2.929 S5 UC-NRLF i__13 ^55 4ie "I / THE TRANSITION FROM "BEWUSSTSEIN" TO "SELBSTBEWUSSTSEIN'' IN Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind AN EXEGETICAL ESSAY With an Introduction and With Notes By Henry Bradford Smith A Thesis Presented to the Fac«Ity of the Graduate School of the University of Pennsylvania, in Partial Fwl- fillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy PrcM of B. D. Smhh & Brothers Pulaski, Virginia PREFACE, np HE aim of this essay is to present an exegesis of the early chapters of Hegel's Phenomenology of Mind in a phraseol- ^ ogy, which, while not untechnical, will be as free as possible of the strange and often mystifying verbiage of Hegel. Hegel is perhaps more than aoy other philosopher the pro- duct of the speculation that preceded him, and it would thus seem possible to reproduce his argument in terms which are the common property of philosophy in general. The advantage of clearness which is thus attained is offset by the impossibility of an exact rendition. It is impossible to render the author in familiar terms without more or less perverting his meaning. Thus the commentators have in general been content to restate the argument in the original verbiage, with no great resulting advantage to clearness; nor is the reader helped if the author's style be imitated in a language other than the German. Hegel largely invented his own technical vocabulary. He was doubtless suspicious of the ambiguity of the terms in famil- iar use and aware of their inadequacy to express his meaning. When a new word is introduced it is usually delined, but the definition will in itself scarcely render the meaning intelligible to the reader. It is only after the term has appeared many times in a context that its real meaning begins to appear. Thus the first parts of the system may only become clear in the light of the last. The Phenomenology is admittedly one of the most difficult of all philosophical works and the present essay makes no pre- tense of an understanding of all these difficulties. Moreover the notions that are philosophically significant will be subject to a multitude of interpretations and will be often presentable from many points of view. It is with the belief that some intelligible system of interpre- tation, even if inexact in some of the details, is better than no system, or a system exact but unintelligible, that the present essaj;^ has been prepared. 228333 INTRODUCTION, npHB interest which the early chapters of the Phenomenol- ogy — viz., those embracing the general headings, "con- sciousness" and the "self-consciousness" — possess, lies partly in the dialectic transition as such, and partly in the fact that the treatment parallels the history of an important philosoph- ical concept, the ' ' Ding an sich ' ' from Kant to Fichte. The chapter on the "Certainty of Sense" presents what is roughly an analysis of this concept as it presents itself in the transcendentale Aesthetik^. This of course is the part of the Critique that elaborates the theory of the a priori forms of sensi- bility, space and time, which are supposed to account for individuality. This chapter, in which the individual takes its place as a " thing in itself" and in which the truth of the cer- tainty of sense turns out to be the universal, is a fine example of Hegelian skill. In the next chapter " the thing of perception " plaj^s the role of the ^'Ding an sich'^ in its new guise in the Analytik,"^ or more exactly as it appears in the corresponding part of the Prolegomena,^ and finally the chapter on " Force and the Understanding" presents a critique of the concept as it^ exhibits itself generally in the Dialectik^. The division whichl deals with the self- consciousness owes its position to the histor^ leal fate of the " thing in itself" in the ethical idealism of Fichte.\ The author himself, however, seems consciously to avoid giving the impression that this order is in mind; and indeed the obser- vation applies only to the whole and not to the details, many of which are historical standpoints selected freely without regard to their chronological origin. The ideal of rationalism is the formulation of a definition of a fact from which the fact's existence is the necessary implica- 1 Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Originalausgabe), S. 3S-73. 2 Ibid, S. 89-349. 3 Ibid, S. 349-732. * Prolegomena zu einer jeden kunftigen Metaphysik.etc. (ed. Reclam) , S. 73-1Q9. tion. The difficulty of the rationalist's position seems patent to the empiricist, who regards his fact as directly given in experi- ence. It is the custom of some to say that the kind of philosophy one chooses depends upon what kind of a human being one happens to be. If temperamentally one prefers reality to general information, he will be an empiricist, while if his philosophic needs compel him to rank the whole as of greater interest than the part, then he will be a rationalist; that in the one case one prefers to submerge himself in the world and lose himself, with a consequent gain in reality, while in the other case one elects to elevate himself above the world and as a consequence be at a loss to account for the facts of experience. One must make up his mind, they will tell you, to have some difficulties at hand for which his system cannot hope to account. The situation is not without humor when it is a professed empiricist who talks in this fashion, for reflection seems to show that the empiricist is in a worse way for his fact than is the rationalist. Absolute knowledge viewed as the limit of a series of approximations may be regarded as attainable if the series have an end; unattainable if the series be infinite. In the latter case the philosopher may perhaps regard his absolute as the percept of a divine intellect or resort toa " pre-established harmony " of his primal substance, or by some postulate or other satisfy this philosophic need. The rationalist either regards this knowledge as attained when his definition is at hand (as Descartes) or if it be the last of a series of definitional implications, its attainment will be determined by whether or not this series has an end. The absolute knowledge of Hegel is a result of the latter sort. Of course the author is not necessarily in any paragraph giving an expression of his own philosophical opinion. Usually some historical standpoint is being considered or one side of an antith- esis is being developed. The true Hegelian view is to be regarded as the outcome which dialectic deduces from the clash of conflicting standpoints. The law of contradiction is for the rationalist the supreme canon of method. The object (as con- cept) whose definition implies its own antithesis is nothing. The dialectic proceeds until through definitional implication, the object of knowledge is defined whose truth is implied. This object is the absolute and is thus distinguished from all other objects of consciousness that appeared in the process, for the definition of each one of these is conceived as involving inherent contradiction. It is suggestive to recall certain passages from Schelling in this connection as making clear the source of the Hegelian view as thus interpreted. The phenomena of the path of the dialectic are the conflicts of contradictory opinions. When the contra- diction is removed, the phenomenon (now appearance) ceases to possess reality; it vanishes and leaves a nothing. Through the dialectic the successive scenes of conflict are left behind until through flight the promised land of the absolute is reached. For Schelling, however, to attain the absolute is to attain pure self- consciousness. " All processes of the mind proceed with this in view, to portray the infinite in the finite. The end of all these processes is the self- consciousness, and the history of these processes is nothing but the history of the self-consciousness. Every process of the soul is also a determinate state of the soul. The history of the human mind will thus be nothing but the history of the different states through which the mind gradually attains unto intuition of itself, unto pure self-consciousness."^ And, again: ''Had we only to do with the absolute there would never have arisen a conflict of different systems. Only when we have left the domain of the absolute does there arise a conflict regarding the same, and only because of this original conflict in the human mind, arise the conflicts of philosophers. Should it ever happen — not to philosophers but — to mankind, to be able to leave this domain in which they have lapsed through desertion of the absolute, then will all philosophy and that domain itself, cease to exist. For the latter originates only through that con- flict and has reality only so long as the conflict continues."^ Again to quote from Fichte: " Epistemology ( Wissenschaftslehre) is necessary not alone as a clearly conceived, systematically exhibited science, but as a natural predisposition — while logic is 1 Werke, Abth. I. Bd. I, S. 382, Erlauterung des Idealismus der Wissenschaf- tslehre. 2 Werke, Abth. I, Bd. I. S. 293, Philosophische Briefe iiber Dogmatismus \\n^ Kriticismus. W an art- prod act of the human mind in its freedom."^ These passages indicate the source of an opinion which has come to be regarded as typically Hegelian. The Phenomenology begins with a consideration of the truth furnished the subject by the fact of immediate observation. When a series of observations is made on some definite quantity by the use (say) of an instrument, as is well known, the individ- ual observations exhibit discrepancies among themselves and this is the case even when all known and avoidable sources of error have been removed. It is the custom of physical science to select a value of the unknown observed quantity, which gives what is regarded as the most probable value — the nearest approx- imation to the true value attainable with the data at hand. This, the physicist will say, is in answer to a logical demand — each one of a series of discordant results cannot be simultaneously true. In introducing the notion of error in this way, empirical science, either tacitly or openly, postulates a real fact forever beyond the reach of knowledge by experiment. That this knowledge is unattainable seems to be a matter of experience^ for while small errors seem to occur more frequently than large errors and while more refined methods of observation seem to give more exact results, even if the object observed were the same from moment to moment, the observer is not the same observer that he was a moment before. However this may be, it follows deHnitionally from the manner in which this real fact is postulated that it will ever remain unknown, for if an in- creasingly large number of observations give an increasingly accurate approximation to the true value and if the probable value of any finite number of observations will always have a probable error attached, then it is an immediate and necessary inference that the true value will be the most probable value of an infinite number of observations and that this true value has no probable error attached. But an infinite number of observa- tions means, if it means anything, a greater number than can ever be taken — an infinite number of observations is by definition impossible. Therefore to postulate the fact thus is to postulate it unknowable — or the fact is unknowable by definition. It can- not be said that the limit of the series is the true value, for the 1 Werke Abth. L Bd. I, S. 69, Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre. [5] series has never a limit but always only a probable limit. The notion is that positive errors will cancel negative errors, but the law that states the equal frequency or facility of occurrence of positive and negative errors only holds when an infinite number of observations is obtained and this is equivalent to saying that it never holds. Again the chances are co :1 according to the post- ulate that any given observation has an error, and hence, defini- tional ly, every observation has an error, which the true value has not. Since every observation has an error attached, whether the number taken be large or small, the compounded result is not an observation but an universal result, i. e., a similar set of observations would give rise to the same value of the unknown quantity. The true value would not cease to be a computation and become an observation in virtue of the number of observa- tions passing from the finite to the infinite. If it is the view of the empiricist that the real fact is postulated because of the discrepancies among certain observa- tions, this is because he would avoid the sceptical conclusion that the truth is the last perception or that there is a different truth for each observer. In so far as this is his motive, however, he is not empiricist but rationalist; his postulate answers a logical de- mand. He is properly empiricist if he asserts that his real fact is postulated on empirical grounds, i. e., because it is a matter of experience that errors occur. But the notion of error is only introduced when a true value without error is postulated. If the observations had no probable error there would be no need of the postulate. If they have a probable error then a true value without error is already postulated. Therefore, a real fact is postulated because a real fact is postulated. If the real fact be postulated in answer to the logical demand which asserts that a series of discordant results cannot be simultaneously true, then the real fact is postulated because of the laio of contradiction. The existence of the fact Jollows from the law of contradiction. This would be the view of the rationalist. The postulate takes another form when it is said that the real fact is postulated because of its definition. But its defini- tion is equivalent to the assertion that it can never be known. The empiricist says: "/t is because it is.