LIBRARY 
 
 UNIVERSITY OP 
 
 CALIFORNIA 
 
 IRVINE
 
 T? 
 
 r .
 
 BURT FRANKLIN RESEARCH AND SOURCE WORKS SERIES No. 43 
 
 THE 
 
 CAMERALISTS
 
 THE 
 
 CAMERALISTS 
 
 THE PIONEERS OF GERMAN 
 SOCIAL POLITY 
 
 BT 
 
 ALBION W. SMALL 
 
 BURT FRANKLIN RESEARCH AND SOURCE WORKS SERIES No. 43 
 
 BURT FRANKLIN 
 
 New York 25, N.Y.
 
 Published by 
 BURT FRANKLIN 
 
 514 West 113th Street 
 New York 25, N. Y. 
 
 First Published 
 
 Chicago 1909 
 
 PRINTED IN U.S.A.
 
 TABLE OF CONTENTS 
 
 PACE 
 
 PREFACE vii 
 
 CHAPTER 
 
 I. INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM ....... i 
 
 II. THE Civics OF OSSE 21 
 
 III. THE Civics OF OBRECHT 4 
 
 IV. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF .... 60 
 V. THE CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 107 
 
 VI. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 135 
 
 VII. THE CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 175 
 
 VIII. THE CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 185 
 
 DC. THE CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER ....:. 206 
 
 X. THE CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 222 
 
 XI. THE CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 232 
 
 XII. THE CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 267 
 
 XIII. THE CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 285 
 
 XIV. THE ARGUMENT OF JUSTI'S " STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 315 
 XV. JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 394 
 
 XVI. JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 43^ 
 
 XVII. JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES .... 459 
 XVIII. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS "INTRODUC- 
 TION" 48: 
 
 XIX. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS "POLICE Y" 505 
 XX. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS "HAND- 
 LUNG" 525 
 
 XXI. THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS "HAND- 
 LUNG UNO FINANZ' 542 
 
 XXII. SUMMARY 586 
 
 INDEX 597
 
 PREPACK 
 
 Like its predecessor in this series, Adam S;w//// and Modern 
 Sociology, the present book is a mere fragment. It deals with 
 a single factor of the social process in the German States. It 
 finds this factor already effective in 1555. It does not attempt 
 to trace each link in the chain of continuity from that date. 
 It reviews the most important seventeenth-century writers in 
 the line of sequence, but the emphasis of the book falls in the 
 eighteenth century. I have carefully excluded the problem of 
 relations between this literary factor and other social elements, 
 and I have purposely refrained from estimating its ratio of 
 importance among the formative forces of the period. Con- 
 clusions of that order must come from a larger synthesis, for 
 which the present study supplies merely a detail. 
 
 To justify my belief that the labor which this book cost 
 was well spent, it would be necessary to prove first, that Amer- 
 icans have much to gain from better understanding of the 
 Germans; and second, that just appreciation of the present 
 social system of the Germans is impossible for Americans unless 
 they are willing to trace it historically. These propositions 
 must be left, however, without the support of argument, merely 
 as the author's profession of faith. 
 
 To readers of English only, cameralism is virtually a lost 
 chapter in the history of the social sciences. Although every- 
 thing now belonging to German polity has a part of its heredity 
 in that type of social theory, not every reputable student of 
 the social sciences in America could correctly define the term, 
 and few could name more than one or two writers to whom 
 it is properly applied. 
 
 In a word, the cameralists were a series of German writers, 
 from the middle of the sixteenth to the end of the eighteenth 
 
 vii
 
 viil THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 century, who approached civic problems from a common view- 
 point, who proposed the same central question, and who devel- 
 oped a coherent civic theory, corresponding with the German 
 system of administration at the same time in course of evolution. 
 To the cameralists the central problem of science was the 
 problem of the state. To them the object of all social theory 
 was to show how the welfare of the state might be secured. 
 They saw in the welfare of the state the source of all other 
 welfare. Their key to the welfare of the state was revenue 
 to supply the needs of the state. Their whole social theory 
 radiated from the central task of furnishing the state with 
 ready means. 
 
 For reasons to be mentioned later, allusions to the cameral- 
 ists in English books, whether original or translated, are more 
 frequent among the economists than elsewhere. If, however, 
 we consult the two handbooks of the history of economic theory 
 in most frequent use by students in this country, we find that 
 they barely allude to cameralism, and their historical perspec- 
 tive would be clearer if they did not mention the subject at 
 all. In the second edition of Cossa, 1 Klock, Becher, Hornigk 
 (sic), and Schroder are disposed of in a paragraph of about 
 seventy words, and another paragraph two lines longer, in 
 the chapter on the physiocrats (!), mentions the "Chamber Sci- 
 ences," as represented by Justi and Sonnenfels only. The third 
 edition of the same book, or the volume which took the place 
 of a third edition, translated under the title An Introduction 
 to the Study of Political Economy, mentions the same three 
 Austrians, and adds a couple of lines on Seckendorff in the 
 section on "Industrial Freedom;" it mentions Gasser, Dithmar, 
 and Darjes in the section on "Professional Chairs, Newspapers, 
 and Academies;" it gives a paragraph each to Justi and Son- 
 
 1 Translated under the supervision of Jevons, with the title, Guide 
 to the Study of Political Economy; original first edition, 1876, second, 
 1878, translation, 1880.
 
 PREFACE ix 
 
 nenfels, in the section entitled "Bureaucratic and Professorial 
 Eclecticism;" and then, after a few statements thirty-four 
 pages later, about the "German Physiocrats," it for the first 
 time finds its bearings among German thinkers with Rau, who 
 began to write a generation after cameralism in the strict sense 
 had passed its prime. Ingram evidently abstracted from 
 Roscher, by some principle of selection which does not appear, 
 a dozen names of German "mercantilists" of the cameralistic 
 period. The summary way in which he disposes of them 
 shows that he had no first-hand knowledge of these writers, and 
 that he utterly misapprehended their place in the history of 
 German thought. If one were so fortunate as to learn the 
 names of the cameralists, and turned to Palgrave for more 
 information, little would be found beyond repetition of scraps 
 gathered from Roscher; and these so disconnected that 
 they would hardly pique curiosity to pry farther. All the 
 other English aids to knowledge of cameralism are so scattered 
 that an adequate introduction to the subject by means of them 
 would be out of the question. 
 
 During the last generation, American readers of German 
 appear to have relied, as a rule, for information about early 
 phases of German economic thought, chiefly upon two writers, 
 Kautz 1 and Roscher. 2 
 
 Of Kautz it is enough to say that he was of the rear guard 
 of the rhetoricians. His book is wonderfully plausible if not 
 lucid reading. Its early pages appear to express method < 
 logical conclusions which the maturest scholarship has not 
 superseded. Unfortunately, the author's own procedure, as 
 it appears in the body of the book, shows that for him these 
 
 1 Julius Kautz, Die geschichtliche Entwickelung der National- 
 Oekonomik und ihrer Literatur, Wien, 1860. 
 
 3 Wilhelm Roscher, Geschichte der National-Oekonomik in Deutsch- 
 land, Miinchen, 1874. In the following pages, if nothing appears to 
 the contrary, this work is referred to whenever the author's name is used.
 
 x THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 imposing propositions had merely the force of impotent general- 
 ities. His actual method is first, derivation, by some occult 
 means, of certain general principles under which to subsume 
 the economists of the period; then, second, use of the writers 
 of the period as so many illustrations of the principles. When 
 projected upon this vicious circle, the course of thought in 
 successive stages falls into alluring symmetry. A little inquiry 
 into the facts, however, shows that these pleasing constructions 
 are mainly fictitious. 
 
 For example, Kautz locates the second of his three great 
 divisions of economic ideas "between the end of the Middle 
 Ages and Adam Smith." This second period he interprets 
 as that of independent investigation, "in which the national- 
 economic ideas and principles were no longer mixed and com- 
 bined with the political, legal, and religious systems of theory, 
 but were presented as a totality of peculiar special cognitions." 1 
 The truth of this generalization depends upon the standard 
 used for measurement of relative bondage to conventionality 
 and independence of it. Compared with the age of the school- 
 men the period from Martin Luther to Adam Smith was of 
 course intellectually free. On the other hand, if contempo- 
 raries of Kautz had gone back to the economic and political 
 theorists of the intermediate period, with no preparation but 
 nineteenth-century ideas, they would have been amazed at 
 the degree in which social thinking of all sorts was paralyzed 
 by dogmatic prepossessions. Even if Kautz's generalization 
 had been qualified in a way to make it valid, use of it as a 
 premise from which to deduce interpretation of the economic 
 theories of the period was like finding a sufficient explanation 
 of the course of American experience since 1776 in terms of 
 the mere negative condition of independence from England. 
 Anyone who can have patience with discursive essays upon 
 long-distance impressions of the development of economic 
 
 * Loc. cit., p. 25.
 
 PREPACK XI 
 
 theory would find Kautz impressive. As a guide to critical 
 study of the actual process he is impossible. 
 
 Whatever our estimate, on the other hand, of the "histori- 
 cal school," and of Roscher's contributions to economic theory, 
 there can be no doubt about the value of his services to economic 
 history. The volume cited above, on the history of economic 
 theory in Germany, has served as an almost unchallenged 
 authority on the subject for a generation. Those who have 
 had most occasion to work in the field which this book surveys 
 will be most sincere in their gratitude to the author. The 
 present volume could surely not have been written if Roscher 
 had not blazed the way. 
 
 Nevertheless, the farther I went in the studies which this 
 book reports, the more my wonder grew that German scholar- 
 ship had not yet produced a work which would be as evident 
 an advance upon Roscher as he was upon Kautz. For obvious 
 reasons such a book must be written in Germany. At the 
 same time, comparison of the perspective of foreign scholars 
 may be worth something as an aid in establishing the viewpoint 
 from which the evolution of German social theories should be 
 reconsidered. 
 
 It is approximately true that knowledge of the cameralists 
 as a group has remained as it was left by Roscher. The most 
 general thesis of the present work is that the cameralists have 
 not yet come to their own in the assignment of historical values. 
 In other words, while acknowledging my debt to Roscher, I 
 find it necessary to impeach his authority. 
 
 In the first place, Roscher was essentially a collector, not an 
 interpreter. Yet, although his chief merit was as an assembler 
 of details, I have still been surprised at the number of times 
 in which I have found him apparently in error about matters 
 of fact. It was not my affair to find out whether these slips 
 were more his fault or his misfortune. At his time the evi- 
 dence which would have corrected the errors of detail may
 
 xii THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 not have l>een accessil>le. At all events, the writers in Die 
 allgemeine deutsche Biographic almost invariably justify more 
 or less important modifications in Roscher's accounts of the 
 individual careers of the cameralists. My own study of these 
 writers has t>een confined to their books. For such biographical 
 introduction as was necessary I have relied throughout, unless 
 exception is noted, upon the work just named, whenever it 
 differed from Rose her. 
 
 But the chief issue with Roscher is much more radical. 
 For a generation the world's interpretation of the cameralists 
 has virtually been stereotyped in the form which he cast. The 
 more sj>ecific thesis of the present work is that his version of 
 the cameralists utterly misses their real meaning. It is a blur 
 produced by a combination of methodological fallacy and 
 historical nearsightedness. German scholars alone are within 
 reach of the means fully to reconstruct the history if the thesis 
 is sustained. I hope I am right, however, that the very dis- 
 tance from the bulk of the sources, which compels attention 
 to the main movement of thought, confers a distinct advantage 
 in making out the larger meanings of the body of literature in 
 question. 
 
 In order to justify this challenge of venerable tradition, 
 account must be taken of the immc-f liate antecedents of Roscher's 
 b(X)k. In 1858 Leopold Ranke submitted to the Bavarian 
 Royal Academy of Sciences a plan for a series of twenty-four 
 volumes on the history of the sciences in Germany. The sub- 
 jects of those volumes in the series which are most intimately 
 related to the present issue are: (i) Gesrhichte; (2) Kriegs- 
 ivisaensrhaft; (3) Jurisprudenz; (4) Allgemeincs Staatsredit 
 und I'olitik; (5) Nationalokonomie und kanieralistisrhe I-tit her; 
 (()) /^andunrthsrha/tslehre. For the convenience of the writers 
 available, and for facility of popular exposition, these subdivi- 
 sions were doubtless more suitable than any others that might 
 have been proposed. As a programme for critical resean h.
 
 PREFACE xin 
 
 however, the standards of today being the criterion, that divi- 
 sion of labor surrendered the work in advance to preconception 
 and misconstruction. A precisely analogous fallacy would 
 be involved in a scheme today to parcel out among different 
 scholars, in accordance with present national boundaries, an 
 analysis of the political conditions of Europe at the time of 
 Charlemagne. The political map of Europe in the ninth 
 century was not as it is today, and analysis based on the con- 
 trary assumption would deserve rejection without a hearing. 
 But the inchoate social sciences, from the middle of the sixteenth 
 century to the end of the eighteenth, were no more homogeneous 
 and coterminous with scientific categories at the middle of the 
 nineteenth century than national frontiers of the ninth century 
 retain their places in the twentieth. In other words, the 
 Bavarian Academy did not undertake to find the centers in 
 the past from which the evolution of the social sciences could 
 be traced step by step and process by process. On the con- 
 trary, it sponsored a plan which called for a conventionalizing 
 of previous centuries in terms of nineteenth-century classifica- 
 tion. This scheme ruthlessly inverted the rule which had 
 been the first great historiographical commandment with 
 promise since Savigny and Niebuhr. 
 
 The result was a conspicuous vindication of the violated 
 principle. The sort of analysis which the present volume 
 reports very early unearths the fact that the conventional divi- 
 sion of labor in the series threw the data out of their relations 
 and retarded discovery of their meaning. In particular it 
 assigned the cameralists to Roscher, 1 while it estopped analysis 
 of them at their proper center within the scope of Bluntschli. * 
 Using the terms in the sense in which they are understood in 
 the United States today, the cameralists were not primarily 
 economists. They were primarily political scientists. This 
 
 1 Under title (5) above. 
 
 Title (4) above.
 
 xiv THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 single perception demonstrates the unreliability of both Roscher 
 and Bluntschli upon the cardinal question of the meaning of 
 the cameralists for the evolution of the sciences in Germany. 
 The first critical question to be answered in an interpretation 
 of the cameralists is: What "was their specific purpose, the 
 center from which they proceeded, the interest which gave the 
 respective ratings to all their other interests ? Rarely is this 
 question answered as promptly and as decisively as in the case 
 of the cameralists. The answer exhibits in cameralism the 
 germination, not of an academic abstraction, but of a whole 
 civic polity. 
 
 Turning to the defect of historical nearsightedness, a typical 
 symptom may be taken from Bluntschli. 1 He says: 
 
 The Germans applied their attention tardily to general civic 
 science (Staatswissenschajt}. In the sixteenth century Italians and 
 Frenchmen, in the seventeenth Dutchmen and Englishmen, and 
 in the eighteenth Englishmen and Frenchmen were far in advance. 
 Only by degrees did the Germans overtake these leaders, and pres- 
 ently it was their fortune, through diligence and thoroughness of 
 investigation, through moral earnestness of endeavor, and through 
 the loftiness of their standpoint and the energy of their thinking, to 
 equal the foremost and to win general recognition. 
 
 In a certain sense the first two of these propositions are as 
 true as the last. At the same time, this conventional judgment 
 is in large part a mere survival of that obsession which filled 
 Germany, and to a certain extent the rest of Europe, during 
 the eighteenth century, with awe and fear of everything political 
 made in France. In effect Bluntschli follows Weitzel 3 in can- 
 celing the cameralists from the account, while he discusses 
 other Germans of much less real importance for civic science. 
 Von Mohl had meanwhile written, 3 and had really given the 
 
 ' Loc. cil., p. xiv. 
 
 3 Geschichte der Slaalrajissenschajt, 2 vols., 1832-33. 
 
 J Geschichte und Literatur der Staatswisscnschajten, 3 vols., 1855-58.
 
 PREFACE xv 
 
 cameralists more credit than Bluntschli allows, though he docs 
 not in principle vary from tradition. It is not necessary, if 
 it were possible, to cloud the title of other countries to respect 
 for their achievements in the political sciences. My conten- 
 tion is that the Germans were not as sterile in this field as it 
 has been their own fashion to suppose. In fact there was no 
 more virile political thinking in Europe in the seventeenth 
 and eighteenth centuries than that of the German cameralists. 
 I do not say that it was as profound, as abstract, as highly 
 generalized, as political works of the first rank produced by 
 other nations. It was suited to the occasions which set its 
 task. It was constructive. It was effective. As in the case 
 of all theory, in comparison with its practical counterpart, it 
 is impossible to demonstrate how much the cameralism of the 
 books was cause and how much effect of the cameralism of 
 the bureaus. I do not raise that question. The same dilemma 
 is at least as pertinent to Grotius or Locke or Montesquieu 
 as to the cameralists; and on the ground of probable influence 
 upon affairs the case of the latter does not on the whole suffer 
 by comparison with any political theorists whatsoever. More- 
 over, the plea that neither the letter nor the spirit of these 
 technologies in any great degree molded the actual political 
 practices of the time would, by parity of reasoning, exclude 
 every great human document from rank among the formative 
 forces of the period that produced it. This arbitrary measure 
 of meaning factors in history would leave among admitted 
 social forces not a single standardizing formutaTion -of human 
 conduct, from the New Testament to Magna Charta and the 
 last three amendments to the American Constitution. 
 
 At all events the cameralists of the books did their share 
 toward systematizing the polity which was most intensively 
 developed by the Germans. Their works contain in embryo 
 everything which has made the German system today the most 
 effective economizer of national energy in the world. If a
 
 XVI THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tree should be known by its fruits, scholars in general, and 
 the Germans in particular, have grossly blundered in slighting 
 the sturdy stock from which the mighty growth of German 
 civic theory and practice has developed. 
 
 There is a contrast between Roscher's method of approach- 
 ing the material and my own in another respect. Rose her 
 attempts in general to exhibit the cameralists in national groups, 
 in connection with the administrative policies of their respective 
 princes. That he is unable strictly to carry out this plan is 
 evident from the titles of his chapters, from the twelfth to the 
 twentieth inclusive, viz.: "The Dutch School and the Mercan- 
 tile System;" "The Conservative National Economics of the 
 Middle of the Seventeenth Century;" "The National Econom- 
 ics of the Last Great German Polyhistorian;" "The Austrian 
 National Economics under Leopold I;" "The Prussian 
 National Economics under the Great Elector;" "Leibniz 
 and the Beginnings of the Halle School;" "The National 
 Economics of Friedrich Wilhelm I;" "The National Econom- 
 ics of Frederick the Great;" "The Older Eclectics of the 
 Eighteenth Century." 
 
 My plan, on the contrary, ignored the merely national 
 relations of the respective authors, and treated them as nearly 
 as possible chronologically, and as phenomena of a coherent 
 tendency of thought. It can hardly be claimed that the last 
 word has been said by or for either of these methods. I would 
 simply point out that each has its advantages, and that the 
 employment of both, at their highest efficiency, and in co-opera- 
 tion with each other, will doubtless be involved in the pro- 
 gramme of future historians of this period. 
 
 There is nowhere between the lines of this book a wish 
 to glorify German bureaucracy at the expense of American 
 republicanism. The advantage to Americans of understand- 
 ing German institutions will not come from adopting or even 
 imitating them, but from adapting whatever may be learned
 
 PREFACE xvn 
 
 from their workings to the improvement of our own institutions. 
 The aim of this book is accordingly to find a point of departure 
 for interpretation of German social theories and practices 
 through their own process of evolution. The Hegelians would 
 say it is a typical manifestation of the nature of things that the 
 German and American polities should lend to complete each 
 other. The one starts with the assumption of the state as t he- 
 social unit. The other starts with the assumption of the indi- 
 vidual as the social unit. Experience has shown that neither 
 assumption is the whole truth, that each assumption is part 
 of the truth, and that the social problem rests hard upon the 
 need of a reconstruction which shall organize these two phases 
 of the truth into a convincing basis for present social action. 
 I venture again to express my belief that a service may be ren- 
 dered to the American side of this assimilation by promoting 
 acquaintance with the spirit of German polity. Taking it 
 for granted that the best way to understand the German type 
 of society and of social theory is through their evolution, I 
 have undertaken to show that the trunk line of this evolution 
 from the Reformation to the French Revolution is marked 
 by the cameralists. 
 
 This book is not a contribution to the social sciences in 
 the sense, that it draws upon previously unknown sources. 
 The cameralists have been catalogued over and over again. 1 
 Additional sources will doubtless be assembled when German 
 scholars interest themselves in recovering this portion of their 
 history. My effort has been rather to determine a new stand- 
 point for explaining the sources. Nor is an attempt to put 
 the cameralists in their proper historical perspective new in 
 itself. Not to speak of interpretations attempted while the 
 
 1 Exhaustive study of the literature of cameralism should take, as 
 its base of operations, Baumstark, Cameralistische Encyklopddie, 1835. 
 The state of tradition about the meaning of the cameralists is ocular 
 proof, however, that it is a far cry from bibliography to interpretation.
 
 xvni THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 cameralistic series in the strict sense was still incomplete, we 
 may date the beginnings of historical treatment of cameralism 
 from Rossig. 1 Almost without exception these reviews of 
 cameralism have been so indiscriminate that the meaning of 
 the movement has been obscured, if not positively misrepre- 
 sented. Thus, to take the most important instance, Roscher, 
 in consequence of begging the methodological question at the 
 outset, makes a hodgepodge of identities by jumbling together 
 survivals of mediaeval legalism like Besold, political scientists 
 of the obsolescent not the evolving type like Bornitz, political 
 philosophers of massive mold like Pufendorf, historical phi- 
 losophers like Moser, metaphysical philosophers like Leibniz, 
 Wolff, and Kant, and incidentally the cameralists. Not by 
 a valid process of analysis, but by sheer force, Roscher reduces 
 these unlike quantities to the common denominator "econo- 
 mist." In the same way, and perhaps even more fallaciously, 
 Bluntschli had joined together heterogeneous elements as a 
 continuous series in political science. I do not deny that every 
 type of theory reacts upon every other type; but it is juvenile 
 to assume that in any age the influence of a metaphysician and 
 of a historian, for example, upon each other's peculiar type of 
 thinking, is as direct and intense as that of two metaphysicians 
 or two historians. Sometimes such cross-fertilization is more 
 fruitful than in-and-in breeding. Again it is not. Neither is 
 it to be assumed in a given case without proof. Nor can it be 
 taken for granted that propositions occurring casually in one 
 theory, but belonging primarily to another, may be carried 
 over at face value into the theory to which they secondarily 
 belong. For instance, a theologian might cull from every 
 economic author of the last fifty years passages which carry 
 some sort of theological implications. Those implications 
 might or might not have been apparent to the authors them- 
 
 1 Versuch eincr Ceschichte der Oekonomie und Cameralwissenschajt, 
 2 vols., 1781.
 
 PRKFACK xix 
 
 selves and intended by them. In any event it would be absurd 
 to make a history of theology for the last fifty years by patching 
 together such passages with others which were immediately 
 theological in their premises and purpose. Before a truthful 
 expression of one type of theory can be made in terms of another 
 the mental latitude and longitude of each group of theorists, 
 and even of each individual theorist, must be accurately deter- 
 mined, and corrections must be made accordingly in the pre- 
 sumptive force of their formulas. Neither Bluntschli nor 
 Roscher properly recognized this principle. It is a marvel 
 therefore that German scholarship has permitted the books of 
 these authors so long to hold their place as standard accounts 
 of the process of evolution in the German social sciences. The 
 following pages are devoted to determining the group equation 
 of the cameralists only. 
 
 Meanwhile the little book of Marchet 1 deserves much more 
 attention than it seems to have received, either in Europe or 
 in this country. Indeed, I could not have expressed myself 
 as above about the persistent authority of Roscher if I could 
 trace in recent German literature any considerable tendency 
 to countenance Marchet's secession. The chief reason for 
 the neglect will doubtless be found in the tacit assumption that, 
 since Bluntschli and Roscher, German social theory previous 
 to the nineteenth century is to be considered as a closed incident. 
 I must acknowledge that Marchet has very largely anticipated 
 my conclusions, particularly upon the fabulous character of 
 tradition with respect to German mercantilism as a theory, 
 and as to the doctrine of population. Any competent scholar 
 was bound to reach similar results if he analyzed the sources 
 instead of repeating hearsay. 
 
 1 Studien fiber die Entwickelung der V erwaltungslehre in Deulschland 
 von der tweiten Hdlfte des IJ. bis zum Ende des 18. Jahrhundcrls. Von 
 Dr. Gustav Marchet, o. 6. Professor an der k.-k. Hochschule fiir Boden- 
 cultur in Wien. Miinchen, 1885 (pp. viii 4-437).
 
 XX THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Until I had reached my own conclusions from examination 
 of the original writers, I deliberately ignored the commentators 
 as far as possible. Marchet was accordingly merely a name 
 to me until I had completed my manuscript. This was for- 
 tunate, because if I had been familiar with his work I could not 
 have been sure of the independence of my own judgment. Tn 
 matters of detail Marchet notes particulars which I had omitted, 
 others which I had not discovered, about Seckendorff, Becher, 
 Hornick, Schroder, and Justi. His estimate of Hornick is 
 especially notable, as he had the advantage of access to his 
 book and other evidence which I could not obtain. On the 
 other hand, comparison of my own method, and its resulting 
 interpretation, with Marchet's tends to confirm my belief that 
 I am on the right track. In the first place, the extent to which 
 Marchet relies on the generalization eudaemonism to explain 
 the political philosophy of the time too closely resembles the 
 method of Kautz. In the second place, Marchet is not suffi- 
 ciently free from the prime fallacy of Roscher. He does not 
 perceive that he has to deal with several distinct types of theo- 
 rists. These must be analyzed in turn, with reference to their 
 respective centers of attention, before a valid synthesis of their 
 unlike doctrines is possible. That is, the same sort of analysis 
 to which this volume subjects the cameralists must be performed 
 upon several distinct groups of thinkers, e. g., the general phi- 
 losophers, the political philosophers, the moral philosophers, 
 etc. Since this particular analysis has not been applied rigor- 
 ously by Marchet to the cameralists as such, or to either of 
 the other groups included in his survey, his book, with all its 
 merits, leaves these theorists still not properly differentiated, 
 and not interpreted strictly by the functional meaning of each, 
 in the whole process of developing a system of social doctrines. 
 
 Schmoller has rescued the method of Roscher from futility 
 by projecting the large survey within which all details of civic 
 development, particularly in (icrmany, must be located. In
 
 PREFACE xxi 
 
 his more intensive historical work Schmoller has dealt imme- 
 diately with industrial and administrative development more 
 than with the growth of theories. Analysis of the cameralists 
 therefore explains one of the systems of communication, so 
 to speak, that penetrated the territory in which Schmoller's 
 primacy among explorers is secure. His monograph, Mer- 
 cantilism, is the best introduction that can be recommended 
 for the present volume. The relation of his more extended 
 and technical treatment of the subject to the present study is 
 indicated in the first chapter of this book. 
 
 In the following pages I have tried to present a digest of 
 everything in the writings of the leading cameralists which is 
 necessary to an impartial conclusion about their meaning for 
 the German social sciences. Accordingly I offer in this volume 
 a source book containing the most pertinent evidence about the 
 real significance of the cameralists. These sources put each 
 reader in possession of the means of testing my conclusions, and 
 of estimating the cameralists for himself. The only precon- 
 ception which I carried to the study of these theorists was the 
 historical commonplace that they must be allowed to speak 
 for themselves, and from their own standpoint, whatever that 
 migjit prove to be. This commonplace has had at best fitful 
 respect among social theorists or historians of social theory. 
 
 My chief interest in the cameralists is least of all antiquarian. 
 I want to know what can be learned from them that is of per- 
 manent use for sociological methodology. My suspicions were 
 early aroused that the fate which had befallen them would 
 turn out to enforce certain primary methodological laws in 
 application to the social sciences; and first of all the law that 
 every historical actor must be judged primarily with reference 
 to his immediate purposes, not as though his purposes were 
 those of the moment at which the judgment was passed. I 
 suspected that some of the non sequiturs \\ liich are epidemic 
 in the social sciences would be found undisguised in a com-
 
 xxii THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 parison of the cameralists as they really were with the tradition 
 of them in the histories. It seemed to me that, if this turned 
 out to be the case, exposure of the bad logic, in an example so 
 far in the past that it enlists no partisan prejudice, would do 
 more to promote valid reasoning upon current questions in 
 the social sciences than possible direct refutations of contem- 
 porary argument. I therefore undertook a laborious historical 
 search, not chiefly from historical interest, but for specifically 
 methodological purposes. If historical valuations of the 
 cameralists had mistreated them, I wanted to ferret out the 
 precise flaw in the process, as a concrete warning against paral- 
 lel miscarriages of judgment at present. 
 
 All that I knew about the cameralists, when I began this 
 study, I had learned from Roscher. On the general grounds 
 indicated above, I decided that if Roscher's composite picture 
 of so many different types did justice to each, and to the syn- 
 thesis of them, it would be an amazing coincidence; and I 
 determined to find out for myself whether such a phenomenon 
 had occurred. I first studied Justi, and at once made out 
 indications which had not appeared in Roscher's report. It was 
 evident moreover that there were more intimate relations than 
 a mere chronological before-and-after between Justi and other 
 writers. Following this clue, I abstracted from Roscher's 
 heterogeneous collection of men who had more or less directly 
 affected economic ideas a group with like marks of species. 
 German civic theory in general so evidently proceeds from or 
 at least through this type of thinkers that the finding marks 
 forthwith furnish the fixed points from which to interpret 
 the whole evolution of German social science. Whether the 
 record proves to contain exhibits of methodological principles, 
 either in the breach or in the observance, is discussed in the 
 concluding chapter. 
 
 I have intentionally disobeyed the rules of good writing 
 by retaining in the text many German words, instead of trying
 
 PREFACE xxin 
 
 to propose English equivalents. This was for two chief rea- 
 sons: first, that translation unavoidably interprets, and in 
 the present connection it almost certainly interprets anachro- 
 nistically. Any terms by which we might translate leading 
 concepts of the cameralists, unless they might be careful cir- 
 cumlocutions, would impute to them shades of meaning which 
 would really be ours, not theirs. In another class of cases I 
 have gone still farther in retaining German terms or even con- 
 siderable quotations, when I judged that the matter in hand 
 would have value only for readers somewhat familiar with 
 German. This was both for the sake of precision and to retain 
 local color. 
 
 With the same purpose in view I have deliberately chosen 
 awkward renderings of many German expressions. By so 
 doing I have most accurately indicated the ideas of the various 
 authors. In many ways their thought was not as our thought, 
 and it is a falsification of history to make them speak as men 
 would now. American conceptions of the growth and mean- 
 ing of German social theory have been confused by neglect 
 of translators to count with this elemental fact. This has 
 been amply emphasized in the body of the book, but I add a 
 typical instance from a different source. , While writing this 
 preface I had occasion, in another connection, to consult the 
 English version of Heeren's Geschichte des europiiischen Staa- 
 tensy stems* Of European states from the beginning of the 
 sixteenth century, Heeren is made to say: 
 
 At first, therefore, the royal authority in these kingdoms was 
 everywhere much limited. Without the aid of the nobility no 
 important war could be carried on; without the consent of the 
 cities no taxes could be levied. Without standing armies (a small 
 
 1 Originally published 1808-9. I re ^ er to ^ e ^h edition (1830), 
 Vol. IX of the Historische Werke, p. 16. The English translation appeared 
 in 1864 under the title, A Manual of the History oj the Political System 
 oj Europe and Its Colonies. The passage is on p. 1 1.
 
 xxiv THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 beginning excepted), without political economy 1 (for no art was 
 known but that of getting money), there existed, in reality, at this 
 time no power, in the present acceptation of the word. 
 
 In the first place, Heeren's own proposition about Staat.s- 
 U'irthschaft was a generality which would not bear rigorous 
 criticism. In the second place, whether the author had a 
 correct idea in mind or not, the term Staatswirthschaft itself 
 has to be credited with a different content for every period of 
 which it is positively or negatively predicated. It did not even 
 have the identical connotations when Heeren's last edition was 
 published which it had carried when the book first appeared; 
 and never and nowhere had it meant precisely what writers 
 or readers in England in 1864 understood by the phrase "polit- 
 ical economy." Still further, as the following clause stands 
 in the quotation it furnishes a second illustration of the need of 
 paraphrase fairly to represent the original. The author's 
 real meaning would be conveyed by the substitute: "the 
 financial administration of states did not go beyond pro- 
 grammes for raising revenues." Standing by themselves, 
 these particular instances are not of firstrate importance. They 
 are merely samples of thousands scattered through English 
 literature of the social sciences. The aggregate effect of unhis- 
 torical renderings of German terms, added to the unsatisfac- 
 tory condition of the German tradition itself, is a state of regret- 
 table misinformation among English readers about the actual 
 course of development in German social theory and practice. 
 I have tried, therefore, to report the cameralists in language 
 that reflects the partial analysis actually in their minds, and 
 which does not represent them as using nineteenth- and twen- 
 tieth-century concepts of Germans, still less of Englishmen 
 or Americans. 
 
 1 The italics are mine, and the author's word is Staatswirlhschajt. 
 The next clause in parenthesis reads: man kannte nur die Kunst, Geld 
 au/iubringen
 
 PREFACE xxv 
 
 It has been my intention also to retain all archaisms and 
 other peculiarities, even to obvious typographical errors, in 
 quotations, titles, etc., in order to represent the exact state of 
 the texts used. My notes, however, were reorganized several 
 times, and were recopied by several hands. Moreover, space 
 limits compelled me to omit an appendix which would have 
 occupied 150 pages. It was to contain the tables of contents 
 of the principal books cited, and other illustrative material. 
 The retrenchment compelled frequent alterations in the body of 
 the book. At the time of revising the proof most of the volumes 
 used had necessarily been returned to libraries in this country 
 and Germany. I have not been unmindful of the duty of 
 verification, but it was thus not strictly within my power. I 
 fear therefore that, although I have fortified myself as well as 
 circumstances would permit against material errors, in matters 
 of form the citations contain inaccuracies which might have 
 been removed if the sources had been longer at my disposal. 
 The capitalization, spelling, punctuation, etc., must accordingly 
 be taken as illustrating rather than precisely transcribing the 
 passages cited. 
 
 My most grateful thanks are due to the Konigliche Biblio- 
 thek at Berlin for the loan of a large number of the cameralistic 
 works without which this book could not have been written. 
 My obligations are equally real for similar assistance from the 
 libraries of Harvard, Columbia, and Cornell and for important 
 information from the British Museum. 
 
 ALBION W. SMALL 
 
 January i, 1909
 
 CHAPTER I 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 
 
 Every theory, system, science is in some way a reflection 
 of the prevailing purposes of the time in which it developed. 
 
 No hypothesis about the precise nature of the cause and 
 effect concerned is concealed in this commonplace. We need 
 not raise that question. Enough that in some way or other, 
 which it is not necessary to discuss at this point, our philosophies 
 echo the dominant purposes of the time that produced them. 
 
 If we attempt to detach a system of thought from the whole 
 scheme of activities impelled by the prevailing systems of pur- 
 poses, and if we try to set forth the meaning of that thought as 
 though it had no connection with those purposes, the result is 
 inevitable misinterpretation. 
 
 The same effect follows unintentional not less than delib- 
 erate separation of a body of thought, in which we are especially 
 interested, from the surrounding circumstances of its develop- 
 ment. It is like abstracting a plant from the soil and atmos- 
 phere which are the media of its existence, and then expecting 
 it both to grow and to reveal the abstract process <f its previous 
 growth. 
 
 Speaking particularly of the social sciences, their crudeness 
 at present is in part the result of arbitrary dismemberment of 
 the process of which science is an interpretation, and consequent 
 substitution of fictitious processes, more or less remote from one 
 another and meaningless for one another. We have then, 
 so far as we depend upon these sciences for knowledge, a col- 
 lection of ghosts stalking abroad in defiance of all known laws, 
 and apparently tending less and less to explain reality. 
 
 A single instance in \\hich this has occurred on a rather 
 large scale furnishes the primary motive of this book We are
 
 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to deal with cameralists and cameralism. A history of neither 
 is to be attempted. At most this book may be called a brief 
 of the argument which a history would have to complete if it 
 were to satisfy sociologists. 
 
 An authentic interpretation of cameralism necessarily 
 gives the most prominent place, in the center of the picture, 
 to Justi. In order however rightly to estimate Justi, the work 
 of other cameralists before and after his time must be analyzed 
 and compared with his system. For the purposes of this survey 
 then we shall regard cameralism as beginning with Seckendorff, 1 
 and ending with Sonnenfels. 2 A history of cameralism would 
 have to begin more than a century before these pioneers. It 
 would trace beginnings earlier than the time of Elector August 
 of Saxony (1553-86) and Landgrave Philipp of Hesse (1518- 
 67). It would follow changes of form, content, relations, and 
 name, and it would be obliged to show, finally, that present 
 differences between German and English institutions must 
 be stated partially in terms of the persistence in the one case 
 of a cameralistic tradition which was never naturalized in the 
 other. 
 
 Lexis, in Conrad's Handivorterbuch, under the title " Kame- 
 ralwissenschaft," states that the emperor Maximilian I estab- 
 lished several Reichskammer, e.g., the Kammergericht, 1495, 
 and that in the course of the sixteenth century the type of admin- 
 istration began to be developed in the chief states of the Empire. 
 If we refer to this infancy of the system and of its technology, 
 we are obliged to set our boundaries back so as to include among 
 the writers Melchior von Osse, whose Testament was written 
 in 1555, and Georg Obrecht, whose Funf unterschiedliche 
 .Secreta Politica appeared in Strassburg in 161 7. These authors 
 will presently be discussed at some length. 
 
 Readers who use English only know cameralism chiefly 
 
 1 'I eutscke Fiirslenslaat, 1655. 
 
 3 Urundsdtie der Poiicey, Handlung und Finant, 1765.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 3 
 
 through the historians of economics. The interpretation of 
 cameralism in English tradition arbitrarily wrests the thing 
 and its science from the setting in which it is intelligible. Exag- 
 gerating almost to paradox, we may say that cameralism was 
 not a theory and practice of economics but of politics. Came- 
 ralism was a technique and a theory of administering a peculiar 
 type of state in a society constructed out of peculiar types of pur- 
 poses. To be sure, economic conditions and purposes formed 
 their share of the circumstances to which cameralism was an 
 adaptation. The argument which will follow is not an attempt 
 to turn the flank of the economic interpretation of history. No 
 issue is raised with those who insist that the ultimate elements 
 of all factors of social situations are economic. Be that as it 
 may, the actors in a given social situation think of the elements 
 with which they are dealing as different in kind, and they 
 construct their systems of theory and practice accordingly. 
 Cameralism raised, directly and deliberately, no fundamental 
 questions of pure economics. It was primarily a theory and a 
 technique of government. Solution of proble'ms of the nature 
 and laws of wealth is logically antecedent to governmental 
 institutions, to be sure, but until the last quarter of the eight- 
 eenth century the principle had been generally ignored. 
 Governmental theory dealt with economic problems of course. 
 Instead of formulating these separately as economic problems, 
 however, it recognized no economic problems of the degree of 
 generality familiar since Adam Smith's time. It dealt with 
 economic relations as merely incidental to the application of 
 governmental principles, and the latter, as proclaimed at the 
 time, were in many respects narrowly provincial. 
 
 The situation which actually existed in Germany in the 
 seventeenth and eighteenth centuries was a resultant of pur- 
 poses which were conditioned first by these chief objective 
 factors, viz., the soil and climate of the country; the state of 
 the arts required for using natural resources; the domestic
 
 4 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 industrial structure, and the foreign trade relations; the eccle- 
 siastical organization; the Holy Roman Empire ; the character 
 of the states within the Empire, and outside of it in Europe 
 including nearer Asia; the prizes for national competition in 
 the wealth of the Americas, the Levant, and the remote East; 
 and the personal equation of the citizens. Then, second, 
 there were firstrate subjective factors, which may be scheduled 
 as the contemporary science, the theology or philosophy, the 
 legal tradition both from Roman and Teuton sources, the 
 political philosophy, and the rule-of-thumb conclusions which 
 passed as wisdom in the conduct of life, from individual habit 
 to the policies of states. 
 
 In this situation, as a matter of fact, the idea of the state 
 and of government dominated all the other factors. So far 
 as interests of the state could be distinguished, they settled the 
 relative importance of everything else. The purposes of the 
 state were paramount. The cameralists were servants of the 
 state. Cameralism was the system elaborated by the chief 
 agents of the rulers, partly as mere classification of practices 
 which rulers had already adopted; partly as ways and means 
 of accomplishing more of the purposes which the state proposed. 
 
 But in order properly to prepare for intelligent interpreta- 
 tion of cameralism still simpler elements of the situation must 
 be called to mind. 
 
 In the first place, we must remember that the German ter- 
 ritorial sovereignties in the period of the Reformation were 
 essentially more like a typical Virginia plantation, in the most 
 flourishing days of the Old Dominion, than like any political 
 unit with which modern Americans are familiar. Even if the 
 prince controlled territories which it would not be extravagant 
 to describe as big farms, it was long before the operations of 
 management were transformed from the primitive type of the 
 big landed estate to a definitive civic structure. The adminis- 
 tration of German states developed by a process which it does
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 5 
 
 not fall within the scope of this book to trace, from the status 
 in which the consort of the prince presided in person over the 
 revenues of the principality, almost as directly as the New 
 England farmer's wife managed her dairy. The advisers and 
 chief functionaries, who gradually acquired the meaning which 
 we find them possessing in the cameralistic period, were ge- 
 netically differentiations of this proprietary relation and policy. 
 The lord of the estate was to their minds, whatever their par- 
 ticular philosophy, a fixed term in the equation of life. They 
 were powerless to think of a social order as rational which did 
 not revolve about him as a regulator. 
 
 The great majority of the people in the German states, 
 the peasants and artisans particularly, were regarded by the 
 wisest men of the time as incapable of successful initiative. 
 As an estimate of actual conditions the judgment was undoubt- 
 edly correct. The people were accordingly held to be dedicated 
 by dispensation of Providence and the laws of nature to the 
 condition of wardship, and to be fit for action only under 
 authority. The fallacy of this generalization need not concern 
 us. It is a historical fact and force. The ruler and his gov- 
 ernment were quite consistently seen in the most plausible light 
 when they were contemplated as fulfilling the duties of guardian- 
 ship over these industrially and politically incompetent masses. 
 Under the circumstances paternalism was not an arrest of 
 development; still less in principle an abuse of power. 
 Whether in operation or in theory, it was the ideal expression 
 of the situation. 
 
 Again, from the beginning, the German states were involved 
 in a struggle for existence. With the kind of necessity here 
 concerned we have now nothing to do, beyond recognizing 
 it as a factor taken for granted by the statesmen of the period. 
 In fact the most importunate problem for every German state 
 was, in its own calculation, that of self-maintenance, and 
 especially by control of an adequate military force.
 
 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The cameralists of the books, as distinguished from the 
 cameralists of the bureaus, although the former class was 
 usually recruited from the latter, were the men who worked 
 out for publication, and especially for pedagogical purposes, 
 the system of procedure in accordance with which German 
 governments were supposed to perform their tasks. As a 
 rule these men were employed in administrative positions of 
 some sort, and spoke to a certain extent from experience. They 
 were not mere academic theorists. We may characterize these 
 cameralists of the books as the group of writers distinguished 
 from tlteir contemporaries and from earlier and later theorists 
 by constructing a "science" or group of "sciences" around the 
 central consideration of the fiscal needs of the prince. We might 
 coin the name "fiscalists" and it would be more appropriate 
 to their actual character than either of the terms by which 
 they have been known. Under the circumstances to which 
 we have referred, the most constant and pressing need of the 
 ruler was ready money. The men who elaborated the theory 
 of government for these German states had virtually to 
 answer this question: What programme must a wise govern- 
 ment adopt, in order first and foremost to be adequately supplied 
 with ready money, and thus able to discharge the duties of the 
 state in their various orders of importance ? The most typical 
 of these men expressed this paramount consideration very 
 positively and frankly. One of the reasons why later cameral- 
 ists used superficially different formulations of the same essen- 
 tial regime, was that the fiscal systems had become relatively 
 fixed, and could be taken for granted. The less convention- 
 alized portions of the system, and especially the idealized 
 versions of its aims, could then come in fpr a larger share of 
 attention ; and there was more room for speculative excursions 
 into the wider political philosophy or the deeper metaphysics 
 by which later writers hoped to buttress the system. 
 
 In the rough, the chronic condition of the European nations
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 7 
 
 during the cameralistic period was war, and the primary task 
 of governments, especially in Germany, was creation of readi- 
 ness for war. The fiscal policy which was the rule in Europe 
 during the period is known as the mercantile system. 1 This 
 policy, as a cardinal political fact, is a datum presupposed 
 by the present study. As Schmoller says (p. 57) : 
 
 If we pause for a while to consider this foreign and external 
 policy of the European states of the seventeenth and eighteenth 
 centuries which it has hitherto been the custom to regard as the 
 essential feature of the mercantile system it is not, of course, our 
 purpose to describe the details of its several forms. The general 
 features of its regulation are well enough known. Difficulties were 
 put in the way of the importation of manufactured goods; and their 
 production and exportation were favored by the prohibition of the 
 export of raw materials, by bounties on export, and by commercial 
 treaties. Encouragement was given to domestic shipping, to the 
 fisheries, and to the coasting trade by restricting or forbidding foreign 
 competition. Commerce with the colonies, and the supplying of 
 them with European wares, was reserved for the mother country. 
 The importation of colonial produce had to take place directly from 
 the colony itself, and not by way of other European ports; and 
 everywhere an attempt was made to establish direct trading relations 
 by great privileged trading companies, and by state aid in manifold 
 
 ways The general features are known; the details have 
 
 even yet not been subjected to due scientific investigation. Our 
 only purpose here is to grasp the fundamental ideas of the system; 
 which, naturalfy, found varying expressions, here in high duties, 
 there in low, here in the prevention, there in the encouragement of 
 the corn trade. The thought pursued everywhere was this: as 
 competition with other countries fluctuated up and down, to cast 
 the weight of the power of the state into the scales of the balance in 
 the way demanded in each case by national interests. 
 
 1 Vide Schmoller, The Mercantile System and Its Historical Sig- 
 nificance (Macmillan, 1902). Translated from the Studien iiber die 
 wirthschajtliche Politik Friedrichs des Grossen (1883), published in the 
 first issue of Schmoller's Jahrbuch (1884).
 
 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 We have accepted Schmoller's general hypothesis in expla- 
 nation of the mercantilist system. His view must be taken 
 as representing, in its main features, the consensus of present 
 historical scholarship. He epitomizes it in this form: 1 
 
 Our purpose was to show by a particular example, that of Bran- 
 denburg, that during the course of the period from the fifteenth to 
 the seventeenth century, the creation of the German territorial state 
 
 was not merely a political but also an economic necessity We 
 
 have to do with a great historical process by which local sentiment 
 and tradition were strengthened, the social and economic forces of 
 the whole territory consolidated, important legal and economic 
 institutions created; by which, further, the forces and institutions 
 thus united were led to a battle of competition with other territories, 
 involving numerous shiftings of toll, confiscation of goods and ships, 
 embargoes and staple-fights, prohibitions of importation and expor- 
 tation and the like; while, within the country itself, old antagonisms 
 softened and trade became more free. 
 
 To so powerful and self-contained a structure and so independent 
 and individual a policy as the town had reached in an earlier age^ 
 the German territory scarcely anywhere attained .... yet this 
 very time the second half of the sixteenth century, and the seven- 
 teenth century was an epoch which gave every inducement for an 
 economic transformation. The way was already clear, out of the 
 narrow circle of the small territory into the larger union of forces 
 
 jx)ssible only in the great state These forces all converging 
 
 impelled society to some large economic reorganization on a broader 
 basis, and pointed to the creation of national states with a correspond- 
 ing policy Everywhere, save in Germany, economic bodies 
 
 were stretching out and becoming political; everywhere new state 
 systems of economy and finance were arising, able to meet the new 
 needs of the time. Only in our Fatherland did the old economic 
 institutions become so petrified as to lose all life; only in Germany 
 were the foreign trade, the manufacturing skill, the supply of capital, 
 the good economic usages, connections and traditions, which the 
 country had possessed up to 1620, more and more completely lost. 
 
 1 Loc. '/., pp. 43 (I.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 9 
 
 And it was not simply the external loss in men and capital which 
 brought about this retrogression of Germany, during a period of 
 more than one century, in comparison with the Powers of the West; 
 it was not even the transference of the world's trading routes from 
 the Mediterranean to the ocean that was of most consequence; it 
 was the lack of politico-economic organization, the lack of consolida- 
 tion in its forces. What, to each in its time, gave riches and supe- 
 riority first to Milan, Venice, Florence, and Genoa; then later to 
 Spain and Portugal; and now to Holland, France, and England, 
 and, to some extent to Denmark and Sweden, was a state policy in 
 economic matters as superior to the territorial as that had been to 
 the municipal. Those states began to weave the great economic 
 improvements of the time into their political institutions and policies, 
 and to bring about an intimate relation between the one and the 
 other. States arose, forming united, and therefore strong and wealthy 
 economic bodies, quite different from earlier conditions; in these, 
 quite unlike earlier times, the state organization assisted the national 
 economy and this the state policy; and, quite unlike earlier times 
 too, public finance served as the bond of union between political 
 and economic life. It was not only a question of state armies, fleets, 
 and civil services, it was a question rather of unifying systems of 
 finance and economy which should encompass the forces of millions 
 and whole countries, and give unity to their social life. There had 
 always been great states; but they had been bound together neither 
 by traffic nor by the organization of labor nor by any other like forces. 
 The question now was with a great society divided into social 
 classes widely different from one another and complicated by the 
 division of labor to bring about, as far as possible, on the basis 
 of common national and religious feelings, a union for external 
 defense and for internal justice and administration, for currency and 
 credit, for trade interests and the whole economic life, which should 
 be comparable with the achievements, in its time, of the municipal 
 government in relation to the town and its environs. This was no 
 mere fancy of the rulers; it was the innermost need of the higher 
 civilization itself that such enlarged and strengthened forms of 
 
 social and economic community should come into existence 
 
 The whole internal history of the seventeenth and eighteenth cen-
 
 io THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tunes, nut only in Germany, but everywhere else, is summed up in the 
 opposition of the economic policy of the state to that of th^ town, the 
 district, and the several Estates; the whole foreign history is summed 
 up in the opposition to one another of the separate interests of the 
 newly rising states, each of which sought to obtain and retain its 
 place in the circle of European nations, and in that foreign trade 
 
 which now included America and India 
 
 Only he who thus conceives of mercantilism will understand it; 
 in its innermost kernel it is nothing but state making not state 
 making in a narrow sense, but state making and national -economy 
 making at the same time; state making in the modern sense, which 
 creates out of the political community an economic community, 
 and so gives it a heightened meaning. The essence of the system 
 lies not in some doctrine of money, or of the balance of trade ; not 
 in tariff barriers, protective duties or navigation laws; but in some- 
 thing far greater, namely, in the total transformation of society and 
 its organization, as well as of the state and its institutions, in the 
 replacing of a local and territorial economic policy by that of the 
 national state. With this accords the fact lately 'pointed out with 
 regard to the literary history of the movement, that what is peculiar 
 to all the mercantilist writers is not so much the regulations of trade 
 which they propose for the increase of the precious metals as the 
 stress they lay on the active circulation of money, especially within 
 the state itself. 1 
 
 The last sentence in this quotation from Schmoller suggests 
 the peculiar relation of the cameralists to mercantilism upon 
 which we shall try to show that their writings prove tradition 
 to be misleading. Mercantilism, the instinctive national 
 policy of states in the process of evolution, while at the same 
 time in miscellaneous struggle with other states, was the most 
 prominent objective reality in the civic life of the time. On 
 the other hand, later writers about mercantilism have created 
 
 1 For Schmoller's later views on this main theme, and especially 
 for bibliography of the various phases of the subject, vide Grundriss, 
 Index, title "Mercantilismus," etc.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 1 1 
 
 a grotesque mythology of the, political and economic theory 
 supposed to have been held by the supporters of the policy. 
 The present study does not extend to mercantilistic theorists 
 outside of Germany. While we are prepared, in the proper 
 place, to challenge the credibility of this mythology as it applies 
 to other countries, our propositions in this book refer not merely 
 to German theorists alone, but to the cameralistic group 
 among those theorists. The cameralists are generally reputed 
 to have been typical mercantilists, in the sense that they are 
 alleged to have taught certain economic doctrines implied by 
 the mercantilistic policy. One of the results of appeal to the 
 cameralistic books themselves is proof that mercantilism in the 
 supposed sense, that is, as a specific system of false economic 
 generalizations, cannot be found in these sources. 
 
 Adam Smith did much to create belief in this mythological 
 mercantilism. When we analyze his chapter on "The Prin- 
 ciple of the Commercial or Mercantile System," 1 we find that 
 it produced its effect in this direction more by innuendo than 
 by precise assertion. The chapter begins with the sentence: 
 
 That wealth consists in money, or in gold and silver, is a popular 
 notion which naturally arises from the double function of money, 
 as the instrument of commerce, and as the measure of value. 
 
