1 LOGIC DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE First Edition, June 1898 (Grant Richards) Second Edition, November 1901 (Grant Richards) Third Edition, January igo6 (A. Moring Ltd.) Reprinted, January 1908 (A. Moring Ltd.) Reprinted, May 1909 (A. Moring Ltd.) LOGIC DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE BY CARVETH READ, M.A. THIRD EDITION, REVISED AND ENLARGED LONDON ALEXANDER MORING LIMITED THE DE LA MORE PRESS 32 GEORGE STREET HANOVER SQUARE W 1909 PREFACE SEPARATION of the facts and laws of Nature into departments for the convenience of study, has been one of the chief con- ditions of scientific progress. It is true that such separation is made for our convenience and does not exist in Nature. Yet it has been the means of revealing the unity of Nature, the connection of facts, the harmony of laws : analysis has been the necessary preliminary to an intelligent synthesis. No further apology need be offered for the separation of Logic, in the present volume, from all other studies, and especially from Psychology and Metaphysics, with greater vigour than has been usual in logical treatises : carrying out the plan that elsewhere has always proved advantageous. The instructed reader will easily see that I have been chiefly indebted to Mill's System of Logic, Professor Bain's Logic, Dr. Venn's Empirical Logic, and Dr. Keyne's Formal Logic. What- ever is due to other authors has been acknowledged as occasion arose. In every case I have tried to make the property con- veyed my own : an excuse for theft that must seem odd to a lawyer, but is well recognised in the courts of literature. For the comprehensive study of contemporary opinion on Logic, several books besides the above-mentioned are needed : especially Mr. Bradley's Principles of Logic, Mr. Alfred Sidg- wick's Process of Argument, and Mr. Bosanquet's Logic: or the Morphology of Knowledge. The last author's Essentials of Logic is expressly intended to popularise his views. Mr. Hob- house's Theory of Knowledge, an original and valuable treatise, did not come into my hands until this book was finished (now some time ago) : else, probably, I should often have referred to it. Those who, not reading German, desire to see a sample 188173 vi PREFACE of the present state of Logic in the empire, may be referred to Professor Sigwart's Logic, recently translated. Ueberweg's System of Logic, and History of Logical Doctrines is invaluable in its historical passages. I owe a great deal to Mr. Alfred Sidgwick, Mr. Thomas Whittaker, and Professor C. M. Thompson, who have been at pains to advise me upon portions of the MS. and proofs. Most of the chapters, however, no one but myself has seen ; so that whatever errors the critic may find must occur in those unsponsored chapters ; and it is, therefore, needless to say which they are. CARVETH READ. LONDON, May 1898. PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION THE alterations made in this edition are numerous ; but most of them amount only to the excision of a redundant word or sentence, or some small addition to clear up the meaning or guard against misunderstanding. The most important changes will be found in c. ii. 2 ; c. vii. 4 ; c. ix. 5 ; c. xiv. 2 ; c, xv. 5 ; c. xvi. 4-5 ; c. xviii. . 3 ; c. xix. 3. Some of these improvements are due to the advice of friendly reviewers, a few of them even to the comments of reviewers who were friends in disguise ; others were privately suggested to me by Prof. Sully, and the rest by my own conscience. C. R. October 19, igoi. PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION THE necessity of reprinting this book as fast as possible has left me no time to do more than to give a list of errata and add a few questions at the end. C. R. October 19, 1905. ERRATA Page viii, line 5, for " categoremetric " read " categorematic," and for " syncategoremetric " read " syncategorematic." xi, line 15, for " Antimony " read " Antinomy." xv, line 4, for "fraction proportion " read "fraction or proportion." 4, line 3, for " How do we know " read " May it not be." n, 2, /or "in" read "is." 1 7) 36, for " innuendos " read " innuendoes." 34, 8, for " autonomasia " read " antonomasia." 40, ,, 16, for " denotation " read " connotation." 49, 1 1, for "purgatory " read\" Purgatory." 49) i> J 5> f or "un-wise" read "not-wise." 53) > 25, /or "most" read "Most." 69, 9> for " A is not not- A " read " B is not both A and not-A ." 69, n, for " not A " read " not-A." 76, 26, for " predicate " read ' predication." 80, 19, /or "4" read" 6." 8o ? > 34) / or " 4 5 since S " read " 6 ; since S." 83, 24, /or " overtend " read " obvertend." 85, 2 9 ,/ r"4"rmrf"6." 8 7> i) 5) f or " alleging " read " alledging." 87, 17, after the first" Some" insert " S." 87, 19, after the first " Some " /wser< " S." ERRATA Page 89, line i8,/or "Some a is b" read "Some a is B" 89, 3 6,/or 4 "m*d"6." 9> J 5> f r " opposition " read " Opposition ." ,. 105, i,> " 4" *"*" 6" I0 7, 35, /or " middle " raxd " Middle." 118, 2$, for "E" read "A." 121, 4,/or"AEO"mzd"EAO." 124, 28, for "i P" rmrf u is P." T 53 7, / or " Hypothetical " tead " Hypotheticals; 186, 7, /or " situtation " read " situation." J 89, 35, /or " chap. xii. I " rm^ " chap. xiii. 2 .' 250, n, after " established" insert " as a cause." 283, 8, 6c/orc " unexplained " insert " the." 287, 16, /or " Here " read " Hence." 287, 36, /or he " read " the." 291, 19, for "deductions" read "inductions." 321. 14, for " Canines" read "canines." 344, 18, for " corrected " read " collected." 347, 3i,/or "absortion" r^arf "absorption." CONTENTS PAGE PREFACE v CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY i. Definition of Logic i 2. General character of proof 2 3. Division of the subject 4 4. Uses of Logic 5 5. Relation of Logic to other sciences 7 to Mathematics (p. 7) ; to concrete Sciences (p. 9) ; to Metaphysics (p. 9) ; to regulative sciences (p. 10) 6. Schools of Logicians 10 Relation to Psychology (p. u) CHAPTER II GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS i. Propositions and Sentences 15 2. Subject, Predicate and Copula 16 3. Compound Propositions 16 4. Import of Propositions 18 5. Form and Matter 21 6. Formal and Material Logic 22 7. Symbols used in Logic 23 viii CONTENTS CHAPTER III OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION PAGE i. Some Account of Language necessary . / 2 ^ 2. Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric . . . / . . . 27 3. Words are Categoremejric or Syncategoremet^ic . . 28 4. Terms Concrete or Abstract 29 5. Concrete Terms, Singular, General or Collective . . 32 CHAPTER IV THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS I. Connotation of General Names 36 2. Question of Proper Names 37 other Singular Names (p. 39) 3. Question of Abstract Terms 39 4. Uni vocal and Equivocal Terms 40 Connotation determined by the suppositio (p. 42) 5. Absolute and Relative Terms 42 6. Relation of Denotation to Connotation .... 45 7. Contradictory Terms 46 8. Positive and Negative Terms ,48 Infinites ; Privitives ; Contraries (p. 49) CHAPTER V CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS i. As to Quantity . 51 Quantity of the Predicate (p. 54) 2. As to Quality . . 54 Infinite Propositions (p. 55) 3. A. I. E. O. . 5 6 CONTENTS ix PACK 4. As to Relation 57 Change of Relation (p. 58) 5. As to Modality 62 6. Verbal and Real Propositions 63 CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE i. Meaning of Inference 66 2. Immediate and Mediate Inference 67 3. The Laws of Thought 69 4. Identity 70 5. Contradiction and Excluded Middle 71 6. The Scope of Formal Inference 73 CHAPTER VII IMMEDIATE INFERENCES i. Plan of the Chapter 76 2. Subalternation 76 3. Connotative Subalternation 77 4. Conversion 79 Reciprocality (p. 81) 5. Obversion 82 6. Contrary Opposition 83 7. Contradictory Opposition 84 8. Subcontrary Opposition 85 9. The Square of Opposition 86 10. Secondary modes of Immediate Inference .... 87 11. Immediate Lnieiences from Conditionals .... 9 CONTENTS CHAPTER VIII ORDER OF TERMS. EULER J S DIAGRAMS. LOGICAL EQUATIONS. EXISTENTIAL IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS FACE i. Order of Terms in a proposition 92 2. Euler's Diagrams 93 3. Propositions considered as Equations 97 4. Existential Import of Propositions 100 CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE i. Nature of Mediate Inference and Syllogism .... 103 2. General Canons of the Syllogism 104 Definitions of Categorical Syllogism; Middle Term; Minor Term; Major Term; Minor and Major Pre- mise (p. 105) Illicit Process (p. 106) ; Distribution of the Middle (p. 106) ; Negative Premises (p. 108) ; Particular Premises (p. 109) 3. Dictum de omni et nullo no 4. Syllogism in relation to the Laws of Thought . . . in 5. Other Kinds of Mediate Inference 113 CHAPTER X CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS i. Illustrations of the Syllogism ...... 116 2. Of Figures 117 3. Of Moods 118 4. How valid Moods are determined . . . . .119 CONTENTS xi PAGE 5. Special Canons of the Four Figures . . . . .121 6. Ostensive Reduction and the Mnemonic Verses . . 122 7. Another version of the Mnemonic Verses . . . .126 8. Indirect Reduction ........ 127 9. Uses of the several Figures 128 10. Scientific Value of Reduction 130 ii. Euler's Diagrams for the Syllogism 131 CHAPTER XI ABBREVIATED AND COMPOUND ARGUMENTS i. Popular Arguments Informal 133 2. The Enthymeme 134 3. Monosyllogism, Poly syllogism, Prosy llogism, Episyllogism . 136 4. The Epicheirema 136 5. The Sorites 137 6. The AntirAoi^y 139 *L "+ CHAPTER XII CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS i. The Hypothetical Syllogism 142 2. The Disjunctive Syllogism 146 3. The Dilemma 149 CHAPTER XIII TRANSITION TO INDUCTION i. Formal Consistency and Material Truth .... 154 2. Real General Propositions assert more than is directly known 155 xii CONTENTS 3. Hence, formally, a Syllogism's Premises seem to beg the Conclusion 157 4. Materially, a Syllogism turns upon the resemblance of the Minor to the Middle Term ; and thus extends the Major Premise to new cases 158 5. Restatement of the Dictum : equivalent to the Nota note . 159 6, Material Subalternation 160 7. Uses of the Syllogism 160 8. Materially, a Syllogism trusts to the Uniformity of Nature . 162 9. The Uniformity of Nature analysed 163 CHAPTER XIV CAUSATION i. The most important aspect of Uniformity in relation to In- duction is Causation 168 2. Definition of " Cause " explained : five marks of Causation 169 3. Hew strictly the conception of Cause can be applied depends upon the subject under investigation 176 4 Scientific conception of Effect. Plurality of Causes . . 178 5. Some condition, but not the whole cause, may long precede the Effect ; and some co-effect, but not the whole effect, may long survive the Cause 180 6. Mechanical Causes and the homogeneous Intermixture of Effects; Chemical Causes and the heteropathic Inter- mixture of Effects 181 7. Tendency, Resultant, Counteraction, Elimination, Resolu- tion, Analysis, Reciprocity ...... 182 CHAPTER XV INDUCTIVE METHOD i. Outline of Inductive investigation ..... 185 2. Induction defined 189 CONTENTS xiii PAGE 3. " Perfect Induction " 189 4. Imperfect Induction methodical or immethodical . . 190 5. Observation and Experiment, the material ground of Induc- tion, compared 191 6. The principle of Causation is the formal ground of Induction 193 7. The Inductive Canons are derived from the principle of Causation, the more readily to detect it in facts observed 195 CHAPTER XVI THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION i. The Canon of Agreement 198 Negative Instances (p. 200) ; Plurality of Causes (p. 200) Agreement may show connection without direct Causa tion (p. 201) 2. The Canon of Agreement in Presence and in Absence . . 203 It tends to disprove a Plurality of Causes (p. 204) 3. The Canon of Difference 207 May be applied to observations (p. 211) 4. The Canon of Variations 212 How related to Agreement and Difference (pp. 214-5) ; The Graphic Method (p. 217) ; Gradations (p. 219) 5. The Canon of Residues 221 CHAPTER XVII COMBINATION OF INDUCTION WITH DEDUCTION i. Deductive character of Formal Induction .... 225 2. Further complication of Deduction with Induction . . 227 3. The Direct Deductive (or Physical) Method . . .228 4. Opportunities of Error in the Physical Method . . . 232 5. The Inverse Deductive (or Historical) Method . . . 234 6. Precautions in using the Historical Method . . . 239 xiv CONTENTS CHAPTER XVIII HYPOTHESES PAGE i. Hypothesis defined and distinguished from Theory . . 244 2. An Hypothesis must be verifiable 246 3. Proof of Hypotheses 248 (1) Must an hypothetical agent be directly observable ? (p. 248) ; Vera causa (p. 249) (2) An Hypothesis must be adequate to its pretensions (p. 250) ; Excepiio firobat regulam (p. 252) (3) Every competing Hypothesis must be excluded (p. 253) ; Crucial instance (p. 255) (4) Hypotheses must agree with the laws of Nature (P- 256) 4. Hypotheses necessary in scientific investigation . . . 257 5. The Method of Abstractions 261 Method of Limits (p. 262) ; In what sense all knowledge is hypothetical (p. 264) CHAPTER XIX LAWS CLASSIFIED; CO-EXISTENCE; EXPLANATION; ANALOGY i. Axioms; Primary Laws; Secondary Laws, Derivative or Empirical ; Facts 266 2. Secondary Laws either Invariable or Approximate Generali- sations 269 3. Secondary Laws trustworthy only in ' Adjacent Cases ' . 271 4. Secondary Laws of Succession or of Co-existence . . 273 Natural Kinds (p. 273) ; Co-existence of concrete things to be deduced from Causation (p. 275) 5. Explanation consists in tracing resemblance, especially of Causation 276 6. Three modes of Explanation 279 Analysis (p. 279) ; Concatenation (p. 279) ; Subsumption (p. 280) 7. Limits of Explanation 282 8. Analogy 283 CONTENTS xv CHAPTER XX PROBABILITY . PAGE i. Meaning of Chance and Probability 286 2. Probability as a fraction /proportion 288 3. Probability depends upon experience and statistics . . 288 4. It is a kind of Induction, and pre-supposes Causation . . 291 5. Of Averages and ' Errors ' 293 Personal Equation (p. 294) ; meaning of ' Expectation ' (P- 295) 6. Rules of the combination of Probabilities .... 295 Detection of a hidden Cause (p. 296) ; oral tradition (p. 297); circumstantial and analogical evidence (p. 298) CHAPTER XXI DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION i. Classification, scientific, special and popular . , . 300 2. Uses of classification 302 3. Classification, Deductive and Inductive .... 304 4. Division, or Deductive Classification : its Rules . . . 305 5. Rules for testing a Division 307 6. Inductive Classification 309 7. Difficulty of Natural Classification 310 8. Darwin's influence on the theory of Classification . . 312 9. Classification of Inorganic Bodies also dependent on Causa- tion, . 316 CHAPTER XXII NOMENCLATURE; DEFINITION; PREDICABLES i. Precise thinking needs precise language .... 317 2. Nomenclature and Terminology 318 3. Definition 320 4. Rules for testing a Definition 321 xvi CONTENTS PAGE 5. Every Definition is relative to a Classification . . . 322 6. Difficulties of Definition 325 Proposal to substitute the Type (p. 325) 7. The Limits of Definition 326 8. The five Predicables 327 Porphpyry's Tree (p. 330) 9. Realism and Nominalism . 333 10. The Predicaments 335 CHAPTER XXIII DEFINITION OF COMMON TERMS i. The rigour of scientific method must be qualified . . 338 2. Still, Language comprises the Nomenclature of an imperfect Classification, to which every Definition is relative ; 339 3. and an imperfect Terminology 343 4. Maxims and precautions of Definition 344 5. Words of common language in scientific use . . . 347 6. How Definitions affect the cogency of arguments . . 350 CHAPTER XXIV FALLACIES i. Fallacy defined and divided 355 2. Formal Fallacies of Deduction 355 3. Formal Fallacies of Induction . . . . . 358 4. Material Fallacies classified 363 5. Fallacies of Observation 364 6. Begging the Question 365 7. Surreptitious Conclusion 367 8. Ambiguity 369 9. Fallacies, a natural rank growth of the Human Mind, not easy to classify, or exterminate 372 QUESTIONS 375 OF THE ( UNIVERSITY ] CHAPTER I INTRODUCTORY i. Logic is the science that explains what conditions must be fulfilled in order that a proposition may be proved, if it admits of proof. Not, indeed, every such proposition ; for as to those that declare the equality or inequality of numbers or other magnitudes, to explain the conditions of their proof belongs to Mathematics : they are said to be quantitative. But as to all other propositions, called qualitative, like most of those that we meet with in conversation, in literature, in politics, and even in the sciences that are not treated mathe- matically (say, Botany and Psychology); propositions that merely tell us that something happens (as that salt dissolves in water], or that something has a certain property (as that the east wind is baneful), or that something is related to a class of things (as that Englishmen are good sailors) : as to these, it belongs to Logic to show how we may judge whether they are true, or false, or doubtful. When propositions are expressed with the universality and definiteness that belongs to scientific statements, they are called laws ; and laws, so far as they are not laws of quantity, are tested by the principles of Logic, if they at all admit of proof. But it is plain that the process of proving cannot go on for ever ; something must be taken for granted ; and this is usually considered to be the case with those highest laws that are called * axioms ' or ' first principles,' of which we can only say that we know of no exceptions to them, that we cannot help believing them, and that they are indispensable to science and 2 LOGIC : DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE to consistent thought. Logic, then, may be briefly defined as the science of proof with respect to qualitative laws and propo- sitions, except those that are axiomatic. 2. Proof may be of different degrees or stages of com- pleteness. Absolute proof would require that a proposition should be shown to agree with all experience and with the systematic explanation of experience, to be a necessary part of an all-embracing and self-consistent philosophy or theory of the universe ; but as no one hitherto has been able to frame such a philosophy, we must at present put up with something less than absolute proof. Logic, assuming certain principles to be true of experience, or at least to be conditions of con- sistent discourse, distinguishes the kinds of propositions that can be shown to agree with these principles, and explains by what means the agreement can best be exhibited. These principles will be found in chaps, vi., ix., xiii., xiv. To bring a proposition or an argument under them, or to show that it agrees with them, is logical proof. The extent to which proof is requisite, again, depends upon circumstances ; whether our aim be general truth for its own sake, or merely to compare a proposition with our own convic- tions, or to satisfy the doubts of a friend. If A and B are conversing, and A asserts that some white races have straight black hair, and B doubts this, but is willing to grant that some races with straight black hair are white, A may perhaps prove his point to the satisfaction of B by showing that these two pro- positions are intrinsically the same, as only differing in the order of the words. This is called proof by Immediate Inference, or by equivalence of meaning. Again, if B is ready to admit that the Basques and Finns are white races, and also that they have straight black hair, then when A puts these two propositions together thus The Basques and Finns have straight black hair ; The Basques and Finns are white races ; Therefore, some white races have straight black hair the truth of the last proposition is not likely to be disputed any , then INTRODUCTORY 3 longer. And this is called proof by Mediate Inference : that is to say, a connection between * some white faces ' and * straight black hair ' is supposed not to be directly perceivable, but to be discovered by finding that both are connected in a certain way with, ' Basques and Finns. 1 If, however, B does not grant that the Basques or the Finns are a white race, or that they have straight black hair, and A tries to prove these propositions, his difficulties greatly increase and may become insuperable. He must collect ethnological evidence, and convince B of its sufficiency ; and if his friend be of a sceptical turn of mind, or desire a reputation for ingenuity rather than for good sense, the conclusion that some white races have straight black hair may be indefinitely postponed. In fact, to follow out this illustration would be altogether unsuit- able to an introductory chapter \ we had better turn to a simpler case. Suppose that A holds in his hand a piece of yellow metal, which he asserts to be copper, and that B doubts this, perhaps suggesting that it is really gold. Then A may propose to dip it in vinegar ; and we will suppose B to agree that, if it then turns green, it is copper and not gold. On trying this experi- ment the metal does turn green ; so that we may put A's argument in this way : Whatever yellow metal turns green in vinegar is copper ; This yellow metal turns green in vinegar ; Therefore, this yellow metal is copper. Now, however, it may occur to B that the liquid in which the metal was dipped was not vinegar, or not pure vinegar, and that the greenness was due to the impurity. A must thereupon show by some means that the vinegar was pure ; and then his argument will be that, since nothing but the vinegar came in contact with the metal, the greenness was due to the vinegar ; or, in other words, that contact with that vinegar was the cause of the metal turning green. Still, on second thoughts, B may suspect that he had formerly conceded too much ; he may reflect that, although it LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE often been shown that copper turned green in vinegar, whilst gold did not, yet the same might not always happen. How-do -wHcew, he might ask, that just at this moment, and perhaps always for the future gold turns, and will turn green in vinegar, whilst copper does not and never will again ? A will probably reply that this is to doubt the uniformity of causation : he may hope that B is not serious : he may point out to his friend that in every action of his life he takes such uniformity for granted. But he will be obliged to admit that, whatever he may say to induce his friend to assent to the principle of Nature's uniformity, his arguments will not amount to logical proof, because every argument in some way assumes that principle. He has come, in fact, to the limits of Logic. Just as the mathe- matician does not try to prove that * two magnitudes equal to the same third are equal to one another,' so the Logician (as such) does not attempt to prove the uniformity of causation and the other principles of his science. 3. Two departments of Logic are usually recognised, De- duction and Induction ; that is, to describe them briefly, proof from principles, and proof from facts. Classification is some- times made a third department ; sometimes its topics are dis- tributed amongst those of the former two. In the present manual the order adopted is, Deduction in chaps, ii. to xiii, : Induction in chaps, xiii. to xx. ; and lastly, Classification. But such divisions do not represent fundamentally distinct and opposed aspects of the science. For although, in discussing any question with an opponent who makes admissions, it may be possible to combat his views with merely deductive argu- ments based upon his admissions; yet in any question of general truth, Induction and Deduction are mutually dependent and imply one another. This may be seen in one of the above examples. A argues that a certain metal is copper, because every metal is copper that turns green when dipped in vinegar. So far his proof appeals to a general proposition, and is deductive. But if B asks how he knows the general proposition to be true, A alleges INTRODUCTORY 5 experiments or facts ; and this is inductive evidence. De- duction then depends on Induction. But when B asks, again, how any number of past experiments can prove a general pro- position, which must be good for the future as well as for the past, A invokes the uniformity of causation ; that is, he appeals to a principle, and that again is deductive proof. Induction then depends upon Deduction. We may put it in this way : Deduction depends on Induc- tion, if general propositions are only known to us through the facts : Induction depends on Deduction, because one fact can never prove another, except so far as what is true of the one is true of the other and of any other of the same kind ; and because, to exhibit this resemblance of the facts, it must be stated in a general proposition. 4. The use of Logic is often disputed : those who have not studied it, often feel confident of their ability to do without it ; those who have studied it, are sometimes disgusted with what they consider to be its superficial analysis of the grounds of evidence, or needless technicality in the discussion of details. As to those who, not having studied Logic, yet despise it, there will be time enough to discuss its utility with them, when they know something about it ; and as for those who, having studied it, turn away in disgust, whether they are justified every man must judge for himself, when he has attained to equal proficiency in the subject. Meanwhile, the following considerations may be offered as inducements to persevere in the study : (a) Logic states, and partly explains and applies, certain abstract principles which all other sciences take for granted ; namely, the axioms above mentioned. (b) By exercising the student in the apprehension of these truths, and in the application of them to particular proposi- tions, it educates the power cf abstract thought. For this reason Logic is the best propaedeutic to Philosophy, that is, to Metaphysics and speculative Ethics. (c) Every science, when well expounded, is a model cf 6 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE method, and a discipline in close and consecutive thinking. This merit Logic ought to possess in a high degree. (d) As the science of proof, Logic gives an account of the general nature of evidence deductive and inductive, as applied in the physical and social sciences and in the affairs of life. Observe: the general nature of such evidence. It would be absurd of the Logician to pretend to instruct the Chemist, Economist and Merchant, as to the special character of the evidence requisite in their several spheres of judgment. Still, by investigating the general conditions of proof, he sets every man upon his guard against insufficient evidence. Of course, Logic does not, in the first place, teach us to reason. We learn to reason, as we learn to walk and talk, by the natural growth of our powers, with some assistance from friends and neighbours. But, to be frank, few of us walk, talk or reason remarkably well ; and, as to reasoning, Logic certainly quickens our sense of bad reasoning, both in others and in ourselves. It helps us to avoid being misled by others, and to correct our own mistakes. A man who reasons deliberately, manages it better after studying Logic than he could before if he tries to, if he has not a perverse liking for sophistry, and if he has the sense to know when formalities are out of place. There are some mental qualities that a man can only get from hTsHfaTEeTland mother. (e) One application of the science of proof deserves special mention : I mean, to that department of Rhetoric that has been the most developed, relating to persuasion by means of oratory, leader-writing, or pamphleteering. It is usually said that Logic is useful to convince the judgment, not to persuade the will : but one way of persuading the will is to convince the judgment that a certain course is advantageous ; and although this is not always the readiest way, it is the most honourabl and leads to the most enduring results. Logic, in fact, is the backbone of Rhetoric. Now, it is in view of these last four uses of Logic (, c, d, e) that it may be treated as an Art. As a Science, it explains the fr : INTRODUCTORY 7 relations of truths to one another, especially to certain first principles : as an Art, it regards Truth as an end desired, and points out some of the means of attaining it; namely, to proceed by a regular method, to test any proposition by the principles of Logic, and to distrust whatever cannot be made consistent with them. It does not give any one originality and fertility of invention; but it enables us to check our inferences, revise our conclusions, and chasten the vagaries of ambitious speculation. On account of this corrective function, Logic is sometimes called a Regulative Science. (/) Finally, Logic is at least a refined mental exercise. And it needs no telescopes, microscopes, retorts or scalpels ; no observatories, laboratories, or museums : it is, therefore, cheap and convenient. Moreover, it is of old and honourable descent; a man studies Logic in very good company. It is the warp upon which nearly the whole web of ancient, mediaeval and modern philosophy has been woven; and is therefore manifestly indispensable to a liberal education. 5. The relation of Logic to other sciences may be indicated thus: (a) Logic is regarded by Spencer as co-ordinate with Mathe- matics, both being Abstract Sciences that is, sciences of the relations in which things stand to one another, whatever the particular things may be that are so related; and this view seems to me to be, on the whole, just subject, however, to a qualification that will appear presently. Mathematics treats of the relations of all sorts of things considered as quantities, namely, as equal to, or greater or less than, one another. Things may be quantitatively equal or unequal in degree^ as in comparing the temperature of bodies; or in duration; or in spatial magnitude, as with lines, superficies, solids; or in number. And it is assumed that the equality or inequality of things that cannot be directly compared, may be proved indirectly on the assumption that ' things equal to the same thing are equal,' etc. 8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Logic also treats of the relations of all sorts of things, but not as to their quantity. It considers (i) that one thing may be like or unlike another in certain attributes, as that a shark is in many ways like a ray, and in many ways unlike a star-fish : (ii) that attributes co-exist or coinhere (or not) in the same subject, as ihe having several rows of teeth and a backbone prolonged into the upper lobe of the tail coinhere in a shark : and (iii) that one event follows another (or is the effect of it), as that the placing of iron in water causes it to rust. The relations of likeness and of coinherence are most prominent in the department of Classification; for it is by resemblance of coinhering attributes that things form classes : the relation of succession, in the mode of causation, is the chief subject of the department of Induction. It is usual to group together these relations of attributes and of order in time, and call them qualitative, in order to contrast them with the quantitative which belong to Mathematics. And it is assumed that qualitative relations of things, when they cannot be directly perceived, may be proved indirectly by assuming the axiom of the Syllogism (chap, ix.) and the law of Causation (chap. xiv.). So far, then, Logic and Mathematics appear to be co- ordinate and distinct sciences. But we shall see hereafter that the satisfactory treatment of that special order of events in time which constitutes Causation, requires a combination of Logic with Mathematics. On the other hand, Logic may be said to be in some respects 4 prior to ' or * above ' Mathematics as usually treated. For the Mathematics assume that one magnitude must be either equal or unequal to another, and that it cannot be both equal and unequal to it, and thus take for granted the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle ; but the statement and elucidation of these principles is left to Logic (chap. vi.). The Mathematics also classify and define magnitudes, as (in Geometry) triangles, squares, cubes, spheres ; but the principles of classification and definition remain for Logic to discuss. INTRODUCTORY 9 (b) As to the concrete Sciences, such as Astronomy, Chemistry, Zoology, Politics Logic (as well as Mathematics) is implied in them all ; for all the propositions of which they consist involve causation, co-existence, and class-likeness. Logic is therefore said to be prior to them or above them : meaning by prior ' not that it should be studied earlier, for that is not a good plan ; meaning by ' above ' not in dignity, for distinctions of dignity amongst liberal studies are absurd. But it is a philosophical idiom to call the abstract ' prior to,' or 'higher than,' the concrete (see Porphyry's Tree, chap. xxii. 8); and Logic is more abstract than Astronomy or Politics, Philosophy may thank that idiom for many a foolish notion. (c) But, as we have seen, Logic does not investigate the truth, trustworthiness, or validity of its own principles ; nor does Mathematics : this task belongs to Metaphysics, the criticism of knowledge and beliefs. Logic assumes, for example, that things are what to a careful scrutiny they seem to be ; that animals, trees, mountains, planets, are bodies with various attributes, existing in space and changing in time; and that certain principles, such as Contradiction and Causation, are true of things and events. But Metaphysicians have raised many plausible objections to these assumptions. It has been urged that natural objects do not really exist on their own account, but only in dependence on some mind that contemplates them, and that even space and time are only our way of perceiving things ; or, again, that although things do really exist on their own account, it is in an entirely different way from that in which we know them. As to the principle of Contradiction that if an object has an attribute, it cannot at the same time and in the same way be without it (e.g., if an animal is conscious, it is false that it is not conscious) it has been contended that the speciousness of this principle is only due to the narrowness of our minds, or even to the poverty of language, which cannot make the fine distinctions that exist in Nature. And as to Causation, it is io LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE sometimes doubted whether events always have physical causes; and it is often suggested that, granting they have physical causes, yet these are such as we can neither perceive nor conceive; belonging not to the order of Nature as we know it, but to the secret inwardness and reality of Nature, to the wells and reservoirs of power, not to the spray of the fountain that glitters in our eyes 'occult causes,' in short. Now these doubts and surmises are metaphysical spectres which it remains for Metaphysics to lay. Logic has no direct concern with them (although, of course, meta- physical discussion is usually expected to be logical), but keeps the plain path of plain beliefs, level with the com- prehension of plain men. Metaphysics, as examining the grounds of Logic itself, is sometimes regarded as * the higher Logic.' (d) The relation of Logic to Psychology will be discussed in the next section. (e) As a Regulative Science, pointing out the conditions of true inference (within its own sphere), Logic is co-ordinate with (i) Ethics, considered as assigning the conditions of right conduct, and with (ii) ^Esthetics, considered as deter- mining the principles of criticism and good taste. 6. Three principal schools of Logicians are commonly recognised : Nominalist, Conceptualist, and Materialist, who differ as to what it is that Logic really treats of : the Nomi- nalists say, ' of language ' ; the Conceptualists, ' of thought ' ; the Materialists, 'of relations of fact.' To illustrate these positions let us take authors who, if some of them are now neglected, have the merit of stating their contrasted views with a distinctness that later refinements tend to obscure. (a) Whately, a well-known Nominalist, regards Logic as the Science and Art of Reasoning, but at the same time as " entirely conversant about language " ; that is to say, it is the business of Logic to discover those modes of statement which shall ensure the cogency of an argument, no matter what may be the subject under discussion. Thus, All fish are cold-blooded, .'. INTRODUCTORY n some cold-blooded things are fish : this is a sound inference by the mere manner of expression ; and equally sound itf the inference, All fish are warm-blooded, .'. some warm-blooded things are fish. The latter proposition may be false, but it follows; and (according to this doctrine) Logic is only concerned with the consistent use of words : the truth or falsity of the proposition itself is a question for Zoology. (b) Hamilton, our best-known Conceptualist, regards Logic as the science of the "formal laws of thought," and "of thought as thought," that is, without regard to the matter thought about. Just as Whately regards Logic as concerned merely with cogent forms of statement, so Hamilton treats it as concerned merely with the necessary relations of thought. This doctrine is called Conceptualism, because the simplest element of thought is the Concept ; that is, an abstract idea, such as is signified by the word man, planet, colour, virtue ; not a representative or generic image, but the thought of all attributes common to any class of things. Men, planets, colours, virtuous actions or characters, have, severally, some- thing in common on account of which they bear these general names ; and the thought of what they have in common, as the ground of these names, is a Concept. To affirm or deny one con- cept of another, as Some men are virtuous, No man is perfectly virtuous, is to form a Judgment, corresponding to the Proposition of which the other schools of Logic discourse. Conceptualism, then, investigates the conditions of consistent judgments. To distinguish Logic from Psychology is most important in connection with Conceptualism. Concepts and Judgments being mental acts, or products of mental activity, it is often thought that Logic must be a department of Psychology. It is recognised, of course, that Psychology deals with much more than Logic does, with sensation, pleasure and pain, emotion, volition ; but in the region of the intellect, especially in its most deliberate and elaborate processes, namely, con- ception, judgment, and reasoning, it is supposed that Logic and Psychology occupy some common ground. In fact, 12 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE however, the two sciences have little in common except a few general terms, and even these they employ in different senses. It is usual to point out that Psychology tries to explain the subjective processes of conception, judgment and reasoning (say, according to the Laws of Association) and to give their natural history ; but that Logic is wholly concerned with the results of such processes, with concepts, judgments and reasonings, and merely with the validity of the results, that is, with their truth or consistency ; whilst Psychology has nothing to do with their validity, but only with their causes. Besides, the logical judgment is (in Formal Logic at least) quite a different thing from the psychological : the latter involves feel- ing and belief, whereas the former is merely a given relation of concepts. S is P : that is a model logical judgment ; there can be no question of believing it ; but it is logically valid if M is P and S is M. If, again, belief has any place in Logic, it depends upon evidence; whereas, in Psychology belief is shown to depend upon causes which may have evidentiary value or may not ; for Psychology explains quite impartially the growth of scientific insight and the growth of prejudice. (c) Mill, Bain, and Venn are the chief Materialist logicians; and to guard against the error of confounding Materialism in Logic with the ontological doctrine that nothing exists but Matter, it may suffice to remember that in Metaphysics all these philosophers are Idealists. Materialism in Logic consists in regarding propositions as affirming or denying relations (rf- 5) between matters-of-fact ; in treating the first principles of Contradiction and Causation as true of things so far as they are known to us, and not merely as conditions or tendencies of thought ; and, indeed, in taking these principles as conditions of right thinking, because they seem to hold good of Nature. To these differences of opinion it will be necessary to recur in the next chapter ( 4) ; but here I may observe that it is easy to exaggerate their importance in mere Logic. There is really little at issue between schools of logicians as such, and as far as their doctrines run parallel ; it is on the metaphysical INTRODUCTORY 13 grounds of their study, or as to its scope and comprehension, that they find a battle-field. As for the present work, it generally proceeds upon the third, or Materialist doctrine. If Deduction and Induction are regarded as mutually dependent parts of one science, uniting the discipline of consistent dis- course with the method of investigating laws of physical phenomena, the Materialist doctrine, that the principles of Logic are founded on fact, seems to be the most natural way of thinking. But if the unity of Deduction and Induction is not disputed by the other schools, the Materialist may regard them as allies exhibiting in their own way the same body of truths. The Nominalist may certainly claim that his doctrine is indispensable : consistently cogent forms of statement are necessary both to the Conceptualist and to the Materialist ; neither the relations of thought nor those of fact can be arrested or presented without the aid of language or some equivalent system of signs. The Conceptualist may urge that the Nominalist's forms of statement and argument exist for the sake of their meaning, namely, judgments and reasonings ; and that the Materialist's laws of Nature are only judgments founded upon our conceptions of Nature ; that the truth of observations and experiments depends upon our powers of perception ; that perception is inseparable from understanding, and that s. system of Induction may be constructed upon the axiom of Causation, regarded as a principle of Reason, just as well as by considering it as a law of Nature, and upon much the same lines. The Materialist, admitting all this, may say that the other schools have not hitherto been eager to recognise the unity of Deduction and Induction or to investigate the conditions of trustworthy experiments and observations within the limits of human understanding ; that thought is itself a sort of fact, as complex in its structure, as profound in its relations, as subtle in its changes as any other fact, and there- fore at least as hard to know ; that to turn away from the full reality of thought in perception, and to confine Logic to artificially limited concepts, is to abandon the effort to push 14 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE method to the utmost and to get as near truth as possible ; and that as to Causation being a principle of Reason rather than of Nature, the distinction escapes his apprehension, since Nature seems to be that to which our private minds turn upon questions of Causation for correction and instruction ; so that if he does not call Nature the Universal Reason, it is because he loves severity of style. CHAPTER II GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS i. Since Logic discusses the proof or disproof, or (briefly) the testing of propositions, we must begin by explaining their nature. A proposition, then, may first be described in the language of grammar as a sentence indicative ; and it is usually expressed in the present tense. It is true that other kinds of sentences, optative, imperative, interrogative, exclamatory, if they express or imply an asser- tion, are not beyond the view of Logic ; but before treating such sentences, Logic, for greater precision, reduces them to their equivalent sentences indicative. Thus, / wish it were summer may be understood to mean, The coming of summer is an object of my desire. Thou shalt not kill may be interpreted as Murderers are in danger of the judgment. Interrogatories, when used in argument, if their form is affirmative, have negative force, and affirmative force if their form is negative. Thus, Do hypocrites love virtue ? anticipates the answer, No. Are not traitors the vilest of mankind ? anticipates the answer, Yes. So that the logical form of these sentences is, Hypocrites are not lovers of virtue; Traitors are the vilest of mankind. Impersonal propositions, such as // rains, are easily rendered into logical forms of equivalent meaning, thus: Rain is falling; or, if this be tautology, The clouds are raining. Exclamations may seem capricious, but are often part of the argument. Shade of Chatham ! usually means Chatham^ being aware of our present foreign policy ', is much disgusted. It is, in fact, an 16 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE appeal to authority, without the inconvenience of stating what exactly it is that the authority declares. 2. But even sentences indicative may not be expressed in the way most convenient to logicians. Salt dissolves in water is a plain enough statement for ordinary purposes; but the logician prefers to have it thus : Salt is soluble in water. For he says that a proposition is analysable into three elements : (i) a Subject (as Salt) about which something is asserted or denied; (2) a Predicate (as soluble in water) which is asserted or denied of the Subject, and (3) the Copula (is or are, or is not or are not), the sign of relation between the Subject and Predicate. The Subject and Pre- dicate are called the Terms of the proposition : and the Copula may be called the sign of predication, using the verb ' to predicate ' indefinitely for either * to affirm ' or * to deny.' Thus S is P means the term P is given as related in some way to the term S. We may, therefore, further define a Proposition as 'a sentence in which one term is predicated of another.' In such a proposition as Salt dissolves, the copula (is) is contained in the predicate, and, besides the subject, only one element is exhibited : it is therefore said to be secuntfi adjacentis. When all three parts are exhibited, as in Salt is soluble, the proposition is said to be tertli adjacentis. For the ordinary purposes of Logic, in predicating attributes of a class, the copula is, or is not, sufficiently represents the relation of subject and predicate ; but when it is desirable to realise fully the nature of the relation involved, it may be better to use a more explicit form. Instead of saying Salt is soluble, we may say Solubility coinheres with the nature of salt, or The putting of salt in water is a cause of its dissolving: thus expanding the copula into a full expression of the relation we have in view, whether coinherence or causation. 3. The sentences of ordinary discourse are, indeed, for the most part, longer and more complicated than the logical form of propositions ; it is in order to prove them, or to use them in the proof of other propositions, that they are in Logic GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS 17 reduced as nearly as possible to such simple but explicit expressions as the above (tertii adjacentis). A Compound Proposition, reducible to two or more simple ones, is said to be exponible. The meansTiy which sentences are compounded may be seen analysed in any book of grammar. One of the commonest forms is the copulative, such as Salt is both savoury and wholesome, equivalent to two simple propositions : Salt is savoury ; Salt is ivholesome. Pure water is neither sapid nor odorous, equivalent to Water is not sapid ; Water is not odorous. Or, again, Tobacco is injurious, but not when used in moderation, equivalent to Much tobacco is injurious ; a little is not. (The word but, however, sometimes needs a third pro- position to bring out its meaning, as in this case : Other nations change, but not the Chinese an assertion of superiority.) Another form of Exponible is the Exceptive, as Klad- deradatsch is published daily, except on week-days, equivalent to Kladderadatsch is published on Sunday ; it is not published any other day. Still another Exponible is the Exclusive, as Only men use fire, equivalent to Men are users of fire ; ~No other animals are. Exceptive and exclusive sentences are, however, equivalent forms ; for we may say, Kladderadatsch is published only on Sunday ; and No animals use fire, except men. There are other compound sentences that are not exponible, since, though they contain two or more verbal clauses, the construction shows that these are inseparable. Thus, If cats are scarce, mice are plentiful, contains two verbal clauses ; but if cats are scarce is conditional, not indicative; and mice are plentiful is subject to the condition that cats are scarce. Hence the whole sentence is called a Conditional Proposition. For the various forms of Conditional Propositions see chap. v. 4. But, in fact, to find the logical force of recognised grammatical forms is the least of a logician's difficulties in bringing the discourses of men to a plain issue. Metaphors, epigrams, innuendos and other figures of speech present far ' i8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE greater obstacles to a lucid reduction whether for approval or refutation. No rules can be given for finding everybody's meaning. The poets have their own way of expressing them- selves ; sophists, too, have their own way. And the point often lies in what is unexpressed. Thus, " barbarous nations make, the civilised write history," means that civilised nations do not make history, which none is so brazen as openly to assert. Or again, " Alcibiades is dead, but X is still with us." The whole meaning of this * Exponible ' is that X would be the lesser loss to society. Even an epithet or a suffix may imply a propo- sition : This personage may mean X is a pretentious nobody. How shall we consider such illusive predications except by cultivating our literary perceptions? The obtuse man who misses the meaning of an epigram may escape some pain ; but * the higher pain ' is good for him. At any rate, to disentangle the compound propositions, and to expand the abbreviations of literature and conversation, is a useful logical exercise. And if it seem a laborious task thus to reduce^to its logical elements a long argument in a speech or treatise, it should be observed that, as a rule, in a long discourse only a few sentences are of principal importance to the reasoning, the rest being explana- tory or illustrative digression, and that a close scrutiny of these cardinal sentences will frequently dispense us from giving much attention to the rest. 4. But now, returning to the definition of a Proposition given in 2, that it is 'a sentence in which one term is predicated of another,' we must consider what is the import of such predication. For the definition, as it stands, seems to be purely Nominalist. Is a proposition nothing more than a certain synthesis of words ; or, is it meant to correspond with something further, a synthesis of ideas, or a relation of facts ? Conceptualist logicians, who speak of judgments instead of propositions, of course define the judgment in their own language. According to Hamilton, it is " a recognition of the relation of congruence or confliction in which two concepts GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS stand to each other." To lighten the sentence, I have omitted one or two qualifications (Hamilton's Lectures on Logic, xiii.). "Thus," he goes on, "if we compare the thoughts water, iron, and rusting, we find them congruent, and connect them into a single thought, thus : water rusts iron in that case we form a judgment." When a judgment is expressed in words, he says, it is called a proposition. There seems at first to be a merely verbal difference upon this point between the three Schools (chap i. 6); for Whately begins by describing a proposition as " a judgment expressed in words," though he prefers to define it as " a sentence indicative." Mill, again, defines it as " a portion of discourse in which a predicate is affirmed or denied of a subject." (Logic, Book I., chap. iv. i.) But further differences come to light when Whately observes that his definition "relates entirely to the words," and when Mill goes on to inquire into the import of propositions. (Book I., chap, v.) Mill finds three classes of propositions : (a) those in which one proper name is predicated of another; and of these Hobbes's Nominalist definition is adequate, namely, that a proposition asserts or denies that the predicate is a name for the same thing as the subject, as Tully is Cicero. (b) Propositions in which the predicate means a part (or the whole) of what the subject means, as Horses are animals, Man is a rational animal. These are Verbal Propositions (see below : chap. v. 6), and their import consists in affirming or denying a coincidence between the meanings of names, as The meaning of ' animal' is part of the meaning of l horse*. But (c) there are also Real Propositions, whose predicates do not mean the same as their subjects, and whose import consists in affirming or denying one of five different kinds of matter of fact: (i) That the subject exists, or does not; as if we say The bison exists, The great auk is extinct. (2) Co-existence, as Man is mortal; that is, the being subject to 20 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE death coinheres with the qualities on account of which we call certain objects men. (3) Succession, as The military precedes the industrial regime. (4) Causation (a particular kind of Succession), as Water rusts iron. (5) Resemblance, as The colour of this geranium is like that of a soldier's coat, or A = B. On comparing this list of real predications with the list of logical relations given above (chap. i. 5^), it will be seen that the two differ only in this, that I have there omitted simple Existence. In fact nothing simply exists, unrelated either in Nature or in knowledge. Still, such a proposition as The bison exists may, no doubt, be used in Logic (subject to interpretation) for the sake of custom or for the sake of brevity. Into the question of the Import of Propositions it would be unsuitable to enter further. This controversy really turns upon a difference of opinion as to the scope of Logic and the foundations of knowledge. Mill was dissatisfied with the " congruity " of concepts as the basis of a judgment. Clearly, mere congruity does not justify belief. In the pro- position Water rusts iron, the concepts water, rust and iron may be congruous, but does any one assert their con- nection on that ground ? In the proposition Murderers are haunted by the ghosts of their victims, the concepts victim, murderer, ghost have a high degree of congruity; yet, un- fortunately, I cannot believe it : there seems to be no such cheap defence of innocence. Now, Mill held that Logic is concerned with the grounds of belief, and that the scope of Logic includes Induction as well as Deduction; whereas, according to Hamilton, Induction is only Modified Logic, a mere appendix to the theory of the "forms of thought as thought." Indeed, Mill endeavoured in his Logic to probe the grounds of belief deeper than the science should pretend to penetrate, and introduced a good deal of Metaphysics certainly, either too much or not enough. But, at any rate, his great point was that belief, and therefore (for the most part) the Real Proposition, is concerned not merely wit* GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS 21 the relations of words, or even of ideas (though, of course, propositions are judgments expressed in words), but with matters of fact; that is, both propositions and judgments point to something further, to the relations of things which we can examine, not merely by thinking about them (com- paring them in thought), but by observing them with the united powers of thought and perception. This is what convinces us that water rusts iron : and the difficulty of doing this is what prevents our feeling sure that murderers are haunted by the ghosts of their victims. Hence, although Mill's definition of a proposition, given above, is adequate for propositions in general ; yet that kind of proposition (the Real) with regard to which Logic (in Mill's view) inves- tigates the conditions of proof, may be more explicitly and pertinently defined as * a predication concerning the relation of matters of fact.' 5. This leads to a very important distinction to which we shall often have to refer in subsequent pages namely, the distinction between the Form and the Matter of a pro- position or of an argument. The distinction between Form and Matter, as it is ordinarily employed, is easily understood. An apple growing in the orchard and a waxen apple on the table may have the same shape, but consist of different materials ; two real apples may have the same shape, but contain distinct ounces of apple-stuff, so that after one is eaten the other remains to be eaten. Similarly, tables may have the same shape, though one be made of marble, another of oak, another of iron. The form is common to several things, the matter is peculiar to each. Metaphysicians have, by analogy, carried the distinction further : apples, they say, may have not only the same outward shape, but the same inward constitution, which, therefore, may be called the Form of apple-stuff namely, a certain pulpiness, juiciness, sweetness, etc. ; qualities common to all dessert apples : yet their Matter is different, one being here, another there differing in place or time, if in nothing else. 22 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE To apply this distinction to the things of Logic : it is easy to see how two propositions may have the same Form but different Matter : not using ' Form ' in the sense of ' shape,' but for that which is common to many things, in contrast with that which is peculiar to each. Thus, All male lions have tufted tails and All water is liquid at 50 Fahrenheit, are two propositions that have the same form, though their matter i^ entirely different. They both predicate something of the whole of their subjects, though their subjects are different, and so are the things predicated of them. Again, All male lions have tufted tails and All male lions have manes, are two propositions having the same form and in their subjects the same matter, but different matter in their predicates. If, however, we take two such propositions as these : All male lions have manes and Some male lions have manes, here the matter is the same in both, but the form is different in the first, predication is made concerning every male lion ; in the second of only some male lions; the first is universal, the second is particular. Or, again, if we take Some tigers are man-eaters and Some tigers are not man-eaters, here too the matter is the same, but the form is different ; for the first proposition is affirma- tive, whilst the second is negative. 6. Now, according to Hamilton and Whately, pure Logic has to do only with the Form of propositions and arguments. As to their Matter, whether they are really true in fact, that is a question, they said, not for Logic, but for experience, or for the special sciences. But Mill desired so to extend logical method as to test the material truth of propositions : he thought that he could expound a method by which experience itself and the conclusions of the special sciences may be examined. To this method, however, some critics persistently object, that the claim to determine Material Truth takes for granted that the order of Nature will remain unchanged, that (for ex- ample) water not only at present is a liquid at 50 Fahrenheit, but will always be so ; whereas (although we have no reason to expect such a thing) the order of Nature may alter it is GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS 23 least supposable and in that event water may freeze at such a temperature. On the other hand, they urge that a certain kind of Formal Truth may be placed beyond even the suppo- sition of possible error. An apple, for example, is either green all over, or it is not : if we affirm the one alternative we must deny the other; this is necessary to all intelligible use of language and to all clearness of thought. But upon the ques- tion of material truth, as to the apple being really green all over, a certain dubiousness is defensible and not undignified. For what, after all, is meant by an apple ' green all over ' ? What is 'green' ? To whom is it green ? Not to the colour-blind. In what circumstances ? Not in the dark. Any matter of fact must depend on observation, either directly, or by inference as when some- thing is asserted about atoms or ether. But observation and material inference are subject to the limitations of our faculties ; and however we may aid observation by microscopes and micrometers, it is still observation; and however we may correct our observations by repetition, comparison and refined mathematical methods of making allowances, the correction of error is only an approximation to accuracy. Outside of Formal Reasoning, suspense of judgment is your only attitude. It is not to be supposed that such reflections did not occur to Mill, though he may have thought them strained and negligible. Here, however, it seems to me right to allow them some weight ; and accordingly prominence will be given to the character of Logic as a Formal Science. It will also be shown that Induction may be included in Logic and treated formally. But it will be assumed that logical forms are only valuable so far as they represent the actual relations of natural phenomena. 7. Symbols are often used in Logic instead of concrete terms, not only in Symbolic Logic where the science is treated algebraically (as by Dr. Venn in his Symbolic Logic\ but in ordinary manuals ; so that it may be well to explain the use of them before going further. It is a common and convenient practice to illustrate logical doctrines by examples : to show what is meant by a Propositioo 24 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE we may give salt is soluble, or water rusts iron : the copulative exponible is exemplified by salt is savoury and wholesome ; and so on. But this procedure has some disadvantages : it is often cumbrous ; and it may distract the reader's attention from the point to be explained by exciting his interest in the special fact of the illustration. Clearly, too, if Logic is only formal, no particular matter of fact can adequately illustrate any of its doctrines. Accordingly, writers on Logic employ letters of the alphabet instead of concrete terms, (say) X instead of salt or instead of iron, and (say) Y instead of soluble or instead of rusted by water ; and then a proposition may be represented by X is Y. It is still more usual to represent a proposition by 5 is (or is not) P, S being the initial of Subject and P of Predicate ; though this has the drawback that if we argue S is P, therefore P is S, the symbols in the latter proposition no longer have the same significance, since the former subject is now the predicate. Again, negative terms frequently occur in Logic, such as not- water, or not-iron, and then if water or iron be expressed by X, the corresponding negative may be expressed by x ; or, generally, if a capital letter stand for a positive term, the corresponding small letter represents the negative. And as terms are often compounded, it may be convenient to express them by a combination of letters : instead of illustrating such a case by boiling water or water that is boiling^ we may write XY ; or since positive and negative terms may be compounded, instead of illustrating this by water that is not boiling, we may write Xy. The convenience of this is obvious ; but it is more than con- venient ; for, if one of the chief uses of Logic is to dicipline the power of abstract thought, this can be done far more effectually by symbolic than by concrete examples ; and if such discipline were the only use of Logic it might be best to discard concrete illustrations altogether, at least In advanced text-books, though no doubt the practice would be too severe for elementary manuals. But on the other hand, to teach GENERAL ANALYSIS OF PROPOSITIONS 25 the practical applicability of Logic to the arguments and proofs of actual life, or even of the concrete sciences, merely symbolic illustration may be not only useless but even mis- leading. When we speak of politics, or poetry, or species, or the weather, the terms that must be used can rarely have the distinctness and isolation of X and Y ; so that the perfunctory use of symbolic illustration makes argument and proof appear to be much simpler and easier matters than they really are. Indeed, in this connection, it is impossible to illustrate Logic sufficiently : the reader who is in earnest about the cogency of arguments and the limitation of proofs, and is scrupulous as to the degrees of assent that they require, must constantly look for illustrations of the science in his own experience and rely at last upon his own sagacity. CHAPTER III OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION i. In treating of Deductive Logic it is usual to recognise three divisions of the subject: first, the doctrine of Terms, words, or other signs used as subjects or predicates ; secondly, the doctrine of Propositions, in which terms are combined ; and, thirdly, the doctrine of the Syllogism in which proposi- tions are combined as the grounds of a conclusion. The terms employed are either letters of the alphabet, or the words of common language, or the technicalities of science ; and since the words of 'common language are most in use, it is necessary to give some account of common language as sub- serving the purposes of Logic. It has been urged 'that we cannot think or reason at all without words, or some substitute for them, such as the signs of algebra; and although this opinion is too sweeping, since minds greatly differ, and some think in definite and comprehensive picturiags, and we all draw many simple inferences by means of mental imagery, and even animals do so when judging of prey, or enemies, or friends by their scent or by the noises they make; yet the more elaborate inferences, and especially the grouping and concate- nation of inferences, which we call reasoning, seem to be impossible without language or some equivalent system of signs. It is not merely that we need language to express our reasonings and communicate them to others : in solitary thought we depend on words 'talk to ourselves,' in fact; though the words or sentences that then pass through our minds are not always fully formed or articulated. In Logic, OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION *; moreover, we have carefully to examine the grounds (at least the formal and proximate grounds) of our conclusions ; and plainly this cannot be done unless the conclusions in question are explicitly stated and recorded. Conceptualists say that Logic deals not with the process of thinking (which belongs t.o Psychology) but with its results ; not with conceiving but with concepts ; not with judging but with judgments. Is the concept self-consistent or adequate, Logic asks-f 'f's the judgment capable of proof ? Now, it is only by fording ouj thoughts in language that it becomes possible to 'distinguish between the process and the result of thought. As a mere train of mental imagery, the act and the product of thinking would be identical and equally evanescent. But by carrying on the:proqess in language and"remembering or other- wise recording it, we obtain a result which may be examined according to the principles of Logic. 2. As Logic, then, must give some account of language, it seems desirable to explain how its treatment of language differs from that of Grammar and from that of Rhetoric. Grammar is the study of the words of some language, their classification and derivation, and of the rules of combining them -according to the usage at any time recognised and followed by those who are considered good authors. Composi- tion may be faultless in its grammar, though dull and absurd. Rhetoric is the study of language with a view to obtaining some special eSect in the communication of ideas or feelings, such* as picturesqueness in description, vivacity in narration, lucidity in exposition, vehjsmence in persuasion, or literary charm. Some of these ends are often gained in spite of faulty syntax or faulty logic ; but since the few whom bad grammar saddens or incoherent arguments divert are not carried away as they else might be by an unsophisticated orator, Grammar and Logic are 'pecessary to the perfection of Rhetoric. Not that Rhetoric is in bondage to those other sciences ; for foreign idioms and such figures as the ellipsis, the anacoluthon, the oxymoron, the hyperbole, and violent inversions have their 2 8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE places in the magnificent style ; but authors unacquainted with Grammar and Logic are not likely to place such figures well and wisely. Indeed, common idioms, though both grammati- cally and rhetorically justifiable, both correct and effective, often seem illogical. ' To fall asleep,' for example, is a perfect English phrase ; yet if we examine severally the words it consists of, it may seem strange that their combination should mean anything at all. But Logic only studies language so far as necessary in order to state, understand, and check the evidence and reasonings that are usually embodied in language. And as long as meanings are clear, good Logic is compatible with false con- cords and inelegance of style. 3. Terms are either Simple or Composite : that is to say, they may consist either of a single word, as 'Chaucer,' 1 civilisation ' ; or of more than one, as ' the father of English poetry,' or * modern civilised nations.' Logicians classify words according to their uses in forming propositions ; or, rather* they classify the uses of words as terms, not the words them- selves ; for the same word may fall into different classes of terms according to the way in which it is used. (Cf. Mr. Alfred Sidgwick's Distinction and the Criticism of Beliefs^ chap, xiv.) Thus words are classified as Categorematic or Syncategore- matic. A word is Categorematic if used singly as a term without the support of other words: it is Syncategorematic when joined with other words in order to constitute the subject or predicate of a proposition. If we say Venus is a planet whose orbit is inside the Earth's^ the subject, ' Venus,' is a word used categorematically as a simple term ; the predicate is a composite term whose constituent words (whether sub- stantive, relative, verb, or preposition) are used syncategorema- tically. Prepositions, conjunctions, articles, adverbs, relative pro- nouns, in their ordinary use, can only enter into terms along with other words having a substantive, adjectival or participial OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION 29 force ; but when they are themselves the things spoken of and are used substantively (suppositio materialis), they are categore- matic. In the proposition, Of was used more indefinitely three hundred years ago than it is now, 'of is categorematic. On the other hand, all substantives may be used categorematically ; and the same self-sufficiency is usually recognised in adjectives and participles. Some, however, hold that the categorematic use of adjectives and participles is due to an ellipsis which the logician should fill up ; that instead of Gold is heavy, he should say Gold is a heavy metal ; instead of The sun is shining, The sun is a body shining. But in these cases the words ' metal ' and 'body' are 'unmistakable tautology, since 'metal' is implied in gold and ' body ' in sun. But, as we have seen, any of these kinds of words, substantive, adjective, or'participle, may occur syncategorematically in connection with others to form a composite term. 4. Most terms (the exceptions and doubtful cases will be discussed hereafter) have two functions, a denotative and a connotative. A term's denotative function is, to be the name or sign of something or some multitude of things, which are said to be called or denoted by the term. Its connotative function is, to suggest certain qualities and characteristics of the things denoted, so that it cannot be used literally as the name of any other things ; which qualities and characteristics are said to be implied or connoted by the term. Thus * sheep ' is the name of certain animals, and its meaning pre- vents its being used of any others. That which a term directly indicates, then, is its Denotation ; that sense or customary use of it which limits the Denotation is its Connotation (ch. iv.). Hamilton and others use * Extension ' in the sense of Denota- tion, and ' Intension ' or * Comprehension ' in the sense of Connotation. Now, terms may be classified, first, according to what they stand for or denote ; that is, according to their ^Denotation. In this respect, the use of a term is said to be either Concrete or Abstract. A term is Concrete when it denotes a ' thing ' ; that is, any 30 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE person, object, fact, event, feeling or imagination, considered as capable of having (or consisting of) qualities and a deter- minate existence. Thus 'cricket ball' denotes any object having a certain size, weight, shape, colour, etc. (which are its qualities), and being at any given time in some place and related to other objects in the bowler's hands, on the grass, in a shop window. Any ' feeling of warmth ' has a certain intensity, is pleasurable or painful, occurs at a certain time, and affects some part or the whole of some animal. An imagination, indeed (say, of a fairy), cannot be said in the same sense to have locality ; but it depends on the thinking of some man who has locality, and is definitely related to his other thoughts and feelings. A term is Abstract, on the other hand, when it denotes a quality (or qualities), considered by itself and without deter- minate existence in time, place, or relation to other things. 