^^ The theologian as- [6] sei'ts: '■'■It is because it can never he known.^^ He names his fact God and describes his postulate as his supreme act of faith. Such an absolute is the natural meeting place for realism and idealism but it is not one in which either realist or idealist is called upon to rejoice. The ground is cleared for an absolute scepticism. Having to deal with an unknowable which is abso- lutely real the sceptic can argue with his opponent as he likes. '■'■ The more information we have of our fact," we may suppose him to say, ''the more real does it become. Of the absolute fact we have no information. Therefore, the absolute fact is absolutely unreal. But the absolute fact was postulated as the most real thing. Therefore, to define the absolute fact as the most real thing is to imply its absolute unreality." Or otherwise: "Nothing is both a and non-a; the absolute fact is both real and unreal and is consequently nothing." Again: " A. thing that is not a possible object of consciousness is no thing. The absolute fact can never be known and is therefore nothing." These contradictions which seem to follow definition- ally are not the only weapons of the sceptic. As an induction from experience, the realist or the idealist asserts that the real fact is never the same from moment to moment. The real fact is postulated with the admission that it is in constant flux. Again the observer is not the same observer from moment to moment. There are as many real facts as observers. The post- ulator may rightly be called upon to explain this. Fichte's fundamental postulate, "I am because lam," is akin to both the empiricist's and the rationalist's mode of asser- tion. In form it is the empiricist's, viz., "The real fact is postulated because it is postulated." In content it is in the rationalist's manner, for the ego as pure activity is no thing (a passive something) and hence can never be object of knowledge. Hence, " it is because it can never be known." The expression " It is because it is," is familiar in the writings of those philos- ophers immediately following Kant. Thus in HegeP " the thing is and it is only because it is." In Fichte the "I" is predicated as existent because it is existent in the same sense. The purely logical law " A is A," does not hold without quali- 1 Fbanomeuologie des Geistes, Qoebhardt, Bamberg und Wurtzburg,1807, S.23 [7] fications, such as, in the same place, at the same time, under the same circumstances, etc., etc. **I am I " holds without qualifi- cation since the subject in question is the absolute subject. Of the first we say: " if A is, A is;" of the second: " because A is, A is." The use of "because ' in the sense of the present context might be expected since the real fact in this connection and the '' I " in Fichte play the same part as '' thing iu itself." Each is predicated absolutely since neither has any ^^Erkennt- nissgrund.'^ The " A is ^ " in Fichte finds its sufiBcient reason in the "I am I." In the Fichtean postulate, form and content being identical, the rationalistic and the empirical dilemma is supposedly transcended. This conclusion is the corollary which Schelling draws and clears the ground for his "identity system." This manner of satisfying the demand of the rationalist and empiricist at once, necessitates the assumption of an ego as pure activity which at the same time is no thing (nothing) and this zero answers the same demand as that of the real fact of science forever beyond the reach of experiment. " In this choice, (we might imagine Schelling to say), in this choice as to how the " thing in itself " shall be postulated, the theologian has the courage to stand on the platform of his dilemma, but he fears to call his God what the concept implies. He clothes his concept with this or that unessential or accidental feature in his vain attempt to supply it with reality. He lacks the courage to submerge himself in the real world. The materi- alist has the courage to submerge himself in his world but he is coward when asked to strip his world of its reality — to admit its absolute unreality." The real fact is qualitatively the same as any individual observation of it: That is to say, if a mass be observed the real mass lies beyond observation but is nevertheless a mass of some definite amount. It is an instance of mass. The necessity of postulating it in this manner is the result of what we may call the necessity of perception. It is the necessity which assures us that we are not observing any one of a number of masses but a determinate mass; that we do not observe a length in general but a particular instance of length. The most probable value of an unknown observed quantity [8] is uot itself observed; it is deduced as the result of a set of observa- tions. The actual value of the unknown (i. e., the limit of the probable value when the number of observations is increased without limit) cannot then be an observation unless, as was sug- gested before, it be argued that it ceases to be a deduction and becomes an observation in virtue of the number of observations taken passiug from the finite to the infinite. The actual value (the real fact) is a general or universal result, i. e., a similar set of observations would lead to the same result. Of course if an in- finite number of observations were taken a second time on the unknown quantity, each observation of the first set would suj)- posedly occur in the second set but in a different position in the series, in such a way, however, that the implied result of each set should be the same unknown quantity. The real fact is uot immediate as was supposed at first and before reflection; its truth appears as universal. As universal its necessity is the kind of necessity that folloios on definition. The contradiction at hand is the contradiction of definitional and perceptive necessity and the presence of this contradiction directs our attention to the fact that the original postulate has failed to meet the initial need. Our difliculty in the beginning was due to the experience that the individual members of a series of observations are not the same. This difficulty was supposedly removed when the individual discrepancies were attributed to the variable state of the observer and when the real result was postulated as independent of the observer, qualitatively the same as the perception of it, but always quantitatively different. De- fined in this way, however, it ceased to be an instance of the observed quantity, since it is never perceived, and became mii- versal. As universal, it fails, however, to meet the initial need, which was for a stable element in the flux of perception. The real fact must then remain an instance of the quality in question but an instance which is independent of the perception of it, a " thing in itself." As such, however, its definition leads to the standing contradiction. Besides its characteristic of being unknowable the definition of the real fact implies as well that it is a limit which may be approached as near as one may wish but never attained. Viewed in this manner it is in the nature of an ideal. Its reality is the kind of reality that attaches to any other concept and is not a reality that subsists somehow independently of the subject. Like the " I am I" of Fichte, the subject postulates it and this is its sole ground of existence. In its lirst form as a reality lying beyond its manifestations in experience and as the objective cause of perception it is the cause of appearances and hence comes to be identified with force (Kraft). As the "inner truth" it is implied by its appear- ances, for it is only postulated because of these. (In the language of Hegel) "The expression of the force implies the force proper." But also in the opposite sense, as the cause of its manifestations, it implies these. Now the force proper has appeared as an ideal, or it is conceptual in its nature, and the only way in which a concept can be the cause of anything in this connection is in the sense that its effects follow as the necessary implications of its definition. (In the language of Hegel) "The force proper im- plies its expression and follows upon the realization of its expression." The use of the term "force" (Kraft) in this connection is intelligible when the habit of thought familiar in Fichte and Schelling is recalled. "She (the soul) does not intuite herself without exhibiting herself in an object. She will thus intuite herself as an object in which there is productive force. "^ Of course the standpoint is the idealism that represents the world as the product of the self. " Since there is in the mind an un- ending striving to organize itself, so too in the outer world, an universal tendency to organization must reveal itself."'^ And again: " No organization is thinkable without productive force. I should like to know how such a force would come into matter, if we regard matter as a thing in itself. * * * Theris is a productive force in things outside us. Such a force is only the force of a mind; thus those things cannot be things in them- selves— i. e., cannot possess reality through themselves. They can only be the creations, the products of a mind."^ 1 Schelling, Werke, Abth. I, Bd. I, S. 385-386, Erlauterung des Idealismus der Wissenschaftslehre. 2 ibid, B. 386. 3 Ibid, S. 387. [10] " Force " appears then as an active principle in the sensible world and its activity is the necessity of definitional implication. In this sense it is the free self-active legislator for appearances and as the ''inner" or "beyond" the perceived world it appears as a kingdom of laws, the true image of reality. This kingdom of laws as the laws of definition and hence as creations of the self, is seen to be nothing but the realm of the self's activity. When these laws have been formulated the self's activity is realized, the curtain is raised on the " beyond '' and the self -consciousness appears. Nevertheless, it is patent that any instance of change in the world of perception is not implied by the law of change itself, for even if all the laws of the universe were formulated, an initial situation would have to be known before all past and future situations could be predicted definitionally. A physicist (as Laplace) might say: ''Give me the mass, velocity and position of all the matter in the universe and I will predict any future situation." But without such data his completed description of the world is an empty form and m itself helpless without this alien assistance. The real fact, defintd as beyond the reach of observation, was introduced at first as a "force" which would account for an initial situation. Since it lies beyond experience it is an ideal and is then recognized as the contribution of the describer. Through the experience of this transformation the self-consciousness makes its appearance, but the gap between the law as universal and its individual illustration is not bridged. By the real fact as initially postulated one was far from meaning the self's activity or even a product due entirely to self's activity. The need to be met was that of an objective stimulus which should somehow remain stable in the flux of sense perception. If the truth be merely the last percep- tion, a thoroughgoing scepticism results. Eegarded as inde- pendent of the self, the real fact appears as a "thing in itself," (i. e., as no thing), and it comes then to be regarded as the constant or invariable character that attaches to change among things or as the law of change.