 The poison in the sentence gets its venom in part by asso- 
 ciation with the title of Book IV, "Of Systems of Political 
 Economy," and with the subtitle of chap. i. The reader under- 
 stands Smith to imply that there have been systems of "politi- 
 cal economy" based on the idea that "wealth consists in money, 
 or in gold and silver;" and that there was a "commercial or 
 mercantile system " which posited this principle. It turns out 
 in the first place that Smith did not distinguish, in this part of 
 his work, between " political economy " as a theory, and eco- 
 nomic policy. He asserts that interested parties have succeeded 
 
 1 Wealth of Nations, Book IV, chap. i.
 
 12 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in persuading nations to act as though money were the only 
 wealth, and thereupon he indulges in a homily upon the absurd- 
 ity of that idea. Nevertheless, he concludes 1 that a system 
 of "political economy" which rested on this absurdity widely 
 prevailed. Thus he says: 
 
 The two principles being established, however, that wealth con- 
 sisted in gold and silver, and that those metals could be brought 
 into a country which had no mines only by the balance of trade, or 
 by exporting to a greater value than it imported ; it necessarily became 
 the great object of political economy (sic) to diminish as much as 
 possible the importation of foreign goods for home consumption, 
 and to increase as much as possible the exportation of the produce 
 of domestic industry. 
 
 A history of the growth of this mercantilistic myth would 
 be instructive, and it is to be hoped that it will some day be 
 written. We may content ourselves with a single comparatively 
 modern and somewhat more full-grown version of the same 
 fiction, this time by a writer who may fairly be presumed to 
 have included the Germans more directly in his generalization 
 than was probably the case with Smith. 2 This historian of 
 political science says: 
 
 The Mercantile System, then, or Colbcrtism, was the first attempt 
 to put the fundamental principles of the theory of management 
 [H'irthschajtslehre] on a scientific and orderly basis. The central 
 point <>} the same was the attribution o] exclusive value to the precious 
 metals.'* Consequently the effort in every possible way to acquire 
 gold and silver, and to retain the same: hence also the anxiety for 
 a favorable balance of trade. The means relied upon were: exclu- 
 sive (sic) promotion of the transforming industries, and of foreign 
 trade, especially attainable through privileges, advances of capital, 
 precise regulations for industries, monopolies, favorable commer- 
 
 1 Bax e<l., Vol. I, p. 450. 
 
 3 Von Mohl, Gesehichte und Literatur der Staatsu-issenschajten, III. 
 Brl. (1858), p. 296. 
 
 3 Italics mine.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 13 
 
 rial treaties and exclusive relations with colonies; then prohibition 
 of the export of the precious metals, and of raw materials fit for 
 domestic manufacture. 
 
 Nothing is easier than to show conclusively the incorrectness 
 of the fundamental idea, as well as the impropriety of the means 
 employed. It would therefore be a waste of time to stop for discus- 
 sion of the absolute truth of the system. At the same time, the ques- 
 tion of its relative value for the times and circumstances is not to 
 be disposed of in the same way. It has long since been observed 
 by others that this first system of political economy (sic) was not a 
 product of minds exploring truth with 1 a distinctly conscious pur- 
 pose. It was rather the generalization of the actual programme of 
 certain eminent statesmen, particularly Colbert. 1 It is equally easy 
 to prove, however, that the essential fundamental idea of these 
 statesmen, and therewith of the system built upon it, emerged neces- 
 sarily from the economic condition of Europe after the middle of 
 the seventeenth century. The accumulation of great sums of money 
 for defraying the costs of war and supplying the luxury of courts 
 was the involuntary task of the officials intrusted with the manage- 
 ment of states. This task could be discharged easiest, not to say 
 solely, by constant increase of the export of goods. These were 
 wanted in the newly accessible parts of the world, and would be paid 
 for in gold and silver. Of a basing of popular welfare, and therewith 
 oj the income of the crown, upon more prosperous agriculture, not a 
 word could be said; partly because of the lack of all rational knowledge 
 of agricultural economy on the part of the landed gentry, together 
 with the utterly suppressed condition of the peasantry, partly because 
 the development of this source of wealth could not keep pace with 
 the above-mentioned need. 
 
 Such mixtures of Wahrheit und Dichtung are the substitutes 
 for objective interpretation of the cameralistic period which 
 our generation has inherited, and we have accepted them almost 
 
 1 Von Mohl fails to discover, and consequently helps to add vogue 
 to, the fallacy of the whole generalization. He does not perceive that 
 the generalizers put into the system what they thought it should be made 
 responsible for, instead of finding out what its followers actually thought.
 
 14 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 without question. How far from the truth was the last sen- 
 tence in the quotation may be inferred from the bibliography 
 of agriculture published by Zincke. 1 
 
 Now the fact is that "mercantilism" as political economy, 
 in the sense at present associated with that term, in contrast 
 with political policy, did not exist among the cameralists. 
 This was, first, because political economy was not born till 
 after their time, and second, because such material for political 
 economy as was contained in their theories was wonderfully 
 sound, as far as it went, on the meaning of money and the 
 precious metals. It is as absurd to charge the theorists of 
 the mercantilistic period with the economic vagaries of which 
 (by inference from the opportunistic policies of the governments 
 which they served, and which they themselves to a certain 
 extent approved) our modern logic might prove them construct- 
 ively guilty, as it would be to charge the economists of England 
 today with dogmas which might be deduced from generaliza- 
 tion of British policy in the Boer war. Mercantilism, the 
 policy, was war more than it was philosophy. It was the prac- 
 tical answer to the practical question, What is the practical 
 thing for our state to do under present circumstances ? A situa- 
 tion might easily be imagined in which, with a war to be fought 
 at a distance with a strong nation, the people of the United 
 States, irrespective of party affiliations or economic principles, 
 might afford a certain type of reasoners all the evidence they 
 would want for the assertion, "The people of the United States 
 all believe that coal is the only wealth." The conclusion would 
 have essentially the same sort of logical support, and would 
 have the same degree of validity, which examination of the 
 sources discovers in the case of the cameralists and their alleged 
 
 1 Vide below, p. 242; cf. p. 256. The blurred view of the cameral- 
 ists given by Cohn is still more notable, because Cohn's book has prob- 
 ably influenced the thinking of many times more students than von 
 Mohl's. Vide Grundriss der Nalionalokonomie, 1885, pp. 99, 100.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 15 
 
 mercantilism. They certainly believed in a mercantilistic 
 policy. They certainly did not believe in the mercantilistic 
 political economy which has been charged to them by an age 
 that does not understand the meaning of the policy. 
 
 Tradition has dealt quite as uncritically with cameralistic 
 beliefs about population. They have been represented as 
 directly contrary to the Malthusian principle. The cameralists 
 have been supposed to believe unlimited increase of the number 
 of citizens both possible and desirable. In reality the Malthu- 
 sian problem never distinctly appeared above their horizon. 
 Their beliefs about population were substantially the same 
 beliefs which the traffic managers of our western railroads, 
 and the farmers of the prairie states act upon every year of 
 abundant crops. They assume that hands enough are not 
 to be had for harvesting. The cameralists knew as well as 
 modern economists do that there was a limit beyond which 
 more mouths could not be fed. They did not qualify their 
 statements about population quite as carefully as men must 
 who have in mind the Malthusian chapter in economic theory. 
 Substantially, however, they held tenable views of the subject 
 as far as they went, and their efforts to promote population 
 would propably be duplicated today, under parallel circum- 
 stances, by the most convinced Malthusians in the world. 
 
 Perhaps the most radical misunderstanding of the cameral- 
 ists, especially on this side of the Atlantic, is in connection with 
 their theories of absolutism. To Americans, absolutism is 
 so unthinkable as a principle of political philosophy, that 
 nothing tolerable can be credited to theories in which such a 
 postulate is a factor. But Americans would have become 
 much profounder political philosophers than they are, if they 
 had been patient enough to learn a little more about the part 
 which the fiction of absolutism has performed in the process 
 of civic evolution. They might have become more docile if 
 they had perceived that the European superstition of the abso-
 
 16 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 lutism of rulers differs more in degree than in kind from the 
 American superstition of the absolutism of the constitution. 
 The truth is, each of these illusions was a legal fiction which 
 promoted social control by expressing in the most vivid way 
 practicable the enormous value of obedience to the accepted 
 authorities. Each of these fictions was the idiom in which 
 an age said, in its most impressive way, "The law must be 
 obeyed." Americans have been taught so exclusively the dark 
 phases of absolutistic regimes that they resent suggestion of 
 factors in the case which they have not considered. While 
 absolutism as a principle is indefensible, it has been of incal- 
 culable service as a makeshift; and sometimes, notably in the 
 case of most of the cameralists, the absolutistic element which 
 occupied the place of honor in the formal philosophy of the 
 state was subordinated in effect by the moral force of judgments 
 which made steadily in the direction of more authentic civic 
 principles. 
 
 But we must indicate the central motive of the cameralists 
 in a positive way. Apart from all details, whether on the 
 credit or debit side, the salient fact about the cameralistic civic 
 theory was its fundamental assumption of the paramount value 
 of the collective interests, or in othtr -words the subordination 
 of the interests of the individual to the interests of the community. 
 The absolutistic state, of which cameralism was the theory, 
 used means and methods which are out of the question for 
 democracies. That same absolutistic state maintained cer- 
 tain scales of social value, and arrived at certain types of con- 
 crete result, to which democracies thus far have not attained. 
 Whether we will or no, human experience is social. The type 
 of association is more important to the continuous process of 
 human achievement than the choices of individuals. Whether 
 any society has found the just balance between social ascend- 
 ency and individual liberty, the principle that social ascendency 
 must practically outrank private preference is vital to civiliza-
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 17 
 
 tion. Whether the Germans have overemphasized the col- 
 lectivistic principle, future centuries must decide. Even if 
 Americans are unprepared to concede that our democracy 
 has given individualism too much license, it will be the part 
 of wisdom for us to inspect the achievements of German col- 
 lectivism without deciding in advance that they contain nothing 
 from which Americans can derive instruction. 
 
 Whether the collectivistic principle is ever beneficially 
 to modify democracy or not, there is hardly room for debate 
 upon the proposition that in sheer economy of social efficiency 
 Germany has no near rival among the great nations. Whether 
 the method of this achievement costs more than it is worth, is 
 an open question. That, in view of what it has accomplished, 
 it is worth understanding, is beyond dispute. The explanation 
 of the German type of success cannot be reached without cal- 
 culating the significance of the cameralists. 
 
 It has passed into a world's proverb that the German school- 
 master won the campaign of Sedan. It would be a superficial 
 version of that approximate truth, if the schoolmaster in the 
 case were supposed to be the pedagogue who taught the men 
 in the three columns that crossed the Rhine. The school in 
 which the wonderful proficiency of modern Germany was 
 trained was its whole civic system. No part of the machinery 
 of modern history has been regarded more contemptuously 
 by the rest of the world than the petty German principalities. 
 They were ignoble and obstructive enough, to be sure, but this 
 is not the complete account. Each, with its minute cameralis- 
 tic organization, functioned like the drill sergeants with the 
 raw levies. The incapable masses of the German people 
 were divided into squads, and disciplined for civic duties, and 
 after the dull drill of centuries were delivered over to the united 
 nation as the most completely socialized citizens in modern 
 European history. 
 
 Without attempting to determine the precise degree of
 
 1 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 influence which each theorist, or the government behind him, 
 exerted upon the development of cameralism, we may begin 
 with a rapid sketch of the more prominent text -writers. In 
 general it is needless to bring into this account biographical 
 material in addition to that to be found in Die allgemeine 
 deutsche Biographic. While it is necessary to base our work 
 upon the presumption of familiarity with Roscher, 1 ' the argu- 
 ment of this book is a direct challenge of the correctness of 
 Roscher's interpretation. 2 We shall go to the writings of the 
 cameralists themselves for direct evidence of the presump- 
 tions, the content, and the sociological significance of their 
 system. 
 
 The term Kammer, derivatives of which have been trans- 
 literated into English to denote' a theory and practice for which 
 Englishmen have no exact equivalent, is itself a variant of the 
 Latin camera, in turn from the Greek Ka/*apa. 3 Cameralism 
 was the routine of the bureaus in which the administrative 
 employees of governments, first of all in the fiscal departments, 
 did their work; or in a larger sense it was systematized govern- 
 mental procedure, the application of which was made in the 
 administrative bureaus. 
 
 Roscher distinguishes in the second half of the seventeenth 
 
 1 Geschichte der Xalional-Oekonomik in Deutschland. 
 
 * While Rosrher partially corrects an error, yet he rehabilitates it 
 at the same time in another form: 7.nr Ceschichle der englischen Volks- 
 'U'irthschajlslehre, p. 122. 
 
 ' Liddell and Srott: "anything with a vaulted roof or arched cover- 
 ing;" Heyse, Fremdu'drterlmch: "'camera or Kammer in the more restricted 
 sense is the apartment where the counselors charged with administration 
 of the revenues of a principality assembled: then the persons them- 
 selves, Kammerrdthe and Kammer- A ssessoren." Cameralia, or Cameral- 
 Wistenschajten, were the theories on which administration of the revenues 
 proceeded; in a wider sense the term was applied to the sciences of the 
 state in general. A cameralist was one who understood these sciences 
 either theoretically or in practice.
 
 INTRODUCTION TO CAMERALISM 19 
 
 century three principal tendencies among the German national 
 economists: 1 
 
 first a practical-conservative tendency, which had its chief seat in 
 the small territories of middle Germany and was best represented 
 by Seckendorff. Then a purely scientific tendency, belonging almost 
 wholly in the north of Germany, where as typical contrasts Pufendorf 
 and Conring loom up. A third group, viz., the practical-progressive, 
 attaches itself most closely in part to Austria, in part to the great 
 Electors. 
 
 It begs the question at the outset, to use the phrase with which 
 Roscher begins detailed discussion of these tendencies. To 
 speak of "the conservative national economics" 2 in the second 
 half of the seventeenth century in Germany is to imply that 
 there already was a systematic economics in the sense in which 
 that phrase was understood two hundred years later, when 
 Roscher wrote. It is certainly not true that an economic 
 theory existed in Germany at that time in the sense carried 
 by the phrase in England since Adam Smith. It would be 
 
 1 Geschichte der National -Oekonomik in Deutschland, p. 237. I shall 
 urge later (p. 49; cf. pp. 195, 196) that it is necessary to supply English- 
 speaking students with a commentary on this term, if they are to be pro- 
 tected against misconceptions of historical facts. The term "National- 
 okonomik" corresponds with what existed in Germany in the seventeenth 
 and eighteenth centuries, only if it has the force of the phrase "national 
 management." This management included morals, education, religion, 
 politics, diplomacy, war, and finance, much more directly and intensively 
 than it concerned itself with economic questions as understood in 
 England and America. It is an anachronism therefore to credit Ger- 
 many, before Adam Smith's critique of economic relations was imported 
 and domesticated, with an economic science in the British sense. The 
 men in Germany who theorized about civic interests before the close of the 
 eighteenth century were political scientists after their kind. They were 
 political economists only in a secondary and incidental sense. This 
 distinction is crucial for the interpretation of all the social sciences in 
 Germany from this point. 
 
 Loc. cit. t p. 238.
 
 20 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 less difficult to support a claim that economics in Germany 
 in the second half of the nineteenth century was merely a more 
 highly developed form of the theory which constituted the social 
 science of the cameralists. This would however at best be a 
 misleading version of the facts. Economic science in Germany 
 was merely a subordinate and subconscious factor in the came- 
 ralistic theory of governmental management. It had not 
 gained independence as a science of wealth relations, irre- 
 spective of the forms of government under which they exist. 
 The economic presumptions of the cameralists, whether 
 essentially sound or not, were at first merely the folklore of 
 homely thrift, not critical analyses of general economic rela- 
 tions. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the center 
 of social interest was civic, not economic. With this theorem 
 as our point of departure we are bound to arrive at a revised 
 version of the economic theories of the period. 1 
 
 1 Readers who want the author's conclusions, but who are unwilling 
 to examine his evidence, may pass from this point to the last chapter.
 
 CHAPTER II 
 THE CIVICS OF OSSE 
 
 If the purpose of this book were to trace minutely the 
 evolution of cameralism, our problem would lead back into 
 investigation of generations of men, princes and their servants, 
 of whom Osse was in many ways typical. Such an inquiry 
 would take us far beyond the scope of the present study. It 
 would be rather an investigation of the history of German 
 political institutions in general, especially after the Reforma- 
 tion, than interpretation of a single quasi-academic factor in 
 that civic development. It would bring to the center of atten- 
 tion quite different types of evidence from that to which this 
 argument is restricted. Osse functioned chiefly as an agent 
 of princes at a time when the territorial sovereignty of the Ger- 
 man rulers was still undecided, and when the administration 
 of German states was in an early formative stage. His activity 
 as an author was relatively accidental, yet his influence in this 
 character was incomparably more lasting than in any other. 
 He is cited here, however, rather as a means of marking the 
 relativity of the writers to be noticed more at length, than as 
 properly within the bounds of the present survey. 
 
 Osse was born in the hamlet of Ossa, near the obscure 
 town of Geithain, in 1506. He studied law at Leipzig, was 
 "scholarly, conscientious, laborious, gentle and deeply pious." 1 
 He served. for a time in the army; for several years he occupied 
 the chief lectureship in law at Leipzig; in 1537 he was men- 
 tioned by Zarncke as consiliarius Misnensis; he remained a 
 counselor of Herzog Georg till the death of the latter; passed 
 to the service of Herzog Moritz, 1541; the same year was 
 released by Moritz to enter the service of the elector Johann 
 
 1 Diestel in Allgemeinc deutsche Biographic, title "Osse." 
 
 31
 
 22 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Friedrich, where he remained as chancellor for six years. 
 There are confusions in dates at this period, but after employ- 
 ment of uncertain length at Meiningen, Osse was in 1547 made 
 Hofrichter in Leipzig. In 1550 he represented the elector 
 at the Diet of Augsburg. On account of ill health he with- 
 drew from his judgeship in 1555, and composed the document 
 which is his chief title to a place in history. He died in 1556. 
 
 A more searching inquiry into the personal record of Osse 
 is unnecessary. In spite of the author's own usage, and that 
 of his editor Thomasius, which we follow, Roscher uses the 
 form "Ossa," corresponding to the acepted spelling of his 
 birthplace. 
 
 It appears further that, in spite of his prestige at Leipzig, 
 Osse was not in full favor with the Saxon theologians. The 
 complete story of this phase of his career would take us far 
 afield, in the general culture-history of the period, and we must 
 pass it with a mere hint. Philipp Melanchthon soundly berated 
 Osse and five other advisers of Herzog Moritz, and he embel- 
 lished one of his denunciations with the couplet : 
 
 Hiengen die Sechs an einen Strick. 
 Das war Sachsen und Meissen Gliick. 1 
 
 The editor, Thomasius, implies that the reputation thus referred 
 to made Osse uncomfortable at the court of Johann Friedrich, 
 and accounts for his resignation. Thomasius protests, how- 
 ever, that he can find no adequate ground for Osse's bad 
 repute with the elector. While declining to enter into the 
 merits of the case, he submits this consideration, viz.: 
 
 Philipp Melanthon (sic) was no angel himself, and there are 
 proofs enough that not everything which came from Melancthon 
 as a judgment of other men can be taken as a divine truth or an 
 infallible gospel. 
 
 At bottom, the case against Osse appears to have been 
 that his break with traditional religious ideas was not as com- 
 
 Testament, ed. Thorn., 1717, "Vorrede," p. 10.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 23 
 
 plete as the Lutherans demanded. He was accused of 
 being still at heart a papist. In commenting upon this charge, 
 Thomasius furnishes the interesting item that Osse's copious 
 quotations from the Vulgate, instead of the Lutheran version, 
 were among the most damaging evidences of his guilt. 
 
 We turn directly to the Testament, the document which 
 entitles its author to rank as a forerunner of the seventeenth- 
 and eighteenth-century cameralists. 1 It is a monograph 
 written in the last year of its author's life, and by command 
 of his prince, and was intended, both by prince and his emeri- 
 tus adviser, to serve the purpose for which Adam Smith later 
 invoked the hypothesis of "the impartial spectator." 
 
 The form in which the document is now most accessible 
 is the edition of Christian Thomasius, the man who is reputed 
 to have been the first in Germany to introduce the innovation 
 of academic lectures in the vulgar language. At the time of 
 his discovery of the document, he was an important factor in 
 the influence of the University of Halle, of which he is called 
 one of the founders. We shall have occasion to refer to him 
 again in his proper chronological place. At present we need 
 to cite only a few details in which he has thrown light upon 
 Osse. 
 
 1 D. Melchiors von Osse "Testament." Gegen Hertzog Augusta 
 Churfursten zu Sachsen. Sr. Churfurst. Gnaden Rdthen und Land- 
 schaffUn. 1556. Anitzo zum ersten mahl vollig gedruckt. Auch hin 
 und wieder durch nutzlicke A ntnerckungen Erldutert. Nebst einer Vorrcde 
 und Anhang von einen Versuch kleiner " Annalium" den damahligen 
 Zustand so wohl bey Hofe als auf Universitaten desto deutlicher sich cin- 
 zubilden. Zum Gebrauch des Tliomasischen "Auditorii." Halle im 
 Magdeburgisch. A. MDCCXVII. A portion of the author's special 
 title-page to the body of the document reads: " Welchergestalt eine 
 Christliche Obrigkeit ingemein, in ihrem Regiment mit Gottes Hulffe eine 
 gottselige, weissliche verniinfftige und rechtmassige Justicien erhalten 
 kan. Darum auch Erwehnung geschieht von dem Regiment. Gericht- 
 barkeit und Policey der I6blichen Chur- und FUrstenthum Sachsen, 
 Thiiringen, und Meissen, Hochermeldtem Churfursten zustandig."
 
 24 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 In the first place, Thomasius says, in the Preface to the 
 document, that he was first shown the imperfect manuscript, 
 (apparently in 1707) in the Furstfiche Bibliothck at Wolffen- 
 biittel. He adds that up to that time it was unknown to him, 
 and he had not even seen the portions that had been printed. 
 Later he bought the full manuscript at an auction. Thomasius 
 appears to have recognized in Osse a man after his own heart. 
 Replying to the supposed challenge, Why publish the book 
 of a man about whom so many suspicions existed ? he says 
 (Vorrcde, p. 16): 
 
 The author is the first of those counselors known to us who 
 gave their opinion as to the way in which the judicial system is 
 to be improved. The first usually breaks the ice, and cannot accom- 
 plish all, but he leaves the rest to his successors. 
 
 The document as we have it occupies, with the editor's 
 notes, 548 pages. In the same binding, and filling 264 pages, 
 is Thomasius' collection of materials on the history of the Uni- 
 versity of Leipzig. The title of the collection is Ein kleincr 
 Versuch von Annalibus. The editing of Osse's work was in 
 Thomasius' mind a propagandist measure, and as he regarded 
 improvement of the educational system as the key to the whole 
 problem, it was appropriate to issue the seemingly unlike docu- 
 ments together. It appears that Thomasius wanted to publish 
 a treatise on political reform, with reference both to the Roman 
 and the Canon law. The difficulties proved too great, and 
 he chose to make Osse's document the vehicle of some of his 
 ideas. His notes on the text number 271. The Testament 
 itself contains only 118 sections. Although the notes are in 
 much smaller type than the text, a rough estimate shows that 
 they fill, in the aggregate, about one-half the whole space. If 
 we should fully analyze both text and notes, we should find 
 in them two separate monuments, of two stadia of development 
 in political philosophy, previous to that marked by the most 
 complete form of cameralism. For that reason we shall not
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 25 
 
 undertake here a detailed account either of Osse or of Thoma- 
 sius. Their determining purpose was not identical with that 
 of cameralism proper. On the whole, they had their center 
 in other groups, with which this book does not attempt to deal. 
 We may simply note in these two writers certain germs which 
 must be examined in more developed form in later theorists. 
 One who knew nothing of the history of the German lan- 
 guage, or of its geographical variations, who assumed that its 
 growth was in a straight line, and who drew conclusions from 
 literary form alone, would promptly place Osse's Testament 
 much later than Obrecht's Secreta Politica; 1 perhaps even 
 later than Becher. 3 Of course the use of Latin by the side 
 of German in the Obrecht collection strengthens the impres- 
 sion of age. Osse's syntax, as well as his vocabulary, 
 approaches closer than that of either of these writers to modern 
 usage. According to Thomasius' statement (Vorrede, p. 33), 
 this is not to be attributed to the editor. He says that he 
 changed little or nothing in the style, with the single exception 
 of substituting the word oder in frequent cases for Osse's word 
 aber. Osse's own statement of his reason for writing in Ger- 
 man is as follows: 
 
 The motives which have moved me to set down my opinions 
 in the German language, are not for the sake of His Electoral Grace, 
 who, God be praised, was in his youth thoroughly instructed in the 
 Latin tongue and good arts, but rather the consideration that this 
 memorial might come to the knowledge of laymen, untaught in the 
 Latin language, and the desire that they might not be hindered in 
 reading it by the intermixture of many Latin words. 3 
 
 Osse begins the Testament with a paragraph which we 
 translate as closely as possible : 
 
 It is among all wise people beyond dispute, that every magistracy 
 (Obrigkeit) may prove and make evident its virtue and aptitude in 
 
 ' Vide pp. 40 ff. below. 3 Zuschrifft, pp. 8 ff. 
 
 a Vide pp. 107 ff. below.
 
 26 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 two ways. First, in time of war, through manly deeds, good sagacious 
 projects, and protection of their lands and subjects, second, in time 
 of peace, through ordering and maintaining of good godly righteous 
 government, judiciary, and Policey. 1 For with these two every 
 magistracy should necessarily be adorned and supplied, in order that 
 in every time of war and peace they (sic) may be able well to govern, 
 protect, control and defend their own. 
 
 Osse then enlarges briefly upon the duties which belong 
 to the ruler in time of war; but he dismisses this side of the 
 case as beyond his competence. As to the other class of duties, 
 he continues (p. 33): 
 
 As to what concerns the government in times of peace, I will 
 write, as much as God vouchsafes me grace, for He is the ground 
 on which all must be built which is good, and wherever such ground 
 is lacking there follows no permanent building. 
 
 The author promises to set down truly all that he has 
 observed in the service of five electors of Saxony, the fifth then 
 living. He frequently repeats that he is doing this not of his 
 own motion, but at the command of the elector. We may 
 safely assume that the passage immediately following represents 
 Osse's fundamental opinions as well as they could be pictured. 
 He says (p. 33): 
 
 Such a command I am not at liberty to disregard, and for this 
 reason I lay down first of all the following ground. All that I here- 
 after write will be built upon it. It must also be observed with 
 special diligence. 
 
 Government over men is such a high, precious and wonderful 
 thing, that no human being, no matter how excellent in understand- 
 ing, reason and wit, is to be intrusted with exercising it according 
 to his own will, caprice and opinion, for such government is a higher 
 thing than that the exercise of it could belong to one over others who 
 by nature are of one origin with him, which same may be known 
 from all races of animals, since a flock of sheep does not allow itself 
 
 1 The reasons for allowing this term to stand in its German form 
 will appear later.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 27 
 
 to be ruled by a sheep, nor a drove of horses or cattle by one of their 
 own kind, but rather for such government something else is necessary, 
 which is higher and better than the other beasts. Now man, who 
 in many ways surpasses the other animals, for the like reason, since 
 man must be governed, he must be governed by something higher 
 and more excellent than man himself, if the government is to be 
 stable. Since now nothing more excellent can be found in this world 
 than man .... who is yet fallible, and has much in common with 
 the beasts, .... and even in case a man were found who could 
 be moved from the right by no irregular affections, he would be sub- 
 ject to mortality, and no one would know what would happen with 
 his successors, therefore almighty God, out of special grace to human 
 kind, has ordained the means of the common written "aw [der ordent- 
 lichen beschriebenen Recht und Gesetze] whereby to keep the temper 
 of magistrates and judges in the right way, in order that the same 
 may govern others and render justice without any hindrance of inor- 
 dinate inclinations and affections, and when one considers the use- 
 fulness of such a divinely given means, one finds that this ordination 
 of rights and laws is one of the highest benefits and gifts with which 
 God has blessed men here in this life, for such laws and rights were 
 in the beginning ordained by wise honorable people after necessary 
 consideration, not from friendship, love or hate, but in general with- 
 out all inordinate affections and inclinations When now 
 
 such common right and law is ordained, even if those who act con- 
 trary to it are punished in accordance with it, .... no one has 
 occasion for complaint, but everyone is satisfied, since we know that 
 justice has been done to one as well as to another, and that so impa- 
 tience and uproar of the subjects is avoided. 1 
 
 A little later (p. 37) the conclusion is drawn still more 
 distinctly: 
 
 1 The uneasiness of Thomasius over the traditional doctrines alxnjt 
 "beschriebene Gesetze" (vide Roscher, in re Thomasius) begins to show itself 
 in the note in this passage, viz., "the written laws are by no means to 
 be preferred to the customs" (Gewohnheiten). The naive reasoning 
 which Osse represents was an effective means of control so long as people 
 accepted it at face value. Revolution was certain wherever it was repu- 
 diated without substitution of a constructive theory.
 
 28 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Hence follows that it is a human duty to hold the common rights 
 and laws in honor, to esteem them high, and to subject oneself to 
 them with patience, as the means whereby common peace, repose 
 and welfare are maintained. And that also the established magis- 
 tracy is under obligation to protect such right and law, to enforce 
 it and to govern according to it, not oppressing anyone by acting 
 contrary to it. For there can be no doubt that as the powers that 
 be are ordained of God (Ad. Rom. 13) likewise also human rights 
 and laws by the powers that be, so that they flow from the providence 
 
 and special destiny of almighty God Accordingly everyone 
 
 should remember that if he disobeys the magistrate and escapes 
 punishment, yet he is not assured of escaping the punishment of 
 almighty God. 1 
 
 At the opening of the second part, Osse says that, in order 
 rightly to understand his reflections as a whole, it is necessary 
 to read what he has said in the first part about all Christian 
 governments. As to electoral Saxony in particular, he adds, 
 it has been the object of special divine favor. He specifies 
 as a fundamental blessing, that the government is not elective 
 but hereditary, and exclusively in the male line. 2 The con- 
 sequence is (p. 204) that the best people in the country are 
 retained in the service of the court, and the good customs and 
 laws continue undisturbed. The country has therefore grown 
 in power, resources, public buildings, and otherwise. Then 
 follows this passage: 
 
 And since every government in temporal affairs is of two partr 
 \auj zweyerley stehet], namely government (sic) and Policey, and 
 then the judiciary and justice, it is in order that the aforenamed 
 
 1 Entirely aside from the familiar dogmatic basis of this argument, 
 Osse's use of the terms " beschriebene " and " geschricbene Rechte" 
 apparently without variation of concept plainly shows that the argu- 
 ment got some of its plausibility from a peculiar form of the ambiguous 
 middle hidden in the logic, i. e., the ecclesiastico-theological associations 
 of the terms "heilige Schri/t," " geschrieben," etc., were carried over 
 to all written laws. 
 
 3 Thomasius at once challenges this dictum, on the ground that 
 debates over " the best form of government" are mere pedantries.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 29 
 
 land in this respect also should l>e blessed of God before many other 
 lands. For, in the first place, as respects the government, "hochcr- 
 meldeter Churjurst" ordered his court with many dignified people, 
 with counts, nobles, doctors, etc., who hear the causes presented, 
 reflect upon these matters, weigh and consult, and with timely advice 
 render true and right decisions. "Seine Churjiirsjt. Gn." has also 
 filled the civic offices with functionaries, with orders that each shall 
 receive what is due, and that justice shall always be rendered to 
 the subjects. For in this country, God be praised, domestic peace 
 is maintained, and many wholesome publications appear against 
 oppression and irregular administration. Moreover, in this land 
 there is a good and proper coinage, whereby the people are impelled 
 to trade with one another in all the things which they need, whereby 
 the revenues of the prince from commerce increase [Zoll und Gfleit], 
 
 etc For where there is good coinage there is much trade, 
 
 and where is much trade and people .... the land in general has 
 improvement and prosperity, etc. 
 
 This passage may be used as a way mark. In the German 
 states at the middle of the sixteenth century, there were officials 
 and administration enough, but measured by the cameralism 
 of the middle of the eighteenth century the officials were unor- 
 ganized, and the administration unspecialized and unsystem- 
 atized. Men of Osse's time were in contact with rudiments 
 of all the governmental activities which have developed since, 
 but these were relatively inchoate and confused. We have 
 distinctly disclaimed the purpose of venturing into study of 
 the evolution of cameralism, either theoretical or applied. Our 
 composite picture of the academic side of it merely draws in 
 a few lines from this embryonic period. 
 
 Osse enumerates as another blessing of the country the 
 founding of "drey Fursten-Schulen, als Meissen, Pforten, 
 Grimma, 1 und zwo treffentliche Universitiiten und hohe 
 Schulen." 2 The author refers to these schools as particularly 
 
 1 The two first in 1543, the last 1550 (Thomasius). 
 3 Leipzig, i-joq. Wittcnlierg, 1502.
 
 30 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to prepare men for official positions and to give them training 
 in legal knowledge. Thomasius comments to the effect that 
 the papacy was influential enough largely to nullify the benefits 
 of these foundations. Then mention is made of the two 
 Hojfgerichtc held by the elector, the one at Leipzig, the other 
 at Wittenberg, and the Schdppen are also praised as beneficent 
 institutions, 1 and besides the other higher and lower courts 
 held by prelates and nobles on their estates, there are many 
 hundred Land-Gerichte, "so that, by the grace of God a praise- 
 worthy justice is present in these lands." Moreover the coun- 
 try possesses a specially fine Policey,* and all affairs are 
 arranged in good order, and we meet fine, courteous, affable 
 persons in all stations. 3 In addition many natural and acquired 
 advantages are enumerated which contribute to the happiness 
 of the country. 
 
 Yet in spite of all these blessings, the author finds that 
 it is possible for abuses to creep in. He finds this danger first 
 in the administration of justice. His earliest attention is given 
 then to the means of avoiding these evils. The caution with 
 which he approaches the subject is again outspoken in prot- 
 estations of obedience to the command of the prince; and the 
 author refers besides to the demands of the common welfare 
 (gemeinen Nutz) of all classes in the country, and of many 
 
 1 These courts were supposed to secure justice in minor cases by 
 a fair combination of official and lay persons. Thomasius has an impor- 
 tant note (p. 210) on the quarrels in the law faculties over Schdppen- 
 stuhle. Vide pp. 208 and 310. 
 
 'Thereupon Thomasius tartly comments, "I will not undertake 
 to judge what sort of a thing a fine or a nasty Policey may be." We shall 
 not go into Osse's discussion of Policey in detail, because it suits our pur- 
 pose to deal with the maturer form of the system particularly as reflected 
 in Justi. Vide below, p. 436 et passim. 
 
 3 Americans receive no more elementary impression in Germany 
 than that the concept gute Ordnung fills the place in German life-philoso- 
 phy which the notion "freedom" occupies in ours.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 3 1 
 
 surrounding countries, as justifying attempts at improvement, 
 in spite of the opposition of those whose selfish interests are on 
 the side of things as they are. 
 
 Osse finds the root of all the difficulties which he has in 
 mind, in the lack of properly taught and trained men to take 
 the places of responsibility in the state. This fundamental 
 opinion accounts for the extent to which his argument turns 
 upon improvement in the universities. He recurs to the three 
 reasons which he had assigned in sees. XCIV-XCVI of Part I, 
 for unsatisfactory conditions in public life, viz.: (a) defective 
 training of children, (ft) omission to admit young men to the 
 councils of their elders, (c) frequent changes in office, and he 
 adds a fourth, viz., favoritism to relatives and friends. This 
 excludes men of more talent from public careers, or from the 
 places which they would be more competent to fill. The first 
 means suggested for correcting the evil is a system of secret 
 representatives of the prince at the universities. Their duty 
 should be to pick out young men of promise, and to recommend 
 them for appointments. Thereupon follow all the propositions 
 for the improvement of schools and universities. With respect 
 to the latter, Osse restricts himself almost exclusively to the 
 "arme betrtibte undfast gefallene Universit&t Leipzig" because 
 he professes ignorance of the facts at Wittenberg (pp. 258 ff.). 
 As a source of information about conditions within and around 
 the University of Leipzig at the middle of the sixteenth century 
 the succeeding chapters are highly important. In this con- 
 nection Thomasius' Appendix of 264 pages must again be 
 mentioned. 1 As will appear however when the systematic 
 cameralists are before us, the principal questions around which 
 
 1 Bin hleiner Versuch von Annalibus von Anno 1409 bis 1629. Eine 
 etwas genauerc Einsicht in die Historie von Ursprung und Fortgang 
 der Univcrsitdten in Deutschland, sonderlich der Universitdt Leipzig und 
 Wittenberg, und denen in denenselben entstandenen Zanchereyen unter- 
 schiedener Facultdten ingleichen des eingefilhrten langweiligen Processes, 
 und was vermittelst dieser Zdnckereyen vor Unruhe an den Chur- und
 
 32 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 cameralistic theory was built up had not yet risen upon Osse's 
 horizon. His document is useful for our purpose merely as 
 a picture of undifferentiated confusion, with which to compare 
 the highly articulated system of two centuries later. The 
 Table of Contents is worth consideration. The titles of chap- 
 ters must be understood to stand for a series of indictments 
 of everything which might be classed under those heads at 
 Leipzig, and enough evidence appears to create a prima-facie 
 case in favor of the author's substantial correctness. Here 
 then was a single group of symptoms which impressed men 
 of Osse's type as calling for correction. In later chapters 
 the reasons will appear why we must be content with a bare 
 reference to this earlier type of social theory. 
 
 This first chapter on the specific subject of justice (chap, 
 xiv) is a fine and typical specimen not merely of Osse's style, 
 but of the moral valuations which were current among the 
 more academic thinkers. The contrast between the objective 
 facts of institutions and conduct on the one hand, and frequent 
 and almost proverbial formulations of abstract moral standards 
 on the other, is perhaps nowhere more evident than in this 
 period. We may simply record in passing that citations might 
 easily be made from the literature of this period, which would 
 compare favorably in moral import with generalizations of 
 the same order in any subsequent generation. The essential 
 demands upon justice, as presented in this chapter, are that 
 it shall be (i) unpartisan, (2) impersonal, (3) incorruptible. 1 
 
 To this particular chapter on justice Thomasius adds a 
 long note (p. 435) to this effect: 
 
 Fiirstlichen Sachsischcn Hojen vcrursacht warden, zu erlangen, zu desto 
 bessern Ver stand des von D. Melchior von Osse auj Churjiirst Augusti 
 Alter gnddigslen Bejehl A. IS55 verjerligten und 1556 ubergebenen Recht- 
 lichen Bedenckens. Zum Gebrauch des Thomasischen Audi tor ii. 
 
 1 The first half at least is a rather notable apostrophe to Justice, 
 and the remainder shows that lofty ideals of practical application were 
 not without witnesses.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 33 
 
 The author has, to be sure, said much that is good and useful 
 about justice. He has however forgotten the best and most necessary, 
 namely, that for good and righteous justice it is necessary that the 
 same shall be administered as promptly as possible, and that justice 
 shall not be tediously suspended. 
 
 In fact, Osse expresses himself with sufficient clearness 
 on this point in the seventh and eighth sections of the same 
 chapter. 
 
 Then follows an account of the evils actually existing in 
 the Saxon courts, and suggestions for their correction. The 
 same general scheme is followed in the succeeding chapters 
 in the division on justice. Distinguishing the chapter on 
 Policey from the latter for purposes of emphasis, and because 
 the subject occupies such a unique position in the cameralistic 
 period, we must give our attention to the editor, although, as 
 we have intimated, he ought not properly to be considered 
 in the series of writers with whom we are chiefly concerned, 
 and although the chronological order is disarranged by atten- 
 tion to him here. Osse begins the chapter on Policey with 
 a remark to this effect: Aristotle and the greater part of the 
 ancient wise men have held that a good Policey of a land or 
 a city requires four "pieces," viz., "Princeps," "Concilium," 
 " Praetorium ," and "Populus." These the author translates, 
 "a ruler or overlord; good wise counsel; unpartisan, good 
 judicature, and a pious obedient people." 1 As in the case of 
 an earlier reference to Policey, Thomasius at once takes the 
 cue, and his note is an important symptom. Beginning with 
 bibliographical references which form one of the lines of 
 evidence by which we trace the influence of authors to be 
 discussed later, 2 Thomasius continues (p. 500): 
 
 1 " Ein Regent und Ober-Herr; guter weiser Rath; unparlheyische 
 gute Gerichtbarkeit, und fin jromm gehorsam Volck." 
 
 3 He first calls to mind the note referred to above (p. 30), and then 
 rites: "aus dem ersten Theil die relation und indicium von Clapmarii
 
 34 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 This very year there appeared at Franckfurth am Mayn a book 
 entitled Entwurff einer wohleingerichteten Policey. It contains seven 
 sheets. The author, who does not give his name, assumes that the 
 flourishing condition of the financial system of a state must rest 
 upon four chief pillars, namely Policey, fiscus, commerce, and taxa- 
 tion. The Policey has to do with the internal and external con- 
 dition (Verjassung) of the state. 1 The internal condition consists 
 in part of a vigorous society, namely, (i) in a vigorous growth of 
 the inhabitants, partly in a joyous life, both of the soul, namely, 
 (2) in a religious worship, (3) in virtuous conduct, and (4) praise- 
 worthy education; and of the body, in its sustenance, and satisfac- 
 tion, through (5) abundance of necessary, useful, and superfluous 
 means-of-life, (6) robust health, and (7) peaceful security. The 
 external condition consists (8) in the good order of people, things, 
 and places, and (9) in a convenient ornamentation of city and coun- 
 try. On the contrary, every state is disintegrated and disordered 
 through (i) decline of population, (2) disregard of religion, (3) 
 vicious life, (4) neglect of education, (5) lack of sustenance and 
 increase of the pauper class, (6) epidemics and plagues, (7) turbu- 
 lence, revolts, and private quarrels, (8) irregular confusion of social 
 strata, affairs, and places, (9) uncultivated lands and badly ordered 
 towns. For promotion of the different kinds of good works, and 
 removal of the evil, the author proposes in general the establishment 
 
 arcanis rerumpublicarunt, von Faust's consilits pro aerario, von Obrechts 
 Politischen Bedencken, von Klokii de Aerario, von der Furstiichen Macht- 
 kunst oder unerschdpfllchen Coldgrube, von des Freyherrn von Schrotern 
 Filrst. Sckatz und Rcnt-Cammer (nota 39, p. 81; nota 41, pp. 96 ff., nota 
 76, pp. 152 ff.) ingleichen von der Einjaltigkeit der Haushaltungs-Regeln 
 (nota 40, p. 95). 
 
 One of the anachronisms in English interpretation of German 
 thought has come in through premature translation of this word Ver- 
 jassung by our modern term "constitution." Unless direct evidence 
 to the contrary appears in. rare cases, the word should never be under- 
 stood to mean "constitution" in the modern sense, until the beginning 
 of the struggle for constitutions. I believe I fairly represent what the 
 word meant to the author cited and even to Thomasius by the vague 
 word "condition." The remainder of the quotation supports this view.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 35 
 
 of a Policey bureau, the members of which should be charged with 
 (i) giving their earnest attention to the above points, (2) averting 
 harmful occurrences, (3) controlling disorder, or (4) bringing com- 
 plaints before the proper tribunals, (5) maintaining reliable watch- 
 men and detectives, (6) conducting unexpected visitations and 
 inquisitions, (7) keeping a watchful eye on peaceful persons, things, 
 and places in the state, (8) to that end drawing useful ordinances 
 relating to persons and things, (9) responsibility for observance of 
 the same. Thereupon the author enlarges upon each of these nine 
 points of good Policey, especially upon the population, religion, 
 virtuous conduct, good kinds of education, riches, health, security, 
 order and adornment of a state, especially upon the means of securing 
 these things, and of avoiding the opposite. Now the author deserves 
 praise, in the first place [continues Thomasius], for attempting to 
 treat of political things in a brief and very well-connected and rather 
 clear didactic fashion, in contrast with the condition of which I 
 have so often complained, viz., that there has been scarcely an attempt 
 in universities at such pedagogy in political things. Indeed everyone 
 who reads this writing will find in it much whose truth he will com- 
 prehend, and the introduction or abolition of which he will agree 
 with the author in finding highly desirable for the state. He will 
 accordingly be pleased that in a few hours' reading he has learned 
 from the author more well-connected truths than if he had spent 
 two years with political works written according to the Aristotelian 
 method 
 
 Thomasius then refers to a second monograph of the same 
 author, another tract also published by him this year, viz., 
 Politische Gedanken, welcher gestalt Monarchen und Konige, 
 Republiquen und Fiirsten, nebst ihren Reichen, Ldndern und 
 Unterthanen, durch eine leichte methode mdchtig und reich 
 seyn oder werden ko'nnen; and he continues: 
 
 In this connection much remains to be said in order to make 
 such a tract complete. I will attempt, however, to mention only 
 the principal things, as suggested by this brief introduction, (i) It 
 is to be wished that the author had explained somewhat more clearly 
 how the Policey system should be distinguished from the fiscal,
 
 36 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 commercial and taxing systems. He observes at the outset, to be 
 sure, that the fiscal system should deal with the Oeconomie 1 of the 
 country and the domains of sovereigns; the commercial systems 
 with trade and business [Handel und Wandel], with the appertaining 
 occupations and professions; the taxing system with the arrange- 
 ments for contribution to the state, and he promises to expand his 
 thoughts upon these three neighboring pillars. After he thereupon 
 announces, however, that the Policey has charge of the internal and 
 external condition [Verfassung] of a state, one is not without reason 
 for the opinion that, because the fiscal, commercial and taxing 
 systems also belong to the internal or external condition of the state, 
 these three pieces must also be counted as parts of the Policey system. 
 And if one should say that the Policey system is here understood 
 in a restricted sense, namely, so far as the same takes account of 
 the well-being [Wohlseyn] of the subjects, since on the other hand 
 the fiscal and taxing systems aim at the well-being of the rulers, this 
 difference might have been announced at once without circumlocution 
 by the author, but on the other hand it would then not be clear how 
 the commercial system is distinguished from the Policey system, 
 especially as everyone understands that the same belongs to the fifth 
 chapter, and the author also there recommends the commercial 
 system as a necessary part of the same. (2) It is very serious 
 that the author regards all these four pillars not as the ground 
 of a peaceful and virtuously reasonable state, but as a ground 
 of the increasingly prosperous fiscal system, and that at the beginning 
 of the second tract he lays down this rule as a basis: "All considerable 
 rulers must attend to their sole ultimate purpose [eintzigen Endzweck] 
 and highest interest, viz., to become powerful and (supplying from 
 the title the words carefully omitted in this passage) rich."* For 
 although in the present tract he chatters about religion and virtue, 
 
 1 The reasons for not translating this term will appear later. Vide 
 Index, title "Economy and Related Terms." 
 
 ' A part of the reason for introducing Osse at all in this book is the 
 value of these editorial notes upon his monograph in throwing light on 
 contemporary estimates of the cameral system. Thomasius here puts 
 his finger upon the central trait of cameralism, and it is astonishing that 
 later writers have so far lost account of this clue to the whole theory.
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 37 
 
 it is on the other hand very suspicious when, at the beginning of the 
 second chapter (p. 18), he announces that he will not inquire whether 
 religion is an invention of the clergy and statesmen, who introduced 
 it for spiritual or secular purposes, but it will be enough that the 
 same furnished the chief foundation of a state. In the same spirit 
 (on p. 5), in reciting the satisfactions of the body he places riches 
 first, and gives precedence to the same not only over health but also 
 over peaceful security. Indeed, in chapter i, 6, p. 9, he recom- 
 mends polygamy as a serviceable means of increasing the population. 
 Again he refers to regulation and limitation only of houses of prosti- 
 tution, where they are to be tolerated for reasons of state, etc., etc. 
 Who the author is, I will not disclose, although I discovered his 
 identity a short time after I had read his two tracts and had made 
 these notes. Meanwhile he has sufficiently betrayed himself when, 
 in the tract, How Great Lords May Become Rich (p. n), he cites a 
 Discurs published by his father in 1655 
 
 It is evident that after writing note 105 above referred to 
 (p. 30) Thomasius saw a great light, partly through the eyes 
 of this unnamed writer, on the place of Policey in the adminis- 
 trative system. So much of the note is quoted, however, not 
 primarily for its connection with Thomasius, but because the 
 resum6 of the document will be useful for comparison later. 
 At the same time a few sentences should be added from the 
 paragraph in Osse to which Thomasius' note is appended. 1 
 They continue his reference to the different divisions of admin- 
 istration. Osse says: 
 
 Everything should be directed toward keeping these four parts 
 in good condition, if one is to maintain a good Policey, for a lord and 
 ruler is in three respects under obligations to the people divinely 
 intrusted to him; namely, that he should maintain the same in good 
 prosperous circumstances, which occurs when the people [das Volck] 
 lives virtuously, and some among them are promoted to learning, 
 and to good arts, and many wise and learned people are in their 
 number, from whom the rest may receive good instruction, and they 
 
 1 Vide above, p. 33.
 
 38 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 are not left to wander in the darkness of ignorance, and everything 
 through which such promotion of things useful to the community 
 is hindered is either prevented or averted by the ruler. 
 
 The foregoing is of firstrate importance when we generalize 
 the civic assumptions of the cameralists. 
 
 It is to be noted that Osse could say, "Praise God, this 
 land is already provided with an honorable, good, and praise- 
 worthy Policey" (p. 506). * He could offer only certain very 
 cautious and vague suggestions about details. For instance, 
 he calls attention to conflicts of interests between rural and urban 
 populations, which tended to injustice toward the former, 
 through the tendency to concentrate certain rural occupations, 
 such as brewing, in the towns (p. 509). Thomasius comments 
 on the justice of his position, in spite of the foolishness of the 
 grounds on which it is based, viz., that in Roman law trade was 
 prohibited to the nobility. Again, Osse denounces the inhu- 
 manity of many of the nobility toward the widows and orphans 
 of their dependents, and calls upon the elector to appoint a 
 supervisor to act as a guardian of such dependent persons, and 
 to secure their rights against conscienceless nobles. In the 
 third place, he urges upon the elector correction of practice in 
 the criminal courts, and especially prevention of illegal resort 
 to torture. Increase of the amount of light and air in prisons; 
 certain sumptuary reforms, on the ultimate ground (p. 516) 
 that luxury drains money from the country; attempts to pre- 
 vent rise in the price of meat; appointment of trustees to keep 
 heirs from squandering their estates, are substantially all the 
 further changes which Osse was able to recommend. 
 
 The Testament proper closes with these considerations. 
 An appendix of seventeen pages, including the editor's notes, 
 is added, with the title, Additio Gemeine des Heil. Reichs 
 
 1 As evidence that this part of the administration was well guarded, 
 he cites the Policey- und Landes-Ordnung, published by Elector August 
 in 1555, "in Corpore Juris Saxonici, torn. I, pp. 31 biss 59 zu lesen."
 
 CIVICS OF OSSE 39 
 
 Wohlfarth belangende. It replies to the hypothetical question, 
 Supposing the conduct advised in the Testament were strictly 
 adopted in Saxony, would it not all be in vain, because of the 
 disorder in the Holy Roman Empire at large ? The unhappy 
 condition of the Empire was attributed by Osse to three causes : 
 (i) the religious quarrels, (2) the weakening of the judicial 
 authority of the Empire, (3) disregard of Landfrieden within 
 the Empire. In discussing the situation he puts the emphasis 
 almost entirely on the first point. The whole matter is pri- 
 marily political in another sense from that in which the came- 
 ralists are to be considered, and it is not therefore material to 
 our inquiry. 1 
 
 Although Thomasius' Versuch von Annalibus is not directly 
 germane to our purpose, its presence in the same volume with 
 the Testament is excuse for alluding to it again. It is profess- 
 edly an attempt to stimulate the neglected study of history. 
 It is a collection of data principally concerning education 
 in Saxony. It covers the period 1409-1629. To the student 
 of Saxon history, and especially of the University of Leipzig, 
 it would be an extremely valuable secondary source. 
 
 1 Thomasius insists (p. 532) that Osse's omission to mention in this 
 connection the Religious Peace of Augsburg (September 25, 1555) 
 strengthens the suspicion that he was not a good Lutheran, but at heart 
 a papist. As the Testament was dated December, 1555, and as the 
 Additio was written later, failure to mention it, the editor thinks, points 
 to the author's lack of sympathy with any arrangement in the nature 
 of a modus Vivendi between the contending forces. Osse's own profes- 
 sions do not tend to confirm this hypothesis.
 
 CHAPTER III 
 
 THE CIVICS OF OBRECHT 
 
 The only writer whom it is necessary to mention between 
 Osse and Obrecht is Georg Engelhard von Lohneyss (some- 
 times written Lohneis, Lohneissen, etc.). Although his name 
 frequently occurs in the cameralistic books, there is no reason 
 to regard him as an important contributor to cameralistic 
 science. Thomasius (Vorrede zum Testatnent, p. 25) intimates 
 that Lohneyss borrowed much without credit from Osse. I 
 have been unable to obtain any of his writings. Inama says 
 of him : ' 
 
 He was of an aristocratic Palatine family. He was first Master 
 of the Horse at the court of Elector August of Saxony. In 1583 he 
 entered the service of Heinrich Julius of Braunschweig-Wolfen- 
 biittel, first as Stallmcisler, then as Bergkauptmann. At both courts 
 he had rare opportunities for training in the practical administrative 
 technique of the time. Each court was supposed to have a model 
 administrative system. August was an eminent and tireless admin- 
 istrator, Heinrich Julius the best trained jurist among contemporary 
 rulers. At the same time these courts were noted for their display. 
 From his purchased estates Lohneyss bore the title "Erbherr in 
 Remlingen und Neundorf." For a while he had his own printing 
 establishment, particularly to secure proper publication of his own 
 writings. His three chief works were printed here.* The latter 
 part of his life is without traces in the confusion of the Thirty Years' 
 War. His printing establishment and the stock of his books were 
 
 ' All. d. Bib., in loc. 
 
