VlAY 15 ^'f 
 
 ROSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION 
 
 TO 
 
 ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 BY 
 
 JOHN 1 AVATA BRUNO, Pu D. 
 
 Suhmittt^a ill partial ftilfllment of the re«|aireinent» for the decree of Doctor of 
 1*lill«i*ophy In lh« Faculty of Philosophy, Columbia University 
 
 ARCHIVES OF PHIJL080PHY 
 
 BDITKD BT 
 
 KPEDKRICK J. E. WOODBHIDGK 
 
 No. 6, FEBRUAKY, 1916 
 
 NEW YOBK 
 
 THE SCIENCE PRESS 
 
 lettt 
 
 fi.'iR5;r::r:: 
 
ROSMIXI-S CONTRIBUTION 
 
 TO 
 
 ETIIICxVL PniLOSOPTlY 
 
 BY 
 
 JOHN FAY ATA BRUNO, PuT). 
 
 V 
 
 Submitted In partial fuUilmeut of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of 
 Philosophy In the Faculty of Philosophy, Columbia miverslty 
 
 ARCHIVES OF PHILOSOPHY 
 
 EDITED Br 
 
 FPEDERICK J. K. WOODBBIDGK 
 
 No. 0, February, 191G 
 
 NEW YORK 
 THE SCIENCE PRESS 
 
 1910 
 
^8B7 
 
 Press of 
 
 THE New Era Printing Cohpany 
 
 Lancaster, pa. 
 
V 
 
 K^ 
 
 OUTLINE 
 
 PA<n 
 
 Introduction 1 
 
 Part I. The Factors of Kosmini 's Philosophy 3 
 
 Chapter I. Historical Situation of Rosmini 's Italy 3 
 
 1. Social and Political Conditions 3 
 
 2. Intellectual Conditions 7 
 
 Chapter II. Eosmini 's Personality 17 
 
 1. Rosmini 's Psychological Dispositions 17 
 
 2. Rosmini 's Leading Motive, Attitude, and Method 20 
 
 3. The Fundamental Principle of Rosmini 's Philosophy 23 
 
 Part II. The Essential Features of Rosmini 's Ethical Theory 25 
 
 Introductory. The Scope and Method of Ethics 25 
 
 Chapter I. The Metaphysical Factor of Morality 28 
 
 Chapter II. The Psychological Factor of Morality 36 
 
 Conclusion • 45 
 
 • • • 
 
 111 
 

 ROSMINrS 
 CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 INTRODUCTION 
 
 The philosopher's life evolves in space and time, in a certain en- 
 vironment anil at a certain historical period, the influence of which 
 he can not fail to undergo. And, indeed, through his education and 
 his surroundings, his native qiudities are stimidatetl and uioditicd, 
 his mind is molded to certain habits of thinking, feeling, and acting. 
 He feels impelled to share the aim and disposition of his time and 
 race. And thus every phase of his thought and behavior is but a 
 concrete, effective response to those specific needs, to those human 
 problems which, being closely connected with social life, focus the 
 attention of all. We can not, accordingly, consider his doctrine as 
 an arbitrary, autonomous construction of ideas; we can not imagine 
 it to be born spontaneously or by chance. The philosopher, anxious 
 to bring his own contribution to social order, organizes a mode of re- 
 flective thinking ([uite personal. His philosophy, as every organized 
 thought, inspired and controlled by a practical motive, is but his 
 characteristic mode of adjustment to the current state of culture, to 
 the prevailing Zeitgeist, and to tlKit peculiar situation in which he 
 happens to be. It embodies his concrete thinking, his lofty aspira- 
 tions, and his endeavors to be useful to social organization. Thus 
 we can not doubt that his point of view, his method, his mental atti- 
 tude, all his psychological situation and activity are determined and 
 conditioned by his own genius, notions, habits, and motives, as well 
 as by contemporary social conditions. His philosophical elaborations 
 may be regarded rather as a human and historical document. For 
 they mirror the experiences and strivings, the wishes and hopes, the 
 whole intimate drama of his life. They display the tints which he, 
 as an artist, imparts to his assumption, combination, and solution of 
 philosophical problems which always appear anew to each age and 
 to each individual. And while they happen to be the genuine and 
 abiding expression of his personality, they manifest the status of 
 vital questions towards which the general interest converges, and the 
 social demands that haunt minds at the time in which the philosopher 
 lives. 
 
 "VVe may, accordingly, explain why a philosophical sj'.stem has a 
 momentous significance, and even a powerful influence on the direc- 
 
 1 
 
*2'' ^ :sd^?I-HXI'S CONTEIBUTION TO ETHICAL P HI LO SOPHY 
 
 tion of coutemporary minds; and yet its justification passes away 
 with its historical conditions. Experience, and consequently philos- 
 ophy, which is the emotional and intellectual attitude of an individual 
 towards the urgent problems of life, follows social changes. Thus, 
 a philosophical doctrine may be a useful instrument of social adjust- 
 ment at a certain age, owing to social conditions which evoke it, and 
 it may, however, lose all its value at another age, because of new 
 social emergencies which call out new purposes and new habitual 
 modes of confronting problems, and then new reflective thinking. 
 
 Thus, if we want to know the meaning, character, and value of 
 a philosophical system, we must replace it in its historical frame, 
 in its natural background. We must regard it as the mental atti- 
 tude which the philosopher assumed towards the problems which 
 were in the air when he lived. Only thus can we retrace the genesis 
 of his ideas, his fundamental thought, and the leading motive of 
 his intellectual efforts. Only then may we have the surest basis 
 for understanding and appreciating his doctrine. To regard it as 
 something merely abstract and isolated from human conditions, as 
 independent of its author 's universe of life and love, aloof from his 
 reality and experience, or divorced from, and unrelated to the de- 
 mands and interests of his social milieu, would lead to inevitable 
 failure. 
 
 To valuate Eosmini's contribution to ethical philosophy it is 
 necessary to trace first the historical tableau of the times in which 
 he happened to live. A mere outline of the salient features of the 
 political, social, and intellectual conditions of Italy while Kosmini 
 was alive will answer our purpose. 
 
 In addition, it is of great importance to portray his personality, 
 namely, his psychological dispositions, the motive which controlled 
 his mental activity, his philosophical method, and the attitude he 
 assumed towards the problems Italy confronted at that very time. 
 After stating the historical and psychological factors of Eosmini's 
 philosophy, I deem it important to give, as an introductory basis 
 of his ethical teaching, a short survey of the fundamental principle 
 of his philosophy, for he was convinced that ethics is dependent upon 
 metaphysics. 
 
 The introductory study of the first part will present Eosmini's 
 philosophical endeavors in the historical light, and will enable us to 
 understand and appreciate the essential features of his ethical theory, 
 which will form the core of the investigation and the subject-matter 
 of the second part of the present study. Finally, after stating what 
 the Italian philosopher contributed to the manifold stock of ethical 
 theories, our interest will center upon the affinity that Eosmini's 
 ethical principles seem to have with those of precedent philosophers. 
 
PART I 
 
 THE FACTORS OF ROSMINI'S PHILOSOPHY 
 
 CHAPTER I 
 lIiSTOiiicAL Situation of Rosmini's Italy 
 
 1. SocicU and Political Conditions 
 
 The period of Rosmini's life was characterized by political and 
 social disturbance.^ 
 
 Italy was kept in slavery by foreign rulers. Unexpected events, 
 however, {rradually concurred, from the second half of the eighteenth 
 century forward, to awake her dormant will. The invigorating 
 breath of political liberty which came from England, as well as the 
 French humanitarian ideas which were spread all over Europe, 
 stimulated some leaders of absolute government to give Italy the first 
 impulse to a peaceful social and economic evolution. Thus, the 
 French Revolution, which broke out contemporaneously with this 
 movement, .seemed there, at its beginning, to be a violent and dis- 
 turbing phenomenon. The republican armies crossed the Alps, ap- 
 
 1 Antonio Rosmini-Scrbati (1797-1855) was horn at Rovereto, in the Italian 
 Tyrol, of noble and rich parents. He spent his bovhood and youth in an at- 
 mosphere of religion and study. In 1821 he entered the priesthood. He devoted 
 most of his life to philosophical investigations and to a religious society which 
 he foumled, having as purpose the promotion of corporeal, intellectual, and 
 spiritual works of Christian charity. In 1848 the philosopher Gioberti, at that 
 time minister of the king Charles Albert, trusted our philosopher with the 
 mission of inducing the Pope to be the chief of the desired Italian confedera- 
 tion. Rosmini undertook it as he was convinced that such a confederation could 
 be the salvation of Italy and of the Church. But the precipitation of political 
 events and the entourage of Pius IX prevented the accomplishment of Ros- 
 mini's diplomatic mission. 
 
 Indc irac! He began to be suspected of liberalism, which at that time in 
 Italy meant patriotism, and his philosophy liegan to be the ol)ject of persistent 
 persecutions. He, however, underwent them, like Socrates, with the grandeur of 
 mind of a genuine philosopher. Penally, he went, weary and disappointed, to 
 seek rest and oblivion in the charming solitude of Stresa, near the Lago M^ag- 
 giore. There the ^'lite of the learned men of Italy and Europe, as Cardinal New- 
 man, Cardinal Wiseman, Lacordaire, Manzoni, Bonghi, anil some others, met 
 together to comfort the good and afflicted heart of the great Italian philosopher. 
 
 3 
 
4 FiOSMINI'S CONTBIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPEY 
 
 parently induced by the desire to redeem Italy, but the outcome of 
 their invasion proved to be in open contradiction with the principles 
 of social and international justice, which were heralded by them with 
 the bold and steady conviction that they corresponded to the uni- 
 versal needs and demands of the civilized world. They did not bring, 
 indeed, any remedy to Italy and only sought material profit ; but 
 they proclaimed there new social ideas, which aimed at the radical 
 destruction of the whole edifice of the old regime, as well as at the 
 organization of a new life. 
 
 Their social gospel regarded all men as equal and free and all 
 nations as mistresses of their own destinies. Accordingly, each na- 
 tion was suggested to unite its parcelled parties and to form a single 
 and independent state. Such notions, promising universal revival, 
 did not fail to make wonderful and rapid strides all over Europe, 
 while they urged in Italy the development of analogus thoughts and 
 feelings, which were carefully disguised with literary forms. But 
 the new principles of uniform, civil organization which Napoleon I. 
 laid down, gave the Italians the most powerful impulse to their na- 
 tional solidarity. He abolished pernicious privileges all over the 
 peninsula. Establishing a strictly laical authority, he inhibited the 
 influence of clericalism or the religious-factionary control over public 
 education and intellectual life. He ended municipal jealousies, local 
 prejudices, and ancient crystallized traditions. Introducing a civil 
 and penal code, permeated with the spirit of the Roman Law and 
 of universal equality, he supplanted conflicting customs and juris- 
 dictions. By the equal and regular administration of justice, he 
 overthrew the confused and fixed forms of government, of the tenure 
 of land, and of the whole structure of the Italian society, which 
 was based upon feudalism. All those changes, as well as the system 
 of military recruiting, and the construction of new roads and bridges, 
 greatly contributed to unite the minds and hearts of all Italians. 
 Besides, the monuments which were erected to perpetuate the mem- 
 ory of the most glorious events and of the greatest men, and, above 
 all, the ambition of Napoleon to embody the greatness of the Roman 
 empire, as the Pope, the German emperor, the men of the Renais- 
 sance, and the glorious Italian republics had endeavored to do before 
 him, could not fail to display the beauty of the deliverance and unity 
 of Italy.2 
 
 But, after Napoleon's downfall, the whole peninsula and the 
 islands which crown it, were thrown again by the congress of Vienna 
 into the same abject condition in which they were before. They 
 were once more morcellated in small sovereign states, which were 
 
 2 See "Les Resurrections Italiennes," by H. Berenger, E. Pelletan, Ed., 
 Paris, 1911. 
 
niSTOEICAL SITUATION OF rOSMIXI'S ITALY 6 
 
 enthralled by the despotic control of Austria. Tradition and ab- 
 solutism were revived by the triumphant reaction. 
 
 Napoleon's rule was reg:arded as an illejral attempt ap:ainst order, 
 and all his activity as propagation of revolution. According^ly, 
 social order was thought again to be a natural emanation from abso- 
 lute government. Legislation began to be directed to check pro- 
 gressive tendencies and every form of revolutioiuiry aspirations. 
 Divine right began to bo opposed to natural right, legitimacy to popu- 
 lar sovereignty, the state to the individual, authority to liberty. 
 The clergy resumed its influence upon education, the censorship of 
 the press, and .some other offices which gave it control of intellectual 
 and moral life. But the Italy of 1815 was no more the Italy of the 
 ante-Napoleonic period. The "geographic expression" was no more 
 quiescent and inert ; on the contrary, it was permeated with a spirit 
 of rebellion and progress. The stream of new ideas which had been 
 brought into the oppressed country from the other nations, whose 
 barriere had been already overthrown by the French wars, could be 
 checked no more. The ferment within the stirred minds was power- 
 ful and pregnant with hopes of bright future. 
 
 The emancipation, the unity, and the greatness of Italy was 
 already the magnificent ideal which focused all the energies and the 
 heroic efforts of the best Italians; to it everything was devoted and 
 subordinated. 
 
 Austria, meanwhile, in her hatred, stopped at no outrage, at no 
 absurdity. She began to see conspiracy and revolution in ever>i:hing 
 and everywhere, and to suppress all feelings of patriotism and lib- 
 erty in the whole peninsula. Accordingly, men of elevated mind 
 were thrown into dungeons, or were wrenched out of their beloved 
 country and exiled. And they, guilty only of patriotic love, wan- 
 dered about over those countries, in which liberty was flourishing, 
 and spread the sad news of their national distress. But Metter- 
 nich's policy failed to extingui.sh the fire of rebellion which seemed 
 to be smothered beneath the peaceful aspect of the Italian penin- 
 sula, though it still raged, like the lava under the picturesque sides 
 of its volcanoes. Under the pressure of the persistent and brutal 
 reaction and of the .sad common experience, the vision of the na- 
 tional ideal became more distinct and suggestive than before. The 
 Italian people strained its powers and brought all its possibilities to 
 its richest unfolding. The oi)prossc(l minds seemed to be revived and 
 inspired by the spirit of the Renaissance, which conveyed the sug- 
 gestion that human personality is the source of all activities and 
 achievements. In every province of life there was a momentous 
 awakening. The life of the Italian race reached the moment of ex- 
 pcrimcntum crucis. Now the problem upon which the universal in- 
 
6 SOSMINI'S CONTEIBUTION TO ETHICAL FHIL0S0PE7 
 
 terest focused was not merely the emancipation and unity of Italy, 
 but the future of her culture and civilization, in harmony with the 
 spirit of her glorious traditions, which was threatened by her tyran- 
 nical rulers. So \dtal a problem evoked and concentrated all social 
 and intellectual forces. It was a moment of great unrest and of in- 
 tense elaboration of means and schemes. From the powerful fermen- 
 tation of ideas three main currents of thought emerged for the sal- 
 vation of the country. Men of different mental attitudes agreed 
 in the diagnosis of the unbearable conditions of Italy; they were 
 all determined not to sit upon her ruins and weep and lament like 
 Jeremiah. But they were united in the common desire of driving 
 away the hated foreigner, who was recognized as the sole cause of 
 the distress of their beloved country. They were, however, divided 
 in regard to the means to be used and to the method of organizing 
 the new Italy. Some put their hope in the house of Savoy. Others 
 thought to have found the panacea of all evils in a confederation of 
 all the Italian states with the Pope as its chief. Such a plan was 
 the outcome of two main factors. The congress of Vienna and the 
 general tendency of minds in all Europe, permeated by the roman- 
 tic spirit, called out the revival of Catholicism. In Italy, many 
 learned men who did not wish to part asunder their love of the 
 Church and their love of country were fascinated by the memory 
 of the medieval commonwealths which were united ander the pro- 
 tecting power of the Pope. 
 
 Besides, convinced that the unity of Italy could not be achieved 
 by revolution, they advocated the conciliation of all forces and ele- 
 ments, of papacy and monarchy, of liberty and civil progress, as 
 the most effective method of national regeneration and organization. 
 
 Mazzini's "Young Italy" stood in opposition to the other par- 
 ties. He urged the Italians to join his association *'in the firm in- 
 tent of consecrating both thought and action to the great aim of re- 
 constructing Italy as one independent sovereign nation of free men 
 and equals." Education and insurrection were the means he sug- 
 gested. But, beyond his own country, he looked to mankind. The 
 idea of nationality was, according to him, the necessary lever for 
 the realization of the cosmopolitan ideal of an international revo- 
 lution and republic. 
 