1 Size,' ' shape,' ' weight,' ' colour,' * intensity,' ' pleasurableness,' are terms used to denote such qualities, and are then abstract in their denotation. * Weight,' you observe, is not something with a determinate existence at a given time; it exists not merely in some particular place, but wherever there is a heavy thing ; and, as to relation, at the same moment it combines in iron with hardness and in mercury with liquidity. In fact, a quality is a point of agreement in a multitude of different things ; as all heavy things agree in weight, all round things in roundness, all red things in redness ; and an abstract term denotes such a point (or points) of agreement among the things denoted by concrete terms. Thus the use of abstract terms results from the analysis of concrete things into their qualities ; and conversely a concrete term may be viewed as denoting a synthesis of qualities in individual things. When several things agree in more than one quality, there may be an abstract term denoting the union of qualities in which they agree, but not their peculiarities ; as ' human nature ' denotes the common qualities of men, ' civilisation ' the common conditions of civilised peoples. OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION 31 Every general name, if used as a concrete term, has, or may have, a corresponding abstract term. Sometimes the concrete term is modified to form the abstract, as ' greedy greediness/ * vain vanity ' ; sometimes a word is adapted from another language, as ' man humanity ' ; sometimes a composite term is used, as * mercury the nature of mercury,' etc. The same concrete may have several abstract correlatives, as * man manhood, humanity, human nature ' ; * heavy weight, gravity, ponderosity ' ; but in such cases the abstract terms are not used quite synonymously ; that is, they imply different ways of considering the concrete. Whether a word is used as a concrete or abstract term is in most instances plain from the word itself, the use of most words being pretty regular one way or the other ; but some- times we must judge by the context. 'Weight' may be used in the abstract for ' gravity,' or in the concrete for a measure ; but in the latter sense it is syncategorematic (in the singular), needing at least the article * a (or the) weight.' * Government ' may mean c supreme political authority,' and is then abstract ; or, the set of men who happen to be ministers, and is then concrete ; but in this case, too, the article is usually prefixed. ' The life ' of any man may mean his vitality (abstract), as in " Thus following life in creatures we dissect " ; or, the series of events through which he passes (concrete), as in ' the life of Nelson as narrated by Southey.' It has been made a question whether the denotation of an abstract term may itself be the subject of qualities. Apparently ' weight ' may be greater or less, * government ' good or bad, ' vitality ' intense or dull. But if every subject is modified by a quality, a quality is also modified by making it the subject of another ; and, if so, it seems then to become a new quality. The compound terms * great weight,' * bad government,' * dull vitality,' have not the same denotation as the simple terms ' weight,' * government,' * vitality ' : they imply, and may be said to connote, more special concrete experience, such as the effort felt in lifting a trunk, disgust at the conduct of officials, 32 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE sluggish movements of an animal when irritated. It is to such concrete terms that we have always to refer in order fully to realise the meaning of abstract terms, and therefore, of course, to understand any qualification of them. 5. Concrete terms may be subdivided according to the number of things they denote and the way in which they denote them. A term may denote one thing or many : if one, it is called Singular; if many, it may do so distributively, and then it is General; or, as taken all together, and then it is Collective : one, then ; any one of many ; many in one. Among Singular Terms, each denoting a single thing, the most obvious are Proper Names, such as Gibraltar or George Washington, which are merely marks of individual things or persons, and often form no part of the common language of a country. They are thus distinguished from other Singular Terms, which consist of common words so combined as to restrict their denotation to some individual, such as, 'the strongest man on earth.' Proper Terms are often said to be arbitrary signs, because their use does not depend upon any reason that may be given for them. Gibraltar had a meaning among the Moors when originally conferred; but no one now knows what it was, unless he happens to have looked it up ; yet the name serves its purpose as well as if it were "Rooke's Nest." Every Newton or Newport year by year grows old, but to alter the name would cause only confusion. If such names were given by mere caprice it would make no difference ; and they could not be more cumbrous, ugly, or absurd than many of those that are given * for reasons.' The remaining kinds of Singular Terms, drawn from the common resources of the language, derive their denotative force from their usual meanings. Thus the pronouns 'he,' 'she/ 'it,' are singular terms, whose present denotation is determined by the occasion and context of discourse : so with demonstrative phrases ' this man,' ' that horse.' Descriptive names may be OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION 33 more complex, as 'the wisest man of Gotham,' which is limited to some individual by the superlative suffix; or 'the German Emperor,' which is limited by the definite article the general term * German Emperor' being thereby restricted either to the reigning monarch or lo the one we happen to be dis- cussing. Instead of the definite, the indefinite article may be used to make general terms singular, as ' a German Emperor was crowned at Versailles ' (individua vagd). Abstract Terms are ostensively singular : ' whiteness ' (e.g.) is one quality. But their full meaning is general : ' whiteness ' stands for all white things, so far as white. Abstract terms, in fact, are only formally singular. General Terms are words, or combinations of words, used to denote any one of many things that resemble one another in certain respects. * George III.' is a Singular Term denoting one man ; but ' King ' is a General Term denoting him and all other men of the same rank ; whilst the compound 'crowned head ' is still more general, denoting kings and also emperors. It is the nature of a general term, then, to be used in the same sense of whatever it denotes ; and its most characteristic form is the Class-name, whether of objects, such as 'king,' 'sheep,' ' ghost ' ; or of events, such as ' accession,' ' purchase,' ' mani- festation.' Things and events are known by their qualities and relations ; and every such aspect, being a point of re semblance to some other things, becomes a ground of general isation, and therefore a ground for the need and use of general terms. Hence general terms are far the most important sort of terms in Logic, since in them general propositions are ex- pressed ; and, moreover (with rare exceptions), all predicates are general. For, besides these typical class-names, attributive words are general terms, such as ' royal,' ' ruling,' ' woolly,' * bleating,' ' impalpable,' ' vanishing.' Infinitives may also be used as general terms, as " To err is human " ; but are best translated into equivalent substantive forms, as Foolish actions are characteristic of mankind. Abstract terms, too, are (as I observed) equivalent to general terms : c 34 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE * folly ' is abstract for ' foolish actions.' * Honesty is the best policy* means people who are honest may hope to find their account in being so ; that is, in the effects of their honest actions, provided they are wise in other ways, and no misfortunes attend them. The abstract form is often much the more succinct and forcible, but for logical treatment it needs to be interpreted in the general form. By autonomasia proper names may become general terms, as if we say c A Johnson ' would not hat? written such a book i.e., any man of his genius for elaborate elo- quence. A Collective Term denotes a multitude of similar things, not distributively, but considered as forming one whole, as ' regi- ment,' * flock,' 'nation.' If in a multitude of things there is no resemblance, except the fact of being considered as parts of one whole, as ' the world,' or * the town of Nottingham ' (meaning its streets and houses, open spaces, people, and civic organisation), the term denoting them as a whole is Singular ; but ' the world ' or ' town of Nottingham,' meaning the inhabitants only, is Collective. In their strictly collective use, all such expressions are equivalent to singular terms; but many of them may also be used as general terms, as when we speak of c so many regiments of the line,' or discuss the ' plurality of worlds'; and in this general use they denote any of a multitude of things of the same kind regiments, or habitable worlds. Names of substances, such as 'gold,' 'air,' 'water,' may be employed as singular, collective, or general terms ; though, perhaps, as singular terms only figuratively, as when we say Gold is king. If we say with Thales, ' Water is the source of all things* ' water ' seems to be used collectively. But sub- stantive names are frequently used as general terms. For ex- ample, Gold is heavy means ' in comparison with other things/ such as water. And, plainly, it does not mean that the aggregate of gold is heavier than the aggregate of water, but OF TERMS AND THEIR DENOTATION 35 only that its specific gravity is greater ; that is, bulk for bulk, any piece of gold is heavier than water. Finally, any class-name may be used collectively if we wish to assert something of the things denoted by it, not distri- butively but altogether, as that Sheep are more numerous than CHAPTER IV THE CONNOTATION OF TEfiMS i. Terms are next to be classified according to their Connotation that is, according to what they imply as characteristic of the things denoted. We have seen that general names are used to denote many things in the same sense, because the things denoted resemble one another in certain ways : it is this resemblance in certain points that leads us to class the things together and call them by the same name ; and therefore the points of resemblance constitute the sense or meaning of the name, or its Connotation, and limit its applicability to such things as have these characteristic qualities. * Sheep/ fa' example, is used in the same sense, to denote any of a multitude of animals that resemble one another : their size, shape, woolly coats, cloven hoofs, innocent ways and edibility are well known. When we apply to anything the term * sheep/ we imply that it has these qualities: ' sheep/ denoting the animal, connotes its possessing these characteristics ; and, of course, it cannot, without a figure of speech or a blunder, be used to denote anything that does not possess all these qualities. It is by a figure of speech that the term * sheep ' is applied to some men ; and to apply it to goats would be a blunder. Most people are very imperfectly aware of the connotation of the words they use, and are guided in using them merely by the custom of the language. A man who employs a word quite correctly may be sadly posed by a request to explain or define it. Moreover, so far as we are aware of the connotation THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 37 of terms, the number and the kind of attributes we think of, in any given case, vary with the depth of our interest, and with the nature of our interest in the things denoted. ' Sheep ' has one meaning to a touring townsman, a much fuller one to a farmer, and yet a different one to a zoologist. But this does not prevent them agreeing in the use of the word, as long as the qualities they severally include in its meaning are not incompatible. All general names, and therefore not only class-names, like * sheep,' but all attributives, have some connotation. 'Woolly' denotes anything that bears wool, and connotes the fact of bearing wool ; ' innocent ' denotes anything that habitually does no harm (or has not been guilty of a particular offence), and connotes a harmless character (or freedom from particular guilt); * edible' denotes whatever can be eaten with good results, and connotes its suitability for mastication, deglutition, digestion, and assimilation. 2. But whether all terms must connote as well as denote something, has been much debated. Proper names, according to what seems the better opinion, are, in their ordinary use, not connotative. To say that they have no meaning may seem violent : if any one is called Alphonso Schultze (which name I invent, hoping that no man bears it), this name, no doubt, means a great deal to his friends and neighbours, reminding them of his stature and physiognomy, his air and gait, his wit and wisdom, some queer stories, and an indefinite number of other things. But all this significance is local or accidental ; it only exists for those who know the individual or have heard him described: whereas a general name gives information about any thing or person it denotes to everybody who under- stands the language, without any particular knowledge of the individual. We must distinguish, in fact, between the peculiar associa- tions of the proper name and the commonly recognised meaning of the general name. This is why proper names are not in the dictionary. Such a name as London, to be sure, or Napoleon 38 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Buonaparte, has a significance not merely local; still, it is accidental. c London ' suggests very different things to a Londoner, to his country cousin, and to a merchant in Buenos Ayres. * Napoleon Buonaparte* excites different ideas in France and in Germany, ; and had another meaning for our grandfathers than it has for us. Moreover, these names are borne by other places and persons than those that have ren- dered them famous. There are Londons in various latitudes, and, no doubt, many Napoleon Buonapartes in Louisiana; and each name has in its several denotations an altogether different suggestiveness. For its suggestiveness is in each application determined by the peculiarities of the place or person denoted, and had any other name been given it would have gathered much the same associations. If the French hero had gone by some flat and vulgar appellation, it would have impoverished the romance of history ; but the great bulk of its significance for us would now be the same. However, the scientific grounds of the doctrine that proper names are non-connotative, are these : The peculiarities that distinguish an individual person or thing are admitted to be infinite, and anything less than a complete enumeration of these peculiarities may fail to distinguish and identify the individual. For, short of a complete enumeration of them, the description may be satisfied by two or more individuals ; and in that case the term denoting them, if limited by such a description, is not a proper but a general name, since it is applicable to two or more in the same sense. The existence of other individuals to whom it might apply may be highly improbable; but, if it be logically possible, that is enough. On the other hand, the enumeration of infinite peculiarities is certainly impossible. Therefore proper names have no assignable connotation. The only escape from this reasoning lies in falling back upon time and place, the principles of individuation, as constituting the connotation of proper names. Two things cannot be at the same time in the same place : hence * the man who was at a certain spot on the bridge of THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 39 Lodi at a certain instant in a certain year ' suffices to identify Napoleon Buonaparte for that instant. Supposing no one else to have borne the name, then, is this its connotation ? No one, I think, has ever said so. And, at any rate, time and place are only extrinsic determinations (suitable indeed to events like the battle of Lodi, or to places themselves like London); whereas the connotation of a general term, like * sheep,' consists of intrinsic qualities. Hence, then, the scholastic doctrine ' that individuals have no essence ' (see chap. xxii. 9), and Hamilton's dictum * that every concept is inadequate to the individual/ are justified. General names, when used as proper names, lose their connotation, as Euxine or Newfoundland. Singular terms, other than Proper, have connotation ; either in themselves, like the singular pronouns ' he/ * she/ * it/ which are general in their applicability, though singular in applica- tion ; or, derivatively, from the general names that combine to form them, as in * the first Emperor of the French ' or the ' Capital of the British Empire.' 3. Whether Abstract Terms have any connotation is another disputed question. We have seen that they denote a quality or qualities of something, and that is precisely what general terms connote : ' honesty ' denotes a quality of some men ; * honest ' connotes the same quality, whilst denoting the men who have it. The denotation of abstract terms thus seems to exhaust their force or meaning. It has been proposed, however, to regard them as connoting the qualities they directly stand for, and not denoting anything ; but surely this is too violent. To denote something is the same thing as to be the name of some- thing (whether real or unreal), which every term must be. It is a better proposal to regard their denotation and connota- tion as coinciding; though open to the objection that 'connote' means ' to mark along with ' something else, and this plan leaves nothing else. Mill thought that abstract terms are connotative when, besides denoting a quality, they suggest a 40 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE quality of that quality (as ' fault ' implies * hurtfulness ') ; but against this it may be urged that one quality cannot bear another, since every qualification of a quality constitutes a distinct quality in the total (' milk-whiteness ' is distinct from ' whiteness,' cf. chap. iii. 4). After all, if it is the most con- sistent plan, why not say that abstract, like proper, terms have no connotation ? But if abstract terms must be made to connote something, should it not be those things, indefinitely suggested, to which the qualities belong ? Thus ' whiteness ' may be supposed to connote either snow or vapour, or any white thing, apart from one or other of which the quality has no existence; whose existence therefore it implies. By this course the denotation and connotation of abstract and of general names would be exactly reversed. Just as the denotation of a general name is limited by the qualities connoted, so the uicnfllaltoTl of an abstract name is determined by the things in which that denotation is realised. But the whole difficulty may be avoided by making it a rule to translate, for logical purposes, all abstract into the corresponding general terms. 4. If we ask how the connotation of a term is to be known, here again the answer depends upon the way it is used. If used scientifically, its connotation is determined by, and is the same as, its definition ; and the definition is determined by examining the things to be denoted, as we shall see in chap. xxii. If the same word is used as a term in different sciences, as ' property ' in Law and in Logic, it will be dif- ferently defined by them, and will have, in each use, a corre- spondingly different connotation. But terms used in popular discourse should, as far as possible, have their connotations determined by classical usage, *.*., by the sense in which they are used by writers and speakers who are acknowledged masters of the language, such as Dryden and Burke. In this case the classical connotation determines the definition ; so that to define terms thus used is nothing else than to analyse their accepted meanings. THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 41 It must not, however, be supposed that in popular use the connotation of any word is invariable. Logicians have at- tempted to classify terms into Univocal (having only one meaning) and ^Equivocal (or ambiguous) ; and no doubt some words (like ' civil,' ' natural,' ' proud,' ' liberal,' ' humorous ') are more manifestly liable to ambiguous use than some others. But in truth all general terms are popularly and classically used in different senses. Figurative or tropical language chiefly consists in the transfer of words to new senses, as by metaphor or metonymy. In the course of years, too, words change their meanings ; and before the time of Dryden our whole vocabulary was much more fluid and adaptable than it has since become. Such authors as Bacon, Milton, and Sir Thomas Browne often used words derived from the Latin in some sense they originally had in Latin, though in English they had acquired another meaning. Spenser and Shakespeare, besides this practice, sometimes use words in a way that can only be justified by their choosing to have it so; whilst their contemporaries, Beaumont and Fletcher, write the perfect modern language, as Dryden observed. Lapse of time is not the chief cause of variation in the sense of words. The matters which terms are used to denote are often so com- plicated or so refined in the assemblage, interfusion, or gradation of their qualities, that terms do not exist in sufficient abundance and discriminativeness to denote the things, and, at the same time, convey by connotation a determinate sense of their agree- ments and differences. In discussing politics, religion, ethics, aesthetics, this imperfection of language is continually felt ; and the only escape from it, short of coining new words (which, forsooth, is inelegant) is to use such words as we have, now in one sense, now in another somewhat different, and to trust to the context, or to the resources of the literary art, to convey the true meaning, or perhaps to insinuate a deceptive one. Against this evil the having been born since Dryden is no protection. It behoves us, then, to remember that terms are not classifiable into Univocal and ^Equivocal, but that all terms are susceptible 42 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE of being used sequivocally, and that honesty and lucidity re- quire us to try, as well as we can, to uie each term univocally in the same context. The context of any proposition always proceeds upon some assumption or understanding as to the scope of the discussion, which controls the interpretation of every statement and of every word. This was called by De Morgan the " universe of discourse " : an older name for it, revived by Dr. Venn, and surely a better one, is suppositio. If now we are talking of children, and 'play' is mentioned, the suppositio limits the suggestiveness of the word in one way ; whilst if Monaco is the subject of conversation, the same word ' play/ under the influence of a different suppositio^ excites altogether different ideas. Hence to ignore the suppositio is a great source of fallacies of equivocation. 'Man' is generally defined as a kind of animal ; but ' animal ' is often used as opposed to and excluding man. 'Liberal' has one meaning under the suppositio of politics, another with regard to culture, and still another as to the disposal of one's private means. Clearly, therefore, the connotation of general terms is relative to .the suppositio^ or " universe of discourse." 5. Relative and Absolute Terms. Some words go in couples or groups : like ' up-down,' ' former-latter,' ' father- mother-children,' ' hunter-prey,' ' cause-effect,' etc. These are called Relative Terms, and their nature, explained by Mill, is that the connotations of the members of such a pair or group are derived from the same set of facts (the fundamentum re- latwnis). There cannot be an ' up' without a ' down,' a 'father' without a ' mother ' and ' child ' ; there cannot be a ' hunter ' without something hunted, nor 'prey without a pursuer. What makes a man a ' hunter ' is his activities in pursuit ; and what turns a chamois into 'prey' is its interest in these activities. The meaning of both terms, therefore, is derived from the same set of facts ; neither term can be explained without explaining the other, and neither can with propriety be THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 43 used without reference to the other, or to some equivalent, as ' game ' for ' prey.' In contrast with such Relative Terms, others have been called Absolute or Non-relative. Whilst 'hunter' and 'prey* are relative, { man ' and ' chamois ' have been considered abso- lute, as we may use them without thinking of any special connection between their meanings. However, if we believe ui the unity of Nature and in the relativity of knowledge (that is, that all knowledge depends upon comparison, or a perception of the resemblances and differences of things), it follows that nothing can be completely understood except through its agreements or contrasts with everything else, and that all terms derive their connotation from the same set of facts, namely, from general experience. Thus both man and chamois are animals ; this fact is an important part of the meaning of both terms, and to that extent they are relative terms. ' Five yards ' and * five minutes ' are very different notions, yet they are profoundly related ; for their very difference helps to make both notions distinct ; and their intimate connection is shown in this, that five yards are traversed in a certain time, and that five minutes are measured by the motion of an index over some fraction of a yard upon the dial. The distinction, then, between relative and non-relative terms must rest, not upon a fundamental difference between them (since, in fact, all words are relative), but upon the way in which words are used. We have seen that some words, such as * up-down,' * cause-effect,' can only be used relatively ; and these might, for distinction, be called Correlatives. But other words, whose meanings are only partially interdependent, may often be used without attending to their relativity, and may then be considered as Absolute. We cannot say ' the hunter returned empty handed,' without implying that ' the prey escaped ' ; but we may say ' the man went supperless to bed,' without implying that * the chamois re- joiced upon the mountain.' Such words as ' man' and 'chamois' may, then, in their use, be, as to one another, non-relative. 44 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE To illustrate further the relativity of terms, we may mention some of the chief classes of them. Numerical order : ist, 2nd, 3rd, etc. Note that ist implies 2nd, and 2nd ist; and that 3rd implies ist and 2nd, but these do not imply 3rd ; and so on. in Time or Place : before-after; early-punctual-late ; right-middle-left ; North-South, etc. As to Extent, Volume, and Degree: greater-equal-less; large-medium-small ; whole and part. Genus and Species are a peculiar case of whole and part (cf. chaps, xxi.-ii.-iii.). Sometimes a term connotes all the attri- butes that another does, and more besides, which, as distin- guishing it, are called differential. Thus ' man ' connotes all that * animal ' does, and also (as differentia} the erect attitude, articulate speech, and other attributes. In such a case as this, where we have well-marked natural classes, the term whose connotation is included in the others' is called a Genus of that Species. Thus we have a Genus, triangle; and a Species, isosceles, marked off from all other triangles by the differential quality of having two equal sides. Or, again : Genus, book ; Species, quarto ; Difference, having each sheet folded into four leaves. There are other cases where these expressions ' genus ' and ' species ' cannot be so applied without a departure from usage, as, e.g., if we call snow a species of the genus ' white,' for ' white ' is not a recognised class. The connotation of white (/.*., whiteness) is, however, part of the connotation of snow, just as the qualities of ' animal ' are amongst those of ' man ' ; and for logical purposes it is desirable to use ' genus and species ' to express that relativity of terms which consists in the connotation of one being part of the connotation of the other. Two or more terms whose connotations severally include that of another term, whilst at the same time exceeding it, are (in relation to that other term) called Co-ordinate. Thus in relation to ' white,' snow and silver are co-ordinate ; in relation to colour, yellow and red and blue are co-ordinate. And when THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 45 all the terms thus related stand for recognised natural classes, the co-ordinate terms are called co-ordinate species ; thus man and chamois are (in Logic) co-ordinate species of the genus animal. 6. From such examples of terms whose connotations are related as whole and part, it is easy to see the general truth of the doctrine that as connotation decreases, denotation increases: for 'animal,' with less connotation than man or chamois, denotes many more objects ; * white,' with less connotation than snow or silver, denotes many more things. It is not, however, certain that this doctrine is always true in the con- crete : as there may be a term connoting two or more qualities, all of which qualities are peculiar to all the things it denotes ; and, if so, by subtracting one of the qualities from its connotation, we should not increase its denotation. If 'man,' for example, has among mammals the two peculiar attributes of erectness and articulate speech, then, by omitting 1 articulate speech ' from the connotation of man, we could not apply the name to any more of the existing mammalia than we can at present. Still we might have been able to do so ; there might have been an erect inarticulate ape, and perhaps there once was one ; and, if so, to omit ' articulate ' from the con- notation of man would make the term 'man' denote that animal (supposing that there was no other difference to exclude it). Hence, potentially, an increase of the connotation of any term implies a decrease of its denotation. And, on the other hand, we can only increase the denotation of a term, or apply it to more objects, by decreasing its connotation ; for, if the new things denoted by the term had already possessed its whole connotation, they must already have been denoted by it. How- ever, we may increase the known denotation without decreasing the connotation, if we can discover the full connotation in things not formerly supposed to have it ; or if we can impose the requisite qualities upon new individuals, as when by annexing some millions of Africans we extend the denotation of ' British subject ' without altering its connotation. 46 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Many of the things noticed in this chapter, especially in this section and the preceding, will be discussed at greater length in the chapters on Classification and Definition. 7. Contradictory Relatives. Every term has, or may have, another corresponding with it in such a way that, whatever differential qualities ( 5) it connotes, this other connotes merely their absence; so that one or the other is always formally predicable of any Subject, but both these terms are never predicable of the same Subject in the same relation : such pairs of terms are called Contradictories. Whatever Subject we take, it is either visible or invisible, but not both ; either human or non-human, but not both. This at least is true formally, though in practice we should think ourselves trifled with if any one told us that * A mountain is either human or non-human, but not both/ It is symbolic terms, such as X and x, that are properly said to be contra- dictories in relation to any subject whatever, S or M. For, as we have seen, the ordinary use of terms is limited by some suppositio^ and this is true of Contradictories. Human and non-human may refer to zoological classification, or to the scope of physical, mental, or moral powers as if we ask whether to flourish a dumb-bell of a ton weight, or to know the future by intuition, or impeccability, be human or non- human. Similarly, visible and invisible refer either to the power of reflecting light, so that they have no hold upon a sound or a smell, or else to power of vision and such qualifi- cations as * with the naked eye ' or * with a microscope.' Again, the above definition of Contradictories tells us that they cannot be predicated of the same Subject " in the same relation"; that is, at the same time or place, or under the same conditions. The lamp is visible to me now, but will be invisible if I turn it out ; one side of it is now visible, but the other is not : therefore without this restriction, " in the same relation," few or no terms would be contradictory. If a man is called wise, it may mean ' on the whole ' or * in a certain action ' ; and clearly a man may for once be wise (or THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 47 act wisely) who, on the whole, is not-wise. So that here again, by this ambiguity, terms that seem contradictory are predicable of the same subject, but not "in the same relation." In order to avoid the ambiguity, however, we have only to construct the term so as to express the relation, as c wise on the whole ' ; and this immediately generates the contradictory ' not-wise on the whole.' Similarly, at one age a man may have black hair, at another not-black hair ; but the difficulty is practically remov- able by stating the age referred to. Still, this case easily leads us to a real difficulty in the use of contradictory terms, a difficulty arising from the continuous change or ' flux ' of natural phenomena. If things are con- tinually changing, it may be urged that contradictory terms are always applicable to the same subject, at least as fast as we can utter them : for if we say a man's hair is black, since (like everything else) his hair is changing, it must now be not-black, though (to be sure) it may still seem black. The difficulty, it may be said, lies in this, that the human mind and its instrument language are not equal to the subtlety of Nature. All things flow, but the terms of human discourse assume a certain fixity of things ; everything at every moment changes, but for the most part we can neither perceive this change nor express it in ordinary language. This paradox, however, may, I suppose, be easily overstated. The change that continually goes on in Nature consists in the movements of masses or molecules, and such movements of things are compatible with a considerable persistence of their qualities. Not only are the molecular changes always going on in a piece of gold compatible with its remaining yellow, but its persistent yellowness depends on the continuance of some of those changes. And as much may be said for the blackness of a man's hair, though, no doubt, at a certain age its colour may begin to be problematical, and the applicability to it of ' black ' or ' not-black ' may become a matter of genuine anxiety. Whilst being on our guard, then, against fallacies of contra- diction arising from the imperfect correspondence of fact with 48 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE thought and language, we shall often have to put up with it. Candour and humility being satisfied with the above acknow- ledgment of the subtlety of Nature, this book will henceforward proceed upon the postulate that it is possible to use contra- dictory terms such as cannot both be predicated of the same subject in the same relation, though one of them may be ; that, for example, it may be truly said of a man for some years that his hair is black ; and, if so, that during those years to call it not-black is false or extremely misleading. It must be observed that the most opposed terms of the literary vocabulary, such as * wise-foolish,' * old-young,' ' sweet- bitter,' are rarely true contradictories : wise and foolish, indeed, cannot be predicated of the same man in the same relation ; but there are many middling men, of whom neither can be predicated on the whole. For the comparison of quantities, again, we have three correlative terms, * greater equal less/ and none of these is the contradictory of either of the others. In fact, the contradictory of any term is one that denotes the sum of its co-ordinates ( 6) ; and to obtain a contradictory, the surest way is to coin one by prefixing to the given terra the particle * not ' or (sometimes) * non ' : as * wise-not-wise/ ' human-non-human,' { greater-not-greater.' The separate word * not ' is surer to constitute a contradictory than the usual prefixes of negation, ' un-' or * in-', or even ' non.' Since compounds of these are generally warped by common use from a purely negative meaning. Thus, * Nonconformist ' does not denote everybody who fails to conform. * Unwise ' is not equivalent to * not-wise,' but means ' rather foolish ' a very foolish action is not-wise, but can only be called unwise by meiosis or irony. Still, negatives formed by * in ' or * un ' or 1 non ' are sometimes really contradictory of their positives ; as 1 visible-invisible,' ' equal-unequal.' 8. The distinction between Positive and Negative terms is not of much value in Logic, what importance would else attach to it being absorbed by the more definite distinction of contradictories. For contradictories are positive and negative ; THE CONNOTATION OF TERMS 49 in essence and, when least ambiguously stated, also in form. And, on the other hand, as we have seen, when positive and negative terms are not contradictory, they are misleading. As with ' wise-unwise,' so with many others, such as ' happy- unhappy ' ; which are not contradictories ; since a man may be neither happy nor unhappy, but indifferent, or (again) so miserable that he can only be called unhappy by a figure of speech. In fact, in the common vocabulary a formal negative often has a limited positive sense; and this is the case with unhappy, signifying the state of feeling in the milder shades of purgatory. When a Negative term is fully contradictory of its Positive, it is said to be Infinite ; because it denotes an unascertained multi- tude of things, a multitude only limited by the positive term and the suppositio ; thus '$S?4vise ' denotes all except the wise, within the suppositio of ' intelligent beings.' Indeed, formally (dis- regarding any suppositio), such a negative term stands for all possible terms except its positive : x denotes everything but X ; and ' not-wise ' may be taken to include stones, triangles and hippogriffs. In this sense every negative term has some positive meaning, though a very indefinite one, not a specific positive force like 'unwise' or 'unhappy.' It denotes any and everything that has not the attributes connoted by the corresponding positive term. Privative Terms connote the absence of a quality that normally belongs to the thing denoted, as ' blind ' or ' deaf.' We may predicate 'blind* or 'deaf of a man, dog or cow that happens not to be able to see or hear, because the powers of seeing and hearing generally belong to these species ; but of a stone or idol these terms can only be used figuratively. Indeed, since the contradictory of a privative carries with it the privative limitation, a stone is strictly ' not-blind ' : that is, it is ' not-something-that-normally-having-sight-wants-it.' Contrary Terms are those that (within a certain genus or suppositio] severally connote differential qualities that are in fact mutually incompatible in the same relation to the same D 50 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE thing, and therefore cannot be predicated of the same subject in the same relation ; and, so far, they resemble Contradictory Terms : but they differ from contradictory terms in this, that the differential quality connoted by each of them is positive, and, therefore, not infinite but limited (formally) to part of the suppositio excluded by the others ; so that, possibly, neither of two Contraries is truly predicable of a given subject. Thus ' blue ' and * red ' are Contraries, for they cannot both be predicated of the same thing in the same relation ; but are not Contradictories, since, in a given case, neither may be pre- dicable : if a flower is blue in a certain part, it cannot in the same part be red ; but it may be neither blue nor red, but yellow; though it is certainly either blue or not-blue. All co-ordinate terms are formal Contraries, but if, in fact, a series of co-ordinates comprises only two (as male-female), they are Contradictories; since each includes all that area of the suppositio which the other excludes. The extremes of a series of co-ordinate terms are Opposites; as, in a list of colours, white and black, the most strongly contrasted, are said to be opposites, or as among moods of feeling, rapture and misery are opposites. But this distinc- tion is of slight logical importance. Imperfect Positive and Negative couples, like 'happy and unhappy,' which (as we have seen) are not contradictories, are often called Opposites. The members of any series of Contraries are all included by any one of them and its contradictory, as all colours come under ' red ' and { not-red,' all moods of feeling under ' happy ' and ' not-happy. 1 CHAPTER V THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS i. Logicians classify Propositions according to Quantity, Quality, Relation and Modality. As to Quantity, propositions are either Universal or Par- ticular ; that is to say, the predicate is affirmed or denied either of the whole subject or of a part of it of All or of Some S. All Sis P (that is, P is predicated of all S). Some S is P (that is, P is predicated of some S). An Universal Proposition may have for its subject a singular term, a collective, a general term distributed, or an abstract term. (1) A proposition having a singular term for its subject, as The Queen has gone to France, is called a Singular Proposition ; and some Logicians regard this as a third species of propo- sition with respect to quantity, distinct from the Universal and Particular ; but this is needless. (2) A collective term may be the subject, as The Black Watch is ordered to India. In this case, as well as in singular propositions, a predication is made concerning the whole subject as a whole. (3) The subject may be a general term taken in its full denotation, as All apes are sagacious; and in this case a predication is made concerning the whole subject distribu- tively; that is, of each and everything the subject stands ibi. (4) Propositions whose subjects are abstract terms, though they may seem to be formally Singular, are really as to their 52 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE meaning distributive Universals ; since whatever is true of a quality is true of whatever thing has that quality so far as that quality is concerned. Truth will prevail means that All true propositions are accepted at last (by sheer force of being true, in spite of interests, prejudices, ignorance and indifference). To bear this in mind may make one cautious in the use of abstract terms. In the above paragraphs a distinction is implied between Singular and Distributive Universals ; but it is very important to remember that, technically, every term, whether subject or predicate, when taken in its full denotation (or universally), is said to be 'distributed/ although this word, in its ordinary sense, would be directly applicable only to general terms. In the above examples, then, ' Queen,' * Black Watch,' ' apes/ and ' truth ' are all distributed terms. Indeed, a simple defi- nition of the Universal Proposition is { one;whose subject is distributed.' A Particular Proposition is one that has a general term for its subject, whilst its predicate is not affirmed or denied of every- thing the subject denotes ; in other words,, it is one whose subject is not distributed : as Some lions inhabit Africa. In ordinary discourse it is not always explicitly stated whether predication is universal or particular ; it would be very natural to say Lions inhabit Africa, leaving it, as far as the words go, uncertain whether we mean all or some lions. Propositions whose quantity is thus left indefinite are technically called 1 preindesignate,' their quantity not being stated or designated by any introductory expression ; whilst propositions whose quantity is expressed, as All Foundling-hospitals have a high death-rate, or Some wine is made from grapes, are said to be * predesignate.' Now, the rule is that preindesignate propositions are, for logical purposes, to be treated as particular; since it is an obvious precaution of the science of proof, in any practical application, not to go beyond the evidence. Still the rule may be relaxed if the universal quantity of a preindesignate proposition is well known or admitted, as in Planets shine with THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 53 reflected light, or Sinners are wretched, though, indeed, the former of these examples, I suppose, may not be true under all conditions. Again, such a proposition as Man is the paragon of animals is not a preindesignate, but an abstract proposition ; the subject being elliptical for Man according to his proper nature ; and the translation of it into a general proposition is not All men are paragons ; nor can Some men be sufficient, since an abstract can only be adequately rendered by a distributed term ; but we must say, All men who approach the ideal. The marks or predesignations of Quantity commonly used in Logic are : for Universals, All, Any, Every, Whatever (in the negative No or No one, see next ) ; for Particulars, Some. It should be carefully noted that Some, technically used, does not mean Some only, but Some at least (it may be one, or more, or all). If it meant * Some only' every particular propo- sition would be an exclusive exponible (chap. ii. 3) ; since Only some men are wise implies that Some men are not wise. Besides, it may often happen in an investigation that all the instances we have observed come under a certain rule, though we do not yet feel justified in regarding the rule as universal ; and this situation is exactly met by the expression Some (it may be all). The words Many,^ Most, Few are generally interpreted to mean Some ; but as 4nost signifies that exceptions are known, and Few that the exceptions are the more numerous, proposi- tions thus predesignate are in fact exponibles, amounting to Some are and Some are not. If to work with both forms is too cumbrous, so that we must choose one, apparently Few are should be treated as Some are not. The scientific course to adopt with propositions predesignate by Most or Few, is to collect statistics and determine the percentage ; thus, Few men are wise say 2 J per cent. The Quantity of a proposition, then, is usually determined entirely by the quantity of the subject, whether all or some Still, the quantity of the predicate is often an important 54 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE consideration ; and though in ordinary usage the predicate is never predesignate, Logicians agree that in every Negative Proposition (see 2) the predicate is ' distributed,' that is to say, is denied altogether of the subject, and that this is in- volved in the form of denial. To say Some men are not brave, is to declare that the quality for which men may be called brave is not at all found in the Some men referred to : and, similarly, to say No men are proof against flattery > cuts off the being * proof against flattery ' entirely from the list of human attributes. On the other hand, every Affirmative Proposition is regarded as having an undistributed predicate; that is to say, its predicate is not affirmed exclusively of the subject. Some men are wise does not mean that * wise ' cannot be predicated of any other beings ; it is equivalent to Some men are wise (whoever else may be). And All elephants are sagacious does not limit sagacity to elephants: regarding 1 sagacious ' as possibly denoting many animals of many species that exhibit the quality, this proposition is equivalent to * All elephants are some sagacious animals.' Clearly, the affirmative predication of a quality does not imply exclusive possession of it as denial implies its complete absence ; and, therefore, to regard the predicate of an affirmative proposition as distributed would be to go beyond the evidence and to take for granted what had never been alleged. Some Logicians, seeing that the quantity of predicates, though not distinctly expressed, is recognised, and holding that it is the part of Logic "to make explicit in language whatever is implicit in thought," have proposed to exhibit the quantity of predicates by predesignation, thus : * Some men are some wise (beings) ' ; * some men are not any brave (beings); etc. This is called the Quantification of the Pre- dicate, and leads to some modifications of Deductive Logic which will be referred to, but not developed, hereafter. (See 3 ; and chap. vii. 4.) 2. As to Quality, Propositions are either Affirmative or Negative. An Affirmative Proposition is, formally, one whose THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 55 copula is affirmative (or, has no negative sign), as S is P t All men are partial to themselves. A Negative Proposition is one whose copula is negative (or, has a negative sign), as .S is not /*, Some men are not proof against flattery. When, indeed, a Negative Proposition is of Universal Quantity, it is stated thus : No S is P, No men are proof against flattery ; but, in this case, the detachment of the negative sign from the copula and its association with the subject is merely an accident of our idiom ; the proposition is the same as All men are not proof against flattery. It must be distinguished, therefore, from such an expression as Not every man is proof against flattery ; for here the negative sign really qualifies the subject, and the proposition is Particular, being equivalent to Some men are not proof against flattery. When the negative sign is associated with the predicate so as to make this an Infinite Term (chap. iv. 8), the proposition is called an Infinite Proposition, as 5 is not-P (or p\ All men are incapable of resisting flattery, or are not-proof against flattery. Infinite propositions, when the copula is affirmative, are, formally, themselves affirmative, although their force is chiefly negative ; for, as the last example shows, the difference between an infinite and a negative proposition may depend upon a hyphen. It has been proposed, indeed, with a view to superficial simplification, to turn all Negatives into Infinites, and thus render all propositions Affirmative in Quality. But although every proposition both affirms and denies something according to the aspect in which you regard it (as Snow is white denies that it is any other colour, and Snow is not blue affirms that it is some other colour), yet there is a great difference between the definite affirmation of a genuine affirmative and the vague affirmation of a negative or infinite ; so that materially an affirmative infinite is the same as a negative. Generally Mill's remark is true, that affirmation and denial stand for distinctions of facts that cannot be got rid of by 56 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE manipulation of words. Whether granite sinks in water, or not ; whether the rook lives a hundred years, or not ; whether a man has a hundred dollars in his pocket, or not ; whether human bones have ever been found in tertiary strata, or not ; such alternatives require distinct forms of expression. At the same time, it may be granted that many facts admit of being stated with nearly equal propriety in either Quality, as No man is proof against flattery t or All men are open to flattery. But whatever . advantage there is in occasionally changing the Quality of a proposition may be gained by the process of Obversion (chap. vii. 5); whilst to use only one Quality would impair the elasticity of logical expression. It is a postulate of Logic that the negative sign may be transferred from the copula to the predicate, or from the predicate to the copula, without altering the sense of a proposition ; and this is justified by the experience that not to have an attribute and to be without it are the same thing. 3. A. I. E. O. Combining the two kinds of Quantity Universal and Particular, with the two kinds of Quality, Affirmative and Negative, we get four simple types of pro- position, which it is usual to symbolise by the letters A. I. E. O., thus: A. Universal Affirmative All S is P. I. Particular Affirmative Some S is P. E. Universal Negative No S is P. O. Particular Negative Some S is not P. These symbols are exceedingly useful in abbreviating the exposition of Logic; and they should be so learnt as to suggest their meaning without the least need for an effort of recollection. As an aid to this, observe that A. and I. are the first two vowels in affirmo and that E. and O. are the vowels in nego. Those Logicians who explicitly quantify the predicate obtain, in all, eight forms of proposition according to Quantity and Quality : THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 57 U. Toto-total Affirmative All X is all Y. A. Toto-partial Affirmative All X is some Y. Y. Parti-total Affirmative Some X is all Y. I. Parti-partial Affirmative Some X is some Y. E. Toto-total Negative No X is any Y. ij. Toto-partial Negative No X is some Y O. Parti-total Negative Some X is not any Y. w. Parti-partial Negative Some X is not some Y. Here A. I. E. O. correspond with those similarly symbolised in the usual list, merely designating in the predicates the quantity which was formerly treated as implicit. 4. As to Relation, propositions are either Categorical or Conditional. A Categorical Proposition is one in which the predicate is directly affirmed or denied of the subject without any limitation of time, place, or circumstance, extraneous to the subject, as All men in England are secure of justice ; in which proposition, though there is a limitation of place (' in England'), it is included in the subject. Of this kind are nearly all the examples that have yet been given, according to the form S is P. A Conditional Proposition is so called because the predica- tion is made under some limitation or condition not included in the subject, as If a man lives in England he is secure of justice. Here the limitation ' living in England ' is put into a conditional sentence extraneous to the subject, 'he,' repre- senting any man. Conditional propositions, again, are of two kinds Hypo- thetical and Disjunctive. Hypothetical propositions are those that are limited by an explicit conditional sentence, as above, or thus : If Joe Smith was a prophet his followers have been unjustly persecuted. Or in symbols thus : If A is, B is ; If A is B, AisC; If A is B, C is D. Disjunctive propositions are those in which the condition under which predication is made is not explicit but only 58 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE implied under the disguise of an alternative proposition, as foe Smith was either a prophet or an impostor. Here there is no direct predication concerning Joe Smith, but only a predi- cation of one of the alternatives conditionally on the other being denied, as, If Joe Smith was not a prophet he was an impostor ; or, If he was not an impostor ; he was a prophet. Symbolically, Conditionals may be represented thus : A is either B or C, . Either A is B or C is D. Now, formally, every Conditional may be expressed as a Categorical. For our last example shows how a Disjunctive may be reduced to two Hypotheticals (of which one is redundant, being the contrapositive of the other ; see chap. vii. 10). And a Hypothetical is reducible to a Categorical thus : If rain falls on St. Swithirfs Day, it falls every day for the next forty ; or, in other words, The case of rain falling on St. Swithiris Day is a case of rain falling for the next forty. But this, though the common plan of stating the Categorical equivalent, is portentously clumsy. It would be better to say: Whenever rain falls upon St. Swit kin's Day, it falls for the next forty. Or, recalling Mill's remark that the essence of a Hypo- thetical is to state that one clause of it (the indicative) may be inferred from the other (the conditional), we may write : The falling of rain upon St. Swit kin's Day is a sign of its falling for the next forty. Or, similarly, Proof of Joe Smiths prophetic mission is a proof of his not being an impostor. This turning of Conditionals into Categoricals is called a Change of Relation; and the process may be reversed : All the wise are virtuous may be written, If any man is wise he is virtuous ; or, again, Either a man is not wise or he is virtuous. But the categorical form is usually the simplest. If, then, as substitutes for the corresponding conditionals, categoricals are formally adequate, though sometimes inelegant, it may be urged that Logic has nothing to do with elegance ,; or that, at any rate, the chief elegance of science is economy, and that therefore, for scientific purposes, whatever we may THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 59 write further about conditionals must be an ugly excrescence. The scientific purpose of Logic is to assign the conditions of proof. Can we, then, in the conditional form prove anything that cannot be proved in the categorical? Or does a con- ditional require to be itself proved by any method not applic- able to the Categorical ? If not, why go on with the discussion of Conditionals ? For all laws of Nature, however stated, are essentially categorical. c lf a straight line falls on another straight line, the adjacent angles are together equal to two right angles'; 'If a body is unsupported, it falls ' ; * If population increases rents tend to rise ' : here c if ' means * whenever ' or 1 all cases in which ' ; for to raise a doubt whether a straight line is ever conceived to fall upon another, whether bodies are ever unsupported, or population ever increases, is a superfluity of scepticism ; and plainly the hypothetical form has nothing to do with the proof of such propositions, nor with inference from them. Still, the disjunctive form is useful in stating a Division (chap, xxi.), whether formal (as A is B or not-B) or material (as Cats are white, or black, or tortoiseshell, or tabby). And in some cases the hypoihetical form may be useful. One of these occurs where it is important to draw attention to the condition, as something especially requiring examination. If there is a resisting medium in space, the earth will fall into the sun ; If the Corn Laws are to be re-enacted, we had better sell railways and buy land: here the hypothetical form draws attention to the questions whether there is a resisting medium in space, whether the Corn Laws are likely to be re-enacted ; but as to methods of inference and proof, the hypothetical form has nothing to do with them. The propositions predicate causation : A resisting medium in space is a condition of the earth's falling into the sun ; A Corn Law is a condition of the rise of rents, and the fall of railway profits. A second case in which the hypothetical is a specially appropriate form of statement occurs where a proposition relates to a particular matter and to future time, as If there be a storm 60 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE to-morrow, we shall miss our picnic. It is in such cases (which are of very slight logical value) that the categorical form seems most strained and inelegant; but even then it is logically adequate ; and the true reasons why conditionals have to be discussed here and hereinafter are, that it is usual to do so, and that they furnish valuable exercises in formal thinking. Most people find them more difficult to manipulate than categoricals, and therefore they should be more zealously mastered. In discussing Conditional Propositions, the conditional sentence of a Hypothetical, or the first alternative of a Dis- junctive, is called the Antecedent ; the indicative sentence of a Hypothetical, or the second alternative of a Disjunctive, is called the Consequent. Hypotheticals, like Categoricals, may be classed according to Quantity and Quality. Premising that the quantity of a Hypothetical depends on the quantity of its Antecedent (which determines its limitation), whilst its quality depends on the quality of its consequent (which makes the predication), we may exhibit four forms : A. If A is B, Cis D; I. Sometimes when A is B, C is D ; E. If A is B, C is not D ; 0. Sometimes when A is B> C is not D. But I. and O. are rarely used. As for Disjunctives, it is easy to distinguish the two quantities thus : A. Either A is B, or C is D ; 1. Sometimes either A is B or C is D. But I. is rarely used. The distinction of quality, however, cannot be made : there are no true negative forms. If we write : Neither is A B, nor C D, there is here no alternative predication, but only an Exponible equivalent to No A is B, and No C is D. And if we write : Either A is not B, or C is not D, THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 61 this is affirmative as to the alternation, and is for all methods of treatment equivalent to A. Logicians are divided in opinion as to the interpretation of the conjunction ' either, or ' ; some holding that it means * not both,' others that it means * it may be both.' Grammatical usage, upon which the question is sometimes argued, does not seem to be established in favour of either view. If we say A man so precise in his walk and conversation is either a saint or a consummate hypocrite; or, again, One who is happy in a solitary life is either more or less than man ; we cannot in such cases mean that the subject may be both. On the other hand, if it be said that the author of 1 A Tale of a Tub ' is either a misanthrope or a dyspeptic, the alternatives are not incompatible. Or, again, given that X. is a lunatic, or a lover, or a poet, the three predicates have much congruity. It has been urged, however, that in Logic, language should be made as exact and definite as possible, and that this requires the exclusive interpretation ' not both.' But it seems a better argument, that Logic, as the science of evidence, must not assume more than is given ; and, therefore, to be on the safe side, must in doubtful cases assume the least, just as it generally assumes a preindesignate term to be of particular quantity. According to this argument, * either, or ' means * one, or the other, or both.' However, when both the alternative propositions have the same subject, as either A is B, or A is C, if the two predicates are contrary or contradictory terms (as ' saint ' and * hypocrite,' or 'saint' and 'not-saint'), they cannot in their nature be predicable in the same way of the same subject, and, therefore, in such a case ' either, or ' means one or the other, but not both in the same relation. Hence it seems necessary to admit that the conjunction ' either, or ' may sometimes require one interpre- tation, sometimes the other ; and the rule seems to be that it implies the further possibility * or both,' except when both alternatives have the same subject whilst the predicates are contraries or contradictories. 62 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE If, then, the disjunctive A is either B or C (B and C being contraries) implies that both alternatives cannot be true, it can only be adequately rendered in hypotheticals by the two forms (i) If A is B, it is not <7, and (2) If A is not B, it is C. But if the disjunctive A is either B or C (B and C not being con- traries) implies that both may be true, it will be adequately translated into a hypothetical by the single form, If A is not B, it is C. We cannot translate it into If A is B, it is not C , for, by our supposition, if ' A is B ' is true, it does not follow that 'AtsC' must be false. It may be observed that these conditional forms often cover assertions that are not true complex propositions, but a sort of enthymemes (chap. xi. 2), arguments abbreviated and rhetori- cally disguised. The hypothetical, * If Plato was not mistaken poets are dangerous citizens? may be considered as an argument against the laureateship, and may be expanded (informally) thus : ' All Plato's opinions deserve respect ; one of them was that poets are bad citizens ; therefore it behoves us to be chary of encouraging poetry.' Or take this disjunctive, * Either Bacon wrote the works ascribed to Shakespeare, or there were two men of the highest genius in the same age and country! This means that it is not likely there should be two such men, that we are sure of Bacon, and therefore ought to give him all the glory. Now, if it is the part of Logic ' to make explicit in language all that is implicit in thought,' or to put arguments into the form in which they can best be examined, such propositions as the above ought to be analysed in the way suggested, and confirmed or refuted according to their real intention. 5. As to Modality, propositions are divided into Pure and Modal. A Modal proposition is one in which the predicate is affirmed or denied, not simply but cum modo, with a qualifica- tion. And some Logicians have considered any adverb occurring in the predicate, or any sign of past or future tense, enough to constitute a modal : as ' Petroleum is dan- gerously inflammable ' ; * English will be the universal language/ THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 63 But far the most important kind of modality, and the only one we need consider, is that which is signified by some qualification of the predicate as to the degree of certainty with which it is affirmed or denied. Thus, ,* The bite of the cobra is probably mortal,' is called a Contingent or Pro- blematic Modal : * Water is certainly composed of oxygen and hydrogen ' is an Assertory or Certain Modal : ' Two straight lines cannot enclose a space' is a Necessary or Apodeictic Modal (the opposite being inconceivable). Propositions not thus qualified are called Pure. Modal propositions have had a long and eventful history, but they have not been found tractable by the resources of ordinary Logic, and are now generally neglected by the authors of text-books. Accordingly, I shall not enlarge upon the merely logical treatment of them in the present work. No doubt such propositions are common in ordinary discourse, and in some rough way we combine them and draw inferences from them. It is understood that a combination of assertory or of apodeictic premises may warrant an assertory or an apodeictic conclusion ; but that if we combine either of these witha problematic premise our conclusion becomes problematic; whilst the combination of two problematic premises gives a conclusion less certain than either. But if we ask ' How much less certain ? ' we are left to sheer guessing. That the modality of a conclusion follows the less certain of the premises com- bined is inadequate for scientific guidance ; so that, as ordinary Logic can get no farther than this, it is now generally agreed to abandon the discussion of Modals. The true scientific course with regard to them is, to endeavour to determine the degree of certainty attaching to a proposition by collecting statistics with regard to it. Thus, instead of ' The cobra's bite is probably fatal,' we might find that it is fatal 80 times in 100. Then, if we know that of those who go to India 3 in 1000 are bitten, we can calculate what the chances are that any one going to India will die of a cobra's bite (chap. xx.). 6. Verbal and Real Propositions. Another important 64 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE division of propositions turns upon the relation of the predi- cate to the subject in respect of their connotations. We saw, when discussing Relative Terms, that the connotation of one term often implies that of another; sometimes recipro- cally, like ' master ' and * slave ' ; or by inclusion, like species and genus ; or by exclusion, like contraries and contradictories. When terms so related appear as subject and predicate of the same proposition, the result is often tautology e.g., The master has authority over his slave ; A horse is an animal ; Red is not blue ; British is not foreign. Whoever knows the meaning of 1 master/ ' horse,' ' red,' ' British,' learns nothing from these propositions. Hence they are called Verbal propositions, as only expounding the sense of words, or as if they were propo- sitions only by satisfying the forms of language, not by fulfilling the function of propositions in conveying a knowledge of facts. They are also called * Analytic ' and ' Explicative,' when they separate and disengage the elements of the connotation of the subject. Doubtless, such propositions are very useful to one who does not know the language ; and Definitions, which are verbal propositions whose predicates analyse the whole connotations of their subjects, are indispensable instruments of science (see chap. xxii.). Of course, hypothetical propositions may also be verbal, as If the soul be material it is extended ; for 'extension' is connoted by * matter ' : and, therefore, the corresponding disjunctive is verbal. But a true divisional disjunctive can never be verbal (chap. xxi. 4, rule i). On the other hand, when there is no such direct relation between subject and predicate that their connotations imply one another, but the predicate connotes something that cannot be learnt from the connotation of the subject, there is no longer tautology, but an enlargement of meaning e.g., Masters are degraded by their slaves ; The horse is the noblest animal ; Red is the favourite colour of the British army. Such propositions are called Real, Synthetic, or Ampliative, because they are propo- sitions for which a mere understanding of their subjects would THE CLASSIFICATION OF PROPOSITIONS 65 be no substitute, since the predicate adds a meaning of its own concerning matter of fact. It has been seriously questioned whether a verbal propo- sition deserves to be called a proposition at all. We may ask whether, to any one who understands the language, a verbal proposition can ever be an inference or conclusion from evidence ; or whether a verbal proposition can ever furnish grounds for an inference, which might not just as well be found in the meaning of the subject? We shall see hereafter that, without an answer to these questions, some important problems must remain unsolved. The whole subject of real and verbal propositions will inevitably recur in the chapters on Definition ; but verbal propositions are such common blemishes in composition, and such frequent and fatal pitfalls in argument, that attention cannot be drawn to them too early or too often. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE i. The word Inference is used in two different senses, which are often confused but should be carefully distinguished. In the first sense, it means a process of thought or reasoning by which the mind passes from facts or statements presented, to some opinion or expectation. The data may be very vague and slight, prompting no more than a guess or surmise; as when we look up at the sky and form some expectation about the weather, or from the trick of a man's face entertain some prejudice as to his character. Or the data may be important and strongly significant, like the footprint that frightened Crusoe, or as when news of war makes the city expect that Consols will fall. These are examples of the act of inferring, or of inference as a process ; and with inference in this sense Logic has nothing to do ; it belongs to Psychology to explain how it is that our minds pass from one perception or thought to another thought, and how we come to conjecture, conclude and believe (cf. chap. i. 6). In the second sense, 'inference' means not this process of guessing or opining, but the result of it ; the surmise, opinion, or belief when formed ; in a word, the conclusion : and it is in this sense that Inference is treated of in Logic. The subject- matter of Logic is an inference, judgment or conclusion con- cerning facts, embodied in a proposition, which is to be examined in relation to the evidence that may be adduced for it. in order to determine whether, or how far, the evidence amounts to proof. Logic is the science of Reasoning in the CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE 67 sense in which * reasoning ' means giving reasons, for it shows what sort of reasons are good. Whilst Psychology explains how the mind goes forward from data to conclusions, Logic takes a conclusion and goes back to the data, inquiring whether those data, together with any other evidence (facts or principles) that can be collected, are of a nature to warrant the conclusion. If we think that the night will be stormy, that A. Schultze is of an amiable disposition, that water expands in freezing, or that one means to national prosperity is popular education, and wish to know whether we have evidence sufficient to justify us in holding these opinions, Logic can tell us what form the evidence should assume in order to be conclusive. Observe : I say what form the evidence should assume, not that Logic tells us what facts are proper evidence in any of these cases ; that is a question for the man of special experience in life, or in science, or in business. But whatever the facts are that constitute the evidence, they must, in order to prove the point, admit of being stated in conformity with certain principles or conditions ; and of these principles or conditions Logic is the science. It deals, then, not with the subjective process of inferring, but with the objective grounds that justify or discredit the inference. 2. Inferences, in the Logical sense, are divided into two great classes, the Immediate and the Mediate, according to the character of the evidence offered in proof of them. In fact, to speak of inferences, in the sense of conclusions, as immediate or mediate, is an abuse of language, derived from times before the distinction between inference as process and inference as result was generally felt. No doubt we ought rather to speak of Immediate and Mediate Evidence ; but it is of little use to attempt to alter the traditional expressions of the science. An Immediate Inference, then, is one that depends for its proof upon only one other proposition which has the same, or more extensive, terms (or matter). Thus that one means to national prosperity is popular education is an immediate inference, if the evidence for it is no more than the admission that popular 68 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE education is a means to national prosperity : Similarly, 3t is an immediate inference that Some authors are vain, if it be granted that All authors are vain. An Immediate Inference, indeed, is little else than a verbal transformation ; and some Logicians dispute its claims to be called an inference at all, on the ground that it is identical with the pretended evidence. If we attend to the meaning, say they, an immediate inference does not really express any new judgment ; the fact expressed by it is either the same as its evidence, or is even less significant. If from No men are gods we prove that No gods are men, this is nugatory ; if we prove from it that Some men are not gods, this is to emasculate the sense, to waste valuable information, to lose the commanding sweep of our universal proposition. Still, in Formal Logic, it is often found that an immediate inference expresses our knowledge in a more convenient form than that of the evidentiary proposition, as will appear in the chapter on Syllogisms and elsewhere. And in transforming an universal into a particular proposition, as No men are gods, therefore, Some men are not gods, the latter statement, though weaker, is far more easily proved; since a single instance suffices. A Mediate Inference, on the other hand, depends for its evidence upon a plurality of other propositions (two or more) which are connected together on logical principles. If we argue No men are gods ; Alexander the Great is a man ; .*. Alexander the Great is not a god : this is a Mediate Inference. The evidence consists of two propositions connected by the term * man,' which is common to both (a Middle Term), mediating between * gods ' and 'Alexander.' Mediate Inferences comprise Syllogisms with their developments, and Inductions ; and to discuss them further at present would be to anticipate future chapters. We must now deal with the principles or conditions on which CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE 69 Immediate Inferences are valid : commonly called the " Laws of Thought." 3. The Laws of Thought are conditions of the logical statement and criticism of all sorts of evidence; but as to Immediate Inference, they may be regarded as the only conditions it need satisfy. They are three : (i) The principle of Identity (usually stated as * Whatever is, is,' or ' A is A ') ; (2) The principle of Contradiction ( ; It is impossible for the same thing to be and not be,' or ' A is not not- A ') ; (3) The principle of Excluded Middle (' Anything must either be or not be,' or ' B is either A or not A '). These principles are manifestly not * laws ' of thought in the sense in which ' law ' is used in Psychology ; they do not, like the laws of the association of ideas, profess to give an account of the actual mental processes that uniformly take place in judgment or reasoning. If they were such natural laws of thought, it would be impossible for anybody to mistake one thing for another or assume that the same thing may both be and not be ; whereas we know that people frequently make such mistakes. In relation to thought, therefore, these principles can only be regarded as laws when stated as precepts, the observance of which (consciously or not) is necessary to clear and consistent thinking: e.g., Never assume that the same thing can both be and not be. However, in this book, Logic is treated as the science of thought only as embodied in propositions, in respect of which evidence is to be adduced, or which are to be used as evi- dence of other propositions ; and, accordingly, the above laws or principles must be restated as the conditions of consistent argument in such terms as to be directly applicable to propo- sitions. Now, it was shown in the chapter on the connotation of terms, that terms are assumed by Logicians to be capable of definite meaning, and of being used um'vocally in the same context : if, or in so far as, this is not the case, we cannot understand one another's reasons nor even pursue in solitary meditation any coherent train of argument. We saw, too, 70 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE that the meanings of terms were related to one another: some being full correlatives; others partially inclusive one of another, as species of genus ; others mutually incompatible, as contraries ; or alternatively predicable, as contradictories. We now assume that propositions are capable of definite meaning according to the meaning of their component terms and of the relation between them ; that the meaning, the fact asserted or denied, is what we are really concerned to prove or disprove ; that a mere change in the words that constitute our terms, or of construction, does not affect the truth of a propo- sition as long as the meaning is not altered, or (rather) as long as no fresh meaning is introduced ; and that if the meaning of any proposition is true, any other proposition that denies it is false. This postulate is plainly necessary to consistency of statement and discourse ; and consistency is necessary, if our thought or speech is to correspond with the unity and co- herence of Nature and experience ; and the Laws of Thought or Conditions of Immediate Inference are an analysis of this postulate. 4. The principle of Identity is usually written symbolically thus : A is A ; not- A is not-A. It assumes that something is, and that it may be represented by a term. We need not here raise any metaphysical question whether after all anything can be said really to &, to be self-identical and sempiternal. Logic takes for granted a certain relative identity and persistence of things. Socrates in his father's workshop, at the battle of Delium, and in prison, is assumed to be the same man denotable by the same name; and similarly, elephant, or justice, or fairy, in the same con f e\t, is to be understood of the same thing under the same suppositio. But, further, it is assumed that of the same term another term may be predicated again and again in the same sense under the same conditions ; that (in other words) we may epeak of the identity of meaning in a proposition as well as in a term. To symbolise this we ought to alter the usual formula for Identity and write it thus : If B is A, B is A ; if B is CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE 71 not- A, B is not- A. If Socrates is wise, he is wise ; if fairies frequent the moonlight, they do ; if Justice is not of this world, it is not. Whatever affirmation or denial we make concerning any subject, we are bound to adhere to it for the purposes of the current argument or investigation. Of course, if our assertion turns out to be false, we must not adhere to it ; but then we must repudiate all that we formerly deduced from it and begin again with a clean slate. Again, whatever is true or false in one form of words is true or false in any other : this is undeniable ; but in Formal Logic it is not very convenient. If Socrates is wise, is it an identity to say * Therefore the master of Plato is .wise ' ; or, further, that he ' takes enlightened views of life ' ? If Every man is fallible, is it an identical proposition that Every man is liable to error ? It seems pedantic to demand a separate proposition that Fallible is liable to error. But, on the other hand, the insidious substitution of one term for another speciously identical, is a chief occasion of fallacy. How if we go on to argue : therefore, Every man is apt to blunder, prone to confusion of thought, inured to self-contradiction? Practically, I am afraid that the substitution of identities must be left to candour and good-sense ; and may they increase among us. But Formal Logic is, no doubt, safest with symbols ; should, perhaps, content itself with A and B ; or, at least, hardly venture beyond Kand Z. 5. The principle of Contradiction is usually written symbolically, thus : A is not not-A. But, since this formula seems to be adapted to a single term, whereas we want one that is applicable to propositions, it may be better to write it thus : B is not both A and not-A. That is to say : if any term may be affirmed of a subject, the contra- dictory term may be denied of it in the same relation. A leaf that is green on one side of it may be not-green on the other ; but it is not both green and not-green on the same surface, at the same time, and in the same light. If a stick is straight, it is false that it is at the same time not-straight: 72 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE having granted that two angles are equal, we must deny that they are unequal. But is it necessarily false that the stick is * crooked ' ; must we deny that either angle is ' greater or less' than the other ? How far is it permissible to substitute any other term for the formal contradictory? Clearly, the principle of Contradiction takes for granted the principle of Identity and is subject to the same difficulties in its practical application. As a matter of fact and common sense, if we affirm any term, we are bound to deny not only the contradictory but all synonyms for this, and also all contraries and opposites ; which, of course, are included in the contradictory. But who shall determine what these are? Without an authoritative Logical Dictionary to refer to, where all contradictories, synonyms, and contraries may be found on record, Formal Logic will hardly sanction the free play of common sense. The principle of Excluded Middle is usually written : B is either A or not-A ; that is, if any term be denied of a subject, the contradictory term may be affirmed in the same relation. Of course, we may deny that a leaf is green on one side without being bound to affirm that it is not-green on the other. But in the same relation a leaf is either green or not- green ; at the same time, a stick is either bent or not-bent. If we deny that A is greater than B, we must affirm that it is not- greater than B. Whilst, then, the principle of Contradiction (that ' of contra- dictory predicates, one being affirmed, the other is denied') might seem to leave open a third or middle course, the denying of both contradictories, the principle of Excluded Middle derives its name from the excluding of this middle course, by declaring that the one or the other must be affirmed. Hence the principle of Excluded Middle does not hold good of mere contrary terms. If we deny that a leaf is green, we are not bound to affirm it to be yellow; for it may be red ; and, therefore, we may deny both con- traries, yellow and green. In fact two contraries do not CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE 73 between them cover the whole predicable area, but contra- dictories do : the form of their expression is such that (within the suppositio) each includes all that the other excludes ; so that the subject (if brought within the suppositio] must fall under the one or the other. It may seem absurd to say that Mont Blanc is either wise or not-wise ; but how comes any mind so ill-organised as to introduce Mont Blanc into this strange company? Being there, however, the principle is inexorable : Mont Blanc, alas ! is not-wise. In fact, the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle are inseparable ; they are implicit in all distinct experience, and may be regarded as indicating the two aspects of Negation. The principle of Contradiction says : B is not both A and not- A, as if not- A might be nothing at all ; this is abstract negation. But the principle of Excluded Middle says : Granting that B is not A^ it is still something namely, not- A ; thus bringing us back to the concrete experience of a con- tinuum in which the absence of one thing implies the presence of something else. Symbolically : to deny that B is A is to affirm that B is not A, and this only differs by a hyphen from B is not- A. But if any one holds that the hyphen makes all the difference, I give it up. These principles, which were necessarily to some extent anticipated in chap. iv. 7, the next chapter will further illustrate. 6. But first we must draw attention to a maxim (also already mentioned), which is strictly applicable to Immediate Inferences, though (as we shall see) in other kinds of proof it may be only a formal condition : this is the general caution not to go beyond the evidence. An immediate inference ought to contain nothing that is not contained (or formally implied) in the proposition by which it is proved. With respect to quantity in denotation, this caution is embodied in the rule ' not to distribute any term that is not given distri- buted.' Thus, if there is a predication concerning ' Some S,' or ' Some men,' as in the forms I. and O., we cannot infer any- 74 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE thing concerning * All S,' or c All men ' ; and, as we have seen, if a term is given us preindesignate, we are generally to take it as of particular quantity. Similarly, in the case of affirmative propositions, we saw that this rule requires us to assume that their predicates are undistributed. As to the grounds of this maxim, not to go beyond the evidence, not to distribute a term that is given as undistri- buted, it is one of the things so plain that to try to justify is only to obscure them. We might indeed say that such a leap from the particular to the general is not sanctioned by any of the three Laws of Thought. The caution against it may particularly be viewed as supplementary to the principle of Identity, that whatever is true in one form of words is true in any other ; since if for * Some S ' we substitute * All S,' we no longer have the same sense as the given form of words. It is a gratuitous assumption, a mere non-sequitur ; and if any controvertist demands permission to make it, the Formal Logician can only " hold up his hands in respectful amaze- ment." Still we must here state explicitly what Formal Logic assumes to be contained or implied in the evidence afforded by any proposition, such as 'All S is P.' If we remember that in chap. iv. 7, it was assumed that every term may have a contradictory ; and if we bear in mind the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle, it will appear that such a proposition as ' All S is P ' tells us something not only about the relations of ' S ' and * P ', but also of their relations to * not-S ' and ' not-P ' ; as, for example, that ' S is not not-P ', and that ' not-P is not-S.' It will be shown in the next chapter how Logicians have developed these implications in series of Immediate Inferences. If it be asked whether it is true that every term, itself significant, has a significant contradictory, and not merely a formal contradictory, generated by force of the word ' not,' it is difficult to give any better answer than was indicated in 3-5, without venturing further into Metaphysics. I shall merely CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE 75 say, therefore, that, granting that some such term as 'Uni- verse ' or ' Being ' may have no significant contradictory, if it stand for 'whatever can be perceived or thought of; yet every term that stands for less than ' Universe ' or ' Being ' has, of course, a contradictory which denotes the rest of the universe. And since every argument or train of thought is carried on within a special ' universe of discourse,' or under a certain suppositio^ we may say that within the special universe or suppositio every term has a contradictory, and that every pre- dication concerning a term implies some predication concern- ing its contradictory. But the name of the suppositio itself has no contradictory, except with reference to a wider and inclusive suppositio >. CHAPTER VII IMMEDIATE INFERENCES i. Under the general title of Immediate Inference Logicians discuss three subjects, namely, Opposition, Con- version, and Obversion ; to which some writers add other forms, such as Whole and Part in Connotation, Contraposi- tion, Inversion, etc. Of Opposition, again, all recognise four modes : Subalternation, Contradiction, Contrariety and Sub- contrariety. The only peculiarities of the exposition upon which we are now entering are, that it follows the lead of the three Laws of Thought, taking first those modes of Immediate Inference in which Identity is most important, then those which plainly involve Contradiction and Excluded Middle ; and that this method results in separating the modes of Oppo- sition, connecting Subalternation with Conversion, and the other modes with Obversion. To make up for this departure from usage, the four modes of Opposition will be brought together again in 9. 2. Subalternation. Opposition being the relation of propositions that have the same matter and differ only in form (as A., E., I., O.), propositions of the forms A. and I. are said to be Subalterns in relation to one another, and so are E. and O. ; the universal of each quality being distinguished as ' subalternans,' and the particular as ' sub-alternate.' It follows from the principle of Identity that, the matter of the propositions being the same, if A. is true I. is true, and that if E. is true O. is true ; for A. and E. predicate something of All S or Allmen ; and since I. and O. make the same predicate of IMMEDIATE INFERENCES 77 Some S or Some men, the sense of these particular propositions has already been predicated in A. or E. If All S is P, Some S is P; if No S is P, Some S is not P ; or, if All men are fond of laughing. Some men are ; if No men are exempt from ridicule, Some men are not. Similarly, if I. is false A. is false ; if O. is false E. is false. If we deny any predication about Some S, we must deny it of All S ; since in denying it of Some, we have denied it of at least part of All ; and whatever is false in one form of words is false in any other. On the other hand, if I. is true, we do not know that A. is ; nor if O. is true, that E. is ; for to infer from Some to All would be going beyond the evidence. We shall see in discussing Induction that the great problem of that part of Logic is, to determine the conditions under which we may in reality transcend this rule and infer from Some to All; though even there it will appear that, formally, the rule is observed. For the present it is enough that I. is an immediate inference from A., and O. from E. ; but that A. is not an immediate inference from I., nor E. from O. 3. Connotative Subalternation. We have seen (chap. iv. 6) that if the connotation of one term is only part of another's its denotation is greater and includes that other's. Hence genus and species stand in subaltern relation, and whatever is true of the genus is true of the species : If All animal life is dependent on vegetation, All human life is dependent on vegetation. On the other hand, whatever is not true of the species or narrower term, cannot be true of the whole genus : If it is false that ' All human life is happy J it is false that ' All animal life is happy* Similar inferences may be drawn from the subaltern rela- tion of predicates ; affirming the species we affirm the genus. To take Mill's example, if Socrates is a man, Socrates is a living creature. On the other hand, denying the genus we deny the species : if Socrates is not vicious, Socrates is not drunken. 78 LOGIC : DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE It cannot be said that such cases as these are generally recognised by Logicians as immediate inferences coming under the principle of Identity. They are so regarded by Mill and Bain ; but probably most authorities upon our science would treat them as imperfect syllogisms, requiring another premise to legitimate the conclusion, as thus : All animal life is dependent on vegetation ; All human life is animal life ; .: All human life is dependent on "vegetation. Or again : All men are living creatures ; Socrates is a man ; .*. Socrates is a living creature. The decision of this issue seems to turn upon the question (cf. chap. vi. 3) how far a Logician is entitled to assume that the terms he uses are understood, and that the identities involved in their meanings will be recognised. And to this question, for the sake of consistency, one of two answers is required, failing which there remains the rule of thumb. First, it may be held that no term is understood except those that are defined in expounding the science, such as * genus ' and * species/ * connotation ' and * denotation.' But very few Logicians observe this limitation ; few would hesitate to substitute ' not- wise* for * foolish.' Yet by what right? Malvolio being foolish, to prove that he is not-wise, we may construct the following syllogism : Foolish is not-wise ; Malvolio is foolish; .'. Malvolio is not-wise. Is this necessary ? If not, why not ? Secondly, it may be held that all terms may be assumed as understood (amongst those native to the language) unless a definition is challenged. This principle will justify the sub- stitution of ' not-wise ' for * foolish ' ; but it will also legitimate the above cases (concerning ' human life ' and ' Socrates ') as immediate inferences, with innumerable others that might be IMMEDIATE INFERENCES 79 based upon the doctrine of relative names, as, for example, The hunter missed his aim : therefore, The prey escaped. And from this principle it will further follow that all apparent syllogisms, having one premise a verbal proposition, are immediate inferences (cf. chap. ix. 4). Closely connected with such cases as the above are those mentioned by Archbishop Thomson as "Immediate Inferences by added Determinants " (Laws of Thought, 87). He takes the case : * A negro is a fellow -creature : therefore, A negro in suffering is a fellow-creature in suffering? This rests upon the principle that to increase the connotations of two terms by the same attribute or determinant does not affect the relationship of their denotations, since it must equally diminish (if at all) the denotations of both classes, by excluding the same individuals, if any want the given attribute. But, of course, this principle is true only when the added attribute is not merely the same verbally, but has the same significance in qualifying both terms. We cannot argue A mouse is an animal; therefore, A large mouse is a large animal ; for ' large ' is an attribute relative to the normal magnitude of the thing described. 4. Conversion is Immediate Inference by transposing the terms of a given proposition without altering its quality. If the quantity is also unaltered, the inference is called * Simple Conversion ' ; but if the quantity is changed from universal to particular, it is called ' Conversion by limitation ' or ' per accidens? The given proposition is called the ' convertend ' ; that which is derived from it, the ' converse.' Departing from the usual order of exposition, I have taken up Conversion next to Subalternation, because it is generally thought to rest upon the principle of Identity, and because it seems to be a good method to exhaust the forms that come only under Identity before going on to those that involve Contradiction and Excluded Middle. Some, indeed, dispute the claims of Conversion to illustrate the principle of Identity ; and if the sufficient statement of that principle be ' A is A,' it 8o LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE may be a question how Conversion or any other mode of inference can be referred to it. But if we state it as above (chap. vi. 3), that whatever is true in one form of words is true in any other, there is no difficulty in applying it to Conver- sion. Thus, to take the simple conversion of I., Some S is P ; .'. Some P is S. Some poets are men of business ; .*. Some men of business are poets. Here the convertend and the converse say the same thing, and this is true if that is. We have, then, two cases of simple conversion : of I. (as above) and of E. For E. : No Sis P; .'.No Pis S. No ruminants are carnivores; .*. No carnivores are ruminants. In converting I., the predicate (P) when taken as the new subject, being preindesignate, is treated as particular, according to the rule, ' not to go beyond the evidence ' (chap. vi. 4) ; and in converting K, the predicate (P), when taken as the new subject, is treated as universal, according to the rule in chap. iv. i. A. is the one case of conversion by limitation : All S is P; .'. Some P is S. All cats are animals ; .'. Some animals are cats. And here the treatment of the predicate as particular, when taking it for the new subject, is according to the rule in chap. iv. i. Palpably, to infer that All animals are cats would never do. The validity of conversion by limitation may be shown thus : if, All S is P, then, by subalternation, Some S is P, and therefore, by simple conversion, Some P is S. O. cannot be truly converted. If we take the proposition : Some S is not P, to convert this into No P is S, or Some P is not S, would break the rule in chap. vi. 4 ; since S, undis- tributed in the convertend, would be distributed in the con- verse. If we are told that SB .'. B d 5 6 2 " u 4) 1 i *i 1 > > > O 1 * *0 oJ III 111 2 - l '1 1 r ll i g rt 10 '- 1 > fl s 11 11 O O ^ CO CO S > ^ 1 ^ * 1 kTS fcTN O OT o o g, S II <*-! rf to 53 OJ > * 1 y So So ^ * s Co Co "^ i OQ 5 ^> en | g U r r | *** ** O o 1 1 S 8 * ^ to ^ co ^ . ^ . ^ . M E3 ^ S ^ o "^ Co ^ Co IMMEDIATE INFERENCES 89 In this table a and b stand for not-A and not-B and had better be read thus : for No A is b, No A is not-B ; for All b is a (col. 6), All not-B is not-A ; and so on. It may not, at first, be obvious why the process of alternately obverting and converting any proposition should ever come to an end ; though it will, no doubt, be considered a very for- tunate circumstance that it always does end. On examining the results, it will be found that the cause of its ending is the inconvertibility of O. For E., when obverted, becomes A.; every A., when converted, degenerates into I. ; every I., when obverted, becomes O. ; O cannot be converted, and to obvert it again is merely to restore the former proposition : so that the whole process moves on to inevitable dissolution. I. and O. are exhausted by three transformations, whilst A. and E. will each endure seven. Except Obversion, Conversion and Contraposition, it has not been usual to bestow special names on these processes or their results. But the form in columns 7 and 10 (Some a is b Some a is not B ), where the original predicate is affirmed or denied of the contradictory of the original subject, has been thought by Dr. Keynes to deserve a distinctive title, and he has called it the 'Inverse.' Observe, however, that, although the Inverse is one form, Inversion is not one process, but is obtained by different processes from E. and A. respectively. In this it differs from Obversion, Conversion, and Contraposi- tion, each of which stands for one process. The Inverse form has been objected to on the ground that the inference All A is B .: Some not-A is not B, distributes B (as predicate of a negative proposition), though it was given as undistributed (as predicate of an affirmative proposition). But Dr. Keynes defends it on the ground that (i) it is obtained <* obversions and conversions which are all legitimate ; and that although All A is B does not distribute B in relation to yi, it does distribute B in relation to some not-A (namely, in relation to whatever not-A is not-J3). This is one reason why, in stating the rule in chap. vi. 4, I have written : " an immediate go LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE inference ought to contain nothing that is not contained, or formally implied^ in the proposition from which it is inferred " ; and have maintained that every term formally implies its contradictory. ii. Immediate Inferences from Conditionals are those which consist (i) in changing a Disjunctive into a Hypo- thetical, or a Hypothetical into a Disjunctive, or either into a Categorical; and (2) in the relations of Opposition and the equivalences of Obversion, Conversion, and secondary or compound processes, which we have already examined in respect of Categoricals. As no new principles are involved, it may suffice to exhibit some of the results. We have already seen (chap, v. 4) how Disjunctives may be read as Hypotheticals and Hypothetical as Categoricals. And, as to opposition, if we recognise four forms of Hypo- thetical A. I. E. O., these plainly stand to one another in a Square of Opposition, just as Categoricals do. Thus A. and E. (If A is B) C is D) and If A is B, C is not D) are contraries, but not contradictories ; since both may be false (C may sometimes be D, and sometimes not), though they cannot both be true. And if they are both false, their subalter- nates are both true, being respectively the contradictories of the universals of opposite quality, namely, I. of E., and O. of A. But in the case of Disjunctives, we cannot set out a satisfactory Square of Opposition ; because, as we saw (chap. v. 4), the forms required for E. and O. are not to iunctives, but Exponibles. The Obverse, Converse, and Contrapositive, > theticals are exhibited thus : DATUM, OBVERSS. A. IfAisB.C is D IfAisB.C is not a\ I. Sometimes when A is B, C is D Sometimes when A is E. If A is B, C is not D If A is B, C is d O. Sometimes when A is B, C is not D Sometimes when A is IMMEDIATE INFERENCES 91 CONVERSE. CONTRAPOSITIVE. Sometimes when C is D, A is B If C is d, A is not B Sometimes when C is D, A is B (none) IfC is D, A is not B Sometimes when C is d, A is B (none) Sometimes when C is d, A is B As to Disjunctives, the attempt to put them through these different forms immediately destroys their disjunctive character. Still, given any proposition in the form A is either B or C, we can state the propositions that give the sense of obversion, conversion, etc., thus : OBVERSE. A is not both b and c ; CONVERSE. Something either B or C is A ; CONTRAPOSITIVE. Nothing that is both b and c is A. For a Disjunctive in I., of course, there is no Contrapositive. Given a Disjunctive in the form either A is B or C is D, we may write for its Obverse In no case is A b> and C at the same time d. But no Converse or Contrapositive of such a Dis- junctive can be obtained, except by first casting it into the hypothetical or categorical form. The reader who wishes to pursue this subject further, will find it elaborately treated in Dr. Keynes' Formal Logic, Part II. ; to which work the above chapter is indebted. CHAPTER VIII. ORDER OF TERMS, EULER'S DIAGRAMS, LOGICAL EQUATIONS, EXISTENTIAL IMPORT OF PROPOSITIONS i. Which Term is the Subject and which the Predicate of a proposition ? In most of the exemplary propositions cited by Logicians it will be found that the subject is a substantive and the predicate an adjective, as in Men are mortal. But, in literature, sentences in which the adjective comes first are not uncommon, as Loud was the applause, Dark is the fate of man, Great is tfie glory of the conquering sword. Here, then, ' loud,' 4 dark ' and * great ' occupy the place of the logical subject. Are they really the. subject, or must we alter the order of such sentences into The applause was loud, etc.t If we do, and then proceed to convert, we get Loud was the applause, or (more scrupulously) Some loud noise was the applause. The last form, it is true, gives the subject a substantive word, but * applause' has become the predicate; and if the substantive ' noise ' was not implied in the first form, Loud is the applause^ by what right is it now inserted ? The recognition of Conver- sion, in fact, requires us to admit that, formally, in a logical proposition, the term preceding the copula is subject and the one following is predicate. And, of course, materially con- sidered, the mere order of terms in a proposition can make no difference in the method of proving it, nor in the inferences that can be drawn from it. Still, if the question is, how we may best cast a literary sen- tence into logical form, good grounds for a definite answer may perhaps be found. We must not try to stand upon the EULER'S DIAGRAMS 93 naturalness of expression, for Dark is the fate of man is quite as natural as Man is mortal. When the purpose is not merely to state a fact, but also to express our feelings about it, to place the grammatical predicate first may be perfectly natural and most effective. But the grounds of a logical order of statement must be found in its adaptation to the purposes of proof and inference. Now general propositions are those from which most inferences can be drawn, which, therefore, it is most important to establish if true ; and they are also the easiest to disprove if false, since a single negative instance suffices to establish the contradictory. It follows that, in re-casting a literary or colloquial sentence for logical purposes, we should try to obtain a form in which the subject is distributed is either a singular term or a general term predesignate as ' All ' or ' No.' Seeing, then, that most adjectives connote a single attribute, whilst most substantives connote more than one attribute ; and that therefore the denotation of adjectives is usually wider than that of substantives ; in any proposition, one term of which is an adjective and the other a substantive, if either can be distributed in relation to the other, it is nearly sure to be the substantive ; so that to take the substantive term for subject is our best chance of obtaining an universal pro- position. These considerations seem to justify the practice of Logicians in selecting their examples. For similar reasons, if both terms of a proposition are sub- stantive, the one with the lesser denotation is (at least in affirmative propositions) the more suitable subject, as Cats are carnivores. And if one term is abstract, that is the more suitable subject ; for, as we have seen, an abstract term may be interpreted by a corresponding concrete one distributed, as Kindness is infectious ; that is, All kind actions suggest imitation. If, however, a controvertist has no other object in view than to refute some general proposition laid down by an opponent, a particular proposition is all that he need disentangle from any statement that serves his purpose. 2. Toward understanding clearly the relations of the terms 94 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE of a proposition, it is often found useful to employ diagrams \ and the diagrams most in use are the circles of Euler. These circles represent the denotation of the terms. Suppose the proposition to be All hollow-horned animals ruminate : then, if we could collect all ruminants upon a prairie, and enclose them with a circular palisade; and segregate from amongst them all the hollow-horned beasts, and enclose them with another ring-fence inside the other ; one way of interpreting the proposition (namely, in denotation) would be figured to us thus : FIG. i. An Universal Affirmative may also state a relation between two terms whose denotation is co-extensive. A definition always does this, as Man is a rational animal ; and this, of course, we cannot represent by two distinct circles, but at best by one with a thick circumference, to suggest that two coincide, thus: FIG. 2. MEN OR RATIONAL ANIMALS The Particular Affirmative Proposition may be represented in several ways. In the first place, bearing in mind that 'Some' means ' some at least, it may be all,' an I. proposition may be represented by Figs, i and 2 ; for it is true that Some EULER'S DIAGRAMS 95 horned animals ruminate, and that Some men are rational. Secondly, there is the case in which the 'Some things' of which a predication is made are, in fact, not all ; whilst the predicate, though not given as distributed, yet might be so given if we wished to state the whole truth ; as if we say Some men are Chinese. This case is also represented by Fig. i, the outside circle representing ' Men,' and the inside one * Chinese.' Thirdly, the predicate may appertain to some only of the subject, but to a great many other things, as in Some horned beasts are domestic ; for it is true that some are not, and that certain other kinds of animals are, domestic. This case, there- fore, must be illustrated by overlapping circles, thus : FIG. 3. The Universal Negative is sufficiently represented by a single Fig. (4) : two circles mutually exclusive, thus : FIG. 4. That is, No horned beasts are carnivorous. Lastly, the Particular Negative may be represented by any of the Figs, i, 3, and 4 ; for it is true that Some ruminants are not hollow-horned, that Some horned animals are not domestic, and that Some horned beasts are not carnivorous. 96 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Besides their use in illustrating the denotative force of pro- positions, these circles may also be used to verify the results of Obversion, Conversion, and the secondary modes of Immediate Inference. Thus the Obverse of A. is clear enough on glancing at Figs, i and 2 ; for if we agree that whatever term's denota- tion is represented by a given circle, the denotation of the contradictory term shall be represented by the space outside that circle ; then, of course, if it is true that All hollow-horned animals are ruminants, it is at the same time true that No hollow-horned animals are not-ruminants ; since none of the hollow-horned are found outside the palisade that encloses the ruminants. The Obverse of I., E. or O. may be verified in a similar manner. As to the Converse, a Definition is of course susceptible of Simple Conversion, and this is shown by Fig. 2 : ' Men are rational animals ' and ' Rational animals are men.' But any other A. proposition is presumably convertible only by limita- tion, and this is shown by Fig. i ; where All hollow-horned animals are ruminants, but we can only say that Some ruminants are hollow-horned. That I. may be simply converted may be seen in Fig. 3, which represents the least that an I. proposition can mean ; and that E. may be simply converted is manifest in Fig. 4. As for O., we know that it cannot be converted, and this is made plain enough by glancing at Fig. i ; for that represents the O., Some ruminants are not hollow -horned, but also shows this to be compatible with All hollow-horned animals are ruminants (A.). Now in conversion there is (by definition) no change of quality. The converse, then, of Some ruminants are not hollow-horned must be a negative proposition, having 'hollow-horned ' for its subject, either in E. or O. ; but these would be respectively the contrary and contradictory of All hollow-horned animals are ruminants ; and, therefore, if this is true, they must both be false. But (referring still to Fig. i) the legitimacy of contrapositing O. is equally clear ; for if Some ruminants are not hollow- LOGICAL EQUATIONS 97 horned, Some animals that are not hollow-horned are ruminants, namely, all the animals between the two ring-fences. Similar inferences may be illustrated from Figs. 3 and 4. And the Contraposition of A. may be verified by Figs, i and 2, and the Contraposition of E. by Fig. 4. Lastly, the Inverse of A. is plain from Fig. i Some things that are not hollow-horned are not ruminants, namely, all things that lie outside the outer circle and are neither * ruminants ' nor 'hollow-horned.' And the Inverse of E. may be studied in Fig. 4 Some things that are not-horned beasts are carnivorous. Notwithstanding the facility and clearness of the demon- strations thus obtained, it may be said that a diagrammatic method, representing denotations, is not properly logical, It seems to be agreed that fundamentally the relation asserted (or denied) to exist between the terms of a proposition, is a relation between the terms as determined by their attributes or conno- tation ; whether we take Mill's view, that a proposition asserts that the connotation of the subject is a mark of the connotation of the predicate ; or Dr. Venn's view, that things denoted by the subject (as having its connotation) have (or have not) the attribute connoted by the predicate; or, the Conceptualist view, that a judgment is a relation of concepts (that is, of con- notations). At any rate, it is certain that, with a few exceptions artificially framed (such as ' kings now reigning in Europe '), the denotation of a term is never directly and exhaustively known, but consists merely in ' all things that have the conno- tation.' And I venture to think that the value of logical training depends very much upon our habituating ourselves to construe propositions, and to realise the force of inferences from them, according to the connotation of their terms ; and that, therefore, a student does well not to turn too hastily to the circles, but rather to regard them as means of verifying in denotation the conclusions that he has already learnt to recog- nise as necessary in connotation. (Keynes: Formal Logic, Part II. c. 4.) 3. The equational treatment of propositions is closely $8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE connected with the diagrammatic. Hamilton thought it a great merit of his plan of quantifying the predicate, that thereby every proposition is reduced to its true form an equation. According to this doctrine, the proposition All X is all Y(U.) equates X and Y; the proposition All X is some y(A.) equates X with some part of Y; and similarly with the other affirmatives (Y. and I.). And so far it is easy to follow his meaning: the Xs are identical with some or all the Ys. But, coming to the negatives, the equational interpretation is certainly less obvious. The proposition No X is Y (E.) cannot be said in any sense to equate X and Y ; though, if we obvert it into All X is some not- V, we have (in the same sense, of course, as the above affirmative forms) X equated with part at least of ' not-Y.' But what is the sense ? Clearly not the same as that in which mathematical terms are equated, namely, in respect of some mode of quantity. For if we may say Some X is some Y t these Xs that are also Ys are not merely the same in number, or mass, or figure ; they are the same in every respect, both quantitative and qualitative, have the same .positions in time and place, are in fact identical. The proposition 2 + 2 = 4 means that any two things added to any other two are, in respect of number, equal to any three things added to one other ; and this is true of all things that can be counted, how- ever much they may differ in other ways. But AH X is all Y means that Xs and Ys are the same things, although they have different names when viewed in different aspects or relations. Thus all equilateral triangles are equiangular triangles ; but in one case they are named from the equality of their angles, and in the other from the equality of their sides. Similarly, 'British subjects' and * subjects of Queen Victoria' are the same people, named in one case from the person of the Crown, and in the other from the Imperial Government. These logical equations, then, are in truth identities of deno- tation ; and they are fully illustrated by the relations of circles described in the previous section. LOGICAL EQUATIONS 99 When we are told that logical propositions are to be con- sidered as equations, we naturally expect to be shown some interesting developments of method in analogy with the equations of Mathematics; but from Hamilton's innovations no such thing results. This cannot be said, however, of the equations of Symbolic Logic ; which are the starting-point of very remarkable processes of ratiocination. As the subject of Symbolic Logic, as a whole, lies beyond the compass of this work, it will be enough to give Dr. Venn's equations cor- responding with the four propositional forms of common Logic. According to this system, universal propositions are to be regarded as not necessarily implying the existence of their terms ; and therefore, instead of giving them a positive form, they are translated into symbols that express what they deny. For example, the proposition All devils are ugly need not imply that any such things as * devils' really exist; but it certainly does imply that Devils that are not ugly do not exist. Similarly, the proposition No angels are ugly implies that Angels that are ugly do not exist. Therefore, writing x for * devils,' y for 'ugly,' and y for ' not-ugly,' we may express A., the universal affirmative, thus : A. xy = o. That is, x that is not y is nothing ; or, Devils that are not-ugly do not exist. And, similarly, writing x for * angels ' and y for * ugly,' we may express E., the universal negative, thus : E. xy = o. That is, x that isy is nothing; or, Angels that are ugly do not exist. On the other hand, particular propositions are regarded as implying the existence of their terms, and the corresponding equations are so framed as to express existence. With this end in view, the symbol v is adopted to represent ' something/ or indeterminate reality, or more than nothing. Then, taking any particular affirmative, such as Some metaphysicians are obscure, and writing x for ' metaphysicians,' and y for * obscure/ we may express it thus : I. xy = v. ioo LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE That is, x that is y is something ; or, Metaphysicians that are obscure do occur in experience (however few they may be, or whether they be all obscure). And, similarly, taking any particular negative, such as Some giants are not cruel^ and writing x for * giants ' and y for ' not-cruel,' we may express it thus: O. xy = v. That is, x that is not y is something ; or, giants that are not-cruel do occur in romances, if nowhere else. Clearly, these equations are, like Hamilton's, concerned with denotation. A. and E. affirm that the compound terms xy and xy have no denotation ; and I. and O. declare that xy and xy have denotation, or stand for something. He-re, how- ever, the resemblance to Hamilton's system ceases ; for the Symbolic Logic, by operating upon more than two terms simultaneously, by adopting the algebraic signs of operation, + > ~ > x > = (with a special signification), and manipulating the symbols by quasi-algebraic processes, obtains results which the common Logic reaches (if at all) with much greater difficulty. If, indeed, the value of logical systems were to be judged of by the results obtainable, formal deductive Logic would probably be superseded. And, as a mental discipline, there is much to be said in favour of the symbolic method. But, as an introduction to philosophy, the common Logic must hold its ground. (Venn's Symbolic Logic, c. 7.) 4. Whether Formal Logic involves any general assumption as to the real existence of the terms of propositions is a ques- tion that has lately excited some interest, so that a few remarks upon it will be expected here. But if my treatment of it seem somewhat dogmatic, brevity must be my excuse. I observe, then, in the first place, that Logic treats primarily of the relations implied in propositions. This follows from its being the science of proof for all sorts of (qualitative) proposi- tions ; since all sorts of propositions have nothing in common except the relations they imply. But, secondly, relations without terms of some sort are not EXISTENTIAL IMPORT 101 to be thought of; and, hence, even the most formal illustra- tions of logical doctrines comprise such terms as S and P, X and Y, or x and y, in a symbolic or representative character. Terms, therefore, of some sort are assumed to exist (together with their negatives or contradictories)^ the purposes of logical manipulation. Thirdly, however, that Formal Logic cannot directly involve the existence of any particular concrete terms, such as * man ' or ' mountain/ is implied in the word * formal,' that is, * con- fined to what is common or abstract ' ; since the only thing common to all terms is to be related in some way to other terms. The actual existence of any concrete thing can only be known by experience, as with * man ' or ' mountain ' ; or by methodically justifiable inference from experience, as with ' atom ' or * ether.' Nevertheless, fourthly, the existence or non-existence of par- ticular terms may come to be implied : namely, wherever the very fact of existence, or of some condition of existence, is an hypothesis or datum. Thus, given the proposition All S is P, to be P is made a condition of the existence of S : whence it follows that an S that is not P does not exist (xy = o). On the further hypothesis that S exists, it follows that P exists. On the hypothesis that S does not exist, the existence of P is problematic ; but, then, if P does exist we cannot convert the proposition ; since Some P is S (P existing) would involve the existence of S ; which is contrary to the hypothesis. Assuming that Universals do nof, whilst Particulars do, imply the existence of their subjects, we cannot infer the subalternate (I. or O.) from the subalternans (A. or E.), for that is to ground the actual on the problematic ; and for the same reason we cannot convert A. per acddens. Assuming, again, a certain suppositio or universe, to which in a given discussion every argument shall refer, then, any pro- positions whose terms lie outside that suppositio are irrelevant, and for the purposes of that discussion may be called false. Thus propositions which, according to the doctrine of Opposi- 102 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE tion, appear to be Contradictories, may then cease to be so ; for of Contradictories one is true and the other false ; but, in the case supposed, both are technically false. If the subject of discussion be Zoology, all propositions about centaurs or unicorns are absurd; and such specious Contradictories as No centaurs play the lyre Some centaurs do play the lyre ; or All unicorns fight with lions Some unicorns do not fight with lions, are both false or meaningless, because in Zoology there are no centaurs nor unicorns ; and, therefore, in this reference, the propositions are not really contradictory. But if the subject of discussion or suppositio be Mythology or Heraldry, such propositions as the above are to the purpose, and form legitimate pairs of Contradictories. In Formal Logic, in short, we may make at discretion any assumption whatever as to the existence, or as to any condition of the existence of any particular term or terms ; and then certain implications and conclusions follow in consistency with that hypothesis or datum. Still, our conclusions will them- selves be only hypothetical, depending on the truth of the datum ; and, of course, until this is empirically ascertained, we are as far as ever from empirical reality. (Venn : Symbolic Logic, c. 6 ; Keynes : formal Logic> Part II. c. 7.) CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE i. A Mediate Inference is a proposition that depends for proof upon two or more other propositions, so connected together by one or more terms (which the evidentiary proposi- tions, or each pair of them, have in common) as to justify a certain conclusion, namely, the proposition in question. The type or (more properly) the unit of all such modes of proof, when of a strictly logical kind, is the Syllogism, to which we shall see that all other modes are reducible. It may be exhibited symbolically thus : MisP; SisM: .-. S is P. Syllogisms may be classified, as to quantity, into Universal or Particular, according to the quantity of the conclusion ; as to quality, into Affirmative or Negative, according to the quality of the conclusion ; and, as to relation, into Categorical, Hypothetical and Disjunctive, according as all their proposi- tions are categorical, or one (at least) of their evidentiary propositions is a hypothetical or a disjunctive. We will begin with Categorical Syllogisms, of which the following is a concrete example : All authors are vain ; Cicero is an author : .*. Cicero is vain. Here we may suppose that there are no direct means of know- ing that Cicero is vain ; but we happen to know that all authors 104 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE are vain and that he is an author ; and these two propositions put together unmistakably imply that he is vain. In other words, we do not at first know any relation between Cicero ' and 'vanity'; but we know that these two terms are severally related to a third term, ' author/ hence called a Middle Term ; and thus we perceive, by mediate evidence, that they are re- lated to one another. This sort of proof bears an obvious re- semblance to the mathematical proof of equality between two quantities, that cannot be directly compared, by showing the equality of each of them to some third quantity : A = B = C .-. A = C. Here B is a middle term. We have to inquire, then, what conditions must be satisfied in order that a Syllogism may be formally conclusive or valid. A specious Syllogism that is not really valid is called a Para syllogism. 2. General Canons of the Syllogism. (1) A Syllogism contains three, and no more, distinct pro- positions. (2) A Syllogism contains three, and no more, distinct uni- vocal terms. These two Canons imply one another. Three propositions with less than three terms can only be connected in some of the modes of Immediate Inference. Three propositions with more than three terms do not show that connection of two terms by means of a third, which is the desideratum for proving a Mediate Inference. If we write All authors are vain ; Cicero is a statesman there are four terms and no middle term, and therefore there is no proof. Or if we write All authors are vain ; Cicero is an author ; .'. Cicero is a statesman here the term ' statesman ' occurs without any voucher ; it appears in the inference but not in the evidence, and therefore violates the maxim of all formal proof, 'not to go beyond CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE 105 the evidence' (chap. vi. 4). It is true that if any one argued All authors are vain ; Cicero wrote on philosophy ; /. Cicero is vain this could not be called a bad argument or a material fallacy ; but it would be a needless departure from the form of expression in which the connection between the evidence and the inference is most easily seen ; it would generally be called a formal fallacy. Still a mere adherence to the same form of words in the expression of terms is not enough : we must also attend to their meaning. For if the same words be used ambiguously (as ' author ' now for ' father ' and anon for ' man of letters ') it becomes as to its meaning two terms ; so that we have four in all. Then, if the ambiguous term be the Middle, no connection is shown between the other two ; if either of the others be ambiguous, something seems to be inferred which has never been really given in evidence. The above two Canons are, indeed, involved in the definition of a categorical syllogism, which may be thus stated : A Cate- gorical Syllogism is a form of proof or reasoning (way of giving reasons) in which one categorical proposition is established by comparing two others that contain together only three terms, or that have one and only one term in common. The proposition established, derived, or inferred, is called the Conclusion : the evidentiary propositions by which it is proved are called the Premises. The term common to the premises, by means of which the other terms are compared, is called the Middle Term. For the other terms, the subject of the conclusion is called the Minor Term ; the predicate of the conclusion, the Major Term. The premise in which the minor term occurs is called the Minor Premise ; that in which the major term occurs is called the Major Premise. And a Syllogism is usually written thus : 106 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Major Premise All Authors (Middle) are vain (Major) ; Minor Premise Cicero (Minor) is an author (Middle) : Conclusion .*. Cicero (Minor) is vain (Major). Here we have three propositions with three terms, each term occurring twice. The Minor and Major Terms are so called, because, when the conclusion is an universal affirmative (which only occurs in Barbara ; see chap. x. 6), its subject and predicate are respectively the less and the greater in extent or denotation. It should be carefully noticed that the premises are called after the peculiar terms they contain : the expressions ' Major Premise ' and * Minor Premise ' have nothing to do with the order in which the premises are presented ; though it is usual to place the Major first. (3) No term must be distributed in the conclusion unless it is distributed in the premises. It is usual to give this as one of the General Canons of the Syllogism ; but we have seen (chap. vi. 6) that it is of wider application. Indeed, ' not to go beyond the evidence ' belongs to the definition of formal proof. A breech of this rule in a syllogism is the fallacy of Illicit Process of the Minor, or of the Major, according to which term has been unwarrantably distri- buted. The following parasyllogism illicitly distributes both terms of the conclusion : All poets are pathetic ; Some orators are not poets ; .*. No orators are pathetic. (4) The Middle Term must be distributed at least once in the premises. For the use of mediate evidence is to show the relation of terms that cannot be directly compared ; this is only possible if the Middle Term furnishes the ground of comparison ; and this (in Logic) requires that the whole denotation of the Middle should be either included or excluded by one of the others ; since if we only know that the other terms are related to some of the Middle, their respective relations may not be with the same part of it. Indeed, if the Middle is undistributed in both CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE 107 premises, Whately regards it as ambiguous ; in which case the pretended syllogism depending on it has four terms ; so that this 4th Canon may be regarded as reducible to the 2nd. It is true that in what has been strangely called the " numerically definite syllogism," an inference may be drawn, though our canon seems to be violated. Thus : 60 sheep in 100 are horned ; 60 sheep in 100 are blackfaced ; .*. at least 20 blackfaced sheep in 100 are horned. But such an argument, though I presume it may be correct Arithmetic, is not Logic at all ; and when such numerical evidence is obtainable the comparatively indefinite arguments of Logic are needless. Another apparent exception more to the purpose is the following : Most men are 5 feet high ; Most men are semi-rational ; .-. Some semi-rational things are 5 feet high. Here the Middle Term (men) is distributed in neither premise, yet the indisputable conclusion is a logical proposition. Observe, however, that the premises are really arithmetical ; for ' most ' means ' more than half,' or more than 50 per cent. For Mediate Inference depending on truly logical premises, then, it is necessary that one premise should distribute the Middle Term ; and the reason of this may be illustrated even by the above supposed exceptions. For in them the premises are such that, though neither premise by itself distributes the Middle, yet they always do so between them, and that with a certain surplus. For if each premise dealt with exactly half the Middle, thus barely distributing it between them, there would be no logical proposition inferrible (though, of course, there might be a conclusion of numerical probability). We require that the Middle, as used in one premise, should necessarily overlap the Middle as used in the other, so as to furnish common ground for comparing the other terms. Hence I have defined the middle as * that Term common to both premises by means of which the other terms are compared. 1 loS LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE (5) One at least of the premises must be affirmative; or from two negative premises nothing can be inferred. The fourth Canon required that the middle term should be given us distributed, or in its whole extent, in order to afford sure ground of comparison for the others. But that such comparison may be effected, something more is requisite ; the relation of the other terms to the Middle must be of a certain character. One at least of them must be, as to its extent or denotation, partially or wholly identified with the Middle ; so that to that extent it may be known to bear to the other term, whatever relation we are told that so much of the Middle bears to that other term. Now, identity of denotation can only be predicated in an affirmative proposition : one premise, then, must be affirmative. If, however, both premises are negative, we only know that both the other terms are partly or wholly excluded from the Middle, or are not identical with it in denotation : where they lie, then, in relation to one another we have no means of knowing. Similarly, in the mediate comparison of quantities, if we are told that A and C are both of them unequal to B, we can infer nothing as to the relation of C to A. Hence the premises No electors are sober ; No electors are independent however suggestive; do not formally justify us in inferring any connection between sobriety and independence. Formally to draw a conclusion, we must have affirmative grounds, such as in this case we may obtain by obverting both premises : All electors are not-sober ; All electors are not-independent ; .-. Some who are not-independent are not-sober. (6) (a) If one premise be negative, the conclusion must be negative : and (ft) to prove a negative conclusion, one premise must be negative. (a) For we have seen that one premise must be affirmative, and that thus one term must be partly (at least) identified with CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE 109 the Middle. If, then, the other premise, being negative, predicates the exclusion of the other term from the middle, this other term must be excluded from the first term, so lar as we know the first to be identical with the Middle : and this exclusion will be expressed by a negative conclusion. The analogy of the mediate comparison of quantities may here again be noticed : if A is equal to B, and B is unequal to C, A is unequal to C. (3) If both premises are affirmative, the relations of both terms to the Middle are more or less inclusive, and therefore furnish no ground for an exclusive inference. This also follows from the function of the Middle term. For the more convenient application of these canons to the testing of syllogisms, it is usual to derive from them three Corollaries : (i) Two particular premises yield no conclusion. For if both premises are affirmative all their terms are undis- tributed, the subjects by predesignation, the predicates by position (chap. v. i) ; and therefore the middle must be undistributed, and there can be no conclusion. If one premise is negative, its predicate is distributed by position : the other terms remaining undistributed. But, by Canon 6, the conclusion (if any be possible) must be negative ; and therefore its predicate, the major term, will be distributed. In the premises, therefore, both the middle and the major terms should be distributed, which is impossible: e.g., Some M is not P ; Some S is M ; .'. Some S is not P. Here, indeed, the major term is legitimately distributed (though the negative premise might have been the minor) ; but M, the middle term, is distributed in neither premise, and therefore there can be no conclusion. (ii) If one premise be particular, so is the conclusion. For, again, if both premises are affirmative, they only dis- tribute one term, the subject of the universal premise, and this no LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE must be the middle term. The minor term, therefore, is undistributed, and the conclusion must be particular. If one premise is negative, the two premises together can distribute only two terms, the subject of the universal and the predicate of the negative (which may be the same premise). One of these terms must be the middle ; the other (since the con- clusion is negative) must be the major. The minor term, there- fore, is undistributed, and the conclusion must be particular. (iii) From a particular major and a negative minor premise nothing can be inferred. For the minor premise being negative, the major premise must be affirmative (5th Canon); and therefore, being par- ticular, distributes the major term neither in its subject nor in its predicate. But since the conclusion must be negative (6th Canon), a distributed major term is demanded, e.g., Some M is P ; No S is M ; Here the minor and the middle terms are both distributed, but not the major (P) ; and, therefore, a negative conclusion is impossible. 3. First Principle or Axiom of the Syllogism. Hitherto in this chapter we have been analysing the conditions of valid mediate inference. We have seen that a single step of such inference, a Syllogism, contains when fully expressed in lan- guage three propositions and three terms, and that these terms must stand to one another in the relations required by the fourth, fifth, and sixth Canons. We now come to a principle which conveniently sums up these conditions ; it is called the Dictujn de omni et nullo, and may be stated thus : Whatever is predicated (affirmatively or negatively) of a Term distributed, In which Term another is given as (partly or wholly) included, May be predicated in like manner of (part or all of) the latter Term. CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE in Thus stated (nearly as by Whately in the introduction to his Logic) the Dictum follows line by line the course of a Syllogism in the First Figure (see chap. x. 2). To return to our former example : All authors are vain is the same as Vanity is pre- dicated of all authors ; Cicero is an author is the same as Cicero is included amongst authors ; therefore Cicero is vain, or Vanity may be predicated of Cicero. The Dictum then requires : (i) three propositions ; (2) three terms; (3) that the middle term be distributed ; (4) that one premise be affirmative, since only by an affirmative proposition can one term be given as included in another ; (5) that if one premise is negative the conclusion be so too, since whatever is predicated of the middle term is predicated in like manner of the minor. Thus far, then, the Dictum is wholly analytic or verbal, expressing no more than is implied in the definitions of * Syllogism ' and * Middle Term ' ; since (as we have seen) all the General Canons (except the third, which is a still more general condition of formal proof) are derivable from those definitions. However, the -Dictum makes a further statement of a synthetic or real character, namely, that when these conditions are fulfilled an inference is justified ; that then the major and minor terms are brought into comparison through the middle, and that the major term may be predi- cated affirmatively or negatively of all or part of the minor. It is this real assertion that justifies us in calling the Dictum an Axiom. 4. Whether the Laws of Thought may not fully explain the Syllogism without the need of any synthetic principle has, however, been made a question. Take such a syllogism as the following : All domesticated animals are useful ; All pugs are domesticated animals : .*. All pugs are useful. Here (an ingenious man might urge), having once identified pugs with domestic animals, that they are useful follows from the Law of Identity. If we attend to the meaning, and 1 12 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE remember that what is true in one form of words is true in any other form, then, all domesticated animals being useful, of course pugs are. It is merely a case of subalternation : we may put it in this way : All domesticated animals are useful ; .*. Some domesticated animals (e.g., pugs) are useful. The derivation of negative syllogisms from the Law of Contra- diction (he might add) may be shown in a similar manner. But the force of this ingenious argument depends on the participial clause * having once identified pugs with domestic animals.' If this is a distinct step of the reasoning, the above syllogism cannot be reduced to one step, cannot be exhibited as mere subalternation, nor be brought directly under the law of Identity. If 'pug,' Domestic,' and * useful' are distinct terms ; and if ' pug ' and * useful ' are only known to be connected because of their relations to * domestic ' : this is something more than the Laws of Thought provide for : it is not Immediate Inference, but Mediate ; and to justify it, scientific method requires that its conditions be generalised. The Dictum, then, as we have seen, does .generalise these conditions, and declares that when such conditions are satisfied a Mediate Inference is valid. But, after all (to go back a little), consider again that pro- position All pugs are domesticated animals : is it a distinct step of the reasoning ; that is to say, is it a Real Proposition ? If, indeed, * domesticated ' is no part of the definition of ' pug/ the proposition is real, and is a distinct part of the argument. But take such a case as this : All dogs are useful ; All pugs are dogs. Here we clearly have, in the minor premise, only a verbal pro- position : to be a dog is certainly part of the definition of * pug.' But, if so, the inference ' All pugs are useful ' involves no real mediation, and the argument is no more than this : All dogs are useful ; .