^ In this guise, however, it fails 1 Cf. Hegel's words: Die Kraft ist gerade so beschajfen, wie das Oesetz (opp. cit. S. S5). [11] to meet tbc original need. The need was not for an invariable formula of change, but for a term that should remain invariable in such a formula. The initial motive is still unsatisfied if the real fact in its role of law fails to meet the initial need. That it does fail in this is patent if the law carries no criterion of the terms that enter into it, if it furnishes no test of its own appli- cation; for then we have two independent constants — the law itself and the terms that enter into it. The alternative is to regard the law as the definition of the term. The real fact is that which behaves in the way prescribed. Thus mass is that fact which exactly satifies the formula of the law of gravitation. Of course this fact cannot be independent of the self, and Schelling has been quoted above as saying that " the force in nature is nothing but the force of the mind." It is of course evident that the contrast of the law as essence and its individual realization or instance is not thus transcended. The requirements of an initial situation or instance is furnished for Fichte by the so-called intellectual intuition, the intuition of the self as pure activity, in which the self is seen to exist through the mere act of predication. The problem which the idealism of Fichte does not seem to explain naturally is this: If the real fact is the ego, or the ego's activity, how is the multi- plicity of egos to be explained and how is the conclusion to be escaped that there are as many systems of truth as there are egos? The answer to the first question might be that the num- ber of real facts is no difficulty so soon as one is at hand, or as soon as a starting point is attained. For Hegel the absolute is not reached on the attainment of the pure self consciousness, this representing but a station in the ^progress to the final goal. [12] Before taking up an investigation of nature, the critical philosopher is inclined to make a preliminary survey of himself and his faculties, as the subjective medium through which truth is given; to see how far his knowledge is dependent on this medium— in short, to inquire of the true essence of the subjec- tive and the objective. The mechanism of mind, whose func- tion it is to deliver finished truths to the subject, must be approached for its own sake, and a natuial dialectic is hence confronted with the problem of how this approach is to be instigated. The field of choice indeed appears to be open enough, but through previous acquaintance with the problems of mind, it is ventured that on first reflection "the objective" appears as that part which is independent of this medium, and hence the "real" element as over against the "accidental." The "real" received through the medium undergoes a change, a formation; it receives the imprint of the medium. When external reality (the "real" hypothesized) is fed into the mechanism of mind, the re^sultant product ceases to be real. It becomes the "accidental," for it is known, not as it is, but as it appears in the medium.^ It would seem that should we discover the behavior of the mechanism — the laws of its action — the "real" would be dis- tinguished from the "accidental" as well as the true from the false. Should we attempt to remove the "accidental" and so obtain the "real" in its pure state, we require a test that will distinguish the subjective from the objective; but this touchstone would in no way help us, for all appears only through the medium. A formula describing how our knowledge is affected in the medium is not then what we require. We require to know "not the law of refraction of the lays in the medium, but the rays themselves." As a result of this first engagement with its natural exper- ience, dialectic retreats, proceeds to examine her presuppositions, and discovers that various distinctions have been assumed. A medium and something separately existing for itself (the hy- [13] pothesized "real"), and the distinction between a self audits information, are the antitheses which separate out. If the absolute be viewed as "beyond" the province of experience and as a something to which knowledge cannot attain, it is customary to say that the subject is foredoomed to know only an aspect of truth, the phenomenal reflection of the "real." But now the absolute "real" and the knowledge the subject possesses come into stronger antithesis. The chasm is not bridged but only deepened. This characteristic assumption that the absolute is the only " real," effectually blocks a solution. To suppose that we already possess a meaning for such categories as these, is to suppose our first task already accomplished; indeed to attach a complete meaning to them is the task itself. The exposition as just given is not itself the knowledge which dialectic seeks. It is rather to be viewed as a sample of the history of natural dialectic — as the viewing of inner exper- ience in its successive manifestations. It does not represent truth itself but a process of which truth is the final term. The ways of philosophizing are many. The systems, in which great thought has been given classical form, are not to be regarded as ways of exhibiting the same truths with greater or less success, but rather as a continuous dialectic development, which consti- tutes the growth of metaphysical experience.'- The process must be followed to the final term. Forewarned that the successive shapes, into which this experience is cast, are not the goal, con- sciousness views the process as the road of appearances; the shapes at hand present but phenomenal knowledge. The task which the science of mind prescribes for itself is to transcend these its accidents. Each succeeding point of view, as the child of the preceding, is committed to the death of its parent. Viewed in this light the task of metaphysic postulates a faith in its outcome. Viewed for itself and not for its result, the natural dialectic may be regarded as the road of scepticism.^ Not indeed a Carte- sian scepticism, in which, when the doubt has been removed, the original opinion remains as it was before, but a scepticism whose outcome is quite the antithesis of the opinion which gave birth to it. It is the postulate of the untruth of the phenomenal [14] knowledge with which it is committed to deal. It is the postu- late that the self must follow its own conviction, or rather construct its own opinion — that in fact the truth can only be the final product of the self.* The life of natural dialectic is in conformity to law and its progress unavoidable.* The context and interconnection of its phenomena — points of view — on this road of appearances, are the guarantee of its completeness. Since each point of view is the parent of the succeeding one, the omission of any term is the death of the sequence. Indeed the opposite view is one of the natural phenomena of the road. Appearances are the demons the natural dialectic must overcome, before mind is landed in the heaven of truth. On this view the thinking self, as distinguished from the phenomenal self, is perceived as former, classifier and legislator in the world of appearances. The self's thought is reality, and this is the standpoint of idealism. The idealism which assumes this position for its starting point, but which has not trodden the path that leads to it, has not grasped the significance of its stand, for the demons of the road are yet to be slain. Its cer- tainty is immediate, but it stands by the side of other certain- ties which are equally immediate, which in truth may be pred- icated with equal assurance. These alien certainties are for me, but in their presence I admit that something other than I is for me object and certainty. The truth of idealism possesses neither validity nor meaning when presented bald of the context of its deduction. A difficulty, which appears to confront the method of dia- lectic, is the initial lack of a criterion of its procedure, whether this criterion be the touchstone of the content of metaphysic or the test of its starting point. If such a touchstone were at hand it would represent the essence of the process itself, and hence would be expected rather in the outcome. How now can the outcome furnish any assurance of the necessity of the process? Metaphysic viewed as the task of searching for and testing the reality of knowledge, would be expected to find its criterion of truth within itself. This test as the essence "in itself" is our pbject, or it is "for us" and its truth is rather the knowledge [15] that we have of it. These two poles, concept and object, as ''in itself" and "for another," fall within the knowledge which is the domain of our investigation. It is not, however, enough that the touchstone be at hand in consciousness; dialectic must be a contributor as well as an observer. Consciousness is not only consciousness of an object, but consciousness of itself. The object is only for consciousness in the manner in which it is known. If, however, the object does not correspond to the concept, it would seem that con- sciousness must alter the concept. Now, by this act the object is altered, for the knowledge in question was essentially knowl- edge of the object. The object is only "in itself" in the manner that it is "for us." The truth or essence of the process of natural dialectic appears then, first as that which it is "in itself." But in so far as it is the end of our search it is our object, or it is "for us," i. e., the antithesis, which is essential to our understanding of the "in itself" destroys the character- istic feature of the latter term. The modification of the point of view, through the process of dialectic is experience. The truth ot experience is the out- come or the final view- point. The history of the process is itself the science of mind. II. We recognize two classes of information — the knowledge of universals, and that furnished by the senses; the essence of athing as over against its "being" or individuality. Of the latter we appear to be merely receptive; we say the information is given. These "data" unreflectively considered appear as our rich- est knowledge, for their domain, space and time, is boundless, whether by addition or by subdivision of parts. It gives illus- tration to the most rigorous science, mathematics. Thus it appears to give rise as well to our truest knowledge. On reflection, however, the information that these "data" furnish turns out to be the poorest and most abstract. It says nothing of the object, except "it is."^ It predicates only exist- ence. The function of the object, its relation to other objects, the way we come to know it, in short its behavior in the context of experience, is not given in sense ''data." This is to say that we are given no account of the meaning or significance of the experience. It is what remains when all differences are abstracted. Dialectic, at this its starting point, has spun as yet no web of meaning for the term consciousness. Consciousness is certain of its ''datum," but not because it is a manifold and complex something, which furnishes its own contribution to the "datum;" nor because the "datum" is a manifold rich in relationships, within itself, to consciousness, and to experience. "It is." This is the bald information ol the certainty of sense. Con- sciousness is simple "I," the subject of the proposition: I am certain. I am thiSy which is certain, and the "datum" is that of which I am certain. Thus does the first difference or distinction appear. The "datum," besides being the most abstract of abstrac- tions, is also an individual; it is immediate. It is this last how- ever only with reference to a knoioer, and the knower is such only with reference to a thing Jcnoivn.^ I am certain on account of the "datum;" the "datum" furnishes the certainty tome. Thus knower and thing known 0)ily have significance with reference to one another. Neither has a meaning without this reciprocal reference, and hence each ceases to be immediate and becomes mediate. The object is the essential; it may exist whether it be known or not. Or the knower is the essential; the information may remain after the object ceases to exist. That is to say, the essential pole of this reciprocal relation is determined by the view-point. Now the "datum" is only characterized as immediate in the sense that it is an instance of immediateness. In other places and at other times are other ''data," which are with equal justice characterized by this very predicate of immediate- ness. Immediateness is not a feature of that object yonder that applies uniquely. The extension of the class of things immediate is unlimited, for every individual possesses this feature. The essence of the individual is hence an universal.' These distinc- [17] tions— the first of the / and the '^ datum,^^ and the second of the essence and theinstance — are not furnished by me, but are rather the discoveries of the dialectic. We are not helped if we attempt to come upon the singu- larity of the individual by means of a system of codrdinates in space and time.