 With the ascent of Pius IX. to the throne of St. Peter, the con- 
 ciliatory tendency seemed to prevail over the others. "Wliile through 
 all Europe liberalism and reaction were still in conflict, the election 
 of such a Pope seemed to be a tribute to the national feeling of the 
 Italians. The head of the Church, usually reproached with com- 
 plicity in reviving what was already dead, and in killing what was 
 quite alive, showed that he appreciated indeed patriotism, which 
 
niSTOEICAL SITUATION OF EOSMIXI'S ITALY 7 
 
 was still resrarcled as a crime and condomned by the Austrian bishops 
 as the work of the devil. Tiie Pope's liberal tendencies could not 
 fail to foster the kindled tlame of patriotic love and to unite all 
 the Italians in the common purpose. Their enthusiasm culminated 
 in a general cry for war ajxainst the oppressing foreigner. During 
 those momentous days, for the firet time in the history of civilized 
 countries, Plato's ideal form of government seemed to be realized in 
 some aspects; the political attitude, under the pressure of circum- 
 stances, became quite philosophical. 
 
 Rosmini, Gioberti. Mamiani. the most prominent leaders in the 
 movement of thought, forgot their philosophical controversies which 
 had hitherto divided them, and devoted their common efforts to the 
 interest of their country. Gioberti sent our philosopher to Rome 
 as ambassador of Piedmont to induce the Pope, whose constitutional 
 minister was Mamiani, to take part in the war against Austria and 
 to establish the basis of an Italian confederation. But Rosmini's 
 mission failed, because of the reaction which once more prevailed 
 all over Italy. Both the method of revolutionary action and of the 
 impossible idealistic confederation, however, which proved to bo only 
 factors of bitter and general disappointment, were replaced by 
 Cavour's diplomacy. He cleverly broke the dream of a reconcilia- 
 tion which was based upon impossible compromises of principles, 
 tendencies, and attitudes, profoundly diverse, and gave the na- 
 tional party a new direction based upon reciprocal liberty of state 
 and religion. He thus initiated the achievement of the political 
 sjTithesis of the new Italy, free, independent, and united, as she 
 was wished to be by her sons and by the learned abroad. But Ros- 
 mini had not the joy of seeing the final phase of so long and so epic 
 a struggle, to which he had devoted his manifold activity, his 
 health, and reputation. 
 
 2. Intellectual Conditions 
 
 The powerful politit-al action which the Italians displayed for 
 the radical reconstruction of their country was in intimate and or- 
 ganic connection with the unfolding of their mental forces. 
 
 An action so complex and of such high practical importance 
 could not fail to focus the general attention and provoke reflective 
 thought. It involved, indeed, the necessity of criticizing the old and 
 of developing a new intellectual life. The possi])ility of its succes.s- 
 ful issues depended upon changing hal)its of mind, modes of indi- 
 vidual condur-t. and forms of social life. It had to l)e justified and 
 strengtlicncd with theoretical demonstrations of its justice and of its 
 conformity with the principles of human nature and of modern 
 thought. 
 
8 SOSMINI'S CONTEIBVTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Besides, the new ideas, the new scientific principles, which had 
 to be the determining and controlling factors of the national think- 
 ing and willing, could not but be clothed with abstract forms, be- 
 cause only such forms could escape political censure. The mag- 
 nificent and promising mental activity of the Renaissance, which 
 had made Italy the cradle of modern thought, was followed by two 
 centuries of intellectual tyranny and slumber. The religious reac- 
 tion and the deadening influence of Spanish bigotry had endeavored 
 to check the new stream of free and independent thought, and to 
 paralyze the germs of a new life. 
 
 But at the end of the eighteenth century, Italy was again ani- 
 mated by the spirit of Dante and the Renaissance, and emerged 
 from her long intellectual depression and lassitude. She entered 
 then into the general movement of modern thought, to which she 
 had already given the very first vital impetus. 
 
 It was natural that the Italians should feel impelled, while under 
 the hated foreign j^oke, to concentrate all their mental activities 
 upon the reconstruction of their coimtry, like the prisoners who, 
 groaning under the weight of chains, long for liberty and concen- 
 trate all their efforts upon attaining it. The Italians indeed began 
 to keep thought and action in persistent unity, until their patriotic 
 hopes and struggles were crowned with success. Accordingly, since 
 that very time, they began to display the same eager desire, the 
 same method, to vindicate, to magnify, and to convert all the mem- 
 ories of their glorious past into a living motor force. They endeav- 
 ored, impelled by a feeling of national pride, to restore the value 
 of their culture, and to impress a national mark upon politics, art, 
 literature, and philosophy. They did not fail, however, to throw 
 open their minds and hearts to all the invigorating influence which 
 came to them from foreign countries. They became, under the 
 pressure of their awful experiences, more sensible to the beauty and 
 wealth of thought, ancient as well as modern, which was contained 
 cither in foreign literatures, full already of juvenile vigor, or in 
 their own. The function of literature and art became civil and pa- 
 triotic. Lyric and dramatic poetry assumed an aggressive attitude 
 against the evils which the country had so long endured. Tragedies 
 were more or less disguised battles against any kind of despotism 
 and tyranny ; they aimed to stimulate national feeling by revealing 
 upon the stage past injustices, by exalting deeds of national heroism, 
 and by reviving Roman ideas of liberty, of justice, and of respect 
 for human dignity. Satiric poetry took on a social and civil signifi- 
 cance ; it was an embellished protest against the excessive inequality 
 between the rich and the poor, and a defense of the people trampled 
 and dejected. Painting and sculpture revived and embodied what 
 
HISTORICAL SITUATION OF UOSillXI'S ITALY 9 
 
 could foster the consciousness of greatness. Music, throufjii its sug- 
 gestive and universal language, displayed the anguish and the hopes 
 of all Italians. They made historical researches, not for the sake 
 of curiosity, but because they were an.xious to indicate the factors 
 of their national misfortune, and to finil in tiie past the flame of 
 enthusiasm and the experiences of their ancestors, which could be 
 translated into working forces. 
 
 The very dawn of the new intellectual life was, indeed, charac- 
 terized by the critical examination of the ideas they found current 
 and by a great interest in knowledge. Knowledge began to be regarded 
 as a social power and as determining factor in the movement of na- 
 tional regeneration. They nuide scientific investigations to find 
 useful truths, to modify, through experimental methods, mental 
 Imbits, and thus to divert men from the frivolous life of the time 
 and to bring them to serious reflection. Through inner regenera- 
 tion, through a peaceful and normal intellectual evolution, through 
 a national unity of mental life, they wanted to change the distress- 
 ing conditions of the country. Thus the motive, which began to 
 control the evolution of the new intellectual life, was quite practical 
 and determined scientific work. From the beginning, the reflection 
 upon the ideas which permeated social and individual life could 
 afford no satisfaction. The common experience of pu])lic life could 
 not fail to focus the attention of all upon civil laws. These were 
 said to be an emanation from the invisible and eternal will, but 
 proved to be the outcome of the deification of crystallized truths, 
 of hereditary prejudices, and of changeless oppressive political sys- 
 tems, as well as the genuine work of the personal interest of rulers. 
 Such laws were of no public advantage, they did not satisfy any 
 practical need or demand; nay, they were factors in the national 
 oppression and general unhappiness. Accordingly, accommodation I' 
 
 to them seemed to be cowartUy and shameful. Wavering confidence 
 in the practical value of obedience to them inevitably and fatally 
 implied an attack upon the validity of their ground. The .same po- 
 litical situation was bound to undermine also the })rineiples of moral- 
 ity, which controlled individual conduct and required the subser- 
 vience to tyrannical laws and systems. 
 
 These laws were based no less upon tradition tliaii authority, and 
 thus they seemed also to perpetuate the unhappy conditions of the 
 country. Many factors happened to subserve the critical and de- 
 structive attitude the Italians assumed while confronting the polit- 
 ical problem, which involved their iiidividual and social happine.s.s. 
 Authority more and more lost respect, because it was regarded as 
 oppressive. Tradition lost the influence it had exerted upon the 
 
10 EOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 national mind, because it suggested always changeless forms of im- 
 possible life. 
 
 Religious feeling wavered because the Church in Italy was, at 
 that time, identified in the mind of the people with the prevailing 
 political tyranny. And finally the contact with French culture 
 permeated with revolutionary ideas contributed also to foster the 
 feeling of rebellion against the old standards of life and fossilized 
 beliefs. 
 
 The outcome of such great fermentation of new ideas was moral 
 disintegration, political unrest, and skepticism. The pressure of 
 political activity which imposed profound intellectual revolutions 
 did not make skepticism merry, as in France during the eighteenth 
 century, but anxious to reconstruct knowledge, already regarded as 
 a great dynamic agency in the political regeneration of Italy. The 
 emphasis, however, upon the practical significance of knowledge 
 made u'^cessary critical insight into its origin and nature. Political 
 action r-xiuired a philosophical background. 
 
 Whence the crucial question rose whether experience or the mind 
 had to be held as the source of knowledge and consequently of ideas, 
 which are its constituent elements; whether ideas had to be consid- 
 ered as innate or as the product of sensations. This problem was 
 regarded, in Italy as well as throughout Europe, at that time, as 
 the most fundamental problem, and was justly placed in the fore- 
 ground of philosophical discussion. For its solution had to furnish 
 the basis of moral and political sciences which were expected to en- 
 lighten and sustain the national movement. In fact, the innate- 
 ness of ideas meant the previous existence of a priori controlling 
 principles. Accordingly, the national thinking and will, knowledge 
 and action, had to be controlled by abstract, eternal, and crystal- 
 lized notions, as during the long years of unchanged slavery. Ideals 
 and laws had to be regarded as eternally given, and consequently 
 there was no hope of reference to the concrete conditions, of po- 
 litical change, freedom, and progress. 
 
 On the contrary, the belief that ideas were the outcome of ever- 
 changing personal experience involved the conviction that human 
 personality must have a conscious participation in the creation of 
 truths, ideals, and laws, with absolute independence of every exter- 
 nal authority. Thus the individual, reckoning the changed condi- 
 tion, was able to direct his own conduct and become a decisive factor 
 in the regeneration and reconstruction of Italy. The philosophy 
 of experience which based knowledge and morality solely upon per- 
 ception, proclaimed the right of individualism and of rebellion 
 against intellectual and political oppression as well as against every 
 form of despotism, and thus it best responded to the urgent needs 
 
HISTORICAL SITUATION OF ROSMINI'S ITALY H 
 
 and demands of the second half of the eighteentli eentnry and of 
 the early part of the nineteenth t-entiiry. Of course, the interest in 
 the experimental and positive sciences, the closer contact with the 
 En«;lish and French literatures permeated with the spirit of mod- 
 ern philosophy, the loosened respect for tradition, the declinint? in- 
 fluence of the Church, the decreased feelinf; of tiie supernatural, 
 the conviction, also, that idealism, allied with relifjious and civil 
 authority, was an instrument of reaction, but, above all, the per- 
 sonal presence of Condillac,^ were so many factors which contributed 
 to condition and assure the prevalence of empiricism in Italy. 
 
 Gerdil,^ indeed, endeavored to oppose to it a foi-m of idealism 
 permeated with the doctrines of Plato, St. Augustine, and Descartes, 
 but his efforts were frustrated by the practical significance and com- 
 promise of idealism, holding fixed, innate controlling principles of 
 individual and social ethics, and by the rapid translation of Con- 
 dillac's works as well as by the teaching of Soave, who followed and 
 exalted Locke as the greatest metaphysician since he had dared 
 "to destroy the chimera of innate ideas. "^ 
 
 Colleges and universities welcomed the new philosophy, because 
 it seemed to answer the pressing political purpose of that historical 
 moment and to be in harmony with the intellectual temper and 
 with the history of the philosophical thought of the Italians." 
 
 Art and literature endeavored to assimilate and apply its prin- 
 ciples which, spread in diluted form, could not fail to filter through 
 the strata of national consciousness and conduct." 
 
 The fact that Condillac and Soave were priests, and that the 
 
 3 Condillac lived ten years (1758-1768) in Parma, at that time the " reticles- 
 vous" of the best intelligences, as tutor of the young Due Ferdinand of Bourbon. 
 
 •• Sigismond Car<l. Gerdil (1718-1802) published a great number of philo- 
 sophical works in French, Italian, and Latin. See Bouillicr, " Ilistoire de la 
 philosophic cartesienne," t. 11.. ch. XXVIII.; Ueberweg's "Hist, of Phil.," Vol. 
 II., page 480. 
 
 5 Soave translated into Italian first Dr. Winne's summary of Locke's cele- 
 brated "Essay," and later published a complete translation in the "Collezione 
 dei Clasgici Metafisici" in Pavia (1819). His * ' Istituzioni di Logica, Metafisica 
 e Morale" was useil as a text-book of philosophy in many colleges. He was 
 professor of philosophy in the Brera college in Milan. Let us notii-e here that 
 he, like Condillac, was a catholic priest. 
 
 « What is the national characteristic of Italian philosophy? According to 
 Ferri ("Essai sur I'Histoire de la Philosophic en Italic au Di.xXeuviftme Siftcle, " 
 Vol. II., page 343), the Italian miml, although fonil of experience and life, has 
 manifested a tendency to idealism; according to P. Ragnisco (Rivista di Filo- 
 Sofia, Vol. 3, 1911, page 698) the proper characteristic of Italian philosophy 
 is naturalism. 
 
 ~ Foscolo, Leopardi, Giordani. Count L. Cicognara ("Del Bello"), Cesarottl 
 ("Saggio sulla filosofia deile liiigue"), Costa (" Del modo <li comporre le idee"), 
 anil some others wrote under the influence of the new philosophy. 
 
12 EOSMINI'S CONTBIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 Jesuit order, whose influence was so powerful, strongly favored 
 the imported philosophy, helped its rapid spread. It was thought 
 that faith and ethics would not be affected by the principles of em- 
 piricism. Strange irony of history! The most striking charac- 
 teristics of the empirical movement in England, where it was born, 
 as well as in France, where it had been imported by such men as 
 Montesquieu and Voltaire, were disregard for positive religion and 
 opposition to the traditional beliefs presented to individuals through 
 the medium of organized society. The antagonism to innate ideas 
 meant opposition 'to the blind, undiscussed reception of old ideas, 
 and eager desire for independent critical examination. Besides, 
 the theory of transformed sensations assumed the denial of every 
 authority, either religious or political, leaving conventions and facts 
 depending upon man's imagination and will. But the new theory 
 seemed to be in Italy an auxiliary, practical standpoint and a pro- 
 visional method for political activity rather than a fixed and definite 
 philosophical position. The evolving of political conditions gradu- 
 ally modified the strict empiristic attitude. The most prominent 
 philosophers preceding Rosmini, as Gioja, Romagnosi, and Galluppi, 
 although contemporary, formed a rhythmic movement of philosoph- 
 ical thought. They lacked the originality and boldness which had 
 characterized the Italian philosophy of the Renaissance, and neg- 
 lected the fresh thought of the great Vico, who was ''the nine- 
 teenth century in germ,"^ but displayed the same enthusiasm for 
 the new philosophy of experience. They were permeated with the 
 spirit of the Enlightenment, and their main interest was accord- 
 ingly in the problem of knowledge and in the organization of a just 
 social order. Thus philosophy came to be regarded, as amongst 
 the ancient Greeks, as a social power, as a determining factor in 
 political reconstruction, and dependent upon the demands of prac- 
 tical, and in particular, of political life. It assumed, then, an es- 
 sentially human direction and its original mission.** 
 
 They all betrayed, however, the same aversion for the violent 
 breaking from religious tradition as well as the same fear of the 
 moral consequences which could be inferred from the current philos- 
 ophy: whence the same preoccupation we find in all for reconcilia- 
 tion, the same endeavor to fuse together the two great streams of 
 thought which derived from England and France, and to harmon- 
 ize, even in spite of patent inconsistency, idealism and empiricism 
 or sensationalism, Descartes and Locke or Condillac. 
 
 8 See B. Croce, "La Filisofia di G. Vico," page 248, Bari, G. Laterza, 1911. 
 English translation by R. G. CoUingwood. 
 
 9 Windelband, "History of Philosophy," page 6S; Dewey, "Essays," p. 21. 
 
EISTOTxlCAL SITUATION OF liOSMIM'S ITALY 13 
 
 According to Gioja/*' the fune'tioii of philosopliy is to rule the 
 ■whole of human activity for the sake of universal happiness. Ac- 
 cortliufjly, he thouglit that its business was the defence of human 
 rights and the promotion of social wealth and the control of social 
 ethics, which involves hygiene, politeness, and intellectual educa- 
 tion. He relatetl all inner phenomena to sensations, and sensations 
 to the senses. But he recognized within us a certain inner aetivity 
 which he called "the moving force of the soi\l"; this is the source 
 of all changes, either internal or external. 
 
 Romagnosi*' thought that the theory of empiricism and the 
 theory of innate ideas could be reconciled by recognizing within 
 our mind, above mere sensation, a peeuliar natural ])()wer, en- 
 dowed with an activity of its own. whieh he called "senso logico." 
 The function of the logical sense which is prior to the affirma- 
 tion and negation of our judgments, is to perceive in sensation, 
 in the world of phenomena, the supersensible element, the ele- 
 ment of intelligibility whieh is the being and the activity of 
 things "Vessere ed il fare delle cose." Thus, according to him, 
 being and causality only are intelligible or objects of our under- 
 standing. The object of the rational sen.se is the idea, the intel- 
 ligible, the being, not sensations, which only furnish our mind with 
 occa.sions to exercise its logical sense. So his teaching marked an 
 almo.st complete divorce from Locke and Condillac and a definite 
 step in a transition from empiricism to idealism. 
 
