circumlocution. Tautology is saying in other words exactly what has just been said; as, — " A writer should not waste his words for nothing." — " He re- vises all the while." — " It lacked the power of engaging attention and of alluring curiosity." — "Pupils should obey the rules and regulations." Tautology is the form of wordiness most easily detected and, therefore, the least excusable. Redundancy is the addition of ideas not necessary to the sense. Redundancy does not repeat the idea, but adds that which the idea already expressed renders unnecessary; thus, — " The laws of nature are uniform and invariable." — "I wrote to you a letter yesterday." — " I went home full of a great many serious reflections." — "There is no writer so concise in style as not sometimes to use a redundant expression." — " There is noth- ing that disgusts us sooner than the empty pomp of language." — " There can be no doubt but that newspapers at present are read altogether too much." — " Being content with deserving a triumph, he refused to receive the triumph that was offered him." Circumlocution is a much more subtile form of ver- bosity than tautology or redundancy, and hence is a fault more easily committed and less easily detected. It is an unnecessary multiplication of words by some 244 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. roundabout mode of statement. When there is a pur- pose in such indirect statement, it becomes an allowable figure of speech, called Periphrasis; but when resulting from carelessness or affectation, it becomes a serious and inexcusable fault. Circumlocution is characteristic of "fine writing," the dressing out in high-sounding terms commonplace ideas; as, — " The shining leather which encased the limb," — a boot. The explosion of " the leveled tube," — a gun. Lowell, in his introduction to the Biglow papers, gives some good examples : — " Called into requisition the services of the family physician," — " Sent for the doctor." " I shall, with your permission, beg leave to offer some brief observations," — "I shall say a few words." " The progress of the devouring element was arrested," — " The fire was got under." " The conflagration spread its devastating career," — " The fire spread." Circumlocution is usually more difficult to detect than appears in these examples. It is hidden from the first view in this often-quoted sentence: — "Among the eminent men who figured in the eventful history of the French Revolution was M. Talleyrand ; and whether in that scene, or in any portion of modern annals, we shall in vain look for one who represents a more interesting subject of history." D. J. Hill, in commenting on this, says: "In addi- tion to beating out the sense to the thinnest possible film, his lordship makes Talleyrand figure in the his- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 245 tory instead of the scene, then confounds scene and annals, and finally tells us that Talleyrand represents an interesting subject of history. The idea may be more clearly expressed in twenty-four instead of forty- four words: Among the eminent characters of the French Revolution was M. Talleyrand, and, in modern times, we shall find no more interesting subject of history." The remedy for tautology and redundancy is to cut off the superfluous part, — in the first, the useless expression; in the second, the useless idea. Circum- locution is remedied, not by leaving out parts, but by reforming the sentence in terser language. In the fol- lowing exercises, used by Swinton and Kellogg, let the verbosities be classified and removed: — 1 . Every man on the face of the earth has duties to per- form. 2. Another old veteran has departed. 3. Thought and language act and react mutually on each other. 4. Emma writes very well for a new beginner. 5. The time for learning is in the period of youth. 6. Whenever he calls, he always inquires for you. 7. The ocean is the great reservoir for receiving the waters of the rivers. 8. The world is fitly compared to a stage, and its inhabitants to the actors who perform their parts. 9. " Pope professed to have learned his poetry from Dryden, whom, whenever an opportunity presented itself, he praised through the whole period of his existence with a liberality which never varied; and perhaps his character may receive some illus- tration, if a comparison be instituted between him and the man whose pupil he was." 246 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 10. Redundancy sometimes arises from a want of thought, which leads the author to repeat over and over again his little modicum of sense at his command. 1 1. He received divine help from God. 12. The annual anniversary of the landing of the Pilgrims, celebrated yearly, took place a few days since. Prune to concise language the following quotation : — "Importance of Habits of Attention. — The importance of habits of attention cannot be overrated. The power of controlling one's own mental faculties, of directing them at will into whatever channel the occasion may demand, of excluding from the mind all irrelevant ideas, and concentrating the mind on the one object of thought, is a power of the highest value. It is in this that we find the principal difference between one mind and another in the realm of thought and knowledge. Mental power is, to a great extent, the power of attention. " One of the principal elements of genius is strength of will to control the mind and command the mental energies. " To all the Faculties. — Attention is of great value to all the faculties. It is involved in and inseparably connected with the exercise of these faculties, giving them their direction and in- creasing their power. It conditions their activity, and is a meas- ure of their strength and attainments. Its value in relation to each one of the different faculties will be briefly noticed. " To Perception. — The power of perception is mainly due to the power of attention. In an act of perception we need not only the open senses, but also the attentive mind. Mere gazing is not sufficient ; we need the concentration of mind in order to per- ceive. Too many persons have eyes and see not, ears and hear not, fingers that touch and yet communicate no knowledge. A large share of the perception of the world is inattentive and careless. " Attention, in relation to perception, is like a microscope to the eye. I look at a flower and perceive many things concerning it; I place a microscope to my eye, and thus see points of interest I THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 247 never dreamed of before. So attention seems to concentrate the rays of perceptive power, revealing thereby that which was previ- ously unperceived. In its relation to perception, attention may be called a mental microscope. "To Memory. — Attention gives power to the memory. It gives clearness of conception, which is a condition of remember- ing. That which the mind has clearly apprehended, which it has carefully discriminated from other things, takes firm hold of, and thus retains it in its mental grasp. Continuous attention also enables us to fix the idea, to give permanence to the impression. It acts like a kind of die which stamps the picture upon the tablet of memory. Without it, the greater part of what we hear or see would fade from the mind, as a shadow flits across the summer landscape." Besides the sins of commission against brevity, in the form of Tautology, Redundancy, and Circumlocu- tion, there are the sins of omission, in which the com- poser fails to use all legitimate means of condensation. These means are various, some of which are as fol- lows: — Often what is expressed by a compound sentence may be more compactly put in a complex or a simple one ; thus : White garments are cool in summer, be- cause they reflect the rays of the sun, — White gar- ments, which reflect the rays of the sun, are cool in summer, - - White garments, reflecting the rays of the sun, are cool in summer. The omission of an essential part of the sentence, when it can be readily supplied, is an effective means for securing brevity; as, the omission of a subject, verb, object of a verb, conjunction, or other parts more readily supplied than interpreted. Thus: Mirth should be the embroidery of conversation, but it should not be 248 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the web of it, — Mirth should be the embroidery of conversation, but it should not be the web, — Mirth should be the embroidery of conversation, but not the web, — Mirth should be the embroidery of conversa- tion; not the web. The copula, preceding a series of details, is omitted with good effect; as, A beautiful flower is the lily — sweet, graceful, and delicate. A word may often be substituted for a phrase; thus: His writing is such that it cannot be read, — illegible. Participles are frequently used for brief equivalents of phrases and clauses. In many such ways the writer may condense his ex- pression to the least compass of the thought. Yet clearness must be the first consideration. The com- poser should not risk obscurity for brevity. The exact nature of the thought and the knowledge and capacity of the mind addressed must determine each case ; and if there be error, let it favor clearness. What has been said touching the qualities of the sentence which burdens the memory and tries the judg- ment with useless material applies to the discourse as a whole. As the sentence must contain the fewest words consistent with clearness, so the discourse as a whole should contain the fewest sentences consistent with the purpose of the discourse. The positive offense at this point is Prolixity. Prolixity is the enumeration of unimportant things, or things which the reader, from his general knowl- edge, would readily supply from the context. Prolixity gives to incidental and subordinate parts the promi- nence of essential ones. It is avoided by holding the THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 249 attention to the leading idea ; by presenting suggestive characteristics and leaving the imagination to supply- such minutia as it may need. " A prolix writer de- lights in circumlocution, extended detail, and trifling particulars." A concise writer suggests much in saying little. No fault is more directly opposed to the law of economy than is prolixity. The mind often antici- pates in a moment all that a writer narrates in pages ; and then an effort of the will is required to hold the mind in readiness for the needed thought, which may happen along by and by. Examples of this fault are too lengthy for quotation. They are abundantly illus- trated by the conversational bores, who vex, tire, and perplex by endless talk of irrelevant minutia, and personal details which they assume are as interesting to others as to themselves. Literary bores are less numerous and more polite, for they do not hold one fast to listen whether he will. Yet the pleasure of reading such an author, even such as Dickens, would be greatly increased if he were less prolix. Not only must the mind not be burdened with use- less material, but too much material must not be given it for a single organizing act. This makes it necessary to consider The Proper Length of the Sentence. — As shown in the preceding, the memory may be required to carry both unnecessary words and unnecessary ideas. Of essential ideas, it may be required to cany more, or to carry them longer than is possible without conscious effort. This puts a limit to the length of the sen- tence. A sentence may be long without being ver- 25O THK SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. bose. Instead of breaking the truth up into several distinct statements, each expanding and correcting what is said in the first, the whole may be given in one long, involved, complex sentence. The one long sen- tence may be shorter than all the short ones out of which it is made. There is a gain to the memory up to the point of conscious effort in carrying the parts. The greater the amount carried at once, the better, so long as the effort to lift the burden is less than that required in repeating the carrying act. While the short sentence is always less burdensome in itself than the long one, the long sentence is always more eco- nomical than the several short ones out of which it is made, provided the effort to carry the parts is less than the effort through the repetition required in short sentences. Were it always known how many ideas could be carried without conscious effort, the length of the sentence might be absolutely determined. No rule can be given for drawing this line. While it may be said absolutely that no tautological word should be used, the principle controlling the length of the sen- tence must be applied to test anew each case. Some long sentences, owing to their arrangement, are less taxing to the attention than others. The culture of the mind addressed is a determining factor as to the length of the sentence. The trained mind can hold a great many qualifying circumstances without the necessity of depositing them in the principal idea. For the immature, the truth must be presented in short, simple sentences, item by item. The long sentence presents the thought as a whole better than several THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 25 I short ones, and, therefore, requires less effort on the part of the imagination and judgment to organize the material given. It thus appears that as much as pos- sible should be expressed in the single sentence, the limit being the point at which the burden to the memory exceeds the gain to it and to the other faculties. The requirements of the subject itself has much to do with the length of the sentence. Phelps says : "You cannot express the rising and the expanding and the sweep and the circling of eloquent thought, borne up on eloquent feeling, in a style resembling that which seamen call 'a chopping sea.' For such thinking, you must have at command a style of which an oceanic ground-swell or the Gothic interweaving of forest trees is the more becoming symbol. You must have long sentences, involved sentences, magnificent sen- tences, euphonious sentences, sentences which invite a rotund and lofty delivery. This diction is often cen- sured by critics as ' fine writing.' But you must have such a style for the most exact utterance of certain elevated and impassioned thought." The error is usually on the side of long sentences ; sometimes by making complex, involved sentences, and sometimes by connecting a series of sentences by colons and semicolons. The writer should not hesitate to use periods. A. S. Hill says : " Even when the distinction between a long and a short sentence con- sists chiefly in punctuation, the mere substitution of colons or semicolons for periods makes a world of dif- ference to the reader. In unbroken succession, long 252 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. sentences fatigue the eye and the mind; short sen- tences distract them. The skillful writer alternates the two, using the former for the most part to explain, the latter to enforce his views." Certain habits of thought give the mind a tendency toward long or short sentences. It is natural for some to express them- selves in short, simple statements, while others uncon- sciously pack the sentence with all the incidental ideas which accompany the leading thought; others, without having distinct thought, as in the case of children, run statements together by short pauses and conjunctions. Nations, too, have their characteristic type of sentence. The French use short, simple sentences ; the Germans, long, involved, complex ones ; the English, being a mixture of Norman-French and German, naturally pre- fer sentences of intermediate length, with a tendency, however, to the German type. De Quincey, comparing the English sentence with the French and German, says : — " In French authors, whatever may otherwise be the differences of their minds or the differences of their themes, uniformly we find the periods short, rapid, un- elaborate. One rise in every sentence, one gentle descent - - that is the law for French composition, even too monotonously so ; and thus it happens that such a thing as a long, involved sentence could not be pro- duced from French literature, though a Sultan were to offer his daughter in marriage to the man who should find it. "The character of German prose is an object of legitimate astonishment. Whatever is bad in our own THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 253 ideal of prose style, whatever is most repulsive in our own practice, we see there carried to the most out- rageous excess. Lessing, Herder, Richter, and Lich- tenberg, with some few beside, either prompted by nature or trained upon foreign models, have avoided the besetting sin of German prose. Among ten thou- sand offenders we would single out Immanuel Kant. A sentence is viewed by him, and by most of his coun- trymen, as a rude mould or elastic form admitting of expansion, to any possible extent ; it is laid down as a rude outline, and then, by superstruction and episuper- struction, it is gradually reared to a giddy altitude which no eye can follow. Yielding to his natural im- pulse of subjoining all additions or exceptions or modi- fications, not in the shape of separate consecutive sentences, but as intercalations and stuffings of one original sentence, Kant might naturally enough have written a book from beginning to end in one vast hyperbolical sentence." The demand which the truth makes upon the sen- tence cannot always be reconciled with the law of the economy of memory. On this point D. J. Hill remarks: " The most frequently recurring and perplexing problem of style is to adjust the equilibrium between these two forces, the contracting and the expanding. Condensing the sentence too much, we violate truth by omitting details and ignoring limitations. Expanding too much, we render the interpretation of the sentence impossible by forcing upon the mind more labor than it can per- form. A reader may, indeed, recur to the beginning, if he be conscious of failing to grasp the thought fully, 2 54 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. while a hearer has not this privilege. On this account the expansion of sentences is more allowable when they are written than when they are spoken; but readers generally are not willing to read a sentence more than once." To impress the nature of this error, let the following long sentences be broken into shorter ones, and the greater ease of interpretation be observed : — "Although they were all known as Saxons by the Roman peo- ple who touched them only on their southern border where the Saxons dwelt, and who remained ignorant of the very existence of the English or the Jutes, the three tribes bore among themselves the name of the central tribe of their league, the name of English- men." " Each little farmer commonwealth was girt in by its own border or 'mark,' a belt of forest or waste of fen which parted it from its fellow-villages, a ring of common ground which none of its settlers might take for his own, but which served as a death ground where criminals met their doom, and was held to be the special dwelling- place of the nixie and the will-o'-the-wisp." " They found, in fact, a crushing answer in the ' Ecclesiastical Polity ' of Richard Hooker, a clergyman who had been Master of the Temple, but whose taste for the controversies of its pulpit drove him from London to a Wiltshire vicarage at Boscombe. which he exchanged at a later time for the parsonage of Bishops- bourne, among the quiet meadows of Kent." " They sent Tallien to seek out a boy lieutenant, Napoleon Bonaparte, the shadow of an officer, so thin and pallid that, when he was placed on the stand before them, the President of the Assembly, fearful, if the fate of France rested on the shrunken form, the ashy cheek before him, that all hope was gone, asked: ' Young man, can you protect the Assembly ? ' " Having rejected all useless material, and having given the mind only the number of ideas which it can easily THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 255 organize in a single act, the next concern of the com- poser is with the placing of the elements so that they may the most easily and effectively be organized into a whole. The Proper Arrangement of the Sentence. — That is, as determined by the respective claims of the memory and imagination. The idea expressed by the principal part of the subject, is the organizing idea of all the others expressed in that subject, while the idea expressed by the whole subject is the organizing idea of the predi- cate. All ideas in the predicate are organized into the principal one, and the completed idea of the predicate is organized into the completed idea of the subject. As the result of the interpreting process, one concep- tion is formed. The memory must hold each subor- dinate idea until a principal idea is reached. The question here is, In what order should the constituent ideas of the subject, including the predicate, be pre- sented so that the memory will have the least possible labor to perform ? The memory must bear each attri- bute and object until an idea is presented in which they can be organized. At this point the imagination and the judgment relieve the memory by attaching the attribute or object to the leading idea. In the sentence, "A few dilapidated old buildings still stand in the deserted village," all the ideas are organized in the one expressed by the word " buildings." The ideas ex- pressed by the words "A," "few," "dilapidated," and "old " are borne in memory until the idea "buildings" is suggested, and then the memory is relieved by the imagination, which constructs the picture of building, 256 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. containing the attributes that the memory has been holding for that purpose. The idea " still " is borne but a short distance, for the idea " stand," in which it is organized, is immediately suggested. The idea "still stand is a constituent idea of " A few dilapidated old buildings," already pictured by the imagination, and need be carried no further, for the mind at once has the conception of these buildings as standing. The idea of a certain kind of buildings as standing