'nia UNIVERSITY r'XTf LJ A, 1 L ELEMENTS ()/' GENERAL PHILOSOPHY Ex Libris C. K. OGDEN THE LIBRARY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES UNIVERSITY EXTENSION MANUALS EDITED BY PROFESSOR KNIGHT ELEMENTS GENERAL PHILOSOPHY GENERAL PLAN OF THE SERIES. This Series is primarily designed to aid the University Extension Movement throughout Great Britain and America, and to supply the need so -widely felt by students, of Text-looks for study and reference, in connexion ivith the atithorized Courses of Lectures. Volumes dealing with separate sections of Literature, Science, Philo- sophy, History, and Art have been assigned to representative literary men, to University Professors, or to Extension Lecturers connected ivith Oxford, Cambridge, London, and the Universities of Scotland and Ireland. The Manuals are not intended for purposes of Elementary Education, but for students who have made some advance in the subjects dealt -with. The statement of details is meant to illustrate the working of general laws, and the development of principles ; while the historical evolution of the subject dealt with is kept in view, along with its philosophical significance. The remarkable success which has attended University Extension in Britain has been partly due to the combination of scientific treatment with popularity, and to the union of simplicity with thoroughness. This movement, however, can only reach those resident in the larger centres of population, while all over the country there are thoughtful persons who desire the same kind of teaching. It is for them also that this Series is designed. Its aim is to supply the general reader with the same kind of teaching as is given in the Lectures, and to reflect the spirit which has characterized the movement, viz. the combination of principles with facts, and of methods with results. The Manuals are also intended to be contributions to the Literature of the Subjects with which they respectively deal, quite apart from University Extension ; and some of them will be found to meet a general rather than a special want. Elements of General Philosophy BY GEORGE CROOM ROBERTSON LATE GROTK PROFESSOR, UNIVERSITY COLLEGE, LONDON EDITED FROM NOTES OF LECTURES DELIVERED AT THE COLLEGE, 1870-1892 BY C. A. FOLEY RHYS DAVIDS, M.A. LONDON JOHN MURRAY, ALBEMARLE STREET 1896 jforfc HORACE HART, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY Zl INTRODUCTORY NOTE THAT I have been able to compile a second volume of lectures delivered by the late George Croom Robertson is again due, in the first place, to the kindness of Mr. Charles Robertson in placing at my disposal the MS. notes left by the professor, and, in the second place, to the ready help afforded me, through the loan of their note-books, by those students to whom I acknowledged my debt of gratitude in the Elements of Psychology, and to whom I here once more express my grateful obligation \ Once more, too, I wish to record my sense of the benefit derived from the corrections and suggestions made by Mr. Charles Robertson and 1 I append the names of those who contributed materials that I was able to use for this manual : George A. Aitken, Esq. ; Rev. Martin Anstey, M.A. ; Mrs. Archer Hind (Miss Laura Pocock) ; Mrs. Sophie Bryant, D.Sc. : Herman J. Cohen, Esq. ; Professor W. Hall Griffin, B.A. ; Rev. Isidore Harris, M.A. ; H. Frank Heath, Esq., B.A., Ph.D. ; Rev. Alfred Hills, B.A. ; Principal J. Viriamu Jones, M.A., F.R.S. (University College S. Wales and Monmouthshire) ; J. Neville Keynes, Esq., M.A., LL.D. ; Benjamin Leverson, Esq., B.A. ; Rev. S. Levy, B.A. ; J. W. Manning, Esq., M.A. ; Miss Dorothy Marshall, B.Sc. ; Andrew Ogilvie, Esq., B.A. ; Miss Mary Robertson, M.A. ; Ernest C. Robinson, Esq., M.A. ; G. Armitage Smith, Esq., M.A. ; President J. G. Schurman, M.A., D.Sc. (Cornell University); Rev. E. H. Titchmarsh, M.A.; H. J. Tozer, Esq., M.A. viii Introductory Note. Mr. Thomas Whittaker when going through the proofs. I am also indebted for kind advice and cordial help to Professor Knight. Excepting the full draft of an Introductory Lecture on the History of Philosophy, \vhich has been collated with students' note-books to form Lectures III- VI, the author's own materials have been wrought up almost wholly in Part II. For instance, in the concluding three lectures on Kant they practically superseded my having recourse to reports of college lectures. It so happened that, although the professor had more than once had occasion to give college lectures on this subject, only one set of notes on Kant had come into my hands. The first seventeen lectures, presenting a definitely con- secutive treatment an outline-history of Western philosophy (I-VII) and a somewhat closer consideration of the three main problems of that philosophy (VIII-XVII) constituted the annual elementary course on General Philosophy, or Epistemology, delivered in alternation with a course on Ethics during May and June. I do not mean that the number was always precisely seventeen ; it was usually less. The historic outline had sometimes to be dropped or transferred to the special courses, while the consideration of particular problems was prolonged. I have combined lx)th the one and the other in a slightly enlarged course. Finally, in the two lectures on Logic and Ethics, I have borrowed from the annual courses on those subjects, in order that the manual might be enriched by an outline, however brief, of the author's practical philosophy. Introductory Note. ix The special lectures are intended to form a course of somewhat more advanced reading, to succeed the study of Part I. They were delivered to an inner circle of students, small in number, candidates for the most part qualifying for the higher London University examinations, assembled during the years of the lecturer's declining health at a round table in his own house at Netting Hill. The special work or works under discussion lay open before each person. The professor's utterances took therefore the form rather of a running commentary, with here and there a more general disquisition, than of a lecture systematically developed. (This remark does not, of course, apply to the last three ' special ' lectures.) Of these running commentaries I have given the substance in a more or less condensed form. Thus the lecture on Plato's epistemology is a condensation of a course of eight conversational discourses on the Thcaetdus, Timaeus, and part of the Republic (delivered a few months before the professor's death). The lecture on Aristotle's Psychology is condensed from a like number ; those on Descartes from fifteen. There were many such advanced courses given during Professor Robertson's long occupancy of the Grote chair. They would have been even more varied had it not been for the limits in the cycle of philosophical works prescribed by the University of London, to which the curriculum of University College adapts itself 1 . Limits of space made 1 No post-Kantian work was prescribed during Robertson's pro- fessoriate for the examinations in history of philosophy with one exception the Melapfiysic of Lotze. At that time (1887-88) the pro- fessor was, alas ! too ill to lecture. x Introductory Note. it imperative that I should select, and the choice was determined less by the nature of my materials than by what seems to me to have been a salient standpoint in my master's critical philosophy. Holding by an enlightened Experien- tialism, he was repelled by the Individualism prevailing in experiential doctrine from Locke till the present century. Advance in biology has rendered in philosophy, as he says *, for ever impossible the older Experientialist position, that knowledge, with its objectivity, its universality, its necessity, can be acquired by every individual for himself, in the course of his own experience, from the beginning. Close and sympathetic study of the great Rationalist thinkers, from Plato to Kant, enabled him to discern what they, burdened by faulty method and the then scanty store of the fruits of scientific research, were groping after in their insistence on the innate furniture of the mind, namely, the predetermina- tion, the collective endowment of the individual by the race, as a prhis to whatever his own experience can teach him. Adjusting his own philosophy, on the one hand, to take account of every advance in scientific theory, he was careful, on the other, to bring out the continuous evolution of philosophic thought, history of human error though it might be 2 . And he held that the Experientialism even of to-day needed to be widened and deepened, not only by frankly adopting the evolutionary standpoint, but also by being brought face to face at all points with the best teaching of Rationalist thought, including especially the critical stand- points of Kant. Hence it is that I have selected the 1 See below, p. 152. 2 See below, p. 19. Introductory Note. xi Cartesian school and the Kritik rather than lectures on Bacon, Locke, Hume, and others. I need not here repeat what is written in the Elements of Psychology by way of apology to the memory of the dead philosopher for undertaking a task so heavily fraught with responsibility as the editing of these lectures. That re- sponsibility is but slightly alleviated in the present volume by my having had access, in the lectures where it is indicated, to more complete MSS. by the author's own hand. The task was undertaken in the hope of suggesting to the philosophic thought of the generation that has witnessed the untimely close of a life just come to philosophic maturity, with what generous ardour and constructive thought on behalf of the minds he was guiding, that life for a quarter of a century had spent itself, and more than spent itself, in the ungrateful if noble work of the class-room. At the same time, by presenting a part of that work in practically its original form, and in availing myself of the opportunity afforded me of incorporating it in an educational series, I hope no less to serve the interests of the student, standing on the threshold of the precincts of philosophy, by making him partaker in benefits that the living source so richly dispensed. If such a student should take up this volume without having previously read and re-read the companion manual, Elements of Psychology, or some equivalent text-book of modern date on the same subject, he is earnestly recom- mended to lose no time in making good that omission. Thus only will he be able to read this volume with the xii Introductory Note. maximum of profit. It was a fundamental principle with Professor Robertson true to the tradition of the British School that philosophic considerations, from whatever other groundwork they might spring, should not precede, but be complementary to, the study of psychology that, in his own words, the consideration of how we come to know anything should precede that of what it is as known. The reader, on the other hand, who has mastered the essential data of psychology, and naturally he most of all who has acquainted himself therewith as they are ordered by the same mind that planned the philosophic arguments in the present volume, will have his reward. Especially will he see how rich in philosophic import becomes that central point in George Croom Robertson's psycho- logical analysis the theory of objective perception, with its vertebral idea of the coefficient, in sense, of conscious- ness of activity put forth. He will see this point applied, again and again, in the explanation of such ultimate notions as necessity in knowledge, the conception of substance, the idea of causation, and the belief in an external world. And he will find effective in suggestiveness, not to say guidance, a philosophy thus psychologically based. In that philosophy the tradition handed down in this country the school of British psychological philosophy attains a distinct develop- ment. More than its well-known modern exponents, Robert- son had, in his own phrase, ' gone to school under ' Leibniz and Kant. And it is with a philosophic grasp and insight worthy of these two, while carrying on the direct line of succession in the psychological tradition, that he seeks to Introductory Note. xiii show how it is no mere metaphor to say that the world as we know it is as we mentally construct it : that we know it not with, as it were, a quasi-detachable intellect only, but with our whole living energy ; that we know in so far as we act, nay, that ultimately, only as we will, as we put forth activity, as we act, can we claim fully to be \ CAROLINE A. F. RHYS DAVIDS 2 . June, 1896. 1 See below, Lecture XVII. - All footnotes in the lectures, unless the contrary is stated, are parenthetical remarks made by the professor himself. The works, or passages in works, prescribed for the student's special reading were, in nearly every case, those prescribed by the lecturer himself. In a few lectures I have given references to books or subjects discussed, and also to the lecturer's own published writings. CONTENTS PART I. LECTURE PAGE I. THE BOND AND THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PSYCHO- LOGY AND PHILOSOPHY i II. PHILOSOPHY AS EPISTEMOLOGY 10 III. THE HISTORICAL ASPECT OF PHILOSOPHY AND OF SCIENCE 17 IV. HISTORICAL SKETCH OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY . . 24 V. MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY 37 VI. SCHOLASTICISM AND THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY 47 VII. MODERN PHILOSOPHY 56 VIII. UNIVERSALS 68 IX. UNIVERSALS (continued'). NOMINALISM AND CON- CEPTUALISM 77 X. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF 85 XL THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. BEFORE LOCKE . 97 XII. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. AFTER LOCKE. . 112 XIII. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY 124 XIV. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. CAUSATION . .135 XV. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. EVOLUTION . . 147 XVI. THE PERCEPTION OF AN EXTERNAL (OR MATERIAL) WORLD . . 154 XVII. THE PERCEPTION OF AN EXTERNAL (OR MATERIAL) WORLD (continued} 168 XVIII. REGULATIVE PHILOSOPHICAL DOCTRINE . . .181 XIX. THE BASIS AND THE END OF ETHICS . . .191 xvi Contents. PART II. SPECIAL LECTURES. LECTURE TAGK XX. ON THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF PLATO . . . .201 XXI. ON THE PSYCHOLOGY OF ARISTOTLE . . .214 XXTI. ON THE METHOD OF DESCARTES . . . .231 XXIII. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DESCARTES . . . 244 XXIV. ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF DESCARTES (continued) . 258 XXV. ON CARTESIANISM 270 XXVI. ON CARTESIANISM (continued) 287 XXVII. ON KANT'S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY .... 304 I. Kanfs importance in the present state of English thought. XXVIII. ON KANT'S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY (continued') . 317 II. General view of the Kritik and the Prolegomena. III. Mathematical Necessity and Muscular Sense. IV. On the Nature and Conditions of Intellectual Synthesis. XXIX. ON KANT'S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY (continued) . 339 V. The Ideas of Pure Reason. ELEMENTS OF GENERAL PHILOSOPHY. PART I. LECTURE I. THE BOND AND THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN PSYCHOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY. General Philosophy as based upon and supplementing Psychology. IN these lectures I wish to supplement the preceding psychological course in two ways. We found that in the process of psychological discussion certain philosophical questions were more or less involved. Into these, which we then passed by, we will now inquire. Again, our former course touched on many purely psychological questions, which from our wider philosophic standpoint we may review, fill in, and add to. We saw that ' Philosophy of Mind ' meant Science of Mind, whatever else it might mean. But we have also seen that science of mind or psychology does not contain all that is meant by philosophy of mind. And psychological treatment needs to be supplemented, before we can be fully satisfied, by a philosophical consideration of the problems of mind. I do not go so far as to say that philosophy is nothing more than a review of the problems of psychology from another point of view, but it is from this B 2 Elements of General Philosophy. [LF.CT. side that I introduce students to philosophy, and it is this that I mean by ' General Philosophy.' We are going to take up philosophical questions on a psychological basis. Not that we can settle such questions so determinately as those of psychology. We can dogmatise in psychology, for we are there treating of phenomena ; but we cannot do so in philo- sophy, where we can no longer distinguish, as we can in psychology, between thinker and thought. But it is most important for the student to separate from psychology proper the philosophical considerations which arise out of that science, all the more so that in this country psychology has been generally mixed up with philosophy. Mill, Hamilton, Professor Bain, Mr. Spencer are apt to confuse both kinds of inquiry, so that I am the more concerned that students should be fully aware when the aspect is shifted. General Philosophy as Theory of Knowledge. Ethics, associated with ' General Philosophy/ is itself a department of philosophy. It would be impossible to treat of philosophy in general without treating at the same time of ethics in particular. And ethics is no part of psychology at all. Equally is this true with regard to aesthetics. But my intention, during at least the greater part of this course, is not to refer to any philosophical questions arising out of the psychology of conation or of feeling, but to such as have all more or less bearing on knowledge. We see, therefore, what part of our psychology it is mainly that we shall rehearse, review, and supplement, viz. the psychology of intellection. In practical philosophy, i. e. in Logic, Ethics, and ^Esthetics, we need to know what functions of the mind it is that these doctrines regulate. And if General Philosophy is best faced from the point of view of Theory of Knowledge, I.] Elements of General Philosophy. 3 then does philosophy follow rightly from psychology as leading from that which appears to that which is, from the consideration of how we come to know anything to that of what it is as known. Kant's followers, including Green, condemn this method as involving the use of fundamental assumptions before these have been sifted. Then must we indeed begin our sifting early, for all use these assumptions with the use of their mother tongue, every two-year old as well as every coster- monger, though they do not come to the ultimate expression thereof. Those writers end by never getting on to psychology at all ! It is true, on the other hand, that some English philo- sophers have been so content with their psychology that they have never passed on to philosophy. I see the force of the Kantian position ; no scientific basis is ultimate. But a scientific basis is the only sound starting-point, and I will maintain my view till I get new light. Touching intellect, then, we have to make sure of our psychological ground and see if we may draw philosophical conclusions. Theory of Knowledge distinguishable from Logic. Logic, no less than ethics and aesthetics, is a depart- ment of philosophy and intimately concerned with the psychology of intellection. Nevertheless, I propose to mark off logic also from our philosophical inquiry, at least for the present, and to confine our inquiry to Philosophy as Theory of Knowledge in relation to science in general and Science of Mind in particular. Logic, like ethics and esthetics, may be called science from a certain point of view ; but that is not the point of view I adopt. For me, as I shall show later on, they are regulative doctrines or disciplines, or Nomology. Logic is regulative discipline of thought. Has B 2 4 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT, science in itself anything to do with regulation ? No ; the business of science is explanation, or phenomenology. Psychology deals with phenomenology of mind, with in- tellection as it naturally proceeds, with the explanation according to natural laws of the intellectual function called thinking. That function logic sets itself to regulate. This notion of regulation is something which science in no wise expresses. It is one of the ways in which we can define the function of philosophy. And because thought is a means of knowledge, logic in its widest sense is already a part of the philosophical Theory of Knowledge. But logic is concerned with true thinking or truth. Now, by truth of thought we mean that our thought has a certain import, that it is valid. Such considerations, namely, as to whether a given intellectual act has any real validity or not, are altogether outside psychology, though not outside logic. Now, if logic be concerned with the validity of thought, let us generalise this, and we get a definition of philosophy as theory, not merely of the validity of thought, but of the validity of all knowing. We ,can know otherwise than by thought, viz. by perception. Ultimate Inquiry its Nature and its Names. ' How .am I intellective of that pillar ? ' We resolved my act of intellection into certain sensations plus mental activity of a definite kind a complex function termed Perception. And this was a psychological answer to a psychological inquiry an inquiry which may be thus otherwise worded : ' How comes it to pass in my consciousness that I perceive that pillar ? ' But if I ask, ' Is there a pillar a real one ? a real pillar there apart from my perceptive mind ? ' this is a philosophical question, and whatever answer is made is a philosophical statement, though it may be determined I.] Elements of General Philosophy. 5 by psychological insight. For we are here asking a question relating to the import of knowledge; I am concerned to know whether my subjective perception implies a corre- sponding reality or no. Such questions may be raised concerning any intellectual function ; they belong to the ultimate questions which the human mind is able to raise, and for them is still reserved the ancient term Philosophy. If they are raised, as here and now, in connexion with intellection or knowing, the more specific terms are Theory of Knowledge, Epistemology, or Metaphysic. If emphasis is thrown, as it used to be, rather on the question of ' Being ' than of ' Being in as far as known,' they are, or rather were, expressed by the term Ontology. Thus we have got four names which are all more or less related to one another, all being the same in respect of extension but differing in intension; all denoting the same, but having different connotation. Let us enter more fully into their meaning and history, and then more clearly differentiate what they collectively amount to from modern science and psychology. Philosophy. Philosophy is the oldest term of them all ; first to be started, it will probably survive longest. We meet with ' philosophy ' and ' philosopher ' in Greek history earlier than with the other three. Plato, e. g., uses only these two. Philosophy originally stood for reasoned knowledge in general; it was not differentiated from science. Human knowledge was supposed to be a kind of organic whole, and Philosophy was the word for it. But from the time of Plato, and still more in that of Aristotle, another word began to grow up, viz. Epistemology. And Plato was already 6 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. commencing to speak of ' the sciences,' though the only science which then underwent development was mathematics. It is not till the modern period that an antithesis or opposi- tion is set up between sciences and philosophy. The sciences were at first rather departments of philosophy, but from the beginning of the seventeenth century mathematics and other sciences were pursued in a certain method of their own, and regarded apart from anything that may still be called philosophy. An ancient philosopher had a complete view of the whole field of knowledge. Now, thinkers are mainly specialists, knowing little, or but vaguely, of any department except their own. The opposition since then has so far widened that some modern thinkers have said there is nothing beyond science. Comte, e.g. called philosophy a co-ordination of the sciences J . There is a good deal called philosophy beyond that ; at all events, whereas philosophy originally meant all reasoned knowledge, it has now come to mean reasoned knowledge no less, but of a kind that stands apart from certain limited bodies of doctrine pursued according to a strictly definite method called lhat of the sciences, and apart from psychology too, because in respect of method psychology is as much science as chemistry is. Philosophy as Wisdom. Again, all ancient knowledge was bent to a practical issue. This is the specific mark of what was originally called philosophy. Philosophy is ' love of wisdom/ and wisdom is a term of practical import, is knowledge with a practical reference ; is not mere insight, but conduct guided by insight. And still our concern in ultimate questions has 1 V. Positive Philosophy, Bk. VI, ch. xiii. I.] Elements of General Philosophy. 7 a more or less practical object an object which we call the wise conduct of life. But this aspect of philosophy is not found in modern science. Science as such leaves aside practical considerations. It has reached its present development during the last three centuries by such elimina- tion and specialisation. As long as men could and would think about everything they made little advance. Metaphysic. The term Metaphysic in this country and in Germany has been loosely used. It is often used as indistinguishable from psychology itself; e. g. in Hamilton's Lectures on Meta- physics, five-sixths of which are psychological, the remainder philosophical, and in which he passes without warning from psychology into pure philosophy. Professor Bain speaks of ' mental science ' and sometimes of psychology, but there is a goodly amount of philosophy too in his Manual, certain chapters and much in the historical notes being as philo- sophical as can be. Metaphysic also, as a name, has an accidental origin. Aristotle did not use the term, and yet the term has grown out of Aristotle's works. He left, in addition to his treatises on life, mind or soul, and the treatise called Physica, another work dealing with what he sometimes calls First Philosophy, with the notion of ' fundamental/ and at other times 'being as being' (TO bv $ ov), in fact, Ontology. The precise word ontologia is not found there, yet all is there but the word. His editors and commentators placed this treatise after the Physica, and called it so (ra pera TO. EPICURUS (341-270) I Lucretius (95-52) V ZENO Epictetus (fl. A.D. 90-118' M. Aurelius (120-180) iv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 31 Pre-Socratic and Platonic Thought. Let us now, before coming to the Christian era, retrace our steps and bring the Pre-Socratic philosophy into some sort of relation with the teachings of Plato and Aristotle. We see it during those two centuries preceding Socrates active, acute, but slow in development, a movement of great comprehensiveness and variety, and of remarkable philosophic depth. Yet some of what are to us the simplest conceptions were then not attained, and it is only with Socrates and Plato that philosophy begins to be to some extent ' modern.' Scantiness of surviving materials and a general lack of philosophic development justify a somewhat summary treat- ment. Yet some of their thinking was important for Plato and even for us. There were six Pre-Socratics who most strongly influenced Plato HERACLEITUS, the Ionian, fl. about B.C. 504. PARMENIDES, of Elea, Magna Graecia,yf. about B.C. 504. : ANAXAGORAS, of Clazomenae, B.C. 500-428. PYTHAGORAS, of Samos and Magna Gra;cia, B.C. 575-500. DEMOCRITUS, of Abdera, b. B.C. 460. PROTAGORAS, chief of the Sophists, B.C. 480-411. The problem of knowledge as it presented itself to Plato was an effort to transcend and get over the antithesis between the views of the first two. The other thinkers as well as Socrates gave him suggestions towards overcoming this opposition. Of these, the Pythagoreans are of the least importance. Their influence only became prominent, as expressed by one of them, Philolaus, at the time when Plato's theory of ideas was undergoing its later development. 1 According to Mr. Burnet (Early Greek Philosophy, 70) this date is too early by at least thirty years. ED. 32 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. The Pythagorean was the most enduring of the Pre-Socratic schools. Plato never mentions Democritus by name, but it is probably to this great contemporary he refers as representing Materialism, when setting out in conscious antithesis his own Immaterialism. Democritus, living at Abdera, never came under the influence of Socrates. Anticipated by Leucippus early in the fifth century, he worked out his system from the basis of the earlier thinkers. He is the proper antithesis to Plato. Plato's philosophy is Ideological founded on final causes, the ethical element being uppermost. Democritus' philosophy is mechanical, and was the first to be developed as such. His importance by the side of Plato was first recognised by Lange (in his History of Materialism], who holds him to be the more important thinker of the two, in so far that modern scientific theory joins on to him more than on to Plato, whose views are largely discredited. His very prolific works are mostly lost. The antithesis between Heracleitus and Parmenides was metaphysical rather than epistemological. Their philosophy, as with all Pre-Socratics, was cosmological, nevertheless it is epistemological also. All tried to find some simpler expres- sion of the complex experience of daily life, but Heracleitus and Parmenides had a novel and deeper insight. Though Heracleitus adduced fire as a fundamental principle, it is the fact of ceaseless Change or Motion in nature that strikes him iravra pet. Parmenides was struck by Permanence and Fixity in nature. The latter emphasised the One, the former saw chiefly the Many. Thus Heracleitus had to reconcile with his theory the apparent fixity of things ; Parmenides had to make the apparent change in things square with his. Heracleitus accounted better for fixity iv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 33 than Parmenides did for change. Both views were of interest to Plato. Anaxagoras introduced a new principle as determining universal being, viz. vovs, or reason. This, as compared with others brought forward by Pre-Socratics, e.g. water, air, fire, was apparently subjective ; actually however for him vovs is a purely objective moving principle, and he is as cosmological as the rest. With all of these there is latent the beginning of an epistemological theory. The distinction between experience, as we actually find it, and reflexion on our experience is implicit in all ; but no one marked out clearly the difference between experience and reflexion, between sense and thought. They did not ask what the relation is between the two, nor how knowledge arises from both ; they all thought of knowing in terms of sense. But the Sophists and Socrates, with the doctrine of ' Know thyself/ brought the question to the front, causing the theory of knowledge to enter on a new phase. Philosophy, from being cosmological, became anthropological. With Anaxa- goras, man is part of the universe. But Protagoras and Socrates view the universe through man. Man is put before the universe man as knower (theoretical aspect of philo- sophy) and as doer (practical aspect). The Pre-Socratics, with their definite theories of being, were ontologists rather than epistemologists, making no definite reference to the subject as such. So far as they are epistemologists they agree, however much they differ metaphysically. They all, namely, are Sensationalists. They take account of sensation only, and of this as something proceeding in us in a material way. Protagoras, on the other hand, treated the problem of 34 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. knowledge so much from the subjective point of view that he never got beyond that standpoint. With him knowledge is im- possible. There could of course be no knowledge apart from individual experience, but beyond that individual experience it was impossible to get. Knowledge is sense-perception, infinitely varied and changing ; man, the individual per- cipient, is, through his particular sensations, the ' measure of all things' for himself. Thus he despaired of physical science, nor did he attempt any other kind of science, but devoted himself to practical life. Thus, in their consideration of the conduct of life, the Sophists employed moral persua- sion instead of laying down any principles of moral science. Socrates also despaired of a knowledge of external things, holding that our experience of such is so completely relative to the individual that knowledge proper, i. e. having ob- jective validity, is impossible. Nevertheless he was not content to drop epistemological considerations and go into practical life, but, resigning physical science as a worthy or possible object of search, he declared that a knowledge of man as a moral agent was possible. Though unable to get a knowledge of things, man can attain a knowledge of virtue. Accordingly Socrates set himself to formulate a science of moral conceptions, even to the identification of virtue and knowledge. He attempted to get at a definition of ethical notions by the generalisation of particulars, and thus to form concepts scientifically true. Scientific know- ledge for Socrates is generalisation of particulars in the moral sphere, but not outside it. Science for him was general knowledge to know particulars through the concept. This view of the general notion as embodying science first found expression in the teaching of Socrates. It is Socratic conceptualism. iv.J Elements of General Philosophy. 35 Plato's ' Theory of Ideas ' is a development of the Socratic conceptualism. He inherited both the concept of Socrates and also his high moral purpose. But Plato did not drop the general problem of knowledge; he asks, 'What is knowledge ? ' and, ' How is knowledge possible ? ' questions which he puts into the mouth of Socrates (Thecetetus, &c.), but which the latter never really asked, since he never conceived the problem of conduct as one to be solved by the problem of knowledge put universally. End of the First Period. We shall inquire into Plato's theories and those of Aristotle when dealing more specifically with those main questions referred to at the end of my third lecture. Here we need only briefly notice the conclusion of the period of ' ancient ' philosophy. The Aristotelian and Platonic schools went on, but in the later Greek and Roman period fell, as we have seen, into abeyance before Epicureanism and Stoicism. There was no advance in pure philosophy in Greece beyond Aristotle's time. The strong ethical bent inaugurated by Socrates, but tempered by the universal genius of Plato and Aristotle, pre- vailed fully by the third century. The full weight of Aristotle's influence did not really tell until the Scholastic period and after that ; in the early Medieval period it was overshadowed by Platonism. The two or three names of importance in Roman philosophy fall under Epicureans, e.g. Lucretius, or Stoics, e.g. Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius Antoninus. Cicero (B.C. 44) was an Eclectic thinker, interesting chiefly for the information he gives of the various movements. If by the side of these we take thinkers who were not metaphysicians but scientific investigators, we see here and D 2 36 Elements of General Philosophy. there one working with such success as to influence posterity, and, notably in astronomy, making correct conclusions on false grounds e.g. predicting eclipses on fallacious concep- tions of the relations of sun and earth. When we say the ancients had no science, we make exception of Hippocrates (medicine, B.C. 460-357), Euclid the geometer of Alexandria (fl. B.C. 323-283), Archimedes the physicist, the founder of genuine Positive Science, Hipparchus (fl. B.C. 160-145) and Ptolemy (fl. A. D. 139-161), the astronomers. An offshoot from Platonic idealism and the so-called Academic philosophy in the Christian era was Neo-Platonism. I have said that Greek philosophy was not religious. Its latest growth however, Neo-Platonism, sought to meet a religious want born of the social conditions of the time, and entered into direct competition with the young Christian faith for mastery over all the thoughts and actions of men, the most important Neo-Platonist being Plotinus. But Greek philosophers had no kind of scruple as to the ques- tions they raised. Socrates had indeed scruples regarding physical inquiry, but these were curiously unlike later and modern scruples, and are to be explained from the state of contemporary knowledge in regard to the subjects more than from anything else. They bore on the limitations of what could be settled and how to settle it, and not at all of what ought, or ought not, to be discussed. Hence Greek philo- sophy is the prototype of all earnest and unfettered thought. For LECTURES V and VI read : Ueberweg, op. cit. I, pp. 356, 357, 367, 368 (for the way in which the Scholastic thinkers got Greek thought); pp. 410, 411 (for the way in which Greek works went to the Arabs, and were translated into Syriac and then into Arabic) ; pp. 417-419 (for the influence of both on Jewish philosophy). Also pp. 430-432. LECTURE V MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY. Divisions. OUR second or Mediaeval period of Christian or Ecclesias- tical Philosophy is divisible into two sections: (i) Patristic Philosophy, (2) Scholastic Philosophy. The former, beginning in the second century, culminated in Augustin (A.D. 354- 430), then languished on through the virtually positive break of the Dark Ages, while the break-up of the older Western civilisation was proceeding. The latter (2) dates from the eleventh century, when philosophy was reviving in the mon- astic schools founded largely by Charlemagne about A.D. 800, when society had assumed somewhat of the form of modern nationalities, and when universities had just been, or were about to be, founded. The doctors of the Church were called scholasiici viri, and their exposition of Christian dogma according to Greek principles is known as Scho- lastic Philosophy, still taught to-day in Catholic schools. After William of Ockham (d. 1347) it began to break up, and there intervenes the transitional period of the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries ushering in Modern Philosophy. Authority and Philosophy. When Simplicius and his Neo-Platonist companions, the last representatives of Hellenic philosophy, were driven 38 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. eastwards by the action of Justinian, in A.D. 529, and the Athenian schools, for the first time since the age of Socrates and Plato, were deserted and dumb, there was left the Christian Church, which had grown for five centuries till it was so strong that emperors' edicts stood at its command, and so little unconscious of its future glory and its power, so little indisposed to dominate the thoughts of men, that the crushing out of the philosophical schools was but the last of a long series of blows levelled by it at the authority of human thinking. Unless we form a true con- ception of the historical relation of the Church to philosophic thought, we cannot comprehend the modern philosophy begun by Descartes. Greek speculation, though it often had to pick its steps among established faiths (remember the fate of Socrates!) was, as we said, pre-eminently disinterested in its search after reasoned truth. Now too since the last three hundred years it is fully conceded that the human mind may search out anything and everything up to the limit of its powers, in the bare interest of truth and intelligent insight. But between this recurring phase of opinion there was an intervaj when liberty of thought was not the watchword of most, nor even of the most enlightened, minds. This interval, coin- cident with the period of supremacy of the Church in all departments of life, dates back to the beginnings of the Christian movement, and covers an interval whose magnitude it takes an effort, not often made, fully to conceive. Even pagan philosophy, viz. in its Neo-Platonist phase, was much affected by the principles and professions of the growing Church. Let us remember that the best Greek thought was excogitated in some four hundred years and less, and that modern philosophy only dates back three centuries. v.] Elements of General Philosophy. 39 We have thus 1600 years to account for as against those seven or eight hundred. Reduce this term as we may by the fringes of the dwindling of the first and the earliest growth of the latest periods, still there remains a clear thousand of years during which it was not open to men to think as they liked and this is a huge slice out of the history of humanity. What the Church did, or permitted to be done for the enlightenment of the race took three times as long as the great deeds that are crowded into the something more than three centuries from Bacon and Descartes till the present. Those of course were very different times from ours, and there was plenty of other work, hard and grim, for the Church to do, and the Church did much of it bravely. But we must not forget that the seventh and eighth centuries were as long as the seven- teenth and eighteenth. And not to forget this, but to remember and ponder it, in connexion with the intellectual history of mankind, is one of the first things the student of philosophical history is called upon to do. Greek Philosophy in Harness. At the beginning of the sixth century the Church finally stamped out the very feeble remnant representing Greek thought. That date is also critical in another way. Not only was it then that the Church grasped the reins, but a turning-point was also reached in her internal develop- ment. As in after-ages the Church did not so much repress thought as compress it within her own limits, so it is not to be supposed that she at this date had stood altogether outside of the philosophical current. The Christian religion, viewed philosophically, rivalled the Stoic and Epicurean schools as a way of thinking towards an ideal of human 40 Elements of General Philosophy. [LKCT. conduct. The rules of life were given not as rational, but as a revelation from on high. But in time, as the Church grew and brought into her fold more and more men of higher culture, the developed conceptions of pagan philo- sophy came into contact with the Christian philosophy. Epictetus the Stoic, Marcus Aurelius the Stoic emperor, Plotinus and Proclus, are not the only names of philoso- phical note in the early centuries of the new era. Origen (185-254), Athanasius (296-373), Tertullian (160-220), and, above all, Augustin (354-430), are not less worthy of notice, for the historian of philosophy as well as for the Churchman. Augustin, a man of developed pagan culture, appearing at the time when Christianity had gained the mastery, first put forth those conceptions, which came to be the accepted philosophy of the Christian Church, with a breadth of thought hitherto unrivalled. He derived his conception of the soul as real and yet as opposed to matter from the Platonists. Metaphysically he was a Dualist, and fixed philosophy from his time onward as a system of Dualism. In fact the first generation of Christian converts had hardly passed away before philosophic thought began, while three or four centuries of ardent philosophic thinking and dialectical discussion, carried on with Greek subtlety upon principles of Greek philosophy, had been needed before the many-headed dogma of the Church had been settled and the function of the Fathers fulfilled, there being nothing more to create. What one section of Christendom has often bewailed, and another has rejoiced over, may be accepted with some confidence for a fact, viz. that the ecclesiastical doctrine was the result of an incorporation of a few simple tenets with the wisdom of the world, or at. least of the interpretation of a small number of practical v.] Elements of General Philosophy. 41 truths by the refined intelligence of thinkers who had been trained in Greek schools. The fact belongs to the history of philosophy as much as to religion, although the Fathers would for the most part have thrown from them the imputation, so ready as they were to denounce philosophy and all profane wisdom in the interest of faith. Fathers and Doctors of the Church. But after a while all the main dogmas were formed by which the Church was henceforth to stand, the edifice being crowned in the fifth century by Augustin, last and greatest of the Fathers. After him philosophising was bent into other than creative channels. This is what happened. Pagan philosophy having been reduced to silence, and the Fathers of the Church East and West having passed away, their dogmatic work accomplished, when next, under the auspices of the consolidated and all-powerful Church, some- thing of the old inquiring and reasoning spirit appeared, it was given the task of interpreting and unfolding, of sup- porting and upholding, what was there already. To the Fathers of the Church succeeded her Doctors, who in monastic schools and, as time went on, in universities made philosophy conform to dogma, expounding in logical form and sustaining by rational argument the doctrines which no one might any more presume to touch in their substance. This was the second phase or true Scholastic Philosophy. The Dark Ages. The transition was not swiftly made. With the final triumph of the Church in the Roman world, about A.D. 600, when the historian comes upon the time of darkness and chaos, when the great world-empire, falling of itself into 42 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. pieces or broken into fragments by the northern races, was hewn into the rough shapes of modern states and nation- alities, the Church held on its way ; but it was no longer the Church of Augustin, and not yet the Church of Aquinas. Only perhaps a single obscure name in a century stands out from the time of Augustin to the age of Charlemagne. The grandiose attempt of the latter, at the close of the eighth century, to organise European society on the basis of a twofold imperium of Emperor and Pope gave room for some serious beginnings to be made of provision for intel- lectual culture in the monastic schools. Half a century later there appeared one of mark John Scotus Erigena (800- 877), a native of either Ireland or Ayrshire, where the darkness had never been so complete as on the continent. He struck the keynote of all that followed in enunciating the perfect unity of religion and philosophy, of faith and reason. But Charlemagne's construction could not endure, and two centuries more of confusion and anarchy were added to the dismal roll before there arose any prospect of an intellectual succession in Christendom. Erigena was de- nounced as a heretic for his pains ; hence we may not place the beginnings of Scholasticism earlier than the middle of the eleventh century. Thus there was for about five hundred years next to no philosophy among the European races ; during that time philosophic activity was confined to Arabians in Bagdad and Moors in Spain. They in the time of greatest darkness carried on disinterested thinking. Effective Thinking in Christendom confined to the West. In inquiring into the growth of Scholasticism, let it first be borne in mind, that of the two divisions of the Church v.l Elements of General Philosophy. 43 it is practically only the Western or Roman Church with which we have to do. The aim of the Fathers was perhaps not less actively promoted in the East than in the West ; the development of dogma really took place more at Constanti- nople and at Alexandria than at Rome. But at the end of the first period, the great consolidation of doctrine made by Augustin for the West, possessed as it was by a force that could survive five centuries, was paralleled by nothing of its kind in the East. And it was for want of this, as much as for any other reasons, that the Eastern Church in the final division of Christendom, although not assaulted by the storms that for centuries beset the West, never to the last did anything for enlightenment to compare with the remark- able if tardy achievements of the Western Schoolmen. The thinkers of Constantinople were men of third or fourth rate power. The authority of Augustin had been the saving of the West. We consider therefore only the Western Church with its Augustinian code. Philosophic Instruments applied by the Schoolmen. As to the instruments of the Scholastics for the interpreta- tion of the doctrine handed on to them, the Doctors had some philosophical works of the Greeks which had come across the gulf of centuries. Of course they had, besides, Augustin, but his knowledge of Greek philosophy was gained at second hand only. Of Aristotle they had some minor logical works ; they possessed Porphyry's Introduction to the Categories (all in the Latin translation of Boethius), and (also in translation) a small piece of Plato's Timceus. This was all, excepting one or two inferior works by commentators. Plato's speculations were unknown save as transmitted by Augustin and some of the Neo-Platonists. Even the merelv 44 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. logical doctrines of Aristotle were incompletely apprehended before the middle of the twelfth century, while the full scope of his encyclopaedic work remained unknown till the thirteenth century, when the Schoolmen had in a round- about way obtained translations of his works. When in A.D. 529 the Greek professors were dispersed, they fled to Bagdad and the East, bearing with them the records of Greek philosophy the original works of Aristotle, &c. There they were in course of time translated into Syriac and thence into Arabic. The Arabian conquests having established the Mohammedan empire from the East across North Africa into Spain, Greek learning found its way thither in Arabic, and was there again translated by Jews into Hebrew and borne back into Christendom. Then both from Arabic and from Hebrew Latin transla- tions were finally made, and these were received by the Schoolmen as a kind of revelation. But this did not take place till the twelfth century. As it took place, as they became acquainted with Greek philosophy, their view perceptibly widened. And by the time the Schoolmen had learnt their Aristotle as fully as might be in this in- direct way, i. e. at the beginning of the thirteenth century, this knowledge began to be supplemented by acquain- tance with the original Greek, or by direct translations from the same, the originals being sent or brought by the Greeks of Constantinople. Limitations of Scholasticism. Scholasticism was philosophising in support of a limited and foregone conclusion. This is the difference between it and the free movement of Hellenic thought. But still it was philosophising. The Doctors did make a step towards the v.] Elements of General Philosophy. 45 light, in working from blind devotion to more or less rational belief. We can thus distinguish between their great- ness and their limitations. If we dwell on the latter, the case against them can be strongly put and maintained. It is easy to abuse Scholasticism. No new or striking con- ception, like those we find in ancient or in modern philo- sophy, penetrating to the heart of things, sprang from any one of the Schoolmen. From want of ability or lack of liberty they never carried thought farther than the Greek leaders, and for the most part not so far. Their utter dependence upon Aristotle appears in that, as their know- ledge of him widened, their views of philosophy widened and they became able to conceive the full scope of philo- sophic inquiry. Till the thirteenth century they had no conception of philosophy but as a vague science of dialectic or logic, nor had they made any division of its departments as Aristotle had done. And at the last they incurred discredit through comparison with the Greek philosophy, when the fall of Constantinople revealed this in the original form more fully to the West. They were found to have established no alternative claim to modern respect by taking up any branch of thought which the Greeks had neglected, or in which they had failed. And their very acuteness, through being turned on to a fatally narrow circle of subjects, had led to subtleties that were doomed to be the occasion of some of the bitterest reproaches since heaped upon them. The Case for Scholasticism. On the other side it should be noted that the Schoolmen were not responsible for their circumstances, determined by a great and uncontrollable course of events. It was 46 Elements of General Philosophy. something that, after so great a dissolution, there should have been so considerable an attempt at reconstruction. It was not a little wonderful that they should have applied all the enlightenment handed down to them to rationalise faith, and that they struggled as they did against the con- servatism of ecclesiastical authority until official recognition of one newly rationalised doctrine after another was extorted. Theirs became entitled Church philosophy, yet the Church did nothing but accept, did nothing to encourage, their philosophising, witness the case of Scotus Erigena. Often and often was Aristotle solemnly banned before he came to be considered (in the thirteenth century) as 'the fore- runner of Christ in the things of Nature as John Baptist was in the things of Grace.' No, we must not speak only of the servility of the Schoolmen : they showed not only wisdom but also courage in their appeal to heathen Aristotle. And it is more becoming at this time of day, and more important besides, that their wisdom and their courage should not remain unacknowledged. For LECTURE VI : The student should not fail to follow up the lecture by reading Croom Robertson's account of British Schoolmen in the essay, 'The English Mind,' Philosophical Remains, pp. 34-38. ED. LECTURE VI. SCHOLASTICISM AND THE RISE OF MODERN SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY. Realism in Scholasticism. INTO the question which chiefly occupied the Schoolmen in their attempt to interpret and rationalise Christian dogma in the light of Greek philosophy the question of the nature of ' Universals ' or General Ideas we shall enter more fully in a separate lecture. It was not new then any more than it is obsolete now. Before Plato and Aristotle the Greeks had seen its significance ; with those two it was a matter of the deepest concern. Plato, with his archetypal ideas as the only Realities, is the great representative of the one extreme view to which the Schoolmen first gave the name of Realism. Aristotle held a modified Realism. The other extreme view, viz. that only particulars are realities, the universal being but subjective, also had its representatives in Greek thought, Epicurus, e.g. approximating to a modern Nominalist, although on different grounds. Of how the question had been discussed by the Greeks the Schoolmen knew nothing. Nevertheless, Porphyry and the fragments in their hands were enough to suggest the problem, and in fact Erigena in the ninth century, in the fervour of his Neo-Platonism, had raised it, and come to a conclusion in the spirit of a thorough Realist. Moreover, as soon as the philosophic interest was aroused within the 48 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Church, the Schoolmen were quick to see the full bearing of the issues. Their philosophy consisting in the intellectual consideration of the mystery of the faith, they discerned at the foundation of how many articles of that faith the problem lay the Trinity, the Real Presence, the Redemption of the race, the status of the Church as the divinely illumined witness of the Truth. In these and other beliefs they saw how the relation of the Many to the One, the old question of Parmenides and Heracleitus, identical with the later question as to Universals, is implicated. Now whichever view the Schoolmen took, they made an advance in taking any view at all, and the view held by some from the first, and by the majority at the last, showed more intellect and betokened more independence than is ordinarily ascribed to them. Its promulgation heralded the approach of modern thought. Divisions of the Scholastic Period. The whole period falls into three parts : Part I. From the eleventh to the end of the twelfth century. Part II. covers the thirteenth century. Part III. From the fourteenth century till whenever Scholasticism may be supposed to end ; that is, one might say, with the sixteenth century for the active and leading spirits in Europe, with the seventeenth for the universities in the advanced countries, but not even to the present day in the seminaries of the Catholic Church, where Aquinas is still the great philosophical authority. The first period is the Platonic age of Scholasticism. Aristotle, as we have seen, was at this date known chiefly through the medium of the Arabian scholars, while Plato was known directly by a fragment only, but indirectly through VL] Elements of General Philosophy. 49 Neo-Platonic media and Augustin's works. But a Realism as strong as Plato's was supported by Anselm (1033-1109) and others, and this view was tolerated or approved and accepted by the Church. Reason and faith were in process of coming together, but it was an innovation. Scholasticism was struggling to gain its footing. Roscellin (fl. 1092), on the other hand, dared to avow an extreme Nominalism and drove it to an extravagant conclusion. The second period is the Aristotelian age of Scholasticism, when Aristotle, better known at length in Latin, though not in Greek, came to have more influence over the human mind than at any previous period in history. Way had been made for this evolution by Abelard (1079-1142), that restless, critical, but not constructive spirit, antagonistic to Anselm. Independent and unchecked by rules, he is the first and best representative of freedom of thought in the Middle Ages. A multitude of other circumstances concurred to induce the change of attitude. The beginnings of Scholas- ticism coincide with the beginnings of the Papal supre- macy in Europe the period from Hildebrand to Innocent III and the maturity of Scholasticism was attained when the Papacy was putting forth its strongest claims against the civil power in the days, i.e. of Innocent III (1198- 1216) and when the Church was endeavouring as far as possible to widen the organised ecclesiastical teaching. Now the encyclopaedic genius of Aristotle was exactly fitted to satisfy the largest requirements on these lines, and hence Scholasticism, with its ground-principle of reason in the service of faith, flourished at length under Aristotelian influence. In Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) the junction was com- pleted. He retained all of Plato that he needed for dogma 50 Elements of General Philosophy [LECT. where Aristotle fell short. But now reason, unlike the first period when she was struggling to enter, not only had entered into the penetralia of faith, but was fully recognised, on the condition of yielding aid and reverence to the Church, as the legitimate occupant of the realm of nature. The interest in the natural world felt by Roger Bacon was undoubtedly due to Aristotle's observation of natural phe- nomena. The watchword of the thought of the day was the Reasonableness of the Faith, and this, Aquinas maintained, was perfectly intelligible even to the smallest particular. But hardly had the generation of Aquinas passed away than this union was seen to be hollow. The third period is one of rupture and divorce between reason and faith. It is very curious to note how from the two sides equally the fatal change of attitude was effected. John Duns Scotus (1274-1308), who had refined and dis- tinguished beyond all human belief to the extent of twelve folio volumes before he died at the age of 34, was an ardent devoted son of the Church, but he aimed the first blow at Scholasticism by disturbing the concordat of the thirteenth century. He denied that Aquinas had demon- strated the reasonableness of the faith. Christian doctrine transcended reason and had to be believed. Another Briton, William of Ockham, took two strides backward (or forward) for one of Scotus, in reviving the Nominalism of Roscellin, and declaring, like him, that the rational expression of the leading Christian dogmas was impossible. That Roscellin should have beforehand by implication proclaimed the nullity of the Scholastic attempt was as little grateful to the Church as to Anselm, and accordingly Roscellin, who had even exceeded the intellectual licence of Abelard, was condemned and his doctrine banned for two centuries. But the times vi. ] Elements of General Philosophy. 51 had changed, and Ockham, milder than Roscellin, could better gain access to men's minds. Professing implicit belief in all the articles of the faith, he proceeded to show, as Kant did later, how impotent was Reason to establish any one of them. Highly gifted, possessing great force of character, and a Franciscan, Ockham gave the Church little cause to love him, and his doctrines did not at once find favour. Nevertheless the times were ready for it, and the Church had gradually to bring herself to support those who declared that the faith could not be explained because it was too high. But this theory was adopted by independent thinkers as giving, in the mere shadow of restraint it imposed, a chance to get virtually free ; and the Church and the world, having agreed to differ, went farther and farther asunder till they turned their backs on each other. The Church might go on believing and exacting what belief it could; but while far from indisposed to believe, men insisted that they would also freely inquire. The influence of the Church was extinguished in different degrees at different places. Events had happened which would have broken Scholasticism even had it been less shaken from within. Human vision and human power were being extended on all sides, in every sphere of human interest. The East had become known through the crusades, and now explorers had unveiled a world and an ancient civilisation in the far West. The reign of darkness, dimly lit hitherto by a circumscribed stock of ideas, once broken, many of those ideas had to be changed or surrendered. Most revolutionising of all were the results of Copernicus's flash of thought. The earth was not fixed and flat, nor the centre of things, but only a revolving satellite, one of many specks in the starry sky, and away E 2 52 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. on every side, down as well as up, space ran out into the illimitable. Europe was dwarfed in the world ; the world was dwarfed in the universe. The heavens existed for other beings than the human race. The right of private judgment was claimed for every separate individuality till, at the beginning of the sixteenth century, Europe was rent in twain. The revival of letters dates from the fall of Constan- tinople in 1453, when Greek scholars were driven West. The next 150 years witnessed a great revulsion. When through those refugees the true Plato became known, there was a wild wave of Platonic revival. Then attempts were made to understand the true Aristotle, but generally he was decried as the instrument of the Scholastics and, in the heat of reaction, reviled for the artificial supremacy to which they had exalted him. Every Greek school had its adherents who fancied they had lit upon ideas that were all the emancipated world could want. Most remarkable of all were the premature attempts at constructive philosophy by the Italian Nature-philosophers, of whom Telesius was perhaps the most earnest and Giordano Bruno the best known and most imposing. These were endeavours, on a purely secular basis of objective consideration, to bring into order and explain the universe in its new vastness. Bruno was burnt at Rome in 1600. Four years previous had seen the birth of Descartes. Period of Transition. The Church philosophy, while it ceased to advance in the fifteenth century, lingered on until the modern movement in philosophy took definite shape. After the fourteenth century the best minds were no longer content to be church- philosophers, even if they were friendly to the established vi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 53 religion. A time of intellectual transition supervened, coin- ciding with the Renaissance, Renascence, or Revival of Letters. But the movement was very gradual. Many among the Schoolmen had been preparing the way for the Renais- sance. This transition may be considered as having lasted from 1450 till 1600. It was a time of great intellectual activity, chiefly of a destructive and disintegrating nature, although there were many bold constructive attempts. These, however, were only in revival of past points of view. The destroyers, in this epoch of fermentation, left little of per- manent value. The Modern Period. With 1600 begins the modern period, properly speaking. Since that time there has been a continuous intellectual flow till now, and there is reason to expect it may continue. The movement has not only been rich in event, it has been European to an extent to which the Church philosophy was not, much less the Greek. The great Scholastic thinkers, it is true, were of different nationalities, chiefly Italian, French, and British, and of these more especially British. The greatest of all, Aquinas, was an Italian, but nearly all the great steps were taken by men of these islands. But whatever nationality they belonged to, they abjured it and became Churchmen. It is only below the surface that we discern the national characteristics. In the modern period, on the other hand, not only do all the cultured races of Europe take part, but the national differences, especially in the British contributors, are far more marked. There is consequently far greater complexity. And whatever else the period has included, there has been a continuous British philosophy. 54 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. The Modern Scientific Movement. Side by side with modern philosophy there has been, to a degree unparalleled before, a properly scientific movement. There is but one name to represent positive science in the preceding period the name of the Franciscan monk, Roger Bacon (1214-1294). He alone, while the Scholastic mind was turned away from nature and wholly occupied with general philosophy, was profoundly interested in the investigation of natural phenomena. For his pains he was imprisoned twenty or thirty years. Like Archimedes, he stands without known forerunners or successors. It was not till Galileo arose that physical science entered on its modern course. It is in the modern period that the work of special scientific inquiry begins, with ever-increasing subdivision. Some of the leading modern philosophers rank among the scientific discoverers, e.g., Descartes and Leibniz ; but modern science commenced its career before modern philosophy. Galileo figures in the first decades of the seventeenth century (1564-1642). Following him there was a continual scientific advance. He was mainly occupied with physics ; Harvey, (1578-1657) with physiology. Pascal (1623-1662) devoted himself to physics and mathematics as well as to philosophy. Boyle (1627-1691) is the type of the modern scientific man, of no speculative power, content with eliciting positive results without troubling himself about their relations to other results. Newton (1642-1727) is the supreme representative of special scientific inquiry, though of so wide a range that he is quite above the common rank of inquirers. He laid out what has been accepted as the true physical system of the universe, but becomes confused (in comparison, e.g. vi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 55 with Locke) when dealing with its speculative aspect. After Newton science branched out and developed gradually into its present high specialisation. At the present time a man must specialise or do nothing. But it was Copernicus (1473- 1543) who, in setting the minds of men at the proper point of view for contemplating the universe, prepared the way for Galileo and for Newton, and enabled those that came after to engage in their special inquiries. By the philosophic movement, as distinct from the scientific, we mean the thinking of men who put themselves essentially at the subjective point of view. They do not exclude the practice of, or the having regard to, a scientific investigation of nature, but they aim at bringing together the results obtained in science, and hold that the study of things must be supplemented by a study of thoughts, the study of nature by a study of things in relation to man. LECTURE VII. MODERN PHILOSOPHY. Divisions. THE whole movement of Modern Philosophy has been described as an attempt to come at a knowledge of things from a consideration of the conditions and powers of human reason. It starts from the subjective point of view, from that of the knowing mind. Herein it is distinguished from ancient philosophy, which took an objective point of view, as well as from Scholasticism, which was fettered by a system of belief held to be revealed. Within this movement we meet early with an opposition in thought that admits of greatly varied expression. The German classifications, e. g. Schwegler's and others, are somewhat unsatisfactory. Schwegler, Kuno Fischer, and most of the German historians, divide all schools into Realists and Idealists those who explain thoughts from things, and those who explain things from thoughts. But this is a bad use of ambiguous, much abused terms. Realist, e. g. has been used both in the question of the perception of an external world and also in that of the reality of ' universals.' It was proposed by Kant to use the term Metaphysical Dog- matists or Dogmatic Metaphysicians, and the usage has become common in Germany ; but this does not apply Elements of General Philosophy. 