 1 Viz., d) Delia Cavelleria. S. de arte equitando, exercitiis equestribus 
 el torneamenlis, griindlicher Bericht von allem was zu der loblicken Reiterei 
 gehorig, und einem Cavalier zu u'issen von Nothen, auch Chur und War- 
 tung der Pjerde und wie man dieselben au) allerhand Manier abrichten 
 und zdumen soil, 1609, 2<\ cd., 1624; (2) Bericht vom Bergwerk, wit 
 mandieselben bauen und in guten Wohlstand bringen soil, 1617; (3) Aulico- 
 
 40
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 41 
 
 destroyed in the course of that 'struggle. Seckendorff, in his Vorrede, 
 praised the Ho)-Staat- und Regierungskunst; yet like the rest of 
 the author's writings it has no special scientific weight. Still his 
 chief cameralistic work stands, in riches of content and enlightened 
 judgment, as well as practical insight, far above the mass of theoreti- 
 cal political products, and forms an immediate preparation for the 
 flourishing period of German cameralistics inaugurated by Secken- 
 dorff 's Teutscher Fiirstenstaat. 
 
 The biography of Georg Obrecht is best epitomized in 
 Eisenhart's sketch: 1 
 
 Obrecht was bom in Strassburg in 1547, and died in the same 
 city in 1612. As a young man he studied in Paris. After escaping 
 the massacre of St. Bartholomew, which cost the loss of his library, 
 he went to Basel and obtained there the degree of Doctor of Laws 
 in 1574. In 1575 he was made Professor of Law in Strassburg, 
 and he retained the position to the end of his life. As the fleeting 
 glory of Wittenberg began to fade, Strassburg assumed the spiritual 
 leadership of Protestant Germany. Along with Giffen and Gotho- 
 fredus, it was chiefly Obrecht who founded the fame of the Strassburg 
 academy. He held various offices and dignities besides his professor- 
 ship. In 1604 he wa made a noble of the empire, and in 1609 he 
 received the title of Palgrave. 
 
 For the purposes of this book Obrecht is important as the 
 author of a single volume. 8 The chief significance of the five 
 
 politica oder Ho j -Stoats- und Regierungskunst, 1622-24, republished 
 1679. Apparently the last was identical with the book often referred 
 to under the title Teutscher Regentenstaat (vide Roscher, p. 116). There 
 are good reasons for the suspicion that Lohneyss has been mentioned by 
 many writers who neglected to state that their knowledge of him was at 
 second hand. 
 
 ' All. d. Bib., in loc. 
 
 * Fiinff under schiedliche Secreta Politica, von A nstellung, Erhaltung 
 und Vermehrung guter Policey, und von billicher, rechtmassiger und 
 nothwendiger, Erhohung eines jeden Regenten Jahrlichen Gejallen und 
 Einkommen. Allen Hohen und Nidern Obrigkeiten, besonders dess 
 Heiligen Romischen Reichs Standen, in diesen letzten und hochbetrangten
 
 42 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 monographs which make up the volume is disclosed at once 
 in the Preface by the author's son, Joannes Thomas Obrecht 
 ("J. C. et Comes Palatinus Caesareus"). As editor he gives 
 an account of the origin and purpose of the different mono- 
 graphs. Attention is piqued at once by the statement, "I 
 printed the book at my own expense, and secretly." 1 Accord- 
 ing to the editor's explanation, the essays are the outgrowth 
 and development of a central purpose, which is stated in con- 
 nection with the account of the first document. In a word, 
 the wars with the Turks had made the question of money to 
 pay expenses importunate. In the year 1590 Obrecht Sr. 
 had publicly discussed certain theses de principijs belli. In 
 that discussion he had maintained, among other things, that 
 in order to carry on successful war, and to defend their lands, 
 governments (Obrigkeiten) must be provided with an abun- 
 dance of money (mil einem starcken Gelt Nervo). He had also 
 announced that he would be ready, on a more favorable occa- 
 sion, to go into detail as to the ways in which this Nervus belli 
 might be obtained "through Christian, righteous, and proper 
 means." 
 
 A single remark of a relatively obscure writer would be 
 of little weight in supporting a general hypothesis. If there 
 were any doubt that this problem of ways and means for the 
 maintenance of military operations was desperate in every 
 German state, it would be necessary to set down this item for 
 what it is worth, and to go into the political records of Germany 
 for evidence of the fiscal conditions. This has been done so 
 
 Zciien zum besten. Hiebevor gestellet durch Ceorgium Obrechtum, J . C. 
 Sacri Palatij Comitem, Reipub. Argentinens. Advocatum, 6^ Academiae 
 Antecessorem. Hernacher im Jahr 1617 zum Truck befdrdert, und biss 
 ankero ingeheim gehalten: Nunmehr aber zu mdnnigliches Nutzen publi- 
 cirt, und mil nothwendigen Register -n verbesscrt. "Lectio lecta placet, 
 decies repetita placebit" (351 pp. with indexes). 
 
 1 "Auf mcincn Costcn, in geheim und sub secreto," Vorrede, p. i.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 43 
 
 fully, however, by German historians that no question remains 
 about the main facts. Our problem is to interpret the phe- 
 nomena of cameralism as one of the outgrowths of the times 
 in which these facts existed. Here then was a single theorist. 
 He confronted a situation which vexed all types of men theoret- 
 ically or practically concerned with questions of civic polity 
 in Germany. The key to the situation, as he saw it, was the 
 need of more money to strengthen the state for war, in particu- 
 lar, as well as for other purposes. With this as his clue, he 
 reasoned to the best of his ability, and the result was a scheme, 
 on paper, which may fairly be called a respectable first draft 
 of a programme which was later worked out in detail, and 
 quite in the same spirit, by the cameralists. Without pre- 
 judging the theories of later writers, and without generalizing 
 at this point about the extent to which the object of subsequent 
 thinkers was identical with that of Obrecht, we must define 
 his purpose clearly, and make it the explanation of his pro- 
 posals. In a word, he wanted to show how civic authorities 
 might solve their most importunate problem of command- 
 ing the sinews of war, and of providing for the more ordinary 
 expenses of government. His whole discussion centers about 
 this theme. 
 
 The son does not tell why it was thought necessary to keep 
 the monographs secret. Apparently the essential reason was 
 that such subjects were thought to be matters for the rulers 
 and the learned alone, and that either the monographs them- 
 selves were not sufficiently matured for publication, or that no 
 public existed, outside of a select circle, intelligent or respon- 
 sible enough to profit by reading them. So far as evidence 
 appears in the volume itself, Obrecht's theories contained 
 nothing calculated to arouse governmental hostility. At the 
 worst they might be regarded as well intended but visionary. 
 
 On the contrary, as the editor further states, Rudolf II 
 called for Obrecht's opinion on the fiscal problem, and he
 
 44 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 accordingly wrote the first monograph. This document con- 
 tains 59 pages, with an index of 6 pages, and is chiefly in Latin. 1 
 
 It is not clear whether the editor means to imply that his 
 father's further opinion was demanded from high quarters, 
 or whether the above occasion spurred him to further study. 
 At all events the account continues to the effect that Obrecht 
 diligently searched the Politicorum scripta, so far as they were 
 available, and tested them by the Word of God, in order to 
 learn which doctrines were to be rejected, and which, as pre- 
 cious pearl and gems, should be loyally retained, and by 
 the grace of God so set forth and applied that no one could 
 have a grievance against them. The outcome of this study 
 was the second monograph. 2 
 
 Of this Bedencken the editor affirms that it was calculated 
 to inspire confidence, both in rulers and subjects, on the one 
 hand that the proposed means would be sufficient, and on 
 the other hand that the demands of the government would not 
 be unreasonable. 
 
 Obrecht, however, did not fully trust his own judgment 
 about such important matters. He did not venture to call the 
 
 1 Its special title reads: Georgii Obrechti, etc. Discursus Bellico- 
 politicus. Imictissimo et A ugustissimo Principi ac Domino, Dn. Rudoipho 
 Laudatissimae Memoriae. II Romanorum Imperatori, Anno M. DC. 
 I V. ab A uthore humilima animi devotione oblatus, in quo quomodo advur- 
 sus Turcicum Tyrannum bellum commode geri possit, quant jelicissime 
 ostenditur. 
 
 2 Beginning with the initials of the ascription, "Auspice Deo Triuno 
 Optimo Maximo," the title-page reads: " Politisch Bedencken und Dis- 
 curs: Von Verbesscrung Land unnd Leut, Anrichtung guter Policey. Und 
 jurnemblich von nutzlicher Erledigung grosser Aussgaben, und billicher 
 Vermehrung tines jeden Regenten und Oberherren Jdhrlichen Gejallen 
 und Einkommen." This monograph occupies 135 pages, without index. 
 Its main propositions are in German, and they are fortified by copious 
 quotations in Latin from the Politicorum scripta, the same ranging from 
 legendary sayings of Servius Tullius, to dicta of contemporary authorities 
 in canonical and civil law.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 45 
 
 proposal complete until he had consulted, either in person or 
 in correspondence, during several years, "under pledge of 
 silence," eminent theologians, "and highly experienced states- 
 men." With this assistance the Discurs was finished in 1609.' 
 The third document in the series is in form an independent 
 monograph, but the editor says it was drawn from the Bedencken 
 and was intended to show more plainly how the ideas in the 
 former treatise could be applied. It was finished in 1610. 
 It contains 46 pages. 2 
 
 1 There is a discrepancy of no material importance for our pur pose, be- 
 tween the younger Obrecht and Thomasius with reference to this mono- 
 graph. The latter states (Osse, p. 87) that the Politisches Bedencken was 
 printed at Strassburg in the year 1606; that is, three years earlier than it 
 was completed, if the former is correct. Thomasius adds that a copy of 
 this first edition was in his possession. This appears to make him a com- 
 petent witness so far, especially as he quotes enough of the remainder of 
 the title to make the identity of the monograph rather certain. From 
 the context, however, it is plain that Thomasius had never seen the edition 
 of 1617, in which the document in question was virtually the second 
 chapter. Of that edition he says, upon the authority of Deckher, "descrip- 
 
 tis Adespotis, p.m. 335 The other, presumably somewhat enlarged, 
 
 appeared in the year 1617." He further states that copies of the latter 
 edition, at some date which he does not mention, sold for one hundred 
 Gulden, To account for this he quotes that writer as follows: "Testata 
 est Republ. Argentinensis, adferendo omnis exemplaria suae Cancellariae 
 nolle se consilia civis fui, quae illi in proxi pessime cessere, omnibus palam 
 fieri." Thomasius concludes that this "confiscation" was the reason 
 for the scarcity price. The inference is plausible enough, but the only 
 reason that can be surmised for calling in the book is similar to parents' 
 motives for keeping some books which they find profitable for themselves 
 out of reach of their children. 
 
 A little later in the Preface, the editor says of the third document 
 in the volume, the Aerarium Sanctum, "so biss data niemanden communi- 
 ciret worden." The date referred to must mean that on which the collec- 
 tion was published, 1617. 
 
 3 The title and general outline indicate its scope, viz., Constitutio 
 von nothwendiger und niitzlicher Anstellung eines Aerarij Sancti. Durch 
 welches jurnemblich die Bejorderung und Erhaltung gemeiner Wohljahrt
 
 46 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Having gone SP far in his studies, Obrecht discovered 
 that something more was necessary. He concluded that the 
 entire life of sovereigns and subjects must be conducted in 
 accordance with the dictates of thrift and morality, or the means 
 would still be lacking to provide the necessary revenues. Accord- 
 ingly he harked back to Roman exploitation of "Censum et 
 Censuram," and he elaborated a scheme of Policey, partly 
 prompted by his conception of the Roman system, partly 
 appropriating contemporary police arrangements, and partly 
 a speculative proposal. The significant point is that the animus 
 of the whole undertaking was the proposal to devise meam 
 by which adequate revenues might be assured to the stale. At 
 the same time, and this is a trait that runs through the whole 
 cameralistic regime, the total morale of the people was to be 
 improved, primarily to be sure for state purposes, but none the 
 less improvement of the physical, mental, and moral life con- 
 ditions of all the people was an avowed and prominent part 
 
 gesucht und erlangt wird; Beschrieben und angeslelll von Georgia Obrechlo, 
 etc. 
 
 I. Ein sondere Constitutio und Ordnung, dc ludiciario Vectigali. 
 
 II. Von sechs Ordnungen, in welchen die bona Fisci, dem Aerario 
 Sanclo zugeeignet werden: i. Ordinalio, von oedcn und uncrbuwten 
 Giitcren; 2. Ordinatio, de Bonis Vacantibus: 3. Ordinalio de Bonis 
 perditis, &* proderelicto habitis, item de bonis peregrinorum, er* Thesauris; 
 4. Ordinatio, de Bonis Ereptitiis; 5. Ordinatio, de Bonis Damnatorum 
 ct P rotcriptorum; 6. Ordinatio, de Bonis incestas Nuplias conlrahentium; 
 
 III. Von vier Ordnungen, durch welchc ralione bonorum subditorum 
 das Aera.ri.um Sanctum mit vielen starcken Jahrlichcn Gefallen, und 
 Einkommen versehen wird: 7. Ordinalio, de Bonis subditorum in ultima 
 aliqua voluntate Aerario Sancto relictis; 8. Ordinatio, de Bonis Subditorum, 
 qui in ultima aliqua voluntate, extraneis personis aliquid reliqucrunt: 
 9. Ordinatio, de Bonis subditorum, qui :ine herede lineae ascendentis 6* 
 descendentis decedunt, 6 in Linea collaterals tantum ultra septimum 
 gradum heredes post se relinquunt: 10. Ordinatio, von eincr nothwen- 
 digen, und hochnutzlichen Fewr-Ordnung. 
 
 IV. De Fine huius Constitutions, und wahin obcrkliirte red it MS 
 konnen, und sollen verwendet werden.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 47 
 
 of the programme. It was not stated by the cameralists (Justi 
 possibly excepted) as an end-end. It was emphasized with 
 cumulative insistence as a means-end, and this factor became 
 one of the distinguishing elements in German polity. 1 The 
 fifth and last document or "secretum" in the series is referred 
 to as the Aerarium Liberorum. Ostensibly it was a plan of 
 savings and endowment insurance for children. The author 
 avows quite frankly, however, that in essence it is a detail in 
 his fiscal scheme. In a word, parents were to lay by, in the 
 hands of the government, certain regular amounts, to receive 
 interest at 6 per cent., and to be paid to the children named 
 
 1 The so-called "Constitution," in which this scheme of Policey is 
 outlined, contains only 31 pages. Its title-page is as follows: 
 
 Ein sondere Policey-Ordnung, und Constitution, durch ivelche ein 
 jeder Magistrates, vermittels besonderen angestellten Deputaten, jederzeit 
 in seiner Regierung, eine gewisse Nachrichlung haben mag, I. Wie es 
 gleichsam mil seiner ganzen Policey, als eines Polilischen Leibs, und alien 
 desselberen Gliederen, den Underthanen beschaffen. II. Wie gemelter 
 Policey, derselben Gliederen, und Administration, auff: und zunemmen 
 zubejurderen, ab: und undergang zuverhuten. So dann zunt III. Wie 
 (inch die gemeine Wolfarth, so auss vorgedachten drey en Stilcken herkompt, 
 zuvermehren, und zu crhalten seyen, Allen Oberheiten, in diesen letzten, 
 verhehrten, und gejahrlichen Zeiten, hochnotwendig, und in viel Weg 
 niitzlich samt einer kurtzen Information, und Erhlttrung, auch eineni 
 A ppendice. 
 
 The "Information" and " Erkldrung," together with the Appendix, 
 occupy 32 pages. The inscription of the former reads: "Kurtze Infor- 
 mation und Erkliirung. In welchen die Precia Inscriptionum bestimbt, 
 und die Nutzbarkeiten welchc auss den inscriptionibus, inscriptionnm 
 Document is 6* Albis, wie auch aus Anordnung der Deputaten, sowol 
 privalim, als publice zucrlangcn seind, kiirtzlich deducirt werden, Zu 
 bcsserem Verstand, unnd Nachrichtung, voriger Policey Ordnung, und 
 Constitution angestellt." The special title of the Appendix is: "Von 
 underschiedenen Inscriplionum Documentis." 
 
 The passage in which the editor accounts for the writing of the 
 Constitution contains so many side-lights upon the impulses of the docu- 
 ment, which would disappear in a translation, that it would have been 
 quoted in full in an appendix if spare had permitted.
 
 48 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as beneficiaries on arrival at a certain age. If, however, a 
 child died before reaching the specified age, both principal and 
 interest should belong to the government. Since, however, 
 this forfeiture would occur only in consequence of "a special 
 dispensation of God," the editor seriously argues that the 
 scheme, for which he might have quoted Italian precedents, 
 ought not to be considered inequitable, but rather on the whole 
 as favorable to parents as to the government. 1 
 
 Beyond this general analysis of the book, our purpose calls 
 merely for a few notes about incidentals in its contents. Con- 
 sidering the volume then as an exhibit of a coherent scheme of 
 fiscal administration, we may abstract certain items of evidence 
 bearing upon tendencies in fundamental political theory which 
 the scheme exhibits. 
 
 After a brief address to the emperor, the chapter " Billico- 
 Politicus" opens the discussion with a highly pedantic intro- 
 duction upon the topic : Quae ad Constitutionem Belli Turcici 
 necessaria sint. This is like stopping when the house is afire, 
 to settle the metaphysical question, What is necessary to 
 constitute a house afire? The author nevertheless gravely 
 enumerates as the elements in the situation: "Jus; Summus 
 Magistrates; Hostes; Justa Causa; et Legitima Belli Sus- 
 ceptio" In ten pages these implications are expanded, and 
 through brief discussion of the "mature deliberation" which 
 must precede war, the way is paved for the actual problem of 
 the tract, viz., enumeration of all available sources of revenue. 
 Without entering into any of the technical details scheduled, 
 
 1 The monograph contains 56 pages, including an Appendix of 10 
 pages, and in addition an Index of 8 pages. The title-page reads: 
 Constitutio und Ordnung. Von eincm Hochniilzlichen Aerario Liber o- 
 rum, in welches, von den Elteren, allerhand Sum-men Celts, jurnemblich 
 ihren Newgebornen Kinder en, und in eventum ihnen selbs, auch der Obrig- 
 keit, und Gemeiner Wohljahrt turn besten angelegt werden: Sampt aller- 
 hand Erblarungen, und sweyen Kinder Rechnungen. Beschrieben unnd 
 angestellt von Georgia Obrechto etc.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 49 
 
 we may notice that the sources of revenue named are classed 
 under two general heads: first, those which impose a burden 
 upon the persons supplying the revenue; second, those that 
 impose no burden. 1 This distinction often reappears in the 
 cameralistic books. In general it does not correspond with 
 the ideas which would be attached to the terms today. A 
 " burdensome" tax was one which impaired the citizen's means 
 of maintaining his standard of life. A "non-burdensome" 
 tax was one which left the means of livelihood intact, but might 
 theoretically absorb all increments of profit. 2 
 
 A single observation will suffice in connection with the 
 second class of resources. The author names first among 
 the fiscal means which impose no burden upon the persons who 
 supply the revenue, "bona oikonomia." In the text he uses 
 the Greek form otKovofjitav. He explains that he means by 
 it good administration in general. That is, all functionaries 
 are to exhibit fidelity and diligence, they are not to incur need- 
 less expenses, they are to exercise frugality and parsimony, 
 and thus to have in hand the means with which to meet unfore- 
 seen demands. This observation is necessary, because a 
 cardinal datum for interpretation of the cameralists is that they 
 did not have the idea, and consequently did not have a word 
 
 1 I. De necessariarum rerum comparatione: &c. praecipue de modis, 
 quibus cum onere subditorum pecunia comparari possit. II. De modis 
 quibus sine onere subditorum pecunia compariri possit: et praecipue de 
 bona Oeconomia et de venditione vel oppigneratione bonorum. 
 
 9 We may merely name the four classes of resources which the author 
 mentions under the first head, viz., (i) imposition of taxes; (2) extra- 
 ordinary taxes; (3) "51 annul reditus atque census, sique porloria et vecti- 
 galia augentur" (and without entering into the question of the precise 
 connotation of these terms at the date of the book, the author's illustrations 
 permit us to render them in general, income, property, and poll taxes, 
 customs and excise); (4) certain ordinances (constitutiones) which may 
 yield something to the treasury. In a sense the second monograph, and 
 in a much more literal sense the third, fourth, and fifth papers are elabo- 
 rations of the author's meaning under this head.
 
 50 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 for "economics" in the sense attached to that term in nineteenth- 
 century English usage. In this early instance, "bona oikonomia" 
 evidently contained the rudiments, but only the rudiments, 
 of the concept later represented by such a term as Staats- 
 haushaltung. In the second half of the eighteenth century, 
 as we shall see, the Greek term was often reserved for agricul- 
 tural management only. In the intermediate period its mean- 
 ing was unprecise. Our concern at this point is merely to 
 indicate the inchoate condition of the stage of administrative 
 theory represented by Obrecht, and in particular to put on 
 record this early use of a term which, in translations into English, 
 has been the innocent occasion of cardinal misjudgments of 
 essential factors in the development of German social theories. 
 
 The remaining titles in the monograph refer to details of 
 the fiscal resources of the time which yield nothing for our 
 purpose. 1 
 
 The second document opens with a series of specifications 
 which picture most vividly the desperate financial straits of 
 contemporary German rulers, from the emperor down to the 
 minor princes. Incidentally the author furnishes cumulative 
 evidence that the "biological analogy" was as serviceable a 
 working tool for him as for some of the nineteenth-century 
 sociologists. 2 The exhibit and the estimate of money as the 
 
 1 This will be evident from headings of the remaining subdivisions: 
 viz., " DC novorum Acccptorum et rcdituum constitutione: et praecipue 
 de modis quibus mediante justitiae administratione accepta augeri 
 possunt." 
 
 44 De modis quibus sine lustitiae administratione accepta atque 
 reditus absquc onerc sulxlitorum augeri possunt." 
 
 44 DC Commeatu Pabuli et Krumcnti, item de armis, ct dc ijs rebus, 
 quac ad arma pertinent comparandis." 
 
 " De Praccedentibus ad ronstitutioncm belli accommodandis." 
 
 2 Thus, "Sintemal wie in einem Natiirlithen Lcib, die nervi prima 
 animalis sensus et motus instrumenta, auch causa actionum seind: also 
 in carport civili, oder in einer Refiublica, als in einem Ftirstenthumb,
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 51 
 
 vital force of governments lead to succinct statement of the pur- 
 pose of the pamphlet, viz., to call the attention of rulers and 
 governors to the necessity of diligent reflection about these 
 things, and of adopting the means to be proposed, or better 
 ones, in the interest of themselves and their subjects. The 
 terms in which the author further urges these claims first reflect 
 very plainly the inchoate, undifferentiated, and unorganized 
 stage of civic administration in German states, and secondly, 
 they contain a touch which marks an early form of a moral 
 consideration not at that time very effective, but later of co-or- 
 dinate rank with the requirements for offensive and defensive 
 strength against external enemies. In a word Obrecht argues 
 that without money properly to pay civil employees, rulers 
 cannot protect the people against the injustices of their own 
 servants. He observes in this connection that "although there 
 are to be sure many magistri, as Bodinus calls them," who 
 are always well equipped with means of raising money, yet 
 usually these means tend not merely to burden the subjects 
 but completely to strip them. No one appears to point out 
 means which would be just and lucrative, and at the same time 
 serviceable for all sorts of improvement. He proposes, there- 
 fore, to present a scheme which would satisfy these require- 
 ments. 
 
 The body of the essay is divided on the lines drawn in the 
 previous paper, viz., first, means for raising revenues by bur- 
 
 Graffschafft, Herrschafft, und in fiirnemmen Statten, seind Gelt und 
 Gut gleichsam die nervi, und instrumenta, ohn wclche kein Respublica, 
 angericht, gebessert, und so wol zu Friedens Zeit, als in Kriegs Empc- 
 rungen, unnd anderen hochbetrangten Zustanden, erhalten werden kan, 
 etc." A little later the figure continues: "Dann welcher gestalt Gelt 
 und Gut nit weniger Reipublicae von nohten seind, als im Menschlichen 
 Leib seind die nervi senlienles, welche von dem Him entspringen sollen,' 
 ebner massen Gelt und Gut gebiihrlicher weiss zuerlangen, gehort einer 
 jeden Oberkeit zu, die gleichsam in Republica, als in corpore civili, 
 anstatt Hirns ist, und hat soldi corpus vollkommlich zu regieren, etc."
 
 5* THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 dening the subjects ; second, means which would not burden 
 the subjects. This whole range of governmental problems 
 is put under the head, "Oeconomica administratio." In gen- 
 eral the scheme is merely an amplification of ideas contained 
 in the earlier essay. The specific propositions do not concern 
 us, but the conditions which were to be met and the status of 
 reasoning about them may be somewhat more approximately 
 understood by reference to the titles of chapters. 1 
 
 If this were a history of administrative technique, or of 
 administrative technology, Obrecht's book would furnish many 
 details which would mark a stage in the process. As we are 
 in search of the fundamental conceptions and ultimate pur- 
 poses of cameralism, these details are interesting only in so 
 far as they bear testimony about those conceptions and pur- 
 poses. Not because they immediately yield much information 
 on these points, but for use later in connection with other evi- 
 dence, we may note a few items of more than merely administra- 
 tive significance. 
 
 In the first place, Obrecht seems to have understood in a 
 general way the impolicy of debasing the coinage. Thus he 
 says (p. 108): 
 
 That today certain mammon brothers, in search of selfish gain, 
 seek all sorts of private advantage with the different coins, that they 
 diminish and weaken the same in weight and value [Schrott und Korn] 
 is directly contrary to all laws, also to various edicts of the Holy 
 Empire with respect to coinage, and brings with it beyond all doubt 
 the curse of God and temporal punishment. 
 
 In the second place, Obrecht represents a stage and type 
 of political thinking in which the traditional taboo of commerce 
 and trade as pursuits for members of the nobility began to be 
 called in question. Thus, after citing a number of opinions 
 on the conventional side, he asserts (p. in): 
 
 1 These were to have appeared in an appendix.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 53 
 
 I however regard commerce as in a way necessary for a republic; 
 and so necessary, indeed, that it cannot be separated from the body 
 of the republic. For merchants are in the body of the republic, as 
 
 it were, attendants, carriers, feet, etc consequently, I hold it 
 
 as more honorable than despicable when noble and high persons 
 GMTy on trade for the sake of lightening the burdens of their subjects, 
 and of discharging public obligations with the least difficulty. 
 
 To this item should be added a later passage, viz. (p. 122): 
 
 A ruler and overlord should make it an object of diligent atten- 
 tion that in his towns and country regions, so far as opportunity 
 allows, all sorts of traders should be located. For the traders not 
 only bring into the country all sorts of necessary wares, at their own 
 cost and risk, but they also draw out of the country those wares of 
 
 which the country has a superabundance But a ruler should 
 
 look out for the following four points: I, that the merchants should 
 carry on no forbidden traffic, nor should they bring forbidden wares 
 into the country, nor carry them out to forbidden places; II, that 
 no scarcity, nor hindrance of the subjects in disposing of their wares, 
 should be brought about by the merchants; III, that they should 
 make no harmful and usurious bargains but their transactions should 
 all tend to the common advantage, and not to the injury of their 
 neighbors; IV, that the merchants should be protected against all 
 unjust violence, for this is to the advantage not only of the merchants 
 themselves, but of the subjects in general. 
 
 In the third place, Obrecht schedules encouragement of 
 navigation as a means of enlarging a state's revenues. He 
 seems to have no suspicion of questions about "balance of 
 trade," but pleads artlessly for "provision of vessels tha* may 
 bring all sorts of goods and wares from foreign ports, that the 
 same may be sold again." 
 
 Fourthly, he proposes advances from the princely chest, 
 to merchants who bring in foreign goods. The chief reason 
 for this proposal seems to be that the interest on the advances 
 would be a considerable source of profit to the prince. 
 
 Fifth, Obrecht recommends purchase by government of
 
 54 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 certain food stuffs, wine, etc., to be held as a resource against 
 possible scarcity prices, and then to be sold at reasonable rates, 
 to the advantage both of government and subjects. 
 
 Promotion of artisanship is also urged, and for similar 
 reasons. At the same time dangers from improper combina- 
 tions of hand-workers are suggested, and severe punishments 
 for misusing such organization are recommended. In connec- 
 tion with the advice that, to promote trade and crafts, fairs 
 and markets should be arranged, a bare hint of the later popu- 
 lation doctrine appears, viz. (p. 127): 
 
 And it is beyond all doubt that when all the above is set in opera- 
 tion with zeal, it will be to the advantage of rulers and overlords in 
 this respect further, that they will have more populous and belter 
 appointed towns and territories, and that in consequence the various 
 revenues will be strongly increased and improved. 
 
 Disapproval of debts to foreigners, which later became a 
 cameralistic dogma, appears here as a mild preference: thus 
 (p. 129): 
 
 If a ruler is burdened with many and heavy foreign interest 
 charges .... it is advisable that he raise the amount from his 
 subjects who have loanable money, and pay the interest to them 
 rather than to foreigners, for in this way expenses and losses may 
 be avoided. 
 
 The first paragraph of the chapter, "Constitutio Aerarij 
 Sancti," furnishes another direct testimony, the stronger 
 because it was inadvertent, as to the central purpose which 
 was molding administrative theory and policy. It is a pas- 
 sage which distinctly locates the moving springs of cameralism. 
 Translated according to the spirit rather than the letter it is 
 as follows: 
 
 Since it is known to all of good understanding, and an open secret, 
 and attested by daily experience, that in these last troublous times 
 there is scarcely a government whose ordinary resources are not 
 daily and hourly exhausted, and therefore scarcely one can at all
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 55 
 
 times be happily administered and maintained in constant security 
 by means of the ordinary revenues; but on the contrary unless by 
 the side of these customary revenues a government institutes, with 
 the utmost care, through all sorts of just and righteous means, a 
 special and extraordinary treasury, such a government and Policey, 
 at a time of unforeseen war, revolts, and other dangers, will stand 
 unprotected and open to pillage and enemies, and in the presence of 
 such danger and violence it can neither be protected nor administered. 
 And although by extraordinary efforts under such circumstances 
 money may be raised, yet if the money is collected, and the imminent 
 danger is averted, yet another danger immediately follows, namely, 
 that the growing burden of interest charges will ruin the state, as was 
 the case with the Greek republics, and especially Lacedaemonia, 
 which were ruined by borrowing from the Persian and Egyptian 
 kings. Hence it is necessary to show how these dangers may be 
 overcome by an extraordinary treasury. 
 
 As we shall attempt to show, this problem of ways and 
 means to cover the expanding fiscal needs of the state was the 
 central purpose which gave peculiar character to cameralism. 
 All the incidental tenets of this technology, whether they were 
 the opinions of exceptional writers or substantially the con- 
 sensus of all, must be interpreted by their connection with 
 this main interest. 
 
 This particular Constitutio is partly in the form of an ordi- 
 nance to be promulgated by rulers: partly in the ordinary 
 essay form on the merits of certain fiscal propositions. It 
 contains nothing further in principle necessary for our purpose. 
 
 In the fourth document, Policey Ordnung, Obrecht displays 
 foresight which entitles him to higher rank in the rolls of Ger- 
 man political writers than the historians of his own country 
 have assigned. In general, subsequent events conformed 
 to his views, and the Policey system afterward developed, to 
 which we must give so much attention in later portions of this 
 book, was entirely contained in principle in his proposals. 
 Without attempting to prove this in detail, we may briefly note
 
 56 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the standpoint from which his suggestions issued and the aims 
 which he had in view. 
 
 In the Introduction the author points out that all publicists 
 have had regard for two considerations, and have urged them 
 upon magistrates, viz., first, the census and censorship, "the 
 fulcra and pillars of politics, and the supports on which all 
 Policey must rest;" second, "reliable information and sufficient 
 science possessed by every magistrate concerning the structure 
 and organization of the Policey." 
 
 As to the first of these points, Obrecht states that existing 
 administration makes use of census and censorship, yet in 
 no adequate fashion; indeed, he holds that if it were possible 
 the forms in use should be altogether abolished, and more 
 adequate systems substituted. He concedes that such abrupt 
 change would be impracticable, and in the case of the census par- 
 ticularly recommends that the methods now in use be retained. 
 
 With reference to the censorship, however, he declares 
 that its policy may be essentially either preventive or punitive. 
 Just here Obrecht's foresight is exceptional. He declares that 
 police programmes of his time know nothing of preventive 
 policies. The chief emphasis of the document falls therefore 
 on the outline of a police policy calculated to improve the 
 morale of the people, and thus not merely to diminish vice and 
 crime, but to raise the general efficiency of the population. 
 Without asking the question here whether this is a proper 
 function of governments, we have to observe at the outset that 
 (icrman political theory progressively assumed that such 
 guardianship and promotion of public morals formed a neces- 
 sary part of governmental responsibility. Obrecht was accord- 
 ingly a pioneer among post-Reformation thinkers in striking 
 out a path which became one of the trunk lines of later 
 administrative theory. 1 
 
 1 The introduction is such a vivid reflection of the situation within 
 which Obrecht wrote that it would have been reproduced in full if space 
 had permitted.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 57 
 
 The Preface to the proposed Constitution, which is drafted 
 in the form of a royal rescript, reiterates the underlying pur- 
 pose of the proposition in terms which a translation cannot 
 properly represent, but the substance is approximately this: 
 
 The following Police Order and Constitution, with its seven 
 Sanctions [Sanctionibus] is ordained by us especially that we may 
 every year, and as far as practicable at all times, have reliable infor- 
 mation how matters stand with all our subjects, young and old, rich 
 and poor, in all parts of our jurisdiction and territory, and also how 
 matters stand with our whole Policey, and all of its branches, and 
 how, in this later wholly perverted time, they may be protected 
 against ruin, and may be sustained in constant integrity; and how 
 we may bring it about, after ascertaining all the facts, that our sub- 
 jects may rightly, well and usefully bring up their children, and 
 themselves lead a Christian, worthy life, and thus so conduct 
 themselves that they may be to their children, to us their divinely 
 appointed rulers, to their neighbor, and to the common weal, a 
 blessing and an honor, to their own temporal and eternal advantage. 
 
 The first Sanction covered a system of registration of births, 
 both legitimate and illegitimate; the second, registration and 
 guardianship of orphans and widows; the third, registration 
 and supervision of young men "nearer their twentieth than 
 their twenty-third year;" the fourth, registration and con- 
 tinued observation of all other male persons, above the twenty- 
 third year, "in order that we may have direct knowledge 
 of the character of all these persons under our whole govern- 
 ment:" the fifth, registration of marriage intentions; 1 the 
 
 1 For the reason parenthetically assigned: Because " Matrimonia" 
 are "von den Politicis recht und wol principia Urbiunt, seminaria Rerum- 
 publicarum, et jundamenta Rei familiaris genandt werden." In this 
 connection the plan contemplates the appointment of officials who should 
 censor the wedding customs, particularly with reference to extravagant 
 outlays. One of the ends in view was to prevent squandering of the 
 savings with which housekeeping must be set up. The word here used 
 for that idea is worth our notice. The phrase is: "auss welchem sie 
 ihre Otconomi anstellen sollen."
 
 58 THF CAMERALISTS 
 
 sixth, registration of intentions of immigrants to become citi- 
 zens, and of other cases of change of residence by strangers 
 or subjects; seventh, registration of deaths, including certain 
 related details, particularly concerning surviving heirs. 
 
 The explanations subjoined to this third paragraph, or 
 chapter, take up in turn the seven "sanctions," and propose 
 details, beginning with the price to be paid for each type of 
 registration, and including arguments intended to show the 
 benefits that would accrue, first to individuals, then to the pub- 
 lic, from adoption of the programme. For example, we find at 
 >nce (p. 215) the suggestion that each child registered under 
 the first "sanction," should receive ein Geburtsbrieff; obviously 
 an early, if not the earliest proposal of a detail of police tech- 
 nique which later became a matter of course. 
 
 On the side of the public advantages of the proposed pro- 
 gramme, Obrecht urges, still under the device of a supposed 
 ordinance or rescript (pp. 229 ff.), that, at all times, both in war 
 and peace, governments would be able to administer more in- 
 telligently; they could maintain the common welfare (Gemeine 
 Wolf art) with more intelligence and energy; they could also 
 come to the assistance of the subjects more directly and effi- 
 ciently; they could, fourth, through the fidelity of the various 
 sorts of Deputaten contemplated in the programme, in many 
 ways promote the common advantage (Gemeinen \utz) better 
 than without such organization. 
 
 It cannot be said that this final schedule of reasons for adopt- 
 ing the programme is likely to affect the modern reader as very 
 convincing. The underlying fiscal purpose, viz., the collection 
 of fees from the different registrations, is too obvious, while 
 the advantages urged are both vague and problematical. The 
 same is more evidently true of the insurance of children pro- 
 posed in the last document, on which further comment is 
 unnecessary. 1 These things do not, however, diminish the 
 1 Vide above, p. 47.
 
 CIVICS OF OBRECHT 59 
 
 evidential value of such a writer as Obrecht. Whether he 
 actually exerted much influence or little, either upon adminis- 
 trative organization or upon academic theory, his book reflects 
 beginnings of theoretical and practical tendencies in ways 
 which make their essential impulses much more evident than 
 they appear in their later more complex variations.
 
 CHAPTER IV 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 
 
 Veil Ludwig von Seckendorff was born in 1626 and died 
 in 1692. His most persistent influence was exerted through 
 two books, Der Teutsche Fursten Staat, and Der Christen 
 Stoat. 1 For our purposes, these books, rather than details of 
 Seckendorff 's life, are all-important. Enough of his biography 
 may be noted, however, to indicate the interests for which 
 he spoke. In childhood, Seckendorff was taught at home, 
 while his father was most of the time in the wars. He was 
 later sent to school in Coburg and Miihlhausen. In 1636 he 
 went with his mother to Erfurt, where the foundations of his 
 more mature knowledge were laid. He is said to have com- 
 posed Latin orations at the age of eleven. He was a companion 
 of two Wlirttemburg princes in 1639. He attracted the atten- 
 tion of Herzog Ernst of Gotha, who sent him to the Gotha 
 Gymnasium in 1640. Soon after this his father was beheaded 
 on the charge of intended defection to the emperor. The 
 family was provided for, however, in recognition of the father's 
 previous services. The son went the same year to the Univer- 
 sity of Strassburg, where for several years he studied philosophy, 
 jurisprudence, and history. In 1645, on his way to continue 
 study at Erfurt, he visited the court of Gotha. This was the 
 turning-point of his life. The duke gave him 200 Thaler for 
 a visit to the Low Countries, and on his return appointed him 
 Hof junker and superintendent of the ducal library. In these 
 positions his chief duty was to summarize selected books and 
 recite their contents to the duke in his leisure hours, on Sundays 
 
 1 Instead of reducing the various forms of these titles to a single 
 style, the usage of the passages from which they have been cited has 
 been followed. 
 
 60
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SKCKEXDORFF 61 
 
 or during journeys. In 1652, in his twenty-seventh year, he 
 became Hof- und Justitienrath. The first of his important 
 books, the Fiirsten Stoat, was written in 1655. "It may be 
 regarded as a sort of handbook of German civil law, and was 
 valued as such; on the other hand, it had the special approval 
 of contemporaries, because it contained a systematic arrange- 
 ment of rules and prescriptions for a well-regulated govern- 
 mental administration, based on the model of the existing 
 government of Gotha." Seckendorff was soon promoted to 
 the position of Geheimer Hof- und Kammerrath im Verwaltungs- 
 dienst, and in 1664 to the highest dignity in the duchy, that 
 of chancellor. His services were especially valued in finance, 
 but he was also a power in political, ecclesiastical, and educa- 
 tional reform. He collaborated (1666) with the scholars Arto- 
 poeus and Bockler on a Compendium historiae ecdesiasticae, 
 intended primarily for the Gymnasium in Gotha, but after- 
 ward widely used. In 1664 he accepted the call of Duke 
 Moritz of Sachsenzeitz, as Kanzler und Consistorial-Prasident. 
 He retained the position till the death of Moritz in 1681, then 
 resigned all his responsibilities except that of Landschafts- 
 director i~on Altenburg, and retired to his estate, Menselwitz, 
 near Altenburg. The Christen Staat (1685) did much to pro- 
 mote the tendency toward pietism, although the author was 
 not himself strictly a pietist. In reply to the Jesuit de Maim- 
 bourg (Histoire du Lutheranism, Paris, 1680) Seckendorff 
 wrote in an incredibly short time a work which must still be 
 consulted by all historians of the Reformation. 1 He arrived 
 at Halle, as chancellor of the new university, October 31, 1692, 
 but died December 18 following.* 
 
 1 Contmentarius histori'.us el apologeticus de Lutheranismo sen de 
 reformatione, 1688-92. 
 
 Th. Kolde, in AU. d. Bib , title "Seckendorff," and Roscher, inloc. 
 This account should be compared with Se< kendorff's own recollections 
 in the dedication of Der Chrislenstat.
 
 62 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Seckendorff s close relations with Duke Ernst of Gotha 
 were prime factors in his career. Ernst was eminent among 
 the petty princes of his century. His reputation for piety 
 was popularized in the nickname "Praying Ernst," and he 
 was later known as "Ernst the Pious." His ecclesiastical 
 laws have been called a complete course in pastoral theology. 
 He was the father of twenty-two children, and in the manage- 
 ment of his household and of his state he was regarded as an 
 edifying example. Seckendorff systematized Duke Ernst's 
 scheme of life. He virtually composed Ernst's practices as 
 a manager into a didactic treatise. According to the Preface 
 of the second edition of Der Fursten Slaat, his original intention 
 was to treat only of rules for a single German principality, 
 evidently Gotha, but his plan was afterward extended to include 
 all German states of the secularized Protestant class. 
 
 Roscher regards it as a second cardinal fact in Seckendorff's 
 career that, shortly before his death, he gave up the life of 
 retirement upon his estate, to accept the chancellorship of the 
 new University of Halle. The reasons for Roscher's opinion 
 that this change was significant are not apparent. It was a 
 generation after his most important book appeared, and six 
 years after publication of the volume next in importance. Such 
 migrations were by no means exceptional, and in this instance 
 nothing can be inferred from the incident which has the slight- 
 est bearing upon Seckendorff in the only relation in which he 
 was significant for Roscher's professed purpose, viz., inter- 
 pretation of the history of German economics. This emphasis 
 upon a merely personal detail is characteristic. Roscher's 
 service to science was principally in assembling details. He 
 was much less successful in estimating their value. 
 
 Seckendorff is classified by Roscher as conservative, in the 
 sense of adhering to the old ways, while he was liberal, in the 
 sense of thinking freely, if the phrase may be accommodated 
 to the rigors of his time. He was not attracted by the innova-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 63 
 
 tions in the Zeitgeist of his period, but clung to the traditions 
 of the generations before the Thirty Years' War. In this 
 respect he was in nearly the same antithesis with leading pub- 
 licists and mercantilists of his time, that is, to the theories 
 of Leopold I and of the Great Elector, in which Sully stood to 
 Colbert, or in the eighteenth century, Justus Moser to the politi- 
 cal scientists of the time of Frederick the Great and Joseph II. 
 
 Moreover, Seckendorfl was attached to the Reformation 
 type of piety, and in spite of the tendency of the time in the 
 other direction, he gave his political doctrines a strong religious 
 shading. 
 
 Roscher further characterizes Seckendorff as "in civic life 
 no more an absolutist than in court life he was a sycophant." 
 This is true in the sense that he dared to regard the will of 
 God as paramount to the will of the prince; but it is not true 
 in the sense that he believed any power on earth was justified 
 in holding the prince to account for his acts. In other words, 
 political theory had virtually outgrown the conception that the 
 will of the prince was the highest moral law, but it still retained 
 the conception that the will of the prince was the ultimate 
 civic law. Seckendorff was consequently the mouthpiece of 
 the type of German state in the middle of the seventeenth 
 century in which the assumption was fundamental. We shall 
 speak of this as quasi-absolutism. Absolutism in the strictest 
 sense it was not. From the point of view of modern democracy 
 it was virtual absolutism. That is, it was a theory that no 
 one but God had a right to discipline the prince, because he 
 was responsible only to that divine power by whose grace he 
 had been made sovereign over a defined group of men. 1 
 
 We have then to deal, not with the first, but with one of 
 the early doctrinaires and officiating administrators of the type 
 of state thus indicated. Their task was to systematize the 
 
 1 For confirmation of this judgment vide below, pp. 73 ff.; cf. doc- 
 trine of Schroder, pp. 137 ff.
 
 64 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 administrative routine of that type of state. The theory and 
 the application were not so sharply distinguished as they have 
 been in later times. The work of the cameralists was so to serve 
 their quasi-absolute lords tjiat the power and efficiency of their 
 states would be developed, and that their purposes with refer- 
 ence to competing states would be promoted. All the doc- 
 trines of the cameralists were in fact centered about this main 
 purpose, and all their theories and judgments must be under- 
 stood accordingly. 1 
 
 As a side-light upon the foregoing propositions, scarcely 
 anything could be more illuminating than the dedication of 
 Der Fursten Stoat. Because our language makes an exact 
 rendering of the ceremonial titles and phrases impossible, we 
 quote the form of address in the original, viz.: Dem Durch- 
 lauchtigsten, Hochgebornen Fursten und Herrn, Herrn Johann 
 Gear gen Erb-Printzen der Chur- und Hertzogen zu Sachsen, 
 Julich, Cleve und Bergk, Landgrafen in Thuringen, Mark- 
 
 1 For the conditions of the Peace of Westphalia which furnished 
 the general setting within which the problems of the several states of 
 Germany are to be explained, vide Tillinghast's Ploetz, p. 316, following 
 K. F. Eichhorn, Deutsche Starts- u. Rechtsgeschichte, IV, 522 ff. The 
 most useful outline of the condition of Germany in the period in which 
 Seckeodorff wrote is in Bryce, Holy Roman Empire, chap. xx. Vide 
 Tillinghast, loc. cit. t p. 371. "The Emperor was Leopold I, 1658-1705. 
 After 1663 permanent diet at Regensburg, consisting of the representa- 
 tives of the eight electors, the sixty-nine ecclesiastical, the ninety-six 
 secular princes, and the imperial cities. (A miracle of tedious legisla- 
 tion, often degenerating into a squabble for precedence. 'A bladeless 
 knife without a handle'.) Corpus Catholicorum and Corpus Evangeli- 
 corum (the corporate organizations of the Catholic and the evangelical 
 estates, the latter being the most important. This organization of the 
 Protestant estates had existed, fn fact, since the latter half of the sixteenth 
 century, but it was legally recognized in the Peace of Westphalia, when 
 it was decreed that in the diet matters relating to religion and the church 
 should not be decided by a majority, but should be settled by conference 
 and agreement between the Catholic and Protestant estates, as organized 
 corporations.)."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 65 
 
 gra/en zu Meissen, auch Ober- und Nieder-Lausznilz, Graf en 
 zu der March und Ravensberg, Herrn zu Ravenstein, crv. Afei- 
 nem gnddigsten Hcrrn, &c. Durchlauchtigster, Hochge- 
 bohrner, Gnddigster Fiirst und Herr, 6rY. 
 
 The quaintness of expression in the extremely adroit and 
 non-committal dedication itself cannot be reproduced in 
 English. The translation can convey only the substance of the 
 thought, the most obvious peculiarity of which is the rhetorical 
 device of suggestion, instead of direct statement. It is as 
 follows : 
 
 The wisdom, through which kingdoms, principalities, and lands 
 are happily governed, is in its origin divine, in itself it is lordly and 
 incomparable, and comprehends in its scope and generality all that 
 which is found piecemeal in other sciences. It is within the circum- 
 ference of each land the indispensable sun, through which everything 
 is illuminated, warmed, and nourished. It is to be compared with 
 an inexhaustible sea, into which all other wisdoms and arts flow, 
 and through high and occult art, for the common welfare, is again 
 discharged and distributed through the whole land. It is an ever- 
 green of Paradise of all the most beautiful and useful plants, of the 
 virtues and good ordinances, each of which in its turn and place 
 boars grateful fruits. This wisdom King Solomon prayed the All- 
 'vise to grant for his royal office, with which he received also the great- 
 est treasures and riches of the world as an additional gift. Foolish 
 therefore those who would penetrate into the secrets of governments 
 without the attendance and favor of this goddess. All those fall 
 into gross sin who, apart from the divinely appointed and by n;uure 
 sanctioned way, instead of such excellent royal and lofty science, 
 in the name of the state and of politics, offer perverse and crafty 
 counsel which plunges themselves and whole lands into ruin. For 
 what reasons and occasions, Most Gracious Lord, I was moved to 
 the publication of the present little-worthy work, in which, according 
 to the slight measure of my feeble powers, I sought to bring together 
 a few beams of this bright illuminating sun, certain drops from this 
 great sea, and certain fruits from such a general world-garden, and 
 according to opportunity to make them useful for the lands and prin-
 
 66 THK CAMERALISTS 
 
 cipalities of our German fatherland, is to a certain extent set forth 
 in the Preface, wherein also, with humblest apologies to your most 
 illustrious highness, it is explained through what motive I allowed 
 myself to seek, under your eminent name, protection for this very 
 imperfect book. May it please you most graciously to accept this 
 public expression of my most submissive zeal, as I hereby in humility 
 and highest veneration most obediently profess it, and with your 
 gracious permission I remain 
 
 His Most Illustrious Highness' 
 
 Most Submissive 
 
 VEIT LUDWIG VON SECKENDORFF 
 
 According to the standards of the time, this wretched stuff 
 was not fulsome, it was merely conventional. Something of 
 the sort, often much more extravagant, occurs in the dedications 
 of most of the cameralistic books. We shall allow this sample 
 to stand for all. It is turgid of course, but in that respect it 
 fairly reflects the stage of thought which it attempted to express. 
 The style was appropriate to the confused thinking which pre- 
 vailed about everything pertaining to social relations. But 
 this is merely incidental. The main thing is that these forms, 
 dictated by tradition in one respect, yet artfully artless in another, 
 fairly represent the attitude of the cameralists toward the 
 interests of men in civic society. It was fundamentally an 
 attitude of worship toward a supposed superior personage 
 endowed with a prerogative of control over a group of inferior 
 and subject persons. The social science of the time was an 
 effort so to mobilize the attitude that the states which counted 
 upon it as their chief asset could prosper. 
 
