OF THE 
 
 UNIVERSITY 
 
 OF w 
 
THE NEO-PLATONISTS. 
 
Uontom: C. J. CLAY and SONS, 
 
 CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, 
 
 AVE MARIA LANE. 
 
 ffilaggofo: 50, WELLINGTON STREET. 
 
 Hftp?ig: F. A. BROCKHAUS. 
 
 £eUJ Jfork: THE MAGMILLAN COMPANY. 
 
 Bombau: E. SEYMOUR HALE. 
 
THE NEO-PLATONISTS: 
 
 A STUDY IN 
 THE HISTORY OF HELLENISM. 
 
 BY 
 
 THOMAS WHITTAKER, 
 
 AUTHOR OF 'ESSAYS AND NOTICES, PHILOSOPHICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL.' 
 
 CAMBRIDGE: 
 AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 
 
 1901 
 
 [All Rights reserved.] 
 
W-5 
 
 Cambrrtigr : 
 
 PRINTED BY J. AND C. F. CLAY, 
 AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 
 
CONTENTS. 
 
 Introduction 
 
 PAGE 
 
 vii 
 
 CHAPTER I. 
 
 Graeco-Roman Civilisation in its Political Development 
 
 CHAPTER II. 
 
 The Stages of Greek Philosophy 
 
 CHAPTER III. 
 
 Religious Developments in Later Antiquity 
 
 CHAPTER IV. 
 
 Plotinus and his Nearest Predecessors 
 
 18 
 
 27 
 
 CHAPTER V. 
 
 The Phi 
 
 losophical System of Plotinus 
 
 41 
 
 1. 
 
 Psychology 
 
 . 44 
 
 2. 
 
 Metaphysics ...... 
 
 . 54 
 
 3. 
 
 Cosmology and Theodicy .... 
 
 . 71 
 
 4. 
 
 Aesthetics ....... 
 
 . 88 
 
 5. 
 
 Ethics 
 
 CHAPTER VI. 
 
 . 92 
 
 
 99 
 
 S9851 
 
VI CONTENTS 
 
 CHAPTER VII. 
 
 PAGE 
 
 The Diffusion of Neo-Platonism 108 
 
 1. Porphyry 108 
 
 2. Iarnblichus .122 
 
 3. The School of Iarnblichus 132 
 
 CHAPTER VIII. 
 
 The Polemic against Christianity 137 
 
 CHAPTER IX. 
 
 The Athenian School 156 
 
 1. The Academy becomes Neo-Platonic . . . .156 
 
 2. Proclus 158 
 
 3. The End of the Platonic Succession . . . .181 
 
 CHAPTER X. 
 
 The Influence of Neo-Platonism 186 
 
 CHAPTER XI. 
 
 Conclusion 206 
 
 APPENDIX. 
 
 I. The Communism of Plato 217 
 
 II. The Gnostics 220 
 
 III. Iamblichus and Proclus on Mathematical Science . 224 
 
 Index of Names -2-2U 
 
INTRODUCTION. 
 
 ^T^HAT the history of ancient culture effectively ends with 
 -*- the second century of the Christian era is an impression 
 not infrequently derived from histories of literature and even 
 of philosophy. The period that still remains of antiquity is 
 obviously on its practical side a period of dissolution, in which 
 every effort is required to maintain the fabric of the Roman 
 State against its external enemies. And, spiritually, a new 
 religious current is evidently beginning to gain the mastery ; 
 so that, with the knowledge we have of what followed, we can 
 already see in the third century the break-up of the older form 
 of inner as well as of outer life. In the second century too 
 appeared the last writers who are usually thought of as classical. 
 The end of the Stoical philosophy as a living system coincides 
 with the death of Marcus Aurelius. And with Stoicism, it 
 is often thought, philosophy ceased to have an independent 
 life. It definitely entered the service of polytheism. In its 
 struggle with Christianity it appropriated Oriental superstitions. 
 It lost its scientific character in devotion to the practice of 
 magic. It became a mystical theology instead of a pursuit 
 of reasoned truth. The structure of ancient culture, like the 
 fabric of the Empire, was in process of decay at once in form 
 and content. In its permeation by foreign elements, it already 
 manifests a transition to the new type that was to supersede it. 
 An argument for this view might be found in a certain 
 niodernness" which has often been noted in the later classical 
 literature. Since the ancient type was dissolved in the end 
 
Vlll INTRODUCTION 
 
 to make way for the modern, we might attribute the early 
 appearance of modern characteristics to the new growth 
 accompanying incipient dissolution. The general falling-off in 
 literary quality during the late period we should ascribe to 
 decay ; the wider and more consciously critical outlook on life, 
 which we call modern, to the movement of the world into its 
 changed path. Thus there would be a perfectly continuous 
 process from the old civilisation to the new. On the other 
 hand, we may hold that the " modernness " of the late classical 
 period does not indicate the beginning of the intermediate 
 phase of culture, but is a direct approximation to the modern 
 type, due to the existence of a long intellectual tradition of a 
 similar kind. If the latter view be taken, then we must regard 
 the dissolution of the ancient world as proceeding, not by a 
 penetration of new elements into the older form of culture so 
 as to change the type, but indirectly through the conquest 
 of the practical world by a new power; so that, while ancient 
 culture was organically continuous as long as it lasted, it finally 
 came to an end as an organism. The new way into which the 
 world had passed was directed by a new religion, and this 
 appropriated in its own manner the old form of culture, bringing 
 it under the law of its peculiar type. Thus one form was 
 substituted for another, but the first did not spontaneously 
 pass into the second. There was no absolute break in history ; 
 for the ancient system of education remained, though in a 
 reduced form, and passed by continuous transition into another ; 
 but the directing power was changed. The kind of " modern " 
 character the ancient culture assumed in the end was thus an 
 anticipation of a much later period, not a genuine phase of 
 transition. In confirmation of the latter view, it might be 
 pointed out that the culture of the intermediate period, when 
 it assumed at length its appropriate form, had decidedly less 
 of the specifically modern character than even that of early 
 antiquity with all its remoteness. 
 
 Be this as it may in pure literature, it is certain that 
 
INTRODUCTION IX 
 
 the latest phase of ancient philosophy had all the marks of an 
 intrinsic development. All its characteristic positions can be 
 traced to their origin in earlier Greek systems. Affinities can 
 undoubtedly be found in it with Oriental thought, more parti- 
 cularly with that of India; but with this no direct contact can be 
 shown. In its distinctive modes of thought, it was wholly 
 Hellenic. So far as it was " syncretistic," it was as philosophy 
 of religion, not as pure philosophy. On this side, it was an 
 attempt to bring the various national cults of the Roman 
 Empire into union under the hegemony of a philosophical 
 conception. As philosophy, it was indeed " eclectic," but the 
 eclecticism was under the direction of an original effort of specu- 
 lative thought, and was exercised entirely within the Hellenic 
 tradition. And, in distinction from pure literature, philosophy 
 made its decisive advance after practical dissolution had set in. 
 It was not until the middle of the third century that the 
 metaphysical genius of Plotinus brought to a common point 
 the Platonising movement of revival which was already going 
 on before the Christian era. The system founded by Plotinus, 
 and known distinctively as " Neo-Platonism," was that which 
 alone gave unity to all that remained of Greek culture during 
 the period of its survival as such. Neo-Platonism became, for 
 three centuries, the one philosophy of the Graeco- Roman world. 
 It preserved the ancient type of thought from admixture with 
 alien elements ; and, though defeated in the struggle to give 
 direction to the next great period of human history, it had a 
 powerful influence on the antagonist system, which, growing 
 up in an intellectual atmosphere pervaded by its modes of 
 thought, incorporated much of its distinctive teaching. 
 
 The persistence of philosophy as the last living force of the 
 ancient world might have been predicted. Philosophic thought 
 in antiquity was the vital centre of liberal education as it has 
 never been for the modern world. There were of course those 
 who disparaged it in contrast with empirical practice or with 
 rhetorical ability, but, for all that, it had the direction of 
 
X INTRODUCTION 
 
 practical thought so far as there was general direction at all. 
 The dissolution by which the ancient type was broken down 
 did not begin at the centre but at the extremities. The free 
 development of the civic life both of Greece and of Rome had 
 been checked by the pressure of a mass of alien elements 
 imperfectly assimilated. These first imposed a political prin- 
 ciple belonging to a different phase of culture. To the new 
 movement thus necessitated, the culture of the ancient world, 
 whatever superficial changes it might undergo, did not inwardly 
 respond. Literature still looked to the past for its models. 
 Philosophy least of all cared to adapt itself. It became instead 
 the centre of resistance to the predominant movement, — to 
 overweening despotism under the earlier Caesars, to the 
 oncoming theocracy when the republican tradition was com- 
 pletely in the past. The latest philosophers of antiquity were 
 
 pre-eminently 
 
 " The kings of thought 
 Who waged contention with their time's decay." 
 
 And their resistance was not the result of pessimism, of a 
 disposition to see nothing but evil in the actual movement of 
 things The Neo-Platonists in particular were the most 
 convinced of optimists, at the very time when, as they well 
 knew, the whole movement of the world was against them. 
 The}- held it for their task to maintain as far as might be the 
 type of life which they had themselves chosen as the best ; 
 knowing that there was an indefinite future, and that the 
 alternating rhythms in which, with Heraclitus and the Stoics, 
 they saw the cosmic harmony 1 and the expression of providential 
 reason, would not cease with one period. If they did not 
 actually predict the revival of their thought after a thousand 
 years, they would not have been in the least surprised to see it. 
 More than once has that thought been revived, and with 
 various aims ; nor is its interest even yet exhausted. The first 
 revival the philosophers themselves would have cared for was 
 
 1 waXivrovos ap/novh] k6<t/j.ov oKodcrrep Xvprjs xai to^ov. — Heraclitus. 
 
INTRODUCTION XI 
 
 that of the fifteenth century, when, along with their master 
 Plato, they became the inspirers of revolt against the system of 
 mediaeval theology that had established itself long after their 
 defeat. Another movement quite in their spirit, but this time 
 not an insurgent movement, was that of the Cambridge 
 Platonists in the seventeenth century, which went back to 
 Neo-Platonism for the principles of its resistance to the 
 exclusive dominance of the new " mechanical philosophy." As 
 the humanist academies of Italy had appealed against Scholastic 
 dogmatism to the latest representatives in antiquity of free 
 philosophic inquiry, so the opponents in England of " Hobbism " 
 went for support to those who in their own day had intellectually 
 refuted the materialism of the Stoics and Epicureans. Since 
 then, many schools and thinkers have shown affinity with 
 Neo-Platonic thought ; and, apart from direct historic attach- 
 ment or spontaneous return to similar metaphysical ideas, 
 there has been a deeper continuous influence of which something 
 will have to be said. 
 
 Within the last fifty years or thereabouts, the Neo-Platonists, 
 though somewhat neglected in comparison with the other 
 schools of antiquity, have been made the subject of important 
 historical work. To French philosophers who began as disciples 
 of Cousin, a philosophy that could be described as at once 
 "eclectic" and "spiritualist" naturally became an object of 
 interest. The result of that interest was seen in the brilliant 
 works of Vacherot and Jules Simon. For definite and positive 
 information on the doctrines of the school, the portion of Zeller's 
 Philosopliie der Griechen that deals with the period is of the 
 highest value. In English, Mr Benn's chapter on " The 
 Spiritualism of Plotinus," in his Greek Philosophers, brings out 
 well the advance in subjective thought made by the latest on 
 the earlier philosophies of Greece. Of special importance in 
 relation to this point are the chapters on Plotinus and his 
 successors in Siebeck's Gescliichte der Psycliologie. An extensive 
 work on the psychology of the school has appeared since in the 
 
xii INTRODUCTION 
 
 last two volumes of M. Chaignet's Psychologie des Grecs. 
 Recent English contributions to the general exposition of the 
 Neo-Platonist philosophy are Dr C. Bigg's volume in the 
 " Chief Ancient Philosophies " Series (S.P.C.K.), and Mr F. W. 
 BusselPs stimulating book on The School of Plato, which, 
 however, deals more with preliminaries than with the school 
 itself. 
 
 In the later historical treatment of Neo-Platonism a marked 
 tendency is visible to make less of the supposed " Oriental " 
 character of the school and more of its real dependence on the 
 preceding philosophies of Greece. This may be seen in Zeller 
 as compared with Vacherot, and in Mr Benn as compared with 
 Zeller. Of the most recent writers, M. Chaignet and Dr Bigg, 
 approaching the subject from different sides, conclude in almost 
 the same terms that the system of Plotinus was through and 
 through Hellenic. And, as M. Chaignet points out, Plotinus, 
 in all essentials, fixed the doctrine of the school. Whatever 
 attractions the thought of the East as vaguely surmised may 
 have had for its adherents, their actual contact with it was 
 slight. When the school took up a relation to the practical 
 world, it was as the champion of "Hellenism" (EWyivtafios) 
 against the " barbarian audacity " of its foes. On the whole, 
 however, it did not seek to interfere directly with practice, but 
 recognised the impossibility of modifying the course which the 
 world at large was taking, and devoted itself to the task of 
 carrying forward thought and preserving culture. Hence a 
 history of Neo-Platonism must be in the main a history of 
 doctrines internally developed, not of polemic with extraneous 
 systems of belief. At the same time the causes must be 
 indicated of its failure, and of the failure of philosophy, to hold 
 for the next age the intellectual direction of the world, — a 
 failure not unqualified. To bring those causes into view, it will 
 be necessary to give a brief sketch of the political, as well as 
 of the philosophical and religious movement to the time of 
 Plotinus. For the ultimate causes of the triumph of another 
 
INTRODUCTION Xlll 
 
 system were social more than they were intellectual, and go fal- 
 lback into the past. Of the preceding philosophical development, 
 no detailed history can be attempted. As in the case of the 
 political and religious history, all that can be done is to put the 
 course of events in a light by which its general bearing may be 
 made clear. In relation to the inner movement, the aim will be 
 to show precisely at what point the way was open for an advance 
 on previous philosophies, — au advance which, it may be said 
 by anticipation, Neo-Platonism did really succeed in making 
 secure even for the time when the fortunes of independent 
 philosophy were at their lowest. Then, when the history of 
 the school itself has been set forth in some detail, a sketch, 
 again reduced to as brief compass as possible, must be given 
 of the return of the modern world to the exact point where the 
 thought of the ancient world had ceased, and of the continued 
 influence of the Neo-Platonic conceptions on modern thought. 
 Lastly, an attempt will be made to state the law of the 
 development ; and, in relation to this, something will be said 
 of the possibilities that still remain open for the type of thought 
 which has never been systematised with more perfection than 
 in the school of Plotinus. 
 
"Onpourrait dire, sans trop d'exageration, que l'histoire 
 morale des premiers siecles de notre ere est dans l'histoire 
 du platonisme." 
 
 Matter, Histoire Critique du Gnosticisme, 
 livre viii. ch. 28. 
 
CHAPTER I. 
 
 GftAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION IN ITS POLITICAL 
 
 DEVELOPMENT. 
 
 Broadly, the political- history of classical antiquity almost 
 from the opening of the historic period may be described as 
 a slow passage from the condition of self-governing common- 
 wealths with a subordinate priesthood to the condition of a 
 theocratic despotism. This was a reduction of the West to the 
 polity of the civilised East. In the old Oriental monarchies 
 known to the classical world, the type was that of a consecrated 
 despot ruling with the support and under the direction of a 
 priesthood socially supreme. Immemorial forms of it were to 
 be seen in Egypt and in the Assyrio- Babylonian civilisation on 
 which the conquering Persian monarchy was superimposed. 
 In Persia had appeared the earliest type of a revealed as 
 distinguished from an organised natural religion. And here 
 were the beginnings of the systematic intolerance at first so 
 puzzling to the Greeks 1 . Intolerance, however, did not till 
 
 1 Herodotus, though he knew and sympathised with the refusal of the 
 Persian religion to ascribe visible form to the divinity, saw in the persecution 
 of the Egyptian cult by Cambyses and in the burning of Greek temples by order 
 of Xerxes, nothing but acts of wanton impiety. They had come to be better 
 understood in the time of Cicero, who definitely ascribes the latter to the motive 
 of pious intolerance. See De Rep. iii. 9, 14. After a reference to the animal 
 deities of Egypt as illustrating tbe variety of religious customs among civilised 
 men, the exposition proceeds : " Deinde Graeciae sicut apud nos, delubra 
 magnifica humanis consecrata simulacris, quae Persae nefaria putaverunt, 
 eamque unam ob causam Xerxes inflammari Atheniensium faua iussisse dicitur, 
 quod deos, quorum domus esset omnis hie mundus, inclusos parietibus contineri 
 nefas esse duceret." 
 
 W. 1 
 
 
2 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i 
 
 later and from a new starting-point assume a permanently 
 aggressive form. With the Persians, conquest over alien 
 nationalities led to some degree of tolerance for their inherited 
 religions. 
 
 The origin of the monarchies of Egypt and of Western Asia 
 is a matter of conjecture. To the classical world they appeared 
 as a finished type. The ancient European type of polity was 
 new and independent. It did not spring out of the Oriental 
 type by way of variation. In investigating its accessible 
 beginnings we probably get nearer to political origins than 
 we can in the East. We have there before our eyes the plastic 
 stage which in the East can only be conjectured. The Greek 
 tragic poets quite clearly distinguished their own early con- 
 stitutional monarchies with incompletely developed germs of 
 aristocracy and democracy from Oriental despotism. While 
 these monarchies lasted, they were probably not very sharply 
 marked off, in the general consciousness, from other monarchical 
 institutions. The advance to formal republicanism revealed at 
 once a new type of polity and the preparation for it at an 
 earlier stage. That this was to be the conquering type might 
 very well be imagined. Aeschylus puts into the mouth of the 
 Persian elders a lamentation over the approaching downfall of 
 kingship in Asia itself 1 . Yet this prophecy, as we know, is 
 further from being realised now than it may have appeared 
 then. And, though organised despotism on the great scale 
 was thrown back into Asia by the Persian wars, the later 
 history of Europe for a long period is the history of its return. 
 
 The republican type of culture was fixed for all time 8 , first 
 in life and then in literature, by the brief pre-eminence of 
 Athens. The Greek type of free State, however, from its 
 restriction to a city, and the absence of a representative system, 
 
 1 oi)5' is yav wponiTVovTes 
 dp^ovrai ' fla<Tihela 
 yap 8i6\o)\ev iVx^s- 
 oi'5' Ztl yKCoaaa ppoToicnv 
 iv <pvkaKah' XeXi'rtu yap 
 Xaos iXevdepa /Sdfetv, 
 ibs iXvdri frrybv dX^aj. Pers. 590 — 6. 
 
 2 <='s rbv airavra avdpdyirwv §Lov. Herod, vi. 109. 
 
i] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 3 
 
 with other causes, could not maintain itself against the inroads 
 of the monarchical principle, which at that time had the power 
 of conferring unity on a larger aggregate. The Macedonian 
 monarchy, originally of the constitutional type, became, through 
 its conquests at once over Greece and Asia, essentially an 
 Oriental monarchy — afterwards a group of monarchies — dis- 
 tinguished only by its appropriation of the literary culture of 
 Greece. Later, the republican institutions of Rome, which 
 succeeded those of Greece as the type of political freedom, 
 broke down, in spite of their greater flexibility and power of 
 incorporating subjects 1 , through a combination of the causes 
 that affected Greece and Macedon separately. Perhaps the 
 imperial monarchy was a necessity if the civilised world was 
 to be kept together for some centuries longer, and not to break 
 up into warring sections. Still, it was a lapse to a lower form 
 of polity. And the republican resistance can be historically 
 justified. The death of Caesar showed his inheritors that the 
 hour for formal monarchy was not yet come. The complete 
 shaping of the Empire on the Oriental model was, in fact, 
 postponed to the age of Diocletian and Constantine. Mean- 
 while, the emperor not being formally monarch, and the 
 republic remaining in name, the whole system of education 
 continued to be republican in basis. The most revered classics 
 were those that had come down from the time of freedom. 
 Declamations against tyrants were a common exercise in the 
 schools. And the senatorial opposition, which still cherished 
 the ethical ideal of the republic, came into power with the 
 emperors of the second century. What it has become the 
 fashion to call the "republican prejudices" of Tacitus and 
 Suetonius were adopted by Marcus Aurelius, who, after citing 
 with admiration the names of Cato and Brutus, along with 
 those of later heroes of the Stoical protestation against 
 
 1 That the Romans themselves were conscious of this, may be seen for 
 example in a speech of the Emperor Claudius as recorded by Tacitus (Ann. xi. 
 24): "Quid aliud exitio Lacedaemoniis et Atheniensibus fuit, quamquam armis 
 pollerent, nisi quod victos pro alienigenis arcebant? at conditor nostri Romulus 
 tautum sapientia valuit, ut plerosque populos eodem die hostes, dein cives 
 habuerit." 
 
 1—2 
 
4 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i 
 
 Caesarean despotism, holds up before himself " the idea of a 
 polity in which there is the same law for all, a polity ad- 
 ministered with regard to equal rights and equal freedom of 
 speech, and the idea of a kingly government which respects 
 most of all the freedom of the governed." 1 Here the demand 
 for administrative unity might seem to be reconciled with the 
 older ideal ; but the Stoic emperor represented the departing 
 and not the coming age. 
 
 There was a discrepancy between the imperial monarchy on 
 the one hand, potentially absolute, though limited by the 
 deference of the ruler for ancient forms, and on the other hand 
 the ideal that had come down from the past. The ethics of 
 antiquity had never incorporated absolutism. Now the new 
 religion that was already aiming at the spiritual dominance of 
 the Empire had no tradition that could separate it from the 
 monarchical system. Christian ethics from the first accepted 
 absolutism as its political datum. The Christian apologists 
 under the Antonines represent themselves as a kind of legiti- 
 mists, — praying, in the time of Marcus Aurelius, that the right 
 of succession of Commodus may be recognised and the blessing 
 of hereditary kingship secured 2 . Christianity therefore, once 
 accepted, consecrated for the time an ideal in accordance with 
 the actual movement of the world. In substituting the notion 
 of a monarch divinely appointed for the apotheosis of the 
 emperors, it gave a form less unendurable in civilised Europe 
 to a servility which, in its pagan form, appearing as an Asiatic 
 superstition, had been something of a scandal to the rulers who 
 were in a manner compelled to countenance it. The result, 
 unmodified by new factors, is seen in the Byzantine Empire. 
 The Roman Empire of the East remained strong enough to 
 
 1 i. 14 (Long's Translation). With the above passage may be compared 
 Julian's appeal to Plato and Aristotle in support of his conviction that the spirit 
 of laws should be impersonal (Epistola ad Themistium, 261 — 2). The second 
 imperial philosopher, in his satirical composition entitled Caesares, most 
 frequently reaffirms the judgments of Suetonius and Tacitus, but not without 
 discrimination. Tiberius he sums up as a mixed character, and does not 
 represent him as flung into Tartarus with Caligula and Nero. 
 
 2 See Renan, Marc-Aurile, where illustrations are given of this attitude on 
 the part of the apologists. 
 
 ~ 
 
I] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 5 
 
 throw off the barbarian attack for centuries. It preserved 
 much of ancient Greek letters. In distinction from the native 
 monarchies of Asia, it possessed a system of law that had 
 received its bent during a period of freedom 1 . But, with these 
 differences, it was a theocratic monarchy of the Oriental type. 
 It was the last result, not of a purely internal development, 
 but of reaction on the Graeco-Roman world from the political 
 institutions and the religions of Asia. 
 
 The course of things in the West was different. Having 
 been for a time reduced almost to chaos by the irruptions of 
 the Germanic tribes, the disintegrated and then nominally 
 revived Western Empire furnished the Church with the oppor- 
 tunity of erecting an independent theocracy above the secular 
 rule of princes. This type came nearest to realisation in the 
 twelfth and thirteenth centuries. It broke down partly through 
 internal decay and partly through the upgrowth of a stronger 
 secular life. With immense difficulty and with the appearance 
 almost of accident 2 , a new kind of free State arose. The old 
 Teutonic monarchies, like the old Greek monarchies, were not 
 of the Asiatic type. They contained elements of political 
 aristocracy and democracy which could develop under favouring 
 circumstances. In most cases the development did not take 
 place. With the cessation of feudal anarchy, the royal power 
 became too strong to be effectively checked. There was formed 
 under it a social hierarchy of which the most privileged equally 
 with the least privileged orders were excluded as such from all 
 recognised political authority. Thus on the Continent, during 
 the early modern period, the prevailing type became Catholic 
 Absolutism, or, as f* has been called, " European monarchy," — 
 a system which was imitated in the Continental Protestant 
 States. By the eighteenth century this had become, like the 
 
 1 " The period of Roman freedom was the period during which the stamp of 
 a distinctive character was impressed on the Roman jurisprudence." Sir Henry 
 Maine, Ancient Lata, 10th ed. , ch. ii. p. 40. 
 
 - Comte at least regarded Absolutism as the normal development, Consti- 
 tutionalism as a local anomaly, in European history before 1789, 
 
6 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i 
 
 Byzantine Empire or the old Asiatic monarchies, a fixed type, 
 a terminal despotism from which there could be no peaceful 
 issue. It was destroyed — so far as it has since been destroyed — 
 by the revolutionary influence of ideas from the past and from 
 without. In England the germs of freedom, instead of being 
 suppressed, were developed, and in the seventeenth century, 
 after a period of conflict, the modern system of constitutional 
 monarchy was established. To the political form of the modern 
 free State, early English institutions by their preservation 
 contributed most. Classical reminiscences, in England as 
 elsewhere, enkindled the love of freedom ; but deliberate 
 imitation was unnecessary where the germs from which the 
 ancient republics themselves had sprung were still ready to 
 take a new form. From England the influence of revived 
 political freedom diffused itself, especially in France, where it 
 combined with the emulation of classical models and with 
 generalisations from Roman law, to form the abstract system 
 of "natural rights." From this system, on the intellectual side, 
 have sprung the American and the French Republics. 
 
 In the general European development, the smaller con- 
 stitutional States may be neglected. The reappearance of a 
 kind of city-republic in mediaeval Italy is noteworthy, but had 
 little practical influence. The Italian cities were never com- 
 pletely sovereign States like the Greek cities. Politically, it is 
 as if these had accepted autonomy under the supremacy of the 
 Great King. Spiritually, it is as if they had submitted to a 
 form of the Zoroastrian religion from which dissent was penal. 
 Nor did the great Italian poets and thinkers ever quite set up 
 the ideal of the autonomous city as the Greeks had done. In 
 its ideal, their city was rather a kind of municipality : with 
 Dante, under the " universal monarchy " of the restored Empire ; 
 with Petrarch and more distinctly with Machiavelli, under Italy 
 as a national State, unified by any practicable means. Even in 
 its diminished form, the old type of republic was exceedingly 
 favourable to the reviving culture of Europe ; but the prestige 
 of the national States around was too strong for it to survive 
 except as an interesting accident. 
 
 The present type of free State is one to which no terminal 
 
I] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 7 
 
 form can be assigned. In England and in America, in France 
 and in Italy, not to speak of the mixed forms existing else- 
 where, it is still at the stage of growth. The yet living rival 
 with which it stands confronted is the Russian continuation or 
 reproduction of Christian theocracy in its Byzantine form 1 . 
 
 1 This epilogue, sketchiug the political transition to modern Europe, seemed 
 necessary for the sake of formal completeness, although the bearing of political 
 history on the history of philosophy is much less direct in modern than in 
 ancient times. 
 
CHAPTER II. 
 
 THE STAGES OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. 
 
 At the time of the Persian wars the civilisation of the 
 East was in complexity, specialism, organised industry — what- 
 ever relative importance we may attach to those features of 
 progress — in all probability ahead of the civilisation of Greece. 
 The conscious assumption of self-government by the Greek 
 cities had, however, been closely followed by the beginnings of 
 what we may call speculative science, which was a distinctive 
 product of the Greek intellect. For this, the starting-point 
 was furnished by the empirical observations of Egyptians and 
 Chaldaeans, made with a view to real or fancied utility — 
 measurement of land or prediction of future events. The 
 earliest Greek philosophers, natives of the Ionian cities of 
 Asia Minor, and thus on the borders of the fixed and the 
 growing civilisations, took up a few generalised results of the 
 long and laborious but unspeculative accumulation of facts and 
 methods by the leisured priesthoods 1 of Egypt and Babylonia, 
 and forthwith entered upon the new paths of cosmical 
 theorising without regard to authoritative tradition, and of 
 deductive thinking about numbers and figures without regard 
 to immediate utility. As early as Pythagoras, still in the sixth 
 
 1 This way of putting the matter seems to reconcile the accounts of the 
 invention of geometry in Egypt given by Herodotus and Aristotle, which 
 Prof. Burnet (Early Greek Philosophy, Introduction, p. .19) finds discrepant. 
 Herodotus assigns the motive, viz. "the necessity of measuring the lands afresh 
 after the inundations"; Aristotle the condition that made it possible, viz. " the 
 leisure enjoyed by the priestly caste." 
 
II] THE STAGES OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 9 
 
 century B.C., speculative science had begun to show signs of its 
 later division into philosophy properly so-called, and positive 
 science; the first special sciences to become detached, after 
 mathematics, being those to which mathematical treatment 
 seemed applicable. All this took place before the continuous 
 movement of reflective thinking on human knowledge, which 
 marks a new departure in philosophy, not its first origin, began 
 at Athens. 
 
 The emotion in which philosophy and science had their 
 common source was exactly the same in ancient Greece and 
 in renascent Europe. Plato and Aristotle, like Descartes and 
 Hobbes, define it as " wonder." The earliest thinkers did not 
 define it at all. Their outlook has still something very im- 
 personal. With them, there is little inquiry about happiness 
 or the means of attaining it. When the speculative life has 
 been lived by several generations of thinkers, and a self- 
 conscious theory of it is at length set forth, as at the opening 
 of Aristotle's Metaphysics, the happiness involved in it is 
 regarded as something that necessarily goes with mere think- 
 ing and understanding. 
 
 This is the subjective form of early Greek philosophy. 
 In objective content, it is marked by complete detachment 
 from religion. No traditional authority is acknowledged. 
 Myths are taken merely as offering points of contact, quite 
 as frequently for attack as for interpretation in the sense of 
 the individual thinker. The handling of them in either case 
 is perfectly free. Results of the thought and observation of 
 one thinker are summed up by him, not to be straightway 
 accepted by the next, but to be examined anew. The aim is 
 insight, not edification. 
 
 The general result is a conception of the cosmos in principle 
 not unlike that of modern science ; in detail necessarily crude, 
 though still scientific in spirit, and often anticipating the latest 
 phases of thought in remarkable ways. Even the representa- 
 tions of the earth as a disc floating on water, and of the stars 
 as orifices in circular tubes containing fire, are less remote in 
 spirit from modern objective science than the astronomy of 
 later antiquity and of the instructed Middle Ages. This was 
 
10 THE STAGES [il 
 
 far more accurate in its conception of shapes and magnitudes 
 and apparent motions, but it was teleological in a way that 
 purely scientific astronomy cannot be. The earliest Ionian 
 thinkers, like modern men of science, imposed no teleological 
 conceptions on their astronomical theories. 
 
 At the same time, early Greek philosophy was not merely 
 objective, as modern science has become. It was properly 
 philosophical in virtue of its " hylozoism." Life and mind, or 
 their elements, were attributed to the world or its parts. 
 Later, a more objective "naturalism" appears, as in the 
 system of Democritus. Here the philosophical character is 
 still retained by the addition of an explicit theory of know- 
 ledge to the scientific explanation of the cosmos. " Primary " 
 and " secondary " qualities of matter are distinguished, and 
 these last are treated as in a sense unreal. Thus the definite 
 formulation of materialism is accompanied by the beginnings 
 of subjective idealism. But with the earliest thinkers of all, 
 there is neither an explicit theory of knowledge nor an ex- 
 clusion of life and mind from the elements of things. 
 
 The atomism of Democritus and his predecessors was the 
 result of long thinking and perhaps of much controversy. 
 The " Ionians," down to Heraclitus, regarded the cosmos as 
 continuously existing, but as ruled by change in all its parts 
 if not also as a whole. The Eleatics, who came later, affirmed 
 that unchanging Being alone exists : this is permanent and 
 always identical ; " not-being " absolutely does not exist, and 
 change is illusory. The Being of Parmenides, it is now held 1 , 
 was primarily the extended cosmos regarded as a closed sphere 
 coincident with all that is. Yet, though the conception was 
 in its basis physical and not metaphysical, the metaphysical 
 abstraction made by Plato was doubtless implicit in it. And 
 Parmenides himself evidently did not conceive reality as purely 
 objective and mindless. If he had intended to convey that 
 meaning, he would have been in violent contradiction with his 
 predecessor Xenophanes, and this would hardly have escaped 
 notice. The defect of Eleaticism was that apparent change 
 
 1 See Tannery, Pour VHhtoire de la Science Hellene, and Burnet, Early 
 Greek Philosophy. 
 
n ] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 11 
 
 received no satisfactory explanation, though an attempt was 
 made to explain it in what Parmenides called a " deceptive " 
 discourse as dealing with illusory opinion and no longer with 
 demonstrative truth. Atomism mediated between this view 
 and that of the Ionians by asserting a plurality of real beings, 
 each having the characters of the Eleatic "being." "Not- 
 being" for the atomists was empty space; change in the 
 appearances of things was explained by mixture and separation 
 of unchanging elements. The mechanical conception of the 
 purely quantitative atom, which modern science afterwards 
 took up, was completed by Democritus. Anaxagoras, though 
 fundamentally a mechanicist, did not deprive his atoms of 
 quality. And Empedocles, along with ideas of mixture and 
 separation — explained by the attractive and repulsive agents, 
 at once forces and media, to which he gave the mythological 
 names of Love and Strife— retained something of the old 
 hylozoism. Over against the material elements of things, 
 Anaxagoras set Mind as the agent by which they are sifted 
 from their primitive chaos. This was the starting-point for 
 a new development, less purely disinterested than the first 
 because more coloured by ethical and religious motives, but 
 requiring even greater philosophic originality for its accom- 
 plishment. 
 
 The new departure of philosophy, though adopting the 
 Anaxagorean Mind as its starting-point, had its real source 
 in the ethical and political reflection which began effectively 
 with the Sophists and Socrates. To give this reflective 
 attitude consistency, to set up the principles suggested by 
 it against all exclusive explanations of reality from the material 
 ground of things, and yet to do this without in the end letting 
 go the notion of objective science, was the work of Plato. 
 Aristotle continued Plato's work, while carrying forward science 
 independently and giving it relatively a more important posi- 
 tion. One great characteristic result of the earlier thinking — 
 the assertion that materially nothing is created and nothing 
 destroyed — was assumed as an axiom both by Plato and by 
 Aristotle whenever they had to deal with physics. They did 
 not take up from the earlier thinkers those specific ideas that 
 
12 THE STAGES [il 
 
 afterwards turned out the most fruitful scientifically — though 
 Plato had a kind of atomic theory — but they affirmed physical 
 law in its most general principle. This they subordinated to 
 their metaphysics by the conception of a universal teleology. 
 The teleological conception of nature there is good historical 
 ground for attributing also to Socrates. 
 
 The special importance which Plato's Timaeus acquired 
 for his successors is due to its being the most definite attempt 
 made by the philosopher himself to bring his distinctive 
 thought into relation with objective science. Thus, in view 
 of knowledge as it was in antiquity, the later Platonists were 
 quite right in the stress they laid on this dialogue. 
 
 For the period following upon the death of Aristotle, during 
 which Stoicism and Epicureanism were the predominant schools, 
 the most important part of Plato's and Aristotle's thought was 
 the ethical part. Both schools were, on the theoretical side, a 
 return to naturalism as opposed to the Platonic and Aristotelian 
 idealism. Both alike held that all reality is body ; though the 
 Stoics regarded it as continuous and the Epicureans as discrete. 
 The soul, for the Stoics as for the Epicureans, was a particular 
 kind of matter. The most fruitful conception in relation to the 
 science of the future was preserved by Epicurus when he took 
 up the Democritean idea of the atom, defined as possessing 
 figured extension, resistance and weight; all "secondary" 
 qualities being regarded as resulting from the changes of 
 order and the interactions of the atoms. And, on the whole, 
 the Epicureans appealed more to genuine curiosity about 
 physics for itself 1 , though ostensibly cultivating it only as a 
 means towards ridding human life of the fear of meddlesome 
 gods. If the determinism of the Stoics was more rigorous, it 
 did not prevent their undertaking the defence of some popular 
 superstitious which the Epicureans have the credit of opposing. 
 On the other hand, Stoicism did more for ethics. While both 
 schools, in strict definition, were " eudaemonist," the Stoics 
 brought out far more clearly the social reference of morality. 
 Their line of thought here, as the Academics and Peripatetics 
 
 1 Mr Benn, in his Greek Philosophers, points out the resemblance of 
 Lucretius in type of mind to the early physical thinkers of Greece. 
 
Il] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 13 
 
 were fond of pointing out, could be traced back to Plato and 
 Aristotle. So also could the teleology which they combined 
 with their naturalism. But all the systems of the time were 
 more or less eclectic. 
 
 The social form under which the Stoics conceived of 
 morality was the reference, no longer to a particular State, 
 but to a kind of universal State. Since the social reference 
 in Greek morality had been originally to the " city," the name 
 was retained, but it was extended to the whole world, and the 
 ideal morality was said to be that of a citizen of the world. 
 This "cosmopolitanism" is prepared in Plato and Aristotle. 
 Socrates (as may be seen in the Memorabilia of Xenophon) 
 had already conceived the idea of a natural law or justice 
 which is the same for all States. And in Aristotle that 
 conception of " natural law " which, transmitted by Stoicism, 
 had so much influence on the Roman jurisprudence, is definitely 
 formulated 1 . The humanitarian side of Stoicism — which is not 
 quite the same thing as its conception of universal justice — is 
 plainly visible in Cicero 2 . 
 
 Although Zeno, the founder of Stoicism, was by race half 
 a Phoenician, it cannot be said that the East contributed 
 anything definable to the content of his ethics. Its sources 
 were evidently Greek. Down to the end of the ancient world, 
 
 1 See the quotation and references given by Zeller, ii. 2, p. 646, n. 1. 
 (Aristotle, Eng. Trans., ii. 175, n. 3.) 
 
 - See, in De Finibus, the exposition of Cato, deducing from the Stoic 
 principles the existence of a " communis humani generis societas " (iii. 19, 62). 
 "Bonitas" is expressly distinguished from "justitia" (c. 20, 66); cf. De Off. 
 iii. 6, 28. In the fifth book of the De Finibus, Piso goes back for the origin of 
 the whole doctrine to the Platonists and Peripatetics. The following sentence 
 (c. 23, 65) sums up the theory: "In omni autem honesto, de quo loquimur, 
 nihil est tam illustre nee quod latius pateat quam coniunctio inter homines 
 hominum et quasi quaedam societas et communicatio utilitatum et ipsa caritas 
 generis humani, quae nata a primo satu, quod a procreatoribus nati diliguntur 
 et tota domus coniugio et stirpe coniungitur, serpit sensim foras, cognationibus 
 primum, turn affinitatibus, deinde amicitiis, post vicinitatibus, turn civibus et 
 iis, qui publice socii atque amici sunt, deinde totius complexu gentis humanae ; 
 quae animi affectio suum cuique tribuens atque hanc, quam dico, societatem 
 coniunctionis humanae niunirice et aeque tuens iustitia dicitur, cui sunt 
 adiunctae pietas, bonitas, liberalitas, benignitas, comitas, quaeque sunt generis 
 eiusdem." 
 
14 THE STAGES [il 
 
 philosophy was continued by men of various races, but always 
 by those who had taken the impress of Greek or of Graeco- 
 Roman civilisation. 
 
 The same general account is true of the Neo-Platonists. 
 They too were men who had inherited or adopted the Hellenic 
 tradition. On the ethical side they continue Stoicism ; although 
 in assigning a higher place to the theoretic virtues they return 
 to an earlier view. Their genuine originality is in psychology 
 and metaphysics. Having gone to the centre of Plato's ideal- 
 istic thought, they demonstrated, by a new application of its 
 principles, the untenableness of the Stoic materialism ; and, 
 after the long intervening period, they succeeded in defining 
 more rigorously than Plato had done, in psychology the idea of 
 consciousness, in metaphysics the idea of immaterial and 
 subjective existence. Scientifically, they incorporated elements 
 of every doctrine with the exception of Epicureanism ; going 
 back with studious interest to the pre-Socratics, many frag- 
 ments of whom the latest Neo-Platonist commentators rescued 
 just as they were on the point of being lost. On the subjective 
 side, they carried thought to the highest point reached in 
 antiquity. And neither in Plotinus, the great original thinker 
 of the school, nor in his successors, was this the result of 
 mystical fancies or of Oriental influences. These, when they 
 appeared, were superinduced. No idealistic philosophers have 
 ever applied closer reasoning or subtler analysis to the relations 
 between the inner and the outer world. If the school to some 
 extent " Orientalised," in this it followed Plato ; and it diverged 
 far less from Hellenic ideals than Plato himself. 
 
 A certain affinity of Plato with the East has often been 
 noticed. This led him to the most remarkable previsions of 
 the later movement of the world. The system of caste in the 
 Republic is usually said to be an anticipation of the mediaeval 
 order of society. Now in the introduction to the Timaeus and 
 in the Gritias, the social order of Egypt is identified in its 
 determining principles with that of the ideal State, and both 
 with the constitution of pre-historic Athens, also regarded as 
 ideal. Hence it becomes evident that, for his specialisation 
 and grading of social functions, Plato got the hint from the 
 
II] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 15 
 
 Egyptian caste of occupations 1 . Thus his ideal society is in 
 contact, on one side with the pre-Hellenic East, on the other 
 side with the Orientalised Europe of the Middle Ages. By its 
 communism it touches modern schemes of reform 2 . 
 
 Mr Benn has remarked that the stages of degeneration from 
 the ideal aristocracy to a tyranny, set forth in the Republic, are 
 the same as the actual stages of degeneration of the Roman 
 State. To this it may be added that in the Laws Plato lays 
 down the exact conditions that concurred for the establishment 
 of Christianity. The problem is to get a new system of legis- 
 lation received in the projected colony. For this he finds that, 
 though citizens from the same State are better in so far as they 
 are likely to be more orderly, yet they will be too attached to 
 their own laws. There is therefore an advantage in beginning 
 with a mixture of colonists from several States. The character 
 of such colonists will make the task in any case difficult, but 
 the most favourable condition is that the ideas of a great 
 legislator should be taken up by a young and vigorous tyrant. 
 Generalise a little, putting for a single legislator the succession 
 of those who formulated ecclesiastical doctrine and discipline, 
 and for a single tyrant the consummated autocracy of the later 
 Roman Empire, and the conditions are historically given. For 
 there was, in the cosmopolitan Empire, exactly that mixture 
 of different inherited customs which Plato desiderates. Add, 
 what is continually insisted on in the Laws, that towards 
 getting particular precepts enforced it would conduce much 
 if they could be regarded as proceeding from a god, and it will 
 be seen that here also the precise condition of success was laid 
 down. 
 
 The philosopher even anticipated some of the actual legis- 
 lation of the Church. In the tenth book of the Laws, he 
 proposes a system of religious persecution. Three classes of 
 the impious are to be cast out, — those who deny the existence 
 of all gods, those who say that the gods take no heed of human 
 affairs, and those who say that they can be bought off with 
 
 1 Cf. Arist. Pol. iv. (vii.) 9, 13'29 b 23 : 6 W x u P ta f-^ ° xara. ytvos rod 
 iroXiTiKov Tr\-fi$ovs £'£ AlyvTrrov. 
 
 2 See Appendix I. 
 
16 THE STAGES [ll 
 
 prayers and gifts ; or, as we may put it compendiously, — 
 Atheists, Epicureans and Catholics. As, however, the last 
 class would have been got rid of with least compunction, the 
 anticipation here was by no means exact. And probably none 
 of these glimpses, extraordinary as they were, into the strange 
 transformation that was to come in a thousand years, had any 
 influence in bringing it to pass. 
 
 The Neo-Platonists would have carried out an ethical 
 reform of polytheism in the spirit of the Republic and the Laws ; 
 but they did not propose to set up persecution as a sanction. 
 On the contrary, they were the champions of the old intellectual 
 liberty of Hellenism against the new theocracy. One of the 
 most Orientalising sayings to be found in the later Platonists, 
 namely, that the " barbarians " have an advantage over the 
 Greeks in the stability of their institutions and doctrines as 
 contrasted with the Greek innovating spirit 1 , occurs both in 
 the Timaeus and in the Laws' 2 . And Plato's attack, in the 
 Republic, on the myths of Greek religion, was continued by the 
 Christians, not by his Neo-Platonic successors; who sought to 
 defend by allegorical interpretations whatever they could not 
 accept literally ; or at least, in repudiating the fables, did not 
 advocate the expulsion of the poets. 
 
 It is to be remembered further that in the philosophical 
 tradition of antiquity even more than in its general culture, the 
 republican ideal was always upheld. Aristotle as well as Plato, 
 it is true, was less favourable than the statesmen, orators and 
 historians of the great Athenian period to personal spontaneity 
 uncontrolled by the authority of the State. But of course what 
 
 1 Quoted by Bitter and Preller (Historia Philosophies Graecae, 547 b) from 
 the De Mysteriis formerly attributed to Iamblichus : fxera^aWd/xeva ael 5ia ti)v 
 Kcuvorofxiav kclI irapavoixiav tCiv 'EXXiji'wi' ovUv iraveTai....^6.p^apoi de fiovifioi tois 
 ■VjBeaiv oures nal rots X6701S fiefZaiw tois avrois e/xix^vovcn. 
 
 2 Allowance being made for the point of view, the two aspects of Plato are 
 appreciated with perfect exactitude by Joseph de Maistre in his vituperation of 
 the Greek spirit. (Du Pape, livre iv. ch. 7.) Plato's "positive and eternal 
 dogmas," says the brilliant reactionary, "portent si clairement le cachet 
 oriental que, pour le meconnaitre, il faut n'avoir jamais entrevu rAsie....Il y 
 avait en lui un sophiste et un theologien, ou, si Ton veut, un Grec et un 
 Chalde'en. On n'entend pas ce pbilosophe si on ne le lit pas avec cette idee 
 toujours pre"sente a l'esprit." 
 
Il] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 17 
 
 the philosophers desired was the supremacy of reason, not of 
 arbitrary will. Licence in the city seemed to them condemn- 
 able on this ground among others, that under the show of 
 liberty it paved the way for a tyrant. And the later schools, 
 in which philosophy had fixed a sort of official attitude, were 
 always understood to be hostile to despotism 1 . The Stoics in 
 particular had this reputation, which they justified under the 
 early Empire. That the Neo-Platonists, although by their 
 time philosophy had almost ceased to have a political branch, 
 were still of the ancient tradition, is proved by the republican 
 spirit of Julian, who had received from them his self-chosen 
 training'-. In the chiefs of the school also, slight indications to 
 the same effect may be discerned. This attitude of the philo- 
 sophers had its importance in preserving the memory of the 
 higher ideal notwithstanding the inevitable descent due to 
 circumstance. And even in the early Middle Ages, deriving 
 their knowledge of antiquity as they did mainly from a few 
 late compilations, such discussions as there are on the origin 
 of society and of government seem traceable to reminiscences 
 from the philosophic schools; the idea of a social contract in 
 particular coming probably from the Epicureans. 
 
 1 Cf. Sueton. Nero, 52: "Liberalis disciplinas omnis fere puer attigit. Sed 
 a philosophia eum mater avertit, monens imperaturo contrariam esse." 
 
 2 Julian's refusal to be addressed by the title 5etnr6TTis customary in the 
 East, did not conciliate the "average sensual man" of Antioch. See Misopogon, 
 343c — 344a: SeviroT-qs ehai ov (prjs oi<5e avexv tovto d/coiW, d\Xa /cat ayavaKreis,... 
 OovXeveiv 5' r/^as dvayKa^eis apxov<ri /cat vo/xols. kclLtoi woffip Kpenrov -r\v ovo/xd^eadai 
 ix.b> <re SeairdTijv, Zpyy 8e iS.i> ^uas elvai iXevdipovs ; ...&<peh 5e tt)v <tkt)V7]v /cat robs 
 
 flifJLOVS KO.1 TOVS OpX 7 ? " 7 " 05 aTO\ib\eKCLS TJfXUV TT)V TroXiv. 
 
 W. 
 
CHAPTER III. 
 
 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY. 
 
 Though philosophy at its beginning among the Ionians 
 had broken with traditional authority as completely as it has 
 ever done since, religion and free speculation did not cease 
 to interact. In some points, however, their developments 
 were independent. Religious developments independent of 
 philosophy were the establishment and the increased atten- 
 tion paid to the " mysteries," and the importation of new 
 worships from Egypt and Asia Minor. It was also due 
 rather to a new development of religion than to philosophy, 
 that more definite and vivid beliefs came to be popularly held 
 about the immortality of the soul and about future rewards 
 and punishments; though philosophers of religious mind sought 
 to impress these doctrines along with the general conception 
 of a providential government of the universe. In the 
 Homeric poems, the soul goes away to the underworld as 
 soon as the corpse is burnt, and can never afterwards reappear 
 in the world of living men. Yet much later, in the dramatists, 
 the ghost is invoked as still having active powers in this world. 
 Here there is perhaps a survival of a stage of belief more 
 primitive than the Homeric, rather than a development 1 ; but 
 in the notion of definite places of reward and punishment there 
 was clearly some growth of belief. Perhaps the mythical 
 treatment of immortality by which Plato follows up his 
 arguments for it on speculative grounds, is more a reaction 
 
 1 Rohde (Psyche, i.) finds evidences of such survival in Hesiod. 
 
Ill] RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY 19 
 
 of older religion on philosophy than an application of philo- 
 sophy to religion. To the exact truth of the representations 
 given, the philosopher never commits himself, but merely 
 contends that something of the kind is probably true, as 
 against the imaginations in Homer of a world of lifeless shades 
 contrasted in their unreality with the vigour and bloom of 
 life on earth. This side of Plato's teaching had for a long 
 time not much influence. It became influential in proportion ■ 
 as religion revived. With Aristotle and the naturalistic 
 schools, personal immortality almost went out of sight. 
 The Epicureans denied the immortality of the human soul 
 altogether, and with the Stoics survival of consciousness after 
 death, if admitted at all, was only till the end of a cycle or 
 " great year." The religious belief, and especially the belief 
 in Tartarus, became, however, in the end vigorous enough to 
 furnish one point of contact for a new religion that could make 
 it still more definite and terrible. And one side of the new 
 religion was prepared for by the notion, more or less seriously 
 encouraged, that those who partook of the mysteries had 
 somehow a privileged position among the dead 1 . This of course 
 was discountenanced by the most religious philosophers; though 
 they came to hold that it showed a certain want of piety 
 towards ancestral beliefs to make light of initiation into the 
 native mysteries. 
 
 Ancient religion and philosophy had not always been on 
 such amicable terms as are implied in this last approximation. 
 Especially at the beginning, when philosophy was a new thing, 
 what may be called a sporadic intolerance was manifested 
 towards it. Indeed, had this not been so, it would be necessary 
 to allow that human nature has since then changed fundament- 
 all}-. Without such germs of intolerance, its later developments 
 would have been inconceivable. What can be truly said is that 
 the institutions of antiquity were altogether unfavourable to 
 the organisation of it. The death of Socrates had political 
 more perhaps than religious motives. It has even been main- 
 tained that serious intolerance first appeared in the Socratic 
 
 1 Cf. Hatch, The Influence of Greek Ideas and Usages upon the Christian 
 Church, Lecture X. 
 
 2—2 
 
20 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill 
 
 school itself 1 . Plato, it is clear, would have been quite willing 
 that an ethical reform of religion should be carried out by force. 
 After the first collision, however, religion on the one side re- 
 mained unorganised, and philosophy on the other side prac- 
 tically free. 
 
 How far was popular polytheism taken seriously ? That it 
 was not taken seriously by the philosophers is quite evident. 
 Perhaps the Epicureans reacted on it less than any other school ; 
 for they conceived of their ethical ideal as realised by the many 
 gods named in mythology, and they had no other divinities. 
 Their quarrel was not with polytheism as such, but with the 
 belief in gods who interrupted their divine tranquillity to 
 interfere in the affairs of mortals. The belief of the philosophic 
 schools generally was some form of theism, or, as in the case of 
 the Stoics, pantheism, by which the gods of mythology, if 
 recognised at all, were subordinated to a supreme intelligence 
 or allegorised into natural forces. The later philosophers made 
 use of more elaborate accommodations. Aristotle had rejected 
 polytheism in so many words. Plato had dismissed it with 
 irony. Their successors needed those explicit theories of a 
 rationalising kind which Plato thought rather idle. For the 
 educated world, both in earlier and later antiquity, Cudworth's 
 position is probably in the main true, that a sort of monotheism 
 was held over and above all ideas of gods and daemons. 
 
 Thus the controversy between Christian assailants and pagan 
 defenders of the national religions was not really a controversy 
 between monotheism and polytheism. The champions of the 
 old gods contended only for the general reasonableness of the 
 belief that different parts of the earth have been distributed 
 to different powers, divine though subordinate 2 . And in 
 principle the Christians could have no objection to this. They 
 themselves often held with regard to angels what the pagans 
 attributed to gods ; or even allowed the real agency of the 
 pagan gods, but called them "daemons," holding them to be evil 
 beings. The later paganism also allowed the existence of evil 
 
 1 This is the thesis of a very suggestive little book by M. G. Sorel, entitled 
 Le Prods de Socrate (1889). 
 
 2 Cf. Keim, Celsus' Wahres Wort, p. 67. 
 
Ill] IN LATER ANTIQUITY 21 
 
 daemons, and had a place for angels among supernatural powers. 
 Perhaps there is here a trace of Christian influence. 
 
 It is often represented as a paradox that the Christian idea 
 of a suffering God should have triumphed over what is supposed 
 to have been the universal prejudice of paganism that to suffer 
 is incompatible with divinity. There is no real paradox. Ideas 
 of suffering gods were everywhere, and the worship of them 
 became the most popular. The case is really this. The philo- 
 sophers held that absolutely divine beings — who are not the 
 gods of fable — are " impassible." In oratorical apologies for 
 the Crucifixion and the Resurrection, this philosophic view of 
 the divinity had to be met. On the other hand, the Christians 
 made most of their converts among those who were not philo- 
 sophers. By their mode of appeal, they got the advantage at 
 once of a rigorous monotheism such as philosophy was tending 
 to diffuse, and of the idea that expiations could be performed 
 by incarnate and suffering deities, such as were believed in 
 over all the pagan world. Exactly with this kind of popular 
 paganism philosophy had had its quarrel. Of Xenophanes, the 
 earliest explicitly monotheistic philosopher, it is related that, 
 being asked by the people of Elea whether they should sacrifice 
 to Leucothea and lament for her, he replied : " If you think 
 her a god, do not lament; if human, do not sacrifice 1 ." The 
 same view was taken by later philosophers. It was against 
 this, and not against the popular imaginations, that such sayings 
 as the well-known one of Tertullian were directed. 
 
 Coinciding with the rise of Christianity there was, as has 
 lately come to be recognised, a revival, not a decline, of ancient 
 religion. The semblance of decline is due to the effect produced 
 011 modern readers by the literature of the later Roman Republic 
 and earlier Empire, which proceeded for the most part from the 
 sceptical minority. This impression has been corrected by the 
 evidence of archaeology. So far as there was a real decline in 
 the worship of the old gods, it meant only a desertion of in- 
 digenous cults for more exciting ones from the East. First 
 
 1 Arist. Rlwt. ii. 23, 1400 b 5. (R. P. 81 a.) Sevocpduris 'EXedrcus (pwrucnv el 
 duwfft rrj Aewcodeqi Kai dpyvucnv r) fir), <rvve(iov\evev, d fx.ev Oebv uTro\a,ul-idvov<n, /at] 
 dp-qvtlv, el o' dvOpwirov, fir} Ovtiv. 
 
22 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill 
 
 there appeared the cult of the Oriental Bacchus, then of Cybele 
 and of Isis. And all these present curious analogies with 
 Christianity. It is an interesting circumstance that from the 
 Bacchae of Euripides, — which is essentially a picture of the 
 uncontrollable frenzy aroused by devotion to a lately born son 
 of Zeus, persecuted and afterwards triumphant, coming from 
 the East, — several lines were transferred to the Christus Pattens 1 . 
 The neglect of the altars of the gods spoken of by Lucian may 
 be explained by this transfer of devotion. In the dialogue 
 ®edov 'K/acXrjala, the Hellenic gods are called together with a 
 view to the expulsion of intruding barbarian divinities, such as 
 those that wear Persian or Assyrian garments, and above all 
 " the brutish gods of Nile," who, as Zeus himself is obliged to 
 admit, are a scandal to Olympus. Momus insinuates that the 
 purge will not turn out easy, since few of the gods, even among 
 the Hellenic ones themselves, if they come to be closely 
 examined, will be able to prove the purity of their race. Such 
 an attempt at conservative reform as is here satirised by Lucian 
 no doubt represented what was still the attitude of classical 
 culture in the second century ; as may be seen by the invective 
 of Juvenal against the Egyptian religion. Later, the syncretism 
 that took in deities of every nationality came to be adopted 
 by the defenders of classicism. It is this kind of religious 
 syncretism, rather than pure classicism, that revives at the 
 Renaissance. The apology not only for the Greek gods but for 
 those of Egypt, as in truth all diverse representations of the 
 same divinity, is undertaken in one of Bruno's dialogues. 
 What makes this the more remarkable is that Bruno probably 
 got the hint for his Spaccio della Bestia Trionfante precisely 
 from the dialogue of Lucian just referred to. 
 
 The nearest approach in the Hellenic world to the idea of 
 a personal religious revelation was made by the philosophic 
 sect of the Pythagoreans. The early history of the sect is 
 mainly the account of an attempt at ethico-political regulation of 
 cities in the south of Italy by oligarchies imbued with the philo- 
 sophical and religious ideas of Pythagoras. These oligarchies 
 
 1 See the notes in Paley's edition of Euripides. The Christus Patiens was 
 formerly attributed to Gregory Nazianzen, but is now held to be of later date. 
 
Ill] IX LATER ANTIQUITY 23 
 
 made themselves intensely unpopular, and the Pythagorean 
 associations were violently suppressed. Afterwards remains of 
 the societies combined to form a school specially devoted to 
 geometry and astronomy, and in astronomy remarkable for 
 suggestions of heliocentric ideas. Till we come to the Neo- 
 Pythagoreans of about the first century B.C., the history of the 
 school is obscure. Its religious side is observable in this, 
 that those who claim to be of the Pythagorean succession 
 appeal more than other philosophers to the recorded sayings of 
 the founder, and try to formulate a minute discipline of daily 
 life in accordance with his precepts. The writings, mostly 
 pseudonymous, attributed by them to early Pythagoreans 1 are 
 in composition extremely eclectic, borrowing freely from the 
 Stoics as well as from Plato and Aristotle. Coincidences 
 were explained by the assumption that other philosophers 
 had borrowed from Pythagoras. The approach of the Neo- 
 Pythagorean school to the idea of a revelation is illustrated 
 by the circumstance that Apollonius of Tyana, to whom in the 
 first century A.D. miracles and a religious mission were attri- 
 buted, was a Pythagorean. The lives of Pythagoras himself, 
 by Porphyry and Iamblichus, are full of the marvels related in 
 older documents from which both alike drew. According to 
 Zeller, the peculiar doctrines and the ascetic discipline of the 
 Essenes are to be ascribed to Neo-Pythagorean rather than 
 to Indian or Persian influences. Their asceticism — an essen- 
 tially non-Judaic character — has in any case to be explained 
 from a foreign source; and its origin from this particular 
 Hellenic source is on the whole the most probable, because of 
 the number of detailed coincidences both in method of life and 
 in doctrine. 
 
 Closely connected with the idea of the cosmical harmony, so 
 strongly accentuated in the Pythagorean school, is the adoration 
 of the stars thought of as animated beings, which became in 
 quite a special manner the philosophic religion. This may 
 have been first suggested by the star-worship associated with 
 the empirical observations of the Chaldaeans, from which the 
 
 1 Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 100 — 3, gives a long list of them. 
 
24 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill 
 
 Greek rational astronomy arose. There is not much trace of 
 this form of religion in Greek polytheism at its first mytho- 
 logical stage. The genuine gods of Greece were essentially 
 anthropomorphic. In a passage of Aristophanes 1 it is even 
 said that the sun and moon are distinctively the gods of the 
 barbarians. The earliest philosophers did not treat the heavenly 
 bodies as in any special way divine, but regarded them as 
 composed of the same kinds of matter as the other and lower 
 bodies of the universe. When popular religion thought it an 
 impiety on the part of Anaxagoras to explain the nature and 
 action of the sun without introducing divine agency, the divine 
 agency required was no doubt of an anthropomorphic kind, — 
 that of a charioteer for example. By Plato and Aristotle the 
 divinity of the stars themselves was affirmed ; aud it afterwards 
 became an article of faith with what we may call pagan philo- 
 sophical orthodoxy. It was for the philosophers a mode of 
 expressing the teleological relation between the supreme Deity 
 and the animated universe. The heavenly bodies, according to 
 the theory, were placed in spheres to give origin by their 
 motions to the ideas of time and number, and to bring about 
 the succession of day and night and the changes of the seasons 
 for the good of men and other animals. That they might do 
 this, they were endowed with ruling intelligences superior to 
 man's and more lasting. For the animating principle of the 
 stars, unimpeded by any process of growth or decay, can 
 energise continuously at its height, whereas human souls, 
 being temporarily united to portions of unstable matter, lapse 
 through such union from the condition of untroubled intel- 
 lectual activity. This theory, founded by Plato in the Timaeus, 
 was an assertion of teleological optimism against the notion 
 
 1 Quoted in Blakesley's Herodotus, vol. ii. p. 210, n. 
 
 TP. i] yap aek-qvT] x^ navovpyos ijXios, 
 
 v/mv (Tn(3ov\evoi>Te iroXvv ijdri XP° V0V > 
 
 rots ftapfiapoLcri Trpodidorov rr\v EXXdSa. 
 
 EP. (Va tI de tovto dparov ; TP. otitj vt] At'o 
 
 i]fxe?s fJ.ei> vfiiv dvotxev, tovtoigi. de 
 
 oi j3dp(3apoi dvovcn. 
 
 Pax, 406—11. 
 
Ill] IN LATER ANTIQUITY 25 
 
 that the stars are products of chance-aggregation. As such, 
 it was defended by Plotinus against the pessimism of the 
 Christian Gnostics, who— going beyond the Epicureans, as he 
 sa y S — regarded the present world as the work of an imperfect 
 or of an eviL creator. And in the latest period of the Neo- 
 Platonic school at Athens, a high place was given, among the 
 devotional usages adopted from the older national religions, to 
 those that had reference to the heavenly bodies. 
 
 A current form taken by this modification of star-worship 
 was astrology. Its wide dissemination in Italy is known from 
 the edicts expelling the so-called "mathematici" or "Chaldaei," 
 as well as from the patronage they nevertheless obtained at the 
 courts of emperors. Along with magic or " theurgy," it came 
 to be practised by some though not by all the members of the 
 Neo-Platonic school. Plotiuus himself, as a true successor of 
 Plato, minimised where he could not entirely deny the pos- 
 sibility of astrological predictions and of magical influences, 
 and discouraged the resort to them even if supposed real. In 
 his school, from first to last, there were always two sections: 
 on the one hand those who, in their attachment to the old 
 religion and aversion from the new, inquired curiously into all 
 that was still preserved in local traditions about human inter- 
 course with gods or daemons ; and on the other hand those 
 who devoted themselves entirely to the cultivation of philosophy 
 in a scientific spirit, or, if of more religious mind, aimed at 
 mystical union with the highest God as the end of virtue and 
 knowledge. This union, according to the general position of 
 the school, was in no case attainable by magical practices, 
 which at best brought the soul into relation with subordinate 
 divine powers. According to those even who attached most 
 importance to " theurgy," it was to be regarded as a means of 
 preparation for the soul itself in its progress, not as having any 
 influence on the divinity. One here and there, it was allowed, 
 might attain to the religious consummation of philosophy 
 without external aids, but for the majority they were necessary. 
 As " magical " powers, when real, were held to be due to a 
 strictly "natural" sympathy of each part of the universe with 
 all the rest, and as this was not denied, on scientific grounds, 
 
26 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY [ill 
 
 by the opponents of magic, the theoretical difference between 
 the two parties was less than might be supposed. It did not 
 prevent philosophers of opposite views on this point from being 
 on friendly terms with each other. The real chasm was 
 between the philosophers who, however they •might aspire 
 after what they had heard of Eastern wisdom, had at heart 
 the continuance of the Hellenic tradition, and those believers 
 in a new revelation who, even if giving to their doctrines a 
 highly speculative form, like the Gnostics 1 , yet took up a 
 revolutionary attitude towards the whole of ancient culture. 
 
 1 See Appendix II. 
 
CHAPTER IV. 
 
 PLOTINUS AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS. 
 
 A name once customarily but incorrectly applied to the 
 Neo-Platonist school was "the School of Alexandria." The 
 historians who used the name were aware that it was not 
 strictly correct, and now it seems to be again passing out of 
 use. That the Neo-Platonic teachers were not in any close 
 association with the scientific specialists and literary critics of 
 the Alexandrian Museum was elaborately demonstrated by 
 Matter in a work which is really a History of the School — or 
 rather Schools— of Alexandria, and not, like those of Vacherot 
 and Jules Simon bearing the same general title, of Neo- 
 Platonism. In his third volume (1818) Matter devotes a 
 special section to the Neo-Platonic philosophy, " falsely called 
 Alexandrian," and there he treats it as representing a mode of 
 thought secretly antipathetic to the scientific spirit of the 
 Museum. This, however, is an exaggeration. Of the obscure 
 antipathy which he thinks existed, he does not bring any 
 tangible evidence; and, in fact, when Neo-Platonism had 
 become the philosophy of the Graeco-Roman world, it was 
 received at Alexandria as elsewhere. What is to be avoided is 
 merely the ascription of a peculiar local association that did not 
 
 exist. 
 