57 farther than Wolff. Kant, coming after Wolff, it is often said, inaugurated a period of Critical Philosophy, appearing as a critical thinker in relation to two movements pre- ceding him Metaphysical Dogmatism and Empiricism, the latter, he found, having been carried by Hume into Scepticism. Were we at the Kantian point of view this division of modern thought might do; as it is, we must find a place for such as Kant. Descartes and Bacon. Modern philosophy, as distinct from the pursuit of modern science, begins as late as the second generation of the seventeenth century with Descartes, and not before. It is in relation to him that we have to understand all who follow. Bacon, who flourished a generation earlier than Descartes, has more relation to the scientific than to the philosophic movement, and had no intellectual succession till long after Descartes. Hobbes caught none of Bacon's enthusiasm for laborious inductive research (though he came into per- sonal contact with him), and showed only a very general agreement with him as to the ultimate springs of human knowledge in sense. Bacon's system fructified later on, mainly in physical science. Whatever philosophy there was in England in the middle of the seventeenth century was not truly Baconian. Modern Empirical Philosophy, or Empiri- cism, took its proper beginning in Locke's Essay concerning Human Understanding (1690) a work which was partly Baconian and regarded experience as the key of knowledge. All the other leaders in the modern movement grow out from Descartes in a continuous philosophic line. Never- theless, though in Bacon the strictly philosophical ideas and results are a small part of his writings compared with 58 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Descartes', he is without question to be numbered among (mental) philosophers. To proclaim that the human mind must begin, in everything, with simple particular experiences, and that all other knowledge is pretence or error, is a philo- sophical idea. The study of nature on Baconian principles may be only positive physical science, but in him it was philosophy to call men back from a vain manipulation of words and abstractions to the methodic observation and interpretation of the real phenomena of nature. Moreover, Bacon's idea has its application to mind as well as nature, and therein leads and has led to philosophical results of a sufficiently far-reaching cast. Rationalism and Experitntialistn, There are thus two main lines to be distinguished those who say that knowledge is explicable from reason 1 , and those who hold it is explicable from experience and these hold good up to Kant, when we begin to get approximations from one line to another : Kant, e. g. approximates to the Experientialists from the Rationalist side ; nor is Reid a pure Experientialist. We cannot label the varieties of human thought as exclusively of one kind or the other. Descartes undoubtedly heads the former, and Bacon may be allowed to head the latter, but nowhere must we strain the con- nexions. We must look only for general similarity in habits of thought. All schools allow the distinction between reason and experience as being, either or both, the ultimate con- stituents of human knowledge, but in modern times thinkers 1 The student must distinguish between the narrower peculiarly German connotation of Rationalism used here, and its wider meaning 1 , common in this country, of the revolt of individual reason or judgment against authority in all ultimate questions. ED. VIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 59 differ in the prominence they assign to one or the other. English philosophers have always put forward experience as that, in which to seek an explanation of knowledge. Thinkers of other countries, have, on the whole, been dis- posed to give pre-eminence to reason ; but Rationalists differ much in the relative weight they allow to experience as an additional factor to reason, just as Experientialists differ with respect to reason as an additional factor to experience. Let us survey both lines of thought. Rationalists. Descartes began, both in matter and method, a distinct movement during two generations. This was carried on by his (the Cartesian) school Geulincx, Arnauld, Male- branche, and especially Spinoza. Geulincx, Arnauld and Malebranche sought to be thorough-going Cartesians. Spinoza, while following Descartes, had, besides, distinctly independent views ; the most characteristic aspect of him came from the Jewish philosophy of the Middle Ages. Before and after Spinoza's death Leibniz, though bitterly opposed to the former and appealing from Descartes back to the Schoolmen, kept up modern metaphysical Rationalism or a priori speculation for yet another generation. Like Spinoza, he was a markedly original thinker, although he thought with reference to the results of Descartes and Spinoza. He was followed by Wolff, who, of less impor- tance, joins Kant to Leibniz, of whom he is a disciple. Wolff had hardly completed his encyclopaedic labour of putting form and system into Leibniz's disjointed labours when Kant began his academical career in a state of ' dogmatic slumber,' from which it needed the scepticism of Hume to wake him. Kant called these, his predecessors, CQ - <^ E 2 o a o t-~ T 1 M ^ ~ r -s C/) ^g V M H I M c/5 L c i ~ Q^ to I 7 .o o (1 rt R St (J VIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 61 ' dogmatic ' in opposition to himself as critical, and to the sceptical philosophy of Hume. They are also called Sub- stantialists because each starts with a conception of substance, the variations in which constitute the chief differences between them. The Rationalist Succession. Without derogating from individual thinkers, we may say that the three great Rationalists, Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, form stages of one movement in the progressive development of philosophy in an orderly sequence of thought, although Spinoza protested against Descartes, and Leibniz protested against both. Spinoza takes up the problems that Descartes had left, and solves them to all intents and purposes in Cartesian terms, as he would not have done unless Descartes' results and methods had been there. Leibniz also takes those results, and from them tries to get to others, arriving however at such as require him to make a fresh start from a different position. And although he began to arrive at his results without Spinoza, they were emphasised and worked out in conscious antagonism to Spinoza. Cartesianism. Now Descartes gave to modern philosophy its subjective character. Seeking some immediate, irrefutable certainty as a starting-point or fulcrum for all knowledge, he put aside the testimony of authority, of tradition, of opinion, of the sphere of sense, saying of these dubitandum est de omnibus. He only found standing ground in his own reflective self- consciousness. Cogito ergo sum, or rather dubito ergo sum, for it was in the fact of his thought as doubting that he found the immediate certainty he sought. But he soon abandoned this epistemological position for one of dogmatism Ego 62 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. sum res cogitans and then for the dogmatic Dualism of ' I am a thinking substance, thinking of a substance that does not think' Thus he assumed both mind and matter, the key- note of dogmatic metaphysic being that whatever we clearly and distinctly conceive z'j, or represents, Reality that thought is the measure of Reality. And the truth of this dual as- sumption was guaranteed for him, he held, by the existence of a perfect and veracious Deity. The Development of Cartesianism, Now this dualism of Descartes is really double, being a dualism as between God and the world, and also as between mind and body. And the problem of the co-existence of substances in either case was carried on by Spinoza and the Occasionalists, Malebranche, Geulincx and Arnauld. The latter concluded that the apparent interaction between mind and body was illusory, the actions of the mind being only so many occasions for the intervention of divine power resulting in the corresponding bodily action. But the creature was not only robbed of the power of initiating action, he was also deprived of the ability to know. Know- ledge, according to Malebranche, takes place by ' the vision of all things in God/ i. e. it is not we but God that knows through us. Here we have the consistent development of what was implicit in Descartes. It is the ' death of philosophy.' Spinoza's central conception was that of substance. He started with it, whereas Descartes worked up to it. But he could not allow more than one substance, all process and all change in the universe being necessarily determined by the nature of that one. ' Besides God,' he wrote, ' no substance can be given or conceived.' vii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 63 Critical Philosophy. Kant, on the other hand, raised the question as to whether we can know substance at all, substance being a notion which, while it underlies experience, is not given in expe- rience. He critically examined reason and not experience, yet he approaches nearer to Experientialism than the other Rationalists. Kant's movement of thought has had a profound influence over all Europe. So much has grown from his philosophy that we cannot here deal with it. Many thinkers have been his disciples, but the great movement in German philosophy of Schelling, Fichte and Hegel was as relatively independent as the departures of Spinoza and Leibniz with reference to Descartes. They philosophise with reference to Kant's critical inquiry, but are not themselves Kantians. Common Sense Philosophy. The Scottish school of ' Common Sense ' philosophy of Reid and his followers was first of all a protest against the offensive, negative conclusions of Hume, but consisted in a partial departure only from Locke, for it sheltered itself under Bacon as the defender of Experience. Reid sought to make out that, in addition to the senses, there are principles of a common ' sense ' inherent in the human mind from the beginning and transcending experience. Dugald Stewart followed Reid, not contributing much original matter, and was followed by Hamilton, who, although he glories in being a disciple of Reid, was influenced in his thought by Kant. Without being a thorough Kantian or well trained in Kantian philosophy, he became through his Kantian studies heir to a larger insight than Reid possessed. 64 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. The Experientialists. There is nothing on the Experientialist side like the definite succession there is upon the side of the Rationalists, although the books are apt to declare the reverse. Bacon was not carried on by Hobbes, nor Hobbes by Locke. Each went on his own way after his own manner. They all start from a consideration of Sense, but do not constitute definite milestones upon a certain track. All are more or less Nominalist. Bacon preached with unsurpassed fervour the necessity of turning to external nature, and it is mainly scientific men who have felt his influence. His general position (v. p. 58) is that knowledge begins with particular experience that general knowledge must be got from particulars and tested by experience. But he can scarcely rank as the father of Experiential philosophy. Hobbes' s philosophy, again, was markedly provocative to succeeding thinkers, but exercised no regular, systematic influence such as we find on the other side. But when we come to Locke, we encounter a philosophic initiator who may be called so in the same sense as Descartes. He began a new movement which amounted to a definite system of Experientialism. He set himself to prove the problem of human knowledge, and his watchword is Experience as much as Descartes' was Reason. It was the latter who set him thinking, although it was the latter he opposed. Leibniz's Nouveaux Essais were written against the Essay concerning Human Understanding. Locke stirred up Leibniz to investigate the origin of knowledge from a different stand- point from that taken in the essay. Locke's essay was present to the mind of Berkeley, who took up human knowledge in the spirit of an Experientialist. Later on he came to be occupied with the question of our vii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 65 knowledge of matter, and solved it in general correspondence with the principles of Locke's philosophy, yet without being more of a Lockian than Spinoza and Leibniz were Cartesians. He took up the question of knowledge as he did because Locke left it where he did. Twenty-eight years after the appearance of Berkeley's Principles of Human Knowledge Hume wrote his Treatise of Human Nature, carrying for- ward Experientialism as far in some respects as it could be carried, so that in those particular lines there was nothing left for followers to do. He excited more opposi- tion than adherence not only in his own country, but notably in Kant. Hereby English philosophy, as in the case of Locke and Leibniz, came into contact with European thought. Psychological Philosophy. Associationism. While his general philosophy was thus carried out by Berkeley and Hume so as to provoke a reaction, Locke set on foot another movement. Although he was a general philo- sopher and not a psychologist, he nevertheless worked out his philosophy in a psychological spirit. He started from the psychologist's point of view, with the notion of investigating mind in the same scientific way as Newton was investigating nature. This departure had an effect in the very next generation through Berkeley, who carried out special psychological investigation with surprising acuteness in his New Theory of Vision. Hume also, without putting forward any system of psychology, worked in a psychological spirit, and discussed particular psychological questions in a notable way, especially the laws of association as con- taining an explanation of knowledge. Again, Hartley's work on Man is of the utmost importance for the so-called F 66 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Associationist school, which in psychology tries to get a scientific doctrine of mind as such, and in philosophy tries to solve the general problem of knowledge in connexion with that scientific doctrine. Now it is usually said that Hume gave a great impulse to the English Associationist movement. My belief, on the con- trary, is that James Mill had no special impulse from Hume. If he at all resembled the latter, it was because he started from a similar basis tending to similar conclusions. The origin of the later Associationists is in Hartley and not in Hume. Or, to put it more adequately, the origin of the present English school of the Mills is to be found in the trio, Locke, Berkeley, and Hartley, rather than in Hume 1 . Hartley expressly connected himself with Locke, as Berkeley did. Hume expressly connected himself with Berkeley. We may tabulate them thus : Locke Hartley Berkeley James Mill Hume Hartley needs to be connected with Berkeley, though he did not expressly borrow from him. James Mill's direct descendant is Professor Bain, not John Stuart Mill, who follows somewhat more in the philosophical wake of Hume. Hartley had a philosophy, but not an effective one ; he shone as a psychologist. J. S. Mill is, nevertheless, connected with Hartley through his father. Locke's central idea, viz. that the limits of our knowing 1 Vide J. S. Mill's introduction to J. Mill's Analysis of the Human Mind. VIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 67 faculty, in regard to the nature and the validity of our knowledge, are only to be understood in reference to a psychological analysis, was introduced into France, together with the Newtonian philosophy of nature, by Voltaire about 1730, supplanting the Cartesian philosophy in both meta- physic and science. Condillac (1715-1780) and Destutt de Tracy (1754-1836), chief among French Sensationalists, greatly affected the Scottish thinker, Thomas Brown. Brown contributed the most important discussion prior to Professor Bain of the part played by muscular sense in objective perception, and still holds the second place. Of present-day Associationists, Mr. Herbert Spencer is chiefly concerned with a philosophy of evolution on a basis of biological principles. An Experientialist, he approximates as closely to the Rationalist border by allowing non- experiential elements in knowledge as Kant did from the Rationalist side in the other direction. Mr. Spencer himself claims to be just on the border. Many think he unites the two sides. Kant, however, laid claim to a similar position, and yet was very distinct from Mr. Spencer. For LECTURE VIII read Bain, Mental Science, App. A. to p. 26. F 2 LECTURE VIII. UNIVERSALS. Why Scholasticism was mainly occupied with ' Universalia? WE are now in a position to inquire more closely into those great special questions raised by philosophic thought which I enumerated at the close of Lecture III. From Descartes onward the great question of philosophy has been as to the relation of reason and experience in knowledge. Now, Plato and Aristotle (who practically represent ancient epistemology in the West) were interested both in this problem and in that of the universality of knowledge, while during the whole of the middle period the central question of philosophy was not so much the former as that of the relation between the universal and the particular in knowledge. The more modern question is, after all, the same as the latter, but in another form and with a difference of emphasis ; experience is experience of particulars, while reason is concerned with universals. Why, then, does only one of the two questions occupy the thought of the Middle Period? The fact is that both the middle and modern periods were occupied witli both questions, or with these two aspects of the more general question, viz. as to the import of human knowledge; but the Elements of General Philosophy. 69 thought of men in the Middle Ages had been directed to the aspect of the universality of knowledge by an accidental circumstance. This circumstance (v. Bain, App. pp. 23, 24 ; and supra, Lect. V) was that one portion of Porphyry's Isagoge, containing an introduction to the Categories of Aristotle, was preserved in translation during the early Middle Ages, whereas it was not till the twelfth and thirteenth centuries that the Schoolmen had a complete translation of Aristotle's works. Now this fragment suggested the question of the relation of different general notions to one another, and hence it came about that this aspect of knowledge occupied philosophers predominantly down to the end of the Scholastic period, till every side of the question had been touched upon and they had come to practical agreement. Modern philo- sophy also agrees in the main upon the subject, although it was bound in its turn to reconsider it. The difference in modern times is regarding the psychological question. Concept Psychologically and Philosophically regarded. We have distinguished knowledge psychologically regarded from knowledge philosophically regarded. Let us now mark off the psychological bearing of knowledge as universal or general from the philosophical aspect. General intellection, knowing, or cognition we dealt with under thought or con- ception (in the wider sense), and for the product of conception we used the term concept. And the psychological question of the concept became for us, How do we come to know generally? How do we arrive, i.e. under what laws of mental action do we arrive, at that kind of knowledge which we call conceptual ? Conceiving (Elements of Psychology, Lect. XXV, XXVI) arises under certain psychological laws out of historically prior intellectual products. Now of 70 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. these the percept has corresponding to it an objective thing at least, we assume that it has and some images also have a corresponding reality in the realm of being, in so far as they are literal re-percepts, while some again have not. But our question now is, Has the concept a corresponding reality? Is there, for instance, a real being to correspond to the concept ' man ' ? Mill calls ' man ' concrete ; is it as concrete as 'this man ' ? No, we cannot generalise save by abstracting, and ' man ' is abstract as involving generalisation. What then does this abstract generalisation or ' Universal ' portend in the sphere of being? Is it a mere subjective construction, or does the concept represent reality ? What is the relation of 'man' the 'universal' to 'this man 'or 'that man,' of the General to the Particular, of the One to the Many, of in- dividual changing things to the whole universe ? Which has reality ? If only ' The One remains, the many change and pass ' ; as Shelley sang ', the question arises, Do the Many exist at all ? Platonic Realism. Now this question, applied by Schoolmen to religious tenets, had been rationally discussed by Plato, who probed the matter deeper than any before him. By Platonic Realism is meant Plato's doctrine of the relation of the One to the Many, of the Universal to the Particular. His standpoint was a develop- ment of the question as faced by Socrates. Socrates saw that human knowledge is mainly knowing by way of con- cepts, and his philosophy was summed up in efforts at getting clear general notions. We arrive at knowledge on a large scale only through the conceptual form ; only thus 1 Elegy to Keats. viii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 71 can we bring together experience as knowledge. If we know for the most part by way of concepts, if all that we can call scientific knowledge is conceptual, i.e. is knowledge of classes or kinds, then the question arises whether that which we know in the form of concepts or ideas does not represent reality, or that which truly is. Thus Plato, following his master's line and holding that knowledge properly so called is of ideas only, declared that therefore ideas and nought else are what really exist, and that, by comparison with the ideas, known and really existing, anything that we commonly speak of as particular things things of sense have, in the full sense of the word, no reality, and are only pale shadows of real existence. So far from asking, as might in these times of a developed psychology be asked, whether anything corre- sponded to the concept objectively in the same sense as is assumed in the case of the percept, Plato maintained that it was the concepts, general notions or ideas, that are the only real beings, and not so-called individuals. ' Table,' for example, exists ; individual tables are mere passing shows, while the idea ' table ' exists really and eternally. If any one gets a true knowledge of ' table ' it is not by way of sense, but by a reminiscence of a former mental life. Tables this table, that table did not exist yesterday, will not exist to- morrow. But ' table ' was before all tables, and will be after all tables. In other words, the particulars of sense, whether considered separately or brought together in an aggregate or class, do not really, fully exist. That only can be said really and fully to exist which is THOUGHT. Platonic Idealism. This theory viz. to repeat, that if it is the idea (universal or general notion) which we are dealing with when we really know, 72 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. then it is the idea only that really exists is logically possible on the ground it assumes, and marks a special type of mind. In the Middle Ages it came to be called by the Schoolmen, who were great masters of nomenclature, the doctrine of Realism. Plato's expression of this view has never been surpassed, and never will be. But if he is the greatest of Realists in this the original sense of the term, he none the less remains the typical Idealist in any sense and for all time. For Platonic Realism and Platonic Idealism are one and the same doctrine, Plato being a Realist because of the reality he ascribed to ideas, and an Idealist because it is ideas to which he ascribed reality. He is not the one to the exclusion of the other, unless indeed we attach to Realism and Idealism the meaning they have come to bear in modern times as opposite theories of our perception of an external world J . In that case Plato ceases to be a Realist, and is a pure Idealist. In the question of universals, Realism is only another aspect of the more general Idealism. Aristotelian Realism. What, then, is the antithesis to Realism in its original sense? The theory which in Aristotle took shape as a doctrine of essence, and which became divided against itself as the con- trasted theories of Conceptualism and Nominalism (names which are also derived from the nomenclature of Scholasticism), scarcely constitutes an antithesis. Aristotle broke away from the Realism of his master by declaring that particular things have a real existence, but neither they nor universals exist independently of each other ; the universal exists in the 1 The student must not confound the philosophical connotations of these terms with their modern usage in artistic and literary criticism. ED. VIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 73 particular as its essence. He may thus be considered as a modified Realist. He began by saying that all things which can be thought of or predicated can be brought to ten classes or categories of concepts. But only the first, Sub- stance (ova-ia), can be the subject of predication. Quantity, Quality, and the other seven attributes do not exist in the same sense as Substance. Now we can only predicate exist- ence of a coricrete thing, not of an idea. Here he seems to deny reality to the concept. But he further distinguishes between a first and a second substance, the first applicable to a concrete thing of sense which, informed by its universal essence, really and fully exists, and is the subject of a pro- position ; the second, indicating the general concrete, may be subject or predicate. E. g. Socrates is a man. (ist Substance) (2nd Substance) Man is mortal. In this way existence can be predicated of concept. In- dividual things are substance in the full sense ; in essence they are universals. But abstractions have no real existence. Universalia post rem. Plato's position of extreme Realism being summed up in the scholastic formula, Universalia ante rem (res = thing of sense), and Aristotle's modified Realism being described as Um'rersah'a in re, the antithesis to Realism for which there is no inclusive name is best brought out in the corresponding formula, Universalia post rem ; i. e. it is only from a know- ledge of things in particular that we come to know universals. in other words, to form the merely subjective constructions termed concepts, abstract ideas or general notions. Only 74 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. particular things exist ; the universal is a mere instrument of thought for getting at a knowledge of particulars. This was the theory of Epicureans and Stoics. But, as I have indicated, the formula was interpreted in two ways. When, in the first age of the Schoolmen, Platonic Realism was rampant, an extreme form of Nominalism, viz. that the general thought or universal is a name and nothing else (vox el praeterea nihil\ was contended for by Roscellin. We cannot think generally without the help of names ; what, then, is the universal but a name (nomen) ? This in fact was the anti-Realism of the Stoics and Epicureans. Later, in the thirteenth century, when Scholasticism was at its height, the predominant Aristotelian Realism shaded off into Conceptualism, viz. that the universal was not a mere word (flatus vocis] but a mode of human cognition, though formed from and after the perception of particulars. This was coupled with the doctrine of essences, of ' universalia in re.' Some indeed tried to reconcile Platonic Realism with it also by the theory of the real existence of universals in the divine mind. When, however, Scholasticism was dying, William of Ockham (a village in Surrey) gave a very decided expression to Nominalism as opposed to Conceptualism, maintaining that the mind arrives at universals through the use of words. And at the end of the Scholastic period the chief thinkers were declared Nominalists. Harmony between Science and Philosophy. After two centuries of transition the foremost minds of the seventeenth century, Descartes, for example, turned their at- tention to physical nature and helped to create modern science. Now r the modern science of nature is based on a philosophical view that is antithetic to the Platonic theory. Realism has VIIL ] Elements of General Philosophy. 75 never regained its importance in the modern period ; it was practically overthrown by the growth of positive science. Or we may say that modern science has sprung up because the philosophical problem of Realism was fought out. The Realist despises the things of sense as vain shows with no reality. The man of science says they do exist and are worth investigating. With Conceptualism and Nominalism, on the other hand, modern science can get on ; they in fact attuned men's minds for scientific research, which goes on the assumption that it is the particular things which really exist, works up from particulars to universals, and refuses to re- cognise the truth of universals without verifying by particulars. Any one may now be a Platonic Realist, but he must then give up the modern science of nature. In fact there always have been Realists and always will be. It was a mistake for Mill to speak of Realism as exploded (in his Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy}. Carlyle was a Realist ; so also is Ruskin great men, though not philosophers. And the standpoint, consistently developed, leads to an ascetic doctrine of morals. Carlyle and Ruskin recognise the hostility between modern science and Platonism, and this is why they decry the former. Carlyle hated science, but he excepted mathematics, as did Plato, who said that if a man could not geometrise he could not philosophise. From their point of view science cannot but be absurd. No Realist thinks it worth while to treat of physics and chemistry. If a man prefers to live in the contemplation of Eternal Ideas, this in its way is very good. Theologically such a one will be a Pantheist. But if he would rise to something worth calling knowledge of nature, the right way is that of positive science, with its Inductive Method of working up to general expressions from particulars. Positive science is not all-sufficient for the 76 Elements of General Philosophy. inquiring mind, and should be supplemented by a philosophy not inconsistent with it. But Realism is inconsistent with science. No person who is at heart a Realist can have that kind of interest in particular things upon which thorough- going science rests. In external nature we must start from the concrete particular ; hence we have in the modern period an anti-Realistic philosophy, instead of an antagonism between our philosophy and our science. For LECTURE IX read Bain, loc. cit. pp. 26-33. LECTURE IX. UNIVERSALS. NOMINALISM AND CONCEPTUALISM. ' Res ' as real. MODERN philosophy then, as being in the main concordant with modern science, is anti-Realistic, or, in the wider sense of the word, Nominalistic. Philosophy for the most part, and especially English philosophy, has assumed that the Platonic doctrine is untenable, and that some form of the antithesis, that it is particular things which really exist, must be accepted. Thus in modern times the conflict has been narrowed to the opposition between Nominalism and Conceptualism. The great question now became Under what conditions does the human mind conceive ? What con- stitutes thinking as opposed to other modes of intellection ? The Ground of the Problem shifted. Note that the problem has been shifted from metaphysical to psychological ground. It is no longer a question of what may be said really to exist. Conceptualists and Nominalists agree in declaring that the universal has only a subjective existence, that the concept has no objective existence like the percept, but is only arrived at in the mind with a view to the understanding of the particulars. This is the anti- Realistic metaphysic of their position. But if we would give any more positive assertion about them, we must do so 78 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. in psychological terms. The difference between them is psychological only, and it has played an important part in modern psychology. In England, where, from the time of Locke, the psychological interest began to prevail and where psychology first assumed a scientific form, that difference has been much discussed. Not so abroad. Hamilton, it is true, made light of the difference, but then his psychology is decidedly weak. Nominalism in England. The general train of English thought has been in the direction of Nominalism. Now the thorough-going Nomina- list says two things: (i) that it is impossible to think generally without language; (2) that the mind can only represent the concrete particular as such. Hobbes makes both these statements ; Berkeley, only the second ; neverthe- less he as well as Hume and the Mills are distinctly Nominalists, though in different senses. Hobbes seems to say that thought is expression in words and nothing else. Still he is not far wrong. It is since his time that the importance of language in the function of conceiving has been emphasised. Locke, in the immortal third Book of his Essay, is strongly Nominalistic and impressed with the necessity of language. In Book IV, however, he shows a strong Conceptualistic vein, maintaining that we can think of ' triangle ' which is not isosceles, nor equilateral, nor scalene. (This Berkeley denies.) But this Conceptualism of Locke's is probably only a bad way of distinguishing the intension from the extension of the concept. Because ' triangle ' o;tends to all three, no one of the three particulars therefore enters into the /'//tension of ' triangle.' He con- fuses the abstract with the general. The Scottish school, on the other hand, is more Con- ix.] Elements of General Philosophy. 79 ceptualistic than the English, Dugald Stewart less so than others. Reid is Conceptualistic. Hamilton's logic is dis- tinctly Conceptualistic, yet in the lectures on metaphysic he adopts Berkeley's view. Hamilton, however, does not so much give his own thinking as get it from certain German authorities. The Mills, I have said, are Nominalists ; so is Professor Bain. Taine's chapter on the Concept is the best state- ment of good Nominalistic doctrine (see his Intelligence]. The Ground of Difference. The Conceptualists say that the concept is as truly a definite fact of mental construction, an actual subjective somewhat that can be called a representation, as is the percept. Whereas, according to all Nominalists, conceiving is either bringing up a number of particulars one after another, i. e. having a series of percepts, or else we are, when conceiving, only imaging a particular percept, while leaving out of sight the individual particulars. There are Concepts and Concepts. But Conceptualists and Nominalists both err in trying to find one uniform expression for a very graduated aggregate. Concepts vary so much in the scale of abstractness (cf. 'tiger/ ' iron/ ' father/ ' nation ') that it is hopeless to attempt any uniform representation to suit all. The concept is not a collection, nor a series, of particular images. The concept 'sheep' is not a flock of sheep. Just as we distinguish between the collective and the general, so we must distin- guish between the concept and a series of percepts. The former is a means of bringing together a multitude otherwise than as a series, and will vary in definiteness according to the degree of abstractness. In the case of exactly similar 8o Elements of General Philosophy, [LECT. objects the concept abstracts from the differences in time and space only. Generic images represent the truth about those concepts where the similarity is very overpowering. Sometimes, finally, conceiving proceeds by way of symbols ; i. e. there are concepts of which we have no image unless it be of particulars in succession, and between which the likeness is fixed by a word. We use names of course for individuals as well as for concepts ; indeed, we do not know a thing fully till we know its name. But it is remarkable that when a name is a mere adjunct it is apt to be forgotten; but where a conception, e. g. of justice, depends, for any coherence and definiteness it may possess, upon having a name, we do not forget it. A case of pathology throws light here. Some forms of organic decay are connected with a disturbance of the faculty of speech, or aphasia. And instances of this occur where the intellectual powers are very little affected. The patient, e.g. is able to speak in general language, but forgets the names of particular kinds of things. Emerson in his last years was subject to this. Words like ' table ' and ' hat ' he could not recollect, but he was quite able to substitute more general expressions, e. g. ' Put the kind of thing that covers head on to the surface that has legs/ Names of definite concretes were forgotten where abstract terms were still within his power. Why? Because for his knowledge of the former he was not dependent upon language. To express the relation he did need language ; he had not lost speech where it was indispensable. The two Types of Nominalism. Now there are Nominalists and Nominalists. Berkeley, for example, is merely anti-Conceptualistic, and owes his ix.] Elements of General Philosophy. 