^ If we refer our object to any system of coordi- nates in space, the space origin is a new individual which is either assumed arbitrarily or is referred to a new origin which in turn is arbitrarily assumed. If a date be attached to the occurrence of the object, the time origin is the new individual which is in question. On this view the object is characterized as the " here" and the ^' now." " To the question: what is the ' now '? we answer for example: the 'now' is the night." The answer however cannot be a truth unless it remain invariable, and this it does not. The "■ now " is twelve o'clock; while I speak the truth of the statement vanishes. Of the ''here" I say: the "here" is a tree. I turn, and the " here " is no longer a tree but a house. Thus the "here" and the "now" are strictly universals, for they are predicated of any one of a number of objects. If then the certainty of sense be the universal, the object is no longer the essential, but rather the knowledge which the subject has of the object. The truth is to be sought in the im- mediateness of my sense perceptions. I assert that the " here " is a tree because I see the tree. Another subject however asserts that the "here" is a house. Both assertions have the same justification, viz., the immediateness of sense perception. What subsists is the / — the / as universal — a perceiving, which is a perceiving, whether it be that of a tree or that of a house. " I mean, to be sure, an individual subject, but I can say as little of this individual subject as I can say of the ' here ' and the ' now.' In so far as I say this ' Aere,' ' noio ' or an individual, I say every this, every ^ here,^ '■ now,^ individual. Just so when I say: /, this individual 7, I say: every I. Each one is what I say; 7, this, individual 7."^ What then are we to answer to the question: what is the " that yonder % " The answer if it be a truth must be lasting. It must represent a feature of that individual thing which is [18] invarient. It must be a feature of which that individual thing yonder is an illustration. We require to put the object in a class by itself; to name a property which applies to it and can apply to no other thing. No such class is thinkable except a null class; the only solution to the condition hypothesized is zero. This solution, while unique, applies however to every illustra- tion of the " that yonder." But that which can be predicated of every individual we call an universal. The universal then turns out to be the stable element of the certainty of sense. Should it be said that the uniqueness of the "that yonder " consists in its relation to the rest of experience —that its particu- lar context can never be repeated in exact detail — one can reply that no account of this context can be given without reference to general terms; in vain is it to be distinguished from an infinite number of possible experiences. Is the individual immediate from one point of view, it is mediate from another. Predicate its essence to be pure being and it disappears. Give it any positive quality and it will from another point of view exhibit the opposite quality. In truth it behaves strictly as a zero ought to behave. Defined in antithesis to the universal it becomes itself an universal; in fact, " the individual is the most universal thing there is, for everything is an individual. "^° III." The truth of the certainty of sense has proven to be the uni- versal. In the origination of this principle two factors separated out— the mental act of reception (perception) and the object. The two are in essence the same— their principle is the universal; the one is a separation of the elements (perception) and the other their combination (the object). Since it is the function of perception to be aware of the separate qualities as determinate and mutually exclusive, its essence consists in negation, determ- inateness or manifoldness. The perception differs from the immediateness of the supposed individual, for it exhibits itself as property or as universal. The properties in so far as they are determinate have a negative character attached to them, i. e., they are exclusive. [19] i The universal as the truth is the essential; the perception and the object the unessential. However in so far as the latter are the things described through the universal, both are essential. Viewed in their reciprocal relationship the one must be essential and the other unessential. The object as that which exists for itself, whether perceived or not, must be further examined. On the view that the object possesses a self-subsistence apart from the perception of it, and granted that its truth is in the nature of an universal, this same object exhibits itself as the thing of complex attributes.^ The existence of a property is mediate in that it expresses its immediateness as its characteristic. It is mediate again in that it predicates itself as the negation of other simultaneously existing attributes. The several properties are differentiated, the one from the other, and are thus not only universaLs but instances of universality as well. The simple universal is rather the medium, in which the several properties subsist and of which they are the expressions — each and every property partakes of universality. The properties of a thing exist together without disturbing one another. This characteristic constitutes the oneness of the thing. It abstracts from the differences and is a simple universal or the medium in which the properties subsist. This unity is nothing more than the "here " and the " now." The properties subsist together and simultaneously. This salt is white, it is also sharp, also heavy, also cubical in form. This indifferent " also " is the simple universal, the medium, the unity of the thing, which binds the properties together. This togetherness of a complex of properties, this indifference which they entertain toward one another, is characteristic of the object and constitutes its essence. The members of a complex of properties have not however alone the purely negative feature of indifference to one another— they have as w611 a positive feature. If they are to differentiate themselves they must be determinate. They must deny their opposites as well as their indifferents. Thus in this sense they cannot subsist in the same medium. In this suit then to estab- lish the object as the truth of perception, reflection has won tliQ, [20] case for his client perception. The object is defeated on his own premises. It is asserted that the essence of the object is the indifference of the several qualities or their self-subsistence, and the pragmatic result which reflection briugs out is the dis- appearance of the qualities, for these cannot be described save as mutually exclusive. The negative character of the several properties — their in- difference to one another, and the positive side — their opposition, exhibit two aspects of the medium:, it is unitary; it is as well an ''also." The discussion of the object as the truth of perception is then for the present complete. It is: (1) passive universality, indifference, the "also;" (2) the universal of opposition, the determinate, the one; and (3) the properties themselves, the' relation of the first two aspects to one another. The truth of the object in whatever aspect it may present itself, is the universal. All the properties as universals and the simple universal as the medium in which they subsist, are as such the possession of the subject. The subject, however, has as yet no assurance that this medium is invariant and hence no assurance that the manner in which its truth is given is always the same. If the subject furnishes any contribution to the datum, then the truth of the datum is changed. On the supposition that the object is the true, the universal, the essen- tial, the self subsistent, while consciousness is the unessential and the changeable, it can happen that the object is not rightly perceived. It is through the experience of this argument that the perceiver first becomes conscious of the possibility oi deception. The object as the truth of perception is the essential, the perceiver the unessential. If the perception is incorrect it is the fault of the perceiver. The object, viewed in the medium, which is the universal, receives the stamp of the medium. Since the object is the self-subsistent and the true, the untruth arises in the perceiver. Assume that the truth of the object, which I perceive, is its unity, its individuality. I perceive the several properties as indifferent to, and as not affecting one another. Eeflection distinguishes the properties as universals and as exclusive, i. e., it is not perceived in the medium in its true aspect. Keflection tells us that a determinate property excludes its opposites and its indifferentsj the self-subsistence, [21] the indifference of the several properties of the object constitute its individuality. As universals the proj)erties are determinate, opposed to one another, excluding one another, i. e., I do not perceive the object correctly; reflection destroys the continuity of the object. As a result of this dialectic circle, consciousness is landed on a higher level. As a result of these distinctions the ex- perience is gained that the truth of the perception and thing per- ceived is to be sought in reflectLQii. ^^ Consciousness corrects the former impression; it distinguishes truth conceptually attained from the untruth of perception. It is aware of refiectiou within itself as distinguished from simple perception. We are aware that the truth as well as the untruth of the object lies in con- sciousness. To be warned of the untruth of perception is to be armed against the possibility of being deceived. Thus when the contradiction of unity and multiplicity arises we recognize it as a distinction of thought. If then the object is one, if its contradictory aspect — the mutually exclusive character of its attributes — arises in me, it is the subject which is responsible for the destruction of the self-subsistence of the object. Properties are assigned to the object depending on the sense organ affected. The salt is white because brought before the eye; it is sharj) when pressed on the tongue; cubical to the sense of sight and of touch, and so on. Tlie subject contributes the latter result and distinguishes the properties from one another. The subject is the medium in which the properties subsist, and the truth of perception is to be sought in the subject. The latter has however but brief space in which to congratulate itself. The dialectic proceeds as before. It is characteristic of the several properties on account of their determinateness and mutual exclusiveness to destroy the unity and continuity of the object. The essence or truth of the object is then its unity, its continuity, i. e., a universal medium in which the properties subsist together. Thus the circle is complete and we are returned to the starting point. The object is one onjj as opposed to other objects. But its unity does not distinguish it from other objects, but the determinateness of its properties — it is the same as any [22] other object witli respect to its oneness. It has properties which distinguish it from other objects. In truth it is the object which is white and cubical, heavy and sharp; or the object is the '' also," the universal medium, and so conceived it is conceived in its reality. The object is one; it is "for itself," but it is no less for the perceiver, just as otherwise the perceiver is "for it." Thus the essential of the object is doubled; it is the object which this time oifers us the contradiction. The determinateuess of the object which is the essential on the one side, is that which dis- tinguishes it from other objects. But that which distinguishes it from other objects puts it into relation to these, and that is to destroy its self-subsistvence, which is its essential feature. The object predicated as "for itself" or as absolute negation of otherness, falls because of its essential characteristic. Nega- tion of otherness is at the same time negation of self. The fate of the object as the truth of perception is then identical with that of the supposed certainty of sense. The latter proved itself an universal. Viewed in the light of its origin, however, it is essentially conditioned by the sensuous. The universal, as the outcome, is essentially dependent ou the start- ing point; the final term as the child of the initial term, bears the birth-mark of its origin. On the view that this antithesis be somehow