-. Some dogs (e.g., pugs) are useful. CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE 113 Similarly, if the major premise be verbal, thus : All men are rational ; Socrates is a man to conclude that * Socrates is rational ' is no Mediate In- ference ; for so much was implied in the minor premise, 'Socrates is a man,' and the major premise adds nothing to this. Hence I conclude (as by anticipation in chap. vii. 3) that 'any apparent syllogism, having one premise a verbal pro- position, is really an Immediate Inference ' ; but that, if both premises are real propositions, the Inference is Mediate, and demands for its explanation something more than the Laws of Thought. I have not, however, always refrained from using Verbal Syllogisms as formal illustrations^ 5. Other kinds of Mediate Inference exist, yielding valid conclusions, without being truly syllogistic. Such are mathe- matical inferences of Equality, as A = B = C /. A = C. Here, according to the usual logical analysis, there are strictly four terms (i) A, (2) equal to B, (3) B, (4) equal to C. Similarly with the argument bfortiori, A>B>C .: (much more) A>C. This also is said to contain four terms : (i) A, (2) greater than B, (3) B, (4) greater than C. Such inferences are nevertheless intuitively sound, may be verified by trial (within the limits of sense-perception), and are generalised in appropriate axioms of their own, corresponding to the Dictum of the syllogism ; as ' Things equal to the same thing are equal to one another, 1 etc. Now, surely, this is an erroneous application of the usual logical analysis of propositions. Both Logic and Mathematics treat of the relations of terms ; but whilst Mathematics employs the sign = for only one kind of relation, and for that relation exclusive of the terms ; Logic employs the same signs (is or is not) for all relations, recognising only a difference of quality in predication, and treating every other difference of relation as H n 4 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE belonging to one of the terms related. Thus Logicians read A is equal to B : as if equal to B could possibly be a term co-relative with A. Whence it follows that the argument A = jB=C .'. A=C contains four terms ; though everybody sees that there are only three. In fact (as observed in chap. ii. 2) the sign of logical relation (is or is not), whilst usually adequate for class-reasoning (coin- herence) and sometimes extensible to causation (because a cause implies a class of events), should never be stretched to include other relations in such a way as to sacrifice intelligence to formalism. And, besides mathematical or quantitative relations, there are others (usually considered qualitative because indefinite) which cannot be justly expressed by the logical copula. We ought to read : B is before C ; A is before B : .-. A is before C. And in like manner A is simultaneous with B ; etc. Such arguments (as well as the mathematical) are intuitively sound and verifiable, and might be generalised in axioms if it were worth while : but it is not, because no method could be founded on such axioms. Custom justifies some Mediate Inferences, as, The Father of a father is a grand-father. Some cases, however, that at first seem obvious, are really delusive unless further data be supplied. Thus A co-exists with B) B with C ; .'. A with C is not sound unless B is an instantaneous event ; for if B is perdurable, A may co-exist with it at one time and C at another. Again : A is to the left of B, B of C; .'. A of C. This may pass ; but it is not a parallel argument that if A is north of B and B west of C, then A is north-west of C : for suppose that A is a mile to the north of B, and B a yard to the west of C, then A is practically north of C ; at least its westward position cannot be expressed in terms of the manner's compass. In such a case we require to know not only the directions but the CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE 115 distances of A and C from B ; and then the exact direction o A from C is an affair of mathematical calculation. Qualitative reasoning concerning position is only applicable to things in one dimension of space, or in time considered as having one dimension. Under this condition we may frame the following generalisation concerning all Mediate Inferences : Two terms definitely related to a third, and one of them positively, are related to one another as the other term is related to the third (that is, positively or negatively) ; provided that the relations given are of the same kind (that is, of Time, or Coinherence, or Likeness, or Equality). Thus, to illustrate by relations of Time B is simultaneous with C ; A is not simultaneous with B : .*. A is not simultaneous with C. Here the relations are of the same kind but of different logical quality, and (as in the syllogism) a negative copula in the premises leads to a negative conclusion. An examination in detail of particular cases would show that the above generalisation concerning all Mediate Inferences is subject to too many qualifications to be called an Axiom; it stands to the real Axioms (the Dictum^ etc.) as the notion of the Uniformity of Nature does to the definite principles of natural order (cf. chap. xiii. 9). CHAPTER X CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS i. The type of logical, deductive, mediate, categorical Inference is a Syllogism directly conformable with the Dictum : as All carnivores (M) are excitable (P) ; Cats (S) are carnivores (M) : .'. Cats (S) are excitable (P). In this example P is predicated of M, a term distributed ; in which term, M, S is given as included ; so that P may be pre- dicated of S. Many arguments, however, are of a type superficially different from the above : as No wise man (P) fears death (M) ; Balbus (S) fears death (M) : .*. Balbus (S) is not a wise man (P). In this example, instead of P being predicated of M, M is pre- dicated of P, and yet S is given as included not in P, but in M. The divergence of such a syllogism from the Dictum may, however, be easily shown to be superficial by writing, instead of No wise man fears death> the simple converse, No man who fears death is wise. Again : Some dogs (M) are friendly to man (P) ; All dogs (M) are carnivores (S) : .-. Some carnivores (S) are friendly to man (P). Here P is predicated of M undistributed; and instead of S being included in M, M is included in S : so that the diver- CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 117 gence from the type of syllogism to which the Dictum directly applies is still greater than in the former case. But if we transpose the premises, taking first All dogs (M) are carnivores (P), then P is predicated of M distributed ; and, simply converting the other premise, we get Some things friendly to man (S) are dogs (M) : whence it follows that Some things friendly to man (S) are carnivores (P) ; and this is the simple converse of the original conclusion. Once more : No pigs (P) are philosophers (M) ; Some philosophers (M) are hedonists (S) : .'. Some hedonists (S) are not pigs (P). In this case, instead of P being predicated of M distributed, M is predicated of P distributed ; and instead of S (or part of it) being included in M, we are told that some M is included in S. Still there is no real difficulty. To show that it is all right, simply convert both the premises. Then we have : No philosophers (M) are pigs (P) ; Some hedonists (S) are philosophers (M). Whence the same conclusion follows ; and the whole syllogism plainly conforms directly to the Dictum. Such departures as these from the normal syllogistic form are said to constitute differences of Figure (to be further de- fined in 2) ; and the processes by which they are shown to be unessential differences are called Reduction (for a fuller account of which, see 6). 2. Figure is determined by the position of the Middle Term in the premises ; of which position there are four possible variations. The middle term may be subject of the major premise, and predicate of the minor, as in the first example above; and this position, being directly conformable to the requirements of the Dictum, is called the First Figure. Or the middle term may be predicate of both premises, as in the second of the above examples ; and this is called the Second n8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Figure. Or the middle term may be subject of both premises, as in the third of the above examples ; and this is called the Third Figure. Or, finally, the middle term may be predicate of the major premise, and subject of the minor, as in the fourth example given above ; and this is the Fourth Figure. It may facilitate the recollection of this most important point if we schematise the figures thus : SL II. P iM s IM in. Mi P Ml S IV. P -y M M -S The horizontal lines represent the premises, and at the angles formed with them by the slanting or by the perpendicular lines the Middle Term occurs. Note further that the schema of the Fourth and last Figure resembles Z, the last letter of the alphabet : this helps one to remember it in contrast with the First, which is thereby also remembered. Figures II. and III. seem to stand back to back. 3. The Moods of each Figure are the modifications of it which arise from different combinations of propositions accord- ing to Quantity and Quality. In the First Figure, for example, four Moods are recognised ; A. A. A., E. A. E., A. 1. 1., E. I. O. A. AllMisP; A. All S is M : A. .'. All S is P. E. No M is P ; A. All S is M : E. /. No S is P. E. All M is P ; I. Some S is M : I. /. Some S is P. E. No M is P ; I. Some S is M : O. .'. Some S is not P : CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 119 Now, remembering that there are four Figures, and four kinds of propositions (A. I. E. O.), each of which propositions maybe Major Premise, Minor Premise, or Conclusion of a syllogism, it appears that in each Figure there may be 64 Moods, and therefore 256 in all. On examining these 256 Moods, how- ever, we find that only 24 of them are valid (i.e., of such a character that the conclusion strictly follows from the pre- mises), whilst 5 of these 24 are needless, because their con- clusions are 'weaker* or less extensive than the premises warrant ; that is to say, they are particular when they might be universal. Thus, in the First Figure, besides the above 4 Moods, A. A. I. and E. A. O. are valid in the sense of being conclusive ; but they are superfluous, because included in A. A. A. and E. A. E. Omitting then these 5 needless Moods, which are called ' Subalterns ' because their conclusions are subaltern (chap. vii. 2) to those of other Moods, there remain 1 9 Moods that are valid and generally recognised. 4. How these 19 Moods are determined must be our next inquiry. There are several ways more or less ingenious and interesting ; but all depend on the application, directly or indirectly, of the Six Canons, which were shown in the last chapter to be the conditions of Mediate Inference. (i) One way is to begin by finding what Moods of the First Figure conform to the Dictum. Now, the Dictum requires that, in the major premise, P be predicated of a term dis- tributed, from which it follows that no Mood can be valid whose major premise is particular, as in I. A. I. or O. A. O. Again, the Dictum requires that the minor premise be affirma- tive (" in which term a third is given as included ") ; so that no Mood can be valid whose minor premise is negative, as in A. E. E. or A. O. O. By these considerations we find that in the First Figure, out of 64 Moods possible, only six are valid, namely, those above-mentioned in 3, including the two Subalterns. The second step of this method is to test the Moods of the Second, Third, and Fourth Figures, by trying whether they can be reduced to one or other of the four Moods 120 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE of the First (as briefly illustrated in i, and to be further explained in 6). (2) Another way is to take the above six General or Common Canons, and to deduce from them Special Canons for testing each Figure : an interesting method, which, on account of its length, will be treated of separately in the next section. (3) Direct application of the Common Canons is, perhaps, the simplest plan. First write out the 64 Moods that are possible without regard to Figure, and then cross out those which violate any of the Canons or Corollaries, thus : A A A, :S~AHE. (6th Cad. fy A A I. 7n*-9> (6th Can. b}. -&-&A (6th Can. a) A E E^Tt-B-l (6th Can. a} A E O, 7t-J-A-(Cor. if.) 3*(6th Can. o>, A 1 1. -ft~Fa(6th Can. 6) Cao. a } 1r&& (Cor. ii.lT%-G-t (6th Can. a) A O O. Whoever has the patience to go through the remaining 48 Moods will discover that of the whole 64 only 1 1 are valid, namely : A. A. A., A. A. I., A. E. E., A. E. O., A. 1. 1., A. O. O., E. A. E., E. A. O., E. I. O., I. A. I., O. A. O. These n Moods have next to be examined in each Figure, and if valid in every Figure there will still be 44 moods in all. We find, however, that in the First Figure, A. E. E., A. E. O., A. O. O. involve illicit process of the Major Term (3rd Can.) ; I. A. I., O. A. O. involve undistributed Middle (4th Can.) ; and A. A. I., E. A. O. are Subalterns. In the Second Figure all the affirmative Moods, A. A. A., A. A. I., A.I.I., I.A.I., involve undistributed Middle ; O. A. O. involves illicit process of the Major; and A. E.G., E. A. O. are Subalterns. In the Third Figure, A. A. A., E. A. E., involve illicit process of the Minor (3rd Can.); A. E. E., A. E. O., A. O. O. involve illicit pro- cess of the Major. In the Fourth Figure, A. A. A. involves illicit process of the Minor ; A. I. I., A. O. O. involve undis- tributed Middle ; O. A. O. involves illicit process of the Major; and A. E. O. is Subaltern. CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 121 Those moods of each Figure which, when tried by these tests, are not rejected, are valid, namely : Fig. I. A. A. A., E.A.E., A. 1. 1., E.I.O. (A. A. I., A. E. O., Subaltern) ; Fig. II. E. A. E., A. E. E., E. I. O., A. O. O. (E. A. O., A. E. O., Subaltern) ; Fig. III. A.A.I., LA. I,, A. 1. 1., E. A. O., O.A.O., E. I. O. ; Fig. IV. A. A. I., A.E. E., I.A.I., E.A.O., E.I.O. (A. E. O., Subaltern). v Thus, including subaltern Moods, there are six valid in each Figure. In Fig. III. alone there is no subaltern Mood, because in that Figure there can be no universal conclusion. 5. Special Canons of the several Figures, deduced from the Common Canons, enable us to arrive at the same result by a somewhat different course. The Special Canons are not, perhaps, necessary to the Science, but they afford a very useful means of enabling one to thoroughly appreciate the character of formal syllogistic reasoning. Accordingly, I shall indicate the proof of each rule, leaving its elaboration to the reader. In this he can find no difficulty, if he bears in mind that Figure is determined by the position of the Middle Term. Fig. I., Rule (a) : The minor premise must be affirmative. For, if not, in negative Moods there will be illicit process of the major term. Applying this rule to the eleven possible Moods given in 4, as remaining after application of the Common Canons, it eliminates A. E. E., A. E. O., A. O. O. (b) The major premise must be universal. For, if not, the minor being affirmative, the middle term will be undistributed. This rule eliminates I.A.I., O. A. O. ; leaving six Moods, including two Subalterns. Fig. II. (a) One premise must be negative. For else neither premise will distribute the middle term. This rule eliminates A. A. A., A. A. I., A. 1. 1., I. A. I. 122 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE (b) The major premise must be universal. For else, the conclusion being negative, there will be illicit process of the major term. This eliminates I. A. I., O. A. O. ; leaving six Moods, including two Subalterns. Fig. III. (a) The minor premise must be affirmative. For else, in negative moods there will be illicit process of the major term. This rule eliminates A. E. E., A. E. O., A. O. O. (b) The conclusion must be particular. For else, the minor premise being affirmative, there will be illicit process of the minor term. This eliminates A. A. A., A. E. E., E. A. E. ; leaving six Moods. Fig. IV. (a) When the major premise is affirmative, the minor must be universal. For else the middle term is undistributed. This eliminates A. 1. 1., A. O. O. (b) When the minor premise is affirmative the conclusion must be particular. For else there will be illicit process of the minor term. This eliminates A. A. A., E. A. E. (c) When either premise is negative, the major must be universal. For else, the conclusion being negative, there will be illicit process of the major term. This eliminates O. A. O. ; leaving six Moods, including one Subaltern. 6. Reduction is either (i) Ostensive or (2) Indirect. Ostensive Reduction consists in showing that an argument given in one Mood can also be stated in another ; the process is especially used to show that the Moods of the second, third, and fourth Figures are equivalent to one or another Mood of the first Figure. It thus proves the validity of the former Moods by showing that they also essentially conform to the Dictum^ and that all Categorical Syllogisms are only superficial varieties of one type of proof. To facilitate Reduction, the recognised Moods have all had names given them; which names, again, have been strung CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 123 together into mnemonic verses of great force and preg- nancy : Barbara, Celarent, Darii, Ferioque prioris : Cesare, Camestres, Festino, Baroco, secundae: Tertia, Darapti, Disamis, Datisi, Felapton, Bocardo, Ferison, habet : Quarta insuper addit Bramantip, Camenes, Dimaris, Fesapo, Fresison. In the above verses the names of the Moods of Fig. I. begin with the first four consonants B, C, D, F, in alphabetical order ; and the names of all other Moods likewise begin with these letters, thus signifying (except in Baroco and Bocardo) the Mood of Fig. I., to which each is equivalent, and to which it is to be reduced : as Bramantip to Barbara, Camestres to Celarent, and so forth. The vowels A, E, I, O, occurring in the several names, give the Quantity and Quality of major premise, minor premise, and conclusion in the usual order. The consonants s and p, occurring after a vowel, show that the proposition which the vowel stands for is to be converted either (s) simply or (p) per accidens ; except where s or p occurs after the third vowel of a name, the conclusion : then it refers not to the conclusion of the given Mood (say Disamis), but to the conclusion of that Mood of the first Figure to which the given Mood is reduced (Darii). M (mutare, metathesis) means ' transpose the premises ' (as of Cawestres). C means * substitute the contradictory of the conclusion for the foregoing premise,' a process of the Indirect Reduction to be presently explained (see Baroco, 8). The other consonants r, n, t (with b and d, when not initial), occurring here and there, have no mnemonic significance. What now is the problem of Reduction ? The difference of Figures depends upon the position of the Middle Term. To reduce a Mood of any other Figure to the form of the First, then, we must so manipulate its premises that the Middle 124 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Term shall be subject of the major premise and predicate of the minor premise. Now in Fig. II. the Middle Term is predicate of both pre- mises ; so that the minor premise may need no alteration, and to convert the major premise may suffice. This is the case with Cesare, which reduces to Celarent by simply converting the major premise ; and with Festino, which by the same pro- cess becomes Ferio. In Camestres, however, the minor pre- mise is negative ; and, as this is impossible in Fig. I., the premises must be transposed, and the new major premise must be simply converted : then, since the transposition of the pre- mises will have transposed the terms of the conclusion (accord- ing to the usual reading of syllogisms), the new conclusion must be simply converted in order to prove the validity of the original conclusion. The process may be thus represented (s.f. meaning * simply convert ') : Camestres. Celarent. AllPisM; ^^ ^^- NoMisS; NoSisM: ' ^* All Pis M: .-. No S is P. * CT No P is S. The Ostensive Reduction of Baroco also needs special ex- planation ; for as it used to be reduced indirectly, its name gives no indication of the ostensive process. To reduce it osten- sively let us call it Faksnoko, where k means * obvert the foregoing premise.' By thus obverting (k) and simply convert- ing (s) (in sum, contrapositing) the major premise, and obvert- ing the minor premise, we get a syllogism in Ferio, thus : Baroco or Faksnoko. Ferio. AllPisM; contra?, ^ No m (not-M) i P; Some S is not M : > Some S is m (not-M): ,*. Some S is not P. .*. Some S is not P. CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 125 In Fig. III. the middle term is subject of both premises ; so that, to reduce its Moods to the First Figure, it may be enough to convert the minor premise. This is the case with Darapti, Datisi, Felapton and Ferison. But, with Disamis, since the major premise must in the First Figure be universal, we must transpose the premises, and then simply convert the new minor premise ; and, lastly, since the major and minor terms have now changed places, we must simply convert the new conclu- sion in order to verify the old one. Thus : Disamis. Darii. Some M is P ; ^ All M is S ; All M is S : ^^ ^-^v Some P is M : , Some S is P. * !L * .'. Some P is S. Bocardo, like Baroco, indicates by its name the indirect process. To reduce it ostensively let its name be Doksamrosk, and proceed thus : Bocardo or Doksamrosk. Darii. Some M is not P ; ^ _^* All M is S ; All M is S : - ^ Some p (not-P) is M : .*. Some S is not P. * conyert & obvert ^ Some p (not . p) is s> In Fig. IV. the position of the middle term is, in both premises, the reverse of what it is in the First Figure ; we may therefore reduce its Moods either by transposing the premises, as with Bramantip, Camenes, and Dimaris ; or by converting both premises, the course pursued with Fesapo and Fresison. It may suffice to illustrate by the case of Bramantip : 126 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Bramantip. Barbara. AllPisM; ^_ ^r AllMisS. All M is S : ^ All P is M : .-. Some S is P. < >**'l*r*' ... All P is S. This case shows that a final significant consonant (s, p, or sk) in the name of any Mood refers to the conclusion of the new syllogism in the First Figure ; since p in Bramantip cannot refer to its own conclusion in I.; which being already particular, cannot be converted / No M is p (not-P) ; AllSisM: >. AllSisM: 061;. .-. All S is P. < .-. No S is p (not-P). 7. A new version of the mnemonic lines was suggested in Mind No. 27, with the object of (i) freeing them from all meaningless letters, (2) showing by the name of each Mood the Figure to which it belongs, (3) giving names to indicate the ostensive reduction of Baroco and Bocardo. To obtain the first two objects, / is used as the mark of Fig. I., n of Fig. II., r of Fig. III., / of Fig. IV. The verses (to be scanned discreetly) are as follows : CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS I2 7 Balala, Celalel, Dalii, Felioque prioris : /Faksnoko secundae: Cesane, Camenes, Fesmon, |g Tertia, Darapri, Drisamis, Darisi, Ferapro, Doksamrosk -> Bocaro j ' Fensor habet : Q uarta insuper addit Bamatip, Gametes, Dimatis, Fesapto, Fesistot. De Morgan praised the old verses as " more full of meaning than any others that ever were made " ; and in defence of the above alteration it may be said that they now deserve that praise still more. 8. Indirect reduction is the process of proving a Mood to be valid by showing that the supposition of its invalidity involves a contradiction. Take Baroco, and (since the doubt as to its validity is concerned not with the truth of the premises, but with their relation to the conclusion) assume the premises to be true. Then, if the conclusion be false, its contradictory is true. The conclusion being in O., its contradictory will be in A. Substituting this A. for the minor premise of Baroco, we have the premises of a syllogism in Barbara, which will be found to give a conclusion in A., contradictory of the original minor premise ; thus : Baroco. Barbara. All P is M ; . All P is M ; Some S is not M : *^^ i-*L^* AllSisP: /. Some S is not P. - ^-** x> ^~*^. .-. All S is M. But the original minor premise, Some S is not M t is true by hypothesis ; and therefore the conclusion of Barbara, All S is M t is false. This falsity cannot, however, be due to the form of Barbara, which we know to be valid ; nor to the major pre- mise, which, being taken from Baroco, is true by hypothesis : 128 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE it must, therefore, be in the minor premise of Barbara. All S is P ; and since this is contradictory of the conclusion of Baroco Some S is not P, that conclusion was true. Similarly with Bocardo, the Indirect Reduction proceeds by substituting for the major premise the contradictory of the conclusion ; thus again obtaining the premises of a syllogism in Barbara, whose conclusion is contradictory of the original major premise. Hence the initial B in Baroco and Bocardo : it points to a syllogism in Barbara as the means of Indirect Reduction (Reductio ad impossibile). Any other Mood may be reduced indirectly : as, for example, Dimaris. If this is supposed to be invalid and the conclusion false, substitute the contradictory of the conclusion for the major premise, thus obtaining the premises of Celarent : Celarent. No S is P ; Dimaris. Some P is M ; All M is S : .. Some S is P. The conclusion of Celarent, simply converted, contradicts the original major premise of Dimaris, and is therefore false. Therefore the major premise of Celarent is false, and the con- clusion of Dimaris is true. We might, of course, construct mnemonic names for the Indirect Reduction of all the Moods: the name of Dimaris would then be Cicari. 9. The need or use of any Figure but the First has been much discussed by Logicians. Since, in actual debate, argu- ments are rarely stated in syllogistic form ; and, therefore, if reduced to that form for closer scrutiny, generally have to be treated with some freedom ; why not always throw them at once into the First Figure ? That Figure has manifest advan- CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 129 tages : it agrees directly with the Dictum ; it gives conclusions in all four prepositional forms, and therefore serves every pur- pose of full affirmation or denial, of showing agreement or difference (total or partial), of establishing the contradictories of universal statements ; and it is the only Figure in which the subject and predicate of the conclusion occupy the same posi- tions in the premises, so that the course of argument has in its mere expression an easy and natural flow. Still, the Second Figure also has a very natural air in some kinds of negative arguments. The parallelism of the twc premises, with the middle term as predicate in both, brings out very forcibly the necessary difference between the major and minor terms that is involved in their opposite relations to the middle term. P is not, whilst S is, M, says Cesare : that very neatly drives home the conviction that S is not P. Or perhaps even more naturally in Camestres : Deer do, oxen do not, shed t/ieir horns. What is the conclusion ? The Third Figure, again, furnishes in Darapti and Felapton, the most natural forms of stating arguments in which the middle term is singular : Socrates was truthful ; Socrates was a Greek : /. Some Greek was truthful. Reducing this to Fig I., we should get for the minor premise, Some Greek was Socrates : which is certainly inelegant. Still, it might be urged that, in the science of proof, elegance is an alto- gether extraneous consideration. And as for the other advantage claimed for Fig. III. that, as it yields only particular con- clusions, it is useful in establishing contradictories against universals I do not see that for that purpose any of its Moods have superiority over Darii and Ferio. As for Fig. IV., no particular advantage is claimed for it It is of comparatively late recognition (sometimes called the 'Galenian,' after Galen, its supposed discoverer); and its scientific claim to exist at all is disputed. It is said to be a I 130 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE mere inversion of Fig. I. ; which is not true in any sense in which Figs. II. and III. may not be condemned as partial inversions of Fig. I., and as having therefore still less claim to recognition. It is also said to invert the order of thought ; as if thought had only one order, or as if the mere order of thought had anything to do with Formal Logic. The truth is that, if distinction of Figure be recognised at all, the Fourth Figure is scientifically necessary, because it is inevitably generated by an analysis of the possible positions of the middle term. 10. Is Reduction necessary, however ; or have not all the Figures equal and independent validity? In one sense not only every Figure but each Mood has independent validity : for any one capable of abstract thinking sees its validity by direct inspection. But this is true not only of the abstract Moods, but very commonly of particular concrete arguments. Science, however, aims at unifying knowledge ; and after reducing all possible arguments that form categorical syllogisms to the nineteen Moods, it is but another step in the same direction to reduce these Moods to one form. This is the very nature of science : and, accordingly, I cannot look without wonder at the efforts of some Logicians to expound separate principles of each Figure. Grant that they succeed ; and what can the next step be, but either to reduce these principles to the Dictum, or the Dictum and the rest to one of these principles ? Unless this can be done there is no science of Formal Logic. If it is done, what is gained by reducing the principles of the other Figures to the Dictum, instead of the Moods of the other Figures to those of the first Figure ? It may, perhaps, be said that to show (i) that the Moods of the second, third, and fourth Figures flow from their own principles (though, in fact, these principles are laboriously adapted to the Moods) ; and (2) that these principles may be derived from the Dictum, is the more uncompromisingly gradual and regular method : but, on the whole, is not Forma' Logic already sufficiently encumbered with formalities ? CATEGORICAL SYLLOGISMS 131 ii. Euler's diagrams may be used to illustrate the syllogism, thus : FIG. 5. Barbara FIG. 6. Celarent Remembering that 'Some* means 'It may be all,' it is plain that any one of these diagrams in Fig. 7, or the one given above for Barbara, may represent the denotative relations of P, M, and S in Darii ; though no doubt the diagram we generally think of as representing Darii is No. i in Fig. 7. 132 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE FIG. 8. Ferio Here, again, I suppose, we generally think of No. i as the diagram representing Ferio ; but 2, or 3, or that given above for Celarent, is compatible with the premises. It is instructive to work out the diagrams for the Moods of the other Figures, noticing how they stand related to the above. CHAPTER XI ABBREVIATED AND COMPOUND ARGUMENTS i. In ordinary discussion, whether oral or written, it is but rarely that the forms of Logic are closely adhered to. We often leave wide gaps in the structure of our arguments, trust- ing the intelligence of those addressed to bridge them over ; or we invert the regular order of propositions, beginning with the conclusion, and mentioning the premises, perhaps, a good while after, confident that the sagacity of our audience will make all smooth. Sometimes a full style, like Macaulay's, may, by means of amplification and illustration, spread the elements of a single syllogism over several pages a penny- worth of logic steeped in so much eloquence. These practices give a great advantage to sophists ; who would find it very inconvenient to state explicitly in Mood and Figure the preten- tious antilogies which they foist upon the public ; and, indeed, such licences of composition often prevent honest men from detecting errors into which they themselves have unwittingly fallen, and which, with the best intentions, they strive to com- municate to others : but we put up with these drawbacks to avoid the inelegance (forsooth !) and the tedium of a long dis- course in accurate syllogisms. Many departures from the strictly logical statement of reasonings consist in the use of vague or figurative language, or in the substitution for one another of expressions supposed to be equivalent though, in fact, dangerously discrepant. Against such occasions of error the logician can provide no safeguard, except the advice to be careful and discriminating i 3 4 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE in what you say or hear. But as to any derangement of the elements of an argument, or the omission of them, Logic effectually aids the task of restoration ; for it has shown what the elements are that enter into the explicit statement of most ratiocinations, namely, the four forms of propositions ; and what that connected order of propositions is which most easily and surely exposes the validity or invalidity of reasoning, namely, the premises and conclusion of the Syllogism. Logic has even gone so far as to name certain abbreviated forms of proof, which may be regarded as general types of those that actually occur in debate, in leading articles, pamphlets and other persuasive or polemic writings namely, the Enthy- meme, Epicheirema and Sorites'. 2. The Enthymeme, according to Aristotle, is the Syllo- gism of probable reasoning about practical affairs and matters of opinion, in contrast with the Syllogism of theoretical de- monstration upon necessary grounds. But, as now commonly treated, it is an argument with one of its elements omitted ; a Categorical Syllogism, having one or other of its premises, or else its conclusion, suppressed. If the Major Premise is suppressed, it is called an Enthymeme of the First Order ; if the Minor Premise is wanting, it is said to be of the Second Order ; if the Conclusion is left to be understood, there is an Enthymeme of the Third Order. Let the following be a complete Syllogism : All free nations are enterprising : The Dutch are a free nation : .'.The Dutch are enterprising. Reduced to Enthymemes this argument may be put thus : In the First Order : The Dutch are a free nation : .'. The Dutch are enterprising. la the Second Order All free nations are enterprising : .*. The Dutch are enterprising. ABBREVIATED ARGUMENTS 135 In the Third Order- All free nations are enterprising ; And the Dutch are a free nation. It is certainly very common to meet with arguments whose statement may be represented by one or other of these three forms ; indeed, the Enthymeme is the natural substitute for a full syllogism in oratory : whence the transition from Aristotle's to the modern meaning of the term. The most unschooled of men readily apprehend its force ; and a student of Logic can easily supply the proposition that may be wanted in any case to complete a syllogism, and thereby test the argument's formal validity. In any Enthymeme of the Third Order, especially, to supply the conclusion cannot present any difficulty at all ; and hence it is a favourite vehicle of innuendo, as in Hamil- ton's example : Every liar is a coward ; And Caius is a liar. The frankness of this statement and its reticence, together, make it a biting sarcasm upon Caius. To find the missing premise in an Enthymeme of either the First or Second Order, a simple rule may be given : Take that Term of the given Premise that does not occur in the Conclu- sion (and which must therefore be the Middle), and combine it with that Term of the Conclusion which does not occur in the given Premise; the proposition thus formed is the Premise which was requisite to complete the Syllogism. If the premise thus constituted contain the predicate of the conclusion, the Enthymeme was of the First Order ; if it contain the subject of the conclusion, the Enthymeme was of the Second Order. That a statement in the form of a Hypothetical Proposition may really be an Enthymeme (as observed in chap. v. 4) can easily be shown by recasting one of the above Enthyniemes thus : Jf all free nations are enterprising, the Dutch are enter- prising. Such statements should be treated according to their true nature. 136 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE To reduce the argument of any ordinary discourse to logical form, the first care should be to make it clear to oneself what exactly the conclusion is, and to state it adequately but as succinctly as possible. Then look for the evidence. This may be of an inductive character, consisting of instances, examples, analogies ; and, if so, of course its cogency must be evalued by the principles of Induction, which we shall pre- sently investigate. But if the evidence is deductive, it will probably consist of an Enthymeme, or of several Enthymemes one depending on another. Each Enthymeme may be isolated and expanded into a syllogism. And we may then inquire : (i) whether the syllogisms are formally correct according to Barbara (or whatever the appropriate Mood) ; (2) whether the premises, or the ultimate premises, are true in fact. 3. A Monosyllogism is a syllogism considered as standing alone or without relation to other arguments. But, of course, a disputant may be asked to prove the premises of any syllo- gism ; in which case other syllogisms may be advanced for that purpose. When the conclusion of one syllogism is used to prove another, we have a chain-argument ; which, stated at full length, is a Polysyllogism. In any Poly syllogism, again, a syllogism whose conclusion is used as the premise of another, is called in relation to that other a Prosyllogism ; whilst a syllo- gism, one of whose premises is the conclusion of another syllogism, is in relation to that other an Episyllogism. Two modes of abbreviating a Polysyllogism are usually discussed, the Epicheirema and the Sorites. 4. An Epicheirema is a syllogism for one or both of whose premises a reason is added ; as All men are mortal, for they are animals ; Socrates is a man, for rational bipeds are men ; .*. Socrates is mortal. The Epicheirema is called Single or Double, says Hamilton, according as an " adscititious proposition " attaches to one or both of the premises. The above example is of the double ABBREVIATED ARGUMENTS 137 kind. The Single are said to be of the First Order, if the adscititious proposition attaches to the Major Premise ; if to the Minor, of the Second Order. (Hamilton : Lecture xix.) An Epicheirema then is an abbreviated chain of reasoning, or Polysyllogism, comprising an Episyllogism with one or two enthymematic Prosyllogisms. The major premise in the above case, All men are mortal, for they are animals, is an Enthymeme of the First Order, suppressing its own major premise, and may be restored thus : All animals are mortal ; All men are animals ; .*. All men are mortal. The minor premise, however, is an Enthymeme of the Second Order, suppressing its own minor premise, and may be restored thus: All rational bipeds are men ; Socrates is a rational biped ; /. Socrates is a man. 5. The Sorites is a Polysyllogism in which the Conclu- sions, and even some of the Premises, are suppressed until the argument ends. If the chain of arguments were freed of its enthymematic character, the suppressed conclusions would of course appear as premises of Episyllogisms. Two varieties of Sorites are recognised, the Aristotelian (so called, though not treated of by Aristotle), and the Goclenian (named after its discoverer, Goclenius of Marburg, who flourished about 1600 A.D.). In order to compare these two forms of argument, it will be convenient to place side by side Hamilton's classical examples of them. Aristotelian. Goclenian. Bucephalus is a horse ; An animal is a substance ; A horse is a quadruped ; A quadruped is an animal ; A quadruped is an animal ; A horse is a quadruped ; An animal is a substance ; Bucephalus is a horse ; /. Bucephalus is a substance. .-. Bucephalus is a substance. 138 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE The reader wonders what is the difference between these two forms. Of course, in the Aristotelian Sorites the minor term occurs in the first premise, and the major term in the last ; whilst in the Goclenian the major term occurs in the first, and the minor in the last. But since the character of premises is fixed by their terms, not by the order in which they are written, there cannot be a better example of a distinction with- out a difference. At a first glance, indeed, there may seem to be a more important point involved ; the premises of the Aristotelian Sorites seem to proceed in the order of the Fourth Figure. But if that were really so the conclusion would be, Some substance is Bucephalus. That, on the contrary, every one writes the conclusion, Bucephalns is a substance, proves that the logical order of the premises is in the First Figure. Logi- cally, therefore, there is absolutely no difference between these two forms, and pure reason requires either that the "Aris- totelian Sorites " disappear from the text-books, or that it be regarded as in the Fourth Figure, and its conclusion converted. It is the shining merit of Goclenius to have restored the pre- mises of the Sorites to the usual order of Fig. .1. : whereby he has raised to himself a monument more durable than brass, and secured indeed the very cheapest immortality. How ex- pensive, compared with this, was the method of that Ephesian incendiary ! The common Sorites, then, being in the First Figure, its rules follow from those of the First Figure : (1) Only one premise can be particular; and, if any, only that in which the minor term occurs. For, just as in Fig. I., a particular premise anywhere else involves Undistributed Middle. (2) Only one premise can be negative ; and, if any, only that in which the major term occurs. For if there were two negative premises, at the point where the second entered the chain of argument there must be a syllogism with two negative premises, which is contrary to Rule 5 ; whilst if one premise be negative it must be that ABBREVIATED ARGUMENTS 139 which contains the major term, for the same reason as in Fig. I., namely, that the conclusion will be negative, and that therefore only a negative major premise can prevent Illicit Process of the Major Term. If we expand a Sorites into its constituent syllogisms, the conclusions successively suppressed will reappear as major pre- mises ; thus : (1) An animal is a substance ; A quadruped is an animal ; .*. A quadruped is a substance. (2) A quadruped is a substance ; A horse is a quadruped ; .'. A horse is a substance. (3) A horse is a substance : Bucephalus is a horse ; .'. Bucephalus is a substance. This suffices to show that the Protosyllogism of a Goclenian Sorites is an Enthymeme of the Third Order ; after which the argument is a chain of Enthymemes of the First Order, or even of the First and Third combined, since the conclusions as well as the major premises are omitted, except in the last one. Lest it should be thought that the Sorites is only good for arguments so frivolous as the above, I subjoin an example collected from various parts of Mill's Political Economy : The cost of labour depends on the efficiency of labour; The rate of profits depends on the cost of labour ; The investment of capital depends on the rate of profits ; Wages depend on the investment of capital ; /. Wages depend on the efficiency of labour. Had it occurred to Mill to construct this Sorites, he would have modified his doctrine of the Wages-Fund, and would have saved many critics from the malignant joy of refuting him. 6. The Antinomy is a combination of arguments by which 140 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE contradictory attributes are proved to be predicable of the same subject. In symbols, thus : All M is P All N is p All S is M All S is N All S is P All S is p Now, by the principle of Contradiction, S cannot be P and p (not-P) : therefore, if both of the above syllogisms are sound, S cannot exist at all. The contradictory conclusions are called, respectively, Thesis and Antithesis. To come to particulars, we may argue : (i) that a constitu- tion which is at once a monarchy, an aristocracy and a de- mocracy, must comprise the best elements of all three forms ; and must, therefore, be the best of all forms of government : ^the British Constitution is, therefore, the best of all. But (2) such a constitution must also comprise the worst elements of monarchy, aristocracy and democracy ; and, therefore, must be the worst of all forms. Are we, then, driven to conclude that the British Constitution, thus proved to be both the best and worst, does not really exist at all, being, logically impos- sible ? For the proofs seem to me equally good. Again, (1) Every being who is responsible for his actions is free; Man is responsible for his actions : .*. Man is free. (2) Every being whose actions enter into the course of nature is not free ; Man is such a being : .'. Man is not free. Does it, then, follow that ' Man,' as the subject of contradictory attributes, is a nonentity? This doctrine, or something like it, has been seriously entertained ; but if to any reader it seems extravagant (as it certainly does to me), he will no doubt find an error in the above arguments. ABBREVIATED ARGUMENTS 141 For other examples it is enough to refer to the Critique of Pure Reason, where Kant sets out the Antinomies of Rational Cosmology. But even if we do not agree with Kant that the human understanding, in attempting to deal with certain subjects beyond its reach, inevitably falls into such contradic- tory reasonings ; yet it can hardly be doubted that we not unfrequently hold opinions which, if logically developed, result in Antinomies. And, accordingly, the Antinomy, if it cannot be imputed to Reason herself, may be a very fair, and a very wholesome argumentum ad hominem. It was the favourite weapon of the Pyrrhonists against the dogmatic philosophies that flourished after the death of Aristotle. CHAPTER XII CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS i. Conditional Syllogisms may be generally described, AS those that contain conditional propositions. They are usually divided into two classes, Hypothetical and Disjunctive. A Hypothetical Syllogism is one that consists of a Hypo- thetical Major Premise, a Categorical Minor Premise, and a Categorical Conclusion. Two Moods are usually recognised : (1) Modus ponens t or Constructive. If A is B, Cis D; A is B: /. C is D. If Aristotle's reasoning is conclusive, Plato's theory of Ideas is erroneous ; Aristotle's reasoning is conclusive : .*. Plato's theory of Ideas is erroneous. Rule of the Modus ponens : The antecedent of the Major Premise being affirmed in the Minor Premise, the Consequent is also affirmed in the Conclusion. (2) Modus tollens, or Destructive. If A is B, C is D ; C is not D ; .-. A is not B. If Pythagoras is to be trusted, Justice is a number; Justice is not a number : .'. Pythagoras is not to be trusted. CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 143 Rule of the Modus tollens : The Consequent of the Major Premise being denied in the Minor Premise, the Antecedent is denied in the Conclusion. By using negative major premises two other forms are obtainable : then, either by affirming the Antecedent or by denying the Consequent, we draw a negative conclusion. Thus (Modus ponens) : (Modus tollens) : If A is B, C is not D ; If A is B, C is not D ; A is B : C is D : /. C is not D. .'. A is not B. Further, since the Antecedent of the major premise, taken by itself, may be negative, it seems possible to obtain four more forms, two in each Mood, from the following major premises : (1) If A is not B, Cis D; (2) If A is not B, C is not D. But since the quality of a Hypothetical Proposition is deter- mined by the quality of its Consequent, not at all by the quality of its Antecedent, I do not see how we can get from these two major premises any really new Moods, that is to say, Moods exhibiting any formal difference from the four pre- viously expounded. Recognising these four, however, would it not be well to make the names * Constructive ' and ' Destruc- tive ' not synonymous with Modus ponens and Modus tollens respectively, but applicable thus : * Constructive ' to that form of the Modus ponens that has an affirmative conclusion, and * Destructive ' to the other three Syllogisms that conclude in the negative ? It must be carefully observed that, given the hypothetical major premise If A is B, C is D we cannot by denying the Antecedent infer a denial of the Consequent. That A is B, is a mark of C being D ; but we are not told that it is the sole and indispensable condition of i 4 4 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE it. If men read good books, they acquire knowledge; but they may acquire knowledge by other means, as by observation. For the same reason, we cannot by affirming the Consequent infer the affirmation of the Antecedent: Caius may have acquired knowledge ; but we cannot thence conclude that he has read good books. To see this in another light, let us recall chap. v. 4, where it was shown that a hypothetical proposition may be translated into a categorical one ; whence it follows that a Hypothetical Syllogism may be translated into a Categorical Syllogism. Treating the above examples thus, we find that the Modus ponens takes the form of Barbara, and the Modus tollens the form of Camestres : * Modus ponens. If A is B, C is D ; AisB: .-. C is D. Barbara. The case of A being B is a case of C being D : This is a case of A being B : .*. This is a case of C being D. Now if, instead of this, we affirm the Consequent, to form the new minor premise, This is a case of C being D, there will be a Syllogism in the Second Figure with two affirmative premises, and therefore the fallacy of Undistributed Middle. Again : Modus tollens. Camestres. If A is B, C is D ; The case of A being B is a case of C being D : C is not D : This is not a case of C being D : .". A is not B. /. This is not a case of A being B. But if, instead of this, we deny the Antecedent, to form the new minor premise, This is not a case of A being B, there arises a syllogism in the First Figure with a negative CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 145 minor premise, and therefore the fallacy of Illicit Process of the Major Term. By thus reducing the Hypothetical Syllogism to the Cate- gorical form, what is lost in elegance is gained in intelligibility. For, first, we may justify ourselves in speaking of the Hypo- thetical Premise as the Major, and of the Categorical Premise as the Minor; since in the Categorical form they contain respectively the Major and Minor Terms. And, secondly, we may justify ourselves in treating the Hypothetical Syllogism as a kind of Mediate Inference, in spite of the fact that in the Hypothetical Syllogism there are not two Terms compared by means of a third ; since in the Categorical form such Terms distinctly appear : a new Term (' This ') emerges in the position of the Minor ; the place of the Middle is filled by the Ante- cedent of the Major Premise in the Modus pojiens, and by the Consequent in the Modus tollens. The mediate element of the inference in a Hypothetical Syllogism consists in asserting, or denying, the fulfilment of a given condition. In the hypothetical proposition If A is B, C is D the Antecedent, A is B, is the conditio sufficiens, or mark, of the Consequent, C is D ; and therefore the Consequent, C is D, is a conditio sine qua non of the antecedent, A is B ; and it is by means of affirming the former condition, or else denying the latter, that a conclusion is rendered possible. Indeed, we need not say that the element of mediation con- sists in affirming, or denying, the fulfilment of a given con- dition : it is enough to say ' in affirming.' For thus to explain the Modus totlens, reduce it to the Modus ponens (contra- positing the major premise) : Celarent. If A is B, C is D : The case of C not being D is a .'. If C is not D, A is not B ; case of A not being B ; C is not D : This is a case of C not being D : /. A is not B. .'. This is a case of A not being B. K 146 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE The above four forms commonly treated of as Hypothetical Syllogisms, are called by Ueberweg and Dr. Keynes ' Hypo- thetico-Categorical.' Ueberweg restricts the name 'Hypo- thetical ' simply (and Dr. Keynes the name ' Conditional ') to such Syllogisms as the following, having two Hypothetical Premises : IfCis D, EisF; If A is B, C is D : .-.If A is B, EisF. If we recognise particular hypothetical propositions (see chap. v. 4), it is obvious that such Syllogisms may be constructed in all the Moods ,and Figures of the Categorical Syllogism ; and of course they may be translated into Cate- goricals. We often reason in this hypothetical way. For example : If the margin of cultivation be extended, rents will rise ; If prices of produce rise, the margin of cultivation will be extended: /. If prices of produce rise, rents will rise. But it may be noticed that the purpose of the Hypothetical Syllogism (commonly so called), as also of the Disjunctive (to be discussed in the next section) is to get rid of the conditional element, to pass from doubt to certainty, and obtain a decisive Categorical Conclusion ; whereas these Syllogisms with two hypothetical premises leave us still with a hypothetical con- clusion. This circumstance seems to me to ally them more closely with Categorical Syllogisms than with those that are discussed in the present chapter. That they are Categoricals in disguise may be seen by considering that the above syllogism is not materially significant, unless in each proposition the word 'If is equivalent to 'Whenever.' Accordingly, in applying the name ' Hypothetical Syllogism,' I have not seen fit to depart from the older usage. 2. A Disjunctive Syllogism consists of a Disjunctive Major jor CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 147 Premise, a Categorical Minor Premise, and a Categorical Con- clusion. How many Moods are to be recognised in this kind of argument depends on whether the alternatives of the Dis- junctive Premise are regarded as mutually exclusive or possibly coincident. In saying ' Either A is B, or C is D,' do we mean * either, but not both,' or ' either, it may be both ' ? (see chap. v. 4.) When the alternatives of the Disjunctive are not exclusive, we have only the Modus tollendo ponens. Either A is B, or C is D ; A is not B (or C is not D) : . -.CisD (or A is B). Either wages fall, or the weaker hands are dismissed ; Wages do not fall : .-. The weaker hands are dismissed. But we cannot argue Wages fall : /. The weaker hands are not dismissed ; since in ' hard times ' both events may happen together. Rule of the Modus tollendo ponens : If one alternative be denied, the other is affirmed. When, however, the alternatives of the Disjunctive are mutually exclusive, we have also the Modus ponendo tollens. Either A is B, or C is D ; A is B (or C is D) : .-. C is not D (or A is not B). Either the Tories or the Whigs win the election ; The Tories win : .. The Whigs do not win. We may also, of course, argue as above in the Modus tolkndo ponens 143 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE The Tories do not win : /.The Whigs do. But in this example, to make the Modus tolkndo ponens materially valid, it must be impossible that the election should result in a tie. The danger of the Disjunctive Proposition is that the alternatives may not, between them, exhaust the pos- sible cases. Only contradictory alternatives are sure to cover the whole ground. Rule of the Modus ponendo to ! lens : If one alternative be affirmed, the other is denied. Since a disjunctive proposition may be turned into a hypo- thetical proposition (chap. v. 4), a Disjunctive Syllogism may be turned into a Hypothetical Syllogism : Modus tollendo ponens. Modus ponens. Either A is B, or C is D ; If A is not B, C is D ; A is not B : A is not B : .-.CisD. . \CisD. Similarly the Modus ponendo tollens is equivalent to that kind of Modus ponens which may be formed with a negative major premise ; for if the alternatives of a disjunctive proposition be exclusive, the corresponding hypothetical may be affirmative or negative : Modus ponendo tollens. Modus ponens. Either A is B, or C is D ; If A is B, C is not D ; A is B ; A is B ; .-.CisnotD. /. C is not D. Hence, finally, a Disjunctive Syllogism being equivalent to a Hypothetical, and a Hypothetical to a Categorical; a Dis- junctive Syllogism is equivalent and reducible to a Categorical. It is a form of Mediate Inference in the same sense as the Hypothetical Syllogism is ; that is to say, the conclusion depends upon an affirmation, or denial, of the fulfilment of a condition implied in the disjunctive major premise. CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 149 3. The Dilemma is perhaps the most popularly interesting of all forms of proof. It is a favourite weapon of orators and wits ; and "impaled upon the horns of a dilemma" is a painful situation in which every one delights to see his adversary. It seems to have been described by Rhetoricians before finding its way into works on Logic ; and Logicians, to judge from their diverse ways of defining it, have found some difficulty in making up their minds as to its exact character. There is a famous Dilemma employed by Demosthenes, from which the general nature of the argument may be gathered : If j^Eschines joined in the public rejoicings, he is inconsis- tent ; if he did not, he is unpatriotic ; But either he joined, or he did not join : Therefore he is either inconsistent or unpatriotic. That is, reduced to symbols : If A is B, C is D ; and if E is F, G is H : But either A is B, or E is F ; .-. Either C is D or G is H (Complex Constructive). Now, plainly, this is a compound Conditional Syllogism, which may be analysed as follows : Either A is B or E is F. Suppose that E is not F : Suppose that A is not B : Then A is B. Then E is F. But if A is B, C is D ; But if E is F, G is H ; (A is B) : (E is F) : .-. C is D. .-. G is H. .-. Either C is D or G is H. A Dilemma, then, is a compound Conditional Syllogism, having for its Major Premise two Hypothetical Propositions, and for its Minor Premise a Disjunctive Proposition, whose alternative terms either affirm the Antecedents or deny the Consequents of the two Hypothetical Propositions forming the Major Premise. The hypothetical propositions in the major premise, may have all four terms distinct (as in the above example) ; and i5o LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE then the conclusion is a disjunctive proposition, and the Dilemma is said to be Complex. Or the two hypothetical propositions may have a common antecedent or a common consequent ; and then the conclusion is a categorical proposition, and the Dilemma is said to be Simple. Again, the alternatives of the disjunctive minor premise may be affirmative or negative. If they are affirmative, the Dilemma is called Constructive; and if negative, Destructive. However, seeing that the Dilemma is a compound Conditional Syllogism, it would surely ! be better to name its Moods after the corre- sponding Moods of the Hypothetical Syllogism Modus ponens and Modus tollens. If, then, we only use affirmative hypothetical propositions in the major premise, there are four Moods : 1. The Simple Modus ponens (or, Constructive). If A is B, CisD; and if E is F, C is D : But either A is B, or E is F : /. C is D. If the Tories win the election, the Government will avoid innovation; and if the Whigs win, the House of Lords will prevent them innovating ; But either the Tories or the Whigs will win ; /. There will be no innovation. 2. The Complex Modus ponens (or, Constructive). If A is B, C is D ; and if E is F, G is H : But either A is B, or E is F : .'.Either C is D or G is H. If appearance is all that exists, reality is a delusion ; and if there is a substance beyond consciousness, knowledge of reality is impossible : But either appearance is all, or there is a substance beyond consciousness : .'.Either reality is a delusion, or a knowledge of it is im- possible. 3. Simple Modus tollens (or Destructive). CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 151 If A is B, C is D ; and if A is B, E is F: But either C is not D, or E is not F : /. A is not B. If table-rappers are to be trusted, the departed are spirits ; and they also exert mechanical energy : But either the departed are not spirits, or they do not exert mechanical energy : .'. Table-rappers are not to be trusted. 4 . Complex Modus tollens (or, Destructive). If A is B, C is D ; and if E is F, G is H : But either C is not D, or G is not H : .-. Either A is not B, or E is not F. If poetic justice is observed, virtue is rewarded ; and if the mirror is held up to Nature, the villain triumphs ; But either virtue is not rewarded, or the villain does not triumph : .'. Either poetic justice is not observed, or the mirror is not held up to Nature. These then are the four Moods of the Dilemma that emerge if we use only affirmative hypotheticals for the major premise ; but, certainly, it is often quite as natural to employ two nega- tive hypotheticals (indeed, one might be affirmative and the other negative ; but waive that) ; and then four more moods emerge, all having negative conclusions. But it is needless to intimidate the reader by drawing up these four moods in battle array. Of course, they always admit of reduction to the fore- going moods by obverting the hypotheticals ; but by the same process we may greatly decrease the number of moods of the Categorical Syllogism ; so that I am afraid that this objection to them will be thought to prove too much. Just as some Syllogisms are most simply expressed in Celarent or Cesare, so some Dilemmas are most simply stated with negative major premises e.g., The Modus ponens above given would run more naturally thus : If the Tories win, the Government will not innovate ; and if the Whigs, the Lords will not let them : and similarly Demosthenes' Dilemma If ^Eschines joined, he is 152 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE not consistent ; and if he did not, he is not patriotic. Moreover, the propriety of recognising Dilemmas with negative major premises, follows from the above analysis of the Dilemma into a combination of Conditional Syllogisms, even if (as in i of this chapter) we take account of only four Moods of the Hypothetical Syllogism. In the rhetorical use of the Dilemma, it may be observed that the Disjunction in the minor premise ought to be obvious, or (at any rate) easily acceptable to the audience. Thus, Either the Tories or the Whigs will win; Either ^Eschines joined in the rejoicings, or he did not ; such propositions are not likely to be disputed. But if the orator must stop to prove his minor premise, the smacking effect of this figure (if the expression be allowed) will be lost. Hence the minor premises of other examples given above are only fit for a select audience, like students of Logic. That Either ghosts are not spirits, or they do not exert mechanical energy, supposes a knowledge of the principle, generally taught by physical philosophers, that only matter is the vehicle of energy ; and that Either appearance is all, or there is substance beyond consciousness, is a doctrine which only metaphysical philosophers could be expected to under- stand, and upon which they could not be expected to agree. However, the chief danger is that a plausible disjunction may not be really such as to exclude any middle ground : Either the Tories or the Whigs win, is bad, if a tie be possible ; though in the above argument this is negligible, seeing that a tie cannot directly cause innovations. Either ^Eschines joined in the rejoicings, or he did not, does not allow for a decent conformity with the public movement where resistance would be vain ; yet such conformity as need not be inconsistent with subsequent condemnation of the proceedings, nor incompatible with patriotic reserve founded on a belief that the rejoicings are premature and ominous. Another rhetorical consideration is, that the alternatives of the Disjunctive Conclusion of a Complex Dilemma should both point the same way, should be equally distasteful or CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS 153 paradoxical. ' Either inconsistent or unpatriotic ' : horrid words to a politician ! ' Either no reality or no possible knowledge ' : very disappointing to an anxious inquirer ! Thus the Disjunc- tive Conclusion is as bad for an opponent as the Categorical one in a Simple Dilemma. Logicians further speak of the Trilemma, with three Hypo- thetical and a corresponding triple Disjunction ; and of a Folylemma, with any further number of perplexities. But any one who has a taste for mere logical forms may have it amply gratified in numerous text-books. Indeed there are so many opportunities of developing such forms that, if ingenious enough, a man may still hope to discover some quite new ones : and quite innocently, as long as he does not publish them. CHAPTER XIII TRANSITION TO INDUCTION i. Having now discussed Terms, Propositions, Immediate and Mediate Inferences, and investigated the conditions frf Formal Truth or Consistency, we have next to consider the conditions of Material Truth : whether (or how far) it is possible to arrive at propositions that represent the course of nature and human life. Hitherto we have dealt with no sort of proof that gives any such assurance. A valid syllogism guarantees the truth of its conclusion, provided the premises be true : but what of the premises ? The relation, between the premises of a valid syllogism and its conclusion is indeed the same as the relation between the antecedent and consequent of a hypothetical proposition. If A is B, C is D : grant that A is B, and it follows that C is D ; and, similarly, grant the premises of a syllogism, and the conclusion follows. Again, grant that C is not D, and it follows that A is not B ; and, similarly, if the conclusion of a valid syllogism be false, it follows that one, or other, or both of the premises must be false. But, once more, grant that C is D, and it does not follow that A is B ; so neither, if the conclusion of a syllogism be true, does it follow that the premises are. For example : Geology is an exact science ; Mathematics is a branch of Geology ; .*. Mathematics is an exact science. Here the conclusion is true although the premises are absurd. Or again : TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 155 Mathematics is an exact science ; Geology is a branch of Mathematics ; .*. Geology is an exact science. Here the major premise is true, but the minor is false, and the conclusion is false. In both cases, however, whether the con- clusion be true or false, it equally follows from the premises, if there is any cogency in Barbara. The explanation of this is, that Barbara has only formal cogency ; and that whether the conclusion of that, or any other valid mood, shall be true according to fact and experience, depends upon how the form is rilled up. How to establish the premises, then, is a most important problem ; and it still remains to be solved. 2. We may begin by recalling the distinction between the Denotation and Connotation of a General Term : the denota- tion comprising the things or events which the term is a name for; the connotation comprising the common qualities on account of which these things are called by the same name. Obviously, there are very few general terms whose denotation is exhaustively known ; since the denotation of a general term comprises all the things that have its connotation, or that ever have had, or that ever will have it, whether they exist here, or in Australia, or in the Moon, or in the utmost stars. No one has examined all men, all dogs, all falling bodies, all cases of fever, all crystals, all mammoths, all revolutions, all stars nor even all planets, since from time to time new ones are discerned. We have names for animals that existed long before there were men to observe them, and of which we know only a few bones, the remains of multitudinous species : others may continue to exist when men have disappeared from the earth. If, indeed, we definitely limit the time, or place, or quantity of matter to be explored, we may sometimes learn, within the given limits, all that we are concerned about : as all the bones of a particular animal, or the list of English monarchs hitherto, or the names of all the members of the House of Commons at the present time. Such cases, however, do not invalidate the above logical truth that few general terms are exhaustively 156 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE known in their denotation ; for the very fact of assigning limits of time and place impairs the generality of a term. The bones of a certain animal may be all examined, but not the bones of all animals, nor even of one species. The English monarchs that have reigned hitherto may be known, but there may be many still to reign. The General Terms, then, with which Logic is chiefly concerned, the names of Causes and Kinds, such as gravita- tion, diseases, social events, minerals, plants and animals, stand for some facts that are, or have been, known, and for a great many other similar ones that have not been, and never will be, known. Hence the use of a general term depends not upon our direct knowledge of everything comprised in its denotation, but upon our readiness to apply it to anything that has its connotation, whether we have seen the thing or not, and even though we never can see it ; as when a man talks freely of the ichthyosaurus, or of the central heat of planets, or of atoms and ether. Hence Universal Propositions, which consist of general terms, deceive us, if we suppose that their predicates are directly known to be related to all the facts denoted by their subjects. In exceptional cases, in which the denotation of a subject is intentionally limited, such exhaustive direct know- ledge may be possible ; as that " all the bones of a certain animal consist of phosphate of lime," or that every member of the present Parliament wears a black silk hat. But what predication is possible concerning the hats of all members of Parliament from the beginning ? Ordinarily, then, whilst the relation of predicate to subject has been observed in some cases, in much the greater number of cases our belief about it depends upon other evidence than observation, or may be said (in a certain sense) to be taken on trust. ' All rabbits are herbivorous ' : why do we believe that ? We may have seen a few wild rabbits feeding : or have kept tame ones, and tried experiments with their diet ; or have read of their habits in a book of Natural History ; or have studied TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 157 the physiology of digestion in many sorts of animals : but with whatever care we add testimony and scientific method to our own observation, it still remains true that the rabbits observed by ourselves and others are few in comparison with those that live, have lived and will live. And the same truth might be shown to hold good of any other Universal Proposition ; for it plainly follows from the fact that the general terms of which such propositions consist, are never exhaustively known in their denotation. What right have we then to state Universal Propositions ? That is the problem of Inductive Logic. 3. Universal Propositions, of course, cannot always be proved by syllogisms ; because to prove a universal pro- position by a syllogism, its premises must be universal propositions ; and, then, these must be proved by others, and so on for ever. In fact the Formal Syllogism is itself mis- leading if the Universal Proposition is so : if we think that the premises prove the conclusion because they have been established by detailed observation, we are mistaken. The consideration of any example will show this. Suppose any one to argue : All ruminants are herbivorous ; Camels are ruminants : .*. Camels are herbivorous. Have we, then, qxamined all ruminants ? If so, we must have examined all camels, and cannot need a syllogism to prove their herbivorous nature : instead of the major premise proving the conclusion, the proof of the conclusion must then be part of the proof of the major premise. But if we have not examined all ruminants, having omitted most giraffes, most deer, most camels, how do we know that the unexamined (say, some camels) are not exceptional ? Camels are vicious enough to be carnivorous ; and indeed it is said that Bactrian camels will eat flesh rather than starve, though of course their habit is herbivorous. Or, again, it is sometimes urged that 158 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE All empires decay : .