 To the Jewish Platonism of Philo and to the Christian 
 Platonism of Clement and Origen the name of " Alexandrian " 
 may be correctly applied ; for it was at Alexandria that both 
 
28 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 types of thought were elaborated. To the Hellenic Platonism 
 of Plotinus and his school it has no proper application. Plo- 
 tinus indeed received his philosophical training at Alexandria 
 under Ammonius Saccas ; but it was not till long after, at 
 Rome, that he began to put forth a system of his own. After 
 his death, knowledge of his system, through Porphyry and 
 Iamblichus, diffused itself over all parts of the Roman Empire 
 where there was any care for philosophy. Handed on by the 
 successors of Iamblichus, the doctrine of Plotinus at last gained 
 the assent of the occupants of Plato's chair in the Academy. 
 The one brilliant period of Neo- Platonism at Alexandria was 
 when it was expounded there by Hypatia. Its last great 
 names are not those of Alexandrian teachers, but those of the 
 " Platonic successors " at Athens, among whom by far the most 
 distinguished was Proclus. 
 
 The school remained always in reality the school of Plotinus. 
 From the direction impressed by him it derived its unity. A 
 history of Neo-Platonism must therefore set out from the 
 activity of Plotinus as teacher and thinker. Of this activity an 
 account sufficient in the main points is given by his disciple 
 Porphyry, who edited his writings and wrote his life 1 . 
 
 Through the reticence of Plotinus himself, the date and 
 place of his birth are not exactly recoverable. This reticence 
 Porphyry connects with an ascetic repugnance to the body. 
 It was only by stealth that a portrait of the master could be 
 taken; his objection, when asked to sit to a painter, being the 
 genuinely Platonic one that a picture was but an " image of an 
 image." Why perpetuate this when the body itself is a mere 
 image of reality ? Hence also the philosopher did not wish to 
 preserve the details of his outward history. Yet in his 
 aesthetic criticism he is far from taking a merely depreciating 
 view of the fine arts. His purpose seems to have been to 
 prevent a cult of him from arising among his disciples. He 
 would not tell his birthday, lest there should be a special 
 celebration of it, as there had come to be of the birthdays of 
 
 1 Porphyry's Life is prefixed to the edition of Plotinus by E. Volkmann 
 (Teubuer, 1883, 4), from which the citations in the present volume are made. 
 
IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 29 
 
 other philosophers 1 ; although he himself used to keep the 
 traditional birthday-feasts of Socrates and Plato 2 . 
 
 According to Eunapius 3 , he was born at Lyco (or Lycopolis) 
 in Egypt. From Porphyry's Life the year of his birth is 
 inferred to be 204 or 205. In his twenty-eighth year, being 
 dissatisfied with the other Alexandrian teachers of philosophy 
 whom he frequented, he was taken by a friend to Ammonius. 
 When he had heard him^he said to his companion : " This is 
 the man of whom I was in search " (tovtov e&jTovv). With 
 Ammonius he remained eleven years. At the end of that time, 
 he became eager to learn something definite of the philosophy 
 that was cultivated among the Persians and Indians. Ac- 
 cordingly, in his thirty-ninth year he joined the expedition 
 which Gordian was preparing against Persia (242). The 
 Emperor was killed in Mesopotamia, and, the expedition having 
 failed, Plotinus with difficulty escaped to Antioch. At the age 
 of forty, he went to Rome (244) ; where, for ten whole years, 
 though giving philosophical instruction, he wrote nothing. 
 He began to write in the first year of the reign of Gallienus 
 (254). In 263, when Plotinus was about fifty-nine, Porphyry, 
 then thirty years of age, first came into relation with him. 
 Plotinus had by that time written twenty-one " books," on such 
 topics as had presented themselves in lectures and discussions. 
 These Porphyry found issued to a few. Under the stimulus of 
 new discussions, and urged by himself and an earlier pupil, 
 Amelius Gentilianus, who had come to him in his third year at 
 Rome, Plotinus now, in the six years that Porphyry was with 
 him, wrote twenty-four more books. The procedure was as 
 before ; the books taking their starting-point from the questions 
 that occurred 4 . While Porphyry was in Sicily, whither he had 
 retired about 268, Plotinus sent him in all nine more books. 
 
 1 Cicero treats the direction of Epicurus that his birthday should be 
 celebrated after his death as a weakness in a philosopher. De Fin. ii. 31, 102 : 
 " Haec non erant eius, qui inuumerabilis mundos infinitasque regiones, quarum 
 nulla esset ora, nulla extremitas, mente peragravisset." In the last two words 
 there is an evident allusion to Lucr. i. 74. 
 
 2 Porph. Vita Plotini, 2. 
 
 3 Vitae Philoaophorum ac Sophist arum (Plotinus). 
 
 * V. Plot. 5 : 4k irpocTKaipwv Trpo(3\T)/xdTwv raj inro94o'eis XapovTa, 
 
30 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 In 270, during this absence, Plotinus died in Campania. After 
 his death, Amelius consulted the Delphic oracle on his lot, and 
 received a response placing him among the happy daemons, 
 which Porphyry transcribes in full 1 . 
 
 Among the hearers of Plotinus, as Porphyry relates, were 
 not a few senators. Of these was Rogatianus, who carried 
 philosophic detachment so far as to give up all his possessions, 
 dismiss all his slaves, and resign his senatorial rank. Having 
 before suffered severely from the gout, he now, under the 
 abstemious rule of life he adopted, completely recovered 2 . To 
 Plotinus were entrusted many wards of both sexes, to the 
 interests of whose property he carefully attended. During the 
 twenty-six years of his residence at Rome, he acted as umpire 
 in a great number of disputes, which he was able to settle 
 without ever exciting enmity. Porphyry gives some examples 
 of his insight into character, and takes this occasion to explain 
 the reason of his own retirement into Sicily. Plotinus had 
 detected him meditating suicide ; and, perceiving that the 
 cause was only a " disease of melancholy," persuaded him to go 
 away for a time 3 . One or two marvellous stories are told in 
 order to illustrate the power Plotinus had of resisting malignant 
 influences, and the divine protection he was under 4 . He was 
 especially honoured by the Emperor Gallienus 5 and his wife 
 Salonina, and was almost permitted to carry out a project of 
 restoring a ruined city in Campania, — said to have been once a 
 "city of philosophers 6 ," — which he was to govern according to 
 the Platonic Laws, giving it the name of " Platonopolis 7 ." The 
 fortunes of the scheme are curiously recalled by those of 
 Berkeley's projected university in the Bermudas. 
 
 At the time of this project, Plotinus must have been 
 already engaged in the composition of his philosophical books. 
 
 1 V. Plot. 22. - Ibid. 7. 
 
 3 Ibid. 11. * Ibid. 10. 
 
 5 Gallienus tolerated Christianity. He was a man of considerable accom- 
 plishments, though the historians do not speak highly of him as a ruler. 
 
 6 This apparently means, as has been conjectured (R. P. 508 f.), that it had 
 formerly been ruled by a Pythagorean society. 
 
 » V. Plot. 12. 
 
IV ] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 31 
 
 As Porphyry relates, no external demands on his attention, 
 with whatever good will and practical success he might respond 
 to them, could break the continuity of his meditations, which 
 he had always the power to resume exactly at the point where 
 he had left off. Of the characteristics of his lecturing, his 
 disciple gives a sympathetic picture 1 . He did not care for 
 personal controversy ; as was shown by his commissioning his 
 pupils to reply to attacks on his positions. Porphyry mentions 
 a case in which he himself was set to answer an unedifying 
 discourse of the rhetor Diophanes 2 . The books of Plotinus, 
 as we have seen, were not composed on any general plan. 
 Porphyry relates that, through a weakness of the eyes, he 
 never read over again what he had once written. His gram- 
 matical knowledge of Greek remained imperfect, and the 
 revision as well as editing of his writings was committed to 
 Porphyry, from whom proceeds the arrangement of the six 
 " Enneads," — the name the fifty- four books received from their 
 ordering in groups of nine. While he worked in this irregular 
 way, the character of his thought was extremely systematic. 
 He evidently possessed his doctrine as a whole from the time 
 when he began to write. Yet in detail, even to the very last 
 books, in which Porphyry thought he observed a decline of 
 power, he has always something effectively new to add. 
 
 In addition to the grouping according to subjects, which he 
 adopted for his arrangement of the Enneads as we have them, 
 Porphyry has put on record an alternative ordering which may 
 be taken as at least approximately chronological. The chrono- 
 logical order is certain as regards the succession of the main 
 groups. Of these there are three, or, more exactly, four ; the 
 third group being divided into two sub-groups. At the begin- 
 ning of the second main group also the order of four books is 
 certain. For the rest, Porphyry does not definitely state that 
 the books are all in chronological order; but, as his general 
 
 1 V. Plot. 13 : t\v 5' (v tw Xeyeiv r\ 2v5eii;is tov vov &XP 1 T °v TpocwTrov olvtov ri> 
 0uis imXapurovTOS ' ipa.afj.ios fitv 6<pdijvai, koXXIuv 5k t6t€ fidXto-ra bpuifxivos' icai 
 \€7tt6s ns iSptlis ewidei nai r\ irpq.bT-q 1 ; ouXa/XTre ko.1 rb Trpoo-qvts Trpbs to.% ipwrrjcreis 
 ioeinvvTO Kal rb evrovov. 
 
 - Ibid. 15. 
 
I 
 
 32 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 arrangement in this enumeration is chronological, we may take 
 it that he carried it through in detail as far as he could ; and, 
 as a matter of fact, links of association can often be detected 
 in passing consecutively from one book to another. For 
 reading, I have found this order on the whole more convenient 
 than the actual grouping of the Enneads. 
 
 When the books are read in this chronological order, the 
 psychological starting-point of the system becomes particularly 
 obvious, the main positions about the soul coming early in the 
 series. In the exposition that is to follow 1 , these will be set 
 forth first. After Psychology will come Metaphysics, then in 
 succession Cosmology (with Theodicy), Aesthetics and Ethics 2 . 
 A separate chapter will be devoted to the Mysticism of Plotinus 3 . 
 For this order of exposition support might be found in what 
 Plotinus himself says, where he points out that from the 
 doctrine of the soul, as from a centre, we can equally ascend 
 and descend 4 . 
 
 Before beginning the exposition, an attempt must be made 
 to ascertain the points of contact furnished to Plotinus by those 
 nearest him in time. His general relation to his predecessors 
 is on the whole clear, but not the details. Of the teachings 
 of his Alexandrian master, nothing trustworthy is recorded. 
 Ammonius left nothing written, and the short accounts pre- 
 served of his doctrine come from writers too late to have had 
 any real means of knowing. What those writers do is to 
 ascribe to him the reasoned positions of Plotinus, or even the 
 special aims of still later thinkers contemporary with them- 
 selves. Porphyry, in a passage quoted by Eusebius, mentions 
 that Ammonius had been brought up as a Christian, but, as 
 soon as he came in contact with philosophy, returned to the 
 religion publicly professed. He is spoken of as a native of 
 Alexandria ; and the name " Saccas " is explained by his having 
 been originally a porter (5a/c/ca<? being equivalent to craicico- 
 (f)6pos). Hierocles calls him " the divinely taught" (0€oBiBaKTo<;). 
 
 1 See ch. v. 
 
 2 Eoughly, this corresponds to the order : — Enn. iv. v. vi. n. in. i. 
 
 3 See ch. vi. 4 Enn. iv. 3, 1. 
 
IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 33 
 
 Besides Plotinus he had as pupils Longinus the famous critic 1 , 
 Origen the Christian, and another Origen. With this Origen 
 and a fellow-student named Herennius, Plotinus is said to have 
 entered into a compact that none of them should divulge 
 the doctrine of Ammonius. The compact was first broken by 
 Herennius, then by Origen ; lastly Plotinus thought himself 
 at liberty to expound the master's doctrine orally. Not for ten 
 more years did he begin to write 2 . Evidently this, even if 
 accepted, does little towards explaining the source of the 
 written doctrine of Plotinus, — in which there is no reference 
 to Ammonius, — and Zeller throws doubt on the whole story :i , 
 regarding it as suspiciously like what is related about a similar 
 compact among the early Pythagoreans. It is to be observed 
 that Porphyry does not say that he had it directly from 
 Plotinus. 
 
 What is clear is this, that from Ammonius Plotinus must 
 have received some impulse which was of great importance for 
 his intellectual development. In the class-room of Plotinus, 
 we learn from Porphyry 4 , the later Platonic and Aristotelian 
 commentators were read ; but everywhere an original turn was 
 given to the discussions, into which Plotinus carried the spirit 
 of Ammonius. This probably indicates with sufficient clearness 
 the real state of the case. Ammonius was one of those teachers 
 who have the power of stirring up independent thought along 
 a certain line ; but he was not himself the formative mind 
 of the movement. The general line of thought was already 
 marked out. Neither Ammonius nor Plotinus had to create 
 an audience. A large section of the philosophical world had 
 for long been dissatisfied with the Stoic, no less than with the 
 Epicurean, dogmatism. The opposition was partly sceptical, 
 partly Neo-Pythagorean and Platonic. The sceptical opposition 
 was represented first by the New Academy, as we see in Cicero ; 
 afterwards by the revived Pyrrhonism of Aenesidemus and 
 
 1 The Ilept'Ti/'ous, formerly attributed to Longinus, is now generally ascribed 
 to some unknown writer of the first century. See the edition by Prof. W. Rhys 
 Roberts (1899), who, however, points out that in its spirit it is such a work as 
 might very well have proceeded from the historical Longinus. 
 
 2 Porph. V. Plot. 3. a hi. 2, p. 452. 4 V. Plot. 14. 
 
 w. 3 
 
34 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 Sextus. In Cicero we see also, set against both Epicureanism 
 and Stoicism as a more positive kind of opposition, a sort of 
 eclectic combination of Platonic and Peripatetic positions. A 
 later stage of this movement is represented by Plutarch ; when 
 Platonism, though not yet assuming systematic form, is already 
 more metaphysical or "theological," and less predominantly 
 ethical, than the eclecticism of Cicero's time. On its positive 
 side the movement gained strength in proportion as the 
 sceptical attack weakened the prevailing dogmatic schools. 
 These at the same time ceased to give internal satisfaction, 
 as we perceive in the melancholy tone of Marcus Aurelius. 
 By the end of the second century, the new positive current was 
 by far the strongest ; but no thinker of decisive originality had 
 appeared, at least on the line of Greek thought. In Plotinus 
 was now to appear the greatest individual thinker between 
 Aristotle and Descartes. Under the attraction of his systema- 
 tising intellect, all that remained of aspiration after an inde- 
 pendent philosophy was rallied to a common centre. Essentially, 
 the explanation of the change is to be found in his individual 
 power. Yet he had his precursors as well as his teachers. 
 There were two thinkers at least who, however little they may 
 have influenced him, anticipated some of his positions. 
 
 The first was Philo of Alexandria, who was born about 
 30 B.C., and died later than a.d. 40. The second was Numenius 
 of Apamea, who is said to have flourished between 160 and 
 180 a.d. Philo was pretty certainly unknown to Plotinus. 
 Numenius was read in his class-room ; but his disciple Amelius 
 wrote a treatise, dedicated to Porphyry, in which, replying to 
 an accusation of plagiarism, he pointed out the differences 
 between their master's teaching and that of Numenius. 
 Amelius, it may be remarked, had acquired a great reputation 
 by his thorough knowledge of the writings of Numenius. 
 Porphyry cites also the testimony of Longinus. The judgment 
 of the eminent critic was for the unquestionable originality of 
 Plotinus among the philosophers of his own and the preceding 
 age 1 . In what that originality consisted, Plotinus, who spoke 
 
 1 Longinus ap. Porph. V. Plot. 20: ol 8e...Tp6wip Oeupias Idly XPW*M V0 <- 
 H\uTlvb% dai koX Tei>Ti\t.ai>ds 'A/At\ios,...ov5e yap ov8' iyyis ti to, Novfirjvlov ko.1 
 
IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 35 
 
 of him as " a philologist but by no means a philosopher," might 
 not have allowed his competence to decide. He himself con- 
 fessed that he did not understand some treatises of Plotinus 
 that were sent to him. What he ascribes to him in the 
 passage quoted by Porphyry is simply a more accurate mode 
 of interpreting the Pythagorean and Platonic principles than 
 had been attempted by others who took the same general 
 direction. This, however, only renders his judgment the more 
 decisive as to the impression Plotinus made in spite of the 
 difficulties of his style. 
 
 To make clear what doctrines of Plotinus were anticipated, 
 the principles of his metaphysics must be stated in brief pre- 
 liminary outline. Of the causes above the visible world, he 
 placed highest of all the One beyond thought and being. To 
 the One, in the Neo-Platonic philosophy, the name of God is 
 applicable in a peculiar manner. Everything after it that is 
 called divine is regarded as derivative. Next in order, as the 
 effect of the Cause and Principle, comes the di vine Mind, 
 identical with the " intelligible world " which is its object. 
 Last in the order of supramundane causes comes the Soul of 
 the whole, produced by Mind. Thence the descent is to the 
 world of particular souls and changing things. The series 
 composed of the primal One, the divine Mind, and the Soul 
 of the whole, is sometimes called the " Neo-Platonic Trinity 1 ." 
 Now Numenius put forth the idea of a Trinity which in one 
 point resembles that of Plotinus. 
 
 According to Proclus, Numenius distinguished "three Gods." 
 The first he called the Father, the second the Maker, while the 
 third was the World, or that which is made*. The point of 
 
 Kpoviov teal ~Si.obipa.Tov ko.1 QpacuWov tois TIKojtlvov irepl rCiv o.vtG>v crvyypd/xfj.aaii' 
 efs aKpifiaav ■ 6 b~t 'A/uAtos kixt' lx vr l ^ v toutov ^adl^eiv Trpoaipovfievos nai to. ttoWo. 
 /dv tCjv avTwv doy/xaTdiv ix^ > f JLel ' 0S i T V & e^epyaaia iro\vs uv...wv ko.1 fxdvuv i]/xets 
 a^tov elva.i vofdfofiev iirwKOTreio-dcu to. o~vyypdfj./j.a.Ta. 
 
 1 It is of course inexact to speak of a first, second and third "Person" in the 
 Trinity of Plotinus. Even the generalised term "hypostasis" is more strictly 
 applicable in Christian than in Neo-Platonic theology, as Vacherot points out. 
 See Histoire Critique de VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. p. 425 n. 
 
 2 Comm. in Tim. p. 93. (R. P. 506 a ; Zeller, iii. 2, p. 220, n. 6.) Tror^a 
 fj.€V KaKel rbv irpQrrov, noir]Tr]v 8e t'ov SevTepov, iroirip\a 8Z rbv rplrov ' 6 yap Kdcrfxos 
 /car' avrbv 6 rpiros iarl Beds. 
 
 3—2 
 
 
36 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 resemblance here to Plotinus is the distinction of " the first 
 God " from the Platonic Demiurgus, signified by " the Maker." 
 With Numenius, however, the first God is Being and Mind ; 
 not, as with Plotinus, a principle beyond these. Zeller remarks 
 that, since a similar distinction of the highest God from the 
 Creator of the world appears before Numenius in the Christian 
 Gnostics, among whom the Valentinians adopted the name 
 " Demiurgus " from Plato, it was probably from them that 
 Numenius got the hint for his theory ; and that in addition 
 Philo's theory of the Logos doubtless influenced him 1 . To this 
 accordingly we must turn as possibly the original starting-point 
 for the Neo-Platonic doctrine. 
 
 With Philo, the Logos is the principle that mediates be- 
 tween the supreme God and the world formed out of matter 
 Essentially the conception is of Greek origin, being taken 
 directly from the Stoics, who got at least the suggestion of it 
 from Heraclitus 2 . Philo regards the Logos as containing the 
 Ideas in accordance with which the visible world was formed. 
 By this Platonising turn, it becomes in the end a different 
 conception from the divine " Reason " of the Stoics, embodied 
 as that is in the material element of fire. On the other hand, 
 by placing the Platonic Ideas in the divine Mind, Philo inter- 
 prets Plato in a sense which many scholars, both in antiquity 
 and in modern times, have refused to allow. Here Plotinus 
 coincides with Philo. Among those who dissented from this 
 view was Longinus. Porphyry, who, before he came to Rome, 
 had been the pupil of Longinus at Athens, was not without 
 difficulty brought over, by controversy with Amelius, to the 
 view of Plotinus, " that intelligibles do not exist outside in- 
 tellect 3 ." Thus by Plotinus as by Philo the cause and principle 
 of things is distinguished from the reason or intellect which is 
 its proximate effect ; and, in the interpretation of Plato, the 
 divine mind is regarded as containing the ideas, whereas in the 
 
 1 iii. 2, p. 219, n. 3. 
 
 2 See, for the detailed genealogy of the conception, Principal Drummond's 
 Philo Judaeus, vol. i. 
 
 3 V. Plot. 18. The position which he had adopted from Longinus was on 
 
 £i;W TOV VOV il<pt<JTT)K€ TO. VQ-qTO.. 
 
IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 37 
 
 Timaeus they are figured as existing outside the mind of the 
 
 Demiurgus. On the other hand, Plotinus differs both from 
 
 Philo and from the Gnostics in consistently treating as mythical 
 
 the representation of a maker setting out from a certain 
 
 moment of time to shape things according to a pattern out 
 
 of pre-existent matter. And, in spite of his agreement with 
 
 Philo up to a certain point, there is nothing to show that their 
 
 views were historically connected. Against the attempt to 
 
 connect Plotinus, or even Numenius, with Philo, a strong point 
 
 is urged by Dr Bigg. Neither Plotinus nor Numenius, as he 
 
 points out, ever uses Xo'709 as a technical term for the " second 
 
 hypostasis 1 ." Yet, if they had derived their theory from Philo, 
 
 this is evidently what they would have done ; for the Philonian 
 
 X070?, on the philosophical side, was not alien from Greek 
 
 thought, but was a genuine product of it. In truth, to adapt the 
 
 conception to their own systems by means of a change of name, 
 
 would have been more difficult than to arrive at their actual 
 
 terminology directly by combining Stoical and Aristotelian 
 
 positions with their Platonism. This kind of combination is 
 
 what we find in the eclectic thinkers, of whom Numenius was 
 
 one. Plotiuus made use of the same elements ; the presence of 
 
 which in his system Porphyry has expressly noted 2 . And, so 
 
 far as the relation of the Neo-Platonic Trinity to Plato is 
 
 concerned, the exact derivation of the three " hypostases " is 
 
 pointed out in a fragment of Porphyry's lost History of 
 
 Philosophy 3 . The highest God, we there learn, is the Idea of 
 
 1 See Xeoplatonism, pp. 123, 242, etc. Dr Bigg's actual assertions seem too 
 sweeping. It is not quite correct to say, as he does in the second of the passages 
 referred to, that Plotinus expressly refuses to apply to his principle of Intelli- 
 gence the title Logos, which in his system means, as with the Stoics, " little 
 more than physical force." There are indeed passages where he refuses to apply 
 the title in some special reference ; but elsewhere — as in Enn. v. 1, 6 — he says 
 that Soul is the \670s of Mind, and Mind the \6yos of the One. While the term 
 with him has many applications, and among them the Stoical application to 
 the "seminal reasons" of natural things, it may most frequently be rendered by 
 " rational law." 
 
 - V. Plot. 14 : e/AfjLepu.KTa.1 8' ev rots <rvyypdfx/xaaL Kal ra -tuiko. \av6dvovra 
 doy/jLara Kal to. HepnraTrjTiKa' K<xTawtirvKv<jiTcu 6e Kal r/ juera rd (pvaiKa roi 
 AptcrroreXouy wpayfj-areia. 
 
 3 Fragm. 16 in Nauck's Opi/triilo Selecta. 
 
38 PLOTINUS [IV 
 
 the Good in the Republic ; the second and third hypostases are 
 the Demiurgus and the Soul of the World in the Timaeus. To 
 explain the triadic form of such speculations, no theory of 
 individual borrowing on any side is necessary. All the thinkers 
 of the period, whether Hellenic, Jewish or Christian, had grown 
 up in an atmosphere of Neo-Pythagorean speculation about 
 numbers, for which the triad was of peculiar significance 1 . 
 Thus on the whole it seems that Numenius and Plotinus drew 
 independently from sources common to them with Philo, but 
 cannot well have been influenced by him. 
 
 Plotinus, as we have seen, had some knowledge of Numenius ; 
 but, where a special point of contact has been sought, the 
 difference is as obvious as the resemblance. The great differ- 
 ence, however, is not in any detail of the triadic theory. It is 
 that Plotinus was able to bring all the elements of his system 
 under the direction of an organising thought. That thought 
 was a definitely conceived immaterialist monism which, so far 
 as we know, neither Philo nor Numenius had done anything 
 substantially to anticipate. He succeeded in clearly developing 
 out of Plato the conception of incorporeal essence, which his 
 precursors had rather tended by their eclecticism to confuse. 
 That the conception was in Plato, the Neo-Platonists would 
 have not only admitted but strongly maintained. Yet Plato's 
 metaphorical expressions had misled even Aristotle, who 
 seriously thought that he found presupposed in them a spatial 
 extension of the soul 2 . And if Aristotle had got rid of semi- 
 materialistic " animism " even in expression, this had not 
 prevented his successors from running into a new materialism 
 of their own. Much as the Platonising schools had all along 
 protested against the tendency to make the soul a kind of body 
 or an outcome of body, they had not hitherto overcome it by 
 clear definitions and distinctions. This is one thing that 
 
 1 Jules Simon, in his Histoire de VEcole d' Alexandria, dwells on this point 
 as an argument against the view, either that Neo-Platonism borrowed its Trinity 
 from Christianity or Christianity from Neo-Platonism. 
 
 2 Proclus wrote a book to defend Plato's view of the soul against Aristotle's 
 attack. 
 
IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 39 
 
 Plotinus and his successors achieved in their effort after an 
 idealist metaphysic. 
 
 It was on this side especially that the thought of the school 
 influenced the Fathers and Doctors of the Church. On the 
 specific dogmas of Christian theology, Neo-Platonism probably 
 exercised little influence. From Platonising Judaism or 
 Christianity, it received none at all. At most an isolated 
 expression occurs showing that the antipathy to alien religions 
 was not so unqualified as to prevent appreciation, for example, 
 of the Platonism in the Fourth Gospel. Numenius, it is 
 interesting to note, was one of the few earlier writers who 
 attach themselves to the Hellenic tradition and yet show 
 traces of sympathetic contact with Hebraic religion. He it 
 was who called Plato " a Moses writing Attic 1 ." On the other 
 side Philo, though by faith a Jew, was as a philosopher 
 essentially Greek both in thought and in terminology. What 
 divided him from the Hellenic thinkers was simply his ac- 
 ceptance of formal limitations on thought prescribed by a 
 positive religion. 
 
 In concluding the present chapter, a word may be said on 
 the literary style of Plotinus, and on the temper of himself and 
 his school in relation to life. His writing is admittedly difficult ; 
 yet it is not wanting in beautiful passages that leave an 
 impression even of facility. He is in general, as Porphyry says, 
 concentrated, " abounding more in thoughts than in words." 
 The clearness of his systematic thought has been recognised by 
 expositors in spite of obscurities in detail ; and the obscurities 
 often disappear with close study. On the thought when it 
 comes in contact with life is impressed the character of ethical 
 purity and inwardness which always continued to mark the 
 school. At the same time, there is a return to the Hellenic 
 love of beauty and knowledge for themselves. Stoical elements 
 are incorporated, but the exaggerated " tension " of Stoicism 
 
 1 Suid. and Clem. Strom. (R. P. 7 b, 504.) ri yap 4<ttl IW&tuv t) M«wi)s 
 irrudfuv ; Longinus, as we have seen, had enough knowledge of Numenius to 
 compare him with Plotinus. This being so, it is certainly a rather remarkable 
 coincidence, if the treatise On the Sublime was not written by Longinus, that in 
 it also there should be an admiring reference to " the legislator of the Jews." 
 
40 PLOTINUS AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS [iV 
 
 has disappeared. While the Neo-Platonists are more con- 
 sistently ascetic than the Stoics, there is nothing harsh or 
 repulsive in their asceticism. The ascetic life was for them not 
 a mode of self-torture, but the means to a happiness which on 
 the whole they succeeded in attaining. Perhaps the explanation 
 is that they had restored the idea of theoretic virtue, against 
 the too narrowly practical tone of the preceding schools. Hence 
 abstinence from the ordinary objects of pursuit left no blank. 
 It was not felt as a deprivation, but as a source of power to 
 think and feel. And in thinking they knew that indirectly 
 they were acting. For theory, with them, is the remoter source 
 of all practice, which bears to it the relation of the outward 
 effect to the inward cause. 
 
CHAPTER V. 
 
 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM OF PLOTINUS. 
 
 As idealists and their opponents alike recognise, one great 
 stumbling-block of an idealist philosophy is language. This 
 was seen by Plato, by Plotinus, and by Berkeley, just as from 
 the other side it is seen by the materialist and the dualist. 
 Language was formed primarily to indicate the things of sense, 
 and these have not the characters which idealism, whether 
 ancient or modern, ascribes to reality. Ancient idealism refuses 
 to call external things real in the full sense, because they are in 
 flux. The reality is the fixed mental concept or its unchanging 
 intelligible object. Modern idealism regards things as merely 
 " phenomenal," because they appear to a consciousness, and be- 
 yond this appearance have no definable reality. Whether reality 
 itself is fixed or changing, may by the modern idealist be left 
 undetermined ; but at any rate the groups of perceptions that 
 make up the " objects " of daily experience and even of science 
 are not, in his view, objects existing in themselves apart from 
 mind, and known truly as such. Only by some relation to mind 
 can reality be constituted. The way in which language opposes 
 itself to ancient idealism is by its implication that existence 
 really changes. To modern idealism it opposes itself by its 
 tendency to treat external things as absolute objects with a real 
 existence apart from that of all thinking subjects. 
 
 The two forms of developed idealism here regarded as 
 typically ancient and modern are the earliest and the latest — 
 that of Plato on the one side, that of post-Cartesian, and still 
 
42 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v 
 
 more of post-Kantian, thinkers on the other. The idealism of 
 Plotinus contains elements that bring it into relation with both. 
 English readers know how Berkeley insists that, if we are to 
 grasp his doctrine, we must attend to the meanings he desires 
 to convey, and must not dwell on the mere form of expression. 
 Let us see how Plato and Plotinus deal with the same difficulty. 
 
 Plato's treatment of it may be most readily studied in the 
 Gratylus. Language, Socrates undertakes to show, has a certain 
 natural conformity to things named. To those who named 
 them, external things mostly presented themselves as in flux. 
 Accordingly, words are full of devices by the makers of language 
 for expressing gliding and flowing movements. With a little 
 ingenuity and an occasional evasion, those who hold that the 
 true nature of everything is to flow and not to be in any 
 manner fixed, might exhibit the early legislators over human 
 speech as in exact agreement with their philosophical opinions. 
 Yet after all there are some words, though fewer, that appear 
 at first sight to express stability. So that the primitive 
 legislators were not, on the face of things, perfectly consistent. 
 On the whole, however, words suggesting flux predominate. 
 Similarly the early myth-makers, in their derivation of all things 
 from Ocean and Tethys, seem to have noticed especially the 
 fact of change in the world. The Heracliteans, therefore, have 
 the advantage in the appeal to language and mythology. Still, 
 their Eleatic opponents may be right philosophically. The 
 makers of language and myth may have framed words and 
 imagined the origin of things in accordance with what is 
 apparent but not real. Real existence in itself may be stable. 
 If this is so, then, to express philosophic thought accurately, it 
 will be necessary to reform language. In the meantime, the 
 proper method in all our inquiries and reasonings must be, to 
 attend to things rather than words. 
 
 According to the Platonic doctrine, the " place of ideas " is 
 the soul 1 . In virtue of its peculiar relations to those stable 
 and permanent existences known by intellect, the individual 
 soul is itself permanent. It gives unity, motion and life to the 
 
 1 Arist. Be An. iii. 4, 429 a 27. (R. P. 251 c.) 
 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 43 
 
 fluent aggregate of material particles forming its temporary 
 body. It disappears from one body and reappears in another, 
 existing apart in the intervals between its mortal lives. Thus 
 by Plato the opposition of soul and body is brought, as a 
 subordinate relation, under the more general opposition of the 
 stable ideas — the existence of which is not purely and simply 
 in the soul, but is also in some way transcendent — and the flux 
 of material existence. For Plotinus, this subordinate opposition 
 has become the starting-point. He does not dismiss the earlier 
 antithesis ; but the main problem with him is not to find 
 permanence somewhere as against absolute flux. He allows in 
 the things of sense also a kind of permanence. His aim is first 
 of all to prove that the soul has a real existence of its own, 
 distinguished from body and corporeal modes of being. For 
 in the meantime body as such — and no longer, as with the 
 Heracliteans, a process of the whole — had been set up by the 
 dominant schools as the absolute reality. By the Epicureans 
 and Stoics, everything that can be spoken of at all was regarded 
 as body, or a quality or relation of body, or else as having no 
 being other than "nominal." The main point of attack for 
 scepticism had been the position common to the naturalistic 
 schools, that external things can be known by direct appre- 
 hension as they really are. Neither the Academical nor the 
 Pyrrhouist scepticism, however, had taken the place of the 
 ruling dogmatic system, which was that of the Stoics. Thus 
 the doctrine that Plotinus had to meet was still essentially 
 materialism, made by the sceptical attack less sure of itself, but 
 not dethroned. 
 
 The method he adopts is to insist precisely on the para- 
 doxical character of the soul's existence as contrasted with that 
 of corporeal things. How specious is the view of his opponents 
 he allows. Body can be seen and touched. It resists pressure 
 and is spread out in space. Soul is invisible and intangible, 
 and by its very definition unextended. Thus language has to 
 be struggled with in the attempt to describe it ; and in the 
 end can only be made to express the nature of soul by con- 
 straining it to purposes for which most men never think of 
 employing it. What is conclusive, however, as against the 
 
44 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 materialistic view, is that the soul cannot be described at all 
 except by phrases which would be nonsensical if applied 
 to body or its qualities, or to determinations of particular 
 bodies. Once the conception of soul has been fixed as that 
 of an incorporeal reality, body is seen to admit of a kind of 
 explanation in terms of soul — from which it derives its " form " 
 — whereas the essential nature of soul admitted of no explana- 
 tion in terms of body. 
 
 Above soul and beneath body, as we shall see, Plotinus has 
 other principles, derived from earlier metaphysics, by which he 
 is able to construct a complete philosophy, and not merely 
 what would be called in modern phrase a " rational psychology." 
 His psychology, however, is the centre. Within the soul, he 
 finds all the metaphysical principles in some way represented. 
 In it are included the principles of unity, of pure intellect, of 
 moving and vitalising power, and, in some sense, of matter itself. 
 Further, by what may be called his " empirical psychology," 
 he prepared the starting-point for the distinctively modern 
 " theory of knowledge." This he did, as Prof. Siebeck has 
 shown 1 , by the new precision he gave to the conception of 
 consciousness. On this side he reaches forward to Descartes, 
 as on the other side he looks back to Plato and Aristotle. 
 
 1. Psychology. 
 
 It is absurd, or rather impossible, says Plotinus at the 
 opening of one of his earliest expositions 2 , that life should be 
 the product of an aggregation of bodies, or that things without 
 understanding should generate mind. If, as some say, the soul 
 is a permeating air with a certain habitude (Trvev/Aavrm exov) 
 — and it cannot be air simply, for there are innumerable airs 
 without life — then the habitude (7rm exov or exeats) is either 
 a mere name, and there is really nothing but the " breath," or 
 it is a kind of being (rtov ovtiov ri). In the latter case, it is a 
 rational principle and of another nature than body (\0709 av 
 etrj Ti9 >cal ou awfia ical <j>vai<; erepa). If the soul were matter, 
 it could produce only the effects of the particular kind of 
 
 1 Geschichte der Psychologie, i. 2. 2 E1111. iv. 7. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 45 
 
 matter that it is — giving things its own quality, hot or cold, 
 and so forth — not all the opposite effects actually produced in 
 the organism. The soul is not susceptible of quantitative 
 increase or diminution, or of division. Thus it has not the 
 characters of a thing possessing quantity (airoaov apa ?; yfrv-^v)- 
 The unity in perception would be impossible if that which 
 perceives consisted of parts spatially separated. It is impossible 
 that the mental perception, for example, of a pain in the finger, 
 should be transmitted from the "animal spirit" (yfrv^iKov 
 nrv€vp,a) of the finger to the ruling part (to rjyep,ovovi>) in the 
 organism. For, in that case, there must either be accumu- 
 lated an infinity of perceptions, or each intermediate part in 
 succession must feel the pain only in itself, and not in the 
 parts previously affected ; and so also the ruling part when it 
 becomes affected in its turn. That there can be no such 
 physical transmission as is supposed of a mental perception, 
 results from the very nature of material mass, which consists 
 of parts each standing by itself: one part can have no know- 
 ledge of what is suffered by another part. Consequently we 
 must assume a percipient which is everywhere identical with 
 itself. Such a percipient must be another kind of being than 
 body. That which thinks can still less be body than that which 
 perceives. For even if it is not allowed that thought is the 
 laying hold on intelligibles without the use of any bodily organ, 
 yet there are certainly involved in it apprehensions of things 
 without magnitude (ap,eye6wv avTikifaeLs). Such are abstract 
 conceptions, as for example those of the beautiful and the just. 
 How then can that which is a magnitude think that which is 
 not ? Must we suppose it to think the indivisible with that in 
 itself which is divisible ? If it can think it at all, it must rather 
 be with some indivisible part of itself. That which thinks, 
 then, cannot be body. For the supposed thinking body has no 
 function as an extended whole (and to be such is its nature as 
 body), since it cannot as a whole come in contact with an object 
 that is incorporeal. 
 
 The soul in relation to the body, according to Plotinus's own 
 mode of statement, is "all in all and all in every part 1 ." Thus 
 
 ^Enn. iv. 2, 1. 
 
46 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 it is in a sense divisible because it is in all the parts of a 
 divisible body. Properly it is indivisible because it is all in 
 the whole and all in each part of it. Its unity is unlike that 
 of a body, which is one by spatial continuity, having different 
 parts each of which is in a different place ; and unlike that of a 
 quality of body such as colour, which can be wholly in many 
 discontinuous bodies. In the case of a quality, that which is 
 the same in all portions of body that possess it in common 
 is an affection (Trddrj^a), and not an essence (ova la). Its 
 identity is formal, and not numerical, as is the case with the 
 soul 1 . 
 
 In this general argumentation, it will be observed, Plotinus 
 starts from the supposition that the body has a reality other 
 than phenomenal. Allowing this, he is able to demonstrate 
 against his opponents that a reality of a different kind from 
 that of body must also be assumed. In his metaphysics he 
 goes further, and reduces corporeal things in effect to pheno- 
 mena ; but in his psychology he continues to take a view 
 nearer that of "common-sense." Thus he is confronted with 
 the difficulties that have since become familiar about the 
 "connexion of body and mind," and the possibility of their 
 interaction. He lays bare in a single saying the root of all 
 such difficulties. How if, in talking of a "mixture" of a 
 corporeal with an incorporeal nature, we should be trying to 
 realise an impossibility, as if one should say that linear magni- 
 tude is mixed with whiteness' 2 ? The solution for psychology 
 is found in the theory that the soul itself remains " unmixed " 
 in spite of its union with body; but that it causes the pro- 
 duction of a " common " or " dual " or " composite " nature, 
 
 1 Cf. Erin. vi. 4, 1. The peculiar relation of the soul, in itself indivisible, to 
 the body, in itself divisible, and so communicating a kind of divisibility to the 
 soul, Plotinus finds indicated by the "divine enigma" of the " mixture" in the 
 Tiviaeus. Enn. iv. 2, 2: tovto &pa earl rb ddws riviy^ivov 'ttJs d/xeplarov K<xl del 
 Kara to. avra exovaijs [ovaias] kclI ttjs irepl rd auifxara yiyvoixivqs fxeptaTTJs rpirov e| 
 dfj.<pdii> cweKep&aaTO ovaias eldos.' 
 
 - Enn. i. 1, 4 : ftr-qTeov di Kal rbv rpdvov tt)s /u£ews, /xriTrore ov Swards rj, 
 w<nrep dv e'i tis X^yoi /x€/j,lx^ al - Aei/K^ ypa-whv, <pucriv dWrjv aXXij. This book, 
 though coming first in Porphyry's arrangement according to subjects, is given 
 as the last but one in the chronological order. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 47 
 
 which is the subject in perception. By the aid of this inter- 
 mediary, the unity of the soul is reconciled — though not 
 without perplexities in detail — with localisation of the organic 
 functions that subserve its activity. 
 
 The different parts of the animated body participate in the 
 soul's powers in different ways 1 . According as each organ of 
 sense is fitted for one special function, a particular power of 
 perception may be said to be there ; the power of sight in the 
 eyes, of hearing in the ears, of smell in the nostrils, of taste in 
 the tongue, of touch everywhere. Since the primary organs of 
 touch are the nerves, which have also the power of animal 
 motion, and since the nerves take their origin from the brain, 
 in the brain may be placed the starting-point of the actual 
 exercise of all powers of perception and movement. Above 
 perception is reason. This power has not properly a physical 
 organ at all, and so is not really in the head ; but it was 
 assigned to the head by the older writers because it com- 
 municates directly with the psychical functions of which the 
 brain is the central organ. For these last, as Plotinus remarks, 
 have a certain community with reason. In perception there is 
 a kind of judgment ; and on reason together with the imagina- 
 tion derived from perception, impulse follows. 
 
 Tn making the brain central among the organs that are in 
 special relation with mind, Plotinus of course adopts the 
 Platonic as against the Aristotelian position, which made the 
 heart central. At the same time, he incorporates what had 
 since been discovered about the special functions of the nervous 
 system, which were unknown to Aristotle as to Plato. The 
 vegetative power of the soul he places in relation with the 
 liver, because here is the origin of the veins and the blood 
 in the veins, by means of which that power causes the nourish- 
 ment of the body. Hence, as with Plato, appetite is assigned 
 to this region. Spirited emotion, in accordance with the 
 Platonic psychology, has its seat in the breast, where is the 
 spring of lighter and purer blood. 
 
 Both perceptions and memories are " energies " or activities, 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 3, 23. 
 
48 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 not mere passive impressions received and stored up in the 
 soul 1 . Take first the case of the most distinct perception. 
 In sight, when we wish to perceive anything clearly, we direct 
 our vision in a straight line to the object. This outwardly 
 directed activity would not be necessary if the object simply 
 left its impression on the soul. Were this the whole process, 
 we should see not the outward objects of vision, but images 
 and shadows of them ; so that what we see would be other than 
 the things themselves {ware ciXka fieu ehai avrd rd irpdy/xaTa, 
 aXXa 8e ra r)p2v opwfxeva). In hearing as in sight, perceptions 
 are energies, not impressions nor yet passive states (fii) tvttol, 
 /j.r)S€ irelae^). The impression is an articulated stroke in the 
 air, on which it is as if letters were written by that which 
 makes the sound. The power of the soul as it were reads 
 those impressions. In the case of taste and smell, the passive 
 affections (irddr}) are one thing ; the perceptions and judgments 
 of them are another. Memory of things is produced by exercise 
 of the soul, either generally or in relation to a special class of 
 them. Children remember better because they have fewer 
 things to attend to. Mere multitude of impressions retained, 
 if memory were simply an affair of retaining impressions, would 
 not cause them to be less remembered. Nor should we need to 
 consider in order to remind ourselves; nor forget things and 
 afterwards recall them to mind. The persistence of passive 
 impressions in the soul, if real, would be a mark rather of 
 weakness than of strength, for that which is most fixedly 
 impressed is so by giving way (to <ydp evrvTrcoTarov rw eliceiv 
 earl tolovtov). But where there is really weakness, as in the 
 old, both memory and perception are worse. 
 
 The activity of perception, though itself mental, has direct 
 physical conditions. That of memory has not. Memory itself 
 belongs wholly to the soul, though it may take its start from 
 what goes on in the composite being. What the soul directly 
 preserves the memory of, is its own movements, not those of 
 body. Pressure and reaction of bodies can furnish no explana- 
 tion of a storing-up of mental " impressions " (tvttoi), which are 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 6. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 49 
 
 not magnitudes. That the body, through being in flux, is 
 really a hindrance to memory, is illustrated by the fact that 
 often additions to the store cause forgetfulness, whereas memory 
 emerges when there is abstraction and purification 1 . Some- 
 thing from the past that was retained but is latent may be 
 recalled when other memories or the impressions of the moment 
 are removed. Yet. though it is not the composite being but 
 the soul itself that possesses memory, memories come to it not 
 only from its spontaneous activity, but from its activity incited 
 by that which takes place in consequence of its association with 
 the body 2 . There are memories of what has been done and 
 suffered by the dual nature, though the memories themselves, 
 as distinguished from that which incites them, are purely 
 mental. Thus indirectly the physical organism has a bearing 
 on memory as well as on perception. It follows, however, from 
 the general view, that memory as well as reason belongs to the 
 " separable " portion of the soul. Whether those who have 
 attained to the perfection of virtue will, in the life of complete 
 separation from the body, retain indefinitely their memories of 
 the past, is another question. The discussion of it belongs 
 rather to the ethics than to the pure psychology of Plotinus. 
 
 To specific questions about sense-perception, Plotinus de- 
 votes two short books, both of which are concerned primarily 
 with vision. Discussing the transmission of light 3 , he finds 
 that, like all perception, seeing must take place through some 
 kind of body. The affection of the medium, however, need not 
 be identical with that of the sense-organ. A reed, for example, 
 through which is transmitted the shock of a torpedo, is not 
 affected like the hand that receives the shock. The air, he 
 concludes, is no instrument in vision. If it were, we should be 
 able to see without looking at the distant object ; just as we 
 are warmed by the heated air we are in contact with. In the 
 case of heat too, Plotinus adds, we are warmed at the same time 
 with the air, rather than by means of it. Solid bodies receive 
 more of the heat than does the air intervening between them 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 3, 26 : Trpocrride/x^vuv tlvCip XrjOrj, 4v 8' a<pa.t.pl<rei ko.1 Kadapaei 
 avaxinrrei iroWaKts 17 /ivripirj. 
 
 * Enn. iv. 3, 27. 3 Enn. iv. 5. 
 
 w. 4 
 
50 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 and the heated object. In pursuance of this argument, he 
 remarks that even the transmission of sound is not wholly 
 dependent on a stroke in an aerial medium. Tones vary 
 according to the differences of the bodies from which the sound 
 starts, and not simply according to the shock. Furthermore, 
 sounds are transmitted within our bodies without the inter- 
 mediation of air; as when bones are bent or sawn 1 . The shock 
 itself, whether in air or not, when it arrives at perception is the 
 sound. Light Plotinus defines as an incorporeal energy of the 
 luminous body directed outwards. Being an " energy," and not 
 a mere quality (7rotoT?7<?), it is capable of overleaping an interval 
 without becoming inherent in that which occupies the interval; 
 as, in fact, it leaves no impress on the air through which it 
 passes. It can exist in the interspace without a percipient, 
 though a percipient, if present, would be affected by it. 
 
 For positive explanation here, Plotinus falls back on the 
 idea, borrowed from the Stoics, of a " sympathy " binding 
 together remote but like parts of the universe. The other book 
 mentioned 2 , which discusses the question why things seen at a 
 distance appear small, is interesting from its points of contact 
 with Berkeley. To solve the problem, Plotinus sets out in 
 quest of something more directly psychological than the 
 " visual angle 3 ." Is not one reason for differences of estimate, 
 he asks, because our view of magnitude is in an " accidental " 
 relation to colour, which is what we primarily behold 4 ? To 
 perceive how large any magnitude really is, we must be near 
 it, so as to be able to go over its parts in succession. At a 
 distance, the parts of the object do not permit accurate dis- 
 cernment of their relative colouring, since the colours arrive 
 faint (a/xvSpd). Faintness in colours corresponds to smallness 
 in magnitude; both have in common "the less" (t6 tjttov). 
 Thus the magnitude, following the colour, is diminished pro- 
 
 1 Erin. iv. 5, 5 : ovk ev dipt, dXXd o~vyKpoto~avTos Kal TrK-fj^avros dWo dWov' 
 olov Kal outCov Kap\f/eis irpbs dWrfka iro.pa.Tpijiop.ivuv dipos p.r) ovtos pLera^i Kal 
 TrpLcreLs. 
 
 2 Enn. ii. 8. 3 Of. Theory of Vision, § 79. 
 
 4 Enn. ii. 8, 1 : on Kara avp^e^r/Kos opa/rai to p.iyedo$ tov xP<Aucctos irpuxus 
 OewpovpL&ov, 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 51 
 
 portionally (dvd \6yov). The nature of the affection, however, 
 becomes plainer in things of varied colours. Confusion of 
 colours, whether in near or distant objects, causes apparent 
 diminution of size, because the parts do not offer differences by 
 which they can be accurately distinguished and so measured 1 . 
 Magnitudes also of the same kind and of like colours are 
 deceptive because the sight slips away; having, for precisely 
 the same reason as in the ca^e of confused colours, no hold on 
 the parts. Again, distant objects look near at hand because 
 there is loss of visible detail in the intervening scenery. Close 
 as all this comes to Berkeley, at least in psychological method, 
 the incidental remark comes still closer, that that to which we 
 primarily refer visible magnitude appears to be touch. This 
 occurs in a question about the <: magnitude " of sound, to which 
 reference is made by way of illustrating the analogy of great 
 and small in different sense-perceptions 2 . 
 
 Feeling, in the sense of pleasure and pain, according to 
 Plotinus, belongs primarily to the animated body, in the parts 
 of which it is localised 3 . The perception of it, but not the 
 feeling itself, belongs to the soul. Sometimes, however, in 
 speaking of the feeling of pleasure or pain, we include along 
 with it the accompanying perception. Corporal desires too 
 have their origin from the common nature of the animated 
 body. That this is their source is shown by the differences, in 
 respect of desires, between different times of life, and between 
 persons in health and disease. In his account of desire and 
 aversion, Plotinus notes the coincidence between mental and 
 bodily movements 4 . The difference between the affection of 
 the animated body on the one side and the soul's clear per- 
 ception of it on the other, applies both to appetitive and to 
 irascible emotion 5 . Of these the second is not derived from 
 
 1 Cf. Theory of Vision, § 56. 
 
 - Enn. II. 8, 1 : rivi yap irpwTWS to iv rrj <pwvrj /xiyedos, uo-irep Soku Trj 6\(pf) to 
 opdi/xevov ; 
 
 » Enn. iv. 4, 18—21. 
 
 4 Enn. iv. 4, 20 : eV ttjs ddtvrjs iyiveTo r\ yvuxns, ko.1 dirayuv e/c rod ttoiovvtos to 
 irados T] \pvxn Pov\o(*ivr) iiroiei ti)v <pvyr)v, ko.1 tov irpwrov wadovTos OtSacr/coiros tovto 
 <j>evyovTbs irws Kai avrov iv t-q o-vo-to\tj. 
 
 5 Enn. iv. 4 r 28. 
 
 4—2 
 
52 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 the first, but both spring from a common root. That its origin 
 cannot be entirely independent is shown by the fact that those 
 who are less eager after bodily pleasures are less prone to anger 
 and irrational passions. To explain the impulse (op fir}) to repel 
 actively the cause of injury, we must suppose perception added 
 to the mere resentment (a<yavaKrrjcns:), which, as a passion, is 
 primarily a boiling-up of the blood. The " trace of soul " on 
 which this kind of emotion depends (to eKireaov eh Ov/xov 
 Ixvos) has its seat in the heart. 
 
 Error too arises from the common nature, by which right 
 reason becomes weak, as the wisest counsellor in an assembly 
 may be overborne by the general clamour 1 . The rational power, 
 with Plotinus as with Aristotle, is in its own nature " unmixed"; 
 but it has to manifest itself under conditions of time and in 
 relation to the composite being. Further discussion of these 
 points will in the main come better under the head of meta- 
 physics than of psychology. A distinctively psychological 
 theory, however, is the explicit transformation of the Platonic 
 " reminiscence " into a doctrine of " innate ideas " potentially 
 present. The term " memory," Plotinus observes, is improperly 
 applied to the intellectual energising of the soul in accordance 
 with its innate principles 2 . The reason why the older writers 
 ascribed memory and reminiscence to the soul when it thus 
 energises, was apparently because it is then energising in 
 accordance with powers it always had (as it has now latent 
 memories) but does not always bring into action, and especially 
 cannot bring into action on its first arrival in the world. In 
 this place for one Plotinus does not in the least fail to recognise 
 that there has been scientific progress since the time of those 
 whom he calls " the ancients." 
 
 The higher and the lower powers of the soul meet in the 
 imaginative faculty ((fravracrla, to (pavTaaTtKov), which is the 
 psychical organ of memory and self-consciousness. By this 
 view the dispersion is avoided that would result from assigning 
 memory of desires to the desiring part of the soul, memories 
 of perception to the perceiving part, and memories of thought 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 4, 17. 2 Enn. iv. 3, 25. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 53 
 
 to the thinking part. Thought is apprehended by the imagi- 
 nation as in a mirror; the notion (i'6t]fia) at first indivisible 
 and implicit being conveyed to it by an explicit discourse 
 (Xoyo?). For thought and the apprehension of thought are not 
 the same {aWo yap r) vorjats, /cal aWo ?; t?}? vo/jaews dvri- 
 \?;\/a?) ; the former can exist without the latter. That which 
 thus apprehends thought apprehends perceptions also 1 . 
 
 Here we come to the psychological conception of " con- 
 sciousness," which Prof. Siebeck has traced through its formative 
 stages to its practically adequate expression by Plotinus 2 . By 
 Plato and Aristotle, as he points out, such expressions are used 
 as the " seeing of sight," and, at a higher degree of generality, 
 the " perceiving of perception " and the " thinking of thought " ; 
 but they have no perfectly general term for the consciousness 
 with which we follow any mental process whatever, as distin- 
 guished from the process itself. Approximations to such terms 
 were made in the post-Aristotelian period by the Stoics and 
 others, but it was Plotinus who first gained complete mastery 
 of the idea. Sometimes he speaks of " common perception " 
 (o-vvalcrdrjais) in a generalised sense. His most usual expres- 
 sion is that of an " accompaniment " (irapaKo\ov6r]ais) of its 
 own mental activities by the soul. " Self-consciousness," in its 
 distinctive meaning, is expressed by "accompanying oneself" 
 {irapaKoXovOelv kavru>). With these terms are joined expres- 
 sions for mental "synthesis" (avvdeaLS and <tvv€gl<;) as a 
 unitary activity of the soul in reference to its contents. 
 
 Important as the conception of consciousness became for 
 modern thought, it is not for Plotinus the highest. Prof. 
 Siebeck himself draws attention to one remarkable passage 3 in 
 which he points out that many of our best activities, both 
 theoretical and practical, are unaccompanied at the time by 
 consciousness of them ; as for example reading, especially when 
 we are reading intently ; similarly, the performance of brave 
 actions ; so that there is a danger lest consciousness should 
 make the activities it accompanies feebler {ware rets irapa- 
 Ko\ovdi]aeL<; Kivhvveveiv dfivSporepa*; auras tcis evepyeias als 
 
 1 Emi. iv. 3, 28—30. - Geschichte der Psychologic, i. 2, pp. 331 ff. 
 
 3 Enn. i. 4, 10. 
 
54 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 irapaKokovQovai iroielv). The rank assigned to introspective 
 consciousness of mental activities is similar to that which is 
 assigned to memory 1 . It is above sense, but lower than pure 
 intellect, which energises with more perfection in its absence. 
 The organ of introspection and of memory, as we have seen, is 
 the same. 
 
 The highest mode of subjective life, next to the complete 
 unification in which even thought disappears, is intellectual 
 self-knowledge. Here the knower is identical with the known. 
 On this too Plotinus is not without keen psychological observa- 
 tions, apart from the metaphysical developments next to be 
 considered. The strong impression of a sense-perception, he 
 remarks, cannot consist with the attainment of this intellectual 
 unity. Whatever exaggerates feeling lowers the activity of 
 thought. The perception of evils, for example, carries with it 
 a more vehement shock, but less clear knowledge. We are 
 more ourselves in health than in disease, but disease makes 
 itself more felt, as being other than ourselves. The attitude 
 of self-knowledge, Plotinus adds, is quite unlike that in which 
 we know an object by external perception. Even the knower 
 cannot place himself outside like a perceived object and gaze 
 upon himself with the eyes of the body 2 . 
 
 Within the mind as its very centre is the supreme unity 
 beyond even self-knowledge. This is one with the metaphysical 
 cause of all thiugs, and must first be discussed as such, since the 
 proof of its reality is primarily metaphysical. Its psychological 
 relations will best be dealt with in the chapter on the mysticism 
 of Plotinus. 
 
 2. Metaphysics. 
 
 Apart from a unifying principle, nothing could exist. All 
 would be formless and indeterminate, and so would have 
 properly no being. A principle of unity has already been 
 recognised in the soul. It is not absent in natural things, but 
 here it is at a lower stage ; body having less unity than soul 
 
 1 Erin. iv. 4, 2. 
 
 2 Erin. v. 8, 11 : ovok yap ovd' avrbs Swarm it,w dels eavrbv ws aiaO-qTov bvra 
 6(pda\/j.6is rots tov (TLOfxarus (SXeTreiv, 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 55 
 
 because its parts are locally separate. In soul, however, we 
 cannot rest as the highest term. Particular souls, by reason of 
 what they have in common, can only be understood as derived 
 from a general soul, which is their cause but is not identical 
 with all or any of them. Again, the general soul falls short 
 of complete unity by being the principle of life and motion to 
 the world, which is other than itself. What it points to as a 
 higher unifying principle is absolutely stable intellect, thinking 
 itself and not the world, but containing as identical with its 
 own nature the eternal ideas of all the forms, general and 
 particular, that become explicit in the things of time and space. 
 Even intellect has still a certain duality, because, though 
 intelligence and the intelligible are the same, that which thinks 
 distinguishes itself from the object of thought. Beyond thought 
 and the being which, while identical with it, is distinguishable 
 in apprehension, is the absolute unity that is simply identical 
 with itself. This is other than all being and is the cause of 
 it. It is the good to which all things aspire ; for to particular 
 things the greatest unification attainable is the greatest good ; 
 and neither the goodness and unity they possess, nor their 
 aspiration after a higher degree of it, can be explained without 
 positing the absolute One and the absolute Good as their source 
 and end. 
 
 By the path of which this is a slight indication, Plotinus 
 ascends to the summit of his metaphysics. The proof that the 
 first principle has really been attained, must be sought partly 
 in the demonstration of the process by which the whole system 
 of things is derived from it, partly in individual experience. 
 This last, being incommunicable— though not to be had without 
 due preparation — belongs to the mystical side of the doctrine. 
 Of the philosophical doctrine itself, the method is not mystical. 
 The theory of " emanation " on which it depends is in reality 
 no more than a very systematic expression of the principle 
 common to Plato and Aristotle, that the lower is to be explained 
 by the higher 1 . 
 
 1 See for example Enn. v. '.), 4 : ou yap orj, d>s olovrcu, ipvxv vovv reXeiwOdaa. 
 ytvvq.' woOtv yap to dvvafxti evepydq earui, /mtj tou els evipynav ayovTos airiov 
 ovtos ; ...dtb Sti ra irp&TO. tvtpydq rlOtcdai nal airpoaota ko\ re'Xeia. 
 
56 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 The accepted term, " emanation," is derived from one of the 
 metaphors by which Plotinus illustrates the production of each 
 order of being from the next above. He compares the cause 
 of all to an overflowing spring which by its excess gives rise to 
 that which comes after it 1 . This similarly produces the next, 
 and so forth, till at length in matter pure indetermination is 
 reached. The metaphorical character of this representation, 
 however, is carefully insisted on. There is no diremption of the 
 higher principle. God and mind do not disperse themselves 
 in individual souls and in natural things, though these are 
 nowhere cut off from their causes. There is a continual process 
 from first to last, of which the law is the same throughout. 
 Each producing cause remains wholly in its proper seat (iv rfj 
 oUeia ehpa), while that which is produced takes an inferior 
 station 2 . The One produces universal Mind, or Intellect that 
 is one with the Intelligible. Intellect produces the Soul of the 
 Whole. This produces all other existences, but without itself 
 lapsing. Nothing within the series of the three intelligible 
 principles can be said to lapse in production ; the term being 
 applicable only to the descent of the individual soul. The 
 order throughout, both for the intelligible causes and for the 
 visible universe, is a logical order of causation, not an order 
 in time. All the producing causes and their effects in every 
 grade always existed and always will exist. The production 
 by the higher causes has the undeviating character of natural 
 necessity, and is not by voluntary choice and discursive reason, 
 which are secondary resultants within the world of particulars. 
 
 This philosophical meaning Plotinus makes clear again and 
 again. His metaphors are intended simply as more or less 
 inadequate illustrations. One that comes nearer to his thought 
 than that of the overflowing spring, is the metaphor of illumina- 
 tion by a central source of light : for according to his own 
 theory light is an incorporeal energy projected without loss. 
 Since, however, it is still an energy set going from a body, he 
 admits that even this comparison has some inexactitude. In 
 this mode of expression, Mind is the eternal " irradiation " of 
 
 1 Emi. v. 2, 1. 2 Enn. v. 2, 2. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 57 
 
 the One 1 . As Mind looks back to the One, Soul looks back to 
 Mind; and this looking back is identical with the process of 
 generation. 
 
 Plotinus himself traces the idea of this causal series to 
 Plato, for whom, he says, the Demiurgus is Intellect, which is 
 produced by the Good beyond mind and being, and in its turn 
 produces Soul 2 . This historical derivation, as we have seen, 
 was accepted by Porphyry. Plotinus goes on to interpret earlier 
 philosophers from the same point of view. He recognises, how- 
 ever, that the distinctions between the One in its different 
 senses drawn by the Platonic Parmenides were not made with 
 that exactitude by Parmenides himself. Aristotle, he says, 
 coming later, makes the primal reality separable indeed and 
 intelligible, but deprives it of the first rank by the assertion 
 that it thinks itself. To think itself belongs to Mind, but not 
 to the One 3 . 
 
 As in the nature of things there are three principles, so also 
 with us 4 . For there is reality in this world of ours, and not a 
 mere semblance. The virtue and knowledge here are not simply 
 images of archetypes yonder in the intelligible world. If indeed 
 we take the world here not as meaning simply the visible aspect 
 of things, but as including also the soul and what it contains, 
 everything is " here " that is " there 5 ." 
 
 The order of first, second and third in the intelligible prin- 
 ciples is not spatial 6 . In the intelligible order, body may be 
 said to be in soul, soul in mind, and mind in the One 7 . By 
 such -expressions is to be understood a relation of dependence, 
 not the being in a place in the sense of locality. If any one 
 objects that place can mean nothing but boundary or interval 
 of space, let him dismiss the word and apply his understanding 
 
 1 Enn. v. 1, 6: irepi\ap.^/i.v ii- avrov /xeV, e'| avrov 8e /xiuovros, olov rjXiov to nepl 
 avrbv \ap.irpbv (pws irepiOi'ov, e'if avrov del yevv^fievof fxivovros. 
 
 2 Enn. v. 1,8: uxrre TLXaruva eibevai in p.tv Ta.ya.6ov rbv vovv, etc 5£ rod vov rrju 
 
 3 Enn. v. 1, 9. 
 
 4 Enn. v. 1, 10: wawep 5i iv rr\ (pvan rpirra ravra. ian to. eipij/xi'i'a, oi'tu XPV 
 vo/Jii^eiv teal nap' i)ixlv ravra elvai. 
 
 5 Enn. v. 9, 13 : iravra ivravda, baa. Kaxtl. 
 
 6 Enn. vi. 5, 4. 7 Enn. v. 5, 9. 
 
58 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v 
 
 to the thing signified 1 . The incorporeal and unextended in 
 which extended body participates is not to be thought of as a 
 point ; for mass, which includes an infinity of points, participates 
 in it. Nor yet must we think of it as stretched out over the 
 whole of the mass ; but of the whole extended mass as par- 
 ticipating in that which is itself without spatial interval 2 . This 
 is the general relation of the visible to the intelligible world. 
 As non-spatial dependence and implication, we have found that 
 it runs through the intelligible causes themselves. 
 
 In what relates to the difference between the extended and 
 the unextended, the character of intelligible being is already 
 perfectly determinate not only in soul, but in soul as the 
 principle of organic life. For that principle transcends the 
 opposition between small and great. If it is to be called small 
 as having no extension of its own, it may equally be called 
 great as being adequate to the animation of the whole body 
 with which it is connected, while this is growing in bulk 3 . The 
 soul is all in the germ ; yet in a manner it contains the full- 
 grown plant or animal. In itself it undergoes no change of 
 dimensions. Though the principle of growth, it does not grow ; 
 nor, when it causes motion, is it moved in the motion which it 
 causes 4 . 
 
 The primal One from which all things are is everywhere 
 and nowhere. As being the cause of all things, it is everywhere. 
 As being other than all things, it is nowhere. If it were only 
 " everywhere," and not also " nowhere," it would be all things 5 . 
 No predicate of being can be properly applied to it. To call it 
 the cause is to predicate something, not of it but of ourselves, 
 who have something from it while it remains in itself 6 . This 
 is not the " one " that the soul attains by abstracting from 
 magnitude and multitude till it arrives at the point and the 
 arithmetical unit. It is greatest of all, not by magnitude but 
 
 1 Eun. vi. 4, 2 : tt\v tov wo/xaros d(pels Kar-qyopiav rrj diavolq. to Xeyo/xevov 
 XafifiaveTW. 
 
 2 Erin. vi. 4, 13. 
 
 3 Eim. vi. 4, 5 : fxapTvpei 5e ry p.eydXip tt)s ^i'X^s Kai to /xei^oi'os tov oynou 
 yti/o/j.ei'ov (pdaveiv ewl irdv avrov tyjv avTrjv y'vxw, V ew eXaTTOvos oyKov i]v. 
 