is already in the mind to receive the idea of place expressed by the phrase "in the deserted village." In two of the acts of interpretation, the organizing idea is already in the mind to receive the additional idea as soon as inter- preted; and in the other cases the ideas are almost instantly deposited in their subject. Reversing the order, In the deserted village still stand a few dilapi- dated old buildings, and the memory is required to bear all of the accessory ideas to the close. The effect of this in a single sentence is so slight as not to be felt; but a series of such will soon exhaust the energies of the mind, and leave it without the power to realize the thought conveyed. The tiresome effect is perceptible in a single long sentence arranged with the organizing idea at the close; as, — •' Farther than it is connected with the high intellectual and moral endowments when public bodies are to be addressed on momen- tous occasions, when great interests arc at stake, and strong- passions are excited, nothing is valuable in speech." Or this: — " In the Old Colonial days in Plymouth, the land of the Pilgrims, To and fro in a room of his simple and primitive dwelling, THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 257 Clad in doublet and hose, and boots of Cordovan leather, Strode, with a martial air, Miles Standish, the Puritan Captain." Sentences in which the organizing idea is suspended till the close are called Periodic sentences; those in which the sense and the grammatical structure are complete before the close — the organizing idea given before the close — are called Loose sentences. The periodic sentence favors the imagination, but the loose sentence is required to bring relief to the memory. The economy of memory requires that each idea be placed as near as possible to the one to which it belongs. This order is the subject followed by its modifiers, and then the predicate followed by its modi- fiers. On the whole, this is not the most economical arrangement. Subject and predicate should stand in the midst of their modifiers. What is called the natural order, the order that has grown up under the instinct of the mind for ease of interpretation, is the best guide to arrangement; at least so far as the memory is con- cerned. And this is subject, copula, predicate, with the modifiers grouped closely about each. But the claims of the imagination must be more dis- tinctly recognized. We have seen that the imagination pictures the single ideas in the process of word inter- pretation. It, with the judgment, also combines the separate ideas into a single picture or conception. To secure ease in the formation of the picture out of the separate elements, these elements must be supplied in the order in which the imagination most readily and correctly combines them into the new product. In the interpretation of the sentence, " A few dilapi- 258 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. dated old buildings still stand in the deserted village," the imagination constructs one picture out of the objects and attributes named. The process would have been different had the sentence been arranged thus: In the deserted village, still stand a few dilapi- dated old buildings: Or thus: Buildings, a few, old, and dilapidated, still stand in the deserted village. In the second, all the attributes which characterize the object to be pictured are presented before the object, buildings; in the third, the concrete object is first pre- sented, and then the attributes added, one by one. The second being the reverse of the third, the law of the imagination in the process of the interpretation will be determined by ascertaining which of the two requires the least effort in the picture-constructing process. As shown in Herbert Spencer's " Philosophy of Style," the third has decidedly the preference. While the law of memory requires the organizing idea to be presented first, the law of the imagination requires it to be presented last. When the concrete image is given at the outset, as in the last sentence, a complete and, most certainly, an incorrect image is formed; and when the succeeding elements are named, the imagina- tion must reform the picture by removing the incorrect attributes and adding the correct ones. The first impression is apt to persist in the mind to the exclu- sion of the correct one. Thus we frequently carry away from a conversation what we imagine a person said for what he really did say. In the last sentence, when buildings are expressed, the imagination makes THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 259 a complete picture of them, anticipating their number, condition, color, position, and surroundings. But as the sentence continues, it first limits the number to "a few," requiring any previous conception of number to be changed and a new one to be substituted. The few buildings now in mind may be new; and this attribute must be removed and the picture changed to include the old. And so on, at each successive step. But in the second sentence, in which all the abstract elements are first presented, i.e., the attributes named, without any subject to which they may be attached, the imagi- nation brings them all at once to the concrete image of buildings; again illustrating how labor is imposed on the memory, and how it is compensated by the gain to the imagination. The requirements of the memory and the imagina- tion are antagonistic; and the two forms of the sen- tence, the loose and the periodic, growing out of the requirements of each, stand in reverse relation to these faculties. One of these forms cannot be said to be better than the other. The tension between them gives rise to an intermediate form, a compromise, which is better than either, as in the first sentence. Each form has its advantage and its disadvantage. The loose sentence rests the mind, the sense and the grammatical structure being complete at the points before the close is reached. But this is a double source of error: (i) the mind may be satisfied with the partial truth and withdraw attention before all the modifying circum- stances correct and amplify what precedes them; (2) the habit of the imagination to fill out the picture when 26o THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. a concrete object is named and of anticipating what the writer is to say makes necessary a series of correc- tions. The periodic sentence, in bringing the mind directly to the correct conception, relieves the imagina- tion from the necessity of readjusting its work. It also prevents error in another way. In the very nature of the case the attention is compelled to the close, and no error can arise by the omission of qualifying circum- stances. With all of this, it imposes a burden on the carrying power of the mind, and requires a higher tension of activity, which soon exhausts the energies of the mind to such a degree that the thought will be entirely lost. What is called the natural order of the sentence is a compromise between the periodic and the loose sentence, with the difference in favor of the loose. Both the natural and the loose sentence require this order: subject, copula, and predicate, and certain modifiers, as the explanatory, the objective, and phrase and clause modifiers to follow the part modified; while adjective and possessive modifiers, and in most cases the adverb, precede the part modified. The natural order should not, however, be considered as opposed to the periodic order. For some moods of mind, the periodic, or what is often called the inverted order, is the only form natural. The habitual use of either form in a single discourse characterizes the style of the whole as natural or inverted — loose or periodic. Spencer suggests that, " A more appropriate title would be the direct style, as contrasted with the other, or indirect style; the peculiarity of the one being, that it conveys each thought into the mind step by step, with little THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 26 1 liability to err; and of the other, that it gets the right thought conceived by a series of approximations." Since one style is economy to one faculty and a bur- den to the other, and since the other style reverses the economy and the burden, an intermediate sentence, which combines as far as possible the merits of the others, is preferable. Let the following sentences be arranged in the different ways and the relative ease of interpretation tested : — 1. " The live thunder leaps far along from peak to peak, among the rattling crags." 2. " And this our life, exempt from public haunt, finds tongues in trees, books in the running brooks, sermons in stones, and good in everything." 3. " At last, after no small difficulty, and after much fatigue, we came, through deep roads and bad weather, to our journey's end." 4. " Endowed with a rare purity of intellect, a classic beauty of expression, a yearning tenderness toward all God's creatures, no poet appeals more tenderly than Shelley to our love for the beauti- ful, to our respect for our fellow men, to our heartfelt charity for human weakness." 5. "No nobler feeling than this of admiration for one higher than himself dwells in the breast of man." 6. " As long as you have the wisdom to keep the sovereign authority of this country as the sanctuary of liberty, the sacred temple consecrated to our common faith, wherever the chosen race and sons of England worship freedom, they will turn their faces towards you." 7. " At Attri in Abruzzo, a small town Of ancient Roman date, but scant renown, — One of those little places that have run Halfway up the hill, beneath the blazing sun, 262 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. And then sat down to rest, as if to say, ' I climb no farther upward, come what may,' — The Re Giovanni, not unknown to fame, So many monarchs since have borne the name, Had a great bell hung in the market-place." We come now to what is more strictly called the quality of unity in the language. While the preced- ing qualities are essential to it, the very structure of the thought and the language must enforce unity. Unity of Sentence Structure. — This is required to economize the interpreting activity of the imagination and judgment. Every sentence expresses but one object of thought. About this object all the words are organized. The sentence is an organic unit, and should be so arranged as to bring the mind readily and correctly to the organizing idea. Unity is that quality of the sentence by which the central idea is kept obvious while the elements of the thought are being presented one by one. Either the loose or the periodic sentence may have this quality, but the periodic sentence is the more conducive to it. Unity is also more readily secured in short sentences than in long ones. In fact, the chief objection to the long sentence is the difficulty of arranging its parts so as to keep the leading idea before the mind. But whatever the length or the kind, there can be no compromise in the matter of unity. " Some one object must reign and be prominent." It may consist of parts indeed; but those parts must be so closely bound together as to make the impression of one object on the mind, not of many. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 263 Distinctness of conception is the prime condition to unity of thought. If the composer, having decided what one idea the sentence is to exist for, holds clearly and organically the elements of the complex idea which he wishes to express, he will unconsciously obey the law of unity. That confusion and unsteadiness of mind which mingle ideas having little connection, and which turn to a new subject by every idea suggested, will necessarily confuse the reader by incoherency of ideas in the sentence. Lack of unity in thought appears in two forms: (i) the change of subject or scene in the course of a com- pound sentence; (2) the crowding of things which have little connection into one sentence. 1. The mind should not be hurried by sudden tran- sitions from subject to subject, as in the following: — " After we came to anchor, they put me on shore, where I was welcomed by my friends, who received me with the greatest kindness." Here there are four subjects : we, I, they, who. While the objects themselves are closely enough re- lated in the matter under discussion, yet in shifting the subject of thought from one to another, the con- nection is almost lost. The difficulty would have been avoided had it been written thus : — " After we came to anchor I was put on shore, where I was welcomed by all my friends, and received with great kindness." 2. Ideas which have little connection should never be confused and crowded into one sentence. Such often arises from an effort to express as much as pos- 264 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. sible in a single statement. But although they be short, clearness requires separate statements for dis- connected ideas, rather than to have them condensed into one overloaded and embarrassed sentence. The following used by Blair illustrates the nature of this error : — " Archbishop Tillotson died in this year. He was exceedingly beloved both by King William and Queen Mary, who nominated Dr. Tennison, Bishop of Lincoln, to succeed him." The last part of this sentence would not have been expected from the first. In the first part, the mind is resting in the love of King William and Queen Mary for Tillotson, and expects other matter connected with this love; but it is abruptly turned to an event wholly disconnected. Closely connected with this violation of unity is that of the use of parentheses in the middle of sentences. Such expressions often indicate a lack of art on the part of the writer. He has a thought which he does not know how to dispose of. Not having skill to organize it in the line of thought, he drops it in the midst of a statement, with the certain effect of divert- ing the attention from the main subject. In some cases parentheses may be unavoidable; but the writer should beware of them. The footnote is only less objectionable than the parentheses because it is easier skipped by the reader. "Such excrescences," says D. J. Hill, "are omnipres- ent reminders of the limitations of language as a medium of expression. Just in proportion as an author allows this sign of weakness to exhibit itself, in that THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 265 proportion he confesses his own insufficiency or that of his medium. Yet insufficiency is likely to show itself somewhere. He who always writes short sen- tences, and puts his whole thought into them, must take a very short sweep of view. He who writes long ones must tax the interpreting power of his readers. He who constantly lets his thoughts overflow his sen- tences and drip down into footnotes virtually abandons an artistic solution of the great problem of style for a coarse expedient." Point out the nature of the error in the following:, and reconstruct so as to give unity : — 1. "In this uneasy state, both of public and private life, Cicero was oppressed by a new and cruel affliction, the death of his beloved daughter Tullia; which happened soon after her divorce from Dollabella; whose manners and humors were entirely disa- greeable to her." 2. "In summer reindeer feed on various kinds of plants, and seek the highest hill to avoid the gadfly, which at that period deposits its eggs in their skins, from which cause many of them die." 3. "The march of the Greeks was through an uncultivated country, whose savage inhabitants fared hardly, having no other riches than a breed of lean sheep, whose flesh was rank and un- savory, by reason of their continual feeding on seafish." 4. " The Britons, daily harassed by the Picts, were forced to call in the Saxons for their defense, who, after having repelled the invaders, turned their arms against the Britons themselves, drove them into the most remote and mountainous parts of the kingdom, and reduced the greater part of the island under their dominion, so that in the course of a century and a half the country became almost wholly Saxon in customs, religion, and language." 5. " At last the coach stopped, and the driver, opening the door, told us to get out; which we did, and found ourselves in 266 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. front of a large tavern, whose bright and ruddy windows told of the blazing fires within; which, together with the kind welcome of the hostess, and the bounteous supper that smoked upon the board, soon made us forget the hardships of the long, cold ride." 6. " The quicksilver mines of Indria, in Austria (which were discovered in 1 797, by a peasant, who, catching some water from a spring, found the tub so heavy that he could not move it, and the bottom covered with a shining substance which turned out to be mercury), yield, every year, over three hundred thousand pounds of this valuable metal." Unity of ideas avails little without unity of sentence structure to indicate the relation of the ideas. The sentence, in expressing a thought, must express the relation of the ideas which constitute the thought. When the thought has unity, as above stated, and the sentence is so constructed as to express that unity, the sentence itself is said to have that quality. In one sense this quality may be called precision — the exact fit of the words to the thought. The relation of ideas in the thought is indicated in four ways: (1) by the position of words in the sentence; (2) by relative words; (3) by grammatical inflection; (4) by punctuation. Therefore, unity is secured by the correct placing of words, the correct use of relative words, correct syntax, and correct punctuation. Thus we arrive at the ques- tion of correctness in its relation to effectiveness — at the point of dependence of Rhetoric upon Grammar. Accordingly, this matter should be referred to Gram- mar for treatment. There is, however, a phase of " I ' and " 2 " that falls to Rhetoric, because the questions that arise are answered by the law of clearness which THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 267 applies to the particular case, rather than by fixed rules of sentence formation. 1. Since English words have lost most of their inflections, the relation of ideas is generally indicated by the position of words expressing them. The gen- eral law of position may be stated thus:- The position of words in the sentence should be such as to indicate clearly the relation of the ideas in the thought. This requires words which express ideas most closely related in thought to stand as nearly together as pos- sible in the sentence. Close connection in position indicates close connection in meaning. The wrong placing of words gives rise to Confusion, Ambiguity, or Obscurity. In all cases this error engrosses the attention and weakens the effect. The two following sentences criticised by G. Washington Moon, in "The Dean's English," illustrates the nature of the error: — " The great enemies to understanding anything printed in our language are the commas. And these are inserted by the com- positors without the slightest compunction." The meaning intended was, that the commas are inserted without compunction; but by the order of the words, they describe the character of the com- positors, — the compositors are without the slightest compunction. The context prevents ambiguity or obscurity, but not the confusion and the unnecessary effort in the organizing act. In realizing the thought, as the ideas are here presented, the mind gains a wrong conception of compositors; and, observing the relation they sustain to the other ideas, the notion must be 268 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. corrected by transferring the idea " without compunc- tion " to the manner of insertion. " A man does not lose his mother now in the papers." This means that, according to the papers, a man does not now lose his mother. The arrangement of the sentence leads to a grotesque conception, which is readily corrected by the context. But why should the labor of correction be exacted from the reader ? The following sentence illustrates ambiguity by a misplaced modifier: — " Rome once more ruled over the prostrate nations by the power of superstition." This means either that Rome had once ruled over the nations by the power of superstition, and now ruled them thus again, or that she has formerly ruled them by some other means and now ruled them by the power of superstition. Point out the burden that each of the following imposes on the interpreting mind, and correct so as to remove the obstruction: — i. " The dexterity of the Chinese juggler almost appears mirac- ulous." 2. " It is folly to pretend to arm ourselves against the accidents of life by heaping up treasures, which nothing can protect us against." 3. " There is a cavern in the island of Hoonga, which can only be entered by diving into the sea." 4. " Thos. W. Coke put an end to the American war by moving its cessation in the House of Commons," THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 269 5. " A straight line can only cut the circumference of a circle at two points." 6. " I shall neither attempt to palliate it nor deny it." 7. " The journals not only spoke in high terms of Mr. Moon's powers as a critic but also as a writer." 8. " He is to speak of the landing of the Pilgrims, at the Academy of Music." 9. " Sewal refused to accept of inexperienced persons recom- mended by the pontiff of beneficies, on the ground of their ignorance of the English language." 10. "The Greeks fearing to be surrounded on all sides, wheeled about and halted, with the river on their backs." 11. "He advanced against the fierce ancient, imitating his address, his pace and career, as well as the vigor of his horse, and his own skill would allow." 