*. Britain will decay. This is manifestly a prediction : at present Britain flourishes, and shows no signs of decay. Yet a knowledge of its decay seems necessary, to justify any one in asserting the given premise. If it is a question whether Britain will decay, to attempt (while several empires still flourish) to settle the matter by asserting that all empires decay, seems to be ' a begging of the question.' But although this latter case is a manifest prediction, it does not really differ from the former one ; for the proof that camels are herbivorous has no limits in time. If valid, it shows not only that they are, but also that they will be, herbivorous. Hence, to resort to a dilemma, it may be urged : If all the facts of the major premise of any syllogism have been examined, the syllogism is needless ; and if some of them have not been examined, it is a petitio principii. But either all have been examined, or some have not. Therefore, the syllogism is either useless or fallacious. 4. A way of escape from this dilemma is provided, how- ever, by distinguishing between the formal and material aspects of the syllogism considered as a means of proof. It begs the question formally, but not materially ; that is to say, if it be a question whether camels are herbivorous, and to decide it we are told that ' all ruminants are/ laying stress upon the ' all,' as if all had been examined, though in fact camels have not been, then the question as to camels is begged. The form of a universal proposition is then offered as evidence, when in fact the evidence has not been universally ascertained. But if in urging that 'all ruminants are herb- ivorous ' no more is meant than that so many other ruminants of different species are known to be herbivorous, and that the ruminant stomach is so well adapted to a coarse vegetable diet, that the same habit may be expected in other ruminants, such as camels, the argument then rests upon material evidence without unfairly implying the case in question. TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 159 Now the nature of the material evidence is plainly this, that the resemblance of camels to deer, oxen, etc.> in the fact of chewing the cud, justifies us in believing that they have a further resemblance in the fact of feeding on herbs; in other words, we assume that resemblance is a ground of inference. Another way of putting this difficulty with regard to syllo- gistic evidence, which we have just been discussing, is to object that by the Laws of Syllogism a conclusion must never go beyond the premises, and that therefore no progress in knowledge can ever be established, except by direct observa- tion. Now, taking the syllogism formally, this is true : if the conclusions go beyond the premises, there must be either four terms, or illicit process of the major or minor term. But taking it materially, the conclusion may cover facts which were not in view when the major premise was laid down ; facts of which we predicate something not as the result of direct obser- vation, but because they resemble in a certain way those facts which had been shown to carry the predicate when the major premise was formed. ' What sort of resemblance is a sufficient ground of infer- ence^ is, therefore, the important question alike in material Deduction and in Induction ; and we shall presently endeavour to answer it. In the above cases, the fact of chewing the cud is a strong ground for inferring vegetarianism ; the resemblance of Britain to other empires is a much less substantial basis for expecting her ultimate downfall. 5. If, now, the material character of syllogistic proof is such as we have above described, in order to generalise it the axiom de omni et nullo needs to be restated. " That whatever is true of a whole class is true of everything the class includes," seems from our present point of view to be a dictum designed to justify the begging of the question. That whatever is true of all is true of some, is a merely formal subaltern inference : knowing ' all,' how can there be any question about the * some ' ? But if we do not know ' all,' not really the ' whole 160 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE class/ we must write the dictum thus : Whatever we have reason to regard as constantly connected with the nature or connotation of a class or class-name, we may expect to be similarly connected with whatever can be shown to have that nature or connotation. Thus the feeding upon herbage, being connected with the nature of ruminants, is connected with camels, because they ruminate. Another way of putting this principle is Nota notce, nota rei ipsius, ' the mark of a mark is a mark of the thing itself,' or * whatever has a mark has what it is a mark of.' A mark is anything (A) that is never found without something else (B) ; so that where we find A, B may be expected. Now a camel is a mark of ruminating ; and ruminating is a mark of feeding upon herbage : therefore a camel is a mark of feeding upon herbage. 6. I must add that, as we distinguish between the formal and material character of the Syllogism, so we ought in the case of Subalternation. To infer I from A may imply a real advance of knowledge, if the ' Some ' of the I were not in view when ' All ' was attached to the subject of the A. Thus Britain will decay goes beyond the material grounds of All empires decay, namely, those known to have decayed: nevertheless it is a subaltern not a mediate inference ; since such a minor premise as Britain is an empire (only true in the form ' the British empire is an empire ') is a verbal proposition in disguise, and adds nothing to the argument. If the inference Britain will decay is doubtful, it is not because a false minor premise has oeen omitted by enthymeme, but because the subalternans is doubtful, because the empires that have been known to decay may not be fair examples of all empires. It should be expressed All empires having such or such characteristics. There is then room for a real minor premise The British empire has these characteristics; and on whether that is true, or not, depends the value of the inference Britain will decay. 7. The Syllogism has sometimes been discarded by those TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 161 who have only seen that, as formally stated, it is either useless or fallacious : but those who also perceive its material grounds retain and defend it. In fact, great advantages are gained by stating an argument as a formal syllogism. For, in the first place, we can then examine separately the three cond'tions on which the validity of the argument depends : (1) Are the Premises so connected that, if they are true, the Conclusion follows ? This depends upon the formal principles of chap. x. (2) Is the Minor Premise true ? This question can only arise when the minor premise is a real proposition. That Britain is an empire affords no matter for doubt or inquiry ; but whether Britain resembles Egypt, Assyria, Rome in those circumstances that led to their decay is a very difficult subject for investigation. That Camels are ruminants is now a verbal proposition to a Zoologist, but not to the rest of us ; and even to the Zoologist the ascertaining of the rela- tion in which camels stanr 1 to such ruminants as oxen and deer, is not a matter of analysing words but of dissecting specimens. (3) Is the Major Premise true ? Are all ruminants herbi- vorous? If there be any exceptions to the rule, camels are likely enough to be among the exceptions. And here the need of Induction is most conspicuous : how can we prove our premises when they are universal propositions ? A second advantage of the syllogism is, that it makes us fully aware of what an inference implies. An inference must have some grounds, or else it is a mere prejudice ; but what- i W ' ever the grounds are, if thej are sufficient in a particular case f they must be_j5ufficient for all similar c&ses,, thfty must admit of being generalised; and to generalise the grounds of the inference, is nothing else than to state tne Major Premise. If the evidence is sufficient to justify the argument that camels are herbivorous because they are ruminanrs, it must also justify the major premise, All ruminants are herbivorous ; for else -7 the inference cannot really depend merely upon the fact of L 162 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ruminating. To state our evidence syllogistically, then, must be possible, if the evidence is mediate and of a logical kind ; and to state it in this formal way, as depending on the truth of a general principle (the major premise) increases our sense of responsibility for the inference that is thus seen to imply so much ; and if there are any negative instances within our knowledge, we are the more likely to remember them. The use of syllogisms therefore is likely to strengthen our reason- ings. A third advantage is, that an accurate generalisation may be useful to others : it is indeed part of the systematic procedure of science. The memoranda of our major premises, or reasons for believing anything, may be referred to by those who come after us, and either confirmed or refuted. When such a memo- randum is used for further inferences, these inferences are said, in the language of Formal Logic, to be drawn from it, as if the conclusion were contained in our knowledge of the major premise ; but, considering the limited extent of the material evidence, it is better to say that the inference is drawn according to the memorandum or major premise, since the grounds of the major premise and of the conclusion are in fact the same. We shall see hereafter that inductive proofs may be stated in Syllogisms, and that inductive inferences are drawn according to the Law of Causation. 8. Of the above three conditions on which the validity of an argument depends, namely, (i) its formal correctness as a syllogism, (2) the truth of the Minor, and (3) the truth of the Major Premise, the most difficult to ensure are clearly the second and third, and especially the third. And here lies one important connection between Deduction and Induction. How can we know whether the premises of a deductive argument are true ? By Induction. Sometimes, indeed, premises may be deduced by Prosyllogisms : All men are mortal, it may be said, because All animals are mortal ; and All animals are mortal^ because All composite bodies are subject to dissolution. But if TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 163 there were no limit to this process proof would involve a regres- sus ad infinitum, for which life is too short ; and, besides, con- venient Prosyllogisms are not always to be found. Accordingly, Logic accepts certain Principles, Axioms, or ultimate Major Premises, such as the Laws of Thought and Causation, as con- ditions of all reasoning, leaving it to Metaphysics to investigate their grounds ; whilst the common run of general propositions, laws, or premises, if they have any scientific grounds, are either obtained by Induction from facts with the aid of the ultimate Axioms and Principles, or else are Hypotheses (that is, pre- mises provisionally assumed). For example, how do we know that all ruminants are herbi- vorous ? We have only directly observed that great multitudes are so ; the examination of a few specimens shows that their organisation is adapted to a vegetable diet, and we infer that unobserved ruminants are also herbivorous, by assuming that resemblance (in ruminating) is a ground of inference (to the property of feeding on herbage). If you ask, Why ? the usual answer is, 'Because of the Uniformity of Nature.' This is considered to be an ultimate principle, for which it is need- less and useless to ask a reason, but with the help of which our ordinary major premises may be obtained by Induction from facts. And in the same way (as we saw in 4) the conclusion oC a syllogism is obtained from the material evidence embodied in the major premise, namely, by assuming that resemblance is a ground of inference, or that Nature is uniform. 9. The Uniformity of Nature cannot be defined and is there- fore liable to be misunderstood. In many ways Nature seems not to be uniform : there is great variety in the sizes, shapes, colours and all other properties of things : bodies falling in the open air pebbles, slates, feathers descend in different lines and at different rates ; the wind and weather are proverbially uncertain ; the course of trade or of politics, is full of surprises. Yet common maxims, even when absurd, testify to a popular belief that the relations of things are constant : the doctrine of UNIVERSITY 1 164 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE St. Swithin and the rhyme beginning ' Evening red and morning grey,' show that the weather is held to be not wholly impre- dictable ; as to human affairs, it is said that ' a green Yule makes a fat churchyard,' that ' trade follows the flag,' and that * history repeats itself; and Superstition knows that witches cannot enter a stable-door if a horse-shoe is nailed over it, and that the devil cannot cross a threshold inscribed with a perfect pentagon. But the surest proof of a belief in the Uniformity of Nature is given by the conduct of men and animals ; by that adherence to habit, custom and tradition, to which in quiet times they chiefly owe their safety, but which would daily dis- appoint and destroy them, if it were not generally true that things may be found where they have been left and that in similar circumstances there are similar events. Now this general belief, seldom distinctly conceived, for the most part quite unconscious (as a principle), merely implied in what men do, is also the foundation of all the Sciences, which are entirely occupied in seeking the Laws (that is, the Uni- formities) of Nature. And Philosophy, endeavouring, as its nature is, to generalise to the utmost, whilst retaining the definiteness of scientific thought, resolves the comprehensive but indeterminate notion of Uniformity into a number of First Principles, which may be indicated as follows : (1) The Principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle (ch. vi. 3). These are called Laws of Thought ; and so they are : for, in the first place, it is true of thoughts, as of every- thing else, that they have a certain content or not ; occur in a certain order, or do not : and, in the second place, thought, in reference to an object thought about, is bound to observe these laws, on pain of else going wrong. But the reason why the above principles are laws of thought in this secondary sense (that is, as rules or imperatives) is, that they are laws of things in the primary sense of ' laws ' (as uniformities) ; for else they would misdirect us, and it would be (literally) madness to con- form to them. (2) Certain Axioms of Mediate Evidence : as, in Mathe- TRANSITION TO INDUCTION 165 matics, 'that magnitudes equal to the same magnitude are equal to one another ' ; and, in Logic, the Dictum or its equivalent 'the mark of a mark is a mark of the thing itself.' (3) That all Times and all Spaces are commensurable; although in certain relations of space (as TT) the unit of r , *~ measurement must be infinitely small. If Time really r *d*^ trotted with one man and galloped with another, as it ** **t~ seems to ; if space really swelled in places, as De Quincey dreamed that it did ; life could not be regulated, experience ^ ' could not be compared and science would be impossible. The Mathematical Axioms would then never be applicable to space or time, or to the objects or processes that fill them. (4) The Persistence of Matter and Energy : the physical principle that, in all changes of the universe, the quantities of Matter and Energy (actual and potential, so-called) remain , * If ** the same. For example, as to matter, although dew is found r * on the grass at morning without any apparent cause, and p" although a candle seems to burn away to a scrap of blackened < wick, yet every one knows that the dew has been condensed f from vapour in the air, and that the candle has only turned into gas and smoke. As to energy, although a stone thrown up to the housetop and resting there has lost actual energy, it has gained such a position that the slightest touch may bring it to the earth again in the same time as it took to travel upwards; and in that position it is said to have potential energy. When a boiler works an engine, every time the piston is thrust forward (having actual energy), an equivalent in heat (molecular energy) is lost. But for the elucidation of these principles, readers must refer to treatises of Chemistry and Physics. (5) Causation, a special form of the foregoing principles ^ (4), we shall discuss in the next chapter. ^"t 1 * (6) Certain Uniformities of Co-existence ; but for want oi a general principle of Co-existence, corresponding to Causatioa 166 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE (the principle of Succession), we can only classify these uni- formities as follows : (a) The Geometrical ; as that, in a four-sided figure, if the opposite angles are equal, the opposite sides are equal and parallel Countless similar uniformities of co-existence are disclosed by Geometry. The co-existent facts do not cause one another, nor are they jointly caused by something else ; they are mutually involved : such is the nature of space. (b) Universal co-existences among the properties of concrete things. The chief example is the co-existence of gravity with inertia in all material bodies. There is, I believe, no other entirely satisfactory case; but some good approximations to "such uniformity are known to physical science. (c) Co-existence due to Causation ; such as the positions of objects in space at any time. The houses of a town are where they are, because they were put there ; and they remain in their place as long as no other causes arise strong enough to remove or destroy them. Similarly, the relative positions of rocks in geological strata, and of trees in a forest, are due to causes. (d) The co-existence of properties in Natural Kinds ; which we call the constitution, defining characters, or specific nature of such things. Oxygen, platinum, sulphur and the other elements ; water, common salt, alcohol and other com- pounds ; the various species of plants and animals : all these are known to us as different groups of co-existent properties. It may be conjectured, indeed, that these groupings of proper- ties are also due to causation, and sometimes the causes can be traced : but very often the causes are still unknown ; and, at any rate, these cases of co-existence form a sufficiently well- marked class to be separately mentioned. ( /~ Such an experiment requires that in the negative instance r , B C shall be the least assemblage of conditions necessary to co-operate with A in producing p ; and that it is so cannot be ascertained without either general prior knowledge of the nature of the case or special experiments for the purpose. So that invariability will not really be inferred from a single expe- riment ; besides that, every prudent inquirer repeats his experi- ments, if only to guard against his own liability to error. The supposed plurality of causes does not affect the method of Difference. In the above symbolic case, A is clearly one cause (or condition) of p, whatever other causes may be possible ; whereas in the former case of the Single Method of Agreement, it remained doubtful (admitting a plurality of causes) whether A, in spite of being always present with /, was ever a cause or condition of it. Now this method of Difference is perhaps oftener than any other, though without our being distinctly aware of it, the basis of ordinary judgments. That the sun gives light and heat, that food nourishes and fire burns, that a stone will break a window or kill a bird, that turning a tap hastens or checks the flow of water or of gas, and thousands of other propositions are known to be true by rough but often emphatic applications of this method in common experience. It should be noticed that there are two ways in which this application may be made : either (a) by observation, taking for THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 209 our two instances distinct assemblages of conditions, differing only in one phenomenon together with its antecedent or con- sequent ; or (b) by experiment, regarding as our two instances the same assemblage of conditions, before and after the intro- duction of a certain agent. If, for example, there are two men of closely similar age, health, clothing and habits, one of whom stands in the shade and feels cool, whilst the other stands in the sun and feels warm, this shows in the former way, by observation, that the sun gives heat ; but if, instead of this, the man who stands in the shade merely steps into the sun- shine and feels warm, the same proposition is proved in the latter way, by experiment. The experimental way is the better when, as in this case, an immediate sequence can be obtained, because it gives a greater certainty of there being no difference between the two instances except the intervention of the given agent. For, when there are two separate sets of conditions, it may be very difficult to make sure that they are exactly similar except in one circumstance with its antecedent or consequent. On the other hand, the experimental method is unsatisfactory if some time must elapse between the introduction of the agent and the manifestation of its effects ; for then other changes may have occurred meanwhile to which these effects are really due. If you throw a stone at a window and the window breaks (nothing else having happened apparently), it will be thought pretty clear that the missile was the immediate unconditional antecedent of the fracture : but if, feeling out of sorts, you take a drug and some time afterwards feel better, it is not clear on this ground alone that the drug was the cause of recovery, for other curative processes may have been active meanwhile food, or sleep, or exercise. Any book on some branch of Physics or on Chemistry will furnish scores of examples of the method of Difference : such as Galileo's experiment to show that air has weight, by first weighing a vessel filled with ordinary air, and then filling it with condensed air and weighing it again ; when the increased weight can only be due to the greater quantity of air con- o 2io LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE tained. The melting-point of solids is determined by heating them until they do melt (as silver at 1000 C., gold at 1250, platinum at 2000) ; for the only difference between bodies at the time of melting and just before is the addition of so much heat. Similarly with the boiling-point of liquids. That the transmission of sound depends upon the continuity of an elastic ponderable medium, is proved by letting a clock strike in a vacuum (under a glass from which the air has been with- drawn by an air-pump), and standing upon a non-elastic pedestal : when the clock may be seen to strike, but makes only such a faint sound as may be due to the imperfections of the vacuum and.the pedestal. The experiments by which the chemical analysis or synthesis of various forms of matter is demonstrated are simple or com- pound applications of this method of Difference, together with the quantitative mark of causation (that cause and effect are equal) ; since the bodies resulting from an analysis are equal in weight to the body analysed, and the body resulting from a synthesis is equal in weight to the bodies synthesised. That an electric current resolves water into oxygen and hydrogen may be proved by inserting the poles of a galvanic battery in a vessel of water ; when this one change is followed by another, the rise of bubbles from each pole and the very gradual decrease of the water. If the bubbles are caught in receivers placed over them, it can be shown that the joint weight of the two bodies of gas thus formed is equal to the weight of the water that has disappeared; and that the gases are respectively oxygen and hydrogen may then be shown by proving that they have the properties of those gases according to further experi- ments by the method of Difference ; as (e.g.) that one of them is oxygen, because it supports combustion, and combines in certain definite proportions with carbon, sulphur, etc. In the more complex sciences the method of Difference is not so generally applicable, because of the greater difficulty of being sure that only one circumstance at a time has altered ; still, it is frequently used. Thus, if by dividing a certain nerve THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 211 certain muscles are paralysed, it is shown that normally that nerve controls those muscles. In his work on Earthworms^ Darwin argues that, though sensitive to mechanical tremors, they are deaf (or, at least, not sensitive to sonorous vibrations transmitted through the air), by the following experiment. He placed a pot containing a worm that had come to the surface, as usual at night, upon a table, whilst close by a piano was violently played ; but the worm took no notice of the noise. He then placed the pot upon the piano whilst it was being played, when the worm, feeling the vibrations, hastily slid back into its burrow. When, instead of altering one circumstance in an instance (which we have done our best not otherwise to disturb) and then watching what follows, we try to find two ready-made instances of a phenomenon, which only differ in one other circumstance, it is, of course, still more difficult to be sure that there is really only one other circumstance in which they differ. It may be worth while, however, to do our best to find such instances. Thus, that the temperature of ocean currents in- fluences the climate of the shores they wash, seems to be shown by the fact that the average temperature of Newfound- land is lower than that of the Norwegian coast some 15 farther north. Both regions have great continents at their back ; and as the mountains of Norway are higher and capped with perennial snow, we might expect a colder climate there : but the shore of Norway is visited by the Gulf Stream, whilst the shore of Newfoundland is traversed by a cold current from Greenland. Again, when in 1841 the railway from Rouen to Paris was being built, gangs of English and gangs of French workmen were employed upon it, and the English got through about one-third more work per man than the French. It was suspected that this difference was due to one other difference, namely, that the English fed better, preferring beef to thin soup. Now, logically, it might have been objected that the evidence was unsatisfactory, seeing that the men differed in other things besides diet in * race ' (say), which explains so 212 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE much and so easily. But the Frenchmen, having been induced to try the same diet as the English, were, in a few days, able to do as much work : so that the " two instances " were better than they looked. It often happens that evidence, though logically questionable, is good when used by experts, whose familiarity with the subject makes it good. 4. THE CANON OF CONCOMITANT VARIATIONS. Whatever phenomenon varies in any manner whenever another phenomenon (consequent or antecedent) varies in some particular manner \no other* change having concurred} is either a cause or effect of that phenomenon \pr is connected with it through some fact of causation\ This is not an entirely fresh method, but may be regarded as a special case either of Agreement or of Difference, to prove the cause or effect, not of a phenomenon as a whole, but of some modification of it. There are certain forces, such as gravitation, cohesion, heat, friction, that can never be elimi- nated altogether, and therefore can only be studied in their degrees. To such phenomena the method of Difference can never be fully applied, because there are no negative instances. But we may obtain negative instances of a given quantity of such a phenomenon (say, heat), and may apply the method of Difference to that quantity. Thus, if the heat of a body in- creases 10 degrees, from 60 to 70, the former temperature of 60 was a negative instance in respect of those 10 degrees; and if only one other circumstance (say, friction) has altered at the same time, that circumstance (if an antecedent) is the cause. Accordingly, if in the above Canon we insert, after ' particular manner', "[no other change having concurred,] " it is a state- ment of the method of Difference as applicable to the in- crement of a phenomenon instead of to the phenomenon as a whole ; and we may then omit the last clause " [or is con- nected, etc.]" For these words are inserted to provide for the case of co-effects of a common cause (such as the flash and THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 213 report of a gun) ; but if no other change (such as the discharge of a gun) has concurred with the variations of two phenomena, there cannot have been a common cause, and they are therefore cause and effect. If, on the other hand, we omit the clause " [no other change having concurred,] " the Canon is a statement of the method of Agreement as applicable to the increment of a phenomenon instead of to the phenomenon as a whole; and it is then subject to the imperfections of that method : that is to say, it leaves open the possibilities, that an inquirer may overlook a plurality of causes ; or may mistake a connection of two phenomena, which (like the flash and report of a gun) are co-effects of a common cause, for a direct relation of cause and effect. It may occur to the reader that we ought also to distinguish Qualitative and Quantitative Variations as two orders of phenomena to which the present method is applicable. But, in fact, Qualitative Variations may be adequately dealt with by the foregoing methods of Agreement, Double Agreement, and Difference; because a change of quality or property entirely gets rid of the former phase of that quality, or substitutes one for another; as when the ptarmigan changes from brown to white in winter, or as when a stag grows and sheds its antlers with the course of the seasons. The peculiar use of the method of Variations, however, is (as already observed) to formulate the conditions of proof in respect of those causes or effects which cannot be entirely got rid of, but can be obtained only in greater or less amount ; and such phenomena are, of course, quantitative. Even when there are two parallel series of phenomena, the one quantitative and the other qualitative like the rate of air vibration and the pitch of sound, or the rate of ether-vibration and the colour-series of the spectrum the method of Variations is not applicable. For (i) two such series cannot be said to vary together, since the qualitative variations are heterogeneous : 512:576 is a definite ratio ; but the corresponding notes, C, D, 214 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE in the treble clef, present only a difference. Hence (2) the correspondence of each note with each number is a distinct fact. Each octave even is a distinct fact ; there is a difference between C 64 and C 128 that could never have been anticipated without the appropriate experience. There is, therefore, no such law of these parallel series as there is for temperature and change of volume (say) in mercury. Similar remarks apply to the physical and sensitive light-series. We may, then, illustrate the two cases of the method thus (putting a dash against any letter, A' or /', to signify an increase or decrease of the phenomenon the letter stands for) : Agree- ment in Variations (other changes being admissible) ABC A' D E A" F G / q r p' s t p" u v Here the accompanying phenomena (B C q r> D E s /, FG u v) change from time to time, and the one thing in which the instances agree throughout is that any increase of A (A' or A") is followed or accompanied by an increase of/ (p' or/") : whence it is argued that A is the cause of/, according to Prop. III. (a) (ch. xv. 7). Still, it is supposable that, in the second in- stance, D or E may be the cause of the increment of / ; and that, in the third instance, F or G may be its cause : though the probability of such vicarious causation decreases rapidly with the increase of instances in which A and / vary together. And, since an actual investigation of this type must rely on observa- tion, it is further possible that some undiscovered cause, X, is the real determinant of both A and / and of their concomitant variations. Professor Ferri, in his Criminal Sociology, observes : " I have shown that in France there is a manifest correspondence of increase and decrease between the number of homicides, assaults and malicious wounding, and the more or less abundant vintage, especially in the years of extraordinary variations, whether of failure of the vintage (1853-5, 1859, 1867, 1873, 1878-80), attended by a remarkable diminution of crime (assaults and wounding), or of abundant vintages (1850, 1856-8, THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 215 1862-3. 1865, 1868, 1874-5), attended by an increase of crime" (p. 117, Eng. trans.). And earlier he had remarked that such crimes also " in their oscillations from month to month display a characteristic increase during the vintage periods, from June to December, notwithstanding the constant diminution of other offences" (p. 77). This is necessarily an appeal to the canon of Concomitant Variations, because France is never without her annual vintage, nor yet without her annual statistics of crime. We can only faintly imagine what would happen if there were no vintage ! Still, it is an argument whose cogency is only that of Agree- ment, showing that very probably the abuse of the vintage is a cause of crimes of violence, but leaving open the supposition, that some other circumstance or circumstances, arising or varying from year to year, may determine the increase or decrease of crime ; or that there is some unconsidered agent which affects both the vintage and crimes of violence. French sunshine, it might be urged, whilst it matures the generous grape, also excites a morbid fermentation in the human mind. Difference in Variations may be symbolically represented thus (no other change having concurred) : AB A'B A"B pq* / q ' f q' n Here the accompanying phenomena are always the same ; and the only point in which the successive instances differ is in the increments of A (A', A") followed by corresponding incre- ments of/ (/', p") : hence the increment of A is the cause of the increment of/. For examples of the application of this method, the reader should refer to some work of exact science. He will find in Deschanel's Natural Philosophy > c. 32, an account of some experiments by which the connection between Heat and Mechanical Work has been established. It is there shown that " whenever work is performed by the agency of heat " [as in 216 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE driving an engine], "an amount of heat disappears equivalent to the work performed ; and whenever mechanical work is spent in generating heat " [as in rubbing two sticks together], " the heat generated is equivalent to the work thus spent." And an experiment of Joule's is described, which consisted in fixing a rod with paddles in a vessel of water, and making it revolve and agitate the water by means of a string wound round the rod, passed over a pulley and attached to a weight that was allowed to fall. The descent of the weight was measured by a graduated rule, and the rise of the water's temperature by a thermometer. " It was found that the heat communicated to the water by the agitation amounted to one pound-degree Fahrenheit for every 772 foot-pounds of work" expended by the falling weight. As no other material change seems to take place during such an experiment, it shows that the progressive expenditure of mechanical energy is the cause of the progressive heating of the water. The Thermometer itself illustrates this method. It has been found that the application of heat to mercury expands it according to a law ; and hence the volume of the mercury, measured by a graduated index, is used to indicate the tempera- ture of the air, water, animal body, etc.* in which the thermo- meter is immersed, or with which it is brought in contact. In such cases, if no other change has taken place, the heat of the air, water, or body is the cause of the rise of the mercury in its tube. If some other substance (say spirit) be substituted for mercury in constructing a thermometer, it serves the same purpose, provided the index be graduated according to the law of the expansion of that substance by heat, as experi- mentally determined. It may be added that instances of phenomena that do not vary together indicate the exclusion of a supposed cause (by Prop. III. (<:)). The stature of the human race has been supposed to depend on temperature ; but there is no corre- spondence. The " not varying together," however, must not be confused with "varying inversely," which when regular THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 217 indicates a true concomitance. Indeed it is often a matter of convenience whether we regard concomitant phenomena as varying directly or inversely. It is usual to say ' the greater the friction the less the speed ' ; but it is really more intelligible to say 'the greater the friction the more rapidly molar is converted into molecular motion.' The Graphic Method is an interesting way of exhibiting Concomitant Variations to the eye, and is extensively used in physical and statistical inquiries. Along a horizontal line (the abscissa) is measured one of the conditions (or agents) with which the inquiry is concerned, called the Variable ; and along perpendiculars (ordinates) is measured some phenomenon to be compared with it, called the Variant. Thus, the expansion of a liquid by heat may be represented by measuring degrees of temperature along the horizontal, and FIG. 9. <*e 60 so 70 eo eo reo T Degrees of Temperature. the expansion of a column of the liquid in units of length along the perpendicular. In the next diagram, reduced from one given by Mr. C. H. Denyer in an article on the price of tea (Economic Journal^ No. 9), the condition measured horizontally is Time; and, vertically, three variants are measured simultaneously, so that their relations to one another from time to time may be seen at a glance. From this it is evident that, as the Duty on Tea falls, the Price of Tea falls, whilst the Consumption of Tea rises ; and, in spite of some irregularity of correspondence in the courses of the three phenomena, their general causal connection can 2i8 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 4) O ^ Jl Jo* fl Jl 5 *H a) | ^ 7 ^ 1 "o 1 r* regard - as an instance of the absence of/ obtained deduc- A B f lively from the whole phenomenon by our knowledge of A R f* the laws of B and C ; so that p- is an instance of the B f presence of /, differing otherwise from - in nothing except that A is also present. By the Canon of Difference, there- fore A is the cause of /. Or, again, when phenomena thus treated are strictly quantitative, the method may be based on Prop. III. (3), ch. xv. 7. Of course, if A can be obtained apart from B C and directly experimented with so as to produce/, so much the better ; and this may often be done ; but the special value of the method of Residues appears, when some complex phenomenon has been for the most part accounted for by known causes, whilst there remains some excess, or shortcoming, or deviation from the result which those causes alone would lead us to expect, and this residuary fact has to be explained in relation to the whole. Here the negative instance is constituted by deduction, showing what would happen but for the interference of some unknown 222 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE cause which is to be investigated ; and this prominence of the deductive process has led some writers to class the method as deductive. But we have seen that all the Canons involve deduction ; and, considering how much in every experiment is assumed as already known (what circumstances are * material,' and when conditions may be called ' the same '), the wonder is that no one has insisted upon regarding every method as concerned with residues. In fact, as scientific explanation progresses, the phenomena that may be considered as residuary become more numerous and the importance of this method increases. Examples : Tbe recorded dates of ancient eclipses having been found to differ from those assigned by calculation, it has been surmised that the average length of a day may in the meanwhile have increased. If so, this is a residuary pheno- menon not accounted for by the causes formerly recognised as determining the rotation of the earth on its axis ; and it may be explained by the doctrine that the tides, by their friction, are reducing the rate of the earth's rotation, and thereby lengthening the day. Capillarity seems to be a striking exception to the principle that water (or any liquid) ' finds its level,' that being the con- dition of equilibrium ; yet capillarity proves to be only a refined case of equilibrium when account is taken of the forces of adhesion by different kinds of bodies in contact. " Many of the new elements of Chemistry," says Herschel, "have been detected in the investigation of residual phe- nomena." Thus, Lord Rayleigh found that nitrogen from the atmosphere was slightly heavier than nitrogen got from chemical sources. The search for the cause of this difference led to the discovery of argon. The Economist shows that when a country imports goods the chief means of paying for them is to export other goods. If this were all, imports and exports would be of equal value : yet the United Kingdom imports about ^400,000,000 annually, and exports about ^300,000,000. Here, then, is a residuary THE CANONS OF DIRECT INDUCTION 223 phenomenon of ; 100,000,000 to be accounted for. But foreign countries owe us about ^50,000,000 for the use of shipping, and ; 7 0,000,000 as interest on the capital we have lent them, and ;i 5,000,000 in commissions upon business transacted for them. These sums added together amount to ^135,000,000 ; and that is ,35,000,000 too much. Thus another residuary phenomenon emerges ; for whilst foreigners seem to owe us ^435,000,000 they only send us ^400,000,000 of imports. To account for these ^35,000,000 we may suppose that they represent the annual investment of our capital abroad, in return for which no immediate payment is due; and, these being omitted, exports and imports balance. When, in pursuing the method of Variations, the phenomena compared do not always correspond in their fluctuations, the irregular movements of that phenomenon which we regard as the effect may often be explained by treating them as residuary phenomena, and then seeking for exceptional causes, whose temporary interference has obscured the influence of the general cause. Thus, returning to the diagram of the Price of Tea in 4, it is clear that generally the Price falls as the Duty falls; but in Mr. Denyer's more minutely wrought diagram, from which this is reduced, it may be seen that in 1840 the Price of Tea rose from 3*. gd. to 4*. gd. without any increase of Duty. This, however, is readily explained by the Chinese War of that year, which, of course, checked the trade. Again, from 1869 to 1889 the Duty was con- stant, whilst the Price of Tea fell as much as %d. per Ib. ; but this residuary phenomenon is explained by the prodigiously increased production of Tea during that period in India and Ceylon. The above examples of the method of Residues are all quantitative ; but the method is often employed where exact estimates are unobtainable. Darwin, having found certain modifications of animals in form, colouration and habits, that were not clearly derivable from their struggle for existence in relation to other species or 224 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE to external conditions, suggested that they were due to Sexual Selection. The ' vestiges ' and ' survivals ' so common in Biology and Sociology are residuary phenomena. It is a general inference from the doctrine of Natural Selection that every organ and function of a plant, animal, or society is in some way useful to it. There occur, however, organs and functions that have at present no assignable utility, are at least wasteful, and some- times even injurious. And the explanation is that formerly they were useful ; but that, their uses having lapsed, they are now retained by the force of heredity or tradition, CHAPTER XVII COMBINATION OF INDUCTION WITH DEDUCTION i. We have now reviewed Mill's five Canons of Inductive Proof. At bottom, as he observes, there are only two, namely, Agreement and Difference : since the Double Method, Varia- tions and Residues are (as we have seen) only special forms of the other two. And indeed it may almost be said that in final analysis they are all reducible to one, namely, Difference ; foi the cogency of the method of Agreement (as distinguished from a simple enumeration of instances agreeing in the coincidence of a supposed cause and its effect), depends upon the omission, in one instance after another, of all other circumstances ; which omission is a point of difference. Now, the Canons are an analysis of the conditions of proving directly, by means of observation or experiment, any proposition that predicates causation. But if we say * by means of observation or experiment,' it is not to be understood that these are the only means and that nothing else is involved ; for it has been shown that the Law of Causation is itself an indis- pensable foundation of the evidence. In fact Inductive Logic may be considered as haying a purely formal character. It consists, first, in a statement of the Law of Cause and Effect ; secondly, in certain immediate inferences from this Law, expanded into the Canons ; thirdly, in the syllogistic applica- tion of the Canons to special propositions of causation by means of minor premises, showing that certain instances satisfy the Canons. 220 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE At the risk of some pedantry, we may exhibit the process as follows (cf. Prof. Ray's Logic : Appendix D) : Whatever relation of events has certain marks is a case of Causation ; The relation A : p has some or all of these marks (as shown by observation and by the conformity of instances to such or such a Canon) : Therefore, the relation A : p is a case of Causation. Now, the parenthesis, "as shown by the conformity, etc." is an adscititious member of an Epicheirema, which may be stated, as a Prosyllogism, thus : If an instance, etc. (Canon of Difference) ; A Tl C* Ti f~* The instances > - are of the kind required : p q r q r Therefore, A, present where p occurs and absent where it does not occur, is an indispensable antecedent of/. Such is the bare Logic of Induction : so that, strictly speaking, observation or experiment is no part of the logic, but a means of applying the logic to actual, that is, not merely symbolical, propositions. The Formal Logic of Induction is essentially deductive ; and it has been much questioned whether any transition from the formal to the material conditions of proof is possible. As long as we are content to illustrate the Canons with symbols, such as A and /, all goes well ; but can we in any actual investigation show that the relevant facts or f instances ' correspond with those symbols ? In the first place, as Dr. Venn shows, natural phenomena want the distinctness and capability of isolation that belong to symbols. Secondly, the observing whether instances conform to a Canon, must always be subject at last to the limits of our faculties. How can we ascertain exact equality, immediate sequence? The Canon of Difference, in its experimental application, is usually considered the most cogent sort of proof: yet when can the two sequent instances, before and after the introduction of a certain agent, be said to differ in nothing else ? Are not earth and stars always changing posi- COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 227 tion ; is not every molecule in the room and apparatus always oscillating? It is true that our senses are now aided by elaborate instruments ; but the construction of these depends on scientific theories, which again depend on experiments. It is right to touch upon this well-known sceptical topic ; but to insist much upon it is not a sign of good sense. The works of Herschel, Whewell, and Jevons should be consulted for the various methods of correcting observations, by repeating them, averaging them, verifying one experimental process by another, always refining the methods of exact measurement, multiplying the opportunities of error (that if any exist it may at last show itself), and by other devices of what may be called Material Logic or Methodology. But, probably, only many years spent in the study and personal manipulation of scientific processes, can give a just sense of their effectiveness ; and to stand by, suggesting academic doubts, is easier and more amusing. 2. Still, it is not so much in laws based upon direct obser- vation or experiment, that the material validity of scientific reasoning appears, as in the cumulative evidence that arises from the co-ordination of laws within each science, and the growing harmony and coherence of all sciences. This requires a more elaborate combination of deduction with observation and experiment. During the last three hundred years many departments of science have been reduced under principles of the greatest generality, such as the Law of Gravitation, the Undulatory theory of Light, the Conservation of Energy, and the Theory of Natural Selection ; connecting and explaining the less general laws, which, again, are said to connect and explain the facts. Meanwhile, those sciences that were the first to make progress have been useful in developing others which, like Biology and Sociology, present greater difficulties. In fact it is more and more apparent that the distinctions drawn among Sciences are entirely for the convenience of study, and that all Sciences tend to merge in one universal Science of Nature. Now, this process of the ' unification of 228 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE knowledge ' is almost another name for deduction ; but at the same time it depends for its reality and solidity upon a constant reference to observation and experiment. Of the logical character of this process only a very inadequate notion can be given in the ensuing chapters. Let us begin by returning to some earlier considerations. We have seen in chap. xiv. 6, that when two or more agents or forces combine to produce a phenomenon, their effects are intermixed in it, and this in one of two ways according to their nature. In chemical action and in vegetable and animal life, the causal agents concerned are blended in their results in such a way that most of the qualities which they exhibited severally are lost, whilst new qualities appear instead. Thus chlorine (a gas) and sodium (a metal), in a certain combina- tion, form common salt ; which is quite unlike either of them : a man eats bread, and it becomes muscle, nerve and bone. In such cases we cannot trace the qualities of the causal agents in the qualities of the effects ; given such causes, we can prove by experimental analysis and synthesis, according to the canons of induction, that they have such effects ; but we may not be able in any new case to calculate what the effects will be. On the other hand, in Astronomy and Physics, the causes treated of are mechanical ; at least, it is the aim of Physics to attain to a mechanical conception of phenomena ; so that, in every new combination of forces, the intermixed effect, or re- sultant, may be calculated beforehand ; provided that the forces concerned admit of being quantitatively estimated, and that the conditions of their combination are not so complex as to baffle the powers of mathematicians. In such cases, therefore, when direct observation or experiment is insufficient to resolve an effect into the laws of its conditions, the general method is to calculate what may be expected from a combination of its conditions, either as known or hypothetically assumed, and to compare this anticipation with the actual phenomenon. 3. This is what Mill calls the Direct Deductive Method ; or, the Physical Method, because it is so much relied on in COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 229 j\*u- deal/ :ady >. knit ' \ treating of Light, Heat, Sound, etc. ; though it is also the usual method of Astronomy and Economics : Deduction leads the way, and its results are tested by inductive experi- ments or observations. Given any complex mechanica^ / phenomenon, the inquirer considers (i) what laws already ascertained by induction seem likely to apply to it (in default of known laws, hypotheses are substituted : cf. chap, xviii.) ; he then (2) computes the effect that will follow from these laws in circumstances similar to the case before him ; and (3) he verifies his conclusion by comparing it with the actual pheno- menon. A well-tried and staunch example of this method is the explanation of the rise of water in the * common pump.' We know three laws applicable to this case: (a) that the atmosphere weighs upon the water outside the pump with a pressure of 15 Ib. to the square inch; (b) that a liquid (and therefore the water) transmits pressure equally in all directions (upwards as well as downwards and sideways) ; and (c) that pressure upon a body in any direction, if not counteracted by an opposite pressure, produces motion. Hence, when the rise of the piston of the pump removes the pressure upon the water within the cylinder, tending to produce a vacuum there, this water is pushed up by the pressure of the air upon the water outside the cylinder, and follows the rising piston, until the column of water inside the cylinder exerts a pressure equal to that of the atmosphere upon a given area. So much for the computation; does it correspond with the fact ? It is found that at the sea- level water can be pumped to the height of 33 feet ; and that such a column of water has a pressure of 15 Ib. to the square inch. We may show further that, at the sea level, spirits of wine may be pumped higher, according to its less specific gravity ; and that if we attempt to pump water at successive altitudes above the sea level, we can only raise it to less and less heights, corresponding with the lessened atmospheric pres- sure at those altitudes, where the column of air producing the pressure is shorter. Finally, if we try to work a pump, having 250 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE first produced a vacuum over the water outside the cylinder, we shall find that the water inside will not rise at all ; the piston can be raised, but the water does not follow it. The verifica- tion thus shows that the computed effect corresponds with the phenomenon to be explained ; that the result does not depend upon the nature of water only, but is true (allowing for differ- ences of specific gravity) of other liquids ; that if the pressure of the outside air is diminished, the height of pumping is so too (canon of Variations) ; and that if that pressure is. entirely removed, pumping becomes impossible (canon of Difference). Any text-book of Astronomy or Physics furnishes numerous illustrations of this method. Take, for example, the first chap- ter of Deschanel's Optics^ where are given three methods of determining the velocity of Light. This was first deduced from observation of Jupiter's satellites. The one nearest the planet passes behind it, or into its shadow, and is eclipsed at intervals of about 42 \ hours. But it can be shown that, when Jupiter and the Earth are nearest together on the same side of the Sun, an eclipse of this satellite is visible from the earth 16 min. 26-6 sec. earlier than when Jupiter and the Earth are furthest apart on opposite sides of the Sun : 16 min. 26*6 sec., then, is the time in which light traverses the diameter of the Earth's orbit. Therefore, supposing the Earth's distance from the Sun to be 91 J millions of miles, light travels about 185,500 miles a second. Another deduction, agreeing with this, starts from the fact of aberration, or the displacement of the apparent from the actual position of the stars in the direction of the earth's motion. Aberration depends partly on the velocity of light, partly on the velocity of the Earth ; and the latter being known, the former can be computed. Now, these two deductive arguments, verifying each other, have also been verified experimentally. Foucault's experiment to measure the velocity of light is too elaborate to be described here : a full account of it will be found in the treatise above cited, 687. When the phenomena to be explained are of such a -"'* character, so vast in extent, power or duration, that it is COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 231 impossible, in the actual circumstances of the case, to frame experiments in order to verify a deductive explanation, it may still be possible to reproduce a similar phenomenon upon a smaller scale. Thus Monge's explanation of mirage by the great heat of the desert sand, which makes the lowest stratum of air less dense than those above it, so that rays of light from distant objects are refracted in descending, until they are actually turned upwards again to the eye of the beholder, giving him inverted images of the objects as if they were reflected in water, is manifestly incapable of being verified by experiment in the natural conditions of the phenomenon. But by heating the bottom of " a sheet-iron box, with its ends cut away," the rarefied air at the bottom of the box may sometimes be made to yield reflections ; and this shows at least that the supposed cause is a possible one (Deschanel, Optics, 726). Similarly as to the vastest of all phenomena, the evolution of the stellar system, and of the solar system as part of it, from an immense cloudlike volume of matter : Mr. Spencer, in his Essay on 2"he Nebular Hypothesis (Essays, I. vi.), says, amidst a great array of deductive arguments from mechanical principles, that " this a priori reasoning harmonises with the results of experiment. Dr. Plateau has shown that when a mass of fluid is, as far as may be, protected from the action of external Torces, it will, if made to rotate with adequate velocity, form detached rings ; and that these rings will break up into spheroids, which turn on their axes in the same direction with the central mass." The theory of the evolution of species of plants and animals by Natural Selection, again, though, of course, it cannot be verified by direct experiment (since experiment implies artificial arrange- ment), and the process is too slow for observation, is, never- theless, to some extent confirmed by the practice of gardeners and breeders of animals : since, by taking advantage o accidental variations of form and colour in the plants or animals under their care, and relying on the heritability of these variations, they obtain extensive modifications of the original stocks, and adapt them to the various purposes for 232 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE which flowers and cereals, poultry, dogs and cattle are domes- ticated. This shows, at least, that living forms are plastic and extensively modifiable in a comparatively short time. 4. Suppose, however, that, in verifying a deductive argu- ment, the effect as computed from the laws of the causes assigned, does not correspond with the facts observed ; there must then be an error somewhere. If the fact has been accurately observed, the error must lie either in the process of deduction and computation, or else in the premises. As to the process of deduction, it may be very simple and easily revised, as in the above explanation of the common pump ; or it may be very involved and comprise long trains of mathe- matical calculation. If, however, on re-examining the compu- tations, we find them correct, it remains to look for some mistake in the premises. (1) We may not have accurately ascertained the laws, or the modes of operation, of the forces present. Thus, the rate at which bodies fall was formerly believed to vary in proportion to their relative weights ; and any estimate based upon this belief is not likely to have agreed with the facts. Again, the corpuscular theory of light, namely, that the physical cause of light is a stream of fine particles projected in straight lines from the luminous object, though it seemed adequate to the explanation of many optical phenomena, could not be made to agree with the facts of interference and double refraction. (2) The circumstances in which the agents are combined may not have been correctly conceived. When Newton began to inquire whether the attraction of the earth determined the orbit of the moon, he was at first disappointed. '* According to Newton's calculations, made at this time," says Whewell, " the moon, by her motion in her orbit, was deflected from the tangent every minute through a space of thirteen feet. But by noticing the space which bodies would fall in one minute at the earth's surface, and supposing this to be diminished in the ratio of the inverse square, it appeared that gravity would, at the moon's orbit, draw a body through more than fifteen COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 233 feet." In view of this discrepancy he gave up the inquiry for sixteen years, until in 1682, having obtained better data, he successfully renewed it. " He had been mistaken in the magnitude of the earth, and consequently in the distance of the moon, which is determined by measurements of which the earth's radius is the base." It was not, therefore a mistake as to the law or nature of the forces concerned (namely, the law of the inverse square and the identity of celestial with terrestrial gravity), but as to the circumstances in which the agents (earth and moon) were combined, that prevented his calculations being verified. (Hist. 2nd. Sc. : VII. ii. 3.) (3) One or more of the agents affecting the result may have been overlooked and omitted from the estimate. Thus, an attempt to explain the tides by taking account only of the earth and the moon, will not entirely agree with the facts, since the sun also influences the tides. This illustration, however, shows that when the conclusion of a deductive explanation does not entirely agree with the facts, it is not always to be inferred that the reasoning is, properly speaking, wrong ; it may be right as far as it goes, and merely inadequate. Hence (a) it is often in just such cases that an opportunity occurs of applying the Method of Residues, by discovering the agent that must be allowed for in order to complete the explanation. And (b) the investigation of a phenomenon is often designedly begun upon an imperfect basis for the sake of simplicity ; the result being regarded as a first approximation, to be afterwards corrected by including one by one the remaining agents or circumstances affecting the phenomenon, until the theory is complete ; that is, until its agreement with the facts is satis- factory. (4) We may have included among the data of our reason- ings agents or circumstances that do not exist or do not affect the phenomenon in question. In the early days of science purely fanciful powers were much relied upon : such as the solid spheres that carried the planets and stars ; the influence of the planets upon human destiny ; the tendency of every- 234 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE thing to seek " its own place," so that fire rises to heaven, and solids fall to the earth ; the " plastic virtue " of the soil, which was once thought to have produced fossils. It may be said, however, that when such conceptions hindered the progress of explanation, it was not so much by vitiating the deductive method as by putting men off from exact inquiries. More to our present purpose were the supposed cataclysms, or extra- ordinary convulsions of the earth, a belief in which long hindered the progress of Geology. Again, in Biology, Psycho- logy, and Sociology many explanations have depended upon the doctrine that any improvement of structure or faculty acquired by an individual may be inherited by his descendants : as that, if an animal learns to climb trees, his offspring have a greater aptitude for that mode of life ; that if a man tries to be good, his children find it easier to be virtuous ; that if the inhabitants of a district carry on cloth-work, it becomes easier for each successive generation to acquire dexterity in that art. But now the heritability of powers acquired by the individual through his own efforts, is disputed; and, if the denial be made good, all such explanations as the above must be revised. Clearly, then, if the premises of a deductive argument be vitiated in any of these four ways, its conclusion will fail to agree with the results of observation and experiment, unless, of course, one kind of error happen to be cancelled by another that is ' equal and opposite.' We now come to a variation of the method of combining Induction with Deduction, so im- portant as to require separate treatment. 5. The Inverse or Historical Method has of late years become remarkably fruitful. When the forces determining a phenomenon are too numerous, or too indefinite, to be com- bined in a direct deduction, we. may begin by collecting an empirical law of the phenomenon!^ that * the democracies of City-states are arbitrary and fickle'), and then endeavour to show by deductions from " the nature of the case," that is, from a consideration of the circumstances and forces known COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 235 to be operative (of which, in the above instance, the most important is sympathetic contagion), that such a law was to be expected.Y Deduction is thus called in to verify a previous >Iahietron~; whereas in the ' Physical Method ' a Deduction Sr was verified by comparing it with an Induction or an experi- ment ; hence the Method now to be discussed has been named the Inverse Deductive Method. But although it is true that, in such inquiries as we are now dealing with, Induction generally takes the lead ; yet I cannot think that the mere order in which the two logical processes occur is the essential distinction between the two ways of combining them. For, in the first place, in investigations of any complexity both Induction and Deduction recur again and again in whatever order may be most convenient ; and, in the second place, the so-called ' inverse order ' is sometimes resorted to in Astronomy and Physics. For example, Kepler'TX Laws were first collected empirically from observations of the \ planetary motions, and afterwards deduced by Newton from the Law of Gravitation ; this, then, was the Inverse Method r^^ but the result is something very different from any that can be obtained by the Historical Method. The essential difference . between the Physical and Historical Methods is that, in the f f former, whether Direct or Inverse, the deductive process,\ ^T owhen complete, amounts to exact demonstration; whereas, in ) the latter, the deductions consist of qualitative reasonings, andy ""the results are indefinite/'- j^They establish (i) a priori a merely probable connection between the phenomena according to the empirical law (say, between City-democracy and fickle politics) ; (2) connect this with other historical or social generalisations, by showing that they all alike flow from the same causes, namely, from the nature of races of men under certain social and geographical conditions; and (3) explain why such empirical laws may fail, according to the differences that prevail among races of men and among the conditions under which they live. Thus, seeing how rapidly excitement is propagated by the chatter, grimacing, and gesticulation of 236 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE townsmen, it is probable enough that the democracy of a City- state should be fickle (and arbitrary, because irresponsible). A similar phenomenon of panic, sympathetic hope and despair, is exhibited by every stock-exchange, and is not peculiar to political life. And when political opinion is not manufactured solely in the reverberating furnace of a city, fickleness ceases to characterise Democracy ; and, in fact, is not found in Switzerland or the United States, nor even in France so far as politics depend upon the peasantry. This is called the Historical Method, then, because it is more useful than any other in explaining the movements of history, and iri verifying the generalisations of political and social science. We must not, however, suppose that its use is confined to such studies. Only a ridiculous pedantry would allot to each subject its own method and forbid the use of any other ; as if it were not our capital object to establish truth by any means. Wherever the forces determining a phenomenon are too numerous or too indefinite to be combined in a deductive demonstration, there the Historical Method is likely to be useful ; and this seems often to be the case in Geology and Biology, as well as in the Science of History, or Sociology, and its various subsidiary studies. Consider upon what causes historical events depend : customs, character, and opinions of all the people concerned ; the organisation of their government, and the character of their religious institutions ; the development of industry among them, of the military art, of fine art, literature and science ; their relations, commercial, political and social with other nations ; the physical conditions of climate and geographical position amidst which they live. Hardly an event of importance occurs in any nation that is not, directly or indirectly, influenced by every one of mese circumstances, and that does not react upon them. Now, from the nature of the Inductive Methods, it is plain that, in such a complex and tangled situation as history presents, a satisfactory employment of them is rarely possible ; for they all require the actual or virtual isolation of COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 237 the phenomenon under investigation. They also require the greatest attainable immediacy of connection between cause and effect ; whereas the causes of social events may accumulate during hundreds of years. Clearly, therefore, in collecting empirical laws from history, only very rough inductions can be hoped for, and we may have to be content with simple enumeration. Hence the importance of supporting such laws by deduction from the nature of the case, however faint a pro- bability of the asserted connection is thereby raised ; and this even if each law is valued merely for its own sake. Still more, if anything worth the name of Historical Science is to be con- structed, must a mere collection of such empiricisms fail to content us; and the only way to give them a scientific character is to show deductively their common dependence upon various combinations of the same causes. Yet even those who profess to employ the Historical Method often omit the deductive half of it ; and of course ' practical politicians ' boast of their entire contentment with what they call ' the facts. 1 Sometimes, however, politicians, venturing upon deductive reasoning have fallen into the opposite error of omitting to test their results by any comparison with the facts : arguing from certain ' Rights of Man,' or * Interests of Classes,' or * Laws of Supply and Demand,' that this or that event will happen, or ought to happen, without troubling themselves to observe whether it does happen or ever has happened. This method of Deduction without any empirical verification, is called by Mill the Geometrical ; and, plainly, it can be trust- worthy only where there is no actual conflict of forces to be considered. In pure mathematical reasoning about space, time, and number, provided the premises and the reasoning be correct, verification by a comparison with the facts may be needless, because there is no possibility of counteraction. But when we deal with actual causes, no computation of their effects can be relied upon without comparing our conclusions with the facts : not even in Astronomy and Physics, least of all in Politics. 