 4 Enu. in. 6, 4. 5 Enu. in. l J, 3. 
 u Erin. vi. 9, 3. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 59 
 
 by potency ; in such a manner that it is also by potency that 
 which is without magnitude. It is to be regarded as infinite, 
 not because of the impossibility of measuring or counting it, 
 but because of the impossibility of comprehending its power 1 . 
 It is perfectly self-sufficing; there is no good that it should 
 seek to acquire by volition. It is good not in relation to itself, 
 but to that which participates in it. And indeed that which 
 imparts good is not properly to be called "good," but "the 
 Good " above all other goods. " That alone neither knows, nor 
 has what it does not know; but being One present to itself it 
 needs not thought of itself." Yet in a sense it is all beings 
 because all are from it 2 ; and it generates the thought that is 
 one with being. As it is the Good above all goods, so, though 
 without shape or form, it possesses beauty above beauty. The 
 love of it is infinite ; and the power or vision by which mind 
 thinks it is intellectual love 3 . 
 
 Any inconsistency there might appear to be in making 
 assertions about the One is avoided by the position that nothing 
 — not even that it "is" any more than that it is "good" — is to 
 be affirmed of it as a predicate. The names applied to it are 
 meant only to indicate its unique reality 4 . The question is 
 then raised, whether this reality is best indicated by names 
 that signify freedom, or chance, or necessity. Before we can 
 know whether an expression signifying freedom (to e</>' rjfiiv) 
 may be applied in any sense to the gods and to God (eVt deovs 
 ical eri fiaXkov iirl deov), we must know in what sense it is 
 applicable to ourselves 5 . If we refer that which is in our power 
 to will (/3ov\r](T^\ and place this in right reason (iv Xoyw 
 6p9a), we may — by stretching the terms a little — reach the 
 conclusion that an unimpeded theoretic activity such as we 
 ascribe in its perfection to the gods who live according to mind, 
 is properly called free. The objection that to be free in this 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 9, 6 ; \rfivTeov ol ko.1 direLpov clvto ov ry dSu^iTrjTW r) rod fxeyidovs rj 
 tov apiO/xov, ctXXa t<£ drnpCK^TTT^ ttjs ovudfiecos. 
 
 * Enu. vi. 7, 32: ovdev ovv touto tQv 6vtwv /ecu irdvra' ovbev ixiv, on varepa. to. 
 oi'ra, TT&vTa 5e, otl e£ clvtov. 
 
 3 Enn. vi. 7, 35. Plotinus's actual expression is vovs ipQv. 
 
 ■> Enn. vi. 7, 38. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 1. 
 
60 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 sense is to be " enslaved to one's own nature " is dismissed with 
 the remark that that only is enslaved which, being withheld by 
 something else, has it not in its power to go towards the good 1 . 
 The view that seems implied in the objection, namely, that 
 freedom consists in action contrary to the nature of the agent, 
 is an absurdity 2 . But to the supreme principle, from which all 
 things have being and power of their own, how can the term 
 be applied in any sense ? The audacious thought might be 
 started that it " happens to be " as it is, and is not master of 
 what it is, but is what it is, not from itself; and so, that it has 
 no freedom, since its doing or not doing what it has been 
 necessitated to do or not to do, is not in its own power. To 
 this the reply is, that we cannot say that the primal cause is 
 by chance, or that it is not master of its origin ; because it has 
 not come to be 3 . The whole difficulty seems to arise from our 
 positing space (-^wpav /cal tottov) as a kind of chaos, and then 
 introducing the principle into our imaginary space ; whereupon 
 we inquire whence and how it came there 4 . We get rid of the 
 difficulty by assigning to the One no place, but simply the 
 being as it is, — and this because we are bound so to express 
 ourselves by necessity of speech. Thus, if we are to speak of it 
 at all, we must say that it is lord of itself and free. Yet it 
 must be allowed that there is here a certain impropriety, for to 
 be lord of itself belongs properly to the essence {ovaia) identical 
 with thought, and the One is before this essence 5 . With a 
 similar impropriety, its will and its essence may be said to be 
 the same. Each particular being, striving after its good, wills 
 that more than to be what it is, and then most thinks that it 
 is, when it participates in the good. It wills even itself, so far 
 only as it has the good. Carry this over to the Good which is 
 the principle of all particular goods, and its will to be what it 
 is, is seen to be inseparable from its being what it is. In this 
 mode of speech, accordingly, — having to choose between ascribing 
 to it on the one hand will and creative activity in relation to 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 8, 4. "- Enn. vi. 8, 7. 
 
 3 Enn. vi. 8,7: to 5e irpGrrov otire Kara Tvyy)v dv \eyoi/aev, oiire ov Kvpiov rrjs 
 avTou yevicxeuis, oti fxrjde yeyove. 
 
 4 Enn. vi. 8, 11. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 12. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 61 
 
 itself, on the other hand a contingent relation which is the 
 name of unreason, — we must say, not that it is " what it hap- 
 pened to be," but that it is " what it willed to be 1 ." We might 
 say also that it is of necessity what it is, and could not be 
 otherwise ; but the more exact statement is, not that it is thus 
 because it could not be otherwise, but because the best is thus. 
 It is not taken hold of by necessity, but is itself the necessity 
 and law of other things 2 . It is love, and the object of love, 
 and love of itself 3 . That which as it were desires and that 
 which is desired are one 4 . When we, observing some such 
 nature in ourselves, rise to this and become this alone, what 
 should we say but that we are more than free and more than 
 in our own power? By analogy with mind, it may be called 
 operation {evep^fxa) and energy. Its energy and as it were 
 waking {olov eypiiyopais) are eternal 5 . Reason and mind are 
 derived from the principle as a circle from its centre 6 . To 
 allow that it could not make itself other than it did, in the 
 sense that it can produce only good and not evil, is not to limit 
 its freedom and absolute power. The power of choice between 
 opposites belongs to a want of power to persevere in what is 
 best 7 . The One and Good alone is in truth free; and must be 
 thought and spoken of, though in reality beyond speech and 
 thought, as creating itself by its own energy before all being 8 . 
 
 To the question, why the One should create anything beyond 
 itself, Plotinus answers that since all things, even those without 
 life, impart of themselves what they can, the most perfect and 
 the first good cannot remain in itself as envious, and the potency 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 8, 13 : umre ovk otrep Ztvx^v icmv, d\X' owep r)j3ov\-fidr] clvt6s. Cf. c. 
 20 : aurds £o~ti nai 6 wapdyiov iavrov. 
 
 2 Enn. vi. 8, 10. 
 
 3 Enn. vi. 8, 15 : ko.1 epda/xiov nal tpws 6 avrbs ko.1 avrov Upws. 
 
 4 Ibid. : t6 olov iipi.ep.evov t<jS e<p€Ti^ '4v. 
 
 5 Enn. vi. 8, 16. 6 Enn. vi. 8, 18. 
 
 " Enn. vi. 8, 21 : ko.1 yap rb to. avriKel/xeva bvvaadat dovva/utas earl rod iirl rod 
 aplo~Tov fxivuv. 
 
 8 Since it is energy in the Aristotelian sense, or complete realisation, it is 
 dvevtpyqrov. That is, there is no higher realisation to which it can proceed. 
 Cf. Enn. v. 6, 6 : oXws /xei> yap ovSe/xia ivtpyeia ^x €l a ^ ^aXtv evtpyeiav. In this 
 sense, it is said (Enn. i. 7, 1) to be beyond onergy (iw^Ketva evepydas). 
 
62 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 of all things as without power 1 . As that is the potency of all 
 things, Mind, which it first generates, is all things actually. 
 For knowledge of things in their immaterial essence is the 
 things themselves 2 . Mind knows its objects not, like percep- 
 tion, as external, but as one with itself 3 . Still this unity, as 
 has been said, involves the duality of thinking and being 
 thought, and hence is not the highest, but the second in order, 
 of the suprainundane causes. Within its indivisible unity it 
 contains the archetype of the whole visible world and of all 
 that was or is or is to be existent in it. The relation of its 
 Ideas to the whole of Mind resembles that of the propositions 
 of a science to the sum of knowledge which consists of them. 
 By this comparison, which frequently recurs, Plotinus seeks to 
 convey the notion of a diversity in unity not expressed as local 
 separation of parts 4 . The archetype of the world being thus 
 existent, the world in space is necessarily produced because its 
 production is possible. We shall see this " possibility " more 
 exactly formulated in the theory of matter. The general state- 
 ment is this : that, since there is the " intelligential and 
 all-potent nature" of mind, and nothing stands between that 
 and the production of a world, there must be a formed world 
 corresponding to the formative power. In that which is formed, 
 the ideas are divided ; in one part of space the idea of the 
 sun takes shape, in another the idea of man. The archetype 
 embraces all in its unity without spatial division 5 . 
 
 Thus, while suprainundane intellect contains all real being, 
 it has also the productive power by which the essential forms 
 of things are made manifest in apparent separation from itself 
 and from one another. Differences, so far as they belong to 
 the real being, or " form," of things here, are produced by pre- 
 existent forms in the ideal world. So far as they are merely 
 
 1 Enn. v. 4, 1. 
 
 2 Enn. v. 4, 2. Cf. Enn. v. 9, 5 : r; twv dvev i/Xijs ewiaTrifXT] ravrbv t<jJ 
 irpdyfxaTi. 3 Enn. v. 5, 1. 
 
 4 See for example Enn. v. 9, 8. 
 
 5 Enn. v. 9, 9 : <£wrews voepds /cat wavToovvdfxov oilo-ris /cat ovdevbs didpyovros, 
 fxrjdevbs ovtos fxera^u tovtov /cat tov S^aadai dvva.fj.evov, dvdyxT) to fxev Kocrfirjdrjvai, 
 to 5e Koa/xrjacu. /cat to fxev KOO~fX7]6ev ityei to eldos fxefj.epiafx.4vov, dWaxov dvdpwwov 
 /cat dWaxov r/Xiov to 8e ev evl irdvTa. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS G3 
 
 local and temporal, they express only a necessary mode of 
 manifestation of being, under the condition of appearing at a 
 greater degree of remoteness from the primal cause. What 
 then is the case with individuality ? Does it consist merely in 
 differences of position in space and time, the only true reality 
 being the ideal form of the " kind " ; or are there ideal forms 
 of individuals ? Plotinus concludes decisively for the latter 
 alternative 1 . There are as many formal differences as there 
 are individuals, and all pre-exist in the intelligible world. 
 What must be their mode of pre-existence we know from the 
 nature of Intellect as already set forth. All things there are 
 together yet distinct. Universal mind contains all particular 
 minds ; and each particular mind expresses the whole in its 
 own manner. As Plotinus says in one of those bursts of enthu- 
 siasm where his scientific doctrine passes into poetry : " They 
 see themselves in others. For all things are transparent, and 
 there is nothing dark or resisting, but every one is manifest to 
 every one internally and all things are manifest ; for light is 
 manifest to light. For every one has all things in himself and 
 again sees in another all things, so that all things are every- 
 where and all is all and each is all, and infinite the glory. For 
 each of them is great, since the small also is great. And the 
 sun there is all the stars, and again each and all are the sun. 
 In each, one thing is pre-eminent above the rest, but it also 
 shows forth all-." The wisdom that is there is not put together 
 from separate acts of knowledge, but is a single whole. It does 
 not consist of many brought to one ; rather it is resolved into 
 multitude from unity. By way of illustration Plotinus adds 
 that the Egyptian sages, whether they seized the truth by 
 accurate knowledge or by some native insight, appear to have 
 expressed the intuitive character of intellectual wisdom in 
 making a picture the sign of each thing 3 . 
 
 In the intelligible world identical with intellect, as thus 
 conceived, the time and space in which the visible world appears, 
 though not " there " as such, pre-exist in their causes. So too, 
 
 1 See especially Enn. v. 7: Tlepl tov el ko.1 twv ko.0' frcatrra ?cmi> et8t]. 
 
 2 Enn. v. 8, 4. 
 
 3 Enn. v. 8, G. This is quite an isolated reference to Egypt. 
 
64 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 in the rational order, does perception, before organs of percep- 
 tion are formed. This must be so, Plotinus urges, because 
 perception and its organs are not a product of deliberation, but 
 are present for example in the pre-existent idea of man, by an 
 eternal necessity and law of perfection, their causes being in- 
 volved in the perfection of mind 1 . Not only man, but all 
 animals, plants and elements pre-exist ideally in the intelligible 
 world. For infinite variety is demanded in order that the whole, 
 as one living being, may be perfect in all its parts and to the 
 utmost degree. There, the things we call irrational pre-exist 
 in their rational laws 2 . Nor is the thing here anywhere really 
 mindless. We call it so when it is without mind in act; but 
 each part is all in potency, depending as it does on its ideal 
 cause. In the order of ideal causes there is as it were a stream 
 of living beings from a single spring ; as if all sensible qualities 
 were combined in one quality without losing their distinctions 3 . 
 The particular is not merely the one particular thing that it 
 is called. Rational division of it always brings something new 
 to light ; so that, in this sense, each part of the whole is infinite 4 . 
 This infinity, whether of whole or part, is one of successive 
 involution. The process of division is not that of bisection, but 
 is like the unfolding of wrappings 5 . The whole intelligible 
 world may be presented to imagination as a living sphere 
 figured over with every kind of living countenance 6 . 
 
 Universal mind involves the essence of every form of reason, 
 in one Reason as it were, great, perfect, embracing all (els olov 
 \6<yos, fAeyas, reXeios, TrdvTas 'rrepie-^wv). As the most exact 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 7, 3: 'iyKeiTai. rb atV^ij-rt/ccV elvai /cat ovtws alaOriTLKbv iv tqj ei'5et 
 vwb didiov dvdyKTjs Kal reXeibrr/ros, vov iv avru) ^x 0VTOS > e'twep riXeios, t&s alrlas. 
 
 ' 2 Enn. vi. 7, 9: iKe'i be Kal rb dXoyov Xeybfievov Xbyos ijf, /cat rb avow vovs r)v, 
 iwel Kal 6 vou>v ittttov vous iari, /cat 7) vb-qaLS lirirov coOs rjv. 
 
 3 Enn. VI. 7, 12: olov et ris t]v TroibrTjs fxia 7rdcras iv avrrj £x owja KaL o-uj^ovaa 
 rets iroibrrjTas, yXvKiJTTjs fier evubias, /cat b/xov ocvojStjs woibr'qs /cat xiAtDe dvavruv 
 5vvdfM€Ls /cat xpw / ttdrwi' o\peis /cat &aa a<pal yivdjaKOvcnv. iaruaav be /cat 6'ira d/coat 
 dKovovffL, irdvra p.iXi] /cat pvd/xbs iras. 
 
 4 Enn. vi. 7, 13: vovs...ov...raiirbv /cat h> n iv p,ipei, dXXd wdvra' iwel Kal to 
 iv /nipei av ov% &, dXXd Kal tovto Eireipov biaipovp,evov. Cf. Enn. vi. 5, 5 on the 
 infinite nature (dweipos </>t/<ns) of being. 
 
 8 Enn. vi. 7, 14 : /xri /car' evdi, dXX' els rb ivrbs del. 
 e Enn. vi. 7, 15 fin. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 
 
 05 
 
 reasoning would calculate the things of nature for the best, 
 mind has all things in the rational laws that are before reason- 
 ing 1 . Each thing being what it is separately, and again all 
 things being in one together, the complex as it were and com- 
 position of all as they are in one is Mind 2 . In the being that 
 is mind, all things are together, not only undivided by position 
 in space, but without reference to process in time. This 
 characteristic of intellectual being may be called " eternity 3 ." 
 Time belongs to Soul, as eternity to Mind 4 . Soul is necessarily 
 produced by Mind, as Mind by the primal One 5 . Thus it is in 
 contact at once with eternal being, and with the temporal 
 things which it generates by the power it receives from its 
 cause. Having its existence from supramundane intellect, it 
 has reason in act so far as that intellect is contemplated by it 6 . 
 The Soul of the whole is perpetually in this relation to Mind ; 
 particular souls undergo alternation; though even of them 
 there is ever something in the intelligible world 7 . Soul has 
 for its work, not only to think— for thus it would in no way 
 differ from pure intellect— but to order and rule the things 
 after it. These come to be, because production could not stop 
 at intelligibles, the last of which is the rational soul, but must 
 go on to the limit of all possible existence 8 . 
 
 In the relation of the many souls to the one which includes 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 2, 21 : ws yap dv 6 aKpi^araros \oyiap.bs XoyicxaiTo <lis dpiara, ovrws 
 i?X ei TrdpTa iv reus \670ts vpb \oyiap.ov oven. 
 
 2 Enn. vi. 2, 21 : x^/ns p-ev eK&vruv a Ictlv ovrwv, 6/xoO 5' av iv ivl ovtwv, tj 
 
 TTaVTWV (V ivl OVTU1V 6I0V (TV /J.w\o KT) Kal (JVvOtaiS VOVS icFTl. 
 
 3 Enn. in. 7, 4 : avry 17 dtadeens avrov Kal (pvais dt-q av aiuv. 
 
 4 Enn. in. 7, 11. Cf. Enn. iv. 4, 15: alwv /j.iv irepl vovv, xpbvos bi vepl \pvxw- 
 
 5 Enn. v. 1, 7 : i/'i'XV' 7<*P yevvq vovs, vovs uv rAeios. Kal yap ri\eiov ovra. 
 yevvdv USei, Kal fxr] 5vvafJ.iv odcrav Tocravr-qv tiyovov eZVcu. 
 
 6 Enn. v. 1, 3 : i) re ovv virocrraais avry dwb vov re ivepyeia \6yos vov avrrj 
 opu/iivov. 
 
 7 Enn. iv. ft, 8 : ov wdcra ovd' 17 ytxeripa \pvxh Zov, d\X Zen ti aiiTrjs iv tu> vot]t(3 
 dd....irdaa yap Tpvxn ?X eL Tl Kal T °v "dra irpbs rb <ru>/J.a Kal rod avw wpbs vovv. 
 
 8 Enn. iv. 8, 3 : irpoaXafiovaa yap ry voepd dvat Kal aWo, Kad' 6 ttjv oUelav 
 fcX e " UTtbffraaiv, >/o0s ovk i/xeivev, Zx eL Te ^H " Ka ^ o-vtj}, eitrep Kal irav, 8 av rj tQ>v 
 6vtuiv. pXtirovea 5t irpbs p.iu rb irpb iavrrjs voet, els 8e iavr-rjv ffwfri eavrrjv, eU 8i 
 rb ner' avT-ijv KOtTfie? re Kal SioiKet Kal dpxei airrov ' 8n p.r]di olbv re fjv arrival ra 
 ndvra ev rip vot)t$, 8vvap.ivov i<pe$rjs Kal a\\ov yeviffdai iXdrrovos fiiv, dvayKalov 8i 
 elvai, e'iirep Kal rb irpb avrov. 
 
 W. 5 
 
66 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 all, Soul imitates Mind. It too is necessarily pluralised ; and 
 in the inherent distinctions of the particular souls their coming 
 to birth under different sensible manifestations is already neces- 
 sitated. The one soul is the same in all, as in each part of a 
 system of knowledge the whole is potentially present 1 . To soul, 
 the higher intellect furnishes the reasons of all its operations 2 . 
 Knowledge in the rational soul, so far as it is of intelligibles, is 
 each thing that it thinks, and has from within both the object 
 of thought and the thinking (to re i'otjtov ttjv re votjaiv), since 
 mind is within 3 . Plotinus fully recognises the difficulty of the 
 question : How, if Being and Mind and Soul are everywhere 
 numerically one, and not merely of the same formal essence 
 (o/ioeiSe?), can there yet be many beings and minds and souls 4 ? 
 The answer, in the case of soul, as of mind and being, is that 
 the one is many by intrinsic difference, not by local situation 
 (erepoTrjTi, ov t6ttu>). The plurality of souls, as has been said, 
 is in the rational order prior to their embodiment. In the Soul 
 of the Whole, the many souls are present to one another without 
 being alienated from themselves. They are not divided by 
 spatial limits — just as the many portions of knowledge in each 
 soul are not — and the one can contain in itself all. After this 
 manner the nature of soul is infinite 5 . The general soul can 
 judge of the individualised affections in each without becoming 
 conscious to itself in each that it has passed judgment in the 
 rest also 6 . Each of us is a whole for himself, yet all of us, in 
 the reality that is all, are together one. Looking outward, we 
 forget our unity. Turning back upon ourselves, either of our own 
 accord or seized upon as the goddess seized the hair of Achilles, 
 we behold ourselves and the whole as one with the God within 7 . 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 9, 5. 
 
 2 Enn. iv. 9, 3. When the general soul impresses form on the elements of 
 the world, vovs is the x°PVy°s T & v M>yu)v. 
 
 3 Enn. v. 9, 7. 4 Enn. vi. 4, 4. 
 
 5 Enn. vi. 4, 4 Jin.: ovtios earlv dirupos i) ToiavTij cpvais. 
 
 s Enn. vi. 4, 6 : did, tL o&v ov avvaio-ddverai 17 eripa rr)s iripas Kpl/j.a; -q otl 
 Kpiais iariv, d\X ov ir&Oos. elra ovd' avrrj r) Kpivatra K^KpiKa \iyei, d\X' ?Kpive (xhvov. 
 
 7 Enn. vi. 5, 7 : ??W fxiv ovv opuvres t) 86ev ^rjfxfxeda ayvoovnev iv ovres, olov 
 irpdcrcoTra TroWa els rb ?fw Kopv(pr)v ^x 0VTa eis T0 dlffa fxiav. el Si tis iin(TTpa<prjva.i 
 dvvairo 77 irap' airoO 7} ttjs 'Adrjvds avTrjs evrvxyvas rrjs eX£ ewj, 0e6v re Kal avrbv /cat 
 t6 Trdv oi/'erat. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS G7 
 
 The soul is the principle of life and motion to all things ; 
 motion being an image of life in things called lifeless. The 
 heaven is one by the power of soul, and this world is divine 
 through it 1 . The soul of the whole orders the world in accord- 
 ance with the general reasons of things, as animal bodies are 
 fashioned into " microcosms " under the particular law of the 
 organism 2 . It creates not by deliberative intelligence, like 
 human art, which is posterior and extrinsic. In the one soul 
 are the rational laws of all explicit intelligence — " of gods and 
 of all things." " Wherefore also the world has all 3 ." 
 
 Individual souls are the intrinsic laws of particular minds 
 within the universal intellect, made more explicit 4 . Not only 
 the soul of the whole, but the soul of each, has all things in 
 itself 5 . Wherein they differ, is in energising with different 
 powers. Before descent and after reascent of the particular 
 soul, each one's thoughts are manifest to another as in direct 
 vision, without discourse". Why then does the soul descend 
 and lose knowledge of its unity with the whole ? For the 
 choice is better to remain above 7 . The answer is that the 
 error lies in self-will 8 . The soul desires to be its own, and so 
 ventures forth to birth, and takes upon itself the ordering of a 
 body which it appropriates, or rather, which appropriates it, so 
 far as that is possible. Thus the soul, although it does not 
 really belong to this body, yet energises in relation to it, and in 
 a manner becomes a partial soul in separation from the whole 9 . 
 
 But what is finally the explanation of this choice of the 
 worse, and how is it compatible with the perfection of the 
 mundane order? How is the position of the Phaedo, that the 
 body is a prison, and the true aim of the soul release from it, 
 
 1 Enn. v. 1, 2. 
 
 - Enn. IV. 3, 10 : ola Kal ol h> o-rrfp/xaat \6yoi TrXdrrovai Kal nopcpovcri to. £ipa 
 olov fxiKpovs rivas Kdfffiovs. 
 
 3 Enn. iv. 3, 10 fin. 
 
 4 Enn. iv. 3, 5: \6yoi vCsv ovaai ko.1 e^eiXiyfi^vai p.a\\ov t) eKuvoi...rb ravrbv 
 Kal 'irtpov ou^ovaai fiivei re eKaarr) Iv, Kal bfxov ev iraaai.. 
 
 5 Enn. iv. 3, 6. 
 
 B Enn. iv. 3, 18 : olov 6<p0a\/xbs Zkoo-tos Kal o&8tv 5t Kpvirrbv ovU TreirXao-fifrov, 
 dXXd irplv dirt'iv dWui I8wv (Ketvos Zyvco. 
 
 7 Enu. iv. 3, 14. 8 Enn. v. 1, 1. 
 
 9 Enn. vi. 4, 16. 
 
 5—2 
 
68 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 reconcilable with the optimism of the Timaeus ? The answer 
 is that all — descent and reascent alike — has the necessity of a 
 natural law. The optimism has reference to the whole order. 
 Of this order, such as it must be in a world that is still good 
 though below the intelligible and perfectly stable supramundane 
 order, temporary descent, dissatisfaction with the consecmences 
 of the descent, and the effort to return, are all conditions. Any 
 expression that seems to imply arbitrariness at any point, is 
 part of the mythological representation. Thus .when in the 
 Timaeus it is said that God " sows " the souls, this is mythical, 
 just as when he is represented as haranguing them 1 . Necessity 
 and self-caused descent are not discordant. The soul does not 
 go by its will to that which is worse ; yet its course is its own 2 . 
 And it must expiate both the original error, and any evil that 
 it may do actually. Of the first, the mere change of state is 
 the punishment ; to the second, further chastisement is assigned. 
 The knowledge acquired below is a good, and the soul is not to 
 be blamed overmuch if in its regulation of sensible nature it 
 goes a little beyond what 'is safe for itself 3 . On the other 
 hand, a slight inclination at the beginning to the worse, if not 
 immediately corrected, may produce a permanent disposition 4 . 
 Be the error light or grave, it comes under an undeviating law 
 of justice. To the particular bodies fitted for them, the souls 
 go neither by voluntary choice nor sent, but as by some natural 
 process for which they are ready. The universal law under 
 which the individual falls is not outside but within each 5 . The 
 notion that there may be in small things an element of con- 
 tingency which is no part of the order, is suggested but not 
 accepted 6 . The whole course of the soul through its series of 
 bodily lives, and its release from the body when this is attained, 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 8, 4. 2 Enn. iv. 8, 5. 
 
 3 Enn. iv. 8, 7 : ypQais yap evapyecrripa rayadov i] tov kclkov welpa oh 7] dvva/jus 
 acrdeveaTe'pa, rj ware ewLaTrjfxrj to ko.kov irpb irelpas yvQivat. 
 
 4 Enn. in. 2, 4. Cf. in. 3, 4 : Kal o-fxiKpa. pOTrrj dpKei eh ^K^acriv tov opdov. 
 
 5 Enn. iv. 3, 13. 
 
 6 Enn. iv. 3, 16 : ov yap to. /xev Set i>opt.lt;eiv <TWT€TdxOai, to. 8e Kexa\do-0ai eh 
 rb avTe^ovaiov. el yap /car' airlas yivecrdai del xal (pvaiKa 1 ; axoXovdias Kal Kara \6yoi> 
 'iva Kal rd^iv p,lav, Kal tcl a/xiKp6Tepa Bet avvreraxdai. Kal vvvvcpavdat. vop.l£eiP. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 69 
 
 are alike necessarily determined 1 . The death of the. soul, so 
 far as the soul can die, is to sink to a stage below moral evil 
 — which still contains a mixture of the opposite good — and to 
 be wholly plunged in matter 2 . Even thence it may still some- 
 how emerge ; though souls that have descended to the world of 
 birth need not all make the full circle, but may return before 
 reaching the lowest point 3 . 
 
 Here we come to the metaphysical doctrine by which Plotinus 
 explains the contrasts the visible world presents. Neither moral 
 good nor evil is with him ultimate. Of virtues even the highest, 
 the cause is the Good, which in reality is above good (virepd- 
 jaOov). Of moral evil, so far as it is purely evil, the cause is 
 that principle of absolute formlessness and indeterminateness 
 called Matter. At the same time, matter is the receptive prin- 
 ciple by which alone the present world could be at all. Evils 
 accordingly are an inevitable constituent of a world that is 
 subject in its parts to birth and change. And indeed without 
 evil there can be no good in our sense of the term. Nor is 
 there evil unmixed in the things of nature, any more than there 
 is unformed matter. Whence then is this principle opposed to 
 form and unity ? 
 
 That Matter is an independently existing principle over 
 against the One, Plotinus distinctly denies. The supposition 
 is put as inadmissible that there are dp%al 7rXe/ou9 koi Kara 
 avvrvyjav ra irpMra^. Matter is the infinite (to aireipov) in 
 the sense of the indeterminate (to dopio-Tov), and is generated 
 from the infinity of power or of eternal existence that is an 
 appanage of the One, which has not in itself indeterminateness, 
 but creates it 5 . To the term " infinite " in the sense of an 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 3, 24 : tpiperai 8e ko.1 avros 6 iraaxuiv dyvoCiv i(f> a iraOelv irpocrrjicei, 
 a<TT&TU) /uev rrj cpopa wavTaxov aiwpou/j.evos reus 7r\decus, Te\evTQi> 5e Cocnrep iroWa 
 Ka/Awv oh avTeTet.vev eh tov Trpo<rrjKovTa at)ry tottov eveireaev, eKovaiw rrj (popq. to 
 &kov<ti.ov els rb nadelv Hx 03 "- Cf. Enn. iv. 4, 45. 
 
 2 Enn. i. 8, 13: nal tovto ecrrt to eV g.5ov i\B6vTa etn.KaTa5ap6e.lv. Cf. Enn. 
 i. 6, 6. 
 
 3 Enn. iv. 4, 5 fin. 4 Enn. n. 4, 2. 
 
 5 Enn. II. 4, 15 : e'ii] h.v -yevvridev en rrjs tov evbs airetpias fj dvpd/xeojs yj tov del, 
 ovk ovcrvs ev eKeivip diretpias d\\a ttolovvtos. 
 
70 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 actual extent or number that is immeasurable (aSie$JLT7]Tov), or 
 of a quantitative infinite (Kara to ttoo-ov airetpov), there is 
 nothing to correspond. Matter, in itself indeterminate, is that 
 of which the nature is to be a recipient of forms. Like intel- 
 ligible being, it is incorporeal and unextended. Place, indeed, 
 is posterior both to matter and bodies 1 . By its absolute want 
 of all form, that is, of all proper being, matter is at the opposite 
 extreme to things intelligible, and is the principle of ugliness 
 and evil 2 . It receives, indeed, all determinations, but it cannot 
 receive them indivisibly (dfjLepws). One form in matter excludes 
 another; so that they appear as separated by spatial intervals 3 . 
 The reason of this is precisely that matter has no determination 
 of its own. The soul in taking up the forms of things per- 
 ceptible, views them with their mass put away {airoOefieva top 
 6jkoi> opa), because by its own form it is indivisible, and there- 
 fore cannot receive the extended as such. Since matter, on 
 the contrary, has no form of its own by which to unite distinc- 
 tions, the intrinsic differences of being must be represented in 
 it by local separation. Yet, since the intelligible world is in a 
 sense a " world," and is many as well as one, it too must have a 
 kind of matter 4 . This " intelligible matter " is the recipient of 
 formal diversities in the world of being ; as sensible matter is 
 the recipient of the varied appearances in space. The matter 
 of the intelligible world, differing in this respect from matter 
 properly so-called, does not receive all forms indifferently ; the 
 same matter there having always the same form 5 . The matter 
 "here " is thus more truly "the indeterminate" than the matter 
 " there " ; which, in so far as it has more real being, is so much 
 the less truly " matter 6 ." Matter itself may best be called 
 " not-being 7 ." As the indeterminate, it is only to be appre- 
 hended by a corresponding indeterminateness of the soul 8 — a 
 difficult state to maintain, for, as matter itself does not remain 
 
 1 Emi. ii. 4, 12 : 6 5e tottos varepos ttjs vXtjs ko.1 tu>v aw/xdnav. 
 
 2 Enn. ii. 4, 16. 3 Enii. m. 6, 18. 
 
 4 Enn. ii. 4, 4. 
 
 5 Enn. ii. 4, 3 : ij 8e tQv ytvoixivwv uXtj del d\\o /ecu &X\o eldos ?ff%«i twi> di 
 didiuv t) avTT) ravrov del. 
 
 e Enn. ii. 4, 15. 7 Enn. in. 6, 7. 
 
 8 Enn. n. 4, 10: dopcaria tt)s \j/vxns- Cf. Enn. i. 8, 9. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 71 
 
 unformed in things, so the soul hastens to add some positive 
 determination to the abstract formlessness reached by analysis. 
 To be the subject and recipient ever ready for all forms, it 
 must be indestructible and impassible, as it is incorporeal and 
 unextended. It is like a mirror which represents all things 
 so that they seem to be where they are not, and keeps no 
 impression of any 1 . The appearances of sense, themselves " in- 
 vulnerable nothings 2 ," go through it as through water without 
 dividing it. It has not even a falsehood of its own that it can 
 say of things 3 . In that it can take no permanent hold of any 
 good, it may be called evil 4 . Fleeing every attempt of percep- 
 tion to grasp it, it is equally receptive in appearance of the 
 contraries which it is equally unable to retain. 
 
 ■ 
 
 3. Cosmology and Theodicy. 
 
 The theory of matter set forth, though turned to new meta- 
 physical account, is fundamentally that of Aristotle. As with 
 Aristotle, Matter is the presupposition of physics, being viewed 
 as the indestructible " subject " of forms, enduring through all 
 changes in potency of further change ; but Plotinus is careful 
 to point out that the world of natural things derives none of 
 its reality from the recipient. The formal reason (X070?) that 
 makes matter appear as extended, does not " unfold " it to 
 extension — for this was not implicit in it — but, like that also 
 which makes it appear as coloured, gives it something that was 
 not there 5 . In that it confers no qualities whatever on that 
 which appears in it, matter is absolutely sterile 6 . The forms 
 manifested in nature are those already contained in the intellect 
 that is before it, which acquires them by turning towards the 
 Good. All differences of form, down to those of the elements, 
 are the product of Reason and not of Matter 7 . 
 
 While working out his theory from a direct consideration 
 
 1 Enn. in. 6, 7. 
 
 2 Adonais, xxxix. — an exact expression of the idea of Plotinus. 
 
 3 Enn. in. 6, 15. 4 Enn. 111. 6, 11. 
 5 Enn. 11. 4, 9. 6 Enn. in. 6, 19. 
 7 Enn. vi. 7, 11. 
 
72 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 of the necessity that there should be something indestructible 
 beneath the transformations of body, Plotinus tries to prove it 
 not inconsistent with what is known as Plato's " theory of 
 matter" in the Timaeus. The phrases in which the "recipient" 
 is spoken of as a " room " and a " seat " are interpreted meta- 
 phorically. Here Plotinus is evidently arguing against com- 
 mentators in his own time who took the " Platonic matter " to 
 be empty space 1 . This has now become the generally accepted 
 interpretation ; opinions differing only as to whether the space 
 or matter in which the ideas manifest themselves is to be re- 
 garded as objective extension or as a subjective form 2 . Plotinus 
 himself approaches the latter view when he consents to call 
 matter a " phantasm of mass " {(^avTaa^a Be 6'7/cou Xejw), 
 though still regarding it as unextended (a/zeye#e?). His account 
 of the mental process by which the nature opposed to that of 
 the ideas is known (voOcp \ojia/j,a)) quite agrees with Plato's. 
 
 On another point of Platonic interpretation, Plotinus and 
 all his successors take the view which modern criticism seems 
 now to find the most satisfactory. Plausible as was the reading 
 of the Timaeus which would regard it as teaching an origin of 
 the world from an absolute beginning of time, this was never, 
 even at the earliest period, really prevalent in the school of 
 Plato. During the Platonising movement that preceded Plo- 
 tinus, the usual interpretation had been to regard what is said 
 about the making of the world from pre-existent elements 
 as mythological. The visible universe, said the earliest like 
 the latest interpreters, is described by Plato as " generated " 
 because it depends on an unchanging principle while itself per- 
 petually subject to mutation ; not because it is supposed to 
 
 1 See especially Enn. 11. 4, 11 : oOev rives ravrbu ry Kevy ttjv v\t)v elprjKa<n. 
 
 '-' The first is Zeller's view, in which he is followed by Siebeck and by 
 Baeumker (Das Problem der Materie in der griechischen Philosophic, 1890), who 
 have skilfully defended it against objections. Mr Archer-Hind, in his edition of 
 the Timaeus, takes the view that the Platonic matter is space as a subjective 
 form. This would bring it very close to the Kantian doctrine. The more usual 
 view would in effect make it an anticipation of Descartes' attempt in the 
 Principia Philosophiae to construct body out of pure extension. There is 
 certainly a striking resemblance in general conception between Plato's and 
 Descartes' corpuscular theory, which I do not remember to have seen noted. 
 
UNIVERSITY 
 
 V] OF PLOTINUS " 7d 
 
 have been called into being at a particular moment. That this 
 was all along the authorised interpretation may be seen even 
 from Plutarch 1 , who, in defending the opposite thesis, evidently 
 feels that he is arguing against the opinion predominant among 
 contemporary Platonists 2 . Thus Plotinus, when he says that 
 there never was a time when this whole was not, nor was there 
 ever matter unformed, is not introducing a novelty. And on 
 this point we do not hear that opposition to his doctrine arose 
 from any quarter. His difference with Longinus was on the 
 question whether the divine mind eternally contains the ideas 
 in itself or contemplates them eternally as objective existences; 
 not as to whether ideas and unordered matter once stood apart 
 and were then brought together by an act or process of creative 
 volition. The duration of the universe without temporal begin- 
 ning or end was the accepted doctrine of Hellenic Platonism. 
 
 In accordance with this general view, however, it is possible, 
 as Plotinus recognises 3 , to hold either that the universe is per- 
 manent only as a whole, while all its parts perish as individual 
 bodies {Kara to To8e) and are renewed only in type (Kara to 
 dSos), or that some of the bodies in the universe — namely, 
 those that fill the spaces from the sphere of the moon outwards 
 — are always numerically identical. If the former view is the 
 true one, then the heavenly bodies differ from the rest only by 
 lasting a longer time. About the latter view there would be 
 no trouble if we were to accept Aristotle's doctrine that their 
 substance is a fifth element, not subject like the rest to altera- 
 tion. For those who allow that they consist of the elements of 
 which living bodies on earth are constituted, the difficulty is 
 that they must be by nature dissoluble. This Plato himself 
 conceded to Heraclitus. As in his physics generally, so here, 
 Plotinus argues in a rather tentative way. He suggests as the 
 true solution, that the heaven with all its parts consists of a 
 
 1 Ilepi ttjs iv Ti,ucuy \pi>xoyovlas. 
 
 2 It may be noted that the " Platonic matter," according to Plutarch, is 
 simply body or "corporeal substance." i] [xtv ovv awnaros ovala ttjs Xeyofiivrjs 
 vk aiiTov navdexovi (pvaews edpas re Kal Ti6r)vr)s tCiv yivqrCjv oi>x irepa tLs eariv 
 (c. 5 fin.). 
 
 3 Enu. ii. 1, 1. 
 
74 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 purer kind of fire, which we may call " light," moving if at all 
 with a circular motion, losing nothing by efflux, and conse- 
 quently in no need, like mortal bodies, of nourishment from 
 without. This material light, being a kind of body, must of 
 course be distinguished from light as an outflowing energy 1 . 
 Radiant light, as we have seen 2 , is for Plotinus an activity 
 carrying with it no loss either of substance or of efficiency ; 
 whence it furnished an analogy closer than is possible on any 
 modern theory for the metaphysical doctrine of emanation. 
 
 For the rest, this picture of the physical universe does not 
 essentially differ from Aristotle's. The whole forms a single 
 system, with the fixed stars and the seven planets (including 
 the sun and moon) revolving round the spherical earth in com- 
 binations of perfect circles. Like the stars, the earth too has 
 a divinity of its own 3 . The space which the universe fills is 
 finite. Body is not atomic in constitution but continuous. 
 The complex movements of the whole system recur in astro- 
 nomical cycles. In order to solve difficulties connected with 
 the infinite duration of a world in constant change, Plotinus 
 sometimes takes up the Stoical theory that in the recurrent 
 periods the sequence of events is exactly repeated. This he 
 does especially where the question presents itself, how that 
 infinity in the world of sense is possible which is required by 
 his doctrine that there are " ideas of particulars." Individual 
 differences, he allows, must according to this view be infinite, 
 seeing that there is no limit to the duration of the world either 
 in the past or in the future. The difficulty would be met by 
 supposing that differences finite in number recur exactly in 
 succeeding cycles. Thus, in any one cycle no two individuals 
 are without all formal difference, and yet the number of "forms " 
 is limited 4 . This solution, however, seems to be offered with 
 no great confidence. The point about which Plotinus is quite 
 clear is that individual as well as specific differences have their 
 rational determination in the ideal world. From this he deduces 
 that, in any one period of the cosmos at least, there are no two 
 
 1 Enn. ii. 1,7: to 6/j.wvv/j.ov avrf' </><£?, 6 dr} cpa/xep kcli dawfj-arov elvai. 
 - Cf. Enn. iv. 5. 3 Enn. iv. 4, 22—27. 
 
 4 Enn. v. 7, 2. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 75 
 
 individuals that differ only numerically, without a trace of 
 inward distinction 1 . About infinity in the ideal world or in 
 the soul there is no difficulty 2 . The conception of an actual 
 quantitative infinite is not merely difficult, but impossible. 
 
 Yet, while repeatedly laying down this position, Plotinus 
 allows that space and number as prefigured in eternal intellect 
 have an infinitude of their own. We may say that number is 
 infinite, though infinity is repugnant to number (to diretpov 
 fid^eTai Tftl dpL0/j,a>), as we speak of an infinite line ; not that 
 there is any such (oi>x 0Tt ^ a " TL Tt<? Toiavrr)), but that we can go 
 in thought beyond the greatest existing. This means that in 
 intellect the rational law of linear magnitude does not carry 
 with it the thought of a limit 3 . Similarly, number in intellect 
 is unmeasured. No actual number can be assigned that goes 
 beyond what is already involved in the idea of number. In- 
 tellectual being is beyond measure because it is itself the 
 measure. The limited and measured is that which is prevented 
 from running to infinity in its other sense of indeterminateness 4 . 
 Thus limited and measured is the visible cosmos. 
 
 To time is allowed an explicit infinity that is denied to 
 space. It is the "image of eternity," reflecting the infinite 
 already existent whole of being by the continual going to infinity 
 of successive realisations 5 . Time belongs to apartness of life 
 (BLdaraci^ ovv t,wr\<i XP° V0V € W e )- Tne Soul of tne Whole 
 generates time and not eternity, because the things it produces 
 are not imperishable. It is not itself in time; nor are individual 
 souls themselves, but only their affections and deeds 6 , which are 
 really those of the composite nature. Thus the past which is 
 the object of memory is in things done ; in the soul itself there 
 is nothing past 7 . Of Zeus, whether regarded as Demiurgus or 
 
 1 Erin. v. 7, 3. 
 
 2 Erin. v. 7, 1 : rr\v 5e ev tw vorjTco direipiav ov Sec dedievai ' irdcra yap iv 
 dfxepel. As regards the soul and its \6yoi, of. c. 3. 
 
 a Enn. vi. 6, 17 : 17 to dweipov aWou rpdirou, oi>x us ddteiiiTt]ToV dXXd iruis 
 dirupos ; rj iv ry \6ycp rrjs avToypa.pL/j.TJs ovk Zvi wpoavoovp.evov irepas. 
 
 * Enn. vi. 6, 18. 5 Enn. in. 7, 11. 
 
 B Enn. iv. 4, 15. 
 
 7 Enn. iv. 4, 16: dXXd -rrdvrts ol \6yoi dVa, uo-irep dpr)Tai...rb de r6de /xerd rode 
 tV rots Trpdyp.acni' ou dui/a/xevois dp.a wavra. 
 
7G THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 as Soul of the World, we must deny even the "before and after" 
 implied in memory 1 . That which guides the whole (to rj<yov- 
 fievov rod ttcivtos) knows the future as present {Kara to ea-rdvat), 
 and has therefore no need of memory and discursive reason to 
 infer it from the past 2 . These faculties belong to acquired in- 
 tellect, and, as we shall see, are dismissed even by the individual 
 soul when it has reascended to intuitive knowledge. 
 
 If things eternal were altogether alien to us, we could not 
 speak of them with intelligence. We also then must participate 
 in eternity 3 . How the -soul's essence can be in eternity while 
 the composite nature consisting of soul and body is in time, can 
 only be understood when the definition of time has been more 
 strictly investigated. To define it in relation to physical move- 
 ment does not express its essential character. The means by 
 which we learn to know time is no doubt observation of motion, 
 and especially of the revolutions of the heavenly bodies. Yet 
 while ordered external motion more than anything else shows 
 time forth to mental conception, it does not make time be. 
 When the motion of the whole is measured in terms of time, 
 which itself is fixed according to certain intervals marked out 
 in the space through which the motions proceed, this is an 
 " accidental " relation. The parts of time, invisible and inappre- 
 hensible in themselves, must have remained unknown till thus 
 measured, but time itself is prior to the measurement of its 
 parts. We must bring it back finally to a movement of the 
 soul, though the soul could hardly have known it to any purpose 
 without the movement of the heaven. Time is not, however, 
 in the merely individual soul, but in all souls so far as they are 
 one. Therefore there is one uniform time, and not a multitude 
 of disparate times ; as in another relation there is one eternity 
 in which all participate 4 . Thus the one soul, in which individual 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 4, 10. 
 
 2 Erin. iv. 4, 12. Hence, adds Plotinus, the creative power (to ttolovv) is not 
 subject to labour and difficulty, as was in the imagination of those who thought 
 the regulation of the whole would be a troublesome business. 
 
 3 Enn. in. 7, 7 : Set dpa /cat i]fuv /zeretVat rod alQvos. 
 
 4 Enn. in. 7, 13 : ap ovv /cat ev r\plv [6] xpopos ; fj ev ^pvxQ T-fi TOiavTy irdcrr] icai 
 6/u,oei5ws ev waai /cat at wdaai. p.la. did ov diaaTrairdrjaeTai 6 xP^vos' eVet ovd' 6 aiCbv 
 6 KO.T d\Xo ev tois ofioeideaL iraaiv. 
 
y] OF PLOTINUS 77 
 
 souls are metaphysically contained, participates in eternity and 
 produces time, which is the form of a soul living in apparent 
 detachment from its higher cause. 
 
 Unity in the soul of the whole, here so strongly insisted on, 
 does not with Plotinus exclude the reality of particular souls. 
 We have seen that he regards individuality as determined by 
 differences in the Ideas, and not by the metaphysically unreal 
 modes of pluralising ascribed to Matter. What comes from 
 matter is separateness of external manifestation, and mutability 
 in the realisations attained; not inner diversity, which pre- 
 exists in the world of being. This view he tarns against the 
 fatalism that would make the agency of the individual soul 
 count for nothing in the sum of things. He is without the 
 least hesitation a determinist. Within the universal order, he 
 premises, the uncaused (to ava'iTiov) is not to be received, 
 whether under the form of " empty declinations," or of a sudden 
 movement of bodies without preceding movement, or of a 
 capricious impulse of soul not assignable to any motive 1 . But 
 to say that everything in each is determined by one soul that 
 runs through all, is, by an excess of necessity, to take away 
 necessity itself and the causal order ; for in this case it would 
 not be true that all comes to pass by causes, but all things 
 would be one, without distinction between that which causes 
 and that which is caused; "so that neither we are we nor is 
 anything our work 2 ." Each must be each, and actions and 
 thoughts must belong to us as our own 3 . This is the truth 
 that physical, and especially astrological, fatalism denies. To 
 
 1 Etm. in. 1, 1: t? yap to j3ov\r)Tov—TOVTo 8e 77 §£u 77 eiVw — 7? rb iTndvfitirbv 
 ii<iv7}<j(V ij, el fj-riSev bpeKTov ei<lvqo-ev, ov5' av 6'Xws tKivqdr}. The principle of 
 psychological determinism could not be more clearly put. In view of this, it is 
 not a little surprising that Zeller should vaguely class Plotinus and his 
 successors as champions of "free-will." On the other hand Jules Simon, who 
 quite recognises the determinism of the school, misstates the doctrine of Plotinus 
 as regards the nature of the individual when he says (Histoire de VEcole 
 (V Alexandria, t. i. pp. 570—1) that that which is not of the essence of each soul, 
 and must consequently perish, is, according to Plotinus, its individuality, and 
 that this comes from matter. 
 
 2 Enn. in. 1, 4. 
 
 3 Cf. Enn. in. 4, 6: ov yap o.uolus lv rois avrois ttSs Kii/eirai 7) fiovXerai 77 
 
 ivepyet. 
 
78 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 preserve the causal order without exception while at the same 
 time allowing that we ourselves are something, we must intro- 
 duce the soul as another principle into the contexture of 
 things, — and not only the soul of the whole, but along with it 
 the soul of each 1 . Being in a contexture, and not by itself, it 
 is not wholly master, and so far fate or destiny (el/nap fievrj) 
 regarded as external, has a real existence. Thus all things 
 come to pass according to causes ; but some by the soul, and 
 some through the other causes among which it is placed. 
 Of its not thinking and acting rationally (tov p-rj cppovelv) 
 other things are the causes. Rational action has its cause 
 within ; being only not hindered from without 2 . 
 
 Virtue therefore is free ; and the more completely free the 
 more the soul is purified from mixture. To the bad, who do 
 most things according to the imaginations excited by bodily 
 affections, we must assign neither a power of their own nor a 
 proper volition 3 . How then can punishment be just? The 
 answer is that the composite nature, which sins, is also that 
 which pays the penalty of sin 4 . The involuntariness of sin 
 (on n/xapTia aKovaiov) does not prevent the deed being from 
 the doer 5 . Some men indeed come into being as if by a 
 witchcraft of external things, and are little or nothing of 
 themselves: others preserve the original nature of the soul's 
 essence. For it is not to be thought that the soul "alone of all 
 things is without such a nature 6 . In preserving or recovering 
 this lie virtue and freedom. 
 
 A more elaborate treatment of the problem of theodicy here 
 raised is contained in three books that belong to Plotinus's last 
 period 7 . This problem he does not minimise. Although, in 
 metaphysical reality, the world has not come to be by a process 
 of contrivance resembling human art, yet, he says, if reasoning 
 
 1 Enn. in. 1, 8. 2 Enn. in. 1, 10. 
 
 3 Enn. vi. 8, 3 : oiirt to eV avroh ovre to eKotiaiov dwaofiev. 
 « Enn. i. 1, 12. 5 Enn. in. 2, 10. 
 
 6 Enn. ii. 3, 15 : ov yap dij vofjucrr^ov toiovtov dvai ^uxV"j olov, 6 tl hv 'i^wdtv 
 iradrj, ravrqv cpvcrLv iax e <- v P&vrpt twv tt&vtwv olndav (pvav ovk ix ov,Jav - 
 i Enn. in. 2, in. 3, i. 8. 
 
y] OF PLOTINUS 79 
 
 had made it, it would have no reason to be ashamed of its 
 work 1 . This whole, with everything in it, is as it would be if 
 providentially ordered by the rational choice of the Maker 2 . 
 
 If, indeed, the world had come into existence a certain time 
 ago, and before was not, then the providence which regulates it 
 would be like that of rational beings within the world; it would 
 be a certain foresight and reasoning of God how this whole 
 should come to exist, and how it should be in the best manner 
 possible. Since, however, the world is without beginning and 
 end, the providence that governs the whole consists in its being 
 in accordance with mind, which is before it not in time but as 
 its cause and model so to speak. 
 
 From mind proceeds a rational law which imposes harmony 
 
 on the cosmos. This law, however, cannot be unmixed intellect 
 
 like the first. The condition of there being a world below the 
 
 purely intelligible order — and there must be such a world, that 
 
 every possible degree of perfection may be realised — is mutual 
 
 hindrance and separation of parts. The unjust dealings of men 
 
 with one another arise from an aspiration after the good along 
 
 with a want of power to attain it. Evil is a defection (e'A.\en/a<?) 
 
 of good ; and, in a universe of separated existences, absence of 
 
 good in one place follows with necessity from its presence in 
 
 another. Therefore evils cannot be destroyed from the world. 
 
 What are commonly called evils, as poverty and disease, Plotinus 
 
 continues to assert with the Stoical tradition, are nothing to 
 
 those who possess true good, which is virtue ; and they are not 
 
 useless to the order of the whole. Yet, he proceeds, it may still 
 
 be argued that the distribution of what the Stoics after all 
 
 allow to be things " agreeable " and " not agreeable " to nature, 
 
 is unfair. That the bad should be lords and rulers of cities, and 
 
 that men of worth should be slaves, is not fitting, even though 
 
 lordship and slavery are nothing as regards the possession of 
 
 real good. And with a perfect providence every detail must be 
 
 as it ought to be. We are not to evade the difficulty by saying 
 
 that providence does not extend to earth, or that through 
 
 chance and necessity it is not strong enough to sway things 
 
 1 Enn. in. 2, 3 : ov8' tl Xoyicr/xbs dij 6 Troir)<ras, aicx vl '^' ral T V iroiifOivTi.. 
 
 2 Enn. vr. 8, 17. 
 
80 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 here. The earth too is as one of the stars (&>? ev rt twi' 
 aarpcov) 1 . If, however, we bear in mind that we are to look 
 for the greatest possible perfection that can belong to a world 
 of mixture, not for that which can belong only to the intelligible 
 order, the argument may be met in full. Among men there 
 are higher and lower and intermediate natures, — the last being 
 the most numerous. Those that are so degenerate as to come 
 within the neighbourhood of irrational animals do violence to 
 the intermediate natures. These are better than those that 
 maltreat them, and yet are conquered by the worse in so far 
 as they themselves are worse in relation to the particular kind 
 of contest to be undergone. If they are content to be fatted 
 sheep, they should not complain of becoming a prey to the 
 wolves. And, Plotinus adds parenthetically, the spoilers too 
 pay the penalty ; first in being wolves and wretched men, and 
 then in having a worse fate after death, according to their 
 acquired character. For the complete order of justice has 
 regard to the series of past and future lives, not to each present 
 life by itself. But to take things as seen in one life : always the 
 mundane order demands certain means if we are to attain the 
 end. Those who have done nothing worthy of happiness cannot 
 reasonably expect to be happy. The law is, for example, that 
 out of wars we are to come safe by proving our courage, not by 
 prayer. Were the opposite the case, — could peace be preserved 
 amid every kind of folly and cowardice, — then indeed would 
 providence be neglectful. When the bad rule, it is by the 
 unmanliness of those that are ruled ; and it is just that it 
 should be so. Yet, such as man is, holding a middle rank, 
 providence does not suffer him to be destroyed, but he is 
 borne up ever toward the higher; the divine element giving 
 virtue the mastery in the long run. The human race partici- 
 pates, if not to the height, in wisdom and mind, and art and 
 justice, and man is a beautiful creation so far as he can be 
 consistently with his place in the universe. Reason (o \6yos) 
 made things in their different orders, not because it envied a 
 greater good to those that are lower placed, but because the law 
 
 1 Enn. in. 2, 8. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 81 
 
 itself of intelligential existence carries with it variety (ov $66vo3, 
 aXka \6y<o iroiKiXiav voepav e^oi/Tt). Thus in a drama all the 
 personages cannot be heroes. And reason does not take the 
 souls from outside itself and fit them into the poem by 
 constraining a portion of them from their own nature for the 
 worse. The souls are as it were parts of reason itself, and it 
 fits them in not by making them worse, but by bringing them to 
 the place suitable to their nature. If then, it may be asked, 
 we are not to explain evil by external constraint, but reason is 
 the principle and is all, what is the rational necessity of the 
 truceless war among animals and men ? First, destructions of 
 animals are necessary because, in a world composed of changing 
 existences, they could not be born imperishable. Thus, if they 
 were not destroyed by one another they would no less perish. 
 Transference of the animating principle from body to body, 
 which is promoted by their devouring each other, is better than 
 that they should not have been at all. The ordered battles 
 men fight as if dancing the Pyrrhic dance, show that what we 
 take for the serious affairs of mankind are but child's play, and 
 declare that death is nothing terrible 1 . It is not the inward 
 soul but the outward shadow of a man that groans and laments 
 over the things of life. But how then, the philosopher proceeds, 
 can there be any such thing as wickedness if this is the true 
 account ? The answer which he ventures' 2 is in effect that of 
 maleficent natures the Reason in the world might say : ' These 
 too have their part in me, as I too in these." This reason (ovto? 
 6 \0709) is not unmixed mind {aKparo^ vovs). Its essence is to 
 consist of the contraries that were in need of strife with one 
 another so that thus a world of birth might hold together (rrjv 
 avaracriv avra> Kal olov ouaiav tt}? TOLavTiy; ivavTHocreaiS 
 <}>epov(n)<;). In the universal drama the good and the bad must 
 perform the opposite parts assigned them. But from this does 
 it not follow that all is pardonable 3 ? No, answers Plotinus, for 
 
 1 Enn. in. 2, 15: uinrep 8b iwl tuv dedrpuv rah OKi]vah, ovtu \Pn "al rovs 
 <pbvovs dedffdat. Kal iravras davdrovs Kal irdXewv d\w<r«S Kal apirayds, ^era^crets 
 iravra Kal yuera(rxwa r 'ff«s * a ' Opv v ^ v Kal oinuywv viroKpicreis. 
 
 - Enn. in. 2, 16: reroW^w yap- rax* 5' hv Kal njxoifiev. 
 
 3 " Tout comprendre est tout pardonner." 
 
 w. 6 
 
82 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 the reason which is the creative word of the drama fixes the 
 place both of pardon and of its opposite ; and it does not assign 
 to men as their part that they should have nothing but forgive- 
 ness for the bad 1 . In the consequences of evil for the whole 
 there is nevertheless a rational order, and an order out of which 
 good may come 2 . 
 
 Still, that good may come of evil is not the deepest ground 
 of its existence. Some one might argue that evil, while it is 
 actual, was not necessary. In that case, even if good comes of 
 it, the justification of providence must fail. The reply has 
 been given already in outline. The necessity of evil results 
 from matter. Matter is necessary because, the principle of 
 things having infinite productive power, that power must 
 manifest itself in every possible degree : there must therefore 
 be a last term, to eoyaTov, which can produce nothing beyond 
 itself. " This is matter, having nothing any longer of its own ; 
 and this is the necessity of evil 3 ." If it is argued that moral 
 evil in us, coming as it does from association with the body, is 
 to be ascribed rather to form than to matter, since bodies derive 
 their distinctive character from form, the reply is that it is not 
 in so far as the forms are pure that they are the source of 
 ignorance and bad desires, but in so far as they are mixed with 
 matter (\6yot evv\oi). The fall of the soul is its approach to 
 matter, and it is made weak because its energies are impeded 
 by the presence of matter, which does not allow all its powers 
 to arrive at their realisation 4 . Yet without this principle of 
 indeterminateness that vitiates the pure forms, causing them 
 to miss their true boundary by excess or defect, there would be 
 for us neither good nor any object of desire. There would be 
 neither striving after one thing nor turning away from another 
 
 1 Enn. in. 2, 17: dXX' tacas crvyyvdofxrj to?s KaKocs' el fii) Kal to rrjs avyyvui/x^s 
 Kal /j.rj 6 \6yos noier iroiel de 6 \6yos /j.r]de o~vyyvu)/j.oi>as eirl tois toioutols elvcu. 
 
 2 Enn. in. 2, 18 : olov iK /xoi^et'as Kal alx/^a\uirov dycjyrjs TcuSes Kara cpvcriv 
 j3e\Tiovs Kal avdpes, el ti>xoi, Kal iroheis dXXcu a/meivovs tQiv ireiropOrin.ivwv iiirb 
 avdpQv irovqpQv. From a passage like this may we not infer that Plotinus was 
 able to see the barbarian inroads without despairing of the future ? 
 
 3 Enn. i. 8, 7. 
 
 4 Enn. i. 8, 14 : v\t) to'ivvv Kal aaffeveias \pvxy atria Kal KaKias ahla. wporepov 
 dpa KaKrj avTr] Kal irpwrov KaKbv. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 83 
 
 nor yet thought. " For our striving is after good and our 
 turning away is from evil, and thought with a purpose is of 
 good and evil, and this is a good 1 ." 
 
 The last sentence contains one of the two or three very 
 slight possible allusions in the whole of the Enneads to orthodox 
 Christianity. With Christian Gnosticism Plotinus deals ex- 
 pressly in a book which Porphyry has placed at the end of the 
 second Eimead 2 . A separate exposition of it may be given 
 here, both because it is in some ways specially interesting, and 
 because it brings together Plotinus's theory of the physical order 
 of the world and of its divine government. Any obscurity that 
 there is in it comes from the allusive mode of dealing with the 
 Gnostic theories, of which no exposition is given apart from 
 the refutation. The main points of the speculations opposed 
 are, however, sufficiently clear. 
 
 After a preliminary outline of his own metaphysico-theo- 
 logical doctrine, in which he dwells on the sufficiency of three 
 principles in the intelligible world, as against the long series 
 of " aeons " introduced by the Platonising Gnostics 3 , Plotinus 
 begins by asking them to assign the cause of the "fall" (acfxiX/xa) 
 which they attribute to the soul of the world. When did this 
 fall take place ? If from eternity, the soul remains fallen. If 
 the fall had a beginning, why at that particular moment and 
 not earlier ? Evidently, to undergo this lapse, the soul must 
 have forgotten the things in the intelligible world ; but if so, 
 how did it create without ideas ? To say that it created in 
 order to be honoured is a ridiculous metaphor taken from 
 statuaries on earth 4 . Then, as to its future destruction of the 
 
 1 Enn. I. 8, 15 : 17 yap opeiiis ayaOov, r\ 5£ ZkkXhtis kcikov, tj 5£ vbrjats Kal i] 
 (pp6vijffts ayadov Kal Kaicov, Kal axirij '4v tl tCiv ayaQCbv. 
 
 - Enn. 11. 9. Ilpds tovs KaKbv t6v drj/jnovpybv toO k6<thov Kal rbv Kbup.ov KaKov 
 dvai \tyovras, or Ilpds to i>s yvdXTTiKoijs. 
 
 3 Cf. Enn. 11. 9, 6 : ras 5£ aXXas vwoGTaaeis ii XPV X^7«" as daayovat, 
 TrapoiKiqaeis Kal dfTirinrovs Kal /leravoias ; 
 
 4 Enn. 11. 9, i : tl yap ai> cavrfi Kal iXoytfero ytviadai £k rod Koap.o- 
 voirjcai ; yeXoiov yap rb iVa tl/j.i2to, Kal p.tracpepbvTuii' dirb tCiv aya\p.aToirotwi> rQiv 
 ivTavda. 
 
 6—2 
 
84 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 world, if it repented of its creation, what is it waiting for ? If 
 it has not yet repented, it is not likely to repent now that it 
 has become more accustomed to that which it made, and more 
 attached to it by length of time. Those who hold that, because 
 there are many hardships in the world, it has therefore come 
 into existence for ill, must think that it ought to be identical 
 with the intelligible world, and not merely an image of it. 
 Taken as what it is, there could be no fairer image. And why 
 this refusal to the heavenly bodies of all participation in the 
 intelligible, — especially by men who complain of the disorder 
 in terrestrial things ? Then they introduce another soul, which 
 they make to be compacted of the material elements, as if that 
 was possible for a soul 1 . Not honouring this earth, they say 
 that there is a " new earth " to which they are to go, made in 
 the pattern of a world, — and yet they hate " the world." 
 Whence this pattern if not from the creative power which 
 they say has lapsed ? Much in their teaching Plotinus never- 
 theless acknowledges to be true. The immortality of the soul, 
 the intelligible world, the first God, the doctrine that the soul 
 ought to flee association with the body, the theory of its 
 separation, the flight from the realm of birth to that of being, 
 all these are doctrines to be found in Plato ; and they do well 
 in proclaiming them. On the part of Plato's disciples, there is 
 no disposition to grudge them the right to declare also the 
 points wherein they differ. They ought, however, to try to 
 prove what they have to say of their own on its merits, putting 
 their opinions with good feeling and like philosophers; not with 
 contumely towards " the Greeks," and with assertions that they 
 themselves are better men. As a matter of fact, they have only 
 made incongruous additions to that which was better in the form 
 given to it by the ancients 2 ; introducing all sorts of births and 
 destructions, and finding fault with the universe, and blaming 
 the soul of the whole for its communion with the body, and 
 casting reproach upon the ruler of this whole, and identifying 
 
 1 Enn. ii. 9, 5 : ttws yap av fwiji' tjvtivovv ^x° l V ^ K T & v (TTOtxelfat cnjaraais; 
 
 '-' Enn. ii. 9, 6 : eTrel t& ye elpr]fxiva tois iraXaiois -wepl twv votjtGjv 7roA\<J3 dfxelvu 
 /cat TreTraiSev/xtvcos etp^rat /cat tois p.7) i^aTraTup.ii'ois tt\v einde'ovaav eh dvOpuTrovs 
 &TT&Tr]v padius yvtxxrdriaerai. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 85 
 
 the Demiurgus with the Soul of the World 1 , and attributing the 
 same affections to that which rules the whole as to particular 
 things. 
 
 That it is not so good for our soul to be in communion with 
 the body as to be separate, others have said before; but the case 
 is different with the soul of the whole, which rules the frame 
 of the world unimpeded, whereas ours is fettered by the body. 
 The question wherefore the creative power made a world is the 
 same as the question wherefore there is a soul and wherefore 
 the Demiurgus made it. It involves the error, first, of suppos- 
 ing a beginning of that which is for ever ; in the next place, 
 those who put it think that the cause of the creation was a 
 turning from something to something else. The ground of that 
 creative action which is from eternity, is not really in discursive 
 thought and contrivance, but in the necessity that intelligible 
 things should not be the ultimate product of the power that 
 mauifests itself in them. And if this whole is such as to 
 permit us while we are in it to have wisdom, and being here 
 to live in accordance with things yonder, how does it not bear 
 witness that it has its attachment there ? 
 