necessarily dissoluble into a unity, consciousness stands in the presence of the absolute universal, and has for the first time truly entered the kingdom of the understanding. The conviction that the individual of sense is the immediate certainty has been displaced for the conviction that this certainty is the universal, but this universal because of the way in which it has arisen remains the itm'yersaZ of sense. The "thing" of perception is in like manner no less "for itself" than "for another." These sophistries, the "also," the "in so far as," the "es- sential" and the "unessential" as well as the different "points of view, ' ' are the subterfuges of this lower consciousness in the role of the immediate certainty and of perception. They are the weapons of the so-called "sound common sense" ou account [23] of which philosophy is so often accused of having to do only with ' 'things of thought. " In this fashon is this mode of consciousness accustomed to metaphysicize against metaphysics. IV. The truth of the object of consciousness has proven to consist neither in its relation to other objects nor to the subject, for predicate either of these to be essential and it turns out prag- matically to be unessential, i. e., to postulate the relationship involves inherent contradiction. The object has now presented itself in three roles. The dialectic of the certainty of sense ex- hibited this same object as the immediate individual — the im- mediateness of seeing, hearing, etc. It appeared next in the guise of perception as the thing, and lastly in the outcome as undetermined universal, (i. e., undetermined as to content), or as thought. The undetermined universal is now (1) the existent for itself, (2) absolute self-subsistence, — as related to an unessential it is itself unessential — and (3) absolute activity — its range of appli- cation is unlimited — which is equivalent to absolute rest since it is contentless. Consciousness has not yet transcended the deceit of perception, for the attempt to supply a content or an object for its activity must be discarded as unsuccessful. Conscious- ness returns to itself; itself as undetermined universal, for it has not yet seen itself in this contentless form. Again, since its content is lacking, its concept (as form) is still in question, for a concept without application is empty. None the less its essence for consciousness is an objective essence. The object as such subsists so long as consciousness as object and consciousness as subject have not exhibited themselves as coextensive. Thus it is customary to say that for the absolute form and content are identical. The positive result of the outcome is that the untruth of perception, and simultaneously that of the understanding, is removed and consequently the concept of truth is attained. Until the experience of untruth the conception of truth is not realized. This concept appears as the existent '' true in itself," [24] as lacking a ''consciousness in itself," as a something for which the understanding stands sponsor, and as an existent of which consciousness is aware but in which it does not partake. Con- sciousness that is not consciousness of an object is not conscious- ness. It is form without content, or otherwise activity divorced of passivity. Consciousness must become this concept in all its phases and is then become thinking consciousness. The outcome is universal in the purely negative sense that the one- sided concept formerly adhered to is discarded, but also in the positive sense, in the conviction that the two poles of the antithesis — the "in itself" and the "for another'' — are essentially identical. The universal in question would seem to exhibit merely the form, or the relation of the one pole to the other, but it represents as well the content, since the antithesis can have no other illustration than is given in the outcome. Again, the con- tent is universal since it applies to any "existent" that is in a determinate way both "in itself" and "for another." The experience is gained that form and content as univ^ersals, (and hence in the true sense), are identical. The essential nature of the outcome is that it presents the object of consciousness as universally "in itself" and "for another," so that the result is universal in the absolute sense. "^ The undetermined universal, since it is the o^'ect of con- sciousness, may be considered both as to form and as to content and to examine this opposition of form and content is to perceive that we are again on familiar ground. The content is on the one hand an universal medium, in which subsists a pluralism of prop- erties, and on the other a self-contained unity. As self-contained unity it is viewed as the "existent in itself;" as universal medium it implies the dissolution of the thing's self- subsistence. The medium reveals itself as passivity, as the "existent for another." The experience is now at hand that these ways of viewing the universal are not unconnected but are essentially related through the form: they are the modes in which the universal reveals itself, for both moments are in essence undetermined universals and are predicated as essentially contradictory aspects of the same. The medium is to be viewed as identical with the self- subsistence of a group of properties or the medium as universal [25] IS nothing more than this self-subsistence. This self- subsistence implies a group of properties that are essentially exclusive; the properties are different but exist side by side. The self-subsist- ence however implies the dissolution of the differences and this the pure "existent for itself." The last is the medium and this again is uothiug unless something in which differences subsist. On the one hand we are aware of the uuiversal as the medium, the self- subsistence of the properties, or the essence of the object, i. e., the universal is essentially the pluralism of the several properties. The movement of the dialectic presents two mo- ments. On the one view the object is a collection of self-subsistent material, on the other it is a self-subsistent unity. The second aspect does not properly appear until the first has presented itself to view. Either aspect immediately implies the other or contains this implication in itself, while each one requires the other to render it meaningful. This implied transition, this implication of the other, which each moment possesses in itself, is termed force^* (Kraft). It is in nature essentially periodic, for the points of view are seen to repeat themselves, although the outcome is not coincident with the starting point. The one moment, the truth of the ob- iect regarded as a collection of propeities self-subsistent in the medium, its development, is the expressio'n}^ of the force. The other moment the vanishing of this self-subsistence is the force proper- The latter result cannot however be obtained until the expression is realized, for it follows upon this. On the view that these distinctions are essentially the im- plications of the dialectic they are seen to be the property of the understanding. The differences in question are not in them- selves distinguished; they are distinctions of thought or they are conceptual in nature. The aspects of the object are only mean- ingful in so far as they exhibit themselves in this antithetical guise. The concept of the process represents then the carrier of the two moments, or the substance of the process. Each moment is substantial in so far as each one contains the process by im- plication in itself. We have as features of this concept, on the one hand the two vanishing moments, each one holding the warrant for the dissolution of the other, and on the other hand [20] the force proper as exclusive unity. The force as such only exists (by definition) in the form of this antithesis. The object of consciousness has now for its content these two contradictory self-destructive moments. Being for consciousness this content is objective-, but, since it is contradictory and so, self- destructive the truth becomes the non-objective, (something not for con- sciousness), or tbe " inner side of things-'' ^^^ The "force"' of the understanding has ceased to be the simple unitary concept that it was in its origin. Without its development, its expression, the "force'' of perceptiom it is unrealized and hence presents itself as postulating and as depend- ent upon this expression. It contains within itself the impli- cation of the expression but it contains as well the implication that the expression be dissolved, or it presents itself as unity, for the " force" of perception and the "force" of the under- standing are self- destructive (contradictory) and cannot exist side by side. As unity its essence is alien to it, for this consists in the standing contradiction. Nevertheless the "other," (the alien essence), that implies expression and dissolution is itself "force." If then "force" as unity and "force" as "other" are self-subsistent "forces " the domination of unity is dissolved. On the other hand as the " inner side " of things or the non-ob- jective — perception is nothing if not objective — the development of the self-subsistent properties is excluded and hence " force" is another again distinct from ' ' force ' ' proper. These distinctions are: As content— As form— The unity of The medium of Postulating Postulated the two "forces" self-subsistent (active). (passive), (expression and materials, force proper), "for us," objective "In itself" self-subsistent, mutually or for a conscious- exclusive and opposed, ness. Ij as form : active, postula- IJ as content : passive, postulated, ting, "for itself" "for another." Then as content : Then as form : universal medium "force" proper. of different properties. [27] The non-objective or "inner side of things" is, as its con- cept implies, far from being the immediate object of conscious- ness. The nuderstanding is supposed to gain this vision of the true background of things through the medium of the self- destructive " forces." An A, which contains within itself the immediate implication of a nou-A, is self- contradictory. For this reason we call it appearance; not as instance or as illustra- tion but as a totality of appearance or as universal Every genuine appearance as such implies its own unreality. Through the mean of appearance the true or "inner" side becomes the object of consciousness, but only as concept without content, as the negation of appearance. Because then of the contradiction of perceptive and defini- tional necessity, the understanding distinguishes the sensible world or the world of appearances from the supersensible or the true world- The mean that unites the understanding with the inner truth is appearance, and it is this because it does not represent truth itself but rather the pathway to truth. It is the medium through which truth is seen. To render the notion of truth intelligible we require the notion of apparent truth or falsity. The absolute universal which unites conceptually the antithesis of individual and universal is a thought distinction and hence furnished by the understanding. If the " inner truth " is to be perceived at all it is by this side of consciousness. On this view the sensible world takes its place as the world of appearance in contradistinction to a supersensible or the true world — the transient "present" as over against the permanent " beyond." Our object is then this antithesis, the two extremes which consciousness on the side of the understanding has before it. The mean that unites conceptually the two extremes is appear- ance. The "beyond" has as yet no content. It is only defined as the negation of appearance and as simple universal. This mode of the "beyond" is the Kantian sort. As such then it is unknowable, V)eing defined as that which lies beyond conscious- ness. Because the reason is too shortsighted or limited, it is only known through its manifestations in appearances. But now if this "beyond"' be forever unknowable; if the curtain can never [28] €3^ be raised and its content revealed, then there is no choice but to cling to appearances, i. e., to hold that true which is not true \ by definition. Nevertheless the supersensible has arisen and is at hand. It comes from appearance and appearance is its mean, its e^^sence, indeed its consummation. It is the truth of appearance. But the truth and essence of the perceived world is that it be appear- ance, and thus the supersensible is apijearauce as appeanmce and hence the world of immediate sensuous certainty and per- ception. But appearance is the sensible world of perception stripped of its reality and predicated as having its truth in the "beyond." The sensible world as in itself reality is not appearance. Appearance and the "inner side'' immediately