 In order to provide ourselves with a background for the 
 doctrines which we are to analyze, we should from step to step 
 parallel with this analysis unroll the general picture of German 
 and European politics. For this part of the process recourse 
 must be had to the historians. We can merely in passing 
 make note of the dependence of such a study as this upon their
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 67 
 
 larger work. Of the situation just before our time of depar- 
 ture Bryce writes: 
 
 To all parties alike the result of the Thirty Years' War was 
 thoroughly unsatisfactory to the Protestants, who had lost Bohemia, 
 and were still obliged to hold an inferior place in the electoral college 
 and in the Diet; to the Catholics, who were forced to permit the 
 exercise of heretical worship and leave the church lands in the grasp 
 of sacrilegious spoilers: to the princes, who could not throw off the 
 burden of imperial supremacy: to the Emperor, who could turn 
 that supremacy to no practical account. No other conclusion was 
 possible to a contest in which everyone had been vanquished and 
 no one victorious: which had ceased because, while the reasons for 
 war continued, the means of war had failed. Nevertheless, the sub- 
 stantial advantage remained with the German princes, for they 
 gained the formal recognition of that territorial independence whose 
 origin may be placed as far back as the days of Frederick the Second, 
 and the maturity of which had been hastened by the events of the 
 last preceding century. It was, indeed, not only recognized, but 
 justified as rightful and necessary. For while the political situation, 
 to use a current phrase, had changed within the last two hundred 
 years, the eyes with which men regarded it had changed still more. 
 Never by their fiercest enemies in earlier times, not once by Popes 
 or Lombard republics in the heat of their strife with the Franconian 
 and the Swabian Caesars, had the Emperors been reproached as 
 mere German kings, or their claim to be the lawful heirs of Rome 
 denied. The Protestant jurists of the seventeenth century were the 
 first persons who ventured to scoff at the pretended lordship of the 
 world, and declare their empire to be nothing more than a German 
 monarchy, in dealing with which no superstitious reverence need 
 prevent its subjects from making the best terms they could for them- 
 selves, and controlling a sovereign whose religious predilections 
 bound him to their ecclesiastical enemies 
 
 The Peace of Westphalia is an era in the history of the Holy 
 Empire not less clearly marked than the coronation of Otto the 
 Great, or the death of Frederick the Second (1250). As from the 
 days of Maximilian I (1493-1519) it had borne a mixed or transitional 
 character, well expressed by the name Romano-Germanic, so hence-
 
 68 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 forth it is in everything but title purely and solely a German Empire. 
 Properly, indeed, it was no longer an Empire at all, but a Federation, 
 and that of the loosest sort. For it had no common treasury, no 
 efficient common tribunals, no means of coercing a refractory mem- 
 ber; its states were of different religions, were governed according 
 to different forms, were administered judicially and financially with 
 out any regard to each other. The traveller by rail in central Ger- 
 many used, up till 1866, to be amused to find, every hour or two, by 
 the change in the soldiers' uniforms, and in the colour of the stripes 
 on the railway fences, that he had passed out of one and into another 
 of its miniature kingdoms. Much more surprised and embarrassed 
 would he have been a century earlier, when, instead of the present 
 twenty-two, there were three hundred petty principalities between 
 the Alps and the Baltic, each with its own laws, its own court (in 
 which the ceremonious pomp of Versailles was faintly reproduced), 
 its little army, its separate coinage, its tolls and custom-houses on 
 the frontier, its crowd of meddlesome and pedantic officials, presided 
 over by a prime minister who was often the unworthy favorite of his 
 prince and sometimes the pensioner of a foreign court. This vicious 
 system, which paralyzed the trade, the literature and the political 
 thought of Germany, had been forming itself for some time, but 
 did not become fully established until the Peace of Westphalia, by 
 finally emancipating the princes from imperial control, had left them 
 masters in their own territories. The impoverishment of the infe- 
 rior nobility, and the decline of the commercial cities caused by a war 
 that had lasted a whole generation, removed every counterpoise to 
 the power of the electors and princes, and made absolutism supreme 
 just where absolutism is least defensible, its states too small to have 
 any public opinion, states in which everything depends on the mon- 
 arch, and the monarch depends on his favorites. After A. D. 1648 
 the provincial estates or parliaments became obsolete in most of these 
 principalities, and jwwcrlcss in the rest. Germany was forced to 
 drink to its very dregs the cup of feudalism, feudalism from which 
 all the sentiment that once ennobled it had departed. 1 
 
 If then we disregard on the one hand the theologians, on 
 
 1 Lot. cil., p. 389; vide Lowell, Governments and Parties in Continen- 
 tal Europe, Vol. t, pp. 231-36.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 69 
 
 the other hand the legists, each group in its way acting rather 
 as ballast or as a brake in the several states than as a propulsive 
 force, the positive social science of Germany from the Peace 
 of Westphalia to the Napoleonic peril was the theory useful 
 in the administrative bureaus of these quasi-absolute states. 
 Our purposes will draw a sharp line between the technical 
 details of this theory and the general social ideas which the 
 theories implied, on the one hand as their basis and on the 
 other hand as their aims. The technical details we shall 
 ignore, except as they are necessary for making out the more 
 important general ideas. Our principal question is, What 
 conceptions of social relations were peculiar to the cameralists, 
 and what bearing have cameralistic theories upon the problems 
 of social science in general ? 
 
 To assist in fixing landmarks, we may say that Seckendorff 
 was the Adam Smith of cameralism. The evidence now in 
 order is first and chiefest in the two volumes already named. 
 We shall first examine Der Fiirsten Stoat. 1 
 
 The Preface, in archaic and bungling fashion, indicates 
 that the purpose of the book is not to discuss general political 
 ideas, nor forms of government in the abstract, but to furnish 
 an account of the operative machinery of a typical German 
 state. Of this preface, we may note, first, that it indicates 
 knowledge of only one previous writer in precisely this field, 
 viz., "an experienced courtier, Herr Lohneisen." 2 Secken- 
 dorff states, however, that he did not have the book at hand 
 when he wrote, and that only a dim recollection of its contents 
 was in his mind. His book was rather the result of his own 
 
 1 Herrn Veit Ludwigs von Seckendorff, etc., Teutscher Fiirsten 
 Stoat, nun zum fiinfftenmal ubersehen und au/gelegt, Auch mil einer ganz 
 neuen Zugabe. Sonderbahrer und unchtiger Materien urn ein grosses 
 
 Thett vermehret Anno MDCLXXIIX. In my revision of this 
 
 chapter I have been able to refer only to this fifth edition. 
 
 * Vide above, p. 40, and Roscher, p. 116.
 
 70 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 observation. Second, the author thinks that his description 
 of a medium-sized state may easily be adapted either to the 
 largest or the smallest members of the German civic family. 
 Third, the author deliberately excludes consideration of the 
 abuses which occur in the management of states. He con- 
 fesses that so many of them are within his knowledge that it 
 is difficult not to write satirically about government, but on 
 the whole he thinks it better to describe administration as it 
 is intended to be, rather than as it really is. Fourth, the 
 author protests that he has not consciously or intentionally 
 said anything in the book which invades the sanctity of imperial 
 or princely prerogative. The fact that such an explanation 
 could be thought of at all is a cardinal symptom of the arbi- 
 trariness of the regime which it reflects. Fifth, the Preface 
 ends with a devout invocation of the divine blessing upon the 
 emperor and all the members of the imperial system. Nothing 
 in this petition could be construed as a direct assertion that 
 these governments are peculiarly sacred. The mixture of poli- 
 tics and piety, however, is quite in character with what is other- 
 wise in evidence about the dominant civic conceptions. 
 
 The book is divided into four parts. The first and shortest 
 (22 pages) is merely a demand for a description of the external 
 characteristics of a state, from the geographical and typo- 
 graphical features, the condition of cultivation and improve- 
 ment, to the governmental and social structure. The second 
 part (278 pages) approximately includes the subjects which 
 Justi afterward assigned both to Staatskunst and to Policey, 
 i. e., it treats "of the government and organization \VerJassun l \ 
 of a land and principality in spiritual and secular affairs." 
 The third part (266 pages), on the properties and revenues 
 of a ruler, corresponds with the Finanzuissenschaft, or Catneral- 
 
 ' The translation "constitution" is avoided because it carries 
 associations which would be largely anachronistic if referred to the quasi- 
 absolute type of state. Vide p. 34 above.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 71 
 
 wissenschaft in the restricted sense, of the later cameralists. 
 Instead of a fourth part, co-ordinate with the first three, 198 
 pages are devoted to a more specific scheme of organization, 
 in accordance with the foregoing discussion. The editions 
 after 1664 contain an appendix of 208 pages, consisting of 
 notes upon various passages in the body of the book. 
 
 While the contents of Seckendorff's system should be rear- 
 ranged in another form, to show most distinctly their relations 
 to cameralism as a whole, we must be content to sketch them 
 in brief, so far as they are important for our purpose, in the 
 order in which they appear in Der Fursten Stoat and Der 
 Christen Stoat. 
 
 Seckendorff begins the former book by calling attention to 
 the unreliability, for purposes of precision, of most previous 
 attempts to exhibit in print the exact conditions of German 
 states and the consequent need of accurate accounts (pp. 30- 
 32). These accounts should contain precise descriptions not 
 only of the form of government of the state in question, the 
 particular subject with which Seckendorff proposes to deal, 
 and for subsequent treatment of which he hopes his book will 
 serve as a model; but they should also describe the external 
 conditions of the country, to which all rulers and magistrates 
 must accommodate their policies. Because the present book 
 does not refer to a specific country alone, he says, it can offer 
 on the latter division of the subject only a tentative (unver- 
 Jangiick) model or scheme in accordance with which the neces- 
 sary description of the external conditions of each country 
 may be worked out (p. 33). The scheme proposed is in brief 
 as follows: 
 
 First, an account of the name, origin, and circumstances of 
 the principality; viz., (a) whence the designation is derived; (&)' 
 how the sovereignty over this territory arose; (c) the geographical 
 and topographical peculiarities of the territory; (d) the need of maps 
 which shall show these facts (pp. 33-35). Second, an account of
 
 72 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the subdivisions of the country and dependencies; i. e., (a) according 
 to natural boundaries; (6) according to various artificial arrange- 
 ments; (c) the distribution of the territory among various officials; 
 (d) the subdivisions of magisterial and judicial jurisdictions in the 
 country; (e) more specific description of each subdivision of the 
 country under this scheme; (/) streets, bridges, and passes (pp. 35- 
 41). Third, an account of the qualities and fertility of the territory; 
 i. c., (a) the fertility of countries in general; (b) varieties of produc- 
 tivity of countries; (c) special topics to be treated in the description 
 of the fertility of particular countries (pp. 41, 42). Fourth, an 
 account of the inhabitants of the country; viz., (a) the uncertainty 
 of the natural disposition of people; 1 (6) class divisions of the inhabit- 
 ants; 2 (c) somewhat more essential marks of difference; 3 (d) per- 
 sonal and peculiar qualities of the sovereign* (pp. 49, 50). Fifth, 
 a roster of the servants of the ruler and of the government (p. 50). 
 
 If the present purpose were to write a history of cameralism, 
 it would be necessary to analyze these beginnings of a tech- 
 
 1 It appears that amateur social psychologists had already brought 
 rash generalizations about the character of peoples into disrepute. Sec- 
 kendorff demands that judgments of that nature shall be based on adequate 
 examination of the facts, instead of accidental and fragmentary evidence. 
 He also points out that many characteristics of people which are attrib- 
 uted to their "natural traits" are due rather to their bringing up and 
 their food supply (Aufferziehung und Nahrung); a decidedly farsighted 
 paragraph (p. 43). 
 
 1 The criterion in mind here is essentially that of civic and eccle- 
 siastical structure, on the administrative side. 
 
 3 Here the reference is to social differences which reflect group inter- 
 ests not primarily official, but the analysis suggested is very crude. It 
 names differences of religion, differences connected with differentiation 
 of a learned class, differences between the imperial and the local nobility, 
 differences between the status of burghers in free cities and those of other 
 cities, etc. 
 
 The specifications under this head concern chiefly the traditions 
 which hedge about the succession. They are of an entirely different 
 order, according to modern methodology, from those with which the 
 chapter began: i. e., they are political, constitutional, legal, not physical.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 73 
 
 nology, in order to trace, first, the development of consciousness 
 of the problems, administrative and theoretical, to be solved, 
 and second, the development of the technique for dealing with 
 those problems. Our concern, however, is not with these 
 details. Our object is to visualize the relation which cameral- 
 ism bore to the problems of social science in general. The 
 first book of Der Fursten Stoat has no bearing upon this pur- 
 pose beyond its use in confirming the theorem that cameralism 
 was essentially a phase of the quasi-absolutism which was the 
 central factor in the machinery of the social process in Ger- 
 many from the Reformation to the French Revolution. There 
 was nothing in the programme of description marked out in 
 this book except the fourth and fifth categories which would 
 not be equally in place in a democratic country. As it stands 
 in Seckendorff 's scheme, however, it is a plan for taking account 
 of the stock with which a quasi-absolutism has to do business. 
 The second -part directly addresses the task of planning 
 the administration of the state, and it still more directly con- 
 firms our theorem of quasi-absolutism. Chap, i deals with 
 the government, sovereignty (Hoheif), and authority of ruling 
 princes in general. 1 Under this head the analysis proceeds: 
 First, The government of a country is by no means an autoc- 
 racy (eigenwillige Herrschaff). The distinction, as Secken- 
 dorff saw it, between an autocracy and the typical German 
 
 1 I do not think it is necessary to enter into any of the constantly 
 recurring questions about theoretical relations of the princes to the Empire. 
 In practice, from this time on, the titular head of the Empire was virtually 
 only one of the most powerful among the scores of rival quasi-sovereign 
 princes in Germany, the ruler of Prussia looming up more and more as 
 his most formidable competitor. The political plot, down indeed to 
 the Franco-Prussian war, turned in the first instance upon the fluctuating 
 success of these principal actors in controlling the lesser princes. I take 
 the liberty of using the term sovereignty in connection with these rulers 
 and states, because in relation to their subjects it was so nearly an unqual- 
 ified fact that the modifications of the fact through relations to the Empire 
 were relatively trivial.
 
 74 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 state of his time, which we describe as a quasi-absolutism, may 
 best be indicated in a translation of his own words. He says 
 (pp. 52 ff.): 
 
 In German lands, God be praised, we have no knowledge of a 
 power exercised by a single man in the country, who regards himself 
 as the highest, and who, with or without right, uses the greatest 
 power upon all the others for his profit and advantage, according 
 to his will and caprice alone, as a master is in the habit of domineering 
 over his chattel men servants and maid servants. On the other 
 hand the princely government in the German principalities and 
 lands, as in almost every rightly and wisely ordered Policey, is nothing 
 else than the supreme and highest dominion of the properly ruling 
 territorial prince or lord, which is enforced and exercised by him 
 over the estates and subjects of the principality, also over the land 
 itself and its appurtenances, for the maintenance and promotion of 
 the common profit and welfare, and for the administration of justice. 
 
 If ideals were realities, German states at this period could 
 not be classed as absolutistic in spirit and in essence, whatever 
 they were in form. The fallacy which it required the Revolu- 
 tion to expose was that this type of pious statement of the pur- 
 poses of government was not protected by effective safeguards 
 against the arbitrariness of rulers on whose talent and virtue 
 the realization of the ideal depended. In other words, the 
 rulers were to such an extent the final judges of what was 
 involved in "profit and welfare," and they had so large liberty 
 to decide that whatever was "profit and welfare" for themselves 
 was identical with the good of the people and the state, that 
 the regime which cameralism represented was qualified autoc- 
 racy, from the modern point of view. We shall see what 
 some of the qualifications were, and we shall see that the came- 
 ralists in general were opposed to any further qualifications 
 which would tend to make the ruler more responsible to the 
 people. The cameralists did much to raise the standards 
 which a benevolent despot should adopt. They did virtually
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKEXDORFF 75 
 
 nothing directly to raise the standards of the citizens' rights 
 to insist that their rulers should adopt them. Within limits, 
 to be sure, but with a scope which developing civic conscious- 
 ness presently found intolerable, the princes were the sole 
 judges of what was good for their peoples and states. Cameral- 
 ism was the technique and the philosophy of states in which 
 this situation was taken for granted. 
 
 In the second place (p. 53) Seckendorff brings the sovereignly 
 of the prince into stronger light by comparing it with the subject 
 condition of everybody else in the state. "When we thus ascribe 
 this supreme authority to the person of the territorial lord alone, or 
 thereby set aside all other persons in a country, whom we have already 
 described in the first part, although they also are empowered with 
 certain lordship and authority either by the prince himself and his 
 
 ancestors, as well as by other foreign governments All these, 
 
 however powerful and rich they are, in comparison with the prince, 
 are to be regarded severally and collectively as mere subjects." 
 
 In the next paragraph (p. 54) the author bases this doctrine on 
 (i) the ancient tradition, (2) the feudal concession of lordship by 
 the emperor to the territorial prince, (3) the recognition of the 
 supreme authority of the prince by the other estates and subjects 
 of the country by taking the customary oath of allegiance to him. 
 
 Confirmation of the claim is found further (p. 56) in the fact 
 that other high personages, even of the rank of count, no longer use 
 the form with reference to themselves, "by the grace of God," nor 
 does such a person speak or write of himself as "we." The prince 
 uses that form, and therewith he expresses his tenure of the supreme 
 governing station, by the will of God, and his preferment over his 
 subjects. 
 
 On the other hand, as previously asserted, the government of a 
 principality consists fn achieving and maintaining the common 
 advantage and well-l>eing, in spiritual and wordly things (p. 56). 
 Thereupon Seckendorff moralizes: "The final purpose of all human 
 actions and deeds is the honor of God, for which the human race was 
 especially created. Particularly however is it seemly for those high 
 authorities who are God's deputies on earth to see that the honor of
 
 76 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 their sovereign heavenly overlord is sought in all things, etc." 
 
 (]> 57)- 
 
 In further commentary on the sacred functions of the prince, 
 the argument continues: "In former times the clergy deprived princes 
 of large parts of their sacred prerogatives, hut since a large part 
 of Germany, more than a hundred years ago, turned to evangelical 
 religion by adopting the Augsburg Confession, the princes have 
 resumed those sacred offices which belonged to them." 
 
 In the third place, the prerogative of the prince in worldly admin" 
 istration may be specified under four heads (p. 58): First, in 
 establishing his own power and dignity, so that he will be able to 
 suppress disorders, and will have prestige enough to make his govern- 
 ment efficient in gaining its ends; second, he has to establish power, 
 good laws and ordinances in the country, by which righteousness, 
 peace, and repose, and the means 1 of the country and of the people 
 will be brought into being, and maintained, the evil punished, and 
 the good promoted; third, the supreme jurisdiction in the country 
 belongs to the prince, that is, to pronounce the law between his 
 subjects in case they quarrel, and to enforce the findings according 
 to the desert of each; fourth, it is his duty to establish and use all 
 the means whereby the foregoing institutions may be set in motion 
 and administered in case of need against disobedient subjects or 
 foreign enemies and aggressors. 
 
 Chap, ii treats of the qualification of the sovereignty of the prince 
 by his relations to the Empire. In sec. i, on the " Reichs Hoheit" 
 over the German principalities, Seckendorf! continues in substance: 
 "In order that the opinion may not be inferred from the previous 
 chapter that any German Landes-Herrschajt is absolutely free, we 
 have to call attention to the fact that we are speaking of countries 
 within the Roman Empire o) the German Nation, of which the impe- 
 rial majesty is the supreme head. It follows that each German 
 country is under the emperor and the Empire. This involves the 
 
 1 The word Vermogen is an extremely loose term in camcralistic usage. 
 We shall have to call attention to it frequently. It may mean "wealth," 
 oftener it means wealth plus everything else, from Ixwlily strength to 
 the arts and sciences and a strong army, which is a civic resource. The 
 rolorless term "means" is therefore chosen as a rendering.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 77 
 
 consequence that a German prince or Landes-Herr is not responsible 
 alone to his conscience toward God the Almighty for his government 
 and actions, but that he is also under obligations, and in many ways 
 bound by his sworn duties to pay the due respect and obedience to 
 the regularly chosen ruling Roman emperor and to the Empire, and 
 to all that the imperial majesty, with the electors, princes, and estates 
 of the Empire have ordained and may ordain" (pp. 60, 61). 
 
 This section, with the remainder of the chapter, is ample 
 commentary upon Roscher's judgment cited above (p. 62; vide 
 Roscher, p. 243), that Seckendorff was a champion of the old 
 order. To him the Empire was still a vital reality. There can 
 of course be no valid interpretation of German history, not 
 merely in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, but even 
 to the present moment, which does not trace the actual work- 
 ings of this survival among the other factors which complicated 
 the collisions of interests after the Empire became more a theory 
 than a fact. It is as unnecessary for our present purpose as 
 it would be impossible to compress into a brief formula the 
 incalculable variety of modifications which the increasingly 
 spectral reminiscence called the Empire wrought upon the 
 changing political situations of the period in which cameralism 
 developed. The most essential consideration is this: On the 
 score of absolutism there was no essential difference for the 
 masses between the graded feudal type of sovereignty repre- 
 sented by the Empire, and the quasi-absolute type represented 
 by the would-be independent German princes, with slowly 
 increasing modifications, down to the Franco-Prussian War. 
 Democracy made progress directly or indirectly toward its 
 own by collisions of interests among which, sometimes for 
 weal and sometimes for woe, the imperial interest was a factor. 
 If our present task were to enter upon analysis of the forces 
 which played upon one another in Germany from Seckendorff 
 to Sonnenfels, the imperial factor would constantly be a mean- 
 ing term in the equation, though with a steadily diminishing
 
 7 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 coefficient. For our present purpose the perception suffices 
 that however power and authority were divided between princes 
 and emperor, the net result for the people of Germany was 
 quasi -absolutism as the foundation course of their social struc- 
 ture. The quarrels between the shadowy imperial sovereign 
 and the matter-of-fact territorial sovereigns, whether of major 
 or minor importance in their immediate effects upon the evo- 
 lution of constitutionalism, as the next species of political order 
 in Germany, were in principle negligible from our present 
 point of view. They were merely details in the administration 
 of control, which was quasi-absolutism, however it was dis- 
 tributed. To the ordinary German citizen the presence or 
 absence of the imperial factor in the political situation simply 
 meant one privileged player more or less in the game in which 
 in any event he was only a pawn. We may therefore cancel 
 Seckendorff's imperialism from our calculation, for it was of 
 no significance for our main consideration, viz., the essential 
 relation of government to citizens, which was the major premise 
 of cameralism. 
 
 For parallel reasons we need not concern ourselves with 
 the class of questions which Seckendorff raises in chap, iii, viz., 
 the relation of the prince to the hereditary or customary rights 
 of certain other persons, particularly agnates of the princely 
 house. These rights may vary from claim to petty prerogative 
 to presumptive share in the sovereignty. However these items 
 are arranged, they are, as it were, family matters among the 
 quasi-absolute few, and the political tutelage of the many 
 remains unaffected. 
 
 In chap, iv on the other hand we come upon limitations 
 of quasi -sovereignty which were in the last analysis of a more 
 democratic character. One of the most constant difficulties 
 of the modern student of conditions under the rdgime of "benev- 
 olent despotism" is to understand how there can have been 
 an irreducible minimum of law for the individual and for
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKFXDORFF 79 
 
 non-privileged groups which the quasi-autocrats were bound 
 to respect. Of course the explanation is that the equilibrium 
 of controlling and of controlled groups at any moment is a 
 resultant of forces which have previously passed through many 
 other forms of adjustment. In the conflicts of interests out 
 of which German civilization of the seventeenth century took 
 shape, a great body of tradition defining the rights of citizens 
 had been accepted as settled. In the cameralistic period this 
 body of tradition represented a mass of social inertia, compared 
 with which imperial claims were merely casual grit in the polit- 
 ical running gear, while the prerogatives of territorial princes 
 were to a considerable extent recent acquisitions. These cus- 
 toms, which insured a great body of relatively satisfactory 
 private rights, were in a large degree inconsistent with the auto- 
 cratic type of sovereignty which the princes represented. Yet 
 the customary laws were often more firmly established than 
 the sovereignties, and whatever the theories of divine right, 
 respect for ancient private rights was the price which the quasi - 
 absolutisms had to pay for tenure of their balance of power. 
 The critical fact in the quasi-absolutisms of this period, from 
 our present point of view, was that the people, in the modern 
 sense, had no initiative in legislation, and a minimum of influ- 
 ence upon public policies which might at last decide whether 
 their ancient private rights were worth having. At the same 
 time there was a body of law which in general amounted to 
 much more of a real limitation upon the conceivable autocracy 
 of the princes, from the democratic side, than the shadowy 
 remainder of the older re'gime exerted from the imperial side. 
 In the passage next in order (pp. 72 ff.) the nature of these 
 limitations of absolutism is briefly indicated. 
 
 In the first place "the subjects in a country are not slaves." The 
 alternative description of what they are is formulated in syntax as 
 cloudy as the idea which it attempts to express. Its substance is 
 that "subjects are under the righteous government of authorities
 
 8o THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 divinely appointed to guard the welfare of their bodies and souls 
 according to Christian, Godly, natural and imix/rial law, and that 
 they are always to be protected and cherished by this government 
 according to the cardinal principles of a commendable form of gov- 
 ernment, according to the circumstances of the German principali- 
 ties, as will be set forth in the remainder of the book." 
 
 Thus there are particular rights and powers [Bejiignisse] of sub- 
 jects which the ruler is bound to respect, not merely because they 
 are matters of conscience and of ultimate accountability to God, 
 but because of certain externally binding obligations. For instance, 
 either the ruler or his predecessors may have promised or conceded 
 something, or it is incumbent upon him because it is involved in 
 general German laws and principles, or it is in accordance with 
 ancient tradition. 1 Thus the prince must, in the first place, have 
 a care for the maintenance of religion, according to both custom 
 and usage of the country. In the second place the prince must 
 listen to the complaints of subjects against one another, and must 
 execute justice between them. In the third place the subjects may 
 rightfully claim that the ruler may not act in a tyrannical manner 
 toward their possessions. In the fourth place, if he has entered 
 into agreements with the estates or subjects of his land, the ruler 
 may not act contrary to his promises, without the consent of said 
 estates or subjects. If it becomes necessary to change the traditional 
 order, as will often be the case in matters of taxation, it is proper 
 that the ruler should grant a hearing to the estates, and that he gain 
 their consent, in order to avoid serious complications. Besides 
 these chief points there are many others, with reference to which 
 the ruler, "although not from obligation, yet from praiseworthy 
 
 1 II should be observed that while SeckcndorfT probably thought 
 he was thus defining freedom, from our angle of vision he was simply 
 drawing the outlines of quasi-absolutism. The ruler was relatively 
 free to deride for himself whether and in what particulars he would 
 respec t these limitations, and what spec ific actions respect for them 
 demanded. The subjects were not free to hold him strictly responsible 
 to the law, or to take part in making new laws. They were thus at the 
 mercy of the caprice of the prince to such an extent that their ancient 
 liberties might at any moment virtually be nullified.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 81 
 
 and excellent custom, takes council with the estates, and hears their 
 loyal opinions, although he is not immediately bound thereby" 
 (p. 76).' 
 
 Chap, v enters upon analysis of the secular administration. 
 The first theorem is that the prince should himself administer the 
 weightiest affairs of his land and not leave them to his servants 
 (p. 84). The fulfilment of this condition consists first in the effort 
 of the prince to obtain a thorough acquaintance with the circum- 
 stances of his land (die eigentlichc Beschaflenheit seines iMndcs 
 nmbstandlich zu utrissen).* 
 
 Chap, vi enters into particulars about organization of a chan 
 cellcry, but it contains nothing that contributes in principle to our 
 inquiry. It continues the impression however that its specifications 
 
 1 A general description of a Landtag follows (pp. 77 ff.). The 
 whole discussion is typical of a state of things already referred to, and 
 to be emphasized later, viz., that during the cameralistic period there 
 was growing dcriniteness of opinion about the things wanted of govern- 
 ments. Very little appears in the writings of the cameralists to show 
 that their eyes were opening to the need of some reinforcement of these 
 wants beyond the irresponsible will of the rulers. In other words, the 
 cameralists formulated governmental standards which involved more 
 and more consideration of the wants of the people. They do not come 
 out into the open with any theories of effective sanctions for these popular 
 demands. 
 
 2 The context elaborates the proposition by making it equivalent 
 to a demand that the prince shall know all that is in the programme of 
 the cameralists a naive way of reiterating the supreme importance of 
 cameralism ! The astonishing thing, to the modern mind, in the elalx>ra- 
 tion of this theorem is that its tone is that which we might expect in a 
 tutor toward a prince in his early teens. One wonders whether the author 
 was really addressing rulers, or was actually attempting to make the read- 
 ing public believe that his picture of what a prince ought to be was a cor- 
 rect likeness of rulers as they were. One wonders too whether the theorems 
 alx)ut the selection of the servants of the prince (pp. 80-02) could have 
 l>een intended as exhortations. They are so axiomatic that no one at 
 all acquainted with government could be expected to express any other 
 views for public consumption. The fact that they were usually disre- 
 garded at will by the quasi-absolute rulers was a large part of the social 
 logic which ultimately alx>lished absolutism.
 
 82 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 about the qualifications and duties of civil servants constitute a highly 
 idealized picture of the desirable, rather than a literal analysis of 
 actual, official traits. 
 
 Chap, vii recurs to the first cardinal division of governmental 
 functions 1 "which consists in maintaining the sovereign power and 
 dignity in themselves" (p. 102). 
 
 At this point we come upon the plainest exhibition of that 
 peculiarity of cameralism which for the purposes of this inter- 
 pretation is fundamental. Cameralism posited the dignity 
 and power of the government as the foremost consideration. 
 Whether this is a tenable position we are not now concerned 
 to inquire. Our primary object is to make plain that, this 
 being the fundamental principle of cameralism, all the sub- 
 sequent contents of the system must be understood strictly 
 in their relations to this center. If they are detached from 
 this base, and treated as though they were taught as universals 
 by the cameralists, or with the same emphasis in relation to 
 some other center, the whole meaning of cameralism as a 
 phase of social science is radically misinterpreted. Suppose 
 we say that Abraham Lincoln's "government of the people, 
 for the people, by the people" means that the foremost aim 
 of the state is what the people want, because they want it. 
 Whether this would be a tenable principle we are also not now 
 concerned to inquire. It is obvious at a glance, however, 
 that the latter formula taken as a major premise of soial theory 
 would tend to arrange institutions and policies in a system very 
 different from that which would follow from the cameralistic 
 assumption. The cameralistic principle tended to exalt gov- 
 ernment to the rank of an end in itself. The alternative sug- 
 gested would tend to subordinate government to the rank 
 of a means, to be employed in one way or another according 
 to circumstances, and to be respected much or little in propor- 
 tion to what it proved to be worth. Meanwhile, all sorts of 
 
 1 Vide above, p. 76.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKEXDORFF 83 
 
 variations of judgment would occur between people who 
 reasoned from one and the other basis, about almost everything 
 with which governments have to do. It might turn out that from 
 the one standpoint it would appear, in given circumstances, 
 that taxes should be high, armies large, governmental employees 
 many, individual initiative distrusted, commercial policies 
 exclusive, etc., while from the other standpoint the opposite 
 conclusions would be equally plausible. If we are interpreting 
 incidentals of a theory, it makes all the difference in the world, 
 therefore, what the basic presumptions of the theory are. 
 
 Roscher taught his generation to interpret the cameralists 
 as economists, or at least English-speaking readers and imita- 
 tors have understood him so to teach. As we have said above, 1 
 that interpretation is a cardinal error. The cameralists were 
 primarily political scientists, and with a theory which pre- 
 judged economic questions that had not yet arisen in abstract 
 form, but which came later into the center of debate. The 
 judgments which the cameralists passed on such matters as 
 population, money, taxes, trade, were dictated by the particu- 
 lar type of political preconception which they adopted. That 
 is, they were estimates of political expediency under certain 
 assumed conditions, among them being the presumption of 
 the paramount worth of the government and its incarnation, 
 the ruler. These cameralistic judgments were not passed 
 upon economic questions in the shape in which they arose 
 when economic problems were abstracted and generalized, 
 instead of being treated as details subordinate to political pre- 
 conceptions. In so far as we find economic theory in the 
 cameralistic systems at all, therefore, we have to understand it 
 as virtually an answer to the question, What, in the given case, 
 best promotes the purposes of the quasi-absolutism which is the 
 main consideration ? Whether the cameralists judged sanely 
 on that question or not, the answer was not intended by them 
 
 1 Vide Preface, p. xiii.
 
 84 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to fit the primarily economic questions which were later 
 raised ; and it is a historical fallacy to summon them as witnesses 
 on questions which never came within the range of their 
 reckoning. 
 
 The chapter (vii) in which maintenance of the sovereign 
 power and dignity is discussed occupies, with its prefixed 
 summary, eighty-two pages. This is a natural and propor- 
 tional allotment of space to correspond with the prominence 
 which the theory assigns to the subject. It is altogether incon- 
 sistent with the supposition that the book was attempting to 
 frame a social theory in which economic problems, as under- 
 stood since Adam Smith, should receive due attention. We 
 need to notice the chapter only enough to illustrate what we 
 have said about its character as a symptom of partiality for 
 a type of political structure. 
 
 In the first place, the chapter deals very largely with details 
 which a modern democrat would lightly waive aside as mere matters 
 of ceremonial, and good form. On the other hand, the first impor- 
 tant stipulation is of another kind, viz., that the prince must annually 
 verify the boundary lines of his territories to make sure that his 
 neighbors are not encroaching (p. 116); and the next follows natu- 
 rally, viz., that as a last resort force must be used to end the aggression 
 (p. 117). The specifications under the head of protection of the 
 princely dignity with respect to the emperor (pp. 119 ff.) are largely 
 ceremonial pedantries, but if they pertain to matters of importance 
 they touch the location of authority, not the principle of authority 
 itself; that is, they refer to balance between the imperial and the 
 princely prerogative. The insistence (p. 123) upon stickling about 
 the terms of treaties, hereditary dispositions, primogeniture, etc., 
 betrays systematic cultivation of princely self-consciousness, more 
 than care for more important interests which might be endangered 
 by laxness about precedents and technicalities. Specification of the 
 regalia, the revenues, etc., would belong under this head in any 
 system which made room for government at all, and Seckendorff's 
 treatment of them here is in no respect peculiar. The political type
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 85 
 
 for which he spoke becomes conspicuous, however, when he turns 
 to the means which must be used to maintain the person and dignity 
 of the prince himself (pp. 129 ff.). The safety and comfort of the 
 chief magistrate will always be of importance in a civilized state- 
 but Seckendorff raises details of the most trifling sort, like matters 
 of petty etiquette, or the kinds of amusements proper to the prince, 
 to a degree of prominence which would be possible only under arbi- 
 trary preconceptions about the relative values of political persons 
 (c. g., pp. 175 ff.). Parts of the chapter are prolegomena to a plan 
 of mental and moral education for young princes (e. g., pp. 136, 137, 
 and 138-164). No doubt all this is pertinent to the author's purpose, 
 but the pathos of it is that it is exhortation to which no power in the 
 state was supposed to be justified in compelling the prince to listen. 
 Other parts of the chapter (e. g., pp. 135, 136) are appeals to the 
 piety of the prince, and rather broad hints that if his intelligence is 
 not equal to his responsibilities, he may by prayer and consultation 
 with wise advisers obtain from God the necessary guidance. This 
 is also very sound advice under the circumstances, but it all empha- 
 sises the crucial presumption that government by a prince relatively 
 irresponsible to his subjects must be taken for granted. The prin- 
 ciples and policies and working rules of such a government were the 
 matter in hand. No question was admitted which would go behind 
 this presupposition of the divine right of such a type of government 
 and ruler. All the subdivisions of the cameralistic system turned 
 around this primary reservation. 
 
 Nothing in this interpretation of Seckendorff is a reflection 
 upon the loftiness of his views or upon their value as a formu- 
 lation of the ideals which might make benevolent despotism 
 tolerable. On the contrary his theory was on a plane so high 
 that a modern reader is bound to suspect him of secreting 
 between the lines of his treatise conclusions which he does not 
 state. One can hardly doubt that these conventional formu- 
 lations, whether intentionally or not, actually were elements 
 of the social dynamics steadily making for more equitable 
 distribution of political power. On the surface, however, no 
 hint of the moral appears that if princes do not observe these
 
 86 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 counsels of righteousness and prudence their occupation will 
 presently be gone. Whether or not such men as Seckcnclorff 
 and Justi, not to say Sonnenfels, had any premonition of the 
 lest awaiting quasi-absolutism, their high ideals of government, 
 and of the character which rulers should maintain, must have 
 been factors in sharpening the perception of citizens that the 
 reality was too often in glaring contrast with the standard. 
 The cameralists must thus be scheduled as among the factors 
 which contributed indirectly to the political reconstructions 
 of the nineteenth century. Our present business, however, 
 is to show just what cameralism was, in theory and in practice, 
 in order to find the explanation of the changes in theory and 
 in practice which impended. In a word, the best elements 
 in the camcralistic theory were essentials of good government 
 for which the system of quasi-absolutism furnished no suffi- 
 cient guarantee. A reversal of the camcralistic presumptions 
 was therefore inevitable. Instead of starting with the para- 
 mount value of the quasi-absolutislic type of government, and 
 making political and social theory a technique of maintaining 
 it, post-camcralistic philosophy posited certain popular pur- 
 poses as paramount, and then proceeded to adopt the govern- 
 mental means by which their ends might be attained. 
 
 Chap, viii approaches the classes of subjects which for the 
 rrxxlern mind must be central and essential in political prin- 
 ciples and programmes, viz., "the establishment of good order 
 and laws for the welfare and common benefit of the Father- 
 land." ( Vide above, p. 76.) That is, Scckendorff is now occupy- 
 ing the standpoint indicated by the preamble of the Constitution 
 of the United States. In this chapter he begins to outline the 
 things which in his judgment would make for ends correspond- 
 ing with the later specifications, "form a more perfect union, 
 establish justice, insure domestic tranquillity, provide for the 
 common defense, promote the general welfare, and secure the 
 blessings of liberty to ourselves and our posterity." The
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 87 
 
 essential difference in the two situations was that cameralism 
 gave hostages to quasi-absolutism before it entered upon this 
 division of the inquiry. Its answer, therefore, was foreordained 
 to be in terms of the interests of the type of government assumed 
 as paramount; while the American constitution-makers ima- 
 gined themselves free from all political preconceptions; they 
 supposed they were judging questions of popular welfare upon 
 their merits, and they believed that they were acting upon the 
 principle of framing political institutions solely for their prob- 
 able utililty as means to popular ends. However actual bias 
 may have vitiated the American presumption of political 
 impartiality, there was a distinct contrast in principle between 
 the republican attitude and that of the cameralists. The 
 latter, as we have said, formulated their problem as principally 
 a question of the welfare of the preordained quasi-absolutism, 
 thus at the outset making the government primary and the 
 people secondary. The latter formulated their problem as a 
 question of the welfare of presumably equal citizens, thus at 
 the outset making the people primary and the government 
 secondary. Only so far as the welfare of equal citizens and 
 the welfare of quasi-absolute governments involve identical 
 relations could correspondence be expected between systems 
 starting from such contradictory principles. 
 
 Because our inquiry makes the history of administrative 
 technique merely incidental, our plan does not require analysis 
 of Seckendorff's cameralism on its administrative side. We 
 are trying to discover the relation of the cameralists to general 
 problems of social science. In so far as Justi proves to be 
 representative of the cameralists, his system will presently 
 be exhibited in considerable detail, as typical in spirit and 
 purpose, while at the same time more highly elaborated in 
 structure than the schemes of his predecessors. 
 
 Seckendorff begins his outline of the governmental pro- 
 cesses by which the peace and prosperity of the land are to
 
 88 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 be promoted, by repeating that "the power and authority to 
 establish such ordinances pertains to the territorial lord and 
 ruler alone, and it is his duty to promote them according to 
 his best understanding and knowledge" (p. 192). At the same 
 time he declares (p. 193)? "The object of such ordinances in 
 general is that by means of them justice, peace and prosperity 
 [Auflnehmen], or the welfare of the land and of the people, 
 may be sought." 
 
 We shall have occasion frequently to point out that, during 
 this quasi-absolutistic period, inchoate ideas of popular welfare 
 were expressed side by side with formulas of the paramount 
 importance of the government. The solution of the problems 
 of adjustment thus presented is simply this: In effect, the ideas 
 of the primacy of governmental and dynastic interests pre- 
 vailed until the democratic period changed the balance. Pre- 
 vious to the democratic revolutions, popular welfare was 
 always construed, in case of conflict, as a phase of governmen- 
 tal welfare. Meanwhile expression of popular interests in 
 more and more distinct form must have weakened the force 
 of the governmental presumption long before the consequences 
 of the change were visible in more democratic institutions. 
 
 In general Seckendorff represents the perspective of political 
 desirability as follows: 
 
 Peace, or the internal concord of the country, and security against 
 enemies, are the consequence of justice, and this in turn will be 
 promoted by peace and concord, so that it is true, according to the 
 teaching of King David, that the two kiss each other, and the one 
 without the other does not exist. Finally, prosperity and welfare 
 are established chiefly upon these two precious gifts of God, but 
 they are manifest especially in abundant sustenance and growth of 
 the number of the people, and in their means, conduct and manners. 
 The supreme purpose (sic) of all these is the salutary maintenance 
 of the Policey or of the whole government, in its honor, power and 
 sovereignty, and the last aim is the honor of God, as we have else- 
 where shown (p. 193).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKEXDORIT 89 
 
 Accordingly Seckendorff regards it as the task of govern- 
 ment, and so of cameralism, to provide an organization and 
 a technique which will not only secure peace and order, but 
 the good morals of the citizens (p. 195). An extended discus- 
 sion follows of details in which the state, partly through the 
 secular administration, partly through the ecclesiastical and 
 educational system, must curb vice and plant the seeds of 
 virtue in the people. 
 
 If it were a part of our purpose to weigh the merits and 
 defects of quasi-absolutism or paternalism as compared with 
 democracy, this might be the proper point for undertaking 
 the process. Instead of that, the occasion may be taken for 
 a single remark by way of caution and qualification, viz. : Our 
 constant appeal to democracy in contrast with paternalism 
 does not imply disregard for the historic mission of paternalism. 
 Certain national groups have reached a stage of development 
 after which persistence of paternalism would have involved 
 arrest of progress. Other groups have at the same time pro- 
 gressed more securely and rapidly under the guidance of pater- 
 nalism than would have been probable or perhaps possible 
 with any other form of control. German populations in the 
 seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were unquestionably 
 illustrations of the latter situation. We are not impeaching 
 German quasi-absolutism in its character as a stage of evolu- 
 tion. We are trying to expose its fallacy when proposed as 
 an a-priori principle. 
 
 Resuming the problem of securing peace and concord, Secken- 
 dorff indicates as means thereto (pp. 201 ff.): good organization of 
 justice and the use of wholesome laws; (2) strict prohibition of 
 self-enforcement of suppressed rights; (3) good organization and 
 readiness for action of the personnel of civic control. 
 
 On the means of guarding the health and increasing the numbers 
 of the people, Seckendorff indicates a governmental programme 
 extending from the maintenance of midwives and nurses, the support
 
 9 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of orphans, the subsidizing of physicians and surgeons, 1 to inspection 
 of foods, of water supplies, measures for cleaning and draining 
 towns, etc. 
 
 Passing to problems of securing to the people means of support, 
 SeckcndorlT's programme includes (pp. 204(1.): d) the intention 
 on the part of government that no subject shall lack means of secur- 
 ing the necessities of life, "except as a special punishment and provi- 
 dence of God, or by his own fault;" (2) that the surplus or special 
 products of the country shall be specially conserved as a means of 
 securing in exchange from other countries their necessary and useful 
 products. Details under this programme are scheduled to the num- 
 IKT of twelve, viz., (i) the fundamental provision, i. e., the good 
 education of youth; (2) adequate ordering of all means of making 
 the land yield support; 2 (3) special attention to those goods which 
 are most generally necessary, i. e., the products of the field, of graz- 
 ing, of forestry, of the iron, spinning, weaving, and wool trades; 
 (4) proportional attention to the more vulgar occupations, i. e., of 
 day-laborers and common servants; (5) ordinances regulating prices; 
 (6) abolition of usury; (7) regulation of weights and measures; (8) 
 certain classes of sumptuary laws, i. e., feasting and celebration; 
 (9) other types of sumptuary laws, i. e., clothing, etc. ; (10) discourage- 
 ment of use of foreign wares as clothing and food; (u) suppression 
 of various classes of parasites, e. g , gamblers, fakirs, fraudulent 
 bankrupts, etc.; (12) just management of income-producing prop- 
 erties belonging to communities. 
 
 Thereupon follows a similar outline, under five heads, of measures 
 to foe employed in getting the most advantage from a country's 
 surplus products, viz. (pp. 214 ff.): (i) Special account is to be 
 made of the peculiar products of the country, and special provision 
 made for their encouragement; (2) the influences of government 
 must be exerted to maintain the zeal of the people for continuing 
 these specially advantageous occupations; (3) encouragement must 
 
 1 The use of the word Balbierer tells its own story of the degree ot 
 differentiation which the professions had then attained. 
 
 2 The sertion suggests a curiously unassorted mixture of physical 
 and moral devices, from compulsion of each industrial class to stick to 
 its traditional occupations, to moral discipline of apprentices and artisans.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 91 
 
 be given to traders from other countries to purchase these goods; 
 (4) special attention must be given to regulation of subjects who 
 want to carry on foreign trade in these goods; (5) the people must 
 be protected by regulation of domestic trade against various kinds 
 of fraud. 
 
 In these two series of categories we have in embryo the 
 Policeywissemchaft worked out in so much greater detail, and 
 with so much more orderly arrangement, by a succession of 
 writers up to Justi. Seckendorff's schedules call for two 
 comments only: first, they show farseeing discernment of 
 factors which must always be rather elementary in the pros- 
 perity of communities; second, they are crude judgments about 
 wise ways and means for securing these desirable details. In 
 other words, Seckendorff's technology was a collection of very 
 premature conclusions about social causes and effects. The 
 ^situations to which such judgments were supposed to apply 
 had not been generalized, and the validity of these rough and 
 ready judgments had not been adequately tested. That is, 
 Seckendorff's embryonic Policeywissenschaft, from the view- 
 point of our present analysis, was merely a collection of pro- 
 visional working rules, one effect of which was presently (in 
 the time of Adam Smith) to produce an effective demand for 
 radical reconsideration of the presuppositions on which govern- 
 mental relations to ail economic activities had been based. 
 In comparison with Justi, Seckendorff formulated these rules 
 in a very loose fashion. They reflected the fundamental poli- 
 cies of quasi-absolutism plainly enough, however, and progress 
 in systematizing these policies merely intensified their abso- 
 lutistic character. 
 
 Chap, ix (pp. 218-39) deals with the organization of the 
 courts. There is no question of principle between quasi- 
 absolutistic and democratic theories of government, as to the 
 fundamental conception that the government must administer 
 justice. In this respect there is nothing peculiar to cameralis-
 
 92 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tics which calls for our attention. If we were making a study 
 of comparative juridical institutions, the systems of courts in 
 Germany during the cameralistic period would of course occupy 
 an important subdivision of the treatment. The purposes of 
 this book neither require nor permit an attempt to consider 
 that branch of German administration. 
 
 For similar reasons we may neglect chap, x (pp. 240-59), 
 which deals very summarily with the means of executing the 
 decrees of courts and with the war powers of governments. 
 Chaps, xi-xiv (pp. 260-328) deal with the general subject of 
 the relation of the ruler to ecclesiastical administration, under 
 which rubric educational administration is included. Here 
 again details are not material for our purpose. We may observe 
 that, so far as space is an index, Seckendorff makes these sub- 
 jects six times more prominent in his general theory of the state 
 than Justi does in the same connection. 1 This difference 
 probably corresponds with the emphasis actually placed by 
 the two men upon the ecclesiastical side of government. Sec- 
 kendorff appears to have had no doubts whatever that the 
 divine order of the universe necessarily worked through divinely 
 ordained princes, in whom secular and religious prerogatives 
 were indissoluble. Justi had no other views for publication. 
 He accepted the ecclesiastical organization as he found it, and 
 though he expressed a good deal of contempt for some of its 
 workings he did not venture to offer a theory of its place in 
 the governmental scheme essentially different from that assigned 
 to it by Seckendorff. 
 
 Reference to the Table of Contents and comparison of 
 Parts III and IV with the corresponding portions of Justi's 
 system* will afford all the evidence it falls within our purpose 
 to cite about the place of Seckendorff in the development of 
 the technique of the subject. We may pass, then, from this 
 
 1 Vide the corresponding passage in Staatswissenschaft, i. e., pp. 
 122-32.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 93 
 
 outline of the more important of his two books to a brief analy- 
 sis of Der Christen Stat. 
 
 Our account of Scckendorff would be incomplete without 
 examination of the version of his views published thirty years 
 later than the volume just described. This book would be 
 more properly classified primarily as a religious exhortation 
 than as a political treatise. Since the relations between religion 
 and politics were more in evidence at the time of its composition 
 than they are at present, more may be learned from a disquisi- 
 tion of this type, about the shadings of contemporary political 
 doctrines, than could safely be inferred from a similar book 
 today. So far as possible, we shall confine our notice to cer- 
 tain features of the book which throw light upon the author's 
 cameralistic theories. 1 
 
 An incidental touch in the dedication, all the more signifi- 
 cant because it was casual, yet at the same time conventional, 
 was the assumption that the descendants of the prince to whom 
 the book was dedicated would continue to exercise his pre- 
 rogatives "to the end of the world." If there was any specu- 
 lation in the mind of cameralistic authors to the effect that the 
 structures of states might be changed in the course of time, 
 such vain imaginings were kept below the surface. The strong 
 
 1 The title-page reads: Herrn Veit Ludwig's von Seckendorff Chris- 
 ten-Stat. In Drey Bucher abgetheilet. 1m Ersten wird von dem Chris- 
 tenthum an sick selbst, und dessen Behauptung, wider die At heist en und 
 dergleichen Leute; 1m Anderen von der Verbesserung des Weltlichen, 
 und 1m Dritten des Geistlichen Standes, nach dem Zweck des Christen- 
 thums gehandelt. Darbey unterschiedliche merckliche Stellen, aus alien 
 und neuen Autoribus, in besonderen Additionen zur Bekrdftigung und 
 Nachdencken angehdngt zu befinden. Leipzig, verlegts. Joh. Friedrich 
 Gleditsch. M.DC.XCIII. This second edition (first dated April 18, 
 1685) is the only one that I have seen. It is apparently a reprint of the 
 first, without change. Nothing appears in it to show whether it was 
 given to the printer by the author, or by an editor after his death. The 
 body of the book, after a dedication, preface, etc.. occupying 38 pages, 
 consists of 719 pages. The Additiones and Index occupy 570 pages.
 
 94 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 probability is, in Seckcndorffs case at least, that no such fancy 
 had ever disturbed conventional reflections. 
 
 The Preface recites that, twenty years earlier, when the 
 author was in service at the court of Moritz of Saxony, that 
 prince, his consort, and some of the younger members of the 
 family were greatly disturbed by symptoms of "atheism" 
 among persons who were regular or occasional visitors at court. 
 The impulse of Pascal's writings led Seckendorff to attempt 
 a refutation of atheism, and this constitutes the substance of 
 the first part of the present book. As the author describes this 
 portion of his work, it was purely theoretical. It found such 
 a favorable reception at court, however, that he was encouraged 
 to expand it, and especially to show "how the many and great 
 evils in all classes were best to be remedied, if the ground of 
 Godliness were rightly considered, and its chief aim were kept 
 in sight as the guide of all human actions." In order to carry 
 out this idea, "the three so-called chief strata [Haupt-Stande] 
 and their doings" were taken into particular consideration, 
 with especial reference to the requirements of Christianity 
 upon them. While this reflection was still in progress (1681) 
 the death of the elector so changed the situation that the author 
 was able to retire and give more time to writing. He mentions 
 Philipp Jacob Spener of Franckfurt as among those who read 
 parts of his manuscript and made useful suggestions. The 
 pains which he takes to excuse the failings of the book, on the 
 ground that he had always been a man of affairs and not a 
 scholar, savor more of vanity than of modesty. They affect 
 one as the pettiness of an amateur who was not too zealous 
 about the substance of his message to be fussy about the impres- 
 sion he would make with respect to immaterial details of form. 
 
 The first book of Der Christen-Stat contains nothing which 
 need occupy our attention. 1 It is simply a layman's apolo- 
 
 ' The reasons are obvious from the title, viz., Das Erste Buck, Von 
 dem Chriitenthum an sich selhst, wie es wider die Atheisten, Deisten und
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SKCKFADORFF 95 
 
 getic for religion as formulated in the Augsburg Confession. 
 Seckcmlorff states in his Preface that belief in this body of 
 doctrine was handed down to him from ancestors who gave 
 their adherence to it during the lifetime of Luther. It has its 
 chief interest not as an interpretation of Lutheranism. For 
 that we should go to the theologians. It has merely a second- 
 ary value as a statesman's attempt to commend Lutheranism 
 primarily to men of his own class. It is a document of more 
 significance for the religious than for the cameralistic side of 
 German experience. ' 
 
 The second book sets forth the ways in which true religion, 
 as expounded in the previous book, should be applied in the 
 reform of civic conduct. 2 Seckendorff recurs to a division of 
 citizens which he often employs, viz., the spiritual, the secular, 
 and the domestic strata. 3 He admits that in a way the third 
 of these strata includes the others. For this reason he discusses 
 it first. 
 
 Heuchler, durch ausserliche Griinde zu behaupten, und worinnen es inge- 
 mein bestehe. Of course this whole theological background must have 
 its full reckoning in a calculus of the various social factors of the period. 
 It must be kept in mind as the ultimate sanction to which the principles 
 of statecraft were referred by the cameralists in Lutheran states, as a 
 parallel sanction was appealed to in states which adopted other confes- 
 sions. We simply cannot consider it here in detail. 
 
 1 Among the curiosities of this chapter is an argument for the exist- 
 ence of God based on an ad hominem appeal to the current belief in the 
 existenreof ghosts. "Whosoever admits the existence of spirits, must 
 also admit God as the supreme and highest spirit." The plausibility 
 of the argument was also derived in part from the double meaning of 
 the word Geiat. 
 
 3 Das Andere Buck, Von der Verbesserung der Stdnde nach dem 
 (,'rund des Christenthums und dessen Haupt-Zwecks, nemlich der wahren 
 und ewigen GlUckseligkeil, insonderheit aber von Verbesserung des Haus- 
 Slandes, wie auch des weltlichen Regiments. 
 
 3 "Den Geistlichen, Weltlichen und Haus-Stand" The problem 
 which the word "Stand" in this sense always presents to the English 
 translator is only partially solved by the rendering "stratum."
 
 g6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 He distinctly formulates the purpose of this second book 
 in this way: "To show that all strata would be most surely 
 reformed according to the rule of Christianity and its chief 
 purpose." His initial aim is to show that if this reform should 
 first take place in domestic life it would make all other civic 
 improvement easier. 
 
 The argument proceeds from this premise (p. 188): 
 
 The happiness of the domestic stratum, or of each separate human 
 being, regardless of accidental social status, is to be sought approxi- 
 mately in this, that one may have health, food, clothing, and other 
 comforts and necessities of life; then further, according to circum- 
 stances of age and time, that he may marry well, beget children, 
 live long, and come to no exceptional end. To this must be added 
 the common civic well-being [bttrgerliche Wolfarth], the freedom or 
 right to associate with his own, to be thereby in appropriate respect 
 or honor, also to enjoy peace and protection against wrong and 
 violence. 
 