81 reputation for Nominalism solely to the opinion of Hume. He only takes up the negative attitude, that there is no definite representation of anything but either as perceived or as definitely imaged. He says nothing about the necessity for names. On the contrary, he declares that we can think without language, and that we should think better than we do, could we keep the names of our ideas out of our thoughts so strangely has knowledge ' been perplexed and darkened by the . . . general ways of speech V Whereas extreme Nominalists like Roscellin declare that concepts are nothing more than names. With regard to the former type of Nominalists, there is this to be said: So far from it being true that the idea is always of a particular concrete, it might be maintained that our imagining and perceiving are always a kind of abstraction. Do I, in looking at that pillar, perceive all the attributes? No; I fill it in by repeated perceptions. My percept of it at any moment is a perception of it under some one aspect only. Perception of a particular involves abstraction. The generic image, to which I have already alluded, was Mr. Gallon's term for that resultant to which, he affirmed, a number of like images give rise a resultant which is not like any one of them, nor is the whole together, but is yet representative of all (El. of Psy. p. 168). This position was supported by the now widely practised composite photography, by which Mr. Galton obtained not a blur of many faces, but an actual portrait, yet not of any one individual. This does not prove anything in relation to our conscious experience, but it may well be that the process of conceiving is analogous. But in so far as the Conceptualists maintain that we have always a clear 1 Berkeley, Principles, Introduction. G 82 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. consciousness of a body of concepts as such, they go too far. No Conceptualist has ever given a sufficient and satisfactory analysis of general knowledge. The Truth in Nominalism. With regard, on the other hand, to the latter type of Nominalists, whereas their identifying the concept with a name and nothing more is nonsensical and goes too far in the opposite direction, they are right to the extent of maintaining that all the more purely abstract ideas are had through and by, and not without, the help of signs, viz. language. Here ' no speech, no thought.' In proportion as thought becomes more general and more abstract, it needs some kind of instrument to work with. All thinking that is more than rudimentary necessitates language. Savages with poor language have poor thoughts. We must be careful to distinguish. Can we know without speech ? Unquestionably. Can we think (know generally, generalise) without speech ? Only to an elementary extent. The proper position then to take is that our power of bringing percepts together into concepts depends upon our power of using signs. Science, which is general knowledge, is found to progress according as it becomes embodied in a definite system of symbols. Condillac the Sensationalist had so strong an opinion of the importance of language that he defined a science as une langue bien faile. Indeed, Nominalism is often supposed to be connected with Sensationalism, because the two theories are associated in Condillac's philosophy. But it is just sensation that is independent of names and symbols. The error of the Sensationalist school consisted, as Mansel pointed out, in confounding the indispensable instrument of thought with thought itself. Philosophy is so backward because it ix.] Elements of General Philosophy. 83 has not a set of symbols for itself, but has to work with popular names. Nothing can be called an element of knowledge till it is taken up by others and thrown back on the speaker. People who are cut off from the use of language are found to have imperfect powers of generalisa- tion. Even with their manual system the dumb cannot develop any great ability for generalising. The signs no doubt are less pliable, but the chief reason is that they are still cut off from communication wilh the majority of their fellows. Speech is, as we saw in our psychology, a social, not an individual, product. It is with the need of communicating that speech arises. ' Sheep ' may be imaged in general without language, but a variety which we cannot image ' squeezes out,' i. e. expresses, some general sign from us. But this squeezing out would not have taken place but for the requirements of the common life. A man does not con- ceive for himself but in relation to others. Thus the true psychology of conception throws us back on the origin of speech. And hence what a man shall think will depend less on what he is in himself than on his social circumstances. If left to himself, his mental powers would be comparatively undeveloped. If knowledge were a mere aggregate of sensa- tions, the savage might be better off than other people. The superiority of civilised people consists in the fact that there are expressions in force for the new-born individual to avail himself of. It is impossible to over-estimate the importance of this factor, and of late years this idea of the great part played by language in helping us to arrive at knowledge, to which by ourselves we could not have attained, has been gaining ground 1 . 1 Cf. e. g. Professor Sayce's Introduction to the Science of Language. See also Mind, i. 263, and iv. 149, on the education of Laura Bridgman. G 2 84 Elements of General Philosophy. Conclusion. I do not, then, profess to solve the philosophic question at issue. Any man's philosophy is the expression of his whole being ; in every man's thinking there must be a personal subjective element. For me the true doctrine lies partly with Conceptualism and partly with Nominalism. It is a case of the shield with two sides : each theory says it has only one, and therein lies the error as well as the truth of each. Each side makes statements that are too absolute: they are true in what they affirm and false in what they deny. Conception varies too much for any universal statement as to concepts to hold good. But the statement that there may be a representation that is definite without being particular is true. For LECTURE X read : Bain, op. cit. Book IV, ch. viii. The student may also refer to Professor James's article : ' The Psychology of Belief,' Mind, xiv. p. 321. LECTURE X. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. KNOWLEDGE AND BELIEF. Transition to the Second Question. Some concepts, then, at least are explicable from sense- perception, i. e. are formed by way of abstraction from particular experiences. Are all concepts formed thus, or are some obtained otherwhence? What, in other words, does sense contribute to knowledge ? Granted that sense is of account for knowledge, it does not follow that know- ledge is mere sense or sense transformed. Thus we connect the question of universals with the controversy on the Nature, or, as it is also called, the Origin of Knowledge, which is the great central problem in dispute among the philosophers of the modern period. The Origin of Knowledge is not a good name for this question ; it is too psychological, and the philosophical question is not answered together with the psychological question. What we have to consider is the Nature of Knowledge how knowledge is constituted. Whereas in psychology we do not exhaust the consideration of know- ledge properly so called. 86 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Knowledge and Belief. Now the term ' knowledge ' is necessary for philo- sophy, especially modern philosophy, the central thought of which, from its beginning with Descartes, is that we cannot determine the nature of being before we have determined the nature of knowing, and that in any ultimate question we are strictly considering not so much what we are as what we know that we are. Hence we see the advantage of getting a word that is purely psychological, like intellection. We have also asserted that the term 'belief is of import for philosophy. Belief has both a psychological explanation and a philosophical import very much implicated in the question of the nature or origin of knowledge, and therefore it is that a short consideration of belief under both aspects will serve to show the bond and the distinction between psychology and philosophy, and also to introduce our special subject. The Psychology of Belief. Belief is a kind of conscious experience. Our psycho- logical question is to determine which kind. Professor Bain appears to treat it as a kind of volition by putting it under the head of Will. This is not so bad as it looks, for by Will he means, as we know, Conation ; wherefore he does not mean that when a man is believing he is necessarily willing, or making a voluntary determination. What then does he mean ? He places the consideration of belief where he does because he finds it has a certain reference to action. In believing we are ready to act ; unless we can show some kind of reference to action we are not believing. Under Will he deals with all activities as set on by feeling, and x.] Elements of General Philosophy. 87 generally with all motives to action, Belief being taken as one such motive. I excuse the arrangement but do not justify it. Whatever else Belief is, this is not the most funda- mental aspect. In willing we are doing something else than believing : in believing we are doing something else than will- ing. We all believe that life must come to an end, but this is different from willing to die. Yet, while there is an obvious difference between willing and believing, there is a subtle underlying connexion between the two. How often do we not say, a man believes a thing because he wants it so ? How much is not our belief an expression of our wishes ? It is quite possible to go on willing so intently that we end by believing. And I think that is at the bottom of Professor Bain's mind in his choice of treatment here. There is something in believ- ing which has a special kind of relation to willing. But is the fact that what we believe we are prepared to act on a real differential attribute of Belief, marking it off from other conscious experience? Is there any other state of mind where we are prepared to act ? Yes ; if I am prepared to act on belief, I am still more prepared to act on knowledge ; e. g. if I believed there were a tiger in the next room, I might venture to peep in ; but if I were ' sure,' if I knew there was, I should at once proceed either to lock myself in here or to run downstairs. This reference to action therefore, which unquestionably belongs to belief, is not its distinctive attribute since it is at least equally characteristic of another state. What else has Professor Bain said ? That our beliefs always contain an element of feeling. When we are believing we are always at the same time emotionally affected. Is this the differentia of belief as compared with knowledge ? Yes, 88 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. belief distinctly varies with feeling. Is our tiger heard scratching, the bold one says, Nonsense ! the timorous one says, Yes, it is there ! But knowledge is intellectual expres- sion apart from feeling. 2 + 2 = 4, however you may feel. It is a valuable point in Professor Bain's exposition to have thus connected belief with original spontaneity of feeling, with difference of temperament. We see then the difference between I imagine, I believe, I know, a tiger is in class-room No. 3. Belief is something like knowledge, but falling short of it. We may know that 9x7 = 63, but a child who does not yet understand the multiplication table may say, I feel sure that 9x7 = 63. ' Sure ' shows the connexion with intellection, ' feel ' the emotional aspect. Again, the phrase morally certain, another equivalent for ' believe/ brings out the conational aspect : ' certain ' is intellective, ' morally ' means ' certain so as to act upon it,' but not absolutely certain. Not full knowledge, but probability, and that is after all the guide of life. This distinctly emotional character of belief may help us to understand the relation of belief to conation. Conation is action under an impulse of feeling, action that is feeling- guided or determined by feeling ; it is action for an ' end,' and ' end ' always involves feeling. Belief is not action for an end, in order to feeling, but is something that goes on under feeling. Thus we see how easily the one could pass into the other, how action for feeling may result in action under feeling, so that what we will in starting, we end by believing. Well then, whatever emotional elements there may be in belief, there is something in it non-emotional. Here again we shall find the relation of belief to conation brought out markedly. In the instance of volition employed in our course of Psychology, namely, ' I will to open the door,' can I will x.] Elements of General Philosophy. 89 to open it without either knowing it can be opened, or believing it can be opened ? No, and hence whatever we call volition involves intellection. Believing the door can be opened and willing to open it are not the same, but the difference in my confidence lies between my believing that the door opens in a certain way and my knowing that it does. What then is there common to the belief and the knowledge as such ? A fact of intellectual representation. Belief is essentially a representative state of mind, and repre- sentation, as we know, enters into all intellection. But willing, or the disposition to act, is as such not representation, is not intellection with its discriminating and assimilating. In believing we are intellective, as in knowing. I believe the moon is round, i. e. I represent the back of it. Were the moon to turn round, I should know at least more than I do now. Belief, then, is fundamentally a mode of intel- lection. But whereas knowledge is, from the psychological point of view, adequately and exhaustively expressed as intellectual representation, belief, from the same point of view, is not adequately and exhaustively expressed as intel- lectual representation, because of the feeling involved in it. The Essential Complexity of Belief. Since belief is fundamentally a mode of intellection, and to a certain extent a mode of feeling also, it cannot be treated as merely a mode of conation. Professor Bain indeed only seems to do this ; his exposition really comes to this, that belief is a kind of intellectual representation, accompanied with, and liable to be modified by, feeling and involving essentially readiness to act. The result for us is, that we cannot refer belief to any one phase of mind. It is an essentially complex mental state, describable in every one 90 Elements of General PJiilosophy. [LECT. of the three phases a mode of representative intellection, tinged with feeling, having relation to the native tendency to act. I wish not to divorce belief from action. I would assert their connexion more decisively and explicitly even than Professor Bain. We allow in life that a man's belief is justified by his actions. Popular consent and psychological inquiry converge on this point. Where we are not prepared to act we don't believe. Many beliefs, it is true, like many cognitions, seem to have no relation to action, e. g. my belief that the moon is round. But this belief implies that if I were projected thither, I should in exploring be able to make the tour of it. There is no belief and no cognition that cannot, may not, have a reference to action, but cog- nitions rather than beliefs. Judgment, memory, expectation, all imply a relation to action, while other modes of intellection reflexion, reverie, imagining (in the narrower sense) are as such accompanied by a more receptive attitude of mind. It is true that all developed volition also involves feeling and intellection, but that does not prove that the bare fact of volition or conation is anything beyond impulse to act. Therefore we hold by our three phases, and say that volition (will) is complex and belief is complex. Disbelief and Doubt. Two other topics connected with belief should be con- sidered, viz. disbelief and doubt. Disbelief is itself belief, namely, in the truth of the opposite ; there is nothing to be said of it which has not already been said of belief. Doubt, on the other hand, is the opposite, the contradictory of belief. It is not present when we are believing, or at least in as far as we are believing, but it is only really excluded by knowledge. In proportion as belief is remote x.] Elements of General Philosophy. 91 from knowledge, doubt tends to be the more present. Doubt is also complex, having its three aspects it paralyses action, involves wavering representation, is of marked emotional character. We want to know (i. e. to represent clearly, if we cannot attain to presentative consciousness), and we cannot. Consequently representation follows repre- sentation, one chasing another and being itself chased away a wavering intellectual condition which in its emotional aspect is essentially distressing. The Philosophy of Belief. Belief and knowledge, then, have each a practical aspect. They are not simply subjective states or mental facts, but are related to a something believed or known, which cannot be adequately expressed in terms of bare subjective experi- ence, i. e. of psychology. Conceiving and thinking may be said to have an object in the concept or thought, but there is nothing in either, nor in the image, that is not fully accounted for by psychology alone. But the object of belief or of knowledge is expressed in terms of fact, objective fact, real existence, reality, which cannot be exhausted by psycho- logical inquiry. Now a real belief is one we are prepared to act on. Mere imagining is representing what is out of relation to our actions. We may also conceive what is out of such relation, whereas my readiness to act on what I believe determines the reality of that belief. Every cogni- tion and every belief has or may have relation to action and I can find no other meaning of Reality. We distinguish in ourselves a mental constitution con- cerned with the functioning of a bodily organism. Let us put ourselves on physiological ground : the organism is liable to be affected and to send forth impulse ; when stimu- 92 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. lated, we act ; this is the most fundamental fact. Of course we can act apart from external stimuli, and we can be stimulated without ensuing overt action. But, broadly speaking, action follows from stimulus. Now therefore reflex action is the type of action ; any act may be expressed in terms of reflex action. The efficacy of the act depends, in the last resort, on the stimulus received. And it is the stimulus received that suggests what we call Real in giving us occasion for acting. There is no mark of unreality more fundamental than the absence of any tendency to produce activity. Here then are philosophical implications : it is the deepest meaning of Reality that it gives occasion for action, that it is that to which action has relation. So far belief and knowledge are parallel ; so far we can only distinguish them both from imagination, &c. We must go further than this. There are two philosophical aspects of the relation of belief to knowledge : (i) of belief as some- thing less than knowledge; (2) of knowledge as based on belief, i. e. as explained by certain principles underlying knowledge which themselves we cannot know, but can only hold as beliefs. We must face both. Belief as Inadequate Knowledge. The first is the common usage. Of two intellective acts (to keep to psychological terms) to which we ascribe reality, it is to knowledge that we ascribe it more confidently, inas- much as knowledge involves less representation and more presentation than belief. As the presentative element pre- ponderates, so does belief merge into knowledge; the attention we give is then called knowledge. Taking my treatment of Seeing and Touch we can generalise therefrom. Sight gives knowledge in regard to some cognitions, but belief X.] Elements of General Philosophy. 93 relatively to Touch. The difference between belief and knowledge depends on the possibility of verification. In Logic a hypothesis is the best representation we can make under given circumstances. Theory, as opposed to hypothesis, is knowledge as distinct from belief. What is now belief may, at another point of view or time, amount to knowledge. ' Seeing is believing, but touch is the real thing.' Till I touch that pillar, I, strictly speaking, believe it is one ; much more if I am out of the room. I am then thrown on to representa- tive consciousness. I believe in default of knowing. Not that there is such a thing as pure presentation, or that there is no presentation in belief. Belief is relative predominance of representative consciousness. Touch is relatively pre- sentative to Sight. Perception involves belief, yet it is more knowledge than other intellective functions are. Knowledge as based on Belief. But if intellection, in so far as it has presentative elements, is knowledge and, in so far as it has representative ele- ments, is belief, how is it that we can speak of knowing anything by re-representative intellection, e.g. when we are reasoning about facts in general terms ? Take the argument, ' Kings are mortal because they are men.' This is an act of intellection that would be admitted as a clear case of knowledge, not belief of reasoned, though not presen- tative, knowledge. Hence we may have knowledge away from a presentative base when dealing with concepts. This is deductive reasoning, or knowledge of the why. If I say ' I know kings are mortal,' and am asked how I know, my answer is, ' Because they are men ' ; and this is accepted because I know not only the fact but the wJiy. Does this give rise to any further question about the 94 Elements of General Philosophy, [LECT. relation between knowledge and belief? We may say ' Kings are mortal, for kings are men ' ; but then arises the question, ' Do you know men are mortal, or do you only believe it ? ' One assertion given as the basis of another may be regarded as a ground for knowledge, but it only throws back the difficulty. As to the ground of that funda- mental assertion, How do we know men are mortal? We say, ' Because men are animals.' Now if anybody is prepared to say he accepts the mortality of animals on inductive experience, the question is whether this is to be called belief or knowledge. Certainly whatever we inductively infer (if it be material induction) is belief rather than knowledge. If a material induction goes beyond the experience on which it is based and to be a real induction it must then it is a case of belief rather than knowledge. Whatever we have direct expeiience of we may be said to know; hence an inductive inference is always more or less hypothetical or probable only. We see, then, that what is confessedly mere belief, viewed with reference to the experience from which it was inferred, becomes the ground of knowledge both in induction and deduction. Our statement is belief or knowledge according to the point of view from which we make our major premise. Thus : ' All men are mortal ' is knowledge, if got by deduc- tion from ' All animals are mortal,' but belief, if got as inductive inference from experience. Our knowledge that is got by reasoning may always be looked at in relation to two sources: first, as experience or generalisation beyond experience, i. e. as belief. But, in the second place, are there not other sources of knowledge ? Beside the particular facts of experience we need to assume certain general principles to account for knowledge, allowed even by those x.] Elements of General Philosophy. 95 who emphasise the sufficiency of experience. It is impossible for me to perform a careful induction from experience without such an assumption as the ' Uniformity of Nature.' Mill, striving here to preserve consistency, maintains that this is itself an induction from particulars ; and we must grant that much that is taken by us as generality for controlling individual experience may be seen gradually developing in force as induction based on experience, according as it is in con- formity with that experience. But I hold that we should not in the least hesitate to allow, in addition to experience as a source of knowledge, the assumption of some general principles, before or apart from experience, though never to be held independent of verification. In whatever way I have hold of them, e.g. of the uniformity of Nature, whether I believe or know, I believe rather than I know. If the uniformity of Nature is an induction from experience, we can but say we believe it ; if it be an assumption made by way of pure postulate or hypothesis, we believe still more. To know Nature in detail is found to be impossible except on the ground of the uniformity of Nature ; and is not this belief which is what we assume by way of a postulate for action postulated because we cannot get on without it ? Hence belief much better expresses the uniformity of Nature because of its highly representative character. And so, from our point of view, we come round to the conclusions of Hamilton and Augustin. Knowledge is more than belief, yet involves certain principles held as belief. It seems strange that belief should thus be something less than knowledge and yet the basis of knowledge, but if we remember the relation to action which is common to both, and which is the ultimate meaning of their reality, then we see how it is that the foundations of knowledge are held 96 Elements of General Philosophy. rather as belief than as knowledge. Particular facts got by an approximately presentative experience are knowledge, but not general knowledge. For that is of the nature of a coherent system with a foundation expressed as general principles ; and these are believed in rather than known. For LECTURE XI read : Bain, op. cit. App. B, for an able and useful historical exposition of Experience and Intuition. Locke, Essay concerning Human Understanding, Book I. LECTURE XI. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. BEFORE LOCKE. The Objectivity of Knowledge. BELIEF and knowledge then are conceptions that are closely intertwined, and the difference between them is one of degree, or lies in the way of looking at the same fact. Let us now see how the whole question has been faced by philosophers ; what it is that the problem of knowledge involves. It is a subject that appeals most generally to our interest, and it is suggested by our previous psychology. Knowledge, as involving more than mere intellection, is a coherent system which we call real, fact, objectively valid. I want to bring prominently forward this Objectivity of Knowledge. The word ' objective ' in philosophy is taken in a wider sense than in psychology, where it is the adjective of the perceived object ; here it applies to all real, valid knowledge, whether of sense-objects or no. All objects indeed can be shown to be ultimately objects perceived by sense, but we are now concerned with 'objective' as applied to that knowledge which is valid for the consciousness of all, not only for mine but also for that of every one. I know that 2 x 2 = 4, that the earth attracts stones, that every effect has a cause : these are cognitions and objectively valid, yet H 98 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. not sense-objects ; I do not say, without relation to sense at all, but not involving sense as such. Something may be a fact about a particular object or not a fact, but as fact it must hold for all. Do I know objectively ? Then I must so think that you can think it too. I know nothing really unless I can show that you are capable of knowing it as well as I. We must not imagine there is any objectivity without a subject ; knowledge always involves a knower ; still it is possible for me to put together in my mind a synthesis which will not hold good for any but myself; but then I cannot give grounds for it to other people, so that it has no objective validity. Suppose I said, ' The effect always goes before its cause' this would be an example of a cognition lacking objective validity \ No account which fails to bring forward this aspect of knowledge grapples with the question of the nature of knowledge ; it may contain good psychology, but it must fall short in philosophy. How the Problem has been met. We see, however, that if we have to find subjective repre- sentations which can be set forth in such a way as to appeal to all consciousnesses, it is not an easy task. All earnest philosophers have faced it, and I want now to give a notion of how, from different points of view, this definition of the conditions of knowledge has been met. This fact constitutes the central problem that knowledge is so held that other minds are viewed as participating in it, and that it is com- municable to others. Distinctively intellectual philosophy has always been concerned with the problem, meeting it for 1 Cf. Bain, p. 201, sec. 7. That which he here gives as the distinctive feature of perception of a sense-object applies equally well to all objective knowledge. XL] Elements of General Philosophy. 99 the most part from the side of the chief factor or factors in knowledge. Here we are at once confronted by our antithesis of Rationalism and Experientialism, or Sensationalism as, in its first form, the latter doctrine may be called. According to the former, knowledge is wholly explicable from Intellect or Reason (vovs) ; according to the latter, knowledge is wholly explicable from Sense or Sense-experience. And according to a third position knowledge is explicable from both. The antithesis to the word Rationalism in the fullest sense is given by the word Sensationalism. If Rationalism is the doctrine of reason, which is one kind of mental function, Sensationalism is the doctrine of sensation, another kind of mental function. Again, experience may mean bare sense-experience, or sense ordered by reason or intellect to form knowledge. Nevertheless Experientialism is on the whole the more accurate term, since no theory of knowledge was ever pure Sensationalism. Plato's Rationalism. Plato naturally took the extreme doctrine of Intellectualism, or Rationalism. Sense, he said, is only a hindrance to knowledge ; knowledge involves an ignoring of sense. Know- ledge is the grasping of ideas with the intellect which never were in sense, were never got from sense, and which therefore the mind must have brought with it ; it consists in the mind's possession of innate ideas originally. (He does not use the word 'innate,' but he teaches the doctrine.) Plato was a poet as well as a philosopher, and clothed his philosophical ideas in poetical form. Mythically sometimes and mystically always he expresses the doctrine of knowledge as reminiscence H 2 ioo Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. of ideas not formed from sense, but brought from a state of prior existence. In a previous existence men had converse with Ideas. Now they see through a glass darkly, but there was a time, and again will be, when, freed from matter or sense, man will see face to face. Plato's theory of knowledge, then, is a general negation of the import of sense is a denial that sense can be sublimated into knowledge. This tendency has been reproduced throughout the history of thought, especially at the beginning of the modern period. Descartes, though he takes sense as a factor of human being, seeks to explain knowledge out of relation to sense, and considers it apart from sense. With Rationalists first and last the burden of the story has been that in knowledge there is obviously something that sense can give no account of that there are in it notions out of all relation to sense, as for instance ' Cause.' Here is a notion necessary to our know- ledge, yet do any of our senses give us an idea of cause as cause ? Obviously not, yet we know what cause is. ' Sub- stance ' is another such notion. We come to know by sense this, that, or the other affection which objects are said to cause in us; but how do we come to know substance as something seemingly apart from us ? Hence it was that Plato looked for some other source to explain knowledge, and found one so fruitful that he denied the value of sense. This source was Reason. Reason knows by way of ideas, and as there was no possible account he could give of how these ideas arose in us, he did not hesitate to imagine that we are carrying on in this life a life that has been begun before, and in a previous stage of which we got our ideas. How much of this was philosophy, how much only poetry, it is hard to say ; but we get out of the Dialogues a positive doctrine of Innate Ideas, viz. that the mind comes XL] Elements of General Philosophy. 101 into the world with a certain means of knowing in its original constitution. /, according to this view, supply for myself the idea of cause by the constitution of my mind. Aristotle as Conciliator. In Plato's time the opposite doctrine had already sprung up, viz. that knowledge is only sense transformed. Later on this found pronounced upholders in the Epicureans, the Stoics and some of the Sceptics. To a certain extent this antithesis was represented and headed by Aristotle, yet not in extreme opposition. He occupied a middle ground, acting as a kind of conciliator between the Platonic doctrine and Experientialism. Never one-sided, he saw the truth in both aspects ; hence his great influence on succeeding ages. Those have judged him superficially who, with Coleridge, have said that every man is a Platonist or an Aristotelian. The expression that mind is a smooth tablet or tabula rasa occurs in Aristotle l , but he is no Sensationalist. He does not say that knowledge can be explained from sense, but he does say that it cannot be explained without reference to sense. Neither is it possible to make him out to be an Experientialist of the modern type, as Grote does. There are passages in Aristotle which must be interpreted as implying independence in the intellect as a factor of knowledge. By likening the mind to a tablet written on by experience he meant only that the Nous was not a fixed body of innate principles, but something potential which can be developed by way of experiential realisation. We are provided with such con- ditions of thought as will enable us to frame ideas in 1 De Anima, Bk. Ill, ch. iv : 'We must suppose, in short, that the process of thought is like that of writing on a writing-tablet on which nothing is yet actually written.' (E. Wallace's transl.) Infra, p. 230. 