 In the distribution of riches and poverty and such things, 
 the man of elevated character (o (nrovhalos) does not look for 
 equality, nor does he think that the possessors of wealth and 
 power have any real advantage. How if the things done and 
 suffered in life are an exercise to try who will come out victorious 
 in the struggle ? Is there not a beauty in such an order 2 ? If 
 you are treated with injustice, is that so great a matter to your 
 immortal being? Should you be slain, you have your wish, 
 since you escape from the world. Do you find fault with civic 
 life ? You are not compelled to take part in it. Yet in the 
 State, over and above legal justice with its punishments, there 
 is honour for virtue, and vice meets with its appropriate dis- 
 honour. In one life, no doubt the fulfilment is incomplete, but 
 
 1 Enn. n. 9, 6: nal els ravrbv dyovres rbv byjuiovpybv rrj xf/vxv- Both Yacherot 
 and Jules Simon find this identification in the system of Plotinus himself. The 
 error is corrected by Zeller, iii. 2, p. 633, n. 3. 
 
 - Enn. II. 9, 9 : «' de yv/xvdaiov eli) vikwvtuiv xal ^ttw/x^vuv, wQs oi) ko.1 ravrri 
 /coXws (x a * 
 
86 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v 
 
 it is completed in the succession of lives ; the gods giving to 
 each the lot that is consequent on former existences. Good 
 men should try to rise to such height of goodness as their 
 nature allows, but should think that others also have their 
 place with God, and not dream that after God they themselves 
 are alone in their goodness, and that other men and the whole 
 visible world are without all part in the divine. It is easy, 
 however, to persuade unintelligent men who have no real 
 knowledge what goodness is, that they alone are good and the 
 sons of God 1 . 
 
 Having remarked on some of the inconsistencies in the 
 mythological cosmogonies of the Gnostics, Plotinus returns 
 again to the point that the causation of natural things should 
 not be compared to the devices of an artist, the arts being 
 posterior to nature and the world 2 . We must not blame the 
 universe because all is' not equally good. That is as if one 
 were to call the power of growth evil because it is not 
 perception, or the perceptive faculty because it is not reason. 
 There are necessarily degrees in things. 
 
 The practice of exorcisms and incantations by the Gnostics 
 is especially attacked. They compose charms, says Plotinus, 
 addressed not only to the soul of the world but to still higher 
 powers, as if incorporeal things could be acted on by the sounds 
 of the voice modulated according to some cunningly devised 
 rules of art. Claiming as they do to have power against 
 diseases, they would say rightly if, with the philosophers, they 
 said that the means of keeping clear of them is temperance 
 and a regular mode of life. They ascribe them, however, to the 
 entrance of demons into the body, and profess to expel them by 
 forms of words. Thus they become of great repute with the 
 many, who stand in awe of magical powers ; but they will not 
 persuade rational men that diseases have not their physical cause 
 
 1 Near the end of c. 9, a comparison is borrowed from Plato, Rep. iv. 426 : 
 i) otet olbv t' ehai avSpl /j.7] eiriara/jLeity fxerpelv, irepcov tolovtuv voWQv \eybvrwv 
 otl TETpairqxv'S eariv, avrbv ravra p.rj ^yeiadai irepi avrov; 
 
 Enn. ii. 9, 12 : </>vcriKWTepoi> yap ttolvtus, d\\' ovx ws at Te'x"at ewolu ' varepai 
 yap Trjs </>i''<rews Kal tov Kba/nov at re'x"at. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 87 
 
 in "changes externally or internally initiated 1 ." If the demon 
 can enter without a cause, why is the disease not always 
 present ? If there is a physical cause, that is sufficient without 
 the demon. To say that, as soon as the cause comes to exist, 
 the demonic agency, being read}', straightway takes up its 
 position beside it, is ludicrous. 
 
 Next the antinomian tendency of the Gnostic sects is 
 touched upon. This way of thinking, the philosopher proceeds, 
 with its positive blame of providence going beyond even the 
 Epicurean denial, and dishonouring all the laws of our mundane 
 life, takes away temperance, and the justice implanted in moral 
 habits and perfected by reason and practice, and in general all 
 human excellence. For those who hold such opinions, if their 
 own nature is not better than their teaching, nothing is left 
 but to follow pleasure and self-interest ; nothing thought 
 excellent here being in their view good, but only some object 
 of pursuit in the future. Those who have no part in virtue, 
 have nothing by which they can be set in motion towards the 
 world beyond. To say, " Look to God," is of no use unless you 
 teach men how to look. This was taught in the moral dis- 
 courses of the ancients, which the present doctrine entirely 
 neglects. It is virtue carried to the end and fixed in the soul 
 with moral wisdom that points to God. Without true virtue, 
 God is but a name 2 . 
 
 The concluding chapters are directed against the refusal to 
 recognise in sensible things any resemblance to intelligible 
 beauty. How, Plotinus asks the Gnostic pessimists, can this 
 world be cut off from its intelligible cause ? If that cause is 
 absent from the world, then it must also be absent from you ; 
 for the providence that is over the parts must first be over the 
 whole. What man is there who can perceive the intelligible 
 harmony of music and is not moved when he hears that which 
 is in sensible sounds? Or who is there that is skilled in 
 geometry and numbers and does not take pleasure in seeing 
 
 1 Enu. II. '.I, 14 : tovs fiivroL ei> cppovovvras ovk av weiOoiev, u>s ovx o.l vbcot raj 
 airtas Zx ov(JLV V Kafiarois rj Tr\T}a/xouais rj ivodats t) cr)\j/((TL koX o'Xcjs /u.era/3o\cus 7] 
 i^uidev tj)v dpXTT' V IvooOev \aj3ovcrais. 
 
 2 Enn. ii. 0, 15 : avev 5e dperJJs a\i]0ii/rjs Oeos Xeyofxevos ouo/xd (<ttii>. 
 
88 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 the orderly and proportionate with his eyes ? And is there 
 any one who, perceiving all the sensible beauty of the world, 
 has no feeling of anything beyond it ? Then he did not 
 apprehend sensible things with his mind. Nothing can be 
 really fair outside and foul within. Those who are called 
 beautiful and internally are ugly, either have a false exterior 
 beauty also, or their ugliness is adventitious, their nature 
 being originally beautiful. For the hindrances here are many 
 to arriving at the end. Since this reason of shortcoming does 
 not apply to the whole visible world, which contains all, that 
 must necessarily be beautiful. Nor does admiration of the 
 beauty by which the physical universe participates in good 
 tend to bind us more to the body. Rather, it gives us reasons 
 for living well the life that is in the body. By taking all strokes 
 from without as far as possible with equanimity, we can make 
 our souls resemble, as nearly as may be, the soul of the whole 
 and of the stars. It is therefore in our power, while not finding 
 fault with our temporary dwelling-place, not to be too fond of 
 the body, and to become pure, and to despise death, and to know 
 the better and follow it, and to regard without envy those 
 higher mundane souls that can and do pursue the same intel- 
 ligible objects, and pursue them eternally 1 . 
 
 4. Aesthetics. 
 
 The passages devoted by Plotinus to aesthetics are not 
 lengthy, but among ancient writings that touch upon the 
 general theory of beauty and the psychology of art, they are 
 
 1 Philo also, it may be noted here, accepted the opinion attributing life and 
 mind to the stars. In his optimism of course the Jewish philosopher agrees with 
 Plato and Plotinus. The Gnostics seem to have taken up from the popular 
 astrology the notion that the planets exercise malignant influences. Plotinus has 
 some ironical remarks on the terror they express of the immense and fiery bodies 
 of the spheres. Against the astrological polytheism which regarded the planetary 
 gods as rulers of the world, he himself protests in a book where he examines 
 sceptically and with destructive effect the claims of astrology. See Enn. n. 3, 6: 
 6'Aus 5e fjLTjdevl ivi to Ktjpiov ttjs dLoiKrjcreus SiSopcu, tovtols 5£ rd Trdvra didovai, w&irep 
 ovk eTricrraTouvTos evos, d</>' oil dtrjprfjcrdac to irav endarui 8l86vtos Kara (pvcnv to aiiTov 
 irepalvew ko.1 ivepyeiv to. avTov avvTfTayfx^vov av /xer' avrov, \vovtos £o~ti kclI ayvoovvTos 
 Kdfffiov <pvaiv dpx^v exovTos /cat airiav irpwTrjv iwl wavra lovcrav. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 89 
 
 of exceptional value. In his early book " On the Beautiful 1 ," 
 where he closely follows Plato, he at the same time indicates 
 more than one new point of view. A brief summary will make 
 this clear. 
 
 Beauty, he first argues, cannot depend wholly on symmetry, 
 for single colours and sounds are beautiful. The same face too, 
 though its symmetry remains, may seem at one time beautiful, 
 at another not. And, when we go beyond sensible beauty, how 
 do action and knowledge and virtue, in their different kinds, 
 become beautiful by symmetry ? For, though the soul in which 
 they inhere has a multiplicity of parts, they cannot display a 
 true symmetry like that of magnitudes and numbers 2 . 
 
 The explanation of delight in sensible beauty, so far as it 
 can be explained, is that when the soul perceives something 
 akin to its own nature it feels joy in it; and this it does when 
 indeterminate matter is brought under a form proceeding from 
 the real being of things. Thus beauty may attach itself to 
 the parts of anything as well as to the whole. The external 
 form is the indivisible internal form divided in appearance by 
 material mass. Perception seizes the unity and presents it to 
 the kindred soul. An example of this relation is that among 
 the elements of body fire is especially beautiful because it is 
 the formative element 3 . 
 
 The beauty of action and knowledge and virtue, though not 
 seized by sense-perception, is like sensible beauty in that it 
 cannot be explained to those who have not felt it. It is itself 
 in the soul. What then is it that those who love beauty of 
 soul take delight in when they become aware of it either in 
 others or in themselves ? To know this, we must set its 
 opposite, ugliness, beside beauty, and compare them. Ugliness 
 we find in a disorderly soul, and this disorderliness we can only 
 understand as superinduced by matter. If beauty is ever to be 
 regained in such a soul, it must be by purification from the 
 admixture. The ugliness is in fact the admixture of disorderly 
 
 1 Enn. i. 6. Tiepl rod koKov. 
 
 2 Eim. I. 6, 1 : ovre yap ws fieyidr) otire us apidp.ol avp.jj.iTpa /ccu'toi wXeidvuv 
 fiepwv rrjs ipi'xys ovtuv. 
 
 3 Here the theoretical explanation is to be found in the Stoic physics. 
 
90 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 passions derived from too close association with the body, and 
 it is the soul itself in its unmixed nature that is beautiful. All v 
 virtue is purification. Now the soul, as it becomes pure of 
 regard for outward and inferior things, is borne upward to 
 intellect. In intellect accordingly is the native and not alien 
 beauty of the soul ; because only when thus borne upward is it 
 in truth soul and nothing else. Thus beauty is being, which is 
 one with intellect, and the nature other than being is the ugly. 
 The good and the beautiful are therefore to be looked for 
 together, as are the ugly and the evil. The first principle 
 (to irpoiTov) is Beauty itself (icaXkovr)), as it is the Good 
 (rdyadov). Intellect is the beautiful (to koKov). Soul is 
 beautiful through intellect. All other things are beautiful 
 through the formative soul. 
 
 A return must therefore be made again to the principle 
 after which every soul aspires, to the Idea of the Good in itself 
 and of Beauty in itself. This is to be reached by closing the 
 eyes to common sights and arousing another power of vision 
 which all have but few make use of 1 . For such vision you 
 must prepare yourself first by looking upon things done 
 beautifully by other souls. Thus you will be enabled to see 
 the beauty of the soul itself. But to see this, you must refer 
 it to your own soul. If there is any difficulty here, then your 
 task must be to shape your soul into accord with ideal beauty 
 as a sculptor shapes a statue. For only by such inward reference 
 is the beauty to be seen that belongs to souls 2 . 
 
 At the end of this book, Plotinus suggests a distinction 
 afterwards developed. If, he says, we speak broadly and with- 
 out exact discrimination, then the first principle, which projects 
 or radiates beauty from itself, may be called beautiful. If we 
 distinguish more accurately, we shall assign to the Ideas "intel- 
 ligible beauty " ; the Good which is beyond, we shall regard as 
 
 1 Euu. i. 6, 8. No vehicle of land or sea is of avail, dXXa ravra iravra 
 &<peivai 5et /cat pi] fikiiretv, dXX' olov fx.vaa.VTa 6\f/iv dWr/v dWd^aadai /cat dv eyelpai, 
 rjv ^x et V&v irds, xP&vTai <>e 0X1701. 
 
 2 Enn. 1. 6, 9 : to yap bpH.v irpbs to bpup-evov crvyyevks /cat op.oiov Troirjadpevov 
 Set e7ri/3dXXetf rjj 6ia. ou yap av nuiwoTe eldev 6<p8a\p.bs ijXiov r/Xtoet5rys /at) 
 yeyevrj.ucvos, ovde to na\di> &v loot \pvxh P-T] Ka\i) yevopivq. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS ' 1)1 
 
 the spring and principle of beauty 1 . Elsewhere he gives a 
 psychological reason why beauty is in the second place. Those 
 who apprehend the beautiful catch sight of it in a glimpse, and 
 while they are as it were in a state of knowledge and awake. 
 The good is always present, though unseen, — even to those that 
 are asleep, — and it does not astound them once they see it, nor 
 is any pain mixed with the recognition of it. Love of the 
 beautiful gives pain as well as pleasure, because it is at once a 
 momentary reminiscence and an aspiration after what cannot 
 be retained''. In another place 3 , the higher kind of beauty that 
 transcends the rules of art is declared to be a direct impress of 
 the good beyond intelligence. It is this, says Plotiuus, that 
 adds to the mere symmetry of beauty, which may still be seen 
 in one dead, the living grace that sets the soul actively in 
 motion. By this also the more lifelike statues are more 
 beautiful even when they are less proportionate. The irregu- 
 larity that comes from indeterminate matter is at the opposite 
 extreme, and is ugliness. Mere size is never beautiful. If bulk 
 is the matter of beauty (to fieya v\r) tov /ca\ov), this means 
 that it is that on which form is to be impressed. The larger 
 anything is, the more it is in need of beautiful order. Without 
 order, greater size only means greater ugliness 4 . 
 
 Discussing in a separate book, Intellectual or Intelligible 
 Beauty 5 , Plotinus begins by observing that the beauty of a 
 statue comes not from the matter of the unshapen stone, but 
 from the form conferred by art (irapd tov el'Sovs, o evfj/cev rj 
 Te^vr]). If any one thinks meanly of the arts because they 
 imitate nature 6 , first it must be pointed out that the natures of 
 the things imitated are themselves imitations of ideal being, 
 
 1 Enn. i. 6, 9 : ware bXoax^p^ fJ-t" Xbyo: to wpwToi/ ko\6v ■ SiaipQu be r& vo-qra, 
 to p.kv vorjTov koKov rbv twv elowv <pr\au t6ttov, to 5' dyaObv to ew^Keiua /cat wrjyr]!/ 
 teal &pxi v T °u koXov. 
 
 2 Enn. v. 5, 12 : ko.1 Z<tti de to fxev ffwiov koX wpoo-qvh koi afipbTepov kuI, (is 
 (0e\ei ris, irapbv aiVy to bi 6dp.(3os Hx ei Kai ficirXijfti» kclI av/x/xiyij ti£ dXyvvovn 
 tt\v rjoovqv. 
 
 3 Enn. vi. 7, 22. « Enn. vi. 6, 1. 
 
 5 Enn. v. 8. Ilept tov vot)tov k&Wovs. 
 
 6 The argument here is no doubt, as Mr Bosanquet remarks in his History 
 of Aesthetic, tacitly directed against Plato himself. 
 
92 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 which precedes them in the logical order of causation. And 
 the arts do not simply imitate the thing seen, but run back to 
 the rational laws whence its nature is. Besides, they create 
 much from themselves (7ro\Xa irap avrwv -ttoiovcti), filling up 
 deficiencies in the visible model. Thus Phidias did not shape 
 his Zeus after anything in perception, but from his own appre- 
 hension of the God as he might appear if he had the will to 
 manifest himself to our eyes. 
 
 The arts themselves — which as creative ideas are in the 
 soul of the artist — have a beauty surpassing that of the works 
 that proceed from them ; these being necessarily, from the 
 separateness of manifestation which takes the place of the 
 original unity, weakened resemblances of the mental concep- 
 tion that remains. Thus we are brought back to the thought 
 that if we would recognise true beauty, whether seen in nature 
 or in art, we must look within 1 . The proper abode of beauty 
 is the intellectual being to which the soul attains only by 
 inward vision. Above it is the good beyond knowledge, from 
 which it is infused. Below it is the beauty found dispersed 
 in visible things, by which the soul, if not altogether depraved 
 from its original nature, is awakened to the Beauty of the 
 Ideas. 
 
 5. Ethics. 
 
 The good which is beyond beauty is also beyond moral 
 virtue, as we saw at an earlier stage of the exposition. The 
 attainment of it belongs to the mystical consummation of 
 Plotinus's philosophy, and not properly to its ethical any more 
 than to its aesthetical part. At the same time, it is not regarded 
 as attainable without previous discipline both in practical moral 
 virtue and in the pursuit of intellectual wisdom. The mere 
 discipline is not sufficient by itself to assure the attainment of 
 the end ; but it is, to begin with, the only path to follow. 
 
 In treating of virtue on its practical side, Plotinus differs 
 from his Stoical predecessors chiefly in the stress he lays on the 
 interpretation even of civic virtue as a preliminary means of 
 
 1 Enn. v. 8, 2. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 93 
 
 purifying the soul from admixture with body. The one point 
 where he decidedly goes beyond them in the way of precept is 
 his prohibition of suicide 1 except in the rarest of cases 3 . Here 
 he returns in the letter of the prohibition to the view of earlier 
 moralists. The philosopher must no longer say to his disciples, 
 as during the period of the Stoic preaching, that if they are in 
 any way dissatisfied with life " the door is open." A moralist 
 under the Empire cannot, on the other hand, take the ground 
 of Aristotle, that suicide is an injury to the State. No public 
 interest was so obviously affected by the loss of a single unit 
 as to make this ground of appeal clearly rational. The argu- 
 ment Plotinus makes use of is substantially that which Plato 
 borrowed from the Pythagoreans. To take a violent mode of 
 departing from the present life will not purify the soul from 
 the passions that cling to the composite being, and so will not 
 completely separate it and set it free from metempsychosis. 
 Through not submitting to its appointed discipline, it may 
 even have to endure a worse lot in its next life 3 . So long as 
 there is a possibility of making progress here, it is better to 
 remain. - - 
 
 The view that in moral action the inward disposition is the 
 essential thing, is to be found already, as a clearly formulated 
 principle, in Aristotle. The Stoics had persistently enforced 
 it ; and now in Plotinus it leads to a still higher degree of 
 detachment, culminating as we shall see in mysticism. Porphyry 
 made the gradation of the virtues by his master somewhat 
 more explicit ; and Iamblichus was, as Vacherot has remarked 4 , 
 more moderate and practical in his ethical doctrine ; but invari- 
 ably the attitude of the school is one of extreme inwardness. 
 Not only is the inner spring that by which moral action is to 
 be tested ; the all-important point in relation both to conduct 
 and insight is to look to the true nature of the soul and, 
 
 1 Enn. i. 9. 
 
 2 Cf. Enn. I. 4, 7 : d\\' el cu'x/xdXwros 1x704x0, irdp rot iariv 656s i^vai, el fir) 
 eti) evSaifJ-ovetv. 
 
 3 Enn. 1. '.) : /cat el elixapfxivos x/>6Vos 6 bodels e/cdorw, wp6 tovtov ovk eiirvx^s, el 
 ix-q, tlicrwep (pa/xiv, avayKatov. 
 
 4 Jlistoire Critique tie VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. p. 62. 
 
94 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V 
 
 keeping this in view, to rid it of its excrescences. First in 
 the order of moral progress are the " political " virtues, which 
 make the soul orderly in the world of mixture. After these 
 come the " cathartic " virtues, which prepare it to ascend to the 
 ideal world. Positive virtue is attained simply by the soul's 
 turning back to the reality it finds when with purged sight it 
 looks within; and it may find this reality as soon as the negative 
 "purification" has been accomplished 1 . 
 
 The perfect life of the sage is not in community but in 
 detachment. If he undertakes practical activity, it must be 
 from some plain obligation, and the attitude of detachment 
 ought still to be maintained internally. Neither with Plotinus 
 nor with any of his successors is there the least doubt that the 
 contemplative life is in itself superior to the life of action. 
 Here they are Aristotelian. The chance that the philosopher 
 as such may be called on to reform practical life seems to them 
 much more remote than it did to Plato. Yet, in reference to 
 politics, as Zeller points out 2 , a certain predilection may be 
 noticed for the " Platonic aristocracy." It may be observed also 
 that Plotinus by implication condemns Asiatic monarchy as 
 unjust and contrary to nature 3 . And the view is met with 
 incidentally that practical wisdom is the result of deliberation 
 in common ; each by himself being too weak to achieve it. 
 Thus, in the single resolution arrived at by the joint effort 
 of all, political assemblies imitate the unity that is in the 
 world 4 . 
 
 That genuine freedom or self-dependence belongs properly 
 to the contemplative and not to the active life Plotinus main- 
 tains in one place 5 by the following argument. If virtue itself 
 were given the choice whether there should be wars so that it 
 might exercise courage, and injustice so that it might define 
 and set in order what is just, and poverty so that it might 
 display liberality, or that all things should go well and it should 
 
 1 Erin. i. 2, 4. - iii. 2, p. 605. 
 
 3 Enn. v. 5, 3. 
 
 4 Enn. vi. 5, 10 : /j.ifj,ovvTai 5i kclI eKKXrjcriai Kal vacra avvobos w? els ev ry (ppoveiv 
 ibvrwv • koX x^pts e/cacrroj els to (ppovelv aadevr/s, (TV/J.j3a\\wv de els b* was ev rfj avvddw 
 Kal tt) Cos dXyjOws <xvvio~ei to ppovelv eyivvrjcre Kal evpe. 
 
 5 Enn. vi. 8, 5. 
 
y] OF PLOTINUS 95 
 
 be at peace, it would choose peace. A physician like Hippo- 
 crates, for example, might choose, if it were within his choice, 
 that no one should need his art. Before there can be practical 
 virtue, there must be external objects which come from fortune 
 and are not chosen by us. What is to be referred to virtue 
 itself and not to anything external, is the trained aptitude of 
 intelligence and the disposition of will prior to the occasion of 
 making a choice. Thus all that can be said to be primarily 
 willed apart from any relation forced upon us to external things, 
 is unimpeded theoretical activity of mind. 
 
 In another book, the philosopher sets himself to defend in 
 play the paradox that all outgoing activity is ultimately for 
 the sake of contemplation 1 . Production (woi.r)cn<;) and action 
 {-TTpa^i^) mean everywhere either an inability of contemplation 
 to grasp its object adequately without going forth of itself, or 
 a secondary resultant (7rapaKo\ov07]fxa) not willed but naturally 
 issuing from that which remains in its own higher reality. 
 Thus external action with its results, whether in the works of 
 man or of nature, is an enfeebled product of contemplation. 
 To those even who act, contemplation is the end ; since they 
 act so that they may possess a good and know that they possess 
 it, and the knowledge of its possession is only in the soul. 
 Practice, therefore, as it issues from theory, returns to it 2 . At 
 the end of the book Plotinus, passing beyond the half-serious 
 view hitherto developed, indicates that the first principle of all 
 is prior even to contemplation. Here occurs the comparison of 
 it to the spring of life in the root of an immense tree. This 
 produces all the manifold life of the tree without becoming 
 itself manifold 3 . It is the good which has no need even of 
 mind, while mind contemplates and aspires after it. 
 
 The doubt for Plotinus is not whether the contemplative 
 
 1 Enn. in. 8, 1 : iral'SovTes 5r} ttjv irpwr^v irplv iwixa-P^v <nrovdd^ii> el Xe'yot./j.ei' 
 ■jravTa Oewplas i<pUadai Kal els tAos tovto /3\6rai>, ...ap av tis dva.axot.TO t6 irapdbo^ov 
 tqv \6yov : 
 
 - Enn. m. 8, 6 : dvlKap.\pev ovv trd\iv rj 7rpa£is els Oewpiav. Cf. c. 8 : irdpepyov 
 Oewpias rd wavra. 
 
 3 Enn. m. 8, 10: airrrj roivvv irap{o~x e ^ (v T V l/ "^dcrav £<jir\v rip <puTip tt\v woWtjv, 
 ffieive 5i avrr] ov ttoWt) ovaa, d\V dpxv rrjs iroWrjs. 
 
96 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v 
 
 life is higher than the life of action, but whether it can properly 
 be described as consisting in volition. Volition, he holds, is 
 hardly the right term to apply to pure intellect and the life in 
 accordance with it. Still less is it applicable to the One before 
 intellect. Yet, as he also insists, to speak of the first principle 
 as not-will and not-thought and not-knowledge would be even 
 more misleading than the application to it of the positive 
 terms. What is denied of the primal things is not denied in 
 the sense that they are in want of it, but in the sense that they 
 have no need of it, since they are beyond it. On the other 
 hand, when the individual nature takes upon itself, as appears, 
 one addition after another, it is in truth becoming more and 
 more deprived of reality 1 . To recover the reality that is all, 
 it must dismiss the apparent additions — which, if they indeed 
 affected the being that remains, would be diminutions — and 
 return to itself. Of such additions are practical activities. In 
 the world of mixture they are necessary, but they must be 
 treated as such, not thought of as conferring something more 
 upon the soul than it has in itself. Only by rising above them 
 in self-knowledge can the soul become liberated. Otherwise, it 
 remains attached to its material vehicle, and changes from body 
 to body as from one sleep to another. " True waking is a true 
 rising up from the body, not with a body 2 ." This cannot be 
 completely attained by practical virtue, which belongs to the 
 composite nature and not to the separable soul ; as the poet 
 indicates in the Odyssey when he places the shade of Hercules 
 in Hades but " himself among the gods." The hero has been 
 thought worthy to ascend to Olympus for his noble deeds, but, 
 as his virtue was practical and not theoretical, he has not wholly 
 ascended, but something of him also remains below 3 . The man 
 of practical virtue, as the Homeric account is interpreted else- 
 where 4 , will retain some memory of the actions he performed 
 on earth, though he will forget what is bad or trivial ; the man 
 of theoretic virtue, possessing now intuitive knowledge, will 
 
 1 Enn. VI. 5, 12: ov yap £k tov ovtos vjv t\ irpoadr)Kr) — ovdev yap iKeivuj wpocrOrj- 
 <reis- — dAAct tov fi-q ovtos. 
 
 2 Enn. in. 6, 6. 3 Enn. i. 1, 12. 
 4 Enn. iv. 3, 32. 
 
V] OF PLOTINUS 97 
 
 dismiss all memories whatever 1 . Memory, however, seems to 
 be thought of not as actually perishing, but as recoverable 
 should the soul redescend to relation with the material uni- 
 verse. 
 
 Here Plotinus is expressing himself, after Plato, in terms 
 of metempsychosis. As in the Platonic representation of the 
 future life, intermissions are supposed during which the purified 
 soul gets temporary respite from occupation with a body. 
 Plotinus, however, as we have seen, does not treat that which 
 is distinctively called the Platonic " reminiscence " as more than 
 a myth or a metaphor. When the soul, even here, is energising 
 in accordance with pure intellect, it is not "remembering." 
 Memory is of past experience, and is relative to time and its 
 divisions. The energy of pure intellect is not in relation to 
 time, but views things in the logical order of concepts. Hence 
 it is that the better soul strives to bring the many to one by 
 getting rid of the indefinite multiplicity of detail ; and so 
 commits much to oblivion. 
 
 Consistently with this general view, Plotinus holds that the 
 happiness of the sage receives no increase by continuance of 
 time 2 . We cannot make a greater sum by adding what no 
 longer exists to what now is. Time can be measured by 
 addition of parts that are not, because time itself, the " image 
 of eternity," belongs to things that become and are not. 
 Happiness belongs to the life of being, and this is incom- 
 mensurable with the parts of time. Is one to be supposed 
 happier for remembering the pleasure of eating a dainty 
 yesterday or, say, ten years ago ; or, if the question is of 
 insight instead of pleasure, through the memory of having had 
 insight last year / To remember things that went well in the 
 past belongs to one who has them nut in the present and, 
 because now he has them not, seeks to recall those that have 
 been. To the argument that time is necessary for the per- 
 formance of fair deeds, the reply is, first, that it is possible to 
 be happy — and not less but more so — outside the life of action. 
 In the next place, happiness comes not from the actual per- 
 
 1 Enn. iv. 4, 1. 
 
 %l Enn. I. 5. Et iv iro.po.7a.cti. xpovov rb tvoo.ip.ovuv. 
 
 w. 7 
 
98 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM OF PLOTINUS [V 
 
 formance of the deeds, but from the disposition with which 
 they are done. The man of right disposition will find happiness 
 in disinterested appreciation, for example, of patriotic deeds 
 which he has not himself had the opportunity of performing. 
 Hence (as the Stoics also held against Aristotle) length of life 
 is not necessary for its moral perfection 1 . 
 
 Several points of the ethics of Plotinus are brought together 
 in a book giving a philosophical interpretation of the fancy 
 that to each person is allotted his particular genius or 
 " daemon 2 ." Plotinus's interpretation is that the daemon of 
 each of us is the power next above that in accordance with 
 which his actual life is led. For those who live the common 
 life according to sense-perception, it is reason ; for those who 
 live the life of reason, it is the power above that. How then, 
 he asks, with reference to the " lots " in the Republic, if each 
 while " there " chooses his tutelary daemon and his life " here," 
 are we masters of anything in our actions ? The explanation 
 he suggests is, that by its mythical choice once for all " there," 
 is signified the soul's will and disposition in general every- 
 where 3 . Continuing in terms of the Platonic imaginations on 
 the destiny of souls, he observes that since each soul, as a 
 microcosm, contains within itself a representation not only of 
 the whole intelligible world, but also of the soul which guides 
 the visible universe 4 , it may find itself, after departure from 
 the body, in the sun or one of the planets or in the sphere of 
 the fixed stars, according as it has energised with the power 
 related to this or that part of the whole. Those souls that 
 have overpassed the " daemonic nature " are at this stage of 
 their mutation outside all destiny of birth and beyond the limits 
 of the visible heaven. 
 
 1 Enn. i. 5, 10 : to 5& ev reus Trpd^ecri to evbaifiovuu rideadat ev to?s e'fw ttjs 
 aperrjs Kal ttjs ^pvxvs e0 " rt tl9(vtos' tj yap tvepyeia Trjs i/'i'X 1 7 s & v T V 4>povr)aai Kal ei> 
 iavrfi wSl ivtpyrjcrai. Kal tovto to evdai/novus. 
 
 - Enn. in. 4. Hepl tov elXr/xoTOS Tinas dal/j.oi'os. 
 
 3 Enn. in. 4, 5 : dXX' el e^e? alpe?Tai tov Ba'ifxova Kal tov /3iov, ttws £ti twos 
 Kvpioi ; r; Kal i] a'ipeais eKei r) \tyofxevr} ttjv tt/s i/'i'X'? 5 Trpoaipeciv Kal Siddftnv Kad6\ov 
 Kal iravraxov atViTTerai. In Enn. n. 3, 15, the "lots" are interpreted as 
 meaning all the external circumstances of the soul at birth taken together. 
 
 4 Enn. m. 4, 6 : XPV 7<*P oteffOai Kal kSct/jlop dvai iv ttj \frvx3J rjfj.wv fir] ixbvov 
 vot)tov, d\\a Kal ^ux^s r V* xoafiov 6fioeL8rj Otiadecnv. 
 
CHAPTER VI. 
 
 THE MYSTICISM OF PLOTINUS. 
 
 The aim of philosophic thought, for Plotinus as for Plato, is 
 pure truth expressed with the utmost exactitude. And, much 
 as he abounds in metaphor, he knows how to keep his intellectual 
 conceptions clear of mixture with their imaginative illustration. 
 On the interpretation of myths, whether poetic or philosophic, 
 he is as explicit as intelligent readers could desire. After 
 allegorising the myth of Pandora and of Prometheus, for 
 example, he remarks that the meaning of the story itself may 
 be as any one likes, but that the particular interpretation has 
 been given because it makes plain the philosophic theory of 
 creation and agrees with what is set forth 1 . Again, in inter- 
 preting the Platonic myth of Eros, he calls to mind that myths, 
 if they are to be such, must separate in time things not 
 temporally apart, and divide from one another things that are 
 in reality together ; seeing that even rational accounts have to 
 resort to the same modes of separation and division 2 . This 
 relation between science and myth remained substantially the 
 same for his successors. Some of them might devote greater 
 attention to mythology, and indulge more seriously in fancies 
 that a deep philosophic wisdom was embodied in it by the 
 ancient " theologians " ; but the theoretical distinction between 
 
 1 Enn. IV. 3, 14 : ravra ixkv ovv 071-77 rts Soifdfet, d\\' otl €fj.<paiva to. ttjs et's tov 
 k6<t/j.op 56(7€0)s, /cat Trpoaq.dei rots Xeyo^vots. 
 
 2 Enn. in. 5, 9 : Set 8Z tovs fivdovs, dfrep tovto taovrai, /cat nepifeiv x/^ois a 
 \4yovat, Kal BiaipeTv air' d\\rj\wu noWd twi> 6vtuv 6/xou fxev cWa, rctfei 5t fj Owdfiecri 
 SuarUTa, oirov /cat ol \6yot /cat 7eef<rets tCjv dyevvriTwif irotovffi, /cat to, 6/j.ov ovra Kal 
 avrol 5iaLpovcrt, /cat Stodijaeres d>s ovvavrai rif voqeavTi tfo-q avyx^povai ovvaipeiv. 
 
 7—2 
 
100 THE MYSTICISM [VI 
 
 truth of science and its clothing in imaginative form is made, if 
 anything, sharper. The distinction comes to be used — as it is 
 already to some extent by Plotinus — to explain the physical 
 cosmogonies of early philosophers without supposing that they 
 meant to teach an actual emergence of the world from some 
 primordial element or chaotic aggregate and its return to this. 
 What the oldest philosophers had in view, according to the 
 Neo-Platonist system of interpretation, was only to render 
 their logical analysis of the world into its permanent con- 
 stituents easier to grasp. As the Neo-Platonist doctrine itself 
 was thought out wholly on the line of the philosophical 
 tradition, its relation to " positive religion " is quite the 
 opposite of subservience. The myths are completely plastic 
 in the hands of the philosophers. Of their original meaning, 
 no doubt they have a less keen sense than Plato, who saw the 
 real hostility of a naturalistic " theogony " like that of Hesiod 
 to his own type of thought ; but this only shows how dominant 
 the philosophical point of view has become. Plato could not 
 yet treat the myths of Greek religion so arbitrarily as would 
 have been necessary for his purpose, or did not think it worth 
 while. For the Neo-Platonists the poetic mythology has 
 become like their own "matter," absolutely powerless to 
 modify the essence of thought, but equally ready to take on 
 an elusive reflexion of every idea in turn. Not in this quarter, 
 therefore, need we look for any derogation from the scientific 
 character of Neo-Platonic thought. 
 
 If Plotinus accepted Hellenic religion as the basis of culture, 
 the reason was because he saw in it no obstacle to the adequate 
 expression of philosophic truth ; which, moving freely on its 
 own plane, could turn the images of mythology themselves to 
 the account of metaphysics and ethics. Some members of the 
 school, as we know, were given to devotional practices and to 
 theurgy ; but in all this the master did not personally join. 
 On one occasion indeed, he seemed to his disciples to speak too 
 loftily on the subject, though, as Porphyry tells us, they did not 
 venture to ask his meaning. Amelius had become diligent in 
 sacrificing and in attending the feasts of the gods, and wished 
 to take Plotinus with him. He declined, saying, "It is for 
 
VI] OF PLOTINUS 101 
 
 them to come to me, not for me to go to them 1 ." The 
 explanation is no doubt to be found in the contrast between 
 the common religious need for a social form of worship and 
 the subjective intensity of the mystic. That this was in the 
 temperament of Plotinus is evident all through the Enneads. 
 His religious attitude invariably is that the soul, having duly 
 prepared itself, must wait for the divinity to appear. External 
 excitement is the very reverse of the method he points out : 
 he insists above all on internal quietude. Porphyry also has 
 something to tell us on the subject. Four times while he was 
 with him, he relates, Plotinus attained the end of union with 
 the God who is over all, without form, above intellect and all 
 the intelligible. Porphyry himself attained this union once, in 
 his sixty-eighth year-. The mystical " ecstasy " was not found 
 by the later teachers of the school easier to attain, but more 
 difficult ; and the tendency became more and more to regard it 
 as all but unattainable on earth. Are we to hold that it was 
 the beginning of Plotinus's whole philosophy ; that a peculiar 
 subjective experience was therefore the source of the Neo- 
 Platonic doctrines ? This will hardly seem probable after the 
 account that has been given of Plotinus's reasoned system ; 
 and, in fact, the possibility of the experience is inferred from 
 the system, not the propositions of the system from the 
 experience. It is described as a culminating point, to be 
 reached after long discipline ; and it can only be known from 
 itself, not from any description. Not being properly a kind of 
 cognition, it can become the ground of no inference. Now, 
 since the philosophy of Plotinus undoubtedly claims to be a 
 kind of knowledge, it must have its evidence for learners in 
 something that comes within the forms of thought. While he 
 was personally a mystic, his theory of knowledge could not be 
 mystical without contradicting the mysticism itself. 
 
 In modern phraseology, it was a form of Rationalism. 
 Cognition at its highest degree of certainty, as Plotinus 
 understands it, may best be compared to Spinoza's " knowledge 
 of the third kind," or '' scieutia intuitiva 3 ." Exactly as with 
 
 1 Porpli. V. Plot. 10: eKeivovs Sd vpbs ipie 2px«r0ai, ovk i/xe irpbs indvov>. 
 - V. Plot. 23. ;i Eth, ii. Prop. 40, Scbol. 2. Cf. Enu. vi. 7, 2. 
 
102 THE MYSTICISM [VI 
 
 Spinoza, the inferior degrees that lead up to it are : first, the 
 " opinion " that is sufficient for practical life ; second, the 
 discursive " reason " that thinks out one thing adequately from 
 another, but does it only through a process, not grasping the 
 relation at once in its totality. The difference is that Plotinus 
 conceives the highest kind of knowledge not as mathematical 
 in form but as " dialectical." By " dialectic " he means, not a 
 purely formal method, a mere " organon," but a method of 
 which the use, when once attained, gives along with the form 
 of thought its content, which is true being 1 . Before the learner 
 can reach this stage, he must be disciplined in the other 
 branches of liberal science. As with Plato, dialectic is the 
 crown of a philosophical education. Nor does Plotinus alto- 
 gether neglect the logical topics he regards as subsidiary to 
 this. At the beginning of the sixth Ennead is placed a 
 considerable treatise'- in which he criticises first the Stoic and 
 then the Aristotelian categories, and goes on to expound a 
 scheme of his own. This scheme, as Zeller remarks, has not 
 the same importance for his system as those of Aristotle and of 
 the Stoics for theirs. Porphyry, in his larger commentary on 
 the Categories, defended Aristotle's treatment against the 
 objections of Plotinus, and thenceforth the Aristotelian cate- 
 gories maintained their authority in the school 3 . On the other 
 hand, it must be observed that this affects only a subsidiary 
 part of Plotinus's theory of knowledge. His general view 
 regarding the supremacy of dialectic as conceived by Plato, 
 was also that of his successors. In subordination to this, 
 Aristotle's list of the most general forms of assertion about 
 being held its own against the newer scheme of Plotinus. By 
 the Athenian successors of Plotinus more definitely than by 
 himself, Aristotle came to be regarded as furnishing the needful 
 preliminary training for the study of Plato 4 . 
 
 1 Enn. i. 3. He pi SiaXeKTiKrjs. 
 
 - Emi. vi. 1-3. llepi twv yev&v tou ovtos. 3 Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 523 — i. 
 
 4 The doctrine of categories elaborated by Plotinus being for the most part in 
 no organic relation to his general system, it did not seem necessary to give a 
 detailed exposition of it. Its abandonment by the Neo-Platonic school, besides, 
 makes it historically less important. 
 
Vl] OF PLOTINUS 103 
 
 The philosophic wisdom of which dialectic is the method, 
 Plotinus expressly declares 1 , cannot be achieved without first 
 going through the process of learning to know by experience. 
 Knowledge and virtue at lower stages can exist, though not in 
 perfection, without philosophy; but except by starting from 
 these, the height of theoretic philosophy is unattainable. Even 
 when that height is attained, and being is known in intuitive 
 thought, there is something remaining still. The One and 
 Good, which is the first principle of things, is beyond thought. 
 If it is to be apprehended at all, and not simply inferred as 
 the metaphysical unity on which all things necessarily depend, 
 there must be some peculiar mode of apprehending it. Here 
 Plotinus definitely enters upon the mystical phase of his 
 doctrine. The One is to be seen with " the eyes of the soul," 
 now closed to other sights. It becomes impossible, as he 
 recognises, to use terms quite consistently, and he cannot 
 altogether dispense with those that signify cognition ; but it 
 is always to be understood that they are not used in their strict 
 sense. That which apprehends the One is intellect — or the 
 soul when it has become pure intellect ; so that the principle 
 above intelligence has sometimes to be spoken of as an " in- 
 telligible," and as that which mind, when it " turns back," 
 thinks before it thinks itself. For by this reflexive process — in 
 the logical order of causes — mind comes to be, and its essence 
 is to think. On the other hand, the One does not "think"; 
 its possession of itself is too complete for the need to exist 
 even of intuitive thought. Accordingly, since it can only 
 be apprehended by the identification with it of that which 
 apprehends, mind, to apprehend it, must dismiss even the 
 activity of thought, and become passive. At last, unexpectedly, 
 the vision of the One dawns on the purified intellectual soul. 
 The vision is "ineffable": for while it can only be indicated in 
 words that belong to being, its object is beyond being. All 
 that can be done is to describe the process through which it 
 comes to pass, and, with the help of inadequate metaphors, 
 to make it recognisable by those who may also attain it 
 themselves. 
 
 1 Enn. i. 3, 0. 
 
104 THE MYSTICISM [VI 
 
 Since that which is sought is one, he who would have the 
 vision of it must have gone back to the principle of unity in 
 himself; must have become one instead of many 1 . To see it, 
 we must entrust our soul to intellect, and must quit sense and 
 phantasy and opinion, and pay no regard to that which comes 
 from them to the soul. The One is an object of apprehension 
 {avveai'i) not by knowledge, like the other intelligibles, but 
 by a presence which is more than knowledge. If we are to 
 apprehend it, we must depart in no way from being one, but 
 must stand away from knowledge and knowables, with their 
 still remaining plurality. That which is the object of the 
 vision is apart from no one, but is of all ; yet so as being 
 present not to be present except to those that are able and 
 have prepared themselves to see it 2 . As was said of matter, 
 that it must be without the qualities of all things if it is to 
 receive the impressions of all, so and much more so, the soul 
 must become unformed {uveiheos;) if it is to contain nothing to 
 hinder its being filled and shone upon by the first nature*. 
 The vision is not properly a vision, for the seer no longer 
 distinguishes himself from that which is seen — if indeed we 
 are to speak of them as two and not as one 4 — but as it were 
 having become another and not himself, is one with that other 
 as the centre of the soul touching the centre of all 5 . While 
 here, the soul cannot retain the vision ; but it can retreat to it 
 in alternation with the life of knowledge and virtue which is 
 the preparation for it. " And this is the life of gods and of 
 godlike and happy men, a deliverance from the other things 
 here, a life untroubled by the pleasures here, a flight of the 
 alone to the alone." 
 
 1 Enn. vi. 9, 3. 
 
 2 Enn. vi. 9, 4 : oi'» yap 8r] aireuriv ov8evus exe'ivo Kal irdvTwv 8e, ware irapbv fir) 
 irapetvai dXX' r) rols 5e'xf<r#cu Swa/nevoLS Kal ira.pi<TKtva<jp.ivoi.s. Cf. C. 7 : ov yap Kelral 
 ttov ip-qp-Ciaav avrov t& dXXa, dXX' ecrrt tu dwafxevLi} diyelv (Kelvo irapbu, ra; 5' 
 abvvarovvri ov iraptcrriv. 
 
 6 Enn. vi. 9, 7 : el /xeXXet p.7]bev e/xwodiov iyKad-qfxtvov ZotaOai rrpbs TrXrjpwcriv 
 Kal ^Wapi-if/iv avrrj rrjs tpvcreus 7^s irpwTTjs. 
 
 4 "An audacious saying," adds Plotinus. 
 
 5 Enn. vi. 9, 10. Cf. c. II : to 5e i<rus yjv ov Otajj-a, dXXd dXXos rpowos rod 
 £de?v, '{KGTaais Kal airXwcris Kal eVicotns avrov Kal e<peo~is Trpos a<f>7)v Kal oraffis. 
 
Vl] OF PLOTINUS 105 
 
 These are the concluding words of the Enneads in Porphyry's 
 redaction. In another book, which comes earlier but was written 
 later 1 , Plotinus describes more psychologically the method of 
 preparation for the vision. The process, which may begin at 
 any point, even with the lowest part of the soul, consists in 
 stripping off everything extraneous till the principle is reached. 
 First the body is to be taken away as not belonging to the true 
 nature of the self ; then the soul that shapes the body ; then 
 sense- perception with appetites and emotions. What now 
 remains is the image of pure intellect 2 . Even when intellect 
 itself is reached by the soul turning to it, there still remains, 
 it must be repeated, the duality and even plurality implied in 
 synthetic cognition of self as mind". Mind is self-sufficing, 
 because it has all that it needs for self-knowledge ; but it needs 
 to think itself. The principle, which gives mind its being and 
 makes it self-sufficing, is beyond even this need ; and the 
 true end for the soul is, by the light it sees by, to touch and 
 gaze upon that light. How is this to be done ? Take away 
 all 4 . 
 
 All other things, as Plotinus says elsewhere, in comparison 
 with the principle have no reality, and nothing that can be 
 affirmed of them can be affirmed of it. It has neither shape 
 nor form, and is not to be sought with mortal eyes. For those 
 things which, as perceptible by sense, are thought most of all 
 to be, in reality most of all are not. To think the things of 
 sense to be most real is as if men sleeping away all their lives 
 should put trust in what they saw in their dreams, and, if one 
 were to wake them up, should distrust what they saw with 
 open eyes and go off to sleep again 5 . Men have forgotten what 
 even from the beginning until now they desire and aspire after. 
 " For all things strive after that and aspire after it by necessity 
 
 1 Enn. v. 3. 
 
 '-' This is related to intelleet itself as the moon to the sun. Cf. Enn. v. <>, 4. 
 •' Enn. v. 3, 13: Kivbvvevei yap o\ws to voetv iroWwv (is avrb avveXdbvTwv 
 o~vvaio~0r)cns elvai rov o\ov, brav avro tl eavrb vorj' 6 Srj Kvpius icri vouv. 
 
 4 Enn. v. 3, 17 : Kal tovto to reXos raXridivbv ^i'xf?> e<p&ipacrdcu <pwrbs entivov 
 
 Kal (xvtu avrb 0ed<rao~dai, ovk dWui ipwri, d\\" cu't^j, 5t' ov Kal bpq. wws dv ovv 
 
 tovto yevoiTo; &<pe\e irdvTa. 
 
 5 Enn. v. 5, 11. 
 
106 THE MYSTICISM [VI 
 
 of nature, as if having a divination that without it they 
 cannot be 1 ." 
 
 Much as all this may resemble Oriental mysticism, it does 
 not seem to have come from any direct contact with the East. 
 Zeller indeed finds in the idea of a mental state beyond 
 cognition a decisive break with the whole direction of classical 
 thought, and makes Philo here the sole predecessor of Plotinus' 2 . 
 But, we may ask, whence came the notion to Philo himself? 
 The combination of the most complete " immanence " in one 
 sense with absolute transcendence of Deity in another, does not 
 seem native to Jewish religion, any more than the asceticism 
 for which, in the Essenes, Zeller finds it necessary to recur to 
 a Greek origin. Once get rid of the presupposition that Neo- 
 Platonism sprang from a new contact with Eastern theosophy, 
 and the solution is clear. To Philo and to Plotinus alike, the 
 direct suggestion for the doctrine of "ecstasy" came from Plato. 
 The germinal idea that there is a mode of apprehension above 
 that of perfectly sane and sober mind appears already in more 
 than one Platonic dialogue. During the period of almost 
 exclusively ethical thinking, between Aristotle and revived 
 Pythagoreanism and Platonism, hints of the kind naturally 
 found little response. After the revival of speculative thought, 
 it is not surprising that they should have appealed to thinkers 
 of widely different surroundings. The astonishing thing would 
 have been if in all the study then given to Plato they had 
 been entirely overlooked. That neither Philo nor Plotinus over- 
 looked them may be seen from the references and quotations 
 given by Zeller himself 3 . What is more, Plotinus definitely 
 contrasts intellect soberly contemplating the intelligible with 
 intellect rapt into enthusiasm and borne above it ; and explains 
 the Platonic imagery of " insanity " and " intoxication " as 
 referring to the latter state. Mind is still sane while con- 
 templating intellectual beauty, and is seized upon by the 
 "divine madness" only in rising above beauty to its cause 
 
 1 Enn. v. 5, 12. 
 
 2 iii. 2, pp. 448, 611. 
 
 3 See, for Philo, iii. 2, p. 415, u. 5; for Plotinus, p. 615, n. 3. Cf. Porph. 
 V. Plot. 23. 
 
Vl] OF PLOTINUS 107 
 
 beyond 1 . That Plotinus derived from Plato his conception of 
 the Good beyond being is generally admitted. It is equally 
 clear that for the theory of its apprehension also there 
 presented itself a Platonic point of view. Thus even the 
 mystical consummation of his philosophy may be traced to a 
 Hellenic source. 
 
 Plato's own imagery, and in connexion with it his occasional 
 mention of " bacchants " and "initiates," may of course have 
 been suggested by forms of worship that were already coloured 
 bv contact with the East ; but this does not affect the character 
 of the Neo-Platonic school as in its own age essentially a 
 classical revival. It was not inhospitable to Oriental cults, 
 being indeed vaguely conscious of an affinity to those that were 
 associated, in the higher order of their devotees, with a con- 
 templative asceticism ; and, as willingly as Plato, it found 
 adumbrations of philosophic truth in religious mysteries. 
 These, however, as we have seen, in no case determined the 
 doctrine, which was the outcome of a long intellectual tradition 
 worked upon by thinkers of original power. The system left 
 by Plotinus was further elaborated by the best minds of his 
 own period; and, during the century after his death, we find 
 it making its way over all the Graeco-Roman world. Defeated 
 in the practical struggle, it became, all the more, the accepted 
 philosophy of the surviving Greek schools; to take up at last 
 its abode at Athens with the acknowledged successors of 
 Plato. These stages will be described in the chapters that 
 follow. 
 
 1 Enn. VI. 7, 35 : koX rbv voxiv ro'ivvv [Set] rrjv fxev ^x eiv Svvapup els to voelv, 17 to, 
 iv ai'Tw /3\e7ret, tt]v 8e, 77 ra eireKuva avrou eTrifioXfj tivi ko.1 irapaboxa, K ^' V" *<*' 
 ■wportpov eiipa fxofov Kai 6pu>v vcrrepov KaX vovv ^<xxe Kai 'iv iari ' tcai icrriv ixtivri p.tv 
 7} dka vov Zp.<ppovos, avTt) 8i vovs epQv. orav [yap] atppuv yevrjTai fitOvafjels tov 
 ViKrapos, rote tpuv yiverai air\u)6th us tvwdOfiav toj Kopu>. 
 
CHAPTER VII. 
 
 THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM. 
 
 1. Porphyry. 
 
 Both for his own and for succeeding times, the name of 
 Porphyry stands out conspicuous among the disciples of Plotinus. 
 Eunapius, writing towards the end of the fourth century, observes 
 that Plotinus is now more in the hands of educated readers than 
 Plato himself; and that, if there is any popular knowledge of 
 philosophy, it consists in some acquaintance with his doctrines. 
 He then proceeds to give credit for this to the interpretations of 
 Porphyry. And thus, he says, the honour was distributed from 
 the first. Universally the doctrine was ascribed to Plotinus; 
 while Porphyry gained fame by his clearness of exposition — 
 "as if some Hermaic chain had been let down to men 1 ." He 
 then goes on to celebrate Porphyry's knowledge of all liberal 
 science (ovSev 7raiSeia<i el8os 7rapa\e\oi7ra><;) ; of which we have 
 independent evidence in his extant works and in the titles of 
 those that are lost. Eunapius's biography seems to have been 
 mostly compiled— not always with perfect accuracy — from the 
 information given by Porphyry himself in his Life of Plotinus. 
 
 Porphyry was born in 233 and died later than 301. He was 
 a Tyrian by birth. His name was originally " Malchus," the root 
 of which, in the Semitic languages, means " a king." At the 
 
 1 Eunap. Vitae (Porphyrins) : 6 jih yap UXomVos rip re ttjj V' l 'X^ s ovpav'up /cat 
 ry XoijtfS /cat alviy/jLaTwdei twv \6yuv, (3apvs e56/cei /cat Sixttjkoos ' 6 de llop(pvpLOS, 
 ai<77re p ' Epixal'Krj tls aeipa /ecu 7rpos avdpwirovs emvevovcra, 5ia ttoikIXtis iratdelas iravTa 
 eis to iiiyuwcTOV /cat Kadapbv e^rjyytWev. 
 
VI l] THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM 109 
 
 suggestion of his teachers he Hellenised it first into "Basileus" 
 and then into " Porphyrins" (from the colour of regal garments). 
 After having studied under Longinus at Athens, he visited 
 Rome, and there, as we have seen, became a disciple of Plotiuus 
 from the year 203. His journey to Sicily, with its cause, has 
 been already mentioned. Afterwards he returned to Rome ; 
 and it was in Rome, according to Eunapius, that he gained 
 reputation by his expositions of Plotinus. Late in life he 
 married the widow — named Marcella — of a friend ; for the 
 sake of bringing up her children, as we learn both from 
 Eunapius and from Porphyry's letter to her which is extant. 
 She was subjected to some kind of persecution by her neigh- 
 bours, who, Jules Simon conjectures', may have been Christians, 
 and may have sought to detach her from philosophy. The 
 letter is an exhortation to perseverance in philosophical 
 principles, and is full of the characteristic ethical inwardness 
 of Neo-Platonisnr. That Porphyry engaged in controversy 
 with Christianity, now on the verge of triumph, is well known : 
 and with him, as with Julian, the effect is a just perceptible 
 reaction of Christian modes of thought or speech. As theo- 
 logical virtues he commends (t faith, truth, love, hope " ; adding 
 only truth to the Christian three 3 . 
 
 A distinctive character of his treatise against the Christians 
 seems to have been its occupation with questions of historical 
 criticism. Very little of it has been preserved even in fragmen- 
 tary form, the set replies of apologists, as well as the treatise 
 itself, being lost ; but the view he took about the Book of 
 Daniel is on record. According to Jerome, he maintained that 
 it was written in the time of Antiochus Epiphanes ; so that the 
 historical events supposed to have been predicted were really 
 events that had taken place before the time of the writer. 
 
 1 Histoire <L' VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. pp. 98 — 9. 
 
 - See for example Epittola ad Marcellam, c. 9 : 7rtDs oTv ovk drotrov tt)v 
 iveTrei<Jixtvr)v iv aol elvat Kai rb <tQ$ov Kai rb <np'^6p.(vov Kai rb ye airoWvov Kai <rb> 
 diroWvuevov tov re ttXovtov Kai ttjv Trcvlav t6v re iraripa ko.1 rbv dvbpa Kai tov tuiv 
 ovtws dyadQv Kadrjyt/Mbva, Kexv"tvai ""po* T h v T °v v<pr]yrjTov GKidv, ws 8rj rbv 6vtus 
 v<pr)yy]Tr\v /xt) ivrbs £x ovo ~ av f* 7 )^ itapd ffavrfj iravra rbv ttXovtov ; 
 
 3 Ad Marcellam, 24: T^craapa aroix^a p-dXiara KfKparvvOu nepl deov' ttIgtis, 
 d\r)deia, fycus, iKrls. 
 
110 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 This, Jerome says, proves the strength of the case in favour 
 of its genuinely prophetic character; for if events subsequent 
 to the time of Daniel had not been very clearly prefigured, 
 Porphyry would not have found it necessary to argue against 
 the ascription to him of the authorship 1 . 
 
 In the time of Plotinus, Porphyry recounts, there were 
 members of various sects, both Christians and others, who put 
 forth apocalypses such as those attributed to Zoroaster and 
 Zostrianus, by which they " deceived many, themselves also 
 deceived." Amelius wrote against the book of " Zostrianus " ; 
 Porphyry himself against that of " Zoroaster," showing it to be 
 spurious and recent and forged by the authors of the sect in 
 order to give currency to the opinion that their own doctrines 
 were those of the ancient Zoroaster 2 . The spirit of critical 
 inquiry thus aroused in Porphyry seems to have led him more 
 and more to take the sceptical view about all claims to 
 particular revelations from the gods, including the " theurgic " 
 manifestations to which attention was paid by some members 
 of the Neo-Platonic school. It was probably at a late period of his 
 life that he wrote the letter to the Egyptian priest Anebo,to which 
 an unknown member of the school of Iamblichus replied, under 
 the name of " Abammon," in the famous book De Mysteriis. 
 
 One little book of Porphyry, entitled De Antro Nympkarum, 
 is an interesting example of the mode of interpreting poetic 
 mythology current in the school. Porphyry there sets out to 
 show that Homer, in his description of the Grotto of the 
 Nymphs at Ithaca 3 , probably did not give an account of an 
 actual cavern to be found in the island — for topographers 
 make no mention of any that resembles the description — but 
 deposited in allegorical form an ancient " theological wisdom " 
 identical with true philosophy. If there really is such a 
 
 1 Cf. Jules Simon, Histoire de VEcole cVAlexandrie, t. ii. p. 181. " L'on peut 
 juger," says the historian on the preceding page, "par l'indignation menie que 
 cet ouvrage excita dans l'Eglise, de l'importance et de la gravite des attaques 
 qu'il contenait." 
 
 2 Vita Plotini, 16 : vodov re ko.1 veov to j3ij3\iov trapadetKuvs irew\affp.evov re 
 virb tuiv rrjv a'ipecnv aiKTrqaafxivwu els So^af rod elvai rov Trakaiod 7iupoa(TTpov ra 
 86yp.a.Ta, a avrol eiXovro Trpe<r[3ei!iei)>. 
 
 3 Od. xiii. 102—112. 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 111 
 
 cavern, then those who wrought it had the hidden meaning, 
 which in that case was only transmitted by the poet. This 
 meaning Porphyry educes with an ingenuity that has an 
 attractiveness of its own. It must be noted, however, that 
 the philosophers do not add, and do not think they are adding, 
 anything to the content or even to the authority of their 
 doctrine. All such interpretations are in the interest of the 
 old mycologists and no longer of the philosophers, who are 
 not now putting themselves under the protection of the legends, 
 but on the contrary are seeking if possible to save them. 
 
 Of all Porphyry's writings, that which had the most far- 
 reaching influence on culture was his short introduction to the 
 Aristotelian Categories. Coming down to the Middle Ages in 
 the Latin translation of Boethius, it sufficed, by a few words at 
 the opening, to set going the whole discussion on " universals " 
 with which early Scholasticism was preoccupied. This of course 
 was not due to any special originality, but to its summing up 
 clearly and briefly the points of the rival theories maintained 
 by Platonists, Peripatetics and Stoics. Porphyry's logical works 
 generally were expository, and well adapted for use in the 
 schools through keeping the subject clear of metaphysics 1 . 
 Besides devoting much labour to commenting on Aristotle, he 
 wrote a History of Philosophy, to which his extant Life of 
 Pythagoras probably belonged ; psychological works from which 
 many passages are cited by Stobaeus ; and mathematical works 
 referred to by Proclus. Among his occasional writings of a 
 more original kind, the most extensive now remaining is the 
 Be Abstinentia (Tlepl uttox^ e^vx^v), a treatise against the 
 eating of animal food. His expositions of Plotinus, already 
 referred to, are still represented in the Sententiae ('A^op/xat 
 7rpo9 T(i vorjrd 2 ). 
 
 In what is recorded of Porphyry's metaphysical doctrines, a 
 tendency is found to greater elaboration of the triadic method 
 of grouping, carried out still more systematically by later Neo- 
 Platonism. The real importance of the writings in which he 
 
 1 Cf. Zeller. iii. 2, pp. 640—3. 
 
 '-' Prefixed to the Didot edition of Plotinus (1855). 
 
112 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 set forth the doctrine of his school was due, however, as his 
 contemporaries recognised, to the insight with which he pene- 
 trated to his master's essential thought and to his lucidity in 
 expounding it. Some illustration of this may be furnished from 
 the Sententiae. Then, as an example of his more personal 
 work, an exposition may be given of the Be Abstinentia. The 
 treatise has, besides, a more general interest in the specimens 
 it offers of the ethical questions raised and discussed in later ' 
 antiquity, not in a spirit of scholastic casuistry but with a 
 genuine desire for their solution in the light of reflective 
 conscience. 
 
 Preoccupation with ethics may be noticed in the Sententiae, 
 which contain a more systematic classification of the virtues 
 than Plotinus had explicitly given. Porphyry classifies them 
 into Political, Cathartic, Theoretic and Paradigmatic. The 
 virtues of the first class set the soul free from excess of 
 passionate attachment to the body, and produce moderation ; 
 those of the second class liberate it altogether from this 
 attachment, so that it can now turn to its true good. The 
 third class comprises the virtues of the soul energising intellec- 
 tually ; the fourth, those that are in intellect itself, to which 
 the soul looks up as patterns. Our care must be chiefly about 
 the virtues of the second class, seeing that they are to be 
 acquired in this life. Through them is the ascent to the 
 contemplative virtues of soul and to those that are their 
 models in pure intellect. The condition of purification is 
 self-knowledge 1 . 
 
 When the soul knows itself, it knows itself as other than 
 the corporeal nature to which it is bound. The error to which 
 we are especially liable is ascription of the properties of body 
 to incorporeal being. The body of the world is everywhere 
 spatially, its parts being spread out so that they can be dis- 
 criminated by the intervals between them. To God, Mind and 
 Soul, local situation does not apply. One part of intelligible 
 being is not here and another there. Where it is, it is as a 
 whole. The union of an incorporeal nature with a body is 
 
 1 Sententiae, 34. 
 
VI r] OF NBO-PLATONISM 113 
 
 altogether peculiar 1 . It is present indivisibly, and as numeri- 
 cally one, to tlie multitude of parts, each and all. What appears 
 to be added — as locality or relation— in departing from incor- 
 poreal being, is really taken away. Not to know being and not 
 to know oneself, have the same source, namely, an addition of 
 what is not, constituting a diminution of being which is all, — 
 and which, except in appearance, cannot be diminished. Recovery 
 of yourself by knowledge is recovery of being which was never 
 absent, — which is as inseparable from you in essence as you are 
 from yourself 2 . 
 
 This is of course the doctrine of Plotinus taken at its 
 centre. With equal exactitude Porphyry reproduces his con- 
 ception of being as differentiated intrinsically and not by 
 participation in anything external 3 . Plurality of souls is prior 
 to plurality of bodies, and is not incompatible with the continued 
 unity of all souls in one. They exist without diremption, yet 
 unconfused, like the many parts of knowledge in a single soul 4 . 
 Time accompanies the cognitive process in soul, as eternity 
 accompanies the timeless cognition of intellect. In such 
 process, however, the earlier thought does not go out to give 
 place to the later. It appears to have gone out, but it 
 
 1 Sententiae, 35: oOre oftv Kpdcrts, r) M<s' J > V crvvodos, rj irapdOfuis ' d\\' erepos 
 Tpowos. Cf. 6 : ov to ttoiouv els dWo rreXdcrei Kai d(py iroLtl d rroiel' d\\d Kai ra 
 ireXdcrei Kai drpfj ti iroiovvra, Kara o~vp.j3e(3riKbs rrj ire\d<rei XPV T<XI - On this Ritter 
 and Preller remark (524 a), " Favet theurgicis hoc placitnm." Here is a good 
 illustration of the readiness which historians have often displayed to see the 
 "theurgical" in preference to the scientific side of the Neo-Platonists. Whether 
 by itself or taken along with the context, what the passage suggests is a kind of 
 Occasionalist phenomenism. All changes, even in bodies, have their true 
 cause in immaterial being. Material approach or contact is not an efficient 
 cause, but accompanies as its "accident" the real order of metaphysical 
 causation. 
 
 -' Sententiae, 41 : o or; oi>rw aov eariv dvairoairacnov tear ovcriav, ws <rv 
 cravTov. 
 
 3 Sententiae, 38 : ov yap ft-wOei* iiriKTr)Tos, ovbe iireio-odiwbris avrov rj erepbr-qs, 
 ovbe <z\\oi> p-edti-ei, d\\' eavry iroWd. 
 
 4 Sententiae, 39 : buo-rrjo-av yap, ovk dwoKOirdaai, ovbe drroKeppaTiaao-ai els 
 eavras ti\v 6\r)i> ' /cat irdpticiv d\\r)\ais, ov o-vyKexvp-tvo-h ovbe awpbv -woiovaat. tt)v 
 6\r)v '...wo-rrep ovde ai eTrio-Trjp.au o-vvexvO-qaav al woWai ev ^pvxv M'P — K <*' ai 7ra<rat, 
 pia - Kai TrdXtv i) o\t? a\\rj rrapa wdcras. 
 
 W. 8 
 
1]4 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 remains ; and what appears to have come in is from the 
 movement of the soul returning on itself 1 . 
 
 Thus closely does the disciple follow the master into the 
 psychological subtleties 2 by which he anticipated the modern 
 position that, as the idea of extension is not extended, so the 
 succession of thoughts does not suffice to give the thought of 
 succession. After the illustration offered of his penetrating 
 clearness of exposition, we may go on to a work which shows 
 him in a more distinctive light. 
 