 One is reminded that certain familiar traits of human nature 
 are not modern inventions, by a reflection which follows this 
 schedule, viz.: 
 
 Most people seek to fix the blame and to locate the cause of evils 
 and misfortunes at the wrong point. Each is more ready to blame 
 another than himself. Hence arise envy, hatred, hostility, resistance 
 and embitterment against those who live in better fortune, especially 
 against government. 
 
 All sorts of impotent complaints, the author adds, are 
 accordingly lodged against rulers, and at last against God, 
 while people ought rather to ask themselves whether they are 
 themselves in any way the authors of their own troubles. 
 Then follows homely exhortation, in the name of religion, to 
 observe commonplace rules of prudence in connection with 
 body and estate. These rules are urged as having a peculiarly 
 Christian content and force, to be sure, but that fact does not 
 affect the essential purport and tendency of the argument.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 97 
 
 The fundamental prudence of good bodily habits, of temper- 
 ance, of frugality, are presented in their proper relations to 
 subsequent conditions of happiness. 
 
 Then follows an equally judicious chapter on the domestic 
 virtues. With mere changes of detail in the illustrations, it 
 would serve fairly well as the syllabus of a lecture, or indeed 
 of a series of lectures, in a modern sociological course on the 
 family. 
 
 The argument then passes to the second of the "strata," 
 but it would be more in accordance with later usage to say 
 that the rest of the book amounts to a treatise on practical 
 Christian ethics in the social as distinguished from the individ- 
 ual phases of conduct, and of course with the theology of the 
 Augsburg Confession as the constant presupposition. With 
 very crude grouping and analysis of the kinds of activity treated, 
 the discussion in a way covers the whole range of conduct in 
 the state, as it presented itself to Seckendorff's understanding. 
 
 The first main proposition is to the effect that all the difficul- 
 ties encountered in civic life come from spurious Christianity. 
 Beginning with enumeration of types of petty neighborhood 
 quarrels, and pointing out their departure from Christian pre- 
 cepts and ideals, the author treats in a similar way the grosser 
 vices and crimes. Incidentally, and by departing rather 
 obviously from his text, he introduces in the fifth chapter an 
 excursus of more interest for our purpose than his proper argu- 
 ment. It is an observation bearing on the doctrine of popula- 
 tion, and seems to have only a forced relation to the context. 
 He says: 
 
 When one however undertakes to speak of the common means 
 of support and the freedom of citizens, and of the measures necessary 
 for improving their condition in these respects, a considerable differ- 
 ence must be taken into account between countries: for the situation 
 is of one sort in the case of those which derive their ordinary support 
 from agriculture, and of another sort with those that are devoted to
 
 98 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 trade and commerce, particularly to navigation. Because less of 
 the latter exists in Germany, than in other regions, we have the more 
 occasion to speak of the other sort. We must know, therefore, that 
 under ordinary circumstances each region can properly maintain only 
 so many people jrom its own resources as can gel their means of support 
 jrom its yield. For example, if we consider a village which has only 
 arable land enough for the cultivation of ten plows, no more than 
 that number of peasants or teamsters can profitably live there, but 
 the others must get their living by artisanship, or get a chance to 
 work outside the boundaries of the locality. If this does not occur, 
 each hinders the others, or there is a scarcity of support. There 
 can also be no more handworkers in the locality than these peasants 
 need, etc. (p. 243). 
 
 In this paragraph the author seems to be distinctly on the 
 trail of the law of diminishing returns. He certainly does not 
 squint toward the conception of population which has been 
 attributed to the cameralists of the following century. We shall 
 see that his successors were also much more intelligent on this 
 subject than tradition has testified. 
 
 After expanding the propositions quoted, Seckendorff ap- 
 proaches the moral which he wishes to enforce, in this way: 
 
 Where the Christian doctrine has been accepted, and ecclesiastics 
 and especially monks have been introduced, from the better culti- 
 vated and improved countries, Italy, France, England, etc., also 
 the police, or the more comfortable and at the same time more expen- 
 sive mode of life, a change has taken place in all localities which could 
 not be properly supervised or controlled, especially because of the 
 many magistracies, but it was allowed in many respects to take its 
 own course. Accordingly no one understands why a given occupa- 
 tion flourishes in a given locality, whether from some particular 
 natural advantage, or from special skill on the part of the inhabitants. 
 The present purpose is to urge that the people chose their course of 
 life almost entirely without reflection, and as a consequence they 
 
 do not succeed in spite of diligence Christianity comes in 
 
 to improve this state of things, by laying down certain rules about 
 livelihood, and especially about moderation.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKEXDOR1-T 99 
 
 The point of interest about this argument, for our purpose, 
 is not the strength or weakness of the reasoning, but the evi- 
 dence it contains as to the views of the official class at this 
 period about the appropriate aims of government. However 
 practical men or theorists arranged their aims in the relation 
 of means and end, the physical and moral well-being of the 
 population governed was a definite and positive purpose. In 
 the minds of the same men, religion was also both an end and 
 a means with reference to individual as well as governmental 
 welfare. It is not our affair to criticize the crudeness and the 
 confusion in their reasonings about religion, and about its 
 relation to morals and government. The main thing is that 
 they actually recognized desiderata, with some common sanc- 
 tions of religion, of philosophy, of prudential and political 
 expediency, which positively prescribed moral ideals both for 
 governments and for individuals. These standards of moral 
 value and obligation, which stood for partially developed 
 interests in German populations, were factors, weaker or 
 stronger, in shaping both official and popular programmes 
 throughout the cameralistic period. While other interests 
 were in a sense paramount, these elementary, and in a sense 
 ultimate, human interests were always perceptibly or imper- 
 ceptibly in the balance along with other considerations of state, 
 and their actual importance, as compared with the interests 
 of rulers as a distinct class, never long at a time ceased to gain 
 an increasing ratio of influence. 
 
 It is characteristic of the lack of system in social ideas at 
 Seckendorff's time that from the remarks just quoted he passes 
 immediately to discussion of the sin of tax-dodging, as we now 
 phrase it, and of evading military service in the just wars which 
 Christianity does not disapprove. This leads to discussion of 
 the Christian ethics of conduct in war, and evils both govern- 
 mental and individual are enumerated and condemned in 
 considerable detail.
 
 ioo THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 In the sixth chapter of this book, the author, with a slight 
 departure from the classification which he made at the outset, 
 enters upon discussion of the ethics of the governing stratum. 
 He at once acknowledges the delicacy of the subject. He says: 
 
 This is a dangerous and difficult matter: partly because inborn 
 human perversity provides that no one hears the truth more impa- 
 tiently than those who have the power to ignore it, and to insult 
 those who present it; partly because, on the other hand, it is a duty 
 to avoid speaking of the failings of rulers in such a way as to stir 
 up hatred and scorn and even rebellion among citizens toward those 
 rulers who try to act as true Christians (p. 255). 
 
 The wise suggestion is made in this connection that preach- 
 ers would often do better to send to rulers in writing their 
 complaints about bad government, than to utter them in the 
 pulpit, in the presence of those who least need to hear them, 
 and in the absence of those who should be concerned with them 
 most. At the same time Seckendorff betrays very plain symp- 
 toms of the prevailing tendency to demand that true Christian 
 subjects shall renounce all claim to a right of bringing direct 
 pressure to bear on rulers if their government is oppressive. 
 The only recourse which his philosophy and theology fully 
 sanction is prayer to God, that He might soften the heart and 
 instruct the mind of the delinquent sovereign. On the other 
 hand, the appeal which Seckendorff makes to rulers to observe 
 the obligations of religion in their conduct of government, puts 
 the final emphasis not on considerations of justice, and the 
 rights of the subject, but on the rulers' hopes of eternal happi- 
 ness (p. 259). 
 
 However we may appraise the force or validity of the sanc- 
 tions upon which Seckendorff 's political ethic relied, he cer- 
 tainly outlined a relatively exacting standard of governmental 
 conduct. It began with the obligation of setting a Christian 
 example to subjects, in personal habits, on the principle of 
 noblesse oblige, and covered the whole range of governmental
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 101 
 
 activities. Seckendorff plainly asserts (p. 266) that Christian- 
 ity puts the origin of ruling authority beyond question. Thus: 
 The ruling class is ordained of God, although in certain places 
 human means, such as election or investiture, are instrumental in 
 attaining that position, and the specific duties of government arc to 
 be learned from the light of reason, and cannot be found in revela- 
 tion or the Holy Scriptures. When a sovereign therefore according 
 to custom writes "by the grace of God," that is no vain title. It 
 shows rather in part the sovereignty [Hoheit], and in part the duty: 
 the sovereignty because of sitting in the place of God, and having 
 to conduct the office according to the divine order. Hence rulers, 
 as such, are accountable first of all to God, and may also hope for 
 his protection. This their sovereignty they may use for the suppres- 
 sion of seditious thoughts of subjects, when the latter presume to 
 override the rulers. The duty may be learned from the considera- 
 tion that, because they are ordained by the grace of God, rulers are 
 bound to conform to the divine law, and thus to promote the welfare 
 of the people committed to them, and also to observe and fulfill 
 what is promised according to the ancient usage of the land and 
 
 people And although in the fewest places external means 
 
 of compulsion are to be practiced, and thus a ruler, if he disregards 
 his capitulary or his promise, sins before God alone, and is liable 
 to no investigation by his subjects, yet the fear of God will sufficiently, 
 and more than any external compulsion, restrain him, and he will 
 regard those who advise him in a contrary way, and would release 
 him from all laws, as wicked counselors, yes, as tools of the devil. 
 What is true of these high magistrates, who are subordinated to no 
 other human power, is true also in its degree of subordinate rulers, etc. 
 
 In the following chapter (vii) the author expands the above 
 theorems about the authority of rulers by going elaborately 
 into the biblical and especially the Pauline doctrine of the 
 relation of rulers to other Christians. In chap, viii, however, 
 he returns to the other side of the case, and argues with equal 
 energy that 
 
 At last rulers attain salvation in one and the same way as other 
 Christians, i. e., by Christian faith, the fruits of which are love and
 
 102 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 a pious life. There is only one, and that the straight and narrow 
 way, through which is the entrance into life Just as the poor- 
 est peasant, so also the greatest king, must attain salvation. Every- 
 thing which people of high degree claim for themselves as emancipa- 
 tion, exemption, and privilege, is sheer deception, and those who 
 help them to these imaginings are their guides and companions 
 toward destruction. 
 
 Upon this doctrinal basis, exhibit of specific duties is con- 
 tinued; thus, further duties of setting worthy examples to 
 subjects, for instance, in checking drunkenness and neglect 
 of attendance at divine worship by members of the court; 
 duties of the positive sort, such as promoting the progress of 
 true religion among the subjects; in particular the duty not 
 merely of protecting the institutions of religion but of laying 
 down rules of church government. Christian rulers should 
 reform evils in the church and the clergy. 
 
 This duty belongs especially to those Protestant princes who 
 took upon themselves the prerogatives of Episcopus in externis, 
 and who administer the other jura Episcopalia, which the bishops 
 alone previously administered, either in person or through their 
 Officiates, through certain appointed and sworn persons called 
 Consistoriales or Superintendents (merely other names for bishops). 
 
 On the other hand, it is urged as the duty of rulers to refrain 
 from prescribing articles of faith for their subjects, even when 
 the bishops agree thereto; the duty of abolishing unnecessary 
 display in church worship is expounded; the importance of 
 sound learning and the reading of good books by rulers is 
 emphasized. At the close of the chapter, subjects are exhorted 
 to observe the duties of true Christians in all these matters, 
 even if rulers fail in any of these respects. 
 
 Chap, x develops the author's ideas of Christian duty with 
 respect to all sorts of situations before, during, and in conse- 
 quence of war. It begins with the premise that peace is a 
 good much to be desired, and its preservation is the first work
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 103 
 
 of government. Nevertheless, righteous war being permissible 
 and necessary, it is the duty of governments properly to prepare 
 for it and to carry it on as far as possible in accordance with 
 the behests of religion. The implications of this doctrine are 
 developed with considerable detail. The evils of war are 
 frankly admitted, and remedies pointed out in better observance 
 of Christian precepts. It is urged that "true and right bravery 
 in war must spring from Christian courage, by reason of the 
 assurance of a good conscience, and of a better life after death" 
 (p. 346). Eleven clauses from the imperial articles of war are 
 quoted, to show that Christian principles are recognized as 
 part of the law of the land for soldiers. 1 The chapter contains 
 also an argument for the reinstitution of universal military 
 duty; an essay, in twenty-seven sections, on organization and 
 discipline of a military establishment so created; and concludes 
 that the proposed scheme would lead to successful ending of 
 war with the Turks, and efficient conduct of all necessary 
 minor wars. 
 
 Chap, xi applies the test of Christian doctrine to the duties 
 of magistrates in administering justice; chap, xii, to miscel- 
 laneous relations of government to subjects, as in excessive 
 taxation, in infringement upon proper liberty, in luxurious 
 living at the expense of subjects, in experimenting with alchemy 
 and other magic arts, in manipulating the coinage, in traffic 
 in public offices, and in establishing monopolies. 
 
 The last chapter of this second book returns to one of the 
 initial presumptions of German civic theory, namely, that 
 the government is bound to -perform the functions of a presid- 
 ing genius over the general welfare of subjects. At the same 
 time it reiterates a theorem which in some form and force or 
 other plays its part in all the cameralistic systems. The chapter 
 begins with a brief expression of both these ideas to this effect : 
 
 1 1. e., from "des Heil Romischen Reichs Reuter-Bcstallung, Anno 
 S7o" (p. 330.
 
 104 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 From Christianity, or from Christian love, flows the provision 
 of God-fearing rulers that their subjects shall have all possible encour- 
 agement and success in their livelihood and occupations, that their 
 numbers shall increase rather than diminish, because the greatest 
 treasure of the country consists in the number of well-nourished 
 people; and to that end not merely external peace and the moderation 
 of the governing power in collecting taxes, etc., are useful, .... 
 but every other good institution which governments may adopt 
 whereby means of livelihood may be assured to the people, and 
 multiplied in reliable ways, for the more important Christian pur- 
 pose that they may have something to give to the needy and thus 
 may be and remain able to provide for the support of the community 
 [Gemeinen Wesens] and the care of the poor and the needy. 
 
 In the spirit of this introduction, the chapter concludes 
 this division of the author's system of ethics with brief reference 
 to the duties of rulers toward vagrants and other forbidden 
 types, such as gypsies, beggars, etc.; toward promotion of 
 profitable occupations through good police organization; 
 toward moderation of duties and imports; toward encourage- 
 ment of manufactures and commerce; toward selection of 
 competent officials for dealing with these subjects: and two 
 closing sections contain further warnings to subjects about their 
 own delinquencies in commerce and artisanship, with praises 
 of peasants, artisans, and soldiers for their relatively faithful 
 observance of Christian duty, and a final appeal to the self- 
 interest of rulers to guard the welfare of these lower classes. 
 
 The third book hews much less closely to the lines of the 
 original plan than the other two. Its title is On the Spiritual 
 Stratum and Its Reform in Particular. The author's treatment 
 of the ethics of his two other divisions of activity leads to the 
 expectation that he will follow the same model with reference 
 to the clergy. Instead of this, the book deals with every sort 
 of question which could concern people with ecclesiastical 
 interests at the period of its publication. It has sections which 
 would have to be classed in turn as exegesis, church history,
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SECKENDORFF 105 
 
 dogmatic theology, homiletics, pastoral duties, clerical ethics, 
 religious pedagogy, the theory of missions, and church polity. 
 It deals briefly with the education of women. In so far as it 
 touches clerical ethics, it is on the same general basis as the 
 earlier books. The most notable fact is the degree to which 
 the relation of the church to the secular government is slurred 
 over. If one knew nothing of Seckendorff's writings beyond 
 this book, the most obvious inference would be that he had in 
 mind an ecclesiastical organization practically identical with 
 that of the Protestant Episcopal church in the United States, and 
 as independent of the civil government. There are passages, 
 e. g., pp. 705 ff., from which one familiar with his previous 
 writings would immediately supply the necessary connections 
 of these details with his whole theory of government. I have 
 found no other passage in the whole succession of came- 
 ralistic authors which treats of ecclesiastical questions with so 
 little reference to the relations with the political administration. 1 
 A more general comparison than that of one cameralist 
 with another may help to interpret the authors in this group. 
 In one particular not yet referred to Seckendorff was typical 
 of all the cameralists. It may be stated by contrast with Adam 
 Smith. The latter was plainly a philosopher first, and inciden- 
 tally an economist. 2 The cameralists were first and last theo- 
 retical or practical administrators. They betray almost no 
 consciousness that their technique runs back to problems of 
 a fundamental philosophy. The exceptions to this rule are in 
 the form of barkings back to religious premises. According 
 to their ecclesiastical connections, they pay more or less per- 
 functory tribute to popular Catholic or Protestant religious 
 
 1 Seckendorff's Vier und vierzig TetUsche Reden, and PolUische und 
 moralische Discurse uber dreyhundert auserlesene lehrreiche Spriiche des 
 Lucani, I have not been able to obtain. 
 
 3 Vide Small, Adam Smith and Modern Sociology, pp. 9, 27, 32, 65, 
 et passim.
 
 106 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 doctrine. The allusions hardly go deeper, however, than to 
 phases of doctrine which might have been derived merely from 
 their pre-confirmation instruction. In short, cameralistics 
 was primarily a system of and for the bureau. It had only 
 indirect and remote affiliations with the academy. We shall 
 find that this fact was a very serious obstacle to the progress 
 of cameralism as a university subject. Dithmar and Stisser 
 will furnish typical evidence. 
 
 In this sketch, then, we have presented first of all the con- 
 ception of a ruler by divine right, and of the government which 
 he should maintain, as it was put into literary form by one of 
 the men best entitled to speak for the system. The sketch 
 is of chief value for this initial element. The secondary fea- 
 tures of the regime, although in the germ in Seckendorff's 
 doctrines, will appear in more mature form in the descriptions 
 of later cameralists.
 
 CHAPTER V 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF BKCHER 
 
 The cameralistic series next includes three men, Becher, 
 Hornick, and Schroder, whose chief contribution to the theory 
 was on its mercantilistic side. To the first and third of these 
 men a chapter will be devoted. Since it has proved impossible 
 to make a first-hand study of Hornick, his place in the develop- 
 ment of cameralism will be indicated more briefly. 
 
 Johann Joachim Becher was born at Speier in 1635. He 
 died in London in 1682. He was the supposed originator of 
 the chemical "phlogiston theory." In the midst of the 
 material and spiritual ruin which followed the Thirty Years' 
 War, struggling against great difficulties, he became a self- 
 taught man of no mean attainments in several directions. He 
 is said to have supported himself, as well as, for a time, his 
 mother and two brothers, by serving as an informer. At the 
 age of nineteen he published a monograph, De lapide tris- 
 megisto; six years later, a Metallurgia; in 1661, a L'niversal- 
 sprache, etc. Then he entered into negotiations with the 
 Palatine elector about establishment of various factories in 
 Mannheim; later, with the elector of Bavaria about founda- 
 tion of a German colony in Guiana, a West Indian colony, etc. ; 
 further, about the introduction of a Commercien collegium, and 
 other administrative devices. In 1666 he was teacher of medi- 
 cine and body physician of the elector of Mainz, but in the same 
 year went to Vienna as Commercienrath. He was sent to 
 Holland on an imperial errand, and in 1667 wrote in ten days 
 (?) his Methodus didactica; and soon afterward, Regeln dcr 
 christlichen Bundesgenossemchaft, his chief cameralistic work, 
 if it may properly be so designated. Meantime he had an 
 appointment as body physician and chemist in electoral Bavaria 
 
 107
 
 io8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and here appeared his Physica Subterranea sen Acta Labora- 
 torii Monacensis. In the same year he acquired a feudal title 
 for the Count of Hanau to 3,000 square miles of land between 
 the Oronoco and the Amazon, and published a Griindlicher 
 Bericht in description of the region. The plan was to form 
 a "High German West Indian Company." Nothing ever 
 came of it. In 1670 Becher was called to Vienna in connec- 
 tion with a silk company and other enterprises, tncidentally, 
 while his personal affairs were developing poorly, he dashed 
 off a programme for setting the world to rights, in the mono- 
 graphs Psychosophia and Einladung zu einer psychologischen 
 Societal. A location for a demonstrative experiment under 
 the latter head was expected from the bounty of the duke of 
 Giistrow (1674). In 1675 Becher wrote Theses chemicas 
 veritatem trans wntationibus metallorum evincentis, and experi- 
 mented in Vienna on extracting gold from the sands of the 
 Danube. His most practical occupation seems to have been 
 at this period as head of a so-called Manufacturhaus in Vienna, 
 an institution supported by the government. He fell into 
 disfavor, went to Holland, sold to the city of Harlem a machine 
 for winding silk, and tried to get the Dutch government inter- 
 ested in his attempts to get gold from sand. The enmity of 
 Count Zinzendorf, which had cut short his stay in Vienna, still 
 pursued him, and he went to England in 1680. The imperial 
 ambassador tried to obstruct his plans here, but the body 
 physician Dickinson gave him money, and he went to Scotland 
 to study mines for Prince Ruprecht von der Pfalz. It is said 
 that he wrote his Narrische Weisheit und weisse Narrheit in 
 the twenty-eight days (?) while he was on the water making 
 this trip. He returned to London in 1682, and died in 
 October of that year. 1 
 
 While Becher's influence upon cameralism was somewhat 
 indirect, it was actual, and must therefore be duly credited. 
 
 1 Vide Oppenheim, in All. d. Bib., in loc.; vide Roscher, pp. 270 ff.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 109 
 
 He cannot be called in the full sense a cameralist. It is even 
 doubtful if he ever regarded himself in that light at all. 1 This 
 matter of labels, however, is not important. Whatever may 
 have been the differences between Becher and the more typical 
 cameralists, he added something to the content of a theory 
 which at last had a recognized place for his type of interest. 
 
 While Becher's title to classification as a cameralist is 
 questionable, his moral rating is still more dubious. Some of 
 his vicissitudes were more his misfortune than his fault, to be 
 sure, as for example when he was ostracized at Wiirzburg for 
 dissecting the body of a woman who had been executed. He 
 was nowhere in the favor of the clergy. The merchants 
 disliked him for his activities in promoting the theory of the 
 organization of trading companies. He lost his standing in the 
 Palatinate by the failure of a perpetual-motion scheme, and 
 he made himself ridiculous among scholars by a book which 
 promised to teach all Haushaltungskunst in twenty-four hours. 2 
 Taken in connection with odious personal traits, Becher's 
 individual and professional equation has simply the permanent 
 value for our purposes of a factor in establishing a technical 
 tradition. 
 
 Becher's most memorable cameralistic work was published 
 in i668. 3 Its place in the cameralistic series is entirely different 
 from that of Seckendorff. Indeed, as we have seen, it can only 
 by accommodation of terms be said to have had a place in the 
 series. Each petty German state had its little army of func- 
 
 1 Vide Dixcurs, p. 38, 11. 23, 24. 
 
 1 " Kluger Hausvater, verstdndige Hausmutter, vollkommencr Land- 
 Medicus, wie auch erfahrener Ross- und Vieharzt." 
 
 3 D. Johann Joachim Bechers von Speyer, Rom. Kiiyserl. Majcstiit 
 Commercien-Raths Politische Discurs von den eigentlichen Ursachen des 
 Auff- und Abnehmens der Stddt Lander und Republicken. "In specie: 
 Wie ein Land Volckreich und Nahrhafft zu machen, und in eine rechte 
 Societatem civilem zu bringen. Auch wird von dem Bauren- Handwercks- 
 und Kauffmanns-Standt derer Handel und Wandel, Item, von dem
 
 no THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tioning cameralists, the hierarchies of the bureaus. Few of 
 them wrote books, but in some particulars such a sorry sub- 
 stitute for a book as this miscellaneous collection of Bee her 
 better reflects what they were doing and thinking than the 
 more systematic treatises. Becher's Discurs contains no direct 
 internal evidence that the author had ever heard of Seckendorff . 
 It seems to be the record of the impression made upon an unsys- 
 tematic mind by contact with the workings of bureaucracy 
 in various capitals. 1 
 
 In the dedication to the emperor Leopold, dated September 
 i, 1672, Becher asserts that his reasons for the dedication were 
 three: first, that the book was largely written while the author 
 was on the imperial civil list, and that the material was largely 
 collected in the course of that service; second, because enemies 
 had scattered the slander that the author was of no visible 
 use in the imperial service, and the book would be an answer 
 to the charge; third, because enemies who were identical with 
 the enemies of the German Roman Empire and of the imperial 
 house had attacked the author for addressing the common 
 German Fatherland in plain vernacular German, instead of 
 academic Latin. 
 
 Monopolio, Polypolio uml Propolio, von allgemeinen Lanrl-Magazinen, 
 Niedcrlagen, KaufT-Hiiusern, Montibus Pietatis, Zucht- und Werck- 
 Hiiusern, Wechselbancken uml dergleichen ausftihrlich gehandelt. 
 Dritte Edition, mit vier Theilen vermehret, worinnen viel niitzlichc, 
 
 wi( hligc und curiosc Sachcn begriffen. Franckfurt M.DC.LX- 
 
 XXVIII." I have used only this third edition. The first is dated 1668. 
 
 1 As a sample of judgments passed upon Becher in less critical scien- 
 tific periods than ours, we may cite estimates quoted by Rose her from 
 Zinckc's Leipziger Sammlungen (1758). Becher is spoken of as "the 
 first reformer of German systems of artisanship, manufacture, trade, 
 Polizei, and finance." Of the Discurs, the same author says: "almost 
 to the present time the only fundamental book which can be used in a 
 certain degree as introduction to Stadtwirthschaft and its Policei system" 
 (Roschcr, p. 435).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 1 1 1 
 
 Becher adds that he may be reproached for the presumption 
 of dedicating to the emperor a hook which contains discussions 
 of commercial affairs, with which nobility has nothing to do. 
 The reply is that his majesty is not expected to concern himself 
 directly with such subjects, but the book is designed to bring 
 more clearly before his eyes the fact that the commercial 
 classes are contributing to the population and wealth of the 
 country, and that ways and means of establishing a populous 
 and self-sustaining community are the most suitable subject- 
 matter of a political policy. 
 
 In the Preface to the second edition Becher refers to the 
 contents of the book as Commercien Materien. He must be 
 interpreted, therefore, in contrast with Seckendorff, as making 
 the interests of trade his point of departure. While Becher 
 was thus concerned only secondarily with the theory of admin- 
 istrative organization in general, it is no less true of him than 
 of the other cameralists that the test to which he would bring 
 all commercial questions was their relation to the interests of 
 the state as represented by the government. 
 
 Becher goes on to say that, although the first edition found 
 many enemies, and was in several places forbidden by the 
 clergy, yet it was soon entirely sold. It appears that the imme- 
 diate cause of the enmity of the clergy was an innocent quotation 
 upon the title-page from the jurist Calvinus. It was assumed 
 that John Calvin was the author quoted, and that the book 
 must contain Protestant poison 1 
 
 Perhaps the most significant clause in this preface is that 
 in which the author anticipates charges of partisanship. The 
 implication is that the book contains, perhaps the author would 
 even have said it is, a commercial programme. Such a pro- 
 gramme is open to misconstruction or to disapproval from 
 many sides. It will wholly please no party. To the non- 
 Catholics it will seem to be too strongly imperial or Spanish 
 in its leanings; to the Catholics it will appear too favorable
 
 112 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to Holland, etc. Bccher protests, however, that he has intro- 
 duced d(K.-umcnls into the collection rather as samples of vari- 
 ous sorts of instruments, than because he approves the policies 
 in the course of which the documents were executed. He 
 continues: "The sole end of this new edition is on my part 
 to give the reader a formulary of various transactions and politi- 
 cal concepts which serve the welfare of the state " (des gemeinen 
 H'Mcn.v). 1 Further expressions in the Preface emphasize the 
 fact that the hook was written in an atmosphere thick with petty 
 political strifes. Prejudice and suspicion would construe it 
 as a party pamphlet, whether it was so intended or not. Under 
 such circumstances, neither the author nor his public could 
 take an objective and critical attitude toward the abstract 
 questions involved. The book attempted to deal with public 
 policy, primarily commercial, as a matter of pure theory. It 
 was in spite of itself to a large degree a discussion of immediate 
 policies. In drawing conclusions about its contents, caution 
 must accordingly always be observed against generalizing 
 specific conclusions into universal doctrines. Becher did not 
 undertake to present a complete social philosophy. His pur- 
 pose must be gathered from his own professions. " It is enough 
 for me to have done what belongs to an upright German man, 
 namely, conscientiously and faithfully to have served the Ger- 
 man Fatherland and its head, the Roman Imperial Majesty." 
 
 Becher begins the first section of his introduction with this 
 preamble and definition: 
 
 Since I am now to make a beginning of showing wherein the 
 prosperity of a land or of a state consists, I must necessarily at the 
 outset call to mind that man, as the material of the Republic, is an 
 animal sociabile, and seeks society, as the sacred text itself says, "It 
 is not good that man should live alone." In order that he may have 
 a society, other and more men are necessary, and that these may be 
 
 1 Reasons for this rendering will be assigned in connection with 
 Justi's employment of the same phrase. Vide below, p. 299.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 113 
 
 born God has created the female sex and ordained marriage, the 
 end of which is to be fruitful and replenish the earth. I must call 
 to mind further that, next to reason, human society alone distinguishes 
 the life of man from that of the beasts, which society is solely and 
 alone the fundamental cause, beginning, means, and end of all laws 
 and ordinances which men, both pagans and Christians, have made 
 
 for the preservation of this society If then I were rightly 
 
 to define a state I should call it a populous, sel) -supporting community 
 [eine volckreiche nahrhajte Gemein}. 
 
 The two chief elements in the concept are then expanded 
 in turn, to the effect that, on the one hand, unless a community 
 is populous it cannot defend itself, but must be the prey of every 
 enemy; and on the other hand, that a populous community 
 is impossible unless sufficient means of support are at command. 
 The idea is also emphasized that the people in a community 
 furnish one another mutual support. They live on one another. 
 "When the members of a community arrange their affairs so 
 that the one lives from the other, the one can earn his piece 
 of bread from the other, yes that the one plays his support into 
 the hand of the other, that is the right community." 1 Becher 
 accordingly concludes that the community is the third person 
 of a trinity, people, sustenance, community : 
 
 For where the latter exists, there will be no lack of people and 
 sustenance; where this is disturbed \yerstimmt}, however, there will 
 be nothing but hatred, enmity, persecution, oppression of the poor, 
 exaltation of the rich, rebellion, and finally impoverishment and 
 total ruin. Accordingly, just as when one is to play on a violin one 
 must first examine and tune each string, so when its sustenance is 
 to be assured to a community, attention must certainly be paid to 
 every sort of human being that is there, and nothing appears to me 
 more remarkable than that in many places no thought whatever is 
 given to these most difficult points. Each is left to get his living as 
 
 1 It would be unkind to ask Socratic questions of this wisdom. 
 Why not let such simplicity alone and not invent the historical fiction 
 that it is to be understood as political economy I
 
 114 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 he may; whether he is ruined and ruins a hundred others with him, 
 or he prospers, with the common gain or loss, prosperity or adver- 
 sity, no one asks any questions. Because this is the crucial point, 
 however, I will do my best to consider and dissect [anatomiren] the 
 members of the community ^ in respect to the way in which they 
 should work with each other in the matter of support, I will try then 
 to put them together, and to form them into a political skeleton 
 [sceleton politicum], 
 
 In the second section the analysis continues: 
 
 There are necessarily two sorts of people in a community: the 
 first, the majority, the second who are the servants of the former, 
 and here is included the magistracy [Obrigkeit], which is a servant 
 of the community, and holds the people in good order and social 
 regulation, so that one may live by the side of another, because the 
 community is not for the sake of the magistracy, but the magistracy 
 for the sake of the community. .Also the clergy are the servants of 
 the community in protecting the soul, the learned who protect the 
 mind [Gemiith], the physicians, apothecaries, barbers, bathers, who 
 guard the health, the soldiers who guard the body and the whole 
 state and land. All these are servants of the community, and 
 although they help to increase and maintain the societatem civilem, 
 they are still not the community itself, but as stated only servants 
 of the same, who must be paid and supported by the community, 
 and hence, in order that they may not become burdensome to the 
 community, they should be made proportional by the community, 
 that they should be neither too many nor too few. For if there are 
 more Bur germeister than citizens in a city, more preachers and con- 
 fessors than hearers and penitents, more schoolmasters than pupils, 
 more doctors than patients, more soldiers than citizens and peasants, 
 
 more nobles than subjects, that land is in bad shape The 
 
 other sort of people, who essentially constitute the civic society 
 [societatem civilem essentialiter constituirn], are those of whom the 
 society most consists, because there are most of them in the society. 
 Such men now, whose servants the former are, may properly be 
 divided into three orders. The first is the largest, namely, the peas- 
 ant order, the second is the handicraft order, the third is the trades-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECHER 115 
 
 man's order. The last is the smallest order While the peas- 
 ant order is the most numerous, it is also the most necessary 
 
 In the peasant order there are various classes Hence the 
 
 infallible rule, Where there is no peasant, the handicraftsman has 
 no material to work over, and where nothing is worked over there the 
 tradesman can have nothing to sell; moreover, while the peasant 
 cultivates the field, he cannot be at home, and while the handicrafts- 
 man works at home, he cannot run about and sell his wares, and 
 while the tradesman does this he cannot be a peasant or a handi- 
 craftsman. Hence follows the undoubted conclusion, These three 
 orders should not be mixed together, but it should be possible for 
 them to stand close together and to make a real community; that 
 is, to support each other, for where this occurs, .... the object 
 of a proper Policey is attained, i. e., a respectable and necessary 
 human society. 
 
 Referring not to the cameralists in general, but to Becher in 
 particular, I cannot refrain from pointing out the resemblance of 
 the first part of this remarkable passage to a pearl in a swine's 
 snout. If we accept the gem as genuine, we must confess that 
 its occurrence at just this point is an unexplained sport of 
 nature. It seems to shed almost pure light of insight into 
 the vicarious character of human society. It is an ungrateful 
 task to inquire in this case if things really are as they seem, 
 but I find myself unable to accept these appearances at full 
 value. The evidence hardly warrants a theory in explanation 
 of ideas which seem to be so at variance with the conceptions 
 of the time. If I were to propose an explanation it would be 
 that this was merely imitation of pulpit conventionalities, and 
 repetition of a stilted form which was not vital with new insight 
 and had not even retained the spirit of the New Testament 
 doctrine of which it was a hollow echo. 
 
 I will add but a single query. If Becher actually saw that 
 society is a system of reciprocal services, if he saw that the 
 performance of functions for one another is that which makes 
 desirable citizens, and failure to perform such functions makes
 
 n6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the undesirable citizen, if he used the term "servant" as a digni- 
 fying epithet for citizens of the former class, by what reasoning 
 or association of ideas did he draw the line between the few 
 whom he classed as servants of society and the many whom 
 he left in the ignominious company of the served ? Until we 
 are instructed by what right the tiller of the soil and the artisan 
 and the tradesman are rated as essentially less serviceable 
 to their fellows than those who carry on the relatively non- 
 essential occupations, we must conclude that Becher's apparent 
 penetration must be held under suspicion as tawdry rhetorical 
 embellishment. 
 
 We come then to the body of the book, the first part of which 
 treats of "the form of the government, that is, of those who 
 rule and of those who assist them therein." We may repeat 
 that it is not our purpose to investigate the evolution of cam- 
 eralism. We are not attempting to make out the stages in the 
 elaboration of the system. We are not drawing specific com- 
 parisons between the programmes of administration outlined 
 by the successive writers, nor are we trying to appraise the 
 relative merits of their proposals as a governmental technique. 
 We are studying them in turn in order to be justified in present- 
 ing what they have in common as a typical attitude toward 
 social problems. We shall present that attitude as it seems 
 to be most characteristically defined in Justi. Our use of the 
 other writers is rather for the purpose of assembling features 
 which belong in a composite picture, than to distinguish degrees 
 of theoretical completeness or variations of technical detail. 
 We refer therefore to his table of contents for more specific 
 indications of Becher's analysis, and we confine our further 
 observations to a few items which may serve as shadings for 
 the picture. For this purpose we find the opening paragraph 
 available, viz.: 
 
 As concerns the first point, namely the kinds of civic authorities 
 [Obrigkeilen], five sorts are to be distinguished, first spiritual or
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECHER 117 
 
 secular. The proverb runs, "where parsons rule, there is no good 
 in the end." Because their government is not hereditary, their 
 aim is only to enrich their own, el fit pax in nostris diebus. If a war 
 comes, they make themselves scarce, after the manner of the hireling 
 in the gospel. A secular lord does not do this, for the sheep belong 
 to him, and since there is a succession, such rulers strive much more 
 for the conservation and the improvement of the land. 
 
 Here speaks the partisan, and he reflects one of the sharpest 
 contrasts of his day. The issue was in some respects more 
 acute in Catholic than in Protestant states. In the former, 
 the Reformation had agitated and modified, but had left the 
 social structure externally unchanged. There was accordingly 
 quite as much restiveness under clerical influence, and some- 
 times even more, than in the Protestant states, where the politi- 
 cal power of the clergy was assumed to have been broken. In 
 Catholic and Protestant states alike, the struggle between state 
 and church was not ended, but merely changed in detail. 
 Neither Catholic nor Protestant clergy were by any means 
 cured of their lust for power. Whether openly or covertly there 
 was almost everywhere antagonism between the two types of pre- 
 tension. In nearly every German state the antithesis between 
 the temporal and the spiritual power was as real if not as 
 evident a political factor as it had been when the immediate 
 form of the issue was Papacy or Anti-Papacy. So long and 
 so far as this conflict was undecided, the cameralism of a given 
 German state was in part one of the military arms of that secu- 
 larism which was still in battle array against ecclesiasticism. 
 
 With entire sang-froid as to co-ordination of categories, 
 Becher follows tradition in naming as the other types of gov- 
 ernment: third, aristocracy, fourth, democracy, fifth, a mixture 
 of these. 
 
 The basic theorem of Becher's cameralism is in the 
 proposition: 
 
 Monarchical government has the advantage over all the others,
 
 n8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and is the most usual. Indeed it is, so to speak, a duplicate of the 
 divine government, established in the Holy Scripture, accepted of 
 all nations, and very profitable for the community (p. 14). 
 
 The claim on which Bcchcr chiefly relics to support the 
 theorem is this: 
 
 A lord who has a succession is more concerned for his land and 
 people, and makes their interests more his own [halt bey ihncn slich] 
 than a government to which the sheep do not belong (sic). Con- 
 sequently a monarchical government is when a ruler has his own 
 land and people, and governs over them according to his own will 
 without interference and limitation [Einredcn und Massgebcn], but 
 has such rule in heredity. 1 
 
 In discussing the merits and demerits of the different types 
 of governments, Becher assembles a list of counts against 
 monarchy and aristocracy which modern democrats have 
 judged to be decisive. A sample of his quality may be cited 
 from the paragraph in which he disposes of democracy: 
 
 Namely, where the officials arc under obligation to account to 
 the subjects for their government, and the subjects, if they please, 
 are present in council, and contribute their best observations, also 
 see and hear the business that is transacted. But the lacks above 
 found in aristocracies arc also found in democracies. In addition 
 to those it must be mentioned specifically that in the democratic 
 government (sic) there is no respect for the authorities [der Obern], 
 by reason of the multitude there is no secrecy, by reason of the num- 
 ber of voices there is often an unskilful consultum, in a word, in this 
 sort of government occur too often factions, seditions and rebellions. 
 
 Having considered the pure governmental forms, Becher 
 discusses mixed forms under the two heads Monarchal (sic) 
 
 1 The parallel should be noted, for further use in other connections, 
 between the argument from succession in the case of monarchy and the 
 similar argument today in the case of property. The first stand taken 
 today against possible modification of our institutions of inheritance is on 
 essentially the same ground as that chosen by the defenders of monarchy 
 of the "benevolent despot" type. Is the ground more tenable in the 
 one case than in the other ?
 
 CAMEKALISTICS OF BECHER 119 
 
 and Aristocratic (pp. 16 ff.) and reaches almost the identical 
 judgment in favor of mixed monarchy which he expressed 
 four pages earlier in favor of pure monarchy, viz. : 
 
 Among all sorts of governments this mixed form retains the 
 preference, and is most in vogue in Europe. Indeed the Roman 
 Empire itself consists at this moment of such a government. The 
 Roman emperor is the supreme head, and presents a monarch. 
 The eight Electors are the Seniorrx Imperil, el Patrcs conseripli, 
 the princes, estates, and cities present as it were a democracy. All 
 these three parts secure themselves against one another. Thus 
 the electoral princes require of the emperor the capitulation, while 
 on the other hand they must take the oath of allegiance to him. 
 Princes, estates, and cities of the Empire also co-operate in both ways, 
 
 and enter into both the above forms of obligation This 
 
 mixed form of government then is the sole conscn-ation of the Roman 
 Empire, the guarantee that it will never be an absolulum purum irl 
 aristocraticum, or a Democraticitm Imperium, for if this should hap- 
 pen the remaining freedom would be at an end The mixed 
 
 form is thus the best, but it should be in supcrlath'o monarchical, 
 in comparative) aristocratic, and in positivo democratic. Hence it 
 is evident that the Roman emperor in this mixed government should 
 have the most to say, and that it would not be well if the imperial 
 sovereignty were too strictly held down by capitulations 
 
 One who had read Seckendorflf would instantly decide that in 
 this chapter he was dealing with an inferior order of mind. 
 There is no such discrimination here as that which we found 
 in Der Fursten Stoat between the king and the tyrant, although 
 we must confess that the earlier writer was as much in the dark 
 as the later about means of eliminating the one type and secur- 
 ing the other. I cannot believe that responsible statesmen, 
 or even strong thinkers of the academic type, could have 
 regarded this chapter seriously. It bears no marks of deriva- 
 tion from evidence which would have been likely to carry 
 weight with experienced men, even in that less exacting period. 
 It is a jumble of judgments about confused and unauthentic
 
 120 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 statements of fact. It shows no evidence of insight into the 
 contemporary meaning of the Roman Empire. It speaks of 
 government as though rtb more personal interests were con- 
 cerned than those of rulers on the one hand, and princes, estates, 
 and cities on the other. It is in short a schoolboyish essay on a 
 subject of which the elements were not comprehended by the 
 writer. It had approximately the same relation to the more 
 respectable contents of the book which we shall discover below 
 between the historical survey at the beginning of Justi's Staats- 
 wissenschaft and the portions of which he was competent to 
 speak from pertinent evidence. It was the perfunctory work 
 of a man retained by a type of government which he was bound 
 to support. 
 
 The second chapter (pp. 20 ff.) treats of the "qualities and 
 correlations of those who rule and those who serve the ruler." 
 The style suggests the hearsay quality of the so-called "society 
 novel," written by an author whose ideas of society are gained 
 through other novels or the newspapers and observation of 
 supposed representatives of society in public places. One 
 can hardly imagine that the ruling class could have had any 
 use for the book, except to promote its circulation among 
 those in whom rulers and their courtiers would like to inculcate 
 the notion that their superiors consulted such oracles. 
 
 For example, the first specification is ttyat a ruler 
 
 .... must before all things consider whether he has come legiti- 
 mately or illegitimately to his station, for upon this foundation he 
 may infallibly rest all his future weal or woe, and easily guess that 
 he who seizes at government by violence will also usually be expelled 
 by force and he whose cause is just will have God's help, though 
 all the world should be opposed. 
 
 A most edifying doctrine, but hardly likely to strike the 
 ruling classes as a novel variation of the stock formulas of the 
 preachers, or to exert great influence against the esoteric prac-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 121 
 
 tices of their kind. The second specification is a similar 
 platitude, viz.: 
 
 The magistracy must preserve order in its affairs, and must 
 observe a strict routine: i. e., not write letters when it is the time to 
 go to church, not hunt when a session of the council should be held, 
 etc., etc. 
 
 The third detail is one which a Louis XVI, for instance, 
 found it difficult to arrange, viz. : 
 
 A ruler must be sagacious, and himself understand the art of 
 governing, in order that he need not always believe the doctors. 
 There are sometimes rulers who are not sagacious, others are too 
 sagacious. The first do not know how to discriminate between 
 counsels, and must therefore follow all their advisers. The others 
 will never follow advice, and resort to compulsion whenever they 
 are opposed. 
 
 It does not seem to have occurred to Becher that, under 
 the regime in which he was employed, it would be just as logi- 
 cal for a writer on farming to specify the sorts of weather to 
 be desired. The specifications would have had as much com- 
 petence practically in the one case as in the other. 
 
 Fourth, some rulers are too diligent, others too indolent 
 
 Fifth, there are rulers who in their action and character are either 
 
 too deliberate or too hasty Sixth, sometimes rulers have too 
 
 short memories, and sometimes they remember grudges too long. 
 7i;' r i . Seventh, a ruler should be neither too credulous nor too incred- 
 ulous Eighth, in all these things it will be very helpful if a 
 
 ruler has a care for his authority, does not make himself too common, 
 but is heroic, brave and resolute: but he must not be too distant, 
 
 arrogant, and proud Ninth, a ruler, government, and land 
 
 should seek the same consideration among neighboring states as at 
 
 home, but to that end should not be quarrelsome, etc Tenth, 
 
 a ruler must find the mean between prodigality and parsimony 
 
 Eleventh, a ruler should be neither too communicative nor too 
 
 reserved Twelfth, the cardinal virtue of great lords and 
 
 rulers is, finally, that they should be just and merciful. Too severe 
 is tyranny, too sympathetic is womanish.
 
 122 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 There follows, in similar style, a series of ten propositions, 
 which Becher calls "the ten commandments" for the use of 
 rulers in relations with their servants. The illustrations by 
 which the several specifications in the two series are enforced 
 contain rich material for the culture history of the period. 
 They show that the abuses which at length doomed 
 quasi-absolutism were evident enough, even then, to those 
 who cared to observe them. But they show more plainly 
 that they had hardly begun to make for modification of 
 the fundamental political presumptions held by cameralistic 
 theorists. The inference from them is merely, "the wise 
 ruler should do so and so." The fact that the presumptions 
 of quasi-absolutism provide the people with no way of requiring 
 the ruler to observe these precepts had not yet weakened these 
 presumptions in the minds of the cameralists. We shall find 
 that this continues to be the case, with no acknowledged modi- 
 fication, and so far as decisive evidence goes with no great 
 modification even in the private opinion of this type of theorist, 
 until the movement for constitutionalism had won its right to 
 recognition. 
 
 On the other hand, the total impression of the collection of 
 commonplaces in the chapter before us is that of a rather strong 
 appeal to the self-interest of princes to observe the rules of 
 prudence and justice in the treatment of their people. There 
 is surprising directness in the hint contained in such words as 
 these: 
 
 A great lord must know that he must deal cautiously with soldiers 
 and learned folk, for sword and quill are two sharp and glorious 
 instruments. The sword has often marred the master whom it 
 had previously served, and the quill can praise and blame, it can 
 write panegyrics and satires, it can also write those things which 
 find their way to the ends of the earth, and no one is exempt from 
 its influence. Hence it is well for great lords to be more careful 
 with their servants and subjects than with their closest kin (p. 27).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 123 
 
 The bearing of the material prosperity and moral well- 
 being of the subjects upon the strength of the state and of the 
 prince is repeatedly urged, and indeed is seldom entirely out 
 of sight in the cameralistic arguments. The intimate history 
 of the court of each German principality would have to be 
 investigated in connection with the cameralistic doctrines 
 current from generation to generation in each, if we were to 
 know how actual government and the theories of the cameral- 
 ists reacted upon each other as alternate cause and effect. 
 
 In chap, iii, on "the form and order of a good government," 
 Becher attempts to set forth "the universal political laws by 
 which land and people are conveniently and well governed." 
 He regards it as necessary, however, to begin the chapter with 
 "a short digression, and as a preliminary to show how and 
 whence magistracies and laws are derived, how they must be 
 constituted [bestellt] and how far they extend." 
 
 The origin of governments is explained upon the traditional 
 dogmatic basis, and there is nothing to indicate that the stilted 
 thought and expression contained anything more than prudent 
 reflection of prevailing orthodoxy. Thus: 
 
 Government is said to be the means by which man is enabled 
 to live according to his nature, which is created in the divine image. 
 This nature is made up of five elements [Stiicke], each corresponding 
 to one of the cardinal elements in the nature of the divine being. 
 These latter are, (i) his existence, (2) his perfection, (3) his omni- 
 science, (4) his omnipotence, (5) his eternity. Accordingly, after 
 "the fall," by which man had lost the ability to realize the divine 
 image in himself, God instituted government, and gave laws to bind 
 men to the laws of nature. Since the laws of nature are of five 
 sorts, so there are now in the world five strata [Stande], laws and 
 governments, (i) The spiritual stratum and its laws affect religion. 
 (2) The moral laws affect honor, virtue, good conduct, and the nobil- 
 ity (sic!). (3) The doctrinal stratum and its laws affect the learned 
 and sciences. (4) The civil courts pertain to possessions, sustenance, 
 and goods. (5) The criminal court has to do with body and lift-,
 
 124 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 under which may be included the maintenance of health, and defense 
 by force and war. The exposition continues: 
 
 "Since in these five points all is included which belongs to the 
 maintenance of the human condition, in order to govern these five 
 kinds of laws and their subjects, that is, to hold men in the state of 
 humanity and the natural laws, God has ordained magistracy [Obrig- 
 keil] which should be obeyed as God himself. As has been said, 
 it is the office of the rulers by good laws to maintain, protect, govern, 
 and control their subjects in the true religion; love and knowledge 
 of God; in good morals, discipline, honor and integrity; in good 
 and various sciences; with respect to their support and honorable 
 earnings, their health and life, also legitimate increase. In these 
 five points consists the origin of all laws and the foundation of author- 
 ity and obedience. 1 .... Hence arises an important double ques- 
 tion, namely, in what form princes, lords and the nobility in their 
 government receive an hereditary succession and complete power 
 over the subjects ? Is it that they should make them chattels, and 
 sell them at will to others, incidentally with no respect for the above- 
 mentioned welfare of the subjects; i. e., that they should act con- 
 trary to all the five points above indicated; and can subjects with 
 good conscience obey rulers of this sort ?" 
 
 Becher's attempt to answer the latter question throws still 
 stronger light upon the obsession of quasi-absolutism which 
 is the determining factor in the thought of the time. He had 
 no difficulty in entertaining the supposition that a ruler might 
 be oppressive. The possibility does not appear to have shaped 
 itself in his imagination that the oppressed might conceivably 
 govern themselves. When the hypothetical question is put 
 in terms which make obedience to an oppressive ruler intoler- 
 able, the only alternative which Becher is able to consider is 
 recourse to another ruler. Thus he says: 
 
 Here arises the most difficult question, Who shall pass on the 
 errors of the government? For it is not seemly 'for the subjects 
 
 1 For further expansion of this theme, Becher refers to his tract, 
 Bilanx humanae Jelicitaiis et infelicitatis.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECHER 125 
 
 themselves to censor their government. I say therefore they should 
 lay their complaints before their neighbors 1 or other unpartisan 
 judges, and urge their government to answer, and much rather intrust 
 the matter to strangers, than attempt to carry it out themselves 
 (P- 45)- 
 
 Immediately following this passage, Becher distinguishes 
 between pagan and Christian slavery. He calls the former 
 tyrannical; he pronounces the latter conducive to the good of 
 the subjects. He urges accordingly that peasants have no 
 right to resist their lords, when the latter coerce them for their 
 own (the peasants') good ! Thereupon he adds the judgment 
 that rulers will be condemned by the heavenly powers to tem- 
 poral misfortune and eternal punishment if they are utterly 
 regardless of their subjects' good. 
 
 Having thus satisfied his conscience by warning rulers of 
 the supposed consequences of misusing their power, Becher 
 turns to the positive question, By what means are the five 
 departments of government above indicated to be carried on ? 
 The reply is that a ruler who purposes to govern with regard 
 to what has been said, should organize five distinct collegia, 
 each to have in charge one of the five sorts of laws and admin- 
 istration above scheduled. 
 
 The first collegium should have charge of the souls of the sub- 
 jects, their religion, worship, fear of God, etc. The second should 
 care for the moral discipline of the subjects. The third should be 
 charged with the education of youth, promotion of the sciences, etc. 
 The fourth is civil, and attends to ordinary questions touching tem- 
 poral prosperity of the state, property, outlays, and income. The 
 fifth might be called collegium i4tale, for its duties are with the health 
 and protection of the subjects, against both secret and public enemies. 
 
 The further exposition of the duties of these bureaus con- 
 sists more of incoherent complaints about evils which need 
 correction in the different groups of activities than of technical 
 
 1 That is, neighboring governments.
 
 126 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 details. The inference is that most of this organization, so far 
 as the author was informed, was not yet in existence. There- 
 upon follows in the fourth chapter a sample scheme of Policey. 
 It is a plan approved by the bishop of Mainz for adoption in 
 his episcopal city, but apparently not actually put into execu- 
 tion (p. 60). It is a code of city ordinances, and it is a first- 
 rate source of information about municipal conditions in Mainz 
 at the middle of the seventeenth century. 
 