238 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Burke, then, has well said that "without the guide and light of sound, well-understood principles all our reasoning in politics, as in everything else, would be only a confused jumble of particular facts and details without the means of drawing any sort of theoretical or practical conclusion " ; but that, on the other hand, the statesman, who does not take account of circumstances, infinite and infinitely combined, "is not erroneous, but stark mad he is metaphysically mad" (On the Petition of the Unitarians). There is, or ought to be, no logical difference between the evidence required by a states- man and that appealed to by a philosopher ; and since, as we have seen, the combination of principles with circumstances cannot, in solving problems of social science, be made with the demonstrative precision that belongs to astronomical and physical investigations, there remains the Historical Method as above described. Examples of the empirical laws ffom which this method begins will occur to every one. They abound in histories, newspapers, and political discussions, and are of all shades of truth or half-truth : as that ' History consists in the biographies of great men ' ; in other words, that the movements of society are due to exceptional personal powers, not to general causes ; That at certain epochs great men occur in groups ; That every Fine Art passes through periods of development, culmination and decline; That Democracies tend to change into Des- potisms ; That the possession of power, whether by classes or despots, corrupts the possessor ; That ' the governments most distinguished for sustained vigour and abilities have generally been aristocracies ' ; That l revolutions always begin in hunger ' ; That civilisation is inimical to individuality ; That the civilisation of the country proceeds from the town ; That 1 the movement of progressive societies has hitherto been a movement from Status to Contract (/.*., from a condition in which the individual's rights and duties depend on his caste, or position in his family as slave, child, or patriarch, to a condition in which his rights and duties are largely determined COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 239 by the voluntary agreements he enters into) ; and this last is treated by Mr. Spencer as one aspect of the law first stated by Comte, that the progress of societies is from the military to the industrial state. The deductive process we may illustrate by Mr. Spencer's explanation a priori of the co-existence in the military state of those specific characters, the inductive proof of which furnished an illustration of the method of Agreement (ch. xvi. i). The type of the military State involves the growth of the warrior class, and the treatment of labourers as existing solely to support the warriors ; the complete subordination of all indi- viduals to the will of the despotic soldier-king, their property, liberty and life being at the service of the State ; the regimen- tation of society, not only for military, but also for civil purposes ; the suppression of all private associations, etc. Now all these characteristics arise from their utility for the purpose of war, a utility amounting to necessity if war is the State's chief purpose. For every purpose is best served when the whole available force co-operates toward it : other things equal, the bigger the army the better ; and to increase it, men must be taken from industry until only just enough remain to feed and equip the soldiers. As this arrangement is not to everybody's taste, there must be despotic control; and this control is most effective through regimentation by grades of command. Private associations, of course, cannot live openly in such a State, because they may have wills of their own and are convenient for conspiracy. Thus the induction of charac- teristics is verified by a deduction of them from the nature of the case. r 6. The greater indefiniteness of the Historical, compared with the Physical Method, both in its inductions and in its deductions, makes it, perhaps, even more difficult to work with. It wants much sagacity and more sincerity; for the demon of Party is generally too much with us. Our first care should be to make the empirical law as nearly true as pos- sible, collecting as many as we can of the facts which the law 24 o LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE is supposed to generalise, and examining them according to the canons of Induction, with due allowance for the imperfect applicability of those canons to such complex, unwieldy, and indefinite instances. Turning to the examples of such laws given above, it is clear that in some cases no pains have been taken to examine the facts. What is the inductive evidence that Democracies change into Despotisms ; that revolutions always begin in hunger ; or that civilisation is inimical to individuality ? Even Mill's often quoted saying, " that the governments remarkable in history for; sustained vigour and ability have generally been aristocracies," is oddly over-stated. For if you turn to the passage (Rep. Gov. chap, vi.), the next sentence tells you that such governments have always been aristocracies of public functionaries ; and the next sentence but one restricts, appa- rently, the list of such remarkable governments to two Rome and Venice. Whence, then, comes the word " generally " into Mill's law? As to deducing our empirical law from a consideration of the nature of the case, it is obvious that we ought (a) to take account of all the important conditions; (b) to allow weight to them severally in proportion to their importance; and (c) not to include in our estimates any condition which we cannot show to be probably present and operative. Thus the Great-Man-Theory of history must surely be admitted to assign a real condition of national success. The great man organises, directs, inspires : is that nothing ? On the other hand, to recognise no other condition of national success is the manifest frenzy of a mind in the mythopoeie age. We must allow the great man his due weight, and then inquire into the general conditions that (a) bring him to birth in one nation rather than another, and (b) give him his opportunity. Mill's explanation of the success of the aristocratic govern- ments of Rome and Venice is, that they were, in fact, bureau- cracies; that is to say, their members were trained in the science and art of administration and command. Here, again, COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 241 we have, no doubt, a real condition ; but is it the only one ? The public mind, which little relishes the scaling down of Mill's original law to those two remote cases, is persuaded that an aristocracy is the depository of hereditary virtue, especially with reference to government, and would at once ascribe to this circumstance the greater part of the success of any aristo- cratic government. Now, if the effects of training are inherited, they must, in an hereditary aristocracy, increase the energy of the cause assigned by Mill ; but, if not, such heredity is a con- dition "not present or not operative." Still, if families are ennobled for their extraordinary natural powers of administra- tion or command (and this sometimes happens), it is agreed on all hands that innate qualities are heritable ; at least, if care be taken to intermarry with families similarly distinguished, and if by natural or artificial selection all the failures among the off- spring be eliminated. The Spartans had some crude notion of both these precautions ; and if such measures had been widely adopted, we might deduce from the doctrine of heredity a pro- bability in favour of Mill's original proposition, and thereby verify it in its generality, if it could be collected from the facts. The Historical Method may be further illustrated by the course adopted in that branch of Social Science which has been found susceptible of the most extensive independent develop- ment, namely, Economics. First, by way of contrast, I should say that the general, abstract, or theoretical treatment of Economics is according to the Physical Method ; because, as Mill explains, although the phenomena of industry are no doubt influenced, like other social affairs, by all the other cir- cumstances of Society, government, religion, war, art, etc. ; yet, where industry is most developed, as in England and the United States, certain special conditions affecting it are so much the most important that, for the purpose at least of a first out- line of the science, they may conveniently be considered as the only ones. These conditions are : (i) the general disposition of men to obtain wealth with as little trouble as possible, and (2) to spend it so as to obtain the greatest satisfaction of their Q 242 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE various desires ; (3) the facts that determine population, and (4) the tendency of extractive industry, when pushed beyond a certain limit without any improvement in the industrial arts, to yield " diminishing returns." From these premises it is easy to infer the general laws of prices, of wages and interest (which are the prices of labour and of the use of capital), and of rent ; and it remains to verify these by comparing them with the facts in each case ; and (if they fail to agree with the facts) to amend them, according to the Method of Residues, by taking account of those influential conditions which were omitted from the first draft of the theory. Whilst, h6wever, this is usually the procedure of those inquirers who have done most to give Economics its scientific character, to insist that no other plan shall be adopted would be sheer pedantry ; and Dr. Keynes has shown, in his Scope and Method of Political Economy, that Mill has him self some- times solved economic problems by the Historical Method. With an analysis of his treatment of Peasant Proprietorship in Book II., cc. 7 and 8 of his Principles of Political Economy, we may close this chapter. Mill first shows inductively, by collecting evidence from Switzerland, Germany, Norway, Belgium, and France, that peasant proprietors are super- humanly industrious, intelligent cultivators, and generally intelligent men, prudent, temperate, and |ndee^entand that they exercise self-control in avoiding inrpTovldSnt marriages. This group of empirical generalisations as to the character of peasant proprietors he then deduces from the nature of the case : their industry, he says, is a natural consequence of the fact that, however much they produce, it is all their own ; they cultivate intelligently, because for generations they have given their whole mind to it; they are generally intelligent men, because the variety of work involved in small farming, requir- ing foresight and calculation, necessarily promotes intelligence ; they are prudent, because they have something to save, and by saving can improve their station and perhaps buy more land ; they are temperate, because intemperance is incompatible with COMBINED INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 243 industry and prudence ; they are independent, because secure of the necessaries of life, and from ( having property to fall back upon ; and they avoid improvidence in marriage, because the extent and fertility of their fields is always plainly before them, and therefore how many children they can maintain is easily calculated. The worst of them is that they work too hard and deny themselves too much : but, over the greater part of the world, other peasantry work too hard ; though they can scarcely be said to deny themselves too much, since all their labour for others brings them no surplus to squander upon self-indulgence. CHAPTER XVIII HYPOTHESES i. An Hypothesis, sometimes employed instead of a known law* as a premise in the deductive investigation of nature, is denned by Mill as " any supposition which we make (either without actual evidence, or on evidence avowedly insufficient) in order to endeavour to deduce from it con- clusions in accordance with facts which are known to be real ; under the idea that if the conclusions to which the hypothesis leads are known truths, the hypothesis itself either must be, or at least is likely to be, true." The deduction of known truths from an hypothesis is its Verification ; and when this has been accomplished in a good many cases, and there are no manifest failures, the hypothesis is often called a Theory ; though this term is also used for the whole system of laws of a certain class of phenomena, as when Astronomy is called the ' theory of the heavens.' Between hypothesis and theory in the former sense no distinct line can be drawn ; for the complete proof of a certain speculation may take a long time, and meanwhile the gradually accumulating evidence pro- duces in different minds very different degrees of satisfaction ; so that the sanguine begin to talk of ' the theory,' whilst the melancholic continue to call it l the hypothesis.' An Hypothesis may be made concerning (i) an Agent, such as the ether ; or (2) a Collocation, such as the plan of our solar system whether geocentric or heliocentric ; or (3) a Law of an agent's operation, as that light is transmitted by a wave- motion. HYPOTHESES 245 The received explanation of Light involves both an agent, the ether, as an all-pervading elastic fluid, and also the law of its operation as transmitting light in waves of definite form and lengths, with definite velocity. The agreement between the calculated results of this complex hypothesis and the observed phenomena of light is the chief part of the verifica- tion, which has now been so successfully accomplished that we generally hear of the * Undulatory Theory.' Sometimes a new agent only is proposed ; as the planet Neptune was at first assumed to exist in order to account for perturbations in the movements of Uranus, influencing it according to the already established law of Gravitation. Sometimes the agents are known, and only the law of their operation is hypothetical, as was at first the case with the law of Gravitation itself. For the agents, namely, Earth, falling bodies on the Earth, Moon, Sun, and planets were manifest ; and the hypothesis was that their motions might be due to their attracting one another with a force proportional to the product of their masses and inversely proportional to the squares of the distances between them. In the Ptolemaic Astronomy, again, there was an hypothesis as to the collocation of the heavenly bodies (namely, that our Earth was the centre of the universe, and that Moon, Sun, planets and stars revolved around her) : in the early form of the system there was also an hypothesis concerning agents upon which this arrangement depended (namely, the crystalline spheres in which the heavenly bodies were fixed, though these were after- wards declared to be imaginary) ; and an hypothesis concerning the law of operation (namely, that circular motion is the most perfect and eternal, and therefore proper to celestial things). Hypotheses, of course, are by no means confined to the physical sciences : we all make them freely in private life. In searching for anything, we guess where it may be before going to look : the search for the North Pole is likewise guided by hypotheses how best to get there. In estimating the characters or explaining the conduct of acquaintances or of public men, we frame hypotheses as to their dispositions and principles. 246 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE * That we should not impute motives ' is a peculiarly absurd maxim, as there is no other way of understanding human life. To impute bad motives, indeed, when good are just as pro- bable, is to be wanting in the scientific spirit, which views every subject in 'a dry light.' Nor can we help 'judging others by ourselves ' ; for self-knowledge is the only possible starting-point when we set out to interpret the lives of others. But to understand the manifold combinations of which the elements of character are susceptible, and how these are deter- mined by the breeding of race or family under various con- ditions, and again by the circumstances of each man's life, demands an extraordinary union of sympathetic imagination with scientific habits of thought. Such should be the equip- ment of the historian, who pursues the same method of hypothesis when he attempts to explain (say) the state of parties upon the Exclusion Bill, or the policy of Louis XI. Problems such as the former of these are the easier ; because, amidst the compromises of a party, personal peculiarities obliterate one another, and expose a simpler scheme of human nature with fewer fig-leaves. Much more hazardous hypo- theses are necessary in interpreting the customs of savages, and the feelings of all sorts of animals. Thus the method of our every-day thoughts is identical with that of our most refined speculations. Literary criticisms, again, abound with hypo- theses : e.g.) as to the composition of the Homeric poems, the order of the Platonic dialogues, the authorship of the Caed- monic poems, or the Ossianic, or of the letters of Junius. And in all these cases we have to ask whether the hypothesis accounts for the facts. 2. It follows from the definition of an hypothesis that none is of any use that does not admit of verification (proof or disproof), by comparing the results that may be deduced from it with facts or laws. If so framed as to elude every attempt to test it by facts, it can never be proved by them nor add anything to our understanding of them. Suppose that a conjurer asserts that his table is controlled HYPOTHESES 247 by the spirit of your deceased relative of virtuous memory, and makes it rap out an account of some domestic adventure that could hardly have been expected to be within a stranger's knowledge. So far good. Then, trying again, the table raps out some absurd blunder about your family history which the deceased relative could not have committed ; but the conjurer explains that 'a lying spirit' sometimes possesses the table. Plainly, this amendment of the hypothesis makes it equally compatible with success and with failure. It has been said of a certain supposed biological agent, "It would seem that by a little skilful manipulation it can be made to account for any- thing that has ever been observed, or is ever likely to be observed. It is one of those convenient invisibles that will do anything that you desire." And whatever the justice of this criticism, it shows a sound conception of what is to be required of an hypothesis. Very similar was the case of the Ptolemaic Astronomy : by perpetual tinkering, its hypothesis was made to correspond with accumulating observations of the celestial motions ; so that, until the telescope was invented, it may be said to have been almost unverifiable. Consider, again, the sociological hypothesis, that civil order was at first founded on a Contract which remains binding upon all mankind : this is reconcilable with the most opposite institutions. For we have no record of such an event; and if the institutions of one State (say the British) include ceremonies, such as the coronation oath and oath of allegiance, which may be remnants of an original contract, they may nevertheless be of comparatively recent origin : whereas if the institutions of another State (say the Russian) contain nothing that admits of similar interpreta- tion, yet traces of the contract once existing may long since have been obliterated. Moreover, the actual contents of the contract not having been preserved, every adherent of this hypothesis supplies them at his own discretion, * according to the dictates of Reason ' ; and so one derives from it the duty of passive obedience, and another with equal cogency estab- lishes the right of rebellion. 248 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE To be verifiable, then, an hypothesis must be definite; if somewhat vague in its first conception (which is reasonably to be expected), it must be made definite in order to be put to the proof. But, except this condition of verifiability, and denniteness for the sake of verifiability, without which a proposition does not deserve the name of an hypothesis, it seems inadvisable to lay down rules for a ' legitimate ' hypo- thesis. The epithet is infelicitous. It suggests that the Logician makes rules for scientific inquirers ; whereas his business is to discover the principles which they, in fact, employ in what are acknowledged to be their most successful investigations. If he did make rules for them, and they treated him seriously, they might be discouraged in the exercise of that liberty of hypothesising which is the condition of all originality ; whilst if they paid no attention to him, he must suffer some loss of dignity. To say that a ' legitimate hypothesis ' must explain all the facts, at least in the department for which it is invented, is decidedly discouraging. No doubt it may be expected to do this in the long run when (if ever) it is completely established ; but this may take a long time : Is it meanwhile illegitimate? Or can this adjective be applied to Newton's corpuscular theory of light, even though it has failed to explain all the facts ? 3. Given a verifiable hypothesis, however, what constitutes proof or disproof ? (i) If a new agent be proposed, it is desirable that we should be able directly to observe it, or at least to obtain some evidence of its existence of a different kind from the very facts which it has been invented to explain. Thus, in the discovery of Neptune, after the existence of such a planet outside the orbit of Uranus had been conjectured (to account for the movement of the latter), the place in the heavens which such a body should occupy at a certain time was calculated, and there by means of the telescope it was actually seen. Agents, however, are assumed and reasoned upon very HYPOTHESES 249 successfully which, by their nature, never can be objects of perception : such are the atoms of Chemistry and the ether of Optics. But the severer Methodologists regard them with suspicion: Mill was never completely convinced about the ether. He was willing, however, to make the most of the evidence that has been adduced as indicating a certain property of it distinct from those by which it transmits radiation, namely, mechanical inertia, whereby it has been supposed to retard the career of the heavenly bodies, as shown especially by the history of Encke's comet. This comet returned sooner than it should, as calculated from the usual data ; the difference was ascribed to the influence of a resisting medium in reducing the extent of its orbit ; and such a medium may be the ether. If this conjecture (now of less credit) should gain acceptance, the ether might be regarded as a vera causa (that is, a condition whose existence may be proved independently of the pheno- mena it was intended to explain), in spite of its being excluded by its nature from the sphere of direct perception. After all, it is very difficult to say what is within the sphere of direct perception. Waiving this question, however, Science is not a way of perceiving things, but essentially a way of thinking about them. It starts, indeed, from perception and returns to it, and its thinking is controlled by the analogies of perception. Atoms and ether are thought about as if they could be seen or felt, not as noumena ; and if they are found necessary to connect and explain perceptions, those who can understand the explanation will no doubt be reconciled to them. For most men of Science, I suppose, their existence is as good as axiomatic. On the other hand, a great many agents, once assumed in order to explain phenomena, have since been explained away. Of course, a fact can never be ' explained away ' : the phrase is properly applicable to the fate of erroneous hypotheses, when, not only are they disproved, but others are established in their places, Of the Aristotelian spheres, which were supposed to support and translate sun, moon and planets, no trace has 250 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ever been found : they would have been very much in the way of the comets. Phlogiston, again, an agent much in favour with the earlier Chemists, was found, Whewell tells us, when their theories were tested by exact weighing, to be not merely non- existent but a minus quantity ; that is to say, it required the assumption of its absolute lightness " so that it diminished the weight of the compounds into which it entered.'* These agents, then, the spheres and phlogiston, have been explained away, and instead of them we have the laws of motion and oxygen. (2) Whether the hypothetical agent be perceptible or not, it cannot be established, nor can a supposed law of such an agent be accepted as sufficient to the given inquiry, unless it is adequate to account for the effects which it is called upon to explain, at least so far as it pretends to explain them. The general truth of this is sufficiently obvious, since to explain the facts is the purpose of an hypothesis ; and we have seen that Newton gave up his hypothesis that the moon was a falling body, as long as he was unable to show that the amount of its deflection from a tangent (or its fall) in a given time, was exactly what it should be, if the Moon was controlled by the same force as falling bodies on the Earth. It is worth while, however, to observe the limitations to which this canon is subject. In the first place, it says that, unless adequate to explain the facts in question, an hypothesis cannot be 'established* ': but, for all that, such an hypothesis may be a very promising one, not to be hastily rejected, since it may take a very long time fully to verify an hypothesis. Some facts may not be obtainable that are necessary to show the connection of others : as, for example, the hypothesis that all species of animals have arisen from earlier ones by some process of gradual change, can be only imperfectly verified by collecting the fossil remains of extinct species, because immense depths and expanses of fossiliferous strata have been destroyed. Or, again, the general state of culture may be such as to pre- vent men from tracing the consequences of an hypothesis ; for which reason, apparently, the doctrine that the Sun is the HYPOTHESES 251 centre of our planetary system remained a discredited hypo- thesis for 2000 years. Surely, this should instruct us not to regard an hypothesis as necessarily erroneous or illegitimate merely because we cannot yet see how it works out : but neither can we in such a case regard it as established, unless we take somebody's word for it. Secondly, the canon says that an hypothesis is not estab- lished, unless it accounts for the phenomena so far as it professes to. But it implies a complete misunderstanding to assail a doctrine for not explaining what lies beyond its scope. Thus, it is no objection to a theory of the origin of species, that it does not explain the origin of life : it does not profess to. For the same reason, it is no objection to the theory of Natural Selection, that it does not account for the variations which selection presupposes. But such objections might be perfectly fair against a general doctrine of Evolu- tion. An interesting case in Mr. Wallace's Darwinism (chap, x.) will illustrate the importance of attending to the exact condi- tions of an hypothesis. He says that in those groups of " birds that need protection from enemies," "when the male is brightly coloured and the female sits exposed on the nest, she is always less brilliant and generally of quite sober and protec- tive hues " ; and his hypothesis is, that these sober hues have been acquired or preserved by Natural Selection, because it is important to the family that the sitting bird should be incon- spicuous. Now to this it might be objected that in some birds both sexes are brilliant or conspicuous ; but the answer is that the female of such species does not sit exposed on the nest ; for the nests are either domed over, or made in a hole ; so that the sitting bird does not need protective colouring. If it be objected, again, that some sober-coloured birds build domed nests, it may be replied that the proposition ' All conspicuously coloured birds are concealed in the nest,' is not to be converted simply into ' All birds that sit concealed in the nest are con- spicuously coloured.' In the cases alleged the domed nests 252 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE are a protection against the weather, and the sober colouring is a general protection to the bird, which inhabits an open country. It may be urged, however, that jays, crows, and magpies are conspicuous birds, and yet build open nests : but these are aggressive birds, not needing protection from enemies. Finally, there are cases, it must be confessed, in which the female is more brilliant than the male, and which yet have open nests ! Yes : but then the male sits upon the eggs, and the female is stronger and more pugnacious ! Thus every objection is shown to imply some inattention to the conditions of the problem ; and in each case it may be said, exceptio probat regulam the exception tests the rule. (Of course, the usual translation " proves the rule," in the restricted modern sense of " prove," is absurd.) That is to say, it appears on examination : (i) that the alleged exception is not really one, and (2) that it stands in such relation to the rule as to confirm it. For, you will notice that, to all the above objec- tions it is replied that, granting the phenomenon in question (special protective colouring for the female) to be absent, the alleged cause (need of protection) is also absent ; so that the proof is, by means of the objections, extended, from being one by the method of Agreement, into one by the Double Method. Unfortunately, it is not always that an assailant's neglect to observe the exact conditions of the doctrine in dispute can be turned to such good account. Thirdly, an hypothesis originally intended to account for the whole of a phenomenon and failing to do so, though it cannot be established in that sense, may nevertheless contain an essential part of the explanation. Thus the Neptunian Hypothesis in Geology, was an attempt to explain the formation of the Earth's outer crust, as having been deposited from an universal ocean of mud. In the progress of the science other causes, seismic, fluvial and atmo- spheric, have been found necessary in order to complete the theory of the history of the Earth's crust : but it remains true that the stratified rocks, and some that have lost their straiified HYPOTHESES 253 character, were originally deposited under water. Inadequacy, therefore, is not a reason for entirely rejecting an hypothesis or treating it as illegitimate. (3) Granting that the hypothetical cause is real and ade- quate, the investigation is not complete. Agreement with the facts is a very persuasive circumstance, the more so the more extensive the agreement, especially if no exceptions are known. Still, if this is all that can be said in favour of an hypothesis, it amounts to proof by the method of Agreement only ; it does not exclude the possibility of vicarious causes ; and if the hypothesis proposes a new agent that cannot be directly observed, an equally plausible hypothesis about another imagined agent may perhaps be invented. According to Whewell, it is a strong mark of the truth of an hypothesis when it agrees with distinct inductions concerning different classes of facts, and he calls this the * Consilience of Inductions,' because they jump together in the unity of the hypothesis. It is particularly convincing when this Consilience takes place easily and naturally without necessitating the mending and tinkering of the hypothesis ; and he cites the Theory of Gravitation and the Undulatory Theory of Light as the most conspicuous examples of such ever-victorious hypo- theses. Thus, Gravitation explains the fall of bodies on the Earth, and the orbits of the planets and their satellites ; it applies to the tides, the comets, the double stars, and gives consistency to the Nebular Hypothesis, whence flow important Geological inferences ; and all this without any need of amend- ment. Nevertheless, Mill, with his rigorous sense of duty, points out, that an Induction is merely a proposition concerning many facts, and that a consilience of Inductions is merely a multiplication of the facts explained; and that, therefore, if the proof is merely Agreement in each case, there can be no more in the totality : the possibility of vicarious causes is not precluded; and the hypothesis may, after all, describe an accidental circumstance. Whewell also laid great stress upon Prediction as a mark of 254 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE a true hypothesis. Thus, Astronomers predict eclipses, occultations, transits, long beforehand with the greatest pre- cision ; and the prediction of the place of Neptune by sheer force of deduction is one of the most astonishing things in the history of science. Yet Mill persisted in showing that a pre- dicted fact is only another fact, and that it is really not very extraordinary that an hypothesis that happens to agree with many known facts should also agree with some still undis- covered. And, I must say, there seems to be some illusion in the common belief in the probative force of prediction. Pre- diction surprises us, puts us off our guard, and renders per- suasion easy,; in this it resembles the force of an epigram in rhetoric. But cases can be produced in which erroneous hypotheses have led to prediction ; and Whewell himself pro- duces them. Thus, he says that the Ptolemaic theory was confirmed by its predicting eclipses and other celestial pheno- mena, and by leading to the construction of Tables in which the places of the heavenly bodies were given at every moment of time. Similarly, both Newton's theory of Light and the Chemical doctrine of Phlogiston led to predictions which came true. What sound method demands in the proof of an hypip- thesis, then, is not merely that it be shown to agree with the facts, but that every other hypothesis be excluded. This, to be sure, may be beyond our power ; there may in some cases be no such negative proof except the exhaustion of human ingenuity in the course of time. The present theory of colour has in its favour the failure of Newton's corpuscular hypothesis and of Goethe's anti-mathe- matical hypothesis ; but the field of conjecture remains open. On the other hand, Newton's proof that the solar system is controlled by a central force, he supported by the demonstra- tion that a force having any other direction could not have results agreeing with Kepler's second law of the planetary motions, namely, that, as a planet moves in its orbit, the areas described by a line drawn from the sun to the planet are HYPOTHESES 255 proportional to the times occupied in the planet's motion. When a planet is nearest to the sun, the area described by such a line is least for any given distance traversed by the planet ; and then the planet moves fastest : when the planet is furthest from the sun, the area described by such a line is greatest for an equal distance traversed ; and then the planet moves slowest. This law may be deduced from the hypothesis of a central fo^:e, but not from any other ; the proof, therefore, as Mill says, satisfies the method of Difference. Apparently, to such completeness of demonstration certain conditions are necessary : the possibilities must lie between alternatives, such as A or not-A, or amongst some definite list of cases that may be exhausted, such as equal, greater or less. He whose hypothesis cannot be brought to such a definite issue, must try to refute whatever other hypotheses are offered, and naturally he will attack first the strongest rivals. With this object in view he looks about for a " crucial instance," that is, an observation or experiment that stands like a cross (sign-post) at the parting of the ways to guide us into the right way, or, in plain words, an instance that can be explained by one hypothesis but not by another. Thus the phases of Venus, similar to those of the Moon, but concurring with great changes of apparent size, when dis- covered by Galileo, presented a crucial instance in favour of the Copernican hypothesis, as against the Ptolemaic, so far at least as to prove that Venus revolved around the Sun inside the orbit of the Earth. Foucault's experiment determining the velocity of Light (cited in the last chapter) was at first intended as an experimentum cruets to decide between the corpuscular and undulatory theories ; and answered this purpose, by show- ing that the velocity of a beam passed through water was less than it should be by the former, but in agreement with the latter doctrine (Deschanel : 813). Perhaps experiments of this decisive character are com- monest in Chemistry : chemical tests, says Herschel, " are almost universally crucial experiments." The following is 256 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE abridged from Playfair (Encycl Met., Diss. III.): The Chemists of last century observed that metals were rendered heavier by calcination ; and there were two ways of accounting for this : either something had been added in the process, though what, they could not imagine ; or, something had been driven off that was in its nature light, namely, Phlogiston. To decide between these hypotheses, Lavoisier hermetically sealed some tin in a glass retort, and weighed the whole. He then heated it ; and, when the tin was calcined, weighed the whole again, and found it the same as before. No substance, there- fore, either light or heavy, had escaped. Further, when the retort was cooled and opened, the air rushed in, showing that some of the air formerly within had disappeared or lost its elasticity. On weighing the whole again, its weight was now found to have increased by ten grains ; so that ten grains of air had entered when it was opened. The calcined tin was then weighed separately, and proved to be exactly ten grains heavier than when it was placed in the retort ; showing that the ten grains of air that had disappeared had combined with the metal during calcination. This experiment, then, decided against Phlogiston, and led afterwards to an analysis of common air confirming Priestley's discovery of oxygen. (4) An hypothesis must agree with the rest of the laws of Nature ; and, if not itself of the highest generality, must be derivable from primary laws (chap. xix. i). Thus gravitation and the diffusion of heat, light and sound from a centre, all follow the " law of the inverse square," and agree with the relation of the radius of a sphere to its surface. Any one who should think that he had discovered a new central force would naturally begin to investigate it on the hypothesis that it conformed to the same law as gravitation or light. A Chemist, again, who should believe himself to have discovered a new element, would expect it to fill one of the vacant places in the "Periodic System." Conformity, in such cases, is strong confirmation, and disagreement is an occasion of misgivings. HYPOTHESES 257 A narrower hypothesis, as * that the toad's ugliness is pro- tective ', would be supported by the general theory of protective colouring and figure, and by the still more general theory of Natural Selection, if facts could be adduced to show that the toad's appearance does really deter its enemies. Such an hypothesis resembles an Empirical Law in its need of deriva- tion (chap. xix. i, 2). If underivable from, or irreconcil- able with, known laws, it is a mere conjecture or prejudice. The absolute levitation of Phlogiston, in contrast with the gravitation of all other forms of matter, was discreditable to that supposed agent. That Macpherson should have found the Ossianic poems extant in the Gaelic memory, was contrary to the nature of oral tradition; except where tradition is organised, as it was for ages among the Brahmins. The sug- gestion that xanthochroid Aryans were " bleached " by exposure during the glacial period, does not agree with Wallace's doc- trine concerning the colouration of Arctic animals. That our forefathers being predatory, like bears, white variations amongst them were then selected by the advantage of concealment, is a more plausible hypothesis. Although, then, the consilience of Inductions or Hypo- theses is not a sufficient proof of their truth, it is still a condition of it ; nonconsilience is a suspicious circumstance, and resilience (so to speak), or mutual repugnance, is fatal to one or all. 4. We have now seen that an hypothesis must, to deserve the name in science, be verifiable and therefore definite ; and that to establish itself as a true theory, it must present some symptom of reality, and be adequate and unconditional and in harmony with the system of experience. Thus guarded, hypo- theses seem harmless enough; but, certainly, people some- times have a strong prejudice against them, as against a tribe of savages without government, or laws, or any decent regard for vested interests. It is well known, too, that Bacon and Newton disparaged them. But Bacon in his examples of an investigation according to his own method, is obliged after a B 258 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE preliminary classification of facts, to resort to an hypothesis, calling it permissio intellectus, interpretatio inchoata or vinde- miatio prima. And what Newton meant by hypotheses non fingo, seeing that he invented so many, is itself fair game for an hypothesis. At any rate, it is plain that hypotheses are essential aids to discovery : indeed, speaking generally, deliberate investigation depends wholly upon the use of them. It is true that we may sometimes observe a train of events that chances to pass before us, either when we are idle or engaged with some other inquiry, and so obtain a new glimpse of the course of nature. ^Or we may try experiments hap- hazard, and watch the results. But, even in these cases, before our new notions can be considered knowledge, they must be definitely framed hi hypotheses and reobserved or experimented upon, with whatever calculations or precautions may be necessary to ensure accuracy or isolation. As a rule, however, when inquiring deliberately into the cause of an event, whether in nature or in history, we first reflect upon the circumstances of the case and compare it with similar ones previously investigated, and so are guided by a preconception more or less definite of * what to look for/ what the cause is likely to be, that is, by an hypothesis. Then, if our precon- ception is justified, or something which we observe leads to a new hypothesis, either we look for other instances to satisfy the canons of Agreement : or (if the matter admits of experi- ment) we endeavour, under known conditions according to the canons of Difference and Variations, to reproduce the event by means of that which our hypothesis assigns as the cause ; or we draw remote inferences from our hypothesis, and try to test these by the Inductive Canons. If we argue from an hypothesis and express ourselves formally, it will usually appear as the Major Premise ; but this is not always the case. In extending ascertained laws to fresh cases, the Minor Premise may be an hypothesis, as in testing the chemical constitution of any doubtful substance, such as a HYPOTHESES 259 piece of ore. Some solution or preparation, A, is generally made which (it is known) will, on the introduction of a certain agent, B, give a reaction, C, if the preparation contains a given substance, X. The major premise, then, is the law of reaction Whenever A is X, if treated with B it is C. The minor premise is an hypothesis that the preparation con- tains X. An experiment then treats A with B. If C results, a probability is raised in favour of the hypothesis that A is X ; or a certainty, if we know that C results on that condition only. So important are hypotheses to science, that Whewell insists that they have often been extremely valuable even though erroneous. Of the Ptolemaic system he says, " We can hardly imagine that Astronomy could, in its outset, have made so great a progress under any other form." It served to connect men's thoughts on the subject and to sustain their interest in working it out; by successive corrections "to save appearances," it attained at last to a descriptive sort of truth, which was of great practical utility; it also occasioned the invention of technical terms, and, in general, digested the whole body of observations and prepared them for assimilation by a better hypothesis in the fulness of time. Whewell even defends the maxim that " Nature abhors a vacuum," as having formerly served to connect many facts that differ widely in their first aspect. "And in reality is it not true," he asks, " that nature does abhor a vacuum, and does all she can to avoid it ? " Let no forlorn cause despair of a champion ! Yet no one has accused Whewell of Quixotry; and the sense of his position is that the human mind, of course, is a rather feeble affair, which can hardly begin thinking except with blunders. The progress of science may be plausibly attributed to a pro- cess of Natural Selection ; hypotheses are produced in abund- ance and variety, and those unfit to bear verification are destroyed, until only the fittest survive. Wallace, a practical 260 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE naturalist, if there ever was one, as well as an eminent theorist, takes the same view as Whewell of such inadequate conjec- tures. Of * Lemuria,' a hypothetical continent in the Indian Ocean, once supposed to be traceable in the islands of Madagascar, Seychelles and Mauritius, its surviving frag- ments, and named from the Lemurs, its characteristic denizens, he says (Island Life, chap, xix.) that it was " essentially a provisional hypothesis, very useful in calling attention to a remarkable series of problems in geographical distribution [oi plants and animals], but not affording the true solution oi those problems." We see, then, that ' provisional hypotheses,' though erroneous, may be very useful or (as Whewell says) necessary. Hence, to be prolific of hypotheses is the first attribute of scientific genius ; the first, because without it no progress whatever can be made. And some men seem to have a marked felicity, a sort of instinctive judgment even in their guesses, as if their heads were made according to Nature. But others among the greatest, like Kepler, guess often and are often wrong before they hit upon the truth, and them- selves, like Nature, destroy many vain shoots and seedlings of science for one that they find fit to live. If this is how the mind works in scientific inquiry (as it certainly is, with most men, in poetry, in fine art, and in the scheming of business), it is useless to repine. We should rather recog- nise a place for fool's hypotheses, as Darwin did for " fool's experiments." But to complete the scientific character, there must be great patience, accuracy, and impartiality in examining and testing these conjectures, as well as great ingenuity in devising experiments to that end. It is the want of these qualities that leads to crudity and public failure and brings hypotheses into derision. Not partially and hastily to believe in one's own guesses, nor petulantly and hastily to reject them, but to consider the matter, to suspend judgment, is the mora lesson of science : difficult, distasteful, and rarely mastered. HYPOTHESES 261 Everybody, according to his lights, makes haste to frame hypotheses, whether for scientific or private uses ; because, as Whewell says, "man is prone to become a deductive reasoner," and hypotheses, anticipating the laborious induction of highly general laws, are a short cut to deduction. There are two sides to this proneness of our nature, a good and a bad. The good is that hypothesis and deduction have in fact been the great means of explaining or enabling us to understand the world ; so that our instinctive resort to them is a predisposition to science. The bad is that this method encourages superficiality. Deduction is generally easier than Induction, because it is carried on far more by means of signs, whether in Mathematics or common language. To wield the higher Mathematics needs a distinguished head ; but this power cannot be put into com- petition with the lucid and comprehensive imagination neces- sary to represent masses of facts for inductive analysis. For the great use of language and of all symbols in thinking, is to economise this energy of imagination. Without such devices the human race could never have developed: for who can imagine the purport in denotation of a single general name ? But these devices show * the defects of their qualities ' by often quite superseding thought and degenerating into gibberish. Whether, indeed, this is ever true of the higher Mathematics is not for me to say ; but everybody knows how true it is of common speech. 5. The word ' hypothesis ' is often also used for the scientific device of treating an Abstraction as, for the purposes of argu- ment, equivalent to the concrete facts. Thus, in Geometry, a line is treated as having no breadth ; in Mechanics, a bar may be supposed absolutely rigid, or a machine to work without friction ; in Economics (as we saw in the last chapter), man is sometimes regarded as actuated solely by love of gain and dislike of exertion. The results reached by such reasoning may be made applicable to the concrete facts, if allowance be made for the omitted circumstances or properties, in the several cases of lines, bars, and men; but otherwise all 262 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE conclusions from abstract terms are limited by their defini- tions. Abstract reasoning, then (that is, reasoning limited by definitions), is often said to imply * the hypothesis ' that things exist as their names are denned, having no properties but those enumerated in their definitions. This seems, however, a needless and confusing extension of the term ; for an hypothesis proposes an agent, collocation, er law hitherto unknown; whereas abstract reasoning proposes to exclude from consideration a good deal that is well known. There seems no reason why the latter device should not be plainly called an Abstraction. Such Abstractions are, of course, also necessary to science ; for no object is comprehensible by us in all its properties at once. But if we forget the limitations of our abstract data, we are liable to make strange blunders by mistaking the character of the results: treating the results as simply true of actual things, instead of as true of actual things only so far as they are represented by the Abstractions. In addressing abstract reasoning, therefore, to those especially who are unfamiliar with scientific methods, pains should.be taken to make it clear what the Abstractions are, what are the con- sequent limitations upon the argument and its conclusions, and what corrections and allowances are necessary in order to turn the conclusions into an adequate account of the concrete facts. The greater the number, variety, and subtlety of the properties possessed by any object (such as human nature), the greater the qualifications required in the conclusions of abstract reasoning, before they can hold true of such an object in practical affairs. Closely allied to this method of Abstraction is the Mathe- matical Method of Limits. In his History of Scientific Ideas (B. II. c. 12), Whewell says : " The Idea of a Limit supplies a new mode of establishing mathematical truths. Thus with regard to the length of any portion of a curve, a problem which we have just mentioned ; a curve is not made up of straight lines, and therefore we HYPOTHESES 263 cannot by means of any of the doctrines of elementary geometry measure the length of any curve. But we may make up a figure nearly resembling any curve by putting together many short straight lines, just as a polygonal building of very many sides may nearly resemble a circular room. And in order to approach nearer and nearer to a curve, we may make the sides more and more small, more and more numerous. We may then possibly find some mode of measurement, some relation of these small lines to other lines, which is not dis- turbed by the multiplication of the sides, however far it be carried. And thus we may do what is equivalent to measuring the curve itself; for by multiplying the sides we may approach more and more closely to the curve till no appreciable difference remains. The curve line is the Limit of the polygon ; and in this process we proceed on the Axiom that * What is true up to the Limit is true at the Limit.' " Now, what Whewell calls the Axiom here, others might call an Hypothesis ; but perhaps it is properly a Postulate. And it is just the obverse of the Postulate implied in the Method of Abstractions, namely, that ' What is true of the Abstraction is true of concrete cases the more nearly they approach the Abstraction.' What is true of the * Economic Man ' is truer of a broker than of a farmer, of a farmer than of a labourer, of a labourer than of the artist of romance. Hence the Abstrac- tion may be called a Limit or limiting case, in the sense that it stands to concrete individuals, as a curve does to the figures made up " by putting together many short straight lines." Correspondingly, the Proper Name may be called the Limit of the class-name ; since its attributes are infinite, whereas any name whose attributes are less than infinite stands for a possible class. In short, for logical purposes, a Limit may be defined as any extreme case to which actual examples may approach without ever reaching it. And in this sense 'Method of Limits' might be used as a term including the Method of Abstractions ; though it would be better to speak of them generically as * Methods of Approximations.' 264 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE We may also notice the Assumptions (as they may be called) that are sometimes resorted to to facilitate an investigation, because some definite ground must be taken and nothing better can be thought of : as in estimating national wealth, that furniture is half the value of the houses. It is easy to conceive of an objector urging that such devices as the above are merely ways of avoiding the actual problems, and that they display more cunning than skill. But Science, like good sense, puts up with the best that can be had; and, like prudence, does not reject the half-loaf. The position, that a conceivable case that can be dealt with may, under certain conditions, be substituted for one that is unworkable, is a touchstone of intelligence. To stand out for ideals that are known to be impossible, is only an excuse for doing nothing at all. In another sense, again, the whole of Science is sometimes said to be hypothetical, because it takes for granted the Uniformity of Nature; for this, in its various aspects, can only be directly ascertained by us as far as our experience extends ; whereas the whole value of the principle of Uniformity consists in its furnishing a formula for the extension of our other beliefs beyond our actual experience. Transcendentalists, indeed, call it a form of Reason, just because it is presupposed in all knowledge; and they and the Empiricists agree that to adduce material evidence for it, in its full extent, is impossible. If, then, material evidence is demanded by any one, he cannot regard the conclusions of Mathematics and physical Science as depending on what is itself unproved ; he must, with Mill, regard these conclusions as drawn " not from but according to " the axioms of Equality and Causation. That is to say, if the axioms are true, the conclusions are ; the material evidence for both the axioms and the conclusions being the same, namely, uncontradicted experience. Now when we say, * If Nature is uniform, Science is true ', the hypothetical character of Science appea in the form of the statement. Nevertheless, it seems und : HYPOTHESES 265 sirable to call our confidence in Nature's uniformity an * hypo- thesis ': it is incongruous to use the same term for our tentative conjectures and for our most indispensable beliefs. ' The Universal Postulate ' is a better term for the principle which, in some form or other, every generalisation takes for granted. CHAPTER XIX LAWS CLASSIFIED; EXPLANATION; CO-EXISTENCE; ANALOGY i. Laws are classified, according to their degrees of generality, as higher and lower, though the grades may not be decisively distinguishable. First, there are Axioms or Principles, that is real, universal, self-evident propositions. They are (i) real propositions ; not, like 'The whole is greater than any of its parts/ merely definitions, or implied in definitions. (2) They are regarded as universally true of phenomena, as far as the form of their expression extends ; that is, for example,. Axioms con- cerning quantity are true of everything that is considered in its quantitative aspect, though not (of course) in its qualitative aspect. (3) They are self-evident ; that is, each rests upon its own evidence (whatever that may be) ; they cannot be derived from one another, nor from any more general law. Some, indeed, are more general than others : the Logical Principle of Contradiction, ' if A is B, it is not not-B ', is true of qualities as well as of quantities ; whereas the Axioms of Mathematics apply only to quantities. The Mathematical Axioms, again, apply to time, space, mental phenomena, and matter and energy ; whereas the Law of Causation is only true of concrete events in the redistribution of matter and energy : such, at least, is the strict limit of Causation, if we identify it with the Conservation of Energy ; although our imperfect knowledge of life and mind often drives us to speak of feelings, ideas, volitions, as causes. Still, the Law of Causation cannot LAWS CLASSIFIED 267 be derived from the Mathematical Axioms, nor these from the Logical. The kind of evidence upon which Axioms rest, or whether any evidence can be given for them, is (as before observed) a question for Metaphysics, not for Logic. Axioms are the upward limit of Logic, which, like all the special Sciences, necessarily takes them for granted, as the starting point of all deduction and the goal of all generalisation. Next to Axioms, come Primary Laws of Nature : these are of less generality than the Axioms, and are subject to the conditions of methodical proof; being universally true only of certain forces or properties of matter, or of nature under certain conditions ; so that proof of them by logical or mathematical reasoning is expected, because they depend upon the Axioms for their formal evidence. Such are the law of Gravitation, in Astronomy; the law of definite Proportions, in Chemistry ; the law of Heredity, in Biology ; and in Psycho- logy, the law of Relativity. Then, there are Secondary Laws, of still less generality, resulting from a combination of primary conditions or forces in given circumstances, and therefore conceivably derivable from the laws of those conditions or forces, if we can discover them and compute their united effects. Accordingly, Secondary Laws are either (i) Derivative, having been analysed into, and deduced from, Primary Laws ; or (2) Em- pirical, those that have not yet been deduced (though from their comparatively special and complex character, it seems probable they may be, given sufficient time and ingenuity), and that meanwhile rest upon some unsatisfactory sort of induction by Agreement or Simple Enumeration. Whether laws proved only by the canon of Difference are to be considered Empirical, is perhaps a question : their proof derives them from the principle of Causation ; but, being of narrow scope, some more special account of them seems requisite in relation to the Primary Laws before we can call them Derivative in the technical sense. Many Secondary Laws, again, are partially or imperfectly 268 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Derivative; we can give general reasons for them, without being able to determine theoretically the precise relations of the phenomena they describe. Thus, Meteorologists can explain the general conditions of all sorts of weather, but have made but little progress toward predicting the actual course of it (at least, for our island) : Geologists know the general causes of mountain ranges, but not why they rise just where we find them : Economists explain the general course of a commercial crisis, but not why the great crises recur at intervals of about ten years. Derivative Laws make up the body of the exact Sciences, having been assimilated and organised ; whilst Empirical Laws are the undigested materials of Science. The theorems of Euclid are good examples of Derivative Laws in Mathematics ; in Astronomy, Kepler's laws and the laws of the tides; in Physics, the laws of shadows, of perspective, of harmony ; in Biology, the law of Natural Selection, and others from this ; in Economics, the laws of prices, rents, wages, interest. Empirical Laws are such as Bode's law of the planetary distances ; the laws of the expansion of different bodies by heat, and formulae expressing the electrical conductivity of each substance as a function of the temperature. Strictly speaking, I suppose, all the laws of chemical combination are Empirical : the law of definite proportions is found true in all cases that have been examined, except for variations that may be ascribed to errors of experiment. Much the same is true in Biology ; most of the secondary laws are Empirical, except so far as structures or functions may be regarded as specialised cases in Physics or Chemistry and deducible from these Sciences. The theory of Natural Selection, however, has been the means of rendering many laws, that were once wholly Empirical, at least partially Derivative ; namely, the laws of the Geographical distribution of plants and animals, and of their adaptation in organisation, form and colour, habits and instincts, to their various conditions of life. The laws that remain Empirical in Biology are of all degrees of generality LAWS CLASSIFIED 269 from that of the tendency to variation in size and in every character shown by all (or nearly all) species (though as to the reason of this there are promising hypotheses), down to such curious cases as that the colour of roses and carnations never varies into blue, that scarlet flowers are never sweet-scented, that bullfinches fed on hemp-seed turn black, that the young of white, yellow and dun pigeons are born almost naked (whilst others have plenty of down) ; and so on. The deriva- tion of Empirical Laws is the greater part of the Explanation of Nature ( 5, 6). A ' Fact,' in the common use of the word, is a particular Observation : it is the material of science in its rawest state. As perceived by a mind, it is, of course, never absolutely particular: for we cannot possibly perceive anything without classing it, more or less definitely, with things already known to us ; nor describe it without using connotative terms which imply a classification of the things denoted. Still, we may consider an Observation as particular, in comparison with a Law that includes it with numerous others in one general proposition. To turn an Observation into an Experiment, or (where experiment is impracticable) to repeat it with all possible precautions and exactness, and to describe it as to the duration, quantity, quality and order of occurrence of its phenomena, is the first stage of scientific manufacture. Then comes the formulation of an Empirical Law; and lastly, if possible, deduction or derivation, either from higher laws previously ascertained, or from an hypothesis. However, as a word is used in various senses, we often speak of laws as ' facts ' : we say the law of Gravitation is a fact, meaning that it is real, or verifiable by observations or experiments. 2. Secondary Laws may also be classified according to their constancy into (i) the Invariable (as far as experience reaches), and (2) Approximate Generalisations in the form Most X's are Y. Of the Invariable we have given examples above. The following are Approximate Generalisations : Most comets gp round the Sun from East to West ; Most metals are 270 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE solid at ordinary temperatures ; Most marsupials are Austral- asian ; Most arctic animals are white in winter ; Most cases of plague are fatal ; Most men think first of their own interests. Some of these laws are empirical, as that * Most metals are solid at ordinary temperatures ' : at present no reason can be given for this ; nor do we know why most cases of plague are fatal. Others, however, are at least partially derivative, as that * Most arctic animals are white ' ; for this seems to be due to the advantage of concealment in the snow; whether, as with the bear, the better to surprise its prey, or, with the hare, to escape the notice of its enemies. But the, scientific treatment of such a proposition requires that we should also explain the exceptions : if ' Most are ', this implies that ' Some are not ' ; why not, then ? Now, if we can give reasons for all the exceptions, the Approximate Generali- sation may be converted into an universal one, thus : * All arctic animals are white, unless (like the raven) they need no concealment either to prey or to escape; or unless mutual recognition is more important to them than concealment (as with the musk-sheep) '. The same end of universal statement may be gained by including the conditions on which the phenomenon depends, thus : ' All arctic animals to whom con- cealment is of the utmost utility are white '. When Statistics are obtainable, it is proper to convert an Approximate Generalisation into a proportional statement of the fact, thus : instead of l Most attacks of plague are fatal ', we might find that in a certain country 70 per cent, were so. Then, if we found that in another country the percentage of deaths was 60, in another 40, we might discover, in the different conditions of these countries, a clue to the high rate of mortality from this disease. Indeed, even if the proportion of cases in which two facts are connected does not amount to * Most', yet, if any definite percentage is obtainable, the pro- position has a higher scientific value than a vague ' Some ' : as if we know that 2 per cent, of the deaths in England are due to suicide, this may be compared with the rates of suicide in LAWS CLASSIFIED 271 other countries ; from which perhaps inferences may be drawn as to the causes of suicide. In one department of life, namely, Politics, there is a special advantage in true Approximate Generalisations amounting to 1 Most cases '. The citizens of any State are so various in character, enlightenment, and conditions of life, that we can expect to find few propositions universally true of them : so that propositions true of the majority must be trusted as the bases of legislation. If most men are deterred from crime by the fear of punishment; if most men will idle if they can obtain support without industry ; if most jurymen will refuse to convict of a crime for which the prescribed penalties seem to them too severe ; these are most useful truths, though there should be numerous exceptions to them all. 3. Secondary Laws can only be trusted in ' Adjacent Cases ' ; that is, where the circumstances are similar to those in which the laws are known to be true. A Derivative Law will be true wherever the forces concerned exist in the combi- nations upon which the law depends, if there are no counter- acting conditions. Thus, that water can be pumped to about 33 feet at the sea- level, is a derivative law on this planet : is it true in Mars ? That depends on whether there are in Mars bodies of a liquid similar to our water ; whether there is an atmosphere there ; and how great its pressure is; which will vary with its height and density. If there is no atmosphere, there can be no pumping ; or if there is an atmosphere of less pressure than ours, water such as ours can only be pumped to a less height than 33 feet. Again, we know that there are arctic regions in Mars ; if there are also arctic animals, are they white ? That may depend upon whether there are any beasts of prey. If not, concealment seems to us of no use. An Empirical Law, being one whose conditions we do not know, the extent of its prevalence is still less ascertainable. Where it has not been actually observed to be true, we cannot trust it unless the circumstances, on the whole, 272 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE resemole so closely those amongst which it has been observed, that the unknown causes, whatever they may be, are likely to prevail there. And, even then, we cannot have much confidence in it ; for there may be unknown circumstances which entirely frustrate the effect. The first naturalist who travelled (say) from Singapore east- ward by Sumatra and Java, or Borneo, and found the mam- malia there similar to those of Asia, may naturally have expected the same thing in Celebes and Papua ; but, if so, he was entirely disappointed ; for in Papua the mammalia are marsupials like those of Australia. Thus his empirical law, * The mammalia of the Eastern Archipelago are Asiatic,' would have failed for no apparent reason. According to Mr. Wallace, there is a reason for it, though such as could only be dis- covered by extensive researches : namely, that the sea is deep between Borneo and Celebes, so that they must have been separated for many ages ; whereas it is shallow from Borneo westward to Asia, and also southward from Papua to Australia ; so that these regions, respectively, may have been recently united : and the true law is that similar mammalia belong to those tracts which at comparatively recent dates have formed parts of the same continents. A considerable lapse of time may make an empirical law no longer trustworthy ; for the forces from whose combination it resulted may have ceased to operate, or to operate in the same combination ; and since we do not know what those forces were, even the knowledge that great changes have taken place in the meantime cannot enable us, after an interval, to judge whether or not the law still holds true. New stars shine in the sky and go out ; species of plants and animals become extinct ; diseases die out and fresh ones afflict mankind : all these things doubtless have their causes, but if we do not know what they are, we have no measure of the effects, and cannot tell when or where they will happen. Laws of Concomitant Variations may hold good only within certain limits. That bodies contract as the temperature falls, CO-EXISTENCE 273 is not true of water a little above freezing point. In Psychology, Weber's Law is only true within the middle range of sensation- intensities, not for very faint, nor for very strong, stimuli. In such cases the failure of the laws may depend upon some- thing imperfectly understood in the collocation : as to water, on its molecular constitution ; as to sensation, upon the structure of the nervous system. 