 Plotinus, though personally an ascetic, laid no stress in his 
 writings on particular ascetic practices. His precepts reduce 
 themselves in effect to a general recommendation to thin down 
 the material vehicle so that the soul may be borne quietly upon 
 it 3 . There is no suggestion in the Enneads that the perfection 
 of philosophic life requires abstinence from animal food. Not 
 infrequently, however, both earlier and later, this abstinence 
 was practised as a strict duty by those who traced their 
 philosophic ancestry to Pythagoras. Now the Neo-Platonists, 
 on the practical side, continued the movement of religious and 
 moral reform represented by teachers like Apollonius of Tyana 4 . 
 
 1 Sententiae, 44 : ipvxv Se fxeraftaivei air' dWov eis dWo, ewafieifiovcra to, 
 vorj/J-ara' ovk e^iarap-ivuv rdv irpurepuiv, oi>8e wodev dXXodev eireiffibvTwv tQv 
 devre'pujv dXXd t& p.ev wcnrep &Tre\r]\vde, Kalirep fxivovra ev avrfj' rd 5 wairep 
 dWaxiOev e'lreiai.v. dcpiKaro 5' ovk dWaxbdeu, dXX' avryjs Kai avrbdev eis eavrrjv 
 KivovpLevrjs, Kai to op.pLa. (pepovavs eis d ^X eL KaT d /nepos. irrfyrj ydp ZoLKev ovk 
 diroppvTip, dXXd kvk\lp eis eavrr/v dvaj3\v^ov(rri d exec. 
 
 2 To ignore the subtleties of the school is especially misleading in the case 
 of a doctrine like that of "ecstasy." Jules Simon (Histoire de VEcole. d' 
 Alexandria, t. ii. p. 156), referring to a passage of the Sententiae (26), says that, 
 for Porphyry, "ecstasy is a sleep." What Porphyry really says is that, while 
 we have to speak of the existence beyond mind in terms of thought, we can only 
 contemplate it in a state that is not thought; as sleep has to be sjDoken of in 
 terms of waking life, but can only be known through sleeping. Ecstasy, that is 
 to say, is compared to sleep because it also has to be apprehended by its like, 
 and because language, by which alone we can try to communicate our appre- 
 hension to others, has been framed for a different realm of experience ; not at 
 all because it is a kind of sleep. 
 
 3 Enn. in. 6, 5. 
 
 4 Eunapius, in the introduction to his Lives, says of Apollonius that he is 
 not to be counted as a mere philosopher, but rather as something between the 
 gods and man (ovk4ti (pCK6co<pos ' dXX' t\v ti Oewv re Kai dvdpdnrov fieaov). 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 115 
 
 Thus many of them refrained on principle from flesh-eating. 
 Among these was Porphyry. The occasion of his treatise was 
 that Castricius Firmus, one of the disciples of Plotinus, having 
 begun to practise abstinence from flesh, had returned to the 
 ordinary custom. He could easily defend himself on theoretical 
 grounds; for Peripatetics, Stoics and Epicureans had all their 
 systematic refutation of the Pythagorean abstinence. To the 
 arguments current in the schools, accordingly, Porphyry first 
 sets himself to reply. 
 
 The contention of the Stoics and Peripatetics was that the 
 idea of justice is applicable only to rational beings ; to extend 
 it beyond them to irrational beings, as those do who refuse to 
 kill animals for food, is to subvert its nature and to destroy the 
 possibility of that in it which is practicable. The Epicurean 
 argument which Porphyry cites is founded on a conjectural 
 account of the origin of laws. The primitive legislator per- 
 ceived some utility, and other men, who had not perceived it at 
 first, as soon as their attention was drawn willingly attached to 
 its violation a social prohibition and a penalty. It is for 
 reasons of utility that there are laws against homicide but 
 not against the slaughter of animals. If indeed a contract 
 could have been made, not only among men but also between 
 men and animals, to refrain from killing one another at random, 
 it would have been well that justice should be so far extended, 
 for thus safety would have been promoted ; but it is impossible 
 for animals that do not understand discourse to share in law. 
 To the general argument Porphyry in the first book replies 
 provisionally that he does not recommend this abstinence to 
 all men — not for example to those who have to do with the 
 mechanical arts, nor to athletes, nor to soldiers, nor to men 
 of affairs— but only to those who live the life of philosophy. 
 Legislators make laws not with a view to the theoretic life, but 
 to a kind of average life. Thus we cannot adopt their conces- 
 sions as rules for a life that is to be better than written law. 
 The asceticism of the philosopher consists in a withdrawal from 
 the things of ordinary life, if possible without trial of them. 
 No one can dwell at once with the things of sense and the 
 
 8—2 
 
116 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 things of the mind 1 . The life of the body generally, and such 
 matters as diet in particular, cannot safely be left unregulated 
 by reason. The more completely they are put in order once for 
 all, the less attention they will occupy, and the freer the mind 
 will be for its own life. The Epicureans have to some extent 
 recognised this in advising abstinence from flesh, if not on the 
 ground of justice yet as a means of reducing needs and so 
 making life simpler. 
 
 From the practical side the objection was raised that to 
 reject the flesh of animals as food is inconsistent with the 
 custom of offering them as sacrifices to the gods. Porphyry 
 replies by an unsparing attack on the custom. This fills the 
 second book. An account of the origin of animal sacrifices 
 is quoted from Theophrastus, who with reason, Porphyry says, 
 forbids those who would be truly pious to sacrifice living 
 things 2 . Offerings of fruits and corn and flowers and spices 
 came earliest. The custom of sacrificing animals was not 
 earlier than the use of them for food, which began, together 
 with cannibalism, in a dearth of fruits. Living things then 
 came to be sacrificed because men had been accustomed to 
 make first offerings to the gods of all that they used 3 . Re- 
 sponses of oracles and sayings from the poets are quoted to show 
 that the least costly sacrifices with purity of mind are the most 
 pleasing to the gods. Porphyry disclaims any intention of 
 overthrowing established customs ; but remarks that the laws 
 of the actual State allow private persons to offer the plainest 
 sacrifices, and such as consist of things without life. To make 
 an offering to the gods of food from which we ourselves abstain 
 would undoubtedly be unholy ; but we are not required to do 
 it. We too must sacrifice, but in accordance with the nature 
 
 1 De Abst. i. 42. The theories of some of the Gnostics are alluded to. to 5Z 
 OLeadai Kara ttjp atadrjaiv iradaiubp-evov irpbs roh voyroh evepyetv ttoWous ko.1 twi> 
 Papfidpuv e£erpax??Wo'- 
 
 2 De Abst. ii. 11 : eiVorws 6 Qeb<ppaaTOS airayopevei fx-q dveiv ra e/j.\[/vxa tous rip 
 ovtl evtre^eiv edeXovras. 
 
 3 This is a generalised account. Here and elsewhere in the De Abstinentia 
 there is much curious lore about the origin both of flesh-eating and of animal 
 sacrifices. 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 117 
 
 of the different powers. To the God over all, as a certain wise 
 man 1 said, we must neither offer nor even name anything 
 material. Our offering must be contemplation without even 
 inward discourse. To all the gods, the special thank-offering 
 of the philosopher will be fair thoughts regarding them. Some 
 of those who are devoted to philosophy, Porphyry allows, 
 hesitate here, aud make too much of externals. We will not 
 quarrel with them, lest we too should be over-precise on such 
 a matter, but will add contemplation, as our own offering, to 
 their observance of pious tradition. 
 
 He who cares about piety knows that to the gods none but 
 bloodless sacrifices are to be offered. Sacrifices of another kind 
 are offered only to the daemons — which name Plato applied 
 without distinction to the multitude of invisible powers below 
 the stars. On the subject of daemons, Porphyry then proceeds 
 to give an account of the views popularly expounded by some 
 of the Platonists (a rwv YlXarcovifcwv rwes i8rj/j.oa leva av 2 ). 
 One of the w r orst injuries done by the bad among the daemons 
 is to persuade us that those beings are the causes of earthly 
 ills who are really the causes of quite the opposite. After this, 
 they turn us to entreaties and sacrifices to the beneficent gods 
 as if they were angry 3 . They inflame the desires of men with 
 love of riches and power and pleasure, whence spring factions 
 and wars. And, what is most terrible, they reach the point of 
 persuading them that all this has been stirred up by the highest 
 God. Nor are the philosophers altogether blameless. For some 
 of them have not kept far enough apart from the ideas of the 
 multitude, who, hearing from those that appeared wise things 
 in harmony with their own opinions, were still further en- 
 couraged in unworthy thoughts about the gods. 
 
 If cities must propitiate such powers, that is nothing to us 
 (ouSei; 7T/JO? ?//ia?). For by these wealth and external and bodily 
 things are thought to be goods and deprivation of them an evil, 
 
 1 Apollonius of Tyana, as is mentioned in a note in Nauck's edition 
 (Porphyrii Opuscula Selecta). 
 
 2 Be Abst. ii. 37—43. 
 
 3 De Abst. ii. 40 : rpiwovalv re fiera tovto (irl Xiraveias rip-cis /cat Ovaias tQiv 
 dyaOoepyuiv Vewv uis usp-yiap-ivuiv. 
 
118 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 and they have little care about the soul. The same position 
 must be taken as regards divination by the entrails of victims. 
 This, it may be said, will be clone away with if we refrain from 
 killing and eating animals. Why not, then, kill men also for 
 the purpose ? It is said that better premonitions are to be got 
 in that way, and many of the barbarians really practise this 
 mode of divination. As a matter of fact, whether the victim 
 is human or is an irrational animal, thus to gain knowledge 
 of the future belongs to injustice and greed 1 . 
 
 Here Porphyry recounts a number of cases of human 
 sacrifice in former times, and their commutation into animal 
 or symbolical sacrifices; appealing to historical authority for 
 the statement that it was not until the time of Hadrian that 
 all survivals of such rites throughout the Empire were practi- 
 cally abolished' 2 . Before concluding the book, he observes that 
 even the unperverted ideas of the multitude make some 
 approach to right opinion about the gods ; and illustrates the 
 remark by passages from comic poets ridiculing the notion 
 that divine powers are pleased with such things as are usually 
 offered to them. Then he points to the swarm of evils brought 
 in by those who introduced costly sacrifices 3 . To think that 
 the gods delight in this kind of expenditure must have a 
 specially bad influence on the minds of youth, teaching them 
 to neglect conduct ; whereas to think that they have regard 
 above all to the disposition must tend to make them pious and 
 just. The philosopher, in Plato's view, ought not to accom- 
 modate himself to bad customs, but to try to win men to the 
 better ; if he cannot, let him go the right way himself, caring 
 neither for dangers nor abuse from the many. And surely if 
 Syrians and Hebrews and Phoenicians and Egyptians could 
 resist even to the death kings that strove to make them depart 
 
 1 Be Abst. ii. 51 : d\\' oicnrep ddisias Kal wXeope^ias yv to eW/ca p.a.vTtla.% 
 dvaipuv tov bpbcpvKov, ovtu kcu to dXoyov £wov cr^drretc fxavTilas fVe/ca adtKOV. 
 
 2 De Abut. ii. 56 : Ka.TaXvdrji'ai oe rds dvOpwirodvaias ax^bv rds Trapd iraaiv 
 (pijdi IldXXas 6 dpiffTa rd irepl tG>v tov Widpa crvvayaylov fivcT-qpioJv i(p' ' Adpiavov tov 
 avTOKpaTopos. 
 
 3 De Abst. ii. 60: dyuoovo-iv 5£ oi tt\v ■no\vTi\eiav elcrayayovTes els tcls dvaias, 
 owus dp.a TauTy eo-pbv kclkGiv d<n)yayov, beioib'aiiJ.ovlav, Tpvcp-qv, VTrb\r) T 'ii> tov 
 8eKd£eii> bvvao-dat. to delov />at Ovaiais aKeladai Tr\v dbiKlaf. 
 
VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 119 
 
 from their national laws in the matter of food, we ought not to 
 transgress the laws of nature and divine precepts for the fear of 
 men. 
 
 In the third book, Porphyry undertakes to show that 
 animals, in so far as they have perception and memory, have 
 some share in reason, and therefore are not beyond the range 
 of justice. Defining uttered discourse, not according to the 
 doctrine of any particular school but in the perfectly general 
 sense of " a voice significant through the tongue of internal 
 affections in the soul," we shall find that animals capable of 
 uttering sounds have a kind of discourse among themselves. 
 And before utterance, why should we not suppose the thought 
 of the affection to have been there 1 ? Even if we pass over 
 some of the stories about men that are said to have understood 
 the tongues of animals, enough is recorded to show that the 
 voices of birds and beasts, if intently listened to, are not wholly 
 unintelligible. Voiceless animals too, such as fishes, come to 
 understand the voices of men ; which they could not do with- 
 out some mental resemblance. To the truth of Aristotle's 
 assertion that animals learn much both from one another and 
 from men, every trainer can bear witness. Those who will not 
 see all these evidences of their intelligence take the part of 
 calumniating the creatures they mean to treat ruthlessly 2 . 
 Animals are subject not only to the same bodily diseases as 
 men but to the same affections of the soul. Some have even 
 acuter senses. That animals do indeed possess internal reason 
 is shown by the knowledge they display of their own strength 
 and weakness and by the provisions they make for their life. 
 To say that all this belongs to them " by nature " amounts to 
 saying that by nature they are rational 3 . We too arrive at 
 reason because it is our nature; and animals, as has been said, 
 
 1 I)e Abst. iii. 3: r: 5^ ov\l «al a irdax (L T <> irporepov Kai wplv elirciv 8 p.i\\ei, 
 SievorjOr] ; 
 
 !)(' Abst. iii. 6: d\\' 6 fiev evyvu:fiwi> Kal etc toutwv fieraSidwcri avveaeus tois 
 j'oiois, 6 5e dyvwfj.u)v Kal dvicrT6pr)Tos clvtQu <f>4p(Tai ovvepyCov avrov rrj els avrd 
 ■jr\eove^l(f. Kai 7r<£s 7<ip oil/c ^eWee KaKoXoyqauv Kal SiapaXetv a KaraKowTetv u>s 
 \L6ov irporipriTai ; 
 
 3 De Abst. iii. 10: 6 8e <pu<rei Xiyuv avrois irpoaehai ravra dyvod A^yto? 6ti 
 <pvaa tarl \oyiKa. 
 
120 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 learn by being taught, as we do. They have vices of their own, 
 though these are lighter than those of men ; and the virtues of 
 the social animals are undeniable, however difficult their mental 
 processes may be for us to follow. 
 
 Against the external teleology of Chrysippus, according to 
 which all other animals were created for the use of man, 
 Porphyry cites the argument of Carneades, that where there 
 is a natural end for any being, the attainment of the end must 
 be marked by some profit to that being, and not to some other. 
 If we were to follow the teleological method of the Stoics, we 
 could not well escape the admission that it is we who have been 
 produced for the sake of the most destructive brutes ; for while 
 they are of no use to us, they sometimes make their prey of 
 men. This they do driven by hunger, whereas we in our 
 sports and public games kill in wantonness 1 . Returning to the 
 question about the reason of animals, Porphyry argues, after 
 Plutarch, that to an animal that could not reason at all, its 
 senses would be of no use towards action for ends. Inferiority 
 in reasoning power is not the same as total deprivation of it. 
 We do not say that we are entirely without the faculty of 
 vision because the hawk has sharper sight. If normally 
 animals had not reason, how could they go mad, as some do ? 
 Porphyry next cites from Theophrastus an argument for a 
 relation of kinship not only among all men, but between men 
 and all animals 2 . In the bodies and souls of both, we find the 
 same principles. For our bodies consist not only of the same 
 primary elements but of the same tissues — " skin, flesh, and 
 
 1 De Abst. iii. 20. Here follow some pages adapted from Plutarch's De 
 Sollertia Animalium, cc. 2 — 5, beginning: e£ wv 5tj ko.1 rb /j.ei> (povinov ko.1 dr)piu>8e$ 
 r)/j.u>i> Eirepptl'ffdT] nai to vpbs oiktov awades, tov 5' rj/mepov to nXeiaTov a.Trrjp.j3\vvav ol 
 TrpuiTOi touto To\fj.7}oai>Tes. ol 5k Uvdaybpeiot tt)v wpbs to. Bripia TrpaoTrjTa pt,e\eTqv 
 iiroi-qeavTo tov tpiXavdpilwov tcai {piXoiKTip/xovos. In view of modern discussions on 
 teleology and evolution, a passage that occurs later may be found interesting. 
 Having enumerated the devices of animals that live in the water for catching 
 prey and escaping from enemies, one of the spokesmen in the dialogue argues 
 that the struggle is nature's means of promoting animal intelligence. De 
 Sollertia Animalium, 27 (979 a) : kclI tov k6k\ov tovtov ko.1 ttjv wepioSov reus /car' 
 dWr/Xcov 5iu>i;ecri ko.1 tpvyah yi/Mvafffia /ecu p.e\eTi]v r\ (pvffis avTols eva.yiovi.ov ireTrolyKe 
 8fivbT7)Tos kclI ovvtaews. 
 
 2 De Abst. iii. 25. 
 
VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 121 
 
 the kind of humours natural to animals." Likewise the souls 
 of animals resemble those of men by their desires and impulses, 
 by their reasonings, and above all by their sense-perceptions. 
 The difference, in the case of souls as of bodies, is in degree 
 of fineness. Therefore, in abstaining from the flesh of animals, 
 Porphyry concludes, we are more just in that we avoid harming 
 what is of kindred nature ; and, from thus extending justice, 
 we shall be less prone to injure our fellow-men. We cannot 
 indeed live in need of nothing, like the divinity ; but we can 
 at least make ourselves more like God by reducing our wants. 
 Let us then imitate the " golden race," for which the fruits of 
 the earth sufficed. 
 
 The fourth book, which is incomplete, accumulates tes- 
 timonies to show that . abstinence from Mesh is not a mere 
 eccentric precept of Pythagoras and Empedocles, but has been 
 practised by primitive and uncorrupted races, by communities 
 of ascetics like the Essenes, and by the Egyptian and other 
 priesthoods, some of whom have abstained from all kinds of 
 animal food, some from particular kinds. Then, after giving 
 an account of the Brahmans and of the Buddhist monks (who 
 are evidently meant by the ^.a/xaraLoi) on the authority of 
 Bardesanes (perhaps the Gnostic), who derived his information 
 from an Indian embassy to the imperial court early in the 
 third century, Porphyry returns to the general ascetic argument 
 for abstinence. One who would philosophise ought not to live 
 like the mass of mankind, but ought rather to observe such 
 rules as are prescribed to priests, who take upon themselves 
 the obligation of a holier kind of life 1 . 
 
 This is the strain in which the work breaks off, but it will 
 be observed that on the whole the point of view is as much 
 humanitarian as ascetic. Transmigration of human souls into 
 the bodies of animals Porphyry explicitly denied. Here he 
 mentions it only as a topic of ridicule used against Pythagoras. 
 The stories of men who have been transformed into animals, 
 he interprets as a mythical indication that the souls of 
 animals have something in common with our own. The way 
 
 1 De Abst. iv. 18. 
 
122 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 in which the whole subject is discussed reveals a degree of 
 reflectiveness with regard to it in the ancient schools which 
 has scarcely been reached again by civilised Europe till 
 quite modern times. And perhaps, for those who wish to 
 preserve the mean, no more judicious solution will be found 
 than Plutarch came upon incidentally in his Life of Cato the 
 Censor; where he contends that, while justice in the proper 
 sense is applicable only among men, irrational animals also 
 may claim a share of benevolence 1 . 
 
 2. Iamblich us. 
 
 Iamblichus, who was regarded as the next after Porphyry 
 in the Neo-Platonic succession 2 , had been his pupil at Rome. 
 He was a native of Chalcis in Coele- Syria, aud his own later 
 activity as a teacher was in Syria. He died in the reign of 
 Constantine, about 330. Eunapius describes him as socially 
 accessible and genial, and as living on familiar terms with his 
 numerous disciples. Though he is often described as having 
 given to the Neo-Platonic school a decisive impulse in the 
 direction of theurgy, the one well-authenticated anecdote on 
 the subject in his biography does not lend any particular 
 support to this view. A rumour had gone abroad that some- 
 times during his devotions he was raised in the air and 
 underwent a transfiguration. His disciples, fearing that they 
 were being excluded from some secret, took occasion to ask 
 him if it was so. Though not much given to laughter, he 
 laughed upon this inquiry, and said that the story was prettily 
 invented but was not true 3 . Eunapius was told this by his 
 teacher Chrysanthius ; and Chrysanthius had it from Aedesius, 
 who bore a part in the conversation. The biographer certainly 
 
 1 Vitae, Cato Major, 5 : Kairoi tt]v xPV crT ° T V Ta T ?7 S diicaio<n'ivr)s irXarvrtpov 
 t6ttov opwfjLev fTnXa.fj.ftai'ovcTa.v vbfiu> /j.(p yap Kal ru> Sikcu'oj 7rpos avdpwwovs fxbvov 
 XP^crdai ire(pvKap.ev, irpbs evepyeoias dt Kal x^-P LTa ^ 2<ttiv ore Kal p.ixP L T ^ v o-Xbywv 
 fyiov uiawtp £k Tnjyqi irXovcrias awoppel rrjs i)p.epbTT]To%. 
 
 2 See Julian, Or. vn. 2'22 B, where Plotinus, Porphyry and Iamblichus are 
 mentioned in order as carrying on the tradition of Plato. 
 
 3 Eunap. Vitae (Iamblichus) : 6 p.ev dirarrjaas v/xcis ovk i)v &xapis, ravra 5£ oi'x 
 
 OVTiOS ?x €U 
 
VIl] OF NEO-PLATOXISM 123 
 
 goes on to relate some marvels on hearsay, but he mentions 
 distinctly that none of the disciples of Iamblichus wrote them 
 down. He records them, as he says himself, with a certain 
 hesitation; but he did not think himself justified in omitting 
 what was told him by trustworthy witnesses. 
 
 The literary style of Iamblichus, Eunapius allows, has not 
 the beauty and lucidity of Porphyry's. Not that it altogether 
 fails of clearness, nor that it is grammatically incorrect; but it 
 does not draw the reader on. As Plato said of Xenocrates, he 
 had not sacrificed to the Hermaic Graces. An interesting 
 account is given of the way in which he was stirred up to 
 reflection on political topics by Alypius, an acute dialectician 
 of Alexandria. A public disputation having been arranged 
 between them, Alypius put to him a question from which he 
 at first turned away with disdain. The query was : " Whether 
 a rich man is necessarily either unjust or the heir of one who 
 has been unjust 1 ." According to the traditional philosophic 
 view that poverty and wealth, in comparison with the goods of 
 the mind, are alike indifferent, the question seemed frivolous; 
 but further* thought modified the impression, and Iamblichus 
 became an admirer of Alypius and afterwards wrote his life. 
 The composition, Eunapius thought, was not successful; and 
 this he ascribes to the author's want of aptitude for political 
 discussion and of real interest in it. It conveyed a sense of 
 Iamblichus's admiration for Alypius, but did not succeed in 
 giving the reader any clear idea as to what he had said or 
 done. ^ 
 
 Eunapius himself was not by special training a philosopher, 
 but a rhetorician. He was an adherent of the party attached 
 to the old religion. Commonly, he is described as an indis- 
 criminate panegyrist of all the philosophers of his party ; but, 
 as we see, he was not wanting in candour. While looking 
 back with reverence to Iamblichus as the intellectual chief 
 of the men whose doctrines he followed, he does not in the 
 least understate his defects of style. And on no one does he 
 lavish more praise than on his Athenian teacher in rhetoric, 
 
 1 'EtV^ fioi, <pt\6ffocf>e,' Trpds cli'toi* ^0t;, '6 w\ov<nos rj aoiKos r) o.5lkov KXripovo/xos, 
 val r) o\i ; tovtujv yap fxtaov ovdiv.' 
 
124 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 Prohaeresius, who was a Christian. Iamblichus was one of those 
 who are placed higher by their own age than by later times. 
 His reputation had probably reached its greatest height about 
 the time of Julian, who spoke of him as not inferior in genius 
 to Plato 1 . Still, he remains a considerable philosopher. He 
 modified the doctrine of Plotinus more deeply than Porphyry ; 
 and the changes he made in it were taken up and continued 
 when it came to be systematised by the Athenian school. If 
 he does not write so well as Porphyry or Proclus, he succeeds 
 in conveying his meaning. And, while professedly expounding 
 the tradition of a school, and freely borrowing from his pre- 
 decessors, he always has a distinctive drift of his own. 
 
 The surviving works of Iamblichus belonged to a larger 
 treatise in which the Pythagorean philosophy was regarded as 
 the original source of the tradition he expounds. The whole 
 treatise was entitled %vvay(oy>} rcov HvOwyopelcov Boyfidrcou. Of 
 the separate works, the first in order is a Life of Pythagoras. 
 The second is mainly ethical in content, and is a general 
 exhortation to the study of philosophy (A070? TrpoTpeirTLKos 
 iirl <pi\oao<pLav). The remaining three are mathematical 2 . 
 The best notion of the individual tone of Iamblichus's thought 
 will be given by an abstract of the second book — the Pro- 
 trepticus. But first a word must be said on the kind of 
 modification he made in the doctrine of Plotinus. 
 
 From the references in later writers, it is known that he 
 attempted a more systematic analysis of the stages of emanation 
 by resolving them into subordinate triads. As there are traces 
 
 1 Or. iv. 146 A. To save their genuineness, the letters of Julian " to 
 Iamblichus the philosopher " are as a rule assumed to have been written to 
 a nephew of Iamblichus, known from the correspondence of Libanius. Zeller 
 (iii. 2, p. 679, n. 2) points to circumstances wbich show that they must have 
 purported to be written to the elder Iamblichus, who died near the time when 
 Julian was born (331). He therefore follows Dodwell (" A Discourse concerning 
 the Time of Pythagoras," cited by Fabricius, Bibliotheca Graeca) in regarding 
 them as spurious. Dodwell gives what seems a decisive reason for rejecting them, 
 namely, that Sopater, who was executed under Constantine, is referred to as alive. 
 
 - Tbe genuineness of one of these (Ta deo\oyou/j.eva rrjs dpi.0/J-r]TtKT]s) has 
 been contested. The other two bear the titles Ilepl rrjs koivtjs /xadrjuartKiis 
 tiri<TTr)/J-ys and Ilepi tt}s ^iko/xixxov dptdfxT]TiKTJs daayuyfjs. See, on the former, 
 Appendix III. 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 125 
 
 of this already in Porphyry, and as Proclus carried the method 
 much farther, the interest of Iamblichus here is that he 
 illustrates the continuous effort of the school towards com- 
 pleteness and consistency. He dwelt with special emphasis on 
 the position that the causal process from higher to lower is 
 logical, and not in time ; and thought it not without danger to 
 suppose a temporal production of the world even as a mere 
 hypothesis. More explicitly than Plotinus or Porphyry, he 
 insisted that no individual soul can remain permanently in 
 the intelligible world any more than in Tartarus. It is the 
 nature of every particular soul to descend periodically and to 
 reascend in accordance with a law of universal necessity. The 
 point where he was most original was, however, his affirmation, 
 as against Plotinus, that when the soul "descends" it descends 
 wholly. The whole soul, and not merely a kind of effluence of 
 it, is in relation with this world so long as it is here at all. 
 There is no " pure soul " that remains exempt from error while 
 the " composite nature " is at fault. If the will sins, how can 
 the soul be without sin 1 ? This correction in what seemed 
 Plotinus's over-exalted view was almost universally allowed, 
 and was definitively taken up by Proclus. It certainly does 
 not bear out the notion that Iamblichus was a thinker who 
 deserted all sobriety in order to turn a philosophic school into 
 an association of theosophic adepts. 
 
 The Protrepticus is in considerable part made up of excerpts 
 from Plato, Aristotle, and Neo-Pythagorean writings, but it is 
 at the same time consistently directed to the end of showing 
 the importance of theoretical knowledge both for itself and in 
 relation to practice. Contemplation is put first; but, of all the 
 school, Iamblichus dwells most on the bearing of knowledge 
 upon practical utilities. At the beginning he brings out the 
 point that general scientific discipline must be communicated 
 before philosophy, " as the less before the greater mysteries 2 ." 
 We are to regard the constancy of the stellar movements, so 
 
 1 Procl. in Tim. 341 D. (R. P. 528.) el de 17 irpoalpeois ap.apT&vei, irws 
 
 dvafldpTTlTOS 1) ^pvxv ; 
 
 2 Protrepticus, a 2, ed. H. Pistelli, p. 10: ws irpb rC)v fMeyaXuv /xvaTrjpiwf to. 
 fUKpa wapaoortov, nal irpb (f)i\o<xo(pias 7rcu5ei'ae. 
 
126 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 that we may be prepared to adapt ourselves to the necessary 
 course of things. From scientific knowledge we are to rise to 
 wisdom {ao(f)La) as knowledge of first principles, and finally as 
 theology. We need knowledge to make use of "goods," which 
 without the wisdom to use them are not goods, or rather are 
 evils. Things in use (rd ^pri^ara) have reference to the body, 
 and the body is to be attended to for the sake of the soul and 
 its ruling powers. Each of us is the soul, and knowledge of the 
 soul is knowledge of oneself. The physician as such does not 
 know himself. Those who practise arts connected not with the 
 bod}' directly but with things that are for the body, are still 
 more remote from self-knowledge, and their arts are rightly 
 called mechanical. We must exercise the divinest part of the 
 soul by the appropriate motions. Now to what is divine in us 
 the movements of the whole are akin 1 . In the part of the soul 
 that has rational discourse is the intellectual principle, which is 
 the best that belongs to the soul. For the sake of this, and of 
 the thoughts with which it energises, all else exists. 
 
 While without philosophy practical life cannot be well 
 regulated, the theoretic life is yet not finally for the sake of 
 practice. Rather, mind itself and the divine are the ultimate 
 end, the mark at once of the intellectual eye and of love. It is 
 by the power of living the life of theory that we differ from 
 other animals. Of reasou and prudence there are in them' also 
 some small gleams, but they have no part in theoretic wisdom ; 
 whereas in accuracy of perception and vigour of impulse many 
 of them surpass man. Since, however, we are discoursing with 
 men and not with gods, we must mingle exhortations bearing 
 on civic and practical life Now philosophy alone, in relation 
 to the other kinds of knowledge, can judge and direct. And 
 philosophical knowledge is not only possible but is in one way 
 more attainable than other knowledge, because it is of first 
 principles, which are better known by nature and are more 
 determinate. It is of the highest degree of utility, because it 
 definitely makes its object the insight by which the wise man 
 judges and the reason which proceeds from insight and is 
 
 1 Protr. 5, p. 31 : rep 8' ev tj/jup delip ^v-yyeveli ejVi lavqaeis ai tov iravrbs 
 biavor)oei% /ecu irtpupopal. 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 127 
 
 expressed in law. And that it is not inaccessible is shown by 
 the eagerness with which students devote themselves to it. 
 Unlike other scientific pursuits, it demands no special ap- 
 pliances or conditions of time and place. 
 
 After further elaborating this argument, Iamblichus pro- 
 ceeds to infer from " common notions " that insight (<j>povr]cri<;) 
 is most to be chosen for itself, and not for the sake of other 
 things. Suppose a man to have everything else and to suffer 
 from a malady in the part of him that has insight, life would 
 not be for him a gift to choose, for none of its other goods 
 would be of any use to him 1 . Insight, therefore, cannot be a 
 mere means to gaining other things. The way too in which 
 death is shunned proves the soul's love of knowledge ; for it 
 flees what it does not know, the dark and the unapparent, and 
 by nature pursues what is plain to sight and knowable 2 . And 
 although, as they that declare the mysteries say, our souls are 
 bound to our bodies to pay the penalty of some antenatal 
 offence, yet, in so far as human life has the power of sharing in 
 divine and immortal intellect, man appears as a god in relation 
 to the other things that are on earth. 
 
 Iamblichus next argues on Aristotelian grounds that man 
 has a natural end, and that this end is that which in the 
 genetic order, fulfilling itself as this does continuously, is the 
 latest to be perfected 3 . Now in human development mental 
 insight is that which is last attained. This then is the final 
 good of man. For we must at length stop at something that is 
 good in itself. Otherwise, by viewing each thing in turn as 
 a means to some extraneous end, we commit ourselves to a 
 process to infinity. Yet, though insight is not properly a 
 utility, but a good to be chosen for itself, it also furnishes the 
 greatest utilities to human life, as may be seen from the arts. 
 
 1 l'mtr. S, p. 45 : el yap Kai iravra tis e'x 0l > SutpOap/nevos 5e eftj kclI voctGiv Tip 
 (ppovovvTi, oi'x aiperos 6 /3tos - ov5ev yap o<pe\os ov8e twv aXXwv ayatiiov. 
 
 Protr. 8, p. 46 : Kai to (ptvyeiv 5e rbv Oavarov rovs ttoWovs delicvwi tt\v 
 <pt\op.ddetav rrjs ^i'xn^- (pevyet yap a fxrj ytyvuvKei, to (TKOTwdes Kai to /at] orjXov, 
 (pvati. 5e 8iu3K€L to (pavepbv tcai to yvuicrTdv. 
 
 Protr. 9, p. 51 : tAos 5£ Kara <pvo~iv tovt6 i&Tiv 6 KaTa ttjv yeveo-w ireQvuev 
 vcTaTov (TrtTeXuudaL trepatvop.ivrjs ttjs yevecrews cn/eexws. 
 
128 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 Just as the physician needs a knowledge of nature, so the 
 lawgiver and the moralist need theoretical knowledge, though 
 of another kind, if they are to regulate the social life of man. 
 The relation of this knowledge to the whole of life is like that 
 of sight to physical action. In itself it simply judges and 
 shows, but without it we could do nothing or very little. 
 
 Those who enjoy the pleasure of insight enjoy most the 
 perfection of life in itself; an enjoyment which is to be dis- 
 tinguished from incidental pleasures, received while living but 
 not springing essentially from the proper activity of life. The 
 difficulty of living the theoretic life here, comes from the 
 conditions of human nature ; for now we have to be constantly 
 doing things that have relation to needs. This is most of all 
 the lot of those deemed happiest by the many. If, however, 
 we prepare ourselves by philosophising, we may hope, having 
 returned whence we came, to live in untroubled contemplation 
 of divine truth. Thus Iamblichus is led from the Aristotelian 
 ideal of the contemplative life to the thought of the Phaedo, 
 that philosophising is a kind of dying; death being nothing but 
 the separation of the soul from the body to live a life by itself. 
 Our soul can never perceive truth in its purity till it is released. 
 To prepare it for such knowledge, and to approach that know- 
 ledge as near as possible while we live, we must purify the soul 
 from all that comes to it from the body, — from common desires 
 and fears, care about needs, and the hindrances thrown in the 
 way by external sense. The genuine virtues of courage, 
 temperance and justice proceed from the insight reached by 
 philosophic purification ; the virtues that result from a 
 balancing of pleasures and pains are a mere adumbration of 
 virtue. When a distinction is drawn between the lot in Hades 
 of the uninitiated and of the initiated, we may understand by 
 the truly initiated (' vapOijKocpopoi fiei> 7toX\ol, /3('tK)^ot Se re 
 iravpot') no other than those who have become purified through 
 philosophy. Those who do not arrive in Hades as purified 
 souls, quickly become subject to rebirth in new bodies. There- 
 fore, since the soul is immortal, there is for it no escape from 
 ills and no safety except to acquire as much goodness and 
 insight as possible. 
 
Vn] OF NEO-PLATONISM 129 
 
 The character of the philosopher is next set forth by an 
 excerpt of the celebrated passage in the Theaetetus. An account 
 of the ideal philosophic education is adapted from the seventh 
 book of the Republic. The Platonic view is enforced that the 
 special function of philosophy is to remove from the soul the 
 accretion that comes to it from birth, and to purify that energy 
 of it to which the power of reason belongs 1 . The argument of 
 the Gorgias is then taken up, that the intemperate soul, which 
 would be ever getting and spending, is like a " leaky vessel," 
 while orderliness in the soul resembles health in the body. 
 After some further development of this topic, Iamblichus returns 
 to the point that philosophy is the most directive of all the 
 arts (rjyefxoviKwraTT] iraaoov rwv re^vwi'). Hence most pains 
 ought to be spent in learning it. An art of dealing with words, 
 indeed, might be learned in a short time, so that the disciple 
 should be no worse than the teacher; but the excellence that 
 comes from practice is only to be acquired by much time and 
 diligence. The envy of men, too, attaches itself to rapid 
 acquisitions of every kind ; praise is more readily accorded to 
 those that have taken long to acquire. Further, every acquire- 
 ment ought to be used for a good end. He that aims at all 
 virtue is best when he is useful to most 2 . Now that which is 
 most useful to mankind is justice. But for any one to know 
 the right distribution of things and to be a worker with the 
 true law of human life, he must have acquired the directive 
 knowledge that can only be given by philosophy. 
 
 Iamblichus then goes on to argue that even if one were to 
 arise exempt from wounds and disease and pain, and gigantic 
 of stature, and adamantine of body and soul, he could in the 
 long run secure his own preservation only by aiding justice. 
 An evil so monstrous as tyranny arises from nothing but law- 
 lessness. Some wrongly deem that men are not themselves the 
 causes of their being deprived of freedom, but are forcibly 
 deprived of it by the tyrant. To think that a king or tyrant 
 
 1 Protr. 10, p. 83 : rb yap irepiaipelv ryv ykvecnv airb t^s ipvxv* Kal (KKaBatpeiv 
 ttju XoyifecrQai 5vva/xtvr]v avrrjs ivepyeiav /xaXtara avrr} irpoarjKet. 
 
 - Protr. 20, p. 97 : t6v re av apexes dpeydfxevov rrjs <ri'M7rd<rijs GKeirreov elvai, tK 
 rlvos av \6yov rj Zpyov apto-ros efjj ' toiovtos 5' av en? 6 ir\d<TToi.s axpeXi^os wv. 
 
 W. ^ 
 
130 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 arises from anything but lawlessness and greed is folly 1 . When 
 law and justice have departed from the multitude, then, since 
 human life cannot go on without them, the care of them has to 
 pass over to one. The one man whom some suppose able by 
 his single power to dissolve justice and the law that exists for 
 the common good of all, is of flesh like the rest and not of 
 adamant. It is not in his power to strip men of them against 
 their will. On the contrary, he survives by restoring them when 
 they have failed. Lawlessness then being the cause of such 
 great evils, and order being so great a good, there is no means 
 of attaining happiness but to make law preside over one's own 
 
 life. 
 
 The Protrepticus concludes with an interpretation of thirty- 
 nine Pythagorean " symbols," or short precepts which are taken 
 as cryptic expressions of philosophic truths. In their literal 
 meaning, Iamblichus says, they would be nonsensical; but, 
 according to the "reserve" (ixefMvOia) inculcated by Pythagoras 
 on his disciples, not all of them were intended to be understood 
 easily by those who run (rots a7r\w<? cikovovctiv e'£ eirihpofxrj^ re 
 evTvyxdvovatv). Iamblichus proposes to give the solutions of 
 them all, without making an exception of those that fell under 
 the Pythagorean reserve. 
 
 The interpretations contain many points of interest. If the 
 precepts were ever literal " taboos," not a trace of this character 
 is retained. The last given, which was generally understood to 
 command abstinence from animal food, is interpreted simply as 
 inculcating justice with fit regard for what is of kindred nature 
 and sympathetic treatment of the life that is like our own 2 . 
 The absence of any reference to the literal meaning seems to 
 indicate that Iamblichus did not follow Porphyry on this point. 
 In interpreting the "symbols" relating to theology, if the whole 
 of what he says is fairly considered, he seems to give them a 
 turn against credulity ; his last word being that that which is 
 
 1 Protr. 20, p. 103: oans yap riyeiTcu /3a<riA<?a rj rOpavvov e£ d\\ov tlv6s 
 ylyveadat ?? e'£ dvofxias re /cat wXeovc i^cas, P-upbs effriv. 
 
 2 Protr. 21, p. 125 : to 5e ' ip.\pi>xuv avtx ov ' e7r ' SiKaioavvrjv Trporpewet ko.1 
 wacrav tt]v tov avyyevovs Tip.r}v ko.1 t\\v ttjs 6/iot'as fw^s AirodoxV" *«' ^pds eYe/>a 
 roiaOra TrXeiova. 
 
VII ] OF NEO-PLATONISM 131 
 
 to be believed is that which is demonstrable. One of them 
 runs, " Mistrust nothing marvellous about the gods, nor about 
 the divine opinions." After pointing out generally the weakness 
 of man's faculties, which should prevent him from judging rashly 
 as to what is possible to the gods. Iamblichus goes on to explain 
 more particularly that by "the divine opinions" (to. 6 da 
 SojfiaTa) are meant those of the Pythagorean philosophy, 
 and that they are proved by cogent demonstration to be 
 necessarily true 1 . The precept therefore means : Acquire 
 mathematical knowledge, so that you may understand the 
 nature of demonstrative evidence, and then there will be no 
 room for mistrust. That is also what is meant in reference to 
 the gods 2 . The truth about the whole, Iamblichus says in 
 another place, is concealed and hard to get hold of, but is to 
 be sought and tracked out by man through philosophy, which, 
 receiving some small sparks from nature, kindles them into a 
 flame and makes them more active by the sciences that proceed 
 from herself 3 . Many of the sayings are interpreted as com- 
 mending the method of philosophising from intelligible principles 
 setting forth the nature of the stable and incorporeal reality. 
 The " Italic " philosophy — which had long since come to be 
 regarded as a doctrine of incorporeal being — is to be preferred 
 before the Ionic 4 . The precept, not to carve the image of a god 
 on a ring (' 6eov tvttov ixr) iTriy\v<j)6 8aKTv\l(p ') is interpreted 
 to mean, " Think of the gods as incorporeal 5 ." The model of 
 
 1 Protr. 21, pp. 110—111. 
 
 2 This extended interpretation, with its preface about the inadequacy of 
 human judgments on divine things, comes out of its proper place. The 
 " symbol," which is the twenty-fifth, is also explained in due order (p. 121), and 
 there the preface is omitted and the whole runs thus: To 8e ' irepl deQv p.i]8ev 
 6a.vfjLa.aTov airioTti fiijde irepl deluv 8oyfj.dTwi> ' irpoTpewei ixerUvai Kal KTaadai eKelva 
 to. /j.a.dr)fxaTa, 6V a ovk dirio-Trj<reis ovk^ti irepl OeQv Kal irepl Oeiwv doy/x&Tiov f'^wi' Ta 
 fxadri/jiaTa. /cat rets eino-Tr)fj.oviKas dirodei^ets. 
 
 3 Protr. 21, p. 116 : eirel yap awbKpv<pos (pt'crei 7/ irepl rod iravTos dXrjOeia, Kal 
 SvcrdopaTOS iKavws' fyT-qrea 5e o'/uws avOpuiirtj) Kal i^xvevria fj.aXi.o-Ta 81a <piXucro<pias. 
 5lo. yap aXXov tivos eiriTijdevfj.aTos ovtus ddufarov ' avrrj 8e fxiKpa Tiua evava/xaTa 
 irapd Tift (puffeuis Xa/xiSduovaa Kal toaavel ecpoOiagofievri fwirvpei re aura Kal p.tyt6i<vei 
 Kal evepyeaTepa 5td ra>i> wap' at)r?)s fxadrju.dTUi' direpydftTai. 
 
 4 Prolr. 21, p. 125 : irporifia tt)v 'IraXiKifv <piXoo-o<piav ttiv rd do-dinara Kad' 
 aura dewpovaav r^s 'luviKrjs ttjs rd crcu^ara irpo-qyovpjvwi eiTLo-Koirov/xiuijs. 
 
 " Protr. 21, p. 120. 
 
 9—2 
 
132 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 method for the discovery of truth about divine things is, as has 
 been said, that of mathematics. Thus the precept ' ev 6Sg5 fir) 
 a-^i^e ' is turned against the method of search by a series of 
 dichotomies, and in favour of a process which leads directly to 
 truth without ambiguity because each step of the way is 
 demonstratively certain as soon as it is taken 1 . The special 
 bearing of the Pythagorean philosophy, with its appeal to 
 equality and proportion, on the virtue of justice (tt}v reXeioraTrjv 
 aperrjit) is dwelt on 2 . Then, in nearing the end, Tamblichus 
 points out as one incitement to philosophise, that of all kinds 
 of knowledge philosophy alone has no touch of envy or of joy 
 in others' ill, since it shows that men are all akin and of like 
 affections and subject in common to unforeseen changes of 
 fortune. Whence it promotes human sympathy and mutual 
 love 3 . 
 
 3. The School of Iamblichus. 
 
 After the death of Iamblichus, his school dispersed itself 
 over the whole Roman Empire 4 . His most brilliant disciple 
 was Sopater, a man of ambitious temperament, who, as 
 Eunapius expresses it, thought to change the purpose of 
 Constantine by reason. He did in fact succeed in gaining 
 a high position at Court ; but in the struggle of intrigue his 
 enemies at last got the better of him, and he was condemned 
 by the Christian emperor to be executed, apparently on a 
 charge of magic. According to Eunapius, he was accused of 
 binding the winds so as to prevent the arrival of the ships on 
 which Constantinople depended for its supply of corn 5 . 
 
 Both now and for some time later, philosophers and others 
 who were not even nominal adherents of Christianity could 
 be employed by Christian rulers. Eustathius, another of 
 Iamblichus's disciples, was sent by Constantius on an embassy 
 
 1 Protr. 21, pp. 118—119. 2 Protr. 21, p. 114. 
 
 3 Protr. 21, p. 123. 
 
 4 Eunap. Vitae (Iamblichus) : aXXot fiii> yap dWaxov tu>v dp-qfxevwv 6/j.i\rjTu>i> 
 5i€Kpld7jcrav eh awacrav ttjv ~P(i)(ml'Ck))v cirixpaTeiav. 
 
 3 Eunap. Vitae (Aedesius). 
 
VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 133 
 
 to Persia. Themistius, who was an Aristotelian, held offices 
 at a later period. The Christians themselves, long after the 
 death of Julian, were still for the most part obliged to resort 
 to the philosophical schools for their scientific culture 1 . The 
 contest in the world, however, was now effectively decided, 
 and the cause represented by the philosophers was plainly seen 
 to be the losing one. Of its fortunes, and of the personalities 
 of its adherents, we get a faithful picture from Eunapius, whose 
 life of Aedesius is especially interesting for the passages 
 showing the feelings with which the triumph of the Church 
 was regarded. Aedesius was the successor of Iamblichus at 
 Pergamum in Mysia. The biographer, it may be noted, dis- 
 tinctly tells us that he had no reputation for theurgy. The 
 marvels he connects with his name relate to the clairvoyance 
 of Sosipatra, the wife of Eustathius. Aedesius educated the 
 sons of Eustathius and Sosipatra; hence the connexion. One 
 of them, Antoninus, took up his abode at the Canopic mouth 
 of the Nile, whither came the youth eager for philosophical 
 knowledge. To him again, as to Aedesius, no theurgical 
 accomplishments are ascribed ; a possible reason in both cases, 
 Eunapius suggests, being concealment on account of the 
 hostility of the new rulers of the world. Those who put 
 before him logical problems were immediately satisfied ; those 
 who threw out anything about " diviner " inquiries found him 
 irresponsive as a statue. He probably did not himself regard 
 it as supernatural prescience when he uttered the prophecy, 
 afterwards held for an oracle, that soon " a fabulous and 
 formless darkness shall tyrannise' over the fairest things on 
 earth " (kcil tl /u,uOo)Se<; icai aetSe? (tkotos rupavv?]aec ra iirl 
 yij'i KaXkicna) 1 . The accession of Julian to the empire created 
 
 1 ZeUer, ill. 2, p. 739. 
 
 - Cf. Gibbon on the " Final Destruction of Paganism," where the prediction 
 is quoted iu a note. (Decline and Fall of tin- Roman Empire, ed. J. B. Bury, 
 vol. iii. p. 208.) In the chapter referred to, however, Gibbon antedated the 
 disappearance of pagan rites ; as may be seen from the lives of philosophers 
 later than Eunapius's period. With the impression made on the biographer, it 
 is interesting to compare his contemporary St Jerome's description, cited by 
 Grote at the end of the preface to his Plato, of the desertion of the philosophic 
 schools. Who now, asks the Christian Father, reads Plato or Aristotle? "llus- 
 ticauos vero et piscatores nostras totus orbis loquitur, universus mundus sonat." 
 
134 THE DIFFUSION [VII 
 
 no illusion in the most clear-sighted of the philosophers. 
 Chrysanthius, one of his instructors in the Neo-Platonic 
 philosophy, was pressingly invited by him to come and join 
 him in the restoration of Hellenism. Deterred, the biographer 
 says, by unfavourable omens, he declined. The Emperor never- 
 theless conferred on him, in association with his wife Melite, 
 the high-priesthood of Lydia 1 . This he accepted : but, fore- 
 warned of the failure of Julian's attempt to revive the ancient 
 worship, he altered as little as possible during his tenure of 
 office ; so that there was hardly any disturbance there when 
 the state of things was again reversed ; whereas elsewhere the 
 upheavals and depressions were violent. This was at the time 
 looked upon as an example of his unerring foresight, derived 
 from the knowledge of divine things communicated by his 
 Pythagorean masters 2 . It was added, that he knew how to 
 make use of his gift of prevision ; this, no doubt, in contrast 
 with Maximus 3 . 
 
 Maximus and Chrysanthius were fellow-pupils of Aedesius, 
 and were united in their devotion to theurgy. When Julian 
 was first attracted to the philosophic teachers of his time, the 
 aged Aedesius had commended him to his disciples Eusebius 
 and Chrysanthius, who were present, and Priscus and Maximus, 
 who were then absent from Pergamum. Eusebius, whose 
 special interest was in logical studies, spoke with disparage- 
 ment of theurgy, but Julian's curiosity was excited by what he 
 heard. To satisfy it, he visited Maximus at Ephesus, at whose 
 suggestion he sent for Chrysanthius also. Under Maximus and 
 Chrysanthius he continued his philosophical studies. It may 
 have been his interest in theurgy that led him to seek initia- 
 tion, during his visit to Greece, in the Eleusinian mysteries ; 
 though his argument afterwards for being initiated was merely 
 compliance with ancient usage ; he treats it as a matter of 
 
 1 Eunap. Vitae (Maximus). Melite was a kinswoman of Eunapius, and 
 Chrysanthius became his teacher in philosophy. 
 
 2 Eunap. Vitae (Chrysanthius): bpdv yovv dv tis avrbv ecp-qae pdWov to. 
 eab/xeva t) TrpoXtyeiv t& fiiWovra, ourws diravra birjdpei Kai avveXdpi^avev, waavei 
 Trapwp re Kai avviov tois deoTs. 
 
 Hi. : €$av/j.d<rdr] yovv em tovtois, ws ov fxbvov deivbs rd /JLeWovra wpovoetv, dWd 
 Kai Toh yvwaddai xp?jcra<T0<xi. 
 
VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 135 
 
 course that such ceremonies can make no difference to the 
 soul's lot 1 . When he had become Emperor, he invited Maximus 
 with Chrysanthius, and afterwards Priscus, to Court. Unlike 
 Chrysanthius, Maximus, when he found the omens unfavourable, 
 persisted till he got favourable ones. In power, as Eunapius 
 frankly acknowledges, he displayed a want of moderation which 
 led to his being treated afterwards with great severity. He 
 was put to death under Valens, as the penalty of having been 
 consulted regarding divinations about the Emperor's successor. 
 Priscus, we learn' 2 , had been from his youth up a person of 
 rather ostentatious gravity and reserve. He was, however, no 
 pretender, but maintained the philosophic character consistently 
 during the reign of Julian ; nor was he afterwards accused of 
 any abuse of power. He died at the time when the Goths 
 were ravaging Greece (396—8). Preserving always his grave 
 demeanour, says Eunapius, and laughing at the weakness of 
 mankind, he perished along with the sanctuaries of Hellas, 
 having lived to be over ninety, while many cast away their 
 lives through grief or were killed by the barbarians. During 
 the events that followed Julian's reign (361-363), the bio- 
 grapher was himself a youth 3 . He was born probably in 346 
 or 347, and died later than 414. 
 
 Of the literary activity of the school during the period 
 from the death of Iamblichus to the end of the fourth ceutury, 
 there is not much to say. Many of the philosophers seem to 
 have confined themselves to oral exposition. Chrysanthius 
 wrote much, but none of his works have come down to us. 
 We have reports of the opinions of Theodore of Asine 4 , an 
 immediate disciple buth of Porphyry and of Iamblichus. His 
 writing seems to have taken the form chiefly of commentaries. 
 Proclus had a high opinion of him and frequently cites him. 
 We learn that with Plotinus he maintained the passionlessness 
 
 1 Or. vii. 239 BC : tovtois pt.lv, oh djjtws tou p.vwdrivaL /^e/3twrat, aai fj.rj 
 pwqdeloiv o't deoi rds ap.oi^as aKepaious <pv\&TTov(Ti, tois 5e fj.oxQypoh ovolv eari w\iov 
 Kav «<xa> twv Upwv eio~(ppri<Two~i 7rept/36\u>e. 
 
 - Eunap. Vitae (Priscus). 
 
 8 Eunap. Vitae (Maximus) : kcu 6 raura ypa,<pwv eiraiOeveTo kcit' eVce/eons tovs 
 Xpwovs wait wv ko.1 els ifprjfiovs dpri reXaJc. 
 
 * Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 721 ft'. 
 
136 THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM [VII 
 
 and uninterrupted activity of the higher part of the soul ; and 
 that he defended Plato's position on the equality of the sexes. 
 Dexippus, another disciple of Iamblichus, wrote, in the form of 
 a dialogue with a pupil, a work on the Aristotelian Categories 
 which survives 1 . The book Be Myst&riis, long attributed to 
 Iamblichus himself, is now considered only as illustrating the 
 general direction of his school 2 . Its most distinctive feature 
 is insistence on the necessity and value of ceremonial religion 
 for the mass of mankind, and indeed for all but an inappreciable 
 minority. It is admittedly well-written, as is also the little 
 book of Sallust Be Biis et Mundo 9 . This Sallust, according 
 to Zeller 4 , was pretty certainly the friend of Julian known 
 from the Emperor's Orations and from references in the 
 historians ; and the book may have been put forth with a 
 popular aim as a defence of the old religious system now 
 restored and to be justified in the light of philosophy. A 
 noteworthy point in it is the apology for animal sacrifices. 
 As in the Be Mysteriis, the higher place of philosophy is saved 
 by the position that the incorporeal gods are in no way affected 
 by prayer or sacrifice or by any kind of ceremony, and are 
 moved by no passions. The forms of traditional religion, it is 
 nevertheless maintained, are subjectively useful to men, and 
 its modes of speech admit of a rational interpretation. The 
 book ends by affirming the position of the Republic, that virtue 
 would be sufficient for happiness even if there were no rewards 
 reserved for it in another life. 
 
 J Zeller, iii. 2, p. 737, n. 1. 
 
 2 An edition of it was published at Oxford by Gale in 1678, with Latin 
 version and notes and a reconstruction of Porphyry's letter to Anebo, to which it 
 is a reply. The later edition by Parthey (Berlin, 1857) is based on Gale's. 
 English readers will find an exact account of the sceptical queries of Porphyry, 
 and of the solutions given by the author, in Maurice's Moral and Metaphysical 
 Philosophy, vol. i. 
 
 3 Edited by Orelli, with Latin version and notes, in 1821. 
 
 4 iii. 2, p. 734. 
 
CHAPTER VIII. 
 
 THE POLEMIC AGAINST CHRISTIANITY. 
 
 In taking up the defence of the old against the new 
 religious institutions of the Roman Empire, the Neo-Platonists 
 were simply continuing the attitude of earlier philosophical 
 culture. From the time when the new religious phenomenon 
 was first consciously recognised — that is to say, from about the 
 beginning of the second century — it had aroused an instinctive 
 antagonism among men who were as far from believing the 
 pagan myths as the Christians themselves. The outlines of 
 the apology for paganism, so far as it can be recovered, remain 
 from first to last without essential modification. Celsus, writing 
 in the second century, conceives the problem to be that of 
 reconciling philosophical theism with diversities of national 
 worship. It may be solved, in his view, by supposing the 
 supreme Deity to have allotted different regions to subordinate 
 divine powers, who may either be called gods, as by the Greeks, 
 or angels, as by the Jews. Then, to show that the Christians 
 have no philosophical advantage, he points to the declarations 
 of Greek thinkers that there is one supreme God, and that the 
 Deity has no visible form. On the other side, he insists on 
 the resemblances between Hebrew and Greek legends. Greek 
 mythology, he remarks, has in common with Christianity its 
 stories of incarnations. In other religions also resurrections 
 are spoken of. Such are those of Zamolxis in Scythia and of 
 Rhampsinitus among the Egyptians. Among the Greeks too 
 there are cases in which mortal men have been represented as 
 raised to divinity. Noah's flood may have been borrowed from 
 
138 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 Deucalion's, and the idea of Satan from the Greek Titanomachies. 
 The more intelligent Jews and Christians are ashamed of much 
 in Biblical history, and try to explain it allegorically. What is 
 supposed to be distinctive of Christian ethics has been put 
 better, because more temperately, by the Greek philosophers. 
 Plato holds much the same view about the difficulty there is 
 for a rich man to enter into the kingdom of heaven. He 
 declares likewise that evil is never to be returned for evil. 
 The reproach of idolatry against the non-Judaic religions is a 
 calumny. Statues are not regarded as deities, but only as aids 
 to devotion. To the highest God, as all agree, only the worship 
 of the mind ought to be offered. But why should not hymns 
 be addressed to beneficent visible powers like the sun, or to 
 mental attributes such as Wisdom, represented by Athena ? 
 Piety is more complete when it has regard to all the varied 
 manifestations of divinity in the world 1 . 
 
 On their side, the Christians were quite willing to appeal 
 to philosophers and poets who had had ideas of a purer religion 
 than that of the multitude. All such ideas, they maintained, 
 were borrowed from the Hebrew Scriptures. Philo had pre- 
 viously taken that view ; and, as we saw, among men who 
 attached themselves to the Hellenic tradition, Numenius was 
 ready to allow something of the same kind. Theodoret, early 
 in the fifth century, is sarcastic upon the ignorance displayed 
 by the pagans of his time, who are not aware of the fact, to be 
 learned from their own sages, that the Greeks owed most of 
 their knowledge of the sciences and arts to the " barbarians 2 .'' 
 As against unmodified Judaism, the Christians could find 
 support for some of their own positions in the appeal to 
 religious reformers like Apollonius of Tyana ; who, condemning 
 blood-offerings as he did on more radical grounds than them- 
 selves, was yet put forward by the apologists of paganism as a 
 half-divine personage. So far did this go that Hierocles, the 
 
 1 See Keim's reconstruction of the arguments of Celsus from Origen's reply 
 (Celsus 1 Wahres Wort, 1873). 
 
 2 See p. 89 of Neumann's prolegomena to his reconstruction of Julian's 
 work against the Christians, to be spoken of later. In taking for granted the 
 essential independence of Hellenic culture, it would seem that Greek popular 
 opinion was sounder than much learned opinion. 
 
VIIl] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 139 
 
 Proconsul of Bithynia who wrote against the Christians in the 
 time of Diocletian, gave his ecclesiastical antagonist Eusebius 
 occasion to treat the part of his book that dealt with Apollonius 
 as the only part worth replying to. And Porphyry, in whom 
 the Christians saw their most dangerous adversary, himself 
 made a distinct claim to what we should now call religious as 
 distinguished from philosophical liberty in the matter of food 
 and of sacrificing. Nor was any objection usually raised by the 
 authorities to reforming sects that aimed at personal holiness. 
 The Roman Government even looked upon it as part of its own 
 function to repress savage rites, such as human sacrifices. 
 Whence then sprang the repugnance almost uniformly to be 
 observed in the statesmen, philosophers and men of letters who 
 were brought into contact with the new religion ? For they 
 were quite prepared to appreciate a monotheistic worship, and 
 to welcome anything that afforded a real prospect of moral 
 reform. 
 
 We might be tempted to find the cause in the want of 
 culture among ordinary Christians. Julian, for example, who de- 
 tested the "uneducated Cynics" of his time, can think of nothing 
 worse to say of them than that they resemble the Christian 
 monks (cnroTaKTiGTaiy. The only difference is that the Cynics 
 do not make a business of gathering alms ; and perhaps this is 
 only because they can find no plausible pretext. It is those, he 
 adds, who have shown no capacity for rhetorical or philosophical 
 culture that rush straight to the profession of Cynicism 2 . Yet, 
 he goes on to admit, there is really, as the Cynics claimed on 
 their own behalf, a " shorter path " to philosophic virtue than 
 the normal one of intellectual discipline. The shorter path is, 
 however, the more difficult ; requiring greater and not less 
 vigour of mind and firmness of will. Of those who took it were 
 the elder Cynics like Diogenes. The true as distinguished 
 from the false Cynic remained, in fact, for Julian as for Epic- 
 tetus, a hero among philosophers. This was part of the Stoical 
 
 1 Or. vn. 224 a— c. 
 
 2 Or. VII. 225 is: tCiv pyropinuiv oi 5vcr/j.a6ecrTa.T0i nal ovo' vir' avrov rod BacriXtus 
 'Ep/xov TT)V yXCoTTav eKKadapdr/vai. Ovvd/xevot, <ppevudi}i>ai 5£ oi)5e 7rpos avTrjs ttjs 
 'Adr)i>as avv tu 'Epfi.-g,...6ppiu)cnv £irl tov Kwicrfidf. 
 
140 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 tradition continued into Neo-Platonism. And, as we know, it 
 was a commonplace with philosophic preachers to make light 
 of mental accomplishments as compared with moral strength. 
 Besides, the Christians had among them men of rhetorical 
 training who were not without knowledge of philosophy. The 
 antagonism therefore cannot be accounted for altogether on this 
 line. 
 
 The truth is that the Graeco-Roman world had a perception, 
 vague at first but gradually becoming clearer, of what was to 
 be meant by Christian theocracy. When Tacitus spoke of the 
 " exitiabilis superstitio," he had doubtless come face to face in 
 Asia with nascent Catholicism. In the fourth century, the new 
 types of the fanatical monk and the domineering ecclesiastic 
 were definitely in the world, and we may see by the expressions 
 of Eunapius the intense antipathy they aroused 1 . Already in 
 the second century, Celsus, while he treated the Gnostic sects, 
 with their claims to a higher "knowledge," as having a perfect 
 right to the Christian name, was evidently much more struck 
 by the idea of a common creed which was to be humbly 
 accepted. This was the distinctive idea of that which he 
 recognises as the " great Church " among the Christians. It is 
 remarkable that, in dealing with the claims of Christianity 
 generally, and not with the strange tenets of some speculative 
 sects, the defender of the established order in the Roman State 
 treats philosophy as the true wisdom by which everything is to 
 be tested, and reproaches the revolutionary innovators on the 
 ground that they say to their dupes, "Do not examine." 
 Celsus was probably a Roman official ; and he may have seen 
 already some of the political aims of the new society. For of 
 course the word " catholic " as applied to the Church was not 
 intended to remain without a very tangible meaning. The 
 Christian apologists of the second century are already looking 
 forward to spiritual control over the public force of the Empire 2 . 
 
 1 Eunap. Vitae (Aedesius) : elra eneio-rjyov roh iepo7s tottois tovs KaXov/j.ei'ovs 
 iu.ova.xovs, avOpuirovs /u.ev Kara to eldos, 6 5£ /St'os auTois <jv<J)Sr)S, ...rvpavvLKrjV yap 
 €lx ev e^ovo-iav Tore ttcls avdpwiros /xiXaivau <popGiv iaOrJTa /cat drjfxoaig, j3ov\6/J.evos 
 ao-x'THJ-ovdv. 
 
 - See Renan, Marc-Aurele. The alternative imposed by the Church on the 
 Empire was, Renan says, to persecute or to become a theocracy. 
 
VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 141 
 
 A verse of the New Testament by which the claim was held to 
 be made is pointed to by Julian in arguing that the Christians 
 are not legitimate successors of the Israelites. Christ, according 
 to the view of the Church, was the prophet that Moses foretold, 
 of whom it was said, " that every soul, which will not hear that 
 prophet, shall be destroyed from among the people " (Acts iii. 
 28). The Church possessed the teachings of Christ, and was 
 a living body with the right to declare them authoritatively. 
 The true religion was not now, as under an earlier dispensation, 
 for one chosen race, but for the whole world. Hence the whole 
 world was bound to hear and to obey it. The reply of Julian 
 was that the application of the prediction supposed to have 
 been made was false. Moses never had the least idea that his 
 legislation was to be abrogated, but intended it for all time. 
 The prophet he meant was simply a prophet that should renew 
 his own teaching of the law. The law was for the Jews only, 
 and the Christians had no claim to represent them. The 
 Jewish religion had its proper place as one national religion 
 among others. It was open even to those who were not born 
 under it to adopt it as their own if they chose ; but they should 
 have submitted to all its obligations. The care of the Jews 
 about religious observances, and their readiness to face perse- 
 cution on behalf of them, are contrasted by the Emperor in one 
 place with the laxity and indifference of the Greeks. They are 
 in part pious, he says, worshipping as they do the God who 
 rules the visible world, whom we also serve under other names. 
 In this only are they in error, that they arrogate to themselves 
 alone the worship of the one true God, and think that to us, 
 " the nations," have been assigned none but gods whom they 
 themselves do not deign to regard at all 1 . 
 