imply one another and the necessity of this implication is essentially defi- nitional. Appearances are the implications of the "inner" — the "inner" is the legislator — appearances are legislated for- Appearances are the eajpression of the "inner." The "inner" postulates its expression and is in so far active, while appearance is the postulated and is thus passive- This distinction as the universal aspect of the play of "force" is its truth or the law of "force." The "inner" appears then as a kingdom of laws,^^ beyond the pe"rceived world and legislating for appearance. When the curtain is raised on this "beyond," this self-active legislator, the self-consciousness is revealed- This kingdom of laws is however only the ^'first trutK'' and does not wholly account for appearance. The law is in some sense present in the process of change but does not supply the entire reality of the process. It can never supply the existential ele- ment. Under different circumstances the law is differently realized. Thus there remains for appearances an aspect unac- counted for by the "inner truth'' of the supersensible world." This weakness of law to account for appearance appears to lie in its universal character; in its jack of determinateness. Indeed the kingdom is essentially a plurality and this contradicts the supposition that the truth of the understanding is in nature an unitary something. In so far now as this kingdom is one law— not law in general— it is determinate, and what we would [29] wish to do would be to reduce all law to one law, e. g., the law of gravitatioD. But by this very process the law loses its determinateuess. Its rauge of application becomes more and more general. The concept arrived at is only the very general one of the universal conformity to law of all reality, a concept however with a content, a feature lacking in the "inner truth" as first conceived, but one that in no way accounts for the sensi- ble world itself. Eeflection upon the problem of change and its explanation continually points to the standing contrast of these two worlds — the one thedomain of rationality, of definition, of description, the intellectual, the fixed, the birthplace of inferences; the other the realm of perception, the changeable, the world of appearances, where accidents, the unclassified and undescribed residue of ex- isting things are born. It is in the latter sphere that natural law seems to find its realization. The concept of law, we are tempted to say, cannot be the essential aspect of change, for the concept is only created in answer to a practical demand. It is in essence an after-thought, a postulate superadded. If the determinate character of law is that which adheres to appearance or has its sufficient reason in appearances than this feature of law is accidental. We are accustomed to contrast the concept with what is accidental to our formula of change, but in devel- oping this contrast we are continually reminded that what is accidental is incidental as well. The accidental as the unexplained residue is father to the concept, for its existence provokes a logical demand. It arouses an activity whose response is the concept. As such it is a "force" responsible for the creation of its own antithesis, and on this view it is prior to its antithesis. The concept that does not arise in answer to a practical demand is a phantasy of the imagination and itself an accident, and thus the meaningful or intelligible concept is essentially dependent upon the phenomenal. Nevertheless since the accidental is not meaningful until its contrast with what is essential comes to light, the concept is prior to the appearance. If the latter be contrasted with the concept, then it is the concept of law that exhibits the law's inner necessity. A law establishes or states a relationship that obtains among [30] appearances and at the same time presnpposes a difference or a distinction. This difference is however a general one; the law furnishes no test of its own application. The distinction supplied is not one which cleaves to the sensible world itself but is furnished by the understanding. When for example we speak of a positive electricity, we at once suppose another kind, a negative electricity. This distinction is not one that attaches to the thing in itself but is rather supplied by the subject. The necessity of the law which describes the behavior of positive and negative electricity with reference to one another, is the necessity which follows on the definition of the describer. This is to say that it is its own necessity which the understanding predicates, and not a necessity that inheres in the natural event itself. In so far however as the law is recognized at all it is in the sensible world. It is always this last which gives illustration to the law. If then the supersensible world be only mediate, if it be only known through appearances, its characterization as the king- dom of laws, as the unchangeable image of the perceived world, is lost. Conceived only through appearances the sensible world be- comes its only reality. It is through the experience of this result that consciousness is aware that it is indeed its own contradiction, which is at hand. This contradiction is the " inverted world.^^ The ' 'inverted world' ' is the construct of the self', the contradiction is produced by me- I distinguish myself from the conclusion that my judgment draws; it is the behavior of my own conscious- ness that must be further examined. The procedure of meta- physic has then no alternative but to view these results in the light of their newly found origin, as the constructs of the self's consciousness. The second supersensible world, the " inverted world," is the antithesis of the first and of itself, for it contains this implication within itself. An appearance is genuine if it contains within itself the implication of its own unreality and it is after this fashion that the supersensible world presents itself. It is appearance as appearance. An appearance is an A which implies the truth of a non-A. Thus what is in the first super- sensible world sweet, is in the second or " inverted world " sour; the moral principles which the one world exalts are the prin- piples of evil in the second. The supersensible world as the [31] realm of the self's activity is appearance, and since this appear- ance has become object of consciousness, now for the first time consciousness is become the self-consciousness.^^ The Truth of the Certainty of Self. The truth of the certainty of the modes of consciousness considered up to now has been distinct from the certainty itself. Up to now truth has been for consciousness, but always in some sense distinct from consciousness. In the mill of dialectic this truth — the "existent" of sensuous certainty, the "thing" of perception, the "force" (Kraft) of the understanding — was seen to disappear. Every one of these three modes of supposed certainty, each after its own manner, played th© part of a " thing in itself," and when each "in itself" remained unintel- ligible without reference "to another," the truth and the certainty vanished together. Dialectic has then to treat of a mode of certainty that has not previously appeared. The alternative immediately at hand is the identification of certainty with the "existent" conscious of itself (Selbstbewusstein), and it is in the role of this alterna- tive that the self- consciousness appears. To test the validity of the identity of certainty and consciousness in its new guise is the next task of the natural dialectic. The immediate, the "in itself," shall not be obtained conceptually but shall be intuited. The certain fact is the fact of consciousness. The " for another' ' shall be robbed to pay the "in itself." The certainty in question lies "in itself" but it is no less "for another;"for in so farasit is "for itself" it is for conscious- ness. In the sense that the ego is the certainty it is "/or itself," but in the sense that it is its own object or the object of conscious- ness — in the sense that is object — it is "for another." The philosophical satisfaction which is our gain in viewing the ego as the certain fact of consciousness is that we have our hands on the elusive individual; if an illustration of singularity, of uniqueness, is to be found, it is here. On this view the world of j)erception presents itself as pure negation — negation of the self — while the self is the negation of the perceived world. In this relationship the self is " in itself," [32] but it is also ''for another," viz: the perceived world. Viewed in itself it is viewed as the certain or the true; in relation to the other as the false or as appearance. N^evertheless this antithesis of certainty and appearance is essential, for without it there remains but the empty tautology, the "I am I." To seek the true is to suppose the possibility of the false. Our relationship presents a complete reciprocity. Does the certainty of self require the concept of apparent certainty or falsity to give it meaning, then for like reason does appearance find its justifica- tion in antithesis to a supposed certainty. Is the ego in any sense self-subsistent, then so in the same sense must be the non-ego. The need, which the ego has for the non-ego, without which the ego is devoid of meaning, is desire.^^ Those aspects of the non-ego which have a meaning and value and hence an interest for the ego are in so far living^^ (organic). Those features of the non-ego which lack significance for the ego are in so far inorganic- It is the task of philosophy to render the inorganic meaningful; to indicate the values that attach to the varied phases of the cosmos, designated in its elementary state, the perceived world. Thus through the medium of dialectic the inorganic constantly tends to become organic. The real cosmos in its full signification is the final term of a developmental process. "What of the non-ego is of meaning for the ego thereby ceases to be non-ego. Thus is its reference, its value, destroyed and created by the same act. Its truth is, as it was before, both "in itself and ''for another" and in this consists its individuality or the substance of its life. In so far as the process of rendering meaningful the non-ego is viewed as living process or as experi- ence is the concept of pure ego attained. In so far as the non-ego (as object) is absorbed in the ego (subject) does there not result philosophical satisfaction, and must result, for the outcome is truth. The inorganic, as the negation and object of desire of consciousness, is a consciousness. "The sell's consciousness attains its satisfaction only in another self's consciousness." Here first in the "I which is we and the we which is I" does the concept of mind make its appearance. In the reciprocal relationship of ego and non-ego the be- Jiavior of the one is always in some sense behavior of the [33] other. lu different senses each is at the same time knower and thing known. The life of the selfs consciousness as "in itself" consists in the overthrow of its neg:atives and indifferents — a one -directional process. The life of the other is equally a one- directional process but in the opposite sense. The life of the one is not compatible then with that of the other; each is com- mitted to the death of the other, and must enter the contest, ^^ for the task prescribed it is to raise the certainty of self to the rank of the truth for it, and the truth for the other. The individual which has not risked^^ this experience has not attained the truth which the starting point assumed, (viz, the certainty of self), for it has not yet seen itself in the other. Through this very process however is the initial postulate of the certainty of self destroyed. Does the non-ego turn out to be the essential then the ego is the unessential. Does the ego survive either actually through the act or as the final term of a process conceived as an ideal, then there is lost the antitheses which rendered it meaningful, for if all is ego, what is the utility of the certainty of self postulated as an initial truth ? In the experience of this process the self at first appears alone as the self-subsistent certainty; but it required to make it intelligible an antithetical term. This term in so far as it turned out to have a positive content or to be intelligible was in so far the possession of the self; in so far as it was mere negation, or unrealized possibility, it dissolved. The final result is the loss of the initial truth on the death of the antithetical term. The self, because of its behavior in the context of this dia- lectic and after the experience of it, is become master- The abstract existence, the non-self, for the like reason and since it too was essential, is become servanf^'^ These