4. Secondary Laws, again, are either of Succession or of Co-existence. Those of Succession are either (i) of direct causation, as that ' Water quenches fire ', or (more strictly) that 'Evaporation reduces temperature ' ; or (2) of the effect of a remote cause, as ' Bad harvests tend to raise the price of bread ' ; or (3) of the joint effects of the same cause, as that ' Night follows day ' (from the revolution of the earth), or the course of the seasons (from the inclination of the earth's axis). Laws of Co-existence are of several classes, (i) One has the generality of a Primary Law, though it is proved only by Agreement, namely, ' All gravitating bodies are inert '. Others, though less general than this, are of very extensive range, as that * All gases that are not decomposed by rise of temperature have the same rate of expansion ' ; and, in Botany, again, that * All monocotyledonous plants are endogenous '. These laws of Co-existence are concerned with the most fundamental properties of bodies. (2) Next come laws of the Co-existence of those properties which are comprised in the definitions of Natural Kinds. Mill distinguished between (a) classes of things that agree among themselves and differ from others only in one or a few attributes (such as c red things ', * musical notes ', * car- nivorous animals ', * soldiers '), and (/3) classes of things that agree among themselves and differ from others in a multitude of characters : and the latter he calls Natural Kinds. These comprise the chemical elements and their pure compounds (such as water, alcohol, rock-salt, chalk), and the species of plants and animals. Clearly, each of these is constituted by 274 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE the co-existence or co-inherence of a multitude of properties, some of which are selected as the basis of their definitions. Thus, Gold is a metal of high specific gravity, high melting point, low chemical affinities, great ductility, yellow colour, etc. : a Horse has ' a vertebral column, mammae, a placental embryo, four legs, a single well-developed toe in each foot provided with a hoof, a bushy tail, and callosities on the inner sides of both the fore and the hind legs ' (Huxley). Since Darwinism has obtained general acceptance, some Logicians have doubted the propriety ot calling the organic species * Kinds,' on the grounds that they are not, as to definite- ness and permanence, on a par with the chemical elements or such compounds as water and rock-salt; that thejr vary extensively, and that it is only by the loss of former generations of animals that we are able to distinguish species at all. But to this it may be replied that species (so-called) are often approximately constant for immense periods of time, and may be called permanent in comparison with human generations ; and that, although the leading principles of Logic are perhaps eternal truths, yet upon a detail such as this, the science may condescend to recognise a distinction if it is good for (say) only 100,000 years. That if former generations of plants and animals were not lost, all distinctions of species would dis- appear, may be true; but they are lost for the most part beyond hope of recovery ; and accordingly the distinction of species is still recognised ; although there are cases, chiefly at the lower stages of organisation, in which so many varieties occur as to make adjacent species almost or quite indistinguish- able. So far as species are recognised, then, they present a complex co-existence of qualities, which is certainly a logical problem; and, coming more naturally under the head of Natural Kinds than any other, they must be mentioned in this place. (3) There are, again, certain coincidences of qualities not essential to any kind, and sometimes prevailing amongst many different kinds : such as ' Insects of nauseous taste have vivid CO-EXISTENCE 275 (warning) colours' ; * White tom-cats with blue eyes are deaf; * White spots and patches, when they appear in domestic animals, are most frequent on the left side.' (4) Finally, there may be constancy of relative position, as of sides and angles in Geometry ; and also among concrete things (at least for long periods of time), as of the planetary orbits, the apparent positions of fixed stars in the sky, the distribution of land and water on the globe, opposite seasons in opposite hemispheres. All these cases of Co-existence (except the Geometrical) present the problem of deriving them from Causation ; for there is no general Law of Co-existence from which they can be derived ; and, indeed, if we conceive of the external world as a perpetual redistribution of matter and energy, it follows that the whole state of Nature at any instant, and therefore every Co-existence included in it, is due to Causation issuing from some earlier distribution of matter and energy. Hence, indeed, it is not likely that the problems of Co-existence as a whole will ever be solved, since the original distribution of matter is, of course, unknown. Still, starting with any given state of Nature, we may hope to explain some of the co- existences in any subsequent state. We do not, indeed, know why heavy bodies are always inert, nor why the chemical elements are what they are; but it is known that "the properties of the elements are functions of their atomic weight," which (though, at present, only an empirical law) may be a clue to some deeper explanation. As to plants and animals, we know the conditions of their generation, and can trace a connection between most of their characteristics and the conditions of their life : as that the teeth and stomach of animals vary with their food, and that their colour generally varies with their habitat. Geometrical Co-existence, when it is not a matter of definition (as ' a square is a rectangle with four equal sides '), is deduced from the Definitions and Axioms : as when it is shown that in triangles the greater side is opposite the greater 276 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE angle. The deductions of theorems or secondary laws, in Geometry is a type of what is desirable in the Physical Sciences : the demonstration, namely, that all the connections of phenomena, whether successive or co-existent, are conse- quences of the redistribution of matter and energy according to the principle of Causation. Coincidences of Co-existence (Group (3)) may sometimes be deduced and sometimes not. That * nauseous insects have vivid coloration ' comes under the general law of * protective coloration ' ; as they are easily recognised and therefore avoided by insectivorous birds and other animals. But why white tom-cats with blue-eyes should be deaf, is (I believe) unknown. When Co-existences cannot be derived from Causation, they can only be proved by collecting examples and trusting vaguely to the Uniformity of Nature. If no exceptions are found, we have an empirical law of considerable probability within the range of our exploration. If exceptions occur, we have at most an Approximate Generalisation, as that * Most metals are whitish,' or * Most domestic cats are tabbies' (but this is probably the ancestral colouring). We may then resort to staiistics for greater definiteness, and find that in Hampshire (say) 90 per cent, of the domestic cats are tabby. 5. Scientific Explanation consists in discovering, deducing, and assimilating the laws of phenomena ; it is the analysis of that Heracleitan 'flux' which so many philosophers have regarded as intractable to human inquiry. In the ordinary use of the word, ' explanation ' means the satisfying a man's under- standing; and what may serve this purpose depends partly upon the natural soundness of his understanding, and partly on his education ; but it is always at last an appeal to the primary functions of cognition, discrimination and assimila- tion. Generally, what we are accustomed to seems to need no explanation, unless our curiosity is particularly directed to it. That boys climb trees and throw stones, and that men go fox- CO-EXISTENCE 277 hunting, may easily pass for matters of course. If any one is so exacting as to ask the reason, there is a ready answer in the ' need of exercise.' On reflection, however, this will not explain the peculiar zest of those exercises, which is something quite different from our feelings whilst swinging dumb-bells or tramping the highway. Others, more sophisticated, tell us that the civilised individual retains in his nature the instincts of his remote ancestors, and that these assert themselves at stages of his growth corresponding with ancestral periods of culture or savagery : so that if we delight to climb trees, throw stones, and hunt, it is because our forefathers once lived in trees, had no missiles but stones, and depended for a livelihood upon killing something. To some of us, again, this seems an explanation ; to others it merely gives annoyance, as a super- fluous hypothesis, the fruit of a wanton imagination and too much leisure. However, what we are not accustomed to immediately excites curiosity. If it were exceptional to climb trees, throw stones, ride after foxes, whoever did such things would be viewed with suspicion. An eclipse, a shooting star, a solitary boulder on the heath, a strange animal, or a Chinaman in the street, calls for explanation ; and among some nations, eclipses have been explained by supposing a dragon to devour the sun or moon ; solitary boulders, as the missiles of a giant ; and so on. Such explanations, plainly, are attempts to regard rare phenomena as similar to others that are better known ; a snake having been seen to swallow a rabbit, a bigger one may swallow the sun : a giant is supposed to bear much the same relation to a boulder as a boy does to half a brick. When any very common thing seems to need no explanation, it is because the several instances of its occurrence are a sufficient basis cf assimilation to satisfy most of us. Still, if a reason for such a thing is demanded, the commonest answer has the same implication, namely, that assimilation or classification is a sufficient reason for it. Thus, if climbing trees is referred to the need of exercise, it is assimilated to running, rowing, etc. \ 278 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE if the customs of a savage tribe are referred to the command of its gods, they are assimilated to those things that are done at the command of chieftains. Explanation, then, is a kind of classification ; it is the finding of resemblance between the phenomenon in question and other phenomena. In Mathematics, the explanation of a theorem is the same as its proof, and consists in showing that it repeats, under different conditions, the definitions and axioms already assumed and the theorems already demonstrated. In Concrete Sciences, to discover the cause of a pheno- menon, or to derive an empirical law from laws of causation, is *to explain it ; because a cause is an invariable antecedent, and therefore reminds us of, or enables us to conceive, an indefinite number of cases similar to the present one wherever the cause exists ; and, as we have seen that the discovery of the laws of nature is essentially the discovery of causes, the discovery and derivation of laws is scientific explanation. The discovery of quantitative laws is especially satisfactory, because it not only explains why an event happens at all, but why it happens just in this direction, degree, or amount; so that (the only likeness between quantities, as such, being equality), the cause is shown to be equal not only to other causes but to its own effect ; wherefore, whether the conservation of matter and energy be universally true or not, it must still be an universal postulate of scientific explanation. The mere discovery of an empirical law of co-existence, as that ' white tom-cats with blue eyes are deaf ', is indeed something better than an isolated fact : every general propo- sition relieves the mind of a load of facts ; and, for many people, to be able to say ' It is always so ' may be enough ; but for scientific explanation we require to know the reason of it, that is, the cause. Still, if asked to explain an Axiom, we can only say, * It is always so : ' though it is some relief to point out particular instances of its realisation, or to exhibit the similarity of its form to that of other axioms as of the nota note to the axiom of equality. EXPLANATION 279 6. There are three modes of scientific Explanation ; First, the analysis of a phenomenon into the laws of its causes and the concurrence of these causes. The pumping of water implies (i) pressure of the air, (2) distribution of pressure in a liquid, (3) that motion takes the direction of least resistance. Similarly, that thunder follows forked lightning, and that the report of a gun follows the flash, are resolvable into (i) the discharge of electricity, or the ex- plosion of gunpowder ; (2) distance of the observer from the event ; (3) that light travels faster than sound. The planetary orbits are analysable into the tendency of planets to fall into the sun, and their tendency to travel in a straight line. When this conception is helped out by swinging a ball round by a string, and then letting it go, to show what would happen to the earth if gravitation ceased, we see how the recognition of resemblance lies at the bottom of explanation. Secondly, the discovery of steps of causation between a cause and its remote effects ; the interpolation and concatenation of causes. The maxim ' No cats no clover ' is explained by assigning the intermediate steps in the following series ; that the fructi- fication of red clover depends on the visits of humble-bees, who scatter the pollen in seeking honey ; that if field-mice are numerous they destroy the humble-bees' nests ; and that (owls and weasels being exterminated by game-keepers) the destruc- tion of field-mice depends upon the supply of cats ; which, there- fore, are a remote condition of the clover crop. Again, the com- munication of thought by speech is an example of something so common that it seems to need no explanation; yet to explain it is a long story. A thought in one man's mind is the remote cause of a similar thought in another's : Here we have (i) a thought associated with mental words ; (2) a connection between these thoughts and some tracts of the brain ; (3) a connection between these tracts of the brain and the muscles of the larynx, the tongue and the lips ; (4) movements of the chest, larynx and mouth, propelling and modifying waves of 280 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE air ; (5) the impinging of these air-waves upon another man's ear, and by a complex mechanism exciting the aural nerve ; (6) the transfer of this excitation to certain tracts of his brain ; (7) a connection there with sounds of words and their associated thoughts. If one of these links fail, there is no communication. Thirdly, the Subsumption of several laws under one more general expression. Thus the tendency of bodies to fall to the earth and the tendency of the earth itself (with the other planets) to fall into the sun, are subsumed under the general law that ' All matter gravitates.' The same law subsumes the movements of the tide. By means of the notion of specific gravity, it includes ' levitation,' or the actual rising of some bodies, as of corks in water, of balloons, or flames in the air ; the fact being that these things do not tend to rise, but to fall like everything else ; only as the water or air weighs more in proportion to its volume than corks or balloons, the latter are pushed up. This process of Subsumption bears the same relation to Secondary Laws, that these do to particular facts. The generalisation of many particular facts (that is, a statement of that in which they agree) is a law ; and the generalisation of these laws (that is, again, a statement of that in which they agree) is a higher law; and this process, upwards or down- wards, is essentially the course of scientific progress. The perfecting of any science consists in comprehending more and more of the facts within its province, and in showing that they all exemplify a smaller and smaller number of principles, which express their most profound resemblances. It can easily be shown that these three modes of explanation all consist in generalising or assimilating the phenomena. The pressure of the air, of a liquid, and motion in the direc- tion of least resistance, are all commoner facts than pumping ; that light travels faster than sound is a commoner fact than a thunder-storm or gun-firing. Each of the laws 'Cats kill mice,' ' Mice destroy humble-bees' nests,' * Humble-bees EXPLANATION 281 fructify red clover' is wider and expresses the resemblance of more numerous cases than the law that ' Clover depends on cats ' ; because each of them is less subject to further condi- tions. Similarly, every step in the communication of thought by language is less conditional, and therefore more general, than the completion of the process. In all the above cases, again, each law into which the phenomenon (whether pumping or conversation) is resolved, suggests a host of related resemblances : as the modifying of air-waves by the larynx and lips suggests the various devices by which the strings and orifices of musical instruments modify the character of notes. As for Subsumption (case (3)), it consists entirely in proving the existence of an essential similarity between things where it was formerly not observed : as that the gyrations of the moon, the fall of apples, and the flotation of bubbles are all examples of gravitation : or that the purifying of the blood by breathing, the burning of a candle, and the rusting of iron are all cases of oxidation : or that the colouring of the underside of a red- admiral's wings, the spots of the giraffe, the shape of a stick- caterpillar, the transparency of deep-sea animals, and countless other cases, though superficially so different, agree in this, that they conceal and thereby protect the organism. Not any sort of likeness, however, suffices for scientific explanation : it must be ' fundamental ' ; or (as this is a vague expression) we may say that the only satisfactory explanation of concrete things or events, is to discover their likeness to others in respect of Causation. Hence attempts to help the understanding by familiar comparisons are often worse than useless. Any of the above examples will show that explana- tion, instead of making a phenomenon seem familiar, puts (as the saying is) ' quite a new face upon it.' The proneness to substitute familiarisation for radical explanation, is the easily besetting sin of human understanding : the most plausible of fallacies, the most attractive, the most difficult to avoid even when we are on our guard against it. 282 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 7. The explanation of Nature (if it be admitted to consist in generalisation, or the discovery of resemblance amidst differences) can never be completed. For (i) there are (as Mill says) facts, namely, fundamental states or processes of consciousness, which are distinct ; in other words, they do not resemble one another, and therefore cannot be generalised or subsumed under one explanation. Colour, heat, smell, sound, touch, pleasure and pain, are so different that there is one group of conditions to be sought for each ; and the laws of these conditions cannot be subsumed under a more general one "without leaving out the very facts to be explained. A general condition of sensation, such as the stimulating of the sensory organs of a living animal, gives no account of the special characters of colour, smell, etc. ; which are, however, the phenomena in question : and each of them has its own law. Nay, each distinct sensation, quality, or degree must have its own law ; for in each ultimate difference there is something that cannot be assimilated. Such differences amount, accord- ing to experimental Psychologists, to more than 40,000. (2) When physical science is treated objectively (that is, with as little reference as possible to the fact that all pheno- mena are only known in relation to the human mind), colour, heat, smell, sound (considered as sensations) are neglected, and attention is fixed upon certain of their conditions : Ex- tension, Figure, Resistance, Weight, Motion, with their derivatives, Density, Elasticity, etc. These are called the Primary Qualities of Matter; and it is assumed that they belong to matter by itself, whether we look on or not : whilst colour, heat, sound, etc., are called Secondary Qualities, as depending entirely upon the reaction of some conscious animal. From this point of view, the world is considered in the abstract, as a perpetual redistribution of matter and energy. But, not to dwell upon the difficulty of reducing the activi- ties of life and chemistry to mechanical principles, and even the modes of mechanical and physical energy to one another EXPLANATION 283 (for, as Dr. Croll observed, equivalence is not identity) even if this were done, complete explanation could not be attained. For (a) as explanation is the discovery of causes, we no sooner succeed in assigning the causes of the present state of the world than we have to inquire into the causes of those causes, and again the still earlier causes, and so on to infinity. But, this being impossible, we must be content, wherever we stop, to contemplate the uncaused, that is, unexplained ; and then all that follows is really unexplained. Besides this difficulty, however, there is another that prevents the perfecting of any theory of the abstract material world, namely (), that it involves more than one first principle. For we have seen that the Uniformity of Nature is not really a principle, but a merely nominal generalisation, since it cannot be definitely stated ; and, therefore, the principles of Contra- diction, Mediate Equality, and Causation remain incapable of subsumption ; nor can any one of them be reduced to another : so that they remain unexplained. (3) Another limit to explanation lies in the infinite character of every particular fact; so that we may know the laws of many of its properties and yet come far short of understanding it as a whole. A lump of sandstone in the road : we may know a good deal about its specific gravity, temperature, chemical composition, geological conditions ; but if we inquire the causes of the particular modifications it exhibits of these properties, and further why it is just so big, containing so many molecules, neither more nor less, disposed in just such relations to one another as to give it this particular figure, why it lies exactly there rather than a yard off, and so forth, we shall get no explanation of all this. The causes determining each particular phenomenon are infinite, and can never be computed ; and, therefore, it can never be fully explained. 8. Analogy is a kind of probable proof based upon imperfect similarity (as the best that can be discovered) between the data of comparison and the subject of our inference. Like Deduction and Induction, it assumes that 2 S 4 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE things which are alike in some respects are also alike in others ; but it differs from them in not appealing to a definite general law assigning the essential points of resemblance upon which the argument relies. In Deductive proof, this is done by the major premise of every syllogism : if the major says that ' All fat men are humourists,' and we can establish the minor, * X is a fat man,' we have secured the essential resemblance that carries the conclusion. In Induction, the Law of Causation and its representatives, the Canons, serve the same purpose, specifying the essential marks of a cause. But/in Analogy, the resemblance relied on cannot be stated categorically. If we argue that Mars is inhabited because it resembles the datum, our Earth, (i) in being a planet, (2) neither too hot nor too cold for life, (3) having an atmosphere, (4) sea and land, etc., we are not prepared to say that ' All planets having these characteristics are inhabited.' It is, therefore, not a deduction ; and since we do not know the original causes of life on the Earth, we certainly cannot show by induction that adequate causes exist in Mars. We rely, then, upon some such vague notion of Uniformity as that * Things alike in some points are alike in others ' ; which, plainly, is either false or nugatory. But, of course, if the linear markings upon the surface of Mars indicate a system of canals, the inference that he has intelligent inhabitants is no longer analogical, since canals can have no other cause. The cogency of any proof depends upon the character and definiteness of the likeness which one phenomenon bears to another ; but Analogy trusts to the general quantity of likeness between them, in ignorance of what may be the really important likeness. If, having tried with a stone, an apple, a bullet, etc., we find that they all break an ordinary window, and thence infer that a cricket ball will do so, we do not reason by Analogy, but make instinctively a deductive extension of an induction, merely omitting the explicit generalisation, * All missiles of a ANALOGY 285 certain weight, size and solidity break windows.' But if, knowing nothing of snakes except that the viper is venomous, a child runs away from a grass-snake, he argues by Analogy ; and, though his conduct is prudentially justifiable, his inference is wrong : for there is no law that ' All snakes are venomous/ but only that those are venomous that have a certain structure of fang ; a point which he did not stay to examine. Analogical argument, therefore, is only probable, and that in various degrees. (i) The greater the number and importance of the points of agreement, the more probable is the inference. (2) The greater the number and importance of the points of difference, the less probable is the inference. (3) The greater the number of unknown properties in the subject of our argument, the less the value of any inference from those that we do know. Of course the number of unknown properties can itself be estimated only by Analogy. In the case of Mars, they are probably very numerous; and, apart from the evidence of canals, the prevalent assumption that there are intelligent beings in that planet, seems to rest less upon probability than on a curiously imaginative extension of the gregarious senti- ment, the chilly discomfort of mankind at the thought of being alone in the universe, and a hope that there may be conversable and ' clubable ' souls nearer than the Dog-star. CHAPTER XX PROBABILITY Y Chance was once believed to be a distinct power in the world, disturbing the regularity of Nature ; though, according to Aristotle, it was only operative in occurrences below the sphere of the moon. As, however, it is now admitted that every event in the world is due to some cause, if we can only trace the connection, whilst nevertheless the notion of Chance is still useful when rightly conceived, we have to find some other ground for it than that of a spontaneous capricious force inherent in things. For such a conception can have no place in any logical interpretation of Nature : it can never be inferred from a principle, seeing that every principle expresses an uniformity ; nor, again, if the existence of a capricious power be granted, can any inference be drawn from it. Impossible alike as premise and as conclusion, for Reason it is nothing at all. Every event is a result of causes : but the multitude of forces and the variety of collocations being immeasurably great, the overwhelming majority of events occurring about the same time are only related by Causation so remotely that the connection cannot be follo\Nfcd. Whilst my pen moves along the paper, a cab rattles down the street, bells in the neighbouring steeple chime the quarter, a girl in the next house is practising her scales, and throughout the world innumerable events are happening which may never happen together again ; so that should one of them recur, we have no reason to expect any of the others. This is Chance, or chance coincidence. The word coincidence PROBABILITY 287 is vulgarly used only for the inexplicable concurrence of in- teresting events " quite a coincidence ! " On the other hand, many things are now happening together or coinciding, that will do so, for assignable reasons, again and again ; thousands of men are leaving the City, who leave at the same hour five days a week. But this is not chance ; it is causal coincidence due to the custom of business in this country, as determined by our latitude and longitude and other circum- stances. No doubt the above chance coincidences writing, cab-rattiing, chimes, scales, etc. are causally connected at some point of past time. They were predetermined by the condition of the world ten minutes ago ; and that was due to earlier con- ditions, one behind the other, even to the formation of the planet. But whatever connection there may have been, we have no such knowledge of it as to be able to deduce the coincidence, or calculate its recurrence. Here Chance is defined by Mill to be : Coincidence giving no ground to infer uniformity. However, in fact, some chance coincidences do recur ac- cording to laws of their own : I say some, but it may be all. If the world is finite, the possible combinations of its elements are exhaustible ; and, in time, whatever conditions of the world have concurred will concur again, and in the same relation to former conditions. This writing, that cab, those chimes, those scales will coincide again : the Argonautic expedition, and the Trojan war, and all our other troubles will be renewed. But, to avoid melancholy, let us consider some more manageable instance, such as the throwing of dice. Every one who has played much with dice knows (so I am told) that double sixes are sometimes thrown, and sometimes double aces. Such coincidences do not happen once and only once ; they occur again and again, and a great number of trials will show that, though their recurrence has not the regularity of cause and effect, it yet has a law of its own, namely a tendency to average regularity. In 10,000 throws there will be some number of double sixes ; and the greater the number of throws he 288 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE more closely will the average recurrence of double sixes, or double aces, approximate to one in thirty-six. Such a law of average recurrence is the basis of Probability. Chance being the fact of coincidence without assignable cause, Proba- bility is expectation based on the average frequency of its happening. 2. Probability is an ambiguous term. Usually, when we say that an event is ' probable,' we mean that it is more likely than not to happen. But, scientifically, an event is probable if our expectation of its occurrence is less than certainty, as long as the event is not impossible. Probability thus conceived is represented by a fraction. Taking i to stand for certainty, and o for impossibility, probability may be -f^f t r TTTUTJ"* or (generally) ~. The denominator, of course, represents the number of times that an event happens, and the numerator the number of times that it coincides with another event. In throwing a die, the probability of ace turning up is expressed by putting the number of throws for the denominator and the number of times that ace is thrown for the numerator ; and we may assume that the more trials we make the . nearer will the resulting fraction approximate to . Instead of speaking of the ' throwing of the die ' and its * turning up ace ' as two events, the former is often called ' the event ' and the latter * the way of its happening.' And these expressions may easily be extended to cover relations of distinct events ; as when two men shoot at a mark and we desire to represent the probability of both hitting the bull's eye together, each shot may count as an event (denominator) and the coincidence of ' bull's-eyes ' as the way of its happening (numerator). It is also common to speak of probability as a proportion. If the fraction expressing the probability of ace being cast is , the proportion of cases in which it happens is i to 5 ; or (as it is, perhaps, still more commonly put) ' the chances are 5 to i against it.' 3. As to the grounds of probability opinions differ. PROBABILITY 289 According to one view the ground is subjective : probability depends, it is said, upon the quantity of our Belief in the happening of a certain event, or in its happening in a particular way. According to the other view the ground is objective, and, in fact, is nothing else than experience, which is most trust- worthy when carefully expressed in statistics. To the subjective view it may be objected, (a) that Belief cannot by itself be satisfactorily measured. Surely, no one will maintain that Belief, merely as a state of mind, always has a definite numerical value of which one is conscious, as T J^ or y 1 ^. Let anybody mix a number of letters in a bag, knowing nothing of them except that one of them is X, and then draw them one by one, endeavouring each time to estimate the value of his belief that the next will be X ; can he say that his belief in the drawing of X regularly increases as the number of letters left decreases ? If not, we see that (b) Belief does not uniformly correspond with the state of the facts. If in such a trial as proposed above, we really wish to draw X, as when looking for something in a number of boxes, how common it is after a few failures to feel quite hopeless and to say : " Oh, of course it will be in the last." For belief is subject to hope and fear, temperament, passion, and prejudice, and not merely to rational considerations. And it is useless to appeal to ' the Wise Man,' the purely rational judge of probability, unless he is producible. Or, if it be said that belief is a short cut to the evaluation of experience, be- cause in fact it is the resultant of all past experience, we may reply that this is not true. For everybody knows that one striking experience, or two or three recent ones, will immensely outweigh a great number of faint or remote experiences. More- over, the experience of two men may be practically equal, whilst their beliefs upon any question greatly differ. Any two English- men have about the same experience, personal and ancestral, of the weather ; yet their beliefs in the saw that ' if it rain on St. Swithin's Day it will rain for forty days after,' may differ as confident expectation and sheer scepticism. Upon which of 290 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE these beliefs shall we ground the probability of forty days' rain? But (<;), at any rate, if Probability is to be connected with Inductive Logic, it ought surely to rest upon the same ground, namely Observation. Induction, in any particular- case, is not content with beliefs or opinions, but aims at probing, testing, verifying or correcting them by appealing to the facts ; and Probability has the same object and the same basis. There are, indeed, cases in which the conditions of an event are "supposed to be mathematically predetermined, as in tossing a penny, throwing dice, dealing cards. In throwing a die, the ways of happening are six ; in tossing a penny only two, head and tail : and we usually assume that the odds with a die are fairly 5 to i against ace, whilst with a penny ' the betting is even' on head or tail. Still, this assumption rests upon another, that the die is perfectly fair, or that the head and tail of a penny are exactly alike ; and this is not true. With an ordinary die or penny, a very great number of trials would, no doubt, give an average approximating to J- or \ ; yet might always leave a certain excess one way or the other, which would also become more definite as the trials went on ; thus showing that the die or penny did not satisfy the mathematical hypothesis. Bufton is said to have tossed a coin 4040 times, obtaining 1992 heads and 2048 tails; a pupil of De Morgan tossed 4092 times, obtaining 2048 heads and 2044 tails. There are other important cases in which probability is estimated and numerically expressed, although statistical evidence directly bearing upon the point in question cannot be obtained ; as in betting upon a race ; or in the prices of stocks and shares, which are supposed to represent the probability of their paying, or continuing to pay, a certain rate of interest. But the judgment of experts in such matters is certainly based upon experience; and great pains are taken to make the evidence as definite as possible by comparing records of speed, or by financial estimates ; though something must still be PROBABILITY 291 allowed for reports of the condition of horses, or of the prospects of war, etc. However, where statistical evidence is obtainable, no one dreams of preferring to estimate probability by the quantity of his belief. Insurance offices, dealing with fire, shipwreck, death, accident, etc., prepare elaborate statistics of these events, and regulate their rates accordingly. Apart from statistics, at what rate ought the lives of men aged 40 to be insured, in order to leave a profit of 5 per cent, upon jiooo payable at each man's death ? Is l quantity of belief ' a suffi cient basis for doing this sum ? 4. The ground of probability is experience, then, and, whenever possible, statistics ; which are a kind of inductions. It has indeed been urged that induction is itself based upon probability ; that the subtlety, complexity and secrecy of nature are such, that we are never quite sure that we fully know even what we have observed ; and that, as for laws, the conditions of the universe at large may at any moment be completely changed; so that all imperfect deductions, in- cluding the law of Causation itself, are only probable. But, clearly, this doctrine turns upon another ambiguity in the word * probable.' It may be used in the sense of * less than abso- lutely certain'; and such doubtless is the condition of all human knowledge, in comparison with the comprehensive intuition of archangels : or it may mean * less than certain according to our standard of certainty,' that is, in comparison with the law of Causation and its derivatives. We may suppose some one to object that " by this relative standard even empirical laws cannot be called * only probable ' as long as we * know no exception to them ' ; for that is all that can be said for the boasted law of Causation; and that, accordingly, we can frame no fraction to represent their probability. That * all swans are white ' was at one time, from this point of view, not probable but certain ; though we now know it to be false. It would have been an indecorum to call it only probable as long as no other-coloured swan was 292 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE known ; not merely because the quantity of belief amounted to certainty, but because the number of events (seeing a swan) and the number of their happenings in a certain way (being white) were equal, and therefore the evidence amounted to i or certainty." But we reply, that such an empirical law is only probable, and that the estimate of its probability must be based on the number of times that similar laws have been found liable to exceptions. White crows, though rare, are exceptions to the law that crows are black ; and it is not uncommon to find allied varieties of animals differing in colour in different localities. Had the evidence been known and duly weighed, then, it could never have seemed more than probable that ' all swans are white.' But what law, similar in rank to the law of Causation, presents any exceptions ? It ought not to be difficult to see that induction, ' humanly speaking/ does not rest on probability ; but that the probability of concrete events (not of mere mathematical abstractions like the falling of absolutely true dice) rests on induction and, therefore, on causation. The inductive evidence underlying an estimate of probability may be of three kinds: (a) direct statistics of the events in question ; as when we find that, at the age of 20, the average expectation of life is 39-40 years. This is an empirical law, and, if we do not know the causes of any event, we must be content with an empirical law. But (b) if we do know the causes of an event, and the causes which may prevent its happening, and can estimate the comparative frequency of their occurring, we may deduce the probability that the effect (that is, the event in question) will occur. Or (c) we may combine these two methods, verifying each by means of the other. Now either the method (b) or (a fortiori) the method (c) (both depending on causation) is more trustworthy than the method (a) by itself. But, further, a merely empirical statistical law will only be true as long as the causes influencing the event remain the PROBABILITY 293 same. A die may be found to turn ace once in six throws, on the average, in close accordance with mathematical theory ; but if we load it on that facet the results will be very different. So it is with the expectation of life, or fire, or shipwreck. The increased virulence of some epidemic such as influenza, an outbreak of anarchic incendiarism, a moral epidemic of over- loading ships, may deceive the hopes of insurance offices. Hence we see, again, that probability depends upon causation, not causation upon probability. That uncertainty of an event which arises not from ignorance of the law of its cause, but from our not knowing whether the cause itself does or does not occur at any particular time, is Contingency. 5. The nature of an average supposes deviations from it. These deviations, or 'errors,' conform to the law that the greater are less frequent than the smaller, so that most of the events approximate to the average. The calculation of probabilities, in fact, supposes a class or series of instances or events, subject (as far as known) to somewhat similar con- ditions, though the conditions are not so similar as to result in uniformity. Where the more similar conditions predominate, they produce average instances; where dissimilar conditions occur, but in such a way as to cancel one another, the average again results ; where unusual conditions occur without can- celling, extraordinary instances appear. Hence if the average height of a nation is 5 ft. 6 in., most men will be about that size ; men of 5 ft. and 6. ft. will be rare, and those of 4 ft. 6 in. and 6 ft. 6 in. rarer still; whilst limits to height in both directions seem to be fixed by the nature of things. In casting a die, in sets of six throws, ace will turn up oftener once than twice in each set of throws, oftener twice than three times, though it may appear every time in six, and even in continuous sets of sixes ; and, in such a case, there seems (a priori} to be no necessary limit to the length of sequences that may occur in infinite trials. These considerations have an important bearing upon the 294 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE interpretation of probabilities. The average probability for any general class or series of events cannot be confidently applied to any one instance or to any special class of instances, since this one, or this special class, may exhibit a striking error or deviation ; it may, in fact, be subject to special causes. Within the class whose average is first taken, and which is described by general characters as ' a man/ or ' a die,' or ' a rifle shot/ there may be special classes marked by special characters and determined by special influences. Statistics giving the average for * mankind ' may not be true of ' civilised men,' or any still smaller class such as * inhabitants of U.S.A.* Hence life-insurance orifices rely not merely on statistics of life and death in general, but collect special evidence in respect of different ages and sexes, and make further allowance for teetotalism, inherited disease, etc. Similarly for individual cases : the average expectation for a class, whether general or special, is only applicable to any particular case if that case is adequately described by the class characters. In England, for example, the average expectation of life for males at 20 years of age is 39*40; but at 60 it is still 13*14, and at 73 it is 7*07 ; at 100 it is i *6 1. Of men 20 years old those who live more or less than 39*40 years are deviations or errors ; but there are a great many of them. To insure the life of a single man at 20, in the expectation of his dying at 60, would be a mere bet, if we had no special knowledge of him ; the safety of an insurance office lies in having so many clients that opposite deviations cancel one another : the more clients the safer the business. It is quite possible that a hundred men aged 20 should be insured in one week and all of them die before 25 : this would be ruinous, if others did not live to be So or 90. Not only in such a practical affair as insurance, but in matters purely scientific, the minute and subtle peculiarities of individuals have important consequences. Each man has a certain cast of mind, character, physique, giving a distinctive turn to all his actions even when he tries to be normal. In every employment this determines his Personal Equation, or PROBABILITY 295 average deviation from the normal. The term Personal Equation is used chiefly in connection with scientific observa- tion, as in Astronomy. Each observer is liable to be a little wrong, and this error has to be allowed for and his observations corrected accordingly. The use of the term Expectation,' and of examples drawn from insurance and gambling, is apt to convey the notion that probability relates entirely to future events ; but if it is based on laws and causes it can have no reference to point of time. As long as conditions are the same events will be the same, whether we consider uniformities or averages. We may there- fore draw probable inferences concerning the past as well as the future, subject to the same hypothesis, that the causes affecting the events in question be the same and similarly combined. On the other hand, if we know that conditions bearing on the subject of investigation, have changed since statistics were collected, or were different at some time previous to the collection of evidence, every probable inference based on those statistics must be corrected by allowing for the altered conditions, whether we desire to reason forwards or backwards in time. 6. The rules for the combination of probabilities are as follows : (1) If two events or causes do not concur, the probability of one or the other occurring is the sum of the separate pro- babilities. A die cannot turn up both ace and six ; but the probability in favour of each is J : therefore, the probability in favour of one or the other is J. Death can hardly occur from both burning and drowning : if i in 1000 is burned and 2 in 1000 are drowned, the probability of being burnt or drowned ic 3 15 TT5UTF- (2) If two events are independent, having neither connection nor repugnance, the probability of their concurring is found by multiplying together the separate probabilities of each occurring. If in walking down a certain street I meet A once in four 296 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE times, and B once in three times, I ought (by mere chance) to meet both once in twelve times : for in twelve occasions I meet B four times ; but once in four I meet A. This is a very important rule in scientific investigation, since it enables us to detect the presence of causation. For if the coincidence of two events is more or less frequent than it would be if they were entirely independent, there is either connection or repugnance between them. If, e.g., in walking down the street I meet both A and B oftener than once in twelve times, they may be engaged in similar business, calling them from their offices at about the same hour. If I meet them both less often than once in twelve times, they may belong to the same office, where one acts as a substitute fo.T the other. Similarly, if in a multitude of throws a die turns six oftener than once in six times, it is not a fair one : that is, there is a cause favouring the turning of six. If of 20,000 people 500 see apparitions and 100 have friends murdered, the chunce of any man having both experiences is -g-enju ; but if each lives on the average 300,000 hours, the chance of both events occurring in the same hour is If tne two events occur in the same hour oftener than this, there is more than a chance coincidence. The more minute a cause of connection or repugnance between events, the longer the series of trials or instances necessary to bring out its influence. The less a die is loaded, the more casts must be made before it can be shown that a certain side tends to recur oftener than once in six. (3) The rule for calculating the probability of a dependent event is clearly the same as the above ; for the concurrence of two independent events is itself dependent upon each of them occurring. My meeting with both A and B in the street is dependent on my walking there and on my meeting one of them. Similarly, if A is sometimes a cause of B (though liable to be frustrated), and B sometimes of C (C and B having no causes independent of B and A respectively), the occurrence of C is dependent on that of B, and that again on the occurrence PROBABILITY 297 of A. Hence we may state the rule : If two events are dependent each on another, so that if one occur the second may (or may not), and if the second a third ; whilst the third never occurs without the second, nor the second without the first ; the probability that if the first occur the third will, is found by multiplying together the fractions expressing the probability that the first is a mark of the second and the second of the third. Upon this principle the value of hearsay evidence or tradition deteriorates, and generally the cogency of any argument based upon the combination of approximate generalisations dependent on one another or " self-infirmative." If there are two witnesses, A and B, of whom A saw an event, whilst B only heard A relate it (and is therefore dependent on A), what credit is due to B's recital ? Suppose the probability of each man's being correct as to what he says he saw, or heard, is f : then (f x J = T 9 F ) the probability that B's story is true is a little more than J. For if in 16 attestations A is wrong 4 times, B can only be right in f of the remainder, or 9 times in 16. Again, if we have the Approximate Generalisations, ' Most 'attempts to reduce wages are met by strikes,' and ' Most strikes are successful,' and learn, on statistical inquiry, that in every hundred attempts to reduce wages there are 80 strikes, and that 70 p.c. of the strikes are successful, then 56 p.c. of attempts to reduce wages are unsuccessful. Of course this method of calculation cannot be quantita- tively applicable if no statistics are obtainable, as in the testimony of witnesses ; and even if a numerical value could be attached to the evidence of a certain class of witnesses, it would be absurd to assume it for particular members of the class without taking account of their education, interest in the case, prejudice, or general capacity. Still, the numerical illustration of the rapid deterioration of hearsay evidence, when less than quite veracious, puts us on our guard against rumour. To retail rumour may be as bad as to invent an original lie. 298 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE (4) If an event may coincide with two or more other independent events, the probability that they will together be a sign of it, is found by multiplying together the fractions representing the improbability that each is a sign of it, and subtracting the product from unity. This is the rule for estimating the cogency of cumulative testimony, circumstantial evidence, analogical evidence; or, generally, for combining Approximate Generalisations " self corroboratively." If, for example, each of two independent witnesses, or cir- cumstances, raises a probability of 6 to i in favour of a certain event; taking i to represent certainty, i- is the improbability of the event, notwithstanding each witness. Then TX^- = ^J-, the improbability of both proving it. Therefore the proba- bility of the event is 48 to i . The matter may be plainer if put thus : A is right 6 times in 7, or 42 in 49 ; in the remain- ing 7 times in 49 B will be right 6 times. Therefore, together they will be right 48 times in 49. If in an analogical argument there were 8 points of com- parison, 5 for and 3 against a certain inference, and the probability of each point could be quantified, the total value of the evidence could be estimated by doing a similar sum. When approximate generalisations that have not been pre- cisely quantified combine their evidence, the cogency of the argument increases in the same way, though it cannot be made so definite. If it be true that most poets are irritable, and also that most invalids are irritable, a still greater pro- portion will be irritable of those who are both invalids and poets. On the whole, from the discussion of probabilities there emerge four principal cautions as to their use : Not to make a pedantic parade of numerical probability, where the numbers have not been ascertained ; Not to trust to our feeling of what is likely, if statistics can be obtained ; Not to apply an average probability to special classes or individuals without inquiring PROBABILITY 299 whether they correspond to the average type ; and Not to trust to the empirical probability of events, if their causes can be discovered and made the basis of reasoning which the empirical probability may be used to verify. The reader who wishes to pursue this subject further should read a work to which the foregoing chapter is greatly indebted, Dr. Venn's Logic of Chance, CHAPTER XXI DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION i. Classification, in its widest sense, is a mental grouping of facts or phenomena according to their resemblances and differences, so as best to serve some purpose. I say a " mental grouping " ; for although in museums we often see the things themselves arranged in classes, yet such an arrangement only contains specimens representing a classi- fication. The classification itself may extend to innumerable objects most of which have never been seen at all. Extinct animals, for example, are classified from what we know of their fossils ; and some of the fossils may be seen arranged in a museum ; but the animals themselves have disappeared for many ages. Again, things are classed according to their resemblances and differences : that is to say, those that most closely resemble one another are classed together on that ground ; and those that differ from one another in important ways, are distributed into different classes. The more the things differ, the wider apart are their classes both in thought and in the arrangements of a museum. If their differences are very great, as with animals, vegetables and minerals, the classing of them falls to different departments of thought or science, and is often repre- sented in different museums, zoological, botanical, minera- logical. We must not, however, suppose that there is only one way of classifying things. The same objects may be classed in DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 301 various ways according to the purpose in view. For gardening, we are usually content to classify plants into trees, shrubs, flowers, grasses and weeds ; the ordinary crops of English agri- culture are distinguished, in settling their rotation, into white and green ; the botanist writes about monocotyledons and dicotyledons. The principle of resemblance and difference is recognised in all these cases; but what resemblances or differences are important depends upon the purpose to be served. Purposes may themselves be classified ; and here the most important distinction for Logic is between (a) special or practical purposes, as in gardening or hunting, and (/3) general or scientific, as in Botany or Zoology. The scientific purpose is merely knowledge ; it may indeed subserve all particular or practical ends, but has no other end than knowledge directly in view. And whilst, even for knowledge, different classi- fications may be suitable for different lines of inquiry, in Botany and Zoology the Morphological classification is (I suppose) that which gives the most general and com- prehensive knowledge (see Huxley, On the Classification of Animals i ch. i). Most of what a logician says about classi- fication is applicable to the practical kind ; but the scientific (often called ' Natural Classification '), as the most thorough and comprehensive, is what he keeps most constantly before him. Scientific classification, of course, comes late in human history, and at first works over earlier classifications which have been made by the growth of intelligence, of language, and of the practical arts. Even in the distinctions recognised by animals, may be traced the grounds of classification. A cat does not confound a dog with one of its own species, nor water with milk, nor cabbage with fish. But it is in the development of language that the progress of instinctive classi- fication may best be seen. The use of general names implies the recognition of classes of things corresponding to them, which form their denotation, and whose resembling qualities 302 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE so far as recognised, form their connotation ; and such names are of many degrees of generality. The use of abstract names shows that the objects classed have also been analysed, and that their resembling qualities have been recognised amidst diverse groups of qualities: Of the classes marked by popular language it is worth while to distinguish two sorts (cf. chap. xix. 4) : Kinds, and those having but few points of agreement. But the popular classifications, made by language and the primitive arts, are very imperfect. They omit innumerable things which have not been found useful or noxious, or have been inconspicuous, or have not happened to occur in the region inhabited by those who speak a particular language; and even things recognised and named may have been very superficially examined, and therefore wrongly classed, as when a whale or porpoise is called a fish, or a slowworm is con- founded with snakes. A scientific classification, on the other hand, aims at the utmost comprehensiveness, ransacking the whole world from the depths of the earth to the remotest star for new objects, and scrutinising everything with the aid of crucible and dissecting knife, microscope and spectroscope, to find the qualities and constitution of everything, in order that it may be classed among those things with which it has most in common and distinguished from those other things from which it diners. A scientific classification continually grows more comprehensive, more discriminative, more definitely and systematically coherent. Hence the uses of classification may be easily perceived. 2. The first use of classification is the better understanding of the facts of Nature (or of any sphere of practice) ; for under- standing consists in perceiving and comprehending the likeness and difference of things, in assimilating and distinguishing them; and in carrying out this process systematically new correlations of properties are continually disclosed. Thus classification is closely analogous to we may say, a kind of explanation. Explanation has been shown (chap. xix. 5) to DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 303 consist in the discovery of the laws or causes of changes in Nature ; and laws and causes imply similarity, or like changes under like conditions : in the same way classification consists in the discovery of resemblances in the things that undergo change. We may say (subject to subsequent qualifications) that Explanation analyses Nature in its dynamic, Classification in its static aspect. In both cases we have a feeling of relief. When the cause of any event is pointed out, or an object is assigned its place in a system of classes, the gaping wonder, or confusion, or perplexity, occasioned by an unintelligible thing, or (worse) by a multitude of such things, is dissipated. No doubt, some people are more than others susceptible of this pleasure and fastidious about its purity. A second use of classification is to aid the memory. It strengthens memory, because one of the conditions of our remembering things is, that they resemble what we last thought of ; so that to be accustomed to study and think of things in classes must greatly facilitate remembrance. But, besides this, it improves the character of memory, by making us more likely to remember what we want. For what we want in any emer- gency is to remember what served the purpose in similar cases ; or to recall cases similar to the present one, as in warding a blow, or solving a problem, or illustrating an essay. Here again, explanation and classification have the same use : they both tend to rationalise the memory, and to organise the mind in correspondence with Nature. Every one knows how a poor mind is always repeating itself, going by rote through the same train of words, ideas, actions ; and that such a mind is neither interesting nor practical. It is not practical, because the circumstances of life are rarely exactly repealed, so that it is rarely enough for our present purpose to remember only one former case ; we need several, that by comparing (perhaps automatically) their resemblances and differences with the one before us, we may select a course of action, or a principle, or a parallel, suited to our immediate needs. 304 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE Thus, greater fertility and flexibility of thought seem naturally to result from the practice of explanation and classification. But it must be honestly added, that the result depends upon the spirit in which such study is carried on ; for if we are too fond of finality, too eager to believe that we have already attained a greater precision and comprehension than are in fact attainable, nothing can be more petrific than * science,' and our last state may be worse than the first. Of this, students of Logic have often furnished examples. 3. Classification may be either Deductive or Inductive ; that is to say, in the formation of classes, as in the proof of propositions, we may, on the whole, proceed from the more to the less, or from the less to the more general ; not that these two processes are entirely independent. If we begin with some large class, such as * Animal/ and subdivide it deductively into Vertebrate and Invertebrate, yet the principle of division (namely, central structure) has first been reached by a comparison of examples and by generalisa- tion; if, on the other hand, beginning with individuals, we group them inductively into classes, and these again into wider ones (as dogs, cats, horses, whales and monkeys 'into mammalia) we are guided both in special cases by hypotheses as to the best grounds of resemblance, and throughout by the general principle of classification to associate things that are alike and to separate things that are unlike. This principle holds implicitly a place in classification similar to that of causation in inductive proof; and whatever the remote origin or basis of these principles, that is a question for Psychology or for Meta- physics : they are now principles of intelligence, of Logic and of Science. Here, therefore, as in proof, induction is implied in deduction, and deduction in induction. Still, the two modes of procedure may be usefully distinguished : in deduction, we advance from a whole to its parts, from general to special ; in induction, from special (or particular) to general, from the parts to their whole. DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 4. The process of Deductive Classification, or Formal Division, may be represented thus : A 1 1 AB 1 1 Ab I 1 ABC 1 ABc 1 AbC 1 Abe Given any class (A) to be divided. 1. Select one important character, attribute, or quality (B), not common to all the individuals comprehended in the class, as the basis of division (Jundamcntum divisionis). 2. Proceed by Dichotomy ; that is, cut the given class into two, one having the selected attribute (say, B), the other not having it (b). This, like all formal processes, assumes the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle, that * No A is both B and not-B,' and that ' Every A is either B or not-B ' (chap. vi. 3) ; and if these principles are not true, or not applicable, the method fails. When a Class is thus subdivided, it may be called, in relation to its subclasses, a Genus ; and in relation to it, the subclasses may be called Species : thus Genus A, Species AB and Ab, etc. 3. Proceed gradually in the order of the importance of characters ; that is, having divided the given class, subdivide on the same principle the two classes thence arising ; and so again and again, step by step, until all the characters are exhausted : Divisio ne fiat per saltum. Suppose we were to attempt an exhaustive classification of things by this method, we must begin with ' All Things,' and divide them (say) into phenomenal and not-phenomenal, and then subdivide phenomena, and so on, thus : 3 o6 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE All Things I I I Phenomenal Not-phenomenal I I Extended Unextended (e.g., Pleasure and Pain) ! r I Resistant Non-resistant (Matter) (Space) I I I Gravitating Non-gravitating . I I Simple Compound Having subdivided 'Simple 7 by all possible characters, we must then go back and similarly subdivide Not-phenomenal, Unextended, Non-resistant, Non-gravitating, and Compound. Now, if we knew all possible characters, and the order of their importance, we might prepare a priori a classification of all possible things; at least, of all things that come under the principles of Contradiction and Excluded Middle. It might, indeed, appear that many of our compartments had nothing actual answering to them ; there may, for example, be nothing that is not phenomenal to some mind, or nothing that is extended and non-resistant (no vacuum), and so forth. It is true that this implies a breach of the rule, that the dividing quality be not common to the whole class ; but, in fact, doubts have been, and are, seriously entertained whether these com- partments are filled or not. If they are not, we have concepts representing nothing, which have perhaps been generated by the mere force of grammatical negation ; and, on the strength of these empty concepts, we have been misled into dividing by an attribute, which (being universal) cannot be a funda- menfum divisioMs. But though in such a classification places might be empty, there would be a place for everything ; for DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 307 whatever did not come into some positive class, such as Gravitating, must, at any rate, fall under one of the negative classes (the ' Nots ') that would run down the right-hand side of the Table and of its subdivisions. This is the ideal of classification. Unfortunately, however, we have to learn what characters or attributes are possible, by experience and comparison; we are far from knowing them all : and we do not know the order of their importance ; nor are we even clear what ' important ' means in this context, whether ' widely prevalent,' or * ancient,' or ' causally influential,' or ' indicative of others.' Hence, in classifying actual things, the inductive method of beginning with particular things, and sorting them according to their likeness as discovered by investigation of their nature, must clearly always be resorted to. The exceptional cases, in which deduction is really useful, occur where certain limits to the number and combination of qualities happen to be known, as they may be in human institutions, or where there are mathematical conditions. Thus, we might be able to classify orders of Architecture, or the legitimate metres and stanzas of English Poetry ; though, in fact, these things are too free, subtle and complex for deductive treatment : for do not the Arts grow like trees ? The only sure cases are mathematical ; as we may show that there are possible only three kinds of plane triangles, four conic sections, five regular solids, etc. 5. The rules for testing a Division are as follows : i. Each Sub-class, or Species, should comprise less than the Class, or Genus, to be divided. This provides that the Division shall be a real one, and not based upon an attribute common to the whole class ; that, therefore, the first rule for making a division shall have been completely adhered to. But, as in 4, we are here met by a logical difficulty. Suppose the class to be divided is A, and we attempt to divide upon the attribute B, into AB and Ab ; is this now a true division, if we do not know any A that is not B ? As far as our knowledge extends, we have not divided 308 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE A at all. But, on the other hand, our knowledge of concrete things is never exhaustive ; so that, although we know of no A that is not B, it may yet exist, and we have seen that it is a logical caution not to assume what we do not know. In a deductive classification, at least, it seems better to regard every attribute as a possible ground of division. Hence, in the above division of 'All Things,' 'Non-phenomenal/ 'Ex- tended-Non-resistant,' * Resistant-Non-gravitating,' appear as negative classes (that is, classes based on the negation of an attribute), although their real existence may be doubtful. But, if this is justifiable, we must either rewrite the first test of a division thus : ' Each sub-class should possibly comprise less than the class to be divided ' ; or else we must confine the rule to (a) thoroughly empirical divisions, as in dividing Colour into Red and Not-red, where we know that both sub-classes are real ; and (b) divisions under demonstrable conditions as in dividing the three kinds of triangles by the quality equi- lateral, we know that it is only applicable to acute-angled triangles, and do not attempt to divide the right-angled or obtuse-angled by it. 2. The Sub-classes taken together should be equal to the Class to be divided : the sum of the Species constitutes the Genus. This provides that the Division shall be exhaustive ; which is always secured by dichotomy, according to the prin- ciple of Excluded Middle ; because whatever is not in the positive class, must be in the negative : Red and Not-red include all colours. 3. The Sub-classes must be opposed or mutually exclusive : Species must not overlap. This again is secured by Dichotomy, according to the principle of Contradiction, provided the Division be made upon one attribute at a time. But, if we attempt to divide simultaneously upon two attributes, as ' Musicians ' upon ( nationality ' and ' method,' we get what is called a Cross-division, thus : ' German Musicians/ ' Not- German,' * Classical/ 'Not-Classical/ for these classes may overlap, the same men sometimes appearing in two groups DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 309 Bach in ' German ' and * Classical,' Pergolesi in ' Not-German and ' Classical.' If, however, we divide Musicians upon these attributes successively, cross division will be avoided, thus : Musicians I 1 Classical 1 1 Non-classical 1 1 German 1 Non-German 1 German 1 Non-German Here no Musician will be found in two classes, unless he has written works in two styles, or unless there are works whose style is undecided. Let this " unless or unless " suggest caution in using dichotomy as a short cut to the classification of realities. 4. No Sub-class must include anything that is not comprised in the class to be divided : the Genus comprises all the Species. Do not divide Dogs into fox-terriers and dog-fish. 6. The process of Inductive Classification may be repre- sented thus : Given any multitude of individuals to be classified: (1) Place together in groups (or in thought) those things that have in common the most, the most widely diffused and the most important qualities. (2) Connect those groups which have, as groups, the greater resemblance, and separate those that have the greater difference. (3) Demarcate, as forming higher or more general classes, those groups of groups that have important characters in common ; and, if possible, on the same principle, form these higher classes into classes higher still : that is to say, graduate the classification upwards. Whilst, in Division the terms ' Genus ' and ' Species ' are entirely relative to one another and have no fixed positions in a gradation of classes, it has been usual, in Inductive Classifi- cation, to confine the term 'Species' to classes regarded as lowest in the scale, to give the term * Genera ' to classes on the 3 io LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE step above, and at each higher step to find some new term such as * Tribe,' ' Order,' ' Sub-kingdom/ ' Kingdom ' ; as may be seen by turning to any book on Botany or Zoology. If, having fixed our Species, we find them subdivisible, it is usual to call the Sub-species * Varieties.' Suppose we attempt to classify by this method the objects in an ordinary sitting-room. We see at a glance carpets, mats, curtains, grates, fire-irons, coal-scuttles, chairs, sofas, tables, books, pictures, musical instruments, etc. These we may call * Species.' Carpets and mats clearly go together; so do chairs and sofas ; so do grates, fire-irons, and coal-scuttles ; and so on. These greater groups, or higher classes, we may call *' Genera.' Putting together carpets, mats and curtains as * warmth-fabrics '; chairs, sofas and tables as * supports'; books, pictures and musical instruments as * means of culture ' ; these groups we may call Orders. Sum up the whole as, from the housewife's point of view, ' furniture/ If we then subdivide some of the species, as books into poetry, novels, travels, etc. these Sub- species may be considered ' Varieties.' A Classification thus made, may be tested by the same rules as those given for testing a Division ; but if it does not stand the test, we must not infer that the classification is a bad one. If the best possible, it is good, though formally imperfect: whatever faults are found must then be charged upon the * matter,' which is traditionally perverse and intractable. If, for example, there is a hammock in the room, it must be classed not with the curtains as a warmth-fabric, but with the sofas as a support; and books and pictures may be classed as, in a peculiar sense, means of culture, though all the objects in the room may have been modified and assorted with a view to gratifying and developing good taste. 