 Galluppi^- assumed a different philosophical attitude towards the 
 problems which the pressure of political conditions and the general 
 intelleetual movement of Europe brought to the foreground of philo- 
 sophical interest. His teaching marked, indeed, a very important 
 stage in the movement of philosophical thought in Italy. For he 
 was the first to understand and welcome the revolution brought 
 into philosophy by Kant, and to awaken the minds of his own coun- 
 trymen from their dogmatic slumber and from their fond attach- 
 ment to sen.sualism or rationalism by pointing out to tliem the 
 necessity of critical investigation.^^ 
 
 1'^ Molchiorre-Gioja (1707-1829). See Ucberweg, "History of Philosophy," 
 Vol. ir.. pages 483—484; Ferri, Histoire do la Philosoi)hic en Italic au XIX"" 
 si^de, ' ' Vol. I. 
 
 11 G. Domenico Roniagnosi (17G 1-1 8.3.5). See Ueberweg, op. cit., pages 
 484-85. Vol. II.; Ferri, op. cit.. Vol. I. 
 
 n Baron Pasquale Galliippi (1770-184fi). See Forri an<l Ueberweg, op. 
 cit.; R. Mariano, "La Philosophie contemporaine en Italie," 1868; Palhori&s, 
 "La Th^orie Id^logique de Galluppi," Paris, Mean, 1908. 
 
 >•'» Kant's philosophy was known in Italy through two books published in 
 French, i. c, "Philosophie do Kant, on principcs fondamcntaux do la i>hilosophie 
 transcendentale, " par Ch. Villers, Metz, 1801, and " Essai d'unc exposition 
 
14 EOSMINI'S CONTEIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 His works are pervaded by both conflicting tendencies, empiri- 
 cistic and rationalistic. He aimed at the reform of philosophy, and 
 accordingly endeavored to correct empiricism and Kantism, but 
 he proved to be unable to extricate himself entirely from both 
 philosophies, in which he found a valuable treasure for his own 
 elaboration. 
 
 Knowledge and action, according to him, or thought, its elements, 
 functions, and value for truth and good, are the main subject- 
 matter of philosophy. He was aware that the problem of knowl- 
 edge was in his day "the object of meditation in all Europe," and 
 upon this problem he focused his attention. Against sensationalism 
 he held that the mind is not only sensitive, but intelligent and reason- 
 able, and made the distinction between sense and intelligence, sen- 
 sation and thought. Against Condillac he stated that our mind is 
 something more than a mere collection of internal states; that it is 
 a reality, a being, a substance, endowed with the power of analysis 
 and synthesi.s. He rejected innate ideas in the sense of ideas prior 
 to sensations and independent of all experience, but he accepted 
 them in the sense of natural ideas, or ideas for whose acquisition we 
 have a natural disposition, "una virtualita naturale." Galluppi 
 agreed with Kant that knowledge is a combination of subjective and 
 objective elements, but he found Kant's form and matter equally 
 subjective, and hence the failure to solve the problem of knowledge. 
 The crucial point is to determine what is objective and subjective in 
 knowledge. We find objective elements only in the immediate con- 
 tact of the self with reality or in primitive experience; reflective 
 experience which is based upon ideal sj'nthesis is the outcome of the 
 objective elements given by sensations and of the subjective elements 
 produced by the mind itself. This was the solution which Galluppi 
 gave the great problem of critical philosophy. His teaching, char- 
 acterized by simple and attractive eloquence, permeated by the 
 principles of the Kantian and of the Scottish school, and involving 
 the suggestion to descend from theology to psychology, from nature 
 to humanity, from abstractions to facts, provoked a great interest 
 in philosophy amongst the Italians, and seemed to the national 
 party to be a powerful instrument of political action and easy to be 
 assimilated by the people because stripped of the obsolete and dry 
 scholastic form. 
 
 But during the time of his teaching important new political 
 changes which affected Italy as well as all Europe, brought out 
 
 succinte de la critique de la raison pure de Kant," par M. Kinker, traduit du 
 hollandais par J. Le Fr., Amsterdam, 1801. The first Italian translation of the 
 Critique of Pure Reason was published by Mantovani, in 1821 and 1822. Galluppi 
 examined Kantian philosophy in detail. 
 
HISTORICAL SITUATIOX OF HOSMIM'S ITALY 15 
 
 ehaiifjes of intellectual attitudi-. Wlini the rovolutionarv storm 
 was over, a reaction was inevitable. Admiration for the preceding 
 intellectual movement changi:cd to aversion and iiatrcd. Reason was 
 held responsible for the violence done to political ami relipfious ene- 
 mies. "Philosophy" was blamed for the general unrest and dis- 
 order. The French Revolution, welcomed at the beginning as a 
 manifestation of reason and the triumph of man, stripped of re- 
 ligious preoccupations, culminated in excesses of bloody violence. 
 Its issue was a numifest confession of impotence for constructive 
 purposes and social peace. Empiricism transformed into sen- 
 sualism, naturalism changed into materialism, deism degenerated 
 into atheism, enthusiastic morals sunk into egoistic morals, proved 
 to be unable to settle the questions which were .so closely connected 
 with individual and social happiness. The nations of Europe wliose 
 barriers had been overthrown amongst the vicissitudes of the revolu- 
 tionary wars could already freely communicate with one another, 
 fuse together their ideas, and thus participate in a general culture, 
 but they longed for peace and order, for a new source of life, and 
 for a new system of ideas and purpo.ses. So it happened that the 
 general feeling against the violences and destructions of the Revo- 
 lution, the over-excitement and exhaustion produced by sensualistie 
 excesses, the impuissanee of the rationalistic and materialistic 
 "philosophism" to reform society, the universal eager desire of a 
 new center of gravitation, the same programme of the "Holy Al- 
 liance" which heralded the reconstruction of moral order and the 
 regeneration of the political .system of Europe on the basis of Chris- 
 tianity and thus the revival of religion, and finally the triumphant 
 return of the Pope to Rome, evoked a spiritualistic reaction. The 
 romantic movement favored the revival of the Christian religion. 
 For it appealed to spontaneity, sensibility, feeling, emotion, and en- 
 thusiasm which are the main religious factors, and while revelling 
 in the vast world of the unknown as well as in a new n>alm of mar- 
 vels and nw.steries, it evoked the Middle Ages in which Christianity 
 and papacy had predominated. Besides, the satisfaction of estlietic 
 feeling which the dominant religion afforded, the romantic concep- 
 tion of Christianity as perfectly compatible with the highest intel- 
 lectual culture, contribiitcd to present as "ultimatum" to the con- 
 vulsed society the religion against which the revolutionary fury had 
 been directed. 
 
 Thus, "through a common movement," says Taine, "along the 
 whole line of human thought, causes draw back into an abstract 
 region, where philosophy had not been to search them out for eighteen 
 centuries. Then was manifest the disea.se of the age, the restless- 
 ness of Werther and Faust, very like that which in a similar^jjijc^ .^^^^ 
 
 i 
 
 OK THE ' 
 
16 SOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ment agitated men eighteen centuries ago: I mean, discontent with 
 the present, the vague desire of a higher beauty, and an ideal hap- 
 piness, the painful aspiration for the infinite."^* 
 
 But then arose in Italy the question whether or not the whole 
 heritage of the eighteenth century had to be rejected, which age of 
 Italian history had to be copied ; whether the genuine greatness of 
 Italy had to be founded on the revival of the age of the Roman 
 Empire and the Renaissance, when social life and human person- 
 ality were free and independent of supernatural preoccupation, 
 and the Italians enjoyed a spiritual unity of knowledge and will ; 
 or on the revival of the Middle Ages, when the intimate union of 
 Church and monarchy, of religion and authority, of faith and reason, 
 of theology and philosophy, prevailed. 
 
 Men who were imbued with the spirit of classicism and of the 
 eighteenth-century culture, took the former alternative. Those 
 whose enthusiasm was directed towards romanticism wanted the 
 life of the new Italy to be a continuity of the harmony of all social 
 forces. They displayed, nevertheless, great sympathy for all modern 
 aspirations, and endeavored to subserve their national cause by 
 spreading, under an evangelical disguise, forbidden ideas of liberty, 
 patriotism, and universal equality. 
 
 The conciliatory tendency was bound to prevail, under the pres- 
 sure of religious and national enthusiasm. Such a tendency, to- 
 gether with the influence of the reactionary and theological, and of 
 the ps.ychologico-spiritualistic movement in France, and the power- 
 ful impulse from Germany to construct gigantic systems in order 
 to have a comprehensive view of spiritual life, could not fail to pro- 
 voke in Italy a philosophy which, by an encyclopedic synthesis should 
 seek to unite all intellectual efforts for the sake of a common na- 
 tional action. The genius of Rosmini provided the needed philo- 
 sophical formula of universal harmony, source of truth, and moral- 
 ity, of reciprocal respect and love, of social justice and individual 
 rights, as symbol of the coming national unity. 
 
 14 "History of English Literature," Book lY., €h. I. 
 
CHAPTEK U 
 RosMLNi's Person ALiTv 
 
 1. h'osmini's Vsychological Dispositions 
 
 An extraordinary Imnfjcr for learning associatod with a powor- 
 ful inti'llifriMU'c. ii proiiduiiced relipfious tendency. ;iii<l a deep feel- 
 ing of sympathy for men were the important features of Rosmini's 
 psyeholoprjeal inlieritanee. These native dispositions were devel- 
 oped hy the social environment in which he was reared, and exerted 
 a constant influence on his mental activity. His early tuition as 
 well as his acadiMuic course was permeated with rt'li<rious ideals. 
 The atmosphere which he and the learned men with whom he was 
 in continuous intercourse breathed was pervaded hy I'cligious reac- 
 tion against the movement of modern thought, regarded as the main 
 factor of social disturbance. Accordingly, his mind did not escape 
 hal)its of analogous thinking, feeling, and acting, and partaking 
 of the prevailing reactionary aim and disposition of his times and 
 cla.ss. 
 
 The silent, beautiful scenes of immensity and mystery which the 
 snowy Alps display provoked the eager mind of the young Ros- 
 mini to wonder and philosophy. We are told, indeed, that he began 
 very early to incline to the investigation of truth, and to display a 
 striking tendency to moralize. While he was a boy. playing the 
 game of "policeman." or "catch thief," he preferred the part of 
 judge to every other, for he liked to pose as a "wise man," and to 
 give good advice to his little friends. 
 
 We are told also that the young thinker surpri.sed his tutor with 
 his advanced philosophiciil knowledge. Just when the good teacher 
 judged his pupil al)le to be initiated in the philosophy of empiricism, 
 he discovered that he did not need to be taught philosophy, for he 
 knew enough and mastered Afpiinas's "Summa. " The precocious 
 philosopher showed at an early age that he felt the great importance 
 of "the queen and mother of all sciences"; philosophy was always 
 the subject of his con vereat ions and letters. lie was so enamored 
 of the .study of philosophy, that lie spent much of his youth and of 
 the rest of his stormy life in devotion to it. 
 
 "Philosophy and the contemplation of nature," he said, "far 
 
 17 
 
18 KOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PEILOSOPHY 
 
 from wearjnng us, form such an agreeable recreation that I sliould 
 not be disposed to sacrifice it for any other. "^ 
 
 "Day and night," he said, "I roamed through flowery paths, as 
 it were, in the vast demesne of philosophical lore, feelihg all that 
 joy which the first aspect of truth infuses into the soul, feeling that 
 security which borders on hardihood, feeling those indefinite hopes 
 peculiar to youth when for the first time turning, with elevated 
 and conscious reflections, to the universe and its Creator, thinking 
 to absorb the one and the other as easily as we breathe."^ 
 
 We are told that no difficulty daunted him; nay, difficulties in- 
 flamed his ardor, because in every difficulty he saw a secret calcu- 
 lated to arouse his curiosity, a treasure to discover. Such intellec- 
 tual enthusiasm actuated him to read all the ancient, medieval, and 
 modern philosophers, and to collect together the many scattered 
 fragments of truth he found in their works. It is said of him that 
 like an industrious bee, he went everj'where in quest of honey, and 
 wherever he found any, he drew it forth. Thus here and there, the 
 shadow of some antecedent philosophy can be retraced in his works, 
 but he was a disciple of nobody. His immense philosophical elab- 
 oration had as its source only his intellectual and moral temper, his 
 native genius as well as his mental habits, molded as they were by 
 his social environment. 
 
 The bent and disposition of Eosmini's mind converged not only 
 towards contemplation, but toward action as well. He was ani- 
 mated by altruistic feelings; he felt impelled to communicate his 
 ideas to his fellow-men. 
 
 For he was convinced that high intellectual culture is refining 
 and ennobling, and to discover truth means to discover the means 
 of moral progress. It filled him with pain ' ' to think that truths ex- 
 cellent in themselves and congenial to the human intelligence should 
 be monopolized by a small circle of individuals, as though none but 
 themselves had a right to possess them. "^ 
 
 And referring to the Scholastic attitude he says, "Is there not 
 something odious and hurtful to human feeling in a science which, 
 under the pretence of being scholastic, envelops itself in mystery; 
 which seems to hate the light of day; which wears all the appear- 
 ance of a sect, with a language, or rather jargon, of its own, and 
 forbidden to the rest of men, and which assumes an ambitious, or 
 
 1 Impelled by the desire of spreading philosophical knowledge, he formed 
 an academy of young philosophers in his house. The members of the new aca- 
 demy, eager to imitate the Peripatetics, indulged in philosophical discussions, 
 wandering about the charming surroundings of Eovereto. 
 
 2 "Introduzione alia filosofia. " 
 
 » "The Origin of Ideas," Vol. I., Ch. III., §36. 
 
EOS MINI'S PERSONALITY 19 
 
 at least a strange and exclusive tone, as if it liad some great secret 
 to conceal, or some dark ends to accomplish?"* 
 
 Thus, Rosmini could not conceive philosophy divorced from 
 human affairs and interests. "Why," he asks, "should this science, 
 which boasts of being the motiier of all the arts, keep itself aloof 
 from, and sullenly refuse to hold friendly intercourse with, the 
 human family? Has it, then, like some beasts of a new species, im- 
 penetrable lairs, wh(>re to abide in solitude, from fear lest its in- 
 terests shouUl sutler by being mixed up with those of the world at 
 large? Or has heaven bestowed the gift of reason on a few indi- 
 viduals only? And siuill, therefore, the great bulk of numkind for- 
 ever have to be led, like a Hoek of sheep, by the command or the 
 rod of those favored ones? Must incti be for everlasting debarred 
 from judging in a body or pronouncing on matters on which their 
 own dignity and happiness depend?"'' 
 
 Accordingly, "a good instinct" of his nature irresistibly 
 prompted him to applaud "intentions so humane, and to feel the 
 liveliest gratitiule for those who labor with the intent of placing the 
 very highest truths within the reach of the greatest number. . . . 
 For if this were well and successfully done, the masses would be 
 able to enjoy in some way the lovable aspect of those truths, and 
 would rise to a better condition."" 
 
 Moreover, he thought that the masses, by bringing their collec- 
 tive judgment to bear on the interminable disputations of the 
 learned, might, perhaps, speak out with such an overwhelming 
 weight of authority as would effectually recall these disputants to 
 more profitable occupations and sountler ways of thiidving, and to 
 work for the true benefit of the indiviilual and society. Rosmini, 
 persuaded of the social and humane mission of philosophy, could 
 not fail to direct his attention to the national problem, which was 
 already the focus of the general intellectual activity. He, in fact, 
 like the elite of his time, did not make a mystery of his love for the 
 common mother, the beloved from whom he had had "life and lan- 
 guage."^ 
 
 Eye-witnes.s of the violences perpetrated by th(^ French armies 
 as well as of the angry despotism of the restored governments, he 
 grieved over Italy's unhappy state anrl longed for the freedom, in- 
 dependence, and unity, which he openly proclaimed to be "a uni- 
 versal cry" that set throbbing the heart of every Italian.'' 
 
 * "The Origin of Ideas," toe. cif. 
 5 "The Origin of Meas," loc. cit. 
 o"The Origin of Ideas," loc. cit. 
 
 7 See " Xuovo Saggio HuH'origine delle idee," preface. 
 
 8 See "Discorso suH'Unitii .1 'Italia." 
 
20 EOSMINrS COXTHIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHT 
 
 It seems, however, that Rosmini was distressed rather by the 
 moral disintegration than by the political situation of his country. 
 All his works, in fact, betray a strong moral preoccupation and a 
 persistent endeavor to point out moral reconstruction as a factor of 
 social happiness. But the Church's declining influence, above 
 everything else, attracted his attention. His native religious bias, 
 under the constant influence of his social environment, became a 
 deep and inalterable love for his parents' religion. And to such a 
 love the Italian philosopher subordinated his whole intellectual ac- 
 tivity. Thus, it was inevitable that a life of earnest and close ad- 
 hesion to his religion would have created in his mind habits of in- 
 tellectual submission and criticism not at all independent and im- 
 partial. Besides, his woi'ks bespeak his fondness for abstract, fixed, 
 and eternal principles, his idealistic tendency, his dogmatic affirma- 
 tion, his conviction of the necessity of universals, his determination 
 to organize an absolute system, and consequently, his rationalistic 
 type of mind." 
 