 The speculative and academic character of this first part 
 of the Discurs leaves the impression that it was in effect rather 
 hortatory than responsible. The inference which it suggests 
 throughout is that, so far as Becher was acquainted with the 
 facts, provision for all these details of administration was incom- 
 plete and inefficient. 
 
 Part II proposes an analysis of "the material of the republic, 
 that is, of those who are governed, namely the subjects." In 
 comparison with the first part, this portion of the book seems 
 to reflect less certain conventional forms of thinking, if not of 
 acting, and more of the author's own individuality. Although 
 this second part is amateurish enough, it bears evidence of 
 closer approach to the affairs discussed than is visible in the 
 earlier chapters. The inference that the author was not pri- 
 marily a cameralist is strengthened. That is, in the course 
 of his occupational mutations he had now become interested 
 in promoting trade. Under the circumstances of the time, 
 the only hope of accomplishing much in this direction was 
 through governmental initiative. Becher accordingly patched 
 his appeal for attention to the promotion of trade into a sort 
 of general cameralistic scheme. It does not appear, however, 
 that the aim to strengthen the government was as distinctly 
 central and paramount in his thinking as in the programmes 
 of the more typical cameralists. Indeed, we may say that, 
 so far as this book is concerned, he was in rather striking con- 
 trast with them. His chief purpose could not be called eco-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECHER 127 
 
 nomic in the scientific sense, but it was primarily commercial 
 and secondarily political. If Rose her had not ranked him 
 with the cameralists, the perspective of the literary history 
 of the period would be more accurately indicated by passing 
 him over with a much briefer notice than the undue prominence 
 given to him by Roscher will permit. 
 
 This second part of the Discurs may be described as an 
 account of the state of trade in Germany. The subject is 
 approached through a characterization of the three strata that 
 make up the bulk of the population the traders, the artisans, 
 and the peasants. Because this was more nearly fallow ground 
 as a literary theme than the subject of government in the abstract, 
 Becher could appropriate less in the way of current generaliza- 
 tion, and the result is a painful exhibition of untrained powers 
 of expression. The style is hopelessly involved. The sen- 
 tences run distractedly from one predicate into another, and 
 their relation to their subjects is left so largely to the discretion 
 of the reader that the precise affirmation intended by the 
 author is always open to doubt. So far as distinct steps in 
 the argument are discoverable, the following is the main line 
 of thought (pp. 98 ff .) : 
 
 1. These three strata should be under one administration, not 
 three, else confusion will result. 
 
 2. The main end to be aimed at for these strata is increase of 
 their numbers. 
 
 3. Consumption is the center and source of the well-being of 
 these strata. The fundamental aim of governmental policy there- 
 fore should be to promote consumption. In a word, consumption 
 maintains these three strata. Consumption is their soul. Con- 
 sumption is the only means of binding these strata together, and it 
 enables them to live upon one another. For promoting consumption, 
 indeed, the trading stratum is necessary in the community in pro- 
 portion to the size of the peasant stratum. The latter increases 
 the population, but the former nourishes it (sic), for as I shall pres- 
 ently show, the sole consumption of these three strata, and thus their
 
 128 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 sustenance, depends on the merchant, for the artisan lives on him 
 and the peasant on the artisan. I am best acquainted with such of 
 this stratum as are wholesalers [Verlager]. 1 .... These wholesalers 
 must truly be regarded as the foundation pillars of the community. 
 
 4. Trade in foreign goods, when the same could be produced 
 at home, makes for the destruction of the community. Instead of 
 favoring men who enrich themselves by bringing in foreign goods, 
 we ought to deal with them as the meanest criminals (p. 106). On 
 the other hand, those merchants by whom the state gains in money 
 and sustenance are, next to nature, the nursing-mother that makes 
 the desert to bloom. 
 
 This theme is elaborated with a zeal that the earlier sections 
 did not betray. 
 
 5. These three strata have three dangerous and highly harmful 
 and destructive enemies: the first checks population, viz., Monopo- 
 lium; the second limits means of support, Polypolium; the third 
 divides the community, Propolium. 
 
 In a following section these three abuses are considered in turn; 
 the first being described as "when one member alone in the com- 
 munity has that in the way of support upon which otherwise many 
 others could live." The term Polypolium (unrestricted competition 
 for employment) is defined by the statement: 
 
 "In order to remedy the evils of monopoly the Dutch have 
 abolished all 'Ziinfite,' and have admitted Polypolium, in that 
 everyone is at liberty to earn his living as he may, on which account 
 people flock thither in great numbers and rob one another of work 
 .... by which the traders and wholesalers keep the artisans in 
 constant poverty and toil." 
 
 Propolium is not directly defined, but Becher evidently uses the 
 word in the sense of the old English terms "forestalling" and 
 "engrossing." 
 
 From this general introduction Becher passes to his specific 
 and technical material, the state of trade, and wise methods of 
 
 * Becher applies the term to the type in the industrial system of the 
 time which combined the processes of the modern manufacturer and 
 jobber. They not only kept large stocks of goods, but they furnished 
 capital to those who produced the goods (p. 103).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 129 
 
 promoting it, through a general account of trading companies, 
 as devices by which the evils of monopoly and of Polypolium 
 may be avoided. Having specified the general conditions 
 under which he would have the privileges of such companies 
 restricted, Becher divides trade into fourteen types, "to which 
 all others may be reduced." For each of these branches of 
 trade he proposes the organization of a trading company under 
 governmental patronage and control. 
 
 This then completes the theoretical part of the book. The 
 remainder is occupied, first, with a survey of the condition 
 of each of these fourteen branches of trade, second, with a 
 miscellaneous collection of documents illustrating commercial 
 and other transactions more or less properly governmental, 
 with which in most instances Becher claims to have had some- 
 what intimate connection. 
 
 We may append all that it is necessary to say about the second 
 of the three men named in the opening paragraph of this chapter. 
 
 Philipp Wilhelm von Hornick (sometimes written Hornigk, 
 Homeck, etc.) was born in 1638. He sjjent his early years in Vienna, 
 studied law at Ingolstadt, and obtained the Doctor's title there in 
 1661. He lived a considerable time at Vienna, visited the German 
 courts on a political mission in the company of the Spanish Fran- 
 ciscan and Bishop of Croatia, Christopher Rojas, and about 1690 
 entered the service of Cardinal Lamberg, Prince Bishop of Passau, 
 as Privy Counselor. He died in 1712. His first political publica- 
 tion was Hippophili Galeadi de Corneliis Francopolitae wahrer 
 Bericht von dem alien Konigreich Austratien, in which he argued 
 for political consolidation of the estates of the German Empire, and 
 support of a common army to resist French attempts at annexation. 
 The book which appears to have made most impression appeared 
 in 1684, with the title, Oesterreich iiber alles, Wann es nur will. Das 
 ist: Wohlmeinender FtirscMag, Wie Mittelst einer Wohlbestellten 
 Landes-Oeconomie, Die Kayserl. Erb-Lande in kurtzem iiber die 
 andern Staaten von Europa zu erheben, und mehr als einiger derselben, 
 von denen andern independent zu machen.
 
 130 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 From all the allusions to the book which I find in the cameralistic 
 series, as distinguished from later commentators, I discover no 
 reason for crediting the author with firstrate constructive influence 
 upon the theory. Roscher quotes the publisher of the edition of 
 1784 to the effect that "Austria owes to this book the greater portion 
 of its well-being." If this is not gross exaggeration, it is very strange 
 that the theorists betray so little sense of debt to him. Since I have 
 been unable to examine the book, my opinion is of little value, but 
 all the indications which the succeeding cameralistic books contain 
 lead me to classify Hornick with his brother-in-law Becher by the 
 modern commercial term "promoter." Apparently Hornick made 
 an impressive argument for industrial and commercial development. 
 If he did more than this for cameralistic theory, I have been unable 
 to trace it. (Vide Inama, All. d. Bib., in loc., and Roscher, pp. 289 ff.) 
 
 The following paragraphs contain the substance of Roscher's 
 account of Hornick's book. 1 
 
 This book was written under immediate influence of impressions 
 made by the frightful experiences, of Germany, and especially Aus- 
 tria, in the eastern and western wars between 1680 and 1684. I 
 recall only on the side of Louis XIV "the Chambers of Reunion," 
 1680, the conquest of Strassburg and Casale, 1681, the French inva- 
 sion of the Spanish Netherlands, 1683, the seizure of Luxembourg 
 and Trier, 1684: all as humiliating as the contemporary siege of 
 Vienna by the Turks was horrible. "The cunning of the French 
 has brought almost everything into such chaos, that one can reckon 
 one's dates from nothing except God and oneself," says Hornick 
 (chap. ii). But the author hopes for "decisive war with that arrogant 
 nation" which "will find its way into France" (25). The thing to 
 do is to make economic preparations for that alternative, especially 
 as France bases its predominance quite essentially upon economic 
 things. "Would to God we might take the general French pro- 
 gramme [allgemeine Lands-Oeconomie] in many particulars as a 
 good model (23). No state in Europe can look to its policy, without 
 either in much or in little thereby breaking with hated France" 
 (33). There can be no more dallying in Austria. The might of 
 
 1 Op. cit., p. 290.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BI-X'IIEK 131 
 
 a jK'oplc depends essentially upon the ratio of its means to those 
 of its neighbors. \o\v Germany, as compared with the mighty 
 advances made by France, Kngland, and Holland in the last hundred 
 and fifty years, has not only stood still (7) but through war, Refor- 
 mation, loss of population, etc., it has even absolutely declined (17). 
 The greater the necessity of its rise, and especially through the same 
 programme which has made Holland and France so rich, in spite of 
 all the wars, which at this moment is followed by the English against 
 France (24). The state must prevent "loss of our best blood, the 
 very marrow of our strength, our good gold and silver, by the million, 
 by purchase of useless wares from our hereditary enemies." 
 
 It cannot be said that Hornick identified possession of money 
 with wealth. On the contrary he made this definition: " The power 
 and excellence of a land is its surplus of gold, silver, and all other 
 things necessary or convenient for its subsistence, and so far as pos- 
 sible derived from its own means, without dependence upon others, 
 and including the appropriate cultivation, use and application of 
 the same" (9). Quite special worth must be attributed to the inde- 
 pendence of a land, which to be sure can never be complete, but 
 must always be aimed at as an ideal. Everything pertaining to the 
 thrift of a land falls into two classes: Gold and silver, and indeed 
 copper, "which in their worth and use equal all other things, and 
 on account of their civic use are in a class by themselves;" then the 
 means of food, clothing, shelter, etc. A land that had only gold 
 and silver would be rich, to be sure, but very dependent, since gold 
 and silver can neither feed nor clothe people. A land that has all 
 other things except gold and silver is somewhat more independent, 
 to be sure, but yet not sufficiently so, "because gold and silver are 
 somewhat necessary in the most of human circumstances, while in the 
 rest they are indispensable." A land with neither of the two species 
 of goods in its own resources, like Holland or Genoa, is insecure, 
 even in the most splendid development of its commerce. Most 
 independent is the land which is rich in both classes of goods, for 
 example, China (8). The comparison of gold with the blood leads 
 Hornick to the thought that the princely treasure may play the role 
 of the heart (22). Yet he is not consistent. His views on mining 
 and on foreign trade are rather quite mercantilistic. "It were
 
 132 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 better, no matter how strange it may appear to the ill-informed, to 
 pay two Thaler for a ware if they remain in the country, than one if 
 it is to leave the country" (9). It also sounds paradoxical, but it 
 is true, that mining should be continued even when its cost is much 
 in excess of its output. "The outlay remains in the country; what 
 is extracted from the earth remains not less in the country." Accord- 
 ingly the scale is as much richer from the so-called Freibauzechen 
 as a merchant who gets 100 per cent, on his capital (31). 
 
 Homick bases these views on the difference between the thrift 
 of individuals and that of countries, or as we would say, between 
 private and public economy: and he even makes the fine observa- 
 tion, somewhat in advance of his time, that the so-called cameral- 
 management (as we say, Finanziuirthschaft} is " particular manage- 
 ment," thus maintainable only on the basis of the general thrift of 
 the country. This latter is the chief reason why the attention of the 
 state to the general thrift cannot be rated as a mere parergon of the 
 treasury (2, 32).* 
 
 Quite in the spirit of the mercantile system are the "nine chief 
 rules of public economy," which Homick offers as "a merchant's 
 or cameral alphabet" (9): (i) Precise investigation of a land, 
 also through experiments, and full use of its productive capacity, 
 especially of precious metals; (2) transformation (Verarbeitung) 
 in the country itself of all raw materials not fit for use in their natural 
 state; (3) utmost increase and useful employment of population; 
 (4) no export nor useless hoarding of gold and silver; (5) so far as 
 possible, restriction to use of home products; (6) necessary foreign 
 wares should be exchanged at first hand, and not for money, but 
 for home products, and (7) so far as possible (they should be bought 
 [?]) in unmanufactured form; (8) greatest possible export of "super- 
 fluous" home products, and preferably for gold and silver; (9) no 
 importation to be permitted, if enough of the same goods, and of 
 tolerable quality, can be furnished at home.* 
 
 1 Vide the chapter on Schroder, for more explicit development of 
 essentially the same view. 
 
 Roscher adds the note: "If we compare these rules with the still 
 very unsystematic mercantilism of a Bornitz, a Resold, and a Klock,
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF BECKER 133 
 
 To the author these rules seemed such an obvious version of "eyes 
 open and hands ready to take hold," that he thought "their reason- 
 ableness must be evident to everybody. Only a peasant might not 
 be able to understand them" (24). Whoever contradicts them, 
 sit nobis velut ethnicus et publicanus et patriae hostis (3). 
 
 The bulk of Hornick's book is an attempt to furnish proof that 
 Austria, more than any other European state, possesses the natural 
 endowment for economic independence and wealth. It has at once 
 productive veins of the precious metals (and not so far off as Spain's !) 
 and abundance of the chief necessities of life (10-14). Everything 
 to be sure is still in the highest degree undeveloped. There is no 
 enterprise or venture, the richest natural treasures are allowed to 
 lie unused, raw materials are exported to be brought back at doubled 
 price in manufactured form, the population is sparse, their luxury 
 seeks mostly foreign products, etc. (16-18). Still the inhabitants 
 are by no means lacking in mental equipment for trade and industry 
 (15). It occurs here, as usual, that the raw material countries are 
 poorer than those where manufactures flourish, that the former, 
 if they will, can supply the lack "by proper use of their raw materials," 
 and then can be more secure than the latter (8). Hence there is 
 need in Austria only of earnest grasping of the situation from the high- 
 est quarters down, and Hornick urges that this programme should 
 take the form of total prohibition of imports in case of silk, woolen, 
 linen, and French manufactured articles (22). Violations should 
 be punished as treason (23). Then, in his judgment, all the incon- 
 veniences of the transition period would be passed in a few years at 
 most. Many foreigners, who have hitherto supplied our market, 
 will settle in the country and continue their industry (21). The 
 necessary amounts of capital will be created of themselves, through 
 discontinuance of the outflow of money. Inordinate rise of prices 
 for domestic goods could be prevented by the government, by estab- 
 lishing scales of prices (24). 
 
 Hornick urges further that artists and great Verleger should be 
 more honorably treated by the state (28) ; and he argues that a mari- 
 
 who were already acquainted with the great Italian mercantilists Botero 
 and Serra, we get an idea of the meaning of the practical impulse which 
 Colbert also gave to the theory."
 
 134 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 time country without naval strength cannot be powerful; while 
 naval power without sea commerce is impossible (30). On the utility 
 of means of exhibiting the resources of the state, on the harm of guild 
 abuses, the classification of traders into the publicly useful and 
 the harmful, he is quite in accord with Becher. Privilegia private 
 are to be regarded with suspicion; their reasonable purpose, namely, 
 control of consumption in the public interest, may be better secured 
 through prohibition of imports, and then free domestic trade (28).
 
 CHAPTER VI 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 
 
 The third of the group mentioned in the preceding chapter 
 was Wilhelm Freyherr von Schroder. 1 
 
 No writer in the cameralistic series has been portrayed in 
 more conflicting colors. On the one hand, he has been repre- 
 sented as an oracle of cameralistic wisdom, and a model of 
 civic righteousness. On the other hand, so long as his influ- 
 ence was apparent, equally extreme depreciation of his character 
 and doctrines was uttered. This latter estimate is typified by 
 the remarks in a private letter by Seckendorff (quoted by 
 Roscher, p. 294). Speaking of Schroder's book, Seckendorff 
 says: " stdtissimus liber, et prams repletus opinionibus .... 
 a homine perverse; et hos tamen homines foment principes" 
 
 In a certain sense this second type of appraisal of Schroder 
 gives him an importance which he would not have obtained 
 if he had always been treated judicially. In spite of his 
 admirers, he occupies on the whole the place of a suspicious 
 character in the literature of the subject. To express it 
 melodramatically, he is the heavy villain, whose shadow ever 
 and anon falls athwart the plot. Even if later writers do not 
 refer to him by name, ideas which were rightly or wrongly 
 attributed to him, and which were not indorsed by cameralists 
 in general, constantly recur. They not only furnish many 
 texts on which the cameralists delivered homilies against 
 tendencies to which they might have given the name Schrbder- 
 
 1 The title-page of the first edition of Schroder's chief work does 
 not contain the author's name. It reads: Furstliche Schatz- und Rent- 
 Cammer, ad Augustissimunt & Invictissimum Imperatorem Leopoldum 
 I. Principem Triumphantem. Cum speciali Privilegio Sacr. Goes. 
 Majest., .... 1686. Unless otherwise specified, the references are 
 to this edition. I have also used the edition of 1744. 
 
 '35
 
 ltf> THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ismus, but perversely enough, these more or less imaginary 
 faults of Schroder have come down to our time as peculiarly 
 characteristic of cameralism. The perversion, the exaggera- 
 tion, the exception have thus been reported as the rule. In 
 order to reach an objective judgment of cameralism, therefore, 
 it is necessary to form a correct estimate of the man who has 
 been used more than any other to prejudice its reputation. 
 With the help of the article by Marchet, the necessary biblio- 
 graphical details about Schroder may be summarized. 1 
 
 There has been much inaccuracy in accounts of his life, especially 
 through confusion of his career with that of his father. The latter 
 represented Gotha in the negotiations for peace at Osnabriick in 
 1643. In 1654 he took a prominent part in the Diet at Augsburg; 
 he became Kanzler and Cekcimratk, and died, 1663. The younger 
 Schroder with whom we are concerned, is known only from the time 
 of his entrance into Austrian service. Possibly as early as 1663, 
 not later than 1673, e became a member of the English "Academy 
 of Sciences," and he maintained rather intimate relations with 
 England throughout his life. One of the faults in his writing was 
 his failure precisely to indicate the English sources which he freely used. 
 
 Schroder succeeded Becher as director of the Manujacturhaus 
 at Vienna. Becher had lost favor, partly because of his irascible 
 temper and arbitrary manner, partly because he was accused of 
 conducting his office with an eye primarily to his own, rather than 
 the public, interest. Two years before Becher was removed, Schroder 
 was called upon to make a report to the emperor on existing manu- 
 facturing conditions in Austria, and he took the opportunity to 
 make propositions about expanding industries and making them 
 profitable for the treasury. Marchet says: 
 
 " With Becher and Homick, Schroder composed the triple con- 
 stellation which from the seventh to the ninth decades promoted 
 the industrial advance of Germany and especially of Austria. I 
 should arrange the series in the order Homick, Becher, Schroder. 
 They used approximately the same means, viz., opposition to guild 
 abuses, especially through destruction of the guild monopolies, and 
 
 All. d. Bib., in loc.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 137 
 
 the establishment of a Manujadur Haus, high tariff on foreign 
 industrial products, especially French goods, the attainment of a 
 favorable balance of trade, etc. Hornick was most aggressive, and 
 did not stop to think of his own interests; Becher and Schroder 
 acted more cautiously, and with more consideration for their own 
 advantage. The means for attaining these purposes was for all 
 three the absolute prince. Schroder was in the most advanced line 
 in this respect, and swayed between the interest of the prince and that 
 of the people without a fixed point of attachment, although he always 
 affirmed that the prince can be happy and prosperous only when the 
 subjects themselves are well situated. With this conception of the 
 paramount character of the princely power, Schroder takes a rank 
 
 far behind Seckendorff, and occupies the standpoint of Horn 
 
 In spite of his subservience to princes, Schroder must count as one 
 of those persons who helped to lift Germany from that economic 
 depression and national decline into which the Thirty Years' War 
 and the predominance of the territorial lords had plunged it." 
 
 A study of Schroder's writings without previous prejudice 
 leads to conclusions somewhat different from either of those 
 cited. We shall try to present a completely objective judgment. 
 
 In the first place, Schroder took the doctrine of divine 
 right, with an extremely absolutistic interpretation of the right, 
 literally, seriously, and as compared with most of his successors, 
 consistently. That is, instead of clinging to the essential 
 doctrine, while glossing it over with all sorts of disguises to 
 conceal its extravagance, Schroder frankly accepted conclusions 
 along with premises. On the whole, we are bound to feel a 
 certain respect for this rugged type of intellectual integrity, 
 in contrast with the perplexed philosophy which insists upon 
 primary theorems but balks at their logical consequences. 
 
 It would be difficult to find in the whole literature of 
 "divine right" a more compact and uncompromising profes- 
 sion of the faith than in Schroder's Disquisitio Politico, Vom 
 absoluten Fiirstenrecht. 1 In substance his position is this: 
 
 1 Vide pp. 552-69 of ist cd., Furst. Schatz- und Rent-Cammtr.
 
 138 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 II is the common madness of scholars to assume that all govern- 
 ments, the monarchical included, are based upon certain compacts 
 between chiefs or rulers, and their subjects. They assume that the 
 rulers arc consequently bound to observe these compacts rigidly. 
 
 For my part, I fail to see who shall have bound this yoke on the 
 neck of monarchical government, since the same had its beginning 
 not in a compact between the prince and the people, because Saul 
 was made king by the immediate declaration of God, who also 
 caused him to be anointed by his prophets before the people knew 
 the least thing alx>ut it. Moreover God had the jura and praero- 
 gativ of this king and his successors put on paper and proclaimed 
 and published by the heralds (I Sam. 8:9). And in order that such 
 jura might not in the course of time be obsolete or weakened, the 
 same had to be put aside and guarded in the archive for the Lord 
 (I Sam. 10:25). Moreover the Holy Ghost himself was so careful 
 about this whole matter, that with his own fingers he wrote the 
 whole history and the first origin of the kings, with their rights and 
 prerogatives, in the great book of the unchangeable truth of God, 
 commonly called the Holy Bible, and he saw fit to substantiate the 
 memory of the same to the end of the world. Moreover the people 
 voluntarily abandoned all further pretensions, when God the Lord 
 ordained such Jura regia, and thereby made plain that when the 
 king was once chosen, they would no longer be heard (I Sam. 8: 
 18, 19). 
 
 Such princely right now as God dictated to the pen of Samuel 
 may be read in plain and clear words, namely: 
 
 Details (Puncta) oj the Right oj the Prince 1 
 
 "This will be the manner of the king that shall reign over you: 
 
 "i. He will take your son-s, and appoint them for himself, 
 
 for his chariots, and to be his horsemen, and some shall run before 
 
 his chariots, and he will appoint him captains over thousands, and 
 
 captains over fifties. 
 
 1 Under this sub-title Schroder quotes I Sam. 7:11-19 as a divine 
 code defining princely prerogative in general. The Lutheran rendering 
 is even more drastic than the King James version in the text. For 
 example, we cannot fail to trace an effect of the Zeitgeist upon Luther
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 139 
 
 "2. He will set them to ear his ground, and to reap his harvest, 
 and to make his instruments of war, and instruments of his chariots 
 
 "3. And he will take your daughters to be confectionaries, and 
 to be cooks and to be bakers. 
 
 "4. And he will take your fields, and your vineyards, and your 
 oliveyards, even the best of them, and give to his officers, and to his 
 servants. 
 
 "5. And he will take the tenth of your seed, and of your vine- 
 yards, and give to his officers, and to his servants. 
 
 "6. And he will take your menservants, and your maidservants, 
 and your goodliest young men, and your asses, and put them to his 
 work. 
 
 "7. He will take the tenth of your sheep; and 
 
 "8. Ye shall be his servants." 
 
 With the puerilities of the exegesis and application we have 
 no concern, beyond recognizing the fact that Schroder simply 
 voiced a certain contemporary orthodoxy, both in the general 
 practice of grotesque construction of biblical material into 
 evidence to support preconceptions, and in the particular 
 doctrine of the divine origin and ^wasi-absoluteness of princely 
 authority. This latter datum itself, however, must be put in 
 its true relations with Schroder's reasoning, and with cameral- 
 ism as a whole. 
 
 Schroder does not mince words in stating his inferences. 
 He declares that, in consequence of Saul's appointment, all 
 Christian princes and potentates derive their position and 
 right to rule immediately from God. Besides that, "most 
 princely governments and monarchies" have in the course of 
 time "conquered and maintained their prerogatives with the 
 sword, and I therefore see no way in which this contradiction 
 
 in the gloss which he forces upon the passage, thus turning the episode 
 from its historical meaning, by translating the first sentence: "Das 
 wird des Konigs Recht sein, der iiber euch herrschen wird." In the 
 quotation above, the King James version is adapted to the same liberties 
 which Schroder takes with the Lutheran text.
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 that rulers are under obligation to some one or other, of which 
 the learned write, can have any basis whatsoever." The 
 author concedes: 
 
 There are few monarchs to be sure, who are not involved in a 
 thousand Capitulationen, transaclionen, and recessen, but such 
 arrangements cannot be cited as a basis of royal rule. They are 
 rather mere limitations to which rulers were compelled to consent 
 by force of circumstances. They can in no sense be regarded as 
 subtracting from the right which inheres in the royal office, and which 
 is conferred upon the prince by God, not by the people. They 
 cannot prejudice the title "by the grace of God," since, as we have 
 seen, God left the people no freedom by which they were entitled 
 to dispute with kings, or to hamper them with restrictions. Con- 
 sideration of misuse of royal power is reserved to the divine majesty, 
 and God has already announced the decision that the people's 
 complaint will be rejected, according to the decree published by the 
 prophet Samuel (I Sam. 8:18), "And ye shall cry out in that day 
 because of your king, and the Lord will not hear you in that day." 1 
 Consequently, although, through many successions, princes and 
 their posterity have consented and sworn to many things, no jus 
 has been thereby created, and no prince can be bound thereby, as 
 though he had lost his original divine right. Hence a sovereign 
 prince is authorized, without violation of a good conscience, in 
 re-establishing himself, so soon as he has opportunity, in possession 
 of his princely right, in spite of previous compacts, oaths, prescrip- 
 tions or whatever the limitations may be called. This does not 
 mean that a prince is released in his conscience from all laws, and 
 that he is not bound as a private person to his private contracts, 
 
 ' It is characteristic of this exegetical method that it had no com- 
 punctions about falsifying the very evidence on which it relied. What- 
 ever the bearing of the episode referred to, on its face it lends more 
 countenance to the social compact conception than to Schroder's inter- 
 pretation. It pictures the people as taking the initiative in demanding 
 a king, and God as reluctantly acquiescing. Schroder not only expur- 
 gates this part of the record, in his original statement, but in this clinching 
 passage he omits the clause "which ye shall have chosen you," which 
 would be a sufficient ad hominem argument to refute his main contention.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER Mi 
 
 and that he may at will practice all sorts of tyranny without regard 
 to God, and justice and Christian love, for he is a man and has to 
 deal with men, and like his subjects he is a member of the body of 
 Christ. In short, the prince must have respect to the rule (Eph. 
 5:9), "know that your master is in heaven." 
 
 The prince must recognize two great obligations as appertaining 
 to his prerogative; first, that he must administer justice among his 
 people: to wit, according to Christian love, and the principles and 
 fundamental doctrines of Christianity; second, that he must be 
 the leader of his people in war, and expose his body and life to 
 defend them against foreign enemies. 
 
 The monograph concludes with this summary: 
 
 These two obligations of a prince are truly hard matters, since 
 a prince, without violation of his conscience, cannot disregard them. 
 And just as a people, or the subjects, may under no pretext pre- 
 scribe laws to their prince and king, and as those which are thu 
 de facto made have no validity, and do not bind the prince; so on 
 the other hand a prince must so conduct himself in his government 
 that he may be able one day to give account to God alone; as David 
 says, "Against thee, thee only, have I sinned" (Ps. 51:4). And a 
 prince must well reflect with what a rigid law and severe tribunal 
 he must deal, where the judge himself is the accuser, and his own 
 conscience must be the witness against him, where no exception and 
 no excuse can be made, but where no other penalty will be decreed 
 than eternal woe, torture and pain. 
 
 In the Preface of the Schatz- und Rent-Cammer, 1 the rela- 
 tions of the prince to the state, and thus the landmarks of the 
 theory to be expounded in the book, are still more tersely 
 indicated. Having recapitulated the arguments of the pub- 
 licists on the question how a prince may best establish his 
 
 1 I refer to the edition of 1744. The Vorrede does not appear in the 
 first edition. It purports to have been written by the author of the 
 body of the book, and the fact that it did not appear in the original 
 edition is the only reason I have for suggesting that there is a possible 
 question of authorship. The internal evidence leaves little room for 
 doubt that Schroder was the writer.
 
 T42 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 power, viz., he must either (a) pin his hopes to the powerful 
 class; or, (b) he must make friends of the masses; or, (c) he 
 should rob and plunder, i. e., he should be a tyrant; the author 
 cancels the last theory from consideration, on the ground that 
 it is essentially un-Christian, and of the remaining two doctrines 
 he siys: 
 
 Between the two views it is not for me to decide, for each prince 
 will know best where to find support in his own case. For it seems 
 to me that those- people are very thoughtless who imagine that a 
 prince can do anything he pleases l>ecause he is a prince. Those 
 who talk in this way do not understand the difficulties of government. 
 They judge only from outward appearances. They do not know 
 
 how many small and large wheels belong in a clock To cope 
 
 wiih these difficulties of government the statesmen rely upon four 
 means, viz.: (i) sapientiam summam in constituendo leges; (2) 
 xiimmfim a uctorit i tent nt eliam vita religiosa sit; (3) vitae diumi- 
 tnteni; (4) bonam jortunam. If I might take the liberty, however> 
 I would trust myself to hit the mark with two arrows: first with 
 
 a stnndinff army, second with plenty oj money in the chest 
 
 The army may be left to others, but I have undertaken to write in 
 this little book of the ways in which a prince may get money. I have 
 tnken for granted throughout that the interest of the prince will be 
 join -d with the interest of the subjects, and accursed be he who 
 intentionally separates the one from the other, because they cannot 
 prevail unless they are united, and those who rightly examine the 
 chain by which the members of a state are bound together must 
 acknowledge, in accordance with sound reason and experience, 
 Ih-it the prosperity and wdjare oj the subjects is the foundation upon 
 n-hirh all h'ippinrss oj a prince as ruler oj such subjects is based. 
 .... The common man is not satisfied with words. He wants 
 good subsistence, cheap times and protection. I have accordingly 
 shown in general all possible means and ways by which a prince may 
 make his subjects or his land rich and prosperous. In order how- 
 evr that a prince, in exacting tribute and in ordering institutions, 
 may make no mistake, I have advised that he make his demands 
 where there is something to take, and where he who must pay can
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 143 
 
 afford it. To that end it is necessary that a prince shall be informed 
 about his land and his subjects, their occupations and their gains. 
 I have accordingly proposed the necessary schedules. 
 
 SchrSder is half apologetic about his proposals (Vorrede, 
 p. 14) and describes his book as a Utopia. Apparently he does 
 not use the word in quite the usual sense. He means by it 
 that while his scheme does not profess to correspond with 
 actual administration in Germany, it is on the other hand not 
 impracticable, and should be set up as an ideal to be attained. 
 He reiterates his general idea in this way: 
 
 I think I have shown how the happiness of a prince is conjoined 
 with that of his subjects, and the prince himself may be made rich 
 by ways and means which are opposed neither to God nor to virtue, 
 and that all Machiavellian maxims which are based upon jealousies, 
 mistrust, secret subtle tricks for oppressing the subjects, and other 
 tyrannies, should be avoided in all Christian governments, and in 
 their stead should be introduced, to the advantage of both prince and 
 subjects, mutual confidence and love that would be pleasing to God 
 and would give peace of conscience, and at the last great day of 
 judgment would obtain for prince and subjects the divine blessing. 
 
 Those who, after the common fashion, with Adoram who was 
 over the tribute of Rehoboam (I Kings, chap. 12), are accustomed 
 to suck the life blood of the people, may scoff as they will, and may 
 think to gain by it; to me they are like the geographers who measure 
 off the whole world with their circles on paper, without the least 
 concern whether the surface of the earth is made of wood or straw, 
 nor how long it can last, Latronum, non principum est, omnia auferre. 
 A robber strips off my shirt. A prince does not even demand my 
 coat. 
 
 With this preliminary survey of SchrSder's general con- 
 ception of government, we may attempt to do justice to the 
 main argument of his book. The opening passage was seized 
 upon by later writers as containing a sinister meaning, and 
 the whole book was prejudged accordingly. The paragraph 
 reads:
 
 144 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 A prince who has no treasure in the chest, hut plans to rely upon 
 the good will of his subjects and lands, is walking on stilts: for the 
 tempers of subjects are lame dogs, with which one can catch no 
 particular hares. Consequently I cannot agree with those publicists 
 who so far neglect care for a full treasury and for accumulating a 
 common fund, that they believe, if a prince only puts himself in the 
 good graces of the subjects by great liberality, or by waiving all 
 gifts, he will always in case of need find abundant treasure among 
 them. 
 
 Instead of finding a cause of offense in this passage, the 
 historian who has any sense of social values must give Schroder 
 credit for wise prevision of the necessity of a well-defined fiscal 
 administration. The German states at his time were not yet 
 fully through with the process of evolution from the household 
 to the civic type. The publicists with whom Schroder took 
 issue evidently preferred a regime of hand-to-mouth patri- 
 archalism to an orderly impersonal system of creating govern- 
 mental revenue. There was no issue between the two types 
 of theorists about the fundamental relations of prince and 
 subjects. The question was simply whether the relation 
 should proceed upon the basis of a sort of happy-go-lucky 
 plantation improvidence, or whether there should be an 
 attempt to anticipate fiscal needs by organizing an adequate 
 system of supplying governmental wants. It would be self- 
 stultifying for anyone in our generation, who believes neither 
 that the social process should have halted with the big-farm 
 type of rural civilization, nor that philosophical anarchism 
 pictures the structure best adapted to secure the utmost devel- 
 opment of diversified civilization, to decide against Schroder 
 and in favor of his critics. If he was a king-maker, he was 
 more a Samuel than a Warwick. He cannot be made respon- 
 sible for the abuses of governmental power by arbitrary rulers. 
 The things which the people of the period most wanted required 
 responsible and capable governments. These governments
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 145 
 
 depended upon relatively fixed sources of income. The 
 creation of such sources of income gave to rulers in turn power 
 to oppress the people. The exercise of this power presented 
 problems with which subsequent stages of civic experience 
 had to deal. Meanwhile it would be hysterical to blame 
 Scrhoder for his meritorious work in planning the sort of civic 
 machinery without which the main purposes of the German 
 peoples of his time could not have been promoted. His 
 critics were of the type who demand the miracle of arriving at 
 ends without use of the necessary means. While we cannot 
 accept as general truth all the reasons which Schroder assigned 
 for his dissent from the policy of relying upon extemporized 
 popular generosity for governmental supplies, we must judge 
 them in connection with the state of opinion to which they were 
 addressed. In other words, the whole issue between him and 
 his critics resolves itself in the retrospect into balancing of 
 ad hominem arguments. Briefly, the issue reduces to this: a 
 (/Mast-absolute ruler being by common consent assumed, and 
 quasi-absolute rulers being inclined to aggression upon other 
 states than their own, thus constantly jeopardizing the peace 
 and security of all states, and each state assuming that its own 
 ruler is more devoted to its own interests than other rulers are, 
 is it wise or not that the ruler should have control of regular 
 fiscal resources, so that he might act promptly and efficiently 
 for the general weal ? In this connection it would be irrelevant 
 to criticize these premises. Whatever their merits or demerits, 
 they were the presuppositions of all theorists who had an 
 appreciable influence upon the passage in political experience 
 which we are considering. None of the subsequent cameral- 
 ists so much as hinted at a theory of government which essen- 
 tially modified these assumptions. 1 That being the case, we 
 
 I do not mean that no betrayals of views pointing to reconsidera- 
 tion of political philosophy are to be found in the cameralistic books. 
 Instances of contrary impulses, if not insights, may be found between the
 
 146 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 are bound to conclude that those cameralists who affected to 
 regard Schroder as a wicked partner impeached either their 
 own mental competence or their sincerity. Whatever room 
 there was for difference of opinion about details, we can have 
 little respect for his contemporaries, or his successors for the 
 next century, who failed to give him credit for foresight and 
 service upon the constructive side of the issue a fiscal system 
 vs. no system. 
 
 It has often been repeated to Schroder's discredit, for 
 example, that he made it a part of the right of a prince to 
 prefer his own welfare to that of his subjects, if they came into 
 collision. The fact is, however, that not a single man in the 
 series, from Osse to Sonnenfels, ever stated a fundamental 
 theorem about the rights of rulers of which Schroder's proposi- 
 tion would not be a consistent and necessary corollary. Some 
 of them gave pathetic evidence of an unreconciled conflict 
 between judgment and sympathy, in opinions about specific 
 acts or types of acts. To a modern man some of these opinions 
 would be utterly irreconcilable with an absolutistic theory of 
 government. In this connection the cameralists did not have 
 the courage of their sympathies, however, and they held to 
 their absolutistic theories in general, while incontinently utter- 
 ing more democratic opinion about particulars. Even the 
 free-thinking Justi never ventured to deny in print the essential 
 theorem which Schroder put in the most uncompromising 
 theological form, viz. (p. 7): 
 
 For that is the right of the prince in the empire of Christ which 
 the prophet David describes, when he says: "He has given thce the 
 heathen for thine inheritance and the uttermost parts of the earth 
 for thy possession," 1 whence it is seen that the prerogative of kings 
 
 lines of almost every one of them. So far as they were willing to state 
 their basic presumptions, however, the cameralists all adhered to sub- 
 stantially the view above indicated. 
 
 1 A.^ain by changing the tense from future to past Schroder alters the 
 text just enough to make it suit his purpose better than the actual language 
 (I's. 2:8).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 147 
 
 is a hereditary right [jus hacreditarium], that it is a complete and 
 proprietary right [vollig und eigenthiintlich Recht], and not as it is 
 called by the Cromwellians in England, a royal office [officium 
 Regium]. It does not say, "he has given the heathen a king," but 
 "he has given thee the heathen for a possession," whereby the 
 absolute government of princes is evidently established. Accord- 
 ingly it is impossible that the interest of a prince will not sometimes 
 
 differ from the interest of the people When therefore a 
 
 prince, in order to conserve his monarchical, not his private interests, 
 must often use means not agreeable to the people, he can in such 
 cases surely look for little help from them, and consequently it is 
 not to be hoped that a prince must rely upon his subjects. ' 
 
 The discussion which follows, of the advantages of absolute 
 over limited monarchy, differs in no essential from the views 
 expressed at length, or implied, by all the later cameralists. 
 It is of course less finished in form than the identical philosophy 
 a hundred years later, and it has less sense of shame to hide 
 under palliating phrase. It is more frank than the same 
 doctrine in later and sophisticated types, but no more justly 
 chargeable with subornation of oppression. The man who 
 believed in the divine origin and absolute right of kingship, 
 and who tried to show what was necessary to sustain such an 
 institution, cuts a much more respectable figure in history than 
 men who still professed allegiance to the premises of the doctrine 
 but hedged on its conclusions. Even a democrat, to whom the 
 dogma of the divine right of kings is a childish superstition, 
 but who prefers logical consistency to mental confusion, must 
 find something to admire in the Bismarckian ring of Schroder's 
 ultimatum (p. 12): 
 
 In order now that a prince may be independent of his subjects, 
 and absolute in himself, I regard it as safest and most profitable that 
 
 ' Although this is a literal rendering, the last sentence must be 
 understood as referring to the alternatives presented above, and it means 
 "he cannot rely upon mobilizing the good will of his subjects whenever 
 occasion demands, but must have a regular system of revenue."
 
 148 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 he should have the hilt in his hand and money in his chest, whereby 
 he may put his demands into effect, and prostitute neither himself 
 nor his reputation, nor be obliged to put his subjects off with fine 
 words, because he is unable to act from lack of means. As Demos- 
 thenes said, "Opus sunt opes." .... With gold and silver we 
 can work miracles. 
 
 If we fairly consider the civic problems of German states 
 in the second half of the seventeenth century, and if we give 
 Schroder the benefit of his own explanations, we can no more 
 join with those who treat him as the black sheep of the camera- 
 listic flock than we can pass a similar judgment upon Alexander 
 Hamilton for trying to lay a firm foundation for American 
 finance. On the contrary, we must number him among the 
 sane and wise builders upon the structure of German fiscal 
 administration. His second chapter, on the directorate of the 
 income of a reigning prince, begins with a keen analysis of the 
 prevalent unwisdom of European governments in committing 
 both disbursements and the creation of revenues to the Cammer. 
 The consequence is, according to Schroder, that when the 
 prince needs money, the tradition-bound Cammer knows no 
 other way than to hunt out some new objects on which a tax 
 has not been levied; or to grant some new monopoly; thus 
 causing the subjects to sweat blood because more of their 
 support is taken away; or to exact a new loan; or to demand 
 the ox that has grown fat while working on the lord's estate; 
 or to sell the claim to some future lucrative service for a large 
 sum of money, or some such device. By these means the 
 cameralists have made themselves so hated and suspected in 
 the land that they have frequently been excluded from assem- 
 blies of the estates. "Moreover," continues Schroder, "this 
 point, so far as I know, has never been touched. I must there- 
 fore dwell upon it, and express my unauthoritative opinion 
 about it." The substance of this expanded opinion is that 
 raising the princely revenues calls for quite other persons and
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 149 
 
 talents from those engaged in the work of disbursement. 
 Schroder accordingly elaborates work for a comprehensive 
 system of Policey, although it is not as definitely classified under 
 that title as in most of the other cameralists, and he does not 
 draw sharp distinctions between measures that other writers 
 distribute between "Handlung," "Policey" and "Finanz" 1 
 A glance at Schroder's table of contents would disclose that 
 he was interested in a wide range of industrial development, 
 which would make both prince and people richer. He simply 
 concludes (p. 21): 
 
 It consequently seems highly necessary that cameral affairs, 
 at present so called, should be divided into two separate Collegia, 
 the one of which, as aforesaid, should have the income and the dis- 
 bursements, the other should be a Collegium which should have 
 nothing else to do but to raise the revenues of the reigning prince. 
 
 The remainder of the book is devoted to showing the 
 different kinds of work which such a bureau could do. 
 
 As Schroder saw the situation, the treasury officials, from 
 preoccupation, or ignorance, or both, rather than from evil 
 intentions, were effective smotherers of new industrial ventures 
 An independent organization should therefore be established 
 by the prince, with the special duty of attending to the very 
 enterprises for which the treasury had no competence. More- 
 over this Collegium ought not to be hampered by other bureaus. 
 Hence it is properly to be called "summum 6r* absolutum 
 Collegium." The members should have large salaries, in 
 order that they need not be forced by their own pecuniary 
 necessities to prefer their private interests to those of the prince. 
 Moreover a certain fund should be at the disposal of this 
 Collegium, so that it might carry out its plans (p. 23). Schroder 
 cites, as an illustration of what he has in mind, the "Courts of 
 augmentations of the revenues, of the King's crowone" (27 
 Hen. VIII). He anticipates opposition to the plan on the part 
 
 1 E. g., Sonnenfels. Vide pp. 481 3. below.
 
 150 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of the existing court functionaries, but he sees promise of 
 accomplishing the establishment of the proposed bureau in the 
 beginnings made "some years ago" by a minister, who is not 
 named, but presumably an Austrian official, whose untimely 
 death postponed the undertaking. 
 
 The only plausible hypothesis which remains to account 
 for Schroder's dubious reputation among the cameralists is 
 that the reactionary officials set a fashion of misrepresenting 
 his proposals. A reader of the present day, who should examine 
 his book without knowing the worst that had been said about 
 it, would pronounce the author first and foremost a zealot for 
 establishing a stable fiscal system, but at the same time, and 
 with practically equal earnestness, a champion of popular 
 interests against official greed. The argument is, in the first 
 place, a most judicial analysis of the workings of previous 
 systems of taxation. Schroder admits that the traditional 
 forms of taxation are necessary, and that in extreme cases the 
 rate of the same must be temporarily raised. He declares that 
 they are inadequate for the needs of the state, and that they 
 can never be applied with impartial justice (pp. 29 ff.). The 
 people who rely on them are simply like tenants of the soil, 
 whose only interest is to strip it, regardless of those who must 
 depend on it for their living afterward. 
 
 This is well illustrated, in the case of artisans, by the closing 
 paragraph of chap. xcii. The subject under discussion is the 
 reasons for the deplorable depression in German manufactures. 
 The last reason assigned is: 
 
 . VJ'. the greed of the ruling classes and the consequent bad treat- 
 ment of laborers and artisans. For no sooner does a foreign or 
 even a native handicraftsman by his science, and art, in the sweat 
 of his brow, earn a better piece of bread than others can ordinarily 
 gain, than the government falls on him like crows on garbage, and 
 tries to take all it can. For it says such a fellow ought not to have 
 more. He should know that he owes his earnings to me as his ruler,
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 151 
 
 who favors his trade. He should divide with me. Oh! the great 
 foolishness of such magistracies! They have no idea what it means 
 to have prosperous subjects. All that they accomplish is to drive 
 such people out of the country, and at the same time to prevent 
 others from entering. 
 
 In the chapter on "Saving as the Second Customary Deiice 
 for Enriching the Treasury" Schroder shows that he had 
 thought much ahead of most of his comtcmporaries in tracing 
 out certain economic relations. His exposition of the false 
 economy of hoarding leaves nothing to be said on the essential 
 principle, and his exposure of the penny-wise and the pound- 
 foolish policies of certain penurious types of officials is as 
 merciless as it is just. Incidentally Schroder cites an unnamed 
 "world-renowned publicist" who blames the untimely parsi- 
 mony of a treasury chief, and adds that he "should distinguish 
 between Oeconomiam Rusticam 6 Oeconomiam Politicam." 
 The latter phrase is notable as apparently anticipating the 
 nineteenth-century conception of economic science. The 
 context shows, however, that the expression must not be taken 
 in its full modern sense. It apparently connoted only an 
 undefined perception that rural management could not be 
 taken in all respects as a model for civic management. This 
 part of the argument concludes with the resume: 
 
 Although frugality is a great virtue, it should be exercised with 
 a certain discretion, and indeed with a prudenlia politico,. Other- 
 wise it will be called greed or senseless miserliness. If it is greed, 
 it is the root of all evil and misfortune, and is more destructive than 
 all prodigality. If it is unreasoning miserliness, not only the reputa- 
 tion of the prince, but also his interests will be sacrificed, for always to 
 take from the country, and in turn to consume nothing, makes the 
 land waste and barren, the subjects useless, and consequently the 
 prince poor instead of rich (p. 39). 
 
 The argument turns at once to an aspect of the situation 
 which has greater interest for its connection with another
 
 152 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 element in cameralism, viz., the so-called mercantilist theory, 
 of which more must be said later. The author continues: 
 
 Sound judgment shows also that when a prince without great 
 reason takes much money from his subjects, and locks it in his chest, 
 and guards it as a treasure, both prince and land must finally be 
 
 ruined and impoverished The result would be that the 
 
 country would be stripped of money to fill the chest of the prince, 
 and that not a Groschen would be left for him to take from the country 
 as revenue. This would be reckoning without the host. Whence 
 it follows that if money, which is the pendulum of the state, which 
 brings all inequality in the life of the state [Handel und Wandd] 
 into regular movement, is lost, commerce must collapse, and the 
 people must become poor and needy, and because the means [Ver- 
 nuigen] of the country must then grow only from the soil, the fraction 
 of the people, however, who really support themselves from the soil 
 and its produce is always the smallest and poorest portion [Haufjen] 
 in a country, the majority of the inhabitants of the country, from 
 lark of support, will depart, and there will remain a barren land and 
 a jxxir prince; for although the prince has all that money stored 
 in his chest, and alone preserves what was otherwise divided among 
 so many, he still cannot be called a rich prince, although he is called 
 
 a rich man For common people are rich in money: a 
 
 prince, however, is to be regarded as rich only when he has rich 
 subjects (pp. 42 ff.). 
 
 This last passage calls for further preliminaries on the 
 subject of mercantilism. In no respect has tradition so grossly 
 failed to understand the cameralists of the books, in distinction 
 from the cameralists of the bureau, as in this connection. The 
 cameralism of the bureau was a policy with reference to the 
 paramount interests of the princely treasury. The cameralism 
 of the books was a theory and a technology of government, 
 with the needs of the treasury taken for granted as the norm 
 of judgment. 
 
 It would be useless to question the notorious fact that the 
 policy called mercantilism prevailed in Germany during the
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 153 
 
 cameralistic period. It would be fatuous to question the 
 equally familiar fact that promotion of commerce, with cal- 
 culation upon a favorable balance of trade, was the most 
 prominent factor in this mercantilist policy. It vould be quite 
 futile to question the further fact that the cameralists of the 
 books were virtually unanimous in approving this policy. 
 Our interpretation must take issue with tradition, first, upon 
 the precise meaning of this mercantilist policy, and, second, 
 upon the place which the policy occupied within the whole 
 cameralistic theory of politics. 
 
 In the first place, then, mercantilism was a policy, not a 
 philosophy. Speaking for the cameralists of the books only, 
 because this investigation does not go into the evidence about 
 the cameralists of the bureaus, there was a political philosophy 
 after its kind within which the policy had its setting; but the 
 interpretation of mercantilism as a philosophy has the marks 
 of a fixed idea in the modern literature of the subject, and that 
 interpretation is sheer misrepresentation of the cameralistic 
 theorists. The most urgent problem which the cameralists 
 had to solve was that of raising revenues for the prince. In 
 their judgment, the line of least resistance, in cases where it was 
 practicable at all, was through development of commerce. 
 Almost all the literary cameralists, consequently, put more 
 emphasis on the fiscal importance of a favorable trade balance 
 than upon any other single factor in governmental calculation. 
 Incidentally, their arguments treated money in a way which 
 it has proved very easy to distort into a dogma that money is 
 the only wealth. They no more believed, nor intended to 
 assert this, than writers on the financial pages of today's 
 newspapers believe and assert that the bank balances of the 
 money centers are the only wealth of the world. There is 
 rather more prima-facie evidence that the congressional and 
 other debaters of the Aldrich-Fowler-Vreeland propositions 
 believed in 1908 that an "emergency currency" is the only
 
 154 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 wealth, or that the political economists of the United States 
 since the Civil War have believed that a protective tariff is the 
 only means of creating wealth, than there is to warrant the 
 historical fiction that the German mercantilistic theorists held 
 gold and silver to be the only wealth. 
 
 In fact, not one of the cameralists generalized the concept 
 "wealth" much more than the ordinary man on the street does 
 today when he uses the phrase "making money." To make 
 the term Reichthum, as it was used by the cameralists, equiva- 
 lent to the term wealth in nineteenth-century abstract political 
 economy, is an arrant anachronism. The term was virtually 
 a synonym of the more technical cameralistic phrase, bereitestes 
 Vernwgen, or "ready means." Instead of giving to gold and 
 silver the final and paramount place which tradition makes 
 the cameralists assign to them, these thinkers were rather 
 remarkably clear in treating them as means to happiness, and 
 under the circumstances the most decisive means, but they 
 did not raise the larger and deeper problem. The whole 
 cameralistic experience was an unconscious preparation for the 
 abstract question, What is wealth ? It was a progressively 
 searching analysis of the sources from which the people of a 
 state may procure the means of subsistence, and thus be in a 
 position to turn a part of the output of their gainful occupations 
 into treasure for the support of government. The inquiry 
 was on the whole so concrete in its impulse that there was no 
 apparent tendency to extend abstraction beyond the range of 
 practical transactions. Schroder is nearer than most of the 
 cameralists to the concept "wealth" in Adam Smith's sense, 
 however, when he uses the term surplus (Ueberfluss). Thus 
 chap. Ixviii begins with the paragraph: 
 
 Respecting the surplus, whence it is derived, the same consists 
 either in rebus naturalibus, or rebus arlificialibus, that is, first, it 
 comes from the natural fertility of the land; or, second, from the 
 diligence of the men which we make use of in trade when we bring
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 155 
 
 something from one place, and sell it to advantage in another place 
 and thus make trade in all sorts of foreign wares in our country; 
 or third, from the art of men, which is included under the general 
 title manufactures, each of which must be treated in particular. 
 
 Developing the idea of the former source of "surplus," 
 chap. Ixx proceeds in this vein: 
 
 Since then so much depends upon the fertility of the land, a 
 prince should pay good heed to the Curam Rei Rusticae, in order 
 that the land may be well cultivated, and the inhabitants may not 
 only derive from it their food and drink but also something to sell. 
 .... By agriculture (sic) is to be understood not merely that which 
 serves for eating and drinking, but also the other things that grow 
 out of the earth and belong to manufactures or to trade. 
 