102 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. connexion with the gradual growth of our experience 1 . It is surprising how Aristotle had begun to conceive how sense becomes worked up by certain definite laws into those cogni- tions which seem furthest removed from sense. Scholastic Rationalism. Most of the Schoolmen, as we have seen, followed Aristotle, but assigned perhaps greater predominance than he did to the intellectual factor, and were apt to bring in ' innate ideas.' Some were pure Intellectualists, declaring sense to be of no account for knowledge. The greatest of them, Aquinas, contended for the importance of sense, but he too admitted innate ideas as co-factors in knowledge. Bacon outside the Controversy. Bacon is of no importance for this question. He is a methodologist. He sought for a ' method of discovery,' but prefaced it by no psychological or critical investigation (I use ' critical ' here in the Kantian sense), nor did he view the question from the subjective point of view as Descartes did. Had he gone into the question, he must have been a Sensationalist. He speaks of sense as a source of knowledge, but he was no metaphysician. Cartesian Rationalism. Descartes was more of a metaphysician than a theorist of knowledge. He made no attempt to give a detailed theory of knowledge, nevertheless the philosophical position he took up has influenced thought till the present day. To him as to Plato sense is the antithesis of knowledge, and is to be discounted and banned as an illusion and a show. He fell back upon the doctrine that we have innate ideas of God, 1 DC An. Bk. Ill, ch. iii. XL] Elements of General Philosophy. 103 substance, cause, &c., and interpreted it in a definite way. As a discoverer in mathematics and physics, Descartes came to terms with sense. As a metaphysician he revived and maintained the pre-existing doctrine of Innate Ideas, though in later life he modified it. He distinguished in all mental states three classes of ideas : (i) Innate, (2) Adventitious, and (3) Factitious or Imaginary Ideas. The last involve a definite mental construction that can be traced. Adventitious ideas come by way of sense. But he insists that there are certain definite concepts or notions which are in no respect adventitious, but are imprinted on the mind from the first as part of its original constitution. Chief among these is the idea of God. On this idea he lays great stress ; it plays an important part in his whole philosophy. We know what we mean when we use such a term, yet the idea involves no element of sense. Intuition and Idea in Descartes. Another word which Descartes is more especially inclined to use is ' Intuition.' Whenever the knowledge which he cannot conceive to come by way of sense assumes the form of propositions, of the truth of which we are absolutely sure, he uses this term. Through his initiative it has come to be more and more opposed to sense-experience, and thus diverted from its original meaning of inspection, vision, direct apprehension, such as we have in sense. Some philosophers distinguish between ' pure ' and ' empirical ' intuition, the latter expressing the original meaning. We shall revert to this in dealing with Kant. The student, by the way, should avoid confounding intuition with instinct the primitive power of conceiving and judging with the primitive tendency or ability to perform certain acts, unlearned action, or action 104 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. prompted by knowledge that is not got by experience. There is a relation between the two ; intuitions may involve activities ; instincts may be used with reference to the unlearned know- ledge rather than the actions ; but there is an approach to a philosophic Malapropism in an indiscriminate use of the terms. Descartes' use of the term 'idea' is wider than that of Plato; he applies it to any kind of conscious experience. (His use of ' thought ' (pensee) is similar.) He even uses ' idea ' for the nervous process accompanying sense-expe- rience. It is only since Hume, who contrasts ' impressions ' and 'ideas,' that the latter much-abused term has been restricted to a synonym for representative consciousness. Cartesianism modified already in Descartes. Descartes then admitted that sense was a mode of mental experience which the philosopher must account for as entering into some cognitions, viz. Adventitious Ideas ; but he had to assume other elements, viz. Innate Ideas, or Intuitions, according as he referred to their primitive character, or to the immediate certitude characterising them. Extension. Number, are for him innate ideas. ' I am a thinking being ' is a fundamental intuition ; so is ' Out of nothing nothing can come,' and 'A cause must contain at least as much reality as its effect.' We have no sensation of extension, but we interpret our sense-affections as coming from an extended thing by means of our idea of extension. To the question, ' What guarantee have we that the idea has objective validity ? ' he answered, ' The existence of a veracious God, incapable of deceiving us.' And to that of ' How is the mind cognisant of these ideas ? ' he said, ' Mind is a being constantly con- sciously thinking.' When pushed into a corner by the XL] Elements of General Philosophy, 105 objection that, if such ideas are innate, children ought to be more conscious of them than adults, he modified his position by saying that the mind has predispositions to innate ideas. His ' Innate ' theory is really a protest against the Sensa- tionalist position a protest with which as such I agree and will not bear direct setting out here. Locke's Experientialism. Locke, who really began the English philosophic move- ment, thinks in relation to Descartes, though he generally opposes him. The first book of his Essay is devoted to a hostile criticism of the doctrine of Innate Ideas, all know- ledge being traced from experience. Here then is a distinct counter-assertion. Instead of the assertion that the nature and community of knowledge are inexplicable save by way of ideas implanted in the mind, and in all minds alike, together with a theory as to the import of this innate knowing with respect to all minds, a theory in short of the objectivity of knowledge, we have the opposite view, that the mind comes into the world devoid of ideas or of any original means of interpreting experience, analogous in fact to a wax tablet ready for the stylus that is to say, with a capacity for receiving impressions and with nothing more. Knowledge is that which arises in the mind as the result of the im- pressions imparted by experience. It was Locke who objected that if there were innate ideas and principles (intuitions in the form of propositions), then, according to Descartes' axiom, that mind does not exist to the extent that it does not think, every one, but especially children, would be always conscious of them ; whereas such is not the case ; indeed it would seem that none but Cartesian philosophers were conscious of some of Descartes' 106 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. innate ideas ! Locke probably did not know, when he wrote, how Descartes had (in a letter) modified his theory by admitting predispositions. But Locke used the figure of the tabula rasa J in a much more dogmatic sense than Aristotle. The notion, on Locke's own line, has long been abandoned. It must not, however, be supposed that Locke by the metaphor meant to exclude ' natural faculties ' 2 or ' natural tendencies imprinted in the minds of men ' 3 . It is merely his strong way of saying that without actual experience (either that which comes by way of the senses or 'that which he calls ' Reflection ') there comes to pass nothing of what we call knowledge. In this point of view he need not be supposed to exclude anything that later inquirers contend for under the head of Inherited Predisposition. He does not assert that all tablets alike may be indifferently written upon, or, on the other hand, deny that all human minds are fitted to receive impressions in certain like ways. He may however be charged, by his way of putting the case, with throwing out of view this important element of a complete theory of knowledge, viz. that there is a certain common limit of knowing for the race and a certain personal range for the individual, both predetermined in a manner that admits of investigation (whether by Kant's way of analysis or by the evolutionist historic procedure). Locke's whole case against innate knowledge has reference to the supposed ' universal consent ' respecting it in all men and its express manifestation in the consciousness of each. He seeks to show that no principle, speculative or practical, that has ever been held innate, is as a matter of fact expressly recognised and allowed for by all mankind, as 1 Essay, Bk. II, ch. i. 2. 2 Ibid. I, ii. i. 3 Ibid. I, iii. 3. XL] Elements of General PhilosopJiy. 107 it must be if innate. The uniformity of knowledge in different men, so far as it exists, he explains by their being exposed to the same experience, by their having the same ' natural faculties/ and by their communication with one another 1 . Thus he does not wholly overlook the influence of the social relation. Whatever may be said of Locke's polemic against innate knowledge however he fails to see what really was contended for under that shibboleth (viz. that the fabric of knowledge, for any mind, is never explicable from incidental experience simply) it must be pronounced good and possible against the doctrine as it had till then been maintained; and this is shown by the necessity laid upon Leibniz to shift ground and maintain the position in quite a new way. Thus a real advance in philosophy was rendered necessary. Subsequent Mutual Convergence. While Descartes maintained the extreme position of Rationalism, and while we appear to find an extreme counter- assertion of Sensationalism by Locke, what we discover on tracing the course of subsequent philosophy is mainly in the way of reconciliation and mutual approximation. The Rationalists recognise sense as an indispensable factor of what we call knowledge, the Sensationalists meanwhile pro- gressively deepen and broaden their conception of what enters into or is experience. The dogmatic assertion of innate ideas died slain by Locke's Essay, or at least it only lingered on here and there down to our own times. Leibniz, who was most distinctly a Rationalist, finding knowledge in- explicable from anything we can call external experience, never asserted that the mind comes into the world with innate 1 See especially Essay I, iii. 22 ff. io8 Elements of General Philosophy. [LKCT. ideas, but declared it has only predispositions, aptitudes, as means of interpreting what comes to it by way of sense a notion which shows a distinct advance towards an appreciation of the other side. Ideas were only implicit in the infant mind as a statue of Hercules might be said to be implicit in a block of marble. Leibniz's theory of what really enters into knowledge was based on his theory of substance. Descartes had expressed the distinction between mind and matter as between substances the whole character of which can be expressed in thinking, and substances the whole character of which can be expressed in extension. Leibniz gave up this dualism, and allowed the existence of one substance only, the reality of which lay neither in thinking nor in extension. Trying to get a word deeper than either, he called the ground of its reality active force, and the one substance a system of monads, or mental unitary beings. Not all have a self-con- scious existence, and those which have do not have it at every moment of their existence. Mind appears at different grades throughout the universe, from the Deity down to inanimate objects appears, that is to say, as capable of all degrees of subjective apprehension, from full self-conscious apperception to semi- or sub- consciousness and down to unconsciousness. Hence arose the theory of latent mental modifications, springing originally from Locke's objection to Descartes' definition of mind as something constantly self-conscious. Leibniz and Locke, In defining his own theory of knowledge, Leibniz took up the formula of the Sensationalists : Nihil cst in intellectu quod non prius fuerit in sensu, and gave it a turn noteworthy and original by adding nisi ipse intellectus. 'Except the intellect itself.' By this alone, he claimed, do we possess necessary xi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 109 knowledge, necessary truth. Some truths are merely truths of fact ; others are necessary truths. We know sometimes that ' S is P/ but sometimes we know that ' S must be P.' And he said, as against Locke, that, while we can account for any mere assertion of fact from experience, to say that anything ' must be ' is not explicable from any kind of experience. Locke, on the other hand, with never so blank a tablet, found it necessary to assume beyond sense much else, which he called faculties of analysing, compounding, and the like. Experience for him was either external or internal, i.e. either Sense or Reflexion, meaning by Sense only the five passive senses, or modes of passive affection. What then is Reflexion ? Consciousness of the fact of perceiving, imagining, &c. To use modern phraseology there is an order of objective experience and an order of subjective experience : this expresses Locke's meaning. Knowledge, he found, was altogether made up by experience of Sense and Reflexion. But he has no definite idea how these come together and combine. Compared with Leibniz's profound psychological insight, Locke must be charged with superficiality, with inability to apprehend the complexity of the subject he sets himself to deal with. Leibniz, however, by reason of his metaphysical start, is in constant danger of diverting real psychological facts into supports for questionable metaphysical positions. The psychological fact that conscious life is composed of elements multitudinous in number and of every degree of intensity may be, should be, recognised quite apart from the meta- physical hypothesis of monads. Leibniz, while he does not deny that, not only truths of fact, but even necessary truths come into conscious view only upon the occasions supplied by sense, is disposed to no Elements of General Philosophy, [LECT. lay greater stress, for the explanation of knowledge, upon that which the mind must be in itself in order to be affected so. And as even the most occasional cognition may be viewed in relation to the mind's inherent capacity, he con- tends for innate knowledge in a sense which, if it departs from the older view against which Locke contends, is not in the least excluded by anything that Locke advances. The Question advanced by a Step. Locke thus appears after all as a masked Rationalist. He merely opened up the Experientialist side of the question, and it might well be said that Leibniz was only giving a definite expression to Locke's implicit admission, when he insisted on ' intellectus ipse ' as that which had not its origin in sense. It was impossible that the question could remain as Locke left it. Advance was necessary, or else a falling back on Descartes. When we come to Berkeley we shall see (infra, Lect. XVI) that his Principles are directed against Locke's dogmatising on matter. Still Locke it was who first began to transform Philosophy into Theory of Knowledge. Philosophy with Descartes was Theory of Being ; with Locke it was so only secondarily. And more : his philosophy, if not psychologically based, is at least penetrated through and through with the psychological spirit. In Descartes' science we get some good physics, but of any psychological understanding we get next to no trace. Between his work on vision and that of Berkeley there is all the difference between fancy and science. What then enabled Berkeley in 1709 to do that which Descartes of far greater scientific and philosophical ability had been unable to do in 1637 ? I can assign no other reason than the appearance in 1690 of Locke's Essay. For XL] Elements of General Philosophy. in whatever Spinoza's influence on the time may have been, he had no influence upon Berkeley. Locke's ideas of Sense are crude, but he compelled all subsequent philosophy to admit that into the fabric of know- ledge Sense enters as a distinct constituent, and that there is no explanation of knowledge possible which does not take account of Sense as a factor. What else there is in knowledge beside Sense philosophers have since sought to make out. The three chief verdicts are those of the Common Sense or Scottish School, the Critical School, and the Associationist School. These we will proceed to consider. For LECTURE XII read : Hamilton, Lectures on Metaphysics, XX and XXXVIII. Hamilton, Works of Reid, with Dissertations by Hamilton Note A, ' On the Philosophy of Common Sense.' LECTURE XII. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. AFTER LOCKE. A ssocialion ism . THE Associationist doctrine has developed along two lines of thought, both of which may be said to have arisen in Locke one through Berkeley to Hume, the other through Hartley to the Mills. Its theory of knowledge is that know- ledge is explicable from the elements of sense-experience united through the bonds (laws) of association, such con- nexions being made within the life-experience of the individual. Knowledge is thus an individual construction, and is a compound resulting from the fusion, under certain laws, of sense-elements. It is the product of sense and association. An Associationist must maintain that there is nothing in the mind that could not be developed by the individual for himself. He may be helped to his special associations by others, but he could do it all for himself. This is the purest form of Experientialism. Locke himself was an Associationist, not explicitly but by implication. Associationists have not worked out a consistent Theory of Knowledge, but they do make a real attempt to begin at the beginning. xii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 113 Locke and Berkeley. Locke's ideas of sense and of the construction of knowledge are, as we have seen, very crude ; nevertheless he first opened the question of ^.^.psychological origin of knowledge. Berkeley, Locke's immediate successor, marks a distinct advance along this line. He began a definite psychological inquiry, while he also took a philosophical position in regard to the know- ledge of matter, which is at least more circumspect than that of Locke. He based his philosophy on his psychology ; yet he was not set philosophising because he was a psychologist, but because, as a theologian, he wished to get rid of the, to him, pernicious effects of Materialism. Thenceforward philosophy and psychology really began to have a separate history. Berkeley got away from Locke's notion of the five senses as barely passive ; and further, he began that definite reference to a principle or principles of intellectual synthesis without which it is hopeless to explain knowledge. Associationism is traced to him though he does not use the word. His theory of knowledge bears more especially on our third problem the perception of an external world. Hume. Hume not only carried out further Locke's theory of knowledge, but put the question into such a shape as to rouse the strongest opposition and so bring about a great advance in thought. In regard to the cognition of extension, Hume is behind Berkeley and not superior to Locke. But he was beyond both in his statement of the formal principles of knowledge. He proceeds wholly upon Locke's individual- istic view that there is nothing in the developed knowledge of any mind which is not explicable from the (incidental) ii4 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. experience of that mind ; and expresses this (by a modi- fication of Locke's language) in the oft-repeated formula, that whenever we ' really ' have any idea there is some assignable impression from which it is derived of which it is the copy. By thus distinguishing idea from impression, he gives greater precision to the psychological data which he assumes in common with Locke. But further, when Locke, in order to account for the developed complex of knowledge, is content to assume faculties of 'abstracting,' 'compounding' and the like, Hume formulates definite principles of association under which the synthesis takes place : (i) Contiguity, (2) Similarity, (3) Association of Cause and Effect. He does not work out the last principle at all, nor the two others at all fully. But not in regard to these can we gauge the importance of Hume. There are two facts in cognition that he set himself to account for knowledge of substance and knowledge of causation. He was led to the question of cause from the prominence in modern science of the inquiry, ' What is the cause of what ? ' Berkeley already and the Cartesians before him (e. g. Male- branche) had seen that what science was concerned with was the establishment of uniformity in phenomena. But Hume went so far as to say, that if any phenomenon is by us con- nected with any other phenomenon in Nature, it is because of the customary sequence of experience. A subjective bond is thereby established and that is all, although through 'custom' one phenomenon comes to be considered as the objective ' cause ' of the other. Thus he decries knowledge, at least from the Rationalist point of view. While his Treatise of Human Nature contains an almost complete theory of know- ledge, while he vaguely but distinctly recognises intellectual elaboration of sense-data arranged by 'Abstraction/ he XIL] Elements of General Philosophy, 115 stunned the philosophic mind of the century by showing that all previous investigation had, so to speak, led up to a dead wall that Locke's Experientialism, logically carried out, landed philosophy in scepticism. Besides his Individual- ism, his Particularism (i.e. that everything complex or general has to be made out of particular elements) is very pronounced as put in the formula which he is constantly referring to : ' All ideas which are different are separable ' (i.e. have somehow to be brought together if they appear in one mature consciousness as conjoined). Hartley. Hume's contemporary, Hartley, was independent of him, but a follower of Locke. He was the first to formulate the law of Contiguous Association as accounting sufficiently, without other laws of association, for intellectual synthesis. Berkeley did not formulate any such laws ; Hume did, as we have seen, but he did not apply them. When later Associationists (the Mills and Professor Bain) faced the problem of knowledge, they worked with reference to Hartley and not to Hume's laws of association. Hartley was the first who distinctly asked how a multitude of sensations, which for us are discretes, come to be fused, or to coalesce into that coherent appearance of an object with a variety of qualities which expresses what our experience really is. It is, he said, by this one associative principle. Thinkers before him, from Aristotle onwards, had used association only in accounting for the imaginative life or representative experience. Hartley was the first to employ it in explaining the synthesis of sensations. He did not give a complete exposition of this theory, or analyse sufficiently the elements of sense, but he first started the Associationist method. I 2 u6 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Brown. Thomas Brown was a strong Associationist, thinking with ultimate relation to Locke, but with modifications due to the influence of the French Sensationalists, Destutt de Tracy and others. They first laid hold decisively on ' muscular sense,' a discovery of great importance in philosophic theories of extension. To this subject Brown's lectures were largely devoted, and to it we shall return. Brown used Hartley's theory of association most earnestly, but was repelled by the latter's introduction of the physiological theory of vibrations. J. S. Mill. It is John Stuart Mill and Professor Bain who, as inheritors of the Sensationalist tradition of the eighteenth century, have set up the formulated theory of knowledge, both psychological and philosophical, known as Associationism. The latter gives better data for a true theory, especially in regard to external perception ; the former is the better systematiser. In my judgment their Associationism, while it is an approxi- mation to a theory of knowledge, comes evidently short. However important are the factors brought out by Mill, he just fails to solve the problem. He declares that a number of the subjective experiences, had by an individual human being, become for him aggregated according to certain laws (of association), and that these aggregated appearances can come to assume the form of knowledge for the individual and since it is knowledge to be objective or valid for all. But it is just this last point that he does not account for. Our knowledge, as I have said, is a coherent system of fact and relation held in common by me and equally by others. This objectivity is the distinctive constituent of knowledge, yet Mill never satisfactorily accounts for it never gets out XIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 117 of the charmed circle, the sphere of the subjective. No doubt this is the right way to begin, but it is the wrong way to end if we want to give an account of knowledge as the common property of all men. Mill never gets off psycho- logical ground. Now I am in sympathy with Associationism as psychology only. Mill's psychology is rather defective. He borrows from Professor Bain without comprehending him properly. However, Mill's shortcomings in framing a philosophical theory of knowledge do not detract from his great philosophical merit in his theory of general knowledge, viz. his logic. It is as a logician that he is effective, rather than as an epistemologist not that I always go with him in his logic. In this he gives an account of knowledge in a constructive spirit that is very different from the destructive spirit of Hume. Living in a scientific age, Mill attempted to set up a fundamental theory of positive science involved in all the special sciences. But he does not explain how we come to know the world as consisting of a number of things, of bodies and minds. He works from the phenomenal point of view and from that of individual experience. He' tries to show how the individual experiences of the mind can become associated so as to enable one man to ask another to accept them as valid. Even as an inquiry of positive science Mill's work is defective. From one point of view his positive theory may be called no less sceptical than that of Hume. Jevons's Principles of Science is more complete though still less philosophical. Professor Bain has been the most important contributor to psychology in England in this century. His pre-eminence extends over the whole field of psychology as distinct from u8 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. philosophy. Towards the general theory of knowledge he does not contribute any advance on Mill and the Associationists generally. He works from the individual point of view. He makes but little attempt to apply the laws of association to cognition as such. He does not ask, e. g. how we can explain the concreteness of an object on the principles of association, although he gives a careful statement of those laws. Yet he posits an element of personal initiative for the explanation of developed consciousness; he tacitly denies the tabula rasa hypothesis. In the mature consciousness he finds an element not derived from the sense-experience of the individual because he considers mental life in connexion with the nervous system. It is recognised that the individual comes into the world organised up to a certain point ; and this fact, taken into account on the bodily side, has correspond- ing to it a certain pre- determination of conscious life. The ' Common Sense ' School. Reid, Stewart and Hamilton put forth their epistemological view in antithesis to Hume's theory of knowledge. The first declared that, while sense was of account for knowledge, knowledge could not be explained out of the elements assumed by the Associationist doctrines. So he fell back on other assumptions. What struck him in the general theory of knowledge, as distinct from the special problem of the cognition of an external world, was the community of knowledge was the fact that while there is more than sense in knowledge, this ' more ' is had by all, cultivated or uncultivated, young or old. This he attributed to the sub- jective factor of common sense. Now common sense in psychology is a name for organic or general sensation 1 . 1 V. Elements of Psychology, p. 62. ED. xii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 119 In popular parlance it is the faculty of ready judgment, mother wit. Reid employed it thus : We are so con- stituted that we interpret our experience alike. When we are affected through our senses, we refer those sensible impressions to a thing or substance of which they are qualities, by a fundamental principle of judgment or common sense. If we interrogate consciousness we reach this ultimate and objectively valid principle, beyond which we cannot reason. This was a valuable idea, but Reid's method was hap- hazard, his assertions too readily made, his elementary principles too easily found. His ' common sense ' expresses rather the result, than the means, of the determination of our impressions. It was a kind of revival of the old doctrine of innate ideas, although accompanied by a much more elabo- rate analysis of knowledge than any preceding Rationalists had given. We may not agree with him, nevertheless his system was an advance on Locke and Hume, if only because it made other thinkers more circumspect. Dugald Stewart carried on the doctrine on the same lines. Knowledge could not be explained without the assumption of certain fundamental principles of belief which determine the objective validity of knowledge. Hamilton. Reid, Stewart and Hamilton are the three typical ex- ponents of faculty-psychology. The term 'faculty' is very crudely used by the first two, but definitely by the last. Hamilton, while he justifies his own use of the word by saying that it is merely a way of massing together a number of mental phenomena, points out, as against his predecessors, that the discrepancies in their use of it show a want of principle 120 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. and are essentially indeterminate. Reid, e.g. is redundant in making two distinct powers of Conception and Abstraction. He and Stewart pretend to fulfil the whole function of psycho- logy, viz. explanation, whereas they only describe. For the only scientific mode of explanation is the bringing phenomena under laws. Explaining facts by faculties is essentially un- scientific, for we must ascribe a quasi-independence to these faculties. Even Hamilton, in spite of his having guarded himself, falls into using the word as if for so many mutually independent powers, as though as some one has said he were dealing with European Powers. Psychology, as a rule, begins where Reid and Stewart leave off. Still for Hamilton I claim a certain amount of exemption from blame. He is guided, moreover, as to much of his scheme by a scientific principle : he goes from simple to complex. The most salient feature in his classification is that each faculty is explicable from the preceding. His scheme is better than a mere string of beads. But in it psychology and philosophy become hopelessly confused. His scheme divides intellect into six faculties, in which we find a close correspondence with our own arrangement : (1) Presentative (a) External . . . Perception. ,, (6) Internal . . \ (2) Conservative Representative (3) Reproductive Imagination. (4) Representative j (5) Elaborative or Discursive . . . Conception, Thought. (6) Regulative 1 . 1 I am not disposed to reject the prominence given to (2) apart from (3) and (4). Decidedly some retain well, but cannot at will reproduce equally well. I could rather object to separating (3) and (4). The fifth is the most instructive to study. I commend his emphatic use of the word ' thought ' as meaning re-representative xii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 121 Hamilton confuses Psychology and Philosophy. Now here in faculties (2) to (5) Hamilton is on psycho- logical ground ; in (i) and (6) he trespasses on philosophy. For instance, his first faculty he defines as that by which we have (a) consciousness of objects, (3) consciousness of self. This is more than we undertook to find in intellection ; it is cognition in the fullest sense. Under the guise of psychology he is already dealing with the problem of knowledge. Now it is hardly fair to speak as though Hamilton professed to give us a work on psychology, when for his title he has Metaphysics. But we must charge him with not making the necessary distinction, any more than Professor Bain does in another direction, between psychology and philosophy. Here he certainly does not pass gradually from simple to complex. And the matter is made worse by the use of the apparently very simple term Presentative. He over-simplifies in one way, over-complicates in another. He himself, when in a psychological mood, sees that Presentation is but a starting- point. I deny ( i ) that we can start from perception of object and self, (2) that there is purely presentative intellection. The profit to the reader in those lectures on the first faculty lies in the historical information; otherwise there is much that is confusing and inconsistent. It was not a fortunate start. Then as to the sixth. Till this is exercised, till the results of the other five have been operated upon, regulated, by it, intellection only, and have sought to establish in the traditions of English psychology this usage, brought in first by Hamilton from Kant. ' Discursive ' too is a valuable old term, first showing the function of thought as a 'ranging over' in order to bring together. He calls this faculty also ' understanding,' as opposed to reason or ratio, his sixth faculty. i22 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. you have not, according to Hamilton, got knowledge. Not professedly does he here pass again over to philosophy ; he thinks it is all psychology. Yet he himself denies that this is a faculty in the same sense as the others. He calls it by a Latin name, as though English were not good enough for it the locus principiorum nest or aggregate of principles which have to be made manifest as involved in knowledge. Hamilton s 'Reason? What does he mean by this Regulative Faculty, or the Reason ? ' Regulative ' is a term he borrowed from Kant, though not exactly the Kantian usage along with it. He did not use it as I do to describe the function of such philosophical doctrines as Logic or Ethics, his generic term for such functioning being Nomology (as distinct from Phenomenology). By ' Regulative ' he meant ordering or interpreting or conditioning. Certain principles constitute so many forms or conditions under which what we perceive, remember, think, &c. comes to be held as knowledge. For instance, by the action of the principle of Substance we interpret what is presented in consciousness as qualities cohering in a substance. And again, the flow of our representations does not give us cognition till they are ordered by the principle of Causality as effects of certain causes. Not content herewith, he endeavours to reduce all principles to one the principle of the Conditioned. Note how he had already begged the sixth faculty to expound the first. We have now seen what the Common Sense school found wanting in the Associationist doctrine, and how they sought to supply it. In connexion herewith they tend to use belief as being the ( foundation of knowledge, those fundamental XIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 123 principles of Common Sense or Reason being held in the mind in the form of belief. No student will lose his time if he study Hamilton. What- ever his faults, his work is unsurpassed for instructive, stimulative value. He really and consciously exhausted intellect no less than is done in Mr. Spencer's scheme and my own. Whereas with the classifications of Reid and Stewart we might ask why they stop where they do. For LECTURE XIII read : Mill, Logic, Bk. II, ch. v. vi ' Of Demonstration and Necessary Truths.' LECTURE XIII. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY. Kant. KANT was struck and even oppressed by the negative result of Hume's analyses. It seemed to him that, if Hume was right, no explanation of even the plain facts of science was possible. He was prepared to accept Hume against the older doctrines of metaphysics Platonic realism, innate ideas, and so forth but he felt that there was that in know- ledge which Hume had not touched that his negation of knowledge was wrong, in that he had not faced the whole problem. So he sought in the Kritik of Pure Reason to work out a positive theory of knowledge and to destroy scepticism, not by mere dogmatism like Descartes and Leibniz, but by putting the whole of knowledge on a new footing, and so to find a via media between the Experientialism of Locke run out into the scepticism of Hume, and the Rationalism of Descartes and Leibniz. Kanfs Inquiry into the Constituents of Knowledge. He said that we must first settle what enters into know- ledge. That sense is of account for knowledge he takes for granted. Our knowledge is of sensible things. Not that we have not moral convictions of something beyond, but know- Elements of General Philosophy. 125 ledge proper always contains sense-elements. Sense itself does not explain knowledge. Knowledge is not simply sense transformed, but a resultant of certain elements a posteriori (empirically given) wrought up with certain other a priori elements. A priori and a posteriori. To these terms, which are to be found in Logic since the time of Aristotle, Kant gave an epistemological significance. The logical a priori is cognition of anything on the side of its conditions, of what it can be shown by the laws of thought to depend upon ; it is knowledge in deductive form. And it is so called because it can be shown to be dependent, through the laws of thought or consistency, on what has been already known or assumed, i. e. on premises. This is the only kind of conclusion that is absolutely certain. But we can make other inferences, for which we can never claim absolute certainty, and yet which are the most important, viz. induc- tions, or general assertions about facts. Here, except in Jevons's trivial case of Perfect Induction, the certainty of our inference is technically open to dispute ; it is only probable. Such an inference is termed knowledge a posteriori. Kant uses the terms for the two kinds of factors present in knowledge. That which comes from sense, without which no exercise of ' pure ' reason has any validity, is knowledge a posteriori. But without the a priori factor of ' pure reason ' (reason not derived from experience) working on experience we cannot get knowledge. For Kant, a priori is a general name for ' rational ' as opposed to ' empirical ; ' it is what Leibniz, in correcting Locke, meant by intellecttis, or that which is furnished by the mind's original constitution. Kant, be it noted, was very vague in his use of ' experience.' Sometimes it means with him the contribution of sense to i26 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. knowledge ; at other times it stands, not for bare sense- material, but for sense as ordered and interpreted by a priori principles in fact for knowledge. A priori Forms. Again, just as in Logic a distinction is drawn between matter and form of thought, so Kant distinguished episte- mologically between matter and form of cognition generally. The matter of knowledge is the data of sense; these are taken up into, or perceived under, ' pure forms.' The ' forms ' of sense are space and time. When I get external sensations I am so constituted that I order them in space. And I order all my sensations in time. Space and time are pure forms of intuition a term which Kant was careful to connect with sense-perception only, and not with Reason, seeing how related the words are. Next, sense-perception, so explained from the conjunction of matter and pure forms, becomes ready for conceptual know- ing, i.e. for an orderly scheme or fabric of knowing common to man and man in other words, objective knowledge. Objective knowledge does not necessarily refer to objects in space. Is it a fact that every event has a cause ? If it be agreed that this is so, here is objective knowledge, although it does not refer to objects in space. Such knowledge con- sists of sense-phenomena subsumed or brought under pure concepts of the understanding or fundamental principles of judgment, by which Kant did not understand so many 'innate ideas,' but postulated certain necessary forms of thought. Universality and Necessity in Knowledge. For there is a part of our knowledge, there are some of our cognitions, which are not only universal or objective, but also necessary. Some judgments assume the form ' S is P,' XIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 127 but some that of ' S must be P.' Now no experience can explain so philosophers said why a ' must be ' is used any more than it can warrant universal validity. Experience deals with particulars only. It cannot tell us that all are so, or that all must be so ; we only know by it that this, that, and the other are so. We do not hesitate to say ' All men are mortal,' but we only know that certain men of whom we have had experience have died. Knowledge may, on the warrant of experience, assume a general form from particulars, but then it is only probable ; it is of the nature of belief; it is practical, not theoretical necessity. So for universality. Kant paid most attention to necessity, defining more exactly than had ever been done before the nature of the problem and distinguishing between kinds of necessity. Necessity in know- ledge first found explicit statement (as we have seen) in Leibniz. Locke gave an account of necessary truth, and Hume tried to account for the aspect of necessity by the merely subjective explanation that it is habit or custom that determines us to think thus. Mill argued for inseparable association. Now Kant distinguished between Analytic and Synthetic propositions: these do but correspond to the Essential and Non-essential judgments of the Schoolmen and to Mill's Verbal and Real predication. An analytic proposition is one where P (predicate) is involved in the thought of S (subject). Locke miscalled such propositions ' trivial.' ' Man is rational ' is an analytic proposition, because by ' man ' we mean rational animal. Man must be rational or he is not man. Kant saw that all such judgments have the character of logical necessity necessity under the laws of thought (of Identity, Contradiction, Excluded Middle, or generally, of Consistency). Every step in thought that proceeds under the laws of thought may be 128 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. expressed in terms of necessity. Deny and, as Aristotle would say, you are a vegetable. This is a kind of necessity experience may give distinct occasion for, e. g. ' Body is extended ; ' ' Crows are black.' We can put this kind aside. But, said Kant, we often have judgments which are not analytic and yet are necessary, e.g. ' Two straight lines cannot enclose a space.' This is a synthetic proposition ; Professor Bain (in his Logic) tried to show it, on no ground whatever, to be analytic. It is also necessary. We may say merely ' do not enclose,' but the necessity, even if excluded from the form of the proposition, lies in its matter. Now Kant found necessities of thought of this kind, not only in mathematics but throughout the whole fabric of knowledge, e. g. ' Every event must have a cause.' And he called such judgments synthetic propositions a priori, i. e. necessary because of an a priori synthesis formed in the very nature of human reason, and not a posteriori or constructed by the light of experience. It was thus that he answered the question, ' How are synthetic propositions a priori possible ?' ' How is real predication also necessary?' The human mind brings to the results of bare sense-experi- ence certain subjective factors, viz. (i) pure intuitions, in order to perception; (2) pure categories of concepts, in order to understanding ; (3) pure ideas, in order to reason. Of these (i), i.e. space and time, are not general notions, but pure forms for the reception of the bare matter of sensa- tion that arises in us. They are the conditions under which sense-impressions are consciously experienced by us as having the character of definite phenomena mutually related in the way of succession or co-existence. There is nothing in sense to explain sensations as apart from each other in space and time. This represents the first stage of cognition as we have it. XIII.] Elements of General Philosophy. 129 The phenomena thus found to be the transformed data of sense now become matter for further elaboration, and get into definite relations with each other, as causes and effects, &c.; and by these new kinds of ' form ' applicable to phenomena as their ' matter/ just as space and time are applicable to sense-impressions as their matter, the order of nature becomes explicable. If I simply say ' The earth draws a stone/ there is involved this double elaboration of the bare facts of sense as originally given. They are first ordered as phenomena, then ordered into relations. And the forms into which phenomena are thus taken up are twelve ' categories of the understanding 1 .' All are involved in physical experience, for these ' forms ' of the mind are not cognitions in and for themselves, but apply to phenomena only, and have no meaning out of relation to them. Even what we call experi- ence is saturated with ' reason/ with those highest elabora- tions or syntheses the ideas of the self or soul, the cosmos, God which completed the Kantian account of the subjective factor in knowledge. Kanfs Theory of Space. So much for general exposition. I will now confine myself to space and those propositions about it which are both neces- sary and synthetic. Kant maintained that we cannot account 1 ' Discoverable from the common analysis of judgments in logic, (a) Three categories of QUANTITY : Unity, Plurality, Universality (as involved in Singular, Particular, Universal judgments respectively). (6) Three of QUALITY. Reality, Negation, Limitation (in Positive, Negative, Infinite judgments), (c) Three of RELATION : Substantiality, Causality, Community or Reciprocal action (in Categorical, Hypothetical, Disjunctive judgments), (rf) Three of MODALITY: Possibility, Existence, Necessity (in Problematic, Assertory, Apodeictic judgments).' Bain, op. cit. App. B, p. 60. ED. K. 130 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. for our knowledge of space by reference to experience, for if we could, we could never form necessary synthetic propositions about it. We have a pure intuition of space ; it is a pure form, and we put our experiences into it. In support of this position he adduced psychological evidence both negative and positive negative, in that he asks us to produce those sources of experience, whence we have notions of space ; positive, in that space in relation to sensation stands in a quite peculiar position, thus : we experience our sensations as in space, and while we can think of any of those sensations as eliminated, we cannot think away space. We can think of a pillar as having colour, as emitting sound when struck, but we cannot think away its extension. We may colour our space as we like, but it must always remain extended. Space, then, is one of the two ' forms ' of sensibility, a form to which sense supplies the matter; it is there before experience, and there- fore we can utter synthetic propositions not built up by experience. Associationist Explanation of Necessity in Knowledge. Kant's insight into this question surpassed that of his pre- decessors both Rationalist and Experientialist. I think that we may yield him this pre-eminence and yet, in the light of our more advanced psychology, be able to explain those aspects of our cognition of space which led him to deny its experiential origin. Let us face him with the developed position of his Associationist opponents as best seen in Mill and Professor Bain. The latter in his Psychology gives the very data which we shall use to show where Kant was wrong, yet he does not make use of them as he might have done. Had he seen the full import of what he makes out, he would have had a better argument against the Kantian position. Take XIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 13: Mill : For him there is nothing in our knowledge of space which may not be accounted for by the amount and constancy of our experience going to form the cognition. If we find that we cannot think of colour except as in space, it is because we find that they always do go together. Associations, though formed within experience, may become inseparable. ' Space a form in which we receive colour as matter ? ' No, said "Mill ; we have always apprehended colour as extended, extension as coloured. Necessity depends upon the amount of experi- ence, which is here of a peculiarly simple kind. Experience that is frequent and constant enough can give rise to a ' must be,' a 'cannot be.' Criticism of both Positions. Now I have thrown doubt on how Associationism can ever account for the necessity of synthetic propositions. I take a middle position, neither Kantian nor Associationist, finding neither view perfectly valid. Is Space a form for all external sensations ? (I omit Time for lack of it.) Yes, said Kant, sensations are by us ordered in space. Well, I have shown, in dealing with perception \ that every sensation does come to have some kind of spatial reference more or less. But there is all the difference in the world, of DEGREE. For that difference of degree we must account in detail, and this puts a check on our agreeing with Kant's superficial assertion, that space is form for all sensations alike. Do the notes in the scale of an octave or in a chord appear to us spread out in space like the colour-spectrum ? It is true that we should hear them as ' in space,' yet the spatial order is very different. On the other hand, I protest against ranking our experience of space on a level with that of colour or sound, as the Associationists do. How can we have experience of colour? 1 V. Elements of Psychology, p. 96. ED. K 2 132 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. By way of sensations passively received. How of space ? There is no such simple source of space-experience. In- separable association exists, it is true, as a psychological fact, and explains much that looks like necessity. Mill uses it to account for mathematical necessity. The ideas, e. g., of ' two straight lines ' and ' what cannot enclose a space ' have come, through personal experience, to be so closely associated as to be practically inseparable. But however that may be, colour and extension do not constitute a case of inseparable associa- tion. We must find one where the associates were first known in separation, e. g. the name ' hat ' and the thing ' hat.' In- separable association refers to what is practically inseparable, not to what is theoretically inseparable. And if we look at how the human organism is constituted, we see that the relation of colour and extension cannot be a case of two more or less indifferent elements being brought together by chance- experience and fused. It lies in the constitution of our per- ceptive faculty that we cannot but have the experience of extended colour if we have eyes. I am so constituted that when I am affected by colour I move my eyes. This is a necessity of the constitution, and not of acquired experi- ence. Inseparable association can never explain necessity in knowledge. But have we not seen, it may be asked, how extension is explicable by ' muscular sense'? This is really important, though more is required. It is by reference to ' active sense,' the resultant of muscular sense in conjunction with passive sense, that we do get an actual experiential origin of our perception of space. Space, as we have seen, is no simple experience, but a complex product of data given by colours and touch. Thus space is a ' form ' I have no objection to the term as expressing the relation of space to simple sensa- XIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 133 tions but it is not therefore a ' pure intuition,' since we can psychologically explain it. Nor is it the universal form of external sensation. Organic Necessity. Now if, constituted as we are, some sense-organs only are muscular, and if it is the fact of muscularity whereby we have apprehension of extension, it becomes a necessity for us to have those sensations ' in ' space. We are so ordered, through the mobility of our hands, eyes, &c., as to have those sensa- tions so. Here is the explanation of this necessity because of our organic constitution. And this is not to explain mind from matter; I use 'eyes,' 'muscles,' &c., to designate the factors, not to explain them. The material differences in the brains of different men suggest differences of mental ability. Kant, then, was right in maintaining that our reference of colours to space was of our original constitution, though what he called pure intuition I term bodily organs. Whether the tendency be innate I know not, not knowing the consciousness of myself as an infant or that of other infants. Even were it not so, the psychological facts we have mentioned can account for the development of the cognition within the lifetime of the individual. And if it were so, the tendency would still be not a pure intuition, but the result of the principle of heredity. Pure intuition cannot satisfy ; we must inquire further. I am far from dogmatically asserting that the idea of space is got in the life of the individual ; it may, or may not, be so. It were possible to go deeper than Mill or Bain, and yet give a psychologically based explanation. Enough here to say that the line is fruitful, and that more may be done therein by English psychologists than Kant ever achieved. I am not hostile to Mill's exposition on demonstrative science in the second book of the Logic. It is good as far as it goes, and 134 Elements of General Philosophy. is the best explanation yet made from the point of view of individual experience. Professor Bain gives his adhesion to Mill's mathematical theory, but extraordinary is the way in which in his Logic ! he throws away the advantages got from his position in psychology as to our unique apprehension of extension, and never refers to it. For if extension is not had merely by experience from without, but by activity of ours put forth, springing from within, it is absurd to say that we are reduced to the same conditions for our knowledge of space as for that of the qualities of things. It is always possible for us to perform movement of some sort, and this movement is involved in our apprehension of extension. My knowledge of space depends upon my acting when I like ; other per- ception depends upon whenever, in a broken, limited way, I happen to be sensibly affected. We make, we determine space ; we come to know it by way of construction not of r? priori construction, not of spontaneity of thought, as Kant said, but by conscious bodily exertion, not limited by occasions of passive sense-impressions. And this is because we are what we are. We are thrown back on our original constitution. Hence it is that the science of space is different from the inductive sciences of nature ; hence it is that mathematics is a demonstrative science. The explanation applies to all sciences in so far as they are demonstrative to Arithmetic and Physics, e. g. as well as to Geometry for all are to that extent concerned with matter as apprehended by activity, by construction ; and herein lies their ' necessity.' Other sciences we form piecemeal from experience 2 . 1 'Deduction.' Bk. II. ch. v. The lecturer referred students, for a fuller explanation, to his article 'Axiom' in the Encyclopaedia Bnianuica. (Reprinted in Philosophi' al Remains, pp. 119- 132. N ED. LECTURE XIV. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. CAUSATION. The Category of Causality. WE will now proceed to Kant's Categories of the Under- standing, and single out for examination and comparison that one which the growth of modern science has brought most prominently under discussion. When things are sensibly perceived they are ordered in space or in time ; but when thought or generally known, i. e. when in the form of concept, we say they must have a cause. Now according to Kant this is a synthetic assertion a priori. Cause, or cause and effect, is a pure concept not got by experience. We are naturally determined to look for something before and after an action. W T ith cause, as with space, a necessity is laid upon us in the act of knowing. This was an immense step beyond earlier views ; it is perfectly intelligible and satisfactory also as far as it goes. Before Kant's time no one took the trouble fully to analyse knowing as we find it. The Growth of the Notion of Cause. The question of causation is as old as Plato, but the epistemological aspect of it ' How do we, in our knowledge, come to relate phenomena to one another as cause and 136 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. effect ? ' has (in addition to the consideration of space) only come to the front since the time of Hume and Kant in connexion with the establishment and progress of modern science. Through that, Nature has come to be regarded as a realm within which law reigns universally. Nature has always, it is true, been considered as a realm in which there are things having a fixed occurrence, and a law of universal causation is no new thing in philosophy. Without the acceptance of the law there could be no science as science is now constituted. Yet it is only lately that Nature has been scientifically investigated in a thorough-going manner, and the law applied to every kind of phenomena. People have not always referred every thing and every happening to cause and effect. Even Aristotle expressly distinguished a region of cause from a region of chance. And there are some who still deny that mental phenomena are regulated by it. For example, it is a question still raised whether human action, the action of beings having a conscious volition, is a fixed and orderly action which can be investigated and forecast like other facts in nature. This is the famous free-will con- troversy (v. infra, Lecture XIX). The difference of opinion which we see yet prevailing with regard to this sphere of occurrence formerly prevailed with regard to all nature. It was held that things would happen otherwise than under the condition of strict uniformity. Causation as Universal. Generally speaking, however, the causal connexion may now be considered as established. In regard practically to anything that happens, we are prepared to make one pre- supposition if none other, namely, that it is caused, or determined to happen, and that it does not happen except as it xiv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 137 is caused. When anything happens, I say, we also assume that it follows on something else, not as on a bare antecedent in time, but as on a cause or determinant. We assume that Nature is an aggregate of events all determined to happen as they do happen, i. e. that Nature is uniform in respect to cause and effect. When an event happens we seek to conjoin it with some other event as cause. On this assumption is based all scientific generalisation, all inductive inference, every real and complete induction. For a complete induction is one where the nature of the instances is such that any other result than the universal assertion we commit ourselves to would run contrary to the universality of the law of causation ] . The causal connexion then being at this time of day established, we have to account for it. Rationalist and Experientialist Explanations of Cause. Now Hume was the first to account for the causal con- nexion on the ground of experience, there being nothing beyond experience that he can find to explain it from. Locke was too far back in time to touch the subject. Science was then too little established as a system of know- ledge to draw the attention of philosophers. But Kant, who professed to account for science as we find it, had specially to occupy himself with this question. And since his time Rationalists have held cause to be a ' pure concept.' Hamilton indeed thought to advance beyond Kant in saying that the judgment of causality is a work not of the Elabora- tive, but of the Regulative Faculty an act of reason as opposed to the understanding. We are, according to him, to account for universal causation, not by a pure concept brought by the mind, i.e. by the mind's ability \ but as due 1 Cf. J. S. Mill, Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy, p. 402, note. 138 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. rather to its impotence. It is owing to the limitation of the mind that we bring everything in relation to something else. Every event must have a cause ; we cannot help it. This is in connexion with his fundamental ' Law of the Conditioned.' Hamilton's turn to the argument should be studied, but his doctrine of causation is not good. Kant's position is preferable. He best represents the Rationalist position, Hume and Mill that of Experientialism. I throw up a stone, and it falls to the ground. I say, ' The earth attracts the stone.' Now the Experientialist explains this judgment, as made on the strength of the individual's countless experiences of this sequence of phenomena. He asserts causation as a generalisation from experience. Whereas Kant maintained that, unless he could first pass an a priori judgment of causality, he could never have the experience at all that we bring our category of causality to bear on, and elaborate the judgment out of, the bare experience of the stone falling to earth. (Notice that Kant and he is not alone in this usage employs experience ambiguously as meaning either raw sense-material, or phenomena ordered in certain ways, i.e. according to the categories.) According to Kant, I repeat, unless we knew a priori that every event must have a cause, we should never have got so far as to say ' The earth attracts the stone.' According to Mill the phenomenon is a simple particular by which we rise to the universal assertion. Criticism of both Positions. Now I am wholly dissatisfied with this common-place Experientialism of Mill and others. Not thus can we account for knowledge. On the other hand, we are not driven to Kant's alternative, to assert cause as a pure concept of the xiv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 139 understanding. For as we found that his pure form of intuition was not pure since space has a development so we find that cause is not a pure concept. It comes by way of sense, although not given by experience already developed. Nevertheless, as against crude Experientialism, I side with Kant, who gives a much profounder analysis of knowledge. Cause in Science and in Popular Usage. Before suggesting a solution of the question, it is necessary to make a distinction. There is a real difference between cause as understood in science and cause as used in every- ' day speech. The cause of anything that science seeks to account for is the set of conditions of a phenomenon ; it tries, in assigning cause and effect, to establish a certain fixed relation among phenomena a certain kind of unifor- mity. Science has nothing to say of the reason why one phenomenon should be followed by another, and in no way professes to account for the relation except as a mere uniformity of occurrence. Thus when oxygen and hydrogen in combination are exploded by a spark there results water. For the purposes of science the cause of this is explained by proving the presence of oxygen and hydrogen, and the application of the spark. But no one can say what ultimately brings about the result. Science has only words to denote a certain fixed succession. Popular speech is, however, much more definite in assigning a cause. Where a stone falls to the earth it says at once, ' The earth draws, attracts the stone/ i.e. has power to produce this effect. Science only points to the fixed relation or succession of phenomena. Any succession is not causal, but causation is only succession of a certain kind. Now what else is there besides succession when the principle of causality 140 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. is assumed ? There seems an implication in the philosophical principle resembling that in common speech, namely of, power in one thing to bring about another thing. Our language certainly commits us to more than the bare scientific notion. The scientific conception of cause has grown up lately, because it is only of late that nature has been regarded phenomenally. Before positive science grew up nature was regarded as an aggregate, not of inter-related phenomena, but of active beings. No science came to pass until men looked away from this view and established definite relations among facts as they found them. As this aspect of phenomenal relation, of co-existences and successions, developed, the popular notion of cause and effect, with its implied assumption of power, became attenuated to indicate merely a special kind of phenomenal succession, and theorists began to dispute the propriety of using the word ' cause ' in this connexion as misleading. Hume's philosophy centres entirely round this part of the subject, namely, the great question : Can this relation among phenomena that science takes account of be properly called causall Mill answered this affirmatively, and tried to show that the notion of power (in cause to produce effect) ought to be excluded from the notion of causation. This is equivalent to asserting that a causal relation, as it is made out in science, is purely phenomenal. Both Hume and Kant agree with him here. Berkeley regarded cause not as a phenomenal antecedent, but as a spiritual reality, as the connexion between the real being (mind) and what appears. He spoke of the scientific cause as a ' phenomenal sign ' of the true cause, science dealing with ideas (phenomena) that are significant of other ideas. Comte was the most thorough xiv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 141 phenomenalist of them all ; he would not even raise the question as to any reality beyond phenomena. And just because he was a phenomenalist, he wanted to get rid of the notion of cause altogether, and asserted that the utmost object of science was to determine uniformities of phenomena or laws. According to Mill, scientific relations, though all phenomenal, may yet be called causal. According to Comte, because they are phenomenal they must not be called causal. Comte agrees in expression, though not in thought, with Berkeley and also with Dr. Martineau. These two concur in saying that science is concerned only with the signification of phenomena by phenomena, in order to show that, beyond all considerations of phenomenal relation, there is a deeper consideration of cause, viz. as to how any phenomenon is related as effect to a cause in the sphere of metaphysical reality or ultimate being. They hold that when we have got science we are only at the beginning of our investigation and not, as Comte believed, at the end of all possible inquiry. Cause in Cartesianism. The attenuated notion of cause that we find in science had already been anticipated in philosophic thought by Occasion- alism, although based on different premises from those of Hume and Mill. Occasionalism explained all change in Nature as mere sequence, the full working of cause being only between God and every creature. The creature was robbed of causal efficiency \ this being placed to the credit of the account of the Deity. Geulincx especially came near to scientific Pheno- 1 In Aristotle 'efficient cause' includes the notion of power, but, as opposed to 'final,' ' formal, 'and 'material' causes, is equivalent to the modern idea of causation. 142 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. menalism in seeking to account for the apparent interaction of two such opposed substances as mind and body. Male- branche also explained every event as due to direct divine intervention, finding in the world only phenomenal conjunction. Descartes himself went nearly as far as this in controversy. They tended to the Pantheism, with its notion of immanent causation, which was fully developed by Spinoza. The Logical Weakness of Miffs Theory. What account do we give of this problem ? Can we say with Mill that every human mind, from seeing things happen, develops the conviction that every event must have a cause ? If we study what Mill says in his Logic for this position, we find it gives strength to Kant's view. Data that he assumes to account for causation are already co-ordinated by the application of the pre-existent principle, for we are naturally determined to interpret our experiences by way of causation. The difficulties in the way of accepting Mill's view are insuperable. Universal Causation a Postulate in Science. For purposes of science, I think that at present it is a sufficient explanation of the universality of causation when it is set out as a postulate, without which it is impossible to have science at all. If things happened now in one way and now in another we could make no general assertion about them. We must postulate a fixity in the occurrence of phenomena. This will be sufficient to account for the universality of causation in science. If with .some we doubt whether it be universal there is so much of science blotted out for us. We may use the word ' cause ' for the mere phenomenal relation, but it must be without misunderstanding it. The question xiv.] Elements of General PJiilosopliy. 