 2. Rosmini' s Leading Motive, Attitude, and Method 
 
 Rosmini seemed to be convinced of the fact that the growing indi- 
 vidualism, the ascending democracy, the progress of national feel- 
 ing, and, finall}^, the intellectual undercurrents of social life had 
 already brought into question the ancient beliefs and moral stan- 
 dards, and that even the position of the Catholic Church had been 
 compromised, being thrown by clericalism into the political turmoil 
 of the times. He, accordingly, felt stimulated to bring his contri- 
 bution to the political, intellectual, and moral reconstruction of his 
 beloved country. Impelled by a motive so eminently practical, he 
 applied his mind to an etiological inquiry into the actual conditions 
 of the Church, of Italy, and of philosophy. 
 
 Under the pressure of his native dispositions, acquired habits, 
 intellectual temper, and of the dominant current of thought, per- 
 meated with spiritualism and religion, the Italian philosopher found 
 out that the divorce of the Church from social and political aspira- 
 tions, of faith from reason, of theology from philosophy, was the 
 main factor in the restlessness of his social environment. He, 
 therefore, urged the reconciliation of all the intellectual and social 
 forces as the panacea for all the evils of his times. Besides, agree- 
 ing with the prevailing romantic spirit, he pointed to the Middle 
 Ages as the epoch in which the ideal reconciliation he dreamed of, 
 the genuine greatness of Papacy and of Italy, and the lofty task of 
 
 » See W. .James, "Pragmatism," pages 7, 51; "Some Problems of Phi- 
 losophy," page 35. 
 
EOSMIXI'S PEESOXALITY 2i 
 
 philosophy, were fully realized. His discovery, indeed, could not 
 be otherwise ! But Rosmini thought that such harmonious union 
 had been shattered by tlie movement of modern philosophy. Ac- 
 cording to him, philosophy "from Locke to Kant, in spite of so many 
 efforts, went on wandering farther and fartlier astray, and en- 
 tangling itself in its very ])n)gress, until men grew weary of it, and 
 lost all faith in doctrines tiiat were contimially changing."'"' 
 
 Thus, he believed that reason was to.ssed about by the waves of 
 skepticism and opinion, and that there was no longer faith in any 
 universally valid truth, or in the possibility of any certain knowl- 
 edge, while respect for authority and tradition sank, religious feel- 
 ings and ideals wavered, ami iinlividuals governed themselves. 
 
 Sensationalism and subjectivism, indeed, acknowledging no es- 
 sential objectivity of ideas and then no objective measure of truth, 
 and relying only on the relativity of individual ideas, built human 
 knowledge as well as ethical principles upon a relativism of indi- 
 vidual opinions, and, consequently, upon the insecurity of change 
 and caprice. This philosophical attitude and its inevitable conse- 
 quence, the absolute independence of the individual in the theoret- 
 ical and practical sphere, and "the deification of human faculties 
 and affections" plainly proclaimed by Kantian doctrine, hurt Ros- 
 mini 's religious feeling, for they meant a mortal blow to religious 
 tradition and to organized authority. Thus he felt that there was 
 "a yearning for the invaluable boon of a true and .sound philos- 
 ophy," and that the yearning was due to the uncertain utterances 
 and to the imperfect and unsatisfactory .systems which philosophers 
 had already propounded. 
 
 Rosmini was penetrated with the importance of philosophy be- 
 cause of its all-embracing influence, determining the source of 
 knowledge, and thus making all sciences dependent on itself. Be- 
 sides, philosophy, in his opinion, has an anthropological, a social, 
 and a religious mission, since it is the interpreter of nature as well 
 as of the wishes of the luiman heart, and it unites men amongst 
 themselves and with their Creator. Finally, it aims at the better- 
 ment of men by discovering and transforming truth into reality, 
 and by leading to good and to virtue, as to their natural end.*^ 
 Accordingly, for Rosmini, the restoration of philo.soi)hy was aji 
 urgent need, and it could not be achieved without a firm epistemo- 
 logical ground. 
 
 Rosmini, agreeing with Locke and Kant, was impres.sed from 
 his early youth, by the practical importance of the problem of 
 
 ""Theodicy," Ch. XXIX, No. 148. Longmans, Green, and Company, \ew 
 York, 1912. 
 
 11 See ''Introduzione alia filosofia. " 
 
 / 
 
22 BOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPnY 
 
 knowledge. He justly recognized that the most urgent question to 
 be solved in philosophy was whether, above and beyond individual 
 opinions and purposes, there is anything universally valid, true, 
 and right in itself; whether our ideas have a really objective value 
 and provide a firm basis for knowledge and morality ; wliether at 
 that time of political and moral unrest there could be found a basis 
 for common truth and good which might become a ground of a 
 social agreement and political cooperation. According to our philos- 
 opher, the science of individual and social ethics, law, government, 
 education, which the political situation threw into the front rank of 
 intellectual interests; man's faith in absolute justice; the changeless 
 right of nations to political independence and liberty ; the necessity 
 of suppressing despotism as well as rebellion ; had to rest upon a 
 knowledge, not transient and relative, but stable and unchangeable. 
 Such a knowledge, however, must have for its basis, not the chance 
 ideas furnished by sense-experience, but the ideal order, "the innate 
 idea of the universal which is the truly real;" it must rest "on an 
 object," says Rosmini, "which is always before us, necessary, uni- 
 versal, and independent of us and all created things. "^^ 
 
 The persistent effort to indicate the idea of the universal as 
 source of objective and absolute truth, as nucleus of the new national 
 mental and moral life, as point of centralization of intellectual and 
 political activity, meant the accumulation of individual energies, 
 the absorption and submission of the individual to organized society 
 as well as to the common supreme ideal of national solidarity and 
 unity, and constitutes the essential characteristic of Rosmini 's phi- 
 losophy. 
 
 The mental attitude Rosmini assumed towards the philosophical 
 problems which his contemporaries confronted was religious and 
 reactionary, but softened by a spirit of conciliation that was in the 
 air. He seemed to be determined to revive the attitude of the Holy 
 Fathers, who did not hesitate to avail themselves of whatsoever 
 truth the systems of pagan philosophers contained in order to secure 
 rational support for their beliefs. 
 
 But our philosopher, like them, wanted to subordinate knowl- 
 edge to the lofty ends of faith, reason to revelation, philosophy to 
 theology, science to dogma. Besides, he endeavored to bring Chris- 
 tianity as an efficient factor into philosophical speculation, and thus 
 to harmonize natural and supernatural truths. Convinced that the 
 most striking characteristics of every true and efficient philosoph- 
 ical system are "unity and totality," he built, like his contemporary 
 German philosophers, a gigantic system in which he thought it pos- 
 sible to take in at a glance, almost all truths, arranged in a scheme 
 
 12 "The Origin of Ideas," No. 1037, Vol. II. 
 
EOSMINI'S PERSONALITY 03 
 
 of beautiful uuity, and enhanced with new life by "the evidence of 
 a supreme principle."'^ 
 
 But in one point Rosniini gladly ajjreed with modern philoso- 
 phers, namely, in the method to be used in philosophy, that is, a 
 method which starts from facts. lie found, howevt-r, that "modern 
 philosophers have contented themselves with analyzin<; the faculties 
 of the soul, and have paid little attention to the analysis of tlieir 
 product, /. e., human cojjnitions. "'^ 
 
 Acconlinj]: to him, the rijjjht method is to observe what is pjiven 
 by our corporeal senses and at the same time the facts of our inner 
 life and then to accept imj)artially the lc<;itimate eonse(iuenct's of 
 the same.^^ 
 
 Our philosopher, however, almost exclusively employed the syn- 
 thetic method and thus replaced the concrete by the abstract, the 
 fact by the idea, the internal observation by (i priori reasoning, 
 making the study of man depend on metaphysics. He preferred 
 deduction to induction, the a priori to direct observation, reasoning 
 to experience. He proved, indeed, to be a psychologist, but he often 
 recurred to hypothesis rather than to analysis, to syllogism rather 
 than to experiment. 
 
 ;i. The Fundamental Principle of Rosniini\s rhilosophij 
 
 "Unity and totality" is, according to Rosniini. the main charac- 
 teristic of a true and efficient philosophy.'" This characteristic, 
 which we find in the contemporary romantic philosophy, he endeav- 
 ored to .stamp upon his own. Accordingly, he elaborated his ethical 
 and theoretical doctrine in close connection; his ideology and ethics 
 are so interrelated that the one lends light to tlu^ other. Thus, the 
 distinctive marks of the leading principles of his ethical theory 
 can not be given apart from the general principles of his philosophy. 
 
 A.S we have seen, Rosmini, under the pres.sure of Italy's political 
 and moral problem thought that the main business of philosophy 
 was to build human knowledge upon a fixed basis, and thus to cheek 
 the deplored outcome of skepticism and materialism, and. by placing 
 rea.son in opposition to opinion, to overcome anarchical change which 
 sensationalism and empiricism favored. Rut, according to him. as 
 well as to Kant, the difficulty of the problem of knowledge lies in the 
 po.ssibility of the first judgment. Knowledge is judgment, and then 
 the analysis of the first knowledge or judgment is the first step in 
 every serious philosophical research. Now, the essence of judgment 
 
 13 See " Introdiizione alia filosofia. " 
 ""The Origin of Ideas," No. 410. 
 ""Theorlioy," No. 138, Vol. 1. 
 16 See " Introtluzione alia filosofia." 
 
24 BOSMINI'S CONTBIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 consists in the union of a subject individual and of a predicate, of 
 a particular idea and of a universal idea. Thus every judgment 
 supposes a universal idea. Experience gives us particular ideas or 
 the matter of knowledge. The universal idea, however, or the form 
 can derive neither from sense-experience, for this happens w'ithin 
 the sphere of contigent facts and reaches nothing beyond the indi- 
 vidual, nor from reflection, which is an operation of the mind, and 
 every intellectual operation is a judgment. The exclusion of these 
 two possibilities, the former as insufficient, and the latter as form- 
 ing a vicious circle, leaves one last hypothesis, namely, that the uni- 
 versal idea is prior, that is, innate. Thus within human reason 
 there is at least a notion wiiich is primitive, indispensable to the 
 formation of the first judgment, and which is the first condition and 
 link of human knowledge. This primitive idea is the light and life 
 of reason, and the form of forms; since it is universal, it is also the 
 most elementary and simple and it is to be found, accordingly, in 
 every judgment, in every operation of our mind as its most essen- 
 tial factor. It contains necessarily as in germ all human knowl- 
 edge ; it is the ruling thought, and successively becomes cause, sub- 
 stance, finality. According to Rosmini, such an idea can not but be 
 the ''idea of being" or the "ideal being." In fact, our internal 
 analysis shows us that our cognitions have the idea of being as a 
 common element. This idea is at the bottom of every thought. 
 
 "The idea of being," he says, "is the most universal of all 
 ideas. It is w^hat remains after the last abstraction possible ; and 
 its removal puts an end to all thought and makes every other idea 
 impossible. "^^ 
 
 ' ' Man has by nature an intuition of that ideal and indeterminate 
 being which contains all entity in an indistinct state, in a way ana- 
 logous to that in which a large block of marble contains all the 
 statues which the sculptor proposes to make out of it, or a given 
 superficies all the figures that can be designed thereon. "^^ 
 
 This "corner-stone" of the edifice of human knowledge, virtue, 
 and happiness, which Rosmini sought from his early youth, this 
 nucleus, source, and rule of every art and science, this very efficient 
 means of philosophical and social restoration, is not a production of 
 reason itself; it does not derive from the thinking self, like the Kan- 
 tian forms; but it is communicated from without, and it is, there- 
 fore, not subjective, but objective.^" 
 
 17 "The Origin of Ideas," A'ol. II., No. 411, page 17. 
 
 18 " Theodicy, " Vol. II., No. 668, page 159. 
 
 19 See "Filosofia del Diritto, " Introdiizione. Pagani reports in his "Life 
 of Rosmini ' ' that the Italian philosopher proposed to himself the great problem 
 of the origin of ideas when he was seventeen years old (1814), and that in the fol- 
 lowing year he discovered the fundamental principle of his philosophy. 
 
PART II 
 
 THE ESSENTIAL FEATURES OF KOSMINI'S ETHICAL THEORY 
 
 INTRODUCTORY 
 
 The Scope and ^Ietuod of Ethics 
 
 The science of ethics is, according to Rosmini, the director of 
 human life, since its purpose is to direct man's rational activity. 
 Man's goodness, however, depends upon the goodness of his will, for 
 the will is the supreme and active rational power, which controls 
 and synthesizes all his intellectual and moral actions. Nay, the 
 will is precisely the same radical and immanent activity which con- 
 stitutes human personality. Whence our philosopher concludes 
 that man is moral, because his will is susceptible of good and bad 
 activity, of moral or immoral acts and habits, or, in one word, of 
 morality.^ 
 
 Thus the crux of every theory is to discover the factors which 
 make good man's will, or, in other words, what is "moral good" or 
 "virtue." Man is endowed with the faculty of sensation as well as 
 with that of intelligence. By the faculty of .sensation, he perceives 
 things as they are; by the faculty of intelligence, he perceives things 
 as possible. This different mode of perceiving is, according to our 
 philosopher, the cause of distinction between subjective and objec- 
 tive good. 
 
 The sense is the source of subjective good ; the intellect is the 
 source of objective good. Every sensible good stimulates and satis- 
 fies man; and he is naturally impelled to unite himself to such a 
 good, and to enjoy it. Man, however, does not regard the objective 
 or "intelligible" good as .sometliing which belongs to himself, as 
 something which may be felt by him. He merely eonsidei's it as an 
 object of his intelligence, of his intellectual intuition everywhere 
 and in wliatsoever mode it may be found. "The objective good is 
 merely contemplated by the intelligence." Now, the burning ques- 
 tion is whether the moral good is subjective or objective. 
 
 Rosmini believes this distinction to be of the highest importance, 
 
 1 See "Antropologia," I., IV.. €hs. VL, VIII.; "Prefazione alle opere di 
 filosofia morale"; "Compendio di etica." Introduzione, §§I., 11.; "Thco<licy," 
 Xo9. 398, 410. 
 
 25 
 
26 BOSMINI'S CONTSIBVTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 since the confusion of tlie two kinds of good has brought ruin to 
 philosophy and morals.- He praises the German school because of 
 its contribution to the important distinction, whereby ethics has 
 been delivered from the motivation of happiness.^ 
 
 To say that moral good is subjective, is, according to Rosmini, 
 to base it upon the relativity of human ideas and purposes, and, 
 consequently, upon individual opinions, preferences, and caprices; 
 thus it can be found together with a bad will. This is the fatal 
 consequence of the philosophy of sense. But our philosopher, im- 
 pelled by the bias of his mind and character, is determined to oppose 
 such philosophical premises and ethical consequences. He seems 
 thoroughly convinced that the ethical conduct of life needs sure 
 principles, that the norm and standard for the valuation of worth 
 must be unique, fixed, and absolute, and, finally, that it may be 
 found above and beyond individual experience, in a Platonic meta- 
 physical atmosphere, 
 
 Rosmini, following the German philosophers, eliminates happi- 
 ness, that is to say, just what the Greek thought to be its essential 
 element, from the science of ethics. He holds that ethics is only 
 concerned with moral good. Eudemonology is the science which 
 deals with happiness. 
 
 Thus, the great problem the moral philosopher is called upon 
 to solve is the problem of the nature of moral good. It is indeed a 
 problem of the highest practical importance, since human happiness 
 depends upon its right solution. The nature of moral good, how- 
 ever, may be traced only by the analysis of its fundamental factors. 
 Now, from all Rosmini 's ethical works it may be concluded that he 
 thinks the moral good to be the outcome of two main factors, one 
 of which we may call ''metaphysical" and the other "psycholog- 
 ical.'' According to him, all ethical judging, the will and its whole 
 activity, must conform to a supreme and fundamental law of action, 
 which is categorically imperative, universally true and valid as well 
 as universally uniform. This is, for him as for Kant, the most sig- 
 nificant feature of morality. Such a law, however, which he sup- 
 poses to be prior to all particular laws, grounding their existence 
 and obligatory force, is objective, absolute, and independent of all 
 empirical motives. 
 
 This primal and fundamental law is the metaphysical and chief 
 factor of morality ; it constitutes its essence. Bufr the law presup- 
 poses an agent, and an agent capable of adjusting himself; it presup- 
 
 2 See "Prefazione alle opere di filosofia morale"; "Priucipii della scienza 
 morale," Ch. III.; "Storia comparativa e critica intorno al principio della 
 morale," etc. 
 
 3 See "Prineipii della scienza morale," op. cit., Ch. III.^ a. I. 
 
THE SCOPE AND METHOD OF ETHICS 27 
 
 poses a free will. Neither the law nor the will alone constitutes 
 morality. 
 
 The moral situation, according to Rosmini, involves also the 
 psychological factor, and both ethical factors, not asumler, but in 
 reciprocal relation. The science of ethics is then confronted by 
 another problem of no less importance : the problem of the nature 
 of the agent and of the relation between law and the will in order 
 to have human actions clothed with morality, and therefore good. 
 