 The proposition is elaborated by citations of the experience 
 of other countries, by specification of particular products, 
 which are profitable articles of cultivation, by reference to the 
 book Oesterreich uber alles 1 for additional particulars, and by 
 special emphasis upon silk-culture (Seiden-Oeconomie) as 
 likely to be as valuable to Germany as it had already begun 
 to be to France. The paramount factor in the calculation, 
 namely, the conversion of resources into ready means, reap- 
 pears in the summary (xii): 
 
 Here, as in the case of all other surplus which we desire, this 
 principle is to be observed, that the same shall be sought in products 
 which our neighbors need, and which we can best and with greatest 
 gain convert into money. Otherwise the surplus is of no advantage 
 to us, but is often even harmful, since from the same an abuse of the 
 same may arise.* 
 
 1 Vide p. 129. 
 
 3 The discussion then passes to certain political considerations which 
 should govern the policy of states with respect to promotion of specific 
 kinds of cultivation. The necessary methods of promoting trade, and 
 the value of the same as a source of "surplus" are discussed in chaps. 
 Ixxi-lxxix, and the subject of manufactures as means of procuring a 
 "surplus" is treated in chaps. Ixxxviii-cv.
 
 156 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Schroder must be given credit for dealing with the rela- 
 tively concrete problem of putting to most discreet use the 
 opportunities at hand for acquiring ready means. He must 
 not be judged as though he had anticipated a century and had 
 devoted himself to the underlying problem of wealth in general. 
 In the rough, the same proposition applies to all the cameral- 
 ists included in this study. To confirm this in the case of 
 Schroder, we must notice one of the passages which the tradi- 
 tional interpreters of cameralism always find a conclusive 
 proof-text, viz., chap. xxix. The title reads: "Whence a 
 Prince May Learn Whether His Country Is Gaining or Losing 
 in Riches" (Reichthum). Now it would be a waste of time 
 to defend the chapter against the charge of superficiality, 
 if philosophical economists should prefer the charge. The 
 whole aim of the cameralists was on the superficial plane of 
 practical efficiency, not on the deeper level of economic philos- 
 ophy. Their problem was the development of a programme 
 which would supply the prince with ready means. The general 
 tendency of thought which Schroder represented, and in winch 
 presently all the cameralists more or less consciously joined, 
 assumed that ready means for the prince either caused or was 
 caused by ready means for the people. Without analyzing 
 these alternative phases of the idea, we must allow Schroder 
 to speak for his own practical interest, and must not hold him 
 to account for the meaning which his words might have if he 
 were discussing Adam Smith's problem of the sources of wealth 
 in general. When the modern railroad president studies the 
 problem of increasing the net earnings of his road, he may use 
 language which hypercriticism could distort into expressions 
 of belief that freight charges are the ultimate sources of wealth. 
 No one would take seriously an attempt to prove that a rail- 
 road president could see no farther, if he should turn from 
 practical business to economic theory. The cameralists were 
 not interested in wealth as a general concept, but they were
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 157 
 
 intensely interested in ready means as an efficient tool for 
 everyday purposes. It goes without saying that their theories 
 would have been much more adequate if they had gone deeper 
 into economic philosophy; but our present purpose is to rescue 
 ourselves from the errors of that tradition which has treated 
 them as though they did pry into that antecedent philosophy 
 and consequently propounded fantastic doctrines. The expres- 
 sions which have been distorted into the dogma that gold and 
 silver are the only wealth are no more properly liable to that 
 construction than our railroad presidents' judgment that more 
 freight is necessary for more dividends could fairly be con- 
 strued into the dogma that freight rates are the only source 
 of wealth. Schroder says: 
 
 By the different gainful occupations [Handel und Wandel\ in the 
 country a country supports itself, to be sure, and becomes powerful 
 [machtig], but it does not necessarily thereby increase in riches 
 [Reichthum; that is, in the sense of "ready means"). For such 
 
 traffic with itself can properly be called only a commutation 
 
 Hence the country becomes richer only in the degree in which 
 money and gold are brought into the land either from the earth, 
 or from some other source, and poorer in the degree in which 
 money leaves the country. For since by common consent of nations 
 gold and silver are the universal price of all things, and the value 
 of the same is everywhere in the world reckoned according to the 
 value of gold and silver, for which everything can be bought, we 
 must estimate the riches of a country according to the quantity of 
 the gold and silver in the same. Hence we shall name in order the 
 means by which a land acquires riches, and then those practices 
 through which a land becomes poorer, in order that a prince may 
 promote the former and obstruct the latter (chap. xxix). 
 
 The present argument is by no means an attempt to prove 
 that the cameralists had thought out precise economic concepts. 
 They most certainly had not. It is absurd, however, to hold 
 them responsible for use of certain terms in the exact technical 
 sense fixed upon them much later, and thus by forcing an
 
 158 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 arbitrary interpretation into their concepts to convict them of 
 errors of which they were innocent. It is in principle as unjust 
 to the cameralists to infer from such language as that just 
 quoted that they regarded gold and silver as the only wealth, 
 as it would be to interpret writers in the London Statist as 
 believing that the bank balances are the only wealth, while 
 corn and cotton and iron are not wealth. Schroder was talking 
 about the species of wealth which presented the most immediate 
 problems to men who were primarily interested in supplying 
 the treasury. The very fact that he prefaced the passage with 
 the reservation about the occupations by which the country 
 supports itself and makes itself powerful shows that his appar- 
 ent error about what is wealth and what is not is largely a 
 verbal matter. Not having thought through the concept 
 denoted by the English technical term "wealth, " he used a word 
 (Reichthum) which we most naturally translate "wealth" for 
 the one species of wealth in which he was peculiarly interested. 
 Thereupon we charge him with identifying his specific con- 
 cept, most justly represented by the phrase "ready means," 
 with the generic concept "wealth," which he had never found 
 occasion to use at all. 
 
 Nor is our argument an attempt to show that Schroder, 
 and the cameralists in general, actually had a perspective 
 of the relation of "ready means" to other wealth, which ade- 
 quately generalized the facts for all times and places. They 
 certainly had not. The point to be made is that we must 
 abandon the myth that they attempted such generalization. 
 They were not economists in the nineteenth-century sense. 
 They were political theorists dealing incidentally with rela- 
 tively concrete fragments of economic relations. Those 
 fragments called for generalization later. Meanwhile the 
 cameralists must be interpreted by the conditions of the exact 
 technical task which they proposed, not by the conditions of 
 the subsequent philosophical task which they did not propose.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 159 
 
 It is very true also that Schroder did practically nothing 
 to develop the theory of extractive industries. This fact has 
 been cited against him over and over again. It has been 
 interpreted to mean, first, that he did not regard agricultural 
 products as ''wealth;" second, that he had no sympathy with 
 the agricultural population, and did not care how miserable 
 its condition might be. However this misrepresentation of 
 Schroder may have come into circulation, a historian who 
 should today assert that his book confirmed this judgment 
 would thereby prove either that he had not read it (e. g., the 
 passages cited above, pp. 152 ff.) or that he was incapable of 
 reading it understandingly. 
 
 In the face of his explanation above (p. 142) Schroder 
 might as properly be accused of caring nothing for an army as 
 a governmental recourse. The task which Schroder undertook, 
 in the volume upon which his reputation chiefly rests, was 
 not unlike that which Professors Winthrop M. Daniels and 
 Henry C. Adams had in mind when they wrote their books, 
 The Elements of Public Finance, and The Science of Finance. 
 Because neither of these modern authors included in his 
 volume on finance a treatise on the improvement of agriculture, 
 it has occurred to no one that they should be accused of omitting 
 agriculture from the sources of wealth, or of heartlessness 
 toward the agricultural population. The charge is equally 
 absurd in the case of Schroder. He evidently knew much 
 less about details of agricultural conditions on the operative 
 side than the majority of the cameralists. So far as he betrays 
 his state of mind on the subject, he seems, it is true, to have had 
 no idea that much could be expected in the way of improving 
 agriculture. Indeed he expressly says as much of manu- 
 factures and commerce, and by implication of agriculture, at 
 the close of chap. Ixix: 
 
 For the fertility of a country brings about cheapness of living, 
 which is the spirit of all trade, and for the reason that cheapness in
 
 i6o THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 eating and drinking causes cheap wages for labor, and consequently 
 makes manufactures and wares cheap, so that they can be sold at a 
 lower price than others offer, and hence the market can be held by 
 underbidding others, because everything follows after cheapness. 
 From the examples cited is to be seen what Austria could do, and 
 how rich and powerful it could be if through a good Policey it would 
 combine the surplus of nature, with which more than all other lands 
 in the wide world it is endowed, with the diligence of men, and 
 through establishment of splendid manufactures and commerce 
 would apply the bounty of nature to its profit. Details on this 
 subject are to be found in the little book, Oestcrreich uber attes wenn 
 es nur unit. I despair of anything adequate in manufactures and 
 commerce in this country however. My reasons I have resolved 
 to set forth in a special tract entitled Oesterreichs entdeckte Wunden. 
 
 At the beginning of chap, xcii Schroder declares explicitly 
 that Germany has both the materials and the skill to excel 
 England, France, Holland, and Italy in manufactures, if the 
 will were only present. With reference to agriculture as a 
 source of revenue, he was not so wrong as to general theory 
 as he was incredulous about feasibility of improving prevailing 
 conditions. This would in part explain away the traditional 
 inferences from such a passage as the following (chap. Ixxxviii) : 
 
 The third surplus comes from manufactures, and the latter, if 
 conjoined with commerce, must be much preferred to the fertility 
 of the soil, whence we see that unfertile countries where manufac- 
 tures and commerce flourish are richer than the fertile countries, 
 which have no manufactures. The matter is in itself as clear as 
 the sun. If we appraise a pound of iron in the mine where it origi- 
 nates, it will have very little value. If however a watchmaker or 
 similar skilled laborer takes this pound of iron in his hand and works 
 it according to his art, the pound of iron is worth a hundred times 
 as much as before, etc., etc. 
 
 It would be difficult to find in modern political economy 
 a basis for impeachment of the essential conceptions involved 
 in such language. Schroder plainly underestimated the
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 161 
 
 relative importance of the extractive industries; but this was 
 less from misconception of their fundamental nature than from 
 overestimate of the subsequent processes of securing ready 
 means which the endowment of nature made possible, and 
 especially from belief that it would be relatively easier to 
 stimulate necessary use of these latter agencies than to get 
 equivalent results from more intensive cultivation of the soil. 
 
 Schroder's position was that it would be unreasonable to 
 expect much more public revenue from the workers on the soil, 
 for they were already as miserable as they could be, without 
 being driven out of the country or out of existence. Without 
 taking up the problem of improving the condition of agricul- 
 tural populations, which was not his division of labor, he 
 insisted that a wise fiscal policy would drop the idea of further 
 exactions from this overburdened stratum, and would set 
 about developing more fruitful sources of supply. 
 
 On the other hand, the very expressions which have been 
 distorted into evidence that Schroder did not regard the soil as 
 a source of wealth, and did not care how much the rural folk 
 were oppressed, are evidently, in the light of the context, first, 
 acknowledgments that agriculture is the first and obvious 
 resource of a people and a state, and second, protests against 
 exhausting this resource. 
 
 It should not be necessary for an American democrat to 
 guard himself by repeating that he is not an apologist for the 
 doctrine of divine right. It is no longer necessary nor tolerable, 
 however, for Americans to caricature the doctrine as it was 
 actually held by men in the seventeenth and eighteenth cen- 
 turies. In order correctly to interpret the cameralism of the 
 books, as a distinct movement in the development of a tech- 
 nology of the state, we must do justice to Schroder, especially 
 against endeavors, prompted by a surviving civic formalism, 
 to discredit his most worthy ideas. 
 
 For example, separated from their context, the opening
 
 162 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 sentences of chap, vii, "How a Prince May Have as Much 
 Money as He Will," are among the evidences which the 
 opponents of Schroder quoted to prove that he sanctioned 
 unlimited extortion by rulers. He says: 
 
 In a well-ordered state, neither metes nor bounds nor times nor 
 seasons prescribe to the prince how much money he shall raise from 
 his country nor how often. For the course of circumstances is 
 uneven, and there is no regularity about the gains of different 
 
 subjects Hence a prince must seek his interest with the 
 
 parties who are gaining, and are thus in a position to pay, and if a 
 prince always gets a share of the profits of those who gain, he will 
 have a daily source of supply, for someone always gains, and no one 
 can find fault, because only a tithe is sought by the prince of the 
 gains which are made under his protection (pp. 61, 62). 
 
 In this passage Schroder simply starts with the common 
 absolutistic premises of all theorists of his time, and as we 
 have said above, his cameralistic critics discredited themselves 
 by attempting to turn against him the very theory which they 
 themselves asserted. More than this, Schroder's use of the 
 absolutistic formula in this connection evidently meant just 
 what an expounder of the idea of eminent domain would mean 
 if he should say today, for the sake of emphasis, "in the last 
 analysis there is no limit to the right of the state to expropriate 
 the private owner of land, with due compensation, if the needs 
 of the state require." The latter expression in the mouth of a 
 modern lawyer would hardly be understood as committing 
 him to a general policy of expropriation. In the same way 
 Schroder first stated in its extremest form a principle to which 
 all civic theorists of his class assented ; but this statement was 
 merely to introduce the counterbalancing consideration that 
 it would be fatal to the prosperity of the state to carry the pre- 
 rogative to this extreme. The whole significance of Schroder's 
 book is in its attempt to show how the prince might get revenues 
 more successfully by promoting unexploited sources of supply
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 163 
 
 than by crushing the life out of the primary sources by extorting 
 the last fraction which they could be made to yield. 
 
 It would be disingenuous not to quote the most extreme 
 expressions in which Schroder seems to betray a quite different 
 spirit. Perhaps the most difficult case is chap, cviii, which 
 consists of a single paragraph. The title of this chapter reads: 
 "How a Prince May Also Seize and Use the Capital of the 
 Country, and Still Not Ruin the Country Thereby." The 
 following is the entire discussion under that head: 
 
 Although I have demonstrated that a prince may hoard in his 
 chest no more wealth than the country has earned [erworben], yet 
 I must say something further, namely, how a prince without ruin of 
 the country and of business may also go farther and employ [angrrif- 
 jen] the capital of his land. This takes place if a prince causes ihe 
 subjects to do business with his own capital. Since now this is one 
 of the secrets of a monarchy, I wonder that princes do not reflect 
 more upon it, because by this means they could gradually obtain an 
 absolute sovereignty, and could make the subjects virtually their 
 body slaves, when the latter in time would see their worldly goods 
 in the hands of the prince. 1 
 
 His language in an earlier passage (p. 66) may be cited as 
 a fairer index of the spirit of Schroder's theory and policy. 
 
 And this in my opinion is the inexhaustible treasure of a prince, 
 by means of which he may be a benefactor of the poor, a refuge for 
 the oppressed, a builder of fine cities, and fortifications, founder of 
 
 * I confess that I am unable to offer a plausible explanation of this 
 passage, beyond the. observation that it is too summary and too detached 
 from the rest of the author's argument to reveal his full meaning. On 
 the whole, I classify it as a vagrant concert which the author did not 
 regard as within the scope of practical politics. From the absolutistic 
 point of view, it was a counsel of perfection; a vision of the absolutistic 
 regime so realized that the prince would be a corporation sole, both 
 politically and industrially, while the subjects would have legal existence 
 merely as his agents. The passage, however, has the effect of a mere 
 fugitive suggestion, without significance enough of any sort to affect our 
 estimate of the author's general purpose.
 
 1 64 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 many churches and schools. This is the treasure with which a 
 prince may equip his capital city with qualified people, and may 
 sustain the magnificence of his court, with all of which the land need 
 not be ruined, as the common man thinks, but it will rather be made 
 prosperous. In all these things a prince has only to see that the 
 money so expended remains in the country. For in this way a prince 
 does only that which is fitting. Since he sees that gains in the 
 country are unevenly divided, he takes from him who seems to have 
 gained from others more than his social position or his merit justifies, 
 and gives it to another. In order, however, that the latter may not 
 enjoy his gains in idleness, he must in return do something which 
 will either contribute to the upbuilding of the land or to the pleasure 
 and magnificence of the prince. Thus I can with complete right 
 call a prince a great national Lord of Exchange, or as Aristotle 
 
 expresses it, Custodis et Dispensatoris communium bonorum 
 
 Accordingly a prince may use the whole capital of the country, and 
 as much more as the whole capital is worth (sic), if he only soon 
 consumes it and causes it to course among the people; fora prince 
 is the stomach of the country, the assessments are the foods which it 
 digests. If the foods are not digested in the stomach, and the 
 strength divided among the parts of the body, the members will lose 
 strength and die, but the stomach will die with them. 
 
 Since we have said, however, that the prince should take where 
 there is ability to give, and where it can be spared, it follows that a 
 prince must know the means of each person in the country, together 
 with his manner of support and his earnings, in order that he may 
 perceive how the money in the land is divided, and in what direction 
 it tends. This, however, appears to be an impossible affair, and 
 there is no practicable proposition to make it possible. 
 
 It is not necessary to notice all the naive economic con- 
 ceptions which this language implies. Our attention may be 
 confined to the main line of argument. The strategic point in 
 Schroder's calculation is indicated by the title of chap, viii, 
 "Whether a Prince Can Know How Much Each Citizen 
 Earns or Might Earn, in Order That He May Know How 
 the Money Is Distributed." Schroder does not profess to have
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 165 
 
 discovered a perfect method of answering the question, but 
 he thinks an approach may be made to it that would go far to 
 remove the existing chaos, and increase fairness in demands 
 for payments to the princely treasury. He begins by dividing 
 the population into nine sorts, each to be treated in accordance 
 with their relative abilities: (i) clergy; (2) nobility; (3) 
 peasants; (4) artisans; (5) merchants; (6) court or state 
 functionaries; (7) lenders; 1 (8) usurers; 3 (9) players. 3 
 
 The last section of the chapter presents a puzzle by naming 
 four ways which each of these classes have of gaining money, 
 viz.: (a) finding treasure, whether in natural deposits, or 
 hidden or lost goods; (6) conversion of the unripe or imperfect 
 metals (sic) into good gold or silver; (c) inheritance; (d) 
 presents. This schedule does not seem to correspond with 
 the subsequent analysis of the gainful occupations of the nine 
 classes. The clue to the discrepancy is, first, that the section 
 is not, as might appear at first reading, a re'sume' of the ordinary 
 sources from which these classes get their incomes. It is an 
 enumeration of extraordinary sources common to all of them. 
 The precise language is: "All these have still" (e. g., in addi- 
 tion to the resources peculiar to each) "four means of getting 
 money, or of becoming rich, which appertain to one as well 
 as to the others, viz.," etc. 
 
 The more one reflects upon the use of language in such 
 passages as this, the more clear it becomes that tradition has 
 forced into it associations which the words did not carry in the 
 minds of the cameralistic authors. As we have said above, 
 it is an unpardonable anachronism to make these authors 
 discourse upon the antecedent problems of wealth in the 
 abstract, when they were discussing merely the most available 
 
 > I. e., not of money but of other useful articles. 
 
 Not necessarily in the invidious sense. 
 
 3 Including not merely gamblers but purveyors of amusement, etc.
 
 i66 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 method of accumulating ready means for the individual or for 
 the state. 
 
 Schroder goes on immediately to cite the schedules in use 
 in the duchy of Gotha, for the twenty years previous to his 
 writing, for classifying the extractive industries within the 
 state, and for purposes of assessment. 1 It is not our affair to 
 pass on the skill or the wisdom displayed in Schroder's attempt 
 to outline a more complete industrial census either for rural 
 or urban taxation. The essential point is that what he did 
 in a relatively crude way became a matter of course with later 
 cameralists; and a large part of their work was devoted either 
 to explanation of the routine methods of assessment upon this 
 basis, or to elaboration of other schemes along lines partly 
 drawn by Schroder. It is impossible to decide from the sub- 
 sequent literature to what extent use was made in practice of 
 Schroder's calculus of the relative value to the nation of different 
 branches of manufacture (chaps, xv-xviii). At the least, it 
 was a serious attempt to understand a division of industry 
 which was rapidly assuming firstrate importance in the reckon- 
 ing of all German states. 
 
 Schroder's conception of the functions of Policey are by 
 
 means as farsighted as his fiscal perceptions. They do 
 
 t even seem to be as comprehensive as Osse's. They did 
 
 u.)t go beyond emphasis of the need of governmental inter- 
 
 1 These schedules are reduced to a conspectus which is numbered 
 as chap, xii, and appears as an insert in the edition of 1744. The insert 
 has been removed from the copy of the original edition which I have 
 used. The table is a complete answer to the irresponsible charge that 
 Schroder ignored the extractive industries as a source of wealth. It 
 should have estopped Sec kendorff's denunciation (vide above, p. 135). 
 If SeckendorfFs master, Krnst the Pious, was not an extortioner and a 
 villain in using this schedule for fiscal purj>oscs, surely Schroder cannot 
 be condemned for making it his point of departure in attempting to 
 outline a more: equitable system. Thomasius recorded a fairly judicial 
 estimate of Schroder, in the Testament, p. 152, n. 76.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 167 
 
 ference to prevent neglect of duties by servants of all classes. 
 The phrase, however, which Schroder applies to Policey in 
 chap, xxviii, viz., "die Grundfeste upon which all that has 
 previously been said must rest," quite likely furnished the 
 suggestion which gave Justi the title for his most elaborate 
 cameralistic volume, on Policeywissenschaft. 1 
 
 If we reach a clear understanding that Schroder, and all 
 the rest of the cameralists, when treating of their central fiscal 
 problem, did not raise the later question of pure economics, 
 but were dealing primarily with problems of immediate appli- 
 cation of fiscal means to fiscal ends, and secondarily with 
 problems of adjustment of the people's activities to the need 
 of improved standards of life, whether principally in their own 
 interest or that of the treasury, this perception at once shows 
 that as pure economists or sociologists we have no immediate 
 concern with their conclusions about technological details. 
 Our interest is primarily in the part which they played in 
 developing a general philosophy of society, and the particulars 
 are of value to us only as indexes of their relation to larger 
 conceptions. Enough has been said, therefore, to establish 
 the position of Schroder in the cameralistic series. His main 
 object was to increase the ready means of the prince, while 
 incidentally lightening the burdens of the people. The general 
 scope of his conclusions may be gathered by reference to his 
 table of contents, especially to the titles of chaps, xxx-cv. 
 
 Our analysis of Schroder may be completed by a reflection 
 which has also some measure of relevance to all the cameralists. 
 We must distinctly note that the cameralistic estimate of 
 proportions between gold and silver and other goods, which 
 we have discussed, is less a vagary about economic principles 
 than an appraisal of civic values corresponding with con- 
 temporary judgments of relative civic needs. If Schroder had 
 been plied with Socratic questions about wealth, in Adam 
 Vide below, p. 452.
 
 1 68 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Smith's sense, after getting the concept denned, he would have 
 been obliged to retract nothing in principle which he had 
 intended to assert before that more generalized term had been 
 brought to his attention. Maintaining his position, he might 
 have restated his views in this way: "I quite agree that we 
 may give a common name to all the material things which men 
 want to use, and which they may exchange. If we call these 
 wealth, the agricultural products which feed people, the manu- 
 factured forms of those products which clothe people, and the 
 other manufactured forms which satisfy people's demands for 
 convenience and comfort, are of course wealth, just as much 
 as the gold and silver which enable the prince to maintain the 
 government, and the people to make their exchanges. My 
 contention is, however, that the need of making the govern- 
 ment strong is so pre-eminent that the wealth which satisfies this 
 need is beyond all comparison the most important wealth, and 
 must be provided for whether there is increase of other wealth 
 or not." 
 
 Here would be a plain contrast between the cameralistic 
 and the modern scale of social values. It would assign to 
 money a higher ratio of value in the state than it has in modern 
 theory. The reason would be not that cameralism essentially 
 varied from modern theory on the economic principles of 
 wealth, but rather that cameralism varied from modern theory 
 on antecedent political philosophy. It posited an order of 
 precedence between governmental strength and popular 
 prosperity which democratic theory has inverted. That is, 
 the cameralistic theory was that popular prosperity depends 
 on strong government. Modern theory, at least in its demo- 
 cratic forms, holds that strong government depends upon 
 popular prosperity. Thus the cameralistic theory, which 
 systematized mercantilistic practice, did not so much assert 
 fundamentally incorrect economic principles as it transferred 
 emphasis from more to less ultimate principles, for the sake
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 169 
 
 of supposed immediate political expediency. The needed 
 correction of cameralism was less new knowledge of the sources 
 of material goods than new valuations of the scale of ends to 
 which material goods should be applied. Along with the 
 absolutistic major premise, "The fiscal needs of the prince are 
 the paramount needs in the state," went the minor premise, 
 "There is more to be gained for the princely fiscus by exploit- 
 ing other means of revenue than by depending upon further 
 exploitation of the primary natural resources." Thij was 
 not a false economic principle, but a specific judgment about 
 the relative availability of an economic principle in a particular 
 situation. The subsequent development of cameralism shows 
 a marked increase of relative emphasis upon the value of the 
 extractive industries. This change does not reflect a revolu- 
 tion in fundamental economic conceptions. It denotes on the 
 one hand increased attention to the technique of agricultural 
 management, with correspondingly enlarged ideas of the 
 maximum resources of nature; and on the other hand, expan- 
 sion of cameralistic science so that its fiscal division was better 
 balanced by variously classified divisions which brought some 
 of the neglected elements of the civic situation under equally 
 systematic analysis. 
 
 Of Schroder as a promoter of the practical economic policy 
 of Austria it does not fall within the scope of this book to speak. 
 Whether his judgment was the wisest under the circumstances, 
 and whether the commercial expedients which he advocated 
 were in the line of general technological prudence, are questions 
 which would be appropriate in a more special study than our 
 programme proposes. The foregoing analysis sufficiently 
 covers the most essential question about him. Objective 
 study permits us to accept the judgment neither of certain 
 interested contemporaries, who would have had Schroder 
 regarded as a prophet of evil, nor of the schematic appraisers 
 of mercantilism in general, who represent all its theorists as
 
 170 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 teaching grotesque doctrines. These vagaries appear to have 
 been imputed to them first by opponents of the mercantilist^ 
 programme, and to have come down to us in place of the 
 authentic opinions of a group of thinkers whose economic 
 conceptions turn out to have been much more valid than their 
 views of political philosophy. 
 
 In this connection a few words must be said about four 
 writers who, by general consent of the historians, rank as 
 satellites of the principal group discussed in this and the 
 preceding chapter. We name first the otherwise apparently 
 unknown writer, von Klenck. 1 His book may be called a 
 shorter catechism of mercantilism. It contains 262 pages of 
 large pocket-diary shape. It can be inserted in the vest pocket, 
 and if printed on thin paper, with flexible covers, would be 
 conveniently portable. Roscher says: 
 
 A lxx>k in many respects enigmatical is the FursUiche Macht- 
 kunst .... which I have been able to obtain only in the ninth 
 edition, Frankfurth and Leipzig, 1740, under the title: Tractat 
 von Manufacturen und Commercio. It is said to have been published 
 in 1702 at Halle, or in 1703 at Weissenfels, by the well-known 
 Hcinrich Bode, professor of law at Halle. The author, a certain 
 Herr von Klenck, is said to have suppressed it, after it had been 
 severely attacked in 1704, in the monograph, Das Gold des publiquen 
 credits, welches der vornehme Autor der jurstlichen Machtkunst und 
 uncrschdpflichen Goldgrubcn durck Herrn G. B.'s Giitigkeit und 
 Vermittelung bcschauen lasscn, auj dem Probierstein der gesunden 
 Vernunjt zum Commercio untauglich bejunden von einem Lubecker 
 Kaujmann (p. 303).' 
 
 FursUiche Macht-Kunst, Oder Unerschopfliche Gold-Grube, 
 Wordurch tin Fursl sick kan mtichlig und seine Untertkanen reich machen. 
 Durch eincn in vielen Wisscnsthafften Erfahrnen Vornehmen Cavallier 
 entworffen, und mil dcssen Gutbefindcn heraus gcgeben Von Heinrich 
 Ikxlcn, Konigl. Preussis. Rath im Hcrtzogthum Magdeb. und Prof. 
 Jur. in Halle, Kditio III. The editor's preface is dated Halle, July 3, 
 1702. 
 
 The third edition, which I have used, is not dated. It appears to 
 be identical with the original.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 171 
 
 Roscher also quotes the statement (p. 303, note), that 
 Klenck's book was republished in 1773 as an appendix to the 
 volume Klugheit zu leben und zu herrschen. 
 
 Although Roscher finds in Klenck some slight variations 
 from Schroder, and even improvements upon his teachings 
 (pp. 303, 304), they are not important enough to require our 
 attention. In his Preface the author expressly states that he 
 wrote the book in the hope that it would be more successful 
 in attracting the notice of young princes than the more pre- 
 tentious writings on the subject. He apparently had some 
 particular prince in mind. At the same time he expressly 
 disclaims the purpose of being original, and declares that he 
 has drawn his conclusions from the best authorities. The 
 book emphasizes and popularizes the best in the previous 
 mercantilists. It is especially clear and strong in its assertions 
 that the strength and riches of the prince must be based upon 
 the strength and riches of the people, and that the ancient 
 prejudice against industrial and commercial pursuits as 
 unworthy of the nobility must give place to pride in those 
 occupations. 
 
 Whether the author's hope of appealing to young princes 
 was realized does not appear. References to his book by 
 later and influential writers show that he actually did have a 
 share in winning respect for the views which he represented. 1 
 We need note simply that Klenck leaves no room for doubt 
 that he is a typical cameralist, as described in our general 
 formula.* He begins his Vorrede with the observation: 
 
 All the world knows that in a few centuries France, England, 
 and Holland, not so much through force of arms, as through a special 
 princely art and science, have advanced to such a high power, that 
 the gold and silver streams of the whole world seem to run into them, 
 
 1 For example, vide Thomasius on Klenck, Testament, pp. 99 ff., 
 n. 41. 
 
 * Vide above, p. 6.
 
 172 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as to an exhaustless sea. To reflect upon such princely power, and 
 with it to serve the Fatherland, is demanded of every true patriot. 
 I accordingly devote this study to the art of princely power, and I 
 feel at liberty to call it a Studium Magnificum quod Magnos jacit, 
 whereby in our beloved Fatherland hidden springs of gold may be 
 opened. I accordingly call this Machtkunst a science highly neces- 
 sary for princes, of so directing all gainful occupations that, ex 
 Bono Publico of the land, the princely treasury may be enriched, 
 and the prince may become powerful. The finis Primarius is 
 thus the Bonum Publicum, the riches and prosperity of the land, 
 quo Reipublicae bene fit; whence flows the Finis Secundus or Secun- 
 darius, the power and great might of the ruling prince, as from the 
 proper source and spring. If the same contains much water, the 
 prince can also have much. Hence the welfare of the prince is so 
 closely bound up with that of his subjects that the one without the 
 other cannot come into being, and still less be permanent. 
 
 The second of these lesser writers is Paul Jacob Marperger, 
 1656-1730. He made an impression by his much writing, but 
 he was the author of nothing of even second-rate importance. 1 
 
 The third in this minor group, "much less known by his 
 contemporaries, but intellectually much the superior of Mar- 
 perger, was Johann Georg Leib." a 
 
 While it is not certain that Leib added anything to the 
 theory of his predecessors, writers of his class are important 
 for our purpose. They furnish cumulative evidence of the 
 spirit of the doctrine which they tried to expound. The 
 Vorrede to Leib's book begins in this way: 
 
 There are many who have such a bad opinion of the Studium 
 Cameralis or Oeconomiae Principis that they think it impossible to 
 
 1 Roscher seldom packs as much into a few words as in his estimate: 
 "In der Hauptsache ist Marperger als ein Verwasserer des von ihm 
 bewunderten Becher zu charakterisiren. Ein entsetzlicher Vielschreiber, 
 der z. B. in seinem Ersten Hundert gelehrter Kaufleute (1717) 35 Biicher 
 aufzahlt, die er seit 1698 herausgegeben, und noch 71 andere, zum 
 Druck bereite Schriften." (Vide Roscher, p. 301.) 
 
 Von Verbesserung Land und Leuten, und wie ein Regent seint 
 Mackt und Anseken erkeben konne (1708).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SCHRODER 173 
 
 raise the revenues of a great lord without adding to the tears and 
 sighs of their subjects. How mistaken this idea is may easily be 
 shown by the fact that the chief and only purpose of this study is 
 to put the whole body of subjects in a permanent condition of well- 
 being, and only from their surplus, and in a just manner, to increase 
 the income of the lord of the land, and to raise his power and repute; 
 .... I cannot deny that abuses which have entered into fiscal 
 administration as a common evil have been my sole reason for this 
 writing, out of love for the common good. Accordingly, I have 
 attempted to show how the welfare of the land, or the well-being of 
 the subjects, is inseparably bound up with the interest of the ruler, 
 and this is the true and sole principle of the whole cameralistic study. 
 Moreover, my chief rule for increasing the power of the land is to 
 retain money in the country, and to bring it from other countries. 
 If this rule is observed, it follows without dispute that the welfare 
 of the land will be thereby promoted, and the subjects will be made 
 richer. And if the subjects are made richer, then they can without 
 harm and embarrassment pay to the lord of the land, for the pro- 
 tection which is so profitable, an increased tribute. Then the 
 ampler treasure of the prince must put him in power and repute 
 with other rulers. 
 
 The whole book is an amplification of these propositions. 
 Whatever may have been the morale of the typical German 
 government in this period, these theorists represent the stand- 
 ards which the governments were supposed to respect. 
 
 Finally, we must select from others who might be named 
 in this connection Theodor Ludwig Lau. 1 
 
 If Lau was not personally a grievous ass, he went far out 
 of his way to misrepresent himself, not only in his dedication, 
 but in his garrulous and "kittenish" Vorrede. The one detail 
 
 1 Roscher refers to him (p. 379) as " Der kurldndische Hofrath und 
 Cdbinetsdircctor." His- book is entitled Aufrichtiger Vorschlag: von 
 Glucklicher: vortheilhaff tiger: bestandiger Einrichtung der Intraden: 
 und Einkunjften; der Souverainen: und ihrer Unterthanen; In welchen: 
 Von Policey- und Cammer-Negocien und Steuer Sachen: gehandelt nvird. 
 Entworffen Von dem HochfUrstlich-Curlandischem Hoff-Rath, und 
 Cabinets-Directeur, Theodor Ludwig Lau .... 1719.
 
 174 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 which is worthy of record about his book is that it made more 
 than any previous text of the classification of cameralistic 
 science into the divisions which were in general accepted to 
 the end of the cameralistic period. That is, the Aufrichtiger 
 Vorschlag was divided into four books, treating respectively 
 of (i) Policey; (2) finance (Entwurff einer woUeingerichteten 
 Cammer)\ (3) commerce (Entwurff wohlregulirter Negocien), 
 in which the first part is entitled "Von den Manufacturen" 
 and the second, "Von den Commercien;" (4) taxation (Entwurff 
 Wohleingerichteter Steureri). This main part of the volume 
 occupies 324 pages. There follows a monograph of 130 pages 
 treating in detail certain practical phases of the subject of the 
 fourth part of the text. The title-page of this tract is notable 
 for its reiteration of the idea of community of interest between 
 subjects and rulers. 1 
 
 A still more complete account of cameralistic literature 
 at this period would include such writers as Gleichmann, 3 
 Gundling,3 and a little later Schreber, 4 and J. A. Hoffmann. 5 
 
 1 Practische Vorschldge, Welcher gestalt Steuer und respective Con- 
 tribution zum Nutzen Eines Landes-Herren, und ohne Nachtheil der 
 Unterthanen einzurichten seye, Damit unter alien steuerbaren und Con- 
 trilmablen Dingen eine proportionirte Gleichheit, Nock Anleitung der 
 Reichs-Abschiede, gehalten, und kein Unter than vor dem andern graviret 
 werdt, Auch, wie alle Unter schleiffe und viele Kosten vermieden, Und der 
 Steuer- und respective Contributions-Stock in bestdndiger Richtigkeit 
 erhalten werden kan, Ausfuhrlich projectirt und turn Druck befordert. 
 Im Jahr 1721. 
 
 1 Kurtzer Begri/ von einer unbetrdglichen Furstlichen Machtkunst 
 (1711); vide Roscher, p. 377. 
 
 3 Einleitung zur wahren Staatsklugheit (posth., 1751); vide Roscher, 
 loc. cit. 
 
 * "Der Leipziger Professor der Oekonomie, Polizei und Cameral- 
 wisscnschaft." Hauptwerk: Abhandlung von Cammergutern und 
 Einkunften, deren Verpachtung und Administration (1743); vide 
 Roscher, loc. cit. 
 
 i Politische A nmerkungen uber die wahre und falsche Staatskunst, 
 worin aus den Geschichten alter Zeit bemerket wird, was einem Lande 
 zutrdglich oder schadlich sei (Latin, 1718; German, 1725); vide Roscher, 
 p. 3o.
 
 CHAPTER VII 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 
 
 Gerhard is of value in the first instance as a witness to the 
 influence of Seckendorff. His book is a mere tract of seventy 
 pages. 1 It is notable for mobilizing the term Staatswissen- 
 schaft as a synonym of the term Staats-tehre used in the title; 
 and this fact evidently corresponds with an enlargement of 
 vision which was widening the outlook of German political 
 theorists, and at the same time giving their views a more coherent 
 content. The author declares that his intention in writing 
 the book is to introduce beginners to the subject, not to address 
 the learned. He also frankly states that he wants the book, 
 and the lectures based on it, to lead up to the study of Secken- 
 dorff's Teutscher Fursten Stoat. With the book and the 
 lectures on it as a preparation for his course on Seckendorff, 
 he hopes to give his students an adequate idea of "the whole 
 studium politicum in general." Gerhard was apparently a 
 member of the law faculty at Jena in 1713, and was among the 
 academic men who were smuggling the beginnings of camera- 
 listics into the universities before special professorships of that 
 subject were founded. 
 
 Gerhard's book consists of six chapters, with an appendix 
 on Seckendorff's political writings. If it were to be judged 
 by its size, it would be set down as a negligible factor in the 
 interpretation of cameralism. There is strong internal evidence, 
 however, that the author deserves more attention than he has 
 received. Roscher, for example, devotes to him less than a 
 whole sentence.' He was not a mere echo of Seckendorff. 
 In the first place, as a lecturer at Jena, he evidently did more 
 
 1 D. Ephraim Gerhards " Einleitung zur Staats-Lehre" Nebst ange- 
 kengten Discurs von des Herrn von Seckendorf Politischen Schriften. 
 .... 1713. 
 
 > Op. ci/., p. 238. 
 
 '75
 
 176 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to prepare the way for admission of civics, as Justi understood 
 that concept, to good standing in the universities than that 
 writer imagined. 1 In the second place, he was a most instruct- 
 ive sign of the times with reference to currents of thought 
 about the whole range of subjects which we now refer to as 
 "the social science^" His prolegomena show that his general 
 conceptions of scientific relationships were far nearer those 
 which we hold today than were those which found expression 
 in some of the more pretentious books. Quite likely this 
 accounts for his inconspicuous place as an author. Apparently 
 he was a man whose insight and outlook surveyed wider 
 reaches of knowledge than he had the constructive power to 
 control. He seems to have had the talents of a scout rather 
 than of a commissary-general. He detected strategic points, 
 but was not qualified to conduct campaigns. Dropping the 
 figure, it seems likely that Gerhard lacked the force or the 
 equipment necessary for writing books which would have 
 accredited his methodological perceptions. It would have 
 required altogether exceptional genius and learning to com- 
 pose at that time treatises which would have filled out his 
 classification of knowledge. He has consequently left on record 
 merely evidence of a certain precocity which must have affected 
 his students as a liberalizing influence, but he lacked the 
 energy to make much impression upon the slowly developing 
 social ideas of the period. 
 
 Not because Gerhard's direct influence can be traced in 
 the later literature of the social sciences, but because he gives 
 expression to ideas which were gathering force among the 
 formative influences of his time, we must give him attention 
 out of proportion to the angle which his book subtends in the 
 literature of cameralism. 1 
 
 1 Vide below, p. 296. 
 
 In his preface to Stisser's Einleilung, Zincke throws light on Ger- 
 hard's influence by the remark that Stisser "sich nebst denen beriihmten
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 177 
 
 The first chapter deals primarily with very elementary 
 matters of terminology. The discussion turns upon the ques- 
 tion, What is properly to be understood by the name "Poli- 
 ticus" ? The value of the chapter for us is in the light it throws 
 upon the state of mind at that time, both in the general public 
 and among academic people, about subjects which have since 
 developed into the social sciences. The first misunderstanding 
 to which Gerhard addresses himself is that there is nothing 
 in common between scholars and Politici, and that there is no 
 room in universities for subjects in which Politici would be 
 interested. This error, he declares, is a part of the confusion 
 which has come in with the practice of using the words Politicus 
 and Staatsmann as synonyms. People at court declare that 
 politics can be understood by courtiers alone; the universities 
 should therefore at most explain languages and the Institu- 
 tiones inns. 
 
 Gerhard's reply is substantially the familiar academic 
 exposition of the utility of general training in theory as a 
 preparation for acquirement of technical knowledge and skill. 
 Attempting to show in particular what sort of knowledge may 
 be acquired in universities as a preparation for practical 
 politics, Gerhard distinguishes first between "the rules of 
 righteousness and love, and the rules of prudence." The 
 latter are usually regarded as the domain of politics, the former, 
 of natural and moral philosophy. Gerhard urges that this 
 division of labor is not wholly wise, because moral philosophy 
 must be the foundation of civic prudence (Staats-Klugheit). 
 He says further: 
 
 If I may speak to suit myself, I may be allowed to distinguish 
 between civic science [Stoats -Gelahrtheit] and civic prudence [Staats- 
 
 Mannern, Herrmanns, Stollens, Dithmars, Struvens, Kressens, Wild- 
 vogels und Schroders, sonderlich des Unterrichts-Hausses und Tisches 
 des Herrn D. Gerhards .... bediente, unter dessen Vorsiz er auch, 
 1711, eine Dissert, de crimine Lenocinii schrieb und vertheidigte."
 
 1 78 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Klugheit], while at the same time I want to do justice to each. Civic 
 science is the affair of scholars, and shows the fundamental principles 
 upon which a proper civic prudence rests its observations. Civic 
 prudence, however, consists in skilful application of those rules which 
 are prescribed by civic science. Civic prudence must be learned by 
 grasp of affairs, civic science by appropriate reasoning. The latter 
 is as little the monopoly of the court as the former of the university, 
 although the one is more prominent at courts and the other at 
 universities (p. 9). 
 
 Gerhard goes on to say that he is not much concerned about 
 mere matters of words, such as Staats-Wissenschaft, Staats- 
 Klugtieit, Staats-Kunst, and Staats-Lehre. The main thing 
 for him is "that an upright teacher should not confuse distinct 
 disciplines, and that a right-minded statesman must not 
 despise learning, while he exercises a high degree of prudence 
 in his daily duties." 
 
 Advancing in the second chapter to more precise description 
 of civic science, Gerhard proposes at the outset the most com- 
 pact formula of civic science as he views it, viz. : 
 
 "A theory which presents in proper order of dependence the 
 rules of prudence, through which the community [gemeines Wesen} 
 is kept in a good state of welfare, and which have as their whole aim 
 the maintenance of the public state." In expanding this definition 
 Gerhard urges that " civic science is thus obviously a constituent 
 part of true science [Gelahrtheit] in general, since genuine science is 
 nothing else than a theory through which human thoughts are set 
 toward the attainment and retention of permanent happiness, and 
 moreover it places definitely before the eyes of each this appropriate 
 purpose." The courage of the author's convictions speaks further 
 in the assertion: "I conclude still more that no one has a right to 
 claim the name scholar who has not laid a reasonable basis of 
 scholarship in this very useful division of learning." 
 
 In further analysis of science Gerhard proceeds: 
 
 The happiness of men is to be sought either in this or in a future 
 life of which God's revelation gives us knowledge, and of which
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 179 
 
 reason itself gives us hope. In a word, it is either temporal or 
 eternal. To the latter we are led by die hochweise Erkennlniss der 
 Wahrheit zur Gottseligkeit, oder die Lehre der Gottesfurcht, which 
 therefore is called the science or knowledge of God. Temporal 
 happiness, however, may be sought partly in subjective contentment 
 of mind, partly in external repose and well-being, also health and a 
 competence; hence various treatments of these subjects have 
 become parts of practical learning (p. 15). 
 
 Accordingly Gerhard enumerates, with some indication of 
 their respective contents, the theory of virtue, the theory of 
 health, "which cannot be given over entirely to the art of 
 medicine, but is also closely related with the theory of virtue," 
 the theory of justice or natural law, the theory of morals, and 
 the theory of the state, or of prudence. 1 He adds: 
 
 Prudence is accordingly nothing else than a theory which equips 
 man with the rational keys with which he may skilfully and system- 
 atically employ the means to his happiness which come in his common 
 life, whereby he may attain the indicated end. 
 
 And a little later he further explains: 
 
 Accordingly our civic science is chiefly concerned with finding 
 out good external and voluntary means, through which, without 
 harm or injustice to others, the welfare of the community [gemeinen 
 Wesens], that is, the permanence and security of the same, may be 
 properly maintained, promoted, and increased. 
 
 On the basis of this explanation the author goes into further 
 details about the various sciences he has named, and especially 
 their dependence upon one another. In this latter respect his 
 views approach much closer to those of methodologists today 
 than his notions of divisions of labor among the sciences. 
 He is especially definite and sagacious in showing (chap, iii) 
 how scholars in each of the faculties in turn, theology, medicine, 
 
 1 This schedule suggests the conceptions which Adam Smith appro- 
 priated from the philosophy in which he was trained. Vide Dugald 
 Stewart, Account of the Life and Writings of Adam Smith (Bohn ed., 
 p. xvii). Vide Small, Adam Smith and Modern Sociology, p. 32 et passim.
 
 i8o THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 philosophy, and law, would profit by the study of social science. 
 It is hardly too much to say that these few pages read almost 
 like a vision of the development of sociological consciousness 
 which has been manifest during the past generation. Upon 
 chap, iv, on "Abuses of Civic Science," a similar judgment may 
 be passed. Although less sophisticated, it is very much in the 
 spirit of Herbert Spencer's essay, The Sins of Legislators. 
 
 Chap, v, "On the Purpose, Content, and Sub-Divisions of 
 Civic Science" begins with a proposition which in terms is 
 two centuries in advance of the scientific mediocrity of the 
 author's generation. Although we may not read into it all 
 that we should now imply by such language, we must not fail 
 to recognize the notable breadth of view which the most 
 grudging interpretation would have to concede. Gerhard says: 
 
 In order to realize the above indicated advantages, and to avoid 
 the contrasted abuses of civic science, it is necessary never to leave 
 the purpose of the same out of sight. The duty of every Politicus 
 is contained in the rule: "Whatsoever thou doest, so consider the 
 end and the outcome of thy devising, that thou shalt nevermore do 
 harm" (p. 42). 
 
 From the context we can hardly conclude that this precept 
 meant less in principle to its author than was contained in one 
 of Herbert Spencer's wisest sociological aphorisms: "The 
 question of questions for the politician should ever be 'What 
 type of social structure am I tending to produce?' But this 
 is a question he never entertains." 1 Gerhard's next paragraph 
 reads: 
 
 As above observed, all the care of civic science should be directed 
 toward the welfare of the state.* This consists principally in external 
 peace and satisfaction, so far as these can be maintained by natural 
 
 * "The Coming Slavery," in Appleton's edition of Social Statics; 
 The Man versus the State (1892), p. 312. 
 
 * " Wohlscyn des Staates. " Comments on this and related phrases 
 will be reserved until we reach Justi; vide below, pp. 404 3.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 181 
 
 means, without illegal offense to others. It is not to be believed that 
 the first men who subjected themselves to a human scepter surren- 
 dered their freedom which belonged to them by nature, without this 
 intention. If now worldly governments are not to be repugnant 
 to the law of nature and the eternal decrees [RathsMdge} of Almighty 
 God, their counsels must also seek to maintain this intention. The 
 greatest emperors and princes have most laudably recognized that 
 subjects were not created for their benefit, but they for the subjects. 
 How much more must those who are appointed by them as servants 
 and watchmen of the common well-being [gemeinen Wohlseyns] 
 entertain no other thoughts? 
 
 In the next paragraph but one the author reduces these 
 generalities to somewhat more specific form in this way: 
 
 Everything which preserves, promotes, and makes permanent 
 common repose and peace with pleasing security in the Republique 
 in permissible and righteous ways, that must with all care and 
 attention be undertaken and put in execution. It follows, however, 
 that anything which is in any degree capable of hindering common 
 repose and peace must be omitted, prevented, and excluded. Who- 
 ever reasonably meditates these two rules, he may arrive in his own 
 head, if he will only at the same time open his eyes and look into 
 the world, at a reflection of all civic science. Indeed, means will 
 often thereby be put in his hand, without his special attention, for 
 putting this science into useful application. 
 
 Then follow still more specific reassertions of the ends of 
 civic society as represented by the quasi-absolutistic state, and 
 of the corresponding outlook of civic science as it was coming 
 to be defined in cameralism. Thus: 
 
 Since external assaults were probably the chief occasion for the 
 first raisonablen Republique, political sagacity must also make this 
 its first care. Hence it has come to pass that the principal attention 
 has been given to the power of a prince. The power however con- 
 sists in adequate strength to protect the lands which belong to a 
 state against assaults of its neighbors. Since now, in the judgment 
 of all, people and money are necessary for this purpose, it cannot be
 
 1 82 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 denied that where these things are in readiness the happiness of a 
 country is thereby quite visibly guaranteed (p. 45). 
 
 After referring at some length to the other side of the case, 
 viz., "where there is the greatest power, there it is easiest to do 
 wrong," Gerhard once more formulates the essentials of civic 
 policy as he sees it, in terms of "population, money, and 
 friends." 1 
 
 Returning to the subject of scientific method, Gerhard 
 concludes, quite sanely: 
 
 If one is right on these matters, then it will amount to one and the 
 same thing whether one divides civic science into two or two and 
 
 twenty parts There is no harm done if, for the sake of 
 
 grasping the concepts more thoroughly, one subdivides the matter 
 a little. One must however not imagine that the fate of the Holy 
 Roman Empire hangs on such subdivisions; and quarrels about 
 such arbitrary matters are ridiculous. Each is entitled to his own 
 way of dealing with the subject, and although it is well to fall in with 
 the prevailing fashion, yet there is no law to force such conformity 
 upon us; if there were, the fashions could not change so often. In 
 my judgment, there would be no harm in dividing civic science into 
 a general and a special division, for there are rules of prudence which 
 apply to all men alike. Each has on the contrary his own reasons 
 of state, and the special portion of civic science may have as many 
 varieties as there are orders of society in the world 
 
 If God should grant me opportunity and sufficient experience 
 to develop in an orderly written form the thoughts on civic science 
 which I have thus far only communicated orally to my students, I 
 would first set in order the general rules of treatment. I would then 
 discuss the most complete society of the Republique in accordance 
 with its purpose, and finally I would point out their duties to the 
 societies that occur in ordinary life, i. e., of married people, of 
 parents and children, of masters and servants, of intermediate rulers 
 and subjects. Especially would I picture to my dearly beloved 
 
 1 Thereupon he quotes with approval "D. Leib, in seinen vier 
 Proben." Vide above, p. 172.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GERHARD 183 
 
 students an ideally organized student-state, and I should think that 
 
 in so doing I was discharging the duty of an upright teacher 
 
 As to the subdivisions of the second (special) part of the science, 
 they would require many sections. It is however not necessary to 
 anticipate them. Whoever understands the science of making the 
 subjects numerous, rich, and moral, in accordance with what has 
 preceded, will easily find out for himself an order for the means 
 thereto necessary. I will at present say only this much: that to 
 this end before all others the didactic method of the incomparable 
 von Seckendorff seems best adapted. In his Fiirstenstaat he affords 
 so much opportunity for profitable comment that I believe my 
 independent efforts in connection with this science may be long 
 deferred. 
 
 Not only in the breadth of comprehension which these 
 observations indicate, but in the detail of seeing a place for a 
 general and a special treatment of the science of the state, 
 Gerhard was well in advance of his time. Justi was most 
 successful among the cameralists in making use of this sug- 
 gestion. Gerhard deserves credit for perceptions about 
 scientific technique which men of his type did not fully appro- 
 priate until a century after he had put them on record. In so 
 far he anticipated the established practice of modern German 
 scholars in all the social sciences. 
 
 It is also not too much to say that, in his brief discussion of 
 the subjects which should be studied in connection with civic 
 science (pp. 53 ff.), Gerhard showed breadth of intelligence, 
 if not insight into detail, equal to that afterward exhibited by 
 Justi. Indeed, it is plain that the former had a much broader 
 foundation for his special programme of civic science than the 
 latter. Justi furnishes no clear evidence that his foundations 
 were as strong as those on which Gerhard rests when he says: 
 
 Accordingly it is right to say that civic science begins where 
 moral philosophy ends, and it sufficiently appears that the student 
 of politics, before he can become a statesman, must be a student of 
 moral philosophy. Whoever does this with reason and at the right
 
 1 84 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 time, while the tree is still capable of being inclined, and thereby is 
 properly molded in justice, good manners, honor, and the fear of 
 God: if he otherwise has good understanding, will not find any 
 
 portion of civic science difficult To sum up the whole 
 
 matter: Whoever will learn civic science to advantage, let him first 
 leam to understand other men, the forces of nature, and the estab- 
 lished institutions of the world. Then civic science can teach him 
 besides nothing but the ways in which he may best apply such 
 intelligence (p. 57). 
 