12. "A man can only attain to distinction in one line by devoting his whole life to that line." 13. " But the effect is not alone seen in the drunkard." Energy, through unity of structure, further requires that the words be so arranged as to give emphasis to the prominent idea. In oral speech emphasis is given to the principal idea by the manner of speak- ing; but in written speech emphasis is marked by itali- cized words, and by the position of words. Usually italics indicate a lack of skill in forcible arrangement. Words must be so placed that they will emphasize themselves. This is an essential condition to leading the mind of the interpreter correctly and without loss of effort to the unity of the thought expressed. The arrangement of language is a most effective means of securing energy. Ideas may be so organized in the expression as to secure stress of attention on those ideas which need to be most thoroughly im- 27O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. pressed; or, so that a constant stress of attention will be required on the thought as a whole. This gives the energy of emphasis, which directs attention to the idea which the writer desires to make prominent; and the energy of suspense, which compels attention to the close. Both are secured by arrangement. a. Emphatic ideas seek prominent places. " Sweet are the uses of adversity." Change this to, The uses of adversity are sweet, and the weakness is at once felt. In this case, the emphatic word stands at the beginning of the sentence. The end of the sentence is a still more emphatic position. It is important that the significant word gather up the meaning at the close. If this word is such as to give the sentence a full ca- dence, Energy is still further secured. For this reason, unless the connection gives it emphasis, a small word should not close a sentence. The arbitrary rule, so often laid down, that a preposition should never close a sentence applies only to pleasant cadence. Emphasis may require such a closing; at any rate, the best writers do so close their sentences, and with good effect. The only rule that applies when Energy is to be se- cured is that an insignificant word should neither begin nor close the sentence. Energy through emphasis may require the inverted order of the sentence; and the order itself contributes to Energy. Not only because it is unusual, but because the energy of feeling, when it accompanies thought, naturally tends to invert the sentence — feeling revers- ing the order of thought. Note in the following sentences how Energy is THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 27 1 secured through inversion and the placing of the significant ideas : — 1. " Beyond that I seek not to penetrate the veil." 2. " Now all is to be changed." 3. " In no country, perhaps, in the world is the law so general a study." 4. "In large bodies, the circulation of power is less vigorous at the extremities." 5. " Slavery they can have anywhere." 6. " But until you become lost to all feeling of your true interest and your natural dignity, freedom they can have from none but you." The beginning or the end are the emphatic places of the sentence; and a word, to be emphatic, must stand in one or the other of these places. Which of the two it shall occupy is determined by its usual position. If the word usually stands first, it is made emphatic by removing it to the close; and if it usually stands at the close, it should be removed to the begin- ning. Emphasis reverses the grammatical order, and attracts attention to ideas by expressing them out of their accustomed places. The verb, adjective, and noun as predicate gain special distinction by standing in the place of the subject; modifiers, by changing places with the objects which they modify; and subjects, by being driven to the close of the sentence. The anticipative expressions it is, there is (or there are) are frequently used as means of giving the subject an emphatic place at the close. These words stand pro- visionally for the subject, leaving it free to seek the most distinctive position. This is a double source of 272 THE SCJENCE OF DISCOURSE. emphasis; for, besides securing emphatic position, expectation is aroused, and more mental energy is expended on the idea when reached. This fact brings us to another principle of the periodic structure of the sentence. This, as already noted, reverses the ordi- nary arrangement, and so fulfills the law of emphasis. In this the leading idea is kept back till the close; thus stimulating the mind by anticipation and curiosity, it is prepared to receive the idea with its full force when presented. Explain the arrangement by which emphasis is secured in the following, and examine selections from authors, noting their method of emphasis: — 1. " Now is the accepted time." 2. Had I known of the acci- dent, I should have gone. 3. " Flashed all their sabres bare." 4. He left the room quickly. 5. Insolent though he was, he was silent at last. 6. It was Lincoln who freed the slaves. 7. " We ought not to bestow the reverence that is due to the great benefactors of mankind upon a mere conqueror." 8. " Jesus I know, and Paul I know; but who are ye?" 9. " Military courage, the boast of the sottish German, of the frivolous and prating Frenchman, of the romantic and arrogant Spaniard, he neither possesses nor values." 10. " On whatever side we contemplate Homer, what principally strikes us is his wonderful invention." 11. " Slowly and sadly we laid him down." 12. " Certainly the spread of religion will ele- vate the morals of a country if anything will." 13. " Fain would I pause to dwell upon the world of charms that burst upon the enraptured gaze of my hero as he entered the state parlor of Van Tassel's mansion." 14. " It was many and many a year ago, In a kingdom by the sea, That a maiden there lived whom you may know By the name of Annabel Lee." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 273 15. " In the greenest of our valleys By good angels tenanted, Once a fair and stately palace — Radiant palace — reared its head." b. Attention through suspense is secured through the periodic structure. This arrangement throws for- ward emphasis to the end, excites expectation, and compels attention to the close. This structure is essen- tial to dignified and lofty thought. The following from Burke's speech on " Conciliation with America " are good examples of Energy through this means: — 1. "While we follow them among the tumbling mountains of ice, and behold them penetrating into the deepest frozen recesses of Hudson Bay and Davis Strait, whilst we are looking for them beneath the arctic circle, we hear that they have pierced into the opposite region of polar cold." 2. "When I contemplate these things; when I know that the colonies owe little or nothing to any care of ours and that they are not squeezed into this happy form by the constraints of watch- ful and suspicious government, but that, through a wise and salu- tary neglect, a generous nature has been suffered to take her own way to perfection, — when I reflect upon these effects, when I see how profitable they have been to us, I feel all the pride of power sink, and all the presumption in the wisdom of human contrivances melt and die away in me." Not only the sentence, but the entire discourse may have the periodic structure. In this, as in the sentence, the point to be brought out is suspended till the close, thus exciting expectation and compelling attention throughout. The recipient is made to feel that if his attention at any time should relax he would miss something important to follow. And this attention is ^^LA 274 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. intensified by curiosity aroused by the suspense. If this structure is not skillfully managed, however, the com- poser loses more than he gains. Unless curiosity can be greatly excited, or there is habit of prolonged atten- tion on the part of the recipient, there is danger of losing attention altogether. The element of curiosity must not be relied on as the chief source of the inter- est, as is usual in the lower grade of novels. Mere curiosity to know the outcome is not a legitimate means of sustaining the interest and holding the at- tention. Shakespeare, feeling that there is a deeper source of interest than curiosity, keeps back no secrets, but reveals the truth as rapidly as the development permits. But under certain conditions and within cer- tain limits, the chief thought may be withheld until the mind is opened and well prepared by circumstan- tial truths and a general background of thought and sentiment. 2. Not only is the relation of ideas indicated by the position of words, but also by the use of relative words, as already stated. These words include such as refer to an antecedent for their meaning; namely, pronouns — personal, relative, and demonstrative-- conjunctive adverbs, prepositions, and phrases of reference. Either (a) the incorrect use of these or (b) their omission or the omission of some word to which they refer confuses the mind, and often leads to obscurity or ambiguity. a. Relative words refer to some antecedent term ; and error arises when they are so used that it is not clear which of several apparent antecedents is the real THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 275 one. Accordingly, the simple rule is to use relative words so that their antecedents are obvious and unmis- takable. In the case of pronouns, they should follow the nouns to which they refer without the intervention of another noun. And further, as stated by Campbell: " It is but seldom that the same pronoun can be used twice or oftener in the same sentence, in reference to different things, without darkening the expression." But in short, whatever the relative word, its reference must be so certain that the reader or hearer need give no attention to making out the connection intended. In the following, show how the mind is unnecessarily engaged by uncertain reference of relatives to their antecedents: — 1. " Her home was near the village church, and this seems to have had great influence on her religious character." 2. " Thus patriotism begets patriotism and makes the Republic a nation of patriots, which becomes evident when the occasion is presented." 3. "I saw my old schoolfellow again by mere accident when I was in London at the time of the first Exhibition, walking down Regent Street and looking at the shops." 4. " The laws of nature are truly, what my Lord Bacon styles his aphorisms, laws of laws. Civil laws are always imperfect, and often false deductions from them, or application of them; nay they stand in many instances in direct opposition to them." 5. " When a man considers the state of his own mind, about which every member of the Christian world is supposed at this time to be employed, he will find that the best defense against vice is preserving the worthiest part of his own spirit pure from any great offense against it." 6. " The general told him that he thought he had come none too soon." 276 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 7. " This hill forms a very pleasing part of this picture, but the most pleasing part of it is the trees that surround these houses." 8. " Are our schools so conducted that the poor can and must attend ? Any one who has visited American cities will answer that they do not, on account of their poverty." 9. " And since at least a part of the emigrants are provided with specie it brings a considerable amount of money to this country." 10. "One may have an air which proceeds from a just suffi- ciency and knowledge of the matter before him, which may natur- ally produce some motion of his head and body which might become the bench better than the bar." 11. " The sharks who prey on the inadvertency of young heirs, are more pardonable than those, who trespass upon the good opinion of those, who treat with them upon the foot of choice and respect." 12. " They were persons of such modern intellects, even before they were impaired by their passions." 13. " While treating of pronunciation of those who minister in public, two other words occur to me which are very commonly mangled by our clergy. One of them is covetous, and its substan- tive covetousness. I hope some who read these lines, will be in- duced to leave off pronouncing them covetious and covetiousness. I can assure them that when they do thus call them, one, at least, of their hearers has his appreciation of their teaching disturbed." b. The omission of words necessary to make the connection clear is a common violation of the law of economy of attention; thus: — Cardinal Richelieu hated Buckingham as sincerely as the Spaniard Olivares — as did the Spaniard Olivares. Here the omission of did obscures the meaning. A good illustration of undue attention required by omis- sion is found in what is called " splitting particles." As, " He heard of, and went to see the man," instead of this: He heard of the man and went to see him. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 277 Both are grammatically correct; but the first requires effort to hold the abstract relation till the object is sup- plied. The greater the number of words intervening, the greater the effort. The omission of any part of speech, when necessary to give distinctness and promi- nence to the idea expressed, causes undue attention in fixing the relation of the ideas expressed. The value of this law will appear in pointing out the source of undue effort in the following, and in others that may be selected: — 1. " Lovest thou me more than these ? " 2. Smith has traveled more, but is not so well educated as his friend. 3. He might have been happy and is now fully convinced of it. 4. Industry has always been the way to succeed, and it will so long as men are what they are. 5. " He professes to be helping the nation, which is in reality suffering from his flattery, and will not permit any one else to give it advice." 6. There is a great difference between the French and English. 7. Platinum is heavier but is not so useful as iron. 8. The error has and will again be ex- ploded. 9. He has worn to-day a silk and felt hat. 10. "It bears us back eighty-two years, when the eyes of the whole world were turned toward France." n. "Any country can afford to get rid of its lawless and mischievous subjects by a small fare." 21. " With this ambition was a will that, uncontrolled, made him stub- born and disagreeable." 13. "Occasions were quite frequent when the goodness of his heart and tender sympathies were needed." 14. " When we study the character of a man, we naturally turn to his childhood for the influences that have the most lasting effects upon his life." 15. " All the pleasing illusions which made power gentle, and obedience liberal, harmonized the different shades of life, and, by a blind assimilation, incorporated into politics the sentiments that beautify and soften private society, are to be dissolved by this new conquering empire of light and reason." 2^8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Unity in the Discourse Structure. — As soon as the mind has interpreted two sentences, it organizes the two thoughts into one. This new thought combines with a third into a new product. Thus the drift of thought is soon discerned, and the series of thoughts begin to crystallize about the central theme. The mind establishes a tentative theme at the outset. As thoughts succeed each other, this theme is modified and filled out till one thought — the true theme — is found in which all the others will organize. Thus the immediate work of the imagination and the judgment is to search out the theme. If the interpretation be made for the sake of the content of the discourse, the process ends when the theme is se- cured; but if the purpose be to make a critical estimate, another step is required; namely, that of estimating the workmanship, the effectiveness of the discourse, in the light of the purpose, the theme, and all the other determining factors. It is obvious from the preceding examples that energy of utterance is secured through arrangement. Thought which is compactly and logically organized, which is strong in its cohesion of parts, has power to impress itself on the recipient's mind. This requires such selection, method of arrangement, and completeness of parts as to give the theme obvious unity. It ought to be observed, also, that as well as obvious unity, the thought should have obvious parts; or, rather, that in having unity it will have such parts. There can be no strength through unity without dis- tinct parts unified. The theme must be brought out THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 279 in definite features. Nothing is weaker than a dead level in the succession of thoughts. The mind can gain no foothold in monotonous thought, and is offended by it as the ear is by monotonous delivery. Only the highly articulated organism can have vivacity and vigor of movement. Ease of interpretation and Energy both require that the phases of the theme be given distinct outline and striking prominence. The most noticeable and the radical failure of the young composer is in not, while holding his theme with a steady hand, pressing on the attention clearly and fully the phases of the truth which organize into his subject. Strength through unity includes not only strength of organization in the thought itself, but the organiza- tion which gives it definite and direct movement to the end sought — unity in the purpose. The thought must have a definite, progressive movement controlled by some central, ordering principle, — a movement which carries the mind along irresistibly to the issue of the discourse. Only the one end proposed must be consulted; and to this the thought must move in a straight line. No undue enlargement, no attention to unnecessary details, no tarrying by the wayside to gather flowers when the head is to be convinced and the heart won. When the purpose is to instruct, every temptation to indulge in the pleasures of taste must be withstood. When the purpose is to arouse to action, care must be taken not to elaborate truth for its own sake; not to spin out subtile distinctions; not to lose the aim in the rounding out of logical processes. 28o THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Nothing must stand in the way of the direct motives to action. Everything must submit itself to the purpose of the speaker; must be held in equal balance and just proportion to that purpose. This quality of strength through the organization of thought requires strict obedience to the laws of thought in the discourse processes ; that is, the strength of unity can be secured only under a definite purpose to give the thought directness and precision, aided by the laws of selection, method, and completeness to give such parts and such arrangement of parts as will give the strength of unity to the whole. The student is, therefore, already supplied with the chief means of securing Energy in the thought, and needs most to be referred to the laws of the discourse processes for specific guidance. i. The first means which the writer employs to aid in realizing the theme is its general statement in the heading. There are reasons for suspending the theme and concealing the purpose; but these reasons are not found in the requirement of Clearness. When the will is to be moved, it may be necessary to conceal the real intent and meaning until the mind is opened to a favor- able hearing, and when the feelings are to be stirred, suspense may be necessary to arouse curiosity and to exhilarate by surprise. But when the purpose is to instruct, when the only requirement is that of Clear- ness, the theme must be stated at the outset. The law which requires the theme to be stated at the outset also forbids any hidden, fanciful, or figurative expression of it, so often indulged in by young writers. The effort THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 28 1 should be to state in the heading of the discourse, as nearly as possible, the exact idea which the discourse is to embody. 2. The second means to facilitate the interpretation of the discourse as a whole is the relation which the sentences bear to each other. Unity in their arrange- ment is the chief requirement. As unity in the sen- tence is required in order to keep the leading idea prominent before the mind, so unity in the whole of language in the discourse is required to hold it like- wise constantly before the mind. As in the sentence, too, this unity is primarily in the thought and second- arily in the language structure. The law of unity in the thought has already been treated under the law of unity in the thought processes of discourse, and needs no further statement here. As to language structure, there is nothing to be added except the means of in- dicating the relations between sentences. a. How to get from one sentence to another so that the mind of the reader will naturally flow from one thought to another without waste of effort is always an important question with a writer. Each sentence must seem to arise out of the preceding; each must seem to " ctow out of the last and into the next." The life of the composition is in this vital juncture of thoughts; and the labor of composing is scarcely begun when each separate thought has found its own state- ment. Says De Ouincey: "Every man as he walks through the streets may contrive to jot down an inde- pendent thought; a short-hand memorandum of a great truth. . . . Standing on one leg, you may accomplish 282 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. this. The labor of composition begins when you have to put your separate threads of thought into a loom; to weave them into a continuous whole; to connect, to introduce them; to blow them out or expand them; to carry them to a close." No rule can be given for this process further than this: Each sentence must express an idea different from the preceding, and at the same time bear such a close relation to it as naturally to arise from it. Frequently sentences are thrown in for no other purpose than that of making an easy and natural transition from one thought to another. b. Sometimes the transition is effected by repeating a word or by the use of a conjunction or some other phrase of reference. But these formal connectives avail little unless there is the inner connection men- tioned above. Thoughts so ordered as to suggest in themselves their connection, so that the preceding directs the mind toward the succeeding, need no formal introduction. Whatever means the writer uses, he should so vary them and introduce them as not to betray the process. This gives rise to what is called an "easy and flowing style," than which nothing is more effort-saving or agreeable in ordinary discourse. The student will here find profit in making a study of graceful transition as illustrated by some master of it, as Irving or Addison. c. The paragraph is a valuable aid in making the transition to a new division or phase of the theme, and of indicating the connection of thoughts with the new idea. The law of unity which pertains to the sentence THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 283 and to the discourse as a whole controls the formation of the paragraph. The foregoing has already suggested that each thought should be a step forward. Each in rising out of the preceding gives an upward and an onward movement to the discourse as a whole. The whole should be continuous and cumulative, compact and organic. 