143 whether cause has poiver to produce an effect has no meaning in science. But this is not accounting philosophically for the notion. The Truth in MilTs Theory. Having excluded the notion of ' efficient cause ' from science, Mill seeks the origin of our notion of cause and effect in generalisation from the phenomenal relation. He argues that the principle of causation on which induction is based is itself an induction. This is to beg the question. And he reckons this generalisation from experience of cause and effect as, according to Bacon's term, an induction ' by simple enumeration of instances,' i.e. by the weakest, the least scientific method of induction, Mill himself allowing, as we have seen, that he cannot make a good induction until he has got the principle of causation. Hence he gets the principle by a bad induction. This is not worked out as well as it might have been. Nevertheless there is reason in his position. He arrives at his primary assertion tentatively, and it is strengthened by every fresh induction. We may trust simple enumeration in regard to the general fact of causation in Nature, but not in regard to cause in a special case ; in the latter we need to base our inquiry on the law of causation itself. In point of fact it must have been from experience that people arrived at the idea of universal causation, because it is only lately that universal causation has become recognised. Whereas if it were a pure concept, why was it not recognised before ? Kant does not face this evolution in thought. An experiential origin of the notion of cause may be defended as against his view. Yet I do not put the case like Mill. The notion of cause is not derived from a consideration of the phenomenal 144 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. relation, because this is not a natural but an artificial view of the question, whereas the notion of cause has grown up with men from the beginning. It is from the popular idea, whence the scientific sense of causation has been derived by attenuation, that the philosophical notion of cause was first got, and it is in reference to thai, that the question of ground should be raised. For we do ultimately think of cause as something with power to produce an effect. Whence then does this arise ? Through external experience or apart from it ? The Psychological Basis of the Notion of Cause. Exactly that which Mill protests against Reid's adducing to account for the notion of cause may be maintained in explanation of the popular idea. The notion of power in the conception of cause is got from our consciousness of being able to put forth activity, from our consciousness of volition. Both Hume and Mill argue that actual experience of cause and effect shows only a relation between phenomena either from the objective or the subjective point of view. I demur. However necessary it may be for scientific purposes to regard our subjective states as phenomena, no man regards himself simply as a phenomenon or series of phenomena. We know ourselves as beings that may or may not exert a definite energy, and this quite takes our actions out of the category of phenomenal successions. Now just as, in regard to movements of my body, I come to consider them as depending on my will, so I come to conceive there is a similar 'causal' power determining other movements in nature. Mansel thought this not enough, and that to find the root of the notion it was necessary to go down to the power of xiv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 145 man to determine the successive states of his mind. This is of course one case of the exercise of our volition, but it is better to take the more general and the older view. So when we say that the earth draws a stone we ascribe a personality to the earth just as we are conscious of our own personality, in the same way as I ascribe to another personality the power of moving the arm. If I credit you and the earth with being reservoirs of power, it is because I have read my own consciousness into everything that I say acts. I have read into my experience what is not directly in it. Not that we really think that the earth is endowed with a personality like ourselves, but we have a tendency to read it into the earth, despite our real convictions. The Larger Experientialism. Thus there is a good ground for urging that we do not get the notion of cause from strictly phenomenal experience. The Rationalist position is so far good. Yet if we consider the circumstances fully, we shall come to see that this mode of interpretation is not fixed and fast, but has gradually grown up, and, like the constitution of the human mind, has been developed with the human race, or anterior to it in the succession of animal life. This mode of interpreting our experience as a world of active causes, however natural for all of us now, even for the uninstructed more perhaps for them has only, as there is every reason to believe, come to be developed gradually, as men have awaked to full con- sciousness. Man came to interpret the world in this way after the experience of ages, and not within the experience of the individual. In this way only may the Experientialist position be justified. It does seem to me that, despite the position taken up by the English Associationists, we can L 146 Elements of General Philosophy. find no sufficient explanation of our view of the world, as an aggregate of active agents in relation to one another, in terms of their principles only. My view of the world as known is not explained by my simple sense-experiences becoming aggregated under principles of association. There is more in my knowledge than my experience can account for. For LECTURE XV read : G. C. Robertson, Philosophical Remains, pp. 63-74: 'How we come by our Knowledge' (or Nineteenth Century, March, 1877). ED. LECTURE XV. THE NATURE OF KNOWLEDGE. EVOLUTION. The Principle of Heredity applied to the Problem of Knowledge. THE problem of knowledge, then, cannot be solved without reference not only to our consciousness but to our organic structure and functions, either according to Kant's view of the constitution of the mind, or according to the scientific point of view which takes into account our nervous system. Now here we see how entirely the philosophical question of knowledge has changed in consequence of our wider scientific view. Evolution has given the problem quite a new expression. I do not say that the evolution of our physical organisation explains consciousness, but it yields us a statement of external conditions. Our experience is determined from the first, and definitely combined in certain ways. Anything more inappropriate, more ludicrous than the tabula rasa theory, with its implication that all minds are at starting alike and, if exposed to the same conditions, would all develop alike, is not to be found. Allowance must be made for the predetermining of primitive endowment : aptitudes must be recognised, as Leibniz saw better than Locke. No child's knowledge is explicable from its own experience. This no doubt involves a starting-point somewhere, but L 2 148 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. scientific explanation does not pretend to give absolute beginnings. We need not assume the primitive endowment of a child as something inexplicable. Heredity is a real factor, and accounts for facts in knowledge which Associationists cannot explain. Breed was always allowed to count for some- thing, but prior to Darwin and Mr. Spencer there was no formulated theory of it. The organism, more especially the nervous system, becomes modified by a change of environment. What one generation acquires in the way of adaptation to environment another gets the benefit of. An accommodation takes place in the individual and modifies the character of the progeny. The individual inherits the experience, or the effects of the experience, of the race. Mr. Spencer, it is true, is not so effective in applying it as he makes out : he should have gone to school under Kant, whose is the insight if not the power of explaining : his theory of knowledge halts, because he fails to see the problem of knowledge in its fullness. The principle of heredity, if applied intelligently, would account for more than he has made it do. By it we can not only explain the difference between your constitution and mine, but we can partly account for the community of know- ledge by the fact of common ancestry, a common inheritance of mental and nervous constitution. This fact, properly understood, is of the greatest importance in explaining. It is a dim fore-feeling of this that we get in Plato's ideas had in a prior existence, and in the theory of innate ideas generally, Experience has gone before us. It is quite evident that our own experience does not determine us to perform acts we do perform before experience can teach us. The mere study of the individual organism will give no explanation of knowledge as we find it. There are factors to be sought outside of the experience of the individual. xv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 149 This does not cut us off from Experientialism, but it does cut us off from Individualism. Heredity explains both the individual element in the conscious living organism and also its element of relation to the conscious life of others. The Social Factor. When we have made every allowance for heredity in the Evolutionist sense, and for experience in the Associationist sense, we have accounted for but a very small part of our knowledge. What the knowledge of an individual comes to be is not to be accounted for by accidental experience alone, nor by heredity, nor by the original constitution of the mind. There is something, principally speech, passed on from generation to generation, which has gone on increasing as it has passed. This the individual finds ready for him to take hold of; it takes hold of him, and through this we have our knowledge. The child comes into the world in a social relation ; when it begins to act for itself, then it is that it comes under the influence of the Social Factor. No ; the question of knowledge is not to be resolved in terms of individualistic experience. The eighteenth century theorists of knowledge Locke, Hume, Berkeley, Kant none of them take into account the social conditions of the individual. Hegel, the great Rationalist, recognised that man has his being determined and moulded by social circum- stances. But it was Comte who first clearly apprehended the ' solidarity ' of the individual in society, and the debt we owe to our fellows and especially to past generations, not by way of organic inheritance, but by way of intercourse, and chiefly by the social engine of thought expressed in language. Lewes's thought too was impregnated with this doctrine. It was he who brought it to the front in this 150 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. country. Man is no mere unit with independent development, but depends for that development on his environment and the overpowering influence of social tradition. It is when he has passed through the training imposed by society that he first begins to assert himself. Speech and Knowledge. Now this social influence, I say, is exerted chiefly by the medium of language. The Nominalists, e.g. Hobbes, Locke and Hume, denying that we have any, or any save very imperfect, powers of general thinking except by means of verbal signs, have always recognised the importance of language. But they were mainly concerned with the special psychological question, ' how we think generally.' They did not discern the far more widely pervading function of language. Whatever the individual develops into can be shown to be a product of his relations with others through the moulding medium of language. For language is a natural social product of the mind, which is not come at or elaborated by any one person, but consists of expressions caught up between man and man and become current. No child coming into being is allowed to follow his own bent, save in a limited degree. For awhile a spontaneous language is allowed free course, but very soon progress in language consists not in his own creations, but in what he shows aptitude in getting from others. Imitation is natural. Through it he is laid hold of by society and moulded after its kind. For the language that is its chief instrument has been developed by accumulated deposits of the countless experiences of the society of the past. The more he works into that language the more he adopts what transforms his whole being, involving as it does an entire theory of the universe. xv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 151 The simple fact of an active verb implying, involving, a sub- ject and object, cause and effect, and the like, embodies such a theory, and becomes a way of interpreting his experience which that experience itself does not adequately provide. Experience is interpreted for him, in spite of him, so as to compel his explanations into the course they take. Here is, for the individual, a non-empirical factor within sense ; not a mere system of sounds, but also an a priori factor of knowledge. But not on Kantian lines. There is no need to fall back on pure intuitions and concepts that cannot be accounted for. The child thinks with con- cepts formed prior to its own experience, concepts which have been developed and which were in past times different from what they are. We have seen that the notion of the world as a realm of cause and effect has developed with the human race. That language has moulded and dictated its development is no justification of Mill's theory, that invariable sequence teaches us to distinguish causal action. Relatively to the individual the concept is pure : it is not developed by him ; others have done this and handed it on ready made. Well then, is the concept absolutely pure from the first ? Was it intuitive ? Or has it been developed in the history of the race ? The question is unanswerable : and yet does there not lie a pretty strong suggestion in the development of languages themselves, with systems of metaphysic variously developed in each? Kant said that effect and cause can never have been developed in the individual or in the race ; such a necessity of thought as that never ! / say, the gradual development of the conviction that nature is a realm of law, that everything is caused, is a historical fact. Even Aristotle's mind, as I pointed out, had no full notion of 152 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. universal causation; some things, he held, happened by chance, causelessly. Necessities of thought can be explained in terms of experience, z/"we let experience include accreted racial experience. This is an extension of Experientialism. Mr. Spencer's Heredity or ' organised experience,' on the one hand, and the fact of growing language on the other, as an impersonal factor, seem to go much further to explain knowledge than unbelievers think. Scientific psychological data, if sound and wide, will answer philosophical questions. In Conclusion, One word more. Kant's importance in the history of philosophy can never be overrated, and, in his own line, no one can go beyond him. No serious study of him is ever lost, for through no thinker can the student be so well led into the heart of the philosophical questions of the day. He is the first philosopher who fully understood the complexity of the problem of knowledge, however mystical his ultimate as- sumptions may appear in the light of the advance of science. Working on independent lines, although a Rationalist, he went as far in the direction of reconciliation between the two opposed standpoints as was possible a century ago. On the other hand, it is the great merit of the English school that, with its feet firmly planted on psychological ground, it has answered as to the nature of knowledge in conformity with this ground. It is true that biological advance has rendered for ever impossible the older Experientialist position, that knowledge with its objectivity, its universality, its necessity, has to be acquired by every individual for himself, in the course of his own experience, from the begin- ning. But the Experientialism of to-day is far in advance of that of the last century. We have advanced all round, xv.] Elements of General Philosophy. 153 e. g. psychologically, by the distinction drawn between active sense and passive sense a discovery which has completely altered the state of the question. Thus the means are now present for working out a systematic theory of knowledge from the point of view of modern Experientialism. Philosophy is not science, but its problems should be solved as far as possible from a scientific point of view. For LECTURE XVI read : Bain, op. cit. 'Theories of a Material World ' (p. 202"!. Mill, Examination of Hamilton's Philosophy, ch. xi. 'The Psycho- logical Theory of the Belief in an External World.' Hamilton, Works of Reid, Notes C and D. Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge. LECTURE XVI. THE PERCEPTION OF AN EXTERNAL (OR MATERIAL) WORLD. Berkeley's Influence. WITH this our third problem we have been dealing more or less by implication. In considering how we come by our knowledge, what are the psychological factors in our cognition, it only remained to add the special emphasis know- ledge, cognition, of oljects. Objectivity as applied to percepts is only a case of the objectivity of knowledge. What account can we give of the existence, in our system of knowledge, of an external, extended, material world? Is there a real pillar corresponding to my individual percept of it? The question is specially an English one, and it was Berkeley who first gave this direction to English thought. The same Berkeley who denied the existence of things of sense, as a philosopher and Immaterialist, was the first man to begin a perfectly scientific doctrine of sense-per- ception as a psychologist. He approached the philosophical question through his psychology. Yet although he was foremost in the psychology of his century and made great positive additions to science, he is almost the only first- rate modern thinker who set to work with a definite Elements of General Philosophy. 155 religious and even theological purpose ; for the note of modern philosophy is that it leaves out religion as such in its explanations. I said 'first-rate/ for some second-rate thinkers, e. g. Butler, did have a religious purpose ; whereas Berkeley psychologised for philosophy, and philosophised for theology. Before Berkeley. Descartes' position was that mind and matter are utterly differentiated, the former by thought, the latter by extension. Mind exists and thinks and is not extended. Matter exists and is extended and does not think. The resultant problem was, How, in the human constitution, can mind be conjoined with a body ? Further : if matter exists in so far as it is ex- tended, is there or is there not much in material things that can be proved not to exist in the same sense, e. g. colour, sound, &c ? Locke was not, like Descartes, a dogmatic metaphysician at least, not to the same extent. Philosophy with Des- cartes was theory of being, and his fundamental assumption was substance either extended or thinking. With Locke it tended to become theory of knowledge, constructed if not on a psychological basis, at least in a psychological spirit. Nevertheless Locke's psychological view of external things is largely coloured by Cartesian metaphysical dogmatism. He asserted at times the existence of matter in a manner as absolute as that of the growing materialistic science of his day. Locke's doctrine of matter as known was that, of our ideas of external things, some correspond to qualities really existing in external bodies, while some are of qualities wrongly imputed by us to those bodies, and which have no objective existence. The former are ' extension, figure, motion, rest, solidity or impenetrability, and number;' the 156 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. latter are ' all other sensible qualities, as colours, sounds, tastes, and so forth V Those he calls primary, these, secondary qualities. The latter are not in things, but are sensations of ours interpreted as absolute qualities of things. Primary qualities exist absolutely, but of them too we have sensible apprehension. These primary and secondary qualities were the equivalents of Aristotle's Com- mon and Special Sensibles. The special sensibles were the impressions conveyed each by a special sense to con- sciousness, but the common sensibles, e. g. extension, were the result of a number of senses being affected together, or rather of what Aristotle called common sense, a sense over and above the special senses. Now Locke thought of extension only as something apprehensible by different senses at the same time, and so he translated common sensibles into primary qualities, holding that all those aspects thus apprehended are fundamental or primary, as representing qualities of objects as they really are. Locke was bound to assume an absolute matter in which these qualities cohered. But if primary qualities are such as we have sensible apprehension of, they are not so different from secondary qualities. Berkeley on Locke. It was here that Berkeley stepped in and broke up this absolute distinction between primary and secondary qualities of matter. He contended that the former are as much explainable in terms of ideas as the latter. All are agreed that colour, sound, heat, &c., are things we impute to matter on the strength of our sensible experience. Berkeley main- tained that this was equally and in the same way true of 1 Locke, Essay, Bk. II, ch. viii ; Berkeley, Principles of Human Knowledge, Pt. I, 9. xvi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 157 the former. They also are ideas, and just as little repre- sentative of any reality in matter as colour, sound, &c., are. If colour is something we impute to external things, there is a sense in which we impute extension to them also. All qualities of things, primary as well as secondary, are for philosophy phenomenal. Berkeley's Theory of Matter. Now this was Berkeley's reason for denying that material things exist at all apart from mind. He regards them as mere aggregates of sensations. All that we mean by matter is uniformity of sense-experience. All that absolutely exists is mind. External things only exist for mind. Esse est percipi. Nothing can be except as perceived. Being, apart from being perceived, is ' a direct repugnancy and altogether inconceivable.' ' The absolute existence of unthinking things are words without a meaning, or which include a contradic- tion 1 .' As we know everything through our senses, and cannot know in any other way, it follows that nothing perceived is absolute, and that matter can only exist if the sense is there. Berkeley does not get rid of the reality to each perceiving mind of the external world, but he does claim to have got rid of its absolute reality, i. e. of its existence apart from perceiving minds. Granted the existence of mind, there is nothing that we cannot express as orderly experience of mind. Such was Berkeley's doctrine of Immaterialism a less ambiguous term than Idealism by which he thought, 1 Principles of Human Knowledge, Pt. I, 17, 24. ' A " contradic- tion " if it means that sensible objects are at once . . . phenomenal and yet not phenomenal.' Fraser's Selections from Berkeley, 3rd ed. pp. 48, 53 note. ED. 158 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. in a community of pure Materialists, to get rid of the matter which was their one fundamental assumption, and at the same time to confute the half-hearted dogmatism of Locke. Berkeley was born in the century which saw the beginning of modern science, and at the end of it, when that science was tending to be very materialistic. Matter was not only assumed, for science as for the practical purposes of life, as an absolute, as something extended and consisting of minute invisible parts having motion in relation to each other a fact which accounted for colour, sound, heat, &c. but was posited as the one thing that really did exist. Locke, on the other hand, as we have seen, allowed only a partial accounting for matter as mental construction. Berkeley contended that, if it can be shown that object is a psychological construction in regard to its secondary qualities, it is equally a psychological construction in regard to its primary qualities. We are not to regard our senses as giving absolute copies, as Locke did, of objects ; we must explain how objects come to appear extended, figured, and moved just as much as how they appear coloured, heated, and so forth. This it was Berkeley's great merit to be the first to put forward. Berkeley fails in legitimate Psychological Explanation. The psychologist has no right to assume object, viz. the object he is going to explain. By this I do not mean that the psychologist, beginning his scientific procedure with an account of the senses, has no right to assume an external world affecting his body and senses. He is bound, for instance, to assume the sun and his own eye before he can give any account of sense-experience in regard to vision. Thinkers of the Hegelian, or, as it is sometimes called, the XVL] Elements of General Philosophy. 159 neo-Kantian, school of Green are constantly insisting that the psychologist assumes what he afterwards professes to explain, and that it is only thus that he contrives to explain. Green made out very cleverly that this was the case with Locke, but though the charge is here well founded, it is not so when made against philosophers who seek to reason on a psychological basis. It is one thing to assume sun and eye in order to get language to explain sensation ; it is another to assume that we have explained what the sun ultimately is. We go on afterwards as philosophers to explain in subjective terms the very things which as psychologists we were bound to assume, and I say that Berkeley's great merit was to see that nothing was present in primary qualities of object which we cannot explain. But then he did not go on to give this explanation : he did not see that primary qualities are dif- ferent from secondary, and why they are so. Why are some forms of our experience of more account for making up our knowledge of that pillar than others ? Berkeley's Fundamental Assumption. So far Berkeley's statements have appeared as negative criticism, but he had constructive aims. He felt it necessary to give a consistent theory of things, a theory which would sufficiently explain the facts of science and also satisfy all the demands of religious conceptions and of every-day experi- ence. Now the fundamental necessary assumption on which he grounds his theory is the existence of one infinite spirit and other finite spirits. What we call Nature is only a mere orderly sequence of ' ideas,' and these are brought to pass by the real causation of the infinite spirit in the minds of finite spirits, these being so far like the infinite spirit that they too can have ideas. 160 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. After Berkeley. Hume. Berkeley's argument against the validity of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities was completely accepted by Hume. He did not dwell on this side of the problem, regarding it as finally made out that, from the point of view of psychology, or, as he would have expressed it, of philosophical consideration, there was no ultimate ground for Locke's division. But he went on to assert that, on the same grounds on which Berkeley had declared that beyond ideas aggregated in certain ways we could get no knowledge of matter, it would be no less incontestably established that it was impossible to get below ideas, or subjective states in general, or subjective phenomenal experi- ence, to the existence of mind. Just as matter was resolved by Berkeley into ideas expressed in certain ways, so by the same kind of resolution was mind reduced by Hume to what we may call a phenomenal expression. Hume worked this out as a part of his general dialectic, in which he was really concerned not to set up any positive theory of knowledge, but rather to follow the bent of his mind and show that when philosophers attempted from their reasoning to make out the ultimate nature of things and dogmatically to determine all that is, they were going a great deal beyond the legitimate sphere of knowledge. His theory of Substance is the first serious and anything like sufficient attempt to give a psychological explanation. He dwells especially upon the amount of representation (work of imagination) involved in objective perception, but fails in not distinguishing either the psychological factor of muscular activity, as lying at the basis of all objective synthesis, or the 'social factor.' As a positive theory it is to be described as an inadequately filled-in Phenomenalism. I am not xvi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 161 concerned here to defend Hume's argument, which to me is imperfect in the last degree. But it is irrefutably true in maintaining that all our knowledge, whether of matter or of mind, is confined to phenomenal aspects. Of either, save in their phenomenal aspects, we know nothing. Kant's Idealism. Now Hume argued sceptically, so as to imply that human knowledge was next to nothing. Kant, on the other hand, while he accepted Hume's general position in this matter, was of those who hold that human knowledge is of a very positive nature. Kant distinctly declared that all our know- ledge was of phenomena. He declared indeed that for our knowledge of physical phenomena we are not wholly depen- dent upon experience, inasmuch as we can make a priori determinations about nature; nevertheless these determina- tions are always about nature as phenomenal. But in regard to our knowledge of mind, we are positively confined to experience. However much we ascribe our subjective states to an Ego, we commit a 'paralogism' if we claim to know mind otherwise than in its manifestations. Kant takes up the question in quite a different way from the English thinkers. He is concerned mainly with the general theory of knowledge, within which theory he has of course a view about the material world as such. And that view I bring into relation not only with Hume, but also with Berkeley. Kant agrees with the latter in refusing to allow the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, declaring that the former are to use his own terms just as subjective or phenomenal as the latter. And though he has by no means the same explanation of extension as Berkeley, though he does not declare, as Berkeley does, M 1 62 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. that for our apprehension of extension we are dependent entirely upon experience, and that it is developed by associa- tion of touches and sights, yet he, even more expressly than Berkeley, declares that the extension of things is no real objective quality of them. For, as we saw, he declares that space is a mere subjective form of sensibility. According to Kant there is positively nothing in our perception of this table which is not subjective. Kant in this respect is an Idealist not an empirical Idealist, since he does not suppose that all the (subjective) elements into which we could analyse this table are such as come to us by way of experience. And he even accuses Berkeley's Idealism of making matter out to be illusory because it is phenomenal, showing herein a very imperfect apprehension of the latter's theory. Kant's Realism. But Kant does not rest in this Idealism. Beyond pheno- mena knowledge, for him, cannot go; nevertheless he declared that phenomena imply an underlying reality which he called the thing in itself, or noiimenoru The former is the less misleading term, since noiimenon suggests a knowing subject no less than phenomenon. Thing-in-itself, then, for him underlay the double stream of experience, subjective and objective, constituting probably a single existence or entity, if that might be called existence or entity which he admitted was an unknown quantity. Self as a particular entity with a possibly immortal future we could hold only as a moral conviction. The Ding an sich an inconsistent Theory. Now Kant declared that all things in themselves are in relation to, or ideas of, ' pure reason ; ' it is on the ground xvi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 163 of this pure reason that we hold them to exist ; in other words, it is a necessity of reason that gives a foundation for noiimena. But then he is placed under this difficulty : if it is upon the ground of reason that we assert these things to exist, have we any rational knowledge of them ? This he was forward to deny, saying that through reason as such no knowledge proper is possible. In the same breath, then, in which he posits, as beyond phenomena, the thing in itself as what cannot be theoretically known, he assumes it as the cause of sensations in us, which we group and interpret in various ways as knowledge. He supposed therefore that when we have a sensation, say, of colour, received according to the law of our being in time and space, and worked up into knowledge according to the categories or laws of the understanding, this phenomenon of colour was really explicable from a thing in itself, the character of which he did not pretend further to define, which he most con- fidently asserted was not in space or time, nor subject to the categories, and yet to which he applied the category of cause. This seems to me the fundamental inconsistency in his philosophy. Reids and Hamilton's Eclecticism. I now come to the English stream of thought to show what followed upon Hume's scepticism. Reid, while he contested Hume's philosophy altogether and, like Kant, set up a general theory of knowledge, was more especially moved to criticise both Berkeley and Hume in their theories of the external world. His whole philosophy was accom- modated to his own theory of this problem. And his theory is that, however philosophers may give a subjective expres- sion to the qualities of matter, yet at the last the philosophical M 2 164 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. position should be that of common sense, namely, that underneath qualities there is a real entity existing apart from the mind. You do not want, he said, a theory of the external world. Open your eyes and see it ! In the very fact of perception there is a present apprehension both of subject and of object, opposed entities, real existences. This view is also called Natural Realism and Natural Dualism, because it agrees with the common view. It may be said that this after all is only Kantianism, with its assertion of our conviction that things exist in themselves. But Reid went further and declared, as against Berkeley and Hume, that, however it might be with secondary qualities and these he gave up this real entity outside of us had as inherent qualities of its own those called primary. Thus he directly took up the position declared by Berkeley to be untenable. But the champion of common sense was, as Hamilton pointed out (v. p. 820 of his edition of Reid), by no means always consistent with himself. At times he declared that on the ground of common sense real things exist outside of us, with qualities of extension and so forth ; at other times he falls back upon the position which Hamilton called Representationism, namely, that our sensible apprehension of things, our mental experience, is a mere substitute or representative for a reality beyond, for which we cannot find an expression that both primary and secondary qualities, instead of being at once subjective and objective facts, or in other words mental experience and real qualities, merely represent that ultimate undefinable reality. And while I bring here no charge against Reid that is not brought against him by his follower Hamilton, I bring this further charge against both, that they depart from the XVL] Elements of General Philosophy. 165 position of common sense to the extent of depriving matter of all secondary qualities. Now it is unquestionable that, in the apprehension of every-day life, we ascribe colour as confidently to external things as we ascribe form. If in philosophising we are to go by common sense at all, we must go by it altogether. This reserve then is objectionable and opens their whole theory to doubt. Hamilton often says that if the testimony of consciousness is false in one thing it is false in everything. But my consciousness gives me the same evidence for the secondary as for the primary qualities. His eclecticism shows that the views of ' the man in the street' are not necessarily correct. And his theory of the immediateness and intuitiveness of our knowledge of an external world involve an absolute element that is at variance with the philosophical doctrine of the Relativity of Knowledge J ' Everything known is only known in relation to a knowing mind' which he assents to and asserts. We cannot take either common sense or consciousness as our ultimate referendum, and then accept or reject this or that in its testimony as we please. My opinion is that what- ever common sense may say, it is common sense that says it, and common sense is one thing and philosophic insight another. Ferrier in this generation has with very great force done over again the work accomplished by Berkeley in the last century. He has done it, if not in the full light of modern psychology, and rather in a metaphysical than a psychological way, yet with a force of thought and expression not to be surpassed. He may be studied either in his Institutes of Metaphysic or his Posthumous Works. 