correlatives are not intelligible apart from one another. The truth then of the certainty of self lies in this serving consciousness, for predicate it unessential and our initial truth vanishes. It follows that our essential pole is reversed, and the truth of the certainty of self is destroyed. The consciousness of the self, which first appeared as abstract or simple ego in the certainty of self, has come then to present many differences in its make up. At first characterized as sim- ple, self-subsistent, inert, it is become producing or formative [34J iu nature. Its life is conserved through its relation to an antithet- ical term (thingness). Because of its formative nature it is free, in the sense that it is controlled only by the necessity of its own nature, but its freedom only is intelligible as in contrast to a serving consciousness — the visualized, the imaged, the external existent. It is former or producer because of a thing formed or produced and in this sense it is free. Again the substance of its life is that it thinks, and thought deals in concepts, not images or objects. The last are the wares of the serving consciousness, which he lays at the feet of his monarch which is thought. But a monarch without a vassel is a meaningless term; the freedom of a thinking consciousness is clear because of a consciousness whose perceptions are given. Not the consciousness of a world order subject to teleological or mechanical description, whether this consciousness be my own or an alien one, is the essential consciousness, but the thinking consciousness, which cannot be represented as other than mine and inseparable from me. The exaltation of this free or thinking consciousness as an ethical end, is the principle of the Stoic. ^^ The freedom of the thinking consciousness is exercised how- ever no less in the realm of the serving consciousness than in its own domain. The macrocosm, the world of individual things and natural events, calls for description and explanation, and hence presents a choice to«microcosm as to how this task is to be accomplished. The microcosm is free within certain limits.^* Not as the ruling consciousness does it find its truth in the serv- ing consciousness but ''on its throne even as in its chains" in the concept of its freedom. Its essence is thought (an abstract essence) and consists not in the actual exercise of its freedom, but in a self- subsistence that stands apart from the serving con- sciousness. Standing apart from the world of individual things as a forming principle, it has in itself no content but its content is given. The content is alien to it, and in so far as it thinks, it thinks an alien existence. In this manner is the dilemma of Stoicism presented. The good, the true, is the attainment of pure reason, contentless thought. But would the free consciousness think, it must think [35] a content. ^-^ The end is forbidden through its own legislation. The ideal hypothesized prevents its own attainment and our interest in it is lost because of its consequent. For the Stoic the world of perception is the unessential. His task is the attainment of a world of pure thought the chief feature of which is that it shall be free. But free of what ? Why, the world of perception. The latter is essential then on the Stoic's own premises, for it is presupposed by him if his freedom is to have a meaning. The realization of this dilemma, to be aware that this mode of the "in itself is but an incomplete negation of the "other," is the standpoint of scepticism. For the Stoic the dilemma did not appear as such, by the Sceptic it is realized and accej^ted. Dialectic has now arrived at a new station in her progress. Convinced of the freedom of the thinking self as the negation of the world of perception (the unessential), the Sceptic is aware that his truth has vanished without knowing how. The world of perception is repudiated for the thinking self, but by this very act is the truth of the thinking self destroyed. The nothingness of the materials furnished by perception is asserted by the subject and yet the subject sees, feels, hears. Moral principles are exalted as the ruling principles of action and their nothingness asserted in the same breath. The pleasure of th^ceptic is to remain in contradiction with himself. Let one assert that ''a" is ''b," he will prove the opposite on the same premises. For the sophistic temperament, the presence of inner contra- diction is a satisfaction. Its delight is to hold the antithetical poles apart; to see the truth vanish the instant one attempts to lay hands on it. The rationalistic temperament in the presence of this dilemma is the "unfortunate consciousness." The latter feels the need and indeed the necessity of overcoming the dilemma but is at the same time convinced of its binding force. This dual consciousness, which presents the inner contradic- tion, must be unified. The most prominent feature of this unity is as yet the radical difference of the thinking (invariant) self and the serving (variant) self. We perceive the law as in some pense present in the process of change. By the act of putting [36] that red thing yoDder in the class of red things; in so far as that quality (red) is a familiar quality, is the universal perceived as present income sense in that thing yonder. The serving or alien consciousness perceives the thinking consciousness in itself. But the thinking consciousness, in so far as it thinks, thinks an alien content, or it perceives the other in itself. Each conscious- ness perceives the other in itself, and the motive for the belief of the "unfortunate consciousness" that in truth it must be one consciousness, free of contradiction, finds its justification in this reciprocal relationship. [37] NOTES. Page 13, Note 1. " The existence of finite things, (and so of finite ideas), cannot be explained according to notions of cause and effect. With the appreciation of this law all philosophy begins; for without it we have never the need to philosophize— with- out it all our knowledge is merely empirical, a progression from cause to effect." {Schelling's s'ammtliche Werke, Abth. I. Bd. /., 8. 368.) Page 14, Note 2. Fichte {Soimmtliche Werke, Abth. I.Bd. I., S. 422-423) divides the objects of consciousness (Vorstellungen) into two classes, (1) those accompanied by the feeling of freedom and (2) those accompanied by the feeling of necessity. Of the first class it is meaningless to ask why they are so and not otherwise (in the absolute sense), since the law of suflScient reason does not govern the domain of freedom. They are so because we say they shall be so; had we said they should be otherwise then they would be otherwise. The system of ideas accom- panied by the feeling of necessity is called experience, and it is the problem of philosophy to furnish the sufficient reason for this second class. (Thus the mathematician may select his parameters in accordance with any conditions that he may see fit to impose, the number of conditions being only limited by the number of parameters. He has certain degrees of freedom. The astronomer is free to regard the sun as revolving around the earth or vice I'ersa, his choice being governed in this case by the simplicity of description that results from the latter selection. Again the physicist, the biologist, or the psy- chologist arbitrarily dictates the conditions of any given experiment.) The science of the first class of ideas would be, for Fichte, scientific method, that of the second class, philosophy. The phenomena of mind brought out by the dialectic as a necessary tendency are called then experiences by Hegel in the same sense as the term is employed by Fichte. Page 14, Note 3. Compare in this connection two passages, the first from Fichte and the second from Schelling. "If it be undeniable that the speculative reason is indebted for every human advance that she has accomplished to the comments of scepticism on the uncer- tainty of her previous resting point, * * * then nothing is more desirable than that the sceptic should crown his work and that the investigating reason should attain her exalted end." (I. 1, 3.) "How infinitely more has the sceptic served the cause of true philosophy by declaring war on every system claiming universal validity ! how infinitely more than the dogmatist, who would have all minds swear by the symbol of a theoretical science!" (1. 1, 307.) Page 15, Note 4. This is the view of Schelling. "Philosophy must not be a creation that only causes one to admire the inge- [38] nuity of the author. She must portray the march of the human mind itself not that of this or that individual's." (I. 1, 293.) Page 16, Note 5. * * * "the thing is, and it is only because it is." {Phiinomenologie des Oeistes, Ooebhardt, Bamberg und Wicrzburg, 1807, S. 23) Also Schelling Werke, Abth. I. Bd. /., Moglichkeit einer Form der Philosophie, and Fichte Werke, Abth. I. Bd. /., Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre. Page 17, Note 6. "Now the more immediate the experience so much the nearer its disappear- ance. Indeed the intuition of sense, so long as it is merely this, borders on nothing. * * * But so long as the intuition turns to objects, i. e. so long as it is sensuous, it runs no risk of losing itself. The ego in so far as it discovers opposition, is necessitated to contrast itself with this, i. e., to return unto itself . * * * Were I to pursue the intellectual intuition I would cease to live. I go then 'out of time into eternity.' " {Hchelling, Werke, I. 1, 325,) Page 17, Note 7. A procedure, by which that individual thing yonder might be characterized uniquely or put in a class by itself, is suggested by the law of traditional logic viz., "as the intension of our descriptive terms is increased, the extension is decreased." Thus by characterizing that individual yonder with a succession of predicates and so excluding other objects which lack these predicates, we might hope to arrive at last at a class whose only illustration is the individual thing in question. Of course the law does not hold if • the extension of our delimiting predicates gives a resultant class whose extension is not limited and the only way to determine whether this extension be finite or not is by the path of experiment. There appear however to be practical difficulties— not to speak of the logical contradiction at hand when such a problem is stated— involved in a complete canvass of possible experience. Moreover no account of this experi- ence can be given save in terms of universals. If contradictory predicates be attached to the individual in question, it is at once put in the zero class and is admittedly nothing, but excluding this case let predicate be heaped on predicate as long as we please, the extension of the final class having all these predicates is as much open to question as before. Nor is this all. Not even one predicate can be attached with assurance. Any experiment is subject to error. Any measurement has a probable error attached. A knowledge of facts can be only approximated, never exactly attained through experiment. The real fact is the limit of a series of approximations, forever beyond the reach of knowledge by experiment, a " thing in itself." On this latter point cf. Prof. E. A. Singer, Jr., " KanVs First Antinomy, ^^ Philosophical Review, July, 19U9. Page 18, Note 8. Space and time in the " transcendentale Aesthetik" (Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft) are supposed to account for individuality. [39] Page IS, Note 9. It is clear that the individual here plays the part of the Kantian " Ding an sich " — the " Ding an sicli " of the transcendental esthetic. The real individ- ual in this connection is unknowable, and answers appropriately to the concept of nothing. Viewed as an ideal— as the limit of a series of approximations— it is the absolute. The identification of the concept of nothing with that of the absolute may be not without motive. Thus if the absolute be that which has all predicates, (the God of rationalism), then it is nothing, for that which is every- thing is nothing. It may be noted in addition that the existence of the real fact, forever beyond the reach of experiment, is one of the fundamental postulates of physical science. It is on this common ground according to Schelling that realism and idealism merge and become identical. Page 19, Note 10. The "Ding ansich^'' of Kant appears in some connections as '■'■ Empfindung'''' a content somehow alien to the subject, the individual of the present context. Schelling in a foot note expressly designates this a zero. (I. 1, 95. > Cf. Note 6, first sentence. Cf . note 12, the last quotation. Again: "to be afifected is nothing but negative activity. An absolutely passive being is absolutely nothing (a nihil privativum) .'''' (I. 1, 369.) Page 19, Note 11. This discussion should be read in the light of Fichte's Bestimmung des Menschen.'' (I. 2, 199-247.) Page 20, Note 12. "In our experience <7te thing, that which is determined independently of our freedom and that according to which our knowledge should fashion itself, and intelligence, that which knows, are indissolubly connected. The philosopher is able to abstract the one from the other and has then abstracted from experience and raised himself above these. Let him abstract from the latter and he gets an intelligence i7i it self, {that is, one abstracted from its relation to experience) ; let him abstract from the first and he gets a thing in itself, (that is, one abstracted from the fact of its occurrence in experience), as the explanation of experience. The first procedure is idealism, the second dogmatism.'''' {Fichte, Werke, I. 1, 425-6.) The following from Schelling can hardly be translated: "Bedingen heisst die Handlung, wodurch etwas zum Ding wird, bedingt, das was zum Ding gemacht ist, woraus zugleich erhellt, dass nichts durch sich selbst als Ding gesetzt sein kann, d. h. dass ein unbedingtes Ding ein Widerspruch ist. " (1. 