3. The theme, to be clearly apprehended by the reader or auditor, must be held before the mind long enough to secure the necessary attention. The theme must not only be given its distinct features and full outline, as required by the law of completeness in the thought processes, but it must be variously turned to the light, and viewed over and over again in new turns of thought and phrase, in order to gain the requisite amount of activity on the part of the interpreter. Perhaps no point of skill is more essential to the com- poser than that of artful amplification and fullness of expression by which the thought moves no faster than the interpreter can think. Much greater must be this art in oral than in written speech ; for in the latter, the reader may review at pleasure, while in the former, the expression vanishes with the utterance. Care is needed, however, that fullness does not become pro- lixity. The speaker, in addressing an audience com- posed of people of different grades of culture, finds himself constrained, on the one hand, by the necessity of full elaboration lest his thought be missed; and, on the other hand, by the necessity of brevity lest prolixity defeat the purpose of his utterance. 284 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 4. The last condition to economical interpretation of discourse is, that the thought be embodied in lan- guage in obedience to the laws of Unity, Method, Selection, and Completeness of the thought, as already considered under the discourse processes. These laws were there discussed as a means of enabling the recip- ient to appropriate the thought in itself considered, without special reference to the expression of it. But thought thus organized gives that form and organi- zation to the language which makes it the easiest approach to the thought. Let the expression, therefore, be moulded by the laws of Unity, Method, Selection, and Completeness, as the most fundamental condition to economical interpretation. THE INDIRECT RELATION OF LANGUAGE TO THOUGHT. The interpretation of indirect, or figurative, language requires a peculiar act of the mind; namely, that of grasping an idea through indirect relations. Through this peculiar activity the qualities of Clearness, Energy, and Elegance are most effectively secured. It is through such activity that the mind has its deeper insights and visions of whole truth. It is the penetra- tive act of the mind which reaches the hidden mean- ing of things, as well as the supreme organizing act which finds the meaning of the whole in each of the parts. Literal language is language which has an estab- lished relation between its form and its content. Fig- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 285 urative language is any variation from this established relation for the purpose of effective utterance. The dictionary and the grammar treasure up current and established usage; but a writer, under the higher law of discourse, removes the boundaries thus set, and orders language to his own peculiar necessity. Hawthorne, in describing Thoreau to Longfellow, said that Thoreau had iron-poker-stickisJuicss in his make up. This is no part of our established language; but it is made out of literal language forms to meet the exigencies of Hawthorne's peculiar conception. Victor Hugo says, " Pleasing a bishop is a foot in the stirrup for a sub-deaconry." "Foot in the stirrup" here has not the established relation to its idea. The dictionary knows nothing of this meaning. The writer puts this language form in a new relation — one of his own creating — for the purpose of communicating more effectively his idea of how to gain a sub-deaconry. The peculiar and original turns of thought and the necessities of utterance cannot be provided for in lan- guage beforehand. The individual writer, in the stress of composition, must order to his own necessity the materials furnished him in the form of literal language. The greater the creative power of the writer and the higher the tension of his thought, the more will his language diverge from literal statement. A figure, since it results from the bending of literal language into more effective forms of utterance, is not a mere ornament, but a necessity. It gives to an otherwise limited and abstract vocabulary richness, fullness, and power. From a few literal root words, 286 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. through the necessity of using them figuratively to express shades of meaning for which no form of ex- pression was supplied, our language has grown to its present compass and flexibility. While the number of ideas and thoughts are unlimited, the language forms are limited; and necessarily so by the law of economy in learning and using language. How to express the infinite number of ideas and thoughts in all their variety and shades of meaning by means of a compara- tively limited vocabulary is the great problem in lan- guage; and the effort to solve this in practice has been the force that has shaped language in every phase of its growth. When a literal word is used in seventeen different figurative applications, as the dictionary shows to have been the case with the word head, it is equiva- lent to a seventeen-fold increase of the vocabulary. By the frequent use of the word in the same figurative ap- plication, its figurative meaning becomes literal. Thus the increase in the vocabulary. Most words have a figurative origin. All words expressing mental opera- tions were at first figuratively employed ; i.e., these operations were expressed through their relation to material forms and processes. The gain is not solely in the increase of the literal vocabulary, but in the wider extent of application of the figurative words themselves, before they become literal. The literal is constantly encroaching upon the figurative, but dis- charging its obligations to the figurative by making- possible new applications when the necessity arises. The extent of the figurative application of words is much wider than that of the literal. The dictionary THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 287 does not exhaust the scope of language; the latent force is greater than that which is manifest. The skillful writer shapes and fits the literal established language to suit his own necessity, limited only by the suggestive resources of his own mind. " The heavy preponderance of the weight of language is in the scale of its figurative uses. Analogies connect all words with all words. By means of figurative speech, all departments of thought illumine each other. Origi- nality in style appears chiefly in the discovery of analogies, and fitting them to use." 1 Thus the advantage of figurative language does not wholly nor chiefly lie in the economical increase of the vocabulary, but in the greater clearness, elegance, and energy secured by expressing one thing in the form of another. By this means, general and abstract truth can be expressed in vivid, definite, concrete forms. Familiar, beautiful, and striking objects may be used as expressions of unfamiliar, uninteresting, and com- monplace matter, thus contributing to effectiveness, as no literal and abstract word forms could possibly do. This gain is shown by the fact that when the figurative use of a word becomes literal the word loses much of its expressiveness. When the word tribulation ceased to call up the old Roman tribulum, the threshing sledge which separated the wheat from the chaff, it lost both in beauty of suggestion and in the power to express forcibly the truth that afflictions serve to separate the evil and worthless from the good and worthy in the human soul. J Phelps' " English Style." 288 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. As already noted, figurative language is language in which the relation between the form and the content of language is varied from established usage. Figure signifies form. A new form of language may be made to stand for the same idea as the established form; or the established form may be used to set forth some idea other than that to which usage has fixed it. In one case the language form is changed; in the other the form of conception associated with the language is changed. In either case it is a change of form, and therefore figurative. At the same time there is a change of relation between form and content. Since language has both form and content there arise two kinds of figures, — figures of form and figures of content. A change in the form of the language itself is illustrated by the following: "'ghast"; " Do- the-boys"; "aerial cities of joy and affection and freedom." In the first example, the first part of the word is omitted; in the second, a word is made for a special purpose out of three others; in the third, more ands are used than the grammatical structure requires. There is no accompanying change in the conception, yet there is increased power of expression. But when Longfellow says, — " And the night shall be filled with music, And the cares, that infest the day, Shall fold their tents like the Arabs, And as silently steal away," he changes the form of the conception of cares, think- ing of them, not as the literal word would require, but as infesting tribes of Arabs, and as imperceptibly THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 289 passing away under the charm of music like the tribes folding their tents and stealing away in the darkness. The change in the form or in the content gives rise to the two classes of figures known as Figures oj Speech and Figures of Thought. So vital is the relation of the form to the content of language that no sharp line of distinction can be drawn between them. Many figures may properly be put in either class. This explains the seeming confusion and contradictions in books treating them. The varieties of each are so great that a complete classification is both impracticable and undesirable. Only the leading ones need be given ; enough, however, to explain their nature and use, and thus enable the student, as he reads, to observe them in their manifold variety and to extend his classification as far as he may desire. FIGURES OF SPEECH. A figure of speech is indirect language, since the figurative form expresses its idea through the literal form from which it is made. These figures have little value as compared with figures of thought, yet they deserve a brief treatment. Because formal, they must not be supposed to have no relation to content ; for they arise from the free inner impulse of a mind breaking the fetters of an established language form. They are not dead things, formed by external chiselling accord- ing to the rules of the rhetorician; but instinct with life, because struck off by the impulse of the soul, which they serve the reader to interpret. 29O THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Language as form consists of words and sentences; hence, there may be a change in the form of the word or in the form of the sentence. The first is called a Figure of Spelling, or Etymology ; the second, a Figure of Syntax. Figures of Spelling} - - Figures of spelling are formed in four ways: (1) by the omission of some part of the word necessary to its correct spelling; (2) by the in- sertion of some unnecessary part; (3) by the inten- tional misspelling of words; (4) by the combination of words. 1. The first are classed and named from the part omitted. Aphaeresis, the taking of a letter or a syllable from the beginning of a word; as, 'ghast for aghast, 'mazed for amazed, 'fore for before, what 's for what is, she'll for she will, you '11 for you will, I'm for I am, I'd for I would, thou 'rt for thou art, 'Frisco for San Francisco. Syncope, the omission of a letter or letters or a syllable from the middle of a word; as, e'er forever, don't for do not, ne'er for never, ev'ry for every, de'il for devil, sick'd for sickened. Apocope, the omission of a letter or syllable at the end of a word; as, yond for yonder, Mexic for Mexican, morn for morning, suit for sultry. 2. The other figures of spelling, rarely met with, are formed by prefixing, inserting, or affixing a letter 1 A large and interesting collection of figures may be found in Mac- beth's " Might and Mirth of Literature," from which some of these ex- amples have been taken. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 29I or syllable, called respectively Prosthesis, Epenthesis, and Paragoge. 2 . Intentional Misspelling is so prominently employed in the service of wit and humor as to need no illustra- tion. Such tricks with words, however, do not serve the highest grades of wit and humor; and while Ameri- can humorists have distinguished themselves in this line, they, perhaps, have not done so to their perma- nent credit. 4. Combination, the forming of a word out of others, to secure greater force or to meet the emergency of some new turn of thought, as in Lowell's " First Snow Fall," "the good All-Father." Some one speaks of the " How-do-you-do-George-my-boy " sort of style, and the " biggest-river-and-tallest-mountain " recipe. Dick- ens calls, with multiplied effect, Squeers' seminary "Do-the-boys Hall," for there the boys were done. This figure is frequently used, and contributes to energy of expression. Figures of Syntax. — Figures of Syntax are devia- tions from the ordinary construction of words in sen- tences. These are formed in three ways: (i) by omitting parts necessary to grammatical structure; (2) by the insertion of parts unnecessary to grammatical structure; (3) by the substitution of one grammatical part for another. 1. The first method forms a very common and im- portant figure called Ellipsis. An Ellipsis is the omission of a part necessary to complete the grammati- cal structure, though not necessary to the meaning. This figure is characteristic of energetic and impas- 292 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. sioned speech, and may be classed as a figure of Energy. By it tone and vigor may be given to other- wise clear but feeble expression. Expand the following from Carlyle, who uses this figure freely and with good effect, into the full gram- matical form, and note the loss: — "It is well said, in every sense, that a man's religion is the chief fact with regard to him. A man's or a nation of men's. By religion I do not mean here the church creed which he pro- fesses, the articles of faith which he will sign, and in words or otherwise assert; not this wholly, in many cases not this at all." Ellipsis is more common in poetry than in prose. Note the omission of a subject and two verbs in this, from Whittier: — " Christ's love rebukes no home love, breaks no ties of kin apart; Better heresy in doctrine, than heresy of heart." One special form of the Ellipsis, the omission of connectives, is called Asyndeton; as in these: — 1. " Must I relinquish it all, the joy, the hope, the illusion ?" 2. " Urging the suit of his friend, explaining, persuading, expand- ing." 3. " I came, I saw, I conquered." 2. The repetition of parts not necessary to the grammatical structure gives rise to the figure called Pleonasm. Pleonasm is a figure formed by the use of more words than the grammatical expression of the thought would require. Some part already expressed is re- expressed for the sake of giving it greater prominence. It differs from Tautology in that there is purpose in the repetition. It contributes to Clearness through THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 293 emphasis. The following will illustrate both its nature and its use : — " The Lord he is God." " Thy rod and thy staff they comfort me." "The blood of our fathers, let it not have been shed in vain; the great hope of posterity, let it not be blasted." The following paragraph from Gilmore's " Outlines of Rhetoric " contains further illustrations with a valu- able suggestion: — " For example, in the sentence, ' Marshal your argu- ments as a skillful general does his forces, so that they may mutually support each other,' I should regard the introduction of the word ' mutually ' as a case of justi- fiable pleonasm, since it serves to clarify and enforce the author's meaning. Again : in the sentence, ' His anticipations of the future were as gloomy as his recol- lections of the past,' I should not strike out the italicized words, since they serve to make more clear and impressive the contrast intended. I should, how- ever, strike out the italicized words from the sentence: ' His anticipations of the future were of the gloomiest nature,' since in the sentence they serve no useful purpose." The special form of Pleonasm in which a part is repeated after intervening matter is called Epanalepsis, meaning to take up again ; as in these : — " He came to the city, at last, after long and tedious wander- ings — to the city which had, for years, been the shrine of his devotions." "Health, virtue, industry — these are the elements of happi- 294 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. "But the thing a man does practically believe; the thing a man does practically lay to heart, and know for certain; concern- ing his vital relations to this mysterious universe, and his duty and destiny there, that in all cases is the primary thing for him, and creatively determines all the rest." Another form of the general figure of Pleonasm con- sists in the emphatic repetition of a word just uttered, for the purpose of amplifying or emphasizing the idea expressed. This variety is called Epizeuxis, meaning to fasten to or upon; thus: — " Shall I attempt to describe Rome — Rome, the birthplace of all that is beautiful and grand? " "Alone, alone, all, all alone, Alone on a wide, wide sea." Polysyndeton, the excessive use of connectives, is the last pleonastic figure to be noted. This is the opposite of Asyndeton. Both of these are found abundant in all literature. The following Polysyndetons from "The Courtship of Miles Standish " are neat illustrations of this figure: — " Was it for this I have loved, and waited, and worshipped in silence ? " " Breathing their silent farewells, as they fade and wither and perish." " Sacred and safe and unseen, in the dark of the narrow cham- ber." " Sunless and silent and deep, like subterranean rivers." Both Asyndeton and Polysyndeton are beautifully illustrated in the following from Milton: — THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 295 " So eagerly the fiend, O'er bog and steep, through strait, rough, dense, or rare, With head, hands, wings, or feet, pursues the way, And swims, or sinks, or wades, or creeps, or flies." 3. The figure of syntax formed by the third method is called Enallage. It consists of the use of one part of speech for another, or of one grammatical property for another. The following examples will illustrate its nature : — Adverb for noun : — " Full of all the tender pathos Of the Here and the Hereafter. Noun for verb : — " I '11 queen it no inch farther, But herd my ewes and weep." "To out herod Herod." Proper noun for adjective: — "A Nebuchadnezzar curse that sends us to grass like oxen." Adjective for verb: — " It lanks the cheek, and pales the freshest sight." FIGURES OF THOUGHT. A figure of thought is the expression of one thing in the form of another. What is conveyed by the language directly is itself a means of expressing some- thing else. When Longfellow wished to express the truth that the hopes of youth are destroyed by the trials and adversities of life, he brings before the mind 296 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. the image of leaves falling in the blast of cold wind and rain, and then adds: "The hopes of youth fall thick in the blast." He wishes us to see in the leaves falling in the blasts of cold wind and rain the hopes of youth falling in the adversities of life. Figures of thought are not always easily distin- guished from literal expression. We have seen that much of our literal language has grown out of figura- tive language, and the process is still going on. When an expression is in the phase of transition it is not clear whether it is a real or a faded figure. But the test is always the same : Is one thing seen in the form of another ? An expression ceases to be figurative the moment it fails to call up the image through which the thought to be expressed was at first figuratively seen. For instance, in the expression " The truth is obvi- ous," we no longer bring up the image of an obstacle, as a tree across the road {ob, against, or in front ; and via, a road or way). That is, the truth need not be sought, but lies so directly in the path that one cannot help running against it. In every figure of thought an idea is contemplated through its image, — an image which presents the idea under consideration more effectively, more clearly, elegantly, or energetically than is possible through direct language. With a figurative writer an idea springs forth with its image, which wings the idea for its destination. Let the following be tested as to whether they are figurative or literal: — 1. His fortune is dilapidated. 2. The objection is instiperable. 3. The king obliterated the memory of the wrong. 4. The student THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 2Q7 overcame all impediments to scholarship. 5. The merchant has gone into bankruptcy. 6. A rupture of the friendly relations between England and America is feared. 7. This exercise is superfluous. 8. The people congregated for worship. 9. Thor- ough mastery of this point will expedite our future study. 