1 Distinguish from the psychological theory of Relativity, viz. in knowing a thing we know it as distinct from something else. i66 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. Spencerian ' Transfigured Realism.' Mr. Herbert Spencer's Transfigured Realism (as he him- self classes it) is really nothing more than what, in Hamilton'^ classification of theories of External Perception, is called Cosmothetic Idealism. Mr. Spencer himself, it is true, says. Realist I am, only not a crude Realist, i. e. with the Realism of popular opinion which imputes all my special sensations to things outside of me. But he goes further and, like Kant, denies that even primary qualities are inherent in real sub- stances, noiimena, or things in themselves. And he ends by saying, not professedly in the language of common sense, which he rather scouts, and yet in language which practically comes to that, that we have a fundamental certainty, the deepest certainty of our being, that object exists as opposed to subject, and subject exists as opposed to object. He does not, like Hamilton, insist on the essence of object being extension, but he declares that in any act of perception there is involved the ultimate certainty that there is an object outside of and apart from the percipient. Now if a thinker like, e. g. Hamilton or Reid asserts this opposition of object and subject with the view of establishing a duality of substances, I can understand the position and see the force of it. This is what we certainly do assume in daily life, and it is open for any philosopher to say that his object is to give a philosophical expression to that assump- tion. But in the case of Mr. Spencer, who scouts the notion of a human being consisting of two entities, mind and body, mutually opposed, all the pother that he makes on this point (in ch. xviii of Vol. II of his Psychology} seems to me, I must confess, to come to no more than much ado about nothing. Why he should be so anxious to make out an opposition of object and subject outside of conscious- XVL] Elements of General Philosophy. 167 ness to explain what is in consciousness I cannot, from his point of view, for a moment understand. Take the passage : ' Realism, then, would be positively justified even were the genesis of this consciousness of existence beyond conscious- ness inexplicable ' (ch. xix). I say that this is a contradiction in terms, and so much so, that when he comes afterwards to give an explanation of this consciousness of existence out of consciousness, it turns out to be after all altogether in terms of consciousness and he has not got to it at all ! He has only got consciousness of existence that is in consciousness. For LECTURE XVII read: Bain, op. cit. ' Perception of a Material World,' pp. 197 et seq. The student may with profit consult also Leibniz's essay s,LaMonado- logie and Prindpes de la Nature et de la Grace fondes en Raison (CEnvres, ed. Paul Janet, vol. ii. pp. 594-617). ED. LECTURE XVII. THE PERCEPTION OF AN EXTERNAL (OR MATERIAL) WORLD (continued}. The Circle of Consciousness. FOR my own part I agree in this matter essentially with Professor Bain and also with Mill. I hold with them, with Berkeley, Ferrier and others, that outside of the circle of our consciousness it is perfectly impossible to get. Mr. Spencer aims at doing so, at getting a consciousness of object outside of consciousness, claiming this as a more certain, funda- mental testimony of consciousness than anything else. I cannot understand the words. I do not see how we can work with a conception like that. I go further. In daily life we do work with such a conception, we do really suppose things to be outside of us with qualities that demonstrably can not be outside of us. But however we may 'in the street' get on with this, from the point of view of philo- sophical consideration I cannot but call it with Berkeley a self-contradiction, and I frankly confess that I do not pretend to give any account of an object not in conscious- ness, nor of a subject not in consciousness. I cannot help it. I would if I could ; but I do not think it can be done. The whole of this discussion can take place only from the point of view of consciousness, and we can never get away from that point of view. What is the good of trying to get away from it and pretending by mere words that we do so ? Elements of General Philosophy. 169 That we do so in daily life does not alter the philosophical truth of the matter. Any object that I can make out in the universe, I cannot pretend to make out except with regard to my mind. So Professor Bain (p. 197): 'There is no such thing known as a tree wholly detached from perception/ &c. But within that circle I am anxious to make out and more anxious than either he or Mill, for I think the treatment in both writers is incomplete that there is an opposition of what cannot better be expressed than by 'subject' and 'object.' And I think that this is an opposition which should find expression in such terms as psychological inquiry can justify, and such as, in respect of philosophical import, may be admitted to contain the ultimate rationale of what undoubtedly is the fact in our common every-day experience, the fact that we do posit mind and matter as independent existences apart from consciousness, out of consciousness, or even without the slightest reference thereto. In common life when we see anything we usually leave ourselves entirely out of account. It never for a moment occurs to us that we have anything to do with it. Berkeley claimed that his Idealism really expressed the thought of people in common : that to the popular mind external object is really whatever can be felt, seen, &c., of it ', and that the kind of abstract substance supposed by metaphysicians to underlie the qualities of matter is really made no account of in the popular conception. There is some foundation for his view. If we abstract from our table 1 Cf. op. cit. I, 6: 'Some truths there are so near and obvious to the mind that a man need only open his eyes to see them. Such . . . that all the choir of heaven and furniture of the earth . . . have not any subsistence without a mind that their being is to be perceived or known,' &c. ED. 170 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. all its qualities and yet retain for it a metaphysical entity, this is clearly what the popular mind cannot or does not take account of. Still I do not think what Berkeley said is correct. However true it may be that the popular mind expresses in terms of sensation the character of external things, I think it is unquestionable that, in the popular apprehension of us all, we do ascribe a perfectly independent existence to these aggregates. Berkeley said, to be is to be perceived. This cannot be said to be the popular apprehension. Perception is an accident in the popular mind. Commonly we conceive the qualities as real objective qualities of a real existing thing. And I think that this popular apprehension must find its explanation. If psychology leads us to take up another position from that of common sense, it is bound to give some kind of explanation of this. If it holds that there is an unwarrantable assumption in these things, it must yet give some explanation of how it came to be made. I am not saying that we are bound to do this for perceptions of daily life. If we did, we should not get on as well as we do. Human action, human life, is one thing, philosophical insight, I repeat, is another. I have no disposition to hide the difficulties of the case, but I think that psychology should be able not only to give a scientific explanation of subject in relation to object circumspectly expressed, but also to explain how it is that this opposition of subject and object within consciousness becomes aggrandised into an opposition of mind and matter apart from each other, and which, generally speaking, rather leaves mind out of account and ascribes to matter, erroneously as I think, an absolute exist- ence. For this is the way of the, to me, utterly unphilo- sophical doctrine of Materialism : it assumes matter to be a real existence apart from mind, and then pretends from XVIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 171 this to explain mind. The most monstrous inversion of the rational course that can possibly be conceived ! First through mind to get a notion of matter, then to objectify it and give it absolute existence, and then from this to explain mind ! The very term ' phenomenon ' used in science implies that the assumptions it makes are not ultimate. Object developed by way of Active Sense. Now I think that Professor Bain, better than many thinkers, lays hold of that element of difference, that means of differentiation within the circle of consciousness through which the opposition of object and subject is developed. He lays his finger on this when he brings out, first, as the fundamental element in the object-consciousness, the differ- ence in our experience between passive sensations and consciousness of energy put forth, and next that all passive sensations, which in themselves fall to subject as opposed to object, like colour or sound, since they are found to vary definitely with our consciousness of activity put forth, come to be transferred from the subject to the object side of the account. We come to project them, and so absolutely, that we cannot now have them otherwise than as qualities outside of us. So that when we have made this transfer, we have left for subject all those sensations that do not vary with our movements as well as the whole of our representative and emotional life (using emotional to correspond with emotion only and not with sense-feeling as well). Explanation of the Distinction between Primary and Secondary Qualities. It is this consciousness that we have in connexion with muscular activity, or rather, active sense, which gives the real psychological explanation of the difference between 172 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. so-called primary and secondary qualities of matter. The latter are the result of our passive sense ; all the former, except the dubious case of ' number/ being the result of complex active sense. So Locke was only exaggerating a distinction of real importance, while Berkeley, in trying to break down all distinction, was not doing well. He never gave prominence to the fact that we cannot apprehend primary qualities of matter without activity of ours put forth. He approximates towards an analysis of touch in his Theory of Vision ( 45), but does not clearly distinguish between active and passive touch. Mill's Contribution. While Professor Bain takes good account of the material elements in explaining the development of this opposition of subject and object, he scarcely brings forward sufficiently the intellectual laws that are involved. Mill, on the other hand, in his Psychological Theory of the External World, while he gives a much less careful statement of the material factors, gives a careful and relatively correct statement of the laws under which this development takes place. The two taken together, read with discernment, will afford the kind of explanation that can be given from the psychological point of view of the development of the opposition. Object and Subject in the Genii. I say development, implying that originally this opposition was not present in consciousness that, even in the lifetime of the individual, there is a time when in the growing experience of the child this opposition begins to develop. I hold that the vague, discrete consciousness of the infant, while it may be called consciousness, is not to be distinguished as subjective or as objective consciousness in the sense xvii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 173 afterwards meant by these words. It is discrete, else there would not be the fundamental condition of consciousness, i.e. discrimination, but it is too vague to admit of that opposition being present. Probably this comes to be at different times in different minds. At some moment in the history of every mind the confused, vague consciousness centres itself, or a beginning of separation is made, and thenceforth to one term or the other all experiences begin to be referred. I do not say that it is not possible for us, and possible with a certain scientific ground, to interpret our experiences, before the separation takes place, as having a subjective meaning. Unless what afterwards comes to be object had arisen within our individual experience and in that sense been subjective, we never could have got to the separation at all. And I accept the relativity of knowledge in the fullest sense that we can have an experience of object only in relation to subject. But I assert also that there is no subject-experience until there is object-experience. Each implies the other. Now philosophers who have laid stress upon this and made object and subject, or matter and mind, two separate entities, have in one way aggrandised this opposition developed within our psychological experience, but not so aggrandised it as to have overlooked the mutual implication. In popular apprehension this is overlooked. And the scientific excuse for maintaining this exaggerated separation is that it affords an excellent working hypothesis for the purposes of objective science. Projected Personality fills up the Import of Object. And there is this important element still : When we talk about an object outside of us we give but an inadequate i74 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. account of it if we express it psychologically in terms of movements of ours and so forth. To each such object \ve ascribe more or less a subjective existence for itself. Every- thing to me is object primarily, and my subject is as it were to me alone. But I come to see, in the first place, that of all my objective experience there is a certain part more constantly in connexion with my special subjective states than any other; and that is my body. I come to think of myself as a composite entity, and not only as two kinds of experience, but as a prominent subject in relation to a relatively prominent object. Next, I find amongst other outside objects various objective experiences resembling those I have from my own body, but not quite similar, else I should mistake them for my own body, and for that matter rendered distinct by the absence of the double touches afforded by my own body. To the sources of these, on the ground of the similar experiences they afford me, I ascribe conscious states resembling my own a subjective and also an objective experience. Finally, even when there is no such similarity, I ascribe an adumbration of subjective life. I do not ascribe to this table the power of putting forth activity, or the feelings that I ascribe to my hearers or claim for myself. But in as far as I talk about the table as a thing able to enter into relation with other things, and in particular with myself, I do give it a kind of quasi-personality ; and I believe that this element can never be absent from object entirely. In primitive minds we have the tendency to ascribe full life to everything, as we see happen in fetish-worship. Children too have this anthropomorphic interpretation of experience, e.g. when they kick the chair they have hurt their shins against. It is a natural tendency that we have this interpreting what we xvii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 175 experience as analogous to our own subject. And I believe that this is only an exaggeration of what each of us does, and needs to do, in order fully to body out any object. Unless I give the table as it were a highly attenuated personality, I do not think I get full objective experience, I do not think I get at that in my consciousness of object which is metaphysically expressed as substance. The Psychological Explanation of Substance. For we may insist that all qualities have their psychological expression in terms of sensible experience, we may insist, with respect to qualities, on the historically fundamental character of resistance how that object is first obstacle, or impediment in the way of activity, and that object so got is interpreted through experience as extended, so that space is body attenuated rather than body is space filled in and yet, when we have finished this analysis of the psychological conception of perception, it may be urged that from the point of view of the metaphysical conception of perception the question may still be asked, Is the object 'there' reaU Is it anything for itself 1 This is a question not to be answered apart from psychology, but it should not therefore be evaded. Popularly judged, there is in our pillar some- thing more than resistance, extension, colour, and any number of qualities. It is said, there is a substance there. Psychology then has to explain substance as well as attribute. Now, as we have seen, my consciousness presents me to myself under a subjective as well as under an objective aspect. I am an extended object and I have a subjective life, a consciousness, a personal identity. And I attribute to you both body and consciousness. But it is your conscious- ness that is to me the reality of you. You are not so much 176 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. a bundle of qualities which give me impressions as the conscious being who has these sensible aspects. Turning to animals, we find ourselves attributing subjective life to them also. And, going lower still, what we ascribe to the pillar as reality or substance is something analogous to that which in us is personality. Its substantiality, as opposed to its qualities, is a pale reflexion of our own subjective experience. Substance is at bottom subjectivity. This is the psychological explanation of the popular notion of differ- ence of substance and quality, which was overlooked by Berkeley, Hume, Mill, and Professor Bain. The Weakness in Berkeley's Theory. Berkeley said that supposing it were the case, that the qualities of matter were to occur to us in a certain orderly and definite manner, and yet suppose that there was no substance there, would you miss this ' substratum or support ' ? His answer is No, we should not, even as we do not in dreams (op. cit. I, 18). Then, he says, we have no right to assume it; and he claims that all he has to account for in perception is the orderliness of experience, which he does by assuming an Infinite Spirit. And he works round to his original position by the argument : If the only account which scientific men can give of substance is a confused idea of something supporting sensible qualities, what shadow of right have they to say that matter is the only real thing in the universe, and that where there is no matter there is nothing at all ? His demonstration then is that there is nothing whatsoever in the notion of substance which is not accountable for as sensible quality, or if there is, it is nothing at all. Has Berkeley got rid of substance altogether in overturning xvii.] Elements of General Philosophy. 177 either the crude materialism of scientific men or Locke's unsatisfactory account? Have we come to this, that there is in the world only an Infinite Spirit and a certain number of other spirits, and can we not ascribe a real existence to anything but God, Berkeley and other spirits like himself? To me his theory comes as short here as it does in the explanation of primary and secondary qualities. There is no doubt that the notion of substance is reasonable, and that while the common sense, which has found Berkeleianism repugnant, is no final criterion, it is yet a fact that philosophy must take into account, and that too when it says, ' A pillar is there.' Berkeley can get a coherent universe only by supposing a number of other minds plus the Deity. Here is rank assumption ! Where are all these minds ? He may be conscious of his own mind, but how then can he be sure of other minds ? He ought to be able, from the point of view of his psychological experience, to account for this conviction. He would have given another answer had he faced the question, How can a mind allow other minds as existing ? Through Mind to Bodies; through Bodies to other Minds. My own conviction, as I have already shown, is that I infer consciousness in others through my sense-perception of them as bodies. Let me be mind only, and I could never get out of myself. If I assume that minds like mine are, so to say, present, it is because I perceive bodies like mine. If your bodies do not exist, why, mine does not. My con- viction of the double phase of my existence is strengthened by finding that I have objective experience of other bodies, which suggests the existence of other minds. And this conviction, by way of inference that material bodies like mine exist, is extended to animals, to which mind is ascribed N 178 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. because of external manifestations. It is only an extension of the same notion to posit the existence of all living things. Then where may we draw the line ? There is no material object perceived by me which is not for me something more than an aggregate of (Berkeleian) ideas. By what way I become sure of you, I become sure of all objects, because I interpret my experience upon the distinction I make between body and mind. In a sense my body is real enough, just as animals, trees, pillars, &c., have all in a very real sense a substantial existence, which is not adequately accounted for by merely assuming the Deity and a few human subjects. But bodily processes are explainable as mental facts, and not vice versa : these are for us ultimate ; these explain. Though I am body as well as mind, the reality of me lies in the continuity of my conscious being. / am because I am subjectively conscious there is my reality. And where I can infer subjective consciousness I say ''you too are real.' This, extended further, is for me the explanation of the metaphysical notion of substance. We may express substance in terms of quality, viz. as Resistance, but quality in terms of substance needs Sub- ject. Let no one say that because that pillar is perceived as substance by analogy of my consciousness of myself as subject, it is therefore taken up into my own being. If I fritter away the reality of substance, what remains of my own reality and that of others ? There- is just the same reason for accepting the reality of external objects apart from the thinker as there is for accepting other conscious- nesses. The world of sense is just as real to Berkeley as it is to the man in the street. The truth in his teaching suggests to fresh students a distressful sense of a desolate universe with the ground cut away from under their feet. XVIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 179 Any philosophic satisfaction that they win will, it may be, come slowly through struggle, wrestling and trial. The transition, however won through, is a necessary process, but it leaves us with quite as real a world, nay, a world more real than we had before. If I say, I am and none other is the motto of Solipsism this is a position from which I cannot be dislodged, and it is the only logical position for Berkeley. But once I allow other minds, then by the same argument I allow other things, since it is through per- ception of bodies that I get at minds. Mind, then, is that which is absolutely existing ; mind is the ultimate expression. Ago ergo sum. Let us pursue the analogy between subject and substance one step further and deeper. If we resolve the material thing into its physical constituents and stop at molecules, we are still at the stage of qualities. But if we go beyond sense to inference and come to the theoretic atom, we no longer apprehend matter by way of qualities, yet we are compelled to consider the atom as endowed with a certain inherent activity, with force or energy. Matter is not dead when thus considered ; it is only in mass that it deports itself as relatively dead. Now here, in this energy, we get a mean term relating to- matter in its ultimate being and our own personality as we subjectively know it. For the reality of our being consists most fully in putting forth activity, in willing. I am, in another and fuller sense, as I will or put forth activity. So too as far as atoms exert energy they really are. Force then in the atom and force in the individual constitutes real existence, and is the fullest expression of mind. Mind exists everywhere, and must be carried down to explain any true reality. N 2 180 Elements of General Philosophy. Thus we may take advantage of all material phenomena in order to help in the consideration of mind. This is in no sense a materialistic position. Atoms when in combination appear so extended, yet the atom is not extended. Exten- sion is only the ultimate phenomenal appearance of matter. I assume that the universe consists of elements which are not extended, which appear when in conjunction as extended, and which are ultimately expressible in terms of mind. This is the Leibnizian conception of monads, which in conjunction appear to a conscious mind as extended, but taken alone are not extended, and whose ultimate expression is in terms of activity. Monadology is the ultimate philo- sophical analysis of the universe, with its fundamental postulate of real beings, immaterial, unextended, having power to act, of which conscious activity is a higher phase. Here is the platform of philosophical agreement. LECTURE XVIII. REGULATIVE PHILOSOPHICAL DOCTRINE. The Regulation of the Three Phases of Mind. 1 HAVE made allusion in the first lecture of this course to philosophy as connoting, under the aspect of 'love of wisdom,' a reference to practice ; I also claimed in the psycho- logical course that philosophy included logic as well as ethics : and I spoke later on of a ' regulative doctrine ' of feeling. Not only feeling, but also intellection and conation admit of being regulated in order to an end or ideal. We may think, for instance, amiss or well. Now logic deals with the conditions of good and bad, i. e. true and false, thinking with thought so as to make it true. Again, action can be made good and feeling beautiful. Ethics, accordingly. is regulative doctrine with a view to making action good. And aesthetics considers feelings, sees which of them admit of development towards a certain end, namely, beauty or refinement. The fact that we can distinguish these three regulative bodies of doctrine, mutually independent, mutually unre- solvable, exhaustive, is to be regarded as one of the strongest arguments for the tripartite division of mind. In psychology 1 82 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. it is often hard to isolate them and secure their independence. But we can distinguish well enough that intellection in the end has to be made true, conation in the end has to be made good, feeling has to be raised to the grade of the beautiful. And we cannot add hereto ; the summary is exhaustive. Law as Generalisation and Law as Norm. Whereas psychology explains mind, these doctrines are occupied with the regulation of mental functions. In the one case we explain what is (or rather appears], in the other we regulate the phenomenon with a view to an end. Clearly then in the latter case we are beyond psychology. We have passed from Phenomenology to use Hamilton's terms to Nomology ; we are dealing with norms, which, it is true, are laws, but not laws in the scientific sense. Scientific law ex- plains, i. e. expresses the complex in terms of the simple, the particular in terms more general. Thus the function of psychology is to explain by classing mental phenomena together, or generalising with respect to them. For instance, according to the law of similarity, whenever we form concepts we are assimilating. But in the logical sense thinking is being consistent. If you are not consistent, you are ' a vegetable.' Here then is law as norm. Psychology has nothing to do with action as good, any more than it has with thought as true, but simply with any kind of action. It deals with mental action as it naturally comes to pass. The Connexion between Psychology and Practical Philosophy. These three doctrines then come under philosophy, not as a certain deeper kind of knowledge, but as involving that certain practical bearing as implied by wisdom, which XVIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 183 philosophy had at first and will have again. They are de- partments of philosophy in its practical reference, ethics being the branch most closely identified with philosophy thus con- sidered. Ethics is philosophy as regulative of conduct, logic and aesthetics being philosophy as regulative of thought and of feeling. Philosophy results, eventuates, is consummated in ethics, inasmuch as philosophical consideration always in the end must be regarded as having an ethical direction, as having its outcome in guidance of conduct, whether the Ethics be blended with religion or not. Wisdom has reference to conduct ; good conduct is wise ; wise conduct is good ; hence ethics is a philosophical discipline. Logic regarded as a Science. From a certain point of view these doctrines may be regarded as science and treated advisedly from the scientific point of view. Let us take logic first and classify the sciences as once before (v. Appendix) into objective and sub- jective sciences. Now though logic is not a science when considered as in any way dependent upon psychology, yet, considered by itself, it is a science, and moreover it must be placed at the head of the objective sciences. For just as chemistry is more special than physics, and physics more special than mathematics, so is mathematics more special than logic. Every one of the sciences, so far as it is a ' logy/ is a specialised logic ; and before logic there can be nothing. But when it is thus considered, it must not be said to be conversant with thought, since this is essentially a subjective notion. It becomes the science of relation 1 , and relation is as wide objectively as thought is subjectively. Things as 1 Not of quality, which, as it includes quantity, would include mathematics as well. 184 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT thinkable are, objectively considered, things as relateable. Nevertheless logic is not so much a science as a condition of science. Ethics regarded as a Science. Ethics again may be considered as the science investigating the various ways in which men have been found to act in relation to men, and on this basis of historical investigation rules how to act in the best way may be framed. This scientific view of ethics has followed from the evolution theory and rather holds the field, Messrs. Spencer and Leslie Stephen being the chief exponents. Ethics is concerned with good conduct followed by not all individuals and nations. To get a science we must examine the meanings of good and bad, what good, and what bad, men do. Facts have to be collected from all times and a progressive or regressive development sought. This view is an extension of evolution as first applied only to biological, and then to anthropological conceptions ; man as considered in respect of his origin, as evolved, and morality as a product of evolution, appearing in time. Unquestionably we may proceed thus. Ethics may be regarded as the science dealing with moral conduct as mani- festing itself throughout time, and the development of ethical notions as the business of the ethical philosopher. Mr. Spencer too, the great systematiser of evolution, says, with Comte, that ethics is a science dependent upon sociology and not upon psychology, although his work on psychology is put first. Morality is regarded as a historical social fact an affair between man and man. The theory of man's social relations is sociology, and some only of those relations are moral. Ethics is a more specialised sociology. As logic XVIIL] Elements of General Philosophy. 185 may be regarded as the science of things as related, so ethics may be considered as the science of action as practicable, of such actions as men can get on with amongst themselves. Indeed much ethical matter can and ought, much more than it has been, to be treated scientifically, inductively, with verification from history. Scientific Treatment does not exhaust Ethics. But no ultimate problems can be thus fairly gone into. Unawares the scientific moralist is ever making philosophical assumptions which he ought to justify there and then. For instance, ' whatever is, is right ; ' ' if a moral custom is found in use, it is because it is right/ Here is an assumption which may not be justified by scientific consideration alone. Again, ' the conditions of human welfare are those of human being; why need men be dissatisfied with what they find?' this is a philosophical consideration. The ideal morality, the morality of the future, is an inevitable point in ethics, but it cannot be prescribed without pronouncing some one goal preferable. Now why any one in particular ? This is not a question of matter of fact, but of what were better or worse, and needing a criterion of the same. It may not be adequately answered by direct facts of sociological experience, but needs deeper consideration even philosophical. There is room, I say, for plentiful investigation of manners, for inductive inquiry into human relations down the course of history. Already we see a development of ethical conceptions, an ethical progress, a change of ideals. But what is an ideal ? What is good ? And what, we ask at this time of day, as ask we must what direction ought human action to take? The problem of ethics is not soluble by purely scientific analysis ; we cannot help being philosophical. Very much from 1 86 Elements of General Philosophy. [LECT. evolutionary science we can accept, but it just misses the point in that it does not adequately treat of the ' consciously aimed at,' the ideal. Finally, let not this view (of ethics as a science) be made light of; let the works of its exponents be read, but critically, and it will be seen how Mr. Leslie Stephen, scouting metaphysic as he does, is as much a metaphysician as any one, and how Mr. Spencer really deals not only with facts, but also with aims, ends, ideals. Logic and Psychology the Bond and the Distinction. Logic derives the materials it works upon from psychology; it has to regulate that function of mind which, psychologically, we distinguish as intellection. It does not however deal with the whole of intellection, but only with that higher or more complex mode which we have termed ' thought.' Now why is thought the only part of intellection that can be logically regulated ? Let us first consider some of the definitions of logic : (a) The science of reasoning ; (U) The art of reasoning ; (oCy), with the interpolated discussion of imagination or phantasy 1 Book III, chh. iii.-viii. These should not only be read but worried at. Wallace's introduction is not very helpful. xxi.] Elements of General Philosophy. 227 (