 Julian, we see, had no hostility to Hebrew religion as such. 
 On the contrary, he resembles Porphyry in showing special 
 friendliness to it in so far as its monotheism may be taken to 
 coincide with that of philosophy. The problem presented to 
 the Empire by Judaism, so difficult at an earlier period, had 
 now become manageable through the ending of all political 
 
 1 Ep. 63 (ed. Heitlein). aXafovdq, pa.pj3a.piKr), adds Julian, 71756s ravrrivi rr\v 
 aTrovoiav eirapdevres. 
 
142 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 aspirations on the part of the Jewish community. The question 
 as to the respective merits of Hebrew and Greek religion, if no 
 new question had arisen, would soon have been reduced to a 
 topic of the schools. The system, at once philosophical and 
 political, of the classical world in its dealings with religion, was 
 not of course "religious liberty" in its modern sense. In a 
 congeries of local worships, mostly without definite creeds, 
 the question of toleration for dissentients had scarcely arisen. 
 The position reached by the representatives of ancient thought, 
 and allowed in practice, was that the national religions might 
 all be preserved, not only as useful, but as adumbrations of 
 divine truth. To express that truth adequately is the business 
 of philosophy and not of popular religion. Philosophy is to be 
 perfectly free. This is laid down explicitly by Julian 1 . Thus, 
 according to the system, philosophy is cosmopolitan and is an 
 unfettered inquiry into truth. Religion is local and is bound 
 to the performance of customary rites. Those who are in quest 
 of a deeper knowledge will not think of changing their ancestral 
 religion, but will turn to some philosophical teacher. At the 
 same time, the religions are to be moralised 2 . Priests are to be 
 men of exemplary life, and are to be treated with high respect. 
 The harmony of the whole system had of course been broken 
 through by Christianity, which, after the period of attempted 
 repression by force, had now been for more than a generation 
 the religion of the Empire. Julian's solution of the problem, 
 renewed by his reversal of the policy of his uncle, was to grant 
 a formal toleration to all 3 . Both sides are forbidden to use 
 
 1 Or. v. 170 bc. For those of ordinary capacity (rots tfubrais) the utility of 
 divine myths is sufficiently conveyed through symbols without rational under- 
 standing. For those of exceptional intelligence (rots irepLTToh) there can be no 
 utility without investigation into truth of reason, continued to the end, oik aldol 
 Kal irlcrreL ixaXKov dWorpias do^ijs tj rrj <x<peT{pa Kara vovv evepyelg.. 
 
 2 See Ep. 49. The progress of Hellenism is not sufficient without moral 
 reform. The example set by the Christians of philanthropy to strangers, and 
 by the Jews of supporting their own poor, ought to be followed by the Greeks. 
 Anciently, continues Julian, this belonged to the Hellenic tradition, as is shown 
 by the words of Eumaeus in the Odyssey (xiv. 56). 
 
 3 The earliest edicts of Constantine had simply proclaimed a toleration of 
 Christianity; but these, it was well understood, were a mere preliminary to its 
 
VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 143 
 
 violence, which is entirely out of place where opinions are 
 concerned 1 . Nevertheless, for dignities, "the pious" — that is 
 to say, the adherents of the old religions — are to be preferred 2 . 
 Christians are not allowed to be public teachers of Grecian 
 letters ; the reason assigned being that the Greek poets, 
 historians and orators treat the gods with honour, whereas the 
 Christians speak dishonourably of them. It is unworthy of an 
 educated or of a good man to teach one thing and to think 
 another. Let them either change their views about the 
 theology of the Greeks or confine themselves to the exposi- 
 tion of their own 3 . 
 
 By this policy there is no reason to think that the Emperor 
 was putting back a process by which captive Greece might 
 again have led the conqueror captive. The Church absolutely 
 needed the elements of culture if it was to rule the world; and 
 it could find them only in the classical tradition. It was now 
 in more or less conscious possession of its own system, which 
 was precisely the antithesis of the system which Julian desired 
 to restore. A religion had been revealed which claimed to be 
 true for all. Philosophy, so far as it was serviceable, could be 
 treated as a preparation for it or as an instrument in defining 
 its doctrines, but could have no independent standing-ground. 
 Letters, in the hands of ecclesiastics, could furnish the gram- 
 matical and rhetorical training without which the reign of a 
 "spiritual power" would have been impossible. The new 
 system, however, was as yet far from being fully at work. 
 Christian pupils, we must remember, continued to frequent 
 the pagan schools much later. Thus there was evidently no 
 insuperable prejudice by which they would have been univer- 
 sally excluded from a liberal education not subjugated to 
 ecclesiastical authority. If then by any possibility the advance 
 
 acceptance as the State religion. Julian stripped the Church of the privileges, 
 over and above toleration, which it had acquired in the meantime. 
 
 1 Ep. 52, 438 h : \6ycf) 5Z ireidecrtlat XPV Ka ' Sid&fftceirOai tovs avdpuirovs, ov 
 ir\riycus ovde vfipeaiv ovoi aiKta/Atp rod crw/uaros. avdis 5t Kal ttoWcLkls napaivQ tols 
 em T7je a\r]07J Ofocrtfieiav opp-ufievois pL-qdev aBinew r&v Ya\i\a.luv to. ir\7}t)-q, p.t]8e 
 iiriTideadai p.r}be vfipifciv (is avrovs. 
 
 - Ep. 7, 376 c : wpoTip.affda.L fxivTOi tovs 6eoo~fj3eis Kal wavv (f>ijfJ.i 8eiv. 
 
 3 Ep. 42. 
 
144 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 of the theocratic idea could have been checked, it is clear that 
 the Emperor took exactly the right measures. The classical 
 writers were to be seen, so far as public authority could secure 
 it, under the light of the tradition to which they themselves 
 belonged. Pupils were not to be systematically taught in the 
 schools of the Empire that the pagan gods were " evil demons," 
 and that the heroes and sages of antiquity were among the 
 damned. And, hopeless as the defeated party henceforth was 
 of a change of fortune, Julian's memory furnished a rallying- 
 point for those who now devoted themselves to the preservation 
 of the older culture interpreted by itself. Marinus, in writing 
 the biography of Proclus, dates his death "in the 124th year 
 from the reign of Julian." Thus the actual effect of his 
 resistance to that system of ecclesiastical rule which afterwards, 
 to those who again knew the civic type of life, appeared as a 
 " Kingdom of Darkness," may have been to prolong the evening 
 twilight. 
 
 All who have studied the career of Julian recognise that his 
 great aim was to preserve "Hellenism," by which he meant 
 Hellenic civilisation. Of this the ancient religion was for him 
 the symbol. The myths about the gods are not to be taken 
 literally. The marriage of Hyperion and Thea, for example, is 
 a poetic fable 1 . What the poets say, along with the divine 
 element in it, has also much that is human 2 . Pure truth, 
 unmixed with fable, is to be found in the philosophers, and 
 especially in Plato 3 . On the Jewish religion, the Emperor's 
 position sometimes appears ambiguous. He easily finds, in the 
 
 1 Or. iv. 136 c : pvt} 5e avvdvaa/nbv pajS^ ydfiovs vTroXa/j.^dvio/mv, amaTOL ko.1 
 wapddo^a rrjs irotTjTiKTJs /xoijcrrji idipfiara. 
 
 2 lb. 137 C : dXXa t<x p.ei> tu>v ttol^twv xaipetv edawp.ei' ■ £%ei yap nera tov Oeiov 
 
 TT0\V KCLI TO dvdpdlWlVOV . 
 
 3 Julian, however, like the Neo-Platouists generally, is unwilling to allow 
 that Plato could ever have intended to treat the poetic legends with disrespect. 
 In Or. vn. 237 bc, he cites as an example of ev\d(3eia irepl rd tGiv deuv 6v6p.ara, 
 the well-known passage in the Timaeus, 40 d, about the gods that have left 
 descendants among us, whom we cannot refuse to believe when they tell us of 
 their own ancestors. This, he says, might have been ironical (as evidently 
 many took it to be) if put in the mouth of Socrates ; but Timaeus, to whom it 
 is actually assigned, had no reputation for irony. 
 
VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 145 
 
 Old Testament, passages from which to argue that the God of 
 Israel is simply a tribal god like those of the nations. His 
 serious opinion, however, seems to have been that the Hebrew 
 prophets had arrived at an expression, less pure indeed than 
 that of the Greek philosophers, but quite real, of the unity of 
 divine government 1 . In one passage — than which no better 
 could be found to illustrate the antithesis between " Hebraism " 
 and " Hellenism " — he compares them to men seeing a great 
 light as through a mist, and unable to describe what they see 
 except by imagery drawn from the destructive force of fire 2 . 
 While himself regarding the divinity as invisible and incorporeal, 
 he treats as prejudice their denunciations of the making of 
 statues. The kind of truth he would recognise in popular 
 polytheism he finds not altogether inconsistent with the 
 Hebrew Scriptures, which speak of the angels of nations. 
 National deities, whether to be called angels or gods, are 
 interpreted as a kind of genius of each race. The various 
 natural aptitudes of peoples suppose a variety in the divine 
 cause, and this can be expressed as a distribution made by 
 the supreme God to subordinate powers 3 . That is the 
 position taken up by Julian in his book against the Christians 
 — which is at the same time a defence of Hellenism. From 
 the fragments contained in Cyril's reply — of which perhaps half 
 survives — it has been beautifully reconstructed by C. J. Neu- 
 mann 4 . A summary of the general argument will serve better 
 than anything else to make clear the spiritual difference that 
 separated from their Christian contemporaries the men who 
 had received their bent in the philosophic schools. 
 
 Evidently neither Julian's work nor any other was felt to 
 be so peculiarly damaging as Porphyry's. By a decree of the 
 
 1 Cf. E P . 25. 
 
 2 Fragmentum Epistolae, 296 a: olov 0cDs ,u^ya di 6/u.Lx^ys oi dvdpuvoi fiXeirovTes 
 ov KadapQs ovSe dXiKpivus, airrd 5e (Kecvo veuoniKdrfs ovxl <£ws xadapdv, dXXa vvp, 
 /cat twv irepl avro irdvTwv 6vm adearoi /3ou><ri /xtya ' QpiTTere, <f>oj3ua8e, wvp, #\6£ , 
 dd.va.Tos, /xaxaipa, pofj.cf>aia, ttoWoU ovd/j-aai pdav 4^rjyov/j.evoi tt)v fiXairTLKTjv rod 
 irvpbs 8uvafj.iv. 
 
 3 This idea, which we meet with also in Celsus, appears to have been 
 suggested by a passage in the Critias, where such a distribution is described. 
 
 4 Iuliami Imperatorw Librorum contra Christiana* quae supersunt (1880). 
 
 w. 10 
 
14G THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 Council of Ephesus (431) and by a law of Theodosius II. (448), 
 Porphyry's books, though not those of Celsus, Hierocles or 
 Julian, were sentenced to be burned. In the changed form of 
 the law in Justinian's code, the books written by any one else 
 to the same purpose (Kara rrjs evcrefiov? twv X^picrriavoju 
 6prj<TKeia<i) are brought under the decree, but not by name 1 . 
 The difference between Julian's line of attack and Porphyry's, 
 so far as it can be made out, is that Julian, while much that he 
 too says has an interest from its bearing on questions of Biblical 
 criticism, pays no special attention to the analysis of documents. 
 He takes for granted the traditional ascriptions of the Canonical 
 books, and uniformly quotes the Septuagint. Porphyry is said 
 to have known the Hebrew original. We have already met 
 with his view on the Book of Daniel ; and so characteristic was 
 his inquiry into questions of authorship and chronology, that 
 Neumann is inclined to refer to him an assertion of the late 
 and non-Mosaic origin of the Pentateuch, quoted by Macarius 
 Magnes about the end of the fourth century from an unknown 
 philosopher 2 . What line was taken either by Julian or by 
 Porphyry on the primitive teaching of Christianity itself, hardly 
 anything remains to show. Of Porphyry, as was said, all the 
 express refutations have disappeared ; and of the later books of 
 Cyril's reply to Julian there are left only a few fragments. We 
 learn from one of these 3 that the Catholic saint rejected as 
 spurious the words of Christ in Luke xxiii. 34. "The Apostate" 
 had apparently quoted them against anticipations of the 
 mediaeval treatment of the Jews. On the cult of martyrs, 
 the Bishop of Alexandria's reply is not without point, as Julian 
 would have been the first to allow 4 . The Greeks themselves, 
 he says 5 , go in procession to the tombs and celebrate the praises 
 of those who fought for Greece ; yet they do not worship them 
 as gods. No more do we offer to our martyrs the worship due 
 
 1 Neumann, Prolegomena, pp. 8 — 9. 
 
 2 Neumann, Prolegomena, p. 20 : MwiWws ovb*kv dwoaui^erai. ffvyypd/j.fj.aTa 
 yap wavTa crvve/Aweirprjcrdcu tQ vau> Xeyerai. oca 5 iw dvofMtri Mwwfws eypd<f>T) 
 fj.£Ta ravra, /xerd xtXta /cat eKarov /cat oydorjKOVTa irt) ttjs Muvciws reXevrrjs vwb 
 "EcrSpa /cat tuiv dfi<p' avrbv cvveypd<pn- 
 
 3 Neumann, pp. 69, 130 — 1. 
 
 4 Cf. Ep. 78. 5 Neumann, pp. 85— 6. 
 
Viri] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 147 
 
 to God, nor do we pray to them. Moreover, the gods of the 
 Gentiles were men who were born and died, and the tombs of 
 some of them remain. Connected with this recurrence to the 
 "Euhemerism" which the Christian Fathers sometimes borrowed 
 from Greek speculators on the origin of religion, is a quotation 
 from Porphyry's Life of Pythagoras; introduced, Neumann 
 conjectures (p. 80), to prove that the Greeks had no right to be 
 incredulous about the declaration (1 Peter iii. 19, 20) that 
 Christ preached to the spirits in prison ; since Pythagoras is 
 represented as having descended into the Idaean cave (here 
 apparently identified with the underworld) where the tomb of 
 Jupiter was. 
 
 On the relation of Christianity to its Hebrew origins, and 
 on these as compared with the poetry and philosophy of Greece, 
 a coherent account of Julian's view can be put together. He 
 seems to have begun by speaking of the intuitive knowledge 
 men have of God. To such knowledge, he says, — perhaps with 
 an allusion to the elements of Gnostic pessimism that had found 
 their way into orthodox Christianity, — has usually been attached 
 the conviction that the heavens, as distinguished from the earth, 
 are a diviner part of the universe, though it is not meant by 
 this that the earth is excluded from divine care. He entirely 
 repudiates the fables about Cronos swallowing his children, and 
 about the incestuous marriages of Zeus, and so forth. But, he 
 proceeds, the story of the Garden of Eden is equally mythical. 
 Unless it has some secret meaning, it is full of blasphemy, since 
 it represents God as forbidding to his creatures that knowledge 
 of good and evil which alone is the bond of human intelligence, 
 and as envious of their possible immortality. In what do stories 
 like that of the talking serpent — according to the account, the 
 real benefactor of the human race — differ from those invented 
 by the Greeks ? Compare the Mosaic with the Platonic cos- 
 mogony, and its speculative weakness becomes plain. In the 
 language of the Book of Genesis there is no accurate definition. 
 Some things, we are told, God commanded to come into being ; 
 others he " made " ; others he separated out. As to the Spirit 
 (irvevfia) of God, there is no clear determination whether it was 
 made, or came to be, or is eternal without generation. Accord- 
 
 10—2 
 
148 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 ing to Moses, if we are to argue from what he says explicitly 1 , 
 God is not the creator of anything incorporeal, but is only a 
 shaper of underlying matter. According to Plato, on the other 
 hand, the intelligible and invisible gods of which the visible 
 sun and moon and stars are images, proceed from the Demi- 
 urgus, as does also the rational soul of man. Who then speaks 
 better and more worthily of God, the " idolater " Plato, or he of 
 whom the Scripture says that God spoke with him mouth to 
 mouth ? 
 
 Contrast now the opinions of the Hebrews and of the Greeks 
 about the relations of the Creator to the various races of man- 
 kind. According to Moses and all who have followed the 
 Hebrew tradition, the Creator of the world chose the Hebrews 
 for his own people, and cared for them only. Moses has nothing 
 to say about the divine government of other nations, unless one 
 should concede that he assigns to them the sun and moon for 
 deities (Deut. iv. 19). Paul changes in an elusive manner 2 ; 
 but if, as he says sometimes (Rom. iii. 29), God is not the God 
 of the Jews only, why did he neglect so long all but one small 
 nation settled less than two thousand years ago in a portion of 
 Palestine ? Our teachers say that their creator is the common 
 father and king of all, and that the peoples are distributed by 
 him to presiding deities, each of whom rules over his allotted 
 nation or city. In the Father, all things are perfect and all 
 things are one; in the divided portions, one power is pre- 
 dominant here, another there. Thus Ares is said to rule over 
 warlike nations, Athena over those that are warlike with 
 wisdom, and so forth. Let the appeal be to the facts. Do 
 not these differences in the characters of nations exist ? And 
 it cannot be said that the differences in the parts are uncaused 
 without denying that providence governs the whole. Human 
 laws are not the cause of them, for it is by the natural characters 
 
 1 Angels, Julian contends elsewhere, are the equivalents, in the Hebrew 
 Scriptures, of the gods of polytheism. No doubt Moses held that they were 
 produced by divine power, and were not independently existing beings ; but, 
 pre-eminent as their rank in the universe must be, he has no account to give of 
 them in his cosmogony, where we should have expected to find one. 
 
 2 The words are given from Cyril by Neumann (p. 177, 11) : uinrep oi 
 iro\viro8es Trpbs ras irirpas. 
 
VIIl] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 149 
 
 of men that the laws peculiar to each people are determined. 
 Legislators by the lead they give can do little in comparison 
 with nature and custom. Take the case of the Western races 1 . 
 Though they have been so long under Roman rule, you find 
 extremely few among them showing aptitude for philosophy or 
 geometry or any of the sciences. The cleverest appreciate only 
 debate and oratory, and concern themselves with no other 
 branch of knowledge. So strong is nature. 
 
 The cause assigned by Moses for the diversity of languages 
 is altogether mythical. And yet those who demand that the 
 Greeks should believe the story of the tower of Babel, themselves 
 disbelieve what Homer tells about the Aloadae, how they 
 thought to pile three mountains on one another, Xv ovpavos 
 d/x/3arb i i etrj 2 . One story is neither more nor less fabulous than 
 the other. While Moses thus tries to account for the varieties 
 of human speech, neither he nor any of his successors has a 
 clear cause to assign for the diversity of manners and customs 
 and constitutions, which is greater than that of languages. 
 What ueed to go through the particulars : the freedom-loving 
 and insubordinate ways of the German tribes ; the submissive- 
 ness and tameness of the Syrians and Persians and Parthians, 
 and, in a word, of all the barbarians towards the East and the 
 South ? 
 
 How can a God who takes no providential care for human 
 interests like those of legal and political order, and who has 
 sent no teachers or legislators except to the Hebrews, claim 
 reverence or gratitude from those whose good, both mental and 
 physical, he has thus left to chance ? But let us see whether 
 the Creator of the world — be he the same as the God of the 
 Hebrews or not — has so neglected all other men. 
 
 First, however, the point must be insisted on, that it is not 
 sufficient in assigning the cause of a thing to say that God 
 commanded it. The natures of the things that come into 
 existence must be in conformity with the commands of God. 
 
 1 The Gauls and Iberians of course are meant. The Teutonic races had 
 hardly been long enough or extensively enough under the influence of Graeco- 
 lioman culture for their distinctive aptitudes to be noticed, except in warfare. 
 
 - Od. xi. 316. 
 
150 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 If fire is to be borne upwards and earth downwards, fire must 
 be light and earth heavy. Similarly, if there are to be 
 differences of speech and political constitution, they must be 
 in accordance with pre-existing differences of nature. Any one 
 who will look may see how much Germans and Scythians differ 
 in body from Libyans and Aethiopians. Is this also a mere 
 command ? Do not air too and geographical situation act 
 together with the gods to produce a certain complexion ? In 
 reality, the commands of God are either the natures of things 
 or accordant with the natures of things. To suppose these 
 natural diversities all ordered under a divine government 
 appropriate to each, is to have a better opinion of the God 
 announced by Moses, if he is indeed the Lord of all, than that 
 of Hebrew and Christian exclusiveness. 
 
 Julian now turns to the detailed comparison. The admired 
 decalogue, he observes, contains no commandments not recog- 
 nised by all nations, except to have no other gods and to keep 
 the Sabbath Day. For the transgression of the rest, penalties 
 are imposed everywhere, sometimes harsher, sometimes milder, 
 sometimes much the same as those of the Mosaic law. The 
 commandment to worship no other gods has joined with it the 
 slander that God is jealous. The philosophers tell us to imitate 
 the gods as far as possible ; and they say that we can imitate 
 them by contemplating the things that exist and so making 
 ourselves free from passion. But what is the imitation of God 
 celebrated among the Hebrews ? Wrath and anger and savage 
 zeal. Take the instance of Phinehas (Num. xxv. 11), who is 
 represented as turning aside God's wrath by being jealous along 
 with him. 
 
 In proof that God did not care only for the Hebrews, 
 consider the various gifts bestowed on other peoples. Were 
 the beginnings of knowledge given to the chosen race ? The 
 theory of celestial phenomena was brought to completion by 
 the Greeks after the first observations had been made in 
 Babylon. The science of geometry, taking its origin from the 
 art of mensuration in Egypt, grew to its present magnitude. 
 The study of numbers, beginning from the Phoenician mer- 
 chants, at length assumed the form of scientific knowledge 
 
Vlll] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 151 
 
 among the Greeks, who, combining this science with the others, 
 discovered the laws of musical intervals. 
 
 Shall I, the Emperor continues, mention the names of 
 illustrious Greeks as they occur, or bring them under the 
 various heads, — philosophers, generals, artificers, lawgivers ? 
 The hardest and cruellest of the generals will be found 
 dealing more leniently with those who have committed the 
 greatest crimes than Moses with perfectly unoffending people. 
 Other nations have not wanted legislators in sacred things. 
 The Romans, for example, have their Numa, who also delivered 
 his laws under divine inspiration. The spirit from the gods, 
 Julian allows in a digression, comes seldom and to few among 
 men. Hebrew prophecy has ceased ; none remains among the 
 Egyptians ; the indigenous oracles of Greece have yielded to 
 the revolutions of time and are silent. You, he says, turning 
 to the Christians, had no cause to desert us and go over to the 
 Hebrews for any greater gifts they have to boast of from God ; 
 and yet, having done so, you would have done well to adhere to 
 their discipline with exactitude. You would not then have 
 worshipped, not merely one, but many dead men. You would 
 have been under a harsh law with much of the barbarous in it, 
 instead of our mild and human laws, and would have been 
 worse in most things though better as regards religious purity 
 (ayvoTepoi 8e /ecu KaOapwrepoi t<z? aytaTeias). But now you do 
 not even know whether Jesus spoke of purity. You emulate 
 the angry spirit and bitterness of the Jews, overturning temples 
 and altars and slaughtering not only those who remain true to 
 their paternal religion but also the heretics among yourselves 1 . 
 
 1 Cf. Ep. 52, where Julian recalls several massacres of "the so-called 
 heretics" (tuv \eyo/x£vuv aipeTiKuv) in the reign of his predecessor Constantius. 
 Those who are called clerics, he says, are not content with impunity for their 
 past misdeeds ; but craving the lordship they had before, when they could 
 deliver judgments and write wills and appropriate the portions of others, they 
 pull every string of disorder and add fuel to the flames (wavra klvovuiv aKocrfxias 
 k&\wv Kal to \ey6)j.ei>oi> irvp iiri irvp oxerevoven). At the opening of the epistle, he 
 professes to find that he was mistaken in the thought that " the rulers of the 
 Galilaeans " would regard him more favourably than his Arian predecessor, 
 under whom they were banished and imprisoned and had their goods con- 
 fiscated; whereas he himself has repealed their sentences and restored to them 
 their own. 
 
152 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 These things, however, belong to you and not to your teachers. 
 Nowhere did Jesus leave you such commands or Paul. 
 
 To return : the gods gave Rome the empire ; to the Jews 
 they granted only for a short time to be free ; for the most part, 
 they made them alien sojourners and subject to other nations. 
 In war, in civil government, in the fine and useful arts, in the 
 liberal sciences, there is hardly a name to be mentioned among 
 the Hebrews. Solomon, who is celebrated among them for his 
 wisdom, served other gods, deceived by his wife (viro t>}<? 
 <yvvai/c6<;), they say. This, if it were so, would not be a mark 
 of wisdom ; but may he not have paid due honour to the 
 religions of the rest of the world by his own judgment and 
 by the instruction of the God who manifested himself to him ? 
 For envy and jealousy are so far from angels and gods that 
 they do not extend even to the best men, but belong only to 
 the demons. 
 
 If the reading of your own scriptures is sufficient for you, 
 why do you nibble at Greek learning ? Why, having gone over 
 to the Hebrews, do you depart further from what their prophets 
 declare than from our own manners ? The Jewish ritual is very 
 exact, and requires a sacerdotal life and profession to fulfil it. 
 The lawgiver bids you serve only one God, but he adds that 
 you shall " not revile the gods " (Exod. xxii. 28). The brutality 
 of those who came after thought that not serving them ought 
 to be accompanied by blaspheming them. This you have taken 
 from the Jews. From us you have taken the permission to eat 
 of everything. That the earliest Christian converts were much 
 the same as those of to-day is proved by what Paul says of them 
 (1 Cor. vi. 9 — 11). Baptism, of which the Apostle speaks as 
 the remedy, will not even wash off diseases and disfigurements 
 from the body. Will it then remove every kind of transgression 
 out of the soul ? 
 
 The Christians, however, say that, while they differ from the 
 present Jews, they are in strictness Israelites according to the 
 prophets, and agree with Moses and those who followed him. 
 They say, for example, that Moses foretold Christ. But Moses 
 repeatedly declares that one God only is to be honoured. It is 
 true that he mentions angels, and admits many gods in this 
 
Vill] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 153 
 
 sense ; but he allows no second God comparable with the first. 
 The sayings usually quoted by the Christians from Moses and 
 Isaiah have no application to the son of Mary 1 . Moses speaks 
 of augels as the sons of God (Gen. vi. 2) ; Israel is called the 
 firstborn son of God (Exod. iv. 22), and many sons of God 
 (i.e. angels) are recognised as having the nations for their 
 portion ; but nothing is said of a Firstborn Son of God, or #eo<? 
 \6yos, in the sense of the Christian doctrine. 
 
 At this point comes a disquisition on the agreement, in all 
 but a few things, of Hebrew and of Greek religion. According 
 to Cyril, Julian argued that Moses commanded an offering, in 
 the form of the scapegoat (Levit. xvi. 8), to unclean demons 
 (/xtapot? Kal a7rorpo7ratoi<i Satfioai). In not following the 
 general custom of sacrificing, the Christians stand apart from 
 the Jews as well as from all other nations. But the Jews, they 
 will say, do not sacrifice. The reason, however, is that they do 
 not think it lawful for them to sacrifice except at Jerusalem, 
 and that they have been deprived of their temple. And they 
 still keep up customs which are in effect sacrificial, and abstain 
 from some kinds of meat. All this the Christians neglect. 
 That the law in these matters was at some future time to be 
 annulled, there is not the slightest suggestion in the books of 
 Moses. On the contrary, the legislator distinctly declares that 
 it is to be perpetual. 
 
 That Jesus is God neither Paul nor Matthew nor Luke nor 
 Mark ventured to assert. The assertion was first made — not 
 quite distinctly, though there is no doubt about the meaning — 
 by the worthy John, who perceived that a great multitude in 
 many of the Grecian and Italian cities was taken hold of by 
 this malady 2 , and who had heard, as may be supposed, that the 
 
 1 A more exact discussion of them was left over for the second part, to which 
 Cyril's reply has not been preserved. The point is made in passing that any- 
 thing which may be said of a ruler from Judah (Gen. xlix. 10) can have no 
 reference to Jesus, since, according to the Christians, he was not the son of 
 Joseph but of the Holy Spirit. Besides, the genealogies of Matthew and Luke, 
 tracing the descent of Joseph from Judah, are discrepant. 
 
 - What Julian has in view bere is not any and every form of apotbeosis, but, 
 as the context shows, the devotion to corpses and relics, which seemed to him 
 to distinguish the Christians from Jews and Greeks alike. In Ep. 49 he even 
 commends their care about tombs. 
 
154 THE POLEMIC [VIII 
 
 tombs of Peter and Paul were secretly objects of adoration at 
 Rome. In their adoration of tombs and sepulchres, the Chris- 
 tians do not listen to the words of Jesus of Nazareth, who said 
 they were full of all uncleanness (Matth. xxiii. 27). Whence 
 this comes, the prophet Isaiah shall say. It is the old super- 
 stition of those who " remain among the graves, and lodge in 
 the monuments" (Is. lxv. 4), for the purpose of divining by 
 dreams. This art the apostles most likely practised after their 
 master's end, and handed it down to their successors. 
 
 And you, Julian proceeds, who practise things which God 
 abominated from the beginning through Moses and the prophets, 
 yet refuse to offer sacrifices. Thence he returns to the point 
 that, if the Christians would be true Israelites, they ought to 
 follow the Jewish customs, and that these on the whole agree 
 more with the customs of " the Gentiles " than with their own. 
 Approval of animal sacrifices is clearly implied in the account 
 of the offerings of Cain and Abel. Circumcision, which was 
 enjoined on Abraham and his seed for ever, the Christians do 
 not practise, though Christ said that he was not come to destroy 
 the law. " We circumcise our hearts," they say. By all means, 
 replies Julian, for none among you is an evildoer, none is wicked ; 
 thus you circumcise your hearts. Abraham, he goes on to 
 interpret the account in Genesis xv., practised divination by 
 shooting stars (v. 5), and augury from the flight of birds (v. 11). 
 The merit of his faith therefore consisted not in believing 
 without but with a sign of the truth of the promise made to 
 him. Faith without truth is foolishness. 
 
 Incomplete as the reconstruction necessarily remains, there 
 is enough to show the general line the Emperor took. It was 
 to deny any ground, in the Old Testament as it stood, for the 
 idea of Christianity as a universalised Judaism. All else is 
 incidental to this. If then no religion was meant to be universal, 
 but Judaism, in so far as it excludes other religions, is only for 
 Jews, the idea of Christian theocracy loses its credentials. 
 Divine government is not through a special society teaching 
 an authoritative doctrine, but through the order of the visible 
 universe and all the variety of civic and national institutions 
 in the world. The underlying harmony of these is to be sought 
 
VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 155 
 
 out by free examination, which is philosophy. Of philosophy, 
 accordingly, and not of polytheism as such, Julian was the 
 champion. And if the system he opposed did not succeed in 
 finally subjugating the philosophy and culture for which he 
 cared, that was due not to any modification in the aims and 
 ideals of its chiefs, but to the revival of forces which in their 
 turn broke the unity of the cosmopolitan Church as the Church 
 had broken the unity of the Roman State. 
 
CHAPTER IX. 
 
 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL. 
 
 1. The Academy becomes Neo-Platonic. 
 
 About the opening of the fifth century, the chair of Plato 
 was occupied by Plutarch, an Athenian by birth and the first 
 distinguished representative at Athens of Neo-Platonism. By 
 what particular way the Neo-Platonic doctrine had reached 
 Athens is unknown; but Plutarch and the "Platonic successors" 
 (Aiado^ot HXarwviKol) who followed him, connected themselves 
 directly with the school of lamblichus, and through Iamblichus 
 with Porphyry and Plotinus. Their entrance on the new line 
 of thought was to be the beginning of a revival of philosophical 
 and scientific activity which continued till the succession was 
 closed by the edict of Justinian in 529. Strictly, it may be said 
 to have continued a little longer; for the latest works of the 
 school at Athens were written some years after that date. From 
 that year, however, no other teacher was allowed to profess 
 Hellenic philosophy publicly; so that it may with sufficient 
 accuracy be taken as fixing the end of the Academy, and with 
 it of the ancient schools. 
 
 Approximately coincident with the first phase of the revival 
 at Athens, was the brilliant episode of the school at Alexandria, 
 where Neo-Platonism was now taught by Hypatia as its autho- 
 rised exponent. Of her writings nothing remains, though the 
 titles of some mathematical ones are preserved. What is known 
 is that she followed the tradition of Iamblichus, whose doctrines 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 157 
 
 appear in the works of her pupil and correspondent Synesius. 
 Her fate in 415 at the hands of the Alexandrian monks, under 
 the patriarchate of Cyril (as recorded by the ecclesiastical 
 historian Socrates), was not followed immediately by the ces- 
 sation of the Alexandrian chair of philosophy, which indeed 
 continued to have occupants longer than any other. Between 
 415 and 450, Hierocles, the author of the commentary on the 
 Pythagorean Golden Verses, still professed Neo-Platonism. He 
 was a pupil of Plutarch at Athens, but took up the office of 
 teacher at Alexandria, of which he was a native. He too was 
 an adherent of the old religion ; and, for something he had said 
 that was thought disrespectful towards the new, he was sentenced 
 by a Christian magistrate of Constantinople to be scourged 1 . 
 Several more names of Alexandrian commentators are recorded; 
 ending with Olympiodorus in the latter part of the sixth 
 century 2 . All these names, however, — beginning with Hierocles, 
 — belong in reality to the Athenian succession 3 . 
 
 Plutarch died at an advanced age in 431. His successor 
 was Syrianus of Alexandria, who had been his pupil and for 
 some time his associate in the chair. Among the opinions of 
 Plutarch, it is recorded that with Iamblichus he extends 
 immortality to the irrational part of the soul, whereas Proclus 
 and Porphyry limit it to the rational part 4 . A psychological 
 position afterwards developed by Proclus may be noted in his 
 mode of defining the place of imagination (^avracrla) between 
 
 1 See the note, pp. 9 — 10, in Gaisford's edition of the Commentary on the 
 Golden Verses, appended as a second volume to his edition of the Eclogues of 
 Stobaeus (Oxford, 1850). 
 
 - See Zeller, iii. 2, p. 852, n. 1, where it is shown that Olympiodorus the 
 commentator on Plato is identical with the Olympiodorus who wrote (later 
 than 564) the commentary on Aristotle's Meteorology. Olympiodorus the 
 Aristotelian teacher of Proclus at Alexandria is of course much earlier. 
 
 3 In one of his commentaries, Olympiodorus remarks that the succession 
 still continues in spite of the many confiscations (/cai ravra woWQv Srmtvaewv 
 yiPofjLivwf). This, according to Zeller, refers to the succession at Alexandria, 
 not at Athens ; but all the Alexandrian teachers of this last period received 
 their philosophical inspiration, directly or indirectly, from the occupauts of the 
 chair at Athens, and in that way come within the Athenian school. 
 
 4 See the quotation from Olympiodorus given by Zeller, ii. 1, p. 1008, n. 4, 
 where the views of different philosophers on this subject are compactly stated. 
 
158 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 thought and perception 1 . By Plutarch first, and then by 
 Syrian us, the use of Aristotle as an introduction to Plato, with 
 insistence on their agreements rather than on their differences, 
 was made systematic in the school. Most of its activity hence- 
 forth takes the form of exceedingly elaborate critical commen- 
 taries 2 . It is not that originality or the recognition of it 
 altogether ceases. When any philosopher introduces a distinctly 
 new point of view, it is mentioned in his honour by his successors. 
 In the main, however, the effort was towards systematising what 
 had been done. This was the work specially reserved for the 
 untiring activity of Proclus. 
 
 2. Proclus. 
 
 We now come to the last great name among the Neo- 
 Platonists. After Plotinus, Proclus was undoubtedly the most 
 original thinker, as well as the ablest systematiser, of the school. 
 His abilities were early recognised, and the story of an omen 
 that occurred on his arrival at Athens was treasured up. He 
 had lingered outside and arrived at the Acropolis a little late, as 
 his biographer records 3 ; and the porter said to him, " If you 
 had not come, I should have shut the gates." His life was 
 written by his successor in the Academic chair, some time 
 before the decree of Justinian ; so that this anecdote has the 
 interest of showing what the feeling already was in the school 
 about its prospects for the future. 
 
 Proclus (or Proculus) was born at Constantinople in 410, but 
 was of a Lycian family. His father was a jurist ; and he himself 
 studied at Alexandria first rhetoric and Roman law, afterwards 
 
 1 Philop. de An. (Zeller, iii. 2, p. 751, n. 2). tCiv /nev aiad^rCbv to 5i.riprifj.tvov 
 els b> (Tvvadpoi'gei, rb de tQv deluv arrXovv /ecu ws &i> tis eirroi eviKbv els rtiirovs rivas 
 Kai fxop<pas dia<p6povs di'd/xcirreTcu. 
 
 - Plutarch wrote an important commentary on Aristotle's Be Aninia. Be- 
 tween the commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. 200) and that of 
 Plutarch, says Zeller (iii. 2, p. 749, n. 4), none is on record except the 
 paraphrase of Themistius. Syrianus, besides many other commentaries, wrote 
 one on the Metaphysics, portions of which have been published. See Vacherot, 
 Histoire Critique de VEcole d' Alexandria, t. ii. livre iii. ch. 1 ; and Zeller, iii. 2, 
 p. 761, n. 2. 
 
 s Marin us, Vita Prodi, c. 10. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 159 
 
 mathematics and philosophy. Under Olympiodorus, his Alex- 
 andrian teacher, he rapidly acquired proficiency in the 
 Aristotelian logic. Becoming dissatisfied with the philosophical 
 teaching at Alexandria, he went to Athens when he was not 
 quite twenty. There he was instructed both by Syrianus and 
 by Plutarch, who, notwithstanding his great age, was willing to 
 continue his teaching for the sake of a pupil of such promise. 
 At that time Proclus abstained severely from animal food, and 
 Plutarch advised him to eat a little flesh, but without avail ; 
 Syrianus for his part approving of this rigour 1 . His abstinence 
 remained all but complete throughout his life. When he 
 deviated from it, it was only to avoid the appearance of sin- 
 gularity 3 . By his twenty-eighth year he had written his 
 commentary on the Timaeus, in addition to many other 
 treatises. According to Marinus, he exercised influence on 
 public affairs ; but he was once obliged to leave Athens for a 
 year. The school secretly adhered to the ancient religion, the 
 practice of which was of course now illegal. His year's exile 
 Proclus spent in acquiring a more exact knowledge of the ancient 
 religious rites of Lycia 3 . Marinus describes him as an illus- 
 tration of the happiness of the sage in the type of perfection 
 conceived of by Aristotle— for he enjoyed external good fortune 
 and lived to the full period of human life — and as a model of 
 the ascetic virtues' in the ideal form set forth by Plotinus. He 
 was of a temper at once hasty and placable ; and examples are 
 given of his practical sympathy with his friends 4 . Besides his 
 origiuality and critical spirit in philosophy, his proficiency in 
 theurgy is celebrated 5 , and various marvels are related of him. 
 He died at Athens in 485 6 . 
 
 The saying of Proclus has often been quoted from his 
 
 1 Marinus, Vita Prodi, c. 12. 
 
 - Ibid., 19: d 5t irore Kaipos ru foxvpirepos iirl ttjc tovtwv (sc. twv in\pv\^v) 
 Xpyaw e/criXet, jxbvov aireyeveTo, nal tovto ocrlas x°-P lv - 
 
 3 Ibid., 15. 
 
 * Ibid., 17. 5 Ibid., 28. 
 
 6 The dates of his birth and death are fixed by the statement of Marinus 
 (c. 36) that he died, at the age of 75, " in the 121th year from the reign of 
 Julian." This, as Zeller shows (iii. 2, p. 776, n. 1), must be referred to the 
 beginning and not to the end of Julian's reign. 
 
160 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 biography, that the philosopher ought not to observe the 
 religious customs of one city or country only, but to be the 
 common hierophant of the whole world. The closeness, however, 
 with which he anticipated in idea Comte's Religion of Humanity, 
 does not seem to have been noticed. First, we are told that he 
 practised the ceremonial abstinences prescribed for the sacred 
 days of all religions, adding certain special days fixed by the 
 appearance of the moon 1 . In a later chapter, Marinus tells us 
 about his cult of the dead. Every year, on certain days, he 
 visited the tombs of the Attic heroes, then of the philosophers, 
 then of his friends and connexions generally. After performing 
 the customary rites, he went away to the Academy ; where he 
 poured libations first to the souls of his kindred and race, then 
 to those of all philosophers, finally to those of all men. The 
 last observance corresponds precisely to the Positivist " Day of 
 All the Dead," and indeed is described by Marinus almost in 
 the identical words 2 . 
 
 A saying quoted with not less frequency than that referred 
 to above, is the declaration of Proclus that if it were in his 
 power he would withdraw from the knowledge of men for the 
 present all ancient books except the Timaeus and the Sacred 
 Oracles 3 . The reason he gave was that persons coming to them 
 without preparation are injured ; but the manner in which the 
 aspiration was soon to be fulfilled in the Western world 4 suggests 
 that the philosopher had a deeper reason. May he not have 
 
 1 Marinus, 19 : nal IdiKWTepov 5e rivas evr/arevijev rip.e'pas £% ewupaveias. The 
 note in Cousin's edition (Prodi Opera Inedita, Paris, 1864) seems to give the 
 right interpretation : "'E£ e-rrupavdas, ex apparentia, scilicet lunae, ut monet 
 Fabricius et indicant quae sequuntur." Zeller (iii. 2, p. 784, n. 5) refers the 
 observance to special revelations from the gods to Proclus himself. 
 
 2 Ibid., 36 : kclI em train toijtols 6 evayeararos rpirov SXKov Trepiypdxpas tottov, 
 naaais ev avral reus ti2v diroLxop.e'vwv dvdpdnrwv \pv\cus dcpucriovTO. 
 
 "• Ibid., 38: eludei 8e TroWdias ical tovto \eyet.v, tin ' KvpLos el rju, /nova av rQv 
 dpxaiwu dirduTwu /3i/3\t'wi> eirolovv (pepeadai to. Xbyia Kal rbv TifJ.aiov, to. 8£ $\\a 
 rj(pdvi^ov eK tuv vvv dvdpdnruv.' 
 
 4 Corresponding to the Oracles, which Proclus would have kept still current, 
 were of course in the West the Hebrew and Christian Scriptures and the 
 Fathers. Of these he was not thinking ; but, curiously, along with the few 
 compendia of logic and " the liberal arts " which furnished almost the sole 
 elements of European culture for centuries, there was preserved a fragment of 
 the Timaeus in Latin translation. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 161 
 
 seen the necessity of a break in culture if a new line of intel- 
 lectual development was ever to be struck out ? He and his 
 school, indeed, devoted themselves to the task, not of effacing 
 accumulated knowledge for a time, but of storing it up. Still, 
 in the latter part of the period, they must have been consciously 
 preserving it for a dimly foreseen future rather than for the next 
 age. Whatever may have been the intention of the utterance, 
 it did as a matter of fact prefigure the conditions under which 
 a new culture was to be evolved in the West. 
 
 That the Neo-Platonists had in some respects more of 
 Hellenic moderation than Plato has been indicated already; and 
 this may be noted especially in the case of Proclus, who on 
 occasion protests against what is overstrained in the Platonic 
 ethics. His biographer takes care to show that he possessed 
 and exercised the political as a basis for the "cathartic" virtues 1 . 
 And while ascetic and contemplative virtue, in his view as in 
 that of all the school, is higher than practical virtue, its 
 conditions, he points out, are not to be imposed on the active 
 life. Thus he is able to defend Homer's manner of describing 
 his heroes. The soul of Achilles in Hades is rightly represented 
 as still desiring association with the body, because that is the 
 condition for the display of practical virtue. Men living the 
 practical life could not live it strenuously if they were not 
 intensely moved by feelings that have reference to particular 
 persons and things. The heroic character, therefore, while it is 
 apt for great deeds, is also subject to grief. Plato himself would 
 have to be expelled from his own ideal State for the variety of 
 his dramatic imitations. Only in societies falling short of that 
 severe simplicity could lifelike representations of buffoons and 
 men of inferior moral type, such as we meet with in Plato, be 
 allowed. Besides, he varies from one dialogue to another, in 
 the opinions he seems to be conveying, and so himself departs 
 from his ideal. Where Plato then is admitted, there is no 
 reason why Homer too should not be admitted 2 . 
 
 1 Marinus, 14 — 17. 
 
 2 The defence of Homer is to be found in the Commentary on the Republic, 
 which is of special interest for the Neo- Platonic theory of mythology. Cf. 
 Zeller, iii. 2, p. 818, n. 4, for references to the portion of it cited. 
 
 W. 11 
 
162 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [IX 
 
 A large part of the activity of Proclus was given to 
 commenting directly on Plato; but he also wrote mathematical 
 works 1 , philosophical expositions of a more independent kind, 
 and Hymns to the Gods 2 , in which the mythological personages 
 are invoked as representatives of the powers by which the 
 contemplative devotee rises from the realm of birth and change 
 to that of immutable being. Of the philosophical works that 
 do not take the form of commentaries on particular treatises, 
 we possess an extensive one entitled Platonic Theology ; three 
 shorter ones on Providence, Fate, and Evils, preserved only in a 
 Latin translation made in the thirteenth century by William of 
 Morbeka, Archbishop of Corinth ; and the Theological Elements 
 {%roLX€t(oat<i SeoXojiKT]). All these have been published 3 . 
 Of the last, an attempt will be made to set forth the substance. 
 In its groundwork, it is an extremely condensed exposition of 
 the Plotinian doctrine ; but it also contains the most important 
 modifications made in Neo-Platonism by Proclus himself. The 
 whole is in the form of dialectical demonstration, and may 
 perhaps best be compared, as regards method, with Spinoza's 
 expositions of Cartesianism. An abstract of so condensed a 
 treatise cannot of course do justice to its argumentative force, 
 since much must necessarily be omitted that belongs to the 
 logical development; but some idea may be given of the genuine 
 individual power of Proclus as a thinker. A " scholastic " turn 
 of expression, remarked on by the historians, will easily be 
 observed ; but Proclus is not a Scholastic in the sense that 
 he in principle takes any doctrine whatever simply as given 
 from without. 
 
 As a commentator, no doubt his aim is to explain Plato ; 
 and here the critics cannot fairly complain when he says that 
 his object is only to set forth what the master taught. Indeed 
 
 1 See Appendix III. 
 
 2 Seven of these have been preserved. See the end of Cousin's collection. 
 Like Porphyry's De Antro Nympharum, they have a charm of their own for those 
 who are, in Aristotle's phrase, cpikbfxvdoi. 
 
 3 The Platonic Theology does not seem to have been reprinted since 1618, 
 when it appeared along with a Latin translation by Aemilius Portus. The next 
 three works are placed at the beginning of Cousin's collection. The ^roixeicoffcs 
 is printed after the Sententiae of Porphyry in the Didot edition of Plotinus. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 163 
 
 the complaint that he is a "scholastic" in this sense is neu- 
 tralised by the opposite objection that his Platonic Theology 
 contains more of Neo-Platonism than of Plato. And one 
 point of his teaching — not comprised in the treatise now to 
 be expounded — seems to have been generally misunderstood. 
 In more than one place 1 he describes belief (irians) as higher 
 than knowledge (yvwais), because only by belief is that Good 
 to be reached which is the supreme end of aspiration. This 
 has been supposed to be part of a falling away from pure 
 philosophy, though Zeller allows that, after all, the ultimate 
 aim of Proclus "goes as much beyond positive religion as 
 beyond methodical knowing 2 ." And in fact the notion of 
 " belief," as Proclus formulates it, instead of being a resigna- 
 tion of the aims of earlier philosophy, seems rather to be a 
 rendering into more precise subjective terms of Plato's meaning 
 in the passage of the Republic where Socrates gives up the 
 attempt at an adequate account of the Idea of the Good 3 . 
 As Plotinus had adopted for the highest point of his onto- 
 logical system the Platonic position that the Good is beyond 
 even Being 4 , so Proclus formulated a definite principle of 
 cognition agreeing with what Plato indicates as the attitude 
 of the mind when it at last descries the object of its search. 
 At the extreme of pure intellect — at the point, as we might 
 say, which terminates the highest segment of the line re- 
 presenting the kinds of cognition with their objects — is a 
 mode of apprehension which is not even " dialectical," because 
 it is at the very origin of dialectic. And to call this "belief" 
 is to prepare a return from the mysticism of Plotinus — which 
 Proclus, however, does not give up— to the conception of a 
 mental state which, while not strictly cognitive, is a common 
 instead of a peculiar experience. The contradiction between 
 this view and that which makes belief as "opinion" lower 
 than knowledge is only apparent 5 . A view of the kind has 
 
 1 Cf. E. P. 543 ; Zeller, iii. 2, p. 820. 
 
 2 iii. 2, p. 823. 3 Rep. vi. 506. 
 
 4 Rep. vi. 509. 
 
 5 Pico della Mirandola seized the general thought of Proclus on this point, 
 and applied it specially to philosophical theology. See the " Fifty-five Con- 
 clusions according to Proclus" appended to the edition of the Platonic Theology 
 
 11—2 
 
164 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 become more familiar since. Put in the most general terms 
 it is this: that while belief in its sense of opinion is below 
 scientific knowledge, belief as the apprehension of metaphysical 
 principles is above it ; because scientific knowledge, if not at- 
 tached to some metaphysical principle, vanishes under analysis 
 into mere relations of illusory appearances. 
 
 The method of discriminating subordinate triads within 
 each successive stage of emanation, which is regarded as 
 characteristic of Proclus, had been more and more elaborated 
 during the whole interval from Plotinus. The increasing use of 
 it by Porphyry, by Iamblichus, and by their disciple Theodore 
 of Asine, is noted by the historians. Suggestions of the later 
 developments are to be met with in Plotinus himself, who, for 
 example, treats being, though in its essence identical with intel- 
 lect, as prior if distinguished from it, and goes on further to 
 distinguish life, as a third component of primal Being, from 
 being in the special sense and from intellect 1 . This is not indeed 
 the order assigned to the same components by Proclus, who 
 puts life, instead of intellect, in the second place ; but the 
 o-erm of the division is there. A doctrine in which he seems 
 to have been quite original is that of the "divine henads 2 ," 
 to which we shall come in expounding the Elements. For 
 the rest, the originality of many things in the treatise, as well 
 as its general agreement with Plotinus, will become evident 
 as we proceed. 
 
 Every multitude, the treatise begins, participates in a 
 manner in the One. For if in a multitude there were no 
 unity, it would consist either of parts which are nothings, or 
 of parts which are themselves multitudes to infinity. From 
 this starting-point we are led to the position that every multi- 
 tude, being at the same time one and not one, derives its real 
 existence from the One in itself (to avroev). 
 
 already referred to. The words of Pico's forty-fourth proposition are these : 
 " Sicut fides, quae est credulitas, est infra intellectum ; ita fides, quae est 
 vere fides, est supersubstantialiter supra scientiam et intellectum, nos Deo 
 immediate conjungens." 
 
 1 Enn. VI. 6, 8 : to op wpwrov del \a^€?p irpurov ov, efra vovp, elra rb foov. 
 
 - Cf. Zeller, iii. 2, p. 793. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 165 
 
 The producing (to irapdyov), or that which is productive 
 of another (to irapaKriKov dXkov), is better than the nature 
 of that which is produced (/cpeirrov -n}? tov irapayo/xevov 
 (pvaecos). 
 
 The first Good is that after which all beings strive, and is 
 therefore before all beings. To add to it anything else is to 
 lessen it by the addition, making it some particular good 
 instead of the Good simply. 
 
 If there is to be knowledge, there must be an order of 
 causation, and there must be a first in this order. Causes 
 cannot go in a circle : if they did, the same things would be 
 prior and posterior, better and worse. Nor can they go in an 
 infinite series : to refer back one cause to another without a 
 final term would make knowledge impossible 1 . 
 
 Principle and primal cause of all being is the Good. For all 
 things aspire to it ; but if there were anything before it in the 
 order of causes, that and not the Good would be the end of their 
 aspiration. The One simply, and the Good simply, are the 
 same. To be made one is to be preserved in being — which is a 
 good to particular things ; and to cease to be one is to be 
 deprived of being. 
 
 In order that the derivation of motion may not go on in 
 a circle or to infinity, there must be an unmoved, which is 
 the first mover; and a self-moved, which is the first moved ; as 
 well as that which is moved by auother. The self-moved is the 
 mean which joins the extremes 2 . 
 
 Whatever can turn back upon itself, the whole to the whole, 
 is incorporeal. For this turning back is impossible for body, 
 because of the division of its parts, which lie outside one 
 another in space 3 . That which can thus turn back upon itself, 
 
 1 Srcux- OeoX. 11. The order meant here is of course logical, not chrono- 
 logical. All existing things depend on an actual first cause of their being. 
 toTiv curia Trpuorrj twc ovtoiv, d</>' 77s olov ix p'j"??s irpbucriv eKaara, to. /xef eYYt'S oura 
 iKetur/s, ra 6e troppuiTepov. 
 
 2 2t<hx- OeoX. 14. Here again the order is purely logical. There is no 
 notion of a first impulse given to a world that has a chronological beginning. 
 
 3 Ztoix- OeoX. 15 : ovoev dpa <ri2p.a irpbs iavrb iritpvKev iirKTrpicpetv, wj 6\ov 
 iire<rTpa.(pOai. wpbs 6'Xoe. et rt apa irpbs iavrb eiri.<TTpeirri.Kbv eariv, dawp.aTbv £<rri 
 /ecu ap.tp£s. 
 
166 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 has an essence separable from all body. For if it is inseparable 
 in essence, it must still more be inseparable in act ; were it 
 separable only in act, its act would go beyond its essence. That 
 is, it would do what, by definition, is not in its power to 
 do. But body does not actually turn back upon itself. 
 Whatever does thus turu back is therefore separable in essence 
 as in act. 
 
 "Beyond all bodies is the essence of soul, and beyond all 
 souls the intellectual nature, and beyond all intellectual exist- 
 ences the One "\ Intellect is unmoved and the giver of motion, 
 soul self-moving, body moved by another. If the living body 
 moves itself, it is by participation in soul. Similarly, the soul 
 through intellect participates in perpetual thought (/ieTe^et tov 
 del voelv). For if in soul there were perpetual thinking 
 primarily, this would be inherent in all souls, like self-motion. 
 Since not all souls, as such, have this power, there must be 
 before soul the primarily intelligent (to irpooTcos votjtikov). 
 Again, before intellect there must be the One. For intellect, 
 though unmoved, is not one without duality, since it thinks 
 itself; and all things whatsoever participate in the One, but 
 not all things in intellect. 
 
 To every particular causal chain (aeipd ical rd^is), there is 
 a unity (fiovd<i) which is the cause of all that is ordered under 
 it. Thus after the primal One there are henads (ei/aSe?) ; and 
 after the first intellect, minds (i/oes); and after the first soul, 
 souls ; and after the whole of nature, natures. 
 
 First in order is always that which cannot be participated 
 in (to d/xeOe/cTov), — the " one before all " as distinguished from 
 the one in all. This generates the things that are participated 
 in. Inferior to these again are the things that participate, as 
 those that are participated in are inferior to the first. 
 
 The perfect in its kind (to Tekeiov), since in so far as it is 
 perfect it imitates the cause of all, proceeds to the production 
 of as many things as it can ; as the Good causes the existence of 
 everything. The more or the less perfect anything is, of the 
 more or the fewer things is it the cause, as being nearer to or 
 
 1 Stoix- OeoX. 20 : TrdfTuv ffufxarui' iwiKeiva ianv i] i/'i'X^s ovala, ko.1 iraaQv 
 \j/vxu" (Tr^Keiva r\ votpa. (pvais, /cat iracrcov tQv voepwv inrocrT&aewv tTr^Keiva to ev. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 167 
 
 more remote from the cause of all. That which is furthest from 
 the principle is unproductive and the cause of nothing. 
 
 The productive cause of other things remains in itself while 
 producing 1 . That which produces is productive of the things 
 that are second to it, by the perfection and superabundance of 
 its power. For if it gave being to other things through defect 
 and weakness, they would receive their existence through its 
 alteration ; but it remains as it is 2 . 
 
 Every productive cause brings into existence things like 
 itself before things unlike. Equals it cannot produce, since it 
 is necessarily better than its effects. The progression from the 
 cause to its effects is accomplished by resemblance of the things 
 that are second in order to those that are first 3 . Bein^ similar 
 to that which produces it, the immediate product is in a manner 
 at once the same with and other than its cause It remains 
 therefore and goes forth at the same time, and neither element 
 of the process is apart from the other. Every product turns 
 back and tries to reach its cause ; for everything strives after 
 the Good, which is the source of its being ; and the mode of 
 attaining the Good for each thing is through its own proximate 
 cause. The return is accomplished by the resemblance the 
 things that return bear to that which they return to 4 ; for the 
 aim of the return is union, and it is always resemblance that 
 unites. The progression and the return form a circular activity. 
 There are lesser and greater circles according as the return is to 
 things immediately above or to those that are higher. In the 
 great circle to and from the principle of all, all things are 
 involved 5 . 
 
 1 ^.toix- OeoX. 26 : el yap fiinelrai to ev, eKelvo 8e a.Kivr)T<js ixpiaTijo'i to, /xer' 
 avrb, /cat wav to irapayov waatjTOJS £x el T V" T °u irapayeiv airiav. 
 
 " 'Ztolx- OeoX. 27 : ou yap awop.epio~p.bs ecrrt tov irapdyovTos to irapaybpevov ' 
 ovbe yap yevicei tovto wpo-rriKev, ovbe rots yevvqTLKols ai'riois ' ovbe p.e rd/3a<rts " ov 
 yap v\r) yiverai tov irpo'ibvTos ' fxivei yap, olou e'en. Kal to irapaybixevov a\\o irap 1 
 avrb eaTiv. 
 
 3 Ztolx- OeoX. 29 : iracra wpbobos oV oixoiottjtos air oreKe it at tQiv bevTep-cv irpbs to 
 7rpwra. 
 
 4 "Ltolx- OeoX. 32 : ira-ra ein-rTpo-pr) bC bpoLbrr-TOS airoTe\eiTai tuv iirio-Tpe-po- 
 p-evuv, irpbs S €WLO-Tpi<p€Tai, 
 
 5 "Ztoix- OeoX. 33 : irav to wpo'Cbv dirb tlvos Kal einaTpi<pov, kvkKiktjv Zx €i T V" 
 evepyei.av....p.ei^ous be kvkXol Kai eXarrovs tiHv /*ee e-Tt.o~Tpo<p'j)v irpbs to. inrepKeifj.ei>a 
 
168 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [IX 
 
 Accordingly, everything that is caused remains in its own 
 cause, and goes forth from it, and returns to it 1 . The remaining 
 (lJ>ovri) signifies its community with its cause ; the going forth, 
 its distinction from it (afxa yap hiaicpiaei, irpoohos) ; the return, 
 its innate endeavour after its own good, from which its particular 
 being is. Of the things multiplied in progressive production, 
 the first are more perfect than the second, these than the uext, 
 and so forth ; for the " progressions " from cause to effect are 
 remissions of being (vcpecreis) of the second as compared with 
 the first. In the order of return, on the contrary, the things 
 that are most imperfect come first, the most perfect last. Every 
 process of return to a remoter cause is through the same inter- 
 mediate stages as the corresponding causal progression. First 
 in the order of return are the things that have received from 
 their cause only being (to elvcu) ; next, those that have received 
 life with being ; last, those that have received also the power of 
 cognition. The endeavour (ope^t?) of the first to return is a 
 mere fitness for participation in causes 2 ; the endeavour of the 
 second is " vital," and is a motion to the better ; that of the 
 third is identical with conscious knowledge of the goodness of 
 their causes (Kara rrjv yvwaiv, avvala6t]aL<i ovcra rrj<; rcov 
 aiTLoov ayadoTriTos;). 
 
 Between the One without duality, and things that proceed 
 from causes other than themselves, is the self-subsistent (to 
 avdviroaTarov), or that which is the cause of itself. That which 
 is in itself, not as in place, but as the effect in the cause, is self- 
 subsistent. The self-subsistent has the power of turning back 
 upon itself 3 . If it did not thus return, it would not strive after 
 nor attain its own good, and so would not be self-sufficing and 
 perfect ; but this belongs to the self-subsistent if to anything. 
 
 avvexws yivo/j.^vajp, tuv 5e Trpbs ra avwrepu, Kai fxixP 1 - T &v iravruu apxv*- °- wo "yo-P 
 iK(ivy)s iravra, Kai Trpbs eKeivrjv. 
 
 1 2tchx. OeoX. 35 : ttcLv to airiarbu Kai p^evei iv rfj avrov atria, Kai Trpbuaiv <z7r' 
 avrrjs, Kai eiuaTp£<pei Trpbs avrrjv. 
 
 2 2rotx. QeoX. 39 : oixricobr] iroieiTai rrjv enter po<pr)v. That is to say, they 
 tend to be embodied in some definite form, which is their "essence." 
 
 3 Srotx- OeoX. 42 : el yap d.0' eavrou Trpbeiai., Kai rrpi iirtaTpo(pr]v Trotr/nerai Trpbs 
 eavrb. d0' ov yap t) wpbob'os e/cdcrois, els tovto Kai t) rrj Trpobby avaroixos 
 
 llTMJTpOfpT). 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 169 
 
 Conversely, that which has the power of turning back upon 
 itself is self-subsistent. For thus to return, and to attain the 
 end, is to find the source of its perfection, and therefore of its 
 being, within itself. The self-subsistent is ungenerated. For 
 generation is the way from imperfection to the opposite perfec- 
 tion 1 ; but that which produces itself is ever perfect, and needs 
 not completion from another, like things that have birth. The 
 self-subsistent is incorruj)tible, for it never departs from the 
 cause of its preservation, which is itself. It is indivisible and 
 simple. For if divisible, it cannot turn back, the whole to the 
 whole; and if composite, it must be in need of its own elements, 
 of which it consists, and hence not self-sufficing. 
 
 After some propositions on the everlasting or imperishable 
 (ai'8top) and the eternal (alcoviov), and on eternity and time, 
 not specially distinctive of his system, Proclus goes on to a 
 characteristic doctrine of his own, according to which the 
 higher cause — which is also the more general — continues its 
 activity beyond that of the causes that follow it. Thus the 
 causal efficacy of the One extends as far as to Matter, in the 
 production of which the intermediate causes, from intelligible 
 being downwards, have no share. 
 
 That which is produced by the things second in order, the 
 series of propositions begins 2 , is produced in a higher degree by 
 the things that are first in order and of more causal efficacy ; 
 for the things that are second in order are themselves produced 
 by the first, and derive their whole essence and causal efficacy 
 from them. Thus intellect is the cause of all that soul is the 
 cause of; and, where soul has ceased to energise, the intellect 
 that produces it still continues its causal activity. For the 
 inanimate, in so far as it participates in form, has part in 
 intellect and the creative action of intellect". Further, the 
 Good is the cause of all that intellect is the cause of; but not 
 conversely. For privations of form are from the Good, since all 
 
 1 "Ltolx- 0eo\. 45 : /cat yap i] yivtvLS 686s icrnv 4k tou dreXous el$ to ivavrlov 
 riXuov. 
 
 - 'Zrotx- Qeo\. 56. 
 
 3 — toi.x- ©eo\. 57 : /cat yap to a\pvxov, Kadoaov ttdous /xertax^, "ov /uere^et Kal 
 
 TTJS TOU VOV TTOirjOtWS. 
 
170 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 is thence, but intellect, being form, is not the ground of 
 privation 1 . 
 
 The product of more causes is more composite (avvOeroorepov) 
 than the product of fewer. For if every cause gives something 
 to that which proceeds from it, more causes must confer more 
 elements and fewer fewer. Now where there are more elements 
 of the composition, the resultant is said to be more composite ; 
 where there are fewer, less. Hence the simple in essence is 
 either superior to things composite or inferior. For if the 
 extremes of being are produced by fewer concurrent causes and 
 the means by more, the means must be composite while the 
 extremes on both sides are simpler. But that the extremes are 
 produced by fewer causes is evident, since the superior causes 
 both begin to act before the inferior, and in their activity 
 stretch out beyond the point where the activity of the latter 
 ceases through remission of power (Si vcpeatv hvvd/j,e(os). 
 Therefore the last of things, like the first, is most simple, 
 because it proceeds only from the first; but, of these two 
 simplicities, one is above all composition, the other below it. 
 
 Of things that have plurality, that which is nearer the One 
 is less in quantity than the more distant, greater in potency 2 . 
 Consequently there are more corporeal natures than souls, more 
 of these than of minds, more minds than divine henads. 
 
 The more universal (oXtKcorepov) precedes in its causal 
 action the more particular (pcepucooTepov) and continues after 
 it. Thus "being" comes before "living being" (£a>ov), and 
 "living being" before "man," in the causal order as in the 
 order of generality. Again, at a point below the agency of the 
 rational power, where there is no longer " man," there is still 
 a breathing and sentient living being ; and where there is no 
 longer life there is still being. That which comes from the 
 more universal causes is the bearer of that which is communi- 
 cated in the remitting stages of the progression. Matter, 
 which is at the extreme bound, has its subsistence only from 
 the most universal cause, namely, the One. Being the subject 
 
 1 2rotx- OeoX. 57 : vovs 5e areprtaeus viroo-Tar-qs oik ecriv, eI5os tap. 
 
 ' 2 Srwx- Oeo\. 62 : 'ojjloiov yap ry evl fidWov to eyyurepov • rb de Iv tt&vtui> rj» 
 
 inroffTaTiKbv a.Tr\rj6uvTUS. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 171 
 
 of all things, it proceeded from the cause of all 1 . Body in 
 itself, while it is below participation in soul, participates in a 
 manner in being. As the subject of animation (viroKei/xevov 
 tj}? -v/rin^eocreeix?), it has its subsistence from that which is more 
 universal than soul. 
 
 Omitting some auxiliary propositions, we may go on to the 
 doctrine of infinity as formulated by Proclus. In passing, it 
 may be noted that he explicitly demonstrates the proposition 
 that that which can know itself has the power of turning back 
 upon itself. The reason assigned is that in the act of self- 
 knowledge that which knows and that which is known are one. 
 And what is true of the act is true also of the essence 2 . That 
 only the incorporeal has the power of thus turning back upon 
 itself was proved at an earlier stage. 
 