10. He is the candidate for the office of governor. 11. She was aston- ished Tat the news. 12.- He is a desultory reader. 13. The kettle boils. 14. He has read Homer and Virgil. 15. The harbor is crowded with masts. 16. The skies are painted with unnumbered sparks. 17. Their ranks are breaking like clouds before a Biscay gale. 18. " Build thee more stately mansions, O my soul, As the swift seasons roll. Leave thy low vaulted past, Let each temple, nobler than the last, Shut thee from heaven with a dome more vast, Till thou at length art free, Leaving thine outgrown shell by life's unresting sea." While in every figure two objects of thought are brought into the same conception, this fact alone does not make the thought figurative. The thought becomes figurative only when the imagination presents a relation between the two objects which the literal judgment con- tradicts. The imagination substitutes its own relations for the relations of the understanding. In the state- ment "The kettle boils," we have the two objects, ket- tle and water, the former suggesting the latter. The judgment pronounces this statement untrue --that the kettle does not boil; whereupon water is suggested and the judgment satisfied and the truth maintained. The imagination presents us with " The morning of life"; but the judgment says that life has no morning; this belongs only to the day. "The buttercup catches the 298 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. sun in his chalice." The judgment is startled at such announcement, and goes into a dissertation on the absorption of certain rays of light and the reflection of others. But the imagination is delighted with the beau- tiful truth discerned in this action of the buttercup. The imagination declares that " His hands dangled a mile out of his sleeves"; whereupon the judgment is astonished at this bold disregard for truth. Note how, in the foregoing stanza from the " Chambered Nauti- lus," the imagination assumes relations which lie outside those of the understanding. There is no antagonism in this, no opposition of truths; for the imaginative relation is simply a higher order of truth, and the judg- ment must yield supremacy when it comes to the limit of its own territory. Thus a figure of thought is produced by the imagina- tion substituting objects out of the logical relations of the judgment. Figures must, therefore, divide them- selves on the basis of the relation which the object pre- sented by the imagination bears to the object held by the judgment. These relations are those of association, of comparison, and of contrast, giving rise to three classes of figures of the same name. To express an idea more effectively the imagination substitutes, against the truth required by the judgment, some more easily grasped or striking object which customarily forms a part of the same mental state with the object to be expressed. Such association is the ground on which the substitu- tion is permitted, the purpose of it being more effective expression. Or, the imagination substitutes an object bearing an imagined resemblance, against the logical THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 299 differences, to the object to be expressed, the judgment admitting the resemblance when the imagination points it out. This resemblance is the ground of the substi- tution, the purpose again being to present more clearly or more strongly the primary object of attention. Again, the imagination substitutes for the object to be expressed an object as if in unity with it, which the judgment holds to be in utter opposition. In the pre- ceding, the judgment had not opposed the objects, had simply not noted their resemblance in the ordinary log- ical movement of thought, but sanctions it as soon as the imagination brings it to light. The most strained substitution and the boldest effort of the imagination is that in which the objects having irreconcilable differ- ences are conceived as in unity, one being substituted for the other. This contrast, however, is the ground of the substitution, while the purpose is to charge the language with more power than accompanies literal speech. The ascending order of activity on the part of the imagination in making the foregoing substitutions is obvious. And this falls in fairly well with the ascending order of figures as to purpose -- figures promoting clearness, elegance, and energy; the highest effort of the imagination producing energy, while the lowest, least diverging from the judgment, securing clearness. Figures of Association. A figure of association is a figure of thought in which one idea is put in the form of another which is asso- ciated with it as a part of the same mental state. A 300 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. figure of association is based on the law of association of ideas under their logical relations. When two ideas have been associated in the mind as purpose and means, substance and attribute, whole and part, in time and place, and as cause and effect, one of them, when men- tioned, will suggest the other. When one says, " A sail ahead," the idea sail calls up the idea ship, because the mind is accustomed to associate the sail with the ship. "The palace should not spurn the cottage." In this the idea palace brings to mind the wealthy people who are commonly associated in the mind with palaces; the idea cottage, for the same reason, recalls the poor who inhabit them. When we say that he is a slave to the cup, the contents of the cup is readily supplied; and "The pen is mightier than the sword " readily sug- gests intelligence, on the one hand, and the physical force of armies, on the other. In each case the imagi- nation presents, against truth relations, the more defi- nite, conspicuous, and impressive object, trusting the judgment to perceive the real intent through the sub- stitution of the real object in thought. For practical purposes, the relations under which objects are associated may be grouped into two: internal relations and relations of external accompani- ment. The first gives rise to the figure named Synecdoche; the second to the figure named Metonymy. Synecdoche. - -This is a figure of association in which something more or something less is directly expressed than is intended to be conveyed. A Synecdoche ex- presses figuratively what differs "from the original meaning of the word in degree, and not in kind." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 3<DI This figure is based on the inner relations which con- stitute the object; namely, whole and part, and sub- stance and attribute. Most Synecdoches are based on the relation of whole and part, and usually the part is named to suggest the whole; as, A sail ahead! conveying the idea of a ship by the use of one of its parts. In this case there is given a part of an individual; sometimes an individual is named instead of a class; as, "A Daniel, a second Daniel come to judgment! " conveying the idea of the class of wise interpreters of the law. Also, the species may be given for the genera; as, "Give us this day our daily bread," that is, food. By naming apart for the whole, there is secured the gain that belongs to all concrete and specific expression. When it is said that the redcoats are fleeing, the expression is specific and striking, and the object more easily pictured than if it were said that the soldiers are fleeing. The part named may also be more suggestive from some relation it has to the end in view; as, All hands to the pump. - She gave her heart and hand. - - " How beautiful upon the mountains are the feet of him that bringeth good tidings! " Sometimes the whole is named to suggest the part; but this is a rare figure, being contrary to the principle of economy of attention, which requires the concrete and specific rather than the abstract and the general. It sometimes happens, however, that the mention of the whole gives emphasis to the part; as, "the Roman world " impresses the mind with its vastness and im- portance more than to say the Roman Empire. The 302 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. whole is used for the part with good effect when the purpose is to soften the expression; as, He has departed this life; for, He died. — He has closed up business; for, He has gone into bankruptcy. Softening of expression is called Euphemism. The attribute is sometimes used to suggest the sub- ject of the attribute, as youth and beauty, for the young and beautiful. What is classed as giving " the material for the object ' comes under this head; as, He bartered his soul for gold. — He killed him with murderous steel. Here, naming the material sug- gests the striking attributes, — in the one that which pleases the eye; in the other, that which adapts the instrument to its deadly work. The subject of the attribute may be given to suggest the attribute; as, There might have been seen the fox in his conduct. Putting the definite number for an indefinite comes under this figure; as, "Ten thousand fleets sweep over thee in vain." Let the following Synecdoches be explained and classed as to the kind of association involved: — i. They saw the city of spires. 2. The skein fell from her sick hand. 3. '• (live us this day our daily bread." 4. They cut the solid whiteness through. 5. Flesh and blood hath not revealed it unto thee. 6. Unfurl the stars and stripes. 7. The Vandals overran the Roman world. 8. The tired fingers toiled on. 9. He was a man of influence in his day. 10. He barters his soul for gold. 11. "They that take the sword shall perish by the sword." 12. The steel (the sword) glittered in the air. Metonymy.- -This is a figure of association in which an object is suggested by naming some object or attri- THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 303 bute externally associated with it. Hence, the use of the word Metonymy, meaning a change of name. Un- like Synecdoche, Metonymy directly expresses some- thing different from its real meaning. The sail is not a different object from the ship, but a part of it; while in this, " The hotel sets a good table," the word table expresses something entirely different from the food on the table. These two figures, however, are fundamentally alike, each being based on the same law of association of ideas. The table recalls the food upon it for the same reason that the sail recalls the ship. Both, too, have the same value to style, in that each names some accessory idea which recalls the principal idea more clearly or more forcibly than its direct naming would do. There are different kinds of Metonymies, as deter- mined by the different laws of association: — 1. Relation of purpose and means; as, The ballot governs the country. — " The pen is mightier than the sword." 2. Relation of cause and effect; as, Gray hairs should be respected. — Mr. Snyder is a student of Shakespeare. 3. Relation of place; as, The palace should not scorn the cottage. 4. Relation in time; as, "Remember March, the ides of March." Point out the Metonymy in each of the following, and state the relation on which it is based : - 1. His wit set the table in a roar. 2. We have prostrated our- selves before the throne. 3. Strike for your altars and your hres. 3O4 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 4. Who steals my purse steals trash. 5. Too much red tape does not expedite business. 6. He is a slave to the bottle. 7. In the sweat of thy brow shalt thou eat thy bread. 8. " We plant upon the sunny lea, A shadow for the noontide hour, A shelter from the summer shower, When we plant the apple tree." 9. " The snow had begun in the gloaming, And busily all the night Had been heaping field and highway With a silence deep and white." 10. " Girls, whose young eyes o'erflow with mirth, Shall peel its fruit by cottage hearth." Figures of Comparison. A figure of comparison is a figure of thought in which the imagination brings to view some resemblance between the primary and the secondary object, which does not fall under the categorical relations of the judg- ment. By this means the writer throws the unfamiliar, the abstract, and the inner things of spirit into the form of the concrete individual. He is thus permitted to speak in the language of the sensuous imagination, and thereby to give definiteness and to illuminate what would otherwise be dim, vague, and unfamiliar to the understanding. And of more importance still, a figure of comparison serves to give to an object some quality which it has not by nature, and thus elevates or de- grades it. Figures of comparison are based ultimately on the fact that there is a fundamental quality common to all THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 305 objects. " All are manifestations of one force." The imagination penetrates objects and brings to view their inner nature. Figures of comparison arise from the exercise of the imagination as it interprets the inner identity of things; as it perceives the spiritual truth of which physical facts are symbols. Hence, they are profoundly significant, bringing to view the very life and being of common material things, or clothing ideal qualities of spirit in pleasing forms of beauty. Figures of comparison differ from those of asso- ciation in two essential particulars: (i) in figures of association there is no illustrative power or transfer- ence of qualities, as in the others; (2) the imagination required to construct of interpret them is the literal, picturing imagination; while in figures of comparison it is the poetic, the intuitive imagination. In figures of association one idea suggests another because the two have been previously associated in consciousness; in figures of comparison one object suggests another by some resemblance, subtile and new to the mind dis- cerning it. Figures of comparison express ideal rela- tions, — relations which the mind creates for itself and which can be found in the mind only; while figures of association express real relations; that is, relations which are felt to be in the external object, the actual relations, as substance and attribute, time and space, whole and part, cause and effect, and purpose and means. Figurative comparison is not always easily discrimi- nated from literal comparison. Literal comparison, which occupies so prominent a place in the presenta- 306 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. tion of thought, is between objects which are essen- tially alike, and in respect to such points as logical analysis can present ; while figurative comparison is between objects which are essentially unlike, except in respect to what the penetrative imagination alone can find. In figurative comparison there must be an actual likeness, which the mind does not ordinarily detect, because of the prominent and essential unlikeness of the objects compared, — a likeness which cannot be found by any amount of analysis by the judgment, and which only the intuitive imagination can feel. The terms in figurative comparison lie in different worlds — the spiritual and the material ; hence their absorb- ing difference and their hidden resemblance. But there must be some point of identity between them, else the spiritual could not be presented in terms of the material. To explain a figure is to put the finger on the point of identity between what seems contrasted terms. All figures of comparison, like all processes in mathematics, are based on the fact that one thing is identical, at some point, with another. When Long- fellow speaks of his thoughts clinging to the moulder- ing past as the vine to the mouldering wall, he must have discerned that clinging is identical with clinging. And when he says that the hopes of youth fall thick in the blast, having already suggested the falling leaves in the blasts of wind and rain, one readily, by simplify- ing the equation, discerns that falling in blasts equals falling in blasts. Leaves and hopes are conspicuously different, — different in color, form, size, parts, use, structure, etc.; so different that the mind in its regular THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 307 movement of logical thought does not discern the point of identity. By the foregoing suggestions, which of the following are figurative? In which case do the objects com- pared belong to different worlds? Point out the conspicuous differences between the objects in the figurative expressions, and then state precisely the point of identity: — 1. The steamer sweeps along like a lightning train. 2. The snowbird comes whirling down like a leaf. 3. "His russet beard was already flecked with patches of snow, as hedges sometimes in November." 4. " This he said with a smile, that danced in his eyes, as the sunbeams dance on the waves of the sea, and vanish again in a moment." 5. The lion fights like the tiger. 6. The man fights like a tiger. 7. His airy fancy flits about, like a hum- ming bird from flower to flower. 8. The humming bird hums like a spinning top. 9. The eagle soars aloft till he looks like a speck in the sky. 10. The imagination, as the eagle, soars aloft to dizzy heights. 11. "Pleasures are like poppies spread; you seize the flower, the bloom is shed." 12. The bare feet of the boy must soon be "hid in the prison cells of pride." 13. The anchor of the vessel is a thought controlling the vessel's move- ment. 14. Man's life is a rainy day. On the basis of explicitness, figurative comparisons are divided into Expressed Comparison and Implied Comparison, with subdivisions under the second. Expressed Comparison. — The expressed comparison is called a Simi/e, from simi/is, like. This figure is peculiar in that the ideas compared and the comparison are all expressed. The word like is generally used to denote the comparison ; but the words as, so, just as, similar to, and other expressions of comparison may be 308 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. used. Sometimes the word expressing the comparison is understood. The finding of these words of compari- son is no assurance that the expression is figurative. The Simile serves chiefly to illustrate truth to the intellect or to please the emotions by transferring from one object to another some quality more pleasing than naturally belongs to the object under discussion. They may be enlisted in the service of all the esthetic emo- tions — wit, humor, beauty, and sublimity. While less energetic than implied comparisons, they, because ex- pressing the resemblance more fully, may be used to express resemblance which would be obscure in the other forms. To explain a Simile is to point out the identity between the objects compared, and then to show how the identity is expressed. So explain the following, and then change each figure to literal language and note the gain in the ease of interpretation: — 1. " He shall be like a tree planted by the rivers of waters." 2. " Their lives glide on like rivers that water the woodland." 3. " It (mercy) droppeth as the gentle rain from Heaven upon the place beneath." 4. " The Kingdom of God is like a grain of mustard seed." 5. " With oaken brace and copper band, Lay the rudder on the sand, That like a thought, should have control, Over the movement of the whole." 6. " And a whooping billow swept the crew Like icicles from her deck." 7. " How far that little candle throws his beams : So shines a good deed in a naughty world." 8. " For there are moments in life when the heart is so full of emotion. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 309 That if it by chance be shaken, or into its depths, like a pebble, Drops some careless word, it overflows, and its secret Spilt on the ground like water, can never be gathered to- gether." 9. " And my ear with the music impregnated may be, Like the poor exiled shell with the soul of the sea." 10. "As seeds lie dormant in the earth for hundreds of years, and then when brought to the influence of air and light, exhibit their vitality, so the germ of the soul may lie concealed and un- developed during the whole term of human life." Implied Comparisons. — In implied comparisons the resemblance is never expressed, and often one term of the comparison is omitted. They vary as to the degree of implication, and on this basis fall into two classes; namely, the Metaphor and the Allegory, with varieties under each. Metaphor. — This figure, instead of expressing a resemblance, asserts or assumes an identity; thus: "Judah is a lion's whelp." "A cloud of sorrow dark- ened his face." Every Metaphor may be expanded into a Simile. Judah is like a lion's whelp. Sorrows, like a cloud, darkened his face. It would thus seem that the only distinction between the Metaphor and Simile lies in the form. But this distinction in form arises from a distinction under the form. The Meta- phor arises from a greater degree of animation and a bolder effort of the imagination. It thus becomes not only shorter, but stronger, flashing the thought upon the mind. The Metaphor ventures to exaggerate the resemblance, as the more cautious Simile would give it, into total identity. The exaggeration does not 310 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. deceive, for it is understood that only resemblances are meant ; but it excites the mind to a more vivid realization. The reason for the greater force of the Metaphor over the Simile is explained by A. S. Hill in the following: — " According to Dr. Whately, who adopts the idea from Aristotle, the superiority of the Metaphor is ascribable to the fact that ' all men are more gratified at catching the resemblance for themselves than at having it pointed out to them'; according to Herbert Spencer, ' the greater economy it achieves would seem to be the probable cause ' ; but neither explanation is altogether satisfactory. On the one hand, the Meta- phor, though shorter than the Simile, usually makes the mind do more work; on the other hand, the mind is rendered more able to work, — not, however, because it is gratified, but because it is stimulated to exertion." The Metaphor, because of its stimulating power, is classed as a figure of Energy. Yet it contributes largely to Clearness, and is more often elegant than the Simile. No other figure is so common or con- tributes so much to effective expression. The Meta- phor, real or faded, is met with in almost every sentence that drops from tongue or pen. This figure more than any other has increased the power and scope of language; and this it has done by multiplying meanings without increasing words. Language has been designated by Richter "a dictionary of faded metaphors." In some Metaphors the identity is asserted, in others assumed. Macbeth applies the name Metaphor to the THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 3 1 I first only, reserving the second for a distinct class, which he names Implication. "The metaphor," he says, " lies wholly in the copula or verb, which asserts something of the subject that is not literally proper to the nature of that subject." He defines Implication as an implied Metaphor or an implied Simile, giving these examples : — " No palm grove islanded amid the waste." " Rising above the deluge of years," in speaking of Persepolis. " The vales are surging with the grain." There is certainly a clear distinction here, these be- ing briefer and less explicit than the preceding. The term Metaphor, however, is usually applied to both; and this seems justifiable, since the objects compared are always viewed as identical. I think there is not a resemblance assumed ever, but an identity, making the Implication, at most, always an implied Metaphor. From the nature of the Metaphor it is easy, when more than one figurative conception is given of the object under discussion, to confuse the mind by con- tradictory representative images. Such a confusion of figures is called a mixed Metaphor, and is one of the most common faults of a loose and careless speaker. Says Genung: "It arises from giving too little atten- tion to the successive images that crowd upon the brain, and is avoided by simply surrendering one's thoughts to the picture suggested until it is wrought out as far as needed." The following examples illustrate this error: — 1. "He is swamped in the meshes of his argument." 