 It is the business of ethics to answer these central problems, 
 which form the core of every ethical theory. Let us notice here that 
 Rosmini does not regard an ethical theory as a working hypothesis, 
 since ethics is not for him hypothetical, conditional, and relative, 
 lie considers ethical tlicoiy as helpful to morals because of its 
 formulation of fixed precepts for action, rather than for the scien- 
 tific insight it affords into trutli. Tie does not define ethical theory 
 from the standpoint of principles which can provide a method of 
 action, but from that of rules which are prescriptions for it. Ethics, 
 however, is a science for him, not an art, as for Joim Stuart Mill.* 
 It is, indeed, a science because it formulates laws, but it is a 
 practical science, as its laws are formulated for the sake of action. 
 It may, accordingly, be called "the theory of practise" or "the 
 theory of action."^ 
 
 Ethics, says Rosmini, is "the science which gives systematic order 
 to the norms to which human actions must adjust themselves, and 
 determines the relation between actions and norms.""* 
 
 *" Logic," Book 6, Ch. 12. 
 
 5 See "Prefazione alio opore di filosofia morale." 
 
 6 See "Sistcnia lilosofiio, " No. 21G. 
 
CHAPTER I 
 
 The ]\Ietaphysical Factor of Morality 
 
 EosMiNi, being determined to set up the ideal of reason against 
 the relativism of sense, seems to regard as basic the conviction that 
 the concept is the goal of science, since conception alone gives us 
 the permanent essence of things, while the objective content of con- 
 ceptual knowledge is the idea. According to him. the idea is merely 
 the immediate and direct cognition of things in their proper essence, 
 which is eternal.^ 
 
 Since an idea is an essence, and since our judgment is always 
 right when an idea is its rule, Rosmini thinks that an idea, a notion, 
 is also the rule or standard according to which we must judge of 
 the morality of our actions, and behave : that is to say that the 
 moral law is nothing else than an idea.- The notion of "perni- 
 ciousness, ' ' for instance, is the notion through which w^e know what 
 actions are pernicious or not. We compare and conform our ac- 
 tions with such a notion, as if it were a type. The moral law is 
 then a notion. Besides, Rosmini seems to accept the law exalted by 
 Socrates to the principle of scientific method, namely, the law of 
 logical dependence of the particulars upon the universal. He 
 thinks, accordingly, that every notion supposes and depends upon 
 another, anterior to itself, and that a series of notions supposes a 
 primordial one that is the ground upon which all the others are 
 based. Thus, since moral norms are nothing else but notions, ac- 
 cording to our philosopher, they also suppose a notion which is the 
 first of the whole possible series. And he finds that every moral 
 law is indeed permeated with a common form or idea, as every one 
 indicates and prescribes something common, or what is "moral 
 good" in human action. From that he concludes that all laws are 
 derived from a fundamental one, or, in other words, they are noth- 
 ing else but applications and consequences of a primordial and basic 
 one. That is the fundamental idea through which we form our 
 moral judgments. Now, the question arises: Wliat is this funda- 
 mental idea or notion? What is this primal and basal law? Ros- 
 mini thinks that such notion and law are the outcome neither of 
 
 1 See "Psychology," No. 1339; "Prineipii della scienza morale," Ch. I., 
 a. I., and Ch. II., a. II. " L'essenza," says Eosmiui, "non c se non do che si 
 comprende nella idea della medesima." 
 
 2 "Prineipii," op. cit., Ch. I., a. I. 
 
 28 
 
THE METAPnYSICAL FACTOFi OF MOJ^ALITY 2i) 
 
 experience, nor of reflection, as they iiave nothiiipr to do witli man's 
 sensuous nature, nor with the whole workl of phenomena. Man as 
 sensuous being can aft'ord no foundation for a law which is supposed 
 to be supreme, and independent of all emi)irical motives. Its seat is 
 indeed man as noumenon. to use Kant's language, or his rea.son, 
 that is to say, his essential ami characteristic part. The funda- 
 mental law, however, is not a product of rea.son, as Kant holds it to 
 be. Rosmini thinks that the notion which is the root of all laws 
 and moral noi-ms. which is valid and uniform universally for ra- 
 tional beings, can not be created by reason. According to him. it 
 is an original possession of the mind. Our mind is passive, as the 
 law is given to it prior to all perception or individual cognition. 
 Such a notion, moreover, according to Rosmini, is endowed with 
 immutability, eternity, universality, and necessity.^ 
 
 Now, the idea, endowed with such divine characteristics, can not 
 fail to be the idea of being, not of this or that being, but of uni- 
 versal being. The idea of being is anterior to all .sensations and 
 association, and then to all ideas; it is found at the bottom of every 
 thought ; it is used by our mind as the rule of all our judgments.* 
 Since the first Idea is the factor and source of all judgments, it 
 follows that it is also the factor and source of all ethical judgments, 
 and thus that it is the fundamental law, the generator and the 
 raison d'etre of all laws and moral standards. Besides, since it is 
 the light of reason and since our mind, when it reasons and judges, 
 does nothing but apply it, we ought to follow it wlion we perform 
 our actions. By so doing, we follow a fixed and absolute rule and 
 ideal of rightness, or truth itself. 
 
 But how may the ideal being, or the essence of being, be the su- 
 preme moral rule, or the rule of moral good ? IIow may it ho the 
 means whereby we judge of the good and evil of our actions? IIow 
 may it be the supreme criterion or standard of morality? 
 
 Rosmini thinks that the moral good of liuman conduct is a kind 
 of good ; accordingly, we can not judge of it. unless we have first 
 the notion of good in general. By defining the moral good, we do 
 nothing else than determine and limit the universal notion of 
 good, and adapt it to moral science, which does not deal with the 
 general good, but with a special good, namely, with the moral. 
 What is then good in general ? 
 
 Our philosopher makes an original analysis of th<^ nature of 
 pood. Men, he says, usually claim as "good" the object which 
 pleasantly stimulates and answers to our faculty of desiring, namely, 
 the faculty which impels us to enjoy the good. Of course, an ob- 
 
 « See "Principii, op. cit., Cli. T. 
 
 <See "New Essay on the Origin of Idea?," Nos. 558-574. 
 
30 BOSMINI'S CONTEIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 ject which is provocative of abhorrence rather than of longing to 
 possess and enjoy it, is never said to be "good." Thus the real 
 and concrete good involves some interdependence, some connection, 
 some relation between things and our appetitive power; it implies, 
 from one side, the adaptability, the fitness of things to satisfy our 
 needs, our craving, our personal convenience, and, from the other, 
 the existence of our conative impulse towards them. 
 
 Such interrelation supposes, indeed, a being capable of feeling, 
 of desiring, and of seeking the objects which are endowed with pro- 
 vocative characteristics. Now, may such a being fail to desire itself? 
 No, indeed. Its tendencies fatally converge towards the preserva- 
 tion and development of its own nature. It would be an obvious 
 inconsistency to say that a being might long for its own annihilation, 
 as annihilation is nothing, and nothingness can not be the object of an 
 appetite. Every existing being then has a tendency to unfold itself, to 
 better itself, and to preserve itself. Development, perfection, and 
 preservation are its good. 
 
 The same power of desiring is nothing else but the power of aim- 
 ing at its own perfection, and at everything that has the possibility 
 of helping to reach the natural goal of every being, that is to say, its 
 expansion of life, its totality and completion, or, in a word, its good. 
 
 Good and Being, therefore, are identical terms, and the ancients 
 were right to define good as the end of all things and the object of 
 universal desire. The identity of Good and Being is also confirmed 
 by the analysis of the satisfaction of our appetitive faculty. Ros- 
 mini finds in every satisfaction two elements, namely, a general 
 condition of well-being or an enjoyment, and a perfection, a value, 
 or some worth which is enjoyed. The question naturally arises 
 whether these two elements of the subjective good are necessary to 
 constitute the concept of good, or whether one alone is sufficient. 
 When we indicate the perfections or values of a certain nature, do 
 we not indicate so many goods? Do we not give an account 
 of them before considering any appetitive power? Are we not 
 wont to attribute degrees of perfection and good even to inanimate 
 and insensible natures? Do we not usually say that every thing is 
 good, when it is considered in its own nature? Do we not take as 
 synonymous terms "perfection and good"? Do we not conceive 
 the perfections of the various natures as so many beings inde- 
 pendently of the subject which might be stimulated by them, and 
 might long for them ? Rosmini thinks that man 's idea of perfection 
 or value is the outcome of experience. For a sensible being can 
 not perceive any perfection if it does not feel it; and our mind 
 can not think of a certain good, unless it is presented to it by feeling.^ 
 
 5 See ' ' Principii, ' ' op. cit., Ch. II., a. I. ; his " Ideologia. ' ' 
 
TEE METAPHYSICAL FACTOli OF MOEALITT 31 
 
 Accordingly, the former (luestion may be expressed as follows: 
 Since we can not perceive and hence can not know the worth of 
 the various natures, unless we have some feeling and appetite, does 
 it follow that the feeling and appetite are also necessary to their 
 existence? In other words, may a perfection, a ^'ood, exist without 
 being sensible ? 
 
 Rosmini hokls that it is of the highest iiiipoi'tiuiee to iiotiee that 
 a thing to be evaluated, to be a perfection, must afford some sensible 
 satisfaction, that is to say, its qualities must be felt by some agent. 
 It thus implies some relation to some sense, and then to some being, 
 for whom alone it has value. A perfection which does not give any 
 enjoyment, does not perfect, can not be conceived as such. A per- 
 fection, therefore, involves "sensibility," that is to say, adaptation, 
 aptitude to be felt and desired; it involves some relation to a being 
 endowed with the power of feeling. Even the perfections of inani- 
 mate things are said to be perfections because of their relation to 
 some being furnished with senses. 
 
 Thus, we may conclude that neither enjoyment, nor perfection, 
 alone, is the essential constituent of the idea of good. Both are 
 required to constitute it, as both are so closely interdependent that 
 they can not be conceived a.sunder. A desirable object always pre- 
 supposes a feeling subject; and an object which is enjoyed always 
 involves a relation to some agent ; the goodness of both objects im- 
 plies the exi.stence of some being. The analysis of the subjective 
 and empirical good proves, according to Rosmini, that Being and 
 Good are identical terms. Our philosopher proves their identity 
 by considering the good, not only in its relation to sen.se and appe- 
 tites, and then to some being, but even by the analysis of the concept 
 of good, namely, by investigating what our understanding recog- 
 nizes and distinguishes within the concept of good. According to 
 him. our undei'standing considering good as its own object, or as 
 concept, sees it stripped of its relation to feeling. For it is its law 
 to forget, or, at lea.st, not to notice what is mingled at the very be- 
 giiHiing of the process of formation of concepts. These being 
 formed, are kept under a synthetic condition, inuler a fornnda of 
 what our understanding saw in the first and immediate cognition, 
 and to it we refer, without paying any more attention to what is 
 present in .sen.sation. In like manner, if we examine the origin of 
 our idea of good and perfection, we find that at the very beginning 
 we have aasociated an agreeable .sensation with it. .so that we did 
 not recognize any good, uidess it was followed by .some plea.sant 
 impression. After having acquired the habit of attributing the 
 concept of perfection to things we have known by experience to be 
 pleasant, we think of them, without paying any more attention to 
 
32 BOSMINI'S CONTFIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 their power of modifying us pleasantly. Thus the term "perfec- 
 tion" is gradually freed in our mind from its relation to the senses; 
 it acquires a general value; it becomes a universal concept, and 
 thus independent of its connection with sensuous nature, Rosmini 
 notices that our understanding goes further in this process of ideal- 
 ization, as it also observes the pleasant or painful condition of the 
 human body to correspond to a certain disposition of its parts, to a 
 certain order in the measure, in the form, in the number, in the re- 
 ciprocal connection and action of its parts. Thus, such intrinsic 
 order, to which a pleasant sensation corresponds, is considered as 
 perfection of the human body. In that case, however, we still call 
 perfection the condition of the body coexistent with the agreeable 
 feeling. But we afterwards generalize our own experience, and, ob- 
 serving the other beings, animate and sensible like us, regard them 
 as perfect, because we are aware that they realize their ideal type, 
 they arc what they ought to be, they "are," namely, they conform 
 to their essence, and, accordingly, they seem to enjoy the most 
 pleasant existence. 
 
 In the same manner, we see inanimate beings to be more or less 
 fit to subserve our own needs, or those of other beings, because they 
 have a certain condition, configuration, and composition, or, in other 
 words, they are what they ought to be, namely, useful and agree- 
 able. In all these cases the term "perfection" has the meaning of 
 the intrinsic order, of the most complete condition of development 
 and realization of every being. 
 
 Such essential order, however, such completeness or perfection 
 exists only within our understanding, because of its own process, as 
 concept or, what is just the same for Rosmini, as essence. Thus, 
 the essence of a being is its ideal type, or the rule or criterion, ac- 
 cording to which we judge of the degrees of its goodness. We 
 think its good to be what is required by its essence, what unfolds 
 and realizes it, or, in other words, what is appropriate to its nature, 
 and harmonizes with its existence. 
 
 The energies of every being naturally seek that end, as its most 
 perfect and typical condition. Thus the analysis of the idea of 
 good shows that Being and Good are two terms involving each other ; 
 that they are two aspects of the same truth. The Scholastic saying 
 ^'ens et honum convertuntur" is justified. Now, it is important to 
 notice that the value, perfection, or the good of beings is contem- 
 plated, indeed, by our intelligence, but it is contemplated, accord- 
 ing to Rosmini, as something real, objective, and then independently 
 of the pleasant sensuous effect, as it is seen under the light of the 
 primordial object of our mind, or, of ideal being. Whence it fol- 
 lows that all essences are nothing else, for our philosopher, but de- 
 
THE METAPHYSICAL FACTOIl OF MORALITY 33 
 
 terminations and limitations of the universal and ideal Being itself. 
 Besides, it follows that the idea of good, like the idea of being, is 
 more general than sensation, it is prior to it. 
 
 Rosmini notices, moreover, tliat, since the vahie or good of a 
 being is found in the realization of its essence, it follows tiiat every- 
 thing which opposes and thwarts the process of its development is 
 evil. Thus evil is. not absolute negation of good, but lack of some 
 perfection. Accordingly, a series of values, of good, may be found 
 in every beinir. starting inmi its first and imperfect existence and end- 
 ing with its last stage of development and realization. The more ade- 
 (|uately, then, a being realizes its ideal, the more entity it has, the 
 greater is its good. Now, since Being and (iood are one and the same 
 thing, it is obvious that we know the value or the degree of perfection 
 of a being, when we possess its idea ; when we know its essence, its de- 
 gree of existence, as well as its intrinsic order and how far it is real- 
 ized. Besides, from the identity of Being and Good it may be con- 
 cluded that the notion whereby both are known by us is the same. 
 Since, according to Rosmini, the idea of being is the origin of all be- 
 ings, it follows that it is also the origin of all goods; and as it is the 
 means whereby we know all beings, it is evident that it is also the 
 means whereby we know and valuate every kind of good, namely, the 
 good which satisfies .some agent, or subjective good, as well as the 
 good which is independent of all personal and empirical motives, and 
 which is good in itself, or objective good. 
 
 From the fact that Being and CTOod are identical Rosmini finally 
 infei-s the concept of Absolute Good. As Absolute Being is the 
 being which has the whole of es.sence within itself, so also Absolute 
 Good is the good which includes the whole of good. The Complete 
 Being is the Complete Good, which lacks nothing, and for this 
 rea.son it is ab.solute. The Complete Being, however, is the supreme 
 good, not only in and for itself, but it is also the supreme good rela- 
 tively to particular beings. Rosmini calls the complete and abso- 
 lute Being, which is by the same fact the snpreme and absolute 
 Good, "God." God, therefore, is the end of human activity. To 
 become one with ITim is the high destiny of man as rational being." 
 
 Now. to understand Rosmini 's point of view, it is of the highest 
 importance to notice what is fundamental in his ethical theory. He 
 holds that everj' real individual, realizing his own es.sence, does 
 iiothing but realize the essence of being. Since this partakes of 
 the universal, infinite, necessary, and divine essence, it partakes of 
 the Absolute Being, of God Himself. Bv the same fact, everv real 
 individual by realizing good partakes of the Absolute Good. Thns 
 
 cSee "Principii," op. cit., Ch. III., a. VII F. 
 
34 BOSMINI'S CONTSIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 the Absolute Good is the goal of rational activity, and ought to be 
 recognized and loved wherever found. 
 
 Every man, therefore, according to Rosmini, as rational being, 
 and thus partaking of God Himself, makes a moral demand, that 
 is to say, he demands to be recognized and loved, because of his 
 participation in the Absolute Being and Good. The essence of 
 morality, then, or, the ultimate ground of every moral law, of every 
 moral obligation, lies in the respect due to Infinite Essence. Ac- 
 cordinglj'-, the principle of morality may be formulated in the fol- 
 lowing law: ''Recognize the essence of being J' But to recognize 
 the essence of being is the same as to recognize its goodness ; we can 
 say then that the principle of morality consists in the practical 
 recognition of every being, according to the good it is found to 
 possess, that is to say, according to its value and worth. 
 