 Infinity in the sense in which it really exists, with Proclus 
 as with Plotinus, means infinite power or potency. That 
 which ever is, is infinite in potency ; for if its power of being 
 (>/ Kara to elvcu Suva/xis) were finite, its being would some 
 time fail 3 . That which ever becomes, has an infinite power of 
 becoming. For if the power is finite, it must cease in infinite 
 time ; and, the power ceasing, the process must cease. The 
 real infinity of that which truly is, is neither of multitude nor 
 of magnitude, but of potency alone 4 . For self-subsistent being 
 (to avdviroo-TaTax; 6v) is indivisible and simple, and is in potency 
 infinite as having most the form of unity (evoeiSeo-TaTov ) ; since 
 the greatest causal power belongs to that which is nearest the 
 One. The infinite in magnitude or multitude, on the other 
 hand, is at once most divided and weakest. Indivisible power 
 is infinite and undivided in the same relation (fcaTa tcivtov) ; 
 the divided powers are in a manner finite (TreTrepaa/xevai 
 7ra)?) by reason of their division. From this sense of the 
 
 1 Ztoix- 6eo\. 72 : r) ftiv yap i/\r>, viroKtiuevov ovo~a tt&vtwv, e'/c tov Trdvrwv 
 alrlov TrporjXOe. 
 
 2 ^.toix- ©eo\. 83 : irav yap to Tip tvtpye.1v irpbs eavrb eTriOTptTCTinbv /cat oiiaiav 
 £x ei irpbs iavTT)v ovvvtvovcrav, koI ev eavrrj ov<ro.v. 
 
 3 Ztoix- ©«o\. 84. 
 
 4 —Toix- OeoX. 86 : ttolv to ovtus ov Tip 6vti dweipbv iffTi, oStc Kara to irXijdos, 
 oure /caret rb fniyeOos, dWct /cara 7-771/ 5vvap.iv ptbvrjv. 
 
172 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 finite, as limited power, is to be distinguished its sense as 
 determinate number, by which it comes nearest to indivisible 
 unity. 
 
 That which is infinite, is infinite neither to the things above 
 it nor to itself, but to the things that are inferior. To these, 
 there is that in it which can by no means be grasped ; it has 
 what exceeds all the unfolding of its powers : but by itself, and 
 still more by the things above it, it is held and defined as a 
 whole 1 . 
 
 We have already met with the position that in a complete 
 causal series the first term is " imparticipable " (afiWeKTov). 
 This means that in no way do the things it produces share it 
 among them. The cause, thus imparticipable or transcendent, 
 remains by itself in detachment from every succeeding stage. 
 In drawing out the consequences of this position, Proclus 
 introduces those intermediate terms which are held to be 
 characteristic of his system. Within the Being or Intellect of 
 the Plotinian Trinity, he constitutes the subordinate triad of 
 being, life and mind. To these discriminated stages he applies 
 his theory that causes descend in efficacy as they descend in 
 generality. The series of things in which mind is immanent 
 is preceded by imparticipable mind ; similarly life and being 
 precede the things that participate in them ; but of these 
 being is before life, life before mind 2 . In the order of 
 dependence, the cause of more things precedes the cause of 
 fewer. Now all things have being that have life, and all 
 things have life that have mind, but not conversely. Hence in 
 the causal order being must come first, then life, then mind. 
 All are in all ; but in each each is present in the manner 
 appropriate to the subsistence of that in which it inheres 3 . 
 
 1 2tcux- ©eo\. 93 : iavrb 5e <jvv£x ov KaX bpifav owe av eavTui aweipov virapxot., 
 ovbe 7roXXy /xaWov rots virepKeip.e'i'ois, /xolpav ^x ou ttjs ev e/eetWs dfreipias- direipb- 
 repai. yap al tQp oXiKurepwv 5vvap.eis, dXiKwrepai oCtrat /cat eyyvrepu TeTO.yp.enai Trfs 
 TrpuTiffTTjs aweiplas. 
 
 2 Ztoix- ©eo\. 101 : iravToiv tQv vov fierexovTUv 7?yetTCU 6 d/xe#e/eTOS vovs, KaX 
 ruv ttjs fwi;s 7/ fay, /cat tuv tov ovtos to 6v ■ avTuv 8e tovtwv to p.ev bv vpb t?}s s'wtJs, 
 i) be far] wpb tov vov. 
 
 3 "Ltoix- Qeo\. 103 : Travra ev vdcnv oliceim 8e ev eK&ffTO}. As for example, ev 
 TV fafi KaTa ptfcl-iv p.ev to elvai, /car' al-Hav 5e to voeiv ' dXXd ja/n/ews itcdrepov ' 
 Kara tovto yap i) iiirap^s. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 173 
 
 All that is immortal is imperishable, but not all that is 
 imperishable is immortal. For that which ever participates 
 in life participates also in being, but not conversely. As 
 being is to life, so is the imperishable, or that which cannot 
 cease to be, to the immortal, or that which cannot cease to 
 live 1 . Since that which is altogether in time is in every 
 respect unlike that which is altogether eternal, there must 
 be something between them ; for the causal progression is 
 always through similars 2 . This mean must be eternal in 
 essence, temporal in act. Generation, which has its essence 
 in time, is attached causally to that which on one side shares 
 in being and on the other in birth, participating at once in 
 eternity and in time ; this, to that which is altogether eternal ; 
 and that which is altogether eternal to being before eternity 
 (et? to ov, to irpoaioovtovy. 
 
 The highest terms of each causal chain (aeipa), and only 
 those, are connected with the unitary principle of the chain 
 next above. Thus only the highest minds are directly attached 
 to a divine unity ; only the most intellectual souls participate 
 in mind ; and only the most perfect corporeal natures have a 
 soul present to them 4 . Above all divine unities is the One, 
 which is God ; as it must be, since it is the Good ; for that 
 beyond which there is nothing, and after which all things strive, 
 is God 5 . But that there must also be many divine unities is 
 evident, since every cause which is a principle takes the lead in 
 a series of multiplied existences descending from itself by degrees 
 of likeness. The self-complete unities {avrorekeh evdhes) or 
 "divine henads," are "the gods," and every god is above being 
 and life and mind G . In all there is participation, except in 
 the One 7 . 
 
 1 2/roix- ©eoX. 105. 
 
 - "Ztoix- OeoX. 100 : ai irpboboi. iracai 5ta tuv oixoiuv. 3 "Ltoix- OeoX. 107. 
 
 4 Zt(»x- OeoX. 111. Cf. 112 : Trdcrr]s Taijews to. irpwTiaTa fxop<prjv Hx €l r ^ v '"'P 
 avTu>v. 
 
 Stoix- OeoX. 113 : ov yap p.rjSiv iariv tiriKeiva, Kal ov irdvra itpUrai, Oebs 
 
 TOVTO. 
 
 6 2toix- OeoX. 115 : 7ras 0edt VTrepovo~i6$ iari Kal virtpfuos Kal inrtpvovs. 
 ' ^.toix- OeoX. 116: Tras debs p.€0£kt6s eon, ttXtjv tov ev6s....d yap to~Tt.v 6.Wrj 
 /xera rb irpLorov d/xideKTOs ivds, ri 8ioio~ei tov cubs ; 
 
174 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 Much has been written upon the question, what the henads 
 of Proclus really mean. Usually the doctrine is treated as an 
 attempt to find a more definite place for polytheism than was 
 marked out in the system of Plotinus. This explanation, 
 however, is obviously inadequate, and there have not been 
 wanting attempts to find in it a more philosophical meaning. 
 Now so far as the origin of the doctrine is concerned, it seems 
 to be a perfectly consequent development from Plotinus. 
 Proclus seeks the cause of plurality in things at a higher 
 stage than the intelligible world, in which Plotinus had been 
 content to find its beginning. Before being and mind are 
 produced, the One acts as it were through many points of 
 origin ; from each of these start many minds ; each of which 
 again is the principle of further differences. As the primal 
 unity is called #eo?, the derivative unities are in correspondence 
 called 6eol. Thus the doctrine is pure deductive metaphysics. 
 There is hardly any indication that in thinking it out Proclus 
 had in view special laws of nature or groups of natural facts 1 . 
 Though not otherwise closely resembling Spinoza's doctrine of 
 the " infinite attributes," it resembles it in this, that it is a 
 metaphysical deduction intended to give logical completeness, 
 where intuitive completeness becomes impossible, to a system 
 of pure conceptual truth. 
 
 From the divine henads, according to Proclus, the provi- 
 dential order of the world directly descends. This position he 
 supports by a fanciful etymology 2 , but deduces essentially from 
 the priority of goodness as characterising the divinity 3 . After 
 goodness come power and knowledge. The divine knowledge is 
 above intellect ; and the providential government of the world 
 is not by a reasoning process (ov Kara Xoyta/xov). By nothing 
 that comes after it can the divinity in itself either be expressed 
 
 1 A slight development on this line is to be met with in §§ 151 — 8, but not 
 such as to affect the general aspect of the doctrine. 
 
 2 Srotx- OeoX. 120: iv Oeois t] vpbvoia Trpuirw ...7) 5e irpbvoia. (ws roijvopa 
 tp:<paivei) ivipyeid iori irpb vov. rqi eTvai dpa 0eol /ecu rf ayaddTTjres elvai wdvruiv 
 Trpovoovffi, irdvTa rrjs irpb vov TrXr/povvres dyad6rr)Tos. 
 
 3 'Etoix- OeoX. 121 : irav rb deiov virapijiv p.tv @x eL T V V dyaddrijra, 5vvap.iv 5e 
 ivialav teal yvuiatv xpticpiov, dXTjirrov irdaiv bp.ov rots devrepots. ...d\X' 17 07rap£is ti2 
 dplcrip x a P aKT VP L fc TCU > xal i] virdo-Tacns Kara rb dpiarov ' tovto 5£ i) dyadbTijs. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 175 
 
 or known. Since, however, it is knowable as henads from the 
 things that participate in them, only the primal One is entirely 
 unknowable, as not being participated in 1 . The divinity knows 
 iudivisibly the things that are divided, and without time the 
 things that are in time, and the things that are not necessary 
 with necessity, and the things that are mutable immutably ; 
 and, in sum, all things better than according to their own 
 order. Its knowledge of the multiple and of things subject to 
 passion is unitary and without passivity. On the other hand, 
 that which is below has to receive the impassible with passive 
 affection, and the timeless under the form of time 2 . 
 
 The order of the divine henads is graduated ; some being 
 more universal, some more particular. The causal efficacy of 
 the former is greater ; of the latter, less. The more particular 
 divine henads are generated from the more universal, neither 
 by division of these nor by alteration, nor yet by manifold 
 relationships, but by the production of secondary progressions 
 through superabundance of power 3 . The divine henad first 
 communicates its power to mind ; through mind, it is present 
 to soul ; and through soul it gives a resonance of its own 
 peculiar nature even to body. Thus body becomes not only 
 animate and intelligential, but also divine, receiving life and 
 motion from soul, indissoluble permanence from mind, divine 
 union from the henad participated in 4 . Not all the other 
 henads together are equal to the primal One 5 . There are as 
 many kinds of beings that participate in the divine henads 
 as there are henads participated in. The more universal henads 
 are participated in by the more universal kinds of beings ; the 
 more particular by the more particular. Thus the order of 
 beings is in precise accordance with the order of the henads. 
 Each being has for its cause not only the henad in which it 
 participates, but, along with that, the primal One G . 
 
 1 Srotx- OeoX. 123 : /x6vov t6 irpQirov iravTt\Qs &yvuxTTot>, are d/xtdetcTov of. 
 - Ztoix- ©eoX. 124. 3 Srotx- ©«>*• 12G - 
 
 * Ztoi X - OeoX. 129. 
 
 5 1.TOLX- OeoX. 133: ov yap ai iraffai tCov 6eu>v inrdp£eis wapiaodfTai tgj hi ' 
 TO(ravTT)v (Ktivo wpbs to tt\t)0os tCjv Oeuv ZXaxef virep^oXrjv. 
 
 6 2iroiX- OeoX. 137 : iraca eVas awvtpiarr^ai ti2 evl to p.eT^x o " o.vttjs ov. 
 
176 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 All the powers of the divinity penetrate even to the terres- 
 trial regions, being excluded by no limits of space from presence 
 to all that is ready for participation 1 . Beside that providence 
 of the gods which is outside and above the order over which it 
 is exercised, there is another, imitating it within the order and 
 exercised over the things that are at a lower stage of remission 
 by those that are higher in the causal series 2 . The gods are 
 present in the same manner to all things, but not all things 
 are present in the same manner to the gods. It is unfitness 
 of the things participating that causes obscuration of the 
 divine presence. Total deprivation of it would mean their 
 complete disappearance into not-being. At each stage of 
 remission, the divinity is present, not only in the manner 
 peculiar to each causal order, but in the manner appropriate 
 to the particular stage. The progressions have the form of a 
 circle; the end being made like the beginning through the 
 return of all things within the order to its principle 3 . 
 
 The whole multitude of the divine henads is finite in 
 number. It is indeed more definitely limited than any other 
 multitude, as being nearest to the One. Infinite multitude, on 
 the other hand, is most remote from the One 4 . There is at the 
 same time, as has been shown, a sense in which all divine things 
 are infinite. That is to say, they are infinite in potency, and 
 unbounded in relation to what is below them 5 . 
 
 The henads participated in by being which is prior to 
 intellect are intelligible (vorjTaL); those that are participated 
 in by intellect itself are intelligential (voepai), as producing 
 intelligence 6 ; those that are participated in by soul are supra- 
 mundane {virepKoajxioi). As soul is attached to intellect, and 
 
 1 Srooc. Qeo\. 140. 2 Srotx- ©eoX. 141. 
 
 3 Ztoix- ©eo\. 146. Cf. 148 : trdcra 8eia rri£is iavry avvrjvwTai rpix&s ' a7r6 re 
 rrjs aKp6rrjTos ttjs eavTrjs kcli diro ttjs nea6rr]TOS, Kal diro tov t{\ovs....ko.I ovtws 6 
 (Tv/xvas 5ia.KO(Tfios eh ecn 5ia ttjs evowoiov tQv irpwTwv 5vvdp.ews, 8td rrjs ei> rrj 
 /xect6t7?ti cvvoxys, did rrjs rod riXovs eis ttjv dpxw T &v irpooduv eTnarpO(prj<;. 
 
 4 Stoix- ©eo\. 149. 
 
 5 Ztoix- Qeo\. 150: t} 5£ direipia Kara ttjv Suva/xiv eKelvoif rb de aireipov 
 dwepiXrjirrov, oh iariv aireipov. 
 
 6 Xtoix- Qeo\. 163 : oi)x oifru voepai, ws iv vQ ixpeo-TTjicviai, d\V tl)5 xar airlav 
 tov vov Trpovirdpxovaai, Kal diroyevvrjcraaai tov vouv. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 177 
 
 intellect turns back upon intelligible being ; so the supramun- 
 dane gods depend on the intelligential, as those again on the 
 intelligible gods 1 . Something also of visible bodies being from 
 the gods, there are also "mundane henads" (iyKoafuoi ivd&es). 
 These are mediated by mind and soul ; which, according as 
 they are more separable from the world and its divided 
 contents, have more resemblance to the imparticipable 2 . 
 
 Having dealt so far with the ontology of intellect, Proclus 
 goes on to formulate the characters of intellectual knowledge. 
 Intellect has itself for the object of its thought 3 . Mind in act 
 knows that it thinks ; and it does not belong to one mind to 
 think an object and to another to think the thought of the 
 object 4 . The thought, the knowledge of the thought, and the 
 cognisance of itself as thinking, are simultaneous activities of 
 one subject. It is the character of mind to think all things 
 together. Imparticipable mind thinks all of them together 
 simply; each mind that follows thinks them all still together, 
 but under the form of the singular 5 . That mind is incorporeal 
 is shown by its turning back upon itself 6 . In accordance with 
 its being, it contains all things intellectually, both those before 
 it and those after it; the former by participation, the latter by 
 containing their causes intellectually 7 . 
 
 Mind constitutes what is after it by thinking; and its 
 creation is in thinking, and its thought in creating 8 . It is 
 first participated in by the things which, although their thought 
 is according to the temporal and not according to the eternal 
 
 1 Stoix- GeoX. 164 : ws ovv \jsvxv iratra els vovv avqpT7)Tai, Kal vovs els to vot)t6v 
 iwio-Tpairrai, outw brj Kal oi inre pKoa/uoi deol twv voepwv e'te'xoPTai, Ka.da.irep drj ko.1 
 
 OVTOl TOOV V07)TWV. 
 
 2 Stoix- GeoX. 166. 3 Stoix- GeoX. 107. 
 
 4 2toix- GeoX. 168 : nds vovs Kar' evepyetav oldev, on voet, Kal ouk a\\ov /j.ev 
 tbiov tI voelv, aXXou 5e rd voelv, on voei. 
 
 5 1.TOIX- GeoX. 170: 7r£s vovs iravra cL/acl voer dXX' 6 p.ev afiideKros airXws iravra, 
 riov 5e per' 1 eKelvov Hkclvtos Kab" eV awavra. Cf. 180. 
 
 6 2>oix- GeoX. 171 : on /xev ovv do-w/xaros 6 poOs, r\ irpbs eavrbv iirto-Tpo<pri StjXoI • 
 twv yap awixdruiv ovbev irpbs eavTO iiriOTptyeTai. 
 
 7 2rotx- GeoX. 173 : to 5e elvai avrov voepbv, Kal to. atria dpa. voepuis ix ei r ^ v 
 iravTwv • wore iravra voepQs e'xet "■** vovs, kcli to. irpb aiiTov, Kal to. tier' avrbv ' u>s 
 ovv to, votito. voepws e'xet ""^ s vovs, ovtu Kal to. alo~dr}Ta voepws. 
 
 8 Zrotx- GeoX. 171 : irds voOs t£ voelv ixpiaTrjaL to. per' avrbv, Kai t\ iroiifots ev 
 to) voelv, Kal r\ vbi)Cis ev ry 7roteiV . 
 
 w. 12 
 
178 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 order, which is timeless, yet have the power of thinking and 
 actually think during the whole of time. That such existences 
 should be interposed before particular souls, is required by the 
 graduated mediation characteristic of every casual progression 1 . 
 Soul that is sometimes thinking and sometimes not, cannot 
 participate without mediation in eternal mind. 
 
 The intellectual forms in mind are both in one another and 
 each for itself without either spatial interval or confusion. 
 This Proclus demonstrates from the nature of indivisible 
 essence. If any one needs an analogy as well as a demon- 
 stration, then, he says, there is the case of the various theorems 
 existing in one soul. The soul draws forth the propositions 
 that constitute its knowledge, not by pulling them apart from 
 one another, but by making separately clear to itself implicit 
 distinctions that already exist 2 . The minds that contain more 
 universal forms are superior in causal efficacy to those that 
 contain more particular forms. The first by forms that are 
 quantitatively less produce more effects ; the second fewer by 
 forms that are quantitatively more. From the second proceed 
 the finer differences of kinds 3 . The products of intellectual 
 forms are imperishable. Kinds that are only for a time do not 
 subsist from a formal or ideal cause of their own ; nor have 
 perishable things, as such, a pre-existent intellectual form 4 . 
 The number of minds is finite 5 . Every mind is a whole ; and 
 each is at once united with other minds and discriminated from 
 them. Imparticipable mind is a whole simply, since it has in 
 itself all the parts under the form of the whole ; of the partial 
 minds each contains the whole as in a part 6 . 
 
 1 2twx. OeoX. 175 : ovbafiov yap ai irpbobot yivovrai d/j.eo~ios, dXXd Sia tu>v 
 auyyevwv /cat bp.o'uov, Kara re ids VTroaTaaeis Kal ras tQv evepyeiQv reXetoT^ras. 
 
 - "Ltoix- OeoX. 176 : iravra yap ei\iKpivu>s 17 ipvxv irpodyei, Kal X W P' S %KaoT0v, 
 [x-qhev e<p£\KOVo~a airb tQv XonrQv, a (el p.rj Sie/ce/cptro del Kara tt)v ?£w) ov8' av tj 
 eve'pyeia Si^Kpive rrjs ipvxvs- 
 
 3 Utoix- OeoX. 177 : odev oi devrepoi vbes reus tQv eldCbv /j.epiKure'pais SiaKplaeaiv 
 eirtbiapdpovai wus Kal Xewrovpyovcri rds tQv irpuiruiv elboirouas. 
 
 4 Zroix- OeoX. 178: irdv voepbv eldos dtbiuv earlv inroaraTLKdv ovre dpa rd 
 
 yevr) rd Kara riva xpbvov a7r' curias v(pe(TTT]Ktv eldrjTiKTjs, ovre rd (pdaprd, 17 (pdaprd, 
 eldos ?x £l voepbv Trpo'virapxov. 
 
 5 Stoix- OeoX. 179. 
 
 6 'Ztoix- OeoX. 180 : dXX' 6 /xev dp.49eKros vovs a7rXws 6'Xos, Cos rd fitprj iravra 
 b\iKws ix wv & v tavTui, tuiv St /j.epiKuii' e/cacrros ws iv /xipei to 6'Xoe exei. Cf. 170. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 179 
 
 The mean between divine imparticipable mind and mind 
 participated in and intelligential but not divine, is divine 
 mind participated in. In this participate divine souls. Of 
 souls there are three kinds : first, those that are divine ; 
 second, those that are not divine but that always participate in 
 intelligible mind ; third, those that change between mind and 
 deprivation of it. Every soul is an incorporeal essence and 
 separable from the body 1 . For since it knows that which is 
 above it, namely, mind and intellectual things in their purity, 
 much more is it the nature of the soul to know itself. Now 
 that which knows itself turns back upon itself. And that 
 which turns back upon itself is neither body nor inseparable 
 from body; for the mere turning back upon itself, of which 
 body is incapable, necessitates separability. Every soul is 
 indestructible and incorruptible. For everything that can in 
 any way be dissolved and destroyed is either corporeal and 
 composite or has its existence in a subject. That which is 
 dissolved undergoes corruption as consisting of a multitude 
 of divisible parts ; that of which it is the nature to exist in 
 another, being separated from its subject vanishes into not- 
 being. But the soul comes under neither of these determina- 
 tions; existent as it is in the act of turning back upon itself. 
 Hence it is indestructible and incorruptible. 
 
 Proclus now goes on to define more exactly the characters of 
 the soul in relation to things prior and posterior to it. It is self- 
 subsistent and is the principle of life to itself and to all that 
 participates in it. As it is a mean between things primarily 
 indivisible and those that have the divisibility belonging to body, 
 so also it is a mean between things wholly eternal and those 
 that are wholly temporal. Eternal in essence and temporal 
 in act, it is the first of things that have part in the world of 
 generation. In the logical order of causes, it comes next after 
 mind, and contains all the intellectual forms that mind possesses 
 primarily. These it has by participation, and as products of 
 the things before it. Things perceptible it anticipates in their 
 pre-formed models {rrapahecyiiaTiKOis;)- Thus it holds the 
 reasons of things material immaterially, and of corporeal 
 
 1 2-roix- ©eo\. 186. 
 
 12—2 
 
180 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 things incorporeally, and of things apart in space without 
 spatially separating them. Things intelligible, on the other 
 hand, it receives in their expression by images (eUoviKw) ; 
 divisibly the forms of those that are undivided, by multipli- 
 cation the forms of those that are unitary, by self-motion the 
 forms of those that are unmoved 1 . 
 
 Every soul participated in has for its first organ an imperish- 
 able body, ungenerated and incorruptible. For if every soul 
 is imperishable in essence and primarily animates something 
 corporeal, then, since its being is immutable, it animates it always. 
 If that which has soul has it always, it also participates ever 
 in the life of soul 2 . But that which is ever living ever is, that 
 is to say, is imperishable 3 . 
 
 All that participates in time yet is perpetually moved, is 
 measured by circuits. For since things are determinate both in 
 multitude and in magnitude, transition cannot go on through 
 different collocations to infinity. On the other hand, the 
 transitions of that which is ever moved can have no term. 
 They must therefore go from the same to the same ; the time 
 of the circuit furnishing the measure of the motion. Every 
 mundane soul, since it passes without limit through transitions 
 of which time is the measure, has circuits of its proper life, and 
 restitutions to its former position 4 . While other souls have 
 some particular time for the measure of their circuit, the circuit 
 of the first soul measured by time coincides with the whole of 
 
 time 5 . 
 
 With greater distance of souls from the One there goes, 
 according to the general principle already set forth, increase of 
 
 1 2-roix- ©eoX. 195. Cf. Arist. De An. iii. 8, 431 b 21 : j\ \pvxh to. ovra irws earn 
 iravra. 
 
 2 Stoix- ©eoX. 196 : el de rovro rb \pvxov/J.evoi> del \J/vxovto.i, Kal del /wt<?x« 
 
 3 The chief propositions on the imperishable vehicle of the soul are to be 
 found near the end of the treatise (207—10). The substance of tbeni is that, in 
 the descent and reascent of the particular soul, extraneous material clothings 
 are in turn put upon the vehicle and stripped off from it ; the vehicle itself 
 remaining impassible. 
 
 4 2toix- OeoX. 199 : waaa yj/vxh ejK6a/xios ireptodois XPV TaL T V* olxeias fays Kal 
 aTTOKa.Ta<jTdcreaii>. . . .Trdcra yap Trepiodos twv dXSitav dwoKaTaiTTaTiKT] e<m. 
 
 5 Srotx- OeoX. 200. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 181 
 
 number and diminution of casual efficacy 1 . Every particular 
 soul may descend to birth infinite times and reascend from 
 birth to being. For it now follows after the divine and now 
 falls away; and such alternation must evidently be recurrent. 
 The soul cannot be an infinite time among the gods, and then 
 the whole succeeding time among bodies; for that which has 
 no temporal beginning can never have an end, and that which 
 has no end necessarily has no beginning 2 . 
 
 Every particular soul, descending to birth, descends as a 
 whole, It does not partly remain above and partly descend. 
 For if part of the soul remains in the intelligible world, it must 
 either think ever without transition, or by a transitive process. 
 But if without transition, then it thinks as pure intellect, and 
 not as a part of the soul ; and so must be the soul immediately 
 participating in mind, that is, the general soul. If it thinks by 
 a transitive process, then, out of that which always thinks and 
 that which sometimes thinks one essence is composed. But 
 this also is impossible. Besides, it is absurd that the highest 
 part of the soul, being, as it is if it does not descend, ever perfect, 
 should not rule the other powers and make them also perfect. 
 Every particular soul therefore descends as a whole 3 . 
 
 3. The End of the Platonic Succession, 
 
 Of the successors to Plato's chair after Proclus, the most 
 noteworthy was Damascius, the last of all. A native of 
 Damascus, he had studied at Alexandria and at Athens. 
 Among his teachers was Marinus, the immediate successor 
 and the biographer of Proclus. The skill in dialectic for 
 which he was celebrated, he himself attributed to the instruc- 
 tions of Isidore, his predecessor in the chair, whose biography 
 he wrote 4 . In an extensive work on First Principles ('ATropicu 
 
 1 Srotx- ©eoX. 203. 
 
 2 Srotx- 0eo\. 206 : Xeiirerai apa vepidSovs iKaar-qv iroieiadai av68wv re in ttjs 
 yev£<TiW ko.1 twv els ytvevLv Kadoduv, teal tovto a.irav<TTOi> dvai dtdrdv aireipov XP 0V0V • 
 eK&arr) apa ^I'X?? P-epiKV KaTievai re eV direipov dvvarai ko.1 aviivai. /cat tovto ov p.r) 
 iravatTai T€pl airdaas rb irddijfJ.a yevd/xevou. 
 
 3 Sroix- 0«oX. 211. 
 
 4 The fragments of this, preserved by Photius, are printed in the appendix to 
 the Didot edition of Diogenes Laertius. 
 
182 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 /cai XvaeLs nepl twv Trpo&rwv ap-^oov) 1 , he maintained with the 
 utmost elaboration that the principle of things is unknowable. 
 This we have met with as a general position in Proclus 2 ; and 
 it is already laid down distinctly by Plotinus, who says for 
 example that we can learn by intellect that the One is, but not 
 what it is. Even to call it the One is rather to deny of it 
 plurality than to assert any truth regarding it that can be 
 grasped by the intelligence 3 . Still, with Plotinus and Proclus, 
 this is more a recognition of the inadequacy of all forms of 
 thought to convey true knowledge of the principle which is the 
 source of thought, than a doctrine standing out by itself as the 
 last word of their philosophy. Damascius on the other hand 
 seems to exhaust human language in the effort to make plain 
 how absolutely unknowable the principle is 4 . Thus his doctrine 
 has the effect of a new departure, and presents itself as the 
 most definitely agnostic phase of ancient metaphysics. Zeller 
 treats this renunciation of all knowledge of the principle as a 
 symptom of the exhaustion of Greek philosophy ; a view which 
 perhaps, at certain points of time, would not have allowed us 
 to hope much more from modern philosophy. The ancient 
 schools, however, did not die till a final blow was struck at 
 them on behalf of the spiritual authority that now ruled the 
 world. 
 
 It may be read in Gibbon how the Emperor Justinian 
 (527 — 565), while he directed the codification of the Roman 
 law, succeeded in effacing in considerable measure the record 
 of stages of jurisprudence less conformable to the later imperial 
 absolutism. To make that absolutism unbroken even in name, 
 he afterwards suppressed the Roman Consulship, which had 
 
 1 About half of this work was edited by Kopp in 1826 ; the whole by Ruelle 
 in 1889. In 1898 was published a complete French translation by M. Chaignet 
 in three volumes. 
 
 '<■ 2toi X - ©eo\. 123. 
 
 3 Enn. v. 5, 6 : to 5e olov arjixaivoi. av to oi>x olov ' ov yap Hvi ovde to olov, otoi 
 
 ^Se to tI Taxa Se /ecu to £v 6vop.a tovto apo~iv ex ei Tpos to. woWti, bdev /ecu 
 
 'Av6\\uva ot YlvdayopiKol avp.(3o\iKu>s irpbs a\\ri\ovs eo~r)p.aivov airocpaaei twv 
 ttoXXQv. 
 
 4 Cf. R. P. 545 : ko.1 tI -n-ipas ^crrat tov \6yov ttXtjv criyrjs 6.p.rjxd.vov Kol 6p,o\oylas 
 tov p.7]deu yivwaKeiv w pLTjde de/xis, ddwaTWi/ ovtwv eh yvwcnv eXdeiv ; 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 183 
 
 gone on till his time. Before the completion of his Code — the 
 great positive achievement to which he owes his fame — he had 
 already promulgated a decree for securing uniformity in the 
 spiritual sphere. So far, in spite of the formal prohibition of 
 the ancient religion, the philosophers at Athens had retained 
 some freedom to oppose Christian positions on speculative 
 questions. This seems clear from the fact that Proclus had 
 been able to issue a tractate in which he set forth the arguments 
 for the perpetuity of the world against the Christian doctrine of 
 creation 1 . Justinian, who was desirous of a reputation for 
 strictness of orthodoxy, resolved that even this freedom should 
 cease; and in 529 he enacted that henceforth no one should 
 teach the ancient philosophy. In the previous year, when 
 there was a " great persecution of the Greeks " (that is, of all 
 who showed attachment to the ancient religion), it had been 
 made a law that those who " Hellenised " should be incapable 
 of holding offices. Suppression of the philosophical lectures 
 was accompanied by confiscation of the endowments of the 
 school. And these were private endowments ; the public 
 payments to the occupants of the chairs having long ceased 2 . 
 The liberty of philosophising was now everywhere brought 
 within the limits prescribed by the Christian Church. Not 
 till the dawn of modern Europe was a larger freedom to be 
 reassumed ; and not even then without peril. 
 
 The narrative of the historian Agathias (fl. 570) is well 
 known, how Damascius, Simplicius, Eulalius, Priscianus, Her- 
 mias, Diogenes and Isidorus departed from Athens for Persia, 
 having been invited by King Chosroes (Khosru Nushirvan), 
 and hoping to find in the East an ideal kingdom and a 
 philosophic king 3 . Though Chosroes himself was not without 
 a real interest in philosophy, as he showed by the translations 
 he caused to be made of Platonic and Aristotelian writings, 
 their expectations were thoroughly disappointed. They found 
 
 1 A reply to the 'ETnx«-py/J-a- T a Kara. XpicrTiavwv of Proclus was written by 
 Joannes Philoponus, in the form of a lengthy work (now included in the Teubner 
 Series) bearing the title I)e Aeternitate Mundi. 
 
 2 See, for the evidence as to the exact circumstances of the suppression, 
 Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 849—50, with notes. Of. R. P. 547 c. 
 
 ;i P. P. 547. 
 
184 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX 
 
 that the genuine unmodified East was worse than the Roman 
 Empire in its decline. At length they entreated to return to 
 their own country under any conditions ; and Chosroes, though 
 pressing them to stay, not only allowed them to go, but in a 
 special clause of a treaty of peace with Justinian, stipulated 
 that they should not be constrained to forsake their own 
 opinions, but should retain their freedom while they lived. 
 This was in 533. The date of their voluntary exile was 
 probably 532. 
 
 After their return, as has been already indicated, the 
 philosophers devoted themselves to the writing of learned 
 commentaries. The most illustrious of the commentators was 
 Simplicius, whose works on Aristotle's Categories, Physics, Be 
 Caelo and De Anima, and on the Encheiridion of Epictetus, 
 are extant. Even this last period was not marked by complete 
 inability to enter on a new path. What the speculative 
 exhaustion animadverted on by Zeller really led to was a return 
 to the most positive kind of knowledge that then seemed attain- 
 able. Aristotle now came to be studied with renewed zeal ; 
 and it was in fact by a tradition from the very close of antiquity 
 that he afterwards acquired his predominant authority, first 
 among the Arabians and then among the schoolmen of the 
 West 1 . The last Neo-Platonists thus had the merit of compre- 
 hending his unapproached greatness as the master in antiquity 
 of all human and natural knowledge. If to some extent they 
 were wrong in trying to prove his thoroughgoing agreement 
 with Plato, their view was at any rate nearer the mark than 
 that which makes the two philosophers types of opposition. 
 The most recent students of Plato would perfectly agree with 
 one at least of the distinctions by which Simplicius reconciles 
 apparently conflicting positions. When Plato, he says, describes 
 the world as having come to be, he means that it proceeds from 
 a higher cause ; when Aristotle describes it as not having 
 become, he means that it has no beginning in time 2 . Apart 
 from learned research, subtleties may still be found in the 
 commentators that had never before been expressed with such 
 
 1 Cf. Kenan, Averroes et VAverroisme, pp. 92 — 3. 
 
 2 Zeller, iii. 2, p. 84(3. Cf. Archer-Hind, The Timaeus of Plato. 
 
IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 185 
 
 precision. For the rest, they are themselves as conscious of 
 the decline as their modern critics. What they actually did 
 was in truth all that was possible, and the very thing that was 
 needed, in their own age. 
 
 To the latest period, as was said at the beginning of the 
 chapter, belong the names of several Alexandrian teachers. 
 Among these are Hermias, the pupil of Syrianus ; Ammonius, 
 the son of Hermias and the pupil of Proclus 1 ; Asclepiodotus, 
 a physician, who, according to Damascius, surpassed all his 
 contemporaries in knowledge of mathematics and natural 
 science ; and Olympiodorus, a pupil of Ammonius and the last 
 teacher of the Platonic philosophy whose name has been 
 preserved. Commentaries by Hermias and Ammonius, as well 
 as by Olympiodorus, are still extant. 
 
 An exhaustive history of Neo-Platonism would find in the 
 writings of the Athenian school materials especially abundant. 
 Much has been printed, though many works still remain un- 
 published. In the present chapter, only a very general account 
 is attempted. The object, here as elsewhere, has been to bring 
 out the essential originality of the Neo-Platonic movement ; 
 not to trace minutely the various currents that contributed to 
 its formation and those into which it afterwards diverged as it 
 passed into later systems of culture. To follow, " per incertam 
 lunam sub luce maligna," the exact ways by which it modified 
 the culture of mediaeval Europe, would be a work of research 
 for a separate volume. The general direction, however, and its 
 principal stages, are sufficiently clear ; and some attempt will 
 be made in the next chapter to trace first the continued 
 influence of Neo-Platonism in the Middle Ages, and then its 
 renewed influence at the Renaissance and in modern times. 
 For the earliest period — for the unmistakably "dark ages" of 
 the West — the transmission was in great part through Christian 
 writers, who, living at the close of the ancient world, had 
 received instruction as pupils in the still surviving philosophic 
 schools. 
 
 1 Joannes Philoponus (11. 530), the Christian commentator on Aristotle, had 
 Ammonius for his teacher, and quotes him as " the philosopher." See Zeller, 
 iii. 2, p. 829, n. 4. 
 
CHAPTER X. 
 
 THE INFLUENCE OF NEO-PLATONISM. 
 
 The influence of Neo-Platonism on the official Christian 
 philosophy of the succeeding period was mainly in the de- 
 partment of psychology. Biblical psychology by itself did 
 not of course fix any determinate scientific view. Its literal 
 interpretation might seem, if anything, favourable to a kind 
 of materialism combined with supernaturalism, like that of 
 Tertullian. Even the Pauline conception of " spirit," regarded 
 at once as an infusion of Deity and as the highest part of the 
 human soul, lent itself quite easily to a doctrine like that of 
 the Stoics, which identified the divine principle in the world 
 with the corporeal element most remote by its lightness and 
 mobility from gross matter. For a system, however, that was 
 to claim on behalf of its supernatural dogmas a certain justi- 
 fication by human reason as a preliminary condition to their 
 full reception by faith, the idea of purely immaterial soul and 
 mind was evidently better adapted. This conception, taken 
 over for the practical purposes of the Church in the scientific 
 form given to it by the Neo-Platonists, has accordingly main-, 
 tained its ground ever since. The occasional attempts in 
 modern times by sincerely orthodox Christians to fall back 
 upon an exclusive belief in the resurrection of the body, 
 interpreted in a materialistic sense, as against the heathen 
 doctrine of the natural immortality of the soul, have never 
 gained any appreciable following. At the end of the ancient 
 
X] THE INFLUENCE OF NEO-PLATONISM 187 
 
 world Platonic idealism, so far as it was compatible with the 
 dualism necessitated by certain portions of the dogmatic 
 system, was decisively adopted. In the East, Greek ecclesias- 
 tical writers such as Nemesius (fl. 450), who had derived 
 their culture from Neo-Platonism, transmitted its refutations 
 of materialism to the next age. In the West, St Augustine, 
 who, as is known, was profoundly influenced by Platonism, and 
 who had read Plotinus in a Latin translation, performed the 
 same philosophical service. The great positive result was to 
 familiarise the European mind with the elements of certain 
 metaphysical conceptions elaborated by the latest school of 
 independent philosophy. When the time came for renewed 
 independence, long practice with abstractions had made it 
 easier than it had ever hitherto been — difficult as it still 
 was — to set out in the pursuit of philosophic truth from a 
 primarily subjective point of view. 
 
 It was long, however, before Western Europe could even 
 begin to fashion for itself new instruments by provisionally 
 working within the prescribed circle of revealed dogma and 
 subordinated philosophy. The very beginning of Scholasticism 
 is divided by a gulf of more than three centuries from the end 
 of Neo-Platonism ; and not for about two centuries more did 
 this lead to any continuous intellectual movement. In the 
 meantime, the elements of culture that remained had been 
 transmitted by Neo-Platonists or writers influenced by them. 
 An especially important position in this respect is held by 
 Boethius, who was born at Rome about 480, was Consul in 510, 
 and was executed by order of Theodoric in 524. In philosophy 
 Boethius represents an eclectic Neo-Platonism turned to ethical 
 account. His translation of Porphyry's logical work has already 
 been mentioned. He also devoted works of his own to the 
 exposition of Aristotle's logic. It was when he had fallen into 
 disgrace with Theodoric that he wrote the Be Consolation 1 
 Plrilosophiae ; and the remarkable fact has often been noticed 
 that, although certainly a nominal Christian, he turned in 
 adversity wholly to heathen philosophy, not making the 
 slightest allusion anywhere to the Christian revelation. The 
 vogue of the Be Consolatione in the Middle Ages is equally 
 
188 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 noteworthy. Rulers like Alfred, eagerly desirous of spreading 
 all the light that was accessible, seem to have been drawn 
 by a secret instinct to the work of a man of kindred race, who, 
 though at the extreme bound, had still been in living contact 
 with the indigenous culture of the old European world. Another 
 work much read in the same period was the commentary of 
 Macrobius (fl. 400) on the Somnium Scipionis extracted from 
 Cicero's Be Republica. Macrobius seems not to have been 
 even a nominal Christian. He quotes Neo-Platonist writers, and, 
 by the impress he has received from their type of thinking, 
 furnishes evidence of the knowledge there was of them in 
 the West. 
 
 In the East some influence on theological metaphysics was 
 exercised by Synesius, the friend of Hypatia. Having become 
 a Christian, Synesius unwillingly allowed himself to be made 
 Bishop of Ptolemais (about 410); seeking to reserve the 
 philosophical liberty to treat portions of popular Christianity 
 as mythical, but not quite convinced that this was compatible 
 with the episcopal office. A deeper influence of the same kind, 
 extending to the West, came from the works of the writer 
 known under the name of that " Dionysius the Areopagite " 
 who is mentioned among the converts of St Paul at Athens 
 (Acts xvii. 34). As no incontestable reference to those works 
 is found till the sixth century, and as they are characterised by 
 ideas distinctive of the school of Proclus, it is now held that 
 they proceeded from some Christian Platonist trained in the 
 Athenian school. It is possible indeed that the real Dionysius 
 had been a hearer of Proclus himself. We learn from Marin us 1 
 that not all who attended his lectures were his philosophical 
 disciples. The influence of the series of works, in so far as 
 they were accepted officially, was to fix the "angelology" of 
 the Church in a learned form. They also gave a powerful 
 impulse to Christian mysticism, and, through Scotus Erigena, 
 set going the pantheistic speculations which, as soon as thought 
 once more awoke, began to trouble the faith. 
 
 When, about the middle of the ninth century, there emerges 
 
 1 Vita Prodi, 38. 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 189 
 
 the isolated figure of John Scotus Erigena, we may say, far as 
 we still are from anything that can be called sunrise, that 
 
 "now at last the sacred influence 
 Of light appears, and from the walls of Heaven 
 Shoots far into the bosom of dim Night 
 A glimmering dawn." 
 
 He has been regarded both as a belated Neo-Platonist and as 
 the first of the Scholastics. In reality he cannot be classed as 
 a Neo-Platonist, for his whole effort was directed towards 
 rationalising that system of dogmatic belief which the Neo- 
 Platonists had opposed from the profouudest intellectual and 
 ethical antipathy. On the other hand, he was deeply influenced 
 by the forms of Neo-Platonic thought transmitted through 
 Dionysius, whose works he translated into Latin ; and his own 
 speculations soon excited the suspicion of ecclesiastical authority. 
 His greatest work, the De Divisione Naturae, was in 1225 con- 
 demned by Pope Honorius III. to be burned. Scotus had, 
 however, begun the characteristic movement of Christian 
 Scholasticism. And Dionysius, who could not well be anathe- 
 matised consistently with the accredited view about the 
 authorship of his writings — who indeed was canonised, and 
 came to be identified with St Denys of France — had been 
 made current in Latin just at the moment when the knowledge 
 of Greek had all but vanished from the West. 
 
 The first period of Scholasticism presents a great gap 
 between Scotus and the next considerable thinkers, who do 
 not appear before the latter part of the eleventh century. 
 Towards the end of the twelfth century, the second period 
 begins through the influx of new Aristotelian writings and 
 of the commentaries upon them by the Arabians. The Arabians 
 themselves, on settling down after their conquest of Western 
 Asia, had found Aristotle already translated into Syriac. Trans- 
 lations were made from Syriac into Arabic. These translations 
 and the Arabian commentaries on them were now translated 
 into Latin, sometimes through Hebrew; the Jews being at this 
 time again the great intermediaries between Asia and Europe. 
 Not long after, translations were made directly from the Greek 
 
190 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 texts preserved at Constantinople. Thus Western Europe 
 acquired the complete body of Aristotle's logical writings, of 
 which it had hitherto only possessed a part ; and, for the first 
 time since its faint re-awakening to intellectual life, it was put 
 in possession of the works dealing with the content as well as 
 the form of philosophy. After prohibiting more than once the 
 reading of the newly recovered writings, and in particular of 
 the Physics and Metaphysics, the ecclesiastical chiefs at length 
 authorised them; having come to see in the theism of Aristotle, 
 which they were now able to discriminate from the pantheism of 
 pseudo-Aristotelian writings, a preparation for the faith. It is 
 from this period that the predominating scientific authority of 
 Aristotle in the Christian schools must be dated. Taken over 
 as a tradition from the Arabians, it had been by them received 
 from the latest commentators of the Athenian school of Neo- 
 Platonism. 
 
 The Arabian philosophy, highly interesting in itself, is still 
 more interesting to us for its effect on the intellectual life of 
 Europe. Aristotelian in basis, it was Neo-Platonic in super- 
 structure. Its distinctive doctrine of an impersonal immortality 
 of the general human intellect is, however, as contrasted both 
 with Aristotelianism and with Neo-Platon ism, essentially original. 
 This originality it does not owe to Mohammedanism. Its affinity 
 is rather with Persian and Indian mysticism. Not that 
 Mohammedanism wanted a speculative life of its own ; but that 
 which is known to history as " Arabian philosophy " did not 
 belong to that life 1 . The proper intellectual life of Islam was 
 in "theology." From the sharp antagonism which sprang up 
 between the Arabian philosophers and " theologians " seems to 
 date the antithesis which became current especially in the 
 Europe of the Renaissance. For the Greek philosophers, 
 " theology " had meant first a poetic exposition of myths, but 
 with the implication that they contained, either directly or when 
 allegorised, some theory of the origin of things. Sometimes — 
 as occasionally in Aristotle and oftener in the Neo-Platonists — 
 it meant the highest, or metaphysical, part of philosophy. It 
 
 1 See Eenan, Averroes et VAverrolsme, ch. ii. 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 191 
 
 was the doctrine of God as first principle of things, and was 
 accordingly the expression of pure speculative reason. With 
 Islam, as with Christianity, it might mean this ; but it meant 
 also a traditional creed imposed by the authority of Church and 
 State. The creed contained many articles which philosophy 
 might or might not arrive at by the free exercise of reason. 
 To the Mohammedan "theologian," however, these were not 
 points which it was permissible to question, except hypotheti- 
 cally, but principles to argue from. Hence the "philosophers," 
 having made acquaintance with the intellectual liberty of Greece, 
 which they were seeking to naturalise in Arabian science, were 
 led to adopt the custom of describing distinctively as a "theo- 
 logian " one who speculated under external authority and with 
 a practical purpose. Of course the philosophers claimed to 
 deal equally — or, rather, at a higher level — with divine objects 
 of speculation ; but, according to their own view, they were not 
 bound by the definitions of the theologian. At the same time, 
 they were to defer to theology in popular modes of speech, 
 allowing a "theological" truth, or truth reduced to what the 
 multitude could profit by, in distinction from" philosophical" 
 or pure truth. The Jews and the Christians too, they allowed, 
 were in possession of theological truth ; each religion being 
 good and sufficient in practice for the peoples with whom it 
 was traditional. The reason of this procedure — which has no 
 precise analogue either in ancient or in modern times — was that 
 the Arabian Hellenising movement was pantheistic, while the 
 three religious known to the philosophers all held to the 
 personality of God. Hence the Arabian philosophy could not, 
 like later Deism, find what it regarded as philosophic truth by 
 denuding all three religions of their discrepant elements. Since 
 they were expressed in rigorously defined creeds, it could not 
 allegorise them as the ancient philosophers had allegorised 
 polytheism. Nor was the method open to it of ostensibly 
 founding a new sect. The dominant religions were theocratic, 
 claiming the right, which was also the duty, of persecution. 
 The consequence was, formulation of the strange doctrine 
 known as that of the " double truth." 
 
 Under the dominion of Islam, the "philosophers," in spite of 
 
192 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 their distinction between the two kinds of truth, were treated 
 by the " theologians " as a hostile sect and reduced to silence. 
 Their distinction, however, penetrated to Christian Europe, 
 where, though condemned by Church Councils, it long held its 
 ground as a defence against accusations of heresy. The ortho- 
 dox distinction between two spheres of truth, to be investigated 
 by different methods but ultimately not in contradiction, may 
 easily be put in its place. Hence a certain elusiveness which 
 no doubt helped to give it vogue in a society not inwardly 
 quite submissive to the authority of the Church even at the 
 time when the theocracy had apparently crushed all secular 
 and intellectual opposition. The profundity of the revolt is 
 evident alike in the philosophical and in the religious move- 
 ments that marked the close of the twelfth and the opening 
 of the thirteenth century. The ideas that animated both 
 movements were of singular audacity. In philosophy, the 
 intellectual abstractions of Neo-Platonism, and in particular 
 the abstraction of " matter," were made the ground for a 
 revived naturalistic pantheism. Ideas of " absorption," or im- 
 personal immortality, genuinely Eastern in spirit, may have 
 appealed as speculations to the contemplative ascetics of 
 Orientalised Europe. These were not the only ideas that 
 came to the surface. In common with its dogmas, the Catholic 
 hierarchy was threatened ; and, to suppress the uprising, the 
 City of Dis on earth was completed by the Dominican 
 Inquisition. Yet philosophy, so far as it could be made sub- 
 servient to orthodoxy, was to be a most important element in 
 the training of the Dominicans themselves. From their Order 
 proceeded Thomas Aquinas, the most systematic thinker of 
 the Middle Ages, at whose hands scholastic Aristotelianism 
 received its consummate perfection. Against older heresies, 
 against " Averroism," against the pantheism of heterodox 
 schoolmen, the Angelic Doctor furnished arguments acceptable 
 to orthodoxy, marshalled in syllogistic array. For a short 
 time, his system could intellectually satisfy minds of the 
 highest power, skilled in all the learning of their age, if only 
 they were in feeling at one with the dominant faith. 
 
 Over and above its indirect influence through the psy- 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 1 !>3 
 
 chology of the Fathers, Neo-Platonic thought found direct 
 admission into the orthodox no less than into the heterodox 
 speculation of the Scholastic period. Aquinas quotes largely 
 from Dionysius; and Dante was, as is well known, a student 
 both of Aquinas and of Dionysius himself, whose classification 
 of the " Heavenly Hierarchy " he regarded as a direct revelation 
 communicated by St Paul to his Athenian proselyte. Thus, if 
 we find Neo-Platonic ideas in Dante, there is no difficulty about 
 their source. The line of derivation goes straight back to the 
 teaching of Proclus. We are not reduced to the supposition 
 of an indirect influence from Plotinus through St Augustine. 
 Incidental Neo-Platonic expressions in Dante have not escaped 
 notice 1 . More interesting, however, than any detailed coinci- 
 dence is the fundamental identity of the poet's conception of 
 the beatific vision with the vision of the intelligible world as 
 figured by Plotinus. Almost equally prominent is the use he 
 makes of the speculative conception of emanation. That the 
 higher cause remains in itself while producing that which is 
 next to it in order of being, is affirmed by Dante in terms that 
 might have come directly from Plotinus or Proclus 2 . And it 
 is essentially by the idea of emanation that he explains and 
 justifies the varying degrees of perfection in created things. 
 
 The Neo-Platonism of the Divina Commedia, as might be 
 expected, is found almost exclusively in the Paradiso ; though 
 one well-known passage in the Purgatorio, describing the mode 
 in which the disembodied soul shapes for itself a new material 
 envelope, bears obvious marks of the same influence. Here, 
 however, there is an important difference. Dante renders 
 
 1 Some of them are referred to by Bouillet in the notes to his French 
 translation of the Enneads (1857 — 61). 
 
 Here, for want of a more appropriate place, it may be mentioned that there 
 is no complete translation of the Enneads into English. The marvellous 
 industry of Thomas Taylor, "the Platonist," in translating Neo-Platonic 
 writings, did not carry him through the whole of Plotinus. The portions 
 translated by him have been reprinted for the Theosophical Society in Bonn's 
 Series. 
 
 2 Tbe general thought finds expression at the end of Par. xxix. 
 
 " 1' eterno Valor... 
 Uno manendo in se come davanti." 
 
 w. 13 
 
194 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 everything in terms of extension, and never, like the Neo- 
 Platonists, arrives at the direct assertion, without symbol, of 
 pure immaterialism. This may be seen in the passage just 
 referred to, as compared with a passage from Porphyry's 
 exposition of Plotinus closely resembling it in thought. While 
 Dante represents the soul as having an actual path from one 
 point of space to another, Porphyry distinctly says that the 
 soul's essence has no locality, but only takes upon itself 
 relations depending on conformity between its dispositions and 
 those of a particular body ; the body, whether of grosser or of 
 finer matter, undergoing local movement in accordance with its 
 own nature and not with the nature of soul 1 . Again, the point 
 of exact coincidence between Dante and Plotinus in what they 
 say of the communications between souls that are in the world 
 of being, is that, for both alike, every soul "there" knows the 
 thought of every other without need of speech. Plotinus, 
 however, says explicitly that the individualised intelligences 
 within universal mind are together yet discriminated without 
 any reference to space. What Dante says is that while the 
 souls are not really in the planetary spheres, but only appear 
 in them momentarily, they are really above in the empyrean. 
 Even in his representation of the Deity, the Christian poet still 
 retains his spatial symbolism. God is seen as the minutest and 
 intensest point of light, round which the angels— who are the 
 movers of the spheres — revolve in their ninefold order. At the 
 same time, the divine mind is said to be the place of the 
 primum mobile, thus enclosing the whole universe 2 . Viewed in 
 relation to the universe as distinguished from its cause, the 
 angelic movers are in inverted order, the outermost and not the 
 innermost being now the highest. Thus, by symbol, it is finally 
 
 1 Cf. Purg. xxv. 85 — 102 and Sententiae, 32. Porphyry is explaining the 
 way in which the soul may be said to descend to Hades, eVet 5e 5t??/cet to fiapv 
 irvevfxa /cat 'ivvypov dxpL tQiv inroyeitcv tottujv, ovtu /cat avTt] A^yerat xwptiv vtto yr/v ■ 
 ov\otl ij avrr) ovaia fi€Taj3alv€i tottovs, /cat e'c t6ttols ylverai' dXX' oti tu>v ire<pvKOTLcv 
 (rwp.a.Twv rdwovs ixeTafiaiveiv, /cat eiXrixevai tottovs, ux^Cf'S dvadexerai, dexo/J^euuv 
 avTrjv /cara ras e7nTr)5ei6T7]Tas twv tolovtoiv crw/xdrwi' e/c ttjs /car' o.vtt)v iroids 
 diadtaews. 
 
 2 "E questo cielo non ha altro dove 
 
 Che la mente divina.'' 
 
 Par. xxvii. 109—110. 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 195 
 
 suggested that immaterial essence is beyond the distinction of 
 the great and the small in magnitude ; but even at the end the 
 symbolism has not disappeared. 
 
 Like the completed theocratic organisation of society, the 
 Scholastic system which furnished its intellectual justification 
 was hardly finished before it began to break up from within. 
 St Thomas Aquinas was followed by John Duns Scotus, who, 
 while equally orthodox in belief, limited more the demonstrative 
 power of reason in relation to ecclesiastical dogma. Soon after 
 came William of Ockham, whose orthodoxy is to some extent 
 ambiguous. The criticisms of the Subtle and of the Invincible 
 Doctor had for their effect to show the illusoriness of the syste- 
 matic harmony which their great predecessor seemed to have 
 given once for all to the structure composed of dominant 
 Catholic theology and subordinated Aristotelian philosophy. 
 Duns Scotus was indirectly influenced by Neo-Platonism, which 
 came to him from the Jewish thinker Ibn Gebirol, known to 
 the schoolmen as Avicebron. This was the source of his theory 
 of a " first matter " which is an element in the composition of 
 intellectual as of corporeal substances. His view that the 
 " principle of individuation " is not matter but form, coincides 
 with that of Plotinus. Ockham was a thinker of a different 
 cast, representing, as against the Platonic Realism of Duns 
 Scotus, the most developed form of mediaeval Nominalism. In 
 their different ways, both developments contributed to upset 
 the balance of the Scholastic eirenicon between science and faith. 
 The rapidity with which the decomposition was now going on 
 may be judged from the fact that Ockham died about 1349, 
 that is, before the end of the half-century which had seen the 
 composition of the Divina Commedia. 
 
 The end of Scholasticism as a system appealing to the living 
 world is usually placed about the middle of the fifteenth century. 
 From that time, it became first an obstruction in the way of 
 newer thought, and then a sectarian survival. The six centuries 
 of its effective life are those during which Greek thought was 
 wholly unknown in its sources to the West. John Scotus 
 Erigena was one of the very last who had some knowledge of 
 Greek before the study of it revived in the Italy of Petrarch 
 
 13—2 
 
196 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 and Boccaccio. For the new positive beginning of European 
 culture, the classical revival, together with the impulse towards 
 physical research, — represented among the schoolmen by Roger 
 Bacon, — was the essential thing. 
 
 In the familiar story of the rise of Humanism, the point 
 that interests us here is that the first ancient system to be 
 appropriated in its content, and not simply studied as a branch 
 of erudition, was Platonism. And it was with the eyes of the 
 Neo-Platonists that the Florentine Academy read Plato himself. 
 Marsilio Ficino, having translated Plato, turned next to Plotinus. 
 His Latin translation of the Enneads appeared in 1492 \ 
 Platonism was now set by its new adherents against Aristo- 
 telianism, whether in the Scholastic form or as restored by 
 some who had begun to study it with the aid of the Greek 
 instead of the Arabian commentaries. The name of Aristotle 
 became for a time to jiearly all the innovators the synonym of 
 intellectual oppression. 
 
 The Platonists of the early Renaissance were sincere 
 Christians in their own manner. This was not the manner 
 of the Middle Age. The definitely articulated system of 
 ecclesiastical dogma had no real part in their intellectual life. 
 They were Christians in a general way ; in the details of their 
 thinking they were Neo-Platonists. In relation to astrology 
 and magic, indeed, they were Neo-Platonists of a less critical 
 type than the ancient chiefs of the school. Belief in both 
 magic and astrology, it is hardly necessary to say, had run down 
 through the whole course of the intervening centuries ; so that 
 there was little as yet in the atmosphere of the modern time 
 that could lead to a renewal of the sceptical and critical sifting 
 begun by thinkers like Plotinus and Porphyry. The influence 
 of Christianity shows itself in the special stress laid on the 
 religious aspect of Neo-Platonism. An example of this is to 
 be met with at the end of Marsilio Ficino's translation of 
 Plotinus. In the arguments prefixed to the closing chapters, 
 Ficino tries to make Plotinus say definitely that the union of 
 the soul with God, once attained, is perpetual. He has himself 
 
 1 The Greek was printed for the first time in 1580, when it appeared along 
 with the translation. 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 197 
 
 a feeling that the attempt is not quite successful; and he rather 
 contends that Plotinus was logically bound to make the affir- 
 mation than that it is there in his very words. As a matter of 
 fact, Plotinus has nowhere definitely made it ; and it seems 
 inconsistent alike with his own position that differences of 
 individuality proceed with necessity from eternal distinctions 
 in the divine intellect, and with his hypothetical use of the 
 Stoic doctrine that events recur in exactly repeated cycles. 
 When he says that in the intelligible world, though not in 
 earthly life, the vision is continuous, this does not by itself 
 mean that the soul, when it has ascended, remains above 
 without recurrent descents. It is true, nevertheless, that 
 Plotinus and Porphyry did not so explicitly as their successors 
 affirm that all particular souls are subject to perpetual vicissi- 
 tude 1 . 
 
 This point is of special interest because Ficino's interpre- 
 tation may have helped to mislead Bruno, who, in a passage 
 in the dedication of his Eroici Furori to Sir Philip Sidney, 
 classes Plotinus, so far as this doctrine is concerned, with the 
 " theologians." All the great philosophers except Plotinus, he 
 says, have taught that the mutations in the destiny of souls are 
 without term. On the other hand, all the great theologians 
 except Origen have taught that the soul either attains final 
 rest or is finally excluded from beatitude. The latter doctrine 
 has a practical reference, and may be impressed on the many 
 lest they should take things too lightly. The former is the 
 expression of pure truth, and is to be taught to those who are 
 capable of ruling themselves. Great as is for Plotinus the 
 importance of the religious redemption to which his philosophy 
 leads, the theoretic aspect of his system is here misapprehended. 
 Nothing, however, could bring out more clearly than this 
 pointed contrast, Bruno's own view. Coming near the end of 
 Renaissance Platonism, as Ficino comes near its beginning, 
 
 1 Thus St Augustine could commend Porphyry for what he took to be the 
 assertion that the soul, having once wholly ascended to the realm of being, can 
 never redescend to birth. That any soul can remain perpetually lapsed is 
 unquestionably contrary to the opinion both of Plotinus and of Porphyry. One 
 of Porphyry's objections to Christianity was that it taught that doctrine. 
 
) 
 
 198 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 he marks the declared break with tradition and the effort 
 after a completely independent philosophy. 
 
 Other elements as well as Neo-Platonism contributed to 
 Bruno's doctrine ; yet he too proceeds in his metaphysics from 
 the Neo- Platonic school. In expression, he always falls back 
 upon its terms. The system, indeed, undergoes profound 
 modifications. Matter and Form, Nature and God, become 
 antithetic names of a single reality, rather than extreme 
 terms in a causal series descending from the highest to the 
 lowest 1 . Side by side with the identity, however, the difference 
 is retained, in order to express the " circle " in phenomenal 
 things. In Bruno's cosmological view, modifications were of 
 course introduced by his acceptance and extension of the 
 Copernican astronomy. Yet he seeks to deduce this also 
 from propositions of the Neo-Platonic metaphysics. The 
 Neo-Platonists held, as he did, that the Cause is infinite in 
 potency, and necessarily produces all that it can produce. 
 The reason why they did not infer that the extended uni- 
 verse is quantitatively infinite was that, like some moderns, 
 they thought actual quantitative infinity an impossible con- 
 ception. 
 
 One of Bruno's most interesting points of contact with 
 Plotinus is in his theory of the beautiful. For this he may 
 have got the hint from the difference that had struck Plotinus 
 between the emotion that accompanies pursuit of knowledge 
 and beauty on the one hand, and mystical unification with the 
 good on the other. By this unification, however, Plotinus does 
 not mean moral virtue; so that when Bruno contrasts intellectual 
 aspiration with a kind of stoical indifference to fortune, and 
 treats it as a " defect " in comparison, because there is in the 
 constantly baffled pursuit of absolute truth or beauty an 
 element of pain, he is not closely following Plotinus. Yet in 
 their account of the aspiration itself, the two thinkers agree. 
 The fluctuation and pain in the aesthetic or intellectual life are 
 insisted on by both. In Bruno indeed the thought is immensely 
 
 1 Identification of all in the unity of Substance is regarded by Vacherot as 
 characterising Bruno's thought, in contrast with the Neo-Platonic "emanation." 
 See Histoire Critique de VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. iii. p. 196. 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 199 
 
 expanded from the hint of Plotinus ; the Eroici Furori being 
 a whole series of imaginative symbols interpreted as expressive 
 of the same ardour towards " the unknown God of unachieved 
 desire." There is here manifest a difference of temperament. 
 Bruno had more of the restlessness which Plotinus finds in the 
 soul of the artist and the theorist. Plotinus, along with his 
 philosophical enthusiasm, had more of the detachment and 
 repose of the religious mystic. 
 
 The most striking difference between the Platonism of the 
 Neo-Platonists and that of the Renaissance, is the stronger 
 accentuation by the latter of naturalistic pantheism. This, 
 though not absent in Neo-Platonism itself, is subordinate. 
 Plotinus, as we saw, regards the heavenly bodies as divine, 
 and can on occasion speak like Bruno of the earth as one of 
 the stars. This side of his doctrine, however, is less prominent 
 than his conception of intellectual and superessential divinity. 
 With Bruno the reverse is the case. And Campanella too seizes 
 on the naturalistic side of the doctrine to confound the despisers 
 of the visible world. Among his philosophical poems there is 
 one in particular which conveys precisely the feeling of the book 
 of Plotinus against the Gnostics. 
 
 " Deem you that only you have thought and sense, 
 
 While heaven and all its wonders, sun and earth, 
 Scorned in your dullness, lack intelligence ? 
 Fool ! what produced you ? These things gave you birth : 
 So have they mind and God 1 ." 
 
 This tone of feeling, characteristic of the Renaissance, passed 
 away during the prevalence of the new "mechanical philosophy," 
 to reappear later when the biological sciences were making 
 towards theories of vital evolution. It is thus no accident 
 that it should then have been rendered by Goethe, who 
 combined with his poetic genius original insight in biology. 
 
 1 Sonnet xix. in Symonds's translation. The original of the passage may be 
 given for comparison. 
 
 " Pensiti aver tu solo provvidenza, 
 
 E '1 ciel la terra e 1' altre cose belle, 
 Le quali sprezzi tu, starsene senza? 
 Sciocco, d' onde se' nato tu? da quelle, 
 Dunque ci e senno e Dio." 
 
200 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 While the Platonising movement was going on, other 
 ancient doctrines had been independently revived. For the 
 growth of the physical sciences, now cultivated afresh after long 
 neglect, the revival of Atomism was especially important. The 
 one scientific doctrine of antiquity which Neo-Platonism had 
 been unable to turn to account was seen by modern physicists 
 to be exactly that of which they were in need. Thus whether, 
 like Descartes and Hobbes, they held that the universe is a 
 plenum, or, with Democritus himself, affirmed the real existence 
 of vacuum, all the physical thinkers of the seventeenth century 
 thought of body, for the purposes of science, as corpuscular. 
 Corpuscular physics was the common foundation of the 
 " mechanical philosophy." Now it is worthy of note that the 
 first distinctively Platonic revival, beyond the period we call 
 the Renaissance, decisively adopted the corpuscular physics as 
 not incompatible with "the true intellectual system of the 
 universe." The Cambridge Platonists, as represented especially 
 by Cudworth, did not, in their opposition to the naturalism of 
 Hobbes, show any reactionary spirit in pure science ; but were 
 so much awake to the growing ideas of the time that, even 
 before the great impression made by Newton's work, they were 
 able to remedy for themselves the omission that had limited 
 the scientific resources of their ancient predecessors. And 
 More, in appending his philosophical poem on The Infinity of 
 Worlds to that on The Immortality of the Soul, does not shrink 
 from appealing to the authority of Democritus, Epicurus and 
 Lucretius in favour of those infinite worlds in space which the 
 Neo-Platonists had rejected. Neither on this question nor on 
 the kindred one as to the manifestation of Deity in a pheno- 
 menal universe without past or future limit in time, does he 
 commit himself to a final conclusion ; but evidently, after at 
 first rejecting both infinities as involving impossibilities of 
 conception, he inclined to the affirmation of both. 
 