2. " His bosom was swollen with the flame of patriotism." 312 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 3. " The discord will burst forth into a conflagration which will deluge the sea of politics with an earthquake of heresies." 4. " Virtue alone can save us from the hosts of evil when they roll in upon us." 5. " He alone can manage the storm-tossed ship of state on its march." Addison's rule for testing Metaphors will be found serviceable: "Try and form a picture of them." "If the parts," says Macbeth, "when pictured out by a painter, be incongruous, put your Metaphor in the fire, lest there should stand before you a goddess, horse, and ship, all in one." The mixing of literal and figurative language pro- duces the same confusion as the mixing of metaphors, and sometimes a ludicrous descent from the elevated to the mean, called Bathos. These three examples used by De Mille will illustrate the nature of this error: — 1. "The fiend Intemperance is marshaling his hosts, so as to poison the minds and bodies of poor inebriates." 2. " Sailing on the sea of life, we are often in danger from the temptations around us." 3. " If we put on the whole armor of righteousness, we shall be less likely to yield to the allurements of sin." In " i " the image of an armed body of men is inter- mingled with the literal effect of poison — an effect the mind did not expect from marshaling hosts. In "2 " literal temptations are not the clangers which a mind occupied by the image of a voyage would expect. In " 3 " the image of an armed man is confused with lit- eral allurements -- confused because allurements are not expected to be met with arms. Here, as in the THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 3 I 3 mixed Metaphor, the law which requires unity of impression is violated; and, as a result, the mind is interrupted and its energies diverted in the process of interpretation. Let the following Metaphors be expanded into Simi- les, and then explained as were Similes. Test each as to the unity of impression, the gain over literal expres- sion, and over the corresponding Simile: — 1. " The clouds of adversity soon pass away." 2. " Choate was one of the brightest luminaries of the age." 3. " All too soon these feet must hide In the prison cells of pride." 4. " All hearts confess the saints elect Who, twain in faith, in love agree, And melt not in an acid sect The Christian pearl of charity." 5. " For gentleness and love and trust Prevail o'er angry wave and gust; And in the wreck of noble lives Something immortal still survives." 6. " Thus did that poor soul wander in want and cheerless discomfort, Bleeding, barefooted, over the shards and thorns of existence." 7. " They (my observations) have convinced me that, however the surface of character may be chilled and frozen by the cares of the world, or cultivated into mere smiles by the arts of society, still there are dormant fires lurking in the depths of the coldest bosom, which, when once kindled, become impetuous, and are sometimes desolating in their effects." 8. " She sends forth her sympathies on adventure; she embarks her whole soul in the traffic of affection; and if shipwrecked, her case is hopeless — for it is a bankruptcy of the heart." 3 '4 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 9. " Her lithe mind winds itself with surprising grace through the metaphysical and other intricacies of her subject." 10. " Dante's opinions have life in them still, because they were from living sources of reflection and experience, because they were reasoned out from the astronomic laws of history and ethics, and were not weather-guesses snatched in a glance at the doubtful political sky of the hour." n. "His (Dante's) is the first keel that ever ventured into the silent sea of human consciousness to find a new world of poetry." 12. " He wrote too much to write always well; for it is not a great Xerxes-army of words, but a compact Greek ten thousand, that march safely down to posterity." The Metaphor often assumes inanimate things to have life; as, the thirsty ground, a pitiless stone, a raging storm, a frowning precipice, winged words. In these, some quality of living things is attributed to inanimate objects; but sometimes there is a more com- plete identification of human attributes, endowing the object with personality — sex, speech, thought, emotion, and purpose; as, "Good-bye, proud world. I 'm going home. Thou 'rt not my friend, and I 'm not thine." When the personal element becomes prominent the Metaphor is called Personification. Arising by such imperceptible gradations from the Metaphor, there is a broad and very indefinite boundary to which either the name Metaphor or Personification is applied with equal propriety. Personifications of the lowest degree, which consist in merely attributing some quality of living beings to things inanimate, are usually classed under Metaphors also. But Personification, even of the highest degree, may be explained and classed as Metaphor, for it assumes identity of attributes. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 315 The foundation of this figure is obviously in the intuition of the mind which feels a community of life with all objects about it. The mind naturally animates inanimate things. The child elevates into a companion of its life the most common and trivial object; and in the lower phase of the mind's development every object and every phenomena is explained by attributing to it intelligence, feeling, motive. Man never, perhaps, entirely frees himself from the impression that the most common object has personality like himself. Although in his cultured state he does not thus explain them, yet whatever touches him with emotion, he, for the moment, unconsciously bestows upon it the idea of life. The nature of this figure suggests the source of its efficiency. It gives concreteness and animation to style. It makes all objects our companions, and touches us with the joy of human sympathy by the life with which the object is endowed. This figure thus serves to please and to impress. Let the following be explained, stating why they are both Metaphors and Personifications. Note also the grade of Personification, whether they attribute some quality of living beings to inanimate things or entire personality, — sex, speech, human feelings, or purpose, — and the gain over literal statement : — 1. " Build me straight, O worthy master, Staunch and strong, a goodly vessel, That shall laugh at all disaster, And with wave and whirlwind wrestle." 2. " With thy red lips, redder still Kissed by strawberries from the hill." 3 16 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. 3. " Yet Love will dream and Faith will trust, That somehow, somewhere, meet we must." 4. "True it is that Death's face seems stern and cold, When he is sent to summon those we love." 5. "In vain Faith blows her trumpet to summon back her scattered troop." 6. " Philosophy is a noble lady, partaking of the divine essence by a kind of eternal marriage." 7. " Down came the storm, and smote amain The vessel in its strength ; She shuddered and paused, like a frightened steed, Then leaped her cable's length." 8. " Flattery spits her poison at the mightiest peers." 9. " She starts — she moves — she seems to feel The thrill of life along her keel, And spurning with her foot the ground, With one exulting joyous bound, She leaps into the ocean's arms." 10. " Yonder snow-white cloud that floats in the ether above me, Seems like a hand that is pointing and beckoning me over the ocean. There is another hand that is not so ghost-like Holding me, drawing me back, and clasping mine for protection. Float, O hand of cloud, and vanish away in the ether. Roll thyself up like a fist, to threaten and daunt me; I heed not Either your warning or menace, or any omen of evil." The last figure above constitutes the highest degree of Personification, - -the degree in which the inanimate object is introduced as speaking or listening. This is proper only under the most intense feeling. Nothing but violent emotion can stimulate the mind to conceive an insensible object as listening to what we say or as THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 317 making any response to us. This grade of Personifica- tion is frequently, if not generally, called Apostrophe, meaning to turn away - - " a turning away from the real auditory, and addressing an absent or imaginary one." The following are examples: — " Roll on thou deep and dark blue ocean roll. Ten thousand fleets sweep over thee in vain." " Sail forth into the sea, O ship, Through wind and wave, right onward steer." Strictly, however, Apostrophe is limited to an address to a real person, but one absent or dead, as if he were present and listening to the speaker; as, - " Milton, thou should'st be living at this hour. England has need of thee." " Great father of your country, we heed your words, we feel them as if you uttered them with lips of flesh and blood." In its restricted sense, an Apostrophe is never Personification; for there is only the supposition that persons who are absent or dead are present. This assumed identity between the imagined person and the real one is the ground for classifying this figure with those of Comparison. In the highest form of Personi- fication, the object is both personified and addressed, giving it a claim to both classes. Another variety of Implied Comparison, and one closely resembling Apostrophe, is Vision. Vision dif- fers from Apostrophe in the fact that Vision merely narrates or describes, while Apostrophe addresses or invokes persons. An object or event, in the past or fu- 3 I 8 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ture, may make so vivid an impression that it seems to be present, as in this passage from Webster's descrip- tion of a murder: — " The assassin enters, through the window already prepared, into an unoccupied apartment. With noiseless foot he paces the lonely hall half-lighted by the moon; he winds up the ascent of the stairs, and reaches the door of the chamber." The last variety of Comparison to be noted here is the Hyperbole. Hyperbole breaks down the truth limitations of size and degree; while Vision, that of time and distance. In Hyperbole, the object, under excited emotion, is exaggerated beyond the limits re- quired by sober judgment, and the exaggerated object presented as if it were the true one; as, "His hands dangled a mile out of his sleeves." '"His muscles strong as iron bands." Allegory. -- An Allegory is usually defined as an extended Metaphor, both being implied comparisons, differing only in length. But the more fundamental distinction is the fact that in the Allegory the compari- son is more hidden, making the degree of implication rather than length the basis of its classification. The Allegory is usually, and it may always be, longer than the Metaphor, but this is an accident of its more funda- mental quality. Haven says: "It must not be sup- posed that allegories are necessarily long. They are often brief." Our definition must, therefore, contain some mark of distinction other than that of length. If it should be said that Israel is like an empty vine, a Simile would be formed ; both terms of comparison, " Israel " and " empty vine," being brought before the THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 3 19 mind and their resemblance expressed by the word "like." If it should be said that Israel is an empty vine, there would be formed a Metaphor; both terms of comparison being brought before the mind and their identity asserted by the copula. But if the vine, the representative term, alone should be presented, in brief or at length, in such a way as to make it clear that Israel was meant, without bringing the two objects directly together, the figure would be an Allegory. When Longfellow says, " My life is cold, and dark, and dreary," the terms of comparison are intentionally brought together, as in the Metaphor; but when, in the second stanza, after having described the rainy clay and his life in terms of it, he says, " It rains, and the wind is never weary," the secondary, or representative object, only one is mentioned; thus leaving the mind to infer the object which the sentence is intended to describe and forming an Allegory. At first this line appears to be literal; and reflection is required to dis- cern that he means to speak of life, and not the rain and wind. Thus there is a regular graduation from the Simile to the Allegory, — Simile having two terms compared; Metaphor having two terms with comparison omitted; Allegory, expressing only one term, and that the secondary, with the comparison and the primary object to be discovered. The Simile is the clearest, and must be used when the others would be obscure; the Allegory is most obscure, requiring most labor from the mind, but yielding the more pleasure through the greater freedom of discovery which it permits to the imagination. 320 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. It thus appears that the chief fact about an Allegory is not its length, but the manner in which it expresses its truth. It may consist of a single statement, as in the example from Longfellow; or it may fill a volume, as in " Pilgrim's Progress." They may vary in length, but in one point they cannot vary; namely, that the mind must be left to make out, by its own ingenuity, the primary object of comparison. Therefore, an Allegory may be defined as a figure of comparison in which the representative object only is presented, leaving the mind to make out, by its own ingenuity, the primary object. " An Allegory," says Haven, " is a fictitious narrative or description so constructed as to suggest thoughts and facts entirely different from those which it appears to relate." Webster's Dictionary marks clearly the true distinction: "A figurative sentence or discourse, in which the principal subject is described by another subject resembling it in its prop- erties and circumstances. The principal subject is thus kept out of view, and we are left to collect the inten- tions of the writer or speaker by the resemblance of the secondary to the primary subject." It is not necessary, in fact not permissible, for the Allegory to be so hidden as to puzzle the reader. The meaning should be plain, but must not be pointed out. Indeed, a few words of explanation at the outset in order to put the reader on the right track are allowable. This figure does not prevent the mention of the primary ob- ject in the course of presentation; yet it must be so done as to leave the mind to decide that it is the pri- mary object. One may not read far in "Pilgrim's THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 32 I Progress" till he discovers the subject of discussion; but the remainder does not then cease to be allegorical, because each part has a new application to some phase of the theme. When Longfellow says, " Be still sad heart and cease repining, Behind the clouds is the sun still shining," he forms an Allegory in the second line, although the general theme, life, has been mentioned ; but the thought of happiness beyond the present trials is left for the reader to supply. The Allegory is very extensively used, and often constitutes the literary embodiment of an entire dis- course. Many good specimens are found in the Bible, all the Saviour's parables being allegorical; for example, the parable of the Prodigal Son. The eighteenth Psalm contains a neat example: — " Thou hast brought a vine out of Egypt; thou hast cast out the heathen and planted it. Thou prepardest room before it, and didst cause it to take deep root, and it filled the land. The hills were covered with the shadow of it, and the boughs thereof were like the goodly cedars. She sent out her boughs unto the sea, and her branches unto the river. Why hast thou then broken down her hedges, so that all they which pass by the way do pluck her? The boar out of the wood doth waste it, and the wild beast of the field doth devour it. Return, we beseech thee, O (iod of hosts; look down from heaven, and behold, and visit this vine." The following are distinguished examples of the Allegory, and may be further studied to impress the nature, beauty, and force of this figure : — Bryant's " Waiting by the Gate," Longfellow's " Building the Ship," Foe's "Raven" and "Haunted Palace," Hawthorne's 322 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. " Celestial Railroad," Addison's " Vision of Mirza," Spenser's " Faerie Queen," Bunyan's " Pilgrim's Progress, " Chaucer's " House of Fame," Swift's " Tale of the Tub " and " Gulliver's Travels," Dante's " Divina Commedia." Since only the representative term of the compari- son is given in the Allegory, leaving both the com- parison and the real subject of consideration to be made out, sculpture and painting may be allegorical. The statue of a child clasping a dove to its bosom, but as- saulted by a snake, represents innocence attacked by evil; and hope may be allegorically represented by the picture of youth leaning against an anchor. The whole course of man's life may be symbolized by a series of pictures. All the virtues of life, faith, hope, courage, purity, etc., have their emblems. Even architecture is said to be allegorical. " The heavy Gothic style is felt to symbolize mystery, profundity, and to awaken rever- ence, and is therefore suited to a house of worship; while the lighter Grecian styles betoken rather cheer- fulness and social pleasure." When the allegorical relation takes place among men, and from which an instructive lesson is to be drawn, the Allegory is called a Parable. The Parable of the Prodigal Son and of the Sower are good examples. This form of Allegory is chiefly used in conveying a religious truth. When the Allegory is founded on the supposed action of brutes or inanimate things, it is called a Fable. The Fable differs from the Parable in not being confined to the rules of possibility or probability. The Fable, like the Parable, is designed to teach some useful truth. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 323 "Aesop's Fables" are classic examples. The following from the ninth chapter of Judges is a good type of the class. Let it be shown first why it is an Allegory, and then its characteristic mark as Fable should be given : — " The trees went forth on a time to anoint a king over them ; and said unto the olive tree, Reign thou over us. But the olive tree said unto them, Should I leave my fatness, wherewith by me they honor God and man, and go to be promoted over the trees ? And the trees said to the fig tree, Come thou and reign over us. But the fig tree said unto them, Should I forsake my sweetness, and my good fruit, and go to be promoted over the trees ? Then said the trees unto the vine, Come thou and reign over us. And the vine said unto them, Should I leave my wine, which cheereth God and man, and go to be promoted over the trees? Then said all the trees unto the bramble, Come thou and reign over us. And the bramble said unto the trees, If in truth ye anoint me king over you, then come and put your trust in my shadow; and if not, let fire come out of the bramble, and devour the cedars of Lebanon." Figures of Contrast. There are two general classes of figures of contrast, — Expressed Contrast and Implied Contrast. Expressed Contrast. — The first of these is called Antithesis. Antithesis is a figure of contrast which impresses an idea by bringing it into the same concep- tion with its opposite; as, "A false balance is an abomination to the Lord: but a just weight is his delight." The Proverbs are constructed almost wholly on the figure of Antithesis. The Antithesis is not always in the form of the bal- anced sentence as in the above. A part of considerable 324 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. length may be constructed to produce in the mind a state opposite the one intended in order to intensify the feeling which the writer wishes to arouse. Whittier thus introduces " Marguerite " : — " The robins sang in the orchard, the buds into blossoms grew; Little of human sorrow the buds and the robins knew." " Sick, in an alien household, the poor French neutral lay; Into her lonesome garret fell the light of the April day." Byron's description of the battle of Waterloo, in "Childe Harold," bringing before the mind the rap- turous joy of the music and the dance before the appalling horrors of the battle broke upon them, is an example of the effective use of the principle of Antithesis. The second and last figure of expressed contrast is the Climax, meaning literally a ladder. This is a figure or an arrangement in which a sentence rises, as it were, step by step in importance, force, or dignity; as, — " The golden sun, The planets, all the infinite host of heaven, Are shining on the sad abodes of death, Through the still lapse of ages." "Antithesis contrasts objects by bringing them to- gether in opposition; Climax contrasts objects by exhibiting their degrees of difference through a series of intermediates." 