 Now, since the essence of morality is identical with the essence 
 of being, it must be endowed with the same characteristics. Since 
 the essence of being is objective (because it is independent of every 
 subject), so also is moral good or the essence of morality. We do 
 not create it; we only verify it. The essential law of pure reason, 
 according to Rosmini, consists in grasping being in itself, so also the 
 law of practical reason is the good appreciated in itself, or, in its 
 intrinsic and objective value, not according to the merely personal 
 and subjective profit which may derive to the agent from his faith- 
 fulness to duty. Besides, good partakes of the immutability of 
 Being; its stability is then eternal. The good which is object of 
 human actions is, finally, as the essence of being, divine and infinite. 
 God, therefore, ought to be, according to our philosopher, the focus 
 of thought and love, the satisfaction of man 's intelligence and heart. 
 Moreover, since the principle of morality and obligation consists 
 in the practical recognition of every being, according to its essence 
 and goodness, it follows that we must distribute our love among 
 things in proportion to their respective grades of being, and prefer 
 the greater to the lesser grade. ''I must prefer my country," says 
 Rosmini, ''to my life." The moral law says absolutely: "Sacrifice 
 thyself for thy country."^ 
 
 But here it may be asked: How can man, a finite being, ascend 
 to the knowledge and practical recognition of the essence of beings, 
 which is infinite? How can he measure the degrees of entity? 
 Wliat is the first and supreme rule whereby we know when and how 
 the principle of obligation must be applied? Rosmini answers that 
 man is endowed by nature with the intuition of the essence of being. 
 By means of this intuition, he is fitted to know and measure every 
 essence and then every goodness. Since the idea of being is the 
 
 7 "Theodicy," No. 725. 
 
THE METAPHYSICAL FACTOR OF MORALITY 35 
 
 supreme rule whereby we conceive and measure the entity of beings, 
 and con.se(iuently the objective good, or, moral good, end of human 
 actions, the ethical formula "Follow the litjht of reason," may be 
 translated into this other: "Follow the idea of good, as it shoivs 
 you the measure of the entity of every being/' To know its entity 
 is to know its value, its worth, its dignity, and its right to be recog- 
 nized for what it is and to be loved accordingly.** 
 
 Thus, according to Rosmini, the idea of being is the ground of 
 ethical judgments; it is the source of morality and obligation; it is 
 the metaphysical basis of the law of knowledge and action. Epis- 
 temolog}' and ethics have the same foundation, independent of man's 
 experience. This is the kernel of Rosmini 's ethical theory! 
 
 8 "Theodicy," No. 725. 
 
CHAPTER II 
 The Psychological Factor of Morality 
 
 The whole value, the whole good, of beings lies, according to 
 Rosmini, in the fact that beings, realizing their own essence, partake 
 of the infinite, immutable, and absolute essence of the Supreme Be- 
 ing. Their good, however, if it is known and enjoyed only by in- 
 telligence, is "objective good." 
 
 Intelligence considers them in themselves, independently of every 
 personal interest, of every empirical motive, and, by so doing, it 
 attributes to them that which really belongs to them, and thus it does 
 them justice. The moral good, then, can not be anything else than 
 the objective good. And the supreme moral law, the whole moral 
 legislation is rooted and grounded in the objective good, or, in 
 other words, in the Absolute and Eternal. But the possibility of 
 man's subordination to a certain law depends upon its promulga- 
 tion. Man must have knowledge of the law in question ; it must be 
 present in his mind as an idea; for when man obeys a normative 
 rule, he adjusts his rational activity, his will, to it. The root of 
 human activity lies in knowledge itself; action is always directed 
 by idea; and will terminates through action in an object known and 
 set before it by intelligence.^ 
 
 The supreme moral law, therefore, or the objective good, must 
 be, indeed, present to the intelligence, not as a mere object of con- 
 templation. If the will does not intervene to will it, after having 
 knowm it, objective good does not acquire the characteristic of moral 
 good. A merely speculative, formal, sterile knowledge of the good 
 can not constitute the notion of moral good. When the agent wills 
 the good known already by his intelligence, the good is moral. Thus 
 the moral good is, according to Rosmini, the objective good, known 
 by the intelligence and willed by the will.^ 
 
 The quality of morality is simply the relation of the objective 
 good to the intelligent nature willing it. Now, Rosmini thinks that 
 the supreme and fundamental law of morality has been promul- 
 gated to man from the early dawn of his life. Since the idea of 
 being is the light of reason itself, or ''a spark of the divine fire" 
 which enables man to know the entity of beings, it performs the 
 
 1 " Theodicy, " Nos. 398, 631, 637, 644. 
 2"Prmeipii," op. cit., Ch. IV., a. VI. 
 
 36 
 
THE PSYCHOLOGICAL FACTOR OF MORALITY 37 
 
 function of the supreme moral law ; since it is innate, it follows 
 that we carry within ourselves the germ of morals, the source of 
 the whole moral legislation ; we bear within ourselves the reason or 
 will of God Himself, unceasingly proclaiming what is right. ^ 
 
 Thus, for Rosmini. the fundamental law or notion of morality is 
 not the outcome of the course of experience, but something imposed, 
 originating from a transcentlental, invisible authority. The mind 
 is merely passive when it receives the principle of morality, as it 
 can not be legislator to itself; it can impo.se no norms, no standards 
 of action on itself. Accordingly, the basis and justifying principle 
 of the ethical judgment lie outside of the mind itself in transcen- 
 dental conceptions, or considerations that do not result from human 
 experience. Our philosopher is thoroughly convinced that the prin- 
 ciple of morality can not be empirically acquired, but that it must 
 be implanted, because it is universal and categoric ; it is truth itself, 
 whereas experience, however repeated and multiplied, never gives 
 anytiiing more than particular facts.* 
 
 Rca.sons and laws can not be received by the senses; essentially 
 unknown to sense, they are manifest only to rational natures.^ The 
 principle of morality is, therefore, infused into our reason. Thus, 
 it is abstract and .static ! 
 
 But Being has, for Rosmini, always this essential characteristic, 
 that it is good, and hence it can not be known except as good. Now, 
 the knowledge of it as good implies an affection, an inclination 
 toward it. Just as Being, in its character of "light," creates the 
 intellect, a formal cause of the human soul, so the same being, in its 
 essential character of "good," creates the "primitive will," as the 
 final cause which actuates the first affection, the first volition, di- 
 rected to universal being. And as the intellect is the receptive 
 power, so the will is the active power which corresponds to it. Now, 
 according to our philosopher, the intellect has, as its essential object, 
 ideal being. Being is immutable, the intellect, then, has the nature 
 of an "immanent" act rather than of a power. In the same way 
 it may be said that the primitive and universal will has not the 
 nature of a power, but of an immanent act. which is the principle 
 and basis of power. Hence Rosmini prefers to call it "primitive 
 volition," in.stead of primitive will." 
 
 3 " Compcndio di etica." Nos. 5.3, .54; "Theodicy," Nos. 5, 2.59. 262. 
 
 *"Thcodirj-." Nos. 13,8. IM, 1.51. 2.5!). 
 
 5 "Principii," op. dt., Ch. T., a. III. Rosmini think.s that his conception 
 conforni5< to Marcus Aurelius's conception of fundamental law. "Hanc video 
 sapicnti.s.'timorum fuissp scntcntiam, legem neque hominuvi intjeniis rnpHafam, 
 nee scitum nliquod ease populorum, sed (uternum quiddam, quod univcrsum mun- 
 dum regeret, imperandi, prohibendiquc sapicntia." (*'De Leg.," IT.) 
 
 • "Psychology," Nos. 1008-1011. "The immanent act is that which en- 
 
38 HOSMINI'S CONTSIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHT 
 
 Man, accordingly, by the intuition of the essence of the uni- 
 versal being, is enabled to know the essence of real and individual 
 beings, that is to say, their value, their worth, and their "claim" to 
 be recognized and loved. For the same reason he has a natural and 
 spontaneous predisposition toward the universal being or universal 
 good. And since the moral principle imposes adhesion to the known 
 entity of beings, man is by nature predisposed to act in accordance 
 with the fundamental moral law. Such a force which tends to the 
 whole of being, to universal good, may be called "moral," because 
 it comes from being and goes to beiug.^ 
 
 Thus the human will carries within itself a relation of con- 
 formity to the first and eternal law, or notion of being. Man, as a 
 real being, is finite, but by the intuition of Being, he is also intel- 
 lective and moral, and partakes of the infinite. His tendency, how- 
 ever, to act morally, that which Rosmini calls "moral liberty," in so 
 far as it is natural and spontaneous, is not meritorious. Man is neces- 
 sitated to act with moral liberty, that is to say, he is determined to 
 his action, not by external cause, but by his inner impelling bent to 
 adhere to good in general. This natural inclination of the subject 
 to universal good is what constitutes the will itself.'^ 
 
 The will, regarded as such, is not the source of merit ; it deserves 
 neither praise nor blame.'' But if the will acts in accordance with 
 this first activity, it preserves in its operation an order altogether 
 analogous and corresponding to the order of being itself, and by 
 this order it is determined to act with moral perfection. This 
 point of view evidently involves a deterministic and intellectualistic 
 conception of the will, and makes the decision of the will exclusively 
 dependent on inner insight. 
 
 Does it mean that Rosmini does not believe in the freedom of 
 the human will? Rosmini believes in it, and gives an original and 
 interesting analysis of it. Liberty, according to him, springs up 
 at a certain stage of the psychic process of action. Doubtless it 
 does not intervene in the intuition of the essence of being, since this 
 is absolute and necessary. This essential and divine power is given 
 to man and he does not contribute anything to it. Nor does liberty 
 intervene in the spontaneous and immanent tendency which the 
 
 dures with a being so long as no substantial change supervenes in it. ' ' Ibid., 
 1205. 
 
 7 See "Psychology," No. 896; "Etiea," Nos. 514-525; "Teosofia," No. 
 1037. Such moral force is called by Eosniini " Preponderanza morale." It is 
 nothing else but what is called by St. Thomas "Bonum naturae, scilicet naturalis 
 inclinatio ad virtutem," la, Ilae, q. LXIII. and LXXXV., a. I. 
 
 8 See "Teosofia," No. 1037; "Etica," No. 29. 
 
 9 Dante expresses the identical idea^ when he says, ' ' Qiiesta prima voglia 
 Merto di lode o di iiasimo non cape. ' ' Purg. XIXVIII., 59, 60. 
 
THE PSTCnOLOGICAL FACTOR OF MOEALITT 39 
 
 idea of being or the liglit of reason produces in the will, impellinf* 
 it to adhere to, and love, all entity and good. It may be said that 
 the divine craves for the divine which is found in every intelligent 
 being. Liberty, finally, does not intervene in the external action, 
 as that depends on the will, subordiiuited. already, to a certain nor- 
 mative rule, and determined thereby. The role of free will, there- 
 fore, the merit or demerit of actions, and the responsibility of the 
 agent, are to be sought elsewhere. 
 
 Rosmini thinks that man is endowcil ns ith a twofold activity; as 
 an intelligent being he is endowed with rational activity; as a real 
 being he is endowed with sensuous activity. Now, if he were merely 
 intelligent, if he could shuffle off his mortal coil of animal ([ualities, 
 he would be in a state of pure intelligence ; he would comnnuiicate 
 with beings by means of his reason ; he would perceive their whole 
 entity by the same means, and, bj' perceiving their entity, he would 
 perceive also their value, their good. Such transcendental knowl- 
 edge would, of course, induce a universal rational love for all beings ; 
 such universal love would afford intellectual delight to man, rid of 
 his animality. This whole process would be spontaneous, neces- 
 sary, voluntary, as the will of the rational luiture would then follow 
 its own natural inclination. Man, therefore, as an intelligent being, 
 would always act morally, namely, according to his natural rational 
 predisposition toward universal being and good, as well as in ac- 
 cordance with the moral demand of beings to be recognized and 
 loved, in proportion to their entity. As a real being, however, man 
 is endowed with feeling, with physical qualities and needs; in other 
 words, he feels impelled by an inner physical force to act for his 
 own satisfaction, pleasure, or happiness. 
 
 If this activity which, aims, not at the good in itself, but at the 
 good of the agent, could be naturally conformed with the rational 
 and immanent activity, the freedom of the will would be useless. 
 But it happens that both activities come into collision and seek to 
 determine the will in opposite directions; either of which alone would 
 suffice to make it act. At this crucial stage, the objects of opposite 
 order, radically different, produce two kinds of volition. Both 
 volitions are possible; as the one may determine the will towards 
 the intellective and objective good, aiul the other towards the sensi- 
 tive and subjective good. The choice between the two possible voli- 
 tions is free. There is no coercion. Man has. according to Rosmini. 
 the power of making one volition prevail over another, and thus of 
 determining himself to action. This power which the will pos.sesses, 
 is called by Rosmini "liberty of indifference," "bilateral-liberty," 
 or "meritorious libcrtv." 
 
40 EOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 But how does the will display such a power? How does one 
 volition prevail over another? How is the choice between two con- 
 trary volitions brought about? Rosmini holds that the will is a 
 power which acts in accordance with the reasons that man has in 
 his mind and proposes to himself. Whence we may conclude that 
 the will can not operate unless man has reasons or knowledge, ac- 
 cording to which he might deliberate, choose, and will. The reason 
 or motive, however, does not determine the will. 
 
 The determining force, the power of free choice, or "liberty," 
 lies within the agent himself. Liberty affords the agent, in the 
 presence of several motives, the power of making one motive prevail 
 over all others so that the predominating motive determines the will 
 to act." 
 
 Rosmini, however, does not mean that a motive might have the 
 force of directing choice. According to him, there are two kinds 
 of cognition. The first cognition of things is direct, immediate, in- 
 stinctive, necessary, and so not voluntary. Through it we are fur- 
 nished with ideas of thicgs. The understanding forms perceptions, 
 and such ideas as are consequent on these, in an instinctive and 
 natural manner, and, for tliat reason it is not liable to error, for 
 nature does not err. Through this first intellective apprehension 
 we perceive the thing in its entirety, by a simple act, as if it were a 
 simple object. Thus, the direct cognition is purely synthetic; it is 
 the primitive, spontaneous synthesis of being and sensation. Let 
 us notice that in perceiving the things as a whole, we have no in- 
 terest to perceive them in one manner rather than in another. We 
 are then merely passive.^^ 
 
 Besides, we must notice that in perceiving the entity of beings, 
 we have a conception of their value. Accordingly, direct cognition 
 enables our theoretical reason to make speculative judgments and 
 acquire speculative knowledge. The first ideas, however, by which 
 we know things are for Rosmini equally indifferent ; they have, in 
 other words, not purposive, but representative character only. Thus 
 Rosmini fails to notice that all our consciousness is dynamogenic, 
 and that an idea is a nascent act. Our philosopher, however, thinks 
 that the need of action impels the will to reflection, that is to say, 
 to turn back upon what we before perceived directly and involun- 
 tarily; it urges the rational, active power to analyze, decompose, 
 and consider previous and direct cognitions. 
 
 This process of reflection, of analysis, which is thoroughly volun- 
 tary and practical involves a ''practical evaluation" or "judgment" 
 
 10 ' ' Antropologia, ' ' Ch. VII. 
 
 11 See "New Essay on the Origin of Ideas," Vol. III.. Nos. 1258, 1259, 
 1261; "Principii," op. cit., Ch. V., a. III. 
 
THE PSYCnOLOGICAL FACTOR OF MORALITY 41 
 
 of the things, known already throu^rh previous, immediate cogni- 
 tion. At tliis stage the will displays its power of liberty. For it is 
 free to appreciate and recognize things as they are in cognition and 
 to adhere to their entity as known, as it is free to alter their value 
 by arbitrarily increasing or diminishing for itself the degrees of 
 being or entity, thus substituting another entity, feigned and created 
 by the energy of its own caprice. The volitional activity then mani- 
 fests itself by "recognition," either simple or fictitious. It implies, 
 indeed, a previous cognition as well as no alteration of its object. 
 This voluntary recognition is an assent to immediate cognition; it 
 is true, just, moral, if the will, in i-ecognizing the previously known 
 entity, does not alter its value, but is content with that measure of 
 value which direct cognitinn prescribes. On the contrary, it is 
 unjust and immoral, if the will assumes that the entity of things is 
 different from the one contained in the direct cognition, and thus 
 estimates it at more or at less than its true worth, recognizing it as 
 what it is not. not as what it is. 
 
 This practical force of arbitrary evaluation is simjily the reason 
 which prevails and determines the choice. Without the practical 
 force there is no determination, but a mere inclination which does 
 not end in choice. Thus, given the case in which each of two voli- 
 tions has in its favor a reason of equal weight, the free will can. by 
 increasing the force of the reason which is favorable to it, choose one 
 rather than the other. Whence Rosmini concludes that the will may 
 conform its activity to its moral liberty or to the moral claim of 
 beings, and thus to the good, or to the opposite, and thus be unjust 
 and evil.'- 
 
 He notices, besides, that practical esteem produces a "practical 
 love." We act because we are impelled by a practical love which 
 prevails over other loves. We are free to will or not to will actions, 
 because we are free to love or not to love them, to increase or di- 
 minish our love or our hatred of this or that action. This power 
 of ours which is called liberty is practised first on the affections of 
 our heart, and through it on tlie actions themselves. 
 