 The new metaphysical position that philosophy had in the 
 meantime gained, was the subjective point of view fixed by 
 Descartes as the principle of his " method for conducting the 
 reason and seeking truth in the sciences." This, as has been 
 indicated, was remotely Neo-Platonic in origin ; for the Neo- 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 201 
 
 Platonists had been the first to formulate accurately those 
 conceptions of immaterial substance and of introspective con- 
 sciousness which had acquired currency for the later world 
 through the abstract language of the schools. Thus Descartes, 
 with Scholasticism and Humanism behind him, could go in a 
 summary way through the whole process, without immersing 
 himself in one or the other as a form of erudition ; and could 
 then start, so far as the problem of knowledge is concerned, 
 where the ancients had left off. Knowledge of that which is 
 within, they had found, is in the end the most certain. The 
 originality of Descartes consisted in taking it as the most 
 certain in the beginning. Having fixed the point of view, he 
 could then proceed, from a few simple positions ostensibly put 
 forward without appeal to authority, to construct a new frame- 
 work for the sciences of the inner and of the outer world. 
 
 Here was the beginning of idealism in its modern form. 
 The other great innovation of the modern world in general 
 principle, was the notion that there is a mode of systematically 
 appealing to experience as the test of scientific truth ; that 
 rational deduction, such as was still the main thing for 
 Descartes, must be supplemented by, if not ultimately sub- 
 ordinated to, the test of inductive verification. This, though 
 not exclusively an English idea, has been mainly promoted by 
 English thinkers, in its application first to the physical, and 
 then, still more specially, to the mental sciences. In antiquity, 
 experience had indeed been recognised as the beginning of 
 knowledge in the genetic order. Its priority in this sense could 
 be allowed by a school as rationalist as Neo-Platonism. It had 
 not, however, even by the experiential schools, been rigorously 
 defined as a test applicable to all true science. On this side 
 Bacon and Locke, as on the other side Descartes, were the 
 great philosophical initiators of the new time. 
 
 The essential innovations of modern thought, as we see, 
 were innovations in method. They did not of themselves 
 suggest any new answer to questions about ultimate reality or 
 the destiny of the universe. It is not that such answers have 
 been lacking; but they have always remained, in one way or 
 another, new formulations of old ones. The hope cherished by 
 
202 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 Bacon and Descartes that the moderns might at length cut 
 themselves loose from the past and, by an infallible method, 
 discover all attainable truth, has long been seen to be vain. 
 Not only individual genius, but historical study of past ideas 
 and systems, have become of more and not of less importance. 
 The most original and typical ontologies of modern times are 
 those of Spinoza and Leibniz; and, much as they owe to the 
 newer developments of science and theory of knowledge, both 
 are expressed by means of metaphysical conceptions that 
 had taken shape during the last period of ancient thought. 
 Pantheism and Monadism are not merely implicit in the Neo- 
 Platonic doctrine; they receive clear formulation as different 
 aspects of it. If, as some modern critics think, the two 
 conceptions are not ultimately irreconcilable, the best hints 
 for a solution may probably still be found in Plotinus. No 
 one has ever been more conscious than he of the difficulty 
 presented by the problem of comprehending as portions of one 
 philosophical truth the reality of universal and that of in- 
 dividual intellect. 
 
 Perhaps the strongest testimony to the intrinsic value of 
 the later Greek thought is Berkeley's Siris. For if that thought 
 had really become obsolete, Berkeley was in every way pre- 
 pared to perceive it. He had pushed the Cartesian reform as 
 far as it would go, by reducing what Descartes still thought of 
 as real extended substance to a system of phenomena un- 
 consciousness. He had at the same time all the English 
 regard for the test of experience, fortified by knowledge of 
 what had been done in his own age in investigating nature. 
 Thus, he had taken most decisively the two steps by which 
 modern philosophy has made a definite advance. Besides, as a 
 theologian, he might easily have assumed that anything there 
 was of value in the work of thinkers who, living long after 
 the opening of the Christian era, had been the most uncom- 
 promising antagonists of the Christian Church, must have been 
 long superseded. His own early Nominalism, which, as may 
 be seen in Siris itself, he had never abandoned, might also have 
 been expected to prejudice him against Platonic Realism. Yet 
 it is precisely in the Neo-Platonists that Berkeley, near the 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 203 
 
 end of his philosophical career, found hints towards a tentative 
 solution of ontological questions which he had at first thought 
 to settle once for all by a resolutely logical carrying out of the 
 principles of Descartes and Locke. It is true that in actual 
 result Siris makes no advance on the original Neo-Platonic 
 speculations, which are not really fused with Berkeley's own 
 early doctrine, but are at most kept clear of contradiction with 
 it. For all that, Siris furnishes the most decisive evidence of 
 enduring vitality in a school of thought which, to Berkeley's 
 age if to any since the classical revival, must have seemed 
 entirely of the past. 
 
 Berkeley's work here seems in a manner comparable with 
 that of the Platonising English poets from Spenser to Shelley. 
 The influence of Platonism on literature is, however, too wide a 
 subject to be treated episodically. The one remark may be 
 made, that not till modern times did it really begin to influence 
 poetic art. In antiquity it had its theories of art, — varying 
 greatly, as we have seen, from Plato to Plotinus, — but artistic 
 production was never inspired by it. If poetic thought, as 
 some think, is an anticipation of the future, this influence on 
 poetry may be taken as further evidence that the ideas of the 
 philosophy itself are still unexhausted. 
 
 During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the great 
 controversies of metaphysics did not centre in Platonism. 
 There is truth in the view that would make this first period 
 of distinctively modern philosophy a kind of continuation of 
 later Scholasticism, more than of the Renaissance which im- 
 mediately preceded it. Its ostensible questions were about 
 method. The usual division of its schools or phases by 
 historians is into " Dogmatism " (by which is meant the 
 rationalistic theory of certitude) and its opposite " Empiricism," 
 followed by " Scepticism " and then by " Criticism." As these 
 names show, it is concerned less with inquiry into the nature of 
 reality than with the question how reality is to be known, or 
 whether indeed knowledge of it is possible. And, with all its 
 differences, the modern " Enlightenment " has this resemblance 
 to Scholasticism, that a particular system of doctrine is always 
 in the background, to which the controversy is tacitly referred. 
 
204 THE INFLUENCE [X 
 
 This system is in effect the special type of theism which the 
 more rationalistic schoolmen undertook to prove as a preliminary 
 to faith in the Catholic creed. Even in its non-Christian form, 
 as with the "Deists," it is still of the Judaeo-Christian tradition. 
 The assumption about the relation of God to the world is that 
 the world was created by an act of will. Ordinary Rationalism 
 is " dogmatic " by its assertion that " natural religion " of this 
 type can be demonstrated. " Empiricism " usually holds that 
 the same general positions can be established sufficiently on at 
 least " probable " grounds. The Scepticism of Hume proceeds 
 to show the failure of Empiricism — with which he sides philo- 
 sophically as against Rationalism — to establish anything of the 
 kind. Hume's philosophical questioning, while this was the 
 practical reference which aroused so much feeling in his own 
 age, had of course a wider reach. Yet when Kant, stirred 
 by the impulse received from Hume, took up again from a 
 " Critical " point of view the whole problem as to the possibility 
 of knowledge, he too thought with a reference to the same 
 practical centre of the controversy. Having destroyed the 
 Wolffian " Dogmatism," he still aimed at reconstructing from 
 its theoretical ruin a generalised theology of essentially the 
 same type. For Kant, as for the line of thinkers closed by 
 him, there was only one ontology seriously in question ; and 
 that was Christian theism, with or without the Christian 
 revelation. 
 
 The German movement at the opening of the nineteenth 
 century, if it did nothing else, considerably changed this aspect 
 of things. In its aims, whatever may now be thought of its 
 results, it was a return to ontology without presuppositions. 
 The limited dogmatic system which was the centre of interest 
 for the preceding period has for speculation passed out of sight. 
 Spinoza perhaps on the positive side exercises a predominant 
 influence ; but there are returns also to the thinkers of the 
 Renaissance, to Neo-Platonism, and to the ancient systems of 
 the East, now beginning to be known in Europe from trans- 
 lations of their actual documents. A kind of Neo-Christianity 
 too appears, which again treats Christian dogma in the spirit of 
 the Gnostics or of Scotus Erigena. And all this is complicated 
 
X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 205 
 
 by the necessity imposed on every thinker of taking up a 
 definite attitude to the Kantian criticism of knowledge. Among 
 the systems of the time, that of Hegel in particular has fre- 
 quently been compared to Neo-Platonism ; but here the 
 resemblance is by no means close. The character of Hegel's 
 system seems to have been determined mainly by its relation 
 to preceding German philosophy and to Spinoza. Both on 
 Spinoza himself and on Leibniz, the influence of Neo-Platonism, 
 direct or indirect, was much more definite, and points of 
 comparison might be sought with more profit. In Hegel, as 
 in the other philosophers of the period, the resemblance is 
 partly of a quite general kind. They are again ontologists, 
 interested in more possibilities than in the assertion or denial 
 of the rudiments of a single creed. But, knowing the historical 
 position of the Neo-Platonists, they find in them many thoughts 
 that agree with their personal tendencies. 
 
 Up to this point the outline given of the course of later 
 philosophy may, it seems to me, on the whole be regarded as 
 abbreviated history. The next stage may perhaps be summed 
 up as another return from ontology to questions about the 
 possibility of knowledge, and to logical and methodological 
 inquiries. To pursue further the attempt to characterise the 
 successive stages of European thought would be to enter the 
 region where no brief summary can fairly pretend to be a 
 deposit of ascertained results. The best plan, from the point 
 now reached, will be to try to state the law of philosophic 
 development which the history of Neo-Platonism suggests ; and 
 then to make some attempt to learn what positive value the 
 doctrine may still have for the modern world. This will be the 
 subject of the concluding chapter. 
 
CHAPTER XI. 
 
 CONCLUSION. 
 
 Once the Neo-Platonic period, instead of being left in 
 shadow, is brought into clear historical light, the development 
 of Greek philosophy from Thales to Proclus is seen to consist 
 of two alternations from naturalism to idealism. The "physical" 
 thinkers are followed by Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. Then, 
 by a similar antithesis, the more developed naturalism of the 
 Stoics and Epicureans is followed by the more developed 
 idealism of the Neo-Platonists. The psychology of the Greeks 
 has been brought by Prof. Siebeck under the order assigned by 
 this law. Mr Benn has suggested the law as that of Greek 
 philosophy in general, but without carrying it through in its 
 application to the details 1 . When to the empirical formula the 
 test of psychological deduction is applied, this seems to show 
 that it must have a more general character — that it must be a 
 law, not only of Greek thought, but of the thought of mankind. 
 For evidently, as the objective and subjective points of view 
 become distinguished, the mind must tend to view things first 
 objectively, and then afterwards to make a reflective return 
 on its own processes in knowing. Thus we ought to find 
 universally that a phase of speculative naturalism — the ex- 
 pression of the objective point of view — is followed, when 
 
 1 Both historians call the later phase Spiritualism, hut on etymological 
 grounds Idealism is the preferable term. "Spirit" (irveu/xa), as Prof. Siebeck 
 lias shown in his detailed history, was not used by the Greek philosophers 
 themselves as the name of an immaterial principle. 
 
Xl] CONCLUSION 207 
 
 reflection begins to analyse things into appearances for mind, 
 by a phase of idealism. Unfortunately, no exact verification of 
 so extended a deduction can be made out. All that can be said 
 is that the facts do not contradict it. 
 
 The law, in the most general terms, may be stated thus : 
 "Whenever there is a spontaneous development of philosophic 
 thought beyond the stage of dependence on tradition, a natural- 
 istic phase comes first and an idealistic phase second. In no 
 intrinsic development, whether of individuals or of peoples, is 
 there a reversal of the order. One or other of the phases, 
 however, may be practically suppressed. An individual mind, 
 or the mind of a people, may stop at naturalism, or after the 
 most evanescent phase of it may go straight on to pure idealism. 
 Where both phases definitely appear, as in the case of Greece, 
 we must expect returns of the first, making a repeated rhythm. 
 Further, we must take account of foreign influences, which may 
 modify the intrinsic development. Also, when both stages have 
 been passed through, and are represented by their own teachers, 
 revivals of either may appear at any moment. Thus in modern 
 Europe we can hardly expect to trace through the whole deve- 
 lopment any law whatever. When thinkers began to break 
 through the new tradition which had substituted itself for 
 ancient mythology and philosophy alike, and had ruled through 
 the Middle Ages, there was from the first a possibility, according 
 to the temper of the individual mind, of reviving any phase of 
 doctrine, naturalistic or idealistic, without respect to its order 
 in the past. We may occasionally get a typical case of the law, 
 as in the idealistic reaction of the Cambridge Platonists on the 
 naturalism of Hobbes ; but we cannot expect anything like this 
 uniformly. 
 
 Two great national anomalies are the precisely opposite 
 cases of India (that is, of the Hindus) and of China. Nowhere 
 in Asia of course has there been that self-conscious break with 
 traditional authority which we find in ancient Greece and in 
 modern Europe ; in both of which cases, however, it must be 
 remembered that the authoritative tradition has never ceased 
 to exist, but has continued always, even in the most sceptical 
 or rational periods, to possess more of direct popular power than 
 
208 CONCLUSION [XI 
 
 philosophy. The philosophies of India and of China are not 
 formally distinct from their religions, and have not found it 
 necessary to repudiate any religious belief simply as such. 
 Still, each has a very distinct character of its own. The official 
 philosophy of China is as purely naturalistic as that of India is 
 idealistic. And in both cases the learned doctrine succeeds in 
 giving a general direction to the mind of the people without 
 appealing to force. With the Hindus, naturalism seems to have 
 been an almost entirely suppressed phase of development. The 
 traces of it found in some of the philosophic systems may be 
 remains of an abortive attempt at a naturalistic view of things 
 in India itself, or may be the result of a foreign influence such 
 as that of Greek Atomism. On the other hand, the Taoism 
 and the Buddhism of China are admittedly much reduced from 
 the elevation they had at first, and have become new elements 
 in popular superstition instead of idealistic philosophies. Bud- 
 dhism of course is Indian ; and Taoism, in its original form 
 perhaps the sole attempt at metaphysics by a native Chinese 
 teacher, seems to have been an indeterminate pantheism, not 
 strictly to be classed either as naturalistic or as idealistic. Both 
 are officially in the shade as compared with Confucianism ; 
 and this, while agnostic with regard to metaphysics, is as 
 a philosophy fundamentally naturalistic ; adding to ancestral 
 traditions about right conduct simply a very general idea of 
 cosmic order as the theoretic basis for its ethical code. 
 
 India and China being thus taken to represent one-sided 
 evolutions of the human mind, we shall see in ancient Greece 
 the normal sequence under a comparatively simplified form. In 
 modern Europe we shall see a complex balance of the two 
 tendencies. Turning from the question of historical law to 
 that of philosophical truth, we may conjecture that the reflective 
 process must somehow mark an advance in insight ; but that, if 
 nothing is to be lost, it ought to resume in itself what has gone 
 before. And, as a matter of fact, European idealists, both 
 ancient and modern, have not been content unless they could 
 incorporate objective science with their metaphysics. 
 
 Thus we arrive at a kind of " law of three states " — tradition 
 or mythology, naturalism, idealism. In its last two terms, this 
 
Xl] CONCLUSION 209 
 
 law seems to be an inversion of the sequence Comte sought to 
 establish from the " metaphysical " to the " positive " stage ; 
 naturalism being the philosophy underlying " positivism," while 
 idealism is another name for " metaphysics." How then are we 
 to explain Comte's own mental development ? For he undoubt- 
 edly held that he himself had passed from tradition through 
 " metaphysics " to " positivity." Exceptio probat regulam : " the 
 exception tests the rule 1 ." In the first place, what Comte 
 regarded as his own metaphysical stage was not metaphysics 
 at all, but a very early mode of political thought in which he 
 accepted from eighteenth century teachers their doctrine of 
 abstract "natural rights." In the second place, his mental 
 history really had a kind of metaphysical phase ; but this came 
 after his strictly "positive" or naturalistic period. His later 
 philosophy became subjective on two sides. Having at first 
 regarded mathematics as the sufficient formal basis of all the 
 sciences, he arrived later at the view that at the head of the 
 philosophy of mathematics there ought to be set out a more 
 general statement of principles. That is to say, his intention 
 was to fill up the place that belongs properly to logic, which in 
 its formal division is subjective. Again, in his later scheme, after 
 the highest of the sciences, which he called "morality" — meaning 
 really a psychology of the individual, placed after and not before 
 sociology — there came his " subjective synthesis." This was an 
 adumbration of metaphysics in the true sense of the term ; so 
 that his circle of the sciences, beginning with formal principles 
 of reasoning, would have completed itself by running into 
 subjectivity at the other extreme. The apparently exceptional 
 case of Comte therefore turns out to be a real confirmation of 
 the law. 
 
 However it may be with this proposed law of three states, 
 there can be no doubt that a very highly developed form of 
 idealism is represented by the Neo-Platonists. How does this 
 stand in relation to modern thought ? An obvious position to 
 take up would be to allow the merit of Plotinus and his suc- 
 
 1 See Mr Carveth KeacVs Logic, p. 214. 
 w. H 
 
210 CONCLUSION [XI 
 
 cessors in scientifically elaborating the highest metaphysical 
 conceptions, but to dismiss all their detailed ontology as of 
 merely historic interest. Thus we should fall back upon a 
 position suggested by Plato in the Philebus ; namely, that 
 though there may be very little " dialectical," or, as we should 
 now say, metaphysical knowledge, that little may be "pure 1 ." 
 This, however, is too easy a way. The Neo-Platonic thought is, 
 metaphysically, the maturest thought that the European world 
 has seen. Our science, indeed, is more developed ; and so also, 
 with regard to some special problems, is our theory of know- 
 ledge. On the other hand, the modern time has nothing to 
 show comparable to a continuous quest of truth about reality 
 during a period of intellectual liberty that lasted for a thousand 
 years. What it has to show, during a much shorter period of 
 freedom, consists of isolated efforts, bounded by the national 
 limitations of its philosophical schools. The essential ideas, 
 therefore, of the ontology of Plotinus and Proclus may still be 
 worth examining in no merely antiquarian spirit. 
 
 A method of examination that suggests itself is to try 
 whether, after all, something of the nature of verification may 
 not be possible in metaphysics. The great defect of idealistic 
 philosophy has been that so little can be deduced from it. The 
 facts of nature do not, indeed, contradict it, but they seem to 
 offer no retrospective confirmation of it. Now this, to judge 
 from the analogy of science, may be owing to the extreme 
 generality with which modern idealism is accustomed to state 
 its positions. It is as if in physics we were reduced to an 
 affirmation of the permanence of " matter " defined in Aristo- 
 telian terminology. Let us try what can be made of an 
 idealistic system that undertakes to tell us more than that 
 reality is in some way to be expressed in terms of mind. 
 Plotinus and Proclus, from their theory of being, make deduc- 
 tions that concern the order of phenomena. Since their time, 
 great discoveries have been made in phenomenal science. Do 
 these tend to confirm or to contradict the deductions made from 
 their metaphysical principles by the ancient thinkers ? 
 
 ] Phileb. 58 c. 
 
XI] CONCLUSION 21 1 
 
 We must allow, of course, for the defective science of 
 antiquity. The Neo-Platonists cannot be expected to hold 
 any other than the Ptolemaic astronomy. They do not, 
 however, profess to deduce the details of astronomy from 
 their metaphysics. Just as with the moderns, much in the 
 way of detail is regarded as given only by experience. That 
 the universe has this precise constitution — if it has it — is known 
 only as an empirical fact, not as a deduction from the nature of 
 its cause. What the Neo-Platonists deduce metaphysically is 
 not the geocentric system, but the stability of that system — 
 or of any other — if it exists. Thus they do not agree with the 
 Stoics ; who, though taking the same view about the present 
 constitution of the universe, held that the system of earth 
 with surrounding planetary and stellar spheres is periodically 
 resolved into the primeval fire and again reconstituted, the 
 resolution being accompanied by an enormous expansion of 
 bulk. All such ideas of an immense total change from a 
 given state of things to its opposite, Plotinus and his successors 
 reject. Any cycle that they can allow involves only changes of 
 distribution in a universe ordered always after the same general 
 fashion. They cany this even into their interpretation of early 
 thinkers like Empedocles. According to Simplicius, the periods 
 of concentration and diffusion which alternate in his cosmogony 
 were by Empedocles himself only assumed hypothetically, and 
 to facilitate scientific analysis and synthesis 1 . For universal 
 intellect, as all the Neo-Platonists say, is ever-existent and 
 produces the cosmic order necessarily ; hence it does not 
 pometimes act and sometimes remain inactive. Undeviating 
 necessity, in its visible manifestation as in reality, belongs to 
 the divinity above man as to the unconscious nature below him. 
 Change of manifestation depending on apparently arbitrary 
 choice between opposites belongs to man from his intermediate 
 position. To attribute this to the divinity is mythological. 
 There must therefore always be an ordered universe in which 
 every form and grade of being is represented. The phenomenal 
 world, flowing from intellectual being by a process that is 
 
 1 Be Caelo (E. P. 133 i.*). 
 
 14—2 
 
212 CONCLUSION [XI 
 
 necessary and as it were natural, is without temporal begin- 
 ning or end. These propositions we are already familiar with ; 
 and these are the essence of the deduction. Thus if the 
 universe — whatever its detailed constitution may be — does not 
 always as a whole manifest a rational order, the metaphysical 
 principle is fundamentally wrong. To prove scientifically that 
 the world points to an absolute temporal beginning, or that it is 
 running down to an absolute temporal end, or even that it is 
 as a whole alternately a chaos and a cosmos, would be a refu- 
 tation of the form of idealism held by Plotinus. How then 
 does modern science stand with regard to this position ? 
 
 It may seem at first sight to contradict it. For does not 
 the theory of cosmic evolution suppose just such immense 
 periodic changes as were conceived by Empedocles, according 
 to the most obvious interpretation of his words ? So far as the 
 solar system is concerned, no doubt it does ; but the solar 
 system is only a part of the universe. And there seems to be 
 no scientific evidence for the theory that the universe as a 
 whole has periods of evolution and dissolution. Indeed, the 
 evidence points rather against this view. Astronomical ob- 
 servers find existent worlds in all stages. This suggests that, 
 to an observer on any planet, the stellar universe would always 
 present the same general aspect, though never absolute identity 
 of detail as compared with its aspect at any other point of time. 
 For every formed system that undergoes dissolution, some other 
 is evolved from the nebulae which we call relatively "primordial." 
 Thus the total phenomenal manifestation of being remains always 
 the same. If this view should gaiu strength with longer observa- 
 tion, then science may return in the end to the Neo-Platonic 
 cosmology on an enlarged scale, and again conceive of the 
 whole as one stable order, subject to growth and decay only in 
 its parts. At no time, as the metaphysician will say, is the 
 mind of the universe wholly latent. There is no priority of 
 sense to intellect in the whole. The apparent priority of 
 matter, or of the sentiency of which matter is the phenomenon, 
 is simply an imaginative representation of the evolutionary 
 process in a single system, regarded in isolation from the 
 universe of which it forms part. 
 
XI] CONCLUSION 213 
 
 That this view is demonstrated by science cannot of course 
 be said. The evidence, however, is quite consistent with it, 
 and seems to point to this rather than to any other of the 
 possible views. The question being not yet scientifically 
 settled, the idealism of Plotinus still offers itself, by the 
 cosmology in which it issues, for verification or disproof. And 
 empirical confirmation, if this were forthcoming, would be 
 quite real as far as it goes, precisely because the metaphysical 
 doctrine is not so very general as to be consistent with all 
 possible facts. A scientific proof that the universe is running 
 down to a state of unalterable fixation would refute it. 
 
 To the speculative doctrine of Plotinus no very great 
 addition, as we have seen, was made before Proclus. The 
 additions Proclus was able to make have by historians as a rule 
 been treated as useless complications, — multiplications of entities 
 without necessity. Yet the power of Proclus as a thinker is 
 not denied even by those who find little to admire in its 
 results ; and it had undergone assiduous training. He may be 
 said to have known in detail the whole history of ancient 
 thought, scientific as well as philosophical, at a time when it 
 could still be known without any great recourse to fragments 
 and conjecture. And he came at the end of a perfectly con- 
 tinuous movement. It is therefore of special interest to see 
 how the metaphysical developments he arrived at appear in 
 the light of discoveries made since the European community 
 returned again to the systematic pursuit of knowledge. 
 
 What is noteworthy first of all is the way in which, 
 following Aristotle, he has incorporated with the idea of the 
 one stable universe that of an upward movement in the 
 processes that belong to the realm of birth. As we have seen, 
 he distinctly says that in the order of genesis the imperfect 
 comes before the perfect. And this is not meant simply in 
 reference to the individual organism, where it is merely a genera- 
 lised statement of obvious facts, but is applied on occasion to 
 the history of science. Now the technical terms by which he 
 expresses the philosophical idea of emanation admit of trans- 
 ference to an evolutionary process in time through which its 
 components may be supposed to become explicit. The 77730080? 
 
214 CONCLUSION [XI 
 
 and the eiriGrpo^rj, or the going forth from the metaphysical 
 principle and the return to it, are not of course themselves 
 processes of the universe in time. Yet there is no reason why 
 they should not have respectively their temporal manifestations 
 in its parts, so long as neither type of manifestation is supposed 
 to be chronologically prior or posterior in relation to the whole. 
 When the terms are thus applied, they find accurate expression 
 in the idea of an evolution, and not of a lapse manifested 
 chronologically, — with which " emanation " is sometimes con- 
 founded. Primarily, it is the e-maTpofyri, rather than the 
 7T/3ooSo?, that becomes manifest as the upward movement. 
 Indeed the term corresponds pretty closely to " involution," 
 which, as Mr Spencer has said 1 , would more truly express the 
 nature of the movement than " evolution." This process is 
 seen in history when thought, by some great discovery, returns 
 to its principle. The antithetic movement, which may be 
 regarded as the manifestation of the 7r/>6oSo?, is seen when, 
 for example, a great discovery is carried, as time goes on, into 
 more and more minute details, or is gradually turned to 
 practical applications. Thus it corresponds to most of what 
 in modern times is called " progress." A corollary drawn by 
 Proclus from his system, it may be noted, also suggests itself 
 from the point of view of modern evolution. The highest and 
 the lowest things, Proclus concludes, are simple ; "composition," 
 or complexity, belongs to intermediate natures. 
 
 An even more remarkable point of contact between the 
 metaphysics of Proclus and later science is that which presents 
 itself when we bring together his doctrine of the "divine 
 henads " and the larger conceptions of modern astronomy. 
 This doctrine, as we saw, is with Proclus abstract metaphysics. 
 The One, he reasons, must be mediated to the remoter things 
 by many unities, to each of which its own causal " chain " is 
 attached. Elaborate as the theory is, it had, when put forth, 
 hardly any concrete application. If, however, we liberate the 
 metaphysics from the merely empirical part of the cosmology, 
 a large and important application becomes clear. The primal 
 One, as we know, is by Neo-Platonism identified with the 
 1 First Principles, 6th ed., p. 261. 
 
XI] CONCLUSION 215 
 
 Platonic Idea of the Good. Now this, with Plato, corresponds 
 in the intelligible world to the sun in the visible world, and is 
 its cause. But if, as Proclus concluded, the One must be 
 mediated to particular beings by many divine unities, what 
 constitution should we naturally suppose the visible universe 
 to have ? Evidently, to each " henad " would correspond a 
 single world which is one of many, each with its own sun. 
 Thus the metaphysical conception of Proclus exactly prefigures 
 the post-Copernican astronomy, for which each of the fixed 
 stars is the centre of a planetary " chain," and the source of 
 life to the living beings that appear there in the order of birth. 
 
 From the infinite potency of the primal Cause, Bruno drew 
 the inference that the universe must consist of actually in- 
 numerable worlds. If we take the Neo-Platonic doctrine, not 
 in its most generalised form — in which, as soon as we go 
 beyond a single world, it might seem to issue naturally in an 
 assertion of the quantitative infinite — but with the additions 
 made to it by Proclus, the plurality of worlds certainly becomes 
 more scientifically thinkable. For the "henads" — composing, 
 as Proclus says, the plurality nearest to absolute unity — are 
 finite in number. Quantitative infinity he in common with all 
 the school rejects. A kind of infinity of space as a subjective 
 form would have presented no difficulty. Indeed both the 
 geometrical and the arithmetical infinite were allowed by 
 Plotinus in something very like this sense. The difficulty was 
 in the supposition that there are actually existent things in 
 space which are infinite in number. The problem, of course, 
 still remains as one of metaphysical inference. For there can 
 be no astronomical proof either that the whole is finite or that 
 it is infinite. An infinite real ethereal space, with a finite 
 universe of gravitating matter — which seems to be the tacit 
 supposition of those who argue from the fact of radiant heat 
 that the sum of worlds is running down to an end — Bruno and 
 his Neo-Platonic predecessors would alike have rejected. 
 
 The Neo-Platonic idealism, it ought now to be evident, was 
 far removed from the reproach of peculiar inability. to bring 
 itself into relation with the things of time and space. If both 
 finally baffle the attempt at complete mental comprehension, 
 
216 CONCLUSION [XI 
 
 this, the philosophers would have said, is because they are 
 forms of becoming, and hence remain mixed with illusory 
 imagination. Contrasted with the eternity of intellect, that 
 which appears under those forms is in a sense unreal. The 
 whole philosophy of " genesis," however largely conceived, be- 
 comes again what it was for Parmenides, to whom the 
 explanations of physics, though having truth as a coherent 
 order in the world of appearance, where 
 
 irav irXeov iarlv 6fxov <f>deo<i teal vvktos d(f>dvrov, 
 
 t<T(OV dfKJiOTepCOV 1 , 
 
 are yet false as compared with the unmixed truth of being. 
 In whatever sense Parmenides conceived of being, the Neo- 
 Platonists, as we know, conceived of it in the manner of 
 idealism. Their idealistic ontology, not deprived of all its 
 detail but merely of its local and temporal features, would, if 
 accepted, clear up more things than the most ambitious of 
 modern systems. That it does not in the end profess to make 
 all things clear, should not be to a modern mind a reason for 
 contemning it, but should rather tell in its favour. 
 
 1 Parmenides ap. Simplic. Phys. (R. P. 100). 
 
 
APPENDIX. 
 
 I. The Communism of Plato. 
 
 The feature of Plato's Republic that has drawn most general 
 attention both in ancient and in modern times is its communism. 
 This communism, however, had no place in the doctrine of his 
 philosophical successors. And his system is in one important 
 point quite opposed to that which is usual in modern socialism 
 with its effort after equality. Some unremembered anticipation of 
 this may have been caricatured by Aristophanes in the Ecclesiazusae: 
 but the artifices in the comedy for maintaining strict "democratic 
 justice " are of course the very antithesis of the Platonic conception, 
 the essence of which is to cultivate to the highest point, by separa- 
 tion of classes and by special training, every natural difference of 
 faculty. Besides, the Platonic community of goods is applied only 
 to the ruling philosophic class of guardians and to the military 
 class of their auxiliaries. The industrial portion of the community is 
 apparently left to the system of private property and commercial 
 competition — though no doubt with just so much regulation from 
 the guardians as is necessary to preserve the social health and keep 
 down imposthumes. Now the interesting thing is that this offers 
 something far more practicable than socialism of the modern indus- 
 trial type. 
 
 That this is so may be seen by bringing the Platonic community 
 of goods into comparison with Mr Spencer's generalisations, in the 
 third volume of his Principles oj Sociology, on the origin of " Pro- 
 fessional Institutions." Mr Spencer shows that professional, as 
 distinguished from industrial, institutions are all differentiated from 
 the priesthood, which, along with the military class, forms the 
 dominant part of the earliest specialised society. Now the re- 
 muneration of all professional classes is for a long time public. 
 
218 APPENDIX 
 
 Like Plato's guardians, they receive support from the rest of the 
 community, not so much for particular services as for constant 
 readiness to perform certain kinds of service. And a sort of 
 disinterested character long continues to be assumed in professional 
 functions, so that the remuneration is formally a voluntary gift, 
 and not the market price of the service immediately done. This 
 is now looked upon as a " survival." The normal system is thought 
 to be that in which every form of social activity is thrown into the 
 competition of the market-place. Perhaps Mr Spencer himself takes 
 this view. If, however, we follow out the clue supplied by his 
 inductions, we are led to imagine a new transformation by which 
 predominant industrialism might, having done its work, be dis- 
 placed by a reform in the spirit though not according to the 
 letter of the Platonic communism. 
 
 Industrial institutions, as Mr Spencer says, are for the " susten- 
 tation " of life ; professional institutions are for its " augmentation." 
 Now, where there is to be augmentation, sustentation, and the 
 activities subservient to it, must not be the direct aim of everyone 
 in the community. Among Mr Spencer's "professional" activities, 
 for example, are science and philosophy. The beginnings of these, 
 Aristotle had already said, appeared among the Egyptian priests 
 because they had leisure to speculate. As Hobbes put it, " leisure 
 is the mother of philosophy." The same thing is recognised in 
 Comte's social reconstruction, where, though individual property 
 is retained, commercial competition is allowed only in the industrial 
 sphere ; the class that corresponds to the higher class of Plato's 
 guardians being supported publicly on condition of renouncing all 
 claim to a private income. The diffei-ence of Comte's from Plato's 
 scheme is that it is social and not directly political. Comte assigns 
 no " secular power " to his ecclesiastical or philosophical class. What 
 Mr Spencer's inductive conclusions also suggest is a social rather 
 than a political transformation, but oue more generalised than 
 Comte's. For the professional class, as conceived by Mr Spencer, 
 includes much more than the philosophic and scientific class. It 
 is far too differentiated to be restored to anything like the homo- 
 geneity of an early priesthood. Hence it could not, as such, 
 become a ruling class, either directly like Plato's guardians, or 
 indirectly like the Comtean hierocracy. 
 
 The point of the reform that suggests itself is this : if the whole 
 social organism is ever to be brought under an ethical ideal of the 
 
APPENDIX 219 
 
 performance of social duties, transcending the conception of an 
 unmitigated struggle for individual profit or subsistence, the class 
 to begin with is the class which, by its origin, has already something 
 of the disinterested character. The liberal professions must be, as 
 it were, brought back to their original principles. The natural 
 method of achieving this would be an extension of the system of 
 public payment as opposed to quasi-commercial competition. Com- 
 petition itself cannot be dispensed with ; but it would then be in 
 view of selection or promotion by qualified judges, and do longer 
 with a view to individual payments from members of the general 
 community taken at random. Payments would be graduated but 
 fixed ; not left to the chances of employment in each particular 
 case. In short, the method would be that of the ecclesiastical 
 and military professions, and of the Civil Service, generalised ; 
 though it would no doubt be necessary, as Comte admitted in 
 the case of teachers, to leave just enough liberty of private practice 
 to guard against the repression of originality. 
 
 To attempt such a reform from below, as is the idea of industrial 
 socialism, is evidently chimerical. Industrial institutions have their 
 first origin in the necessity of subsistence, not in an overflow of 
 unconstrained energy ; and, so far as they are developed from 
 within, they owe their development to the keenest desire for gain. 
 Hence they cannot but be the last to be effectively "moralised." 
 This is just as fatal to Comte's proposal that the supreme secular 
 power should be handed over to the "industrial chiefs" as it 
 is to "social democracy." A purely industrial society could 
 not supply enough disinterested elements for the work of general 
 regulation. The conclusion seems to be that competition with 
 a view to individual profit must, as Plato and Comte equally 
 recognised, be left in the industrial sphere because in that sphere 
 it supplies the only natural and adequate motive of exertion ; but 
 that, even there, it can only be carried on justly and humanely 
 under political regulation by representatives of the whole com- 
 munity. To constitute a complete political society, it is generally 
 allowed that there must be diversity of interests. If we allow 
 that there must also be disinterested elements, then it is evident 
 that these can only be fitly developed by the reduction of material 
 motives, within a certain portion of the society, to their lowest 
 possible limit. The Platonic communism was the first attempt to 
 solve this problem systematically instead of leaving it to accident. 
 
220 APPENDIX 
 
 II. The Gnostics. 
 
 The most accurate appreciation of Gnosticism seems to me to 
 be that of Lipsius in his extremely valuable article in Ersch and 
 Gruber's Encyclopddie. What Lipsius especially makes clear is 
 that Gnosticism was not in its essence a mixture of Christianity 
 and Hellenism, but was a development of Christianity itself, re- 
 garded as a revealed religion, into a speculative philosophy. In 
 its highest philosophical development, which was the system of 
 Valentinus and his successors, it took over elements both from 
 Greek mythology and from Platonic philosophy ; but this was an 
 accretion on the Judaeo-Christian elements that formed its nucleus. 
 An earlier accretion was that which it received during its first 
 period, when it was springing up in Syria. During this period, 
 before it reached Alexandria, it appropriated elements of Semitic 
 rather than of Greek polytheism. These were in the main 
 Phoenician and Syro-Chaldaic. In its allegorical procedure upon 
 the documents both of Judaism and of Christianity, it was only 
 carrying further a method used by Philo among Jewish thinkers, 
 and by those who afterwards came to be regarded as orthodox 
 among the Christians. The difference of the Gnostic "heretics" from 
 thinkers who, like Clement, desired to be also obedient Catholics, was 
 that the former did not accept the limits imposed by the "ecclesias- 
 tical tradition"; that is to say, by the average Christian consciousness 
 as interpreted by systematisers whose aim was fixed upon the universal 
 reception of a common doctrine. Their speculations had thus one 
 of the characters of a free philosophy as distinguished from a 
 philosophy working in subordination to a recognised authoritative 
 standard. In the expression of their philosophy, on the other hand, 
 the Gnostics could not disentangle themselves from mythological 
 imagination. Though essentially philosophies, their systems never 
 arrive at pure conceptual thought, but turn abstractions into 
 persons, and eternal relations of reality into histories of events in 
 time. I The dualism and pessimism of these systems, and their 
 tendency to regard all phenomena as alike illusory — so that the 
 question whether any historical tradition is literally true or not 
 becomes a matter of indifference — much as they may suggest a 
 remoter Eastern origin, are in reality perfectly independent develop- 
 ments of the Judaeo-Christian data from which all the Gnostics set 
 
APPENDIX 221 
 
 out. For the Gnostics themselves, these data, evaporated as they 
 might be, were still the presupposition of their peculiar type of 
 thought. 
 
 The result appears to be that Gnosticism was, as Neo-Platonism 
 was not, a direct outgrowth of the East. It was a serious attempt 
 at the identification of Christianity as a religion with speculations 
 on the origin and end of things. Now this identification of religion 
 with philosophy is a character of the typically Eastern systems of 
 thought. In its manner it represents a form of speculative freedom. 
 The individual Brahman, for example, is perfectly free to elaborate 
 the data of tradition and of past thought in his own way ' ; though 
 popular mythology is never definitely broken with, and the phi- 
 losophy is never quite purely theoretical. It may lead far beyond 
 the practical virtues, through ascetic contemplation to absolute 
 indifference, but the religious purpose of attaining redemption 
 from evil is always the final aim. The case of the Gnostics is 
 similar. They refuse to enter into the Catholic system of authori- 
 tative dogma wrought out by theological experts with a view to 
 the imposition on all of a creed that keeps within the bounds set 
 by the religious consciousness of the many. Philosophy is not 
 with them, as with the Fathers, an instrument taken up as the 
 means of giving precise intellectual form to an accredited doctrine. 
 It is meant to be the speculative unfolding of the traditional 
 data without regard to any organised enforcement of uniformity. 
 On the other side, the Christian Gnostics have not the Greek 
 conception of perfectly disinterested knowledge, which in the Neo- 
 Platonists subsists along with any mystical aim they may cherish 
 as a religious consummation of their philosophy. Whatever stress 
 the Gnostics, by the very name they assume, may lay on know- 
 ledge as opposed to mere faith, it is always knowledge with a view 
 to the religious life that they mean. In the later Stoics we meet 
 with a similar tendency. Here philosophy is passing by way of 
 ethics into religion, as with the Gnostics religion, by the spirit of 
 measureless speculation, passed into philosophy. But of Greek 
 philosophy the very origin and principle of being is " unspeakable 
 desire to see and know." It began with this and to this it returned. 
 The direction to practice, social or personal, is secondary. In the 
 
 1 Sir Alfred Lyall, in "Letters from Vamadeo Sbastri " (Asiatic Stiirfies, 
 Second Series), points out the resemblance on this side between Gnosticism and 
 Hinduism. 
 
222 APPENDIX 
 
 Gnostic cosmogonies, on the contrary, the pursuit of hidden 
 knowledge is the occasion by which the soul of the whole pre- 
 cipitates itself from its pre-mundane union with the highest divinity 
 into a realm of ill. From the evil world of matter, religious 
 enlightenment is the means of escape. Thus it is only as a 
 divinely-given remedy for the suffering soul that knowledge is 
 desirable. Evidently the Gnostics are here quite faithful to their 
 Judaeo-Christian data. 
 
 In their terminology they are even ultra-Christian. Their 
 technical term -rrXrjpwfjia, as the name for the highest sphere of being, 
 is of Pauline origin. And nothing is more characteristic of them 
 than their use of the words 77-reu/Aa for the highest part of the soul ; 
 and 7tviv[j.o.tikoI for the enlightened. Now this is a peculiarly 
 Christian usage 1 . In the tradition of Greek science, when a higher 
 part of the soul is distinguished from the soul generally, it is called 
 vovs. "When the necessity is supposed of placing a subtler material 
 principle between gross matter and the soul, this principle is called 
 TTvev/xa. From a strictly materialist point of view, the 7rvevfxa might 
 come to be identified with the soul ; but it is never taken psycholo- 
 gically in the sense of its higher part. A modern use of "spirit" in 
 a meaning continuous with this, is when "animal spirits" were 
 regarded as the instrument of the soul for moving the limbs. When, 
 on the other hand, we speak of the "spirit" as equivalent to the 
 "mind" of man, with merely a shade of difference in connotation, 
 we are, etymological ly, continuing the Christian usage. The claim 
 that the Trvei^cu-iKoi, or "spiritual men," alone possess true knowledge 
 (yvwo-is), in distinction from the imperfectly enlightened faith (7tio-tis) 
 of the mass of believers, is thus a claim which, by its very terms, 
 declares its origin as outside the Greek tradition. 
 
 Under favourable circumstances, Gnosticism might have become 
 the starting-point for a sort of Christian Brahmanism. It presents, 
 however, this difference from Brahmanism, that it is the speculative 
 development, not of a natural religion like that of the Vedas, but of 
 a religion tracing its origin to a personal founder. Hence perhaps the 
 impossibility of its ever making good its claim to be the true 
 Christianity. When a religion is proclaimed to have been revealed 
 under given circumstances of time and place, it cannot allow its 
 historical tradition to be indefinitely vaporised without ceasing to 
 
 1 See the discussions of the various meanings of irvevixa in Siebeck's 
 Geschichte der Psychologic 
 
APPENDIX 223 
 
 exist. All the religions of this type, whether aggressively intolerant 
 or not, have had to bind themselves by a creed of more or less 
 precision into a Church of more or less exclusiveness. The opposite 
 extremes as regards rigour of ecclesiastical discipline are probably 
 Roman Catholicism and Buddhism ; but the bond exists in all by 
 the mere fact of their origin. Even Gnosticism organised itself into 
 communities which were not simply philosophic schools. It did not, 
 even at its highest point, produce solitary speculations like those of 
 the Brahmans. 
 
 Long into the Middle Ages communities animated by Gnostic 
 ideas persisted, under various names, as a menace to the dominion 
 of historical Christianity. At the end of his Histoire Critique du 
 Gnosticisme, Matter devotes some pages to this prolongation. In 
 those religious heresies of Languedoc which, at the beginning of the 
 thirteenth century, were stamped out by the Albigensian Crusade 
 and the Inquisition, newly centralised and systematised on the 
 initiative of Dominic, the historian is able to trace Gnostic as well 
 as Manichaean ideas. Now the movement of the Albigenses did 
 not spring up quite spontaneously in southern France. It came 
 originally from the European provinces of the Eastern Empire. 
 Both there and in the Asiatic provinces, it had from time to time 
 come to the surface, only to be suppressed more or less effectively by 
 the Emperors at Constantinople. May it not be that some of the 
 Russian sects which the Orthodox Church is still engaged in 
 suppressing are a continuation of the same type of speculative 
 religion? If so, is it not possible that it has still a future? 
 
 Let us suppose a remarkable religious personality to arise in 
 Russia, modern in relation to science and ethics, yet possessing the 
 type of metaphysical imagination characteristic of the Gnostics. 
 The way seeming now open for another revolution in the Judaeo- 
 Christian line of development, a new religion might be proclaimed, 
 accepting the results of modern science and criticism, but, by the 
 aid of an imaginative ontology, still retaining at its centre the 
 Eastern idea of a redeemer and revealer. It would of course be 
 persecuted by Russian Orthodoxy, but this might be the beginning 
 of its success. Throwing itself on Western Europe, it would meel 
 with States practising toleration, and, in the Latin countries, with 
 a decadent religion. In France and Italy, minds are open, and 
 a desire is felt for something to take the place of the hollow 
 structure which, hampering thought and life, can yet only be 
 
224 APPENDIX 
 
 controlled by the State and not abolished. A new enthusiasm, 
 religious and not merely political, would sweep away the wreck. 
 The condition, if anything can be inferred from history, would 
 seem to be a renewed contact of the religious ideas of East 
 and West. For this, the situation of Russia is exactly adapted. 
 Without the personality, any combination of conditions, however 
 favourable in itself, must of course be powerless; but, if the recurrent 
 aspiration of European minds towards a "religion of the future" is 
 more than a vain reminiscence, this seems the direction in which to 
 look. 
 
 Ill Iamblichus and Proclus on Mathematical Science. 
 
 For the theory of knowledge, the views of the later Neo- 
 Platonists on mathematics are still not without interest even to 
 students of Kant. An outline of some of the positions taken up 
 may be found in the book of Iamblichus on the Common Science 
 of Mathematics 1 , and in the two Prologues of Proclus to his 
 Commentary on the first book of Euclid's Elements". Of these 
 Prologues, the first coincides in subject with the treatise of 
 Iamblichus ; dealing with that which is common to arithmetic and 
 geometry, and prior to all special departments of mathematics. The 
 second is an introduction to the general theory of geometry and to 
 Euclid's Elements in particular, and gives in its course a brief 
 chronicle of the history of the science to the time of Euclid. The 
 first Prologue draws from the same sources as the work of 
 Iamblichus, setting forth views that had gradually taken shape in 
 the schools of Plato and Aristotle. In the case of one theory at 
 least in the second, Proclus seems to lay claim to originality. In 
 other cases, he mentions incidentally that he is only selecting a few 
 things from what earlier writers have said. Iamblichus is pro- 
 fessedly expounding the ideas of the "Pythagorean philosophy." 
 
 The starting-point with both writers is the position of Plato at 
 the end of the sixth book of the Republic. The objects of 
 mathematics and the faculty of understanding (SiaVom) that deals 
 
 1 Iamblichi de Communi Mathematica Scientia Liber, ed. N. Festa, 1891. 
 (Teubner.) 
 
 2 Prodi Diadochi in Primum Euclidis Elementorum Librvm Commentarii, ex 
 rec. G. Friedlein, 1873. (Teubner.) 
 
APPENDIX 225 
 
 with them come between dialectic and its objects above, and sense- 
 perception and its objects below. Being thus intermediate, are 
 mathematical forms and the reasonings upon them derivatives of 
 sense-perception, or are they generated by the soul? In the view 
 most clearly brought out by Proclus, they result from the productive 
 activity of the soul, but not without relation to a prior intellectual 
 norm, conformity to which is the criterion of their truth. What is 
 distinctive of Proclus is the endeavour to determine exactly the 
 character of this mental production. Iamblichus does not so 
 specially discuss this, but lays stress on the peculiar fixity of 
 relations among the objects of mathematics. Mathematical objects 
 are not forms that can depart from their underlying matter, nor yet 
 qualities, like the heat of fire, which though actually inseparable 
 can be thought of as taken away. The forms that constitute number 
 and extension have a coherence which does not admit of this kind 
 of disaggregation, whether real or ideal. 
 
 According to the view made specially clear by Iamblichus, 
 mathematical science does not take over its employment of division 
 and definition and syllogism from dialectic. The mathematical 
 processes to which these terms are applied are peculiar to mathe- 
 matics. From itself it discovers and perfects and elaborates them ; 
 and it has tests of its own, and needs no other science towards the 
 order of speculation proper to it. Its difference from dialectic is 
 that it works with its own assumptions, and does not consider 
 things "simply," without assumptions 1 . As Proclus also says, 
 there is only one science without assumptions (avvn-oOeTos). No 
 special science demonstrates its own principles or institutes an 
 inquiry about them. Thus the investigator of nature (6 cpvarioXoyos) 
 assumes that there is motion, and then sets out from that 
 determinate principle ; and so with all special inquirers and 
 practitioners 2 . 
 
 Both writers, while they make considerations about the practical 
 utility of knowledge subordinate, yet repeatedly draw attention to 
 the applications, direct and indirect, of mathematics to the arts of 
 life. Proclus cites Archimedes as a conspicuous example of the 
 
 1 De Comm. Math. Scieiltia, pp. 89 — 90: d<£' iavTrjs ovv eupLo-Kei re avra. kclI 
 reXeiol ko.1 el-epyafcrai, rd re oUela avTrj Ka\ws dtde doKi/J-dfrut, /ecu ov detrai d'XXf/s 
 emo~Tr)p.ris 7rp6s ttt)v oiKelav deupiav. ov yap rb dirXws Kaddirep rj SiaXe/cTi/ci?, dXXd rd 
 v<p' eavTrjv SiayLvwcTKei, olKeiws re avrd dewpe? Ka66<rov avrrj vn6K(iTa.i. 
 
 2 Prologus n., p. 75. 
 
 w. 15 
 
226 APPENDIX 
 
 power conferred by science when directed to practical invention. 
 And science in general, as both he and Iamblichus insist, derives its 
 necessity from the mathematical principles on which it depends. 
 The perception of the peculiar scientific importance of mathematics, 
 grounded in the necessity of its demonstrations, they ascribe to 
 Pythagoras ; who, as both declare in almost the same terms, brought 
 it to the form of a liberal discipline. By this is meant that, instead 
 of treating it as a collection of isolated propositions, each discovered 
 for itself, Pythagoras began to impress on it the systematically 
 deductive character which it assumed among the Greeks. In the 
 order of genetic development, men turn to knowledge for its 
 own sake when the care about necessary things has ceased to be 
 pressing 1 . 
 
 The classification of the mathematical sciences given in the two 
 treatises is the same. First in order comes the " common mathe- 
 matical science" which sets forth the principles that form a bond of 
 union between arithmetic and geometry. The special branches of 
 mathematics are four : namely, arithmetic, geometry, music, and 
 spherics ((KpatptK^). Music is a derivative of arithmetic ; containing 
 the theory of complex relations of numbers as distinguished from 
 the numbers themselves. Spherics is similarly related to geometry ; 
 dealing with abstract motion prior to the actual motion of bodies. 
 To beginners it is more difficult than astronomy, which finds aid in 
 the observation of moving bodies ; but as pure theory it is prior 2 . 
 Next come the various branches of mixed mathematics, such as 
 mechanics, optics, astronomy, and generally the sciences that employ 
 instruments for weighing, measuring and observing. These owe 
 their less degree of precision and cogency to the mixture of sense- 
 perception with pure mathematical demonstration. Last in the 
 
 1 Prologus i., p. 29: ko.1 yap iraaa 77 yeveins /cat r) iv avrrj arpecpofiivr) ttjs ipvxv* 
 fwr/ ir£<pvKev airb tov dreXoDs els to T^Xeiov x u P e ^ v - Cf. Stoix- ©eoX. 45. 
 
 2 With the substitution of astronomy for "spherics," the four Pythagorean 
 sciences of Iamblichus and Proclus form the "quadrivium," or second division 
 of the "seven liberal arts," of mediaeval tradition. (The "trivium," according 
 to the list usually given, comprises grammar, dialectic and rhetoric.) A more 
 curious point of contact is the identity of the conception of " spherics" — simply 
 as classification of science and apart from philosophical theory of knowledge — 
 with Comte's "rational mechanics," regarded by him as the branch of mathe- 
 matics immediately prior to astronomy, which is the first of the physical 
 sciences. 
 
APPENDIX 227 
 
 theoretic order come simple data of perception brought together as 
 connected experience (ifx.Trei.pia.). 
 
 The ground of this order is to be found in the rationalistic 
 theory of knowledge common to the school. As Proclus remarks, 
 the soul is not a tablet empty of words, but is ever written on and 
 writing on itself — and moreover, as he adds, written on by pure 
 intellect which is prior to it in the order of being. Upon such a 
 basis of psychology and consequent theory of knowledge, he goes on 
 to put the specific question about geometrical demonstration and the 
 activity of the soul in its production. How can geometry enable us 
 to rise above matter to unextended thought, when it is occupied 
 with extension, which is simply the result of the inability of matter 
 to receive immaterial ideas otherwise than as spread out and apart 
 from one another ? And how can the Siavoia, proceeding as it does 
 by unextended notions, yet be the source of the spatial constructions 
 of geometry? The solution is that geometrical ideas, existing un- 
 extended in the Siayoia, are projected upon the "matter" furnished 
 by the epavraaia. Hence the plurality and difference in the figures 
 with which geometrical science works. The idea of the circle as 
 understood (in the StaVoia) is one ; as imagined (in the cpavraa-ia) it 
 is many ; and it is some particular circle as imagined that geometry 
 must always use in its constructions. At the same time, it is not the 
 perceived circle (the circle in the alo-drjais) that is the object of pure 
 geometry. This, with its unsteadiness and inaccuracy, is the object 
 only of applied geometry. The true geometrician, while necessarily 
 working by the aid of imagination, strives towards the unextended 
 unity of the understanding with its immaterial notions. Hence the 
 disciplinary power of geometry as set forth by Plato 1 . According 
 to this view, those are right who say that all geometrical propositions 
 are in a sense theorems, since they are concerned with that which 
 ever is and does not come into being ; but those also are right who 
 
 1 In his theory of " geometrical matter," Proclus remarks, he has taken the 
 liberty of dissenting from Porphyry and most of the Platonic interpreters. See 
 Prologus n. , pp. 56 — 7 : irepi fxev ovv rrjs yew/jLerpiKrjs i/Xtjs rotravra e"xoiJ.ei> X^7«e 
 ovk ayvoovvres, oca. ko\ 6 <f>iko<ro<pos llop<pi'ipios ev rots (Xvliluktois yeypatptv Kal ol 
 ttXuvtoi rCiv lWarwviK&v oiaraTTOvrai, avpL<pujv6repa 8e elvai ravra reus yew/xerptKah 
 e<podois vo/xi^ovres Kal to HX&twvi Siavorjra KaXovvri to. viroKel/xeva rrj yewixeTpiq.. 
 G\<vq.5ci yap otv ravra d\\r)\ois, 8i6ri rwv yeufj.erpiKun' d8£>v ai li£v alriai, Ka6' as 
 Kal 77 didvota 7rpo/3d\\e( ras aTrodei^eis, iv avrrj ir pov<p(arr)Ka<n.v , avrd 5f eKa<rra ra 
 diaipou/xeva Kal <rvvri.diLi.eva axn^ara rrepl tt)v (pavraaiav 7rpo^^\r]Tai. 
 
228 APPENDIX 
 
 say that all are in a sense problems, for, in the way of theorems too, 
 nothing can be discovered without a going forth of the understanding 
 to the " intelligible matter " furnished by the imagination, and this 
 process resembles genetic production 1 . The division once made, 
 however, the theoretic character is seen not only to extend to all but 
 to predominate in all. 
 
 1 Prologus ii., pp. 77—79. 
 
INDEX OF NAMES. 
 
 Aedesius, 122, 133, 134 
 
 Aenesidemus, 33 
 
 Aeschylus, 2 
 
 Agathias, 183 
 
 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 158 n. 
 
 Alfred the Great, 188 
 
 Alypius, 123 
 
 Anielius, 29, 30, 34, 36, 100, 110 
 
 Ammonius Saccas, 28, 20, 32, 33 
 
 Aninionius (pupil of Proclus), 185 
 
 Auaxagoras, 11, 24 
 
 Antoninus, M. Aurelius. See Aurelius 
 
 Antoninus (Neo-Platonic philosopher), 
 
 133 
 Apollonius of Tyana, 23, 114, 117 n., 
 
 138 
 Aquinas, 192 ff. 
 
 Archer-Hind, E. D., 72 n., 184 n. 
 Archimedes, 225 
 Aristophanes, 24, 217 
 Aristotle, 8 n. , etc. 
 Asclepiodotus, 185 
 Augustine, St, 187, 193, 197 n. 
 Aurelius, M., 3, 4, 34 
 Avicebron (Ibn Gebirol), 195 
 
 Bacon, Francis, 201, 202 
 Bacon, Roger, 196 
 Baeumker, CI., 72 n. 
 Bardesanes, 121 
 Benn, A. W., 12 n., 15, 206 
 Berkeley, 30, 41, 42, 50, 202 
 Bigg, C, 37 
 Boccaccio, 196 
 
 Boethius, 111, 187 
 Bosanquet, B., 91 n. 
 Bouillet, M. N., 193 n. 
 Bruno, 22, 197 ff., 215 
 Burnet, J., 8 n., 10 n. 
 
 Campanella, 199 
 Carneades, 120 
 Celsus, 137, 140, 145 n., 146 
 Chaignet, A. E., 182 n. 
 Chosroes, 183 
 Chrysanthius, 122, 134 
 Chiysippus, 120 
 Cicero, 1 n., 13, 29 n., 33, 188 
 Clement (of Alexandria), 27, 220 
 Comte, 5 n., 160, 209, 218, 226 n. 
 Constantine, 3, 132, 142 n. 
 Constantius, 132, 151 n. 
 Cudworth, 20, 200 
 Cyril, St (Bishop of Alexandria), 
 145 ff., 157 
 
 Damascius, 181 ff. 
 
 Dante, 6, 193 ff. 
 
 Democritus, 10, 11, 200 
 
 Descartes, 9, 34, 44, 72 n., 200 ff. 
 
 Dexippus, 136 
 
 Diocletian, 3 
 
 Diogenes, 139 
 
 Dionysius the Areopagite, 188, 193 
 
 Dodwell, H. (the elder), 124 n. 
 
 Dominic, St, 223 
 
 Drummond, J., 36 n. 
 
 Duns Scotus, l!l"> 
 
230 
 
 INDEX OF NAMES 
 
 Empedocles, 11, 121, 211, 212 
 
 Epictetus, 139, 184 
 
 Epicurus, 12, 29 n., 200 
 
 Erigena, John Scotus, 188, 195, 204 
 
 Euclid, 224 ff. 
 
 Eunapius, 123, 135, etc. 
 
 Euripides, 22 
 
 Eusebius (Bishop of Caesarea), 32, 
 
 139 
 Eusebius (Neo-Platonic philosopher), 
 
 134 
 Eustathius, 132 
 
 Ficino, Marsilio, 196 ff. 
 Firmus, Castricius, 115 
 
 Gallienus, 30 
 Gibbon, E., 133 n., 182 
 Goethe, 199 
 Grote, G. , 133 n. 
 
 Hatch, E., 19 n. 
 
 Hegel, 205 
 
 Heraclitus, 10, 36, 73 
 
 Herennius, 33 
 
 Hermias, 185 
 
 Herodotus, 1 n., 8 n. 
 
 Hesiod, 18 n., 100 
 
 Hierocles (Proconsul of Bithynia), 
 
 138, 146 
 Hierocles (of Alexandria), 32, 157 
 Hobbes, 9, 200, 207, 218 
 Homer, 18, 96, 110, 149, 161 
 Hume, 204 
 Hypatia, 28, 156 
 
 Iamblichus. See ch. vn., etc. 
 Isidore, 181. (Not identical with the 
 " Isidorus " mentioned at p. 183.) 
 
 Jerome, St, 109, 133 n. 
 Joannes Philoponus, 183 n., 185 n. 
 Julian. See ch. viii., etc. 
 Justinian, 156, 182 
 Juvenal, 22 
 
 Kant, 204, 224 
 
 Keim, Th., 20 n., 138 n. 
 
 Leibniz, 202, 205 
 
 Lipsius, R. A., 220 
 
 Locke, 201, 203 
 
 Longinus, 33, 34, 36, 39 n., 73, 109 
 
 Lucian, 22 
 
 Lucretius, 12 n., 200 
 
 Lyall, A. C, 221 n. 
 
 Macarius Magnes, 146 
 
 Machiavelli, 6 
 
 Macrobius, 188 
 
 Maine, H. S., 5 n. 
 
 Maistre, J. de, 16 n. 
 
 Marcella, 109 
 
 Marinus, 144, etc. See Proclus. 
 
 Matter, A. J., 27, 223 
 
 Maurice, F. D., 136 n. 
 
 Maximus, 134 
 
 Mirandola, Pico della, 163 n. 
 
 Morbeka, William of, 162 
 
 More, H., 200 
 
 Moses, 39, 141, 146 ff. 
 
 Nemesius, 187 
 
 Neumann, C. J., 138 n., 145 ff. 
 
 Newton, 200 
 
 Numa, 151 
 
 Numenius, 34 ff., 138 
 
 Ockham, William of, 195 
 Olympiodorus (teacher of Proclus), 
 
 157 n., 159 
 Olympiodorus (Commentator on Plato 
 
 and Aristotle), 157, 185 
 Origen (the ecclesiastical writer), 27, 
 
 33, 138 n., 197 
 Origen (Platonic philosopher), 33 
 
 Parmenides, 10, 11, 57, 216 
 
 Petrarch, 6, 195 
 
 Phidias, 92 
 
 Philo Judaeus, 27, 34 ff., 88 n., 106, 
 
 138, 220 
 Plato, 9, etc. 
 
 Plotinus. See chs. iv., v., vi., etc. 
 Plutarch (of Chaeronea), 34, 73, 120, 
 
 122 
 Plutarch (of Athens), 150 ff. 
 
INDEX OF NAMES 
 
 •231 
 
 Porphyry. Sec ch. vn., etc. 
 Preller, L. See Hitter 
 Priscus, 134, 135 
 Proclus. See ch. ix., etc. 
 Prohaeresius, 124 
 
 Pythagoras, 8, 22, 114, 121, 130, 147, 
 220 
 
 Read, C, 209 n. 
 
 Renan, E., 4 n., 140 n., 184 n., 
 190 n. 
 
 Ritter, H. and Preller, L. Cited as 
 R. P. The references are to Hiatoria 
 Philosophiue Graecae, 7th ed. 
 
 Rogatianus, 30 
 
 Rohde, E., 18 n. 
 
 Sallust (Praetorian Prefect under 
 
 Julian), 136 
 Scotus, John. See Erigena 
 Scotus, John Duns. See Duns 
 Sextus Enipiricus, 33 
 Shelley, P. B., 203 
 Siebeck, H., 44, 53, 72 n., 206, 
 
 222 n. 
 Simon, J., 27, 38 n., 77 n., 85 n., 
 
 109, 110 n., 114 n. 
 Sirnplicius, 183, 184, 211 
 Socrates (the philosopher), 11, 12, 
 
 13, 19, 29, 42, 144 n., 163, 206 
 Socrates (ecclesiastical historian), 157 
 Sopater, 124 n., 132 
 
 Sorel, G., 20 n. 
 
 Sosipatra, 133 
 
 Spencer, H., 214, 217 ff. 
 
 Spenser, E., 203 
 
 Spinoza, 101, 162, 174, 202, 204, 
 
 205 
 Suetonius, 3, 4 n., 17 n. 
 Synesius, 157, 188 
 Syrianus, 157 ff. 
 
 Tacitus, 3, 4 n., 140 
 Tannery, P., 10 n. 
 Taylor, T., 193 n. 
 Tertullian, 21, 186 
 Thales, 206 
 
 Themistius, 133, 158 n. 
 Theodore of Asine, 135, 164 
 Theodoret, 138 
 Theophrastus, 116, 120. 
 
 Vacherot, E., 27, 35 n., 85 n., 93, 
 
 158 n., 198 n. 
 Valentinus, 220 
 
 Xenophanes, 10, 21 
 Xenophon, 13 
 
 Zeller, E. The references are to Die 
 Philosophic der Grieehen, n. 1, 
 4th ed.; n. 2, in. 2, 3rd ed. 
 
 Zeno (the Stoic), 13 
 
 Zoroaster, 110 
 
 Cambridge: printed ry .t. and c. f. clay, at the university press. 
 
H 
 
7 D AV t 
 
 VI /*V 
 
 14 DAY USE 
 
 RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED 
 LOAN DEPT. 
 
 This book is due on the last date stamped below, or 
 
 on the date to which renewed. 
 
 Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. 
 
 5 JCL5BGC 
 
 wiiii 42 lo g 
 
 iW* 
 
 6\B' 
 
 tr""/"^*r> 
 
 ^v 
 
 KETCD LD 
 
 AUG 61SS8 
 
 JUN 1 4 1961 
 
 aO^ 
 
 «,9fcC 
 
 asjja m 
 
 'D LD 
 
 REC!D I P 
 
 FEB 2 19ffl 
 
 MAY 10 1962 
 
 
 :ctp t.D 
 
 JUN 7 — tsefr 
 
 I7Jan'61RT| 
 
 LD 21A-50m-8,'57 
 (C8481sl0)476B 
 
 General Library 
 
 University of California 
 
 Berkeley 
 
YC 
 
 31507 
 
 LIBRARY USE 
 
 RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED 
 
 LOAN DEPT. 
 
 THIS BOOK IS DUE BEFORE CLOSING TIME 
 ON LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW 
 
 
 
 
 
 REC'D LD 
 
 
 WW 13*63 -8 PM 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 « 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 
 LD 62A-20m-9,'63 . , . General L ibrary 
 (E709slO)9412A University of California 
 
 Berkeley