7. The difficulty of classifying natural objects is very great. It is not enough to consider their external appearance : exhaustive knowledge of their internal structure is necessary, and of the functions of every part of their structure. This is a matter of immense research, and has occupied many of the DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 311 greatest minds for very many years. The following is a tabular oucline of the classification of the Animal Kingdom I I SUB-KINGDOM : Vertebrates Invertebrates (5 Sub-kingdoms) CLASS : Mam Sauropsida I Ichthyopsida r~ n Amphibia Fishes 1 1 mals Birds Reptiles 1 SOB-CLASS: Placental Implacental 1 I DIVISION : Monodelphia Didelphia I Ornithodelphia I III ORDER: Quadrumana Rodentia Carnivora Ungulata Caetacea, etc. I ! I SECTION: Pinnigrada Plantigrada Digitigrada I I (Seals, etc.) (Bears, etc.) \ I I I I GENUS : Mustelidse Viverridae Hysenidae Canidae Felidae (Weasels, etc.) (Civets, etc.) Ill III SPECIES : Lion Tiger Leopard Puma Lynx Cat, etc. I I I I VARIETY : African Syrian Cave-lion (extinct) As there is not space enough to tabulate such a classification in full, I have developed at each step the most interesting groups : Vertebrates, Mammals, Monodelphia, Carnivora, Digi- tigrada, Felidse, Lion. Most of the other groups in each grade are also subdivisible, though some of them contain far fewer sub-classes than others. 312 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE To see, however, the true character of this classification, we must consider that it is based chiefly upon knowledge of existing animals. Some extinct animals, known by their fossils, find places in it; for others new places have been made. But it represents, on the whole, a cross-section, or cross-sections, of Nature as developing in time ; and, in order to give a just view of the relations of animals, it must be seen in the light of other considerations. The older systems of classification, and the rules for making them, seem to have assumed that an actual system of classes, or of what Mill calls ' Kinds/ exists in nature, and that the relations of Kinds in this system are determined by quantity of resemblance in co-existent qualities, as the ground of their affinity. 8. Darwin's doctrine of the origin of species modifies the conception of natural classification in several ways. In the first place, if all living things are blood-relations, modified in the course of ages according to their various conditions of life, * Affinity ' must mean * nearness of common descent ' ; and it seems irrational to propose a classification upon any other basis. We have to consider the Animal (or the Vegetable) Kingdom as a family tree, exhibiting a long line of ancestors, and (descended from them) all sorts of cousins, first, second, third, etc., perhaps once, twice, or oftener 'removed'. Of course, animals in the relation of first cousins must be classed as nearer than second cousins, and so on. But, if we accept this principle, and are able to trace relationship, it may not lead to the same results as we should reach by simply relying upon the present * quantity of resemblance ', unless we understand this in a very particular way. For the most obvious features of an animal may have been recently acquired, as often happens with those characters which adapt an animal to its habits of life, as the wings of a bat, or the fish-like shape of a dolphin; or as in cases of 'mimicry'. Some butterflies, snakes, etc., have grown to resemble closely, in a superficial way, other butterflies and snakes, from which a stricter investigation widely separates DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 313 them ; and this superficial resemblance is probably a recent acquisition, for the sake of protection : the imitated butterflies being nauseous, and the imitated snakes poisonous. On the other hand, ancient and important traits of structure may, in some species, have dwindled into inconspicuous survivals or be still found only in the embryo ; so that only great know- ledge and sagacity can identify them ; yet upon ancient traits, though hidden, classification depends. The seal seems nearer allied to the porpoise than to the tiger, the shrew nearer to the mouse than to the hedgehog ; and the Tasmanian hyaena, or the Tasmanian devil, looks more like a true hysena, or a badger, than like a kangaroo ; yet the seal is nearer akin to the tiger, the shrew to the hedgehog, and the Tasmanian carnivores are marsupial, like the kangaroo. To overcome this difficulty we must understand the resemblance upon which classification is based to include resemblance of Causation, that is, the fact itself of descent from common ancestors. In the case of organic beings, all other rules of classification are subordinate to one : trace the genealogy of every form. By this rule, however, we get a definite meaning for the phrase 'important or fundamental attribute' as determining organic classes; namely, most ancient, or 'best serving to indicate community of origin.' Grades of classification will be determined by such fundamental characters, and may cor- respond approximately to the more general types (now mostly extinct) from which existing animals have descended. In the second place, by the hypothesis of development the fixity of species is discredited. The lowest grade of a classifi- cation is made up not of well-defined types unchanging from age to age, but of temporary species, often connected by uncertain and indistinct varieties : some of which may, in turn, if the conditions of their existence alter, undergo such changes as to produce new species. Hence, again, the notion that Kinds exist in organic nature must be greatly modified. During a given period of a few thousand years, Kinds may be recognised, because, under such conditions as now Drevail in 314 LOGIC : DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE the world, that period of time is insufficient to bring about great changes. But, if it be true that lions, tigers, and leopards have had a common ancestor, from whose type they have gradually diverged, it is plain that their present distinctness results only from the death of intermediate specimens and the destruction of intermediate varieties. Could we, by the evidence of fossils, restore all the ranks of the great proces- sions that have descended from the common ancestor, we should find nowhere a greater difference than between offspring and parents ; and the appearance of Kinds existing in nature, which is so striking in a museum or zoological garden, would entirely vanish. A classification, then, as formerly observed, represents a cross-section of nature as developing in time : could we begin at the beginning and follow this development down the course of time, we should find no classes, but an ever-moving, chang- ing, spreading, branching continuum. It may be represented thus : Suppose an animal (or plant) A, extending over a certain geographical area, subject to different influences and conditions ADHK ADHL ACliM of climate, food, hill and plain, wood and prairie, enemies and rivals, and undergoing modifications here and there in adapta- tion to the varying conditions of life : then varieties appear. These varieties, diverging more and more, become distinct Species (AB, AC, AD, AX). Some of these Species, the more widely diffused, again produce varieties ; which, in turn, become DIVISION AND CLASSIFICATION 315 Species (ABE, ABF, ADG, ADH). From these again, arise, ABFI, ABFJ, ADHK, ADHL, ADHM. Then ABE, ABF, and ADH are Genera (ADG being extinct) ; and the earlier types represent Families and Orders. If in this age a classifier appears, he finds seven living Species, which can be grouped into four Genera (ABE, ABF, AC, ADH), and these again into three Families (AB, AC, AD), all forming one Order. If the fossils of ADG and AX can be found, he has two more Species, one more Genus (ADG), and one more Family (AX). For AC, which has persisted un- changed, and AX, which has become extinct, are both of them Families, each represented by only one Species. But now suppose that he could find a fossil specimen of every generation (hundreds of thousands of generations), from ABFI, etc., up to A ; then, as each generation would only differ from the preceding as offspring from parents, he would be unable at any point to distinguish a Species ; at most, he would observe a slightly marked variety. ABFI and ABFJ would grow more and more alike, until they became indistin- guishable in ABF ; ABF and ABE would merge into AB ; AB, AC, AD and AX would merge into A. Hence, the appearance of Species is due to our taking cross-sections of time, or comparing forms that belong to periods remote from one another (like AX, ADG, and ADHK, or AD, ADH and ADHK), and this appearance of Species depends upon the destruction of ancestral intermediate forms. In the third place, the hypothesis of development modifies the logical character of classification : it no longer consists in a direct induction of co-existent characters, but is largely a deduction of these from the characters of earlier forms, together with the conditions of variation ; in other words, the definition of a species must, with the progress of science, cease to be a mere empirical law of co-existence and become a derivative law of Causation. But, after all, this was already implied in the position that causation is the fundamental principle of the explanation of concrete things ; and, accord- 3i 6 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ingly, the derivative character of species or kinds extends beyond organic nature. 9. The classification of inorganic bodies also depends on causation. There is the physical classification into Solids, Liquids, and Gases. But these states of matter are dependent on temperature ; at least, it is known that many bodies may, at different temperatures, exist in ail three states. They cannot therefore be defined as solid, liquid, or gaseous absolutely, but only within certain degrees of temperature, and therefore as dependent upon causation. Similarly, the geological classification of bodies, according to relative anti- quity (primary, secondary, tertiary, with their subdivisions), and mode of formation (igneous and aqueous), rests upon causation ; and so does the chemical classification of com- pound bodies according to the elements that enter into them in definite proportions. Hence, only the classification of the elements themselves (amongst concrete things), at present, depends largely upon empirical Co-existence. If the elements remain irresolvable into anything simpler, the definitions of the co-existent characters that distinguish .them must be reckoned amongst the ultimate Uniformities of Nature. But if a definite theory of their origin both generally and severally, whether out of ether vortices or what-not, shall ever gain acceptance, similarity of genesis or causation will naturally be the leading consideration in classifying the chemical elements. In fact, the ultimate explanation of nature is always causation ; or, in other words, the Law of Causation is the backbone of the system of Experience. CHAPTER XXII NOMENCLATURE, DEFINITION, PREDICABLES i. Precision of thought needs precision of language, not only for recording such thought and for communicating it to others, the two uses most frequently insisted upon, but even for forming general or abstract ideas. It is true that we can often remember with great vividness persons, things, landscapes, changes and actions of persons or things, without the aid of language (though words are often mixed with such trains of imagery), and thus may form judgments and inferences in par- ticular cases ; but for general notions, judgments and inferences not merely about this or that man, Bismarck or Garibaldi, but about all men or all Germans, we need something besides the few images we can form of them from observation or from pictures. Even in those cases where we may possess generic images, say, of * horse ' or ' cat ' (that is, images formed, like composite photographs, by a coalescence of the images of all the horses or cats we have seen, so that their common properties stand out and their differences frustrate and cancel one another), these are useless for precise thought ; for the generic image will not correspond with the general appearance of horse or cat, unless we have had proportional experience of all varieties and have been impartially interested in all ; and, besides, what we want for general thought is not a generic image of the appear- ance of things, though it were much more definite and fairly representative than such images ever are, but a general repre- sentation of their important characters ; which may be con- nected with internal organs, such as none but an anatomist 318 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ever sees. We require a symbol connected wiih the general character of a thing, or quality, or process, as scientifically determined, whose representative truth may be trusted in ordinary cases, or may be verified whenever doubt arises. Such symbols are for most purposes provided by language ; Mathematics and Chemistry have their own symbols. 2. First, then, there should be " a name for every important meaning " : (a) A Nomenclature, or system of the names of all classes of objects, adapted to the use of each science. Thus, in Geology there are names for classes of rocks and strata, in Chemistry for the elements and their compounds, in Zoology and Botany for the varieties and species of animals and plants, their genera, families and orders. To have such names, however, is not the whole aim in forming a scientific language, it is desirable that they should be systematically significant, and even elegant. Names, like other instruments, ought to be efficient, and the efficiency of names consists in conveying the most meaning with the least effort. In Botany and Zoology this result is obtained by giving to each species a composite name which includes that of the genus to which it belongs. Thus the species of Felidae given in chap. xvii. 7, are called Felis leo (lion), Felis tigris (tiger), Felis leopardus (leopard), Felis concolor (puma), Felis lyncus (European lynx), Felis catus (wild cat). To take another illustration from the nomenclature of Butterflies : Vanessa Atalanta (red admiral), Vanessa lo (peacock), Vanessa poly- cloros (large tortoise-shell), Vanessa urticcz (small tortoise-shell), Vanessa Antiopa (Camberwell beauty), etc. In Chemistry, again, the nomenclature is extremely efficient. Names of the simpler compounds are formed by combining the names of the elements that enter into them ; as Hydrogen Chloride, Hydrogen Sulphide, Carbon Dioxide ; and these can be given still more briefly and efficiently in symbols, as HC1, H 2 S, CO,. The symbolic letters are usually initials of the names of the elements : as C = Carbon, S = Sulphur ; sometimes of the Latin name, when the common name is English, as Fe= Iron. Each NOMENCLATURE 319 letter represents a fixed quantity of the element for which it stands, viz., the atomic weight. The number written below a symbol on the right-hand side shows how many atoms of the element denoted enter into a molecule of the compound. (b) A Terminology is next required, in order to describe and define the things that constitute the classes designated by the nomenclature, and to describe and explain their actions. (i) A name for every integral part of an object, as head, limb, vertebra, heart, nerve, tendon ; stalk, leaf, corolla, stamen, pistil ; plinth, frieze, etc. (ii) A name for every metaphysical part of an object (that is, for every abstract quality of it, or for a quality considered apart from the rest that constitute it), and for their degrees and modes : as extension, figure, solidity, weight ; rough, smooth, elastic, friable ; the various colours, red, blue, yellow, in all their shades and combinations ; and so with- sounds, smells, tastes, temperatures. The terms of Geometry are employed to describe the modes of figure, as angular, curved, square, elliptical ; and the terms of Arithmetic to express the degrees of weight, elasticity, tem- perature, pitch of sound. When other means fail, qualities are suggested by the names of things which exhibit them in a salient way : figures by such terms as amphitheatre, bowl-like, pear-shaped, egg-shaped ; colours by lias-blue, sky-blue, gentian-blue, peacock-blue ; and similarly sounds, smells and tastes. It is also important to express by short terms complex qualities, as harmony, fragrance, organisation, sex, symmetry, stratification. (iii) In the explanation of Nature we require further suitable names for processes and activities : as deduction, conversion, verification, addition, integration, causation, tendency, momen- tum, gravitation, aberration, refraction, conduction, affinity, combination, germination, respiration, attention, association, development. There may be sometimes a difficulty in distinguishing the terms which stand for qualities from those that express activities, since all qualities imply activities. Weight for 320 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE example, implies gravitation ; and the quality heat is also a kind of motion. But the distinction aimed at lies between a quality as perceived by means of an effect upon our senses (as weight is resistance to our effort in lifting ; heat, a sensation when we approach fire), and that property of a body which is conceived to account for its energy (as gravitation that brings a body to the ground, or physical heat that expands an iron bar or works an engine). The former class of words, expressing qualities, are chiefly used in description : the latter class, expressing activities, are chiefly needed in explanation. They correspond respectively, like classification and explanation, with the static and dynamic aspects of Nature The terms of ordinary language fall into the same classes as those of science : they stand for things, classes of things, parts, or qualities, or activities of things ; but they are far less precise in their signification. As long as popular thought is vague its language must be vague; nor is it desirable too strictly to correct the language whilst the thought is incorrigible. Much of the effect of poetry and eloquence depends upon the elas- ticity and indirect suggestiveness of common terms. Even in reasoning upon some subjects, it is a mistake to aim at an unattainable precision. It is better to be vaguely right than exactly wrong. In the criticism of manners, of fine art, or of literature, in politics, religion and moral philosophy, what we are anxious to say is often far from clear to ourselves ; and it is better to indicate our meaning approximately, or as we feel about it, than to convey a false meaning, or to lose the warmth and colour that are the life of such reflections. It is hard to decide whether most harm has been done by sophists who take a base advantage of the vagueness of common terms, or by honest paralogists (if I may use the word) who begin by deceiving themselves with a plausible definiteness of expres- sion, and go on to propagate their delusions amongst followers eager for systematic insight but ignorant of the limits of its possibility. 3. A Definition is necessary (if possible) for every scien- NOMENCLATURE 321 dfic name. To define a name is to give a precise statement of its meaning or connotation. The name to be defined is the subject of a proposition, whose predicate is a list of the funda- mental qualities common to the things or processes which the subject denotes, and on account of possessing which qualities this name is given to them. Thus, a curve is a line of which no part is straight. The momentum of a moving body is the product of its mass and its velocity (these being expressed in numbers of certain units). Nitrogen is a transparent colourless gas, of specific gravity 9713, not readily combining, etc. A Lion maybe defined as a monodelphian mammal, predatory, walking on its toes, of nocturnal habits, with a short rounded head and muzzle ; dental formula : Incisors 3 ~ 3 Canines ~ * , praemolars 3-3 i - * 3 " 3 molars T = 30 ; four toes on the hind and five 2-2 i - i on the fore foot, retractile claws, prickly tongue, light and muscular in build, about gj feet from muzzle to tip of tail, tawny in colour, the males maned, with a tufted tail. If any- thing answers to this description, it is called a lion ; if not, not : for this is the meaning of the name. For ordinary purposes, it may suffice to give an Incomplete Definition ; that is, a list of qualities not exhaustive, but con- taining enough to identify the things denoted by the given name ; as if we say that a lion is * a large tawny beast of prey with a tufted tail. 1 Such purposes may also be served by a Description ; which is technically, a proposition mentioning properties sufficient to distinguish the things denoted, but not the properties that enter into the definition ; as if a lion is called 'the monarch of the desert that figures in the royal standard,' or * that helps the unicorn to support the crown.' 4. The rules for testing a Definition are : I. As to its Contents (i) It must state the whole connotation of the name to be defined. 322 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE (2) It must not include any quality derivative from the con- notation. Such a quality is called a Proprium. A breach of this rule can do, indeed, no positive harm, but it is a departure from scientific economy. There is no need to state in the definition what can be derived from it ; and what- ever can be derived by causation, or by mathematical demon- stration, should be exhibited in that manner. (3) It must not mention any circumstance that is not a part of the connotation, even though it be universally found in the things denoted. Such a circumstance, if not derivable from the connotation, is called an Accident. That, for example, the Lion at present only inhabits the Old World, is (I presume) an Accident : if a species otherwise like a lion were found in Brazil, it would not be refused the name of lion on the score of locality. Whilst, however, the rules of Logic have forbidden the inclusion of Proprium or Accident in a Definition, in fact the definitions of Natural History often mention such attributes when characteristic. Indeed, defini- tions of superordinate classes Families and Orders not infrequently give qualities as generally found in the subordinate classes, and at the same time mention exceptional cases in which they do not occur. II. As to its Expression (4) A Definition must not include the very term to be defined, nor any cognate. In defining Lion we must not repeat ' lion/ nor use l leonine ' ; it would elucidate nothing. (5) It must not be put in vague language. (6) It nmst not be in a negative form, if a positive form is obtainable. We must not be content to say that a lion is l no vegetarian/ or ' no lover of daylight.' To define a curve as a line ' always changing its direction ' may be better than as * in no part straight/ 5. The process of determining a Definition is inseparable from classification. We saw that classification consists in dis- tributing things into groups according to their likenesses and differences, regarding as a class those individuals which have DEFINITION 323 most qualities in common. In doing so we must, of course, recognise the common qualities or points of likeness ; and to enumerate these is to define the name of the class. If we discover the qualities upon which a class is based by direct observation and induction, by the same method we discover the definition of its name ; and similarly if we discover the qualities of the class by the help of both observation and deduction, as in the modern classification of plants and animals. We saw also that classification is not merely the determina- tion of isolated groups of things, but a systematic arrangement of such groups in relation to one another. Hence, again, Definitions are not independent, but relative to one another ; and, of course, in the same way as classes are relative. That is to say, as a class is placed in subordination to higher or more comprehensive groups, so the definition of its name is subordinate to that of their names ; and as a class stands in contrast with co-ordinate classes (those that are in the same degree of subordination to the same higher groups), so the definition of its name is in contrast or co-ordination with the definitions of their names. Lion is subordinate to Fells, to Digitigrade, to Carnivore and so on up to Animal ; and, beyond the Animal Kingdom, to Phenomenon : it is co-ordinate with Tiger, Puma, etc. ; and more remotely it is co-ordinate with Dog, Jackal, Wolf, which come under Cam's a genus co-ordinate with Felts. The definition of Lion, therefore, is subordinate to that of Felts, and to all above it up to Phenomenon ; and is co-ordinate with that of Tiger, and with all species in the same grade. This is the ground of the old method of Definition per genus et differential*. The Genus being the next class above any Species, the differentia or Difference consists of the qualities which mark that Species in addition to those that mark the Genus, and which therefore distinguish it from all other Species of the same Genus. In the above definition of Lion, for example, all 324 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE the properties down to " light and muscular in build " are generic, that is, are possessed by the whole Genus, Felis ; and the remaining four (size, colour, tufted tail, and mane in the male) are the Difference, or specific properties, because in those points the Lion contrasts with the other Species of that Genus. Differences may be exhibited thus : Lion. SIZE : about g feet from nose to tip of tail. COLOUR : tawny. TAIL: tufted. MANE : present in the male. Tiger. About 10 feet. Warm tawny, striped with black. Tapering. Both sexes maneless. There are other differences in the shape of the skull. In defining Lion, then, it would have been enough to mention the Genus and the properties making up the Difference ; because the properties of the Genus may be found by turning to the definition of the Genus : and, on the principle of economy, whatever it is enough to do it is right to do. To define * by genus and difference,' then, is a point of elegance, when the genus is known ; but the only way of knowing it is to compare the individuals comprised in it and in co-ordinate genera, according to the methods of scientific classification. It may be added that, as the genus represents ancestral derivation, the predication of genus in a definition indicates the remote causes of the phenomena denoted by the name defined. And this way of defining corresponds with the method of double naming by genus and species : Felis leo, Felis tigris, etc.; Vanessa Ata- lanta, Vanessa Io> etc. The so-called Genetic Definition, chiefly used in Mathe- matics, is a rule for constructing that which a name denotes, in such a way as to ensure its possesssing the primary attributes connoted by the name. Thus, for a circle : Take any point and, at any constant distance from it, trace a line returning into itself. In Chemistry a genetic definition of any compound might be given in the form of directions for the requisite synthesis of elements. DEFINITION 325 6. The difficulties and limits of Definition must next be considered. The chief difficulty in the definition of scientific names consists in determining exactly the nature of the things denoted by them, as in classifying plants and animals. If organic species are free growths, continually changing, however gradually, according as circumstances give some advantage to one form over others, we may expect to find such species branching into varieties, which differ considerably from one another in some respects, though not enough to constitute distinct species. This is the case ; and, consequently, there arises some uncertainty in collecting from all the varieties those attributes which are common to the species as a whole ; and, therefore, of course, uncertainty in defining the species. The same difficulty may occur in defining a genus, on account of the extent to which some of its species differ from others, whilst having enough of the common character to deter the classifier from forming a distinct genus on their account. On the other hand the occurrence of numerous intermediate varieties may make it difficult to distinguish genera or species at all. Even the Kingdoms of plants and animals cannot be precisely discriminated : sponges and other organisms seeming to belong to one as much as to the other. Now, where there is a difficulty of classification there must be a corresponding difficulty of definition. It has been proposed in such cases to substitute a Type for a Definition ; to select some variety of a species, or species of a genus, as exhibiting its character in an eminent degree, and to regard other groups as belonging to the same species or genus, according as they agree more with this Type than with other Types representing other species or genera. But the selec- tion of one group as typical implies a recognition of its attributes as generally prevailing (though not universally) throughout the species or genus ; and to recognise these attributes and yet refuse to enumerate them in a Definition, seems to be no great gain. To enumerate the attributes of the Type as an Approximate Definition of the species or genus, true of most of 326 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE the groups constituting the species or genus, answers the same purpose, is more explicit, and can mislead no one who really attends to the exposition. An Approximate Definition is, indeed, less misleading than the indication of a Type ; for the latter method seems to imply that the group which is now typical has a greater permanence or reality than its co-ordinate groups; whereas, for aught we know, one of the outside varieties or species may even now be superseding and ex- tinguishing it. But the statement of a definition as approxi- mate, is an honest confession that both the definition and the classification are (like a provisional hypothesis) merely the best account we can give of the matter according to our present knowledge. 7. The limits of Definition are twofold : (a) A name whose meaning cannot be analysed cannot be defined. This limita- tion meets us only in dealing with the names of the meta- physical parts or simple qualities of objects under the second requisite of a Terminology. Resistance and weight, colour and its modes, many names of sounds, tastes, smells, heat and cold in fact, whatever stands for an unanalysable perception, cannot be made intelligible to any one who has not had experience of the facts denoted ; they cannot be defined, but only exemplified. A sort of genetic definition may perhaps be attempted, as if we say that colour is the special sensation of the retina, or that blue is the sensation produced by a ray of light vibrating about 700,000,000,000,000 times a second ; but such expressions can give no notion of our meaning to a blind man, or to any one who has never seen a blue object. Nor can we explain what heat is like, or the smell of tobacco, to those who have never experienced them ; nor the sound of C 128 to one who knows nothing of the musical scale. If, however, we distinguish the property of an object from the sensation it excites in us, we may define any simple pro- perty as * the power of producing the sensation ' ; the colour of a flower as the power of exciting the sensation of colour in us. DEFINITION 327 Still, this gives no information to the blind nor to the colour- blind. (b) The second limit of Definition is the impossibility of exhausting infinity, which would be necessary in order to convey the meaning of the name of any individual thing or person. For, as we saw in chap, iv., if in attempting to define a proper name we stop short of infinity, our list of qualities or properties may possibly be found in two individuals, and then it becomes the definition of a class-name or general name, however small the actual class. Hence we can only give a Description of that which a proper name denotes, enumerating enough of its properties to distinguish it from everything else as far as our knowledge goes. Abstract names may be defined by defining the correspond- ing concrete : the definition of ' human nature ' is the same as of * man.' But if the corresponding concrete be a simple sen- sation (as blue), this being indefinable, the abstract (blueness) is also indefinable. 8. The five Predicables (Species, Genus, Difference, Pro- prium, Accident) may best be discussed in connection with Classification and Definition ; and in giving an account of Classification, most of what has to be said about them has been anticipated. Their name indeed connects them with the doctrine of Propositions ; for Predicables are terms that may be predicated, classified according to their connotative relation to the Subject of a proposition (that is, according to the relation in which their connotation stands to the connotation of the Subject) : nevertheless, the significance of the relations of such predicates to a subject is derivative from the general doctrine of classification. For example, in the proposition * X is Y,' Y must be one of the five sorts of Predicables in relation to X ; but of what sort, depends upon what X (the subject) is, or means. The subject of the proposition must be either a Definition, or a general Connotative Name, or a Singular Name. If X is a Definition, Y must be a Species ; for nothing but a 328 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE general name can be predicated of a Definition : and, strictly speaking, it is only in relation to a Definition (as subject) that Species can be a predicable ; when it is called Species predica- If X is a Connotative Name, it is itself a Species (Species subjicibilis) ; and the place of the subject of a proposition is the usual one for Species. The predicate, Y, may then be related to the Species in three different ways. First, it may be a Definition, exactly equivalent to the Species ; in fact, nothing else than the Species in an explicit form, the analysis of its connotation ; so that it seems most reasonable to regard this as a second form of the Species predicabilis. Secondly, the pre- dicate may be, or connote, some part only of the Definition or connotation of the Species ; and then it is either Genus (2), or Difference (3). Thirdly, the predicate may connote no partvl the Definition, and then it is either derivable from it, being a Proprium (4), or not derivable from it, being an Accident (5). These points of doctrine will be expanded and illustrated in subsequent pages. If X is a Singular Name, deriving connotation from its con- stituent terms (chap. iv. 2), as ' The present Emperor of China,' it may be treated as a Species subjicibilis. Then that he is * an absolute monarch,' predicates a Genus ; because that is a genus of * Emperor of China,' a part of the Singular Name that gives it connotation. That he wears a yellow robe is a Proprium, derivable from the ceremonial of his court. That he is thirty years of age is an Accident. But if X is a Proper Name, having no connotation, Y must always be an Accident ; since there can then be no Definition of X, and therefore neither Species, Genus, Difference, nor Proprium. Hence, that * Alphonso Schultze is a man ' is an Accidental Proposition : ' man ' is not here a Species predica- bilis ; for the name might have been given to a dog or a mountain. That is what enables the proposition to convey information : it would be useless if the Proper Name implied * humanity.' PREDICABLES 329 Species is most frequently used (as in Zoology) for the class denoted by a general name ; but in Logic it is better to treat it as a general name used connotatively for the attributes pos- sessed in common by the things denoted, and on account of which they are regarded as a class : it is sometimes called the Essence ( 9). In this connotative sense, a Species is implicitly what the Definition is explicitly ; and therefore the two are always simply convertible. Thus, ' A plane triangle ' (Species) is { a figure enclosed by three straight lines ' (Defini- tion) : clearly we may equally say, * A figure enclosed by three straight lines is a plane triangle.' It is a simple identity. A Genus is also commonly viewed denotatively, as a class containing smaller classes, its species ; but in Logic it is, again, better to treat it connotatively, as a name whose definition is part of the definition of a given species. A Difference is the remainder of the definition of any species after subtracting a given genus. Hence, the Genus and Dif- ference together make up the Species ; whence the method of definition per genus et differentiam (ante, 5). It has already been mentioned, that whilst in the classifica- tory sciences (Botany and Zoology), the species is fixed at the lowest step of the classification (varieties not being reckoned as classes), and the genus is also fixed on the step next above it, in Logic these predicables are treated as movable up and down the ladder : any lower class being species in relation to any higher ; which higher class, wherever taken, thus becomes a genus. Lion may logically be regarded as a species of digitigrade, or mammal, or animal ; and then each of these is a genus as to lion : or, again, digitigrade may be regarded as a species of mammal, or mammal as a species of animal. The highest class, however, is never a species ; wherefore it is called a Summum Genus: and the lowest class is never a genus : wherefore it is called an Infima Species. Between these two any step may be either species or genus, according to the relation to other classes in which it is viewed, and is then called Subaltern. The summum genus, again, may be viewed 330 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE in relation to a given universe or suppositio (that is, any limited area of existence now the object of attention), or to the wJiole universe. If we take the animal kingdom as our suppositio, Animal is the summum genus; but if we take the whole universe, * All things ' is the summum genus. "Porphyry's tree" is used to illustrate this doctrine. It begins with a summum genus, 'Substance,' and descends by adding differences, step by step, to the infima species^ ' Man.' It also illustrates Division by Dichotomy. SUBSTANCE ^S CORPOREAL ! INCORPOREAL ANIMATE INANIMATE SENSIBLE INSENSlBLt RATIONAL I IRRATIONAL Beginning with ' Substance,' as summum genus, and adding the difference ' Corporeal,' we frame the species ' Body.' Taking 1 Body ' as the genus and adding the difference ' Animate,' we frame the species * Living Body ; ' and so on till ' Man ' is reached ; which being infima species, is only subdivisible into PREDICABLES 331 individuals. But it should be noted that the division of Man into individuals involves a change of principle : it is a division of the denotation, not an increase of the connotation as in the earlier steps. Only one side of each dichotomy is followed out : if the other side had been taken Incorporeal Substance would be ' Spirit ' ; which might be similarly subdivided. Genus and Species, then, have a double relation. In denotation the Genus includes the Species, in connotation the Species includes the Genus. Hence the doctrine that by increasing the connotation of a name you decrease its deno- tation: if, for example, to the definition of 'lion' you add * inhabiting Africa,' Asiatic lions are no longer denoted by it. On the other hand, if you use a name to denote objects that it did not formerly apply to, some of the connotation must be dropped : if, for example, the name * lion ' be used to include * pumas/ the tufted tail and mane can no longer be part of the meaning of the word ; since pumas have not these properties. This doctrine is logically or formally true, but it may not always be true in fact. It is logically true ; because wherever we add to the connotation of a name, it is possible that some things to which it formerly applied are now excluded from its denotation, though we may not know of any such things. Still, as a matter of fact, an object may be discovered to have a property previously unknown, and this property may be fundamental and co-extensive with the denotation of its name, or even more widely prevalent. The discovery that the whale is a mammal did not limit the class ' whale ' ; nor did the dis- covery that lions, dogs, wolves, etc.) walk upon their toes, affect the application of any of these names. Similarly, the extension of a name to things not previously denoted by it, may not in fact alter its definition; for the extension may be made on the very ground that the things now first denoted by it have been found to have the pro- perties enumerated in its definition, as when the name ' mammal ' was applied to whales, dolphins, etc. If, however, 'mammal' had formerly been understood to apply only to 332 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE land animals, so that its definition included (at least, popularly) the quality of * living on the land,' this part of the connotation was of course lost when the denotation came to include certain aquatic animals. A Proprium is an attribute derived from the definition: being either (a) implied in it, or deducible from it, as ' having its three angles equal to two right angles ' may be proved from the definition of a triangle ; or (b) causally dependent on it, as being c dangerous to flocks ' results from the nature of a wolf, and as * moving in an ellipse ' results from the nature of a planet in its relation to the sun. An Accident is a property accompanying the defining attri- butes without being deducible from them. The word suggests that such a property is merely ' accidental,' or there 'by chance ' ; but, of course, it only means that we do not under- stand the connection. Proprium and Accident bear the same relation to one another as Derivative and Empirical Laws : both Accidents and Empirical Laws present problems, the solution of which consists in reducing them, respectively, to .Propria and Derivative Laws. In fact, the predication of a Proprium is a Derivative Law, and the predication of an Accident is an Empirical Law. Thus the colour of animals was once regarded as an Accident for which no reason could be given ; but now the colour of animals is regarded as an effect of their nature and habits, the most frequent cause of it being the advantage of concealment; whilst in other cases, as among brightly coloured insects and snakes, the cause seems to be the advan- tage of advertising their own noxiousness. If such reasoning is sound, colour is a Proprium (and if so, it cannot logically be included in a Definition ; but it is better to be judicious than formal). If the colour of animals is a Proprium, we must recognise a distinction between Inseparable and Separable Propria, accord- ing as they do, or do not, always accompany the essence : for mankind is regarded as one species ; but each colour, white, ESSENCE 333 black or yellow, is separable from it under different climatic conditions : whilst tigers are everywhere coloured and striped in much the same way ; so that we may consider their colour- ing as inseparable, in spite of exceptional specimens black or white or clouded. The same distinction may be drawn between Accidents. 1 Inhabiting Asia ' is an Inseparable Accident of tiger, but a Separable Accident of lion. Even the occasional characteristics and occupations of individuals are sometimes called Separable Accidents of the species ; as, of Man, being colour-blind, car- pentering, or running. A Proprium in the original signification of the term ('tiiov) was peculiar to a Species, never found with any other, and was therefore convertible with the Subject ; but this restriction is no longer insisted on. 9. Any predication of a Genus, Difference or Definition, is a Verbal, Analytic, or Essential proposition : and any pre- dication of a Proprium or Accident, is a Real, Synthetic, or Accidental proposition (chap. v. 6). A Proposition is called Verbal or Analytic when the predicate is a part, or the whole, of the meaning of the subject ; and of course, the subject being species, a genus or difference is part, and a definition is the whole, of its meaning or connotation. Hence such a proposi- tion has also been called explicative. Again, a proposition is called Real or Synthetic when the predicate is no part of the meaning of the subject; and, the subject being species, a pro- prium or accident is no part of its meaning or connotation. Hence such a proposition has been called ampliative. As to Essential and Accidental, these terms are derived from the doctrine of Realism. Realists maintain that the Essence of a thing, or that which makes a thing to be what (or of what kind) it is, also makes everything else of the same kind to be what it is. The Essence, they say, is not proper to each thing or separately inherent in it, but is an * Universal ' common to all things of that kind. Some hold that the universal nature of things of any kind is an Idea existing apart 334 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE from the things in the intelligible world, a rather shy corner, invisible to mortal eye and only accessible to thought ; whence the Idea is called a nournenon : that only the Idea is truly real, and that the things (say, men, lions, bedsteads and cities) which appear to us in sense-perception, and which therefore are called phenomena, only exist by participating in, or imitating, the Idea of each kind of them. The standard of this school bears the legend Universalia ante rent. But others think that the Universal does not exist apart from particular things, but is their present Essence; gives them actuality as individual substances ; " informs " them, or is their formal cause, and thus makes them to be what they are of their kind according to the definition : the universal lion is in all lions, and is not merely similar, but identical in all ; for thus the Universal Reason thinks and energises in Nature. This school inscribes upon its banners, Universalia in re. To define anything, then, is to discover its Essence, whether transcendent or immanent ; and to predicate the definition, or any part of it (genus or difference), is to enounce, an essential proposition. But a proprium, being no part of a definition, though it always goes along with it, does not show what a thing is ; nor of course does an accident ; so that to predicate either of these is to enounce an accidental proposition. Another school of Metaphysicians denies the existence of Universal Ideas or Forms ; the real things, according to them, are individuals ; which, so far as any of them resemble one another, are regarded as forming classes : and the only Uni- versal is the class-name, which is applied universally in the same sense. Hence, they are called Nominalists. The sense in which any name is applied, is derived, they say, from a comparison of the individuals, and by abstraction of the pro- perties they have in common ; and thus the definition is formed. Universalia post rem is their motto. Some Nominalists, how- ever, hold that, though Universals do not exist in nature, they do in our minds, as Abstract Ideas or Concepts ; and that to PREDICAMENTS 335 define a term is to analyse the Concept it stands for ; whence, these philosophers are called Conceptualists. Such questions belong to Metaphysics and Psychology rather than to Logic ; and I have only given a commonplace account of a subject upon every point of which there is much difference of opinion. 10. The doctrine of the Predicaments, or Categories, is so interwoven with the history of speculation and especially of Logic that, though its vitality is exhausted, it can hardly be passed over unmentioned. The Predicaments of Aristotle are the heads of a classification of terms as possible predicates of a particular thing or individual. Hamilton (Logic : Lect. xi.) has given a classification of them ; which, if it cannot be found in Aristotle, is an aid to the memory, and may be thrown into a table thus (cf. Bain : Logic > App. C.) : Substance otffla (i) i-Quantity 7ro that is, with the suppressed qualification of including past as well as present labour ; but in the inference labour is used simplidter to mean present labour only. (2) A dicto secundum quid ad dictum secundum alterum quid. It may be urged that, since the tax on tea is uniform, there- fore all consumers contribute equally to the revenue for their enjoyment of it. But written out fairly this argument runs FALLACIES 371 thus : Since tea is taxed uniformly $d. per /., all consumers pay equally for their enjoyment of it whatever quality they use. These qualifications introduced, nobody can be deceived. (3) A dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid, also called fallacia accidentis. Thus : To take interest upon a loan is perfectly just, therefore, I do right to exact it from my own father in distress. The popular answer to this sort of blunder is that * circumstances alter cases.' We commit this error in supposing that what is true of the average is likely to be true of each case ; as if one should say : ( The offices are ready to insure my house [with thousands of others] agains fire at a rate per annum which will leave them heavy losers unless it lasts a hundred years ; so, as we are told not to take long views of life, I shall not insure.' The Fallacy of Division and Composition consists in sug- gesting, or assuming, that what is true of things severally denoted by a term is true of them taken together. That every man is mortal is generally admitted, but we cannot infer that, therefore, the human race will become extinct. That the remote prospects of the race are tragic may be plausibly argued, but not from that premise. Changing the Premises is a fallacy usually placed in this division; although, instead of disguising different meanings under similar words, it generally consists in using words or phrases ostensibly differing, as if they were equivalent : those addressed being expected to renounce their right to reduce the argument to strict forms of proof, as needless pedantry in dealing with an author so palpably straightforward. If an orator says ' Napoleon conquered Europe ; in other words, he murdered five millions of his fellow creatures ' and is allowed to go on, he may infer from the latter of these pro- positions many things which the former of them would hardly have covered This is a sort of hyperbole, and there is a corresponding meiosis, as : ' Mill admits that the Syllogism is useful ' ; when, in fact, that is Mill's contention. It may be supposed that, if a man is fool enough to be imposed upon bv 372 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE such transparent colours, it serves him right ; but this harsh judgment will not be urged by any one who knows and con- siders the weaker brethren. 9. The above classification of Fallacies is a rearrangement of the plans adopted by Whately and Mill. But Fallacies resemble other spontaneous natural growths in not submitting to precise and definite classification. The same blunders, looked at from different points of view, may seem to belong to different groups. Thus, the example given above to illustrate fallacia accidentis, 'that, since it is just to take interest, it is right to exact it from one's own father,' may also be regarded as petitio prinripn, if we consider the unconditional statement of the premise ' to take interest upon a loan is perfectly just ' ; for, surely, this is only conditionally true. Or, again, the first example given of simple ambiguity ' that whatever is written in a classical language is classical, etc.\ may, if we attend merely to the major premise, be treated as a bad generalisation, an undue extension of an inference, founded upon a simple enumeration of the first few Greek and Latin works that one happened to remember. It must also be acknowledged that genuine wild fallacies, roaming the jungle of controversy, are not so easily detected or evaded as specimens seem to be when exhibited in a Logician's collection ; where one surveys them without fear, like a child at a menagerie. To assume the succinct mode of statement that is most convenient for refutation, is not the natural habit of these things. But to give reality to his account of fallacies an author needs a large space, that he may quote no inconsider- able part of literature ancient and modern. As to the means of avoiding fallacies, a general increase of sincerity and candour amongst mankind may be freely recommended. With more honesty there would be fewer bad arguments; but there is such a thing as well-meaning inca- pacity that gets unaffectedly fogged in converting A., and regards the refractoriness of O., as more than flesh and blood can endure. Mere indulgence in figurative language, again, is FALLACIES 373 a besetting snare. "One of the fathers, in great seventy called poesy vinum damonum? says Bacon : himself too fanciful for a philosopher. Surely, to use a simile for the discovery of truth is like studying beauty in the bowl of a spoon. The study of the natural sciences trains and confirms the mind in a habit of good reasoning, which is the surest preservative against paralogism, as long as the terms in use are, like those of science, well defined ; and where they are ill defined, so that it is necessary to guard against ambiguity, a thorough training in politics or metaphysics may be useful. Logic seems to me (I must confess) to serve, to some extent, both these purposes. The conduct of business, or experience, a sufficient time being granted, is indeed the best teacher, but also the most austere and expensive. In the seventeenth century some of the greatest philosophers wrote de intellectus emen- datione ; and if their successors have given over this very practical inquiry, the cause of its abandonment is not success and satiety but despair. Perhaps the right mind is not to be made by instruction, but can only be bred : a slow, haphazard process ; and meanwhile the rogue of a sophist may count on a steady supply of dupes to amuse the tedium of many an age. FINIS. QUESTIONS The following questions are chiefly taken from public examination papers: Civil Service [S], Oxford [O], and Cambridge [C]. I. TERMS, ETC. 1. What is a Term ? Explain and illustrate the chief divisions of Terms. What is meant by the Connotation of a Term ? Illustrate. [S] 2. " The connotation and denotation of terms vary inversely." Examine this assertion, explaining carefully the limits within which it is true, if at all. [S] 3. Exemplify the false reasoning arising from the confusion of Contrary and Contradictory Terms. [S] 4. Discuss the claims of the doctrine of Terms to be included in a Logical System. Distinguish between a General and an Abstract Term [S] 5. Explain and illustrate what is meant by the Denotation and Connotation of a Term. What terms have both, and what have one only ? [S] 6. Distinguish between Abstract and Concrete Names. To which of these classes belong (a) adjectives, (b) names of states of consciousness? Are any abstract names connotative ? [S] 7. Distinguish between (a) Proper and Singular Terms, (b] Negative and Privative, (c) Absolute and Relative. Illustrate. 376 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 8. What connection is there between the Connotation and the Relativity of Names ? 9. Examine the logical relations between the following pairs of terms : (a) happy and happiness ; (b) happy and unhappy; (c) 'the juryman' and 'the jury'; (d) parent and offspring. Explain the technical words used in your answer. [C] 10. Distinguish between name; part of speech ; term: and illustrate by reference to the following use, useful, usefully. [C] xi. Describe the nature of Collective terms; examine in par- ticular any difficulties in distinguishing between these and general or abstract terms. [C] 12. Distinguish between positive, negative, and privative names. Of what kind are the following, and why parallel, alien, idle, unhappy ? What ambiguity is there in the use of such a term as " not- white " ? [C] II. PROPOSITIONS AND IMMEDIATE INFERENCE. 13. What is meant by (i) the Conversion, and (2) the Contra- position of a proposition ? Apply these processes, as far as admissible, to the following : (a) All invertebrates have cold blood. (b) Some cold-blooded animals are not invertebrates. (c) No wingless birds are songsters. (d) Some winged birds are not songsters. What can you infer from (a) and (b) jointly, and what from (c) and (O jointly? [S] 14 "The author actually supposes that, because Professor Fawcett denies that all wealth is money, he denies that all money is wealth." Analyse the differences of opinion implied in the above passage. [S] 15. Take any universal affirmative proposition ; convert it by obversion (contraposition) ; attach the negative particle QUESTIONS 377 to the predicate, and again convert. Interpret the result exactly, and say whether it is or is not equivalent to the original proposition. [S] 1 6. What information about the term "solid body" can we derive from the proposition, " No bodies which are not solids are crystals " ? [S] 17. Discuss the proposal to treat all propositions as affirma- tive. 1 8. Convert the proposition "A is probably B." What in- formation does the proposition give us concerning B? [S] 19. Show in how many ways you can deny the following asser- tions : All cathedral towns are all cities; Canterbury is the Metropolitan see. [S] 20. Explain the nature of a hypothetical (or conditional) pro- position. What do you consider the radical difference between it and a categorical ? [S] 21. What is the function of the copula ? In what different manners has it been treated ? [S] 22. Convert " A killed C unjustly": "All Knowledge is pro- bably useful"; "The exception proves the rule"; " Birds of a feather flock together." [S] 23. What is modality ? How are modals treated by (a) formal logic and (b) by the theory of induction ? [S] 24. What is the subject of an impersonal proposition ? Give reasons for your answer. [S] 25. Is the categorical proposition sufficiently described as referring a thing or things to a class ? [S] 26. Enumerate the cases in which the truth or falsity of one proposition may be formally inferred from the truth or falsity of another. Illustrate these cases, and give to each its technical name. [S] 27. Illustrate the relation of Immediate Inferences to the Laws of Thought. 28. Explain what is meant by (a) Symbolic Logic; () the Logic of Relatives. Describe some method of 378 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE representing propositions by means of diagrams ; and indicate how far any particular theory of the import of propositions is involved in such representation. [S] 29. Explain the exact nature of the relation between two Contradictory propositions ; and define Conversion by Contraposition, determining what kind of propositions admit of such conversion. Give the contradictory and the contrapositive of each of the following propositions : (a) All equilateral triangles are equiangular ; (b) No vertebrate animal has jaws opening sideways ; (c) Wherever A and B are both present, either C or D is also present. [S] 30. Define Obversion and Inversion, and apply these processes also to the above three propositions. 31. Propositions can be understood either in extension or in intension. Explain this, and discuss the relative value of the two interpretations. [S] 32. Distinguish between real and verbal propositions; and explain the importance of the distinction. 33. Illustrate the process called ' change of Relation.' III. SYLLOGISM AND MEDIATE INFERENCE 34. What is a Syllogism? Find, without reference to the mnemonic verses, in what different ways it is possible to prove syllogistically the conclusion No S is P ; arid show the equivalence between these different ways. (S] 35. From what points of view can the syllogism be regarded (i) as being, (2) as not being, * pctitio principal [S] 36. What are the figures of syllogism? For what kind of arguments are they severally adapted ? [S] 37. What is meant by Mood and Figure? How can the validity of a Mood be tested ? Should there be four Figures or three ? [S] QUESTIONS 379 38. Construct syllogisms in Camenes, Datisi and Baroco, and reduce them to the corresponding moods of the first figure. 39. Explain the meaning of "ostensive" and "indirect" Re- duction. Show that any Mood of the second Figure may be reduced in either way. 40. Show that A cannot be proved except in the First Figure. Express the following reasoning in as many syllogistic figures as you can : Some theorists cannot be trusted, for they are unwise. [S] 41. Discuss the possibility of reducing the argument a fortiori to the syllogistic form. [S] 42. Can a false conclusion be reached through true premises, or a true conclusion through false premises ? Give reasons for your answer. [S] 43. Can we under any circumstances infer a relation between X and Z from the premises Some Y's are X's Some Y's are Z's? [S] 44. Take an apparent syllogism subject to the fallacy of negative premises, and inquire whether you can correct the reasoning by converting one or both of the premises into the affirmative form. [S] 45. Enumerate the faults to which a syllogism is liable, giving instances of each. [S] 46. State any Enthymeme, and expand it into (i) a Syllogism, (2) an Epicheirema, (3) a Sorites ; and give in each case the technical name of the Mood or Order that results. 47. State any Disjunctive Syllogism, and change it (i) into a Hypothetical, (2) into a Categorical; and discuss the loss or gain, in cogency or significance involved in this process. 48. Can the Syllogism be treated as merely a consequence of the "Laws of Thought"? If not, why not; and what else does it imply ? 3 8o LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 49. Prove that with three given propositions (of the forms A., E., I., O.) it is never possible to construct more than one valid syllogism. [C] 50. Distinguish between a Constructive and a Destructive Hypothetical Syllogism; and show how one may be reduced to the other. [C] IV. INDUCTION, ETC. 51. What constitutes a Valid Induction ? Distinguish it from a legitimate hypothesis. [S] 52. Is it possible to form true universal propositions about facts if we have not actually observed all the individuals designated by the subject of the proposition? If so how? [S] 53. "Perfect induction is demonstrative and syllogistic ; imper- fect induction is neither." Explain the difference between perfect and imperfect induction, and examine the truth of this assertion. [S] 54. Why is it that one should not regard night as the cause, nor even as a universal condition of day? Explain " cause " and condition. [S] 55. What do you understand by an experiment? Can you say how many experiments are required to establish (i) a fact, (2) a law of nature ? 56. How would you define antecedent, cause, effect, consequent? [S] 57. England is the richest country in the world, and has a gold currency. Russia and India, in proportion to population, are poor countries and have little or no gold currency. How far are such kind of facts logically sufficient to prove that a gold currency is the cause of a nation's wealth ? [S] 58. A man having been shot through the heart immediately falls dead. Investigate the logical value of such a fact QUESTIONS 381 as proving that all men shot through the heart will fall dead. [S] 59. Explain the process of induction called the Method of Difference, and give some new instances of its applica- tion. How is it related to the Method of Concomitant Variations ? What is the Major Premise implied in all these methods ? [S] 60. Explain the logical cogency of experiments in the search for physical causes. [S] 6 1. If the effects of A B C D are fully expressed by a b c d, and those of B C D by b c d, what inductive inference can be drawn and on what principle? State the canon according to which it is drawn. [S] 62. Compare the advantage of observation and experiment as means of gaining data for Reasoning. [S] 63. Compare the cogency of different Inductive Methods, showing the kind of evidence each requires, and the principle on which it is based. [S] 64. Compare the Canons of Agreement and Difference (i) as to the difficulty of fitting them with actual " Instances," and (2) as to their conclusiveness. 65. Describe what is meant by residual phenomena, and estimate their value in inductive science. [S] 66. What is the argument from Analogy? How does it differ from (a) Induction, (b) Metaphorical argument ? [S] 67. What are the various senses in which the word Analogy has been used? Distinguish, giving instances, between good and bad analogies. [S] 68. How do you distinguish between what Mill calls the Geometrical, Physical and Historical Methods ? 69. What is meant by a doctrine being unverifiable? If a conclusion reached by deduction does not agree with the facts, where must we look for error ? 70. There are certain cases in which failure of verification is fatal to a theory, and other cases in which it is of 382 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE comparatively little cogency. How would you distin- guish between these classes of cases ? [S] 71. Taking the " evolution," or any other proposed hypothesis, how should one proceed (a) to show whether it satisfies the conditions of a legitimate hypothesis sufficiently to entitle it to investigation, and (b) to test it with a view to its acceptance or rejection as a truth of science ? [S] 72. What do you mean by saying that "a phenomenon has been satisfactorily explained " ? 73. Explain and illustrate the Historical Method of Sociological inquiry. [S] 74. What is the relation of the theory of Probability to Logic ? [S] 75. Explain and discuss the doctrine that Induction is based upon the Theory of Probability. [S] 76. Explain the nature and use of Classification, the means to, and tests of, its successful performance. [S] 77. What is Definition and what is its use? Mention various difficulties that occur in the process, and show how they are to be met. [S] 78. Propose rules for a good Division and a good Definition and exemplify the breach of them. [S] 79. Examine the validity of the idea of Real Kinds. [O] 80. What kind of words are indefinable, and why ? When do we define by negation and by example ? [S] 8 1. Distinguish between the province and aims of classification and (logical) division. Illustrate. [S] 82. What is an infima species or species sperialissima ? Com- pare the use of the terms genus and species in Logic with that which is common in speaking of animals or plants. [S] 83. How far does the formation of Definitions and Classifica- tions constitute the end of Science ? [S] 84. Examine the methodological relations between Definition, Classification and Nomenclature. [S] 85. Give instances of " Differentia," " Property," " Inseparable QUESTIONS 383 Accident"; and examine, with reference to your instances, how far it is possible to distinguish them. [S] V. MISCELLANEOUS. 86. " People can reason without the help of Logic." Why is this not a sufficient objection to the study ? In your answer show distinctly why Logic should be studied. [S] 87. What is the meaning of the assertion that Logic is con- cerned with the form, and not with the matter, of thought ? [S] 88. "Neither by deductive nor inductive reasoning can we add a title to our implicit knowledge." (Jevons.) Ex- plain and criticise. [S] 89. What is the logical foundation of the indirect method or reductio ad absurdum ? Is it applicable to non-mathe- matical subjects ? [S] 90. On what grounds do we believe in the reality of a historical event? [S] 91. "Facts are familiar theories." Explain and discuss this. [O] 92. Wherein lies the difficulty of proving a negative ? [O] 93. Can any limits be assigned to the possible unification of the sciences ? [O] 94. Are the results of inductive inference necessarily certain ? [O] 95. The method of deductive science is hypothetical. Ex- plain and discuss. [O] 96. " The uniformity of Nature can never be more than a working hypothesis." Explain and criticise. 97. " Without speculation there is no good and original ob- servation." Why ? f O] 98. Can the provinces of induction and deduction be kept separate ? [O] 384 LOGIC: DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 99. How far is the relation of logical dependence identical with that of causation ? [O] 100. State in syllogistic form (mood and figure) the following arguments : (a) As polygamy is in many countries legal, we may infer the variability of the moral standard. (b) If gold is wealth, to export it diminishes the national resources. (c) If all good people are happy, unhappiness is an indication of vice. (d) One may be sure of the benefits of inuring young children to cold, from the strength exhibited by all men and women thus treated in infancy, (e) Where there is no law, there is no injustice. (/) " Dissimulation is but a faint kind of policy or wisdom ; for it asketh a strong wit and a strong heart to know when to tell the truth, and to do it ; therefore it is the weaker sort of politicians that are the greatest dissemblers." (Bacon.) (g) Money being a barren product, it is contrary to nature to make it reproduce itself. Usury, therefore, is unnatural, and, being unnatural, is unjustifiable. (h) The study of mathematics is essential to a com- plete course of education, because it induces a habit of close and regular reasoning. [S] 101. Explain and illustrate the following terms: Subalternans, Vera Causa, Plurality of Causes, Law of Nature, Empirical Law, Summum Genus, Predicament, Arbor Porphyriana, Axiom, Universe of discourse (suppositio\ Antinomy, Dilemma, Realism, Dichotomy. 102. Is there any distinction and, if so, what, between a com- plete Description and an Explanation ? [C] 103. On what principles have Fallacies been classified? To what extent do you think a satisfactory classification of Fallacies possible ? [C] 104. Examine how far conceptions of Persistence and of QUESTIONS 385 Invariable Concomitance of Properties are involved in the methodological application of the conception of Cause. Inquire whether the two following propositions can be reconciled with one another : (a) The same conjunc- tion of antecedents is invariably followed by the same consequent ; (fr) We never find the same concurrence of phenomena a second time. [C] 105. Using the term Logic in a wide sense so as to include Methodology, inquire how far a Logic of Observation is possible, and show in what it will consist. [C] 1 06. What is Proof? Explain and discuss the following dicta: (a) Qui nimium probat, nihil probat : (b) A bad proof is worse than no proof ; (c) The exception proves the rule ; (d) Negatives cannot be proved. [C] 107. Examine how far the rules of immediate and syllogistic inference are modified by differences of interpretation of the categorical proposition in respect to the existence of the subject. [S] 108. "An effect is but the sum of all the partial causes, the concurrence of which constitutes its existence." " The cause of an event is its invariable and unconditional antecedent." Explain and compare these two theories of causation. Does either alone exhaust the scientific conception of cause ? [S] 109. Under what logical conditions are statistical inferences authorised, and what is the nature of their conclusions ? [S] no. Distinguish between Psychology, Metaphysics, and Logic; and discuss briefly their mutual relations. [S] in. All processes of inference in which the ultimate premises are particular cases are equally induction. Induction is an inverse deduction. Explain and contrast these two theories of the relation of induction to deduction. [S] 386 LOGIC : DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE 112. What are the Fallacies specially incident to Induction? or to the application of the theory of Probabilities? [S] 113. What is meant by the personal error (or personal equation) in observation ? Discuss its importance in different branches of knowledge. [S] 114. Define and illustrate: Paralogism, ignoratio elenchi, fallacia actidentis, argumentum ad verecundiam^ illicit process, undistributed middle. 115. State the three fundamental laws of thought, explain their meaning, and consider how far they are in- dependent of each other ? [L] 1 1 6. Enumerate the " Heads of Predicables" and define their meaning. Discuss their logical importance. [L] 117. Upon what grounds has it been asserted that the conclusion of a syllogism is drawn, not from, but according to, the major premise ? Are they valid ? [L] 118. " Experiment is always preferable to observation." Why is this ? Explain from the example of any science how observation and experiment supplement each other. M 119. What is a hypothesis? Distinguish between a working hypothesis and an established hypothesis, so as to bring out the conditions on which the latter depends. [L] 120. Explain how good scientific nomenclature and termi- nology are connected with the purposes of good classification. [Ll ALEXANDER MORING LIMITED THE DE LA MORE PRESS 32 GEORGE ST. HANOVER SO,. LONDON W UNIVERSITY' OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW AN INITIAL FINE OF 25 CENTS WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $1.OO ON THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE. OGT 25 1S40 LIBRARY USE LD 21-100m-12, '43 (8796s) VC 36573 189173