1 Climax, like Antithesis, is not confined to a single sentence. Its principle controls the arrangement of the parts of a discourse, which should always rise in force, 1 D. r.Hffl. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 325 beauty, and dignity to the end. Bryant, in his " In- scription for the Entrance to a Wood," forms a unique climax in attributing human feelings to objects in the following order: birds, squirrels, insects, trees, flowers, trunks of trees, and mossy rocks. This at first seems an anticlimax, proceeding from the highest to the low- est, but the personification necessarily becomes stronger as the object becomes lower in the scale of being. To attribute human joy to a bird is more natural and requires less effort of the imagination than to attribute human contentment to a mossy rock. Anticlimax, or Bathos, is a fault in style, unless intentionally used for purposes of wit. In such cases the seeming anticlimax is a true climax; for the effect, while different in kind, is greater in degree. Holmes uses the anticlimax to good effect in the " One-hoss Shay," in descending from the important events of the Lisbon Earthquake and the defeat of Braddock's army to the completion of the Deacon's Masterpiece: — " That was the year when Lisbon-town Saw the earth open and gulp her down. And Braddock's army was done so brown, Left without a scalp to its crown. It was on the terrible Earthquake-day That the Deacon finished the one-hoss shay." Implied Contrast. — These are divided into four classes : the Epigram, Interrogation, Irony, and Wit and Humor: — 1. An Epigram has no clear distinguishing mark. It is the startling expression of a thought by means of the contradiction between the real and the apparent 326 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. meaning. It is in general any pungent way of saying a thing. The following are examples of good Epigrams : — " Language is the art of concealing thought." " Those labori- ous authors who mistake perspiration for inspiration." " When you have nothing to say, say it." " The more haste, the less speed." " One secret in education is to know how wisely to lose time." " The child is father to the man." " He asked for bread and received a stone." " Not louder shrieks to pitying Heaven are cast, When husbands, or when lap-dogs, breathe their last." "He went and told the sexton, and the sexton tolled the bell." The last example is a variety of Epigram called Paronomasia, or Pun, being a play upon words. An Epigram plays a conspicuous part in wit, the charac- teristic element of each being the shock of surprise. So frequently do some authors use the Epigram that their style may be characterized as epigrammatic. Pope belongs to this class. 2. The second figure of implied contrast is Interro- gation. Interrogation, as a figure, does not seek information, but challenges the decision of the hearer, and thus compels his activity; as, — " Hath a dog money? is it possible A cur can lend three thousand ducats ? " The contrast consists in forcing on the attention the opposite truth to the one presented. This figure contributes to Energy, as may be illustrated by chang- ing the foregoing example to a direct statement. It is an appeal for a silent rejoinder. The Interrogation is a sign of thorough conviction on the part of the speaker. THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 327 It shows perfect confidence in the truth of what is uttered, for it implies that the speaker is willing to leave the decision to the auditor. It is the natural expression of the vivid realization of truth, and a pro- found confidence in the acceptance of it by the persons addressed. 3. The third figure of implied contrast is called Irony. This figure states in all solemnity the exact opposite of the truth intended to be conveyed. The following from Whittier's " Hunters of Men " are good examples : — " And woman, kind woman, wife, widow, and maid, For the good of the hunted, is lending her aid." " Oh, goodly and grand is our hunting to see, In this land of the brave and this home of the free." Irony, with its different forms of Burlesque, Ridicule, Derision, Mockery, Satire, and Sarcasm, is a most effec- tive means of impressing truth, and hence, with the other figures of contrast, must be classed with the figures of Energy. These forms of contrast have been cutting weapons in every political and moral reform, as well illustrated in Whittier's "War Poems," Lowell's " Biglow Papers," Nasby's editorials, and Swift's "Gul- liver's Travels." 4. Wit and Humor are also based on contrasts of mental states. These arise from some new, unexpected, and pleasing turn of thought. They involve "an exag- geration, a reversal of ideas, a glimpse of the incon- gruous or the impossible." Lincoln, on entering the room in which the proper length of a man's legs was 3 2 ^ THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. being discussed, was unexpectedly called upon to decide the question. He said that he had given the matter very little consideration, but had always supposed that a man's legs should be long enough to reach from his body to the ground. In this he furnished us with a good example of wit through the incongruous and the impossible. At once there arises a picture of a man walking clear of the earth because his legs are so short that they will not reach it. The mind is pleasantly surprised by the fanciful result from such a cause. Any playful contradiction, reversal, or exaggeration of the thought relations — any playful violation of the accustomed movement of thought — produces the feel- ing of the Ludicrous (ludere, to play) in its different forms of Wit and Humor. There is no sharp distinction between Wit and Humor. Wit is a sudden flash out of the electric atmosphere called Humor. Humor lingers, — pro- duces a more gentle and prolonged stimulation; Wit suddenly overthrows the mental balance with a shock of pleasant surprise. Besides, Humor has a mingling of sympathy and good nature, — has heart in it; while Wit arises chiefly from intellectual surprises. But in whatever form appearing, they arise from contrasts of mental states produced by the imagination in playful exercise on the literal relations of thought. Wit and Humor are effective means of impressing thought, and may be classed under the head of figura- tive energy. They are also productive of pleasure for its own sake and have an esthetic value. Irving;, Addi- son, and Mark Twain are read for the Wit and Humor THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 329 contained. Yet Wit and Humor are appreciated most when in the service of some thought or lesson to be impressed. The speaker or the writer who proposes to be witty for the sake of the wit produces far less pleasure than he who, by means of Wit, clinches a truth or points a moral. Like Irony, Wit and Humor have been powerful weapons in the battles of truth and virtue; and should, therefore, be classed as means of securing Energy. EXERCISE IN CLASSIFYING AND TESTING FIGURES. In the following selections require the student (i) to point out the figures; (2) to state the kind as to nature, and explain its structure; (3) the kind as to effect over literal language : — 1 . " Style is the gossamer upon which seeds of truth float through the world." 2. " Youth is the morning of life." 3. " The fat earth feed thy branchy root." 4. " My days are swifter than the weaver's shuttle." 5. " Her eyelids dropped their silken eaves." 6. " Vice is a monster of so frightful mien, As to be hated needs but to be seen." 7. " But when loud surges lash the shore, The hoarse rough verse should like the torrent roar." 8. " Soft is the strain when zephyr gently blows, And the smooth stream in smoother numbers flows." 9. " Up the high hill he heaved a huge round stone." 10. "The bishop of Alexandria was not the first triumvir who came to an untimely end on the banks of the Nile." 11. "I have not the warmest feeling of affection for that person." 330 THE SCIEKXE OF DISCOURSE. 12. "And there are also many other things which Jesus did, the which if they should be written every one, I suppose that even the world itself could not contain the books that should be written." 13. " Who can number the stars or who can count the sands on the seashore ? " 14. " Hail, hidden to the knees in fern, Broad oak of Summer chace." 15. "A sunbeam flutter'd round her lip Like a golden butterfly." 16. " Who steals my purse, steals trash." 17. "Short lived, indeed, was Irish independence. I sat by her cradle; I followed her hearse." 18. " It is an outrage to bind a Roman citizen; to scourge him is an atrocious crime; to put him to death is almost parricide; but to crucify him — what shall I call it? " 19. "I can tell him, sir, that Massachusetts and her people of all classes, hold him and his love, and his venerations, and his speech, and his principles, and his standards of truth in utter — what shall I say ? — anything but respect." 20. "Can I call you citizens ? Citizens! who have trampled under foot the authority of the Senate? " 21. "I know the circumstances under which it happened — circumstances which could not be avoided." 22. " I am the good shepherd and know my sheep." 23. " The pyramids, doting with age, have forgotten the names of their founders." 24. " The Lord is my song. He is become my salvation." 25. " The scepter shall not depart from Judah." 26. " Caesar leaves Gaul, crosses the Rubicon, and enters Italy." 27. " Death is swallowed up in victory. O death, where is thy sting? O grave, where is thy victory?" 28. " Though grave, yet trifling, zealous, yet untrue." 29. " Her voice is but the shadow of a sound." 30. " Fair science frowned not on his humble birth, And melancholy marked him for her own." THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 331 31. " Elijah said, cry aloud for he is a god." 32. "There went out a decree from Caesar Augustus that all the world should be taxed." 33. " Gray hairs should be respected." 34. " He set up parliament by the stroke of his pen, and scat- tered them by the breath of his mouth." 35. "At length has come the marriage day of beauty and of strength." 36. " Some mute inglorious Milton here may rest ; Some Cromwell, guiltless of his country's blood." 37. " The English gain two hours a day by clipping their words." 38. " Now Ben he loved a pretty maid, Her name was Nelly Gray; So he went to pay her his devours When he'd devoured his pay." 39. "I '11 tell you a story that 's not in Tom Moore: — Young love likes to knock at a pretty girl's door." 40. " His heart kept goin' pity-pat, But her'n went pity Zekle." 41. " Could we forget the widow'd hour, And look on Spirits breathed away, As on a maiden in the day When first she wears his orange flower ! " When crown'd with blessing she doth rise To take her latest leave of home, And hope and light regrets that come Make April of her tender eyes." 42. " Life is not of idle ore, But iron dug from central gloom, And heated hot with burning fears, And dipped in baths of hissing tears, And batter'd with the shocks of doom " To shape and use. Arise and fly The reeling Faun, the sensual feast ; 332 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. Move upward working out the beast, And let the ape and tiger die." 43. " The poet, like a delighted boy, brings you heaps of rain- bow bubbles, opaline, air-borne, spherical as the world, instead of a few drops of soap and water." 44. " An idea steeped in verse becomes suddenly more incisive and more brilliant; the iron becomes steel." 45. "Good-by to Flattery's fawning face; To Grandeur with his wise grimace; To upstart Wealth's averted eye; To supple office, low and high." 46. " Language is fossil poetry. As the limestone of the con- tinent consists of infinite masses of the shells of animalcules, so language is made up of images, or tropes, which now, in their secondary use, have long since ceased to remind us of their poetic origin." 47. " Nature is sanative, refining, elevating. How cunningly she hides every wrinkle of her inconceivable antiquity under roses, and violets, and morning dew! Every inch of the mountain is scarred by unimaginable convulsions, yet the new day is purpled with the bloom of youth and love." 48. " I hear the tread of pioneers Of nations yet to be, The first low wash of waves, where soon Shall roll a human sea. " The rudiments of empire here Are plastic yet and warm; The chaos of a mighty world Is rounding into form." 49. •• We have rolled on life's journey, — how fast and how far! One round of humanity's many-wheeled car, But up-hill and down-hill, through rattle and rub, Old true Twenty-niners! we 've stuck to our hub! THE LANGUAGE IN DISCOURSE. 333 " While a brain lives to think or a bosom to feel, We will cling to it still like the spokes of a wheel ! And age, as it chills us, shall fasten the tire That youth fitted round in his circle of fire." 50. " This many-diapasoned maze, Through which the breath of being strays, Whose music makes our earth divine, Has work for mortal hands like mine. My duty lies before me. Lo, The lever there! take hold and blow! And He whose hand is on the keys Will play the tune as He shall please." 51. " And if I should live to be The last leaf upon the tree In the spring, Let them smile as I do now, At the old forsaken bough Where I cling." 52. " The snow had begun in the gloaming, And busily all the night Had been heaping field and highway With a silence deep and white. " Every pine and fir and hemlock Wore ermine too dear for an earl, And the poorest twig on the elm tree Was ridged inch deep with pearl. " I thought of a mound in sweet Auburn Where a little headstone stood; How the flakes were folding it gently, As the robins the babes in the wood. " Up spoke our own little Mabel, Saying, ' Father, who makes it snow ? ' And I told her of the good All-Father Who cares for us here below. 334 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. " Again I looked at the snowfall, And thought of the leaden sky That arched o'er our first great sorrow, When the mound was heaped so high. " I remembered the gradual patience That fell from that cloud like snow, Flake by flake, healing and hiding The scar of our deep-plunged woe." 53. " The Puritan revolt had made us ecclesiastically, and the Revolution politically, independent, but we were still socially and intellectually moored to English thought, till Emerson cut the cable and gave us a chance at the dangers and the glories of blue water. No man young enough to have felt it can forget or cease to be grateful for the mental and moral nudge which he received from the writings of his high-minded and brave-spirited countryman." 54. " We have said that the Transcendental Movement was the Protestant spirit of Puritanism seeking a new outlet and an escape from forms and creeds which compressed rather than expressed it." 56. " Ah! if our souls but poise and swing Like the compass in its brazen ring, Ever level and ever true To the toil and task we have to do, We shall sail securely and safely we reach The Fortunate Isles, on whose shining beach The sights we see and sounds we hear, Will be those of joy and not of fear." 57. " Your mind is tossing on the ocean; There where your argosies with portly sail, Like seigniors and rich burghers on the flood, Or, as it were, the pageants of the sea, Do overpeer the petty traffickers, That courtesy to them, do them reverence, As they fly by with their woven wings." 58. " He would be crown'd; How that might change his nature, there 's the question; It is the bright day that brings forth the adder." CONCLUSION. The first chapter dealt with the Organizing Princi- ple; and in that chapter, the unity of the whole was ascertained and the phases of it developed. These phases, Purpose, Thought, and Language, have been treated in relation to each other — as organic parts of discourse. A few statements in conclusion are neces- sary to bring the phases together in one view, and thus return our thought to the unity of the whole from which we started. Besides, this will point the applica- tion of the science of discourse to the student's use of construction and analysis. So far, the laws have been applied separately to each of the phases of discourse. The student, in his future course of composition and reading, should consciously apply the theory presented in the preceding pages. To this end, a brief summary and general outline are here given, together with one illustration of their application to a piece of discourse. Discourse was defined to be the expression of thought in language with a definite aim; or, the expression of thought in language for the purpose of communication. This gave unity to our theme and, at the same time, the basis for its subdivision into the phases, Purpose, Thought, and Language. Purpose was found to be the most fundamental idea; Thought and Language being organized as means about Purpose as an end. This gave rise to three kinds of discourse, having dif- 33^ THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ferent qualities of thought and language in adaptation to the three ends for which thought is communicated. The whole may be summarized in the following: — Universal Outline of Discourse. 1. Prose. — i. Purpose, to instruct, to present truth for its own sake; (i) to present individuals to the sensuous or picturing imagination ; (2) to present classes to the judgment; (3) to present universals to the reason — Popular, Scientific, and Philosophical Prose. 2. Thought, matter-of-fact truth presented for its own sake by the logical laws of thought, — individuals presented in their statical relations by Description, and in their dynamical relation by Narration; generals presented for their own sake by Exposition, and in their application, to test truth by Argumentation. 3. Expression, Clear, with Elegance and Energy subordinate. II. Poetry. — 1. Purpose, to please as an end — to touch the esthetic emotions — instruction a means. 2. Thought, idealized truth appealing to the intui- tions, and presented by means of Exposition through the subordinate process of Exemplification. 3. Expression, Elegant, with Clearness and Energy subordinate, — the ideal, universal truth presented to the mind through individual forms. III. Oratory. — 1. Purpose, to move the will to some definite action — instruction and esthetic pleas- ure being means. conclusion. 337 2. Thought, the entire range presented by all the discourse processes; yet such thought as bears a defi- nite relation to the action proposed. 3. Expression, Energetic, with Clearness and Ele- gance as means. Transforming the above for the more immediate appli- cation in construction and analysis gives the following : — Universal Outline for Practice. 1. Purpose. — 1. What? — to instruct, to please, or to move the will? 2. To what grade of either is the discourse adapted ? II. Theme. — 1. By what theme is the purpose accomplished, or to be accomplished? 2. What kind of theme — individual or general? If individual, by what process presented, Description or Narration? If general, by Exposition or Argumen- tation ? If Exposition, whether matter-of-fact or ideal truth ? 3. Analysis of the particular process employed into the thought relations as they are organized in the presentation of the theme, and their presentation tested by all the laws of the process — Purpose, Unity, Selection, Method, and Completeness. III. Style. — 1. From the purpose, should the style be Clear, Elegant, or Energetic? 2. How is the particular quality desired secured? If the quality desired is Clearness, test by applying the laws of Clearness; if Elegance, by applying laws of Elegance ; if Energy, by applying laws of Energy. 338 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. From this point the student is ready to proceed con- sciously and systematically with his general practice of reading and writing — of interpreting and composing discourse. One phase of this will develop into and continue as a special and formal study, called the study of Literature. It is hoped that the foregoing exposition of discourse will form the basis of scientific literary analysis. In conclusion, to point the way in that direction, and to further impress the general application of the doctrine of discourse to practice, a brief outline analysis of a short literary selection will now be given. Analysis of "The Rainy Day." The day is cold, and dark, and dreary; It rains, and the wind is never weary; The vine still clings to the mouldering wall, But at every gust the dead leaves fall, And the day is dark and dreary. My life is cold, and dark, and dreary; It rains, and the wind is never weary; My thoughts still cling to the mouldering Past, But the hopes of youth fall thick in the blast, And the days are dark and dreary. Be still, sad heart ! and cease repining; Behind the clouds is the sun still shining; Thy fate is the common fate of all, Into each life some rain must fall, Some days must be dark and dreary. The purpose of the poem is to touch the emotions. This our experience testifies to in reading it. It gives CONCLUSION. 