 But when we love a thing, we love it because we consider it good ; 
 we may, indeed, love something evil, but when we do so, we love it 
 "suh specie honi." Thus, the intrinsic nature of love involves 
 esteem of the object loved; our personal valuation is a factor in our 
 own loving." 
 
 To sum up; the process of the moral act, according to Rosmini, 
 
 i»See "Psychology." No. llO.'i; " Antropolopia," Nos. (536-64.^; "The- 
 odicy," No. 621; "Etica," Ch. III., a. I., II., III.; "Principii," op. cit., 
 Ch. V. 
 
 13 See "Principii," op. cit.. Hi. V., a. TIT. 
 
 I 
 
 I 
 
42 EOSMINI'S CONTEIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 is as follows: we first have ideas and memories of things; we have 
 direct and necessary cognitions: we see things as they are. After 
 the will provokes the reflection upon these things known, this volun- 
 tary reflection is just or unjust, according as it tends to recognize 
 faithfully the direct cognition, or to alter it. The agent, during 
 voluntary reflection, concentrates his attention, or meditates, upon 
 the immediate cognition. Out of this voluntary meditation springs 
 a keen and active apprehension, which is true or false, according as 
 the act of the will, directing reflection, was right or perverse. The 
 apprehension ends in a practical judgment or esteem. The prac- 
 tical valuation produces an intellectual delight or sorrow. Such a 
 delight is the beginning of the love that immediately follows it as 
 its completion and end, as such a sorrow is the beginning of the 
 hatred that immediately follows it as its mark and fulfilment. 
 
 The external action is the last stage of the complex psychic 
 process which the will instigates, under the pressure of action, carry- 
 ing out its power of liberty. Liberty, then, according to Rosmini, 
 consists in self-determination; the will uses its power of free choice 
 between volitions, categorically different, only when there is con- 
 flict between subjective and objective good, that is to say, between 
 duty, virtue, moral law, and pleasure, satisfaction, happiness, or, 
 in other words, between the ideal and the real, the infinite and finite. 
 Accordingly, it must be the law of the rational principle to consider 
 the value of being in itself, independently of the accidental and real 
 action which it exercises on the rational subject. That value must, 
 therefore, be measured by ideal being, and not by considerations of 
 subjective advantage and disadvantage, and must be estimated by 
 comparison with ideal being. Our practical reason must not esti- 
 mate its object at a different value from that which it has in itself 
 considered with respect to ideal being. It must act in view of the 
 true measure of that object discovered by comparison with the es- 
 sence of being intuited by the mind in universal-ideal being. To 
 act according to this measure is to act rationally and, hence, mor- 
 ally; to act from the mere impulse of the real action which an object 
 exercises on us, is to abandon the law of reason, to follow that of 
 blind, or merely sensible, real being. To act morally, in other words, 
 we must direct our actions to being, as it is their natural end ; thus 
 we must forget ourselves and objectify ourselves in being, or in 
 the object of our activity, as intelligent beings. And as the object 
 of our rational and moral actions is the Infinite, we must merge our- 
 selves in the Infinite, Supreme Being, the Absolute Good. AVlien 
 we love a thing, when we think of it, we do nothing but bring our- 
 selves into the same thing as term of our love and thought, and forget 
 
THE PSYCHOLOGICAL FACTOR OF MOLALITY 43 
 
 and, in a sense, annihilate ourselves. That is what Rosmini wants 
 us to do before the objective, infinite, moral good, the goal of onr 
 rational aetivity.^^ By so doing, we perform a voluntary recogni- 
 tion of what we first necessarily know; we welcome the good of the 
 things we have perceived; we recognize what is true. nay. truth it- 
 self; and thus we subordinate ourselves to the fundamental prin- 
 ciple of moralit}'; we ai"e inoi-ally ^'ood and acfoinplish our supreme 
 duty. 
 
 Now, since the principle of cognition which constitutes the su- 
 preme law, according to which tiie theoretic reason operates, sup- 
 plies, likewise, the law, according to whidi the practical reason ouglit 
 to operate, it follows that if the law of tin' theoretic reason says: 
 "Being is the object of knowing,'' the law of the practical reason 
 says: "Being ought to be object of practical knowing.""^ 
 
 Let us notice here that Rosmini 's endeavors to distinguish reason 
 into theoretical and practical have proved to be vain. He does not, 
 indeed, regard, like Kant, the theoretical reason and the practical 
 reason as two faculties radically different.'" lie thinks that there 
 is but one rational principle, which in so far as it knows is called 
 "theoretic," and in so far as it acts is called "practical." But he 
 identifies them dc facto. And, indeed, since speculative reason is 
 constituted by the intuition of being in general, since the practical 
 reason is the same recognition of the essence of beings, and since 
 good, the term of the practical reason, and being, the terra of pure 
 reason, are one and the same thing, inasmuch as they are con- 
 vertible terms, it follows that both pure and practical reason have 
 the same object and term ; there is no conflict between them ; they 
 are not distinct, but are one reason, one instrument of activity; and 
 thus the rational principle which is found in man is for practise, 
 action, life. 
 
 jNIoreover, let us notice that Rosmini. making morality dependent 
 only upon knowledge, fails to consider man in his totality, as he neg- 
 lects to pay attention to the life of feeling which, as well as the life 
 of reason, claims to be a basis of ethical judging. 
 
 Finally, it is of the highest importance to notice that Rosmini 
 derives the conception of human dignity from the fact that man is 
 endowed with the intuition of Being, whereby he is enabled to ])er- 
 eeive, recognize, and love the entity of beings, and, since their entity 
 is nothing but participation in the Absolute, it follows that man is 
 
 i« " PsTchology, " No. 1429; "Theodicy." Nos. 384-415; "Teosofia." II.; 
 "PrJncipii," op. dt., Ch. V. 
 
 i5'<PsycholoKi'," No. 1399. 
 16 See "Theodicy," No. 161. 
 
44 BOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 enabled to know, recognize, and love the Infinite, the Absolute, or 
 
 God Himself. 
 
 Besides, the light of reason, with which man is by nature en- 
 dowed, is participation in God's light. It is, for Rosmini as for 
 Flavins Justin, the natural revelation of the divine and "germinant 
 Logos." Thus, man partakes of God's dignity. Accordingly, he 
 can not be regarded as a means, but only as an end." 
 
 "See "Principii," op. cit., Ch. III., a. IX.; Ch. IV., a. VIII. and IX.; 
 "Storia comparativa," Ch. I., a. III.; "Teosofia," No. 831; "Etica," Nos. 
 98, 99, 102-104. 
 
CONCLUSION 
 
 The theory of ideal being is the basis of Rosmiiii's vast philo- 
 sophical edifiee; it is the unifying faetor in his whole system of 
 thought; it is the starting point of every philosophical problem lie 
 confronts and discusses, as well as of his theory of ethics. His 
 entire philosophy, then, stands and falls with the doctrine of being. 
 
 The fundamental error in Rosmini's system of philosophy and of 
 ethics lies in his method. He begins with the universal or idea, and 
 attempts to descend to the particular or the phenomenal. Thus he 
 begins with an a priori element, with a theory of what is prior to 
 every experien ?, with the highest abstraction, since the idea of 
 being is one of the last terms of our intellectual elaboration that 
 supposes, indeed, a series of previous operations. Now, to assume 
 an abstraction, as the starting point of knowledge, is to assume a 
 psychological and epistemological impossibility. Positive facts con- 
 stitute the beginning of human knowledge. Something abstract, 
 extra-empirical, can not be the object of experience, of idealization, 
 of desire, of interest, as it has no value, no meaning for life, and 
 consequently it can be neither stimulus nor response to any need or 
 demand. The function of thinking is aroused by the presence of 
 some object, which involves reaction or adjustment. 
 
 It can not be denied, indeed, that every judgment iinplit's the 
 notion of being, but we can not from this fact conclude that the 
 idea of being exists within our mind, prior to all experience, and 
 that it may be the main factor of all our intellectual development. 
 The substitution of idea for fact, of intuition for perception, is an 
 arbitrary and unscientific substitution. In fact, how can we pass 
 from the mere notion of being to real being, from a mere abstract 
 form of our mind to life? What bridges the gulf between the ideal 
 and the real? According to Hegel it is "becoming"; according to 
 Gioberti it is "creation"; according to Rosmini it is an uncontrolled 
 synthesis between perception aiul ideal being. 
 
 Ro.smini endeavors, indeed, to solve the diflieulty by holding that 
 the idea of possil)le being, indeterminate in itself, is determined by 
 the act of perception, and thus it becomes the idea of a real being. 
 
 But such a postulate is not at all justified, and contains contra- 
 dictory affirmations. Tlie idea of a possible being, as it is sim|)le 
 and indeterminate, can not uiulergo the slightest change or modifi- 
 cation, without being no longer what it was, without annihilating 
 
 45 
 
46 EOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 itself, for the sake of being replaced by a new idea. Thus the latter 
 would not be a transformation, but a suppression of the first. 
 
 The phenomenon of perception proves to be impossible in Ros- 
 mini's psychological theory. Perception is an act of adjustment of 
 the organism to the environment, and we do not need any abstrac- 
 tion as means of performing such a biological function. 
 
 Besides, let us remark against Rosmini's theory of knowledge 
 what Aristotle noticed against that of Plato, that is to say that our 
 knowledge does not begin with universal, since our knowledge of 
 the individual precedes our knowledge of the universal.^ 
 
 Moreover, Rosmini, following Plato, hypostatizes the universal, 
 attributing to it a separate existence, characterized by immutability 
 and eternity. But we may object to Plato as well as to Rosmini that 
 the universal can not exist apart from the individual, since, if it did 
 so, the transition from a knowledge of the one to a knowledge of 
 the other would be impossible. Finally, Rosmini holds the uni- 
 versal to be ready-made, apart from phenomena, while we may say 
 that the formal aspect of universality is a production of the mind, 
 and, therefore, the universal, as such, does not exist in individual 
 things, but in the mind alone. It seems to be arbitrary to derive 
 the universal from a transcendental entity as Rosmini does. I can 
 not help regarding as a mere chimera the belief in anj'- abstract idea, 
 containing intelligible essence, and conditioning and determining, 
 as an eternal archetype, reality, the data of experience which is 
 concrete, particular, and determined in space and time. 
 
 To believe in such a thing is to believe that human science may 
 be severed into two orders of objects, absolutely distinct, and having 
 no other relation than a kind of parallelism in their development. 
 The abstract and the concrete are characterized by profound dif- 
 ferences, but, in spite of those differences, both are products of ex- 
 perience. 
 
 But Rosmini's final motive was that of Plato, and he felt it 
 necessary to assume the same rationalistic attitude, and to base his 
 ethics upon metaphysical, or rather mythical epistemology. He, as 
 well as Plato, thought that the knowledge in which virtue is to con- 
 sist must be the cognition of what is truly real, as opposed to opin- 
 ions which may be only relative, and dependent on phenomena, on 
 empirical and subjective motives, thus compromising true knowledge 
 and morals. The leading motive of both philosophers proved to b*» 
 ethico-social, since both wanted to check the moral disintegration of 
 their countries and to lift up the moral standard of national life 
 by indicating moral conduct as factor of true happiness, individual 
 as well as social. Thus the common ideal of their philosophical en- 
 
 1 "Eth. Nic," VI., II., 11-13, b5. 
 
CONCLUSION 47 
 
 deavors was to win true virtuo by true kiiowlod<]:o. So I think that 
 Kosinini assumed as thesis of his epistemologfieal and metaphysical 
 doctrine of ethics, the thesis discussed, in a special way, in IMato's 
 Meno.- 
 
 Phito was convinced that the fundamental principle of morals 
 was exposed to the danger of contiiuious change by the Protagorean 
 doctrhie of relativity. He thou^dit, accordingly, that as Socrates 
 had fii-st taught, virtue is knowleilge, and knowledge of the good. 
 But he thought, moreover, that the absolute truth of conceptual 
 knowledge consists in the fact that it conc(>ivcs in the idea the true 
 being, iiulepentlent of every change. 
 
 Rosmini, like Parmenides, Socrates, and Plato, wanted to place 
 rea.son in opposition to opinion; he thought that sensationalism and 
 empiricism, whii'h were the prevalent currents of piiilosophical 
 thought in Italy at that time of national becoming, compromised or 
 nullified the fundamental principles of epistemology and ethics. 
 Accordingly, identifying being with good, in a Euclidean manner, 
 presupposed a changeless supreme idea in man, as the rational 
 measure, rule, and end of human actions, as it is also the funda- 
 mental source of epistemological and ethical law. lie intciulcd 
 thereby to furnish the new national life with a basis eternally im- 
 mune to change ; he intended to respond to the need of new ideals, 
 of new intellectual beauty, which the revival of Christian ideals 
 and the influence of romanticism brought into every province of life. 
 
 Rosmini, as well as Scotus Erigina. making the individual de- 
 pendent upon the universal, meant to subordinate all the particular 
 forces to the almighty authority of the Supreme Being, and of the 
 Cluirch. He intended, indeed, to focus the minds of the oppressed 
 Italians as well of the oppressors of that time and of all time, upon 
 an inexhaustible .source of truth and justice, (juite independent of 
 all circumstances and motives. That is the reason why he does not 
 account for the dynamic, progressive character of morality, and 
 thinks the moral life to be a changeless structure. He, moreover, 
 intended to say that duties and rights undergo no change, as the 
 moral order does not depend upon the will and the caprices of men, 
 but upon the Absolute, Eternal, Supreme Being. 
 
 The unchangeable moral principle consists in the practical recog- 
 nition of the entity or the good, partaken of by im-n. oi-. in other 
 words, in the love for all who enjoy the divine within themselves. 
 Such an idea, while it suggested reciprocal love and union to the 
 groaning hearts of the Italians, kindled also their ardent desire for 
 political cmatn'ipation. The fundamental moral law. divine in its 
 
 -See " rhacilo, " ami "Republic,'' especially Books IV. and V. 
 
48 BOSMINI'S CONTRIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 origin and nature, imposed on the oppressor's recognition of, and 
 veneration for, human dignity. 
 
 Human rights are sacred as duty is sacred. Since justice is 
 grounded in God's will, Rosmini meant that Italy's political de- 
 liverance and unity were God's will as well. Thus the Italian philos- 
 opher indirectly intended to foster the national aspirations of his 
 compatriots and to help modify their political and social situation. 
 
 But the principle upon which Rosmini endeavored to build his 
 system of ethics, although clothed with rational form, is religious 
 and theological, and, therefore, more adapted to moral theology than 
 to scientfic ethics. A scientific theory of ethics can not be grounded 
 upon an abstract and mystical presupposition, since what is outside 
 phenomena is, by the same fact, outside the control of reason and 
 experience, and can not be verified. The belief in an a priori, tran- 
 scendental principle of morality involves denial of continuity in 
 moral experience, not rational subordination, and hence the im- 
 possibility of scientific inquiry. For ethics, then, would only ex- 
 plain how to execute, how to carry out absolute and fixed ideals of 
 conduct, while its function, as science, is to organize experimental 
 results, and to show how man, free from every preoccupation, con- 
 tributes in the creation of moral ideals. And man is enabled to 
 say what is really good, or worth while in conduct, only by means of 
 personal or racial experience. An ethics, truly human and scien- 
 tific, since it exists precisely for the sake of man who lives and works 
 in the world of phenomena and experience, can not have a basis 
 lying outside all experience, unless it renounces a scientific stand- 
 point, and is satisfied to be mere casuistry or dialectics. Moreover, 
 Rosmini holds as supreme ethical formula the practical recognition 
 of being in its order. If such practical recognition were the out- 
 come of man, regarded in his totality, that is to say in his heart and 
 intelligence, we could use it as a leading measure of the worth and 
 good of beings, as well as for a rule of actions. 
 
 But Rosmini, following Kant, thought that there is an antithesis 
 between the intelligible and the phenomenal world. He, as well as 
 Kant, attempted to discover for ethics a rational foundation, inde- 
 pendent of the world of phenomena. Both thought that experience 
 is conditioned, while the moral law must be unconditioned, and its 
 origin then must be independent of all experience. Both thought 
 that all feeling is empirical, sensuous, egoistic, and can afford no 
 foundation for the moral law. 
 
 Thus, both disregarded the life of feeling and emotion, which 
 claims to build moral ideals in the process of human experience. 
 Both have the same conception of the fundamental problem of ethics, 
 
CONCLUSION 49 
 
 and beg:in, not with an original unity, but with a duality. Kant 
 begins with the spontaneity and receptivity of the mind, while Ros- 
 mini begins with the idea of being and sensation. Such being, of 
 which man has an immediate and intuitive vision, has, according 
 to Rosmini, an objective value. But Rosmini does not prove the ob- 
 jective validity of the internal intuitive knowledge. 
 