1, 166.) Page 22, Note 13. For Fichte the term "■Reflexion"' is opposed to "Abstraction.''^ "Abstrac- tion'''' is the mental act, through freedom, of separating the form from the content, while "Eefle.Hon'^ is the act of supplying form with a given content. (1.1,67.) Page 26, Note 14. The monads, the Leibnitzian substance, are immaterial and besouled, [40] They are perceiving forces. The activity of the monads is an activity of per- ceptions. The tendency of one perception to pass into another is called ''desireJ^ Cf. Note 19. In Fichte (I. 2, 101) the position is assumed for the moment that I am myself the expression of a force alien to me (natural necessity)—! am ■what natural necessity makes of me; to be discarded for the resolution that I will be this force myself, (through freedom)— I will be what I chose to make myself— I will be my own ultimate ground of action. The object here, as the expression of a force alien to it, (the dialectic pro- cess), is what the dialectic has made it. Its features have been supplied by the process. As thought-construct it is the expression of the thinking force. Cf. Note 20. The terms motion {Beiuegung) and expression {Aeusserung) may be explained by comparing their use with Schelling's habit of thought. In so far as the mind views her phenomena as changing creations of her own is she aware of a principal of activity within herself. " Such a being is living." " Live in the visible analogue of spiritual being," (I. 1, 38S.) " The mere succession of ideas, intuited as external, gives the conception of mechanical motion. But the soul should not only intuite this succession, but herself in this succession, and (since she only intuites her own activity) should intuite herself as active in this succession." {Ibid., S. 385.) Page 27, Note 15. " To penetrate the ' inner side ' of objects, i. e., to assume that appearances are determinable, with respect to their reality, independently of the ego." {Schelling, Werke, I. 1, 212, note.) Page 29, Note 16. The early writings of Schelling furnish not only the most important source for the ideas embodied in the early part of the " Phanomenologie " but also the most enlightening commentary on the same. If Hegel could have been clear he might have written the following passage and foreshadowed at once the transi- tion which the present essay has been endeavoring to present. " Doubtless Kant said that the laws of nature are the human mind's modes of action, the conditions under which our intuition itself is first possible; but he added: nature is nothing distinct from these laws, it is only a progressive process of the infinite mind, in which the latter first comes to self-consciousness and through which it gives to this self-consciousness extension, permanence, continuity and necessity." {Schelling, Werke, I. 1, 361.) Page 29, Note 17. This indifference which the law and the law's illustration entertain toward one another is explained for Leibnitz by his theory of the "pre-established harmony'" of the monads; for Berkeley by regarding facts as tho thoughts of a divine intellect. Cf. the quotation above, which is in general a fair enough representation of the standpoint of German idealism. Page 32, Note 18. The law which exhibits the absolute identity of subject and object is arrived [41] at by Pichte after somewhat the same fashion as the dialectic might be expected to deduce it. The starting point is indifferent. Any empirical fact is selected and we are asked to think away the empirical conditions. (In Hegel the accidental is removed in the dialectic process.) That which remains and which cannot be thought away is then recognized as something presupposed by every empirical fact. This is the mental act of predicating the fact's existence and the ego is this act or activity. The ego predicates itself through its mere exist- ence and exists because of the act of predication. The discovery of the fact whose existence is involved in its own defluition is the aim of all rationalism. For Fichte this fact is the ego, the ego as act or activity. (1. 1, 91-98.) rage 33, Note 19. '^Begierde,^^ i. e., the need of the thinking force- for what is essential to it, but which is not yet reality in the sense that it is not yet realized. Cf. the use of the terms "A>a/r' and ''Begierde" in Fichte's Bestimvnoig des Menschen. (I. 2, 176-198, in particular in the context of page 187.) Cf. again note 14, the first paragraph. Page 33, Note 20. For Fichte the object of philosophy is not properly a construct of the philos- opher himself. The object expresses itself as so and so ; the philosopher is merely observer and describer. The artificial object of the first sort is dead concept to which the investigation is related passively. In the case of the improper object of philosophy attention is directed to the matter (as the acci- dental) and not to the form, the self active power (Kraft). Tne matter being passive, the object is then appearance, whereas the proper object is concept. The proper object is active and living concept and through its necessity philosophical knowledge is created. The philosopher observes the behavior of the ego. "He proposes an experiment." (I. 1, 454.) Cf. Note 24, last two quotations. Again, according to the Wissenschaftslehre, every purposive activity, mental or physical, is accompanied by the " intellectual intuition " of the con- sciousness of self. Intellectual intuition and sensuous intuition never occur separately but always in conjunction. Thus the intellectual intuition is viewed as the source of life (activity), in the world of sense and without it the sensuous world is conceived as dead. {Ibid, S. 463.) Cf. the following quotation from Schelling: " We awake from the intel- lectual intuition as from the state of death. We awake through reflection, i. e., through necessitated return to ourselves. But without opposition is no return; without an object no reflection is thinkable. An activity is living if it be di- rected to objects alone, dead if it lose itself in itself. But man should be neither lifeless nor merely living being. His activity turns of necessity to objects but as necessarily does it turn back to himself. Through the former does he distin- guish himself from the lifeless, through the latter from merely living (animal) being." (I. 1, 325.) Cf . Note 6. Again: -'That which is object is something dead, passive, self -capable of no action, and only object, of action." (I. 1, 367.) [42] Page 34, Note 2i. In the following passage from Schelling the non-ego is for the dogmatist the absolute. For the idealist such an absolute disappears in the light of criticism. "I understand you, dear friend! You conceive it more sublime to contest an absolute power and, fighting, to succumb, than to insure yourself in the first place against all risk through the assumption of a moral God. Certainly this struggle against the infinite is not alone the most sublime that a man can con- ceive, but is on my view, itself the principle of all sublimity. But I should like to know how you will find in dogmatism an explanation of the power by which man opposes himself to the absolute, as well as of the feeling which accompanies the struggle. The consistent dogmatism does not succumb through strife but through acquiescence, not through a violent but through a voluntary destruc- tion, through quiet surrender of myself to the absolute object." (I. 1, 284.) Page 34, Note 22. The terms are Fichte's. Cf. " I will that I be lord of nature and that nature be my servant; I will that I have over her an influence appropriate to my own power {Kraft), but that she have none over me." (I. 2, 192-93.) "So long as man remains in the domain of nature, is he in the most appro- priate sense of the word, as he can be loi'd of himself, lord of nature. He knows the objective world in her determinate limits, over which she dare not impose. In that he represents the object to himself, in that he prescribes for the object form and consistency, does he dominate the same. He has nothing to fear from it, for he has himself prescribed its limitations." {Schelling, Werke, I. 1, 337.) Page 35, Note 23. Hegel is frequently nothing but Schelling rendered obscurely. The method of thesis, antithesis and synthesis is illustrated in the following passage: "Whosoever has reflected concerning Stoicism and Epicureanism, the two most contradictory of moral systems, has easily seen that both agree in the same ultimate end. The Stoic, who seeks to free himself of the influence of external objects, struggles after happiness no less than the Epicurean, who sub- merges himself in the arms of the world. The former makes himself independent of sensuous needs, in that he satisfies none, the latter, in that he satisfies all. "The one seeks to attain the final end, absolute happiness, metaphysically , through abstraction from all sensibility ; the other physically, t\iToufc,h cova.- plete indulgence of sensibility. But the Epicurean was metaphysicist, in that his problem, to attain happiness through the successive indulgence of individual needs, was unending. The Stoic was physicist, since his abstraction from all sensibility could only succeed gradually in a temporal series. The one would attain his final end through progression, the other through regression. Never- theless both sought the same ultimate end, the end of absolute happiness and satisfaction " (Opp. cit. S. 829.) It is customary to say that in the absolute freedom and necessity coincide. The absolute both prescribes and obeys its own law. When the absolute is attained all is object of knowledge and freedom is no more. If the absolute become object of knowledge, my own freedom is annihilated by the absolute causality. [43] Page 35, N^ote 24. A Thu8 in Fichte that which introduces limitations is the objective, which is opposed to freedom as indeterminateness. Whenever I think, I think something determinate. "I hold myself with freedom in this sphere when I view myself and / a77i held through this sphere and limited by it." (I. 1, 492.) The view of Schelling is the same : "Thus I will be conscious of my freedom only in so far as I feel myself con- trolled in reference to the object. — JVo consciousness of the object without consciousness of freedom, no consciousness ofjreedom without consciousness of the object." (I. 1, 371.) rage 36, Note 25. "Now along with absolute freedom no self -consciousness is thinkable. An activity, for which there exists no object, no opposition, never returns to itself. Only through return to itself does consciousness arise. Only limited reality is actuality for us. {Schelling, Werke, I. 1, 324.) Again: "When an activity which is no longer limited by objects and which is wholly absolute, is no longer accompanied by any consciousness; when unlimited activity is identical with ab- solute rest; when the supreme moment of being borders on non-being; then does criticism as well as dogmatism involve self -destruction. Does the latter demand that I be submerged in the absolute object, so must conversely the former demand that all which is object shall disappear in the intellectual intuition of myself. In both cases all is for me object, and at the same time all consciousness of myself as subject is lost. My reality disappears in the infinite." {Ibid, 6'. 527.) [44] •H. 14 DAY USE RETURN TO DESK FROM WHICH BORROWED This book IS due on the last date stamped below, on the date to which renewed. Renewed books are subject to immediate recall M^ V hi J 5 2 J>ec ? iff}^ ^ ^ we ^ .A- JATT 8 1978 T- nn LD21-35m-8,'72 (Q4189sl0)476— A-32 General Library University of California Berkeley