3 ^ g no instruction; neither does it stimulate to any definite volition and action. The emotion does not prompt -to action, but is entertained and enjoyed by the reader for the sake of the emotion itself. In reading the poem the feelings absorb the attention to the exclusion of both intellectual and volitional consciousness. Hence, this selection is a poem, or piece of literature. But the effect is more definite than that of arousing emotion in general; to be a poem it must arouse some particular emotion. At the outset there is awakened, through the image of the rainy day, the vague feeling of depression. This is the setting for the more definite feeling of sadness, which is overcome by the hope and cheer of life. The definite effect of the poem thus appears to be the rally of life over the trials and tribu- lations of life; it is a spiritual uprising under the dead- ening weight of grief and melancholy, — the reclaiming of oneself when hope and life seem lost; an idealized resolution to hold on to life in spite of all reverses and undercurrents which tend to forestall the good and promise of life. In this ideal rally of life this selection fills another re- quirement of literature; namely, in that it must appeal to the universal interests of life. It is the law of life that the soul rise upon the dead self to higher things. This rally of life above depressing influences is one of the ever-present phases of human life; hence, every soul is touched by the theme of this poem. It would be interesting to note how many of Longfellow's poems have the same theme. To such an extent is this true that Longfellow is called the poet of consolation. This 340 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. arose from the fact that he was painfully sensitive to such visitations of sorrow, and equally sensitive to the bright and cheerful influence of life. He could well exclaim with Byron: " Man thou pendulum between a smile and a tear." All literature seeks to relieve the soul from some form of bondage, and each selection of literature, as in the present case, seeks to bring relief from some defi- nite limiting condition in which man finds his spiritual nature. In this selection the soul finds itself limited by sadness or grief, and it must overcome its sadness or its sadness will overcome it. It is the typical battle of life — the battle for life. The soul must either strive to persist and hold its own or to make distinct advances in self-realization. All literary themes fall under one or the other of these two forms of striving; the " Rainy Day " is a type of one, " Excelsior " of the other. The theme in this poem is, therefore, emotionally and universally entertained, as required by all true liter- ary selections. But literature deals with the ideal in human life rather than the real. In the present case the victory over the tribulations of life is more complete and decisive than is experienced in the regular order of our lives. That is, the sadness and the cheer are farther apart ; the sadness is more intense and the cheer ideally complete. At first Longfellow would have us feel that there is nothing in life but coldness, darkness, and dreariness; would produce in us an ideal condition of sadness, in order to produce an ideal vic- tory over it. The poem consists in this tension of the CONCLUSION. 34I opposite conditions of life. The amplitude and inten- sity of the vibrating chord measure the poem. If a poem on the same theme could be written to produce a greater amplitude and intensity in the vibrating chord it would be a better poem. This would not be a poem were not the experience of the soul more prolonged and intense than is experienced in the ordinary course of life. Because it is so the theme is an ideal rather than a real condition of life. The only further question to be considered is how the author produces the foregoing effect ; that is, what in his language, or style, gives the ideal effect desired. This is accomplished, chiefly, through figurative, or indirect, language. The primary conception is that of life in the form of a rainy day. The author assumes that life is a rainy day ; hence the poem is allegorical, and more effective than if the comparison were directly made. In all literature the theme is mirrored forth by a concrete object. This object has a point of identity and of difference with the life which it expresses. It is by means of this likeness and difference that the theme is expressed. If Longfellow had asserted instead of assuming he would have said that life is a rainy day. They differ in all obvious points, but there is a point in which a rainy day may be truly affirmed to be human life. In both there are two sides, an upper and a lower; a polarity, a tension, a warfare. The rainy day and life are identical in the point of self- opposition and striving. But every literary embodiment must have not only some essential point of identity to human life, but must 342 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. have some essential point of difference. In this case the difference lies in the fact of the perfect and permanent victory of the sunshine over the rainfall. The polarity between the opposing forces in the rainy day is more definite and stronger than that usually found in life; and the triumph of one over the other is more signal than in the other. The day really accomplishes what the soul is striving to accomplish. What is ideal in life is real in the day. This is the exact point of difference between the soul and the day, and when the soul looks into the day and finds that it has really attained the freedom which it is striving to attain it rejoices in its own ideal freedom. Just this is the esthetic freedom which constitutes the essence of the poem. The soul looks into the day and finds its ideal self-realized, finds the freedom from the bondage of its real. This sense of freedom is the specific feeling which the poem is to awaken. Thus the rainy day, through its identity with and difference from life, makes effective the tension which the poem seeks to produce. The creative act of the poet was in discerning ideal life mirrored in the real day; that the rainy day, in overcoming its own rain, coldness, darkness, and dreariness, is a type of the ideal overcoming of the trials and tribulations of life. The elements of this complex primary conception are brought out in secondary figures to increase the effect - the tension. These leading minor figures are as follows: — " My life is cold and dark and dreary." The poet would have us feci that life and the day are identical in conclusion. 343 being cold and dark and dreary. These are death in one case as in the other- identical in effect. This perception sinks life lower, and thus heightens the effect. The identity is affirmed; hence, the figure is a metaphor and is more effective than a simile would have been, since it would have given only resemblance. " It rains and the wind is never weary." This is an indirect statement, for the author would have us hold back of the image the idea that as the rain and the wind never cease making the day dreary, so the adver- sities of life continue filling it with gloom and sadness. Conceiving life in this palpable form serves again to intensify the effect. Besides, the form of statement being allegorical — the minor term only given — increases the effect over the more explicit form of comparison. Of course there is more risk in the mean- ing not being discerned, for many in reading this state- ment have only the concrete image without the idea symbolized. "My thoughts still cling to the mouldering past." He conceives that thoughts cling to the past as the vine clings to the wall: vine — thought; wall — past. Here a vine is assumed to be identical with a thought, while to all appearances there are nothing but striking differences. They differ in form, size, color, parts, etc., but are identical in the point of clinging. Clinging is clinging, wherever and in whatever it be found. A vine still clinging after it is stripped of its life and ver- dure is a fit, an effective, symbol for the tendency of thoughts to turn to the past after the bitter experiences of life have saddened and deadened them. The mould- 344 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. ering wall is a fit symbol of the decay and dissolution of our mental structures as they are disintegrated by the frosts of bitter experiences. This concrete concep- tion of thoughts and life further sinks life in sadness and heightens the tension which the poem is striving to secure. The figure here used is a metaphor, but it differs from the other in that the identity is implied, and is thus a still stronger statement. "But the hopes of youth fall thick in the blast." Here with all their striking differences hopes are con- ceived as identical with leaves, and they are so since falling equals falling. To conceive hopes as passing away in the concrete form of leaves falling in the blasts of wind and rain still further intensifies the sadness and makes stronger the tension. This figure is a meta- phor, as in the foregoing, and is effective because of its quick grasping of identity between hopes and leaves falling in blasts. Let it be observed that in all these minor figures there is an increase in the feeling of sadness; that they are used for that purpose, and not for the sake of the figure. It is not sufficient merely to classify a figure, but it must be explained in terms of the effect of the whole selection. While the foregoing figures sink life lower and thus increase the tension, those which follow exalt life and increase the tension through opposition to the former. "Be still, sad heart ! ' Emotions personified. Also faded metaphor in "heart." This is the self-assertion against the downward tendencies of life. The personifi- cation is secondary to the imperative command. conclusion. 345 " Behind the cloud is the sun still shining." As the sun is always shining beyond the clouds so there may be permanent cheer even in the present life of sadness. This is the figure which really brings the victory. The complete victory of the day is the assurance of the pos- sibility of the complete victory in life. Here again we have an allegory, the minor term, or the image, only being given, while the major term and the comparison are implied. How much this form of statement con- tributes to the effect will appear by changing it to some other figure. " Into each life some rain must fall; some days must be dark and dreary." In this conception life and the day are identical in that both have, by their nature, the conflict within themselves; that the law of the day and of life are the same. Each must have its lower turmoil; and since this is the essential nature of each, we should not wish to be rid of the darkness and dreari- ness of either. To do so would be to destroy both life and the clay. Life is in and through tension, and every tension must have the terms between which it exists. Here the identity is implied and the major term given; hence, a metaphor. It is well to note here how complete is the concrete embodiment; the day as a whole typifying life, and then the elements of the day typifying the phases of life. This not only gives richness and variety to the concep- tion, but also organic unity. It would be difficult to find a poem more pervaded with figurative conception, and at the same time having the figures so interwoven and organized into one spiritual type. This adds to the 346 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. beauty of simple figures that of organic beauty — variety in unity. In the first line of the first and second stanzas the polysyndeton is employed with good effect. The repetition of " ands " emphasizes the accumulation of the adversities of life. Let these lines be read omitting the first "and," and then again substi- tuting it, and the emotional value of this figure will clearly appear. While the chief literary value of the poem is in its figurative language, still much depends on the sensuous qualities of the language — its euphony and its rhythm. The mere sound of the first line in the first and second stanzas awakens a vague feeling of sadness. This is especially marked in the sound o. This wailing sound is much used to intensify grief and melancholy. Especially is the rhythm of the poem an efficient means of intensifying the feeling. Intense emotion is rhythmical, and rhythmical language is the natural lan- guage of emotion, and serves, therefore, to heighten emotion. The tension in this poem is made slightly stronger through the alliterations dark, dreary, wind, weary; and especially since these are repeated in each stanza. The rhymes have a similar effect. The rhymes are perfect and successive, the fifth rhyming with the first and second, except in the last stanza. Thus there is effective variety. The most important fact in the rhythm is the meas- ure of the verses. This is iambic tetrameter, with an occasional anapaestic foot substituted to give variety and a quicker movement when needed. Variety is conclusion. 347 further secured by giving an extra syllable at the end of the first two lines of each stanza. Especially effective is the rhythm made by repeating in a fifth verse in each of the three stanzas the meaning of the first verse in the first and second stanzas. These fifth verses repeat the meaning already given, and are there only for rhythmical fullness. This is character- istic of Hebrew poetry; the last half of a line in the Psalms repeats the meaning of the first half. This ele- ment of rhythm is characteristic of both Tennyson and Longfellow. The thought becomes so highly emotional that it tends to recur in rhythmical repetition. By reading the poem omitting the last line of each stanza, the value of these lines will become apparent. And, further, the stanzas bear an organic and rhyth- mical relation to each other which enhances the beauty of the poem. The whole poem thus appears as a complex, organic, rhythmical unit. Finally, the poem is made still more concrete and effective by having the personal embodiment of the author himself — by being lyrical. The universal objec- tive is made real and vivid in being regarded as indi- vidual and subjective. Longfellow says " my life," but no one supposes he means merely his own life ; the reader, whoever he may be, must say " my life." Thus the reader makes it a close personal matter with himself. It thus appears that the analysis of this poem consists in organizing the means by which the specific emotional effect is produced. Were it a didactic selection, then all must be shown to have unity in some cognition; 348 THE SCIENCE OF DISCOURSE. and were it an oration, everything must be shown in its tendency to move the will. For a full exposition of the nature of literature and method of literary analysis, see the author's " Literary Interpretations." INDEX Activity, 55. Aesop, 119. Aim, a definite, 16 ; a worthy, 19; intense, 28. Allegory, 318. Alliteration, 217. Amphibrach, 213. Analogy, 143. Analysis, 53. Anapaestic foot, 213. Angelus, 1 1. Antithesis, 323. Aphaeresis, 290. Apocope, 290. Apostrophe, 317. Argumentation, 59, 137 ; general laws of, 160; exercises in, 168. Arguments, a priori, 148 ; a pos- teriori, 1 52 ; by signs and re- semblances, 1 53 ; by testimony, 157; by authority, 160. Arrangement of the sentence, the proper, 255. Art of literary criticism, 22. Aspects, two, 57. . Association, figures of, 299. Asyndeton, 292. Attributes of the theme, 49 ; of relation, 62. Attributive description, 62. Author, 19. Authority, argument by, 160. Barbarism, 223. Bascom, 192, 193. Bathos, 325. Biography, 73. Blair, 209. Boundary of subject-matter, 1. Brevity, 200. Byron, 206, 324. Carlyle, 181. Cause and effect, 62 ; the relation of, 65, 97 ; in argumentation, 146. Change as a whole, the, 96; in its parts, 98. Chaucer, 31, 66, 181. Cicero, 21. Circumlocution, 244. Class unit, 56. Classification, 38. Classify, 35. Clearness, 174, 177; conditions for securing, 185. Climax, 324. Combination, 291. Comparison and contrast, 117. Composer, 33 ; chooses a theme, 46. Composition, art of, 44. Concept, 56, 58. Conciseness, 241. Conclusion, 335. 350 INDEX. Concreteness, 230. Construction of description, 81 ; of narration, 103 ; of exposition, 128. Content of the class, 112; of the theme, 1 13. Correctness, 5, 199. Critic, 23. Criticism, standard of, 28; liter- ary, 38. Culture, all-sided, 21, 24. Dactylic foot, 213. Deduction, 139. Definition, 113; law of, 114; rule for making, 116. Description, 55, 59, 61 ; attribu- tive, 62; partitive, 75; outline of, 80; illustrations of, 81; ex- ercises in, 89. Didactic discourse, 34. Difference, no unity without, 48 likeness and, 62. Discourse, 6, 8 ; definition of, 12 purpose in, 13 ; skill in, 21 ; lit erary, 34; the thought in, 41 four processes in, 59. Distinctness, 199; of conception, 263. Effective speech, 46. Effectiveness, 18; conditions of, iq ; laws of, 178. Efficient means, 13. Elegance, 174, 182; conditions for securing, 194. Elements, the organic, 8 ; order of, 9; organic relation of, 10; unities of, 53; organization of, into theme, 241 ; the proper order of presenting, 255. Ellipsis, 291. Elocutionist, the true, 30. Emphatic ideas, 270. Enallage, 295. End, a worthy, 13. Energy, 174, 179 ; conditions for securing, 191. Enthymeme, 141. Epanalepsis, 293. Epenthesis, 291. Epigram, 325. Epizeuxis, 294. Euphemism, 302. Euphony, 202. Exemplification, 118. Exercises in description, 89-92 ; in narration, 109, no; in expo- sition, 134; in argumentation, 168 ; in synonyms, 239; in par- onyms, 239 ; in poetic form, 219; in verbosity, 245; in sen- tence unity, 265 ; in classifying figures, 329-334. Exposition, 59, 1 1 1 ; outline of, 1 28; illustrations of, 128. Extension, 70. Extent of a class, 112; of the theme, 123. Factor, controlling, 33 ; invariable, 34- Factors, two, 60. Fallacy, 150. Familiarity, 222. Figures of speech, 289 ; spelling, 290 ; syntax, 291 ; thought, 295; association, 299; comparison, 304 ; expressed comparison, 307 ; implied comparison, 309 ; contrast, 323. INDEX. 351 Foot, 212. Form and content of language, 172. Form and size, 71. Fundamental ends of discourse, 38, 59- General, the, 58. General notion, 1 12. Gilmore, "Outlines of Rhetoric," 293- Graduating theme, 32. Greece, history of, 41. Guidance, 54. Habit of reading, 45. Harmony, 207; in discourse, 211. Hawthorne, 1 19. Henry, Patrick, 29. High-school pupil, 32. Hill, A. S., 165, 225, 251, 310. Hill, D. J., 244, 253, 264. Humor, 328. Hyperbole, 318. Iambic foot, 213. Idea, origin in, 55. Idealization, 120. Ideas, association of language forms with, 222. Illustrated, the process of descrip- tion, 81 ; narration, 103; expo- sition, 128. Independence, Declaration of, 44. Individual, 54, 58. Induction, 141 ; lowest phase of, 144 ; highest phase of, 145. Inference, 140. Interpret with efficiency, 45. Interpretation of description, 86; narration, 106; exposition, 132. Interpreter, 19. Interrogation, 326. Irony, 327. Irving, 37, 66, 101. Judgment, 58, 137. Language units, 2; in discourse, 171 ; fundamental law of, 173; qualities required, 174 ; inter- pretation of, 197 ; an object of perception, 198; literal, 284; figurative, 285. Law of unity in definition, 116; comparison and contrast, 117. Laws of partition, 77-79. Likeness and difference, 62-68; order of presenting, 69, 97. Location of an object, 67. " Logic," Mill's, 146. Longfellow, 288. Lowell, 42, 181, 244. Macbeth, 290, 312. Maclaren, Ian, 73. " Maud Muller," 132. Means, 62. Mental state, presenting a, 66. Metaphor, 309; exercises in, 313. Metonymy, 302. Milton, 21, 294. Motive, genuine, 30. Movements of thought, 53. Narration, 55-59, 93 ; compared with description, 93 ; first step in, 96 ; second step in, 98; out- line of, 102; illustrations of law of unity in, 100; exercises in, 109. 352 INDEX. ( )bject, a spiritual, 72. Objects, individual, 59, 63. Obsolete words, 223. Omission of words, 276. Oration, basis of, 35, 36. Oratory, 34, 35. Organic elements, the, 8. Organization of the elements into the theme, 241. Organizing principle, the, I, 12. Parable, 322. Paragraph, 282. Paragoge, 291. Paronomasia, 326. Paronyms, 239. Particular, 1 13. Partition, law of, 77. Partitive description, 75. Parts coexist, the, 54. Personification, description by, 65, 3 r 4- Perspicuity, 174. Phelps, 27, 193, 287. Phillips, Wendell, 29. Place, time and, 62. Pleonasm, 229. Poetry, 34, 36. Polysyndeton, 294. Pope, 31. Position of words in sentence, 267. Precision, 234. Process of description, 61 ; par- tition, 77; narration, 93; expo- sition, in; definition, 113; com- parison and contrast, 117; ex- emplification, 118; idealization, F2o; division, 124; argumenta- tion, 137. Processes, discourse, 53, 59. Prolixity, 248. Properties, 70. Prose, 34. Prosthesis, 291. Pun, 326. Purity, 223. Purpose in discourse, 1 3 ; to the reader, 1 5 ; attributes of, 63, 96. Qualities, primary, secondary, 70, 71; of language, 174; the rhe- torical, secured, 196. Quintilian, 20-22. Rainbow, the, 42. Reasoning by deduction, 140. Redundancy, 243. Relation, attributes of, 62-68 ; of language to thought, the direct, 221 ; the indirect, 284. Relative words, 274. Resistance, 70. Rhyme, 216. Rhythm, 211 ; exercises in, 219. Rhythmical flow, 52. Secondary attributes, 74. Sentence, proper length of the, 249.. Sentences, periodic, loose, 257. Shakespeare, 17, 31. Simile, 307. Simpson, Bishop, 29. Spencer, Herbert, 238, 258. Stanza, 217. Style, affectation of, 26, 173. Subject-matter, boundary of, 2 ; arrangement of, 51. Syllogism, 139. Syncope, 290. INDEX. 353 Synecdoche, 300. Synonyms, 239. Synthesis, 53. Tautology, 243. Testimony, argument by, 157. Theme, the, 41-49 ; in description, 62 ; in narration, 94 ; in exposi- tion, hi. Thought in discourse, the, 41. Time and place, 62, 96. Triangle, 55. Trochaic foot, 213. Two objects, 63. Unit, organic, class, 56. Units, language, 2. Unity, 43 ; in discourse, 46 ; class, 57; law of, in narration, 100- 105; maintained, 108 ; law of, in definition, 116; in compari- son and contrast, 118; in divi- sion, 125; in argumentation, 138, 163; of sentence structure, 262 ; of discourse structure, 278. Universal, 113. Value of a witness, 1 59. Verbosity, 242 ; exercises in, 245. Verse, 215. Vision, 317. "Vision of Sir Launfal," 44. Whittier, 37, 324, 327. Whole, simultaneous, successive, 55 ; changes as, 96. Wholes, parts bounded into, 57. Wit, 327. Witnesses, difference in, 158, 159. UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY Los Angeles This book is DUE on the last date stamped below. hmri MAY 2 3 1966 ' V'' w :_ t ; 138 J J$ECft« MAR 2 9 1984 J 'orm L9— Series 444 3 :iT§ iiii Si UC SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY AA 000 352 175 4