 We may, accordingly, say that his "being" is nothing else 
 than the subjective thought itself in its extreme abstraction. Tims, 
 he does not begin witli God. but. as Kant, with the human mind 
 it.self.3 
 
 Besides, since Rosmini denies to iuiman mind the complete com- 
 prehension of the pure Being, and since he thus implicitly denies 
 the possibility of deducing from it all the determinations of being, 
 it follows that the pure being intuited by the mind is not the true, 
 pure being, namely, God, but merely the being abstracted from re- 
 flection.* 
 
 Rosmini, however, does not agree with Kant in some other 
 points. According to Kant, for instance, man is at once law-giver 
 and subject. According to Rosmini, man can not impose laws on 
 him.self. as .such an action presupposes authority, and hence he can 
 not be legislator to him.self. Moral conceptions, according to Kant, 
 are gained from pure reason itself. Rosmini thinks that the funda- 
 mental law can not be derived from our own reason, but that it is given, 
 and man is passive, Kant holds that duty springs neither from 
 authority, nor from experience. Rosmini is thoroughly convinced 
 that the .source of duty is transcendental, that is to say, it is God. 
 For Kant the characteristic feature of the ethical is autonomy : for 
 Rosmini heteronomy. The dignity of liuman personality, accord- 
 ing to Kant, depends on man's capacity for autonomy, or on his 
 capacity for following the universal law, derived from his own rea- 
 son ; according to Rosmini, the dignity of human personality lies in 
 the immediate intuition of being, in the participation of divine es- 
 sence by means of the light of reason, and, finally, in man's natural 
 capacity to incline to. and to merge him.self in, God, source of moral 
 good and happiness. 
 
 If we examine more particularly the moral edifice wliich Ros- 
 mini intended to build in those moments of intense national move- 
 ment, we find that liberty, according to him. is an act merely intel- 
 lective; that is, not an act of mere contemplation, but an act of 
 assenting contemplation. But is not this a metaphysical hypothesis 
 
 3 Sec Spaventa, "La filosofia di Kant e Rosmini," pages 47-t8; Fiorentino, 
 "La filosofia contemporanoa in Italia," page 23. 
 
 ♦See A. Franchi, "Ultima Critica," page 116; R. Benzoni, "Dottrina dell- 
 Essere nel sistema rosminiano. " 
 
50 BOSMINI'S CONTBIBUTION TO ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 without any true ground? If the assent to contemplated being is 
 a mere business of the intelligence, under the pressure of the idea 
 of being (which is, according to Rosmini, leading, ruling, informing 
 our rational life), does it not follow that the will is thoroughly de- 
 termined a priori? Rosmini is mistaken in considering exclusively 
 in man the intellective factor, making it the unique factor of all 
 our inner events, and subordinating all our psychic activity to it. 
 Conscious, however, of the necessity of accounting in the process 
 of moral action for the active power of feeling, and anxious to 
 explain the passage from idea to act, he discovered the practical 
 love which he supposes to precede the realization of the will. It is 
 an impelling force, but the intellect is, according to our philosopher, 
 the acting force. But is there any volitional act which is not ac- 
 companied by feeling? Is there any act of the human will which 
 is not at the same time conscious, and that, as object of conscious- 
 ness, does not involve a condition, either agreeable or disagreeable? 
 Consciousness of an object implies not only some mental presenta- 
 tion of the object, but also some subject to whom it is presented. 
 The object may or may not appeal to the "whole" subject, not 
 only to his intelligence, but to his impulsive and emotive life as well. 
 If it appeals, it can not fail to arouse interest and desire and agree- 
 able emotion. If it does not appeal, it stimulates aversion, and its 
 consequent emotions. Rosmini fails to recognize that our psychic 
 life is unique, coexistent with its factors, intimately inter-connected. 
 
 The life of intelligence and the life of feeling can not be viewed 
 apart without renouncing the great discoveries of modern psychol- 
 ogy. We can not, accordingly, conceive, as Rosmini does, the prac- 
 tical judgment as determined by mere ideas and abstract relations; 
 for it is the anticipated representation of an act and hence has re- 
 lation alike to sensibility, intelligence, and impulse. Such a repre- 
 sentation can not fail to be accompanied by some emotion, with some 
 active and motor reaction. Has not even the most ideal speculation 
 an active side? Have not material representations as well as the 
 most lofty speculations some relation to our emotive life? Have 
 they not all some value for our personality? And since they have 
 some value, some relation to our entire life why must moral judg- 
 ments, which are quite practical, and in which mind and heart are 
 interested, be regarded as isolated from our daily life ? 
 
 Finally, moral good, according to Rosmini, corresponds to Being, 
 made possible, indeed, by its relation to feeling, but subsistent in 
 itself, independent of the feeling subject which apprehends it. If 
 good, for man, is possible only in relation to feeling, how can 
 Rosmini hold such good to be objective and subsistent in itself, 
 
CONCLUSIOX 51 
 
 takin<2r away every relation? Tliat would be a catharsis, psycho- 
 logically impossibli', since a thing has no value and is no longer a 
 good as soon as it has no relation to anything else. Since, accord- 
 ing to Rosmini, an idea is constituted by matter ami form, how does 
 he imagine idea to be mere form, without any relation to matter? 
 If subject and object, matter and form, ideal possibility and reality, 
 are correlative terms, it is impossible to conceive one without the 
 other. The belief in an ideal order apart from the real, and exist- 
 ing in itself, stripped from every previous relation to the real, is the 
 belief in metaphysical dreams. 
 
 An ethics which claims to be scientific must present a conception 
 or moral good that nuiy be human, immanent, dynamic, developing 
 tlirough, and sinndtanc^usly with, i)syehological factors of indi- 
 vidual and social order as well. — To sum up what has been said, the 
 chief error in Rosmini 's etiiical theory is that it has for basis ide- 
 ology, and not a psychology of human nature. His native qualities, 
 however, his bias, his environment, the prevalence of ronumticism 
 over classicism, the great spiritual influence of Christian ideas, 
 could not fail to determine Rosmini 's mind to seek a system of 
 morals in the region of metaphysics and of a rationalism which he 
 thought immune to change, while everything was changing. Such a 
 system of ethics as he considered to be the most urgently needed, the 
 great Italian philosopher offered to his country, which he hoped to 
 see morally renewed and become politically united and independent. 
 
BIBLIOGRAPHY. 
 
 1. On Bos7nini's Life, see Paoli, "Memorie della vita A. Rosmini-Serbati, " 
 
 Turin, 1880-84; "Antonio Rosmini e la sua prosapia," Rovereto, 1880; 
 "Epistolario completo di A. Rosmini-Serbati," Turin, Casale: 1887-94; 
 W. Lockart, "Life of A. Rosmini-Serbati," London: Kegan, Trench, and 
 Co., 1886; Anon., "La Vita di A. Rosmini," Turin, 1897; Anon., "Pie- 
 cola Vita di A. Rosmini," Casale, 1897; "The Life of A. Rosmini-Ser- 
 bati," tr. from the Italian of Pagani, London, 1907. 
 
 2. Literature on the political situation of Rosmini's Italy is abundant. See, 
 
 however, Rey R., "Histoire de la renaissance politique de 1' Italie, " 
 Paris, 1864; Stillman, W. J., "The Union of Italy" (1815-189.5), Cam- 
 bridge: At the University Press, 1899; Martinengo-Cesaresco Evelyn. L. 
 Ilazeldine (Carrington), "The Liberation of Italy," London: Seeley 
 and Co., 1895; Pietro Orsi, "L 'Italia Moderna," English Ed., London: 
 Fisher; New York: Putnam, 1900; German Ed., Leipzig: Teubner, 1902; 
 Italian Ed., Milano: Hoepli, 1910; Tyffe C. A., "A History of Modern 
 Europe," New York: Henry Holt and Co., 1896; W. Alison Phillips, 
 "Modern Europe," 2 vols. London: Rivingstons, 1905; "The Cambridge 
 Modern History," planned by Lord Acton, edited by A. W. Ward and G. 
 W. Prothero, vol. X and vol. XI, New York: The Macmillan Co.; Quinet, 
 "Revolutions d 'Italic," Paris; B^renger, H., "Les Resurrections Ital- 
 iennes, " Paris: E. Pelletan, 1911; Tivaroni, "Storia critica del Risorgi- 
 mento Italiano, " etc. 
 
 3. For the intellectual condition of Bosmini's Italy, besides those referred to 
 
 above, see Tivaroni C, "Lo svolgimento del pensiero nazionale," 3 vols., 
 Turin, 1894; De Sanctis, F., "Storia della Letteratura Italiana," 2 vols., 
 Napoli: A. Morano, 1909; "La Letteratura Italiana nel secolo XIX," 
 Napoli: A. Morano, 1902; G. Cardueci, "Dello svolgimento della letter- 
 atura nazionale in Italia;" G. Guerzoni, "II terzo rinaseimento, " Milan: 
 Hoepli. G. Barzellotti, "La letteratura e la rivoluzione in Italia avanti e 
 dopo il 1848 e -49;" G. Barzellotti, "Dal Rinaseimento al Risorgimento," 
 Palermo: R. Sandron, 1909; G. Barzellotti, "La nostra letteratura e 
 I'anima nazionale," Nuova Antologia, p. 193, ser. 4, vol. 93, Roma, 1901; 
 Mazzoni, "L'Ottocento," Milano: Vallardi; Marasea A., "Le Origini 
 del roniantismo italiano," Roma: E. Loescher & Co., 1910; Luehaire, ,T., 
 "L'Evolution Tntellectuelle de I'ltalie de 1815 a 1830," Paris: Hachette 
 et Cie, 1906; Seignobos, C, "History of Contemporary Civilization," 
 New York: C. Scribner's Sons, 1909; Draper, "History of the Intellectual 
 Development in Europe," 2 vol.. New York: Harper, 1876; Flint, R., 
 "History of the Philosophy of History," New York: C. Scribner's Sons, 
 1894. 
 
 4. On Bosmini's Philosophy, See Bartholmeso, "Histoire critique des doctrines 
 
 religieuses de la philosophic moderne, " Paris, 1855; M. Debrit, "Histoire 
 des doctrines philosophiques dan I'ltalie contemporaine, " Paris: Meyrueis, 
 1859; A. Conti, "Storia della filosofia." 2 vols., Firenze: Barbera, 1864; 
 and La filosofia contemporanea in Italia, 1865; Mariano, R., "La philos- 
 
 52 
 
BIBLIOGRAPHY ■.,•'': .:;'53' 
 
 ophie contemporaino en Italie, " Paris: Gcrmer Bailli^re, 1868; Ferri, L., 
 " P]ssai sur I'histoire de la philosophio en Italie au XIX* sidcle, " 2 vols., 
 Paris: Didier, IS69; G. Barzellotti, "Philosophy in Italy," in Mind, 
 1878, vol. JII, pp. 505-538 (a rapid but careful survey of the Italian 
 philosophical movement during the nineteenth century) ; Fiorentino, "La 
 filosofia contemporauea in Italia." 
 Barth^iemy Saint-llilaire, "Victor Cousin, sa vie, sa correspondence," Paris, 
 1895, vol. Ill, p. 379, the influence of sensationalism on Italy at that 
 epoch; K, Werner, "Die italienische Philosophic dea XlXten Jahrhun- 
 derts," 5 vols., Wien: Faesy, 1884-87. See vol. I, " Roscniini and seine 
 Schule," by the same; "A. liosmini Stelluug in der Geschichte dor neuren 
 Philosophie, " 1884, vol. XXXV, Denkschrift der philosophistorich. Claase 
 der Koniglichen Academie der Wissenschaf ten, Wien. Ueberweg, * ' History 
 of Philosophy, vol. II, Italian contemporary pliilosophy, pp. 482 fit; Win- 
 delband, "History of i'hilosophy," pp. G24, 031; H. lliiffding, " Phiios- 
 ophes contemporains, " Paris : F. Alcan, 1908, p. 37, "La philosophie 
 italienne apr^ la Renaissance." 
 
 A bibliography, tolerably complete, of Rosmini 's own writings and of the 
 works dealing with his life and philosophy may be found in the philo- 
 sophical system of A. Rosmini-Serbati, trans, by Thomas Davidson, pp. 
 lii-lxxxviii, in Baldwin's Dictionary of Phil, and Psych., p. 444, vol. Ill, 
 Part I, and in Palhorifes's, "La philosophie de Rosmini," Paris: F. 
 Alcan, 1908, pp. 389-394. The treatises in which Roi-niini sets forth his 
 ethical teaching and which are connected with it are " Teodicea " (1828), 
 English trans., vol. 3, Longmans, Green & Co., 1912; " Nuovo Saggio 
 8ul rOrigine delle Idee," 1830, English trans., London: Kegan. 1883- 
 1884; "Psicologia" (1846-1850); English trans., London: Kegan, 3 
 vols. 1884, 1885, 1888; "Principii della scieuza morale" (1831); "Storia 
 comparativa e critica de' sistemi intorno al Principio della morale" 
 (1837) ; " Antropologia in servivio della scienza morale" (1838) ; "Trat- 
 tato della coscienza morale" (1839); "Filosofia del Diritto" (1841- 
 45); "Compendio di Etica, " published at Turin (1847) under a false 
 name, and republished (Roma: Desclee, 1907) under Rosmini 's name. 
 
VITA 
 
 John Favata Bnino was born the 10th February, 1877, at Santa 
 Caterina Villarmosa (Italj-). He had his preliminary education, and 
 pursued literary, scientific, and philosophic studies in his native 
 country. After receiving his Licenza Liceale (1897), he achieved a 
 course of high religious studies in the Great French Seminary St. 
 Louis which lies upon the ruins of the old Carthage. 
 
 In Columbia University, he studied (1910-13) philosophy under 
 Professors John Dewey, Frederick J. E. Woodbridge, Wendell T. 
 Bush, George Stuart Fullerton, Felix Adler, William Pepperrell 
 Montague, and Walter B. Pitkin; and psychology under Professors 
 James McKeen Cattell, Robert Sessions Woodworth, S. S. Colvin, 
 and the Kaiser Wilhelm Exchange Professor. Felix Krueger. 
 
 54 
 
ARClIIVEiS or PHILOSOPHT 
 
 Editorial oommunieatioDM should be addressed to Professor F. J. E Wood- 
 bridge, Colombia UniTersity, New York City. Tlie numbers are as follows : 
 
 1. l*be Concept of Control: Savilla Alice Klkns, Ph.D. 40 cents. 
 
 2. The Will to Believe as a Basis for Defense of Keligions Faith : Ettie 
 
 Stettheimer, Ph.D. $1.00. 
 
 3. The Individual : A Metaphysical Inquiry : William Forbes Cooley, 
 
 B.D., Ph.D. $1.00. 
 
 4. The Ethical Implications of Bergson's Philoeopliy : Una Bernard .*Nait, 
 
 Ph.D. $1.25. 
 
 5. Religions Values and Intellectual Consistency : Edward H. Reisner, 
 
 Ph.D. 75 cents. 
 
 6. Rosmini's Contribution to Ethical Philo.sophy : John F. Bruno, Ph.I). 
 
 75 cents. 
 
 ARCUIVES OF PSYCHOLOGY 
 
 Editorial communications should be addre.ssed to Professor K. S. Woodworth, 
 Colombia University, New York Citv. 
 
 Subscriptions and advertisements should be sent to .\Kcni\ ks .h I'SYCHOL- 
 OOY, Sub Station 84, New York City. The subscription price is five dullaT:- a 
 volume, containing between six and seven hundred page«. Recent Dnml»ers 
 •re as follows : 
 
 29. Experimental Studies in Judgment: H- L. Hollingworth. $1.25. 
 
 (Cloth, $1.50.) 
 
 30. The Psycholojiioal Researches of James .McKeen Cattell : ▲ Ke^iew by 
 Some of his Pupils. $1.00. (Cloth, $1.25. ) 
 
 31. Fatigue and Its Effects Upon Control : Isaiio Emory Ash. 60 cents. 
 
 (Cloth, 85 cents.) 
 
 32. The Transfer Effects of Practice in Cancellation Tests. Melvin Albert 
 Martin. 60 cents. (Cloth. 85 cents. ^ 
 
 33. The Intellectual Status of Children Who are Public Charges: J. L. 
 Stenquist, E- L. Thorndike, and M. R. TraUue. 50 cents. (.Cloth, 
 85 cents. ) 
 
Tn 
 
 PSYCIK 
 
 
 IDS 
 
 N 
 
 There is n 
 It is identitie( 
 iiently for th 
 8xj)erieiice of ' 
 
 The conten 
 
 Philosoj 
 Politi* 
 
 Ncatural 
 Georg 
 
 Social Oi 
 
 The Disc 
 
 The Post 
 
 Conventic 
 Allen 
 
 The Subje 
 Judgme 
 
 Response i 
 Introspect. 
 What is P 
 chologicj 
 Spirit, Mai 
 
 WEISER. 
 
 of 
 
 50?n-8,'26 
 
 T'7EK3S!RSK 
 
 Sub=Station 84, New York City 
 
 $3 per Annum, 26 Numbers 
 
 15 Cents per Copy 
 
Gaylord Bros. 
 
 Makers 
 Syracuse, N. V. 
 
 PAI.J/tN. 21, 1908 
 
 >'D 06^89 
 
 ? -3 '^ 
 
 UNIV^ERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY