OF THE UNIVERSITY OF w THE NEO-PLATONISTS. Uontom: C. J. CLAY and SONS, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE, AVE MARIA LANE. ffilaggofo: 50, WELLINGTON STREET. Hftp?ig: F. A. BROCKHAUS. £eUJ Jfork: THE MAGMILLAN COMPANY. Bombau: E. SEYMOUR HALE. THE NEO-PLATONISTS: A STUDY IN THE HISTORY OF HELLENISM. BY THOMAS WHITTAKER, AUTHOR OF 'ESSAYS AND NOTICES, PHILOSOPHICAL AND PSYCHOLOGICAL.' CAMBRIDGE: AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. 1901 [All Rights reserved.] W-5 Cambrrtigr : PRINTED BY J. AND C. F. CLAY, AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS. CONTENTS. Introduction PAGE vii CHAPTER I. Graeco-Roman Civilisation in its Political Development CHAPTER II. The Stages of Greek Philosophy CHAPTER III. Religious Developments in Later Antiquity CHAPTER IV. Plotinus and his Nearest Predecessors 18 27 CHAPTER V. The Phi losophical System of Plotinus 41 1. Psychology . 44 2. Metaphysics ...... . 54 3. Cosmology and Theodicy .... . 71 4. Aesthetics ....... . 88 5. Ethics CHAPTER VI. . 92 99 S9851 VI CONTENTS CHAPTER VII. PAGE The Diffusion of Neo-Platonism 108 1. Porphyry 108 2. Iarnblichus .122 3. The School of Iarnblichus 132 CHAPTER VIII. The Polemic against Christianity 137 CHAPTER IX. The Athenian School 156 1. The Academy becomes Neo-Platonic . . . .156 2. Proclus 158 3. The End of the Platonic Succession . . . .181 CHAPTER X. The Influence of Neo-Platonism 186 CHAPTER XI. Conclusion 206 APPENDIX. I. The Communism of Plato 217 II. The Gnostics 220 III. Iamblichus and Proclus on Mathematical Science . 224 Index of Names -2-2U INTRODUCTION. ^T^HAT the history of ancient culture effectively ends with -*- the second century of the Christian era is an impression not infrequently derived from histories of literature and even of philosophy. The period that still remains of antiquity is obviously on its practical side a period of dissolution, in which every effort is required to maintain the fabric of the Roman State against its external enemies. And, spiritually, a new religious current is evidently beginning to gain the mastery ; so that, with the knowledge we have of what followed, we can already see in the third century the break-up of the older form of inner as well as of outer life. In the second century too appeared the last writers who are usually thought of as classical. The end of the Stoical philosophy as a living system coincides with the death of Marcus Aurelius. And with Stoicism, it is often thought, philosophy ceased to have an independent life. It definitely entered the service of polytheism. In its struggle with Christianity it appropriated Oriental superstitions. It lost its scientific character in devotion to the practice of magic. It became a mystical theology instead of a pursuit of reasoned truth. The structure of ancient culture, like the fabric of the Empire, was in process of decay at once in form and content. In its permeation by foreign elements, it already manifests a transition to the new type that was to supersede it. An argument for this view might be found in a certain niodernness" which has often been noted in the later classical literature. Since the ancient type was dissolved in the end Vlll INTRODUCTION to make way for the modern, we might attribute the early appearance of modern characteristics to the new growth accompanying incipient dissolution. The general falling-off in literary quality during the late period we should ascribe to decay ; the wider and more consciously critical outlook on life, which we call modern, to the movement of the world into its changed path. Thus there would be a perfectly continuous process from the old civilisation to the new. On the other hand, we may hold that the " modernness " of the late classical period does not indicate the beginning of the intermediate phase of culture, but is a direct approximation to the modern type, due to the existence of a long intellectual tradition of a similar kind. If the latter view be taken, then we must regard the dissolution of the ancient world as proceeding, not by a penetration of new elements into the older form of culture so as to change the type, but indirectly through the conquest of the practical world by a new power; so that, while ancient culture was organically continuous as long as it lasted, it finally came to an end as an organism. The new way into which the world had passed was directed by a new religion, and this appropriated in its own manner the old form of culture, bringing it under the law of its peculiar type. Thus one form was substituted for another, but the first did not spontaneously pass into the second. There was no absolute break in history ; for the ancient system of education remained, though in a reduced form, and passed by continuous transition into another ; but the directing power was changed. The kind of " modern " character the ancient culture assumed in the end was thus an anticipation of a much later period, not a genuine phase of transition. In confirmation of the latter view, it might be pointed out that the culture of the intermediate period, when it assumed at length its appropriate form, had decidedly less of the specifically modern character than even that of early antiquity with all its remoteness. Be this as it may in pure literature, it is certain that INTRODUCTION IX the latest phase of ancient philosophy had all the marks of an intrinsic development. All its characteristic positions can be traced to their origin in earlier Greek systems. Affinities can undoubtedly be found in it with Oriental thought, more parti- cularly with that of India; but with this no direct contact can be shown. In its distinctive modes of thought, it was wholly Hellenic. So far as it was " syncretistic," it was as philosophy of religion, not as pure philosophy. On this side, it was an attempt to bring the various national cults of the Roman Empire into union under the hegemony of a philosophical conception. As philosophy, it was indeed " eclectic," but the eclecticism was under the direction of an original effort of specu- lative thought, and was exercised entirely within the Hellenic tradition. And, in distinction from pure literature, philosophy made its decisive advance after practical dissolution had set in. It was not until the middle of the third century that the metaphysical genius of Plotinus brought to a common point the Platonising movement of revival which was already going on before the Christian era. The system founded by Plotinus, and known distinctively as " Neo-Platonism," was that which alone gave unity to all that remained of Greek culture during the period of its survival as such. Neo-Platonism became, for three centuries, the one philosophy of the Graeco- Roman world. It preserved the ancient type of thought from admixture with alien elements ; and, though defeated in the struggle to give direction to the next great period of human history, it had a powerful influence on the antagonist system, which, growing up in an intellectual atmosphere pervaded by its modes of thought, incorporated much of its distinctive teaching. The persistence of philosophy as the last living force of the ancient world might have been predicted. Philosophic thought in antiquity was the vital centre of liberal education as it has never been for the modern world. There were of course those who disparaged it in contrast with empirical practice or with rhetorical ability, but, for all that, it had the direction of X INTRODUCTION practical thought so far as there was general direction at all. The dissolution by which the ancient type was broken down did not begin at the centre but at the extremities. The free development of the civic life both of Greece and of Rome had been checked by the pressure of a mass of alien elements imperfectly assimilated. These first imposed a political prin- ciple belonging to a different phase of culture. To the new movement thus necessitated, the culture of the ancient world, whatever superficial changes it might undergo, did not inwardly respond. Literature still looked to the past for its models. Philosophy least of all cared to adapt itself. It became instead the centre of resistance to the predominant movement, — to overweening despotism under the earlier Caesars, to the oncoming theocracy when the republican tradition was com- pletely in the past. The latest philosophers of antiquity were pre-eminently " The kings of thought Who waged contention with their time's decay." And their resistance was not the result of pessimism, of a disposition to see nothing but evil in the actual movement of things The Neo-Platonists in particular were the most convinced of optimists, at the very time when, as they well knew, the whole movement of the world was against them. The}- held it for their task to maintain as far as might be the type of life which they had themselves chosen as the best ; knowing that there was an indefinite future, and that the alternating rhythms in which, with Heraclitus and the Stoics, they saw the cosmic harmony 1 and the expression of providential reason, would not cease with one period. If they did not actually predict the revival of their thought after a thousand years, they would not have been in the least surprised to see it. More than once has that thought been revived, and with various aims ; nor is its interest even yet exhausted. The first revival the philosophers themselves would have cared for was 1 waXivrovos ap/novh] k6<t/j.ov oKodcrrep Xvprjs xai to^ov. — Heraclitus. INTRODUCTION XI that of the fifteenth century, when, along with their master Plato, they became the inspirers of revolt against the system of mediaeval theology that had established itself long after their defeat. Another movement quite in their spirit, but this time not an insurgent movement, was that of the Cambridge Platonists in the seventeenth century, which went back to Neo-Platonism for the principles of its resistance to the exclusive dominance of the new " mechanical philosophy." As the humanist academies of Italy had appealed against Scholastic dogmatism to the latest representatives in antiquity of free philosophic inquiry, so the opponents in England of " Hobbism " went for support to those who in their own day had intellectually refuted the materialism of the Stoics and Epicureans. Since then, many schools and thinkers have shown affinity with Neo-Platonic thought ; and, apart from direct historic attach- ment or spontaneous return to similar metaphysical ideas, there has been a deeper continuous influence of which something will have to be said. Within the last fifty years or thereabouts, the Neo-Platonists, though somewhat neglected in comparison with the other schools of antiquity, have been made the subject of important historical work. To French philosophers who began as disciples of Cousin, a philosophy that could be described as at once "eclectic" and "spiritualist" naturally became an object of interest. The result of that interest was seen in the brilliant works of Vacherot and Jules Simon. For definite and positive information on the doctrines of the school, the portion of Zeller's Philosopliie der Griechen that deals with the period is of the highest value. In English, Mr Benn's chapter on " The Spiritualism of Plotinus," in his Greek Philosophers, brings out well the advance in subjective thought made by the latest on the earlier philosophies of Greece. Of special importance in relation to this point are the chapters on Plotinus and his successors in Siebeck's Gescliichte der Psycliologie. An extensive work on the psychology of the school has appeared since in the xii INTRODUCTION last two volumes of M. Chaignet's Psychologie des Grecs. Recent English contributions to the general exposition of the Neo-Platonist philosophy are Dr C. Bigg's volume in the " Chief Ancient Philosophies " Series (S.P.C.K.), and Mr F. W. BusselPs stimulating book on The School of Plato, which, however, deals more with preliminaries than with the school itself. In the later historical treatment of Neo-Platonism a marked tendency is visible to make less of the supposed " Oriental " character of the school and more of its real dependence on the preceding philosophies of Greece. This may be seen in Zeller as compared with Vacherot, and in Mr Benn as compared with Zeller. Of the most recent writers, M. Chaignet and Dr Bigg, approaching the subject from different sides, conclude in almost the same terms that the system of Plotinus was through and through Hellenic. And, as M. Chaignet points out, Plotinus, in all essentials, fixed the doctrine of the school. Whatever attractions the thought of the East as vaguely surmised may have had for its adherents, their actual contact with it was slight. When the school took up a relation to the practical world, it was as the champion of "Hellenism" (EWyivtafios) against the " barbarian audacity " of its foes. On the whole, however, it did not seek to interfere directly with practice, but recognised the impossibility of modifying the course which the world at large was taking, and devoted itself to the task of carrying forward thought and preserving culture. Hence a history of Neo-Platonism must be in the main a history of doctrines internally developed, not of polemic with extraneous systems of belief. At the same time the causes must be indicated of its failure, and of the failure of philosophy, to hold for the next age the intellectual direction of the world, — a failure not unqualified. To bring those causes into view, it will be necessary to give a brief sketch of the political, as well as of the philosophical and religious movement to the time of Plotinus. For the ultimate causes of the triumph of another INTRODUCTION Xlll system were social more than they were intellectual, and go fal- lback into the past. Of the preceding philosophical development, no detailed history can be attempted. As in the case of the political and religious history, all that can be done is to put the course of events in a light by which its general bearing may be made clear. In relation to the inner movement, the aim will be to show precisely at what point the way was open for an advance on previous philosophies, — au advance which, it may be said by anticipation, Neo-Platonism did really succeed in making secure even for the time when the fortunes of independent philosophy were at their lowest. Then, when the history of the school itself has been set forth in some detail, a sketch, again reduced to as brief compass as possible, must be given of the return of the modern world to the exact point where the thought of the ancient world had ceased, and of the continued influence of the Neo-Platonic conceptions on modern thought. Lastly, an attempt will be made to state the law of the development ; and, in relation to this, something will be said of the possibilities that still remain open for the type of thought which has never been systematised with more perfection than in the school of Plotinus. "Onpourrait dire, sans trop d'exageration, que l'histoire morale des premiers siecles de notre ere est dans l'histoire du platonisme." Matter, Histoire Critique du Gnosticisme, livre viii. ch. 28. CHAPTER I. GftAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT. Broadly, the political- history of classical antiquity almost from the opening of the historic period may be described as a slow passage from the condition of self-governing common- wealths with a subordinate priesthood to the condition of a theocratic despotism. This was a reduction of the West to the polity of the civilised East. In the old Oriental monarchies known to the classical world, the type was that of a consecrated despot ruling with the support and under the direction of a priesthood socially supreme. Immemorial forms of it were to be seen in Egypt and in the Assyrio- Babylonian civilisation on which the conquering Persian monarchy was superimposed. In Persia had appeared the earliest type of a revealed as distinguished from an organised natural religion. And here were the beginnings of the systematic intolerance at first so puzzling to the Greeks 1 . Intolerance, however, did not till 1 Herodotus, though he knew and sympathised with the refusal of the Persian religion to ascribe visible form to the divinity, saw in the persecution of the Egyptian cult by Cambyses and in the burning of Greek temples by order of Xerxes, nothing but acts of wanton impiety. They had come to be better understood in the time of Cicero, who definitely ascribes the latter to the motive of pious intolerance. See De Rep. iii. 9, 14. After a reference to the animal deities of Egypt as illustrating tbe variety of religious customs among civilised men, the exposition proceeds : " Deinde Graeciae sicut apud nos, delubra magnifica humanis consecrata simulacris, quae Persae nefaria putaverunt, eamque unam ob causam Xerxes inflammari Atheniensium faua iussisse dicitur, quod deos, quorum domus esset omnis hie mundus, inclusos parietibus contineri nefas esse duceret." W. 1 2 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i later and from a new starting-point assume a permanently aggressive form. With the Persians, conquest over alien nationalities led to some degree of tolerance for their inherited religions. The origin of the monarchies of Egypt and of Western Asia is a matter of conjecture. To the classical world they appeared as a finished type. The ancient European type of polity was new and independent. It did not spring out of the Oriental type by way of variation. In investigating its accessible beginnings we probably get nearer to political origins than we can in the East. We have there before our eyes the plastic stage which in the East can only be conjectured. The Greek tragic poets quite clearly distinguished their own early con- stitutional monarchies with incompletely developed germs of aristocracy and democracy from Oriental despotism. While these monarchies lasted, they were probably not very sharply marked off, in the general consciousness, from other monarchical institutions. The advance to formal republicanism revealed at once a new type of polity and the preparation for it at an earlier stage. That this was to be the conquering type might very well be imagined. Aeschylus puts into the mouth of the Persian elders a lamentation over the approaching downfall of kingship in Asia itself 1 . Yet this prophecy, as we know, is further from being realised now than it may have appeared then. And, though organised despotism on the great scale was thrown back into Asia by the Persian wars, the later history of Europe for a long period is the history of its return. The republican type of culture was fixed for all time 8 , first in life and then in literature, by the brief pre-eminence of Athens. The Greek type of free State, however, from its restriction to a city, and the absence of a representative system, 1 oi)5' is yav wponiTVovTes dp^ovrai ' fla<Tihela yap 8i6\o)\ev iVx^s- oi'5' Ztl yKCoaaa ppoToicnv iv <pvkaKah' XeXi'rtu yap Xaos iXevdepa /Sdfetv, ibs iXvdri frrybv dX^aj. Pers. 590 — 6. 2 <='s rbv airavra avdpdyirwv §Lov. Herod, vi. 109. i] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 3 with other causes, could not maintain itself against the inroads of the monarchical principle, which at that time had the power of conferring unity on a larger aggregate. The Macedonian monarchy, originally of the constitutional type, became, through its conquests at once over Greece and Asia, essentially an Oriental monarchy — afterwards a group of monarchies — dis- tinguished only by its appropriation of the literary culture of Greece. Later, the republican institutions of Rome, which succeeded those of Greece as the type of political freedom, broke down, in spite of their greater flexibility and power of incorporating subjects 1 , through a combination of the causes that affected Greece and Macedon separately. Perhaps the imperial monarchy was a necessity if the civilised world was to be kept together for some centuries longer, and not to break up into warring sections. Still, it was a lapse to a lower form of polity. And the republican resistance can be historically justified. The death of Caesar showed his inheritors that the hour for formal monarchy was not yet come. The complete shaping of the Empire on the Oriental model was, in fact, postponed to the age of Diocletian and Constantine. Mean- while, the emperor not being formally monarch, and the republic remaining in name, the whole system of education continued to be republican in basis. The most revered classics were those that had come down from the time of freedom. Declamations against tyrants were a common exercise in the schools. And the senatorial opposition, which still cherished the ethical ideal of the republic, came into power with the emperors of the second century. What it has become the fashion to call the "republican prejudices" of Tacitus and Suetonius were adopted by Marcus Aurelius, who, after citing with admiration the names of Cato and Brutus, along with those of later heroes of the Stoical protestation against 1 That the Romans themselves were conscious of this, may be seen for example in a speech of the Emperor Claudius as recorded by Tacitus (Ann. xi. 24): "Quid aliud exitio Lacedaemoniis et Atheniensibus fuit, quamquam armis pollerent, nisi quod victos pro alienigenis arcebant? at conditor nostri Romulus tautum sapientia valuit, ut plerosque populos eodem die hostes, dein cives habuerit." 1—2 4 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i Caesarean despotism, holds up before himself " the idea of a polity in which there is the same law for all, a polity ad- ministered with regard to equal rights and equal freedom of speech, and the idea of a kingly government which respects most of all the freedom of the governed." 1 Here the demand for administrative unity might seem to be reconciled with the older ideal ; but the Stoic emperor represented the departing and not the coming age. There was a discrepancy between the imperial monarchy on the one hand, potentially absolute, though limited by the deference of the ruler for ancient forms, and on the other hand the ideal that had come down from the past. The ethics of antiquity had never incorporated absolutism. Now the new religion that was already aiming at the spiritual dominance of the Empire had no tradition that could separate it from the monarchical system. Christian ethics from the first accepted absolutism as its political datum. The Christian apologists under the Antonines represent themselves as a kind of legiti- mists, — praying, in the time of Marcus Aurelius, that the right of succession of Commodus may be recognised and the blessing of hereditary kingship secured 2 . Christianity therefore, once accepted, consecrated for the time an ideal in accordance with the actual movement of the world. In substituting the notion of a monarch divinely appointed for the apotheosis of the emperors, it gave a form less unendurable in civilised Europe to a servility which, in its pagan form, appearing as an Asiatic superstition, had been something of a scandal to the rulers who were in a manner compelled to countenance it. The result, unmodified by new factors, is seen in the Byzantine Empire. The Roman Empire of the East remained strong enough to 1 i. 14 (Long's Translation). With the above passage may be compared Julian's appeal to Plato and Aristotle in support of his conviction that the spirit of laws should be impersonal (Epistola ad Themistium, 261 — 2). The second imperial philosopher, in his satirical composition entitled Caesares, most frequently reaffirms the judgments of Suetonius and Tacitus, but not without discrimination. Tiberius he sums up as a mixed character, and does not represent him as flung into Tartarus with Caligula and Nero. 2 See Renan, Marc-Aurile, where illustrations are given of this attitude on the part of the apologists. ~ I] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 5 throw off the barbarian attack for centuries. It preserved much of ancient Greek letters. In distinction from the native monarchies of Asia, it possessed a system of law that had received its bent during a period of freedom 1 . But, with these differences, it was a theocratic monarchy of the Oriental type. It was the last result, not of a purely internal development, but of reaction on the Graeco-Roman world from the political institutions and the religions of Asia. The course of things in the West was different. Having been for a time reduced almost to chaos by the irruptions of the Germanic tribes, the disintegrated and then nominally revived Western Empire furnished the Church with the oppor- tunity of erecting an independent theocracy above the secular rule of princes. This type came nearest to realisation in the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. It broke down partly through internal decay and partly through the upgrowth of a stronger secular life. With immense difficulty and with the appearance almost of accident 2 , a new kind of free State arose. The old Teutonic monarchies, like the old Greek monarchies, were not of the Asiatic type. They contained elements of political aristocracy and democracy which could develop under favouring circumstances. In most cases the development did not take place. With the cessation of feudal anarchy, the royal power became too strong to be effectively checked. There was formed under it a social hierarchy of which the most privileged equally with the least privileged orders were excluded as such from all recognised political authority. Thus on the Continent, during the early modern period, the prevailing type became Catholic Absolutism, or, as f* has been called, " European monarchy," — a system which was imitated in the Continental Protestant States. By the eighteenth century this had become, like the 1 " The period of Roman freedom was the period during which the stamp of a distinctive character was impressed on the Roman jurisprudence." Sir Henry Maine, Ancient Lata, 10th ed. , ch. ii. p. 40. - Comte at least regarded Absolutism as the normal development, Consti- tutionalism as a local anomaly, in European history before 1789, 6 GRAECO-ROMAN CIVILISATION [i Byzantine Empire or the old Asiatic monarchies, a fixed type, a terminal despotism from which there could be no peaceful issue. It was destroyed — so far as it has since been destroyed — by the revolutionary influence of ideas from the past and from without. In England the germs of freedom, instead of being suppressed, were developed, and in the seventeenth century, after a period of conflict, the modern system of constitutional monarchy was established. To the political form of the modern free State, early English institutions by their preservation contributed most. Classical reminiscences, in England as elsewhere, enkindled the love of freedom ; but deliberate imitation was unnecessary where the germs from which the ancient republics themselves had sprung were still ready to take a new form. From England the influence of revived political freedom diffused itself, especially in France, where it combined with the emulation of classical models and with generalisations from Roman law, to form the abstract system of "natural rights." From this system, on the intellectual side, have sprung the American and the French Republics. In the general European development, the smaller con- stitutional States may be neglected. The reappearance of a kind of city-republic in mediaeval Italy is noteworthy, but had little practical influence. The Italian cities were never com- pletely sovereign States like the Greek cities. Politically, it is as if these had accepted autonomy under the supremacy of the Great King. Spiritually, it is as if they had submitted to a form of the Zoroastrian religion from which dissent was penal. Nor did the great Italian poets and thinkers ever quite set up the ideal of the autonomous city as the Greeks had done. In its ideal, their city was rather a kind of municipality : with Dante, under the " universal monarchy " of the restored Empire ; with Petrarch and more distinctly with Machiavelli, under Italy as a national State, unified by any practicable means. Even in its diminished form, the old type of republic was exceedingly favourable to the reviving culture of Europe ; but the prestige of the national States around was too strong for it to survive except as an interesting accident. The present type of free State is one to which no terminal I] IN ITS POLITICAL DEVELOPMENT 7 form can be assigned. In England and in America, in France and in Italy, not to speak of the mixed forms existing else- where, it is still at the stage of growth. The yet living rival with which it stands confronted is the Russian continuation or reproduction of Christian theocracy in its Byzantine form 1 . 1 This epilogue, sketchiug the political transition to modern Europe, seemed necessary for the sake of formal completeness, although the bearing of political history on the history of philosophy is much less direct in modern than in ancient times. CHAPTER II. THE STAGES OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY. At the time of the Persian wars the civilisation of the East was in complexity, specialism, organised industry — what- ever relative importance we may attach to those features of progress — in all probability ahead of the civilisation of Greece. The conscious assumption of self-government by the Greek cities had, however, been closely followed by the beginnings of what we may call speculative science, which was a distinctive product of the Greek intellect. For this, the starting-point was furnished by the empirical observations of Egyptians and Chaldaeans, made with a view to real or fancied utility — measurement of land or prediction of future events. The earliest Greek philosophers, natives of the Ionian cities of Asia Minor, and thus on the borders of the fixed and the growing civilisations, took up a few generalised results of the long and laborious but unspeculative accumulation of facts and methods by the leisured priesthoods 1 of Egypt and Babylonia, and forthwith entered upon the new paths of cosmical theorising without regard to authoritative tradition, and of deductive thinking about numbers and figures without regard to immediate utility. As early as Pythagoras, still in the sixth 1 This way of putting the matter seems to reconcile the accounts of the invention of geometry in Egypt given by Herodotus and Aristotle, which Prof. Burnet (Early Greek Philosophy, Introduction, p. .19) finds discrepant. Herodotus assigns the motive, viz. "the necessity of measuring the lands afresh after the inundations"; Aristotle the condition that made it possible, viz. " the leisure enjoyed by the priestly caste." II] THE STAGES OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 9 century B.C., speculative science had begun to show signs of its later division into philosophy properly so-called, and positive science; the first special sciences to become detached, after mathematics, being those to which mathematical treatment seemed applicable. All this took place before the continuous movement of reflective thinking on human knowledge, which marks a new departure in philosophy, not its first origin, began at Athens. The emotion in which philosophy and science had their common source was exactly the same in ancient Greece and in renascent Europe. Plato and Aristotle, like Descartes and Hobbes, define it as " wonder." The earliest thinkers did not define it at all. Their outlook has still something very im- personal. With them, there is little inquiry about happiness or the means of attaining it. When the speculative life has been lived by several generations of thinkers, and a self- conscious theory of it is at length set forth, as at the opening of Aristotle's Metaphysics, the happiness involved in it is regarded as something that necessarily goes with mere think- ing and understanding. This is the subjective form of early Greek philosophy. In objective content, it is marked by complete detachment from religion. No traditional authority is acknowledged. Myths are taken merely as offering points of contact, quite as frequently for attack as for interpretation in the sense of the individual thinker. The handling of them in either case is perfectly free. Results of the thought and observation of one thinker are summed up by him, not to be straightway accepted by the next, but to be examined anew. The aim is insight, not edification. The general result is a conception of the cosmos in principle not unlike that of modern science ; in detail necessarily crude, though still scientific in spirit, and often anticipating the latest phases of thought in remarkable ways. Even the representa- tions of the earth as a disc floating on water, and of the stars as orifices in circular tubes containing fire, are less remote in spirit from modern objective science than the astronomy of later antiquity and of the instructed Middle Ages. This was 10 THE STAGES [il far more accurate in its conception of shapes and magnitudes and apparent motions, but it was teleological in a way that purely scientific astronomy cannot be. The earliest Ionian thinkers, like modern men of science, imposed no teleological conceptions on their astronomical theories. At the same time, early Greek philosophy was not merely objective, as modern science has become. It was properly philosophical in virtue of its " hylozoism." Life and mind, or their elements, were attributed to the world or its parts. Later, a more objective "naturalism" appears, as in the system of Democritus. Here the philosophical character is still retained by the addition of an explicit theory of know- ledge to the scientific explanation of the cosmos. " Primary " and " secondary " qualities of matter are distinguished, and these last are treated as in a sense unreal. Thus the definite formulation of materialism is accompanied by the beginnings of subjective idealism. But with the earliest thinkers of all, there is neither an explicit theory of knowledge nor an ex- clusion of life and mind from the elements of things. The atomism of Democritus and his predecessors was the result of long thinking and perhaps of much controversy. The " Ionians," down to Heraclitus, regarded the cosmos as continuously existing, but as ruled by change in all its parts if not also as a whole. The Eleatics, who came later, affirmed that unchanging Being alone exists : this is permanent and always identical ; " not-being " absolutely does not exist, and change is illusory. The Being of Parmenides, it is now held 1 , was primarily the extended cosmos regarded as a closed sphere coincident with all that is. Yet, though the conception was in its basis physical and not metaphysical, the metaphysical abstraction made by Plato was doubtless implicit in it. And Parmenides himself evidently did not conceive reality as purely objective and mindless. If he had intended to convey that meaning, he would have been in violent contradiction with his predecessor Xenophanes, and this would hardly have escaped notice. The defect of Eleaticism was that apparent change 1 See Tannery, Pour VHhtoire de la Science Hellene, and Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy. n ] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 11 received no satisfactory explanation, though an attempt was made to explain it in what Parmenides called a " deceptive " discourse as dealing with illusory opinion and no longer with demonstrative truth. Atomism mediated between this view and that of the Ionians by asserting a plurality of real beings, each having the characters of the Eleatic "being." "Not- being" for the atomists was empty space; change in the appearances of things was explained by mixture and separation of unchanging elements. The mechanical conception of the purely quantitative atom, which modern science afterwards took up, was completed by Democritus. Anaxagoras, though fundamentally a mechanicist, did not deprive his atoms of quality. And Empedocles, along with ideas of mixture and separation — explained by the attractive and repulsive agents, at once forces and media, to which he gave the mythological names of Love and Strife— retained something of the old hylozoism. Over against the material elements of things, Anaxagoras set Mind as the agent by which they are sifted from their primitive chaos. This was the starting-point for a new development, less purely disinterested than the first because more coloured by ethical and religious motives, but requiring even greater philosophic originality for its accom- plishment. The new departure of philosophy, though adopting the Anaxagorean Mind as its starting-point, had its real source in the ethical and political reflection which began effectively with the Sophists and Socrates. To give this reflective attitude consistency, to set up the principles suggested by it against all exclusive explanations of reality from the material ground of things, and yet to do this without in the end letting go the notion of objective science, was the work of Plato. Aristotle continued Plato's work, while carrying forward science independently and giving it relatively a more important posi- tion. One great characteristic result of the earlier thinking — the assertion that materially nothing is created and nothing destroyed — was assumed as an axiom both by Plato and by Aristotle whenever they had to deal with physics. They did not take up from the earlier thinkers those specific ideas that 12 THE STAGES [il afterwards turned out the most fruitful scientifically — though Plato had a kind of atomic theory — but they affirmed physical law in its most general principle. This they subordinated to their metaphysics by the conception of a universal teleology. The teleological conception of nature there is good historical ground for attributing also to Socrates. The special importance which Plato's Timaeus acquired for his successors is due to its being the most definite attempt made by the philosopher himself to bring his distinctive thought into relation with objective science. Thus, in view of knowledge as it was in antiquity, the later Platonists were quite right in the stress they laid on this dialogue. For the period following upon the death of Aristotle, during which Stoicism and Epicureanism were the predominant schools, the most important part of Plato's and Aristotle's thought was the ethical part. Both schools were, on the theoretical side, a return to naturalism as opposed to the Platonic and Aristotelian idealism. Both alike held that all reality is body ; though the Stoics regarded it as continuous and the Epicureans as discrete. The soul, for the Stoics as for the Epicureans, was a particular kind of matter. The most fruitful conception in relation to the science of the future was preserved by Epicurus when he took up the Democritean idea of the atom, defined as possessing figured extension, resistance and weight; all "secondary" qualities being regarded as resulting from the changes of order and the interactions of the atoms. And, on the whole, the Epicureans appealed more to genuine curiosity about physics for itself 1 , though ostensibly cultivating it only as a means towards ridding human life of the fear of meddlesome gods. If the determinism of the Stoics was more rigorous, it did not prevent their undertaking the defence of some popular superstitious which the Epicureans have the credit of opposing. On the other hand, Stoicism did more for ethics. While both schools, in strict definition, were " eudaemonist," the Stoics brought out far more clearly the social reference of morality. Their line of thought here, as the Academics and Peripatetics 1 Mr Benn, in his Greek Philosophers, points out the resemblance of Lucretius in type of mind to the early physical thinkers of Greece. Il] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 13 were fond of pointing out, could be traced back to Plato and Aristotle. So also could the teleology which they combined with their naturalism. But all the systems of the time were more or less eclectic. The social form under which the Stoics conceived of morality was the reference, no longer to a particular State, but to a kind of universal State. Since the social reference in Greek morality had been originally to the " city," the name was retained, but it was extended to the whole world, and the ideal morality was said to be that of a citizen of the world. This "cosmopolitanism" is prepared in Plato and Aristotle. Socrates (as may be seen in the Memorabilia of Xenophon) had already conceived the idea of a natural law or justice which is the same for all States. And in Aristotle that conception of " natural law " which, transmitted by Stoicism, had so much influence on the Roman jurisprudence, is definitely formulated 1 . The humanitarian side of Stoicism — which is not quite the same thing as its conception of universal justice — is plainly visible in Cicero 2 . Although Zeno, the founder of Stoicism, was by race half a Phoenician, it cannot be said that the East contributed anything definable to the content of his ethics. Its sources were evidently Greek. Down to the end of the ancient world, 1 See the quotation and references given by Zeller, ii. 2, p. 646, n. 1. (Aristotle, Eng. Trans., ii. 175, n. 3.) - See, in De Finibus, the exposition of Cato, deducing from the Stoic principles the existence of a " communis humani generis societas " (iii. 19, 62). "Bonitas" is expressly distinguished from "justitia" (c. 20, 66); cf. De Off. iii. 6, 28. In the fifth book of the De Finibus, Piso goes back for the origin of the whole doctrine to the Platonists and Peripatetics. The following sentence (c. 23, 65) sums up the theory: "In omni autem honesto, de quo loquimur, nihil est tam illustre nee quod latius pateat quam coniunctio inter homines hominum et quasi quaedam societas et communicatio utilitatum et ipsa caritas generis humani, quae nata a primo satu, quod a procreatoribus nati diliguntur et tota domus coniugio et stirpe coniungitur, serpit sensim foras, cognationibus primum, turn affinitatibus, deinde amicitiis, post vicinitatibus, turn civibus et iis, qui publice socii atque amici sunt, deinde totius complexu gentis humanae ; quae animi affectio suum cuique tribuens atque hanc, quam dico, societatem coniunctionis humanae niunirice et aeque tuens iustitia dicitur, cui sunt adiunctae pietas, bonitas, liberalitas, benignitas, comitas, quaeque sunt generis eiusdem." 14 THE STAGES [il philosophy was continued by men of various races, but always by those who had taken the impress of Greek or of Graeco- Roman civilisation. The same general account is true of the Neo-Platonists. They too were men who had inherited or adopted the Hellenic tradition. On the ethical side they continue Stoicism ; although in assigning a higher place to the theoretic virtues they return to an earlier view. Their genuine originality is in psychology and metaphysics. Having gone to the centre of Plato's ideal- istic thought, they demonstrated, by a new application of its principles, the untenableness of the Stoic materialism ; and, after the long intervening period, they succeeded in defining more rigorously than Plato had done, in psychology the idea of consciousness, in metaphysics the idea of immaterial and subjective existence. Scientifically, they incorporated elements of every doctrine with the exception of Epicureanism ; going back with studious interest to the pre-Socratics, many frag- ments of whom the latest Neo-Platonist commentators rescued just as they were on the point of being lost. On the subjective side, they carried thought to the highest point reached in antiquity. And neither in Plotinus, the great original thinker of the school, nor in his successors, was this the result of mystical fancies or of Oriental influences. These, when they appeared, were superinduced. No idealistic philosophers have ever applied closer reasoning or subtler analysis to the relations between the inner and the outer world. If the school to some extent " Orientalised," in this it followed Plato ; and it diverged far less from Hellenic ideals than Plato himself. A certain affinity of Plato with the East has often been noticed. This led him to the most remarkable previsions of the later movement of the world. The system of caste in the Republic is usually said to be an anticipation of the mediaeval order of society. Now in the introduction to the Timaeus and in the Gritias, the social order of Egypt is identified in its determining principles with that of the ideal State, and both with the constitution of pre-historic Athens, also regarded as ideal. Hence it becomes evident that, for his specialisation and grading of social functions, Plato got the hint from the II] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 15 Egyptian caste of occupations 1 . Thus his ideal society is in contact, on one side with the pre-Hellenic East, on the other side with the Orientalised Europe of the Middle Ages. By its communism it touches modern schemes of reform 2 . Mr Benn has remarked that the stages of degeneration from the ideal aristocracy to a tyranny, set forth in the Republic, are the same as the actual stages of degeneration of the Roman State. To this it may be added that in the Laws Plato lays down the exact conditions that concurred for the establishment of Christianity. The problem is to get a new system of legis- lation received in the projected colony. For this he finds that, though citizens from the same State are better in so far as they are likely to be more orderly, yet they will be too attached to their own laws. There is therefore an advantage in beginning with a mixture of colonists from several States. The character of such colonists will make the task in any case difficult, but the most favourable condition is that the ideas of a great legislator should be taken up by a young and vigorous tyrant. Generalise a little, putting for a single legislator the succession of those who formulated ecclesiastical doctrine and discipline, and for a single tyrant the consummated autocracy of the later Roman Empire, and the conditions are historically given. For there was, in the cosmopolitan Empire, exactly that mixture of different inherited customs which Plato desiderates. Add, what is continually insisted on in the Laws, that towards getting particular precepts enforced it would conduce much if they could be regarded as proceeding from a god, and it will be seen that here also the precise condition of success was laid down. The philosopher even anticipated some of the actual legis- lation of the Church. In the tenth book of the Laws, he proposes a system of religious persecution. Three classes of the impious are to be cast out, — those who deny the existence of all gods, those who say that the gods take no heed of human affairs, and those who say that they can be bought off with 1 Cf. Arist. Pol. iv. (vii.) 9, 13'29 b 23 : 6 W x u P ta f-^ ° xara. ytvos rod iroXiTiKov Tr\-fi$ovs £'£ AlyvTrrov. 2 See Appendix I. 16 THE STAGES [ll prayers and gifts ; or, as we may put it compendiously, — Atheists, Epicureans and Catholics. As, however, the last class would have been got rid of with least compunction, the anticipation here was by no means exact. And probably none of these glimpses, extraordinary as they were, into the strange transformation that was to come in a thousand years, had any influence in bringing it to pass. The Neo-Platonists would have carried out an ethical reform of polytheism in the spirit of the Republic and the Laws ; but they did not propose to set up persecution as a sanction. On the contrary, they were the champions of the old intellectual liberty of Hellenism against the new theocracy. One of the most Orientalising sayings to be found in the later Platonists, namely, that the " barbarians " have an advantage over the Greeks in the stability of their institutions and doctrines as contrasted with the Greek innovating spirit 1 , occurs both in the Timaeus and in the Laws' 2 . And Plato's attack, in the Republic, on the myths of Greek religion, was continued by the Christians, not by his Neo-Platonic successors; who sought to defend by allegorical interpretations whatever they could not accept literally ; or at least, in repudiating the fables, did not advocate the expulsion of the poets. It is to be remembered further that in the philosophical tradition of antiquity even more than in its general culture, the republican ideal was always upheld. Aristotle as well as Plato, it is true, was less favourable than the statesmen, orators and historians of the great Athenian period to personal spontaneity uncontrolled by the authority of the State. But of course what 1 Quoted by Bitter and Preller (Historia Philosophies Graecae, 547 b) from the De Mysteriis formerly attributed to Iamblichus : fxera^aWd/xeva ael 5ia ti)v Kcuvorofxiav kclI irapavoixiav tCiv 'EXXiji'wi' ovUv iraveTai....^6.p^apoi de fiovifioi tois ■VjBeaiv oures nal rots X6701S fiefZaiw tois avrois e/xix^vovcn. 2 Allowance being made for the point of view, the two aspects of Plato are appreciated with perfect exactitude by Joseph de Maistre in his vituperation of the Greek spirit. (Du Pape, livre iv. ch. 7.) Plato's "positive and eternal dogmas," says the brilliant reactionary, "portent si clairement le cachet oriental que, pour le meconnaitre, il faut n'avoir jamais entrevu rAsie....Il y avait en lui un sophiste et un theologien, ou, si Ton veut, un Grec et un Chalde'en. On n'entend pas ce pbilosophe si on ne le lit pas avec cette idee toujours pre"sente a l'esprit." Il] OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY 17 the philosophers desired was the supremacy of reason, not of arbitrary will. Licence in the city seemed to them condemn- able on this ground among others, that under the show of liberty it paved the way for a tyrant. And the later schools, in which philosophy had fixed a sort of official attitude, were always understood to be hostile to despotism 1 . The Stoics in particular had this reputation, which they justified under the early Empire. That the Neo-Platonists, although by their time philosophy had almost ceased to have a political branch, were still of the ancient tradition, is proved by the republican spirit of Julian, who had received from them his self-chosen training'-. In the chiefs of the school also, slight indications to the same effect may be discerned. This attitude of the philo- sophers had its importance in preserving the memory of the higher ideal notwithstanding the inevitable descent due to circumstance. And even in the early Middle Ages, deriving their knowledge of antiquity as they did mainly from a few late compilations, such discussions as there are on the origin of society and of government seem traceable to reminiscences from the philosophic schools; the idea of a social contract in particular coming probably from the Epicureans. 1 Cf. Sueton. Nero, 52: "Liberalis disciplinas omnis fere puer attigit. Sed a philosophia eum mater avertit, monens imperaturo contrariam esse." 2 Julian's refusal to be addressed by the title 5etnr6TTis customary in the East, did not conciliate the "average sensual man" of Antioch. See Misopogon, 343c — 344a: SeviroT-qs ehai ov (prjs oi<5e avexv tovto d/coiW, d\Xa /cat ayavaKreis,... OovXeveiv 5' r/^as dvayKa^eis apxov<ri /cat vo/xols. kclLtoi woffip Kpenrov -r\v ovo/xd^eadai ix.b> <re SeairdTijv, Zpyy 8e iS.i> ^uas elvai iXevdipovs ; ...&<peh 5e tt)v <tkt)V7]v /cat robs flifJLOVS KO.1 TOVS OpX 7 ? " 7 " 05 aTO\ib\eKCLS TJfXUV TT)V TroXiv. W. CHAPTER III. RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY. Though philosophy at its beginning among the Ionians had broken with traditional authority as completely as it has ever done since, religion and free speculation did not cease to interact. In some points, however, their developments were independent. Religious developments independent of philosophy were the establishment and the increased atten- tion paid to the " mysteries," and the importation of new worships from Egypt and Asia Minor. It was also due rather to a new development of religion than to philosophy, that more definite and vivid beliefs came to be popularly held about the immortality of the soul and about future rewards and punishments; though philosophers of religious mind sought to impress these doctrines along with the general conception of a providential government of the universe. In the Homeric poems, the soul goes away to the underworld as soon as the corpse is burnt, and can never afterwards reappear in the world of living men. Yet much later, in the dramatists, the ghost is invoked as still having active powers in this world. Here there is perhaps a survival of a stage of belief more primitive than the Homeric, rather than a development 1 ; but in the notion of definite places of reward and punishment there was clearly some growth of belief. Perhaps the mythical treatment of immortality by which Plato follows up his arguments for it on speculative grounds, is more a reaction 1 Rohde (Psyche, i.) finds evidences of such survival in Hesiod. Ill] RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY 19 of older religion on philosophy than an application of philo- sophy to religion. To the exact truth of the representations given, the philosopher never commits himself, but merely contends that something of the kind is probably true, as against the imaginations in Homer of a world of lifeless shades contrasted in their unreality with the vigour and bloom of life on earth. This side of Plato's teaching had for a long time not much influence. It became influential in proportion ■ as religion revived. With Aristotle and the naturalistic schools, personal immortality almost went out of sight. The Epicureans denied the immortality of the human soul altogether, and with the Stoics survival of consciousness after death, if admitted at all, was only till the end of a cycle or " great year." The religious belief, and especially the belief in Tartarus, became, however, in the end vigorous enough to furnish one point of contact for a new religion that could make it still more definite and terrible. And one side of the new religion was prepared for by the notion, more or less seriously encouraged, that those who partook of the mysteries had somehow a privileged position among the dead 1 . This of course was discountenanced by the most religious philosophers; though they came to hold that it showed a certain want of piety towards ancestral beliefs to make light of initiation into the native mysteries. Ancient religion and philosophy had not always been on such amicable terms as are implied in this last approximation. Especially at the beginning, when philosophy was a new thing, what may be called a sporadic intolerance was manifested towards it. Indeed, had this not been so, it would be necessary to allow that human nature has since then changed fundament- all}-. Without such germs of intolerance, its later developments would have been inconceivable. What can be truly said is that the institutions of antiquity were altogether unfavourable to the organisation of it. The death of Socrates had political more perhaps than religious motives. It has even been main- tained that serious intolerance first appeared in the Socratic 1 Cf. Hatch, The Influence of Greek Ideas and Usages upon the Christian Church, Lecture X. 2—2 20 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill school itself 1 . Plato, it is clear, would have been quite willing that an ethical reform of religion should be carried out by force. After the first collision, however, religion on the one side re- mained unorganised, and philosophy on the other side prac- tically free. How far was popular polytheism taken seriously ? That it was not taken seriously by the philosophers is quite evident. Perhaps the Epicureans reacted on it less than any other school ; for they conceived of their ethical ideal as realised by the many gods named in mythology, and they had no other divinities. Their quarrel was not with polytheism as such, but with the belief in gods who interrupted their divine tranquillity to interfere in the affairs of mortals. The belief of the philosophic schools generally was some form of theism, or, as in the case of the Stoics, pantheism, by which the gods of mythology, if recognised at all, were subordinated to a supreme intelligence or allegorised into natural forces. The later philosophers made use of more elaborate accommodations. Aristotle had rejected polytheism in so many words. Plato had dismissed it with irony. Their successors needed those explicit theories of a rationalising kind which Plato thought rather idle. For the educated world, both in earlier and later antiquity, Cudworth's position is probably in the main true, that a sort of monotheism was held over and above all ideas of gods and daemons. Thus the controversy between Christian assailants and pagan defenders of the national religions was not really a controversy between monotheism and polytheism. The champions of the old gods contended only for the general reasonableness of the belief that different parts of the earth have been distributed to different powers, divine though subordinate 2 . And in principle the Christians could have no objection to this. They themselves often held with regard to angels what the pagans attributed to gods ; or even allowed the real agency of the pagan gods, but called them "daemons," holding them to be evil beings. The later paganism also allowed the existence of evil 1 This is the thesis of a very suggestive little book by M. G. Sorel, entitled Le Prods de Socrate (1889). 2 Cf. Keim, Celsus' Wahres Wort, p. 67. Ill] IN LATER ANTIQUITY 21 daemons, and had a place for angels among supernatural powers. Perhaps there is here a trace of Christian influence. It is often represented as a paradox that the Christian idea of a suffering God should have triumphed over what is supposed to have been the universal prejudice of paganism that to suffer is incompatible with divinity. There is no real paradox. Ideas of suffering gods were everywhere, and the worship of them became the most popular. The case is really this. The philo- sophers held that absolutely divine beings — who are not the gods of fable — are " impassible." In oratorical apologies for the Crucifixion and the Resurrection, this philosophic view of the divinity had to be met. On the other hand, the Christians made most of their converts among those who were not philo- sophers. By their mode of appeal, they got the advantage at once of a rigorous monotheism such as philosophy was tending to diffuse, and of the idea that expiations could be performed by incarnate and suffering deities, such as were believed in over all the pagan world. Exactly with this kind of popular paganism philosophy had had its quarrel. Of Xenophanes, the earliest explicitly monotheistic philosopher, it is related that, being asked by the people of Elea whether they should sacrifice to Leucothea and lament for her, he replied : " If you think her a god, do not lament; if human, do not sacrifice 1 ." The same view was taken by later philosophers. It was against this, and not against the popular imaginations, that such sayings as the well-known one of Tertullian were directed. Coinciding with the rise of Christianity there was, as has lately come to be recognised, a revival, not a decline, of ancient religion. The semblance of decline is due to the effect produced 011 modern readers by the literature of the later Roman Republic and earlier Empire, which proceeded for the most part from the sceptical minority. This impression has been corrected by the evidence of archaeology. So far as there was a real decline in the worship of the old gods, it meant only a desertion of in- digenous cults for more exciting ones from the East. First 1 Arist. Rlwt. ii. 23, 1400 b 5. (R. P. 81 a.) Sevocpduris 'EXedrcus (pwrucnv el duwfft rrj Aewcodeqi Kai dpyvucnv r) fir), <rvve(iov\evev, d fx.ev Oebv uTro\a,ul-idvov<n, /at] dp-qvtlv, el o' dvOpwirov, fir} Ovtiv. 22 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill there appeared the cult of the Oriental Bacchus, then of Cybele and of Isis. And all these present curious analogies with Christianity. It is an interesting circumstance that from the Bacchae of Euripides, — which is essentially a picture of the uncontrollable frenzy aroused by devotion to a lately born son of Zeus, persecuted and afterwards triumphant, coming from the East, — several lines were transferred to the Christus Pattens 1 . The neglect of the altars of the gods spoken of by Lucian may be explained by this transfer of devotion. In the dialogue ®edov 'K/acXrjala, the Hellenic gods are called together with a view to the expulsion of intruding barbarian divinities, such as those that wear Persian or Assyrian garments, and above all " the brutish gods of Nile," who, as Zeus himself is obliged to admit, are a scandal to Olympus. Momus insinuates that the purge will not turn out easy, since few of the gods, even among the Hellenic ones themselves, if they come to be closely examined, will be able to prove the purity of their race. Such an attempt at conservative reform as is here satirised by Lucian no doubt represented what was still the attitude of classical culture in the second century ; as may be seen by the invective of Juvenal against the Egyptian religion. Later, the syncretism that took in deities of every nationality came to be adopted by the defenders of classicism. It is this kind of religious syncretism, rather than pure classicism, that revives at the Renaissance. The apology not only for the Greek gods but for those of Egypt, as in truth all diverse representations of the same divinity, is undertaken in one of Bruno's dialogues. What makes this the more remarkable is that Bruno probably got the hint for his Spaccio della Bestia Trionfante precisely from the dialogue of Lucian just referred to. The nearest approach in the Hellenic world to the idea of a personal religious revelation was made by the philosophic sect of the Pythagoreans. The early history of the sect is mainly the account of an attempt at ethico-political regulation of cities in the south of Italy by oligarchies imbued with the philo- sophical and religious ideas of Pythagoras. These oligarchies 1 See the notes in Paley's edition of Euripides. The Christus Patiens was formerly attributed to Gregory Nazianzen, but is now held to be of later date. Ill] IX LATER ANTIQUITY 23 made themselves intensely unpopular, and the Pythagorean associations were violently suppressed. Afterwards remains of the societies combined to form a school specially devoted to geometry and astronomy, and in astronomy remarkable for suggestions of heliocentric ideas. Till we come to the Neo- Pythagoreans of about the first century B.C., the history of the school is obscure. Its religious side is observable in this, that those who claim to be of the Pythagorean succession appeal more than other philosophers to the recorded sayings of the founder, and try to formulate a minute discipline of daily life in accordance with his precepts. The writings, mostly pseudonymous, attributed by them to early Pythagoreans 1 are in composition extremely eclectic, borrowing freely from the Stoics as well as from Plato and Aristotle. Coincidences were explained by the assumption that other philosophers had borrowed from Pythagoras. The approach of the Neo- Pythagorean school to the idea of a revelation is illustrated by the circumstance that Apollonius of Tyana, to whom in the first century A.D. miracles and a religious mission were attri- buted, was a Pythagorean. The lives of Pythagoras himself, by Porphyry and Iamblichus, are full of the marvels related in older documents from which both alike drew. According to Zeller, the peculiar doctrines and the ascetic discipline of the Essenes are to be ascribed to Neo-Pythagorean rather than to Indian or Persian influences. Their asceticism — an essen- tially non-Judaic character — has in any case to be explained from a foreign source; and its origin from this particular Hellenic source is on the whole the most probable, because of the number of detailed coincidences both in method of life and in doctrine. Closely connected with the idea of the cosmical harmony, so strongly accentuated in the Pythagorean school, is the adoration of the stars thought of as animated beings, which became in quite a special manner the philosophic religion. This may have been first suggested by the star-worship associated with the empirical observations of the Chaldaeans, from which the 1 Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 100 — 3, gives a long list of them. 24 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS [ill Greek rational astronomy arose. There is not much trace of this form of religion in Greek polytheism at its first mytho- logical stage. The genuine gods of Greece were essentially anthropomorphic. In a passage of Aristophanes 1 it is even said that the sun and moon are distinctively the gods of the barbarians. The earliest philosophers did not treat the heavenly bodies as in any special way divine, but regarded them as composed of the same kinds of matter as the other and lower bodies of the universe. When popular religion thought it an impiety on the part of Anaxagoras to explain the nature and action of the sun without introducing divine agency, the divine agency required was no doubt of an anthropomorphic kind, — that of a charioteer for example. By Plato and Aristotle the divinity of the stars themselves was affirmed ; aud it afterwards became an article of faith with what we may call pagan philo- sophical orthodoxy. It was for the philosophers a mode of expressing the teleological relation between the supreme Deity and the animated universe. The heavenly bodies, according to the theory, were placed in spheres to give origin by their motions to the ideas of time and number, and to bring about the succession of day and night and the changes of the seasons for the good of men and other animals. That they might do this, they were endowed with ruling intelligences superior to man's and more lasting. For the animating principle of the stars, unimpeded by any process of growth or decay, can energise continuously at its height, whereas human souls, being temporarily united to portions of unstable matter, lapse through such union from the condition of untroubled intel- lectual activity. This theory, founded by Plato in the Timaeus, was an assertion of teleological optimism against the notion 1 Quoted in Blakesley's Herodotus, vol. ii. p. 210, n. TP. i] yap aek-qvT] x^ navovpyos ijXios, v/mv (Tn(3ov\evoi>Te iroXvv ijdri XP° V0V > rots ftapfiapoLcri Trpodidorov rr\v EXXdSa. EP. (Va tI de tovto dparov ; TP. otitj vt] At'o i]fxe?s fJ.ei> vfiiv dvotxev, tovtoigi. de oi j3dp(3apoi dvovcn. Pax, 406—11. Ill] IN LATER ANTIQUITY 25 that the stars are products of chance-aggregation. As such, it was defended by Plotinus against the pessimism of the Christian Gnostics, who— going beyond the Epicureans, as he sa y S — regarded the present world as the work of an imperfect or of an eviL creator. And in the latest period of the Neo- Platonic school at Athens, a high place was given, among the devotional usages adopted from the older national religions, to those that had reference to the heavenly bodies. A current form taken by this modification of star-worship was astrology. Its wide dissemination in Italy is known from the edicts expelling the so-called "mathematici" or "Chaldaei," as well as from the patronage they nevertheless obtained at the courts of emperors. Along with magic or " theurgy," it came to be practised by some though not by all the members of the Neo-Platonic school. Plotiuus himself, as a true successor of Plato, minimised where he could not entirely deny the pos- sibility of astrological predictions and of magical influences, and discouraged the resort to them even if supposed real. In his school, from first to last, there were always two sections: on the one hand those who, in their attachment to the old religion and aversion from the new, inquired curiously into all that was still preserved in local traditions about human inter- course with gods or daemons ; and on the other hand those who devoted themselves entirely to the cultivation of philosophy in a scientific spirit, or, if of more religious mind, aimed at mystical union with the highest God as the end of virtue and knowledge. This union, according to the general position of the school, was in no case attainable by magical practices, which at best brought the soul into relation with subordinate divine powers. According to those even who attached most importance to " theurgy," it was to be regarded as a means of preparation for the soul itself in its progress, not as having any influence on the divinity. One here and there, it was allowed, might attain to the religious consummation of philosophy without external aids, but for the majority they were necessary. As " magical " powers, when real, were held to be due to a strictly "natural" sympathy of each part of the universe with all the rest, and as this was not denied, on scientific grounds, 26 RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENTS IN LATER ANTIQUITY [ill by the opponents of magic, the theoretical difference between the two parties was less than might be supposed. It did not prevent philosophers of opposite views on this point from being on friendly terms with each other. The real chasm was between the philosophers who, however they •might aspire after what they had heard of Eastern wisdom, had at heart the continuance of the Hellenic tradition, and those believers in a new revelation who, even if giving to their doctrines a highly speculative form, like the Gnostics 1 , yet took up a revolutionary attitude towards the whole of ancient culture. 1 See Appendix II. CHAPTER IV. PLOTINUS AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS. A name once customarily but incorrectly applied to the Neo-Platonist school was "the School of Alexandria." The historians who used the name were aware that it was not strictly correct, and now it seems to be again passing out of use. That the Neo-Platonic teachers were not in any close association with the scientific specialists and literary critics of the Alexandrian Museum was elaborately demonstrated by Matter in a work which is really a History of the School — or rather Schools— of Alexandria, and not, like those of Vacherot and Jules Simon bearing the same general title, of Neo- Platonism. In his third volume (1818) Matter devotes a special section to the Neo-Platonic philosophy, " falsely called Alexandrian," and there he treats it as representing a mode of thought secretly antipathetic to the scientific spirit of the Museum. This, however, is an exaggeration. Of the obscure antipathy which he thinks existed, he does not bring any tangible evidence; and, in fact, when Neo-Platonism had become the philosophy of the Graeco-Roman world, it was received at Alexandria as elsewhere. What is to be avoided is merely the ascription of a peculiar local association that did not exist. To the Jewish Platonism of Philo and to the Christian Platonism of Clement and Origen the name of " Alexandrian " may be correctly applied ; for it was at Alexandria that both 28 PLOTINUS [IV types of thought were elaborated. To the Hellenic Platonism of Plotinus and his school it has no proper application. Plo- tinus indeed received his philosophical training at Alexandria under Ammonius Saccas ; but it was not till long after, at Rome, that he began to put forth a system of his own. After his death, knowledge of his system, through Porphyry and Iamblichus, diffused itself over all parts of the Roman Empire where there was any care for philosophy. Handed on by the successors of Iamblichus, the doctrine of Plotinus at last gained the assent of the occupants of Plato's chair in the Academy. The one brilliant period of Neo- Platonism at Alexandria was when it was expounded there by Hypatia. Its last great names are not those of Alexandrian teachers, but those of the " Platonic successors " at Athens, among whom by far the most distinguished was Proclus. The school remained always in reality the school of Plotinus. From the direction impressed by him it derived its unity. A history of Neo-Platonism must therefore set out from the activity of Plotinus as teacher and thinker. Of this activity an account sufficient in the main points is given by his disciple Porphyry, who edited his writings and wrote his life 1 . Through the reticence of Plotinus himself, the date and place of his birth are not exactly recoverable. This reticence Porphyry connects with an ascetic repugnance to the body. It was only by stealth that a portrait of the master could be taken; his objection, when asked to sit to a painter, being the genuinely Platonic one that a picture was but an " image of an image." Why perpetuate this when the body itself is a mere image of reality ? Hence also the philosopher did not wish to preserve the details of his outward history. Yet in his aesthetic criticism he is far from taking a merely depreciating view of the fine arts. His purpose seems to have been to prevent a cult of him from arising among his disciples. He would not tell his birthday, lest there should be a special celebration of it, as there had come to be of the birthdays of 1 Porphyry's Life is prefixed to the edition of Plotinus by E. Volkmann (Teubuer, 1883, 4), from which the citations in the present volume are made. IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 29 other philosophers 1 ; although he himself used to keep the traditional birthday-feasts of Socrates and Plato 2 . According to Eunapius 3 , he was born at Lyco (or Lycopolis) in Egypt. From Porphyry's Life the year of his birth is inferred to be 204 or 205. In his twenty-eighth year, being dissatisfied with the other Alexandrian teachers of philosophy whom he frequented, he was taken by a friend to Ammonius. When he had heard him^he said to his companion : " This is the man of whom I was in search " (tovtov e&jTovv). With Ammonius he remained eleven years. At the end of that time, he became eager to learn something definite of the philosophy that was cultivated among the Persians and Indians. Ac- cordingly, in his thirty-ninth year he joined the expedition which Gordian was preparing against Persia (242). The Emperor was killed in Mesopotamia, and, the expedition having failed, Plotinus with difficulty escaped to Antioch. At the age of forty, he went to Rome (244) ; where, for ten whole years, though giving philosophical instruction, he wrote nothing. He began to write in the first year of the reign of Gallienus (254). In 263, when Plotinus was about fifty-nine, Porphyry, then thirty years of age, first came into relation with him. Plotinus had by that time written twenty-one " books," on such topics as had presented themselves in lectures and discussions. These Porphyry found issued to a few. Under the stimulus of new discussions, and urged by himself and an earlier pupil, Amelius Gentilianus, who had come to him in his third year at Rome, Plotinus now, in the six years that Porphyry was with him, wrote twenty-four more books. The procedure was as before ; the books taking their starting-point from the questions that occurred 4 . While Porphyry was in Sicily, whither he had retired about 268, Plotinus sent him in all nine more books. 1 Cicero treats the direction of Epicurus that his birthday should be celebrated after his death as a weakness in a philosopher. De Fin. ii. 31, 102 : " Haec non erant eius, qui inuumerabilis mundos infinitasque regiones, quarum nulla esset ora, nulla extremitas, mente peragravisset." In the last two words there is an evident allusion to Lucr. i. 74. 2 Porph. Vita Plotini, 2. 3 Vitae Philoaophorum ac Sophist arum (Plotinus). * V. Plot. 5 : 4k irpocTKaipwv Trpo(3\T)/xdTwv raj inro94o'eis XapovTa, 30 PLOTINUS [IV In 270, during this absence, Plotinus died in Campania. After his death, Amelius consulted the Delphic oracle on his lot, and received a response placing him among the happy daemons, which Porphyry transcribes in full 1 . Among the hearers of Plotinus, as Porphyry relates, were not a few senators. Of these was Rogatianus, who carried philosophic detachment so far as to give up all his possessions, dismiss all his slaves, and resign his senatorial rank. Having before suffered severely from the gout, he now, under the abstemious rule of life he adopted, completely recovered 2 . To Plotinus were entrusted many wards of both sexes, to the interests of whose property he carefully attended. During the twenty-six years of his residence at Rome, he acted as umpire in a great number of disputes, which he was able to settle without ever exciting enmity. Porphyry gives some examples of his insight into character, and takes this occasion to explain the reason of his own retirement into Sicily. Plotinus had detected him meditating suicide ; and, perceiving that the cause was only a " disease of melancholy," persuaded him to go away for a time 3 . One or two marvellous stories are told in order to illustrate the power Plotinus had of resisting malignant influences, and the divine protection he was under 4 . He was especially honoured by the Emperor Gallienus 5 and his wife Salonina, and was almost permitted to carry out a project of restoring a ruined city in Campania, — said to have been once a "city of philosophers 6 ," — which he was to govern according to the Platonic Laws, giving it the name of " Platonopolis 7 ." The fortunes of the scheme are curiously recalled by those of Berkeley's projected university in the Bermudas. At the time of this project, Plotinus must have been already engaged in the composition of his philosophical books. 1 V. Plot. 22. - Ibid. 7. 3 Ibid. 11. * Ibid. 10. 5 Gallienus tolerated Christianity. He was a man of considerable accom- plishments, though the historians do not speak highly of him as a ruler. 6 This apparently means, as has been conjectured (R. P. 508 f.), that it had formerly been ruled by a Pythagorean society. » V. Plot. 12. IV ] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 31 As Porphyry relates, no external demands on his attention, with whatever good will and practical success he might respond to them, could break the continuity of his meditations, which he had always the power to resume exactly at the point where he had left off. Of the characteristics of his lecturing, his disciple gives a sympathetic picture 1 . He did not care for personal controversy ; as was shown by his commissioning his pupils to reply to attacks on his positions. Porphyry mentions a case in which he himself was set to answer an unedifying discourse of the rhetor Diophanes 2 . The books of Plotinus, as we have seen, were not composed on any general plan. Porphyry relates that, through a weakness of the eyes, he never read over again what he had once written. His gram- matical knowledge of Greek remained imperfect, and the revision as well as editing of his writings was committed to Porphyry, from whom proceeds the arrangement of the six " Enneads," — the name the fifty- four books received from their ordering in groups of nine. While he worked in this irregular way, the character of his thought was extremely systematic. He evidently possessed his doctrine as a whole from the time when he began to write. Yet in detail, even to the very last books, in which Porphyry thought he observed a decline of power, he has always something effectively new to add. In addition to the grouping according to subjects, which he adopted for his arrangement of the Enneads as we have them, Porphyry has put on record an alternative ordering which may be taken as at least approximately chronological. The chrono- logical order is certain as regards the succession of the main groups. Of these there are three, or, more exactly, four ; the third group being divided into two sub-groups. At the begin- ning of the second main group also the order of four books is certain. For the rest, Porphyry does not definitely state that the books are all in chronological order; but, as his general 1 V. Plot. 13 : t\v 5' (v tw Xeyeiv r\ 2v5eii;is tov vov &XP 1 T °v TpocwTrov olvtov ri> 0uis imXapurovTOS ' ipa.afj.ios fitv 6<pdijvai, koXXIuv 5k t6t€ fidXto-ra bpuifxivos' icai \€7tt6s ns iSptlis ewidei nai r\ irpq.bT-q 1 ; ouXa/XTre ko.1 rb Trpoo-qvts Trpbs to.% ipwrrjcreis ioeinvvTO Kal rb evrovov. - Ibid. 15. I 32 PLOTINUS [IV arrangement in this enumeration is chronological, we may take it that he carried it through in detail as far as he could ; and, as a matter of fact, links of association can often be detected in passing consecutively from one book to another. For reading, I have found this order on the whole more convenient than the actual grouping of the Enneads. When the books are read in this chronological order, the psychological starting-point of the system becomes particularly obvious, the main positions about the soul coming early in the series. In the exposition that is to follow 1 , these will be set forth first. After Psychology will come Metaphysics, then in succession Cosmology (with Theodicy), Aesthetics and Ethics 2 . A separate chapter will be devoted to the Mysticism of Plotinus 3 . For this order of exposition support might be found in what Plotinus himself says, where he points out that from the doctrine of the soul, as from a centre, we can equally ascend and descend 4 . Before beginning the exposition, an attempt must be made to ascertain the points of contact furnished to Plotinus by those nearest him in time. His general relation to his predecessors is on the whole clear, but not the details. Of the teachings of his Alexandrian master, nothing trustworthy is recorded. Ammonius left nothing written, and the short accounts pre- served of his doctrine come from writers too late to have had any real means of knowing. What those writers do is to ascribe to him the reasoned positions of Plotinus, or even the special aims of still later thinkers contemporary with them- selves. Porphyry, in a passage quoted by Eusebius, mentions that Ammonius had been brought up as a Christian, but, as soon as he came in contact with philosophy, returned to the religion publicly professed. He is spoken of as a native of Alexandria ; and the name " Saccas " is explained by his having been originally a porter (5a/c/ca<? being equivalent to craicico- (f)6pos). Hierocles calls him " the divinely taught" (0€oBiBaKTo<;). 1 See ch. v. 2 Eoughly, this corresponds to the order : — Enn. iv. v. vi. n. in. i. 3 See ch. vi. 4 Enn. iv. 3, 1. IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 33 Besides Plotinus he had as pupils Longinus the famous critic 1 , Origen the Christian, and another Origen. With this Origen and a fellow-student named Herennius, Plotinus is said to have entered into a compact that none of them should divulge the doctrine of Ammonius. The compact was first broken by Herennius, then by Origen ; lastly Plotinus thought himself at liberty to expound the master's doctrine orally. Not for ten more years did he begin to write 2 . Evidently this, even if accepted, does little towards explaining the source of the written doctrine of Plotinus, — in which there is no reference to Ammonius, — and Zeller throws doubt on the whole story :i , regarding it as suspiciously like what is related about a similar compact among the early Pythagoreans. It is to be observed that Porphyry does not say that he had it directly from Plotinus. What is clear is this, that from Ammonius Plotinus must have received some impulse which was of great importance for his intellectual development. In the class-room of Plotinus, we learn from Porphyry 4 , the later Platonic and Aristotelian commentators were read ; but everywhere an original turn was given to the discussions, into which Plotinus carried the spirit of Ammonius. This probably indicates with sufficient clearness the real state of the case. Ammonius was one of those teachers who have the power of stirring up independent thought along a certain line ; but he was not himself the formative mind of the movement. The general line of thought was already marked out. Neither Ammonius nor Plotinus had to create an audience. A large section of the philosophical world had for long been dissatisfied with the Stoic, no less than with the Epicurean, dogmatism. The opposition was partly sceptical, partly Neo-Pythagorean and Platonic. The sceptical opposition was represented first by the New Academy, as we see in Cicero ; afterwards by the revived Pyrrhonism of Aenesidemus and 1 The Ilept'Ti/'ous, formerly attributed to Longinus, is now generally ascribed to some unknown writer of the first century. See the edition by Prof. W. Rhys Roberts (1899), who, however, points out that in its spirit it is such a work as might very well have proceeded from the historical Longinus. 2 Porph. V. Plot. 3. a hi. 2, p. 452. 4 V. Plot. 14. w. 3 34 PLOTINUS [IV Sextus. In Cicero we see also, set against both Epicureanism and Stoicism as a more positive kind of opposition, a sort of eclectic combination of Platonic and Peripatetic positions. A later stage of this movement is represented by Plutarch ; when Platonism, though not yet assuming systematic form, is already more metaphysical or "theological," and less predominantly ethical, than the eclecticism of Cicero's time. On its positive side the movement gained strength in proportion as the sceptical attack weakened the prevailing dogmatic schools. These at the same time ceased to give internal satisfaction, as we perceive in the melancholy tone of Marcus Aurelius. By the end of the second century, the new positive current was by far the strongest ; but no thinker of decisive originality had appeared, at least on the line of Greek thought. In Plotinus was now to appear the greatest individual thinker between Aristotle and Descartes. Under the attraction of his systema- tising intellect, all that remained of aspiration after an inde- pendent philosophy was rallied to a common centre. Essentially, the explanation of the change is to be found in his individual power. Yet he had his precursors as well as his teachers. There were two thinkers at least who, however little they may have influenced him, anticipated some of his positions. The first was Philo of Alexandria, who was born about 30 B.C., and died later than a.d. 40. The second was Numenius of Apamea, who is said to have flourished between 160 and 180 a.d. Philo was pretty certainly unknown to Plotinus. Numenius was read in his class-room ; but his disciple Amelius wrote a treatise, dedicated to Porphyry, in which, replying to an accusation of plagiarism, he pointed out the differences between their master's teaching and that of Numenius. Amelius, it may be remarked, had acquired a great reputation by his thorough knowledge of the writings of Numenius. Porphyry cites also the testimony of Longinus. The judgment of the eminent critic was for the unquestionable originality of Plotinus among the philosophers of his own and the preceding age 1 . In what that originality consisted, Plotinus, who spoke 1 Longinus ap. Porph. V. Plot. 20: ol 8e...Tp6wip Oeupias Idly XPW*M V0 <- H\uTlvb% dai koX Tei>Ti\t.ai>ds 'A/At\ios,...ov5e yap ov8' iyyis ti to, Novfirjvlov ko.1 IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 35 of him as " a philologist but by no means a philosopher," might not have allowed his competence to decide. He himself con- fessed that he did not understand some treatises of Plotinus that were sent to him. What he ascribes to him in the passage quoted by Porphyry is simply a more accurate mode of interpreting the Pythagorean and Platonic principles than had been attempted by others who took the same general direction. This, however, only renders his judgment the more decisive as to the impression Plotinus made in spite of the difficulties of his style. To make clear what doctrines of Plotinus were anticipated, the principles of his metaphysics must be stated in brief pre- liminary outline. Of the causes above the visible world, he placed highest of all the One beyond thought and being. To the One, in the Neo-Platonic philosophy, the name of God is applicable in a peculiar manner. Everything after it that is called divine is regarded as derivative. Next in order, as the effect of the Cause and Principle, comes the di vine Mind, identical with the " intelligible world " which is its object. Last in the order of supramundane causes comes the Soul of the whole, produced by Mind. Thence the descent is to the world of particular souls and changing things. The series composed of the primal One, the divine Mind, and the Soul of the whole, is sometimes called the " Neo-Platonic Trinity 1 ." Now Numenius put forth the idea of a Trinity which in one point resembles that of Plotinus. According to Proclus, Numenius distinguished "three Gods." The first he called the Father, the second the Maker, while the third was the World, or that which is made*. The point of Kpoviov teal ~Si.obipa.Tov ko.1 QpacuWov tois TIKojtlvov irepl rCiv o.vtG>v crvyypd/xfj.aaii' efs aKpifiaav ■ 6 b~t 'A/uAtos kixt' lx vr l ^ v toutov ^adl^eiv Trpoaipovfievos nai to. ttoWo. /dv tCjv avTwv doy/xaTdiv ix^ > f JLel ' 0S i T V & e^epyaaia iro\vs uv...wv ko.1 fxdvuv i]/xets a^tov elva.i vofdfofiev iirwKOTreio-dcu to. o~vyypdfj./j.a.Ta. 1 It is of course inexact to speak of a first, second and third "Person" in the Trinity of Plotinus. Even the generalised term "hypostasis" is more strictly applicable in Christian than in Neo-Platonic theology, as Vacherot points out. See Histoire Critique de VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. p. 425 n. 2 Comm. in Tim. p. 93. (R. P. 506 a ; Zeller, iii. 2, p. 220, n. 6.) Tror^a fj.€V KaKel rbv irpQrrov, noir]Tr]v 8e t'ov SevTepov, iroirip\a 8Z rbv rplrov ' 6 yap Kdcrfxos /car' avrbv 6 rpiros iarl Beds. 3—2 36 PLOTINUS [IV resemblance here to Plotinus is the distinction of " the first God " from the Platonic Demiurgus, signified by " the Maker." With Numenius, however, the first God is Being and Mind ; not, as with Plotinus, a principle beyond these. Zeller remarks that, since a similar distinction of the highest God from the Creator of the world appears before Numenius in the Christian Gnostics, among whom the Valentinians adopted the name " Demiurgus " from Plato, it was probably from them that Numenius got the hint for his theory ; and that in addition Philo's theory of the Logos doubtless influenced him 1 . To this accordingly we must turn as possibly the original starting-point for the Neo-Platonic doctrine. With Philo, the Logos is the principle that mediates be- tween the supreme God and the world formed out of matter Essentially the conception is of Greek origin, being taken directly from the Stoics, who got at least the suggestion of it from Heraclitus 2 . Philo regards the Logos as containing the Ideas in accordance with which the visible world was formed. By this Platonising turn, it becomes in the end a different conception from the divine " Reason " of the Stoics, embodied as that is in the material element of fire. On the other hand, by placing the Platonic Ideas in the divine Mind, Philo inter- prets Plato in a sense which many scholars, both in antiquity and in modern times, have refused to allow. Here Plotinus coincides with Philo. Among those who dissented from this view was Longinus. Porphyry, who, before he came to Rome, had been the pupil of Longinus at Athens, was not without difficulty brought over, by controversy with Amelius, to the view of Plotinus, " that intelligibles do not exist outside in- tellect 3 ." Thus by Plotinus as by Philo the cause and principle of things is distinguished from the reason or intellect which is its proximate effect ; and, in the interpretation of Plato, the divine mind is regarded as containing the ideas, whereas in the 1 iii. 2, p. 219, n. 3. 2 See, for the detailed genealogy of the conception, Principal Drummond's Philo Judaeus, vol. i. 3 V. Plot. 18. The position which he had adopted from Longinus was on £i;W TOV VOV il<pt<JTT)K€ TO. VQ-qTO.. IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 37 Timaeus they are figured as existing outside the mind of the Demiurgus. On the other hand, Plotinus differs both from Philo and from the Gnostics in consistently treating as mythical the representation of a maker setting out from a certain moment of time to shape things according to a pattern out of pre-existent matter. And, in spite of his agreement with Philo up to a certain point, there is nothing to show that their views were historically connected. Against the attempt to connect Plotinus, or even Numenius, with Philo, a strong point is urged by Dr Bigg. Neither Plotinus nor Numenius, as he points out, ever uses Xo'709 as a technical term for the " second hypostasis 1 ." Yet, if they had derived their theory from Philo, this is evidently what they would have done ; for the Philonian X070?, on the philosophical side, was not alien from Greek thought, but was a genuine product of it. In truth, to adapt the conception to their own systems by means of a change of name, would have been more difficult than to arrive at their actual terminology directly by combining Stoical and Aristotelian positions with their Platonism. This kind of combination is what we find in the eclectic thinkers, of whom Numenius was one. Plotiuus made use of the same elements ; the presence of which in his system Porphyry has expressly noted 2 . And, so far as the relation of the Neo-Platonic Trinity to Plato is concerned, the exact derivation of the three " hypostases " is pointed out in a fragment of Porphyry's lost History of Philosophy 3 . The highest God, we there learn, is the Idea of 1 See Xeoplatonism, pp. 123, 242, etc. Dr Bigg's actual assertions seem too sweeping. It is not quite correct to say, as he does in the second of the passages referred to, that Plotinus expressly refuses to apply to his principle of Intelli- gence the title Logos, which in his system means, as with the Stoics, " little more than physical force." There are indeed passages where he refuses to apply the title in some special reference ; but elsewhere — as in Enn. v. 1, 6 — he says that Soul is the \670s of Mind, and Mind the \6yos of the One. While the term with him has many applications, and among them the Stoical application to the "seminal reasons" of natural things, it may most frequently be rendered by " rational law." - V. Plot. 14 : e/AfjLepu.KTa.1 8' ev rots <rvyypdfx/xaaL Kal ra -tuiko. \av6dvovra doy/jLara Kal to. HepnraTrjTiKa' K<xTawtirvKv<jiTcu 6e Kal r/ juera rd (pvaiKa roi AptcrroreXouy wpayfj-areia. 3 Fragm. 16 in Nauck's Opi/triilo Selecta. 38 PLOTINUS [IV the Good in the Republic ; the second and third hypostases are the Demiurgus and the Soul of the World in the Timaeus. To explain the triadic form of such speculations, no theory of individual borrowing on any side is necessary. All the thinkers of the period, whether Hellenic, Jewish or Christian, had grown up in an atmosphere of Neo-Pythagorean speculation about numbers, for which the triad was of peculiar significance 1 . Thus on the whole it seems that Numenius and Plotinus drew independently from sources common to them with Philo, but cannot well have been influenced by him. Plotinus, as we have seen, had some knowledge of Numenius ; but, where a special point of contact has been sought, the difference is as obvious as the resemblance. The great differ- ence, however, is not in any detail of the triadic theory. It is that Plotinus was able to bring all the elements of his system under the direction of an organising thought. That thought was a definitely conceived immaterialist monism which, so far as we know, neither Philo nor Numenius had done anything substantially to anticipate. He succeeded in clearly developing out of Plato the conception of incorporeal essence, which his precursors had rather tended by their eclecticism to confuse. That the conception was in Plato, the Neo-Platonists would have not only admitted but strongly maintained. Yet Plato's metaphorical expressions had misled even Aristotle, who seriously thought that he found presupposed in them a spatial extension of the soul 2 . And if Aristotle had got rid of semi- materialistic " animism " even in expression, this had not prevented his successors from running into a new materialism of their own. Much as the Platonising schools had all along protested against the tendency to make the soul a kind of body or an outcome of body, they had not hitherto overcome it by clear definitions and distinctions. This is one thing that 1 Jules Simon, in his Histoire de VEcole d' Alexandria, dwells on this point as an argument against the view, either that Neo-Platonism borrowed its Trinity from Christianity or Christianity from Neo-Platonism. 2 Proclus wrote a book to defend Plato's view of the soul against Aristotle's attack. IV] AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS 39 Plotinus and his successors achieved in their effort after an idealist metaphysic. It was on this side especially that the thought of the school influenced the Fathers and Doctors of the Church. On the specific dogmas of Christian theology, Neo-Platonism probably exercised little influence. From Platonising Judaism or Christianity, it received none at all. At most an isolated expression occurs showing that the antipathy to alien religions was not so unqualified as to prevent appreciation, for example, of the Platonism in the Fourth Gospel. Numenius, it is interesting to note, was one of the few earlier writers who attach themselves to the Hellenic tradition and yet show traces of sympathetic contact with Hebraic religion. He it was who called Plato " a Moses writing Attic 1 ." On the other side Philo, though by faith a Jew, was as a philosopher essentially Greek both in thought and in terminology. What divided him from the Hellenic thinkers was simply his ac- ceptance of formal limitations on thought prescribed by a positive religion. In concluding the present chapter, a word may be said on the literary style of Plotinus, and on the temper of himself and his school in relation to life. His writing is admittedly difficult ; yet it is not wanting in beautiful passages that leave an impression even of facility. He is in general, as Porphyry says, concentrated, " abounding more in thoughts than in words." The clearness of his systematic thought has been recognised by expositors in spite of obscurities in detail ; and the obscurities often disappear with close study. On the thought when it comes in contact with life is impressed the character of ethical purity and inwardness which always continued to mark the school. At the same time, there is a return to the Hellenic love of beauty and knowledge for themselves. Stoical elements are incorporated, but the exaggerated " tension " of Stoicism 1 Suid. and Clem. Strom. (R. P. 7 b, 504.) ri yap 4<ttl IW&tuv t) M«wi)s irrudfuv ; Longinus, as we have seen, had enough knowledge of Numenius to compare him with Plotinus. This being so, it is certainly a rather remarkable coincidence, if the treatise On the Sublime was not written by Longinus, that in it also there should be an admiring reference to " the legislator of the Jews." 40 PLOTINUS AND HIS NEAREST PREDECESSORS [iV has disappeared. While the Neo-Platonists are more con- sistently ascetic than the Stoics, there is nothing harsh or repulsive in their asceticism. The ascetic life was for them not a mode of self-torture, but the means to a happiness which on the whole they succeeded in attaining. Perhaps the explanation is that they had restored the idea of theoretic virtue, against the too narrowly practical tone of the preceding schools. Hence abstinence from the ordinary objects of pursuit left no blank. It was not felt as a deprivation, but as a source of power to think and feel. And in thinking they knew that indirectly they were acting. For theory, with them, is the remoter source of all practice, which bears to it the relation of the outward effect to the inward cause. CHAPTER V. THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM OF PLOTINUS. As idealists and their opponents alike recognise, one great stumbling-block of an idealist philosophy is language. This was seen by Plato, by Plotinus, and by Berkeley, just as from the other side it is seen by the materialist and the dualist. Language was formed primarily to indicate the things of sense, and these have not the characters which idealism, whether ancient or modern, ascribes to reality. Ancient idealism refuses to call external things real in the full sense, because they are in flux. The reality is the fixed mental concept or its unchanging intelligible object. Modern idealism regards things as merely " phenomenal," because they appear to a consciousness, and be- yond this appearance have no definable reality. Whether reality itself is fixed or changing, may by the modern idealist be left undetermined ; but at any rate the groups of perceptions that make up the " objects " of daily experience and even of science are not, in his view, objects existing in themselves apart from mind, and known truly as such. Only by some relation to mind can reality be constituted. The way in which language opposes itself to ancient idealism is by its implication that existence really changes. To modern idealism it opposes itself by its tendency to treat external things as absolute objects with a real existence apart from that of all thinking subjects. The two forms of developed idealism here regarded as typically ancient and modern are the earliest and the latest — that of Plato on the one side, that of post-Cartesian, and still 42 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v more of post-Kantian, thinkers on the other. The idealism of Plotinus contains elements that bring it into relation with both. English readers know how Berkeley insists that, if we are to grasp his doctrine, we must attend to the meanings he desires to convey, and must not dwell on the mere form of expression. Let us see how Plato and Plotinus deal with the same difficulty. Plato's treatment of it may be most readily studied in the Gratylus. Language, Socrates undertakes to show, has a certain natural conformity to things named. To those who named them, external things mostly presented themselves as in flux. Accordingly, words are full of devices by the makers of language for expressing gliding and flowing movements. With a little ingenuity and an occasional evasion, those who hold that the true nature of everything is to flow and not to be in any manner fixed, might exhibit the early legislators over human speech as in exact agreement with their philosophical opinions. Yet after all there are some words, though fewer, that appear at first sight to express stability. So that the primitive legislators were not, on the face of things, perfectly consistent. On the whole, however, words suggesting flux predominate. Similarly the early myth-makers, in their derivation of all things from Ocean and Tethys, seem to have noticed especially the fact of change in the world. The Heracliteans, therefore, have the advantage in the appeal to language and mythology. Still, their Eleatic opponents may be right philosophically. The makers of language and myth may have framed words and imagined the origin of things in accordance with what is apparent but not real. Real existence in itself may be stable. If this is so, then, to express philosophic thought accurately, it will be necessary to reform language. In the meantime, the proper method in all our inquiries and reasonings must be, to attend to things rather than words. According to the Platonic doctrine, the " place of ideas " is the soul 1 . In virtue of its peculiar relations to those stable and permanent existences known by intellect, the individual soul is itself permanent. It gives unity, motion and life to the 1 Arist. Be An. iii. 4, 429 a 27. (R. P. 251 c.) V] OF PLOTINUS 43 fluent aggregate of material particles forming its temporary body. It disappears from one body and reappears in another, existing apart in the intervals between its mortal lives. Thus by Plato the opposition of soul and body is brought, as a subordinate relation, under the more general opposition of the stable ideas — the existence of which is not purely and simply in the soul, but is also in some way transcendent — and the flux of material existence. For Plotinus, this subordinate opposition has become the starting-point. He does not dismiss the earlier antithesis ; but the main problem with him is not to find permanence somewhere as against absolute flux. He allows in the things of sense also a kind of permanence. His aim is first of all to prove that the soul has a real existence of its own, distinguished from body and corporeal modes of being. For in the meantime body as such — and no longer, as with the Heracliteans, a process of the whole — had been set up by the dominant schools as the absolute reality. By the Epicureans and Stoics, everything that can be spoken of at all was regarded as body, or a quality or relation of body, or else as having no being other than "nominal." The main point of attack for scepticism had been the position common to the naturalistic schools, that external things can be known by direct appre- hension as they really are. Neither the Academical nor the Pyrrhouist scepticism, however, had taken the place of the ruling dogmatic system, which was that of the Stoics. Thus the doctrine that Plotinus had to meet was still essentially materialism, made by the sceptical attack less sure of itself, but not dethroned. The method he adopts is to insist precisely on the para- doxical character of the soul's existence as contrasted with that of corporeal things. How specious is the view of his opponents he allows. Body can be seen and touched. It resists pressure and is spread out in space. Soul is invisible and intangible, and by its very definition unextended. Thus language has to be struggled with in the attempt to describe it ; and in the end can only be made to express the nature of soul by con- straining it to purposes for which most men never think of employing it. What is conclusive, however, as against the 44 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V materialistic view, is that the soul cannot be described at all except by phrases which would be nonsensical if applied to body or its qualities, or to determinations of particular bodies. Once the conception of soul has been fixed as that of an incorporeal reality, body is seen to admit of a kind of explanation in terms of soul — from which it derives its " form " — whereas the essential nature of soul admitted of no explana- tion in terms of body. Above soul and beneath body, as we shall see, Plotinus has other principles, derived from earlier metaphysics, by which he is able to construct a complete philosophy, and not merely what would be called in modern phrase a " rational psychology." His psychology, however, is the centre. Within the soul, he finds all the metaphysical principles in some way represented. In it are included the principles of unity, of pure intellect, of moving and vitalising power, and, in some sense, of matter itself. Further, by what may be called his " empirical psychology," he prepared the starting-point for the distinctively modern " theory of knowledge." This he did, as Prof. Siebeck has shown 1 , by the new precision he gave to the conception of consciousness. On this side he reaches forward to Descartes, as on the other side he looks back to Plato and Aristotle. 1. Psychology. It is absurd, or rather impossible, says Plotinus at the opening of one of his earliest expositions 2 , that life should be the product of an aggregation of bodies, or that things without understanding should generate mind. If, as some say, the soul is a permeating air with a certain habitude (Trvev/Aavrm exov) — and it cannot be air simply, for there are innumerable airs without life — then the habitude (7rm exov or exeats) is either a mere name, and there is really nothing but the " breath," or it is a kind of being (rtov ovtiov ri). In the latter case, it is a rational principle and of another nature than body (\0709 av etrj Ti9 >cal ou awfia ical <j>vai<; erepa). If the soul were matter, it could produce only the effects of the particular kind of 1 Geschichte der Psychologie, i. 2. 2 E1111. iv. 7. V] OF PLOTINUS 45 matter that it is — giving things its own quality, hot or cold, and so forth — not all the opposite effects actually produced in the organism. The soul is not susceptible of quantitative increase or diminution, or of division. Thus it has not the characters of a thing possessing quantity (airoaov apa ?; yfrv-^v)- The unity in perception would be impossible if that which perceives consisted of parts spatially separated. It is impossible that the mental perception, for example, of a pain in the finger, should be transmitted from the "animal spirit" (yfrv^iKov nrv€vp,a) of the finger to the ruling part (to rjyep,ovovi>) in the organism. For, in that case, there must either be accumu- lated an infinity of perceptions, or each intermediate part in succession must feel the pain only in itself, and not in the parts previously affected ; and so also the ruling part when it becomes affected in its turn. That there can be no such physical transmission as is supposed of a mental perception, results from the very nature of material mass, which consists of parts each standing by itself: one part can have no know- ledge of what is suffered by another part. Consequently we must assume a percipient which is everywhere identical with itself. Such a percipient must be another kind of being than body. That which thinks can still less be body than that which perceives. For even if it is not allowed that thought is the laying hold on intelligibles without the use of any bodily organ, yet there are certainly involved in it apprehensions of things without magnitude (ap,eye6wv avTikifaeLs). Such are abstract conceptions, as for example those of the beautiful and the just. How then can that which is a magnitude think that which is not ? Must we suppose it to think the indivisible with that in itself which is divisible ? If it can think it at all, it must rather be with some indivisible part of itself. That which thinks, then, cannot be body. For the supposed thinking body has no function as an extended whole (and to be such is its nature as body), since it cannot as a whole come in contact with an object that is incorporeal. The soul in relation to the body, according to Plotinus's own mode of statement, is "all in all and all in every part 1 ." Thus ^Enn. iv. 2, 1. 46 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V it is in a sense divisible because it is in all the parts of a divisible body. Properly it is indivisible because it is all in the whole and all in each part of it. Its unity is unlike that of a body, which is one by spatial continuity, having different parts each of which is in a different place ; and unlike that of a quality of body such as colour, which can be wholly in many discontinuous bodies. In the case of a quality, that which is the same in all portions of body that possess it in common is an affection (Trddrj^a), and not an essence (ova la). Its identity is formal, and not numerical, as is the case with the soul 1 . In this general argumentation, it will be observed, Plotinus starts from the supposition that the body has a reality other than phenomenal. Allowing this, he is able to demonstrate against his opponents that a reality of a different kind from that of body must also be assumed. In his metaphysics he goes further, and reduces corporeal things in effect to pheno- mena ; but in his psychology he continues to take a view nearer that of "common-sense." Thus he is confronted with the difficulties that have since become familiar about the "connexion of body and mind," and the possibility of their interaction. He lays bare in a single saying the root of all such difficulties. How if, in talking of a "mixture" of a corporeal with an incorporeal nature, we should be trying to realise an impossibility, as if one should say that linear magni- tude is mixed with whiteness' 2 ? The solution for psychology is found in the theory that the soul itself remains " unmixed " in spite of its union with body; but that it causes the pro- duction of a " common " or " dual " or " composite " nature, 1 Cf. Erin. vi. 4, 1. The peculiar relation of the soul, in itself indivisible, to the body, in itself divisible, and so communicating a kind of divisibility to the soul, Plotinus finds indicated by the "divine enigma" of the " mixture" in the Tiviaeus. Enn. iv. 2, 2: tovto &pa earl rb ddws riviy^ivov 'ttJs d/xeplarov K<xl del Kara to. avra exovaijs [ovaias] kclI ttjs irepl rd auifxara yiyvoixivqs fxeptaTTJs rpirov e| dfj.<pdii> cweKep&aaTO ovaias eldos.' - Enn. i. 1, 4 : ftr-qTeov di Kal rbv rpdvov tt)s /u£ews, /xriTrore ov Swards rj, w<nrep dv e'i tis X^yoi /x€/j,lx^ al - Aei/K^ ypa-whv, <pucriv dWrjv aXXij. This book, though coming first in Porphyry's arrangement according to subjects, is given as the last but one in the chronological order. V] OF PLOTINUS 47 which is the subject in perception. By the aid of this inter- mediary, the unity of the soul is reconciled — though not without perplexities in detail — with localisation of the organic functions that subserve its activity. The different parts of the animated body participate in the soul's powers in different ways 1 . According as each organ of sense is fitted for one special function, a particular power of perception may be said to be there ; the power of sight in the eyes, of hearing in the ears, of smell in the nostrils, of taste in the tongue, of touch everywhere. Since the primary organs of touch are the nerves, which have also the power of animal motion, and since the nerves take their origin from the brain, in the brain may be placed the starting-point of the actual exercise of all powers of perception and movement. Above perception is reason. This power has not properly a physical organ at all, and so is not really in the head ; but it was assigned to the head by the older writers because it com- municates directly with the psychical functions of which the brain is the central organ. For these last, as Plotinus remarks, have a certain community with reason. In perception there is a kind of judgment ; and on reason together with the imagina- tion derived from perception, impulse follows. Tn making the brain central among the organs that are in special relation with mind, Plotinus of course adopts the Platonic as against the Aristotelian position, which made the heart central. At the same time, he incorporates what had since been discovered about the special functions of the nervous system, which were unknown to Aristotle as to Plato. The vegetative power of the soul he places in relation with the liver, because here is the origin of the veins and the blood in the veins, by means of which that power causes the nourish- ment of the body. Hence, as with Plato, appetite is assigned to this region. Spirited emotion, in accordance with the Platonic psychology, has its seat in the breast, where is the spring of lighter and purer blood. Both perceptions and memories are " energies " or activities, 1 Enn. iv. 3, 23. 48 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V not mere passive impressions received and stored up in the soul 1 . Take first the case of the most distinct perception. In sight, when we wish to perceive anything clearly, we direct our vision in a straight line to the object. This outwardly directed activity would not be necessary if the object simply left its impression on the soul. Were this the whole process, we should see not the outward objects of vision, but images and shadows of them ; so that what we see would be other than the things themselves {ware ciXka fieu ehai avrd rd irpdy/xaTa, aXXa 8e ra r)p2v opwfxeva). In hearing as in sight, perceptions are energies, not impressions nor yet passive states (fii) tvttol, /j.r)S€ irelae^). The impression is an articulated stroke in the air, on which it is as if letters were written by that which makes the sound. The power of the soul as it were reads those impressions. In the case of taste and smell, the passive affections (irddr}) are one thing ; the perceptions and judgments of them are another. Memory of things is produced by exercise of the soul, either generally or in relation to a special class of them. Children remember better because they have fewer things to attend to. Mere multitude of impressions retained, if memory were simply an affair of retaining impressions, would not cause them to be less remembered. Nor should we need to consider in order to remind ourselves; nor forget things and afterwards recall them to mind. The persistence of passive impressions in the soul, if real, would be a mark rather of weakness than of strength, for that which is most fixedly impressed is so by giving way (to <ydp evrvTrcoTarov rw eliceiv earl tolovtov). But where there is really weakness, as in the old, both memory and perception are worse. The activity of perception, though itself mental, has direct physical conditions. That of memory has not. Memory itself belongs wholly to the soul, though it may take its start from what goes on in the composite being. What the soul directly preserves the memory of, is its own movements, not those of body. Pressure and reaction of bodies can furnish no explana- tion of a storing-up of mental " impressions " (tvttoi), which are 1 Enn. iv. 6. V] OF PLOTINUS 49 not magnitudes. That the body, through being in flux, is really a hindrance to memory, is illustrated by the fact that often additions to the store cause forgetfulness, whereas memory emerges when there is abstraction and purification 1 . Some- thing from the past that was retained but is latent may be recalled when other memories or the impressions of the moment are removed. Yet. though it is not the composite being but the soul itself that possesses memory, memories come to it not only from its spontaneous activity, but from its activity incited by that which takes place in consequence of its association with the body 2 . There are memories of what has been done and suffered by the dual nature, though the memories themselves, as distinguished from that which incites them, are purely mental. Thus indirectly the physical organism has a bearing on memory as well as on perception. It follows, however, from the general view, that memory as well as reason belongs to the " separable " portion of the soul. Whether those who have attained to the perfection of virtue will, in the life of complete separation from the body, retain indefinitely their memories of the past, is another question. The discussion of it belongs rather to the ethics than to the pure psychology of Plotinus. To specific questions about sense-perception, Plotinus de- votes two short books, both of which are concerned primarily with vision. Discussing the transmission of light 3 , he finds that, like all perception, seeing must take place through some kind of body. The affection of the medium, however, need not be identical with that of the sense-organ. A reed, for example, through which is transmitted the shock of a torpedo, is not affected like the hand that receives the shock. The air, he concludes, is no instrument in vision. If it were, we should be able to see without looking at the distant object ; just as we are warmed by the heated air we are in contact with. In the case of heat too, Plotinus adds, we are warmed at the same time with the air, rather than by means of it. Solid bodies receive more of the heat than does the air intervening between them 1 Enn. iv. 3, 26 : Trpocrride/x^vuv tlvCip XrjOrj, 4v 8' a<pa.t.pl<rei ko.1 Kadapaei avaxinrrei iroWaKts 17 /ivripirj. * Enn. iv. 3, 27. 3 Enn. iv. 5. w. 4 50 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V and the heated object. In pursuance of this argument, he remarks that even the transmission of sound is not wholly dependent on a stroke in an aerial medium. Tones vary according to the differences of the bodies from which the sound starts, and not simply according to the shock. Furthermore, sounds are transmitted within our bodies without the inter- mediation of air; as when bones are bent or sawn 1 . The shock itself, whether in air or not, when it arrives at perception is the sound. Light Plotinus defines as an incorporeal energy of the luminous body directed outwards. Being an " energy," and not a mere quality (7rotoT?7<?), it is capable of overleaping an interval without becoming inherent in that which occupies the interval; as, in fact, it leaves no impress on the air through which it passes. It can exist in the interspace without a percipient, though a percipient, if present, would be affected by it. For positive explanation here, Plotinus falls back on the idea, borrowed from the Stoics, of a " sympathy " binding together remote but like parts of the universe. The other book mentioned 2 , which discusses the question why things seen at a distance appear small, is interesting from its points of contact with Berkeley. To solve the problem, Plotinus sets out in quest of something more directly psychological than the " visual angle 3 ." Is not one reason for differences of estimate, he asks, because our view of magnitude is in an " accidental " relation to colour, which is what we primarily behold 4 ? To perceive how large any magnitude really is, we must be near it, so as to be able to go over its parts in succession. At a distance, the parts of the object do not permit accurate dis- cernment of their relative colouring, since the colours arrive faint (a/xvSpd). Faintness in colours corresponds to smallness in magnitude; both have in common "the less" (t6 tjttov). Thus the magnitude, following the colour, is diminished pro- 1 Erin. iv. 5, 5 : ovk ev dipt, dXXd o~vyKpoto~avTos Kal TrK-fj^avros dWo dWov' olov Kal outCov Kap\f/eis irpbs dWrfka iro.pa.Tpijiop.ivuv dipos p.r) ovtos pLera^i Kal TrpLcreLs. 2 Enn. ii. 8. 3 Of. Theory of Vision, § 79. 4 Enn. ii. 8, 1 : on Kara avp^e^r/Kos opa/rai to p.iyedo$ tov xP<Aucctos irpuxus OewpovpL&ov, V] OF PLOTINUS 51 portionally (dvd \6yov). The nature of the affection, however, becomes plainer in things of varied colours. Confusion of colours, whether in near or distant objects, causes apparent diminution of size, because the parts do not offer differences by which they can be accurately distinguished and so measured 1 . Magnitudes also of the same kind and of like colours are deceptive because the sight slips away; having, for precisely the same reason as in the ca^e of confused colours, no hold on the parts. Again, distant objects look near at hand because there is loss of visible detail in the intervening scenery. Close as all this comes to Berkeley, at least in psychological method, the incidental remark comes still closer, that that to which we primarily refer visible magnitude appears to be touch. This occurs in a question about the <: magnitude " of sound, to which reference is made by way of illustrating the analogy of great and small in different sense-perceptions 2 . Feeling, in the sense of pleasure and pain, according to Plotinus, belongs primarily to the animated body, in the parts of which it is localised 3 . The perception of it, but not the feeling itself, belongs to the soul. Sometimes, however, in speaking of the feeling of pleasure or pain, we include along with it the accompanying perception. Corporal desires too have their origin from the common nature of the animated body. That this is their source is shown by the differences, in respect of desires, between different times of life, and between persons in health and disease. In his account of desire and aversion, Plotinus notes the coincidence between mental and bodily movements 4 . The difference between the affection of the animated body on the one side and the soul's clear per- ception of it on the other, applies both to appetitive and to irascible emotion 5 . Of these the second is not derived from 1 Cf. Theory of Vision, § 56. - Enn. II. 8, 1 : rivi yap irpwTWS to iv rrj <pwvrj /xiyedos, uo-irep Soku Trj 6\(pf) to opdi/xevov ; » Enn. iv. 4, 18—21. 4 Enn. iv. 4, 20 : eV ttjs ddtvrjs iyiveTo r\ yvuxns, ko.1 dirayuv e/c rod ttoiovvtos to irados T] \pvxn Pov\o(*ivr) iiroiei ti)v <pvyr)v, ko.1 tov irpwrov wadovTos OtSacr/coiros tovto <j>evyovTbs irws Kai avrov iv t-q o-vo-to\tj. 5 Enn. iv. 4 r 28. 4—2 52 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V the first, but both spring from a common root. That its origin cannot be entirely independent is shown by the fact that those who are less eager after bodily pleasures are less prone to anger and irrational passions. To explain the impulse (op fir}) to repel actively the cause of injury, we must suppose perception added to the mere resentment (a<yavaKrrjcns:), which, as a passion, is primarily a boiling-up of the blood. The " trace of soul " on which this kind of emotion depends (to eKireaov eh Ov/xov Ixvos) has its seat in the heart. Error too arises from the common nature, by which right reason becomes weak, as the wisest counsellor in an assembly may be overborne by the general clamour 1 . The rational power, with Plotinus as with Aristotle, is in its own nature " unmixed"; but it has to manifest itself under conditions of time and in relation to the composite being. Further discussion of these points will in the main come better under the head of meta- physics than of psychology. A distinctively psychological theory, however, is the explicit transformation of the Platonic " reminiscence " into a doctrine of " innate ideas " potentially present. The term " memory," Plotinus observes, is improperly applied to the intellectual energising of the soul in accordance with its innate principles 2 . The reason why the older writers ascribed memory and reminiscence to the soul when it thus energises, was apparently because it is then energising in accordance with powers it always had (as it has now latent memories) but does not always bring into action, and especially cannot bring into action on its first arrival in the world. In this place for one Plotinus does not in the least fail to recognise that there has been scientific progress since the time of those whom he calls " the ancients." The higher and the lower powers of the soul meet in the imaginative faculty ((fravracrla, to (pavTaaTtKov), which is the psychical organ of memory and self-consciousness. By this view the dispersion is avoided that would result from assigning memory of desires to the desiring part of the soul, memories of perception to the perceiving part, and memories of thought 1 Enn. iv. 4, 17. 2 Enn. iv. 3, 25. V] OF PLOTINUS 53 to the thinking part. Thought is apprehended by the imagi- nation as in a mirror; the notion (i'6t]fia) at first indivisible and implicit being conveyed to it by an explicit discourse (Xoyo?). For thought and the apprehension of thought are not the same {aWo yap r) vorjats, /cal aWo ?; t?}? vo/jaews dvri- \?;\/a?) ; the former can exist without the latter. That which thus apprehends thought apprehends perceptions also 1 . Here we come to the psychological conception of " con- sciousness," which Prof. Siebeck has traced through its formative stages to its practically adequate expression by Plotinus 2 . By Plato and Aristotle, as he points out, such expressions are used as the " seeing of sight," and, at a higher degree of generality, the " perceiving of perception " and the " thinking of thought " ; but they have no perfectly general term for the consciousness with which we follow any mental process whatever, as distin- guished from the process itself. Approximations to such terms were made in the post-Aristotelian period by the Stoics and others, but it was Plotinus who first gained complete mastery of the idea. Sometimes he speaks of " common perception " (o-vvalcrdrjais) in a generalised sense. His most usual expres- sion is that of an " accompaniment " (irapaKo\ov6r]ais) of its own mental activities by the soul. " Self-consciousness," in its distinctive meaning, is expressed by "accompanying oneself" {irapaKoXovOelv kavru>). With these terms are joined expres- sions for mental "synthesis" (avvdeaLS and <tvv€gl<;) as a unitary activity of the soul in reference to its contents. Important as the conception of consciousness became for modern thought, it is not for Plotinus the highest. Prof. Siebeck himself draws attention to one remarkable passage 3 in which he points out that many of our best activities, both theoretical and practical, are unaccompanied at the time by consciousness of them ; as for example reading, especially when we are reading intently ; similarly, the performance of brave actions ; so that there is a danger lest consciousness should make the activities it accompanies feebler {ware rets irapa- Ko\ovdi]aeL<; Kivhvveveiv dfivSporepa*; auras tcis evepyeias als 1 Emi. iv. 3, 28—30. - Geschichte der Psychologic, i. 2, pp. 331 ff. 3 Enn. i. 4, 10. 54 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V irapaKokovQovai iroielv). The rank assigned to introspective consciousness of mental activities is similar to that which is assigned to memory 1 . It is above sense, but lower than pure intellect, which energises with more perfection in its absence. The organ of introspection and of memory, as we have seen, is the same. The highest mode of subjective life, next to the complete unification in which even thought disappears, is intellectual self-knowledge. Here the knower is identical with the known. On this too Plotinus is not without keen psychological observa- tions, apart from the metaphysical developments next to be considered. The strong impression of a sense-perception, he remarks, cannot consist with the attainment of this intellectual unity. Whatever exaggerates feeling lowers the activity of thought. The perception of evils, for example, carries with it a more vehement shock, but less clear knowledge. We are more ourselves in health than in disease, but disease makes itself more felt, as being other than ourselves. The attitude of self-knowledge, Plotinus adds, is quite unlike that in which we know an object by external perception. Even the knower cannot place himself outside like a perceived object and gaze upon himself with the eyes of the body 2 . Within the mind as its very centre is the supreme unity beyond even self-knowledge. This is one with the metaphysical cause of all thiugs, and must first be discussed as such, since the proof of its reality is primarily metaphysical. Its psychological relations will best be dealt with in the chapter on the mysticism of Plotinus. 2. Metaphysics. Apart from a unifying principle, nothing could exist. All would be formless and indeterminate, and so would have properly no being. A principle of unity has already been recognised in the soul. It is not absent in natural things, but here it is at a lower stage ; body having less unity than soul 1 Erin. iv. 4, 2. 2 Erin. v. 8, 11 : ovok yap ovd' avrbs Swarm it,w dels eavrbv ws aiaO-qTov bvra 6(pda\/j.6is rots tov (TLOfxarus (SXeTreiv, V] OF PLOTINUS 55 because its parts are locally separate. In soul, however, we cannot rest as the highest term. Particular souls, by reason of what they have in common, can only be understood as derived from a general soul, which is their cause but is not identical with all or any of them. Again, the general soul falls short of complete unity by being the principle of life and motion to the world, which is other than itself. What it points to as a higher unifying principle is absolutely stable intellect, thinking itself and not the world, but containing as identical with its own nature the eternal ideas of all the forms, general and particular, that become explicit in the things of time and space. Even intellect has still a certain duality, because, though intelligence and the intelligible are the same, that which thinks distinguishes itself from the object of thought. Beyond thought and the being which, while identical with it, is distinguishable in apprehension, is the absolute unity that is simply identical with itself. This is other than all being and is the cause of it. It is the good to which all things aspire ; for to particular things the greatest unification attainable is the greatest good ; and neither the goodness and unity they possess, nor their aspiration after a higher degree of it, can be explained without positing the absolute One and the absolute Good as their source and end. By the path of which this is a slight indication, Plotinus ascends to the summit of his metaphysics. The proof that the first principle has really been attained, must be sought partly in the demonstration of the process by which the whole system of things is derived from it, partly in individual experience. This last, being incommunicable— though not to be had without due preparation — belongs to the mystical side of the doctrine. Of the philosophical doctrine itself, the method is not mystical. The theory of " emanation " on which it depends is in reality no more than a very systematic expression of the principle common to Plato and Aristotle, that the lower is to be explained by the higher 1 . 1 See for example Enn. v. '.), 4 : ou yap orj, d>s olovrcu, ipvxv vovv reXeiwOdaa. ytvvq.' woOtv yap to dvvafxti evepydq earui, /mtj tou els evipynav ayovTos airiov ovtos ; ...dtb Sti ra irp&TO. tvtpydq rlOtcdai nal airpoaota ko\ re'Xeia. 56 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V The accepted term, " emanation," is derived from one of the metaphors by which Plotinus illustrates the production of each order of being from the next above. He compares the cause of all to an overflowing spring which by its excess gives rise to that which comes after it 1 . This similarly produces the next, and so forth, till at length in matter pure indetermination is reached. The metaphorical character of this representation, however, is carefully insisted on. There is no diremption of the higher principle. God and mind do not disperse themselves in individual souls and in natural things, though these are nowhere cut off from their causes. There is a continual process from first to last, of which the law is the same throughout. Each producing cause remains wholly in its proper seat (iv rfj oUeia ehpa), while that which is produced takes an inferior station 2 . The One produces universal Mind, or Intellect that is one with the Intelligible. Intellect produces the Soul of the Whole. This produces all other existences, but without itself lapsing. Nothing within the series of the three intelligible principles can be said to lapse in production ; the term being applicable only to the descent of the individual soul. The order throughout, both for the intelligible causes and for the visible universe, is a logical order of causation, not an order in time. All the producing causes and their effects in every grade always existed and always will exist. The production by the higher causes has the undeviating character of natural necessity, and is not by voluntary choice and discursive reason, which are secondary resultants within the world of particulars. This philosophical meaning Plotinus makes clear again and again. His metaphors are intended simply as more or less inadequate illustrations. One that comes nearer to his thought than that of the overflowing spring, is the metaphor of illumina- tion by a central source of light : for according to his own theory light is an incorporeal energy projected without loss. Since, however, it is still an energy set going from a body, he admits that even this comparison has some inexactitude. In this mode of expression, Mind is the eternal " irradiation " of 1 Emi. v. 2, 1. 2 Enn. v. 2, 2. V] OF PLOTINUS 57 the One 1 . As Mind looks back to the One, Soul looks back to Mind; and this looking back is identical with the process of generation. Plotinus himself traces the idea of this causal series to Plato, for whom, he says, the Demiurgus is Intellect, which is produced by the Good beyond mind and being, and in its turn produces Soul 2 . This historical derivation, as we have seen, was accepted by Porphyry. Plotinus goes on to interpret earlier philosophers from the same point of view. He recognises, how- ever, that the distinctions between the One in its different senses drawn by the Platonic Parmenides were not made with that exactitude by Parmenides himself. Aristotle, he says, coming later, makes the primal reality separable indeed and intelligible, but deprives it of the first rank by the assertion that it thinks itself. To think itself belongs to Mind, but not to the One 3 . As in the nature of things there are three principles, so also with us 4 . For there is reality in this world of ours, and not a mere semblance. The virtue and knowledge here are not simply images of archetypes yonder in the intelligible world. If indeed we take the world here not as meaning simply the visible aspect of things, but as including also the soul and what it contains, everything is " here " that is " there 5 ." The order of first, second and third in the intelligible prin- ciples is not spatial 6 . In the intelligible order, body may be said to be in soul, soul in mind, and mind in the One 7 . By such -expressions is to be understood a relation of dependence, not the being in a place in the sense of locality. If any one objects that place can mean nothing but boundary or interval of space, let him dismiss the word and apply his understanding 1 Enn. v. 1, 6: irepi\ap.^/i.v ii- avrov /xeV, e'| avrov 8e /xiuovros, olov rjXiov to nepl avrbv \ap.irpbv (pws irepiOi'ov, e'if avrov del yevv^fievof fxivovros. 2 Enn. v. 1,8: uxrre TLXaruva eibevai in p.tv Ta.ya.6ov rbv vovv, etc 5£ rod vov rrju 3 Enn. v. 1, 9. 4 Enn. v. 1, 10: wawep 5i iv rr\ (pvan rpirra ravra. ian to. eipij/xi'i'a, oi'tu XPV vo/Jii^eiv teal nap' i)ixlv ravra elvai. 5 Enn. v. 9, 13 : iravra ivravda, baa. Kaxtl. 6 Enn. vi. 5, 4. 7 Enn. v. 5, 9. 58 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v to the thing signified 1 . The incorporeal and unextended in which extended body participates is not to be thought of as a point ; for mass, which includes an infinity of points, participates in it. Nor yet must we think of it as stretched out over the whole of the mass ; but of the whole extended mass as par- ticipating in that which is itself without spatial interval 2 . This is the general relation of the visible to the intelligible world. As non-spatial dependence and implication, we have found that it runs through the intelligible causes themselves. In what relates to the difference between the extended and the unextended, the character of intelligible being is already perfectly determinate not only in soul, but in soul as the principle of organic life. For that principle transcends the opposition between small and great. If it is to be called small as having no extension of its own, it may equally be called great as being adequate to the animation of the whole body with which it is connected, while this is growing in bulk 3 . The soul is all in the germ ; yet in a manner it contains the full- grown plant or animal. In itself it undergoes no change of dimensions. Though the principle of growth, it does not grow ; nor, when it causes motion, is it moved in the motion which it causes 4 . The primal One from which all things are is everywhere and nowhere. As being the cause of all things, it is everywhere. As being other than all things, it is nowhere. If it were only " everywhere," and not also " nowhere," it would be all things 5 . No predicate of being can be properly applied to it. To call it the cause is to predicate something, not of it but of ourselves, who have something from it while it remains in itself 6 . This is not the " one " that the soul attains by abstracting from magnitude and multitude till it arrives at the point and the arithmetical unit. It is greatest of all, not by magnitude but 1 Eun. vi. 4, 2 : tt\v tov wo/xaros d(pels Kar-qyopiav rrj diavolq. to Xeyo/xevov XafifiaveTW. 2 Erin. vi. 4, 13. 3 Eim. vi. 4, 5 : fxapTvpei 5e ry p.eydXip tt)s ^i'X^s Kai to /xei^oi'os tov oynou yti/o/j.ei'ov (pdaveiv ewl irdv avrov tyjv avTrjv y'vxw, V ew eXaTTOvos oyKov i]v. 4 Enu. in. 6, 4. 5 Enu. in. l J, 3. u Erin. vi. 9, 3. V] OF PLOTINUS 59 by potency ; in such a manner that it is also by potency that which is without magnitude. It is to be regarded as infinite, not because of the impossibility of measuring or counting it, but because of the impossibility of comprehending its power 1 . It is perfectly self-sufficing; there is no good that it should seek to acquire by volition. It is good not in relation to itself, but to that which participates in it. And indeed that which imparts good is not properly to be called "good," but "the Good " above all other goods. " That alone neither knows, nor has what it does not know; but being One present to itself it needs not thought of itself." Yet in a sense it is all beings because all are from it 2 ; and it generates the thought that is one with being. As it is the Good above all goods, so, though without shape or form, it possesses beauty above beauty. The love of it is infinite ; and the power or vision by which mind thinks it is intellectual love 3 . Any inconsistency there might appear to be in making assertions about the One is avoided by the position that nothing — not even that it "is" any more than that it is "good" — is to be affirmed of it as a predicate. The names applied to it are meant only to indicate its unique reality 4 . The question is then raised, whether this reality is best indicated by names that signify freedom, or chance, or necessity. Before we can know whether an expression signifying freedom (to e</>' rjfiiv) may be applied in any sense to the gods and to God (eVt deovs ical eri fiaXkov iirl deov), we must know in what sense it is applicable to ourselves 5 . If we refer that which is in our power to will (/3ov\r](T^\ and place this in right reason (iv Xoyw 6p9a), we may — by stretching the terms a little — reach the conclusion that an unimpeded theoretic activity such as we ascribe in its perfection to the gods who live according to mind, is properly called free. The objection that to be free in this 1 Enn. vi. 9, 6 ; \rfivTeov ol ko.1 direLpov clvto ov ry dSu^iTrjTW r) rod fxeyidovs rj tov apiO/xov, ctXXa t<£ drnpCK^TTT^ ttjs ovudfiecos. * Enu. vi. 7, 32: ovdev ovv touto tQv 6vtwv /ecu irdvra' ovbev ixiv, on varepa. to. oi'ra, TT&vTa 5e, otl e£ clvtov. 3 Enn. vi. 7, 35. Plotinus's actual expression is vovs ipQv. ■> Enn. vi. 7, 38. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 1. 60 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V sense is to be " enslaved to one's own nature " is dismissed with the remark that that only is enslaved which, being withheld by something else, has it not in its power to go towards the good 1 . The view that seems implied in the objection, namely, that freedom consists in action contrary to the nature of the agent, is an absurdity 2 . But to the supreme principle, from which all things have being and power of their own, how can the term be applied in any sense ? The audacious thought might be started that it " happens to be " as it is, and is not master of what it is, but is what it is, not from itself; and so, that it has no freedom, since its doing or not doing what it has been necessitated to do or not to do, is not in its own power. To this the reply is, that we cannot say that the primal cause is by chance, or that it is not master of its origin ; because it has not come to be 3 . The whole difficulty seems to arise from our positing space (-^wpav /cal tottov) as a kind of chaos, and then introducing the principle into our imaginary space ; whereupon we inquire whence and how it came there 4 . We get rid of the difficulty by assigning to the One no place, but simply the being as it is, — and this because we are bound so to express ourselves by necessity of speech. Thus, if we are to speak of it at all, we must say that it is lord of itself and free. Yet it must be allowed that there is here a certain impropriety, for to be lord of itself belongs properly to the essence {ovaia) identical with thought, and the One is before this essence 5 . With a similar impropriety, its will and its essence may be said to be the same. Each particular being, striving after its good, wills that more than to be what it is, and then most thinks that it is, when it participates in the good. It wills even itself, so far only as it has the good. Carry this over to the Good which is the principle of all particular goods, and its will to be what it is, is seen to be inseparable from its being what it is. In this mode of speech, accordingly, — having to choose between ascribing to it on the one hand will and creative activity in relation to 1 Enn. vi. 8, 4. "- Enn. vi. 8, 7. 3 Enn. vi. 8,7: to 5e irpGrrov otire Kara Tvyy)v dv \eyoi/aev, oiire ov Kvpiov rrjs avTou yevicxeuis, oti fxrjde yeyove. 4 Enn. vi. 8, 11. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 12. V] OF PLOTINUS 61 itself, on the other hand a contingent relation which is the name of unreason, — we must say, not that it is " what it hap- pened to be," but that it is " what it willed to be 1 ." We might say also that it is of necessity what it is, and could not be otherwise ; but the more exact statement is, not that it is thus because it could not be otherwise, but because the best is thus. It is not taken hold of by necessity, but is itself the necessity and law of other things 2 . It is love, and the object of love, and love of itself 3 . That which as it were desires and that which is desired are one 4 . When we, observing some such nature in ourselves, rise to this and become this alone, what should we say but that we are more than free and more than in our own power? By analogy with mind, it may be called operation {evep^fxa) and energy. Its energy and as it were waking {olov eypiiyopais) are eternal 5 . Reason and mind are derived from the principle as a circle from its centre 6 . To allow that it could not make itself other than it did, in the sense that it can produce only good and not evil, is not to limit its freedom and absolute power. The power of choice between opposites belongs to a want of power to persevere in what is best 7 . The One and Good alone is in truth free; and must be thought and spoken of, though in reality beyond speech and thought, as creating itself by its own energy before all being 8 . To the question, why the One should create anything beyond itself, Plotinus answers that since all things, even those without life, impart of themselves what they can, the most perfect and the first good cannot remain in itself as envious, and the potency 1 Enn. vi. 8, 13 : umre ovk otrep Ztvx^v icmv, d\X' owep r)j3ov\-fidr] clvt6s. Cf. c. 20 : aurds £o~ti nai 6 wapdyiov iavrov. 2 Enn. vi. 8, 10. 3 Enn. vi. 8, 15 : ko.1 epda/xiov nal tpws 6 avrbs ko.1 avrov Upws. 4 Ibid. : t6 olov iipi.ep.evov t<jS e<p€Ti^ '4v. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 16. 6 Enn. vi. 8, 18. " Enn. vi. 8, 21 : ko.1 yap rb to. avriKel/xeva bvvaadat dovva/utas earl rod iirl rod aplo~Tov fxivuv. 8 Since it is energy in the Aristotelian sense, or complete realisation, it is dvevtpyqrov. That is, there is no higher realisation to which it can proceed. Cf. Enn. v. 6, 6 : oXws /xei> yap ovSe/xia ivtpyeia ^x €l a ^ ^aXtv evtpyeiav. In this sense, it is said (Enn. i. 7, 1) to be beyond onergy (iw^Ketva evepydas). 62 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V of all things as without power 1 . As that is the potency of all things, Mind, which it first generates, is all things actually. For knowledge of things in their immaterial essence is the things themselves 2 . Mind knows its objects not, like percep- tion, as external, but as one with itself 3 . Still this unity, as has been said, involves the duality of thinking and being thought, and hence is not the highest, but the second in order, of the suprainundane causes. Within its indivisible unity it contains the archetype of the whole visible world and of all that was or is or is to be existent in it. The relation of its Ideas to the whole of Mind resembles that of the propositions of a science to the sum of knowledge which consists of them. By this comparison, which frequently recurs, Plotinus seeks to convey the notion of a diversity in unity not expressed as local separation of parts 4 . The archetype of the world being thus existent, the world in space is necessarily produced because its production is possible. We shall see this " possibility " more exactly formulated in the theory of matter. The general state- ment is this : that, since there is the " intelligential and all-potent nature" of mind, and nothing stands between that and the production of a world, there must be a formed world corresponding to the formative power. In that which is formed, the ideas are divided ; in one part of space the idea of the sun takes shape, in another the idea of man. The archetype embraces all in its unity without spatial division 5 . Thus, while suprainundane intellect contains all real being, it has also the productive power by which the essential forms of things are made manifest in apparent separation from itself and from one another. Differences, so far as they belong to the real being, or " form," of things here, are produced by pre- existent forms in the ideal world. So far as they are merely 1 Enn. v. 4, 1. 2 Enn. v. 4, 2. Cf. Enn. v. 9, 5 : r; twv dvev i/Xijs ewiaTrifXT] ravrbv t<jJ irpdyfxaTi. 3 Enn. v. 5, 1. 4 See for example Enn. v. 9, 8. 5 Enn. v. 9, 9 : <£wrews voepds /cat wavToovvdfxov oilo-ris /cat ovdevbs didpyovros, fxrjdevbs ovtos fxera^u tovtov /cat tov S^aadai dvva.fj.evov, dvdyxT) to fxev Kocrfirjdrjvai, to 5e Koa/xrjacu. /cat to fxev KOO~fX7]6ev ityei to eldos fxefj.epiafx.4vov, dWaxov dvdpwwov /cat dWaxov r/Xiov to 8e ev evl irdvTa. V] OF PLOTINUS G3 local and temporal, they express only a necessary mode of manifestation of being, under the condition of appearing at a greater degree of remoteness from the primal cause. What then is the case with individuality ? Does it consist merely in differences of position in space and time, the only true reality being the ideal form of the " kind " ; or are there ideal forms of individuals ? Plotinus concludes decisively for the latter alternative 1 . There are as many formal differences as there are individuals, and all pre-exist in the intelligible world. What must be their mode of pre-existence we know from the nature of Intellect as already set forth. All things there are together yet distinct. Universal mind contains all particular minds ; and each particular mind expresses the whole in its own manner. As Plotinus says in one of those bursts of enthu- siasm where his scientific doctrine passes into poetry : " They see themselves in others. For all things are transparent, and there is nothing dark or resisting, but every one is manifest to every one internally and all things are manifest ; for light is manifest to light. For every one has all things in himself and again sees in another all things, so that all things are every- where and all is all and each is all, and infinite the glory. For each of them is great, since the small also is great. And the sun there is all the stars, and again each and all are the sun. In each, one thing is pre-eminent above the rest, but it also shows forth all-." The wisdom that is there is not put together from separate acts of knowledge, but is a single whole. It does not consist of many brought to one ; rather it is resolved into multitude from unity. By way of illustration Plotinus adds that the Egyptian sages, whether they seized the truth by accurate knowledge or by some native insight, appear to have expressed the intuitive character of intellectual wisdom in making a picture the sign of each thing 3 . In the intelligible world identical with intellect, as thus conceived, the time and space in which the visible world appears, though not " there " as such, pre-exist in their causes. So too, 1 See especially Enn. v. 7: Tlepl tov el ko.1 twv ko.0' frcatrra ?cmi> et8t]. 2 Enn. v. 8, 4. 3 Enn. v. 8, G. This is quite an isolated reference to Egypt. 64 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V in the rational order, does perception, before organs of percep- tion are formed. This must be so, Plotinus urges, because perception and its organs are not a product of deliberation, but are present for example in the pre-existent idea of man, by an eternal necessity and law of perfection, their causes being in- volved in the perfection of mind 1 . Not only man, but all animals, plants and elements pre-exist ideally in the intelligible world. For infinite variety is demanded in order that the whole, as one living being, may be perfect in all its parts and to the utmost degree. There, the things we call irrational pre-exist in their rational laws 2 . Nor is the thing here anywhere really mindless. We call it so when it is without mind in act; but each part is all in potency, depending as it does on its ideal cause. In the order of ideal causes there is as it were a stream of living beings from a single spring ; as if all sensible qualities were combined in one quality without losing their distinctions 3 . The particular is not merely the one particular thing that it is called. Rational division of it always brings something new to light ; so that, in this sense, each part of the whole is infinite 4 . This infinity, whether of whole or part, is one of successive involution. The process of division is not that of bisection, but is like the unfolding of wrappings 5 . The whole intelligible world may be presented to imagination as a living sphere figured over with every kind of living countenance 6 . Universal mind involves the essence of every form of reason, in one Reason as it were, great, perfect, embracing all (els olov \6<yos, fAeyas, reXeios, TrdvTas 'rrepie-^wv). As the most exact 1 Enn. vi. 7, 3: 'iyKeiTai. rb atV^ij-rt/ccV elvai /cat ovtws alaOriTLKbv iv tqj ei'5et vwb didiov dvdyKTjs Kal reXeibrr/ros, vov iv avru) ^x 0VTOS > e'twep riXeios, t&s alrlas. ' 2 Enn. vi. 7, 9: iKe'i be Kal rb dXoyov Xeybfievov Xbyos ijf, /cat rb avow vovs r)v, iwel Kal 6 vou>v ittttov vous iari, /cat 7) vb-qaLS lirirov coOs rjv. 3 Enn. VI. 7, 12: olov et ris t]v TroibrTjs fxia 7rdcras iv avrrj £x owja KaL o-uj^ovaa rets iroibrrjTas, yXvKiJTTjs fier evubias, /cat b/xov ocvojStjs woibr'qs /cat xiAtDe dvavruv 5vvdfM€Ls /cat xpw / ttdrwi' o\peis /cat &aa a<pal yivdjaKOvcnv. iaruaav be /cat 6'ira d/coat dKovovffL, irdvra p.iXi] /cat pvd/xbs iras. 4 Enn. vi. 7, 13: vovs...ov...raiirbv /cat h> n iv p,ipei, dXXd wdvra' iwel Kal to iv /nipei av ov% &, dXXd Kal tovto Eireipov biaipovp,evov. Cf. Enn. vi. 5, 5 on the infinite nature (dweipos </>t/<ns) of being. 8 Enn. vi. 7, 14 : /xri /car' evdi, dXX' els rb ivrbs del. e Enn. vi. 7, 15 fin. V] OF PLOTINUS 05 reasoning would calculate the things of nature for the best, mind has all things in the rational laws that are before reason- ing 1 . Each thing being what it is separately, and again all things being in one together, the complex as it were and com- position of all as they are in one is Mind 2 . In the being that is mind, all things are together, not only undivided by position in space, but without reference to process in time. This characteristic of intellectual being may be called " eternity 3 ." Time belongs to Soul, as eternity to Mind 4 . Soul is necessarily produced by Mind, as Mind by the primal One 5 . Thus it is in contact at once with eternal being, and with the temporal things which it generates by the power it receives from its cause. Having its existence from supramundane intellect, it has reason in act so far as that intellect is contemplated by it 6 . The Soul of the whole is perpetually in this relation to Mind ; particular souls undergo alternation; though even of them there is ever something in the intelligible world 7 . Soul has for its work, not only to think— for thus it would in no way differ from pure intellect— but to order and rule the things after it. These come to be, because production could not stop at intelligibles, the last of which is the rational soul, but must go on to the limit of all possible existence 8 . In the relation of the many souls to the one which includes 1 Enn. vi. 2, 21 : ws yap dv 6 aKpi^araros \oyiap.bs XoyicxaiTo <lis dpiara, ovrws i?X ei TrdpTa iv reus \670ts vpb \oyiap.ov oven. 2 Enn. vi. 2, 21 : x^/ns p-ev eK&vruv a Ictlv ovrwv, 6/xoO 5' av iv ivl ovtwv, tj TTaVTWV (V ivl OVTU1V 6I0V (TV /J.w\o KT) Kal (JVvOtaiS VOVS icFTl. 3 Enn. in. 7, 4 : avry 17 dtadeens avrov Kal (pvais dt-q av aiuv. 4 Enn. in. 7, 11. Cf. Enn. iv. 4, 15: alwv /j.iv irepl vovv, xpbvos bi vepl \pvxw- 5 Enn. v. 1, 7 : i/'i'XV' 7<*P yevvq vovs, vovs uv rAeios. Kal yap ri\eiov ovra. yevvdv USei, Kal fxr] 5vvafJ.iv odcrav Tocravr-qv tiyovov eZVcu. 6 Enn. v. 1, 3 : i) re ovv virocrraais avry dwb vov re ivepyeia \6yos vov avrrj opu/iivov. 7 Enn. iv. ft, 8 : ov wdcra ovd' 17 ytxeripa \pvxh Zov, d\X Zen ti aiiTrjs iv tu> vot]t(3 dd....irdaa yap Tpvxn ?X eL Tl Kal T °v "dra irpbs rb <ru>/J.a Kal rod avw wpbs vovv. 8 Enn. iv. 8, 3 : irpoaXafiovaa yap ry voepd dvat Kal aWo, Kad' 6 ttjv oUelav fcX e " UTtbffraaiv, >/o0s ovk i/xeivev, Zx eL Te ^H " Ka ^ o-vtj}, eitrep Kal irav, 8 av rj tQ>v 6vtuiv. pXtirovea 5t irpbs p.iu rb irpb iavrrjs voet, els 8e iavr-rjv ffwfri eavrrjv, eU 8i rb ner' avT-ijv KOtTfie? re Kal SioiKet Kal dpxei airrov ' 8n p.r]di olbv re fjv arrival ra ndvra ev rip vot)t$, 8vvap.ivov i<pe$rjs Kal a\\ov yeviffdai iXdrrovos fiiv, dvayKalov 8i elvai, e'iirep Kal rb irpb avrov. W. 5 66 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V all, Soul imitates Mind. It too is necessarily pluralised ; and in the inherent distinctions of the particular souls their coming to birth under different sensible manifestations is already neces- sitated. The one soul is the same in all, as in each part of a system of knowledge the whole is potentially present 1 . To soul, the higher intellect furnishes the reasons of all its operations 2 . Knowledge in the rational soul, so far as it is of intelligibles, is each thing that it thinks, and has from within both the object of thought and the thinking (to re i'otjtov ttjv re votjaiv), since mind is within 3 . Plotinus fully recognises the difficulty of the question : How, if Being and Mind and Soul are everywhere numerically one, and not merely of the same formal essence (o/ioeiSe?), can there yet be many beings and minds and souls 4 ? The answer, in the case of soul, as of mind and being, is that the one is many by intrinsic difference, not by local situation (erepoTrjTi, ov t6ttu>). The plurality of souls, as has been said, is in the rational order prior to their embodiment. In the Soul of the Whole, the many souls are present to one another without being alienated from themselves. They are not divided by spatial limits — just as the many portions of knowledge in each soul are not — and the one can contain in itself all. After this manner the nature of soul is infinite 5 . The general soul can judge of the individualised affections in each without becoming conscious to itself in each that it has passed judgment in the rest also 6 . Each of us is a whole for himself, yet all of us, in the reality that is all, are together one. Looking outward, we forget our unity. Turning back upon ourselves, either of our own accord or seized upon as the goddess seized the hair of Achilles, we behold ourselves and the whole as one with the God within 7 . 1 Enn. iv. 9, 5. 2 Enn. iv. 9, 3. When the general soul impresses form on the elements of the world, vovs is the x°PVy°s T & v M>yu)v. 3 Enn. v. 9, 7. 4 Enn. vi. 4, 4. 5 Enn. vi. 4, 4 Jin.: ovtios earlv dirupos i) ToiavTij cpvais. s Enn. vi. 4, 6 : did, tL o&v ov avvaio-ddverai 17 eripa rr)s iripas Kpl/j.a; -q otl Kpiais iariv, d\X ov ir&Oos. elra ovd' avrrj r) Kpivatra K^KpiKa \iyei, d\X' ?Kpive (xhvov. 7 Enn. vi. 5, 7 : ??W fxiv ovv opuvres t) 86ev ^rjfxfxeda ayvoovnev iv ovres, olov irpdcrcoTra TroWa els rb ?fw Kopv(pr)v ^x 0VTa eis T0 dlffa fxiav. el Si tis iin(TTpa<prjva.i dvvairo 77 irap' airoO 7} ttjs 'Adrjvds avTrjs evrvxyvas rrjs eX£ ewj, 0e6v re Kal avrbv /cat t6 Trdv oi/'erat. V] OF PLOTINUS G7 The soul is the principle of life and motion to all things ; motion being an image of life in things called lifeless. The heaven is one by the power of soul, and this world is divine through it 1 . The soul of the whole orders the world in accord- ance with the general reasons of things, as animal bodies are fashioned into " microcosms " under the particular law of the organism 2 . It creates not by deliberative intelligence, like human art, which is posterior and extrinsic. In the one soul are the rational laws of all explicit intelligence — " of gods and of all things." " Wherefore also the world has all 3 ." Individual souls are the intrinsic laws of particular minds within the universal intellect, made more explicit 4 . Not only the soul of the whole, but the soul of each, has all things in itself 5 . Wherein they differ, is in energising with different powers. Before descent and after reascent of the particular soul, each one's thoughts are manifest to another as in direct vision, without discourse". Why then does the soul descend and lose knowledge of its unity with the whole ? For the choice is better to remain above 7 . The answer is that the error lies in self-will 8 . The soul desires to be its own, and so ventures forth to birth, and takes upon itself the ordering of a body which it appropriates, or rather, which appropriates it, so far as that is possible. Thus the soul, although it does not really belong to this body, yet energises in relation to it, and in a manner becomes a partial soul in separation from the whole 9 . But what is finally the explanation of this choice of the worse, and how is it compatible with the perfection of the mundane order? How is the position of the Phaedo, that the body is a prison, and the true aim of the soul release from it, 1 Enn. v. 1, 2. - Enn. IV. 3, 10 : ola Kal ol h> o-rrfp/xaat \6yoi TrXdrrovai Kal nopcpovcri to. £ipa olov fxiKpovs rivas Kdfffiovs. 3 Enn. iv. 3, 10 fin. 4 Enn. iv. 3, 5: \6yoi vCsv ovaai ko.1 e^eiXiyfi^vai p.a\\ov t) eKuvoi...rb ravrbv Kal 'irtpov ou^ovaai fiivei re eKaarr) Iv, Kal bfxov ev iraaai.. 5 Enn. iv. 3, 6. B Enn. iv. 3, 18 : olov 6<p0a\/xbs Zkoo-tos Kal o&8tv 5t Kpvirrbv ovU TreirXao-fifrov, dXXd irplv dirt'iv dWui I8wv (Ketvos Zyvco. 7 Enu. iv. 3, 14. 8 Enn. v. 1, 1. 9 Enn. vi. 4, 16. 5—2 68 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V reconcilable with the optimism of the Timaeus ? The answer is that all — descent and reascent alike — has the necessity of a natural law. The optimism has reference to the whole order. Of this order, such as it must be in a world that is still good though below the intelligible and perfectly stable supramundane order, temporary descent, dissatisfaction with the consecmences of the descent, and the effort to return, are all conditions. Any expression that seems to imply arbitrariness at any point, is part of the mythological representation. Thus .when in the Timaeus it is said that God " sows " the souls, this is mythical, just as when he is represented as haranguing them 1 . Necessity and self-caused descent are not discordant. The soul does not go by its will to that which is worse ; yet its course is its own 2 . And it must expiate both the original error, and any evil that it may do actually. Of the first, the mere change of state is the punishment ; to the second, further chastisement is assigned. The knowledge acquired below is a good, and the soul is not to be blamed overmuch if in its regulation of sensible nature it goes a little beyond what 'is safe for itself 3 . On the other hand, a slight inclination at the beginning to the worse, if not immediately corrected, may produce a permanent disposition 4 . Be the error light or grave, it comes under an undeviating law of justice. To the particular bodies fitted for them, the souls go neither by voluntary choice nor sent, but as by some natural process for which they are ready. The universal law under which the individual falls is not outside but within each 5 . The notion that there may be in small things an element of con- tingency which is no part of the order, is suggested but not accepted 6 . The whole course of the soul through its series of bodily lives, and its release from the body when this is attained, 1 Enn. iv. 8, 4. 2 Enn. iv. 8, 5. 3 Enn. iv. 8, 7 : ypQais yap evapyecrripa rayadov i] tov kclkov welpa oh 7] dvva/jus acrdeveaTe'pa, rj ware ewLaTrjfxrj to ko.kov irpb irelpas yvQivat. 4 Enn. in. 2, 4. Cf. in. 3, 4 : Kal o-fxiKpa. pOTrrj dpKei eh ^K^acriv tov opdov. 5 Enn. iv. 3, 13. 6 Enn. iv. 3, 16 : ov yap to. /xev Set i>opt.lt;eiv <TWT€TdxOai, to. 8e Kexa\do-0ai eh rb avTe^ovaiov. el yap /car' airlas yivecrdai del xal (pvaiKa 1 ; axoXovdias Kal Kara \6yoi> 'iva Kal rd^iv p,lav, Kal tcl a/xiKp6Tepa Bet avvreraxdai. Kal vvvvcpavdat. vop.l£eiP. V] OF PLOTINUS 69 are alike necessarily determined 1 . The death of the. soul, so far as the soul can die, is to sink to a stage below moral evil — which still contains a mixture of the opposite good — and to be wholly plunged in matter 2 . Even thence it may still some- how emerge ; though souls that have descended to the world of birth need not all make the full circle, but may return before reaching the lowest point 3 . Here we come to the metaphysical doctrine by which Plotinus explains the contrasts the visible world presents. Neither moral good nor evil is with him ultimate. Of virtues even the highest, the cause is the Good, which in reality is above good (virepd- jaOov). Of moral evil, so far as it is purely evil, the cause is that principle of absolute formlessness and indeterminateness called Matter. At the same time, matter is the receptive prin- ciple by which alone the present world could be at all. Evils accordingly are an inevitable constituent of a world that is subject in its parts to birth and change. And indeed without evil there can be no good in our sense of the term. Nor is there evil unmixed in the things of nature, any more than there is unformed matter. Whence then is this principle opposed to form and unity ? That Matter is an independently existing principle over against the One, Plotinus distinctly denies. The supposition is put as inadmissible that there are dp%al 7rXe/ou9 koi Kara avvrvyjav ra irpMra^. Matter is the infinite (to aireipov) in the sense of the indeterminate (to dopio-Tov), and is generated from the infinity of power or of eternal existence that is an appanage of the One, which has not in itself indeterminateness, but creates it 5 . To the term " infinite " in the sense of an 1 Enn. iv. 3, 24 : tpiperai 8e ko.1 avros 6 iraaxuiv dyvoCiv i(f> a iraOelv irpocrrjicei, a<TT&TU) /uev rrj cpopa wavTaxov aiwpou/j.evos reus 7r\decus, Te\evTQi> 5e Cocnrep iroWa Ka/Awv oh avTeTet.vev eh tov Trpo<rrjKovTa at)ry tottov eveireaev, eKovaiw rrj (popq. to &kov<ti.ov els rb nadelv Hx 03 "- Cf. Enn. iv. 4, 45. 2 Enn. i. 8, 13: nal tovto ecrrt to eV g.5ov i\B6vTa etn.KaTa5ap6e.lv. Cf. Enn. i. 6, 6. 3 Enn. iv. 4, 5 fin. 4 Enn. n. 4, 2. 5 Enn. II. 4, 15 : e'ii] h.v -yevvridev en rrjs tov evbs airetpias fj dvpd/xeojs yj tov del, ovk ovcrvs ev eKeivip diretpias d\\a ttolovvtos. 70 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V actual extent or number that is immeasurable (aSie$JLT7]Tov), or of a quantitative infinite (Kara to ttoo-ov airetpov), there is nothing to correspond. Matter, in itself indeterminate, is that of which the nature is to be a recipient of forms. Like intel- ligible being, it is incorporeal and unextended. Place, indeed, is posterior both to matter and bodies 1 . By its absolute want of all form, that is, of all proper being, matter is at the opposite extreme to things intelligible, and is the principle of ugliness and evil 2 . It receives, indeed, all determinations, but it cannot receive them indivisibly (dfjLepws). One form in matter excludes another; so that they appear as separated by spatial intervals 3 . The reason of this is precisely that matter has no determination of its own. The soul in taking up the forms of things per- ceptible, views them with their mass put away {airoOefieva top 6jkoi> opa), because by its own form it is indivisible, and there- fore cannot receive the extended as such. Since matter, on the contrary, has no form of its own by which to unite distinc- tions, the intrinsic differences of being must be represented in it by local separation. Yet, since the intelligible world is in a sense a " world," and is many as well as one, it too must have a kind of matter 4 . This " intelligible matter " is the recipient of formal diversities in the world of being ; as sensible matter is the recipient of the varied appearances in space. The matter of the intelligible world, differing in this respect from matter properly so-called, does not receive all forms indifferently ; the same matter there having always the same form 5 . The matter "here " is thus more truly "the indeterminate" than the matter " there " ; which, in so far as it has more real being, is so much the less truly " matter 6 ." Matter itself may best be called " not-being 7 ." As the indeterminate, it is only to be appre- hended by a corresponding indeterminateness of the soul 8 — a difficult state to maintain, for, as matter itself does not remain 1 Emi. ii. 4, 12 : 6 5e tottos varepos ttjs vXtjs ko.1 tu>v aw/xdnav. 2 Enn. ii. 4, 16. 3 Enii. m. 6, 18. 4 Enn. ii. 4, 4. 5 Enn. ii. 4, 3 : ij 8e tQv ytvoixivwv uXtj del d\\o /ecu &X\o eldos ?ff%«i twi> di didiuv t) avTT) ravrov del. e Enn. ii. 4, 15. 7 Enn. in. 6, 7. 8 Enn. n. 4, 10: dopcaria tt)s \j/vxns- Cf. Enn. i. 8, 9. V] OF PLOTINUS 71 unformed in things, so the soul hastens to add some positive determination to the abstract formlessness reached by analysis. To be the subject and recipient ever ready for all forms, it must be indestructible and impassible, as it is incorporeal and unextended. It is like a mirror which represents all things so that they seem to be where they are not, and keeps no impression of any 1 . The appearances of sense, themselves " in- vulnerable nothings 2 ," go through it as through water without dividing it. It has not even a falsehood of its own that it can say of things 3 . In that it can take no permanent hold of any good, it may be called evil 4 . Fleeing every attempt of percep- tion to grasp it, it is equally receptive in appearance of the contraries which it is equally unable to retain. ■ 3. Cosmology and Theodicy. The theory of matter set forth, though turned to new meta- physical account, is fundamentally that of Aristotle. As with Aristotle, Matter is the presupposition of physics, being viewed as the indestructible " subject " of forms, enduring through all changes in potency of further change ; but Plotinus is careful to point out that the world of natural things derives none of its reality from the recipient. The formal reason (X070?) that makes matter appear as extended, does not " unfold " it to extension — for this was not implicit in it — but, like that also which makes it appear as coloured, gives it something that was not there 5 . In that it confers no qualities whatever on that which appears in it, matter is absolutely sterile 6 . The forms manifested in nature are those already contained in the intellect that is before it, which acquires them by turning towards the Good. All differences of form, down to those of the elements, are the product of Reason and not of Matter 7 . While working out his theory from a direct consideration 1 Enn. in. 6, 7. 2 Adonais, xxxix. — an exact expression of the idea of Plotinus. 3 Enn. in. 6, 15. 4 Enn. 111. 6, 11. 5 Enn. 11. 4, 9. 6 Enn. in. 6, 19. 7 Enn. vi. 7, 11. 72 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V of the necessity that there should be something indestructible beneath the transformations of body, Plotinus tries to prove it not inconsistent with what is known as Plato's " theory of matter" in the Timaeus. The phrases in which the "recipient" is spoken of as a " room " and a " seat " are interpreted meta- phorically. Here Plotinus is evidently arguing against com- mentators in his own time who took the " Platonic matter " to be empty space 1 . This has now become the generally accepted interpretation ; opinions differing only as to whether the space or matter in which the ideas manifest themselves is to be re- garded as objective extension or as a subjective form 2 . Plotinus himself approaches the latter view when he consents to call matter a " phantasm of mass " {(^avTaa^a Be 6'7/cou Xejw), though still regarding it as unextended (a/zeye#e?). His account of the mental process by which the nature opposed to that of the ideas is known (voOcp \ojia/j,a)) quite agrees with Plato's. On another point of Platonic interpretation, Plotinus and all his successors take the view which modern criticism seems now to find the most satisfactory. Plausible as was the reading of the Timaeus which would regard it as teaching an origin of the world from an absolute beginning of time, this was never, even at the earliest period, really prevalent in the school of Plato. During the Platonising movement that preceded Plo- tinus, the usual interpretation had been to regard what is said about the making of the world from pre-existent elements as mythological. The visible universe, said the earliest like the latest interpreters, is described by Plato as " generated " because it depends on an unchanging principle while itself per- petually subject to mutation ; not because it is supposed to 1 See especially Enn. 11. 4, 11 : oOev rives ravrbu ry Kevy ttjv v\t)v elprjKa<n. '-' The first is Zeller's view, in which he is followed by Siebeck and by Baeumker (Das Problem der Materie in der griechischen Philosophic, 1890), who have skilfully defended it against objections. Mr Archer-Hind, in his edition of the Timaeus, takes the view that the Platonic matter is space as a subjective form. This would bring it very close to the Kantian doctrine. The more usual view would in effect make it an anticipation of Descartes' attempt in the Principia Philosophiae to construct body out of pure extension. There is certainly a striking resemblance in general conception between Plato's and Descartes' corpuscular theory, which I do not remember to have seen noted. UNIVERSITY V] OF PLOTINUS " 7d have been called into being at a particular moment. That this was all along the authorised interpretation may be seen even from Plutarch 1 , who, in defending the opposite thesis, evidently feels that he is arguing against the opinion predominant among contemporary Platonists 2 . Thus Plotinus, when he says that there never was a time when this whole was not, nor was there ever matter unformed, is not introducing a novelty. And on this point we do not hear that opposition to his doctrine arose from any quarter. His difference with Longinus was on the question whether the divine mind eternally contains the ideas in itself or contemplates them eternally as objective existences; not as to whether ideas and unordered matter once stood apart and were then brought together by an act or process of creative volition. The duration of the universe without temporal begin- ning or end was the accepted doctrine of Hellenic Platonism. In accordance with this general view, however, it is possible, as Plotinus recognises 3 , to hold either that the universe is per- manent only as a whole, while all its parts perish as individual bodies {Kara to To8e) and are renewed only in type (Kara to dSos), or that some of the bodies in the universe — namely, those that fill the spaces from the sphere of the moon outwards — are always numerically identical. If the former view is the true one, then the heavenly bodies differ from the rest only by lasting a longer time. About the latter view there would be no trouble if we were to accept Aristotle's doctrine that their substance is a fifth element, not subject like the rest to altera- tion. For those who allow that they consist of the elements of which living bodies on earth are constituted, the difficulty is that they must be by nature dissoluble. This Plato himself conceded to Heraclitus. As in his physics generally, so here, Plotinus argues in a rather tentative way. He suggests as the true solution, that the heaven with all its parts consists of a 1 Ilepi ttjs iv Ti,ucuy \pi>xoyovlas. 2 It may be noted that the " Platonic matter," according to Plutarch, is simply body or "corporeal substance." i] [xtv ovv awnaros ovala ttjs Xeyofiivrjs vk aiiTov navdexovi (pvaews edpas re Kal Ti6r)vr)s tCiv yivqrCjv oi>x irepa tLs eariv (c. 5 fin.). 3 Enu. ii. 1, 1. 74 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V purer kind of fire, which we may call " light," moving if at all with a circular motion, losing nothing by efflux, and conse- quently in no need, like mortal bodies, of nourishment from without. This material light, being a kind of body, must of course be distinguished from light as an outflowing energy 1 . Radiant light, as we have seen 2 , is for Plotinus an activity carrying with it no loss either of substance or of efficiency ; whence it furnished an analogy closer than is possible on any modern theory for the metaphysical doctrine of emanation. For the rest, this picture of the physical universe does not essentially differ from Aristotle's. The whole forms a single system, with the fixed stars and the seven planets (including the sun and moon) revolving round the spherical earth in com- binations of perfect circles. Like the stars, the earth too has a divinity of its own 3 . The space which the universe fills is finite. Body is not atomic in constitution but continuous. The complex movements of the whole system recur in astro- nomical cycles. In order to solve difficulties connected with the infinite duration of a world in constant change, Plotinus sometimes takes up the Stoical theory that in the recurrent periods the sequence of events is exactly repeated. This he does especially where the question presents itself, how that infinity in the world of sense is possible which is required by his doctrine that there are " ideas of particulars." Individual differences, he allows, must according to this view be infinite, seeing that there is no limit to the duration of the world either in the past or in the future. The difficulty would be met by supposing that differences finite in number recur exactly in succeeding cycles. Thus, in any one cycle no two individuals are without all formal difference, and yet the number of "forms " is limited 4 . This solution, however, seems to be offered with no great confidence. The point about which Plotinus is quite clear is that individual as well as specific differences have their rational determination in the ideal world. From this he deduces that, in any one period of the cosmos at least, there are no two 1 Enn. ii. 1,7: to 6/j.wvv/j.ov avrf' </><£?, 6 dr} cpa/xep kcli dawfj-arov elvai. - Cf. Enn. iv. 5. 3 Enn. iv. 4, 22—27. 4 Enn. v. 7, 2. V] OF PLOTINUS 75 individuals that differ only numerically, without a trace of inward distinction 1 . About infinity in the ideal world or in the soul there is no difficulty 2 . The conception of an actual quantitative infinite is not merely difficult, but impossible. Yet, while repeatedly laying down this position, Plotinus allows that space and number as prefigured in eternal intellect have an infinitude of their own. We may say that number is infinite, though infinity is repugnant to number (to diretpov fid^eTai Tftl dpL0/j,a>), as we speak of an infinite line ; not that there is any such (oi>x 0Tt ^ a " TL Tt<? Toiavrr)), but that we can go in thought beyond the greatest existing. This means that in intellect the rational law of linear magnitude does not carry with it the thought of a limit 3 . Similarly, number in intellect is unmeasured. No actual number can be assigned that goes beyond what is already involved in the idea of number. In- tellectual being is beyond measure because it is itself the measure. The limited and measured is that which is prevented from running to infinity in its other sense of indeterminateness 4 . Thus limited and measured is the visible cosmos. To time is allowed an explicit infinity that is denied to space. It is the "image of eternity," reflecting the infinite already existent whole of being by the continual going to infinity of successive realisations 5 . Time belongs to apartness of life (BLdaraci^ ovv t,wr\<i XP° V0V € W e )- Tne Soul of tne Whole generates time and not eternity, because the things it produces are not imperishable. It is not itself in time; nor are individual souls themselves, but only their affections and deeds 6 , which are really those of the composite nature. Thus the past which is the object of memory is in things done ; in the soul itself there is nothing past 7 . Of Zeus, whether regarded as Demiurgus or 1 Erin. v. 7, 3. 2 Erin. v. 7, 1 : rr\v 5e ev tw vorjTco direipiav ov Sec dedievai ' irdcra yap iv dfxepel. As regards the soul and its \6yoi, of. c. 3. a Enn. vi. 6, 17 : 17 to dweipov aWou rpdirou, oi>x us ddteiiiTt]ToV dXXd iruis dirupos ; rj iv ry \6ycp rrjs avToypa.pL/j.TJs ovk Zvi wpoavoovp.evov irepas. * Enn. vi. 6, 18. 5 Enn. in. 7, 11. B Enn. iv. 4, 15. 7 Enn. iv. 4, 16: dXXd -rrdvrts ol \6yoi dVa, uo-irep dpr)Tai...rb de r6de /xerd rode tV rots Trpdyp.acni' ou dui/a/xevois dp.a wavra. 7G THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V as Soul of the World, we must deny even the "before and after" implied in memory 1 . That which guides the whole (to rj<yov- fievov rod ttcivtos) knows the future as present {Kara to ea-rdvat), and has therefore no need of memory and discursive reason to infer it from the past 2 . These faculties belong to acquired in- tellect, and, as we shall see, are dismissed even by the individual soul when it has reascended to intuitive knowledge. If things eternal were altogether alien to us, we could not speak of them with intelligence. We also then must participate in eternity 3 . How the -soul's essence can be in eternity while the composite nature consisting of soul and body is in time, can only be understood when the definition of time has been more strictly investigated. To define it in relation to physical move- ment does not express its essential character. The means by which we learn to know time is no doubt observation of motion, and especially of the revolutions of the heavenly bodies. Yet while ordered external motion more than anything else shows time forth to mental conception, it does not make time be. When the motion of the whole is measured in terms of time, which itself is fixed according to certain intervals marked out in the space through which the motions proceed, this is an " accidental " relation. The parts of time, invisible and inappre- hensible in themselves, must have remained unknown till thus measured, but time itself is prior to the measurement of its parts. We must bring it back finally to a movement of the soul, though the soul could hardly have known it to any purpose without the movement of the heaven. Time is not, however, in the merely individual soul, but in all souls so far as they are one. Therefore there is one uniform time, and not a multitude of disparate times ; as in another relation there is one eternity in which all participate 4 . Thus the one soul, in which individual 1 Enn. iv. 4, 10. 2 Erin. iv. 4, 12. Hence, adds Plotinus, the creative power (to ttolovv) is not subject to labour and difficulty, as was in the imagination of those who thought the regulation of the whole would be a troublesome business. 3 Enn. in. 7, 7 : Set dpa /cat i]fuv /zeretVat rod alQvos. 4 Enn. in. 7, 13 : ap ovv /cat ev r\plv [6] xpopos ; fj ev ^pvxQ T-fi TOiavTy irdcrr] icai 6/u,oei5ws ev waai /cat at wdaai. p.la. did ov diaaTrairdrjaeTai 6 xP^vos' eVet ovd' 6 aiCbv 6 KO.T d\Xo ev tois ofioeideaL iraaiv. y] OF PLOTINUS 77 souls are metaphysically contained, participates in eternity and produces time, which is the form of a soul living in apparent detachment from its higher cause. Unity in the soul of the whole, here so strongly insisted on, does not with Plotinus exclude the reality of particular souls. We have seen that he regards individuality as determined by differences in the Ideas, and not by the metaphysically unreal modes of pluralising ascribed to Matter. What comes from matter is separateness of external manifestation, and mutability in the realisations attained; not inner diversity, which pre- exists in the world of being. This view he tarns against the fatalism that would make the agency of the individual soul count for nothing in the sum of things. He is without the least hesitation a determinist. Within the universal order, he premises, the uncaused (to ava'iTiov) is not to be received, whether under the form of " empty declinations," or of a sudden movement of bodies without preceding movement, or of a capricious impulse of soul not assignable to any motive 1 . But to say that everything in each is determined by one soul that runs through all, is, by an excess of necessity, to take away necessity itself and the causal order ; for in this case it would not be true that all comes to pass by causes, but all things would be one, without distinction between that which causes and that which is caused; "so that neither we are we nor is anything our work 2 ." Each must be each, and actions and thoughts must belong to us as our own 3 . This is the truth that physical, and especially astrological, fatalism denies. To 1 Etm. in. 1, 1: t? yap to j3ov\r)Tov—TOVTo 8e 77 §£u 77 eiVw — 7? rb iTndvfitirbv ii<iv7}<j(V ij, el fj-riSev bpeKTov ei<lvqo-ev, ov5' av 6'Xws tKivqdr}. The principle of psychological determinism could not be more clearly put. In view of this, it is not a little surprising that Zeller should vaguely class Plotinus and his successors as champions of "free-will." On the other hand Jules Simon, who quite recognises the determinism of the school, misstates the doctrine of Plotinus as regards the nature of the individual when he says (Histoire de VEcole (V Alexandria, t. i. pp. 570—1) that that which is not of the essence of each soul, and must consequently perish, is, according to Plotinus, its individuality, and that this comes from matter. 2 Enn. in. 1, 4. 3 Cf. Enn. in. 4, 6: ov yap o.uolus lv rois avrois ttSs Kii/eirai 7) fiovXerai 77 ivepyet. 78 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V preserve the causal order without exception while at the same time allowing that we ourselves are something, we must intro- duce the soul as another principle into the contexture of things, — and not only the soul of the whole, but along with it the soul of each 1 . Being in a contexture, and not by itself, it is not wholly master, and so far fate or destiny (el/nap fievrj) regarded as external, has a real existence. Thus all things come to pass according to causes ; but some by the soul, and some through the other causes among which it is placed. Of its not thinking and acting rationally (tov p-rj cppovelv) other things are the causes. Rational action has its cause within ; being only not hindered from without 2 . Virtue therefore is free ; and the more completely free the more the soul is purified from mixture. To the bad, who do most things according to the imaginations excited by bodily affections, we must assign neither a power of their own nor a proper volition 3 . How then can punishment be just? The answer is that the composite nature, which sins, is also that which pays the penalty of sin 4 . The involuntariness of sin (on n/xapTia aKovaiov) does not prevent the deed being from the doer 5 . Some men indeed come into being as if by a witchcraft of external things, and are little or nothing of themselves: others preserve the original nature of the soul's essence. For it is not to be thought that the soul "alone of all things is without such a nature 6 . In preserving or recovering this lie virtue and freedom. A more elaborate treatment of the problem of theodicy here raised is contained in three books that belong to Plotinus's last period 7 . This problem he does not minimise. Although, in metaphysical reality, the world has not come to be by a process of contrivance resembling human art, yet, he says, if reasoning 1 Enn. in. 1, 8. 2 Enn. in. 1, 10. 3 Enn. vi. 8, 3 : oiirt to eV avroh ovre to eKotiaiov dwaofiev. « Enn. i. 1, 12. 5 Enn. in. 2, 10. 6 Enn. ii. 3, 15 : ov yap dij vofjucrr^ov toiovtov dvai ^uxV"j olov, 6 tl hv 'i^wdtv iradrj, ravrqv cpvcrLv iax e <- v P&vrpt twv tt&vtwv olndav (pvav ovk ix ov,Jav - i Enn. in. 2, in. 3, i. 8. y] OF PLOTINUS 79 had made it, it would have no reason to be ashamed of its work 1 . This whole, with everything in it, is as it would be if providentially ordered by the rational choice of the Maker 2 . If, indeed, the world had come into existence a certain time ago, and before was not, then the providence which regulates it would be like that of rational beings within the world; it would be a certain foresight and reasoning of God how this whole should come to exist, and how it should be in the best manner possible. Since, however, the world is without beginning and end, the providence that governs the whole consists in its being in accordance with mind, which is before it not in time but as its cause and model so to speak. From mind proceeds a rational law which imposes harmony on the cosmos. This law, however, cannot be unmixed intellect like the first. The condition of there being a world below the purely intelligible order — and there must be such a world, that every possible degree of perfection may be realised — is mutual hindrance and separation of parts. The unjust dealings of men with one another arise from an aspiration after the good along with a want of power to attain it. Evil is a defection (e'A.\en/a<?) of good ; and, in a universe of separated existences, absence of good in one place follows with necessity from its presence in another. Therefore evils cannot be destroyed from the world. What are commonly called evils, as poverty and disease, Plotinus continues to assert with the Stoical tradition, are nothing to those who possess true good, which is virtue ; and they are not useless to the order of the whole. Yet, he proceeds, it may still be argued that the distribution of what the Stoics after all allow to be things " agreeable " and " not agreeable " to nature, is unfair. That the bad should be lords and rulers of cities, and that men of worth should be slaves, is not fitting, even though lordship and slavery are nothing as regards the possession of real good. And with a perfect providence every detail must be as it ought to be. We are not to evade the difficulty by saying that providence does not extend to earth, or that through chance and necessity it is not strong enough to sway things 1 Enn. in. 2, 3 : ov8' tl Xoyicr/xbs dij 6 Troir)<ras, aicx vl '^' ral T V iroiifOivTi.. 2 Enn. vr. 8, 17. 80 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V here. The earth too is as one of the stars (&>? ev rt twi' aarpcov) 1 . If, however, we bear in mind that we are to look for the greatest possible perfection that can belong to a world of mixture, not for that which can belong only to the intelligible order, the argument may be met in full. Among men there are higher and lower and intermediate natures, — the last being the most numerous. Those that are so degenerate as to come within the neighbourhood of irrational animals do violence to the intermediate natures. These are better than those that maltreat them, and yet are conquered by the worse in so far as they themselves are worse in relation to the particular kind of contest to be undergone. If they are content to be fatted sheep, they should not complain of becoming a prey to the wolves. And, Plotinus adds parenthetically, the spoilers too pay the penalty ; first in being wolves and wretched men, and then in having a worse fate after death, according to their acquired character. For the complete order of justice has regard to the series of past and future lives, not to each present life by itself. But to take things as seen in one life : always the mundane order demands certain means if we are to attain the end. Those who have done nothing worthy of happiness cannot reasonably expect to be happy. The law is, for example, that out of wars we are to come safe by proving our courage, not by prayer. Were the opposite the case, — could peace be preserved amid every kind of folly and cowardice, — then indeed would providence be neglectful. When the bad rule, it is by the unmanliness of those that are ruled ; and it is just that it should be so. Yet, such as man is, holding a middle rank, providence does not suffer him to be destroyed, but he is borne up ever toward the higher; the divine element giving virtue the mastery in the long run. The human race partici- pates, if not to the height, in wisdom and mind, and art and justice, and man is a beautiful creation so far as he can be consistently with his place in the universe. Reason (o \6yos) made things in their different orders, not because it envied a greater good to those that are lower placed, but because the law 1 Enn. in. 2, 8. V] OF PLOTINUS 81 itself of intelligential existence carries with it variety (ov $66vo3, aXka \6y<o iroiKiXiav voepav e^oi/Tt). Thus in a drama all the personages cannot be heroes. And reason does not take the souls from outside itself and fit them into the poem by constraining a portion of them from their own nature for the worse. The souls are as it were parts of reason itself, and it fits them in not by making them worse, but by bringing them to the place suitable to their nature. If then, it may be asked, we are not to explain evil by external constraint, but reason is the principle and is all, what is the rational necessity of the truceless war among animals and men ? First, destructions of animals are necessary because, in a world composed of changing existences, they could not be born imperishable. Thus, if they were not destroyed by one another they would no less perish. Transference of the animating principle from body to body, which is promoted by their devouring each other, is better than that they should not have been at all. The ordered battles men fight as if dancing the Pyrrhic dance, show that what we take for the serious affairs of mankind are but child's play, and declare that death is nothing terrible 1 . It is not the inward soul but the outward shadow of a man that groans and laments over the things of life. But how then, the philosopher proceeds, can there be any such thing as wickedness if this is the true account ? The answer which he ventures' 2 is in effect that of maleficent natures the Reason in the world might say : ' These too have their part in me, as I too in these." This reason (ovto? 6 \0709) is not unmixed mind {aKparo^ vovs). Its essence is to consist of the contraries that were in need of strife with one another so that thus a world of birth might hold together (rrjv avaracriv avra> Kal olov ouaiav tt}? TOLavTiy; ivavTHocreaiS <}>epov(n)<;). In the universal drama the good and the bad must perform the opposite parts assigned them. But from this does it not follow that all is pardonable 3 ? No, answers Plotinus, for 1 Enn. in. 2, 15: uinrep 8b iwl tuv dedrpuv rah OKi]vah, ovtu \Pn "al rovs <pbvovs dedffdat. Kal iravras davdrovs Kal irdXewv d\w<r«S Kal apirayds, ^era^crets iravra Kal yuera(rxwa r 'ff«s * a ' Opv v ^ v Kal oinuywv viroKpicreis. - Enn. in. 2, 16: reroW^w yap- rax* 5' hv Kal njxoifiev. 3 " Tout comprendre est tout pardonner." w. 6 82 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V the reason which is the creative word of the drama fixes the place both of pardon and of its opposite ; and it does not assign to men as their part that they should have nothing but forgive- ness for the bad 1 . In the consequences of evil for the whole there is nevertheless a rational order, and an order out of which good may come 2 . Still, that good may come of evil is not the deepest ground of its existence. Some one might argue that evil, while it is actual, was not necessary. In that case, even if good comes of it, the justification of providence must fail. The reply has been given already in outline. The necessity of evil results from matter. Matter is necessary because, the principle of things having infinite productive power, that power must manifest itself in every possible degree : there must therefore be a last term, to eoyaTov, which can produce nothing beyond itself. " This is matter, having nothing any longer of its own ; and this is the necessity of evil 3 ." If it is argued that moral evil in us, coming as it does from association with the body, is to be ascribed rather to form than to matter, since bodies derive their distinctive character from form, the reply is that it is not in so far as the forms are pure that they are the source of ignorance and bad desires, but in so far as they are mixed with matter (\6yot evv\oi). The fall of the soul is its approach to matter, and it is made weak because its energies are impeded by the presence of matter, which does not allow all its powers to arrive at their realisation 4 . Yet without this principle of indeterminateness that vitiates the pure forms, causing them to miss their true boundary by excess or defect, there would be for us neither good nor any object of desire. There would be neither striving after one thing nor turning away from another 1 Enn. in. 2, 17: dXX' tacas crvyyvdofxrj to?s KaKocs' el fii) Kal to rrjs avyyvui/x^s Kal /j.rj 6 \6yos noier iroiel de 6 \6yos /j.r]de o~vyyvu)/j.oi>as eirl tois toioutols elvcu. 2 Enn. in. 2, 18 : olov iK /xoi^et'as Kal alx/^a\uirov dycjyrjs TcuSes Kara cpvcriv j3e\Tiovs Kal avdpes, el ti>xoi, Kal iroheis dXXcu a/meivovs tQiv ireiropOrin.ivwv iiirb avdpQv irovqpQv. From a passage like this may we not infer that Plotinus was able to see the barbarian inroads without despairing of the future ? 3 Enn. i. 8, 7. 4 Enn. i. 8, 14 : v\t) to'ivvv Kal aaffeveias \pvxy atria Kal KaKias ahla. wporepov dpa KaKrj avTr] Kal irpwrov KaKbv. V] OF PLOTINUS 83 nor yet thought. " For our striving is after good and our turning away is from evil, and thought with a purpose is of good and evil, and this is a good 1 ." The last sentence contains one of the two or three very slight possible allusions in the whole of the Enneads to orthodox Christianity. With Christian Gnosticism Plotinus deals ex- pressly in a book which Porphyry has placed at the end of the second Eimead 2 . A separate exposition of it may be given here, both because it is in some ways specially interesting, and because it brings together Plotinus's theory of the physical order of the world and of its divine government. Any obscurity that there is in it comes from the allusive mode of dealing with the Gnostic theories, of which no exposition is given apart from the refutation. The main points of the speculations opposed are, however, sufficiently clear. After a preliminary outline of his own metaphysico-theo- logical doctrine, in which he dwells on the sufficiency of three principles in the intelligible world, as against the long series of " aeons " introduced by the Platonising Gnostics 3 , Plotinus begins by asking them to assign the cause of the "fall" (acfxiX/xa) which they attribute to the soul of the world. When did this fall take place ? If from eternity, the soul remains fallen. If the fall had a beginning, why at that particular moment and not earlier ? Evidently, to undergo this lapse, the soul must have forgotten the things in the intelligible world ; but if so, how did it create without ideas ? To say that it created in order to be honoured is a ridiculous metaphor taken from statuaries on earth 4 . Then, as to its future destruction of the 1 Enn. I. 8, 15 : 17 yap opeiiis ayaOov, r\ 5£ ZkkXhtis kcikov, tj 5£ vbrjats Kal i] (pp6vijffts ayadov Kal Kaicov, Kal axirij '4v tl tCiv ayaQCbv. - Enn. 11. 9. Ilpds tovs KaKbv t6v drj/jnovpybv toO k6<thov Kal rbv Kbup.ov KaKov dvai \tyovras, or Ilpds to i>s yvdXTTiKoijs. 3 Cf. Enn. 11. 9, 6 : ras 5£ aXXas vwoGTaaeis ii XPV X^7«" as daayovat, TrapoiKiqaeis Kal dfTirinrovs Kal /leravoias ; 4 Enn. 11. 9, i : tl yap ai> cavrfi Kal iXoytfero ytviadai £k rod Koap.o- voirjcai ; yeXoiov yap rb iVa tl/j.i2to, Kal p.tracpepbvTuii' dirb tCiv aya\p.aToirotwi> rQiv ivTavda. 6—2 84 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V world, if it repented of its creation, what is it waiting for ? If it has not yet repented, it is not likely to repent now that it has become more accustomed to that which it made, and more attached to it by length of time. Those who hold that, because there are many hardships in the world, it has therefore come into existence for ill, must think that it ought to be identical with the intelligible world, and not merely an image of it. Taken as what it is, there could be no fairer image. And why this refusal to the heavenly bodies of all participation in the intelligible, — especially by men who complain of the disorder in terrestrial things ? Then they introduce another soul, which they make to be compacted of the material elements, as if that was possible for a soul 1 . Not honouring this earth, they say that there is a " new earth " to which they are to go, made in the pattern of a world, — and yet they hate " the world." Whence this pattern if not from the creative power which they say has lapsed ? Much in their teaching Plotinus never- theless acknowledges to be true. The immortality of the soul, the intelligible world, the first God, the doctrine that the soul ought to flee association with the body, the theory of its separation, the flight from the realm of birth to that of being, all these are doctrines to be found in Plato ; and they do well in proclaiming them. On the part of Plato's disciples, there is no disposition to grudge them the right to declare also the points wherein they differ. They ought, however, to try to prove what they have to say of their own on its merits, putting their opinions with good feeling and like philosophers; not with contumely towards " the Greeks," and with assertions that they themselves are better men. As a matter of fact, they have only made incongruous additions to that which was better in the form given to it by the ancients 2 ; introducing all sorts of births and destructions, and finding fault with the universe, and blaming the soul of the whole for its communion with the body, and casting reproach upon the ruler of this whole, and identifying 1 Enn. ii. 9, 5 : ttws yap av fwiji' tjvtivovv ^x° l V ^ K T & v (TTOtxelfat cnjaraais; '-' Enn. ii. 9, 6 : eTrel t& ye elpr]fxiva tois iraXaiois -wepl twv votjtGjv 7roA\<J3 dfxelvu /cat TreTraiSev/xtvcos etp^rat /cat tois p.7) i^aTraTup.ii'ois tt\v einde'ovaav eh dvOpuTrovs &TT&Tr]v padius yvtxxrdriaerai. V] OF PLOTINUS 85 the Demiurgus with the Soul of the World 1 , and attributing the same affections to that which rules the whole as to particular things. That it is not so good for our soul to be in communion with the body as to be separate, others have said before; but the case is different with the soul of the whole, which rules the frame of the world unimpeded, whereas ours is fettered by the body. The question wherefore the creative power made a world is the same as the question wherefore there is a soul and wherefore the Demiurgus made it. It involves the error, first, of suppos- ing a beginning of that which is for ever ; in the next place, those who put it think that the cause of the creation was a turning from something to something else. The ground of that creative action which is from eternity, is not really in discursive thought and contrivance, but in the necessity that intelligible things should not be the ultimate product of the power that mauifests itself in them. And if this whole is such as to permit us while we are in it to have wisdom, and being here to live in accordance with things yonder, how does it not bear witness that it has its attachment there ? In the distribution of riches and poverty and such things, the man of elevated character (o (nrovhalos) does not look for equality, nor does he think that the possessors of wealth and power have any real advantage. How if the things done and suffered in life are an exercise to try who will come out victorious in the struggle ? Is there not a beauty in such an order 2 ? If you are treated with injustice, is that so great a matter to your immortal being? Should you be slain, you have your wish, since you escape from the world. Do you find fault with civic life ? You are not compelled to take part in it. Yet in the State, over and above legal justice with its punishments, there is honour for virtue, and vice meets with its appropriate dis- honour. In one life, no doubt the fulfilment is incomplete, but 1 Enn. n. 9, 6: nal els ravrbv dyovres rbv byjuiovpybv rrj xf/vxv- Both Yacherot and Jules Simon find this identification in the system of Plotinus himself. The error is corrected by Zeller, iii. 2, p. 633, n. 3. - Enn. II. 9, 9 : «' de yv/xvdaiov eli) vikwvtuiv xal ^ttw/x^vuv, wQs oi) ko.1 ravrri /coXws (x a * 86 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v it is completed in the succession of lives ; the gods giving to each the lot that is consequent on former existences. Good men should try to rise to such height of goodness as their nature allows, but should think that others also have their place with God, and not dream that after God they themselves are alone in their goodness, and that other men and the whole visible world are without all part in the divine. It is easy, however, to persuade unintelligent men who have no real knowledge what goodness is, that they alone are good and the sons of God 1 . Having remarked on some of the inconsistencies in the mythological cosmogonies of the Gnostics, Plotinus returns again to the point that the causation of natural things should not be compared to the devices of an artist, the arts being posterior to nature and the world 2 . We must not blame the universe because all is' not equally good. That is as if one were to call the power of growth evil because it is not perception, or the perceptive faculty because it is not reason. There are necessarily degrees in things. The practice of exorcisms and incantations by the Gnostics is especially attacked. They compose charms, says Plotinus, addressed not only to the soul of the world but to still higher powers, as if incorporeal things could be acted on by the sounds of the voice modulated according to some cunningly devised rules of art. Claiming as they do to have power against diseases, they would say rightly if, with the philosophers, they said that the means of keeping clear of them is temperance and a regular mode of life. They ascribe them, however, to the entrance of demons into the body, and profess to expel them by forms of words. Thus they become of great repute with the many, who stand in awe of magical powers ; but they will not persuade rational men that diseases have not their physical cause 1 Near the end of c. 9, a comparison is borrowed from Plato, Rep. iv. 426 : i) otet olbv t' ehai avSpl /j.7] eiriara/jLeity fxerpelv, irepcov tolovtuv voWQv \eybvrwv otl TETpairqxv'S eariv, avrbv ravra p.rj ^yeiadai irepi avrov; Enn. ii. 9, 12 : </>vcriKWTepoi> yap ttolvtus, d\\' ovx ws at Te'x"at ewolu ' varepai yap Trjs </>i''<rews Kal tov Kba/nov at re'x"at. V] OF PLOTINUS 87 in "changes externally or internally initiated 1 ." If the demon can enter without a cause, why is the disease not always present ? If there is a physical cause, that is sufficient without the demon. To say that, as soon as the cause comes to exist, the demonic agency, being read}', straightway takes up its position beside it, is ludicrous. Next the antinomian tendency of the Gnostic sects is touched upon. This way of thinking, the philosopher proceeds, with its positive blame of providence going beyond even the Epicurean denial, and dishonouring all the laws of our mundane life, takes away temperance, and the justice implanted in moral habits and perfected by reason and practice, and in general all human excellence. For those who hold such opinions, if their own nature is not better than their teaching, nothing is left but to follow pleasure and self-interest ; nothing thought excellent here being in their view good, but only some object of pursuit in the future. Those who have no part in virtue, have nothing by which they can be set in motion towards the world beyond. To say, " Look to God," is of no use unless you teach men how to look. This was taught in the moral dis- courses of the ancients, which the present doctrine entirely neglects. It is virtue carried to the end and fixed in the soul with moral wisdom that points to God. Without true virtue, God is but a name 2 . The concluding chapters are directed against the refusal to recognise in sensible things any resemblance to intelligible beauty. How, Plotinus asks the Gnostic pessimists, can this world be cut off from its intelligible cause ? If that cause is absent from the world, then it must also be absent from you ; for the providence that is over the parts must first be over the whole. What man is there who can perceive the intelligible harmony of music and is not moved when he hears that which is in sensible sounds? Or who is there that is skilled in geometry and numbers and does not take pleasure in seeing 1 Enu. II. '.I, 14 : tovs fiivroL ei> cppovovvras ovk av weiOoiev, u>s ovx o.l vbcot raj airtas Zx ov(JLV V Kafiarois rj Tr\T}a/xouais rj ivodats t) cr)\j/((TL koX o'Xcjs /u.era/3o\cus 7] i^uidev tj)v dpXTT' V IvooOev \aj3ovcrais. 2 Enn. ii. 0, 15 : avev 5e dperJJs a\i]0ii/rjs Oeos Xeyofxevos ouo/xd (<ttii>. 88 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V the orderly and proportionate with his eyes ? And is there any one who, perceiving all the sensible beauty of the world, has no feeling of anything beyond it ? Then he did not apprehend sensible things with his mind. Nothing can be really fair outside and foul within. Those who are called beautiful and internally are ugly, either have a false exterior beauty also, or their ugliness is adventitious, their nature being originally beautiful. For the hindrances here are many to arriving at the end. Since this reason of shortcoming does not apply to the whole visible world, which contains all, that must necessarily be beautiful. Nor does admiration of the beauty by which the physical universe participates in good tend to bind us more to the body. Rather, it gives us reasons for living well the life that is in the body. By taking all strokes from without as far as possible with equanimity, we can make our souls resemble, as nearly as may be, the soul of the whole and of the stars. It is therefore in our power, while not finding fault with our temporary dwelling-place, not to be too fond of the body, and to become pure, and to despise death, and to know the better and follow it, and to regard without envy those higher mundane souls that can and do pursue the same intel- ligible objects, and pursue them eternally 1 . 4. Aesthetics. The passages devoted by Plotinus to aesthetics are not lengthy, but among ancient writings that touch upon the general theory of beauty and the psychology of art, they are 1 Philo also, it may be noted here, accepted the opinion attributing life and mind to the stars. In his optimism of course the Jewish philosopher agrees with Plato and Plotinus. The Gnostics seem to have taken up from the popular astrology the notion that the planets exercise malignant influences. Plotinus has some ironical remarks on the terror they express of the immense and fiery bodies of the spheres. Against the astrological polytheism which regarded the planetary gods as rulers of the world, he himself protests in a book where he examines sceptically and with destructive effect the claims of astrology. See Enn. n. 3, 6: 6'Aus 5e fjLTjdevl ivi to Ktjpiov ttjs dLoiKrjcreus SiSopcu, tovtols 5£ rd Trdvra didovai, w&irep ovk eTricrraTouvTos evos, d</>' oil dtrjprfjcrdac to irav endarui 8l86vtos Kara (pvcnv to aiiTov irepalvew ko.1 ivepyeiv to. avTov avvTfTayfx^vov av /xer' avrov, \vovtos £o~ti kclI ayvoovvTos Kdfffiov <pvaiv dpx^v exovTos /cat airiav irpwTrjv iwl wavra lovcrav. V] OF PLOTINUS 89 of exceptional value. In his early book " On the Beautiful 1 ," where he closely follows Plato, he at the same time indicates more than one new point of view. A brief summary will make this clear. Beauty, he first argues, cannot depend wholly on symmetry, for single colours and sounds are beautiful. The same face too, though its symmetry remains, may seem at one time beautiful, at another not. And, when we go beyond sensible beauty, how do action and knowledge and virtue, in their different kinds, become beautiful by symmetry ? For, though the soul in which they inhere has a multiplicity of parts, they cannot display a true symmetry like that of magnitudes and numbers 2 . The explanation of delight in sensible beauty, so far as it can be explained, is that when the soul perceives something akin to its own nature it feels joy in it; and this it does when indeterminate matter is brought under a form proceeding from the real being of things. Thus beauty may attach itself to the parts of anything as well as to the whole. The external form is the indivisible internal form divided in appearance by material mass. Perception seizes the unity and presents it to the kindred soul. An example of this relation is that among the elements of body fire is especially beautiful because it is the formative element 3 . The beauty of action and knowledge and virtue, though not seized by sense-perception, is like sensible beauty in that it cannot be explained to those who have not felt it. It is itself in the soul. What then is it that those who love beauty of soul take delight in when they become aware of it either in others or in themselves ? To know this, we must set its opposite, ugliness, beside beauty, and compare them. Ugliness we find in a disorderly soul, and this disorderliness we can only understand as superinduced by matter. If beauty is ever to be regained in such a soul, it must be by purification from the admixture. The ugliness is in fact the admixture of disorderly 1 Enn. i. 6. Tiepl rod koKov. 2 Eim. I. 6, 1 : ovre yap ws fieyidr) otire us apidp.ol avp.jj.iTpa /ccu'toi wXeidvuv fiepwv rrjs ipi'xys ovtuv. 3 Here the theoretical explanation is to be found in the Stoic physics. 90 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V passions derived from too close association with the body, and it is the soul itself in its unmixed nature that is beautiful. All v virtue is purification. Now the soul, as it becomes pure of regard for outward and inferior things, is borne upward to intellect. In intellect accordingly is the native and not alien beauty of the soul ; because only when thus borne upward is it in truth soul and nothing else. Thus beauty is being, which is one with intellect, and the nature other than being is the ugly. The good and the beautiful are therefore to be looked for together, as are the ugly and the evil. The first principle (to irpoiTov) is Beauty itself (icaXkovr)), as it is the Good (rdyadov). Intellect is the beautiful (to koKov). Soul is beautiful through intellect. All other things are beautiful through the formative soul. A return must therefore be made again to the principle after which every soul aspires, to the Idea of the Good in itself and of Beauty in itself. This is to be reached by closing the eyes to common sights and arousing another power of vision which all have but few make use of 1 . For such vision you must prepare yourself first by looking upon things done beautifully by other souls. Thus you will be enabled to see the beauty of the soul itself. But to see this, you must refer it to your own soul. If there is any difficulty here, then your task must be to shape your soul into accord with ideal beauty as a sculptor shapes a statue. For only by such inward reference is the beauty to be seen that belongs to souls 2 . At the end of this book, Plotinus suggests a distinction afterwards developed. If, he says, we speak broadly and with- out exact discrimination, then the first principle, which projects or radiates beauty from itself, may be called beautiful. If we distinguish more accurately, we shall assign to the Ideas "intel- ligible beauty " ; the Good which is beyond, we shall regard as 1 Euu. i. 6, 8. No vehicle of land or sea is of avail, dXXa ravra iravra &<peivai 5et /cat pi] fikiiretv, dXX' olov fx.vaa.VTa 6\f/iv dWr/v dWd^aadai /cat dv eyelpai, rjv ^x et V&v irds, xP&vTai <>e 0X1701. 2 Enn. 1. 6, 9 : to yap bpH.v irpbs to bpup-evov crvyyevks /cat op.oiov Troirjadpevov Set e7ri/3dXXetf rjj 6ia. ou yap av nuiwoTe eldev 6<p8a\p.bs ijXiov r/Xtoet5rys /at) yeyevrj.ucvos, ovde to na\di> &v loot \pvxh P-T] Ka\i) yevopivq. V] OF PLOTINUS ' 1)1 the spring and principle of beauty 1 . Elsewhere he gives a psychological reason why beauty is in the second place. Those who apprehend the beautiful catch sight of it in a glimpse, and while they are as it were in a state of knowledge and awake. The good is always present, though unseen, — even to those that are asleep, — and it does not astound them once they see it, nor is any pain mixed with the recognition of it. Love of the beautiful gives pain as well as pleasure, because it is at once a momentary reminiscence and an aspiration after what cannot be retained''. In another place 3 , the higher kind of beauty that transcends the rules of art is declared to be a direct impress of the good beyond intelligence. It is this, says Plotiuus, that adds to the mere symmetry of beauty, which may still be seen in one dead, the living grace that sets the soul actively in motion. By this also the more lifelike statues are more beautiful even when they are less proportionate. The irregu- larity that comes from indeterminate matter is at the opposite extreme, and is ugliness. Mere size is never beautiful. If bulk is the matter of beauty (to fieya v\r) tov /ca\ov), this means that it is that on which form is to be impressed. The larger anything is, the more it is in need of beautiful order. Without order, greater size only means greater ugliness 4 . Discussing in a separate book, Intellectual or Intelligible Beauty 5 , Plotinus begins by observing that the beauty of a statue comes not from the matter of the unshapen stone, but from the form conferred by art (irapd tov el'Sovs, o evfj/cev rj Te^vr]). If any one thinks meanly of the arts because they imitate nature 6 , first it must be pointed out that the natures of the things imitated are themselves imitations of ideal being, 1 Enn. i. 6, 9 : ware bXoax^p^ fJ-t" Xbyo: to wpwToi/ ko\6v ■ SiaipQu be r& vo-qra, to p.kv vorjTov koKov rbv twv elowv <pr\au t6ttov, to 5' dyaObv to ew^Keiua /cat wrjyr]!/ teal &pxi v T °u koXov. 2 Enn. v. 5, 12 : ko.1 Z<tti de to fxev ffwiov koX wpoo-qvh koi afipbTepov kuI, (is (0e\ei ris, irapbv aiVy to bi 6dp.(3os Hx ei Kai ficirXijfti» kclI av/x/xiyij ti£ dXyvvovn tt\v rjoovqv. 3 Enn. vi. 7, 22. « Enn. vi. 6, 1. 5 Enn. v. 8. Ilept tov vot)tov k&Wovs. 6 The argument here is no doubt, as Mr Bosanquet remarks in his History of Aesthetic, tacitly directed against Plato himself. 92 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V which precedes them in the logical order of causation. And the arts do not simply imitate the thing seen, but run back to the rational laws whence its nature is. Besides, they create much from themselves (7ro\Xa irap avrwv -ttoiovcti), filling up deficiencies in the visible model. Thus Phidias did not shape his Zeus after anything in perception, but from his own appre- hension of the God as he might appear if he had the will to manifest himself to our eyes. The arts themselves — which as creative ideas are in the soul of the artist — have a beauty surpassing that of the works that proceed from them ; these being necessarily, from the separateness of manifestation which takes the place of the original unity, weakened resemblances of the mental concep- tion that remains. Thus we are brought back to the thought that if we would recognise true beauty, whether seen in nature or in art, we must look within 1 . The proper abode of beauty is the intellectual being to which the soul attains only by inward vision. Above it is the good beyond knowledge, from which it is infused. Below it is the beauty found dispersed in visible things, by which the soul, if not altogether depraved from its original nature, is awakened to the Beauty of the Ideas. 5. Ethics. The good which is beyond beauty is also beyond moral virtue, as we saw at an earlier stage of the exposition. The attainment of it belongs to the mystical consummation of Plotinus's philosophy, and not properly to its ethical any more than to its aesthetical part. At the same time, it is not regarded as attainable without previous discipline both in practical moral virtue and in the pursuit of intellectual wisdom. The mere discipline is not sufficient by itself to assure the attainment of the end ; but it is, to begin with, the only path to follow. In treating of virtue on its practical side, Plotinus differs from his Stoical predecessors chiefly in the stress he lays on the interpretation even of civic virtue as a preliminary means of 1 Enn. v. 8, 2. V] OF PLOTINUS 93 purifying the soul from admixture with body. The one point where he decidedly goes beyond them in the way of precept is his prohibition of suicide 1 except in the rarest of cases 3 . Here he returns in the letter of the prohibition to the view of earlier moralists. The philosopher must no longer say to his disciples, as during the period of the Stoic preaching, that if they are in any way dissatisfied with life " the door is open." A moralist under the Empire cannot, on the other hand, take the ground of Aristotle, that suicide is an injury to the State. No public interest was so obviously affected by the loss of a single unit as to make this ground of appeal clearly rational. The argu- ment Plotinus makes use of is substantially that which Plato borrowed from the Pythagoreans. To take a violent mode of departing from the present life will not purify the soul from the passions that cling to the composite being, and so will not completely separate it and set it free from metempsychosis. Through not submitting to its appointed discipline, it may even have to endure a worse lot in its next life 3 . So long as there is a possibility of making progress here, it is better to remain. - - The view that in moral action the inward disposition is the essential thing, is to be found already, as a clearly formulated principle, in Aristotle. The Stoics had persistently enforced it ; and now in Plotinus it leads to a still higher degree of detachment, culminating as we shall see in mysticism. Porphyry made the gradation of the virtues by his master somewhat more explicit ; and Iamblichus was, as Vacherot has remarked 4 , more moderate and practical in his ethical doctrine ; but invari- ably the attitude of the school is one of extreme inwardness. Not only is the inner spring that by which moral action is to be tested ; the all-important point in relation both to conduct and insight is to look to the true nature of the soul and, 1 Enn. i. 9. 2 Cf. Enn. I. 4, 7 : d\\' el cu'x/xdXwros 1x704x0, irdp rot iariv 656s i^vai, el fir) eti) evSaifJ-ovetv. 3 Enn. 1. '.) : /cat el elixapfxivos x/>6Vos 6 bodels e/cdorw, wp6 tovtov ovk eiirvx^s, el ix-q, tlicrwep (pa/xiv, avayKatov. 4 Jlistoire Critique tie VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. p. 62. 94 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [V keeping this in view, to rid it of its excrescences. First in the order of moral progress are the " political " virtues, which make the soul orderly in the world of mixture. After these come the " cathartic " virtues, which prepare it to ascend to the ideal world. Positive virtue is attained simply by the soul's turning back to the reality it finds when with purged sight it looks within; and it may find this reality as soon as the negative "purification" has been accomplished 1 . The perfect life of the sage is not in community but in detachment. If he undertakes practical activity, it must be from some plain obligation, and the attitude of detachment ought still to be maintained internally. Neither with Plotinus nor with any of his successors is there the least doubt that the contemplative life is in itself superior to the life of action. Here they are Aristotelian. The chance that the philosopher as such may be called on to reform practical life seems to them much more remote than it did to Plato. Yet, in reference to politics, as Zeller points out 2 , a certain predilection may be noticed for the " Platonic aristocracy." It may be observed also that Plotinus by implication condemns Asiatic monarchy as unjust and contrary to nature 3 . And the view is met with incidentally that practical wisdom is the result of deliberation in common ; each by himself being too weak to achieve it. Thus, in the single resolution arrived at by the joint effort of all, political assemblies imitate the unity that is in the world 4 . That genuine freedom or self-dependence belongs properly to the contemplative and not to the active life Plotinus main- tains in one place 5 by the following argument. If virtue itself were given the choice whether there should be wars so that it might exercise courage, and injustice so that it might define and set in order what is just, and poverty so that it might display liberality, or that all things should go well and it should 1 Erin. i. 2, 4. - iii. 2, p. 605. 3 Enn. v. 5, 3. 4 Enn. vi. 5, 10 : /j.ifj,ovvTai 5i kclI eKKXrjcriai Kal vacra avvobos w? els ev ry (ppoveiv ibvrwv • koX x^pts e/cacrroj els to (ppovelv aadevr/s, (TV/J.j3a\\wv de els b* was ev rfj avvddw Kal tt) Cos dXyjOws <xvvio~ei to ppovelv eyivvrjcre Kal evpe. 5 Enn. vi. 8, 5. y] OF PLOTINUS 95 be at peace, it would choose peace. A physician like Hippo- crates, for example, might choose, if it were within his choice, that no one should need his art. Before there can be practical virtue, there must be external objects which come from fortune and are not chosen by us. What is to be referred to virtue itself and not to anything external, is the trained aptitude of intelligence and the disposition of will prior to the occasion of making a choice. Thus all that can be said to be primarily willed apart from any relation forced upon us to external things, is unimpeded theoretical activity of mind. In another book, the philosopher sets himself to defend in play the paradox that all outgoing activity is ultimately for the sake of contemplation 1 . Production (woi.r)cn<;) and action {-TTpa^i^) mean everywhere either an inability of contemplation to grasp its object adequately without going forth of itself, or a secondary resultant (7rapaKo\ov07]fxa) not willed but naturally issuing from that which remains in its own higher reality. Thus external action with its results, whether in the works of man or of nature, is an enfeebled product of contemplation. To those even who act, contemplation is the end ; since they act so that they may possess a good and know that they possess it, and the knowledge of its possession is only in the soul. Practice, therefore, as it issues from theory, returns to it 2 . At the end of the book Plotinus, passing beyond the half-serious view hitherto developed, indicates that the first principle of all is prior even to contemplation. Here occurs the comparison of it to the spring of life in the root of an immense tree. This produces all the manifold life of the tree without becoming itself manifold 3 . It is the good which has no need even of mind, while mind contemplates and aspires after it. The doubt for Plotinus is not whether the contemplative 1 Enn. in. 8, 1 : iral'SovTes 5r} ttjv irpwr^v irplv iwixa-P^v <nrovdd^ii> el Xe'yot./j.ei' ■jravTa Oewplas i<pUadai Kal els tAos tovto /3\6rai>, ...ap av tis dva.axot.TO t6 irapdbo^ov tqv \6yov : - Enn. m. 8, 6 : dvlKap.\pev ovv trd\iv rj 7rpa£is els Oewpiav. Cf. c. 8 : irdpepyov Oewpias rd wavra. 3 Enn. m. 8, 10: airrrj roivvv irap{o~x e ^ (v T V l/ "^dcrav £<jir\v rip <puTip tt\v woWtjv, ffieive 5i avrr] ov ttoWt) ovaa, d\V dpxv rrjs iroWrjs. 96 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM [v life is higher than the life of action, but whether it can properly be described as consisting in volition. Volition, he holds, is hardly the right term to apply to pure intellect and the life in accordance with it. Still less is it applicable to the One before intellect. Yet, as he also insists, to speak of the first principle as not-will and not-thought and not-knowledge would be even more misleading than the application to it of the positive terms. What is denied of the primal things is not denied in the sense that they are in want of it, but in the sense that they have no need of it, since they are beyond it. On the other hand, when the individual nature takes upon itself, as appears, one addition after another, it is in truth becoming more and more deprived of reality 1 . To recover the reality that is all, it must dismiss the apparent additions — which, if they indeed affected the being that remains, would be diminutions — and return to itself. Of such additions are practical activities. In the world of mixture they are necessary, but they must be treated as such, not thought of as conferring something more upon the soul than it has in itself. Only by rising above them in self-knowledge can the soul become liberated. Otherwise, it remains attached to its material vehicle, and changes from body to body as from one sleep to another. " True waking is a true rising up from the body, not with a body 2 ." This cannot be completely attained by practical virtue, which belongs to the composite nature and not to the separable soul ; as the poet indicates in the Odyssey when he places the shade of Hercules in Hades but " himself among the gods." The hero has been thought worthy to ascend to Olympus for his noble deeds, but, as his virtue was practical and not theoretical, he has not wholly ascended, but something of him also remains below 3 . The man of practical virtue, as the Homeric account is interpreted else- where 4 , will retain some memory of the actions he performed on earth, though he will forget what is bad or trivial ; the man of theoretic virtue, possessing now intuitive knowledge, will 1 Enn. VI. 5, 12: ov yap £k tov ovtos vjv t\ irpoadr)Kr) — ovdev yap iKeivuj wpocrOrj- <reis- — dAAct tov fi-q ovtos. 2 Enn. in. 6, 6. 3 Enn. i. 1, 12. 4 Enn. iv. 3, 32. V] OF PLOTINUS 97 dismiss all memories whatever 1 . Memory, however, seems to be thought of not as actually perishing, but as recoverable should the soul redescend to relation with the material uni- verse. Here Plotinus is expressing himself, after Plato, in terms of metempsychosis. As in the Platonic representation of the future life, intermissions are supposed during which the purified soul gets temporary respite from occupation with a body. Plotinus, however, as we have seen, does not treat that which is distinctively called the Platonic " reminiscence " as more than a myth or a metaphor. When the soul, even here, is energising in accordance with pure intellect, it is not "remembering." Memory is of past experience, and is relative to time and its divisions. The energy of pure intellect is not in relation to time, but views things in the logical order of concepts. Hence it is that the better soul strives to bring the many to one by getting rid of the indefinite multiplicity of detail ; and so commits much to oblivion. Consistently with this general view, Plotinus holds that the happiness of the sage receives no increase by continuance of time 2 . We cannot make a greater sum by adding what no longer exists to what now is. Time can be measured by addition of parts that are not, because time itself, the " image of eternity," belongs to things that become and are not. Happiness belongs to the life of being, and this is incom- mensurable with the parts of time. Is one to be supposed happier for remembering the pleasure of eating a dainty yesterday or, say, ten years ago ; or, if the question is of insight instead of pleasure, through the memory of having had insight last year / To remember things that went well in the past belongs to one who has them nut in the present and, because now he has them not, seeks to recall those that have been. To the argument that time is necessary for the per- formance of fair deeds, the reply is, first, that it is possible to be happy — and not less but more so — outside the life of action. In the next place, happiness comes not from the actual per- 1 Enn. iv. 4, 1. %l Enn. I. 5. Et iv iro.po.7a.cti. xpovov rb tvoo.ip.ovuv. w. 7 98 THE PHILOSOPHICAL SYSTEM OF PLOTINUS [V formance of the deeds, but from the disposition with which they are done. The man of right disposition will find happiness in disinterested appreciation, for example, of patriotic deeds which he has not himself had the opportunity of performing. Hence (as the Stoics also held against Aristotle) length of life is not necessary for its moral perfection 1 . Several points of the ethics of Plotinus are brought together in a book giving a philosophical interpretation of the fancy that to each person is allotted his particular genius or " daemon 2 ." Plotinus's interpretation is that the daemon of each of us is the power next above that in accordance with which his actual life is led. For those who live the common life according to sense-perception, it is reason ; for those who live the life of reason, it is the power above that. How then, he asks, with reference to the " lots " in the Republic, if each while " there " chooses his tutelary daemon and his life " here," are we masters of anything in our actions ? The explanation he suggests is, that by its mythical choice once for all " there," is signified the soul's will and disposition in general every- where 3 . Continuing in terms of the Platonic imaginations on the destiny of souls, he observes that since each soul, as a microcosm, contains within itself a representation not only of the whole intelligible world, but also of the soul which guides the visible universe 4 , it may find itself, after departure from the body, in the sun or one of the planets or in the sphere of the fixed stars, according as it has energised with the power related to this or that part of the whole. Those souls that have overpassed the " daemonic nature " are at this stage of their mutation outside all destiny of birth and beyond the limits of the visible heaven. 1 Enn. i. 5, 10 : to 5& ev reus Trpd^ecri to evbaifiovuu rideadat ev to?s e'fw ttjs aperrjs Kal ttjs ^pvxvs e0 " rt tl9(vtos' tj yap tvepyeia Trjs i/'i'X 1 7 s & v T V 4>povr)aai Kal ei> iavrfi wSl ivtpyrjcrai. Kal tovto to evdai/novus. - Enn. in. 4. Hepl tov elXr/xoTOS Tinas dal/j.oi'os. 3 Enn. in. 4, 5 : dXX' el e^e? alpe?Tai tov Ba'ifxova Kal tov /3iov, ttws £ti twos Kvpioi ; r; Kal i] a'ipeais eKei r) \tyofxevr} ttjv tt/s i/'i'X'? 5 Trpoaipeciv Kal Siddftnv Kad6\ov Kal iravraxov atViTTerai. In Enn. n. 3, 15, the "lots" are interpreted as meaning all the external circumstances of the soul at birth taken together. 4 Enn. m. 4, 6 : XPV 7<*P oteffOai Kal kSct/jlop dvai iv ttj \frvx3J rjfj.wv fir] ixbvov vot)tov, d\\a Kal ^ux^s r V* xoafiov 6fioeL8rj Otiadecnv. CHAPTER VI. THE MYSTICISM OF PLOTINUS. The aim of philosophic thought, for Plotinus as for Plato, is pure truth expressed with the utmost exactitude. And, much as he abounds in metaphor, he knows how to keep his intellectual conceptions clear of mixture with their imaginative illustration. On the interpretation of myths, whether poetic or philosophic, he is as explicit as intelligent readers could desire. After allegorising the myth of Pandora and of Prometheus, for example, he remarks that the meaning of the story itself may be as any one likes, but that the particular interpretation has been given because it makes plain the philosophic theory of creation and agrees with what is set forth 1 . Again, in inter- preting the Platonic myth of Eros, he calls to mind that myths, if they are to be such, must separate in time things not temporally apart, and divide from one another things that are in reality together ; seeing that even rational accounts have to resort to the same modes of separation and division 2 . This relation between science and myth remained substantially the same for his successors. Some of them might devote greater attention to mythology, and indulge more seriously in fancies that a deep philosophic wisdom was embodied in it by the ancient " theologians " ; but the theoretical distinction between 1 Enn. IV. 3, 14 : ravra ixkv ovv 071-77 rts Soifdfet, d\\' otl €fj.<paiva to. ttjs et's tov k6<t/j.op 56(7€0)s, /cat Trpoaq.dei rots Xeyo^vots. 2 Enn. in. 5, 9 : Set 8Z tovs fivdovs, dfrep tovto taovrai, /cat nepifeiv x/^ois a \4yovat, Kal BiaipeTv air' d\\rj\wu noWd twi> 6vtuv 6/xou fxev cWa, rctfei 5t fj Owdfiecri SuarUTa, oirov /cat ol \6yot /cat 7eef<rets tCjv dyevvriTwif irotovffi, /cat to, 6/j.ov ovra Kal avrol 5iaLpovcrt, /cat Stodijaeres d>s ovvavrai rif voqeavTi tfo-q avyx^povai ovvaipeiv. 7—2 100 THE MYSTICISM [VI truth of science and its clothing in imaginative form is made, if anything, sharper. The distinction comes to be used — as it is already to some extent by Plotinus — to explain the physical cosmogonies of early philosophers without supposing that they meant to teach an actual emergence of the world from some primordial element or chaotic aggregate and its return to this. What the oldest philosophers had in view, according to the Neo-Platonist system of interpretation, was only to render their logical analysis of the world into its permanent con- stituents easier to grasp. As the Neo-Platonist doctrine itself was thought out wholly on the line of the philosophical tradition, its relation to " positive religion " is quite the opposite of subservience. The myths are completely plastic in the hands of the philosophers. Of their original meaning, no doubt they have a less keen sense than Plato, who saw the real hostility of a naturalistic " theogony " like that of Hesiod to his own type of thought ; but this only shows how dominant the philosophical point of view has become. Plato could not yet treat the myths of Greek religion so arbitrarily as would have been necessary for his purpose, or did not think it worth while. For the Neo-Platonists the poetic mythology has become like their own "matter," absolutely powerless to modify the essence of thought, but equally ready to take on an elusive reflexion of every idea in turn. Not in this quarter, therefore, need we look for any derogation from the scientific character of Neo-Platonic thought. If Plotinus accepted Hellenic religion as the basis of culture, the reason was because he saw in it no obstacle to the adequate expression of philosophic truth ; which, moving freely on its own plane, could turn the images of mythology themselves to the account of metaphysics and ethics. Some members of the school, as we know, were given to devotional practices and to theurgy ; but in all this the master did not personally join. On one occasion indeed, he seemed to his disciples to speak too loftily on the subject, though, as Porphyry tells us, they did not venture to ask his meaning. Amelius had become diligent in sacrificing and in attending the feasts of the gods, and wished to take Plotinus with him. He declined, saying, "It is for VI] OF PLOTINUS 101 them to come to me, not for me to go to them 1 ." The explanation is no doubt to be found in the contrast between the common religious need for a social form of worship and the subjective intensity of the mystic. That this was in the temperament of Plotinus is evident all through the Enneads. His religious attitude invariably is that the soul, having duly prepared itself, must wait for the divinity to appear. External excitement is the very reverse of the method he points out : he insists above all on internal quietude. Porphyry also has something to tell us on the subject. Four times while he was with him, he relates, Plotinus attained the end of union with the God who is over all, without form, above intellect and all the intelligible. Porphyry himself attained this union once, in his sixty-eighth year-. The mystical " ecstasy " was not found by the later teachers of the school easier to attain, but more difficult ; and the tendency became more and more to regard it as all but unattainable on earth. Are we to hold that it was the beginning of Plotinus's whole philosophy ; that a peculiar subjective experience was therefore the source of the Neo- Platonic doctrines ? This will hardly seem probable after the account that has been given of Plotinus's reasoned system ; and, in fact, the possibility of the experience is inferred from the system, not the propositions of the system from the experience. It is described as a culminating point, to be reached after long discipline ; and it can only be known from itself, not from any description. Not being properly a kind of cognition, it can become the ground of no inference. Now, since the philosophy of Plotinus undoubtedly claims to be a kind of knowledge, it must have its evidence for learners in something that comes within the forms of thought. While he was personally a mystic, his theory of knowledge could not be mystical without contradicting the mysticism itself. In modern phraseology, it was a form of Rationalism. Cognition at its highest degree of certainty, as Plotinus understands it, may best be compared to Spinoza's " knowledge of the third kind," or '' scieutia intuitiva 3 ." Exactly as with 1 Porpli. V. Plot. 10: eKeivovs Sd vpbs ipie 2px«r0ai, ovk i/xe irpbs indvov>. - V. Plot. 23. ;i Eth, ii. Prop. 40, Scbol. 2. Cf. Enu. vi. 7, 2. 102 THE MYSTICISM [VI Spinoza, the inferior degrees that lead up to it are : first, the " opinion " that is sufficient for practical life ; second, the discursive " reason " that thinks out one thing adequately from another, but does it only through a process, not grasping the relation at once in its totality. The difference is that Plotinus conceives the highest kind of knowledge not as mathematical in form but as " dialectical." By " dialectic " he means, not a purely formal method, a mere " organon," but a method of which the use, when once attained, gives along with the form of thought its content, which is true being 1 . Before the learner can reach this stage, he must be disciplined in the other branches of liberal science. As with Plato, dialectic is the crown of a philosophical education. Nor does Plotinus alto- gether neglect the logical topics he regards as subsidiary to this. At the beginning of the sixth Ennead is placed a considerable treatise'- in which he criticises first the Stoic and then the Aristotelian categories, and goes on to expound a scheme of his own. This scheme, as Zeller remarks, has not the same importance for his system as those of Aristotle and of the Stoics for theirs. Porphyry, in his larger commentary on the Categories, defended Aristotle's treatment against the objections of Plotinus, and thenceforth the Aristotelian cate- gories maintained their authority in the school 3 . On the other hand, it must be observed that this affects only a subsidiary part of Plotinus's theory of knowledge. His general view regarding the supremacy of dialectic as conceived by Plato, was also that of his successors. In subordination to this, Aristotle's list of the most general forms of assertion about being held its own against the newer scheme of Plotinus. By the Athenian successors of Plotinus more definitely than by himself, Aristotle came to be regarded as furnishing the needful preliminary training for the study of Plato 4 . 1 Enn. i. 3. He pi SiaXeKTiKrjs. - Emi. vi. 1-3. llepi twv yev&v tou ovtos. 3 Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 523 — i. 4 The doctrine of categories elaborated by Plotinus being for the most part in no organic relation to his general system, it did not seem necessary to give a detailed exposition of it. Its abandonment by the Neo-Platonic school, besides, makes it historically less important. Vl] OF PLOTINUS 103 The philosophic wisdom of which dialectic is the method, Plotinus expressly declares 1 , cannot be achieved without first going through the process of learning to know by experience. Knowledge and virtue at lower stages can exist, though not in perfection, without philosophy; but except by starting from these, the height of theoretic philosophy is unattainable. Even when that height is attained, and being is known in intuitive thought, there is something remaining still. The One and Good, which is the first principle of things, is beyond thought. If it is to be apprehended at all, and not simply inferred as the metaphysical unity on which all things necessarily depend, there must be some peculiar mode of apprehending it. Here Plotinus definitely enters upon the mystical phase of his doctrine. The One is to be seen with " the eyes of the soul," now closed to other sights. It becomes impossible, as he recognises, to use terms quite consistently, and he cannot altogether dispense with those that signify cognition ; but it is always to be understood that they are not used in their strict sense. That which apprehends the One is intellect — or the soul when it has become pure intellect ; so that the principle above intelligence has sometimes to be spoken of as an " in- telligible," and as that which mind, when it " turns back," thinks before it thinks itself. For by this reflexive process — in the logical order of causes — mind comes to be, and its essence is to think. On the other hand, the One does not "think"; its possession of itself is too complete for the need to exist even of intuitive thought. Accordingly, since it can only be apprehended by the identification with it of that which apprehends, mind, to apprehend it, must dismiss even the activity of thought, and become passive. At last, unexpectedly, the vision of the One dawns on the purified intellectual soul. The vision is "ineffable": for while it can only be indicated in words that belong to being, its object is beyond being. All that can be done is to describe the process through which it comes to pass, and, with the help of inadequate metaphors, to make it recognisable by those who may also attain it themselves. 1 Enn. i. 3, 0. 104 THE MYSTICISM [VI Since that which is sought is one, he who would have the vision of it must have gone back to the principle of unity in himself; must have become one instead of many 1 . To see it, we must entrust our soul to intellect, and must quit sense and phantasy and opinion, and pay no regard to that which comes from them to the soul. The One is an object of apprehension {avveai'i) not by knowledge, like the other intelligibles, but by a presence which is more than knowledge. If we are to apprehend it, we must depart in no way from being one, but must stand away from knowledge and knowables, with their still remaining plurality. That which is the object of the vision is apart from no one, but is of all ; yet so as being present not to be present except to those that are able and have prepared themselves to see it 2 . As was said of matter, that it must be without the qualities of all things if it is to receive the impressions of all, so and much more so, the soul must become unformed {uveiheos;) if it is to contain nothing to hinder its being filled and shone upon by the first nature*. The vision is not properly a vision, for the seer no longer distinguishes himself from that which is seen — if indeed we are to speak of them as two and not as one 4 — but as it were having become another and not himself, is one with that other as the centre of the soul touching the centre of all 5 . While here, the soul cannot retain the vision ; but it can retreat to it in alternation with the life of knowledge and virtue which is the preparation for it. " And this is the life of gods and of godlike and happy men, a deliverance from the other things here, a life untroubled by the pleasures here, a flight of the alone to the alone." 1 Enn. vi. 9, 3. 2 Enn. vi. 9, 4 : oi'» yap 8r] aireuriv ov8evus exe'ivo Kal irdvTwv 8e, ware irapbv fir) irapetvai dXX' r) rols 5e'xf<r#cu Swa/nevoLS Kal ira.pi<TKtva<jp.ivoi.s. Cf. C. 7 : ov yap Kelral ttov ip-qp-Ciaav avrov t& dXXa, dXX' ecrrt tu dwafxevLi} diyelv (Kelvo irapbu, ra; 5' abvvarovvri ov iraptcrriv. 6 Enn. vi. 9, 7 : el /xeXXet p.7]bev e/xwodiov iyKad-qfxtvov ZotaOai rrpbs TrXrjpwcriv Kal ^Wapi-if/iv avrrj rrjs tpvcreus 7^s irpwTTjs. 4 "An audacious saying," adds Plotinus. 5 Enn. vi. 9, 10. Cf. c. II : to 5e i<rus yjv ov Otajj-a, dXXd dXXos rpowos rod £de?v, '{KGTaais Kal airXwcris Kal eVicotns avrov Kal e<peo~is Trpos a<f>7)v Kal oraffis. Vl] OF PLOTINUS 105 These are the concluding words of the Enneads in Porphyry's redaction. In another book, which comes earlier but was written later 1 , Plotinus describes more psychologically the method of preparation for the vision. The process, which may begin at any point, even with the lowest part of the soul, consists in stripping off everything extraneous till the principle is reached. First the body is to be taken away as not belonging to the true nature of the self ; then the soul that shapes the body ; then sense- perception with appetites and emotions. What now remains is the image of pure intellect 2 . Even when intellect itself is reached by the soul turning to it, there still remains, it must be repeated, the duality and even plurality implied in synthetic cognition of self as mind". Mind is self-sufficing, because it has all that it needs for self-knowledge ; but it needs to think itself. The principle, which gives mind its being and makes it self-sufficing, is beyond even this need ; and the true end for the soul is, by the light it sees by, to touch and gaze upon that light. How is this to be done ? Take away all 4 . All other things, as Plotinus says elsewhere, in comparison with the principle have no reality, and nothing that can be affirmed of them can be affirmed of it. It has neither shape nor form, and is not to be sought with mortal eyes. For those things which, as perceptible by sense, are thought most of all to be, in reality most of all are not. To think the things of sense to be most real is as if men sleeping away all their lives should put trust in what they saw in their dreams, and, if one were to wake them up, should distrust what they saw with open eyes and go off to sleep again 5 . Men have forgotten what even from the beginning until now they desire and aspire after. " For all things strive after that and aspire after it by necessity 1 Enn. v. 3. '-' This is related to intelleet itself as the moon to the sun. Cf. Enn. v. <>, 4. •' Enn. v. 3, 13: Kivbvvevei yap o\ws to voetv iroWwv (is avrb avveXdbvTwv o~vvaio~0r)cns elvai rov o\ov, brav avro tl eavrb vorj' 6 Srj Kvpius icri vouv. 4 Enn. v. 3, 17 : Kal tovto to reXos raXridivbv ^i'xf?> e<p&ipacrdcu <pwrbs entivov Kal (xvtu avrb 0ed<rao~dai, ovk dWui ipwri, d\\" cu't^j, 5t' ov Kal bpq. wws dv ovv tovto yevoiTo; &<pe\e irdvTa. 5 Enn. v. 5, 11. 106 THE MYSTICISM [VI of nature, as if having a divination that without it they cannot be 1 ." Much as all this may resemble Oriental mysticism, it does not seem to have come from any direct contact with the East. Zeller indeed finds in the idea of a mental state beyond cognition a decisive break with the whole direction of classical thought, and makes Philo here the sole predecessor of Plotinus' 2 . But, we may ask, whence came the notion to Philo himself? The combination of the most complete " immanence " in one sense with absolute transcendence of Deity in another, does not seem native to Jewish religion, any more than the asceticism for which, in the Essenes, Zeller finds it necessary to recur to a Greek origin. Once get rid of the presupposition that Neo- Platonism sprang from a new contact with Eastern theosophy, and the solution is clear. To Philo and to Plotinus alike, the direct suggestion for the doctrine of "ecstasy" came from Plato. The germinal idea that there is a mode of apprehension above that of perfectly sane and sober mind appears already in more than one Platonic dialogue. During the period of almost exclusively ethical thinking, between Aristotle and revived Pythagoreanism and Platonism, hints of the kind naturally found little response. After the revival of speculative thought, it is not surprising that they should have appealed to thinkers of widely different surroundings. The astonishing thing would have been if in all the study then given to Plato they had been entirely overlooked. That neither Philo nor Plotinus over- looked them may be seen from the references and quotations given by Zeller himself 3 . What is more, Plotinus definitely contrasts intellect soberly contemplating the intelligible with intellect rapt into enthusiasm and borne above it ; and explains the Platonic imagery of " insanity " and " intoxication " as referring to the latter state. Mind is still sane while con- templating intellectual beauty, and is seized upon by the "divine madness" only in rising above beauty to its cause 1 Enn. v. 5, 12. 2 iii. 2, pp. 448, 611. 3 See, for Philo, iii. 2, p. 415, u. 5; for Plotinus, p. 615, n. 3. Cf. Porph. V. Plot. 23. Vl] OF PLOTINUS 107 beyond 1 . That Plotinus derived from Plato his conception of the Good beyond being is generally admitted. It is equally clear that for the theory of its apprehension also there presented itself a Platonic point of view. Thus even the mystical consummation of his philosophy may be traced to a Hellenic source. Plato's own imagery, and in connexion with it his occasional mention of " bacchants " and "initiates," may of course have been suggested by forms of worship that were already coloured bv contact with the East ; but this does not affect the character of the Neo-Platonic school as in its own age essentially a classical revival. It was not inhospitable to Oriental cults, being indeed vaguely conscious of an affinity to those that were associated, in the higher order of their devotees, with a con- templative asceticism ; and, as willingly as Plato, it found adumbrations of philosophic truth in religious mysteries. These, however, as we have seen, in no case determined the doctrine, which was the outcome of a long intellectual tradition worked upon by thinkers of original power. The system left by Plotinus was further elaborated by the best minds of his own period; and, during the century after his death, we find it making its way over all the Graeco-Roman world. Defeated in the practical struggle, it became, all the more, the accepted philosophy of the surviving Greek schools; to take up at last its abode at Athens with the acknowledged successors of Plato. These stages will be described in the chapters that follow. 1 Enn. VI. 7, 35 : koX rbv voxiv ro'ivvv [Set] rrjv fxev ^x eiv Svvapup els to voelv, 17 to, iv ai'Tw /3\e7ret, tt]v 8e, 77 ra eireKuva avrou eTrifioXfj tivi ko.1 irapaboxa, K ^' V" *<*' ■wportpov eiipa fxofov Kai 6pu>v vcrrepov KaX vovv ^<xxe Kai 'iv iari ' tcai icrriv ixtivri p.tv 7} dka vov Zp.<ppovos, avTt) 8i vovs epQv. orav [yap] atppuv yevrjTai fitOvafjels tov ViKrapos, rote tpuv yiverai air\u)6th us tvwdOfiav toj Kopu>. CHAPTER VII. THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM. 1. Porphyry. Both for his own and for succeeding times, the name of Porphyry stands out conspicuous among the disciples of Plotinus. Eunapius, writing towards the end of the fourth century, observes that Plotinus is now more in the hands of educated readers than Plato himself; and that, if there is any popular knowledge of philosophy, it consists in some acquaintance with his doctrines. He then proceeds to give credit for this to the interpretations of Porphyry. And thus, he says, the honour was distributed from the first. Universally the doctrine was ascribed to Plotinus; while Porphyry gained fame by his clearness of exposition — "as if some Hermaic chain had been let down to men 1 ." He then goes on to celebrate Porphyry's knowledge of all liberal science (ovSev 7raiSeia<i el8os 7rapa\e\oi7ra><;) ; of which we have independent evidence in his extant works and in the titles of those that are lost. Eunapius's biography seems to have been mostly compiled— not always with perfect accuracy — from the information given by Porphyry himself in his Life of Plotinus. Porphyry was born in 233 and died later than 301. He was a Tyrian by birth. His name was originally " Malchus," the root of which, in the Semitic languages, means " a king." At the 1 Eunap. Vitae (Porphyrins) : 6 jih yap UXomVos rip re ttjj V' l 'X^ s ovpav'up /cat ry XoijtfS /cat alviy/jLaTwdei twv \6yuv, (3apvs e56/cei /cat Sixttjkoos ' 6 de llop(pvpLOS, ai<77re p ' Epixal'Krj tls aeipa /ecu 7rpos avdpwirovs emvevovcra, 5ia ttoikIXtis iratdelas iravTa eis to iiiyuwcTOV /cat Kadapbv e^rjyytWev. VI l] THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM 109 suggestion of his teachers he Hellenised it first into "Basileus" and then into " Porphyrins" (from the colour of regal garments). After having studied under Longinus at Athens, he visited Rome, and there, as we have seen, became a disciple of Plotiuus from the year 203. His journey to Sicily, with its cause, has been already mentioned. Afterwards he returned to Rome ; and it was in Rome, according to Eunapius, that he gained reputation by his expositions of Plotinus. Late in life he married the widow — named Marcella — of a friend ; for the sake of bringing up her children, as we learn both from Eunapius and from Porphyry's letter to her which is extant. She was subjected to some kind of persecution by her neigh- bours, who, Jules Simon conjectures', may have been Christians, and may have sought to detach her from philosophy. The letter is an exhortation to perseverance in philosophical principles, and is full of the characteristic ethical inwardness of Neo-Platonisnr. That Porphyry engaged in controversy with Christianity, now on the verge of triumph, is well known : and with him, as with Julian, the effect is a just perceptible reaction of Christian modes of thought or speech. As theo- logical virtues he commends (t faith, truth, love, hope " ; adding only truth to the Christian three 3 . A distinctive character of his treatise against the Christians seems to have been its occupation with questions of historical criticism. Very little of it has been preserved even in fragmen- tary form, the set replies of apologists, as well as the treatise itself, being lost ; but the view he took about the Book of Daniel is on record. According to Jerome, he maintained that it was written in the time of Antiochus Epiphanes ; so that the historical events supposed to have been predicted were really events that had taken place before the time of the writer. 1 Histoire <L' VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. ii. pp. 98 — 9. - See for example Epittola ad Marcellam, c. 9 : 7rtDs oTv ovk drotrov tt)v iveTrei<Jixtvr)v iv aol elvat Kai rb <tQ$ov Kai rb <np'^6p.(vov Kai rb ye airoWvov Kai <rb> diroWvuevov tov re ttXovtov Kai ttjv Trcvlav t6v re iraripa ko.1 rbv dvbpa Kai tov tuiv ovtws dyadQv Kadrjyt/Mbva, Kexv"tvai ""po* T h v T °v v<pr]yrjTov GKidv, ws 8rj rbv 6vtus v<pr)yy]Tr\v /xt) ivrbs £x ovo ~ av f* 7 )^ itapd ffavrfj iravra rbv ttXovtov ; 3 Ad Marcellam, 24: T^craapa aroix^a p-dXiara KfKparvvOu nepl deov' ttIgtis, d\r)deia, fycus, iKrls. 110 THE DIFFUSION [VII This, Jerome says, proves the strength of the case in favour of its genuinely prophetic character; for if events subsequent to the time of Daniel had not been very clearly prefigured, Porphyry would not have found it necessary to argue against the ascription to him of the authorship 1 . In the time of Plotinus, Porphyry recounts, there were members of various sects, both Christians and others, who put forth apocalypses such as those attributed to Zoroaster and Zostrianus, by which they " deceived many, themselves also deceived." Amelius wrote against the book of " Zostrianus " ; Porphyry himself against that of " Zoroaster," showing it to be spurious and recent and forged by the authors of the sect in order to give currency to the opinion that their own doctrines were those of the ancient Zoroaster 2 . The spirit of critical inquiry thus aroused in Porphyry seems to have led him more and more to take the sceptical view about all claims to particular revelations from the gods, including the " theurgic " manifestations to which attention was paid by some members of the Neo-Platonic school. It was probably at a late period of his life that he wrote the letter to the Egyptian priest Anebo,to which an unknown member of the school of Iamblichus replied, under the name of " Abammon," in the famous book De Mysteriis. One little book of Porphyry, entitled De Antro Nympkarum, is an interesting example of the mode of interpreting poetic mythology current in the school. Porphyry there sets out to show that Homer, in his description of the Grotto of the Nymphs at Ithaca 3 , probably did not give an account of an actual cavern to be found in the island — for topographers make no mention of any that resembles the description — but deposited in allegorical form an ancient " theological wisdom " identical with true philosophy. If there really is such a 1 Cf. Jules Simon, Histoire de VEcole cVAlexandrie, t. ii. p. 181. " L'on peut juger," says the historian on the preceding page, "par l'indignation menie que cet ouvrage excita dans l'Eglise, de l'importance et de la gravite des attaques qu'il contenait." 2 Vita Plotini, 16 : vodov re ko.1 veov to j3ij3\iov trapadetKuvs irew\affp.evov re virb tuiv rrjv a'ipecnv aiKTrqaafxivwu els So^af rod elvai rov Trakaiod 7iupoa(TTpov ra 86yp.a.Ta, a avrol eiXovro Trpe<r[3ei!iei)>. 3 Od. xiii. 102—112. VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 111 cavern, then those who wrought it had the hidden meaning, which in that case was only transmitted by the poet. This meaning Porphyry educes with an ingenuity that has an attractiveness of its own. It must be noted, however, that the philosophers do not add, and do not think they are adding, anything to the content or even to the authority of their doctrine. All such interpretations are in the interest of the old mycologists and no longer of the philosophers, who are not now putting themselves under the protection of the legends, but on the contrary are seeking if possible to save them. Of all Porphyry's writings, that which had the most far- reaching influence on culture was his short introduction to the Aristotelian Categories. Coming down to the Middle Ages in the Latin translation of Boethius, it sufficed, by a few words at the opening, to set going the whole discussion on " universals " with which early Scholasticism was preoccupied. This of course was not due to any special originality, but to its summing up clearly and briefly the points of the rival theories maintained by Platonists, Peripatetics and Stoics. Porphyry's logical works generally were expository, and well adapted for use in the schools through keeping the subject clear of metaphysics 1 . Besides devoting much labour to commenting on Aristotle, he wrote a History of Philosophy, to which his extant Life of Pythagoras probably belonged ; psychological works from which many passages are cited by Stobaeus ; and mathematical works referred to by Proclus. Among his occasional writings of a more original kind, the most extensive now remaining is the Be Abstinentia (Tlepl uttox^ e^vx^v), a treatise against the eating of animal food. His expositions of Plotinus, already referred to, are still represented in the Sententiae ('A^op/xat 7rpo9 T(i vorjrd 2 ). In what is recorded of Porphyry's metaphysical doctrines, a tendency is found to greater elaboration of the triadic method of grouping, carried out still more systematically by later Neo- Platonism. The real importance of the writings in which he 1 Cf. Zeller. iii. 2, pp. 640—3. '-' Prefixed to the Didot edition of Plotinus (1855). 112 THE DIFFUSION [VII set forth the doctrine of his school was due, however, as his contemporaries recognised, to the insight with which he pene- trated to his master's essential thought and to his lucidity in expounding it. Some illustration of this may be furnished from the Sententiae. Then, as an example of his more personal work, an exposition may be given of the Be Abstinentia. The treatise has, besides, a more general interest in the specimens it offers of the ethical questions raised and discussed in later ' antiquity, not in a spirit of scholastic casuistry but with a genuine desire for their solution in the light of reflective conscience. Preoccupation with ethics may be noticed in the Sententiae, which contain a more systematic classification of the virtues than Plotinus had explicitly given. Porphyry classifies them into Political, Cathartic, Theoretic and Paradigmatic. The virtues of the first class set the soul free from excess of passionate attachment to the body, and produce moderation ; those of the second class liberate it altogether from this attachment, so that it can now turn to its true good. The third class comprises the virtues of the soul energising intellec- tually ; the fourth, those that are in intellect itself, to which the soul looks up as patterns. Our care must be chiefly about the virtues of the second class, seeing that they are to be acquired in this life. Through them is the ascent to the contemplative virtues of soul and to those that are their models in pure intellect. The condition of purification is self-knowledge 1 . When the soul knows itself, it knows itself as other than the corporeal nature to which it is bound. The error to which we are especially liable is ascription of the properties of body to incorporeal being. The body of the world is everywhere spatially, its parts being spread out so that they can be dis- criminated by the intervals between them. To God, Mind and Soul, local situation does not apply. One part of intelligible being is not here and another there. Where it is, it is as a whole. The union of an incorporeal nature with a body is 1 Sententiae, 34. VI r] OF NBO-PLATONISM 113 altogether peculiar 1 . It is present indivisibly, and as numeri- cally one, to tlie multitude of parts, each and all. What appears to be added — as locality or relation— in departing from incor- poreal being, is really taken away. Not to know being and not to know oneself, have the same source, namely, an addition of what is not, constituting a diminution of being which is all, — and which, except in appearance, cannot be diminished. Recovery of yourself by knowledge is recovery of being which was never absent, — which is as inseparable from you in essence as you are from yourself 2 . This is of course the doctrine of Plotinus taken at its centre. With equal exactitude Porphyry reproduces his con- ception of being as differentiated intrinsically and not by participation in anything external 3 . Plurality of souls is prior to plurality of bodies, and is not incompatible with the continued unity of all souls in one. They exist without diremption, yet unconfused, like the many parts of knowledge in a single soul 4 . Time accompanies the cognitive process in soul, as eternity accompanies the timeless cognition of intellect. In such process, however, the earlier thought does not go out to give place to the later. It appears to have gone out, but it 1 Sententiae, 35: oOre oftv Kpdcrts, r) M<s' J > V crvvodos, rj irapdOfuis ' d\\' erepos Tpowos. Cf. 6 : ov to ttoiouv els dWo rreXdcrei Kai d(py iroLtl d rroiel' d\\d Kai ra ireXdcrei Kai drpfj ti iroiovvra, Kara o~vp.j3e(3riKbs rrj ire\d<rei XPV T<XI - On this Ritter and Preller remark (524 a), " Favet theurgicis hoc placitnm." Here is a good illustration of the readiness which historians have often displayed to see the "theurgical" in preference to the scientific side of the Neo-Platonists. Whether by itself or taken along with the context, what the passage suggests is a kind of Occasionalist phenomenism. All changes, even in bodies, have their true cause in immaterial being. Material approach or contact is not an efficient cause, but accompanies as its "accident" the real order of metaphysical causation. -' Sententiae, 41 : o or; oi>rw aov eariv dvairoairacnov tear ovcriav, ws <rv cravTov. 3 Sententiae, 38 : ov yap ft-wOei* iiriKTr)Tos, ovbe iireio-odiwbris avrov rj erepbr-qs, ovbe <z\\oi> p-edti-ei, d\\' eavry iroWd. 4 Sententiae, 39 : buo-rrjo-av yap, ovk dwoKOirdaai, ovbe drroKeppaTiaao-ai els eavras ti\v 6\r)i> ' /cat irdpticiv d\\r)\ais, ov o-vyKexvp-tvo-h ovbe awpbv -woiovaat. tt)v 6\r)v '...wo-rrep ovde ai eTrio-Trjp.au o-vvexvO-qaav al woWai ev ^pvxv M'P — K <*' ai 7ra<rat, pia - Kai TrdXtv i) o\t? a\\rj rrapa wdcras. W. 8 1]4 THE DIFFUSION [VII remains ; and what appears to have come in is from the movement of the soul returning on itself 1 . Thus closely does the disciple follow the master into the psychological subtleties 2 by which he anticipated the modern position that, as the idea of extension is not extended, so the succession of thoughts does not suffice to give the thought of succession. After the illustration offered of his penetrating clearness of exposition, we may go on to a work which shows him in a more distinctive light. Plotinus, though personally an ascetic, laid no stress in his writings on particular ascetic practices. His precepts reduce themselves in effect to a general recommendation to thin down the material vehicle so that the soul may be borne quietly upon it 3 . There is no suggestion in the Enneads that the perfection of philosophic life requires abstinence from animal food. Not infrequently, however, both earlier and later, this abstinence was practised as a strict duty by those who traced their philosophic ancestry to Pythagoras. Now the Neo-Platonists, on the practical side, continued the movement of religious and moral reform represented by teachers like Apollonius of Tyana 4 . 1 Sententiae, 44 : ipvxv Se fxeraftaivei air' dWov eis dWo, ewafieifiovcra to, vorj/J-ara' ovk e^iarap-ivuv rdv irpurepuiv, oi>8e wodev dXXodev eireiffibvTwv tQv devre'pujv dXXd t& p.ev wcnrep &Tre\r]\vde, Kalirep fxivovra ev avrfj' rd 5 wairep dWaxiOev e'lreiai.v. dcpiKaro 5' ovk dWaxbdeu, dXX' avryjs Kai avrbdev eis eavrrjv KivovpLevrjs, Kai to op.pLa. (pepovavs eis d ^X eL KaT d /nepos. irrfyrj ydp ZoLKev ovk diroppvTip, dXXd kvk\lp eis eavrr/v dvaj3\v^ov(rri d exec. 2 To ignore the subtleties of the school is especially misleading in the case of a doctrine like that of "ecstasy." Jules Simon (Histoire de VEcole. d' Alexandria, t. ii. p. 156), referring to a passage of the Sententiae (26), says that, for Porphyry, "ecstasy is a sleep." What Porphyry really says is that, while we have to speak of the existence beyond mind in terms of thought, we can only contemplate it in a state that is not thought; as sleep has to be sjDoken of in terms of waking life, but can only be known through sleeping. Ecstasy, that is to say, is compared to sleep because it also has to be apprehended by its like, and because language, by which alone we can try to communicate our appre- hension to others, has been framed for a different realm of experience ; not at all because it is a kind of sleep. 3 Enn. in. 6, 5. 4 Eunapius, in the introduction to his Lives, says of Apollonius that he is not to be counted as a mere philosopher, but rather as something between the gods and man (ovk4ti (pCK6co<pos ' dXX' t\v ti Oewv re Kai dvdpdnrov fieaov). VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 115 Thus many of them refrained on principle from flesh-eating. Among these was Porphyry. The occasion of his treatise was that Castricius Firmus, one of the disciples of Plotinus, having begun to practise abstinence from flesh, had returned to the ordinary custom. He could easily defend himself on theoretical grounds; for Peripatetics, Stoics and Epicureans had all their systematic refutation of the Pythagorean abstinence. To the arguments current in the schools, accordingly, Porphyry first sets himself to reply. The contention of the Stoics and Peripatetics was that the idea of justice is applicable only to rational beings ; to extend it beyond them to irrational beings, as those do who refuse to kill animals for food, is to subvert its nature and to destroy the possibility of that in it which is practicable. The Epicurean argument which Porphyry cites is founded on a conjectural account of the origin of laws. The primitive legislator per- ceived some utility, and other men, who had not perceived it at first, as soon as their attention was drawn willingly attached to its violation a social prohibition and a penalty. It is for reasons of utility that there are laws against homicide but not against the slaughter of animals. If indeed a contract could have been made, not only among men but also between men and animals, to refrain from killing one another at random, it would have been well that justice should be so far extended, for thus safety would have been promoted ; but it is impossible for animals that do not understand discourse to share in law. To the general argument Porphyry in the first book replies provisionally that he does not recommend this abstinence to all men — not for example to those who have to do with the mechanical arts, nor to athletes, nor to soldiers, nor to men of affairs— but only to those who live the life of philosophy. Legislators make laws not with a view to the theoretic life, but to a kind of average life. Thus we cannot adopt their conces- sions as rules for a life that is to be better than written law. The asceticism of the philosopher consists in a withdrawal from the things of ordinary life, if possible without trial of them. No one can dwell at once with the things of sense and the 8—2 116 THE DIFFUSION [VII things of the mind 1 . The life of the body generally, and such matters as diet in particular, cannot safely be left unregulated by reason. The more completely they are put in order once for all, the less attention they will occupy, and the freer the mind will be for its own life. The Epicureans have to some extent recognised this in advising abstinence from flesh, if not on the ground of justice yet as a means of reducing needs and so making life simpler. From the practical side the objection was raised that to reject the flesh of animals as food is inconsistent with the custom of offering them as sacrifices to the gods. Porphyry replies by an unsparing attack on the custom. This fills the second book. An account of the origin of animal sacrifices is quoted from Theophrastus, who with reason, Porphyry says, forbids those who would be truly pious to sacrifice living things 2 . Offerings of fruits and corn and flowers and spices came earliest. The custom of sacrificing animals was not earlier than the use of them for food, which began, together with cannibalism, in a dearth of fruits. Living things then came to be sacrificed because men had been accustomed to make first offerings to the gods of all that they used 3 . Re- sponses of oracles and sayings from the poets are quoted to show that the least costly sacrifices with purity of mind are the most pleasing to the gods. Porphyry disclaims any intention of overthrowing established customs ; but remarks that the laws of the actual State allow private persons to offer the plainest sacrifices, and such as consist of things without life. To make an offering to the gods of food from which we ourselves abstain would undoubtedly be unholy ; but we are not required to do it. We too must sacrifice, but in accordance with the nature 1 De Abst. i. 42. The theories of some of the Gnostics are alluded to. to 5Z OLeadai Kara ttjp atadrjaiv iradaiubp-evov irpbs roh voyroh evepyetv ttoWous ko.1 twi> Papfidpuv e£erpax??Wo'- 2 De Abst. ii. 11 : eiVorws 6 Qeb<ppaaTOS airayopevei fx-q dveiv ra e/j.\[/vxa tous rip ovtl evtre^eiv edeXovras. 3 This is a generalised account. Here and elsewhere in the De Abstinentia there is much curious lore about the origin both of flesh-eating and of animal sacrifices. VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 117 of the different powers. To the God over all, as a certain wise man 1 said, we must neither offer nor even name anything material. Our offering must be contemplation without even inward discourse. To all the gods, the special thank-offering of the philosopher will be fair thoughts regarding them. Some of those who are devoted to philosophy, Porphyry allows, hesitate here, aud make too much of externals. We will not quarrel with them, lest we too should be over-precise on such a matter, but will add contemplation, as our own offering, to their observance of pious tradition. He who cares about piety knows that to the gods none but bloodless sacrifices are to be offered. Sacrifices of another kind are offered only to the daemons — which name Plato applied without distinction to the multitude of invisible powers below the stars. On the subject of daemons, Porphyry then proceeds to give an account of the views popularly expounded by some of the Platonists (a rwv YlXarcovifcwv rwes i8rj/j.oa leva av 2 ). One of the w r orst injuries done by the bad among the daemons is to persuade us that those beings are the causes of earthly ills who are really the causes of quite the opposite. After this, they turn us to entreaties and sacrifices to the beneficent gods as if they were angry 3 . They inflame the desires of men with love of riches and power and pleasure, whence spring factions and wars. And, what is most terrible, they reach the point of persuading them that all this has been stirred up by the highest God. Nor are the philosophers altogether blameless. For some of them have not kept far enough apart from the ideas of the multitude, who, hearing from those that appeared wise things in harmony with their own opinions, were still further en- couraged in unworthy thoughts about the gods. If cities must propitiate such powers, that is nothing to us (ouSei; 7T/JO? ?//ia?). For by these wealth and external and bodily things are thought to be goods and deprivation of them an evil, 1 Apollonius of Tyana, as is mentioned in a note in Nauck's edition (Porphyrii Opuscula Selecta). 2 Be Abst. ii. 37—43. 3 De Abst. ii. 40 : rpiwovalv re fiera tovto (irl Xiraveias rip-cis /cat Ovaias tQiv dyaOoepyuiv Vewv uis usp-yiap-ivuiv. 118 THE DIFFUSION [VII and they have little care about the soul. The same position must be taken as regards divination by the entrails of victims. This, it may be said, will be clone away with if we refrain from killing and eating animals. Why not, then, kill men also for the purpose ? It is said that better premonitions are to be got in that way, and many of the barbarians really practise this mode of divination. As a matter of fact, whether the victim is human or is an irrational animal, thus to gain knowledge of the future belongs to injustice and greed 1 . Here Porphyry recounts a number of cases of human sacrifice in former times, and their commutation into animal or symbolical sacrifices; appealing to historical authority for the statement that it was not until the time of Hadrian that all survivals of such rites throughout the Empire were practi- cally abolished' 2 . Before concluding the book, he observes that even the unperverted ideas of the multitude make some approach to right opinion about the gods ; and illustrates the remark by passages from comic poets ridiculing the notion that divine powers are pleased with such things as are usually offered to them. Then he points to the swarm of evils brought in by those who introduced costly sacrifices 3 . To think that the gods delight in this kind of expenditure must have a specially bad influence on the minds of youth, teaching them to neglect conduct ; whereas to think that they have regard above all to the disposition must tend to make them pious and just. The philosopher, in Plato's view, ought not to accom- modate himself to bad customs, but to try to win men to the better ; if he cannot, let him go the right way himself, caring neither for dangers nor abuse from the many. And surely if Syrians and Hebrews and Phoenicians and Egyptians could resist even to the death kings that strove to make them depart 1 Be Abst. ii. 51 : d\\' oicnrep ddisias Kal wXeope^ias yv to eW/ca p.a.vTtla.% dvaipuv tov bpbcpvKov, ovtu kcu to dXoyov £wov cr^drretc fxavTilas fVe/ca adtKOV. 2 De Abut. ii. 56 : Ka.TaXvdrji'ai oe rds dvOpwirodvaias ax^bv rds Trapd iraaiv (pijdi IldXXas 6 dpiffTa rd irepl tG>v tov Widpa crvvayaylov fivcT-qpioJv i(p' ' Adpiavov tov avTOKpaTopos. 3 De Abst. ii. 60: dyuoovo-iv 5£ oi tt\v ■no\vTi\eiav elcrayayovTes els tcls dvaias, owus dp.a TauTy eo-pbv kclkGiv d<n)yayov, beioib'aiiJ.ovlav, Tpvcp-qv, VTrb\r) T 'ii> tov 8eKd£eii> bvvao-dat. to delov />at Ovaiais aKeladai Tr\v dbiKlaf. VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 119 from their national laws in the matter of food, we ought not to transgress the laws of nature and divine precepts for the fear of men. In the third book, Porphyry undertakes to show that animals, in so far as they have perception and memory, have some share in reason, and therefore are not beyond the range of justice. Defining uttered discourse, not according to the doctrine of any particular school but in the perfectly general sense of " a voice significant through the tongue of internal affections in the soul," we shall find that animals capable of uttering sounds have a kind of discourse among themselves. And before utterance, why should we not suppose the thought of the affection to have been there 1 ? Even if we pass over some of the stories about men that are said to have understood the tongues of animals, enough is recorded to show that the voices of birds and beasts, if intently listened to, are not wholly unintelligible. Voiceless animals too, such as fishes, come to understand the voices of men ; which they could not do with- out some mental resemblance. To the truth of Aristotle's assertion that animals learn much both from one another and from men, every trainer can bear witness. Those who will not see all these evidences of their intelligence take the part of calumniating the creatures they mean to treat ruthlessly 2 . Animals are subject not only to the same bodily diseases as men but to the same affections of the soul. Some have even acuter senses. That animals do indeed possess internal reason is shown by the knowledge they display of their own strength and weakness and by the provisions they make for their life. To say that all this belongs to them " by nature " amounts to saying that by nature they are rational 3 . We too arrive at reason because it is our nature; and animals, as has been said, 1 I)e Abst. iii. 3: r: 5^ ov\l «al a irdax (L T <> irporepov Kai wplv elirciv 8 p.i\\ei, SievorjOr] ; !)(' Abst. iii. 6: d\\' 6 fiev evyvu:fiwi> Kal etc toutwv fieraSidwcri avveaeus tois j'oiois, 6 5e dyvwfj.u)v Kal dvicrT6pr)Tos clvtQu <f>4p(Tai ovvepyCov avrov rrj els avrd ■jr\eove^l(f. Kai 7r<£s 7<ip oil/c ^eWee KaKoXoyqauv Kal SiapaXetv a KaraKowTetv u>s \L6ov irporipriTai ; 3 De Abst. iii. 10: 6 8e <pu<rei Xiyuv avrois irpoaehai ravra dyvod A^yto? 6ti <pvaa tarl \oyiKa. 120 THE DIFFUSION [VII learn by being taught, as we do. They have vices of their own, though these are lighter than those of men ; and the virtues of the social animals are undeniable, however difficult their mental processes may be for us to follow. Against the external teleology of Chrysippus, according to which all other animals were created for the use of man, Porphyry cites the argument of Carneades, that where there is a natural end for any being, the attainment of the end must be marked by some profit to that being, and not to some other. If we were to follow the teleological method of the Stoics, we could not well escape the admission that it is we who have been produced for the sake of the most destructive brutes ; for while they are of no use to us, they sometimes make their prey of men. This they do driven by hunger, whereas we in our sports and public games kill in wantonness 1 . Returning to the question about the reason of animals, Porphyry argues, after Plutarch, that to an animal that could not reason at all, its senses would be of no use towards action for ends. Inferiority in reasoning power is not the same as total deprivation of it. We do not say that we are entirely without the faculty of vision because the hawk has sharper sight. If normally animals had not reason, how could they go mad, as some do ? Porphyry next cites from Theophrastus an argument for a relation of kinship not only among all men, but between men and all animals 2 . In the bodies and souls of both, we find the same principles. For our bodies consist not only of the same primary elements but of the same tissues — " skin, flesh, and 1 De Abst. iii. 20. Here follow some pages adapted from Plutarch's De Sollertia Animalium, cc. 2 — 5, beginning: e£ wv 5tj ko.1 rb /j.ei> (povinov ko.1 dr)piu>8e$ r)/j.u>i> Eirepptl'ffdT] nai to vpbs oiktov awades, tov 5' rj/mepov to nXeiaTov a.Trrjp.j3\vvav ol TrpuiTOi touto To\fj.7}oai>Tes. ol 5k Uvdaybpeiot tt)v wpbs to. Bripia TrpaoTrjTa pt,e\eTqv iiroi-qeavTo tov tpiXavdpilwov tcai {piXoiKTip/xovos. In view of modern discussions on teleology and evolution, a passage that occurs later may be found interesting. Having enumerated the devices of animals that live in the water for catching prey and escaping from enemies, one of the spokesmen in the dialogue argues that the struggle is nature's means of promoting animal intelligence. De Sollertia Animalium, 27 (979 a) : kclI tov k6k\ov tovtov ko.1 ttjv wepioSov reus /car' dWr/Xcov 5iu>i;ecri ko.1 tpvyah yi/Mvafffia /ecu p.e\eTi]v r\ (pvffis avTols eva.yiovi.ov ireTrolyKe 8fivbT7)Tos kclI ovvtaews. 2 De Abst. iii. 25. VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 121 the kind of humours natural to animals." Likewise the souls of animals resemble those of men by their desires and impulses, by their reasonings, and above all by their sense-perceptions. The difference, in the case of souls as of bodies, is in degree of fineness. Therefore, in abstaining from the flesh of animals, Porphyry concludes, we are more just in that we avoid harming what is of kindred nature ; and, from thus extending justice, we shall be less prone to injure our fellow-men. We cannot indeed live in need of nothing, like the divinity ; but we can at least make ourselves more like God by reducing our wants. Let us then imitate the " golden race," for which the fruits of the earth sufficed. The fourth book, which is incomplete, accumulates tes- timonies to show that . abstinence from Mesh is not a mere eccentric precept of Pythagoras and Empedocles, but has been practised by primitive and uncorrupted races, by communities of ascetics like the Essenes, and by the Egyptian and other priesthoods, some of whom have abstained from all kinds of animal food, some from particular kinds. Then, after giving an account of the Brahmans and of the Buddhist monks (who are evidently meant by the ^.a/xaraLoi) on the authority of Bardesanes (perhaps the Gnostic), who derived his information from an Indian embassy to the imperial court early in the third century, Porphyry returns to the general ascetic argument for abstinence. One who would philosophise ought not to live like the mass of mankind, but ought rather to observe such rules as are prescribed to priests, who take upon themselves the obligation of a holier kind of life 1 . This is the strain in which the work breaks off, but it will be observed that on the whole the point of view is as much humanitarian as ascetic. Transmigration of human souls into the bodies of animals Porphyry explicitly denied. Here he mentions it only as a topic of ridicule used against Pythagoras. The stories of men who have been transformed into animals, he interprets as a mythical indication that the souls of animals have something in common with our own. The way 1 De Abst. iv. 18. 122 THE DIFFUSION [VII in which the whole subject is discussed reveals a degree of reflectiveness with regard to it in the ancient schools which has scarcely been reached again by civilised Europe till quite modern times. And perhaps, for those who wish to preserve the mean, no more judicious solution will be found than Plutarch came upon incidentally in his Life of Cato the Censor; where he contends that, while justice in the proper sense is applicable only among men, irrational animals also may claim a share of benevolence 1 . 2. Iamblich us. Iamblichus, who was regarded as the next after Porphyry in the Neo-Platonic succession 2 , had been his pupil at Rome. He was a native of Chalcis in Coele- Syria, aud his own later activity as a teacher was in Syria. He died in the reign of Constantine, about 330. Eunapius describes him as socially accessible and genial, and as living on familiar terms with his numerous disciples. Though he is often described as having given to the Neo-Platonic school a decisive impulse in the direction of theurgy, the one well-authenticated anecdote on the subject in his biography does not lend any particular support to this view. A rumour had gone abroad that some- times during his devotions he was raised in the air and underwent a transfiguration. His disciples, fearing that they were being excluded from some secret, took occasion to ask him if it was so. Though not much given to laughter, he laughed upon this inquiry, and said that the story was prettily invented but was not true 3 . Eunapius was told this by his teacher Chrysanthius ; and Chrysanthius had it from Aedesius, who bore a part in the conversation. The biographer certainly 1 Vitae, Cato Major, 5 : Kairoi tt]v xPV crT ° T V Ta T ?7 S diicaio<n'ivr)s irXarvrtpov t6ttov opwfjLev fTnXa.fj.ftai'ovcTa.v vbfiu> /j.(p yap Kal ru> Sikcu'oj 7rpos avdpwwovs fxbvov XP^crdai ire(pvKap.ev, irpbs evepyeoias dt Kal x^-P LTa ^ 2<ttiv ore Kal p.ixP L T ^ v o-Xbywv fyiov uiawtp £k Tnjyqi irXovcrias awoppel rrjs i)p.epbTT]To%. 2 See Julian, Or. vn. 2'22 B, where Plotinus, Porphyry and Iamblichus are mentioned in order as carrying on the tradition of Plato. 3 Eunap. Vitae (Iamblichus) : 6 p.ev dirarrjaas v/xcis ovk i)v &xapis, ravra 5£ oi'x OVTiOS ?x €U VIl] OF NEO-PLATOXISM 123 goes on to relate some marvels on hearsay, but he mentions distinctly that none of the disciples of Iamblichus wrote them down. He records them, as he says himself, with a certain hesitation; but he did not think himself justified in omitting what was told him by trustworthy witnesses. The literary style of Iamblichus, Eunapius allows, has not the beauty and lucidity of Porphyry's. Not that it altogether fails of clearness, nor that it is grammatically incorrect; but it does not draw the reader on. As Plato said of Xenocrates, he had not sacrificed to the Hermaic Graces. An interesting account is given of the way in which he was stirred up to reflection on political topics by Alypius, an acute dialectician of Alexandria. A public disputation having been arranged between them, Alypius put to him a question from which he at first turned away with disdain. The query was : " Whether a rich man is necessarily either unjust or the heir of one who has been unjust 1 ." According to the traditional philosophic view that poverty and wealth, in comparison with the goods of the mind, are alike indifferent, the question seemed frivolous; but further* thought modified the impression, and Iamblichus became an admirer of Alypius and afterwards wrote his life. The composition, Eunapius thought, was not successful; and this he ascribes to the author's want of aptitude for political discussion and of real interest in it. It conveyed a sense of Iamblichus's admiration for Alypius, but did not succeed in giving the reader any clear idea as to what he had said or done. ^ Eunapius himself was not by special training a philosopher, but a rhetorician. He was an adherent of the party attached to the old religion. Commonly, he is described as an indis- criminate panegyrist of all the philosophers of his party ; but, as we see, he was not wanting in candour. While looking back with reverence to Iamblichus as the intellectual chief of the men whose doctrines he followed, he does not in the least understate his defects of style. And on no one does he lavish more praise than on his Athenian teacher in rhetoric, 1 'EtV^ fioi, <pt\6ffocf>e,' Trpds cli'toi* ^0t;, '6 w\ov<nos rj aoiKos r) o.5lkov KXripovo/xos, val r) o\i ; tovtujv yap fxtaov ovdiv.' 124 THE DIFFUSION [VII Prohaeresius, who was a Christian. Iamblichus was one of those who are placed higher by their own age than by later times. His reputation had probably reached its greatest height about the time of Julian, who spoke of him as not inferior in genius to Plato 1 . Still, he remains a considerable philosopher. He modified the doctrine of Plotinus more deeply than Porphyry ; and the changes he made in it were taken up and continued when it came to be systematised by the Athenian school. If he does not write so well as Porphyry or Proclus, he succeeds in conveying his meaning. And, while professedly expounding the tradition of a school, and freely borrowing from his pre- decessors, he always has a distinctive drift of his own. The surviving works of Iamblichus belonged to a larger treatise in which the Pythagorean philosophy was regarded as the original source of the tradition he expounds. The whole treatise was entitled %vvay(oy>} rcov HvOwyopelcov Boyfidrcou. Of the separate works, the first in order is a Life of Pythagoras. The second is mainly ethical in content, and is a general exhortation to the study of philosophy (A070? TrpoTpeirTLKos iirl <pi\oao<pLav). The remaining three are mathematical 2 . The best notion of the individual tone of Iamblichus's thought will be given by an abstract of the second book — the Pro- trepticus. But first a word must be said on the kind of modification he made in the doctrine of Plotinus. From the references in later writers, it is known that he attempted a more systematic analysis of the stages of emanation by resolving them into subordinate triads. As there are traces 1 Or. iv. 146 A. To save their genuineness, the letters of Julian " to Iamblichus the philosopher " are as a rule assumed to have been written to a nephew of Iamblichus, known from the correspondence of Libanius. Zeller (iii. 2, p. 679, n. 2) points to circumstances wbich show that they must have purported to be written to the elder Iamblichus, who died near the time when Julian was born (331). He therefore follows Dodwell (" A Discourse concerning the Time of Pythagoras," cited by Fabricius, Bibliotheca Graeca) in regarding them as spurious. Dodwell gives what seems a decisive reason for rejecting them, namely, that Sopater, who was executed under Constantine, is referred to as alive. - Tbe genuineness of one of these (Ta deo\oyou/j.eva rrjs dpi.0/J-r]TtKT]s) has been contested. The other two bear the titles Ilepl rrjs koivtjs /xadrjuartKiis tiri<TTr)/J-ys and Ilepi tt}s ^iko/xixxov dptdfxT]TiKTJs daayuyfjs. See, on the former, Appendix III. VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 125 of this already in Porphyry, and as Proclus carried the method much farther, the interest of Iamblichus here is that he illustrates the continuous effort of the school towards com- pleteness and consistency. He dwelt with special emphasis on the position that the causal process from higher to lower is logical, and not in time ; and thought it not without danger to suppose a temporal production of the world even as a mere hypothesis. More explicitly than Plotinus or Porphyry, he insisted that no individual soul can remain permanently in the intelligible world any more than in Tartarus. It is the nature of every particular soul to descend periodically and to reascend in accordance with a law of universal necessity. The point where he was most original was, however, his affirmation, as against Plotinus, that when the soul "descends" it descends wholly. The whole soul, and not merely a kind of effluence of it, is in relation with this world so long as it is here at all. There is no " pure soul " that remains exempt from error while the " composite nature " is at fault. If the will sins, how can the soul be without sin 1 ? This correction in what seemed Plotinus's over-exalted view was almost universally allowed, and was definitively taken up by Proclus. It certainly does not bear out the notion that Iamblichus was a thinker who deserted all sobriety in order to turn a philosophic school into an association of theosophic adepts. The Protrepticus is in considerable part made up of excerpts from Plato, Aristotle, and Neo-Pythagorean writings, but it is at the same time consistently directed to the end of showing the importance of theoretical knowledge both for itself and in relation to practice. Contemplation is put first; but, of all the school, Iamblichus dwells most on the bearing of knowledge upon practical utilities. At the beginning he brings out the point that general scientific discipline must be communicated before philosophy, " as the less before the greater mysteries 2 ." We are to regard the constancy of the stellar movements, so 1 Procl. in Tim. 341 D. (R. P. 528.) el de 17 irpoalpeois ap.apT&vei, irws dvafldpTTlTOS 1) ^pvxv ; 2 Protrepticus, a 2, ed. H. Pistelli, p. 10: ws irpb rC)v fMeyaXuv /xvaTrjpiwf to. fUKpa wapaoortov, nal irpb (f)i\o<xo(pias 7rcu5ei'ae. 126 THE DIFFUSION [VII that we may be prepared to adapt ourselves to the necessary course of things. From scientific knowledge we are to rise to wisdom {ao(f)La) as knowledge of first principles, and finally as theology. We need knowledge to make use of "goods," which without the wisdom to use them are not goods, or rather are evils. Things in use (rd ^pri^ara) have reference to the body, and the body is to be attended to for the sake of the soul and its ruling powers. Each of us is the soul, and knowledge of the soul is knowledge of oneself. The physician as such does not know himself. Those who practise arts connected not with the bod}' directly but with things that are for the body, are still more remote from self-knowledge, and their arts are rightly called mechanical. We must exercise the divinest part of the soul by the appropriate motions. Now to what is divine in us the movements of the whole are akin 1 . In the part of the soul that has rational discourse is the intellectual principle, which is the best that belongs to the soul. For the sake of this, and of the thoughts with which it energises, all else exists. While without philosophy practical life cannot be well regulated, the theoretic life is yet not finally for the sake of practice. Rather, mind itself and the divine are the ultimate end, the mark at once of the intellectual eye and of love. It is by the power of living the life of theory that we differ from other animals. Of reasou and prudence there are in them' also some small gleams, but they have no part in theoretic wisdom ; whereas in accuracy of perception and vigour of impulse many of them surpass man. Since, however, we are discoursing with men and not with gods, we must mingle exhortations bearing on civic and practical life Now philosophy alone, in relation to the other kinds of knowledge, can judge and direct. And philosophical knowledge is not only possible but is in one way more attainable than other knowledge, because it is of first principles, which are better known by nature and are more determinate. It is of the highest degree of utility, because it definitely makes its object the insight by which the wise man judges and the reason which proceeds from insight and is 1 Protr. 5, p. 31 : rep 8' ev tj/jup delip ^v-yyeveli ejVi lavqaeis ai tov iravrbs biavor)oei% /ecu irtpupopal. VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 127 expressed in law. And that it is not inaccessible is shown by the eagerness with which students devote themselves to it. Unlike other scientific pursuits, it demands no special ap- pliances or conditions of time and place. After further elaborating this argument, Iamblichus pro- ceeds to infer from " common notions " that insight (<j>povr]cri<;) is most to be chosen for itself, and not for the sake of other things. Suppose a man to have everything else and to suffer from a malady in the part of him that has insight, life would not be for him a gift to choose, for none of its other goods would be of any use to him 1 . Insight, therefore, cannot be a mere means to gaining other things. The way too in which death is shunned proves the soul's love of knowledge ; for it flees what it does not know, the dark and the unapparent, and by nature pursues what is plain to sight and knowable 2 . And although, as they that declare the mysteries say, our souls are bound to our bodies to pay the penalty of some antenatal offence, yet, in so far as human life has the power of sharing in divine and immortal intellect, man appears as a god in relation to the other things that are on earth. Iamblichus next argues on Aristotelian grounds that man has a natural end, and that this end is that which in the genetic order, fulfilling itself as this does continuously, is the latest to be perfected 3 . Now in human development mental insight is that which is last attained. This then is the final good of man. For we must at length stop at something that is good in itself. Otherwise, by viewing each thing in turn as a means to some extraneous end, we commit ourselves to a process to infinity. Yet, though insight is not properly a utility, but a good to be chosen for itself, it also furnishes the greatest utilities to human life, as may be seen from the arts. 1 l'mtr. S, p. 45 : el yap Kai iravra tis e'x 0l > SutpOap/nevos 5e eftj kclI voctGiv Tip (ppovovvTi, oi'x aiperos 6 /3tos - ov5ev yap o<pe\os ov8e twv aXXwv ayatiiov. Protr. 8, p. 46 : Kai to (ptvyeiv 5e rbv Oavarov rovs ttoWovs delicvwi tt\v <pt\op.ddetav rrjs ^i'xn^- (pevyet yap a fxrj ytyvuvKei, to (TKOTwdes Kai to /at] orjXov, (pvati. 5e 8iu3K€L to (pavepbv tcai to yvuicrTdv. Protr. 9, p. 51 : tAos 5£ Kara <pvo~iv tovt6 i&Tiv 6 KaTa ttjv yeveo-w ireQvuev vcTaTov (TrtTeXuudaL trepatvop.ivrjs ttjs yevecrews cn/eexws. 128 THE DIFFUSION [VII Just as the physician needs a knowledge of nature, so the lawgiver and the moralist need theoretical knowledge, though of another kind, if they are to regulate the social life of man. The relation of this knowledge to the whole of life is like that of sight to physical action. In itself it simply judges and shows, but without it we could do nothing or very little. Those who enjoy the pleasure of insight enjoy most the perfection of life in itself; an enjoyment which is to be dis- tinguished from incidental pleasures, received while living but not springing essentially from the proper activity of life. The difficulty of living the theoretic life here, comes from the conditions of human nature ; for now we have to be constantly doing things that have relation to needs. This is most of all the lot of those deemed happiest by the many. If, however, we prepare ourselves by philosophising, we may hope, having returned whence we came, to live in untroubled contemplation of divine truth. Thus Iamblichus is led from the Aristotelian ideal of the contemplative life to the thought of the Phaedo, that philosophising is a kind of dying; death being nothing but the separation of the soul from the body to live a life by itself. Our soul can never perceive truth in its purity till it is released. To prepare it for such knowledge, and to approach that know- ledge as near as possible while we live, we must purify the soul from all that comes to it from the body, — from common desires and fears, care about needs, and the hindrances thrown in the way by external sense. The genuine virtues of courage, temperance and justice proceed from the insight reached by philosophic purification ; the virtues that result from a balancing of pleasures and pains are a mere adumbration of virtue. When a distinction is drawn between the lot in Hades of the uninitiated and of the initiated, we may understand by the truly initiated (' vapOijKocpopoi fiei> 7toX\ol, /3('tK)^ot Se re iravpot') no other than those who have become purified through philosophy. Those who do not arrive in Hades as purified souls, quickly become subject to rebirth in new bodies. There- fore, since the soul is immortal, there is for it no escape from ills and no safety except to acquire as much goodness and insight as possible. Vn] OF NEO-PLATONISM 129 The character of the philosopher is next set forth by an excerpt of the celebrated passage in the Theaetetus. An account of the ideal philosophic education is adapted from the seventh book of the Republic. The Platonic view is enforced that the special function of philosophy is to remove from the soul the accretion that comes to it from birth, and to purify that energy of it to which the power of reason belongs 1 . The argument of the Gorgias is then taken up, that the intemperate soul, which would be ever getting and spending, is like a " leaky vessel," while orderliness in the soul resembles health in the body. After some further development of this topic, Iamblichus returns to the point that philosophy is the most directive of all the arts (rjyefxoviKwraTT] iraaoov rwv re^vwi'). Hence most pains ought to be spent in learning it. An art of dealing with words, indeed, might be learned in a short time, so that the disciple should be no worse than the teacher; but the excellence that comes from practice is only to be acquired by much time and diligence. The envy of men, too, attaches itself to rapid acquisitions of every kind ; praise is more readily accorded to those that have taken long to acquire. Further, every acquire- ment ought to be used for a good end. He that aims at all virtue is best when he is useful to most 2 . Now that which is most useful to mankind is justice. But for any one to know the right distribution of things and to be a worker with the true law of human life, he must have acquired the directive knowledge that can only be given by philosophy. Iamblichus then goes on to argue that even if one were to arise exempt from wounds and disease and pain, and gigantic of stature, and adamantine of body and soul, he could in the long run secure his own preservation only by aiding justice. An evil so monstrous as tyranny arises from nothing but law- lessness. Some wrongly deem that men are not themselves the causes of their being deprived of freedom, but are forcibly deprived of it by the tyrant. To think that a king or tyrant 1 Protr. 10, p. 83 : rb yap irepiaipelv ryv ykvecnv airb t^s ipvxv* Kal (KKaBatpeiv ttju XoyifecrQai 5vva/xtvr]v avrrjs ivepyeiav /xaXtara avrr} irpoarjKet. - Protr. 20, p. 97 : t6v re av apexes dpeydfxevov rrjs <ri'M7rd<rijs GKeirreov elvai, tK rlvos av \6yov rj Zpyov apto-ros efjj ' toiovtos 5' av en? 6 ir\d<TToi.s axpeXi^os wv. W. ^ 130 THE DIFFUSION [VII arises from anything but lawlessness and greed is folly 1 . When law and justice have departed from the multitude, then, since human life cannot go on without them, the care of them has to pass over to one. The one man whom some suppose able by his single power to dissolve justice and the law that exists for the common good of all, is of flesh like the rest and not of adamant. It is not in his power to strip men of them against their will. On the contrary, he survives by restoring them when they have failed. Lawlessness then being the cause of such great evils, and order being so great a good, there is no means of attaining happiness but to make law preside over one's own life. The Protrepticus concludes with an interpretation of thirty- nine Pythagorean " symbols," or short precepts which are taken as cryptic expressions of philosophic truths. In their literal meaning, Iamblichus says, they would be nonsensical; but, according to the "reserve" (ixefMvOia) inculcated by Pythagoras on his disciples, not all of them were intended to be understood easily by those who run (rots a7r\w<? cikovovctiv e'£ eirihpofxrj^ re evTvyxdvovatv). Iamblichus proposes to give the solutions of them all, without making an exception of those that fell under the Pythagorean reserve. The interpretations contain many points of interest. If the precepts were ever literal " taboos," not a trace of this character is retained. The last given, which was generally understood to command abstinence from animal food, is interpreted simply as inculcating justice with fit regard for what is of kindred nature and sympathetic treatment of the life that is like our own 2 . The absence of any reference to the literal meaning seems to indicate that Iamblichus did not follow Porphyry on this point. In interpreting the "symbols" relating to theology, if the whole of what he says is fairly considered, he seems to give them a turn against credulity ; his last word being that that which is 1 Protr. 20, p. 103: oans yap riyeiTcu /3a<riA<?a rj rOpavvov e£ d\\ov tlv6s ylyveadat ?? e'£ dvofxias re /cat wXeovc i^cas, P-upbs effriv. 2 Protr. 21, p. 125 : to 5e ' ip.\pi>xuv avtx ov ' e7r ' SiKaioavvrjv Trporpewet ko.1 wacrav tt]v tov avyyevovs Tip.r}v ko.1 t\\v ttjs 6/iot'as fw^s AirodoxV" *«' ^pds eYe/>a roiaOra TrXeiova. VII ] OF NEO-PLATONISM 131 to be believed is that which is demonstrable. One of them runs, " Mistrust nothing marvellous about the gods, nor about the divine opinions." After pointing out generally the weakness of man's faculties, which should prevent him from judging rashly as to what is possible to the gods. Iamblichus goes on to explain more particularly that by "the divine opinions" (to. 6 da SojfiaTa) are meant those of the Pythagorean philosophy, and that they are proved by cogent demonstration to be necessarily true 1 . The precept therefore means : Acquire mathematical knowledge, so that you may understand the nature of demonstrative evidence, and then there will be no room for mistrust. That is also what is meant in reference to the gods 2 . The truth about the whole, Iamblichus says in another place, is concealed and hard to get hold of, but is to be sought and tracked out by man through philosophy, which, receiving some small sparks from nature, kindles them into a flame and makes them more active by the sciences that proceed from herself 3 . Many of the sayings are interpreted as com- mending the method of philosophising from intelligible principles setting forth the nature of the stable and incorporeal reality. The " Italic " philosophy — which had long since come to be regarded as a doctrine of incorporeal being — is to be preferred before the Ionic 4 . The precept, not to carve the image of a god on a ring (' 6eov tvttov ixr) iTriy\v<j)6 8aKTv\l(p ') is interpreted to mean, " Think of the gods as incorporeal 5 ." The model of 1 Protr. 21, pp. 110—111. 2 This extended interpretation, with its preface about the inadequacy of human judgments on divine things, comes out of its proper place. The " symbol," which is the twenty-fifth, is also explained in due order (p. 121), and there the preface is omitted and the whole runs thus: To 8e ' irepl deQv p.i]8ev 6a.vfjLa.aTov airioTti fiijde irepl deluv 8oyfj.dTwi> ' irpoTpewei ixerUvai Kal KTaadai eKelva to. /j.a.dr)fxaTa, 6V a ovk dirio-Trj<reis ovk^ti irepl OeQv Kal irepl Oeiwv doy/x&Tiov f'^wi' Ta fxadri/jiaTa. /cat rets eino-Tr)fj.oviKas dirodei^ets. 3 Protr. 21, p. 116 : eirel yap awbKpv<pos (pt'crei 7/ irepl rod iravTos dXrjOeia, Kal SvcrdopaTOS iKavws' fyT-qrea 5e o'/uws avOpuiirtj) Kal i^xvevria fj.aXi.o-Ta 81a <piXucro<pias. 5lo. yap aXXov tivos eiriTijdevfj.aTos ovtus ddufarov ' avrrj 8e fxiKpa Tiua evava/xaTa irapd Tift (puffeuis Xa/xiSduovaa Kal toaavel ecpoOiagofievri fwirvpei re aura Kal p.tyt6i<vei Kal evepyeaTepa 5td ra>i> wap' at)r?)s fxadrju.dTUi' direpydftTai. 4 Prolr. 21, p. 125 : irporifia tt)v 'IraXiKifv <piXoo-o<piav ttiv rd do-dinara Kad' aura dewpovaav r^s 'luviKrjs ttjs rd crcu^ara irpo-qyovpjvwi eiTLo-Koirov/xiuijs. " Protr. 21, p. 120. 9—2 132 THE DIFFUSION [VII method for the discovery of truth about divine things is, as has been said, that of mathematics. Thus the precept ' ev 6Sg5 fir) a-^i^e ' is turned against the method of search by a series of dichotomies, and in favour of a process which leads directly to truth without ambiguity because each step of the way is demonstratively certain as soon as it is taken 1 . The special bearing of the Pythagorean philosophy, with its appeal to equality and proportion, on the virtue of justice (tt}v reXeioraTrjv aperrjit) is dwelt on 2 . Then, in nearing the end, Tamblichus points out as one incitement to philosophise, that of all kinds of knowledge philosophy alone has no touch of envy or of joy in others' ill, since it shows that men are all akin and of like affections and subject in common to unforeseen changes of fortune. Whence it promotes human sympathy and mutual love 3 . 3. The School of Iamblichus. After the death of Iamblichus, his school dispersed itself over the whole Roman Empire 4 . His most brilliant disciple was Sopater, a man of ambitious temperament, who, as Eunapius expresses it, thought to change the purpose of Constantine by reason. He did in fact succeed in gaining a high position at Court ; but in the struggle of intrigue his enemies at last got the better of him, and he was condemned by the Christian emperor to be executed, apparently on a charge of magic. According to Eunapius, he was accused of binding the winds so as to prevent the arrival of the ships on which Constantinople depended for its supply of corn 5 . Both now and for some time later, philosophers and others who were not even nominal adherents of Christianity could be employed by Christian rulers. Eustathius, another of Iamblichus's disciples, was sent by Constantius on an embassy 1 Protr. 21, pp. 118—119. 2 Protr. 21, p. 114. 3 Protr. 21, p. 123. 4 Eunap. Vitae (Iamblichus) : aXXot fiii> yap dWaxov tu>v dp-qfxevwv 6/j.i\rjTu>i> 5i€Kpld7jcrav eh awacrav ttjv ~P(i)(ml'Ck))v cirixpaTeiav. 3 Eunap. Vitae (Aedesius). VIl] OF NEO-PLATONISM 133 to Persia. Themistius, who was an Aristotelian, held offices at a later period. The Christians themselves, long after the death of Julian, were still for the most part obliged to resort to the philosophical schools for their scientific culture 1 . The contest in the world, however, was now effectively decided, and the cause represented by the philosophers was plainly seen to be the losing one. Of its fortunes, and of the personalities of its adherents, we get a faithful picture from Eunapius, whose life of Aedesius is especially interesting for the passages showing the feelings with which the triumph of the Church was regarded. Aedesius was the successor of Iamblichus at Pergamum in Mysia. The biographer, it may be noted, dis- tinctly tells us that he had no reputation for theurgy. The marvels he connects with his name relate to the clairvoyance of Sosipatra, the wife of Eustathius. Aedesius educated the sons of Eustathius and Sosipatra; hence the connexion. One of them, Antoninus, took up his abode at the Canopic mouth of the Nile, whither came the youth eager for philosophical knowledge. To him again, as to Aedesius, no theurgical accomplishments are ascribed ; a possible reason in both cases, Eunapius suggests, being concealment on account of the hostility of the new rulers of the world. Those who put before him logical problems were immediately satisfied ; those who threw out anything about " diviner " inquiries found him irresponsive as a statue. He probably did not himself regard it as supernatural prescience when he uttered the prophecy, afterwards held for an oracle, that soon " a fabulous and formless darkness shall tyrannise' over the fairest things on earth " (kcil tl /u,uOo)Se<; icai aetSe? (tkotos rupavv?]aec ra iirl yij'i KaXkicna) 1 . The accession of Julian to the empire created 1 ZeUer, ill. 2, p. 739. - Cf. Gibbon on the " Final Destruction of Paganism," where the prediction is quoted iu a note. (Decline and Fall of tin- Roman Empire, ed. J. B. Bury, vol. iii. p. 208.) In the chapter referred to, however, Gibbon antedated the disappearance of pagan rites ; as may be seen from the lives of philosophers later than Eunapius's period. With the impression made on the biographer, it is interesting to compare his contemporary St Jerome's description, cited by Grote at the end of the preface to his Plato, of the desertion of the philosophic schools. Who now, asks the Christian Father, reads Plato or Aristotle? "llus- ticauos vero et piscatores nostras totus orbis loquitur, universus mundus sonat." 134 THE DIFFUSION [VII no illusion in the most clear-sighted of the philosophers. Chrysanthius, one of his instructors in the Neo-Platonic philosophy, was pressingly invited by him to come and join him in the restoration of Hellenism. Deterred, the biographer says, by unfavourable omens, he declined. The Emperor never- theless conferred on him, in association with his wife Melite, the high-priesthood of Lydia 1 . This he accepted : but, fore- warned of the failure of Julian's attempt to revive the ancient worship, he altered as little as possible during his tenure of office ; so that there was hardly any disturbance there when the state of things was again reversed ; whereas elsewhere the upheavals and depressions were violent. This was at the time looked upon as an example of his unerring foresight, derived from the knowledge of divine things communicated by his Pythagorean masters 2 . It was added, that he knew how to make use of his gift of prevision ; this, no doubt, in contrast with Maximus 3 . Maximus and Chrysanthius were fellow-pupils of Aedesius, and were united in their devotion to theurgy. When Julian was first attracted to the philosophic teachers of his time, the aged Aedesius had commended him to his disciples Eusebius and Chrysanthius, who were present, and Priscus and Maximus, who were then absent from Pergamum. Eusebius, whose special interest was in logical studies, spoke with disparage- ment of theurgy, but Julian's curiosity was excited by what he heard. To satisfy it, he visited Maximus at Ephesus, at whose suggestion he sent for Chrysanthius also. Under Maximus and Chrysanthius he continued his philosophical studies. It may have been his interest in theurgy that led him to seek initia- tion, during his visit to Greece, in the Eleusinian mysteries ; though his argument afterwards for being initiated was merely compliance with ancient usage ; he treats it as a matter of 1 Eunap. Vitae (Maximus). Melite was a kinswoman of Eunapius, and Chrysanthius became his teacher in philosophy. 2 Eunap. Vitae (Chrysanthius): bpdv yovv dv tis avrbv ecp-qae pdWov to. eab/xeva t) TrpoXtyeiv t& fiiWovra, ourws diravra birjdpei Kai avveXdpi^avev, waavei Trapwp re Kai avviov tois deoTs. Hi. : €$av/j.d<rdr] yovv em tovtois, ws ov fxbvov deivbs rd /JLeWovra wpovoetv, dWd Kai Toh yvwaddai xp?jcra<T0<xi. VII] OF NEO-PLATONISM 135 course that such ceremonies can make no difference to the soul's lot 1 . When he had become Emperor, he invited Maximus with Chrysanthius, and afterwards Priscus, to Court. Unlike Chrysanthius, Maximus, when he found the omens unfavourable, persisted till he got favourable ones. In power, as Eunapius frankly acknowledges, he displayed a want of moderation which led to his being treated afterwards with great severity. He was put to death under Valens, as the penalty of having been consulted regarding divinations about the Emperor's successor. Priscus, we learn' 2 , had been from his youth up a person of rather ostentatious gravity and reserve. He was, however, no pretender, but maintained the philosophic character consistently during the reign of Julian ; nor was he afterwards accused of any abuse of power. He died at the time when the Goths were ravaging Greece (396—8). Preserving always his grave demeanour, says Eunapius, and laughing at the weakness of mankind, he perished along with the sanctuaries of Hellas, having lived to be over ninety, while many cast away their lives through grief or were killed by the barbarians. During the events that followed Julian's reign (361-363), the bio- grapher was himself a youth 3 . He was born probably in 346 or 347, and died later than 414. Of the literary activity of the school during the period from the death of Iamblichus to the end of the fourth ceutury, there is not much to say. Many of the philosophers seem to have confined themselves to oral exposition. Chrysanthius wrote much, but none of his works have come down to us. We have reports of the opinions of Theodore of Asine 4 , an immediate disciple buth of Porphyry and of Iamblichus. His writing seems to have taken the form chiefly of commentaries. Proclus had a high opinion of him and frequently cites him. We learn that with Plotinus he maintained the passionlessness 1 Or. vii. 239 BC : tovtois pt.lv, oh djjtws tou p.vwdrivaL /^e/3twrat, aai fj.rj pwqdeloiv o't deoi rds ap.oi^as aKepaious <pv\&TTov(Ti, tois 5e fj.oxQypoh ovolv eari w\iov Kav «<xa> twv Upwv eio~(ppri<Two~i 7rept/36\u>e. - Eunap. Vitae (Priscus). 8 Eunap. Vitae (Maximus) : kcu 6 raura ypa,<pwv eiraiOeveTo kcit' eVce/eons tovs Xpwovs wait wv ko.1 els ifprjfiovs dpri reXaJc. * Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 721 ft'. 136 THE DIFFUSION OF NEO-PLATONISM [VII and uninterrupted activity of the higher part of the soul ; and that he defended Plato's position on the equality of the sexes. Dexippus, another disciple of Iamblichus, wrote, in the form of a dialogue with a pupil, a work on the Aristotelian Categories which survives 1 . The book Be Myst&riis, long attributed to Iamblichus himself, is now considered only as illustrating the general direction of his school 2 . Its most distinctive feature is insistence on the necessity and value of ceremonial religion for the mass of mankind, and indeed for all but an inappreciable minority. It is admittedly well-written, as is also the little book of Sallust Be Biis et Mundo 9 . This Sallust, according to Zeller 4 , was pretty certainly the friend of Julian known from the Emperor's Orations and from references in the historians ; and the book may have been put forth with a popular aim as a defence of the old religious system now restored and to be justified in the light of philosophy. A noteworthy point in it is the apology for animal sacrifices. As in the Be Mysteriis, the higher place of philosophy is saved by the position that the incorporeal gods are in no way affected by prayer or sacrifice or by any kind of ceremony, and are moved by no passions. The forms of traditional religion, it is nevertheless maintained, are subjectively useful to men, and its modes of speech admit of a rational interpretation. The book ends by affirming the position of the Republic, that virtue would be sufficient for happiness even if there were no rewards reserved for it in another life. J Zeller, iii. 2, p. 737, n. 1. 2 An edition of it was published at Oxford by Gale in 1678, with Latin version and notes and a reconstruction of Porphyry's letter to Anebo, to which it is a reply. The later edition by Parthey (Berlin, 1857) is based on Gale's. English readers will find an exact account of the sceptical queries of Porphyry, and of the solutions given by the author, in Maurice's Moral and Metaphysical Philosophy, vol. i. 3 Edited by Orelli, with Latin version and notes, in 1821. 4 iii. 2, p. 734. CHAPTER VIII. THE POLEMIC AGAINST CHRISTIANITY. In taking up the defence of the old against the new religious institutions of the Roman Empire, the Neo-Platonists were simply continuing the attitude of earlier philosophical culture. From the time when the new religious phenomenon was first consciously recognised — that is to say, from about the beginning of the second century — it had aroused an instinctive antagonism among men who were as far from believing the pagan myths as the Christians themselves. The outlines of the apology for paganism, so far as it can be recovered, remain from first to last without essential modification. Celsus, writing in the second century, conceives the problem to be that of reconciling philosophical theism with diversities of national worship. It may be solved, in his view, by supposing the supreme Deity to have allotted different regions to subordinate divine powers, who may either be called gods, as by the Greeks, or angels, as by the Jews. Then, to show that the Christians have no philosophical advantage, he points to the declarations of Greek thinkers that there is one supreme God, and that the Deity has no visible form. On the other side, he insists on the resemblances between Hebrew and Greek legends. Greek mythology, he remarks, has in common with Christianity its stories of incarnations. In other religions also resurrections are spoken of. Such are those of Zamolxis in Scythia and of Rhampsinitus among the Egyptians. Among the Greeks too there are cases in which mortal men have been represented as raised to divinity. Noah's flood may have been borrowed from 138 THE POLEMIC [VIII Deucalion's, and the idea of Satan from the Greek Titanomachies. The more intelligent Jews and Christians are ashamed of much in Biblical history, and try to explain it allegorically. What is supposed to be distinctive of Christian ethics has been put better, because more temperately, by the Greek philosophers. Plato holds much the same view about the difficulty there is for a rich man to enter into the kingdom of heaven. He declares likewise that evil is never to be returned for evil. The reproach of idolatry against the non-Judaic religions is a calumny. Statues are not regarded as deities, but only as aids to devotion. To the highest God, as all agree, only the worship of the mind ought to be offered. But why should not hymns be addressed to beneficent visible powers like the sun, or to mental attributes such as Wisdom, represented by Athena ? Piety is more complete when it has regard to all the varied manifestations of divinity in the world 1 . On their side, the Christians were quite willing to appeal to philosophers and poets who had had ideas of a purer religion than that of the multitude. All such ideas, they maintained, were borrowed from the Hebrew Scriptures. Philo had pre- viously taken that view ; and, as we saw, among men who attached themselves to the Hellenic tradition, Numenius was ready to allow something of the same kind. Theodoret, early in the fifth century, is sarcastic upon the ignorance displayed by the pagans of his time, who are not aware of the fact, to be learned from their own sages, that the Greeks owed most of their knowledge of the sciences and arts to the " barbarians 2 .'' As against unmodified Judaism, the Christians could find support for some of their own positions in the appeal to religious reformers like Apollonius of Tyana ; who, condemning blood-offerings as he did on more radical grounds than them- selves, was yet put forward by the apologists of paganism as a half-divine personage. So far did this go that Hierocles, the 1 See Keim's reconstruction of the arguments of Celsus from Origen's reply (Celsus 1 Wahres Wort, 1873). 2 See p. 89 of Neumann's prolegomena to his reconstruction of Julian's work against the Christians, to be spoken of later. In taking for granted the essential independence of Hellenic culture, it would seem that Greek popular opinion was sounder than much learned opinion. VIIl] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 139 Proconsul of Bithynia who wrote against the Christians in the time of Diocletian, gave his ecclesiastical antagonist Eusebius occasion to treat the part of his book that dealt with Apollonius as the only part worth replying to. And Porphyry, in whom the Christians saw their most dangerous adversary, himself made a distinct claim to what we should now call religious as distinguished from philosophical liberty in the matter of food and of sacrificing. Nor was any objection usually raised by the authorities to reforming sects that aimed at personal holiness. The Roman Government even looked upon it as part of its own function to repress savage rites, such as human sacrifices. Whence then sprang the repugnance almost uniformly to be observed in the statesmen, philosophers and men of letters who were brought into contact with the new religion ? For they were quite prepared to appreciate a monotheistic worship, and to welcome anything that afforded a real prospect of moral reform. We might be tempted to find the cause in the want of culture among ordinary Christians. Julian, for example, who de- tested the "uneducated Cynics" of his time, can think of nothing worse to say of them than that they resemble the Christian monks (cnroTaKTiGTaiy. The only difference is that the Cynics do not make a business of gathering alms ; and perhaps this is only because they can find no plausible pretext. It is those, he adds, who have shown no capacity for rhetorical or philosophical culture that rush straight to the profession of Cynicism 2 . Yet, he goes on to admit, there is really, as the Cynics claimed on their own behalf, a " shorter path " to philosophic virtue than the normal one of intellectual discipline. The shorter path is, however, the more difficult ; requiring greater and not less vigour of mind and firmness of will. Of those who took it were the elder Cynics like Diogenes. The true as distinguished from the false Cynic remained, in fact, for Julian as for Epic- tetus, a hero among philosophers. This was part of the Stoical 1 Or. vn. 224 a— c. 2 Or. VII. 225 is: tCiv pyropinuiv oi 5vcr/j.a6ecrTa.T0i nal ovo' vir' avrov rod BacriXtus 'Ep/xov TT)V yXCoTTav eKKadapdr/vai. Ovvd/xevot, <ppevudi}i>ai 5£ oi)5e 7rpos avTrjs ttjs 'Adr)i>as avv tu 'Epfi.-g,...6ppiu)cnv £irl tov Kwicrfidf. 140 THE POLEMIC [VIII tradition continued into Neo-Platonism. And, as we know, it was a commonplace with philosophic preachers to make light of mental accomplishments as compared with moral strength. Besides, the Christians had among them men of rhetorical training who were not without knowledge of philosophy. The antagonism therefore cannot be accounted for altogether on this line. The truth is that the Graeco-Roman world had a perception, vague at first but gradually becoming clearer, of what was to be meant by Christian theocracy. When Tacitus spoke of the " exitiabilis superstitio," he had doubtless come face to face in Asia with nascent Catholicism. In the fourth century, the new types of the fanatical monk and the domineering ecclesiastic were definitely in the world, and we may see by the expressions of Eunapius the intense antipathy they aroused 1 . Already in the second century, Celsus, while he treated the Gnostic sects, with their claims to a higher "knowledge," as having a perfect right to the Christian name, was evidently much more struck by the idea of a common creed which was to be humbly accepted. This was the distinctive idea of that which he recognises as the " great Church " among the Christians. It is remarkable that, in dealing with the claims of Christianity generally, and not with the strange tenets of some speculative sects, the defender of the established order in the Roman State treats philosophy as the true wisdom by which everything is to be tested, and reproaches the revolutionary innovators on the ground that they say to their dupes, "Do not examine." Celsus was probably a Roman official ; and he may have seen already some of the political aims of the new society. For of course the word " catholic " as applied to the Church was not intended to remain without a very tangible meaning. The Christian apologists of the second century are already looking forward to spiritual control over the public force of the Empire 2 . 1 Eunap. Vitae (Aedesius) : elra eneio-rjyov roh iepo7s tottois tovs KaXov/j.ei'ovs iu.ova.xovs, avOpuirovs /u.ev Kara to eldos, 6 5£ /St'os auTois <jv<J)Sr)S, ...rvpavvLKrjV yap €lx ev e^ovo-iav Tore ttcls avdpwiros /xiXaivau <popGiv iaOrJTa /cat drjfxoaig, j3ov\6/J.evos ao-x'THJ-ovdv. - See Renan, Marc-Aurele. The alternative imposed by the Church on the Empire was, Renan says, to persecute or to become a theocracy. VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 141 A verse of the New Testament by which the claim was held to be made is pointed to by Julian in arguing that the Christians are not legitimate successors of the Israelites. Christ, according to the view of the Church, was the prophet that Moses foretold, of whom it was said, " that every soul, which will not hear that prophet, shall be destroyed from among the people " (Acts iii. 28). The Church possessed the teachings of Christ, and was a living body with the right to declare them authoritatively. The true religion was not now, as under an earlier dispensation, for one chosen race, but for the whole world. Hence the whole world was bound to hear and to obey it. The reply of Julian was that the application of the prediction supposed to have been made was false. Moses never had the least idea that his legislation was to be abrogated, but intended it for all time. The prophet he meant was simply a prophet that should renew his own teaching of the law. The law was for the Jews only, and the Christians had no claim to represent them. The Jewish religion had its proper place as one national religion among others. It was open even to those who were not born under it to adopt it as their own if they chose ; but they should have submitted to all its obligations. The care of the Jews about religious observances, and their readiness to face perse- cution on behalf of them, are contrasted by the Emperor in one place with the laxity and indifference of the Greeks. They are in part pious, he says, worshipping as they do the God who rules the visible world, whom we also serve under other names. In this only are they in error, that they arrogate to themselves alone the worship of the one true God, and think that to us, " the nations," have been assigned none but gods whom they themselves do not deign to regard at all 1 . Julian, we see, had no hostility to Hebrew religion as such. On the contrary, he resembles Porphyry in showing special friendliness to it in so far as its monotheism may be taken to coincide with that of philosophy. The problem presented to the Empire by Judaism, so difficult at an earlier period, had now become manageable through the ending of all political 1 Ep. 63 (ed. Heitlein). aXafovdq, pa.pj3a.piKr), adds Julian, 71756s ravrrivi rr\v aTrovoiav eirapdevres. 142 THE POLEMIC [VIII aspirations on the part of the Jewish community. The question as to the respective merits of Hebrew and Greek religion, if no new question had arisen, would soon have been reduced to a topic of the schools. The system, at once philosophical and political, of the classical world in its dealings with religion, was not of course "religious liberty" in its modern sense. In a congeries of local worships, mostly without definite creeds, the question of toleration for dissentients had scarcely arisen. The position reached by the representatives of ancient thought, and allowed in practice, was that the national religions might all be preserved, not only as useful, but as adumbrations of divine truth. To express that truth adequately is the business of philosophy and not of popular religion. Philosophy is to be perfectly free. This is laid down explicitly by Julian 1 . Thus, according to the system, philosophy is cosmopolitan and is an unfettered inquiry into truth. Religion is local and is bound to the performance of customary rites. Those who are in quest of a deeper knowledge will not think of changing their ancestral religion, but will turn to some philosophical teacher. At the same time, the religions are to be moralised 2 . Priests are to be men of exemplary life, and are to be treated with high respect. The harmony of the whole system had of course been broken through by Christianity, which, after the period of attempted repression by force, had now been for more than a generation the religion of the Empire. Julian's solution of the problem, renewed by his reversal of the policy of his uncle, was to grant a formal toleration to all 3 . Both sides are forbidden to use 1 Or. v. 170 bc. For those of ordinary capacity (rots tfubrais) the utility of divine myths is sufficiently conveyed through symbols without rational under- standing. For those of exceptional intelligence (rots irepLTToh) there can be no utility without investigation into truth of reason, continued to the end, oik aldol Kal irlcrreL ixaXKov dWorpias do^ijs tj rrj <x<peT{pa Kara vovv evepyelg.. 2 See Ep. 49. The progress of Hellenism is not sufficient without moral reform. The example set by the Christians of philanthropy to strangers, and by the Jews of supporting their own poor, ought to be followed by the Greeks. Anciently, continues Julian, this belonged to the Hellenic tradition, as is shown by the words of Eumaeus in the Odyssey (xiv. 56). 3 The earliest edicts of Constantine had simply proclaimed a toleration of Christianity; but these, it was well understood, were a mere preliminary to its VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 143 violence, which is entirely out of place where opinions are concerned 1 . Nevertheless, for dignities, "the pious" — that is to say, the adherents of the old religions — are to be preferred 2 . Christians are not allowed to be public teachers of Grecian letters ; the reason assigned being that the Greek poets, historians and orators treat the gods with honour, whereas the Christians speak dishonourably of them. It is unworthy of an educated or of a good man to teach one thing and to think another. Let them either change their views about the theology of the Greeks or confine themselves to the exposi- tion of their own 3 . By this policy there is no reason to think that the Emperor was putting back a process by which captive Greece might again have led the conqueror captive. The Church absolutely needed the elements of culture if it was to rule the world; and it could find them only in the classical tradition. It was now in more or less conscious possession of its own system, which was precisely the antithesis of the system which Julian desired to restore. A religion had been revealed which claimed to be true for all. Philosophy, so far as it was serviceable, could be treated as a preparation for it or as an instrument in defining its doctrines, but could have no independent standing-ground. Letters, in the hands of ecclesiastics, could furnish the gram- matical and rhetorical training without which the reign of a "spiritual power" would have been impossible. The new system, however, was as yet far from being fully at work. Christian pupils, we must remember, continued to frequent the pagan schools much later. Thus there was evidently no insuperable prejudice by which they would have been univer- sally excluded from a liberal education not subjugated to ecclesiastical authority. If then by any possibility the advance acceptance as the State religion. Julian stripped the Church of the privileges, over and above toleration, which it had acquired in the meantime. 1 Ep. 52, 438 h : \6ycf) 5Z ireidecrtlat XPV Ka ' Sid&fftceirOai tovs avdpuirovs, ov ir\riycus ovde vfipeaiv ovoi aiKta/Atp rod crw/uaros. avdis 5t Kal ttoWcLkls napaivQ tols em T7je a\r]07J Ofocrtfieiav opp-ufievois pL-qdev aBinew r&v Ya\i\a.luv to. ir\7}t)-q, p.t]8e iiriTideadai p.r}be vfipifciv (is avrovs. - Ep. 7, 376 c : wpoTip.affda.L fxivTOi tovs 6eoo~fj3eis Kal wavv (f>ijfJ.i 8eiv. 3 Ep. 42. 144 THE POLEMIC [VIII of the theocratic idea could have been checked, it is clear that the Emperor took exactly the right measures. The classical writers were to be seen, so far as public authority could secure it, under the light of the tradition to which they themselves belonged. Pupils were not to be systematically taught in the schools of the Empire that the pagan gods were " evil demons," and that the heroes and sages of antiquity were among the damned. And, hopeless as the defeated party henceforth was of a change of fortune, Julian's memory furnished a rallying- point for those who now devoted themselves to the preservation of the older culture interpreted by itself. Marinus, in writing the biography of Proclus, dates his death "in the 124th year from the reign of Julian." Thus the actual effect of his resistance to that system of ecclesiastical rule which afterwards, to those who again knew the civic type of life, appeared as a " Kingdom of Darkness," may have been to prolong the evening twilight. All who have studied the career of Julian recognise that his great aim was to preserve "Hellenism," by which he meant Hellenic civilisation. Of this the ancient religion was for him the symbol. The myths about the gods are not to be taken literally. The marriage of Hyperion and Thea, for example, is a poetic fable 1 . What the poets say, along with the divine element in it, has also much that is human 2 . Pure truth, unmixed with fable, is to be found in the philosophers, and especially in Plato 3 . On the Jewish religion, the Emperor's position sometimes appears ambiguous. He easily finds, in the 1 Or. iv. 136 c : pvt} 5e avvdvaa/nbv pajS^ ydfiovs vTroXa/j.^dvio/mv, amaTOL ko.1 wapddo^a rrjs irotTjTiKTJs /xoijcrrji idipfiara. 2 lb. 137 C : dXXa t<x p.ei> tu>v ttol^twv xaipetv edawp.ei' ■ £%ei yap nera tov Oeiov TT0\V KCLI TO dvdpdlWlVOV . 3 Julian, however, like the Neo-Platouists generally, is unwilling to allow that Plato could ever have intended to treat the poetic legends with disrespect. In Or. vn. 237 bc, he cites as an example of ev\d(3eia irepl rd tGiv deuv 6v6p.ara, the well-known passage in the Timaeus, 40 d, about the gods that have left descendants among us, whom we cannot refuse to believe when they tell us of their own ancestors. This, he says, might have been ironical (as evidently many took it to be) if put in the mouth of Socrates ; but Timaeus, to whom it is actually assigned, had no reputation for irony. VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 145 Old Testament, passages from which to argue that the God of Israel is simply a tribal god like those of the nations. His serious opinion, however, seems to have been that the Hebrew prophets had arrived at an expression, less pure indeed than that of the Greek philosophers, but quite real, of the unity of divine government 1 . In one passage — than which no better could be found to illustrate the antithesis between " Hebraism " and " Hellenism " — he compares them to men seeing a great light as through a mist, and unable to describe what they see except by imagery drawn from the destructive force of fire 2 . While himself regarding the divinity as invisible and incorporeal, he treats as prejudice their denunciations of the making of statues. The kind of truth he would recognise in popular polytheism he finds not altogether inconsistent with the Hebrew Scriptures, which speak of the angels of nations. National deities, whether to be called angels or gods, are interpreted as a kind of genius of each race. The various natural aptitudes of peoples suppose a variety in the divine cause, and this can be expressed as a distribution made by the supreme God to subordinate powers 3 . That is the position taken up by Julian in his book against the Christians — which is at the same time a defence of Hellenism. From the fragments contained in Cyril's reply — of which perhaps half survives — it has been beautifully reconstructed by C. J. Neu- mann 4 . A summary of the general argument will serve better than anything else to make clear the spiritual difference that separated from their Christian contemporaries the men who had received their bent in the philosophic schools. Evidently neither Julian's work nor any other was felt to be so peculiarly damaging as Porphyry's. By a decree of the 1 Cf. E P . 25. 2 Fragmentum Epistolae, 296 a: olov 0cDs ,u^ya di 6/u.Lx^ys oi dvdpuvoi fiXeirovTes ov KadapQs ovSe dXiKpivus, airrd 5e (Kecvo veuoniKdrfs ovxl <£ws xadapdv, dXXa vvp, /cat twv irepl avro irdvTwv 6vm adearoi /3ou><ri /xtya ' QpiTTere, <f>oj3ua8e, wvp, #\6£ , dd.va.Tos, /xaxaipa, pofj.cf>aia, ttoWoU ovd/j-aai pdav 4^rjyov/j.evoi tt)v fiXairTLKTjv rod irvpbs 8uvafj.iv. 3 This idea, which we meet with also in Celsus, appears to have been suggested by a passage in the Critias, where such a distribution is described. 4 Iuliami Imperatorw Librorum contra Christiana* quae supersunt (1880). w. 10 14G THE POLEMIC [VIII Council of Ephesus (431) and by a law of Theodosius II. (448), Porphyry's books, though not those of Celsus, Hierocles or Julian, were sentenced to be burned. In the changed form of the law in Justinian's code, the books written by any one else to the same purpose (Kara rrjs evcrefiov? twv X^picrriavoju 6prj<TKeia<i) are brought under the decree, but not by name 1 . The difference between Julian's line of attack and Porphyry's, so far as it can be made out, is that Julian, while much that he too says has an interest from its bearing on questions of Biblical criticism, pays no special attention to the analysis of documents. He takes for granted the traditional ascriptions of the Canonical books, and uniformly quotes the Septuagint. Porphyry is said to have known the Hebrew original. We have already met with his view on the Book of Daniel ; and so characteristic was his inquiry into questions of authorship and chronology, that Neumann is inclined to refer to him an assertion of the late and non-Mosaic origin of the Pentateuch, quoted by Macarius Magnes about the end of the fourth century from an unknown philosopher 2 . What line was taken either by Julian or by Porphyry on the primitive teaching of Christianity itself, hardly anything remains to show. Of Porphyry, as was said, all the express refutations have disappeared ; and of the later books of Cyril's reply to Julian there are left only a few fragments. We learn from one of these 3 that the Catholic saint rejected as spurious the words of Christ in Luke xxiii. 34. "The Apostate" had apparently quoted them against anticipations of the mediaeval treatment of the Jews. On the cult of martyrs, the Bishop of Alexandria's reply is not without point, as Julian would have been the first to allow 4 . The Greeks themselves, he says 5 , go in procession to the tombs and celebrate the praises of those who fought for Greece ; yet they do not worship them as gods. No more do we offer to our martyrs the worship due 1 Neumann, Prolegomena, pp. 8 — 9. 2 Neumann, Prolegomena, p. 20 : MwiWws ovb*kv dwoaui^erai. ffvyypd/j.fj.aTa yap wavTa crvve/Aweirprjcrdcu tQ vau> Xeyerai. oca 5 iw dvofMtri Mwwfws eypd<f>T) fj.£Ta ravra, /xerd xtXta /cat eKarov /cat oydorjKOVTa irt) ttjs Muvciws reXevrrjs vwb "EcrSpa /cat tuiv dfi<p' avrbv cvveypd<pn- 3 Neumann, pp. 69, 130 — 1. 4 Cf. Ep. 78. 5 Neumann, pp. 85— 6. Viri] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 147 to God, nor do we pray to them. Moreover, the gods of the Gentiles were men who were born and died, and the tombs of some of them remain. Connected with this recurrence to the "Euhemerism" which the Christian Fathers sometimes borrowed from Greek speculators on the origin of religion, is a quotation from Porphyry's Life of Pythagoras; introduced, Neumann conjectures (p. 80), to prove that the Greeks had no right to be incredulous about the declaration (1 Peter iii. 19, 20) that Christ preached to the spirits in prison ; since Pythagoras is represented as having descended into the Idaean cave (here apparently identified with the underworld) where the tomb of Jupiter was. On the relation of Christianity to its Hebrew origins, and on these as compared with the poetry and philosophy of Greece, a coherent account of Julian's view can be put together. He seems to have begun by speaking of the intuitive knowledge men have of God. To such knowledge, he says, — perhaps with an allusion to the elements of Gnostic pessimism that had found their way into orthodox Christianity, — has usually been attached the conviction that the heavens, as distinguished from the earth, are a diviner part of the universe, though it is not meant by this that the earth is excluded from divine care. He entirely repudiates the fables about Cronos swallowing his children, and about the incestuous marriages of Zeus, and so forth. But, he proceeds, the story of the Garden of Eden is equally mythical. Unless it has some secret meaning, it is full of blasphemy, since it represents God as forbidding to his creatures that knowledge of good and evil which alone is the bond of human intelligence, and as envious of their possible immortality. In what do stories like that of the talking serpent — according to the account, the real benefactor of the human race — differ from those invented by the Greeks ? Compare the Mosaic with the Platonic cos- mogony, and its speculative weakness becomes plain. In the language of the Book of Genesis there is no accurate definition. Some things, we are told, God commanded to come into being ; others he " made " ; others he separated out. As to the Spirit (irvevfia) of God, there is no clear determination whether it was made, or came to be, or is eternal without generation. Accord- 10—2 148 THE POLEMIC [VIII ing to Moses, if we are to argue from what he says explicitly 1 , God is not the creator of anything incorporeal, but is only a shaper of underlying matter. According to Plato, on the other hand, the intelligible and invisible gods of which the visible sun and moon and stars are images, proceed from the Demi- urgus, as does also the rational soul of man. Who then speaks better and more worthily of God, the " idolater " Plato, or he of whom the Scripture says that God spoke with him mouth to mouth ? Contrast now the opinions of the Hebrews and of the Greeks about the relations of the Creator to the various races of man- kind. According to Moses and all who have followed the Hebrew tradition, the Creator of the world chose the Hebrews for his own people, and cared for them only. Moses has nothing to say about the divine government of other nations, unless one should concede that he assigns to them the sun and moon for deities (Deut. iv. 19). Paul changes in an elusive manner 2 ; but if, as he says sometimes (Rom. iii. 29), God is not the God of the Jews only, why did he neglect so long all but one small nation settled less than two thousand years ago in a portion of Palestine ? Our teachers say that their creator is the common father and king of all, and that the peoples are distributed by him to presiding deities, each of whom rules over his allotted nation or city. In the Father, all things are perfect and all things are one; in the divided portions, one power is pre- dominant here, another there. Thus Ares is said to rule over warlike nations, Athena over those that are warlike with wisdom, and so forth. Let the appeal be to the facts. Do not these differences in the characters of nations exist ? And it cannot be said that the differences in the parts are uncaused without denying that providence governs the whole. Human laws are not the cause of them, for it is by the natural characters 1 Angels, Julian contends elsewhere, are the equivalents, in the Hebrew Scriptures, of the gods of polytheism. No doubt Moses held that they were produced by divine power, and were not independently existing beings ; but, pre-eminent as their rank in the universe must be, he has no account to give of them in his cosmogony, where we should have expected to find one. 2 The words are given from Cyril by Neumann (p. 177, 11) : uinrep oi iro\viro8es Trpbs ras irirpas. VIIl] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 149 of men that the laws peculiar to each people are determined. Legislators by the lead they give can do little in comparison with nature and custom. Take the case of the Western races 1 . Though they have been so long under Roman rule, you find extremely few among them showing aptitude for philosophy or geometry or any of the sciences. The cleverest appreciate only debate and oratory, and concern themselves with no other branch of knowledge. So strong is nature. The cause assigned by Moses for the diversity of languages is altogether mythical. And yet those who demand that the Greeks should believe the story of the tower of Babel, themselves disbelieve what Homer tells about the Aloadae, how they thought to pile three mountains on one another, Xv ovpavos d/x/3arb i i etrj 2 . One story is neither more nor less fabulous than the other. While Moses thus tries to account for the varieties of human speech, neither he nor any of his successors has a clear cause to assign for the diversity of manners and customs and constitutions, which is greater than that of languages. What ueed to go through the particulars : the freedom-loving and insubordinate ways of the German tribes ; the submissive- ness and tameness of the Syrians and Persians and Parthians, and, in a word, of all the barbarians towards the East and the South ? How can a God who takes no providential care for human interests like those of legal and political order, and who has sent no teachers or legislators except to the Hebrews, claim reverence or gratitude from those whose good, both mental and physical, he has thus left to chance ? But let us see whether the Creator of the world — be he the same as the God of the Hebrews or not — has so neglected all other men. First, however, the point must be insisted on, that it is not sufficient in assigning the cause of a thing to say that God commanded it. The natures of the things that come into existence must be in conformity with the commands of God. 1 The Gauls and Iberians of course are meant. The Teutonic races had hardly been long enough or extensively enough under the influence of Graeco- lioman culture for their distinctive aptitudes to be noticed, except in warfare. - Od. xi. 316. 150 THE POLEMIC [VIII If fire is to be borne upwards and earth downwards, fire must be light and earth heavy. Similarly, if there are to be differences of speech and political constitution, they must be in accordance with pre-existing differences of nature. Any one who will look may see how much Germans and Scythians differ in body from Libyans and Aethiopians. Is this also a mere command ? Do not air too and geographical situation act together with the gods to produce a certain complexion ? In reality, the commands of God are either the natures of things or accordant with the natures of things. To suppose these natural diversities all ordered under a divine government appropriate to each, is to have a better opinion of the God announced by Moses, if he is indeed the Lord of all, than that of Hebrew and Christian exclusiveness. Julian now turns to the detailed comparison. The admired decalogue, he observes, contains no commandments not recog- nised by all nations, except to have no other gods and to keep the Sabbath Day. For the transgression of the rest, penalties are imposed everywhere, sometimes harsher, sometimes milder, sometimes much the same as those of the Mosaic law. The commandment to worship no other gods has joined with it the slander that God is jealous. The philosophers tell us to imitate the gods as far as possible ; and they say that we can imitate them by contemplating the things that exist and so making ourselves free from passion. But what is the imitation of God celebrated among the Hebrews ? Wrath and anger and savage zeal. Take the instance of Phinehas (Num. xxv. 11), who is represented as turning aside God's wrath by being jealous along with him. In proof that God did not care only for the Hebrews, consider the various gifts bestowed on other peoples. Were the beginnings of knowledge given to the chosen race ? The theory of celestial phenomena was brought to completion by the Greeks after the first observations had been made in Babylon. The science of geometry, taking its origin from the art of mensuration in Egypt, grew to its present magnitude. The study of numbers, beginning from the Phoenician mer- chants, at length assumed the form of scientific knowledge Vlll] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 151 among the Greeks, who, combining this science with the others, discovered the laws of musical intervals. Shall I, the Emperor continues, mention the names of illustrious Greeks as they occur, or bring them under the various heads, — philosophers, generals, artificers, lawgivers ? The hardest and cruellest of the generals will be found dealing more leniently with those who have committed the greatest crimes than Moses with perfectly unoffending people. Other nations have not wanted legislators in sacred things. The Romans, for example, have their Numa, who also delivered his laws under divine inspiration. The spirit from the gods, Julian allows in a digression, comes seldom and to few among men. Hebrew prophecy has ceased ; none remains among the Egyptians ; the indigenous oracles of Greece have yielded to the revolutions of time and are silent. You, he says, turning to the Christians, had no cause to desert us and go over to the Hebrews for any greater gifts they have to boast of from God ; and yet, having done so, you would have done well to adhere to their discipline with exactitude. You would not then have worshipped, not merely one, but many dead men. You would have been under a harsh law with much of the barbarous in it, instead of our mild and human laws, and would have been worse in most things though better as regards religious purity (ayvoTepoi 8e /ecu KaOapwrepoi t<z? aytaTeias). But now you do not even know whether Jesus spoke of purity. You emulate the angry spirit and bitterness of the Jews, overturning temples and altars and slaughtering not only those who remain true to their paternal religion but also the heretics among yourselves 1 . 1 Cf. Ep. 52, where Julian recalls several massacres of "the so-called heretics" (tuv \eyo/x£vuv aipeTiKuv) in the reign of his predecessor Constantius. Those who are called clerics, he says, are not content with impunity for their past misdeeds ; but craving the lordship they had before, when they could deliver judgments and write wills and appropriate the portions of others, they pull every string of disorder and add fuel to the flames (wavra klvovuiv aKocrfxias k&\wv Kal to \ey6)j.ei>oi> irvp iiri irvp oxerevoven). At the opening of the epistle, he professes to find that he was mistaken in the thought that " the rulers of the Galilaeans " would regard him more favourably than his Arian predecessor, under whom they were banished and imprisoned and had their goods con- fiscated; whereas he himself has repealed their sentences and restored to them their own. 152 THE POLEMIC [VIII These things, however, belong to you and not to your teachers. Nowhere did Jesus leave you such commands or Paul. To return : the gods gave Rome the empire ; to the Jews they granted only for a short time to be free ; for the most part, they made them alien sojourners and subject to other nations. In war, in civil government, in the fine and useful arts, in the liberal sciences, there is hardly a name to be mentioned among the Hebrews. Solomon, who is celebrated among them for his wisdom, served other gods, deceived by his wife (viro t>}<? <yvvai/c6<;), they say. This, if it were so, would not be a mark of wisdom ; but may he not have paid due honour to the religions of the rest of the world by his own judgment and by the instruction of the God who manifested himself to him ? For envy and jealousy are so far from angels and gods that they do not extend even to the best men, but belong only to the demons. If the reading of your own scriptures is sufficient for you, why do you nibble at Greek learning ? Why, having gone over to the Hebrews, do you depart further from what their prophets declare than from our own manners ? The Jewish ritual is very exact, and requires a sacerdotal life and profession to fulfil it. The lawgiver bids you serve only one God, but he adds that you shall " not revile the gods " (Exod. xxii. 28). The brutality of those who came after thought that not serving them ought to be accompanied by blaspheming them. This you have taken from the Jews. From us you have taken the permission to eat of everything. That the earliest Christian converts were much the same as those of to-day is proved by what Paul says of them (1 Cor. vi. 9 — 11). Baptism, of which the Apostle speaks as the remedy, will not even wash off diseases and disfigurements from the body. Will it then remove every kind of transgression out of the soul ? The Christians, however, say that, while they differ from the present Jews, they are in strictness Israelites according to the prophets, and agree with Moses and those who followed him. They say, for example, that Moses foretold Christ. But Moses repeatedly declares that one God only is to be honoured. It is true that he mentions angels, and admits many gods in this Vill] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 153 sense ; but he allows no second God comparable with the first. The sayings usually quoted by the Christians from Moses and Isaiah have no application to the son of Mary 1 . Moses speaks of augels as the sons of God (Gen. vi. 2) ; Israel is called the firstborn son of God (Exod. iv. 22), and many sons of God (i.e. angels) are recognised as having the nations for their portion ; but nothing is said of a Firstborn Son of God, or #eo<? \6yos, in the sense of the Christian doctrine. At this point comes a disquisition on the agreement, in all but a few things, of Hebrew and of Greek religion. According to Cyril, Julian argued that Moses commanded an offering, in the form of the scapegoat (Levit. xvi. 8), to unclean demons (/xtapot? Kal a7rorpo7ratoi<i Satfioai). In not following the general custom of sacrificing, the Christians stand apart from the Jews as well as from all other nations. But the Jews, they will say, do not sacrifice. The reason, however, is that they do not think it lawful for them to sacrifice except at Jerusalem, and that they have been deprived of their temple. And they still keep up customs which are in effect sacrificial, and abstain from some kinds of meat. All this the Christians neglect. That the law in these matters was at some future time to be annulled, there is not the slightest suggestion in the books of Moses. On the contrary, the legislator distinctly declares that it is to be perpetual. That Jesus is God neither Paul nor Matthew nor Luke nor Mark ventured to assert. The assertion was first made — not quite distinctly, though there is no doubt about the meaning — by the worthy John, who perceived that a great multitude in many of the Grecian and Italian cities was taken hold of by this malady 2 , and who had heard, as may be supposed, that the 1 A more exact discussion of them was left over for the second part, to which Cyril's reply has not been preserved. The point is made in passing that any- thing which may be said of a ruler from Judah (Gen. xlix. 10) can have no reference to Jesus, since, according to the Christians, he was not the son of Joseph but of the Holy Spirit. Besides, the genealogies of Matthew and Luke, tracing the descent of Joseph from Judah, are discrepant. - What Julian has in view bere is not any and every form of apotbeosis, but, as the context shows, the devotion to corpses and relics, which seemed to him to distinguish the Christians from Jews and Greeks alike. In Ep. 49 he even commends their care about tombs. 154 THE POLEMIC [VIII tombs of Peter and Paul were secretly objects of adoration at Rome. In their adoration of tombs and sepulchres, the Chris- tians do not listen to the words of Jesus of Nazareth, who said they were full of all uncleanness (Matth. xxiii. 27). Whence this comes, the prophet Isaiah shall say. It is the old super- stition of those who " remain among the graves, and lodge in the monuments" (Is. lxv. 4), for the purpose of divining by dreams. This art the apostles most likely practised after their master's end, and handed it down to their successors. And you, Julian proceeds, who practise things which God abominated from the beginning through Moses and the prophets, yet refuse to offer sacrifices. Thence he returns to the point that, if the Christians would be true Israelites, they ought to follow the Jewish customs, and that these on the whole agree more with the customs of " the Gentiles " than with their own. Approval of animal sacrifices is clearly implied in the account of the offerings of Cain and Abel. Circumcision, which was enjoined on Abraham and his seed for ever, the Christians do not practise, though Christ said that he was not come to destroy the law. " We circumcise our hearts," they say. By all means, replies Julian, for none among you is an evildoer, none is wicked ; thus you circumcise your hearts. Abraham, he goes on to interpret the account in Genesis xv., practised divination by shooting stars (v. 5), and augury from the flight of birds (v. 11). The merit of his faith therefore consisted not in believing without but with a sign of the truth of the promise made to him. Faith without truth is foolishness. Incomplete as the reconstruction necessarily remains, there is enough to show the general line the Emperor took. It was to deny any ground, in the Old Testament as it stood, for the idea of Christianity as a universalised Judaism. All else is incidental to this. If then no religion was meant to be universal, but Judaism, in so far as it excludes other religions, is only for Jews, the idea of Christian theocracy loses its credentials. Divine government is not through a special society teaching an authoritative doctrine, but through the order of the visible universe and all the variety of civic and national institutions in the world. The underlying harmony of these is to be sought VIII] AGAINST CHRISTIANITY 155 out by free examination, which is philosophy. Of philosophy, accordingly, and not of polytheism as such, Julian was the champion. And if the system he opposed did not succeed in finally subjugating the philosophy and culture for which he cared, that was due not to any modification in the aims and ideals of its chiefs, but to the revival of forces which in their turn broke the unity of the cosmopolitan Church as the Church had broken the unity of the Roman State. CHAPTER IX. THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL. 1. The Academy becomes Neo-Platonic. About the opening of the fifth century, the chair of Plato was occupied by Plutarch, an Athenian by birth and the first distinguished representative at Athens of Neo-Platonism. By what particular way the Neo-Platonic doctrine had reached Athens is unknown; but Plutarch and the "Platonic successors" (Aiado^ot HXarwviKol) who followed him, connected themselves directly with the school of lamblichus, and through Iamblichus with Porphyry and Plotinus. Their entrance on the new line of thought was to be the beginning of a revival of philosophical and scientific activity which continued till the succession was closed by the edict of Justinian in 529. Strictly, it may be said to have continued a little longer; for the latest works of the school at Athens were written some years after that date. From that year, however, no other teacher was allowed to profess Hellenic philosophy publicly; so that it may with sufficient accuracy be taken as fixing the end of the Academy, and with it of the ancient schools. Approximately coincident with the first phase of the revival at Athens, was the brilliant episode of the school at Alexandria, where Neo-Platonism was now taught by Hypatia as its autho- rised exponent. Of her writings nothing remains, though the titles of some mathematical ones are preserved. What is known is that she followed the tradition of Iamblichus, whose doctrines IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 157 appear in the works of her pupil and correspondent Synesius. Her fate in 415 at the hands of the Alexandrian monks, under the patriarchate of Cyril (as recorded by the ecclesiastical historian Socrates), was not followed immediately by the ces- sation of the Alexandrian chair of philosophy, which indeed continued to have occupants longer than any other. Between 415 and 450, Hierocles, the author of the commentary on the Pythagorean Golden Verses, still professed Neo-Platonism. He was a pupil of Plutarch at Athens, but took up the office of teacher at Alexandria, of which he was a native. He too was an adherent of the old religion ; and, for something he had said that was thought disrespectful towards the new, he was sentenced by a Christian magistrate of Constantinople to be scourged 1 . Several more names of Alexandrian commentators are recorded; ending with Olympiodorus in the latter part of the sixth century 2 . All these names, however, — beginning with Hierocles, — belong in reality to the Athenian succession 3 . Plutarch died at an advanced age in 431. His successor was Syrianus of Alexandria, who had been his pupil and for some time his associate in the chair. Among the opinions of Plutarch, it is recorded that with Iamblichus he extends immortality to the irrational part of the soul, whereas Proclus and Porphyry limit it to the rational part 4 . A psychological position afterwards developed by Proclus may be noted in his mode of defining the place of imagination (^avracrla) between 1 See the note, pp. 9 — 10, in Gaisford's edition of the Commentary on the Golden Verses, appended as a second volume to his edition of the Eclogues of Stobaeus (Oxford, 1850). - See Zeller, iii. 2, p. 852, n. 1, where it is shown that Olympiodorus the commentator on Plato is identical with the Olympiodorus who wrote (later than 564) the commentary on Aristotle's Meteorology. Olympiodorus the Aristotelian teacher of Proclus at Alexandria is of course much earlier. 3 In one of his commentaries, Olympiodorus remarks that the succession still continues in spite of the many confiscations (/cai ravra woWQv Srmtvaewv yiPofjLivwf). This, according to Zeller, refers to the succession at Alexandria, not at Athens ; but all the Alexandrian teachers of this last period received their philosophical inspiration, directly or indirectly, from the occupauts of the chair at Athens, and in that way come within the Athenian school. 4 See the quotation from Olympiodorus given by Zeller, ii. 1, p. 1008, n. 4, where the views of different philosophers on this subject are compactly stated. 158 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX thought and perception 1 . By Plutarch first, and then by Syrian us, the use of Aristotle as an introduction to Plato, with insistence on their agreements rather than on their differences, was made systematic in the school. Most of its activity hence- forth takes the form of exceedingly elaborate critical commen- taries 2 . It is not that originality or the recognition of it altogether ceases. When any philosopher introduces a distinctly new point of view, it is mentioned in his honour by his successors. In the main, however, the effort was towards systematising what had been done. This was the work specially reserved for the untiring activity of Proclus. 2. Proclus. We now come to the last great name among the Neo- Platonists. After Plotinus, Proclus was undoubtedly the most original thinker, as well as the ablest systematiser, of the school. His abilities were early recognised, and the story of an omen that occurred on his arrival at Athens was treasured up. He had lingered outside and arrived at the Acropolis a little late, as his biographer records 3 ; and the porter said to him, " If you had not come, I should have shut the gates." His life was written by his successor in the Academic chair, some time before the decree of Justinian ; so that this anecdote has the interest of showing what the feeling already was in the school about its prospects for the future. Proclus (or Proculus) was born at Constantinople in 410, but was of a Lycian family. His father was a jurist ; and he himself studied at Alexandria first rhetoric and Roman law, afterwards 1 Philop. de An. (Zeller, iii. 2, p. 751, n. 2). tCiv /nev aiad^rCbv to 5i.riprifj.tvov els b> (Tvvadpoi'gei, rb de tQv deluv arrXovv /ecu ws &i> tis eirroi eviKbv els rtiirovs rivas Kai fxop<pas dia<p6povs di'd/xcirreTcu. - Plutarch wrote an important commentary on Aristotle's Be Aninia. Be- tween the commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. 200) and that of Plutarch, says Zeller (iii. 2, p. 749, n. 4), none is on record except the paraphrase of Themistius. Syrianus, besides many other commentaries, wrote one on the Metaphysics, portions of which have been published. See Vacherot, Histoire Critique de VEcole d' Alexandria, t. ii. livre iii. ch. 1 ; and Zeller, iii. 2, p. 761, n. 2. s Marin us, Vita Prodi, c. 10. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 159 mathematics and philosophy. Under Olympiodorus, his Alex- andrian teacher, he rapidly acquired proficiency in the Aristotelian logic. Becoming dissatisfied with the philosophical teaching at Alexandria, he went to Athens when he was not quite twenty. There he was instructed both by Syrianus and by Plutarch, who, notwithstanding his great age, was willing to continue his teaching for the sake of a pupil of such promise. At that time Proclus abstained severely from animal food, and Plutarch advised him to eat a little flesh, but without avail ; Syrianus for his part approving of this rigour 1 . His abstinence remained all but complete throughout his life. When he deviated from it, it was only to avoid the appearance of sin- gularity 3 . By his twenty-eighth year he had written his commentary on the Timaeus, in addition to many other treatises. According to Marinus, he exercised influence on public affairs ; but he was once obliged to leave Athens for a year. The school secretly adhered to the ancient religion, the practice of which was of course now illegal. His year's exile Proclus spent in acquiring a more exact knowledge of the ancient religious rites of Lycia 3 . Marinus describes him as an illus- tration of the happiness of the sage in the type of perfection conceived of by Aristotle— for he enjoyed external good fortune and lived to the full period of human life — and as a model of the ascetic virtues' in the ideal form set forth by Plotinus. He was of a temper at once hasty and placable ; and examples are given of his practical sympathy with his friends 4 . Besides his origiuality and critical spirit in philosophy, his proficiency in theurgy is celebrated 5 , and various marvels are related of him. He died at Athens in 485 6 . The saying of Proclus has often been quoted from his 1 Marinus, Vita Prodi, c. 12. - Ibid., 19: d 5t irore Kaipos ru foxvpirepos iirl ttjc tovtwv (sc. twv in\pv\^v) Xpyaw e/criXet, jxbvov aireyeveTo, nal tovto ocrlas x°-P lv - 3 Ibid., 15. * Ibid., 17. 5 Ibid., 28. 6 The dates of his birth and death are fixed by the statement of Marinus (c. 36) that he died, at the age of 75, " in the 121th year from the reign of Julian." This, as Zeller shows (iii. 2, p. 776, n. 1), must be referred to the beginning and not to the end of Julian's reign. 160 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX biography, that the philosopher ought not to observe the religious customs of one city or country only, but to be the common hierophant of the whole world. The closeness, however, with which he anticipated in idea Comte's Religion of Humanity, does not seem to have been noticed. First, we are told that he practised the ceremonial abstinences prescribed for the sacred days of all religions, adding certain special days fixed by the appearance of the moon 1 . In a later chapter, Marinus tells us about his cult of the dead. Every year, on certain days, he visited the tombs of the Attic heroes, then of the philosophers, then of his friends and connexions generally. After performing the customary rites, he went away to the Academy ; where he poured libations first to the souls of his kindred and race, then to those of all philosophers, finally to those of all men. The last observance corresponds precisely to the Positivist " Day of All the Dead," and indeed is described by Marinus almost in the identical words 2 . A saying quoted with not less frequency than that referred to above, is the declaration of Proclus that if it were in his power he would withdraw from the knowledge of men for the present all ancient books except the Timaeus and the Sacred Oracles 3 . The reason he gave was that persons coming to them without preparation are injured ; but the manner in which the aspiration was soon to be fulfilled in the Western world 4 suggests that the philosopher had a deeper reason. May he not have 1 Marinus, 19 : nal IdiKWTepov 5e rivas evr/arevijev rip.e'pas £% ewupaveias. The note in Cousin's edition (Prodi Opera Inedita, Paris, 1864) seems to give the right interpretation : "'E£ e-rrupavdas, ex apparentia, scilicet lunae, ut monet Fabricius et indicant quae sequuntur." Zeller (iii. 2, p. 784, n. 5) refers the observance to special revelations from the gods to Proclus himself. 2 Ibid., 36 : kclI em train toijtols 6 evayeararos rpirov SXKov Trepiypdxpas tottov, naaais ev avral reus ti2v diroLxop.e'vwv dvdpdnrwv \pv\cus dcpucriovTO. "• Ibid., 38: eludei 8e TroWdias ical tovto \eyet.v, tin ' KvpLos el rju, /nova av rQv dpxaiwu dirduTwu /3i/3\t'wi> eirolovv (pepeadai to. Xbyia Kal rbv TifJ.aiov, to. 8£ $\\a rj(pdvi^ov eK tuv vvv dvdpdnruv.' 4 Corresponding to the Oracles, which Proclus would have kept still current, were of course in the West the Hebrew and Christian Scriptures and the Fathers. Of these he was not thinking ; but, curiously, along with the few compendia of logic and " the liberal arts " which furnished almost the sole elements of European culture for centuries, there was preserved a fragment of the Timaeus in Latin translation. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 161 seen the necessity of a break in culture if a new line of intel- lectual development was ever to be struck out ? He and his school, indeed, devoted themselves to the task, not of effacing accumulated knowledge for a time, but of storing it up. Still, in the latter part of the period, they must have been consciously preserving it for a dimly foreseen future rather than for the next age. Whatever may have been the intention of the utterance, it did as a matter of fact prefigure the conditions under which a new culture was to be evolved in the West. That the Neo-Platonists had in some respects more of Hellenic moderation than Plato has been indicated already; and this may be noted especially in the case of Proclus, who on occasion protests against what is overstrained in the Platonic ethics. His biographer takes care to show that he possessed and exercised the political as a basis for the "cathartic" virtues 1 . And while ascetic and contemplative virtue, in his view as in that of all the school, is higher than practical virtue, its conditions, he points out, are not to be imposed on the active life. Thus he is able to defend Homer's manner of describing his heroes. The soul of Achilles in Hades is rightly represented as still desiring association with the body, because that is the condition for the display of practical virtue. Men living the practical life could not live it strenuously if they were not intensely moved by feelings that have reference to particular persons and things. The heroic character, therefore, while it is apt for great deeds, is also subject to grief. Plato himself would have to be expelled from his own ideal State for the variety of his dramatic imitations. Only in societies falling short of that severe simplicity could lifelike representations of buffoons and men of inferior moral type, such as we meet with in Plato, be allowed. Besides, he varies from one dialogue to another, in the opinions he seems to be conveying, and so himself departs from his ideal. Where Plato then is admitted, there is no reason why Homer too should not be admitted 2 . 1 Marinus, 14 — 17. 2 The defence of Homer is to be found in the Commentary on the Republic, which is of special interest for the Neo- Platonic theory of mythology. Cf. Zeller, iii. 2, p. 818, n. 4, for references to the portion of it cited. W. 11 162 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [IX A large part of the activity of Proclus was given to commenting directly on Plato; but he also wrote mathematical works 1 , philosophical expositions of a more independent kind, and Hymns to the Gods 2 , in which the mythological personages are invoked as representatives of the powers by which the contemplative devotee rises from the realm of birth and change to that of immutable being. Of the philosophical works that do not take the form of commentaries on particular treatises, we possess an extensive one entitled Platonic Theology ; three shorter ones on Providence, Fate, and Evils, preserved only in a Latin translation made in the thirteenth century by William of Morbeka, Archbishop of Corinth ; and the Theological Elements {%roLX€t(oat<i SeoXojiKT]). All these have been published 3 . Of the last, an attempt will be made to set forth the substance. In its groundwork, it is an extremely condensed exposition of the Plotinian doctrine ; but it also contains the most important modifications made in Neo-Platonism by Proclus himself. The whole is in the form of dialectical demonstration, and may perhaps best be compared, as regards method, with Spinoza's expositions of Cartesianism. An abstract of so condensed a treatise cannot of course do justice to its argumentative force, since much must necessarily be omitted that belongs to the logical development; but some idea may be given of the genuine individual power of Proclus as a thinker. A " scholastic " turn of expression, remarked on by the historians, will easily be observed ; but Proclus is not a Scholastic in the sense that he in principle takes any doctrine whatever simply as given from without. As a commentator, no doubt his aim is to explain Plato ; and here the critics cannot fairly complain when he says that his object is only to set forth what the master taught. Indeed 1 See Appendix III. 2 Seven of these have been preserved. See the end of Cousin's collection. Like Porphyry's De Antro Nympharum, they have a charm of their own for those who are, in Aristotle's phrase, cpikbfxvdoi. 3 The Platonic Theology does not seem to have been reprinted since 1618, when it appeared along with a Latin translation by Aemilius Portus. The next three works are placed at the beginning of Cousin's collection. The ^roixeicoffcs is printed after the Sententiae of Porphyry in the Didot edition of Plotinus. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 163 the complaint that he is a "scholastic" in this sense is neu- tralised by the opposite objection that his Platonic Theology contains more of Neo-Platonism than of Plato. And one point of his teaching — not comprised in the treatise now to be expounded — seems to have been generally misunderstood. In more than one place 1 he describes belief (irians) as higher than knowledge (yvwais), because only by belief is that Good to be reached which is the supreme end of aspiration. This has been supposed to be part of a falling away from pure philosophy, though Zeller allows that, after all, the ultimate aim of Proclus "goes as much beyond positive religion as beyond methodical knowing 2 ." And in fact the notion of " belief," as Proclus formulates it, instead of being a resigna- tion of the aims of earlier philosophy, seems rather to be a rendering into more precise subjective terms of Plato's meaning in the passage of the Republic where Socrates gives up the attempt at an adequate account of the Idea of the Good 3 . As Plotinus had adopted for the highest point of his onto- logical system the Platonic position that the Good is beyond even Being 4 , so Proclus formulated a definite principle of cognition agreeing with what Plato indicates as the attitude of the mind when it at last descries the object of its search. At the extreme of pure intellect — at the point, as we might say, which terminates the highest segment of the line re- presenting the kinds of cognition with their objects — is a mode of apprehension which is not even " dialectical," because it is at the very origin of dialectic. And to call this "belief" is to prepare a return from the mysticism of Plotinus — which Proclus, however, does not give up— to the conception of a mental state which, while not strictly cognitive, is a common instead of a peculiar experience. The contradiction between this view and that which makes belief as "opinion" lower than knowledge is only apparent 5 . A view of the kind has 1 Cf. E. P. 543 ; Zeller, iii. 2, p. 820. 2 iii. 2, p. 823. 3 Rep. vi. 506. 4 Rep. vi. 509. 5 Pico della Mirandola seized the general thought of Proclus on this point, and applied it specially to philosophical theology. See the " Fifty-five Con- clusions according to Proclus" appended to the edition of the Platonic Theology 11—2 164 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX become more familiar since. Put in the most general terms it is this: that while belief in its sense of opinion is below scientific knowledge, belief as the apprehension of metaphysical principles is above it ; because scientific knowledge, if not at- tached to some metaphysical principle, vanishes under analysis into mere relations of illusory appearances. The method of discriminating subordinate triads within each successive stage of emanation, which is regarded as characteristic of Proclus, had been more and more elaborated during the whole interval from Plotinus. The increasing use of it by Porphyry, by Iamblichus, and by their disciple Theodore of Asine, is noted by the historians. Suggestions of the later developments are to be met with in Plotinus himself, who, for example, treats being, though in its essence identical with intel- lect, as prior if distinguished from it, and goes on further to distinguish life, as a third component of primal Being, from being in the special sense and from intellect 1 . This is not indeed the order assigned to the same components by Proclus, who puts life, instead of intellect, in the second place ; but the o-erm of the division is there. A doctrine in which he seems to have been quite original is that of the "divine henads 2 ," to which we shall come in expounding the Elements. For the rest, the originality of many things in the treatise, as well as its general agreement with Plotinus, will become evident as we proceed. Every multitude, the treatise begins, participates in a manner in the One. For if in a multitude there were no unity, it would consist either of parts which are nothings, or of parts which are themselves multitudes to infinity. From this starting-point we are led to the position that every multi- tude, being at the same time one and not one, derives its real existence from the One in itself (to avroev). already referred to. The words of Pico's forty-fourth proposition are these : " Sicut fides, quae est credulitas, est infra intellectum ; ita fides, quae est vere fides, est supersubstantialiter supra scientiam et intellectum, nos Deo immediate conjungens." 1 Enn. VI. 6, 8 : to op wpwrov del \a^€?p irpurov ov, efra vovp, elra rb foov. - Cf. Zeller, iii. 2, p. 793. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 165 The producing (to irapdyov), or that which is productive of another (to irapaKriKov dXkov), is better than the nature of that which is produced (/cpeirrov -n}? tov irapayo/xevov (pvaecos). The first Good is that after which all beings strive, and is therefore before all beings. To add to it anything else is to lessen it by the addition, making it some particular good instead of the Good simply. If there is to be knowledge, there must be an order of causation, and there must be a first in this order. Causes cannot go in a circle : if they did, the same things would be prior and posterior, better and worse. Nor can they go in an infinite series : to refer back one cause to another without a final term would make knowledge impossible 1 . Principle and primal cause of all being is the Good. For all things aspire to it ; but if there were anything before it in the order of causes, that and not the Good would be the end of their aspiration. The One simply, and the Good simply, are the same. To be made one is to be preserved in being — which is a good to particular things ; and to cease to be one is to be deprived of being. In order that the derivation of motion may not go on in a circle or to infinity, there must be an unmoved, which is the first mover; and a self-moved, which is the first moved ; as well as that which is moved by auother. The self-moved is the mean which joins the extremes 2 . Whatever can turn back upon itself, the whole to the whole, is incorporeal. For this turning back is impossible for body, because of the division of its parts, which lie outside one another in space 3 . That which can thus turn back upon itself, 1 Srcux- OeoX. 11. The order meant here is of course logical, not chrono- logical. All existing things depend on an actual first cause of their being. toTiv curia Trpuorrj twc ovtoiv, d</>' 77s olov ix p'j"??s irpbucriv eKaara, to. /xef eYYt'S oura iKetur/s, ra 6e troppuiTepov. 2 2t<hx- OeoX. 14. Here again the order is purely logical. There is no notion of a first impulse given to a world that has a chronological beginning. 3 Ztoix- OeoX. 15 : ovoev dpa <ri2p.a irpbs iavrb iritpvKev iirKTrpicpetv, wj 6\ov iire<rTpa.(pOai. wpbs 6'Xoe. et rt apa irpbs iavrb eiri.<TTpeirri.Kbv eariv, dawp.aTbv £<rri /ecu ap.tp£s. 166 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX has an essence separable from all body. For if it is inseparable in essence, it must still more be inseparable in act ; were it separable only in act, its act would go beyond its essence. That is, it would do what, by definition, is not in its power to do. But body does not actually turn back upon itself. Whatever does thus turu back is therefore separable in essence as in act. "Beyond all bodies is the essence of soul, and beyond all souls the intellectual nature, and beyond all intellectual exist- ences the One "\ Intellect is unmoved and the giver of motion, soul self-moving, body moved by another. If the living body moves itself, it is by participation in soul. Similarly, the soul through intellect participates in perpetual thought (/ieTe^et tov del voelv). For if in soul there were perpetual thinking primarily, this would be inherent in all souls, like self-motion. Since not all souls, as such, have this power, there must be before soul the primarily intelligent (to irpooTcos votjtikov). Again, before intellect there must be the One. For intellect, though unmoved, is not one without duality, since it thinks itself; and all things whatsoever participate in the One, but not all things in intellect. To every particular causal chain (aeipd ical rd^is), there is a unity (fiovd<i) which is the cause of all that is ordered under it. Thus after the primal One there are henads (ei/aSe?) ; and after the first intellect, minds (i/oes); and after the first soul, souls ; and after the whole of nature, natures. First in order is always that which cannot be participated in (to d/xeOe/cTov), — the " one before all " as distinguished from the one in all. This generates the things that are participated in. Inferior to these again are the things that participate, as those that are participated in are inferior to the first. The perfect in its kind (to Tekeiov), since in so far as it is perfect it imitates the cause of all, proceeds to the production of as many things as it can ; as the Good causes the existence of everything. The more or the less perfect anything is, of the more or the fewer things is it the cause, as being nearer to or 1 Stoix- OeoX. 20 : TrdfTuv ffufxarui' iwiKeiva ianv i] i/'i'X^s ovala, ko.1 iraaQv \j/vxu" (Tr^Keiva r\ votpa. (pvais, /cat iracrcov tQv voepwv inrocrT&aewv tTr^Keiva to ev. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 167 more remote from the cause of all. That which is furthest from the principle is unproductive and the cause of nothing. The productive cause of other things remains in itself while producing 1 . That which produces is productive of the things that are second to it, by the perfection and superabundance of its power. For if it gave being to other things through defect and weakness, they would receive their existence through its alteration ; but it remains as it is 2 . Every productive cause brings into existence things like itself before things unlike. Equals it cannot produce, since it is necessarily better than its effects. The progression from the cause to its effects is accomplished by resemblance of the things that are second in order to those that are first 3 . Bein^ similar to that which produces it, the immediate product is in a manner at once the same with and other than its cause It remains therefore and goes forth at the same time, and neither element of the process is apart from the other. Every product turns back and tries to reach its cause ; for everything strives after the Good, which is the source of its being ; and the mode of attaining the Good for each thing is through its own proximate cause. The return is accomplished by the resemblance the things that return bear to that which they return to 4 ; for the aim of the return is union, and it is always resemblance that unites. The progression and the return form a circular activity. There are lesser and greater circles according as the return is to things immediately above or to those that are higher. In the great circle to and from the principle of all, all things are involved 5 . 1 ^.toix- OeoX. 26 : el yap fiinelrai to ev, eKelvo 8e a.Kivr)T<js ixpiaTijo'i to, /xer' avrb, /cat wav to irapayov waatjTOJS £x el T V" T °u irapayeiv airiav. " 'Ztolx- OeoX. 27 : ou yap awop.epio~p.bs ecrrt tov irapdyovTos to irapaybpevov ' ovbe yap yevicei tovto wpo-rriKev, ovbe rots yevvqTLKols ai'riois ' ovbe p.e rd/3a<rts " ov yap v\r) yiverai tov irpo'ibvTos ' fxivei yap, olou e'en. Kal to irapaybixevov a\\o irap 1 avrb eaTiv. 3 Ztolx- OeoX. 29 : iracra wpbobos oV oixoiottjtos air oreKe it at tQiv bevTep-cv irpbs to 7rpwra. 4 "Ltolx- OeoX. 32 : ira-ra ein-rTpo-pr) bC bpoLbrr-TOS airoTe\eiTai tuv iirio-Tpe-po- p-evuv, irpbs S €WLO-Tpi<p€Tai, 5 "Ztoix- OeoX. 33 : irav to wpo'Cbv dirb tlvos Kal einaTpi<pov, kvkKiktjv Zx €i T V" evepyei.av....p.ei^ous be kvkXol Kai eXarrovs tiHv /*ee e-Tt.o~Tpo<p'j)v irpbs to. inrepKeifj.ei>a 168 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [IX Accordingly, everything that is caused remains in its own cause, and goes forth from it, and returns to it 1 . The remaining (lJ>ovri) signifies its community with its cause ; the going forth, its distinction from it (afxa yap hiaicpiaei, irpoohos) ; the return, its innate endeavour after its own good, from which its particular being is. Of the things multiplied in progressive production, the first are more perfect than the second, these than the uext, and so forth ; for the " progressions " from cause to effect are remissions of being (vcpecreis) of the second as compared with the first. In the order of return, on the contrary, the things that are most imperfect come first, the most perfect last. Every process of return to a remoter cause is through the same inter- mediate stages as the corresponding causal progression. First in the order of return are the things that have received from their cause only being (to elvcu) ; next, those that have received life with being ; last, those that have received also the power of cognition. The endeavour (ope^t?) of the first to return is a mere fitness for participation in causes 2 ; the endeavour of the second is " vital," and is a motion to the better ; that of the third is identical with conscious knowledge of the goodness of their causes (Kara rrjv yvwaiv, avvala6t]aL<i ovcra rrj<; rcov aiTLoov ayadoTriTos;). Between the One without duality, and things that proceed from causes other than themselves, is the self-subsistent (to avdviroaTarov), or that which is the cause of itself. That which is in itself, not as in place, but as the effect in the cause, is self- subsistent. The self-subsistent has the power of turning back upon itself 3 . If it did not thus return, it would not strive after nor attain its own good, and so would not be self-sufficing and perfect ; but this belongs to the self-subsistent if to anything. avvexws yivo/j.^vajp, tuv 5e Trpbs ra avwrepu, Kai fxixP 1 - T &v iravruu apxv*- °- wo "yo-P iK(ivy)s iravra, Kai Trpbs eKeivrjv. 1 2tchx. OeoX. 35 : ttcLv to airiarbu Kai p^evei iv rfj avrov atria, Kai Trpbuaiv <z7r' avrrjs, Kai eiuaTp£<pei Trpbs avrrjv. 2 2rotx. QeoX. 39 : oixricobr] iroieiTai rrjv enter po<pr)v. That is to say, they tend to be embodied in some definite form, which is their "essence." 3 Srotx- OeoX. 42 : el yap d.0' eavrou Trpbeiai., Kai rrpi iirtaTpo(pr]v Trotr/nerai Trpbs eavrb. d0' ov yap t) wpbob'os e/cdcrois, els tovto Kai t) rrj Trpobby avaroixos llTMJTpOfpT). IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 169 Conversely, that which has the power of turning back upon itself is self-subsistent. For thus to return, and to attain the end, is to find the source of its perfection, and therefore of its being, within itself. The self-subsistent is ungenerated. For generation is the way from imperfection to the opposite perfec- tion 1 ; but that which produces itself is ever perfect, and needs not completion from another, like things that have birth. The self-subsistent is incorruj)tible, for it never departs from the cause of its preservation, which is itself. It is indivisible and simple. For if divisible, it cannot turn back, the whole to the whole; and if composite, it must be in need of its own elements, of which it consists, and hence not self-sufficing. After some propositions on the everlasting or imperishable (ai'8top) and the eternal (alcoviov), and on eternity and time, not specially distinctive of his system, Proclus goes on to a characteristic doctrine of his own, according to which the higher cause — which is also the more general — continues its activity beyond that of the causes that follow it. Thus the causal efficacy of the One extends as far as to Matter, in the production of which the intermediate causes, from intelligible being downwards, have no share. That which is produced by the things second in order, the series of propositions begins 2 , is produced in a higher degree by the things that are first in order and of more causal efficacy ; for the things that are second in order are themselves produced by the first, and derive their whole essence and causal efficacy from them. Thus intellect is the cause of all that soul is the cause of; and, where soul has ceased to energise, the intellect that produces it still continues its causal activity. For the inanimate, in so far as it participates in form, has part in intellect and the creative action of intellect". Further, the Good is the cause of all that intellect is the cause of; but not conversely. For privations of form are from the Good, since all 1 "Ltolx- 0eo\. 45 : /cat yap i] yivtvLS 686s icrnv 4k tou dreXous el$ to ivavrlov riXuov. - 'Zrotx- Qeo\. 56. 3 — toi.x- ©eo\. 57 : /cat yap to a\pvxov, Kadoaov ttdous /xertax^, "ov /uere^et Kal TTJS TOU VOV TTOirjOtWS. 170 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX is thence, but intellect, being form, is not the ground of privation 1 . The product of more causes is more composite (avvOeroorepov) than the product of fewer. For if every cause gives something to that which proceeds from it, more causes must confer more elements and fewer fewer. Now where there are more elements of the composition, the resultant is said to be more composite ; where there are fewer, less. Hence the simple in essence is either superior to things composite or inferior. For if the extremes of being are produced by fewer concurrent causes and the means by more, the means must be composite while the extremes on both sides are simpler. But that the extremes are produced by fewer causes is evident, since the superior causes both begin to act before the inferior, and in their activity stretch out beyond the point where the activity of the latter ceases through remission of power (Si vcpeatv hvvd/j,e(os). Therefore the last of things, like the first, is most simple, because it proceeds only from the first; but, of these two simplicities, one is above all composition, the other below it. Of things that have plurality, that which is nearer the One is less in quantity than the more distant, greater in potency 2 . Consequently there are more corporeal natures than souls, more of these than of minds, more minds than divine henads. The more universal (oXtKcorepov) precedes in its causal action the more particular (pcepucooTepov) and continues after it. Thus "being" comes before "living being" (£a>ov), and "living being" before "man," in the causal order as in the order of generality. Again, at a point below the agency of the rational power, where there is no longer " man," there is still a breathing and sentient living being ; and where there is no longer life there is still being. That which comes from the more universal causes is the bearer of that which is communi- cated in the remitting stages of the progression. Matter, which is at the extreme bound, has its subsistence only from the most universal cause, namely, the One. Being the subject 1 2rotx- OeoX. 57 : vovs 5e areprtaeus viroo-Tar-qs oik ecriv, eI5os tap. ' 2 Srwx- Oeo\. 62 : 'ojjloiov yap ry evl fidWov to eyyurepov • rb de Iv tt&vtui> rj» inroffTaTiKbv a.Tr\rj6uvTUS. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 171 of all things, it proceeded from the cause of all 1 . Body in itself, while it is below participation in soul, participates in a manner in being. As the subject of animation (viroKei/xevov tj}? -v/rin^eocreeix?), it has its subsistence from that which is more universal than soul. Omitting some auxiliary propositions, we may go on to the doctrine of infinity as formulated by Proclus. In passing, it may be noted that he explicitly demonstrates the proposition that that which can know itself has the power of turning back upon itself. The reason assigned is that in the act of self- knowledge that which knows and that which is known are one. And what is true of the act is true also of the essence 2 . That only the incorporeal has the power of thus turning back upon itself was proved at an earlier stage. Infinity in the sense in which it really exists, with Proclus as with Plotinus, means infinite power or potency. That which ever is, is infinite in potency ; for if its power of being (>/ Kara to elvcu Suva/xis) were finite, its being would some time fail 3 . That which ever becomes, has an infinite power of becoming. For if the power is finite, it must cease in infinite time ; and, the power ceasing, the process must cease. The real infinity of that which truly is, is neither of multitude nor of magnitude, but of potency alone 4 . For self-subsistent being (to avdviroo-TaTax; 6v) is indivisible and simple, and is in potency infinite as having most the form of unity (evoeiSeo-TaTov ) ; since the greatest causal power belongs to that which is nearest the One. The infinite in magnitude or multitude, on the other hand, is at once most divided and weakest. Indivisible power is infinite and undivided in the same relation (fcaTa tcivtov) ; the divided powers are in a manner finite (TreTrepaa/xevai 7ra)?) by reason of their division. From this sense of the 1 Ztoix- 6eo\. 72 : r) ftiv yap i/\r>, viroKtiuevov ovo~a tt&vtwv, e'/c tov Trdvrwv alrlov TrporjXOe. 2 ^.toix- ©eo\. 83 : irav yap to Tip tvtpye.1v irpbs eavrb eTriOTptTCTinbv /cat oiiaiav £x ei irpbs iavTT)v ovvvtvovcrav, koI ev eavrrj ov<ro.v. 3 Ztoix- ©«o\. 84. 4 —Toix- OeoX. 86 : ttolv to ovtus ov Tip 6vti dweipbv iffTi, oStc Kara to irXijdos, oure /caret rb fniyeOos, dWct /cara 7-771/ 5vvap.iv ptbvrjv. 172 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX finite, as limited power, is to be distinguished its sense as determinate number, by which it comes nearest to indivisible unity. That which is infinite, is infinite neither to the things above it nor to itself, but to the things that are inferior. To these, there is that in it which can by no means be grasped ; it has what exceeds all the unfolding of its powers : but by itself, and still more by the things above it, it is held and defined as a whole 1 . We have already met with the position that in a complete causal series the first term is " imparticipable " (afiWeKTov). This means that in no way do the things it produces share it among them. The cause, thus imparticipable or transcendent, remains by itself in detachment from every succeeding stage. In drawing out the consequences of this position, Proclus introduces those intermediate terms which are held to be characteristic of his system. Within the Being or Intellect of the Plotinian Trinity, he constitutes the subordinate triad of being, life and mind. To these discriminated stages he applies his theory that causes descend in efficacy as they descend in generality. The series of things in which mind is immanent is preceded by imparticipable mind ; similarly life and being precede the things that participate in them ; but of these being is before life, life before mind 2 . In the order of dependence, the cause of more things precedes the cause of fewer. Now all things have being that have life, and all things have life that have mind, but not conversely. Hence in the causal order being must come first, then life, then mind. All are in all ; but in each each is present in the manner appropriate to the subsistence of that in which it inheres 3 . 1 2tcux- ©eo\. 93 : iavrb 5e <jvv£x ov KaX bpifav owe av eavTui aweipov virapxot., ovbe 7roXXy /xaWov rots virepKeip.e'i'ois, /xolpav ^x ou ttjs ev e/eetWs dfreipias- direipb- repai. yap al tQp oXiKurepwv 5vvap.eis, dXiKwrepai oCtrat /cat eyyvrepu TeTO.yp.enai Trfs TrpuTiffTTjs aweiplas. 2 Ztoix- ©eo\. 101 : iravToiv tQv vov fierexovTUv 7?yetTCU 6 d/xe#e/eTOS vovs, KaX ruv ttjs fwi;s 7/ fay, /cat tuv tov ovtos to 6v ■ avTuv 8e tovtwv to p.ev bv vpb t?}s s'wtJs, i) be far] wpb tov vov. 3 "Ltoix- Qeo\. 103 : Travra ev vdcnv oliceim 8e ev eK&ffTO}. As for example, ev TV fafi KaTa ptfcl-iv p.ev to elvai, /car' al-Hav 5e to voeiv ' dXXd ja/n/ews itcdrepov ' Kara tovto yap i) iiirap^s. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 173 All that is immortal is imperishable, but not all that is imperishable is immortal. For that which ever participates in life participates also in being, but not conversely. As being is to life, so is the imperishable, or that which cannot cease to be, to the immortal, or that which cannot cease to live 1 . Since that which is altogether in time is in every respect unlike that which is altogether eternal, there must be something between them ; for the causal progression is always through similars 2 . This mean must be eternal in essence, temporal in act. Generation, which has its essence in time, is attached causally to that which on one side shares in being and on the other in birth, participating at once in eternity and in time ; this, to that which is altogether eternal ; and that which is altogether eternal to being before eternity (et? to ov, to irpoaioovtovy. The highest terms of each causal chain (aeipa), and only those, are connected with the unitary principle of the chain next above. Thus only the highest minds are directly attached to a divine unity ; only the most intellectual souls participate in mind ; and only the most perfect corporeal natures have a soul present to them 4 . Above all divine unities is the One, which is God ; as it must be, since it is the Good ; for that beyond which there is nothing, and after which all things strive, is God 5 . But that there must also be many divine unities is evident, since every cause which is a principle takes the lead in a series of multiplied existences descending from itself by degrees of likeness. The self-complete unities {avrorekeh evdhes) or "divine henads," are "the gods," and every god is above being and life and mind G . In all there is participation, except in the One 7 . 1 2/roix- ©eoX. 105. - "Ztoix- OeoX. 100 : ai irpboboi. iracai 5ta tuv oixoiuv. 3 "Ltoix- OeoX. 107. 4 Zt(»x- OeoX. 111. Cf. 112 : Trdcrr]s Taijews to. irpwTiaTa fxop<prjv Hx €l r ^ v '"'P avTu>v. Stoix- OeoX. 113 : ov yap p.rjSiv iariv tiriKeiva, Kal ov irdvra itpUrai, Oebs TOVTO. 6 2toix- OeoX. 115 : 7ras 0edt VTrepovo~i6$ iari Kal virtpfuos Kal inrtpvovs. ' ^.toix- OeoX. 116: Tras debs p.€0£kt6s eon, ttXtjv tov ev6s....d yap to~Tt.v 6.Wrj /xera rb irpLorov d/xideKTOs ivds, ri 8ioio~ei tov cubs ; 174 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX Much has been written upon the question, what the henads of Proclus really mean. Usually the doctrine is treated as an attempt to find a more definite place for polytheism than was marked out in the system of Plotinus. This explanation, however, is obviously inadequate, and there have not been wanting attempts to find in it a more philosophical meaning. Now so far as the origin of the doctrine is concerned, it seems to be a perfectly consequent development from Plotinus. Proclus seeks the cause of plurality in things at a higher stage than the intelligible world, in which Plotinus had been content to find its beginning. Before being and mind are produced, the One acts as it were through many points of origin ; from each of these start many minds ; each of which again is the principle of further differences. As the primal unity is called #eo?, the derivative unities are in correspondence called 6eol. Thus the doctrine is pure deductive metaphysics. There is hardly any indication that in thinking it out Proclus had in view special laws of nature or groups of natural facts 1 . Though not otherwise closely resembling Spinoza's doctrine of the " infinite attributes," it resembles it in this, that it is a metaphysical deduction intended to give logical completeness, where intuitive completeness becomes impossible, to a system of pure conceptual truth. From the divine henads, according to Proclus, the provi- dential order of the world directly descends. This position he supports by a fanciful etymology 2 , but deduces essentially from the priority of goodness as characterising the divinity 3 . After goodness come power and knowledge. The divine knowledge is above intellect ; and the providential government of the world is not by a reasoning process (ov Kara Xoyta/xov). By nothing that comes after it can the divinity in itself either be expressed 1 A slight development on this line is to be met with in §§ 151 — 8, but not such as to affect the general aspect of the doctrine. 2 Srotx- OeoX. 120: iv Oeois t] vpbvoia Trpuirw ...7) 5e irpbvoia. (ws roijvopa tp:<paivei) ivipyeid iori irpb vov. rqi eTvai dpa 0eol /ecu rf ayaddTTjres elvai wdvruiv Trpovoovffi, irdvTa rrjs irpb vov TrXr/povvres dyad6rr)Tos. 3 'Etoix- OeoX. 121 : irav rb deiov virapijiv p.tv @x eL T V V dyaddrijra, 5vvap.iv 5e ivialav teal yvuiatv xpticpiov, dXTjirrov irdaiv bp.ov rots devrepots. ...d\X' 17 07rap£is ti2 dplcrip x a P aKT VP L fc TCU > xal i] virdo-Tacns Kara rb dpiarov ' tovto 5£ i) dyadbTijs. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 175 or known. Since, however, it is knowable as henads from the things that participate in them, only the primal One is entirely unknowable, as not being participated in 1 . The divinity knows iudivisibly the things that are divided, and without time the things that are in time, and the things that are not necessary with necessity, and the things that are mutable immutably ; and, in sum, all things better than according to their own order. Its knowledge of the multiple and of things subject to passion is unitary and without passivity. On the other hand, that which is below has to receive the impassible with passive affection, and the timeless under the form of time 2 . The order of the divine henads is graduated ; some being more universal, some more particular. The causal efficacy of the former is greater ; of the latter, less. The more particular divine henads are generated from the more universal, neither by division of these nor by alteration, nor yet by manifold relationships, but by the production of secondary progressions through superabundance of power 3 . The divine henad first communicates its power to mind ; through mind, it is present to soul ; and through soul it gives a resonance of its own peculiar nature even to body. Thus body becomes not only animate and intelligential, but also divine, receiving life and motion from soul, indissoluble permanence from mind, divine union from the henad participated in 4 . Not all the other henads together are equal to the primal One 5 . There are as many kinds of beings that participate in the divine henads as there are henads participated in. The more universal henads are participated in by the more universal kinds of beings ; the more particular by the more particular. Thus the order of beings is in precise accordance with the order of the henads. Each being has for its cause not only the henad in which it participates, but, along with that, the primal One G . 1 Srotx- OeoX. 123 : /x6vov t6 irpQirov iravTt\Qs &yvuxTTot>, are d/xtdetcTov of. - Ztoix- ©eoX. 124. 3 Srotx- ©«>*• 12G - * Ztoi X - OeoX. 129. 5 1.TOLX- OeoX. 133: ov yap ai iraffai tCov 6eu>v inrdp£eis wapiaodfTai tgj hi ' TO(ravTT)v (Ktivo wpbs to tt\t)0os tCjv Oeuv ZXaxef virep^oXrjv. 6 2iroiX- OeoX. 137 : iraca eVas awvtpiarr^ai ti2 evl to p.eT^x o " o.vttjs ov. 176 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX All the powers of the divinity penetrate even to the terres- trial regions, being excluded by no limits of space from presence to all that is ready for participation 1 . Beside that providence of the gods which is outside and above the order over which it is exercised, there is another, imitating it within the order and exercised over the things that are at a lower stage of remission by those that are higher in the causal series 2 . The gods are present in the same manner to all things, but not all things are present in the same manner to the gods. It is unfitness of the things participating that causes obscuration of the divine presence. Total deprivation of it would mean their complete disappearance into not-being. At each stage of remission, the divinity is present, not only in the manner peculiar to each causal order, but in the manner appropriate to the particular stage. The progressions have the form of a circle; the end being made like the beginning through the return of all things within the order to its principle 3 . The whole multitude of the divine henads is finite in number. It is indeed more definitely limited than any other multitude, as being nearest to the One. Infinite multitude, on the other hand, is most remote from the One 4 . There is at the same time, as has been shown, a sense in which all divine things are infinite. That is to say, they are infinite in potency, and unbounded in relation to what is below them 5 . The henads participated in by being which is prior to intellect are intelligible (vorjTaL); those that are participated in by intellect itself are intelligential (voepai), as producing intelligence 6 ; those that are participated in by soul are supra- mundane {virepKoajxioi). As soul is attached to intellect, and 1 Srooc. Qeo\. 140. 2 Srotx- ©eoX. 141. 3 Ztoix- ©eo\. 146. Cf. 148 : trdcra 8eia rri£is iavry avvrjvwTai rpix&s ' a7r6 re rrjs aKp6rrjTos ttjs eavTrjs kcli diro ttjs nea6rr]TOS, Kal diro tov t{\ovs....ko.I ovtws 6 (Tv/xvas 5ia.KO(Tfios eh ecn 5ia ttjs evowoiov tQv irpwTwv 5vvdp.ews, 8td rrjs ei> rrj /xect6t7?ti cvvoxys, did rrjs rod riXovs eis ttjv dpxw T &v irpooduv eTnarpO(prj<;. 4 Stoix- ©eo\. 149. 5 Ztoix- Qeo\. 150: t} 5£ direipia Kara ttjv Suva/xiv eKelvoif rb de aireipov dwepiXrjirrov, oh iariv aireipov. 6 Xtoix- Qeo\. 163 : oi)x oifru voepai, ws iv vQ ixpeo-TTjicviai, d\V tl)5 xar airlav tov vov Trpovirdpxovaai, Kal diroyevvrjcraaai tov vouv. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 177 intellect turns back upon intelligible being ; so the supramun- dane gods depend on the intelligential, as those again on the intelligible gods 1 . Something also of visible bodies being from the gods, there are also "mundane henads" (iyKoafuoi ivd&es). These are mediated by mind and soul ; which, according as they are more separable from the world and its divided contents, have more resemblance to the imparticipable 2 . Having dealt so far with the ontology of intellect, Proclus goes on to formulate the characters of intellectual knowledge. Intellect has itself for the object of its thought 3 . Mind in act knows that it thinks ; and it does not belong to one mind to think an object and to another to think the thought of the object 4 . The thought, the knowledge of the thought, and the cognisance of itself as thinking, are simultaneous activities of one subject. It is the character of mind to think all things together. Imparticipable mind thinks all of them together simply; each mind that follows thinks them all still together, but under the form of the singular 5 . That mind is incorporeal is shown by its turning back upon itself 6 . In accordance with its being, it contains all things intellectually, both those before it and those after it; the former by participation, the latter by containing their causes intellectually 7 . Mind constitutes what is after it by thinking; and its creation is in thinking, and its thought in creating 8 . It is first participated in by the things which, although their thought is according to the temporal and not according to the eternal 1 Stoix- GeoX. 164 : ws ovv \jsvxv iratra els vovv avqpT7)Tai, Kal vovs els to vot)t6v iwio-Tpairrai, outw brj Kal oi inre pKoa/uoi deol twv voepwv e'te'xoPTai, Ka.da.irep drj ko.1 OVTOl TOOV V07)TWV. 2 Stoix- GeoX. 166. 3 Stoix- GeoX. 107. 4 2toix- GeoX. 168 : nds vovs Kar' evepyetav oldev, on voet, Kal ouk a\\ov /j.ev tbiov tI voelv, aXXou 5e rd voelv, on voei. 5 1.TOIX- GeoX. 170: 7r£s vovs iravra cL/acl voer dXX' 6 p.ev afiideKros airXws iravra, riov 5e per' 1 eKelvov Hkclvtos Kab" eV awavra. Cf. 180. 6 2>oix- GeoX. 171 : on /xev ovv do-w/xaros 6 poOs, r\ irpbs eavrbv iirto-Tpo<pri StjXoI • twv yap awixdruiv ovbev irpbs eavTO iiriOTptyeTai. 7 2rotx- GeoX. 173 : to 5e elvai avrov voepbv, Kal to. atria dpa. voepuis ix ei r ^ v iravTwv • wore iravra voepQs e'xet "■** vovs, kcli to. irpb aiiTov, Kal to. tier' avrbv ' u>s ovv to, votito. voepws e'xet ""^ s vovs, ovtu Kal to. alo~dr}Ta voepws. 8 Zrotx- GeoX. 171 : irds voOs t£ voelv ixpiaTrjaL to. per' avrbv, Kai t\ iroiifots ev to) voelv, Kal r\ vbi)Cis ev ry 7roteiV . w. 12 178 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX order, which is timeless, yet have the power of thinking and actually think during the whole of time. That such existences should be interposed before particular souls, is required by the graduated mediation characteristic of every casual progression 1 . Soul that is sometimes thinking and sometimes not, cannot participate without mediation in eternal mind. The intellectual forms in mind are both in one another and each for itself without either spatial interval or confusion. This Proclus demonstrates from the nature of indivisible essence. If any one needs an analogy as well as a demon- stration, then, he says, there is the case of the various theorems existing in one soul. The soul draws forth the propositions that constitute its knowledge, not by pulling them apart from one another, but by making separately clear to itself implicit distinctions that already exist 2 . The minds that contain more universal forms are superior in causal efficacy to those that contain more particular forms. The first by forms that are quantitatively less produce more effects ; the second fewer by forms that are quantitatively more. From the second proceed the finer differences of kinds 3 . The products of intellectual forms are imperishable. Kinds that are only for a time do not subsist from a formal or ideal cause of their own ; nor have perishable things, as such, a pre-existent intellectual form 4 . The number of minds is finite 5 . Every mind is a whole ; and each is at once united with other minds and discriminated from them. Imparticipable mind is a whole simply, since it has in itself all the parts under the form of the whole ; of the partial minds each contains the whole as in a part 6 . 1 2twx. OeoX. 175 : ovbafiov yap ai irpbobot yivovrai d/j.eo~ios, dXXd Sia tu>v auyyevwv /cat bp.o'uov, Kara re ids VTroaTaaeis Kal ras tQv evepyeiQv reXetoT^ras. - "Ltoix- OeoX. 176 : iravra yap ei\iKpivu>s 17 ipvxv irpodyei, Kal X W P' S %KaoT0v, [x-qhev e<p£\KOVo~a airb tQv XonrQv, a (el p.rj Sie/ce/cptro del Kara tt)v ?£w) ov8' av tj eve'pyeia Si^Kpive rrjs ipvxvs- 3 Utoix- OeoX. 177 : odev oi devrepoi vbes reus tQv eldCbv /j.epiKure'pais SiaKplaeaiv eirtbiapdpovai wus Kal Xewrovpyovcri rds tQv irpuiruiv elboirouas. 4 Zroix- OeoX. 178: irdv voepbv eldos dtbiuv earlv inroaraTLKdv ovre dpa rd yevr) rd Kara riva xpbvov a7r' curias v(pe(TTT]Ktv eldrjTiKTjs, ovre rd (pdaprd, 17 (pdaprd, eldos ?x £l voepbv Trpo'virapxov. 5 Stoix- OeoX. 179. 6 'Ztoix- OeoX. 180 : dXX' 6 /xev dp.49eKros vovs a7rXws 6'Xos, Cos rd fitprj iravra b\iKws ix wv & v tavTui, tuiv St /j.epiKuii' e/cacrros ws iv /xipei to 6'Xoe exei. Cf. 170. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 179 The mean between divine imparticipable mind and mind participated in and intelligential but not divine, is divine mind participated in. In this participate divine souls. Of souls there are three kinds : first, those that are divine ; second, those that are not divine but that always participate in intelligible mind ; third, those that change between mind and deprivation of it. Every soul is an incorporeal essence and separable from the body 1 . For since it knows that which is above it, namely, mind and intellectual things in their purity, much more is it the nature of the soul to know itself. Now that which knows itself turns back upon itself. And that which turns back upon itself is neither body nor inseparable from body; for the mere turning back upon itself, of which body is incapable, necessitates separability. Every soul is indestructible and incorruptible. For everything that can in any way be dissolved and destroyed is either corporeal and composite or has its existence in a subject. That which is dissolved undergoes corruption as consisting of a multitude of divisible parts ; that of which it is the nature to exist in another, being separated from its subject vanishes into not- being. But the soul comes under neither of these determina- tions; existent as it is in the act of turning back upon itself. Hence it is indestructible and incorruptible. Proclus now goes on to define more exactly the characters of the soul in relation to things prior and posterior to it. It is self- subsistent and is the principle of life to itself and to all that participates in it. As it is a mean between things primarily indivisible and those that have the divisibility belonging to body, so also it is a mean between things wholly eternal and those that are wholly temporal. Eternal in essence and temporal in act, it is the first of things that have part in the world of generation. In the logical order of causes, it comes next after mind, and contains all the intellectual forms that mind possesses primarily. These it has by participation, and as products of the things before it. Things perceptible it anticipates in their pre-formed models {rrapahecyiiaTiKOis;)- Thus it holds the reasons of things material immaterially, and of corporeal 1 2-roix- ©eo\. 186. 12—2 180 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX things incorporeally, and of things apart in space without spatially separating them. Things intelligible, on the other hand, it receives in their expression by images (eUoviKw) ; divisibly the forms of those that are undivided, by multipli- cation the forms of those that are unitary, by self-motion the forms of those that are unmoved 1 . Every soul participated in has for its first organ an imperish- able body, ungenerated and incorruptible. For if every soul is imperishable in essence and primarily animates something corporeal, then, since its being is immutable, it animates it always. If that which has soul has it always, it also participates ever in the life of soul 2 . But that which is ever living ever is, that is to say, is imperishable 3 . All that participates in time yet is perpetually moved, is measured by circuits. For since things are determinate both in multitude and in magnitude, transition cannot go on through different collocations to infinity. On the other hand, the transitions of that which is ever moved can have no term. They must therefore go from the same to the same ; the time of the circuit furnishing the measure of the motion. Every mundane soul, since it passes without limit through transitions of which time is the measure, has circuits of its proper life, and restitutions to its former position 4 . While other souls have some particular time for the measure of their circuit, the circuit of the first soul measured by time coincides with the whole of time 5 . With greater distance of souls from the One there goes, according to the general principle already set forth, increase of 1 2-roix- ©eoX. 195. Cf. Arist. De An. iii. 8, 431 b 21 : j\ \pvxh to. ovra irws earn iravra. 2 Stoix- ©eoX. 196 : el de rovro rb \pvxov/J.evoi> del \J/vxovto.i, Kal del /wt<?x« 3 The chief propositions on the imperishable vehicle of the soul are to be found near the end of the treatise (207—10). The substance of tbeni is that, in the descent and reascent of the particular soul, extraneous material clothings are in turn put upon the vehicle and stripped off from it ; the vehicle itself remaining impassible. 4 2toix- OeoX. 199 : waaa yj/vxh ejK6a/xios ireptodois XPV TaL T V* olxeias fays Kal aTTOKa.Ta<jTdcreaii>. . . .Trdcra yap Trepiodos twv dXSitav dwoKaTaiTTaTiKT] e<m. 5 Srotx- OeoX. 200. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 181 number and diminution of casual efficacy 1 . Every particular soul may descend to birth infinite times and reascend from birth to being. For it now follows after the divine and now falls away; and such alternation must evidently be recurrent. The soul cannot be an infinite time among the gods, and then the whole succeeding time among bodies; for that which has no temporal beginning can never have an end, and that which has no end necessarily has no beginning 2 . Every particular soul, descending to birth, descends as a whole, It does not partly remain above and partly descend. For if part of the soul remains in the intelligible world, it must either think ever without transition, or by a transitive process. But if without transition, then it thinks as pure intellect, and not as a part of the soul ; and so must be the soul immediately participating in mind, that is, the general soul. If it thinks by a transitive process, then, out of that which always thinks and that which sometimes thinks one essence is composed. But this also is impossible. Besides, it is absurd that the highest part of the soul, being, as it is if it does not descend, ever perfect, should not rule the other powers and make them also perfect. Every particular soul therefore descends as a whole 3 . 3. The End of the Platonic Succession, Of the successors to Plato's chair after Proclus, the most noteworthy was Damascius, the last of all. A native of Damascus, he had studied at Alexandria and at Athens. Among his teachers was Marinus, the immediate successor and the biographer of Proclus. The skill in dialectic for which he was celebrated, he himself attributed to the instruc- tions of Isidore, his predecessor in the chair, whose biography he wrote 4 . In an extensive work on First Principles ('ATropicu 1 Srotx- ©eoX. 203. 2 Srotx- 0eo\. 206 : Xeiirerai apa vepidSovs iKaar-qv iroieiadai av68wv re in ttjs yev£<TiW ko.1 twv els ytvevLv Kadoduv, teal tovto a.irav<TTOi> dvai dtdrdv aireipov XP 0V0V • eK&arr) apa ^I'X?? P-epiKV KaTievai re eV direipov dvvarai ko.1 aviivai. /cat tovto ov p.r) iravatTai T€pl airdaas rb irddijfJ.a yevd/xevou. 3 Sroix- 0«oX. 211. 4 The fragments of this, preserved by Photius, are printed in the appendix to the Didot edition of Diogenes Laertius. 182 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX /cai XvaeLs nepl twv Trpo&rwv ap-^oov) 1 , he maintained with the utmost elaboration that the principle of things is unknowable. This we have met with as a general position in Proclus 2 ; and it is already laid down distinctly by Plotinus, who says for example that we can learn by intellect that the One is, but not what it is. Even to call it the One is rather to deny of it plurality than to assert any truth regarding it that can be grasped by the intelligence 3 . Still, with Plotinus and Proclus, this is more a recognition of the inadequacy of all forms of thought to convey true knowledge of the principle which is the source of thought, than a doctrine standing out by itself as the last word of their philosophy. Damascius on the other hand seems to exhaust human language in the effort to make plain how absolutely unknowable the principle is 4 . Thus his doctrine has the effect of a new departure, and presents itself as the most definitely agnostic phase of ancient metaphysics. Zeller treats this renunciation of all knowledge of the principle as a symptom of the exhaustion of Greek philosophy ; a view which perhaps, at certain points of time, would not have allowed us to hope much more from modern philosophy. The ancient schools, however, did not die till a final blow was struck at them on behalf of the spiritual authority that now ruled the world. It may be read in Gibbon how the Emperor Justinian (527 — 565), while he directed the codification of the Roman law, succeeded in effacing in considerable measure the record of stages of jurisprudence less conformable to the later imperial absolutism. To make that absolutism unbroken even in name, he afterwards suppressed the Roman Consulship, which had 1 About half of this work was edited by Kopp in 1826 ; the whole by Ruelle in 1889. In 1898 was published a complete French translation by M. Chaignet in three volumes. '<■ 2toi X - ©eo\. 123. 3 Enn. v. 5, 6 : to 5e olov arjixaivoi. av to oi>x olov ' ov yap Hvi ovde to olov, otoi ^Se to tI Taxa Se /ecu to £v 6vop.a tovto apo~iv ex ei Tpos to. woWti, bdev /ecu 'Av6\\uva ot YlvdayopiKol avp.(3o\iKu>s irpbs a\\ri\ovs eo~r)p.aivov airocpaaei twv ttoXXQv. 4 Cf. R. P. 545 : ko.1 tI -n-ipas ^crrat tov \6yov ttXtjv criyrjs 6.p.rjxd.vov Kol 6p,o\oylas tov p.7]deu yivwaKeiv w pLTjde de/xis, ddwaTWi/ ovtwv eh yvwcnv eXdeiv ; IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 183 gone on till his time. Before the completion of his Code — the great positive achievement to which he owes his fame — he had already promulgated a decree for securing uniformity in the spiritual sphere. So far, in spite of the formal prohibition of the ancient religion, the philosophers at Athens had retained some freedom to oppose Christian positions on speculative questions. This seems clear from the fact that Proclus had been able to issue a tractate in which he set forth the arguments for the perpetuity of the world against the Christian doctrine of creation 1 . Justinian, who was desirous of a reputation for strictness of orthodoxy, resolved that even this freedom should cease; and in 529 he enacted that henceforth no one should teach the ancient philosophy. In the previous year, when there was a " great persecution of the Greeks " (that is, of all who showed attachment to the ancient religion), it had been made a law that those who " Hellenised " should be incapable of holding offices. Suppression of the philosophical lectures was accompanied by confiscation of the endowments of the school. And these were private endowments ; the public payments to the occupants of the chairs having long ceased 2 . The liberty of philosophising was now everywhere brought within the limits prescribed by the Christian Church. Not till the dawn of modern Europe was a larger freedom to be reassumed ; and not even then without peril. The narrative of the historian Agathias (fl. 570) is well known, how Damascius, Simplicius, Eulalius, Priscianus, Her- mias, Diogenes and Isidorus departed from Athens for Persia, having been invited by King Chosroes (Khosru Nushirvan), and hoping to find in the East an ideal kingdom and a philosophic king 3 . Though Chosroes himself was not without a real interest in philosophy, as he showed by the translations he caused to be made of Platonic and Aristotelian writings, their expectations were thoroughly disappointed. They found 1 A reply to the 'ETnx«-py/J-a- T a Kara. XpicrTiavwv of Proclus was written by Joannes Philoponus, in the form of a lengthy work (now included in the Teubner Series) bearing the title I)e Aeternitate Mundi. 2 See, for the evidence as to the exact circumstances of the suppression, Zeller, iii. 2, pp. 849—50, with notes. Of. R. P. 547 c. ;i P. P. 547. 184 THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL [iX that the genuine unmodified East was worse than the Roman Empire in its decline. At length they entreated to return to their own country under any conditions ; and Chosroes, though pressing them to stay, not only allowed them to go, but in a special clause of a treaty of peace with Justinian, stipulated that they should not be constrained to forsake their own opinions, but should retain their freedom while they lived. This was in 533. The date of their voluntary exile was probably 532. After their return, as has been already indicated, the philosophers devoted themselves to the writing of learned commentaries. The most illustrious of the commentators was Simplicius, whose works on Aristotle's Categories, Physics, Be Caelo and De Anima, and on the Encheiridion of Epictetus, are extant. Even this last period was not marked by complete inability to enter on a new path. What the speculative exhaustion animadverted on by Zeller really led to was a return to the most positive kind of knowledge that then seemed attain- able. Aristotle now came to be studied with renewed zeal ; and it was in fact by a tradition from the very close of antiquity that he afterwards acquired his predominant authority, first among the Arabians and then among the schoolmen of the West 1 . The last Neo-Platonists thus had the merit of compre- hending his unapproached greatness as the master in antiquity of all human and natural knowledge. If to some extent they were wrong in trying to prove his thoroughgoing agreement with Plato, their view was at any rate nearer the mark than that which makes the two philosophers types of opposition. The most recent students of Plato would perfectly agree with one at least of the distinctions by which Simplicius reconciles apparently conflicting positions. When Plato, he says, describes the world as having come to be, he means that it proceeds from a higher cause ; when Aristotle describes it as not having become, he means that it has no beginning in time 2 . Apart from learned research, subtleties may still be found in the commentators that had never before been expressed with such 1 Cf. Kenan, Averroes et VAverroisme, pp. 92 — 3. 2 Zeller, iii. 2, p. 84(3. Cf. Archer-Hind, The Timaeus of Plato. IX] THE ATHENIAN SCHOOL 185 precision. For the rest, they are themselves as conscious of the decline as their modern critics. What they actually did was in truth all that was possible, and the very thing that was needed, in their own age. To the latest period, as was said at the beginning of the chapter, belong the names of several Alexandrian teachers. Among these are Hermias, the pupil of Syrianus ; Ammonius, the son of Hermias and the pupil of Proclus 1 ; Asclepiodotus, a physician, who, according to Damascius, surpassed all his contemporaries in knowledge of mathematics and natural science ; and Olympiodorus, a pupil of Ammonius and the last teacher of the Platonic philosophy whose name has been preserved. Commentaries by Hermias and Ammonius, as well as by Olympiodorus, are still extant. An exhaustive history of Neo-Platonism would find in the writings of the Athenian school materials especially abundant. Much has been printed, though many works still remain un- published. In the present chapter, only a very general account is attempted. The object, here as elsewhere, has been to bring out the essential originality of the Neo-Platonic movement ; not to trace minutely the various currents that contributed to its formation and those into which it afterwards diverged as it passed into later systems of culture. To follow, " per incertam lunam sub luce maligna," the exact ways by which it modified the culture of mediaeval Europe, would be a work of research for a separate volume. The general direction, however, and its principal stages, are sufficiently clear ; and some attempt will be made in the next chapter to trace first the continued influence of Neo-Platonism in the Middle Ages, and then its renewed influence at the Renaissance and in modern times. For the earliest period — for the unmistakably "dark ages" of the West — the transmission was in great part through Christian writers, who, living at the close of the ancient world, had received instruction as pupils in the still surviving philosophic schools. 1 Joannes Philoponus (11. 530), the Christian commentator on Aristotle, had Ammonius for his teacher, and quotes him as " the philosopher." See Zeller, iii. 2, p. 829, n. 4. CHAPTER X. THE INFLUENCE OF NEO-PLATONISM. The influence of Neo-Platonism on the official Christian philosophy of the succeeding period was mainly in the de- partment of psychology. Biblical psychology by itself did not of course fix any determinate scientific view. Its literal interpretation might seem, if anything, favourable to a kind of materialism combined with supernaturalism, like that of Tertullian. Even the Pauline conception of " spirit," regarded at once as an infusion of Deity and as the highest part of the human soul, lent itself quite easily to a doctrine like that of the Stoics, which identified the divine principle in the world with the corporeal element most remote by its lightness and mobility from gross matter. For a system, however, that was to claim on behalf of its supernatural dogmas a certain justi- fication by human reason as a preliminary condition to their full reception by faith, the idea of purely immaterial soul and mind was evidently better adapted. This conception, taken over for the practical purposes of the Church in the scientific form given to it by the Neo-Platonists, has accordingly main-, tained its ground ever since. The occasional attempts in modern times by sincerely orthodox Christians to fall back upon an exclusive belief in the resurrection of the body, interpreted in a materialistic sense, as against the heathen doctrine of the natural immortality of the soul, have never gained any appreciable following. At the end of the ancient X] THE INFLUENCE OF NEO-PLATONISM 187 world Platonic idealism, so far as it was compatible with the dualism necessitated by certain portions of the dogmatic system, was decisively adopted. In the East, Greek ecclesias- tical writers such as Nemesius (fl. 450), who had derived their culture from Neo-Platonism, transmitted its refutations of materialism to the next age. In the West, St Augustine, who, as is known, was profoundly influenced by Platonism, and who had read Plotinus in a Latin translation, performed the same philosophical service. The great positive result was to familiarise the European mind with the elements of certain metaphysical conceptions elaborated by the latest school of independent philosophy. When the time came for renewed independence, long practice with abstractions had made it easier than it had ever hitherto been — difficult as it still was — to set out in the pursuit of philosophic truth from a primarily subjective point of view. It was long, however, before Western Europe could even begin to fashion for itself new instruments by provisionally working within the prescribed circle of revealed dogma and subordinated philosophy. The very beginning of Scholasticism is divided by a gulf of more than three centuries from the end of Neo-Platonism ; and not for about two centuries more did this lead to any continuous intellectual movement. In the meantime, the elements of culture that remained had been transmitted by Neo-Platonists or writers influenced by them. An especially important position in this respect is held by Boethius, who was born at Rome about 480, was Consul in 510, and was executed by order of Theodoric in 524. In philosophy Boethius represents an eclectic Neo-Platonism turned to ethical account. His translation of Porphyry's logical work has already been mentioned. He also devoted works of his own to the exposition of Aristotle's logic. It was when he had fallen into disgrace with Theodoric that he wrote the Be Consolation 1 Plrilosophiae ; and the remarkable fact has often been noticed that, although certainly a nominal Christian, he turned in adversity wholly to heathen philosophy, not making the slightest allusion anywhere to the Christian revelation. The vogue of the Be Consolatione in the Middle Ages is equally 188 THE INFLUENCE [X noteworthy. Rulers like Alfred, eagerly desirous of spreading all the light that was accessible, seem to have been drawn by a secret instinct to the work of a man of kindred race, who, though at the extreme bound, had still been in living contact with the indigenous culture of the old European world. Another work much read in the same period was the commentary of Macrobius (fl. 400) on the Somnium Scipionis extracted from Cicero's Be Republica. Macrobius seems not to have been even a nominal Christian. He quotes Neo-Platonist writers, and, by the impress he has received from their type of thinking, furnishes evidence of the knowledge there was of them in the West. In the East some influence on theological metaphysics was exercised by Synesius, the friend of Hypatia. Having become a Christian, Synesius unwillingly allowed himself to be made Bishop of Ptolemais (about 410); seeking to reserve the philosophical liberty to treat portions of popular Christianity as mythical, but not quite convinced that this was compatible with the episcopal office. A deeper influence of the same kind, extending to the West, came from the works of the writer known under the name of that " Dionysius the Areopagite " who is mentioned among the converts of St Paul at Athens (Acts xvii. 34). As no incontestable reference to those works is found till the sixth century, and as they are characterised by ideas distinctive of the school of Proclus, it is now held that they proceeded from some Christian Platonist trained in the Athenian school. It is possible indeed that the real Dionysius had been a hearer of Proclus himself. We learn from Marin us 1 that not all who attended his lectures were his philosophical disciples. The influence of the series of works, in so far as they were accepted officially, was to fix the "angelology" of the Church in a learned form. They also gave a powerful impulse to Christian mysticism, and, through Scotus Erigena, set going the pantheistic speculations which, as soon as thought once more awoke, began to trouble the faith. When, about the middle of the ninth century, there emerges 1 Vita Prodi, 38. X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 189 the isolated figure of John Scotus Erigena, we may say, far as we still are from anything that can be called sunrise, that "now at last the sacred influence Of light appears, and from the walls of Heaven Shoots far into the bosom of dim Night A glimmering dawn." He has been regarded both as a belated Neo-Platonist and as the first of the Scholastics. In reality he cannot be classed as a Neo-Platonist, for his whole effort was directed towards rationalising that system of dogmatic belief which the Neo- Platonists had opposed from the profouudest intellectual and ethical antipathy. On the other hand, he was deeply influenced by the forms of Neo-Platonic thought transmitted through Dionysius, whose works he translated into Latin ; and his own speculations soon excited the suspicion of ecclesiastical authority. His greatest work, the De Divisione Naturae, was in 1225 con- demned by Pope Honorius III. to be burned. Scotus had, however, begun the characteristic movement of Christian Scholasticism. And Dionysius, who could not well be anathe- matised consistently with the accredited view about the authorship of his writings — who indeed was canonised, and came to be identified with St Denys of France — had been made current in Latin just at the moment when the knowledge of Greek had all but vanished from the West. The first period of Scholasticism presents a great gap between Scotus and the next considerable thinkers, who do not appear before the latter part of the eleventh century. Towards the end of the twelfth century, the second period begins through the influx of new Aristotelian writings and of the commentaries upon them by the Arabians. The Arabians themselves, on settling down after their conquest of Western Asia, had found Aristotle already translated into Syriac. Trans- lations were made from Syriac into Arabic. These translations and the Arabian commentaries on them were now translated into Latin, sometimes through Hebrew; the Jews being at this time again the great intermediaries between Asia and Europe. Not long after, translations were made directly from the Greek 190 THE INFLUENCE [X texts preserved at Constantinople. Thus Western Europe acquired the complete body of Aristotle's logical writings, of which it had hitherto only possessed a part ; and, for the first time since its faint re-awakening to intellectual life, it was put in possession of the works dealing with the content as well as the form of philosophy. After prohibiting more than once the reading of the newly recovered writings, and in particular of the Physics and Metaphysics, the ecclesiastical chiefs at length authorised them; having come to see in the theism of Aristotle, which they were now able to discriminate from the pantheism of pseudo-Aristotelian writings, a preparation for the faith. It is from this period that the predominating scientific authority of Aristotle in the Christian schools must be dated. Taken over as a tradition from the Arabians, it had been by them received from the latest commentators of the Athenian school of Neo- Platonism. The Arabian philosophy, highly interesting in itself, is still more interesting to us for its effect on the intellectual life of Europe. Aristotelian in basis, it was Neo-Platonic in super- structure. Its distinctive doctrine of an impersonal immortality of the general human intellect is, however, as contrasted both with Aristotelianism and with Neo-Platon ism, essentially original. This originality it does not owe to Mohammedanism. Its affinity is rather with Persian and Indian mysticism. Not that Mohammedanism wanted a speculative life of its own ; but that which is known to history as " Arabian philosophy " did not belong to that life 1 . The proper intellectual life of Islam was in "theology." From the sharp antagonism which sprang up between the Arabian philosophers and " theologians " seems to date the antithesis which became current especially in the Europe of the Renaissance. For the Greek philosophers, " theology " had meant first a poetic exposition of myths, but with the implication that they contained, either directly or when allegorised, some theory of the origin of things. Sometimes — as occasionally in Aristotle and oftener in the Neo-Platonists — it meant the highest, or metaphysical, part of philosophy. It 1 See Eenan, Averroes et VAverrolsme, ch. ii. X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 191 was the doctrine of God as first principle of things, and was accordingly the expression of pure speculative reason. With Islam, as with Christianity, it might mean this ; but it meant also a traditional creed imposed by the authority of Church and State. The creed contained many articles which philosophy might or might not arrive at by the free exercise of reason. To the Mohammedan "theologian," however, these were not points which it was permissible to question, except hypotheti- cally, but principles to argue from. Hence the "philosophers," having made acquaintance with the intellectual liberty of Greece, which they were seeking to naturalise in Arabian science, were led to adopt the custom of describing distinctively as a "theo- logian " one who speculated under external authority and with a practical purpose. Of course the philosophers claimed to deal equally — or, rather, at a higher level — with divine objects of speculation ; but, according to their own view, they were not bound by the definitions of the theologian. At the same time, they were to defer to theology in popular modes of speech, allowing a "theological" truth, or truth reduced to what the multitude could profit by, in distinction from" philosophical" or pure truth. The Jews and the Christians too, they allowed, were in possession of theological truth ; each religion being good and sufficient in practice for the peoples with whom it was traditional. The reason of this procedure — which has no precise analogue either in ancient or in modern times — was that the Arabian Hellenising movement was pantheistic, while the three religious known to the philosophers all held to the personality of God. Hence the Arabian philosophy could not, like later Deism, find what it regarded as philosophic truth by denuding all three religions of their discrepant elements. Since they were expressed in rigorously defined creeds, it could not allegorise them as the ancient philosophers had allegorised polytheism. Nor was the method open to it of ostensibly founding a new sect. The dominant religions were theocratic, claiming the right, which was also the duty, of persecution. The consequence was, formulation of the strange doctrine known as that of the " double truth." Under the dominion of Islam, the "philosophers," in spite of 192 THE INFLUENCE [X their distinction between the two kinds of truth, were treated by the " theologians " as a hostile sect and reduced to silence. Their distinction, however, penetrated to Christian Europe, where, though condemned by Church Councils, it long held its ground as a defence against accusations of heresy. The ortho- dox distinction between two spheres of truth, to be investigated by different methods but ultimately not in contradiction, may easily be put in its place. Hence a certain elusiveness which no doubt helped to give it vogue in a society not inwardly quite submissive to the authority of the Church even at the time when the theocracy had apparently crushed all secular and intellectual opposition. The profundity of the revolt is evident alike in the philosophical and in the religious move- ments that marked the close of the twelfth and the opening of the thirteenth century. The ideas that animated both movements were of singular audacity. In philosophy, the intellectual abstractions of Neo-Platonism, and in particular the abstraction of " matter," were made the ground for a revived naturalistic pantheism. Ideas of " absorption," or im- personal immortality, genuinely Eastern in spirit, may have appealed as speculations to the contemplative ascetics of Orientalised Europe. These were not the only ideas that came to the surface. In common with its dogmas, the Catholic hierarchy was threatened ; and, to suppress the uprising, the City of Dis on earth was completed by the Dominican Inquisition. Yet philosophy, so far as it could be made sub- servient to orthodoxy, was to be a most important element in the training of the Dominicans themselves. From their Order proceeded Thomas Aquinas, the most systematic thinker of the Middle Ages, at whose hands scholastic Aristotelianism received its consummate perfection. Against older heresies, against " Averroism," against the pantheism of heterodox schoolmen, the Angelic Doctor furnished arguments acceptable to orthodoxy, marshalled in syllogistic array. For a short time, his system could intellectually satisfy minds of the highest power, skilled in all the learning of their age, if only they were in feeling at one with the dominant faith. Over and above its indirect influence through the psy- X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 1 !>3 chology of the Fathers, Neo-Platonic thought found direct admission into the orthodox no less than into the heterodox speculation of the Scholastic period. Aquinas quotes largely from Dionysius; and Dante was, as is well known, a student both of Aquinas and of Dionysius himself, whose classification of the " Heavenly Hierarchy " he regarded as a direct revelation communicated by St Paul to his Athenian proselyte. Thus, if we find Neo-Platonic ideas in Dante, there is no difficulty about their source. The line of derivation goes straight back to the teaching of Proclus. We are not reduced to the supposition of an indirect influence from Plotinus through St Augustine. Incidental Neo-Platonic expressions in Dante have not escaped notice 1 . More interesting, however, than any detailed coinci- dence is the fundamental identity of the poet's conception of the beatific vision with the vision of the intelligible world as figured by Plotinus. Almost equally prominent is the use he makes of the speculative conception of emanation. That the higher cause remains in itself while producing that which is next to it in order of being, is affirmed by Dante in terms that might have come directly from Plotinus or Proclus 2 . And it is essentially by the idea of emanation that he explains and justifies the varying degrees of perfection in created things. The Neo-Platonism of the Divina Commedia, as might be expected, is found almost exclusively in the Paradiso ; though one well-known passage in the Purgatorio, describing the mode in which the disembodied soul shapes for itself a new material envelope, bears obvious marks of the same influence. Here, however, there is an important difference. Dante renders 1 Some of them are referred to by Bouillet in the notes to his French translation of the Enneads (1857 — 61). Here, for want of a more appropriate place, it may be mentioned that there is no complete translation of the Enneads into English. The marvellous industry of Thomas Taylor, "the Platonist," in translating Neo-Platonic writings, did not carry him through the whole of Plotinus. The portions translated by him have been reprinted for the Theosophical Society in Bonn's Series. 2 Tbe general thought finds expression at the end of Par. xxix. " 1' eterno Valor... Uno manendo in se come davanti." w. 13 194 THE INFLUENCE [X everything in terms of extension, and never, like the Neo- Platonists, arrives at the direct assertion, without symbol, of pure immaterialism. This may be seen in the passage just referred to, as compared with a passage from Porphyry's exposition of Plotinus closely resembling it in thought. While Dante represents the soul as having an actual path from one point of space to another, Porphyry distinctly says that the soul's essence has no locality, but only takes upon itself relations depending on conformity between its dispositions and those of a particular body ; the body, whether of grosser or of finer matter, undergoing local movement in accordance with its own nature and not with the nature of soul 1 . Again, the point of exact coincidence between Dante and Plotinus in what they say of the communications between souls that are in the world of being, is that, for both alike, every soul "there" knows the thought of every other without need of speech. Plotinus, however, says explicitly that the individualised intelligences within universal mind are together yet discriminated without any reference to space. What Dante says is that while the souls are not really in the planetary spheres, but only appear in them momentarily, they are really above in the empyrean. Even in his representation of the Deity, the Christian poet still retains his spatial symbolism. God is seen as the minutest and intensest point of light, round which the angels— who are the movers of the spheres — revolve in their ninefold order. At the same time, the divine mind is said to be the place of the primum mobile, thus enclosing the whole universe 2 . Viewed in relation to the universe as distinguished from its cause, the angelic movers are in inverted order, the outermost and not the innermost being now the highest. Thus, by symbol, it is finally 1 Cf. Purg. xxv. 85 — 102 and Sententiae, 32. Porphyry is explaining the way in which the soul may be said to descend to Hades, eVet 5e 5t??/cet to fiapv irvevfxa /cat 'ivvypov dxpL tQiv inroyeitcv tottujv, ovtu /cat avTt] A^yerat xwptiv vtto yr/v ■ ov\otl ij avrr) ovaia fi€Taj3alv€i tottovs, /cat e'c t6ttols ylverai' dXX' oti tu>v ire<pvKOTLcv (rwp.a.Twv rdwovs ixeTafiaiveiv, /cat eiXrixevai tottovs, ux^Cf'S dvadexerai, dexo/J^euuv avTrjv /cara ras e7nTr)5ei6T7]Tas twv tolovtoiv crw/xdrwi' e/c ttjs /car' o.vtt)v iroids diadtaews. 2 "E questo cielo non ha altro dove Che la mente divina.'' Par. xxvii. 109—110. X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 195 suggested that immaterial essence is beyond the distinction of the great and the small in magnitude ; but even at the end the symbolism has not disappeared. Like the completed theocratic organisation of society, the Scholastic system which furnished its intellectual justification was hardly finished before it began to break up from within. St Thomas Aquinas was followed by John Duns Scotus, who, while equally orthodox in belief, limited more the demonstrative power of reason in relation to ecclesiastical dogma. Soon after came William of Ockham, whose orthodoxy is to some extent ambiguous. The criticisms of the Subtle and of the Invincible Doctor had for their effect to show the illusoriness of the syste- matic harmony which their great predecessor seemed to have given once for all to the structure composed of dominant Catholic theology and subordinated Aristotelian philosophy. Duns Scotus was indirectly influenced by Neo-Platonism, which came to him from the Jewish thinker Ibn Gebirol, known to the schoolmen as Avicebron. This was the source of his theory of a " first matter " which is an element in the composition of intellectual as of corporeal substances. His view that the " principle of individuation " is not matter but form, coincides with that of Plotinus. Ockham was a thinker of a different cast, representing, as against the Platonic Realism of Duns Scotus, the most developed form of mediaeval Nominalism. In their different ways, both developments contributed to upset the balance of the Scholastic eirenicon between science and faith. The rapidity with which the decomposition was now going on may be judged from the fact that Ockham died about 1349, that is, before the end of the half-century which had seen the composition of the Divina Commedia. The end of Scholasticism as a system appealing to the living world is usually placed about the middle of the fifteenth century. From that time, it became first an obstruction in the way of newer thought, and then a sectarian survival. The six centuries of its effective life are those during which Greek thought was wholly unknown in its sources to the West. John Scotus Erigena was one of the very last who had some knowledge of Greek before the study of it revived in the Italy of Petrarch 13—2 196 THE INFLUENCE [X and Boccaccio. For the new positive beginning of European culture, the classical revival, together with the impulse towards physical research, — represented among the schoolmen by Roger Bacon, — was the essential thing. In the familiar story of the rise of Humanism, the point that interests us here is that the first ancient system to be appropriated in its content, and not simply studied as a branch of erudition, was Platonism. And it was with the eyes of the Neo-Platonists that the Florentine Academy read Plato himself. Marsilio Ficino, having translated Plato, turned next to Plotinus. His Latin translation of the Enneads appeared in 1492 \ Platonism was now set by its new adherents against Aristo- telianism, whether in the Scholastic form or as restored by some who had begun to study it with the aid of the Greek instead of the Arabian commentaries. The name of Aristotle became for a time to jiearly all the innovators the synonym of intellectual oppression. The Platonists of the early Renaissance were sincere Christians in their own manner. This was not the manner of the Middle Age. The definitely articulated system of ecclesiastical dogma had no real part in their intellectual life. They were Christians in a general way ; in the details of their thinking they were Neo-Platonists. In relation to astrology and magic, indeed, they were Neo-Platonists of a less critical type than the ancient chiefs of the school. Belief in both magic and astrology, it is hardly necessary to say, had run down through the whole course of the intervening centuries ; so that there was little as yet in the atmosphere of the modern time that could lead to a renewal of the sceptical and critical sifting begun by thinkers like Plotinus and Porphyry. The influence of Christianity shows itself in the special stress laid on the religious aspect of Neo-Platonism. An example of this is to be met with at the end of Marsilio Ficino's translation of Plotinus. In the arguments prefixed to the closing chapters, Ficino tries to make Plotinus say definitely that the union of the soul with God, once attained, is perpetual. He has himself 1 The Greek was printed for the first time in 1580, when it appeared along with the translation. X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 197 a feeling that the attempt is not quite successful; and he rather contends that Plotinus was logically bound to make the affir- mation than that it is there in his very words. As a matter of fact, Plotinus has nowhere definitely made it ; and it seems inconsistent alike with his own position that differences of individuality proceed with necessity from eternal distinctions in the divine intellect, and with his hypothetical use of the Stoic doctrine that events recur in exactly repeated cycles. When he says that in the intelligible world, though not in earthly life, the vision is continuous, this does not by itself mean that the soul, when it has ascended, remains above without recurrent descents. It is true, nevertheless, that Plotinus and Porphyry did not so explicitly as their successors affirm that all particular souls are subject to perpetual vicissi- tude 1 . This point is of special interest because Ficino's interpre- tation may have helped to mislead Bruno, who, in a passage in the dedication of his Eroici Furori to Sir Philip Sidney, classes Plotinus, so far as this doctrine is concerned, with the " theologians." All the great philosophers except Plotinus, he says, have taught that the mutations in the destiny of souls are without term. On the other hand, all the great theologians except Origen have taught that the soul either attains final rest or is finally excluded from beatitude. The latter doctrine has a practical reference, and may be impressed on the many lest they should take things too lightly. The former is the expression of pure truth, and is to be taught to those who are capable of ruling themselves. Great as is for Plotinus the importance of the religious redemption to which his philosophy leads, the theoretic aspect of his system is here misapprehended. Nothing, however, could bring out more clearly than this pointed contrast, Bruno's own view. Coming near the end of Renaissance Platonism, as Ficino comes near its beginning, 1 Thus St Augustine could commend Porphyry for what he took to be the assertion that the soul, having once wholly ascended to the realm of being, can never redescend to birth. That any soul can remain perpetually lapsed is unquestionably contrary to the opinion both of Plotinus and of Porphyry. One of Porphyry's objections to Christianity was that it taught that doctrine. ) 198 THE INFLUENCE [X he marks the declared break with tradition and the effort after a completely independent philosophy. Other elements as well as Neo-Platonism contributed to Bruno's doctrine ; yet he too proceeds in his metaphysics from the Neo- Platonic school. In expression, he always falls back upon its terms. The system, indeed, undergoes profound modifications. Matter and Form, Nature and God, become antithetic names of a single reality, rather than extreme terms in a causal series descending from the highest to the lowest 1 . Side by side with the identity, however, the difference is retained, in order to express the " circle " in phenomenal things. In Bruno's cosmological view, modifications were of course introduced by his acceptance and extension of the Copernican astronomy. Yet he seeks to deduce this also from propositions of the Neo-Platonic metaphysics. The Neo-Platonists held, as he did, that the Cause is infinite in potency, and necessarily produces all that it can produce. The reason why they did not infer that the extended uni- verse is quantitatively infinite was that, like some moderns, they thought actual quantitative infinity an impossible con- ception. One of Bruno's most interesting points of contact with Plotinus is in his theory of the beautiful. For this he may have got the hint from the difference that had struck Plotinus between the emotion that accompanies pursuit of knowledge and beauty on the one hand, and mystical unification with the good on the other. By this unification, however, Plotinus does not mean moral virtue; so that when Bruno contrasts intellectual aspiration with a kind of stoical indifference to fortune, and treats it as a " defect " in comparison, because there is in the constantly baffled pursuit of absolute truth or beauty an element of pain, he is not closely following Plotinus. Yet in their account of the aspiration itself, the two thinkers agree. The fluctuation and pain in the aesthetic or intellectual life are insisted on by both. In Bruno indeed the thought is immensely 1 Identification of all in the unity of Substance is regarded by Vacherot as characterising Bruno's thought, in contrast with the Neo-Platonic "emanation." See Histoire Critique de VEcole d'Alexandrie, t. iii. p. 196. X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 199 expanded from the hint of Plotinus ; the Eroici Furori being a whole series of imaginative symbols interpreted as expressive of the same ardour towards " the unknown God of unachieved desire." There is here manifest a difference of temperament. Bruno had more of the restlessness which Plotinus finds in the soul of the artist and the theorist. Plotinus, along with his philosophical enthusiasm, had more of the detachment and repose of the religious mystic. The most striking difference between the Platonism of the Neo-Platonists and that of the Renaissance, is the stronger accentuation by the latter of naturalistic pantheism. This, though not absent in Neo-Platonism itself, is subordinate. Plotinus, as we saw, regards the heavenly bodies as divine, and can on occasion speak like Bruno of the earth as one of the stars. This side of his doctrine, however, is less prominent than his conception of intellectual and superessential divinity. With Bruno the reverse is the case. And Campanella too seizes on the naturalistic side of the doctrine to confound the despisers of the visible world. Among his philosophical poems there is one in particular which conveys precisely the feeling of the book of Plotinus against the Gnostics. " Deem you that only you have thought and sense, While heaven and all its wonders, sun and earth, Scorned in your dullness, lack intelligence ? Fool ! what produced you ? These things gave you birth : So have they mind and God 1 ." This tone of feeling, characteristic of the Renaissance, passed away during the prevalence of the new "mechanical philosophy," to reappear later when the biological sciences were making towards theories of vital evolution. It is thus no accident that it should then have been rendered by Goethe, who combined with his poetic genius original insight in biology. 1 Sonnet xix. in Symonds's translation. The original of the passage may be given for comparison. " Pensiti aver tu solo provvidenza, E '1 ciel la terra e 1' altre cose belle, Le quali sprezzi tu, starsene senza? Sciocco, d' onde se' nato tu? da quelle, Dunque ci e senno e Dio." 200 THE INFLUENCE [X While the Platonising movement was going on, other ancient doctrines had been independently revived. For the growth of the physical sciences, now cultivated afresh after long neglect, the revival of Atomism was especially important. The one scientific doctrine of antiquity which Neo-Platonism had been unable to turn to account was seen by modern physicists to be exactly that of which they were in need. Thus whether, like Descartes and Hobbes, they held that the universe is a plenum, or, with Democritus himself, affirmed the real existence of vacuum, all the physical thinkers of the seventeenth century thought of body, for the purposes of science, as corpuscular. Corpuscular physics was the common foundation of the " mechanical philosophy." Now it is worthy of note that the first distinctively Platonic revival, beyond the period we call the Renaissance, decisively adopted the corpuscular physics as not incompatible with "the true intellectual system of the universe." The Cambridge Platonists, as represented especially by Cudworth, did not, in their opposition to the naturalism of Hobbes, show any reactionary spirit in pure science ; but were so much awake to the growing ideas of the time that, even before the great impression made by Newton's work, they were able to remedy for themselves the omission that had limited the scientific resources of their ancient predecessors. And More, in appending his philosophical poem on The Infinity of Worlds to that on The Immortality of the Soul, does not shrink from appealing to the authority of Democritus, Epicurus and Lucretius in favour of those infinite worlds in space which the Neo-Platonists had rejected. Neither on this question nor on the kindred one as to the manifestation of Deity in a pheno- menal universe without past or future limit in time, does he commit himself to a final conclusion ; but evidently, after at first rejecting both infinities as involving impossibilities of conception, he inclined to the affirmation of both. The new metaphysical position that philosophy had in the meantime gained, was the subjective point of view fixed by Descartes as the principle of his " method for conducting the reason and seeking truth in the sciences." This, as has been indicated, was remotely Neo-Platonic in origin ; for the Neo- X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 201 Platonists had been the first to formulate accurately those conceptions of immaterial substance and of introspective con- sciousness which had acquired currency for the later world through the abstract language of the schools. Thus Descartes, with Scholasticism and Humanism behind him, could go in a summary way through the whole process, without immersing himself in one or the other as a form of erudition ; and could then start, so far as the problem of knowledge is concerned, where the ancients had left off. Knowledge of that which is within, they had found, is in the end the most certain. The originality of Descartes consisted in taking it as the most certain in the beginning. Having fixed the point of view, he could then proceed, from a few simple positions ostensibly put forward without appeal to authority, to construct a new frame- work for the sciences of the inner and of the outer world. Here was the beginning of idealism in its modern form. The other great innovation of the modern world in general principle, was the notion that there is a mode of systematically appealing to experience as the test of scientific truth ; that rational deduction, such as was still the main thing for Descartes, must be supplemented by, if not ultimately sub- ordinated to, the test of inductive verification. This, though not exclusively an English idea, has been mainly promoted by English thinkers, in its application first to the physical, and then, still more specially, to the mental sciences. In antiquity, experience had indeed been recognised as the beginning of knowledge in the genetic order. Its priority in this sense could be allowed by a school as rationalist as Neo-Platonism. It had not, however, even by the experiential schools, been rigorously defined as a test applicable to all true science. On this side Bacon and Locke, as on the other side Descartes, were the great philosophical initiators of the new time. The essential innovations of modern thought, as we see, were innovations in method. They did not of themselves suggest any new answer to questions about ultimate reality or the destiny of the universe. It is not that such answers have been lacking; but they have always remained, in one way or another, new formulations of old ones. The hope cherished by 202 THE INFLUENCE [X Bacon and Descartes that the moderns might at length cut themselves loose from the past and, by an infallible method, discover all attainable truth, has long been seen to be vain. Not only individual genius, but historical study of past ideas and systems, have become of more and not of less importance. The most original and typical ontologies of modern times are those of Spinoza and Leibniz; and, much as they owe to the newer developments of science and theory of knowledge, both are expressed by means of metaphysical conceptions that had taken shape during the last period of ancient thought. Pantheism and Monadism are not merely implicit in the Neo- Platonic doctrine; they receive clear formulation as different aspects of it. If, as some modern critics think, the two conceptions are not ultimately irreconcilable, the best hints for a solution may probably still be found in Plotinus. No one has ever been more conscious than he of the difficulty presented by the problem of comprehending as portions of one philosophical truth the reality of universal and that of in- dividual intellect. Perhaps the strongest testimony to the intrinsic value of the later Greek thought is Berkeley's Siris. For if that thought had really become obsolete, Berkeley was in every way pre- pared to perceive it. He had pushed the Cartesian reform as far as it would go, by reducing what Descartes still thought of as real extended substance to a system of phenomena un- consciousness. He had at the same time all the English regard for the test of experience, fortified by knowledge of what had been done in his own age in investigating nature. Thus, he had taken most decisively the two steps by which modern philosophy has made a definite advance. Besides, as a theologian, he might easily have assumed that anything there was of value in the work of thinkers who, living long after the opening of the Christian era, had been the most uncom- promising antagonists of the Christian Church, must have been long superseded. His own early Nominalism, which, as may be seen in Siris itself, he had never abandoned, might also have been expected to prejudice him against Platonic Realism. Yet it is precisely in the Neo-Platonists that Berkeley, near the X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 203 end of his philosophical career, found hints towards a tentative solution of ontological questions which he had at first thought to settle once for all by a resolutely logical carrying out of the principles of Descartes and Locke. It is true that in actual result Siris makes no advance on the original Neo-Platonic speculations, which are not really fused with Berkeley's own early doctrine, but are at most kept clear of contradiction with it. For all that, Siris furnishes the most decisive evidence of enduring vitality in a school of thought which, to Berkeley's age if to any since the classical revival, must have seemed entirely of the past. Berkeley's work here seems in a manner comparable with that of the Platonising English poets from Spenser to Shelley. The influence of Platonism on literature is, however, too wide a subject to be treated episodically. The one remark may be made, that not till modern times did it really begin to influence poetic art. In antiquity it had its theories of art, — varying greatly, as we have seen, from Plato to Plotinus, — but artistic production was never inspired by it. If poetic thought, as some think, is an anticipation of the future, this influence on poetry may be taken as further evidence that the ideas of the philosophy itself are still unexhausted. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the great controversies of metaphysics did not centre in Platonism. There is truth in the view that would make this first period of distinctively modern philosophy a kind of continuation of later Scholasticism, more than of the Renaissance which im- mediately preceded it. Its ostensible questions were about method. The usual division of its schools or phases by historians is into " Dogmatism " (by which is meant the rationalistic theory of certitude) and its opposite " Empiricism," followed by " Scepticism " and then by " Criticism." As these names show, it is concerned less with inquiry into the nature of reality than with the question how reality is to be known, or whether indeed knowledge of it is possible. And, with all its differences, the modern " Enlightenment " has this resemblance to Scholasticism, that a particular system of doctrine is always in the background, to which the controversy is tacitly referred. 204 THE INFLUENCE [X This system is in effect the special type of theism which the more rationalistic schoolmen undertook to prove as a preliminary to faith in the Catholic creed. Even in its non-Christian form, as with the "Deists," it is still of the Judaeo-Christian tradition. The assumption about the relation of God to the world is that the world was created by an act of will. Ordinary Rationalism is " dogmatic " by its assertion that " natural religion " of this type can be demonstrated. " Empiricism " usually holds that the same general positions can be established sufficiently on at least " probable " grounds. The Scepticism of Hume proceeds to show the failure of Empiricism — with which he sides philo- sophically as against Rationalism — to establish anything of the kind. Hume's philosophical questioning, while this was the practical reference which aroused so much feeling in his own age, had of course a wider reach. Yet when Kant, stirred by the impulse received from Hume, took up again from a " Critical " point of view the whole problem as to the possibility of knowledge, he too thought with a reference to the same practical centre of the controversy. Having destroyed the Wolffian " Dogmatism," he still aimed at reconstructing from its theoretical ruin a generalised theology of essentially the same type. For Kant, as for the line of thinkers closed by him, there was only one ontology seriously in question ; and that was Christian theism, with or without the Christian revelation. The German movement at the opening of the nineteenth century, if it did nothing else, considerably changed this aspect of things. In its aims, whatever may now be thought of its results, it was a return to ontology without presuppositions. The limited dogmatic system which was the centre of interest for the preceding period has for speculation passed out of sight. Spinoza perhaps on the positive side exercises a predominant influence ; but there are returns also to the thinkers of the Renaissance, to Neo-Platonism, and to the ancient systems of the East, now beginning to be known in Europe from trans- lations of their actual documents. A kind of Neo-Christianity too appears, which again treats Christian dogma in the spirit of the Gnostics or of Scotus Erigena. And all this is complicated X] OF NEO-PLATONISM 205 by the necessity imposed on every thinker of taking up a definite attitude to the Kantian criticism of knowledge. Among the systems of the time, that of Hegel in particular has fre- quently been compared to Neo-Platonism ; but here the resemblance is by no means close. The character of Hegel's system seems to have been determined mainly by its relation to preceding German philosophy and to Spinoza. Both on Spinoza himself and on Leibniz, the influence of Neo-Platonism, direct or indirect, was much more definite, and points of comparison might be sought with more profit. In Hegel, as in the other philosophers of the period, the resemblance is partly of a quite general kind. They are again ontologists, interested in more possibilities than in the assertion or denial of the rudiments of a single creed. But, knowing the historical position of the Neo-Platonists, they find in them many thoughts that agree with their personal tendencies. Up to this point the outline given of the course of later philosophy may, it seems to me, on the whole be regarded as abbreviated history. The next stage may perhaps be summed up as another return from ontology to questions about the possibility of knowledge, and to logical and methodological inquiries. To pursue further the attempt to characterise the successive stages of European thought would be to enter the region where no brief summary can fairly pretend to be a deposit of ascertained results. The best plan, from the point now reached, will be to try to state the law of philosophic development which the history of Neo-Platonism suggests ; and then to make some attempt to learn what positive value the doctrine may still have for the modern world. This will be the subject of the concluding chapter. CHAPTER XI. CONCLUSION. Once the Neo-Platonic period, instead of being left in shadow, is brought into clear historical light, the development of Greek philosophy from Thales to Proclus is seen to consist of two alternations from naturalism to idealism. The "physical" thinkers are followed by Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. Then, by a similar antithesis, the more developed naturalism of the Stoics and Epicureans is followed by the more developed idealism of the Neo-Platonists. The psychology of the Greeks has been brought by Prof. Siebeck under the order assigned by this law. Mr Benn has suggested the law as that of Greek philosophy in general, but without carrying it through in its application to the details 1 . When to the empirical formula the test of psychological deduction is applied, this seems to show that it must have a more general character — that it must be a law, not only of Greek thought, but of the thought of mankind. For evidently, as the objective and subjective points of view become distinguished, the mind must tend to view things first objectively, and then afterwards to make a reflective return on its own processes in knowing. Thus we ought to find universally that a phase of speculative naturalism — the ex- pression of the objective point of view — is followed, when 1 Both historians call the later phase Spiritualism, hut on etymological grounds Idealism is the preferable term. "Spirit" (irveu/xa), as Prof. Siebeck lias shown in his detailed history, was not used by the Greek philosophers themselves as the name of an immaterial principle. Xl] CONCLUSION 207 reflection begins to analyse things into appearances for mind, by a phase of idealism. Unfortunately, no exact verification of so extended a deduction can be made out. All that can be said is that the facts do not contradict it. The law, in the most general terms, may be stated thus : "Whenever there is a spontaneous development of philosophic thought beyond the stage of dependence on tradition, a natural- istic phase comes first and an idealistic phase second. In no intrinsic development, whether of individuals or of peoples, is there a reversal of the order. One or other of the phases, however, may be practically suppressed. An individual mind, or the mind of a people, may stop at naturalism, or after the most evanescent phase of it may go straight on to pure idealism. Where both phases definitely appear, as in the case of Greece, we must expect returns of the first, making a repeated rhythm. Further, we must take account of foreign influences, which may modify the intrinsic development. Also, when both stages have been passed through, and are represented by their own teachers, revivals of either may appear at any moment. Thus in modern Europe we can hardly expect to trace through the whole deve- lopment any law whatever. When thinkers began to break through the new tradition which had substituted itself for ancient mythology and philosophy alike, and had ruled through the Middle Ages, there was from the first a possibility, according to the temper of the individual mind, of reviving any phase of doctrine, naturalistic or idealistic, without respect to its order in the past. We may occasionally get a typical case of the law, as in the idealistic reaction of the Cambridge Platonists on the naturalism of Hobbes ; but we cannot expect anything like this uniformly. Two great national anomalies are the precisely opposite cases of India (that is, of the Hindus) and of China. Nowhere in Asia of course has there been that self-conscious break with traditional authority which we find in ancient Greece and in modern Europe ; in both of which cases, however, it must be remembered that the authoritative tradition has never ceased to exist, but has continued always, even in the most sceptical or rational periods, to possess more of direct popular power than 208 CONCLUSION [XI philosophy. The philosophies of India and of China are not formally distinct from their religions, and have not found it necessary to repudiate any religious belief simply as such. Still, each has a very distinct character of its own. The official philosophy of China is as purely naturalistic as that of India is idealistic. And in both cases the learned doctrine succeeds in giving a general direction to the mind of the people without appealing to force. With the Hindus, naturalism seems to have been an almost entirely suppressed phase of development. The traces of it found in some of the philosophic systems may be remains of an abortive attempt at a naturalistic view of things in India itself, or may be the result of a foreign influence such as that of Greek Atomism. On the other hand, the Taoism and the Buddhism of China are admittedly much reduced from the elevation they had at first, and have become new elements in popular superstition instead of idealistic philosophies. Bud- dhism of course is Indian ; and Taoism, in its original form perhaps the sole attempt at metaphysics by a native Chinese teacher, seems to have been an indeterminate pantheism, not strictly to be classed either as naturalistic or as idealistic. Both are officially in the shade as compared with Confucianism ; and this, while agnostic with regard to metaphysics, is as a philosophy fundamentally naturalistic ; adding to ancestral traditions about right conduct simply a very general idea of cosmic order as the theoretic basis for its ethical code. India and China being thus taken to represent one-sided evolutions of the human mind, we shall see in ancient Greece the normal sequence under a comparatively simplified form. In modern Europe we shall see a complex balance of the two tendencies. Turning from the question of historical law to that of philosophical truth, we may conjecture that the reflective process must somehow mark an advance in insight ; but that, if nothing is to be lost, it ought to resume in itself what has gone before. And, as a matter of fact, European idealists, both ancient and modern, have not been content unless they could incorporate objective science with their metaphysics. Thus we arrive at a kind of " law of three states " — tradition or mythology, naturalism, idealism. In its last two terms, this Xl] CONCLUSION 209 law seems to be an inversion of the sequence Comte sought to establish from the " metaphysical " to the " positive " stage ; naturalism being the philosophy underlying " positivism," while idealism is another name for " metaphysics." How then are we to explain Comte's own mental development ? For he undoubt- edly held that he himself had passed from tradition through " metaphysics " to " positivity." Exceptio probat regulam : " the exception tests the rule 1 ." In the first place, what Comte regarded as his own metaphysical stage was not metaphysics at all, but a very early mode of political thought in which he accepted from eighteenth century teachers their doctrine of abstract "natural rights." In the second place, his mental history really had a kind of metaphysical phase ; but this came after his strictly "positive" or naturalistic period. His later philosophy became subjective on two sides. Having at first regarded mathematics as the sufficient formal basis of all the sciences, he arrived later at the view that at the head of the philosophy of mathematics there ought to be set out a more general statement of principles. That is to say, his intention was to fill up the place that belongs properly to logic, which in its formal division is subjective. Again, in his later scheme, after the highest of the sciences, which he called "morality" — meaning really a psychology of the individual, placed after and not before sociology — there came his " subjective synthesis." This was an adumbration of metaphysics in the true sense of the term ; so that his circle of the sciences, beginning with formal principles of reasoning, would have completed itself by running into subjectivity at the other extreme. The apparently exceptional case of Comte therefore turns out to be a real confirmation of the law. However it may be with this proposed law of three states, there can be no doubt that a very highly developed form of idealism is represented by the Neo-Platonists. How does this stand in relation to modern thought ? An obvious position to take up would be to allow the merit of Plotinus and his suc- 1 See Mr Carveth KeacVs Logic, p. 214. w. H 210 CONCLUSION [XI cessors in scientifically elaborating the highest metaphysical conceptions, but to dismiss all their detailed ontology as of merely historic interest. Thus we should fall back upon a position suggested by Plato in the Philebus ; namely, that though there may be very little " dialectical," or, as we should now say, metaphysical knowledge, that little may be "pure 1 ." This, however, is too easy a way. The Neo-Platonic thought is, metaphysically, the maturest thought that the European world has seen. Our science, indeed, is more developed ; and so also, with regard to some special problems, is our theory of know- ledge. On the other hand, the modern time has nothing to show comparable to a continuous quest of truth about reality during a period of intellectual liberty that lasted for a thousand years. What it has to show, during a much shorter period of freedom, consists of isolated efforts, bounded by the national limitations of its philosophical schools. The essential ideas, therefore, of the ontology of Plotinus and Proclus may still be worth examining in no merely antiquarian spirit. A method of examination that suggests itself is to try whether, after all, something of the nature of verification may not be possible in metaphysics. The great defect of idealistic philosophy has been that so little can be deduced from it. The facts of nature do not, indeed, contradict it, but they seem to offer no retrospective confirmation of it. Now this, to judge from the analogy of science, may be owing to the extreme generality with which modern idealism is accustomed to state its positions. It is as if in physics we were reduced to an affirmation of the permanence of " matter " defined in Aristo- telian terminology. Let us try what can be made of an idealistic system that undertakes to tell us more than that reality is in some way to be expressed in terms of mind. Plotinus and Proclus, from their theory of being, make deduc- tions that concern the order of phenomena. Since their time, great discoveries have been made in phenomenal science. Do these tend to confirm or to contradict the deductions made from their metaphysical principles by the ancient thinkers ? ] Phileb. 58 c. XI] CONCLUSION 21 1 We must allow, of course, for the defective science of antiquity. The Neo-Platonists cannot be expected to hold any other than the Ptolemaic astronomy. They do not, however, profess to deduce the details of astronomy from their metaphysics. Just as with the moderns, much in the way of detail is regarded as given only by experience. That the universe has this precise constitution — if it has it — is known only as an empirical fact, not as a deduction from the nature of its cause. What the Neo-Platonists deduce metaphysically is not the geocentric system, but the stability of that system — or of any other — if it exists. Thus they do not agree with the Stoics ; who, though taking the same view about the present constitution of the universe, held that the system of earth with surrounding planetary and stellar spheres is periodically resolved into the primeval fire and again reconstituted, the resolution being accompanied by an enormous expansion of bulk. All such ideas of an immense total change from a given state of things to its opposite, Plotinus and his successors reject. Any cycle that they can allow involves only changes of distribution in a universe ordered always after the same general fashion. They cany this even into their interpretation of early thinkers like Empedocles. According to Simplicius, the periods of concentration and diffusion which alternate in his cosmogony were by Empedocles himself only assumed hypothetically, and to facilitate scientific analysis and synthesis 1 . For universal intellect, as all the Neo-Platonists say, is ever-existent and produces the cosmic order necessarily ; hence it does not pometimes act and sometimes remain inactive. Undeviating necessity, in its visible manifestation as in reality, belongs to the divinity above man as to the unconscious nature below him. Change of manifestation depending on apparently arbitrary choice between opposites belongs to man from his intermediate position. To attribute this to the divinity is mythological. There must therefore always be an ordered universe in which every form and grade of being is represented. The phenomenal world, flowing from intellectual being by a process that is 1 Be Caelo (E. P. 133 i.*). 14—2 212 CONCLUSION [XI necessary and as it were natural, is without temporal begin- ning or end. These propositions we are already familiar with ; and these are the essence of the deduction. Thus if the universe — whatever its detailed constitution may be — does not always as a whole manifest a rational order, the metaphysical principle is fundamentally wrong. To prove scientifically that the world points to an absolute temporal beginning, or that it is running down to an absolute temporal end, or even that it is as a whole alternately a chaos and a cosmos, would be a refu- tation of the form of idealism held by Plotinus. How then does modern science stand with regard to this position ? It may seem at first sight to contradict it. For does not the theory of cosmic evolution suppose just such immense periodic changes as were conceived by Empedocles, according to the most obvious interpretation of his words ? So far as the solar system is concerned, no doubt it does ; but the solar system is only a part of the universe. And there seems to be no scientific evidence for the theory that the universe as a whole has periods of evolution and dissolution. Indeed, the evidence points rather against this view. Astronomical ob- servers find existent worlds in all stages. This suggests that, to an observer on any planet, the stellar universe would always present the same general aspect, though never absolute identity of detail as compared with its aspect at any other point of time. For every formed system that undergoes dissolution, some other is evolved from the nebulae which we call relatively "primordial." Thus the total phenomenal manifestation of being remains always the same. If this view should gaiu strength with longer observa- tion, then science may return in the end to the Neo-Platonic cosmology on an enlarged scale, and again conceive of the whole as one stable order, subject to growth and decay only in its parts. At no time, as the metaphysician will say, is the mind of the universe wholly latent. There is no priority of sense to intellect in the whole. The apparent priority of matter, or of the sentiency of which matter is the phenomenon, is simply an imaginative representation of the evolutionary process in a single system, regarded in isolation from the universe of which it forms part. XI] CONCLUSION 213 That this view is demonstrated by science cannot of course be said. The evidence, however, is quite consistent with it, and seems to point to this rather than to any other of the possible views. The question being not yet scientifically settled, the idealism of Plotinus still offers itself, by the cosmology in which it issues, for verification or disproof. And empirical confirmation, if this were forthcoming, would be quite real as far as it goes, precisely because the metaphysical doctrine is not so very general as to be consistent with all possible facts. A scientific proof that the universe is running down to a state of unalterable fixation would refute it. To the speculative doctrine of Plotinus no very great addition, as we have seen, was made before Proclus. The additions Proclus was able to make have by historians as a rule been treated as useless complications, — multiplications of entities without necessity. Yet the power of Proclus as a thinker is not denied even by those who find little to admire in its results ; and it had undergone assiduous training. He may be said to have known in detail the whole history of ancient thought, scientific as well as philosophical, at a time when it could still be known without any great recourse to fragments and conjecture. And he came at the end of a perfectly con- tinuous movement. It is therefore of special interest to see how the metaphysical developments he arrived at appear in the light of discoveries made since the European community returned again to the systematic pursuit of knowledge. What is noteworthy first of all is the way in which, following Aristotle, he has incorporated with the idea of the one stable universe that of an upward movement in the processes that belong to the realm of birth. As we have seen, he distinctly says that in the order of genesis the imperfect comes before the perfect. And this is not meant simply in reference to the individual organism, where it is merely a genera- lised statement of obvious facts, but is applied on occasion to the history of science. Now the technical terms by which he expresses the philosophical idea of emanation admit of trans- ference to an evolutionary process in time through which its components may be supposed to become explicit. The 77730080? 214 CONCLUSION [XI and the eiriGrpo^rj, or the going forth from the metaphysical principle and the return to it, are not of course themselves processes of the universe in time. Yet there is no reason why they should not have respectively their temporal manifestations in its parts, so long as neither type of manifestation is supposed to be chronologically prior or posterior in relation to the whole. When the terms are thus applied, they find accurate expression in the idea of an evolution, and not of a lapse manifested chronologically, — with which " emanation " is sometimes con- founded. Primarily, it is the e-maTpofyri, rather than the 7T/3ooSo?, that becomes manifest as the upward movement. Indeed the term corresponds pretty closely to " involution," which, as Mr Spencer has said 1 , would more truly express the nature of the movement than " evolution." This process is seen in history when thought, by some great discovery, returns to its principle. The antithetic movement, which may be regarded as the manifestation of the 7r/>6oSo?, is seen when, for example, a great discovery is carried, as time goes on, into more and more minute details, or is gradually turned to practical applications. Thus it corresponds to most of what in modern times is called " progress." A corollary drawn by Proclus from his system, it may be noted, also suggests itself from the point of view of modern evolution. The highest and the lowest things, Proclus concludes, are simple ; "composition," or complexity, belongs to intermediate natures. An even more remarkable point of contact between the metaphysics of Proclus and later science is that which presents itself when we bring together his doctrine of the "divine henads " and the larger conceptions of modern astronomy. This doctrine, as we saw, is with Proclus abstract metaphysics. The One, he reasons, must be mediated to the remoter things by many unities, to each of which its own causal " chain " is attached. Elaborate as the theory is, it had, when put forth, hardly any concrete application. If, however, we liberate the metaphysics from the merely empirical part of the cosmology, a large and important application becomes clear. The primal One, as we know, is by Neo-Platonism identified with the 1 First Principles, 6th ed., p. 261. XI] CONCLUSION 215 Platonic Idea of the Good. Now this, with Plato, corresponds in the intelligible world to the sun in the visible world, and is its cause. But if, as Proclus concluded, the One must be mediated to particular beings by many divine unities, what constitution should we naturally suppose the visible universe to have ? Evidently, to each " henad " would correspond a single world which is one of many, each with its own sun. Thus the metaphysical conception of Proclus exactly prefigures the post-Copernican astronomy, for which each of the fixed stars is the centre of a planetary " chain," and the source of life to the living beings that appear there in the order of birth. From the infinite potency of the primal Cause, Bruno drew the inference that the universe must consist of actually in- numerable worlds. If we take the Neo-Platonic doctrine, not in its most generalised form — in which, as soon as we go beyond a single world, it might seem to issue naturally in an assertion of the quantitative infinite — but with the additions made to it by Proclus, the plurality of worlds certainly becomes more scientifically thinkable. For the "henads" — composing, as Proclus says, the plurality nearest to absolute unity — are finite in number. Quantitative infinity he in common with all the school rejects. A kind of infinity of space as a subjective form would have presented no difficulty. Indeed both the geometrical and the arithmetical infinite were allowed by Plotinus in something very like this sense. The difficulty was in the supposition that there are actually existent things in space which are infinite in number. The problem, of course, still remains as one of metaphysical inference. For there can be no astronomical proof either that the whole is finite or that it is infinite. An infinite real ethereal space, with a finite universe of gravitating matter — which seems to be the tacit supposition of those who argue from the fact of radiant heat that the sum of worlds is running down to an end — Bruno and his Neo-Platonic predecessors would alike have rejected. The Neo-Platonic idealism, it ought now to be evident, was far removed from the reproach of peculiar inability. to bring itself into relation with the things of time and space. If both finally baffle the attempt at complete mental comprehension, 216 CONCLUSION [XI this, the philosophers would have said, is because they are forms of becoming, and hence remain mixed with illusory imagination. Contrasted with the eternity of intellect, that which appears under those forms is in a sense unreal. The whole philosophy of " genesis," however largely conceived, be- comes again what it was for Parmenides, to whom the explanations of physics, though having truth as a coherent order in the world of appearance, where irav irXeov iarlv 6fxov <f>deo<i teal vvktos d(f>dvrov, t<T(OV dfKJiOTepCOV 1 , are yet false as compared with the unmixed truth of being. In whatever sense Parmenides conceived of being, the Neo- Platonists, as we know, conceived of it in the manner of idealism. Their idealistic ontology, not deprived of all its detail but merely of its local and temporal features, would, if accepted, clear up more things than the most ambitious of modern systems. That it does not in the end profess to make all things clear, should not be to a modern mind a reason for contemning it, but should rather tell in its favour. 1 Parmenides ap. Simplic. Phys. (R. P. 100). APPENDIX. I. The Communism of Plato. The feature of Plato's Republic that has drawn most general attention both in ancient and in modern times is its communism. This communism, however, had no place in the doctrine of his philosophical successors. And his system is in one important point quite opposed to that which is usual in modern socialism with its effort after equality. Some unremembered anticipation of this may have been caricatured by Aristophanes in the Ecclesiazusae: but the artifices in the comedy for maintaining strict "democratic justice " are of course the very antithesis of the Platonic conception, the essence of which is to cultivate to the highest point, by separa- tion of classes and by special training, every natural difference of faculty. Besides, the Platonic community of goods is applied only to the ruling philosophic class of guardians and to the military class of their auxiliaries. The industrial portion of the community is apparently left to the system of private property and commercial competition — though no doubt with just so much regulation from the guardians as is necessary to preserve the social health and keep down imposthumes. Now the interesting thing is that this offers something far more practicable than socialism of the modern indus- trial type. That this is so may be seen by bringing the Platonic community of goods into comparison with Mr Spencer's generalisations, in the third volume of his Principles oj Sociology, on the origin of " Pro- fessional Institutions." Mr Spencer shows that professional, as distinguished from industrial, institutions are all differentiated from the priesthood, which, along with the military class, forms the dominant part of the earliest specialised society. Now the re- muneration of all professional classes is for a long time public. 218 APPENDIX Like Plato's guardians, they receive support from the rest of the community, not so much for particular services as for constant readiness to perform certain kinds of service. And a sort of disinterested character long continues to be assumed in professional functions, so that the remuneration is formally a voluntary gift, and not the market price of the service immediately done. This is now looked upon as a " survival." The normal system is thought to be that in which every form of social activity is thrown into the competition of the market-place. Perhaps Mr Spencer himself takes this view. If, however, we follow out the clue supplied by his inductions, we are led to imagine a new transformation by which predominant industrialism might, having done its work, be dis- placed by a reform in the spirit though not according to the letter of the Platonic communism. Industrial institutions, as Mr Spencer says, are for the " susten- tation " of life ; professional institutions are for its " augmentation." Now, where there is to be augmentation, sustentation, and the activities subservient to it, must not be the direct aim of everyone in the community. Among Mr Spencer's "professional" activities, for example, are science and philosophy. The beginnings of these, Aristotle had already said, appeared among the Egyptian priests because they had leisure to speculate. As Hobbes put it, " leisure is the mother of philosophy." The same thing is recognised in Comte's social reconstruction, where, though individual property is retained, commercial competition is allowed only in the industrial sphere ; the class that corresponds to the higher class of Plato's guardians being supported publicly on condition of renouncing all claim to a private income. The diffei-ence of Comte's from Plato's scheme is that it is social and not directly political. Comte assigns no " secular power " to his ecclesiastical or philosophical class. What Mr Spencer's inductive conclusions also suggest is a social rather than a political transformation, but oue more generalised than Comte's. For the professional class, as conceived by Mr Spencer, includes much more than the philosophic and scientific class. It is far too differentiated to be restored to anything like the homo- geneity of an early priesthood. Hence it could not, as such, become a ruling class, either directly like Plato's guardians, or indirectly like the Comtean hierocracy. The point of the reform that suggests itself is this : if the whole social organism is ever to be brought under an ethical ideal of the APPENDIX 219 performance of social duties, transcending the conception of an unmitigated struggle for individual profit or subsistence, the class to begin with is the class which, by its origin, has already something of the disinterested character. The liberal professions must be, as it were, brought back to their original principles. The natural method of achieving this would be an extension of the system of public payment as opposed to quasi-commercial competition. Com- petition itself cannot be dispensed with ; but it would then be in view of selection or promotion by qualified judges, and do longer with a view to individual payments from members of the general community taken at random. Payments would be graduated but fixed ; not left to the chances of employment in each particular case. In short, the method would be that of the ecclesiastical and military professions, and of the Civil Service, generalised ; though it would no doubt be necessary, as Comte admitted in the case of teachers, to leave just enough liberty of private practice to guard against the repression of originality. To attempt such a reform from below, as is the idea of industrial socialism, is evidently chimerical. Industrial institutions have their first origin in the necessity of subsistence, not in an overflow of unconstrained energy ; and, so far as they are developed from within, they owe their development to the keenest desire for gain. Hence they cannot but be the last to be effectively "moralised." This is just as fatal to Comte's proposal that the supreme secular power should be handed over to the "industrial chiefs" as it is to "social democracy." A purely industrial society could not supply enough disinterested elements for the work of general regulation. The conclusion seems to be that competition with a view to individual profit must, as Plato and Comte equally recognised, be left in the industrial sphere because in that sphere it supplies the only natural and adequate motive of exertion ; but that, even there, it can only be carried on justly and humanely under political regulation by representatives of the whole com- munity. To constitute a complete political society, it is generally allowed that there must be diversity of interests. If we allow that there must also be disinterested elements, then it is evident that these can only be fitly developed by the reduction of material motives, within a certain portion of the society, to their lowest possible limit. The Platonic communism was the first attempt to solve this problem systematically instead of leaving it to accident. 220 APPENDIX II. The Gnostics. The most accurate appreciation of Gnosticism seems to me to be that of Lipsius in his extremely valuable article in Ersch and Gruber's Encyclopddie. What Lipsius especially makes clear is that Gnosticism was not in its essence a mixture of Christianity and Hellenism, but was a development of Christianity itself, re- garded as a revealed religion, into a speculative philosophy. In its highest philosophical development, which was the system of Valentinus and his successors, it took over elements both from Greek mythology and from Platonic philosophy ; but this was an accretion on the Judaeo-Christian elements that formed its nucleus. An earlier accretion was that which it received during its first period, when it was springing up in Syria. During this period, before it reached Alexandria, it appropriated elements of Semitic rather than of Greek polytheism. These were in the main Phoenician and Syro-Chaldaic. In its allegorical procedure upon the documents both of Judaism and of Christianity, it was only carrying further a method used by Philo among Jewish thinkers, and by those who afterwards came to be regarded as orthodox among the Christians. The difference of the Gnostic "heretics" from thinkers who, like Clement, desired to be also obedient Catholics, was that the former did not accept the limits imposed by the "ecclesias- tical tradition"; that is to say, by the average Christian consciousness as interpreted by systematisers whose aim was fixed upon the universal reception of a common doctrine. Their speculations had thus one of the characters of a free philosophy as distinguished from a philosophy working in subordination to a recognised authoritative standard. In the expression of their philosophy, on the other hand, the Gnostics could not disentangle themselves from mythological imagination. Though essentially philosophies, their systems never arrive at pure conceptual thought, but turn abstractions into persons, and eternal relations of reality into histories of events in time. I The dualism and pessimism of these systems, and their tendency to regard all phenomena as alike illusory — so that the question whether any historical tradition is literally true or not becomes a matter of indifference — much as they may suggest a remoter Eastern origin, are in reality perfectly independent develop- ments of the Judaeo-Christian data from which all the Gnostics set APPENDIX 221 out. For the Gnostics themselves, these data, evaporated as they might be, were still the presupposition of their peculiar type of thought. The result appears to be that Gnosticism was, as Neo-Platonism was not, a direct outgrowth of the East. It was a serious attempt at the identification of Christianity as a religion with speculations on the origin and end of things. Now this identification of religion with philosophy is a character of the typically Eastern systems of thought. In its manner it represents a form of speculative freedom. The individual Brahman, for example, is perfectly free to elaborate the data of tradition and of past thought in his own way ' ; though popular mythology is never definitely broken with, and the phi- losophy is never quite purely theoretical. It may lead far beyond the practical virtues, through ascetic contemplation to absolute indifference, but the religious purpose of attaining redemption from evil is always the final aim. The case of the Gnostics is similar. They refuse to enter into the Catholic system of authori- tative dogma wrought out by theological experts with a view to the imposition on all of a creed that keeps within the bounds set by the religious consciousness of the many. Philosophy is not with them, as with the Fathers, an instrument taken up as the means of giving precise intellectual form to an accredited doctrine. It is meant to be the speculative unfolding of the traditional data without regard to any organised enforcement of uniformity. On the other side, the Christian Gnostics have not the Greek conception of perfectly disinterested knowledge, which in the Neo- Platonists subsists along with any mystical aim they may cherish as a religious consummation of their philosophy. Whatever stress the Gnostics, by the very name they assume, may lay on know- ledge as opposed to mere faith, it is always knowledge with a view to the religious life that they mean. In the later Stoics we meet with a similar tendency. Here philosophy is passing by way of ethics into religion, as with the Gnostics religion, by the spirit of measureless speculation, passed into philosophy. But of Greek philosophy the very origin and principle of being is " unspeakable desire to see and know." It began with this and to this it returned. The direction to practice, social or personal, is secondary. In the 1 Sir Alfred Lyall, in "Letters from Vamadeo Sbastri " (Asiatic Stiirfies, Second Series), points out the resemblance on this side between Gnosticism and Hinduism. 222 APPENDIX Gnostic cosmogonies, on the contrary, the pursuit of hidden knowledge is the occasion by which the soul of the whole pre- cipitates itself from its pre-mundane union with the highest divinity into a realm of ill. From the evil world of matter, religious enlightenment is the means of escape. Thus it is only as a divinely-given remedy for the suffering soul that knowledge is desirable. Evidently the Gnostics are here quite faithful to their Judaeo-Christian data. In their terminology they are even ultra-Christian. Their technical term -rrXrjpwfjia, as the name for the highest sphere of being, is of Pauline origin. And nothing is more characteristic of them than their use of the words 77-reu/Aa for the highest part of the soul ; and 7tviv[j.o.tikoI for the enlightened. Now this is a peculiarly Christian usage 1 . In the tradition of Greek science, when a higher part of the soul is distinguished from the soul generally, it is called vovs. "When the necessity is supposed of placing a subtler material principle between gross matter and the soul, this principle is called TTvev/xa. From a strictly materialist point of view, the 7rvevfxa might come to be identified with the soul ; but it is never taken psycholo- gically in the sense of its higher part. A modern use of "spirit" in a meaning continuous with this, is when "animal spirits" were regarded as the instrument of the soul for moving the limbs. When, on the other hand, we speak of the "spirit" as equivalent to the "mind" of man, with merely a shade of difference in connotation, we are, etymological ly, continuing the Christian usage. The claim that the Trvei^cu-iKoi, or "spiritual men," alone possess true knowledge (yvwo-is), in distinction from the imperfectly enlightened faith (7tio-tis) of the mass of believers, is thus a claim which, by its very terms, declares its origin as outside the Greek tradition. Under favourable circumstances, Gnosticism might have become the starting-point for a sort of Christian Brahmanism. It presents, however, this difference from Brahmanism, that it is the speculative development, not of a natural religion like that of the Vedas, but of a religion tracing its origin to a personal founder. Hence perhaps the impossibility of its ever making good its claim to be the true Christianity. When a religion is proclaimed to have been revealed under given circumstances of time and place, it cannot allow its historical tradition to be indefinitely vaporised without ceasing to 1 See the discussions of the various meanings of irvevixa in Siebeck's Geschichte der Psychologic APPENDIX 223 exist. All the religions of this type, whether aggressively intolerant or not, have had to bind themselves by a creed of more or less precision into a Church of more or less exclusiveness. The opposite extremes as regards rigour of ecclesiastical discipline are probably Roman Catholicism and Buddhism ; but the bond exists in all by the mere fact of their origin. Even Gnosticism organised itself into communities which were not simply philosophic schools. It did not, even at its highest point, produce solitary speculations like those of the Brahmans. Long into the Middle Ages communities animated by Gnostic ideas persisted, under various names, as a menace to the dominion of historical Christianity. At the end of his Histoire Critique du Gnosticisme, Matter devotes some pages to this prolongation. In those religious heresies of Languedoc which, at the beginning of the thirteenth century, were stamped out by the Albigensian Crusade and the Inquisition, newly centralised and systematised on the initiative of Dominic, the historian is able to trace Gnostic as well as Manichaean ideas. Now the movement of the Albigenses did not spring up quite spontaneously in southern France. It came originally from the European provinces of the Eastern Empire. Both there and in the Asiatic provinces, it had from time to time come to the surface, only to be suppressed more or less effectively by the Emperors at Constantinople. May it not be that some of the Russian sects which the Orthodox Church is still engaged in suppressing are a continuation of the same type of speculative religion? If so, is it not possible that it has still a future? Let us suppose a remarkable religious personality to arise in Russia, modern in relation to science and ethics, yet possessing the type of metaphysical imagination characteristic of the Gnostics. The way seeming now open for another revolution in the Judaeo- Christian line of development, a new religion might be proclaimed, accepting the results of modern science and criticism, but, by the aid of an imaginative ontology, still retaining at its centre the Eastern idea of a redeemer and revealer. It would of course be persecuted by Russian Orthodoxy, but this might be the beginning of its success. Throwing itself on Western Europe, it would meel with States practising toleration, and, in the Latin countries, with a decadent religion. In France and Italy, minds are open, and a desire is felt for something to take the place of the hollow structure which, hampering thought and life, can yet only be 224 APPENDIX controlled by the State and not abolished. A new enthusiasm, religious and not merely political, would sweep away the wreck. The condition, if anything can be inferred from history, would seem to be a renewed contact of the religious ideas of East and West. For this, the situation of Russia is exactly adapted. Without the personality, any combination of conditions, however favourable in itself, must of course be powerless; but, if the recurrent aspiration of European minds towards a "religion of the future" is more than a vain reminiscence, this seems the direction in which to look. Ill Iamblichus and Proclus on Mathematical Science. For the theory of knowledge, the views of the later Neo- Platonists on mathematics are still not without interest even to students of Kant. An outline of some of the positions taken up may be found in the book of Iamblichus on the Common Science of Mathematics 1 , and in the two Prologues of Proclus to his Commentary on the first book of Euclid's Elements". Of these Prologues, the first coincides in subject with the treatise of Iamblichus ; dealing with that which is common to arithmetic and geometry, and prior to all special departments of mathematics. The second is an introduction to the general theory of geometry and to Euclid's Elements in particular, and gives in its course a brief chronicle of the history of the science to the time of Euclid. The first Prologue draws from the same sources as the work of Iamblichus, setting forth views that had gradually taken shape in the schools of Plato and Aristotle. In the case of one theory at least in the second, Proclus seems to lay claim to originality. In other cases, he mentions incidentally that he is only selecting a few things from what earlier writers have said. Iamblichus is pro- fessedly expounding the ideas of the "Pythagorean philosophy." The starting-point with both writers is the position of Plato at the end of the sixth book of the Republic. The objects of mathematics and the faculty of understanding (SiaVom) that deals 1 Iamblichi de Communi Mathematica Scientia Liber, ed. N. Festa, 1891. (Teubner.) 2 Prodi Diadochi in Primum Euclidis Elementorum Librvm Commentarii, ex rec. G. Friedlein, 1873. (Teubner.) APPENDIX 225 with them come between dialectic and its objects above, and sense- perception and its objects below. Being thus intermediate, are mathematical forms and the reasonings upon them derivatives of sense-perception, or are they generated by the soul? In the view most clearly brought out by Proclus, they result from the productive activity of the soul, but not without relation to a prior intellectual norm, conformity to which is the criterion of their truth. What is distinctive of Proclus is the endeavour to determine exactly the character of this mental production. Iamblichus does not so specially discuss this, but lays stress on the peculiar fixity of relations among the objects of mathematics. Mathematical objects are not forms that can depart from their underlying matter, nor yet qualities, like the heat of fire, which though actually inseparable can be thought of as taken away. The forms that constitute number and extension have a coherence which does not admit of this kind of disaggregation, whether real or ideal. According to the view made specially clear by Iamblichus, mathematical science does not take over its employment of division and definition and syllogism from dialectic. The mathematical processes to which these terms are applied are peculiar to mathe- matics. From itself it discovers and perfects and elaborates them ; and it has tests of its own, and needs no other science towards the order of speculation proper to it. Its difference from dialectic is that it works with its own assumptions, and does not consider things "simply," without assumptions 1 . As Proclus also says, there is only one science without assumptions (avvn-oOeTos). No special science demonstrates its own principles or institutes an inquiry about them. Thus the investigator of nature (6 cpvarioXoyos) assumes that there is motion, and then sets out from that determinate principle ; and so with all special inquirers and practitioners 2 . Both writers, while they make considerations about the practical utility of knowledge subordinate, yet repeatedly draw attention to the applications, direct and indirect, of mathematics to the arts of life. Proclus cites Archimedes as a conspicuous example of the 1 De Comm. Math. Scieiltia, pp. 89 — 90: d<£' iavTrjs ovv eupLo-Kei re avra. kclI reXeiol ko.1 el-epyafcrai, rd re oUela avTrj Ka\ws dtde doKi/J-dfrut, /ecu ov detrai d'XXf/s emo~Tr)p.ris 7rp6s ttt)v oiKelav deupiav. ov yap rb dirXws Kaddirep rj SiaXe/cTi/ci?, dXXd rd v<p' eavTrjv SiayLvwcTKei, olKeiws re avrd dewpe? Ka66<rov avrrj vn6K(iTa.i. 2 Prologus n., p. 75. w. 15 226 APPENDIX power conferred by science when directed to practical invention. And science in general, as both he and Iamblichus insist, derives its necessity from the mathematical principles on which it depends. The perception of the peculiar scientific importance of mathematics, grounded in the necessity of its demonstrations, they ascribe to Pythagoras ; who, as both declare in almost the same terms, brought it to the form of a liberal discipline. By this is meant that, instead of treating it as a collection of isolated propositions, each discovered for itself, Pythagoras began to impress on it the systematically deductive character which it assumed among the Greeks. In the order of genetic development, men turn to knowledge for its own sake when the care about necessary things has ceased to be pressing 1 . The classification of the mathematical sciences given in the two treatises is the same. First in order comes the " common mathe- matical science" which sets forth the principles that form a bond of union between arithmetic and geometry. The special branches of mathematics are four : namely, arithmetic, geometry, music, and spherics ((KpatptK^). Music is a derivative of arithmetic ; containing the theory of complex relations of numbers as distinguished from the numbers themselves. Spherics is similarly related to geometry ; dealing with abstract motion prior to the actual motion of bodies. To beginners it is more difficult than astronomy, which finds aid in the observation of moving bodies ; but as pure theory it is prior 2 . Next come the various branches of mixed mathematics, such as mechanics, optics, astronomy, and generally the sciences that employ instruments for weighing, measuring and observing. These owe their less degree of precision and cogency to the mixture of sense- perception with pure mathematical demonstration. Last in the 1 Prologus i., p. 29: ko.1 yap iraaa 77 yeveins /cat r) iv avrrj arpecpofiivr) ttjs ipvxv* fwr/ ir£<pvKev airb tov dreXoDs els to T^Xeiov x u P e ^ v - Cf. Stoix- ©eoX. 45. 2 With the substitution of astronomy for "spherics," the four Pythagorean sciences of Iamblichus and Proclus form the "quadrivium," or second division of the "seven liberal arts," of mediaeval tradition. (The "trivium," according to the list usually given, comprises grammar, dialectic and rhetoric.) A more curious point of contact is the identity of the conception of " spherics" — simply as classification of science and apart from philosophical theory of knowledge — with Comte's "rational mechanics," regarded by him as the branch of mathe- matics immediately prior to astronomy, which is the first of the physical sciences. APPENDIX 227 theoretic order come simple data of perception brought together as connected experience (ifx.Trei.pia.). The ground of this order is to be found in the rationalistic theory of knowledge common to the school. As Proclus remarks, the soul is not a tablet empty of words, but is ever written on and writing on itself — and moreover, as he adds, written on by pure intellect which is prior to it in the order of being. Upon such a basis of psychology and consequent theory of knowledge, he goes on to put the specific question about geometrical demonstration and the activity of the soul in its production. How can geometry enable us to rise above matter to unextended thought, when it is occupied with extension, which is simply the result of the inability of matter to receive immaterial ideas otherwise than as spread out and apart from one another ? And how can the Siavoia, proceeding as it does by unextended notions, yet be the source of the spatial constructions of geometry? The solution is that geometrical ideas, existing un- extended in the Siayoia, are projected upon the "matter" furnished by the epavraaia. Hence the plurality and difference in the figures with which geometrical science works. The idea of the circle as understood (in the StaVoia) is one ; as imagined (in the cpavraa-ia) it is many ; and it is some particular circle as imagined that geometry must always use in its constructions. At the same time, it is not the perceived circle (the circle in the alo-drjais) that is the object of pure geometry. This, with its unsteadiness and inaccuracy, is the object only of applied geometry. The true geometrician, while necessarily working by the aid of imagination, strives towards the unextended unity of the understanding with its immaterial notions. Hence the disciplinary power of geometry as set forth by Plato 1 . According to this view, those are right who say that all geometrical propositions are in a sense theorems, since they are concerned with that which ever is and does not come into being ; but those also are right who 1 In his theory of " geometrical matter," Proclus remarks, he has taken the liberty of dissenting from Porphyry and most of the Platonic interpreters. See Prologus n. , pp. 56 — 7 : irepi fxev ovv rrjs yew/jLerpiKrjs i/Xtjs rotravra e"xoiJ.ei> X^7«e ovk ayvoovvres, oca. ko\ 6 <f>iko<ro<pos llop<pi'ipios ev rots (Xvliluktois yeypatptv Kal ol ttXuvtoi rCiv lWarwviK&v oiaraTTOvrai, avpL<pujv6repa 8e elvai ravra reus yew/xerptKah e<podois vo/xi^ovres Kal to HX&twvi Siavorjra KaXovvri to. viroKel/xeva rrj yewixeTpiq.. G\<vq.5ci yap otv ravra d\\r)\ois, 8i6ri rwv yeufj.erpiKun' d8£>v ai li£v alriai, Ka6' as Kal 77 didvota 7rpo/3d\\e( ras aTrodei^eis, iv avrrj ir pov<p(arr)Ka<n.v , avrd 5f eKa<rra ra diaipou/xeva Kal <rvvri.diLi.eva axn^ara rrepl tt)v (pavraaiav 7rpo^^\r]Tai. 228 APPENDIX say that all are in a sense problems, for, in the way of theorems too, nothing can be discovered without a going forth of the understanding to the " intelligible matter " furnished by the imagination, and this process resembles genetic production 1 . The division once made, however, the theoretic character is seen not only to extend to all but to predominate in all. 1 Prologus ii., pp. 77—79. INDEX OF NAMES. Aedesius, 122, 133, 134 Aenesidemus, 33 Aeschylus, 2 Agathias, 183 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 158 n. Alfred the Great, 188 Alypius, 123 Anielius, 29, 30, 34, 36, 100, 110 Ammonius Saccas, 28, 20, 32, 33 Aninionius (pupil of Proclus), 185 Auaxagoras, 11, 24 Antoninus, M. Aurelius. See Aurelius Antoninus (Neo-Platonic philosopher), 133 Apollonius of Tyana, 23, 114, 117 n., 138 Aquinas, 192 ff. Archer-Hind, E. D., 72 n., 184 n. Archimedes, 225 Aristophanes, 24, 217 Aristotle, 8 n. , etc. Asclepiodotus, 185 Augustine, St, 187, 193, 197 n. Aurelius, M., 3, 4, 34 Avicebron (Ibn Gebirol), 195 Bacon, Francis, 201, 202 Bacon, Roger, 196 Baeumker, CI., 72 n. Bardesanes, 121 Benn, A. W., 12 n., 15, 206 Berkeley, 30, 41, 42, 50, 202 Bigg, C, 37 Boccaccio, 196 Boethius, 111, 187 Bosanquet, B., 91 n. Bouillet, M. N., 193 n. Bruno, 22, 197 ff., 215 Burnet, J., 8 n., 10 n. Campanella, 199 Carneades, 120 Celsus, 137, 140, 145 n., 146 Chaignet, A. E., 182 n. Chosroes, 183 Chrysanthius, 122, 134 Chiysippus, 120 Cicero, 1 n., 13, 29 n., 33, 188 Clement (of Alexandria), 27, 220 Comte, 5 n., 160, 209, 218, 226 n. Constantine, 3, 132, 142 n. Constantius, 132, 151 n. Cudworth, 20, 200 Cyril, St (Bishop of Alexandria), 145 ff., 157 Damascius, 181 ff. Dante, 6, 193 ff. Democritus, 10, 11, 200 Descartes, 9, 34, 44, 72 n., 200 ff. Dexippus, 136 Diocletian, 3 Diogenes, 139 Dionysius the Areopagite, 188, 193 Dodwell, H. (the elder), 124 n. Dominic, St, 223 Drummond, J., 36 n. Duns Scotus, l!l"> 230 INDEX OF NAMES Empedocles, 11, 121, 211, 212 Epictetus, 139, 184 Epicurus, 12, 29 n., 200 Erigena, John Scotus, 188, 195, 204 Euclid, 224 ff. Eunapius, 123, 135, etc. Euripides, 22 Eusebius (Bishop of Caesarea), 32, 139 Eusebius (Neo-Platonic philosopher), 134 Eustathius, 132 Ficino, Marsilio, 196 ff. Firmus, Castricius, 115 Gallienus, 30 Gibbon, E., 133 n., 182 Goethe, 199 Grote, G. , 133 n. Hatch, E., 19 n. Hegel, 205 Heraclitus, 10, 36, 73 Herennius, 33 Hermias, 185 Herodotus, 1 n., 8 n. Hesiod, 18 n., 100 Hierocles (Proconsul of Bithynia), 138, 146 Hierocles (of Alexandria), 32, 157 Hobbes, 9, 200, 207, 218 Homer, 18, 96, 110, 149, 161 Hume, 204 Hypatia, 28, 156 Iamblichus. See ch. vn., etc. Isidore, 181. (Not identical with the " Isidorus " mentioned at p. 183.) Jerome, St, 109, 133 n. Joannes Philoponus, 183 n., 185 n. Julian. See ch. viii., etc. Justinian, 156, 182 Juvenal, 22 Kant, 204, 224 Keim, Th., 20 n., 138 n. Leibniz, 202, 205 Lipsius, R. A., 220 Locke, 201, 203 Longinus, 33, 34, 36, 39 n., 73, 109 Lucian, 22 Lucretius, 12 n., 200 Lyall, A. C, 221 n. Macarius Magnes, 146 Machiavelli, 6 Macrobius, 188 Maine, H. S., 5 n. Maistre, J. de, 16 n. Marcella, 109 Marinus, 144, etc. See Proclus. Matter, A. J., 27, 223 Maurice, F. D., 136 n. Maximus, 134 Mirandola, Pico della, 163 n. Morbeka, William of, 162 More, H., 200 Moses, 39, 141, 146 ff. Nemesius, 187 Neumann, C. J., 138 n., 145 ff. Newton, 200 Numa, 151 Numenius, 34 ff., 138 Ockham, William of, 195 Olympiodorus (teacher of Proclus), 157 n., 159 Olympiodorus (Commentator on Plato and Aristotle), 157, 185 Origen (the ecclesiastical writer), 27, 33, 138 n., 197 Origen (Platonic philosopher), 33 Parmenides, 10, 11, 57, 216 Petrarch, 6, 195 Phidias, 92 Philo Judaeus, 27, 34 ff., 88 n., 106, 138, 220 Plato, 9, etc. Plotinus. See chs. iv., v., vi., etc. Plutarch (of Chaeronea), 34, 73, 120, 122 Plutarch (of Athens), 150 ff. INDEX OF NAMES •231 Porphyry. Sec ch. vn., etc. Preller, L. See Hitter Priscus, 134, 135 Proclus. See ch. ix., etc. Prohaeresius, 124 Pythagoras, 8, 22, 114, 121, 130, 147, 220 Read, C, 209 n. Renan, E., 4 n., 140 n., 184 n., 190 n. Ritter, H. and Preller, L. Cited as R. P. The references are to Hiatoria Philosophiue Graecae, 7th ed. Rogatianus, 30 Rohde, E., 18 n. Sallust (Praetorian Prefect under Julian), 136 Scotus, John. See Erigena Scotus, John Duns. See Duns Sextus Enipiricus, 33 Shelley, P. B., 203 Siebeck, H., 44, 53, 72 n., 206, 222 n. Simon, J., 27, 38 n., 77 n., 85 n., 109, 110 n., 114 n. Sirnplicius, 183, 184, 211 Socrates (the philosopher), 11, 12, 13, 19, 29, 42, 144 n., 163, 206 Socrates (ecclesiastical historian), 157 Sopater, 124 n., 132 Sorel, G., 20 n. Sosipatra, 133 Spencer, H., 214, 217 ff. Spenser, E., 203 Spinoza, 101, 162, 174, 202, 204, 205 Suetonius, 3, 4 n., 17 n. Synesius, 157, 188 Syrianus, 157 ff. Tacitus, 3, 4 n., 140 Tannery, P., 10 n. Taylor, T., 193 n. Tertullian, 21, 186 Thales, 206 Themistius, 133, 158 n. Theodore of Asine, 135, 164 Theodoret, 138 Theophrastus, 116, 120. Vacherot, E., 27, 35 n., 85 n., 93, 158 n., 198 n. Valentinus, 220 Xenophanes, 10, 21 Xenophon, 13 Zeller, E. The references are to Die Philosophic der Grieehen, n. 1, 4th ed.; n. 2, in. 2, 3rd ed. Zeno (the Stoic), 13 Zoroaster, 110 Cambridge: printed ry .t. and c. f. clay, at the university press. H 7 D AV t VI /*V 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. This book is due on the last date stamped below, or on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall. 5 JCL5BGC wiiii 42 lo g iW* 6\B' tr""/"^*r> ^v KETCD LD AUG 61SS8 JUN 1 4 1961 aO^ «,9fcC asjja m 'D LD REC!D I P FEB 2 19ffl MAY 10 1962 :ctp t.D JUN 7 — tsefr I7Jan'61RT| LD 21A-50m-8,'57 (C8481sl0)476B General Library University of California Berkeley YC 31507 LIBRARY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED LOAN DEPT. THIS BOOK IS DUE BEFORE CLOSING TIME ON LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW REC'D LD WW 13*63 -8 PM « LD 62A-20m-9,'63 . , . General L ibrary (E709slO)9412A University of California Berkeley