 Gerhard may also be observed to advantage as an index of 
 the extent to which there was at his time a recognized camera- 
 listic tradition in academic circles. Those who wish to pursue 
 the subject farther than our present limits permit, should read 
 the Appendix of Gerhard's syllabus. It is a fair index both 
 of the poverty and of the progress of German thought in this 
 subject at the opening of the eighteenth century.
 
 CHAPTER VIII 
 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 
 
 In a period which discriminated more carefully between 
 dilettanteish and critical writing, the subject of this chapter 
 would hardly have attained prominence among specialists. 
 Because of the attention which was actually paid to him by a 
 considerable number of successors, he cannot be omitted from 
 our account. Intrinsically he does not deserve mention with 
 cameralistic writers of the first rank. 
 
 Inama 1 furnishes a biographical sketch to this effect: 
 
 Julius Bernhard von Rohr was the son of a country gentleman 
 (Riltergutsbesitzer), Julius Albert von Rohr. He was born in 1688 
 and died in 1742. His education was carefully planned. At the 
 age of seventeen he was sent to the University of Leipzig, where he 
 studied law, mathematics, chemistry, physics, and Oekonomik. 
 After ending his studies he went with his father to Hamburg, to 
 get acquainted with the business organization of that city. He 
 became an attache of the delegation sent to Frankfurt for the imperial 
 election of 1712. The death of his father and the embarrassed 
 condition of the estate presently put him on a very limited income. 
 He went to Halle to study mathematics with Wolf; in 1713 to Hol- 
 land; in 1714 he received a position as member of the Stijts- und 
 Erblands-Regierung at Magdeburg; in 1726 was transferred to a 
 similar position at Niederlausitz; in 1731 became herzoglicker 
 Landkammerrath; in 1732 Domherr zu Merseberg, but the position 
 seems to have secured his standing rather than to have furnished an 
 occupation. He had been on the waiting-list for this sort of eccle- 
 siastical preferment since he was two years old. He became a mem- 
 ber of the Landkammer at Merseberg, where he remained till his 
 retirement in 1738. 
 
 Rohr somehow managed to retrieve his financial fortunes to such 
 an extent that he accumulated a library for that time rather rich, 
 
 ' In All. d. Bib., in loc. 
 
 '85
 
 1 86 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and also in 1720 acquired a landed estate between Dresden and 
 Meissen, where he carried on wine culture, horticulture, and agri- 
 culture. He had troubled relations with a mistress, 1724-39. He 
 married another woman in 1739, and wrote his friends an elaborate 
 explanation of his domestic affairs. 1 
 
 Rohr is credited with the authorship of twenty-nine pub- 
 lished works, and of nine others left in an unfinished state. 2 
 
 According to Inama, doubtless because of the author's remark 
 on the second page of the Vorrede to the Haushaltungsbibliothek, 
 Rohr spoke of Hauswirthschajtskunst, on the basis of natural science, 
 as the chief task of his life. In his conception of political science 
 he was a devoted admirer of Seckendorff; in his more concrete 
 cameralistics he was equally attached to Schroder. " Under the 
 influence of Wolf's eudaemonism he advanced in many respects 
 beyond either." Under the same influence he escaped some of the 
 poverty of the old Hausvater litter atur, and on the other hand his 
 knowledge of natural science was a factor in promoting the develop- 
 ment of cameralism. In particular, he was of service in preparing 
 the way for academic cameralism, which Dithmar and Gasser were 
 permitted to introduce into the Prussian universities. 
 
 Roscher (p. 378) speaks of the Compendieuse Haushal- 
 tungsbibliothek as Rohr's "chief work." If there can be a 
 "chief" among mediocrities, that designation can hardly 
 
 1 In comparison with this account, it is surprising that Roscher did 
 not probe beyond the misleading contents of the note (p. 178): "Er 
 lebtc unvermahlt, mit vie! Biichcrn, Corresponclenz und Reisen, als 
 Domherr zu Merseberg." For our interests, Rohr's life ended before 
 this appointment. 
 
 * Zedler, Universallexicon, in loc. Chief among these wen-: (i) 
 Compendieuse H aushaltungsbibliothek (1716; 2. Ausg., 1726; 3. Ausg., 
 J?:?. 1 )); ( 2 ) Physikalische Bibliothek (1724; 2. Aufl., 1754); Rohr pro- 
 jected a M ' athemalische Bibliothek, "since these three sciences are united 
 by an inseparable bond;" (3) Einleitung zur Staatsklugheil (1718); (4) 
 Einleitung zur Ceremonial-Wissenschaft der Privatpersonen (1728); (5) 
 Einleitun% zur Ceremonial-Wisscnsckaft der grossen Herrn (1729); (6) 
 O hers fie hxisckes Haurwirthschaflshuch (1722); (7) H auahaltungsrecht 
 (1732, 1734; 2 Bande; 2. Aufl., 1738).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 187 
 
 remain in this case where Roscher placed it. He does not 
 seem to have been acquainted with Rohr's more pretentious 
 works. The Haushaltungsbibliothek, 1 even in the "much 
 enlarged" third edition, is a small handbook of 692 pages. It 
 uses the word Oeconomie as synonymous with its general 
 subject-matter. In the dedication to Kreishauptmann Peter 
 Freyherr von Hohenthal, the author says: 
 
 While writers on management [oconomische] have remained as 
 a rule unread by the learned, because they considered them too low, 
 and by housekeepers, because they found them too high, the useful 
 instruction which you [Ew. Hochwohlgebornen] have instituted shows 
 how many objects not only of important but also of ingenious investi- 
 gation Oeconomie contains, and how little one who is uninformed is 
 competent to conduct with success occupations which demand so 
 much knowledge and reflection. 2 
 
 The author's Preface to the second edition, dated August 
 9, 1726, declares that the first edition had been well received 
 by the public, and that certain scholars in the universities had 
 done it the honor of lecturing upon it. The explanation of the 
 author's intention in citing books which could actually be used 
 in household and agricultural management has an important 
 bearing upon the myth which the critics of mercantilism have 
 propagated, that there was no attention to agriculture and no 
 thought of it. At this time there were not only many writings 
 on the subject, but they were not so very difficult to obtain, 3 
 and Rohr's book refers to the most available of them. 
 
 1 Julius Bernhards von Rohr, Merseb. Domherrn und Land- 
 Cammerraths Haushaltungs Bibliothek worinnen die vornehmsten 
 Schriften, die zur Haushaltungskunst gehoren, angezeiget werden. 
 Dritte und viel vermehrte Auflage, 1755. I have not seen a copy of the 
 original edition of 1716. 
 
 8 This passage is one of the clearest reflections of the meanings 
 attached at this time to variations of the term Oeconomie. It meant 
 plain vulgar thrift, and then the beginnings of systematic thinking about 
 thrift. 
 
 3 We shall return to this point in connection with later writers. 
 Vide p. 256 below.
 
 1 88 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 In the Vorrede of the third edition, 1755, the editor shows 
 that in his mind the word Oeconomie still stands for a very 
 concrete type of technology, not for the sort of generalization 
 which later appropriated the term. He says: 
 
 If we think of Oeconomie, not as it is practiced by the lowest 
 portion of housekeepers [Hauswirthe], but rather as that which it 
 actually is, an art whose prescriptions are based upon knowledge of 
 nature, and which can be properly exercised and extended only by 
 means of this knowledge, then it deserves a respectable place among 
 the learned sciences. It requires also for its completeness the appli- 
 cation of various other parts of human knowledge, and the learning 
 of that which predecessors have done; that is, books must be read. 
 
 As a cameralistic book, in the proper sense, the Haushal- 
 tungsbibliolhek would not deserve mention. As an index of 
 the relation between the subjects known at the time as Oecono- 
 mie and Catneralwissenschaft in general, it is highly instructive. 
 A glance at the Table of Contents would sufficiently fix this 
 relation. A few sentences from the text may be added without 
 comment. The opening sentence of the first chapter declares: 
 
 The art of managing the household [Haushaltungskunst] is a 
 practical science (sic), which teaches how one in a proper way may 
 acquire money and goods [Geld und Gut], may conserve and wisely 
 expend what is acquired, for the promotion or maintenance of one's 
 temporal happiness. 
 
 Sec. 2 of the same chapter continues: 
 
 The art of managing the household may be divided into the 
 Oeconomica of princes and of private persons. In the former case 
 it is called Cameral-Finanz- und Domainenwissenschajt. It consists 
 in a prudence not only in administering his own means and revenues 
 and those of his land, and in maintaining the community, but also 
 
 in adding to the money and goods of the subjects The 
 
 house management of private persons may again be divided into 
 city and country management \Stadt- und Landwirthschaftskunst]. 
 Under the former head I reckon knowledge of the coins, of trans- 
 actions with money, skill in keeping everything in order in the
 
 house, and in placing the furniture in the rooms according to sym- 
 metry and use, proper supply of the table, temperate use of drinks, 
 wise control of servants, etc. Such things occur also in the country, 
 but because these arrangements can be made without possessing 
 estates [liegende GUter], I will not attribute them properly to rural 
 management, which involves immovable landed property. Of this 
 in general the so-called housekeeping books [Haushaltungsbiicher] 
 treat, and the same consists in knowledge of agriculture, of cattle 
 raising, of fisheries, hunting, forests, gardening, vineyards, etc. 
 This latter is much more comprehensive and difficult than the former, 
 for whoever has the skill to carry on management in the country can 
 quickly learn city management. On the contrary, whoever comes 
 from the city to the country, unless he has particular zeal and guid- 
 ance, will find it hard to adapt himself to rural management. 
 
 Both city and country management embrace three parts, namely 
 skill (i) to acquire money and goods, (2) to retain what is acquired, 
 and (3) wisely to expend it. 1 
 
 As cumulative evidence on the general position of the 
 cameralists, the opening sentence of the second chapter is in 
 order. It is the author's definition of cameral science, viz.: 
 
 Cameral science (Cameralwissenschaft) teaches princes not only 
 well to conserve and increase their means, but also to promote their 
 subjects' happiness and to order their management (Oeconomie). 
 
 Then the motive of Schroder's civic philosophy reappears 
 in this form (chap, ii, 4): 
 
 The best means of enriching a land is to take care that many 
 people are drawn into the land, and also that all the subjects through 
 diligent labor may have their support and means of gain [Nahntng 
 und Erwerb]. 
 
 These citations show the general character of this book of 
 homely wisdom. After Rohr had written this earlier book, 
 his notions of his vocation seem to have become more ambitious. 
 
 1 This last proposition is notable because, although it seems to be 
 a platitude, it expresses the common-sense which became one of the 
 working premises of nearly all the later cameralists.
 
 1 90 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 He did not confine himself to "management" in the narrower 
 sense of his first programme. We may therefore find an 
 expansion of his ideas in another book. Though it contains 
 nothing original with the author, it won him not a little recog- 
 nition among later cameralists. 1 
 
 Previous to publication of the books we have named, Rohr 
 had neither academic nor governmental experience to be 
 compared with that of most of the cameralists; and his forms 
 of expression are visibly apologetic toward each of the classes 
 by which he was doubtless rated as an amateur. He writes 
 
 1 Julii Bernhards von Rohr Einleitung zur Staats-Klugheit, oder: 
 Vorstellung Wie Ckristliche und iveise Regenten zur Beforderung ihrer 
 eigenen und ihrcs Landes Gluckseeligkeit Ihre Unterthanen zu beherrschen 
 pflegen. Mil Konigl. Pohln. und Clurfl. Siichss. allergn. Privilegio. 
 Leipzig, 1718. In his Vorrede, Rohr speaks of a previous book, Ein- 
 leitung zur Klugheit zu leben, darinnen ich jungen Leuten einige Regeln 
 der Frivol- Klugheit beybringen wollen. The author refers to the present 
 volume as a companion book, designed for the use of beginners in the 
 study of Staats-Klugheit. He says that the book is quite different from 
 Seckendorffs Teutschen Furstcn-Staate, which had been "up to that 
 time much read by the Germans, and to good advantage." Rohr makes 
 this difference consist first, in describing not only what Christian princes 
 have done in the way of wise and just administration, but also what they 
 might well cease to do; and second, Rohr says that Seckendorff com- 
 posed his book more as a moral than as a political treatise; that is, he 
 showed what a ruler would do in pursuance of civic law, if he acted in 
 accordance with his conscience and his duty to God, and his obligations 
 to his country, but he did not show the means by which the tasks of 
 government are to be carried out in detail. Rohr claims also that his 
 book treats of many subjects which Seckendorff neglected. At the same 
 time he concedes to Seckendorffs works a rank above his own. He 
 explains also that he has had the Evangelical Lutheran states chiefly in 
 mind, because in the Catholic states the doctrines of Staats-Klugheit 
 are concerned with somewhat different objects, and rest upon quite 
 different principles. Besides Seckendorff, Rohr says that he has used 
 particularly Schroder, Leib, Marperger, "the learned and eminent 
 authors of the Unschuldigen Nachrichten," Herr I). Dohler, Hr. 
 Horn.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR IQI 
 
 rather as an essayist than as a technologist. On the one hand 
 the systematic method of the academic thinker is lacking, and 
 on the other hand the firm touch of the man accustomed to deal 
 directly with affairs. He can be included among the cameral- 
 ists only as an evidence of the impressions which the cameral- 
 ism both of the bureaus and of the books had made up to his 
 date upon a university man of a rather refined type. Granting 
 that he helped to gain a hearing for cameralism in the univer- 
 sities, there is no evidence that he exerted a distinct influence 
 upon the development of the theory itself. 1 The Einleitung, 
 however, would be an extremely valuable collection of material 
 for the student of the culture history of the period. 
 
 The book is a compact volume of 1,474 pages, with a table 
 of contents and index filling thirty more pages. The plate 
 opposite the title-page represents a king upon his throne, at 
 his right female figures symbolizing Religion and Justice, at 
 his left Peace and Prudence, and below the couplet: 
 
 Wenn ein Regente will des Landcs Wolfarth baucn, 
 Mus er auf Gottesfurcht, Justiz uncl Klughcit schaucn. 
 
 The opening paragraph reads: 
 
 Prudence [Klugheit] is an adaptability of temper by which actions 
 are directed with reason and foresight toward the promotion of true 
 happiness. It discovers means by which, without prejudice and 
 hindrance to others, one may most conveniently and easily attain 
 and preserve happiness. Because it aims at true happiness, it 
 proposes first eternal and second temporal happiness as its chief 
 and subordinate aim. It is otherwise called die Politic, and is 
 either a true or a false prudence. 
 
 The looseness of thinking in this paragraph may be taken as 
 
 1 The copy of the Einleitung which I have studied was borrowed 
 from the Royal Library at Berlin. While it is much discolored by age, 
 it shows no signs of use. Indeed many of the leaves had evidently never 
 been separated since they left the bindery, and a considerable number, 
 including one containing a part of the Table of Contents, were uncut !
 
 IQ2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 an index of the quality of the book. The ambiguity that is 
 involved in making the same word stand for "adaptability of 
 temper" and "Politic" is symptomatic of the style throughout. 
 The author is popular rather than analytic in his treatment. 
 He can be accepted therefore merely as in certain respects a 
 sign of the times, but not as a factor in the development of 
 cameralistic theory or technology. This popular and uncritical 
 quality is even more apparent in the second paragraph, viz.: 
 
 The true prudence demands nothing except that to which it may 
 properly lay claim according to divine and natural law; it subor- 
 dinates the will, as much as possible, when it would go to excess, 
 and for the accomplishment of its purposes it uses permissible means. 
 Its aim is the well-being of itself (sic) and of other men (sic); yet it 
 recognizes, in case of collision between its own and its neighbor's 
 fortunes, that the preference belongs to itself [! ]. It [Klu^heit] sees 
 from its own experience and that of others that all temporal happi- 
 ness, however plausible, is associated with much unrest, is fluid and 
 fleeting, and that it quite unconsciously slips out of the hands of its 
 possessors. 
 
 Thus while the b(x>k contains much that might have been 
 instructive to certain types of mind, in early stages of education, 
 it is not to be taken seriously as a sample of the academic or 
 professional thinking of the author's generation. It belongs 
 in the class once known as "edifying," rather than among 
 technological treatises. 
 
 Rohr distinguishes "the prudence of private persons" from 
 "that of the reigning princes" (p. 10). The former was 
 treated in the book named above, 1 the latter is the subject 
 of the present volume. More particularly, the prudence of 
 the reigning prince, or civic prudence [Stoats- Klugheit] is 
 described as: 
 
 the adaptability of the understanding, by means of which rulers are 
 capable of promoting not only their own but all their subjects' true 
 happiness (p. 11). 
 
 1 Vide above, p. irjo. Klugheit zu leben.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 193 
 
 The division of civic prudence into general and special, 
 which we find first clearly stated by Gerhard, is adopted by 
 Rohr, but whether or not he was in any way indebted for the 
 idea to the earlier writer does not appear. His distinction, 
 while apparently the same, is really not along the same lines as 
 Gerhard's. Rohr calls application of the rules of general civic 
 prudence to a given state "special civic prudence," instead of 
 grasping the conception of more general and less general 
 principles which may in their way be applicable to all states. 
 Indeed he does not seem to realize that there is a place for 
 general principles, other than religious doctrines or moral 
 truisms, upon which details of civic polity must rest. Instead, 
 he assumes that one may be a specialist in civic science by 
 simply selecting a fraction of it as his task: 
 
 Just as it is impossible that a man, however diligent, should 
 cultivate all civic prudence completely: so it is well done if each 
 should pursue those parts for which he has inclination, talent, and 
 opportunity (p. 33). 
 
 Rohr bases his essay without hesitation upon the idea of 
 the patriarchal prerogative of the prince: 
 
 Just as a ruling prince presents two moral persons, first a private 
 person, who in many acts must conform himself to other private 
 persons, yet also is to be considered as a prince, who has to direct the 
 conduct of his subjects, he must consequently be versed in both 
 private and public prudence (p. 34). 
 
 That the book is rather rhetorical than technical is illus- 
 trated again in the next paragraph : 
 
 The chief task of the prudence of a ruler consists in always seeking 
 to combine his happiness with that of his subjects, and in striving 
 to prevent them from becoming separated. The prosperity of a 
 ruler which is not founded on the weal of his land is of no perma- 
 nence, as is shown by many ancient and modern histories. He must 
 have the prosperity of his subjects in view in all his actions, and must 
 undertake nothing which is inconsistent with the same.
 
 194 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 At the same time, Rohr quite as distinctly affirms the 
 absolutism of rulers. Thus: 
 
 In case of a collision between his own interest and the welfare 
 of the subjects, from love for his land, in order to promote the common 
 interest [gemeinschafttlichc Inlercsse] he must subordinate his own 
 interest. He thereby not only wins the love of his subjects, but he 
 floes that to which he is appointed of God. And while sovereigns are 
 not bound to render account for their actions to anyone in the world, 
 yet they, as well as their subjects, have over them the supreme ruler 
 in heaven, to whom at the great day of judgment they must give 
 answer. 
 
 While the author reiterates on the one hand the sonorous 
 principle, "Solus popttli must be the law of the prince," yet 
 on the other hand he unconsciously betrays the rendering which 
 the spirit of the time tended to give to the principle, when he 
 says: 
 
 The art of government is in fact an art above all arts; because 
 it can make kingdoms out of principalities and empires out of king- 
 doms, can raise a sunken state to its former splendor, and through 
 this rare power of making a prince really great it proves itself the 
 true statecraft. 
 
 In the following section (p. 37) Duke Ernst of Gotha, 
 Seckendorff's master, is cited as a type of the Christian prince, 
 and as evidence that piety is necessary for the success of a ruler. 
 No mention is made at this point of Seckendorff, however, 
 from whom it is probable that Rohr derived the substance of 
 his political ideas. For example, the sections in which he 
 describes the duties of a prince in general, especially 7-19, 
 merely render Seckendorff's views in slightly varied terms, 
 and with trifling additions of detail or illustration. It amounts 
 to no proper acknowledgment to the man who furnished the 
 thoughts when at last, in 18, his name is used in connection 
 with the least important item in the whole programme, viz., 
 the recreations of the prince!
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR IQ5 
 
 Since Rohr was not a camcralist, but merely a contemporary 
 popularizer of cameralism, we repeat that he is worth our 
 notice merely as secondary evidence bearing upon the impres- 
 sion which technical cameralism had made upon the thinking 
 of men at one remove from the more technical writers. 
 
 In a confused paragraph (p. 71) the author raises but does 
 not distinctly answer the question: 
 
 In case a reigning prince violates his fundamental pledges to his 
 subjects, have they a right to resist? Rohr first remarks, "It is 
 well known that those who withstand the divinely appointed author- 
 ities resist the divine order," and he draws the conclusion that a 
 perfidious prince should be left rather to divine justice than forcibly 
 dealt with by his subjects. Without much assurance that the next 
 recourse is very promising, he points out that the constitution of the 
 Empire calls for judgment by imperial authorities upon a prince who 
 disturbs or threatens the order of the Empire by not keeping faitli 
 with his subjects. Pushing the hypothesis to the extreme form, 
 that "the excesses of the prince make the life of a virtuous subject 
 insecure," Rohr ventures the very cautious judgment that in such 
 case one is justified in resisting the prince. He immediately adds: 
 "If the ruler goes only so far, however, as to devise against one ami 
 another private person things contrary to God and to natural decency 
 [Erbarkcit], such subjects must rather depart from the country, or 
 bear the injustice with patience, than oppose the majesty of their 
 ruling sovereign with violence." The whole discussion of contracts 
 to which a ruler is a party is conducted upon a shifting basis of theo- 
 logical dogma, ethical generality, and amateurish Icgalism. In 
 modern vernacular, it amounts to a whitewashing report upon the 
 political status quo, under the form of an impartial inquiry into 
 alternatives. 
 
 The fourth chapter ("Yon dem Oeconomie \Ve.sen") is 
 worth notice as a further index to the current sense of the term 
 Oeconomie. As we try to make evident throughout this analy- 
 sis, the readiness with which this and similar terms have been 
 translated from German into English words which were
 
 196 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 equivalent in appearance, but not in sense, has been a serious 
 hindrance to proper insight into the meaning of German 
 sociological evolution. The one point to be emphasized here 
 is that nowhere, in the "series of writers interpreted in this 
 study, did any variation of the word Oeconomie have the force 
 carried by the English derivative from the same root in the 
 phrase "political economy." In the whole usage of the 
 cameralists Oeconomie was primarily thrifty management, as 
 measured by the prevailing standards of household or public 
 prudence. Oeconomie was literally housekeeping (Haus- 
 haltung, Haushaltungskunst, etc.), and this conception clung 
 to it, whether the immediate reference was to thrift in the 
 household, on the farm, in artisanship, trade, or government. 
 Oeconomie was never, until the period of Smithism, generalized 
 and deepened into consideration of problems underneath 
 rule-of-thumb wisdom. With this in mind, we find in Rohr's 
 approach to the subject of Oeconomie-Wesen an instructive 
 guide to the plane of interests which held the attention of men 
 of affairs, both industrial and governmental, before the stage 
 of critical and philosophical interpretation of economics. He 
 opens the chapter in this way: 
 
 Just as private persons fill their storerooms by orderly and 
 reasonable management [Haushalten], so that they can draw one 
 supply after another; in the same way with ruling princes, if they 
 attend to their FiirsUichen Oeconomie und Cameral-Wesen in a proper 
 manner, the happiness not only of their own persons and of their 
 families, but also of their subjects, which must always be connected 
 with their own, will be promoted and secured. In the case of princely 
 persons a double Oeconomica must have place, .... first, the 
 
 Oeconomica of private persons In this connection they 
 
 must take care that the sums which they lend [Capitdien] are 
 securely invested and kept in good circulation [rouliren]. They 
 must administer their domains to good advantage, apportion the 
 outlays reasonably and see that they are balanced by the income, 
 and always take care that a margin remains. That which God has
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 197 
 
 given them they must conserve, in order that it may not be impaired 
 or lost, etc. In all this they must give exact heed to the same rules 
 and cautions which private persons must observe. Beyond this 
 there is, second, the FUrstliche Oeconomica, since princes must not 
 only pay attention to increase and preservation of their private 
 incomes, but also to enlargement and preservation of the happiness 
 and goods of their subjects. 
 
 Then follows non-technical description of the administra- 
 tive machinery which the cameralists had begun to analyze 
 more precisely. Rohr explains the Oeconomie-Wesen of 
 rulers as an affair of two divisions, distribuendo et augendo, 
 on the one hand of applying the revenues, on the other of 
 raising them. He uses the term Cameralisten for those 
 officials who have the former division in charge, and explains 
 that a quite different body of persons should be employed in 
 the other division. Thus he thinks (p. 99) that Cameral-Sachen 
 should be divided into two distinct collegia the division, 
 by the way, not according precisely with the distribution of 
 functions proposed by the author a few lines before the one, 
 called the Cammer proper, to collect and disburse the reveunes, 
 the other exclusively to deliberate how to increase the revenues. 
 He claims that the usual union of these two collegia in a single 
 Cammer is harmful and costly. 1 Rohr goes into detail about 
 cameralistic technique as though he were an expert, but our 
 purpose does not require attention to the technological side of 
 cameralism, and if it did we should be concerned not with the 
 expositions of amateurs like Rohr, but with those of men who 
 could speak with authority. 
 
 A glance at Rohr's table of contents would show that the 
 personality of the prince, and dynastic policy, are made the 
 center from which the remainder of the book proceeds. While 
 this at once condemns the book, from the standpoint of the 
 
 1 At this point the author appeals to the second chapter of Schro- 
 der's FUrstliche Schatz- und Rcnih-Cammer.
 
 198 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 modern social theorist, it affords the very evidence which makes 
 the book valuable to the historical interpreter. This para- 
 mount value of government, and of the prince as incarnating 
 government, is fundamental in the whole camcralistic regime 
 and theory. It is the pass-key to the whole system. Came- 
 ralism as a technique and as a theory was a means developed 
 in the interest of an end visualized first and foremost in the 
 person of the prince, if never absolutely identical with the prince 
 and his interests. In respect to this one factor, the develop- 
 ment of German civilization, not to carry the generalization 
 at this point beyond Germany, was a progressive realization of 
 other values in society besides those of rulers and governments, 
 and progressive readjustment of ratios between the several 
 values. All the doctrines and policies of the period which 
 we are considering have to be interpreted in their connection 
 with the ruling presumption of the paramount importance 
 of the prince, who may or may not have been differentiated 
 in thought from the government which he represented. In 
 either case, the ideas of prince and government as values in 
 themselves, not as functionaries and functions to be appraised 
 according to their service for other values, were foremost and 
 decisive throughout this regime. We shall have occasion to 
 ask more than once, as we proceed, To what extent had some 
 suggestion of another scale of values begun to work in the minds 
 of the Germans? It is not a part of the task set for this 
 volume to demonstrate the answer to the question. We shall 
 be obliged, however, to point out frequent incidental symptoms 
 of the workings of more democratic impressions. 
 
 Rohr expressly adopts that form of the social contract 
 theory which presupposes nature people contemplating an 
 intolerable social condition, real or impending. To escape 
 or to avert this condition the whole number of individuals 
 make over their wills to one or more rulers. Thereafter the 
 will of the whole community can be expressed only by this
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF RO1IR 199 
 
 single or multiple ruler, and the subject has no rightful alter- 
 native but obedience. The ruler summarizes not only the 
 will but the welfare of the state, or of the individuals merged 
 into a unique personality (pp. 248 ff.). By a chain of reason- 
 ing which we need not follow, Rohr concludes further (p. 258) 
 that a Christian monarch is bound by divine and human law 
 to take responsibility for both the temporal and the eternal 
 welfare of his subjects. This view of course furnishes the 
 basis for explanation of the ecclesiastical polity of Lutheran 
 states, and the author shows decidedly better acquaintance 
 with church problems, and especially with minutiae of parochial 
 procedure, than with the more strictly cameralistic departments 
 of government. This leaning toward ecclesiasticism is shown 
 in a most painfully smug chapter on the proper course of rulers 
 toward "dreamers, pietists, and new prophets" (pp. 322-65). 
 
 It must be admitted, however, that if Rohr's ecclesiastical 
 views belong in a world which Americans cannot understand, 
 his views of the relation of the state to education are at bottom 
 identical with our own. So far as there is a difference in 
 principle it may be traced to his emphasis on the interest of 
 the state in the training of good citizens, while we are inclined 
 to view the matter more from the side of the right of the indi- 
 vidual to education. The ecclesiastical factors in education 
 which Rohr had in mind were, both in subject-matter and in 
 machinery, accidental rather than essential variations of 
 educational principles which modern democracies attempt to 
 apply with other details. 
 
 In the chapter "Von Academien" Rohr partially antici- 
 pates Justi in a plea for "ein Professor Oeconomiae" at the 
 universities. The chapter is entirely in accord with the other 
 evidence found in the writers of this group to the effect that 
 their references to "oeconomica" or any equivalent expression 
 connoted something very different from the implications of 
 the same terms in the nineteenth century, and particularly
 
 200 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 different from English versions of the terms. In the order in 
 which the items occur in the chapter, we may note, first, that 
 the subjects which Rohr wishes such a professor to teach are 
 at once indicated by the phrase Stadt- und Landes-Wirth- 
 scliaft; second, the principal reason alleged for failure to 
 establish such professorships was difficulty of finding men who 
 had university training who at the same time possessed either 
 knowledge of these subjects or fitness to teach them; third, 
 slightly varying the second point, scholars had seldom given 
 attention to Oeconomie, while skilled managers (Haushaltungs 
 Verstandige) had seldom done much with "studiis" in the 
 university sense; third, it ought not to be difficult to find here 
 and there men with experience in administrative offices who 
 understand management (Wirthschafft) from the bottom and 
 couM teach it passably; fourth, in answer to the claim that 
 Oeconomica, Politica und morale ought to be taught by the 
 Professori moralium, and that accordingly increase of the 
 number of professorships is unnecessary, Rohr says it is true 
 that diligent Professori moralium do not fail to introduce into 
 their political courses all sorts of economic observations, but 
 it is impossible that they could fully explain these three 
 sciences; 1 fifth, quoting Dohler, 2 "In the schools the prejudiced 
 opinion prevails that a student should not concern himself 
 with any sort of Hauss-Wesen, that it is even a disgrace for a 
 student to have anything to do with such employments;" sixth, 
 such being the case, it is high time that students in schools 
 and colleges should learn Oeconomie from artisans and even 
 from peasants. 3 
 
 1 At this point appeal is made to Morhoff, "in dem 3. Buche des 
 III. Tomi seines Polykistoris;" and to "der beriihmte Professor zu 
 Franc kfurt, Johann Christoph Beckmann, in dem f 10. des X. Capitels 
 seiner Polit. Parall." 
 
 "Herrn Job. George Dohler in seiner Untersuchung des heut-su- 
 Tage uberhand nthmenden Geld- und Nahrungs-M angels" 
 
 3 The author refers for further considerations on the subject to the 
 first chapter of his Hauskaltungs-Bibliothek.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 201 
 
 From these citations it is evident that by common under- 
 standing among friends and foes of "economic" instruction, 
 the thing intended was technical, not philosophical. It was 
 even more remote from subjects then regarded as within the 
 pale of Wissenschaft than manual training is today in the minds 
 of those who are least inclined to welcome it, or its maturer 
 continuations, into our lower and higher schools. 
 
 Chap, xvi, " Von der Gelehrsamkeit," develops the theorem: 
 
 Since good arts and sciences are fitted in no slight degree to 
 increase and to. maintain the happiness of a land and of its ruler, 
 it follows that a ruler who has the weal of his provinces at heart has 
 the best of reasons for desiring that his subjects should be instructed 
 in all sorts of useful disciplines. The more learned and intelligent 
 they are, the more available are they, whether in peace or in war. 
 
 The discussion takes a turn which shows the limitations of 
 the time with respect to freedom of thought; that is, it dwells 
 more on what should not be permitted in schools, or allowed 
 to appear in print, than upon promotion of unrestricted investi- 
 gation; but in one direction it calls for increased liberality. 
 Sec. 12 opens with the remarks: 
 
 In the case of political writings, people are in many places far 
 too scrupulous. State secrets are made out of matters which are 
 quite innocent, and sometimes people fear to make public anything 
 with reference to state affairs, although no good reason for such 
 caution can be found. 1 
 
 Beginning with chap, xvii, " Von Lastern," the book invades 
 more and more technical ground, but with the equipment of 
 the essayist rather than of the specialist, and in a style addressed 
 rather to the general reader than to close students. As a 
 mirror of the times, it would be of great value to a culture 
 historian who knew how to use such material. For our 
 purpose it yields nothing which is not to be found in more 
 reliable form elsewhere. 
 
 1 Obrecht has already furnished us a case in point. Vide above, 
 P-43-
 
 202 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Two exceptions to the foregoing must be noted. The first 
 is a negative contribution to our inquiry. In the twenty-first 
 chapter, on the police system of cities, Rohr gives one of the 
 clearest testimonies to be found in the cameralistic or quasi- 
 cameralistic literature, that the police system as outlined later 
 was only in a slight degree in existence at the date of the book. 
 The institution had yet to be developed to meet needs that 
 were felt before the means of satisfying them were created. 
 Rohr quotes "a certain unnamed author, who has described 
 the well-organized state of the hitherto much-sought but never- 
 discovered kingdom of Ophir." He is said to have expressed 
 himself as follows: 
 
 Because through observance of good Policey the divine blessing 
 and the prosperity of a land are best insured, certain Policcy-Rathe 
 should be appointed. These should be efficient and learned men in 
 Moralibus, Politicis und Oeconomicis, and they should be used for 
 drawing up good police ordinances, and for zealously supervising 
 their execution. Their office demands requirement that agricul- 
 tural land should everywhere be well cultivated and sowed with the 
 necessary seed, that management [Wirthschaft] should be well and 
 thriftily [hausslich] conducted; impious, immoral, vicious, dissolute, 
 and infamous persons should nowhere be tolerated; that vagrants 
 and idlers should be made to work, the roads and ways be kept good 
 and secure, the streams be made navigable, cities and villages be 
 provided with good inns, traffic by water and land carried on fairly 
 and diligently, children and servants well trained and provided, the 
 offices properly filled, the unworthy expelled from civic stations, law 
 and justice administered, the wicked punished, the pious rewarded, 
 and the poor relieved. In short, that there should everywhere 
 prevail honorable, Christian and righteous life. 
 
 Rohr declares, however, that this ideal must be put in the 
 class of piorum desideriorum. He thinks that no more odious 
 programme could be imagined than the prerogatives proposed. 
 His opinion is of no value to us. The important thing is the 
 evidence which the passage furnishes that the Policey Ordnung
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 203 
 
 afterward introduced was in a very rudimentary stage when he 
 wrote. His ideas of the standards of conduct which ought 
 to be enforced by government seem to conform in spirit to the 
 standard quoted, and he goes into a mass of details, but the 
 particular machinery recommended by the anonymous author 
 alone meets his disapproval. Rohr apparently felt jealous 
 for the prerogatives of the church in connection with these 
 matters. The progress of events realized more of the system 
 foreshadowed in the quotation than its author appears to have 
 expected. Indeed more than half of Rohr's book is occupied 
 with subjects which Justi afterward systematized under the 
 rubric Policey. 
 
 The second exception to the general proposition that Rohr 
 affords little light on the cameralistic problem proper is found 
 in chap, xxviii, on "The Riches of the Country." Recalling 
 his earlier assertion that the interests of the prince are bound 
 up with those of his subjects, he premises in particular that the 
 prince has every reason to do his best that the subjects may be 
 rich. Without mincing words, he frankly puts this identity 
 of interest between prince and subjects in the affluence of the 
 latter on the ground that if the subjects have money the sov- 
 ereign always has means at his command to get it from them. 
 "On the other hand, if the subjects are poor, he can no more 
 get money from them than one can squeeze water out of a dry 
 sponge." 1 
 
 After reciting some of the information which a prince must 
 command, about the wealth and sources of income of his 
 
 1 Rohr cites Schroder, "Fiirstliche Schatx- und Rent-Cammer, as 
 holding the opposite view, viz., "a prince who has no money in his chest, 
 but relies on the good will of his subjects and territories, is walking on 
 stilts." Our review of Schroder, In which we have quoted the same 
 words (above, p. 144), shows that the contradiction was not so direct as 
 Rohr supposes. He had chiefly in mind one stage in the process, while 
 Schroder put the emphasis at another point, relying however on the 
 same ultimate resource.
 
 204 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 subjects, that he may know the location and capacity of the 
 springs which he must tap, Rohr betrays his ideas of wealth 
 itself, and his expressions are rather remarkable. He says: 
 
 A prince must have care that his land may increase in riches. 
 A land becomes richer, in proportion as money and gold (sic) are 
 brought into it, either from its own mines or elsewhere, and poorer 
 as money leaves the country. For inasmuch as by general consent 
 of peoples gold and silver are the universal price of all things, and 
 the worth of the same in all places in the world is estimated according 
 to the worth of gold and silver, for which everything can be bought, 
 one must estimate the riches of a land according to the quantity of 
 the gold and silver in the same. Hence a prince must give his 
 thought to means whereby the land may become richer, and he must 
 remove everything through which it becomes poorer (p. 844).' 
 
 Rohr is not content to let the matter rest with one statement. 
 He repeats it in this form in the next paragraph, almost in the 
 words of Schroder, as indeed the previous quotation was, viz. : 
 We find gold and silver in the mines, and this is the most certain 
 increment of the riches of the country, for as much as gold and silver 
 are found, so much has the country increased in riches. 
 
 1 After Schroder's chap, xxx, no equally clear expression of this 
 opinion is to be found in the cameralistic writers previous to Rohr. If 
 the language is carefully considered it will be seen that even this brash 
 assertion of Rohr cannot properly be construed as a generalization of 
 the same logical order as Adam Smith's propositions about wealth. 
 Rohr was evidently not probing beyond immediate practical utility. 
 He was not seeking for a philosophy of wealth, but for a basis of prudence 
 in dealing with the means necessary for practical wisdom. It would 
 be as preposterous to make such a statement, by a writer of Rohr's type, 
 the clue to the economic basis of cameralism, as it would be to take the 
 enthusiastic declaration of some interested politician, in the days of 
 Dingley and McKinley, that a protective tariff is the only way to create 
 wealth, as the measure of the economic insight of Americans in the 
 present generation. As we have seen, Rohr was not an authority upon 
 any technical or philosophical subject. He is not to be taken as repre- 
 senting the cameralists, except in a relatively remote way. Yet it is 
 from such sources that the extreme forms of statement came which were 
 afterward charged, under the label "mercantilism," to the responsible 
 publicists of Germany for most of the rest of the century.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ROHR 205 
 
 Then follows an uncritical formulation of the theory of the 
 balance of trade. At the same time, without perception of its 
 bearing upon the idea of the exceptional character of gold and 
 silver as riches, the fundamental necessity of making the country 
 as fertile as possible is urged as strenuously as though the 
 author were the extremest physiocrat. 
 
 In the chapter on mining (xxxvi), Rohr again falls back 
 upon Schroder. 1 The theorem of the latter is: 
 
 A prince should cause the gold and silver mines to be worked, 
 if they yield anything at all, whether with a loss or a profit, for that 
 matters not to the country, since I have shown [chap, xxx] that this 
 is the most certain approach of a country to riches. 2 
 
 The most direct evidence which we get of Rohr's sources 
 in the next chapter, on forests, is his citation of von Carlowitz' 
 Sylvicultura Oeconomica, yet he writes with great confidence, 
 and evidently from a larger range of direct observation than in 
 any other portion of the book, unless it may be the ecclesiastical 
 sections. The essay style and quality prevail in the remainder 
 of the book, and it yields nothing farther that is notable for 
 our purpose. 
 
 1 Particularly on p. 278 of the first edition of Fiirstl. Schatz- und 
 Rent-Cammer. In the edition of 1744, which I have compared, the 
 passage is on p. 181. 
 
 a In the same connection Rohr remarks, "Es ware zu wttndschen, 
 dass die Bergwercks-Lehren, die der Herr Abraham von Schonberg in 
 seiner Berg-information, Tit. von Berg-Herren, s. 15, vortraget, von alien 
 Potentaten in wiirckliche Observanz gesetzt wiirden." Except that 
 Justi does not find occasion to lay stress on the first of Schonberg's six 
 recommendations, viz., gratitude to God, if the country has been blessed 
 with gold and silver deposits, Justi developed his mining policy along 
 the lines of this predecessor. Vide below, pp. 358 ff.
 
 CHAPTER IX 
 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 
 
 We come now to the point at which cameral science was 
 first officially designated as a subject to be taught in universi- 
 ties. Whatever their scientific merits or defects, the men who 
 mark this event in the history of cameralistics are notable. 1 
 
 i The most complete survey up to date of the academic phase of 
 cameralism is Stieda, Die Nationalokonomie als Universitatswissenschaft, 
 I^eipzig, 1906. Within the period covered by the present study, the 
 cameralism even of the book-writers centered in the bureaus rather than 
 in the universities. The reverse became the case in the following period. 
 Stieda (p. 9) credits Thomasius with having been the first to read a course 
 on national economy in a German university. Such judgments do not 
 impress me as at all reliable. In the first place, if we had syllabi of all 
 the courses given at this period, it would be difficult to gain a consensus 
 about the way of drawing the line between those that should be regarded 
 as economic in the general sense of the time, and those that should not. 
 In the second place, judging from Thomasius' notes on Osse (vide above, 
 pp. 24 ff.), it seems to me altogether probable that Nicolaus Hieronymus 
 Gundling (vide Stintzing, All. d. Bib., in loc.), although a pupil of Tho- 
 masius in Naturrecht, may have been earlier and quite as distinguished 
 as he in the economic field. Stieda does not seem to have run down 
 the facts in this instance (vide p. 28). Again, it is certain that 
 Gerhard was lecturing at Jena on economics, in the contemporary 
 sense, as early as 1713 (vide above, p. 175). Gerhard's name does not 
 appear in Stieda's index. As a sign of the difficulty of obtaining the 
 literature of cameralism, it is worth noting that, in spite of his vantage 
 ground at Leipzig, Stieda says he has been unable to see a copy of Sin- 
 cerus, Projekt der Oeconomie in Form einer Wissenschaft nfbst einem 
 unmassgeblichen Bedenken, wie diese Wissenschaft, beydes in Theorie 
 und Praxi, mil mehrerm Fleiss und Nutzen getrieben werden k&nne, 
 Frankfurt und Leipzig, 1660; he failed also to find a copy of Zincke, 
 Programm von practiscnen Collegiis juridico- politico-earner alibus, 1741- 
 42; he appears to have found in one library only (Leipziger Stadtbiblio- 
 thek) the monograph of Justi (1754), Auf hochsten Befehl an Sr. Rom. 
 Kaiserl. und zu Ungarn und Bohmen Konigl. Majestat erstattetes aller- 
 
 206
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 207 
 
 According to Inama, 1 Gasser's father was KurfUrstlich 
 brandenburgischer Landrentmeister. The range of ideas within 
 which the paternal duties were discharged must account in 
 part for the interests and limitations of the son. As Inama 
 further says, "he had a clear but extremely jejune intellect, 
 with total absence of higher philosophical, ethical and histori- 
 cal conceptions." Gasser built upon Seckendorff, but was 
 far from appreciating the whole range of the earlier author's 
 wisdom. For our purposes, the fact that Gasser was professor 
 of law, and also a member of the Schdppenstuhl at Halle, 
 before he was appointed to the newly created chair of camera- 
 listics, is all that is necessary by way of introduction to his book. 
 
 Since Gasser was the first to occupy the economic profes- 
 sorship established at Halle (1727), his book, published two 
 years after beginning the new duties, would deserve attention 
 as a waymark, even if it contained nothing otherwise notable.* 
 
 untertanigstes Gutachten von dent verniinftigen Zusammenhange und 
 praktischen Vortrage alter Oekonomischen u. Kameralwissenschaften; 
 he found no copy of John Christian Forster, Einleitung in die Cameral- 
 Policey- und Finanz-Wissenschaft, 1779 (?); etc. Although I have 
 failed to get access to certain of the cameralistic books, my examination 
 of previous accounts of them leads me to the belief that on the whole 
 they have never been subjected to a more conscientious examination than 
 in this study. At least, I have expressed no judgment as my own upon 
 books which I have not carefully analyzed. There are good reasons for 
 doubting whether even Roscher could have said as much. I venture to 
 hope that this necessarily incomplete survey will provoke German scholars 
 to attempt a completely objective restoration of the cameralistic writers. 
 
 ' All. d. Bib., in loc. 
 
 * Simon Peter Gassers, JCti, Einleitung zu den Oeconomixclien 
 Politischen und Cameral Wissenschaften, Worinnen fur dieses mat die 
 Oeconomico-Cameralia Von den Domainen- oder Cammer- auch andern 
 Cittern, deren Administration und Anschldgen, so wol des Ackerbaues alx 
 anderer Pertinentien halber, saint den Regalien angezeiget und erldutert 
 werden. Nebst einem Vorbericht Von der Fundation der neuen oecono- 
 mischen Profession, und der Allerdurchlauchtigsten Stifters eigentlichen 
 oiler gnadigsten Absicht, Halle; In Verlegung des Waysenhauses, 
 MDCCXXIX (pp. 347 ff.).
 
 208 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The items in the book which mean most for our purpose 
 are contained in the Preface. They may be reduced to a very 
 brief resume, but the process of extracting this tincture from the 
 fibrous rhetorical pulp which contains it is extremely perplexing. 
 
 In the dedication to Friedrich Wilhelm I prominence is 
 given to the statement that the king had both excited the 
 admiration and gratified the wish of many scholars by taking 
 the lead in establishing economic professorships. With respect 
 both to the "admiration" and the "many," Gasser's own 
 account shows that our acceptance of the record must be care- 
 fully qualified. All the evidence goes to show that the scholars 
 in Germany who looked with any favor whatever at this period 
 upon the idea of introducing economics into the universities 
 were few and far between. It appears further that some of 
 the credit for the innovation in Prussia is probably due to 
 Thomasius, the editor of Osse's Testament, at that time rector 
 of the University of Halle. 
 
 In explaining the king's objects in founding the new "eco- 
 nomic professorship," Gasser incidentally betrays facts in the 
 situation which are doubtless more apparent to the present 
 reader of his book than they were to his own mind. He states, 
 first, that the king wanted young men to get in the universities 
 some of the elementary knowledge which would make them 
 available as civic employees. With the zeal of a new convert 
 he contrasts this desirable knowledge with the sort of thing 
 which had up to that time been the nearest approach to 
 preparation "juridical pedantries and lawyers' tricks." 1 He 
 rings many changes on this charge. He thereby shows, 
 first, that the subject which he represented was fighting for 
 its life, and, second, that men of his type had already formulated 
 in their own minds, if they had not widely published, some 
 rather specific counts against the scholastic formalism of the 
 law faculties of the period. 
 
 1 "Blosse Juristcrey odtr wol gar Advocaten-Streichtn."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 209 
 
 The next item which we disentangle from the author's 
 labored and involved form of explanation is that he felt himself 
 on the defensive for delaying as long as two years before pub- 
 lishing this book on the subject of his professorship! His 
 explanation is, in brief, that his duties required him to teach 
 "from morning till five or six in the evening," 1 that his official 
 duties "auf der Kammer und Deputation" consumed his 
 forenoons, that from six o'clock till late at night he had 
 "enough duties connected with the bureau, the faculty and 
 other official labors to occupy two or three men," and that 
 consequently there remained to him for work on economic 
 subjects "only the few morning hours up to eight o'clock!" 
 Furthermore, he contemptuously describes authorship in the 
 legal faculty as a process of picking out passages from ninety- 
 nine volumes and scribbling them into a hundredth. On the 
 contrary, "although a heap of economic rubbish has been 
 brought to light already, there are few if any pioneers in this 
 subject, but everything must be collected with much labor 
 and reflection, also by inquiries and collation." 8 Gasser 
 returns several times to the additional difficulty that "the 
 scholarly and efficient Hauswirthe and Politici are more at 
 odds with one another tha'n any other scholars can possibly be." 3 
 
 Returning to the reasons why economic professorships had 
 not been established earlier, Gasser quotes Thomasius, first, 
 on the proposition that the jurists had become mere word- 
 
 * He retained his legal professorship, and his economic teaching 
 occupied only a portion of his time. 
 
 * Inasmuch as he presently acknowledges Seckendorff as a pioneer 
 to whom he is greatly indebted, it seems necessary to connect this remark 
 particularly with the special sort of material to which Gasser' s book is 
 devoted. This conclusion carries with it a judgment as to the sense in 
 which Gasser used all variations of the term occonomisch. 
 
 3 For Justi's comments on the situation at this period, vide 
 below, pp. 296 ff. 
 
 *Cautele der Rechts-Gelahrtheit, cap. 17, |i.
 
 210 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 splitters and no longer edifying instructors of candidates for 
 civic positions; second, that Oeconomie ought to be taught in 
 the universities by professors especially charged with that 
 subject; and third, on the reasons for omission to supply this 
 need. Thomasius covers all the points on which we have 
 already quoted Rohr in this connection, 1 and he adds the 
 following reasons: 
 
 First, because Aristotle left us no economic books, and at the 
 founding of the first universities the monks knew nothing but Aris- 
 totle; second, the belief has prevailed that the scholar should concern 
 himself with something different from that which the drudge and 
 common man understands; third, it has possibly been partly from 
 fear that the laity would discover the tricks of clerical Oeconomie; 
 fourth, scholars of the traditional sorts have little fitness to investi- 
 gate economic subjects, and so make light of them ; fifth, the same, 
 and indeed all scholars, are apt to be poor economists in their own 
 private affairs; sixth, good economy would not tolerate monkish 
 laziness, but is based on the contrary belief that "man is destined 
 for labor, and that he who does not work is not worthy to eat." a 
 
 1 Vide p. 200 above. 
 
 * In further explanation of the royal purpose in establishing the 
 professorship at Halle to improve the situation thus indicated, Gasser 
 inserts abstracts from the official correspondence leading to his appoint- 
 ment. The most significant expressions are these: "Es haben Seine 
 Konigliche Majest. in Preussen .... resolviret auf beyden Universi- 
 tatcn, Halle und Franckfurth, Professores Oeconomiae bestellen zu lassen, 
 welche denen Studiosis die principia der Land-Wirthschaft, wie auch 
 der Policey, ingleichen die Einrichtung der Anschlage von Aemtern 
 und Giitern, nicht weniger guter Verfass- und Regulirung der Stadte 
 beybringen sollen." Further, in the final rescript: " Friederich Wilhelm, 
 Konig, Demnach Wie aus hochst eigener Bewegung allergnadigst resol- 
 viret, dass auf der dortigen Universitat die cameralia oeconomica und 
 Policey-Sachen gleichergestalt, wie die iibrige Studia und Wissenschaften, 
 dociret werden sollen, .... damit die studirende Jugend in Zeiten, und 
 ehe sic zu Bedienungen employret werden, einen guten Grund in obge- 
 
 dachten Wissenschaften erlangen mogen, etc., etc Berlin den 
 
 24. Julii 1727." Gasser also refers to a monograph by the pro-rector 
 of the University of Halle, von Ludewig. Vide below, p. 216.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 211 
 
 The sense in which the king understood the term Oeconomie, 
 and in which Gasser undertook to use it, appears in part, though 
 by no means fully, in the further explanation by the author: 
 
 His majesty manifested in the beginning great displeasure at 
 the bad Oeconomie which young people were in the habit of practicing 
 in their own affairs, so that when they come back from universities 
 and tours, they are usually already so loaded with debts that they 
 are helpless, and especially those who have landed estates carry on 
 such thriftless management because of aforesaid debts, that they 
 cannot rescue even the most important estates from embarrass- 
 ment when they at last gradually get some insight into Oeconomie, 
 especially because the people who operate and superintend the estates 
 can defraud the uninstructed owners in countless ways. 
 
 This being the state of things, continues Gasser, his majesty 
 was zealous to change the proportion of lawyers, who filled the 
 country and sucked it dry. He wanted young men to learn not 
 merely the elements of jurisprudence, but to add the elements of 
 politico,, oeconomica and cameralia (p. 8). 
 
 Gasser explains that in order to meet this demand, he 
 devotes the first half-year to lectures on Seckendorff's Fiirsten- 
 Staat. He says that although this schones Tractattein does 
 not contain much about Oeconomica proper, yet it in general 
 corresponds with the royal intention in surveying the whole 
 state, and thus in furnishing a basis for setting the lawyers 
 right. Gasser also mentions Rohr's book as a compendium 
 oeconomicum, but he does not agree with the author that it 
 would form a useful basis for university lectures, because it 
 contains too much that is specific and practical in form, but 
 not available until it can be reconsidered and applied after 
 adoption of fundamental rules. "Besides," adds Gasser, 
 "there is nothing in the book in the way of correct formulation 
 of the budgets." 
 
 This latter remark is explained by a glance at Gasser's 
 categories of Anschldge for all sorts of minor industrial opera- 
 tions. This estimate of the unavailability of Rohr is apparently
 
 212 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to be understood primarily by comparison with Seckendorff, 
 because Gasser shows that he is interested in quite as minute 
 details as those presented by Rohr. He finds in Seckendorff, 
 however, the necessary statement of fundamental principles 
 upon which specific rules of management must rest. 
 
 After elaborating this claim at some length, Gasser cites 
 "von Schroter," 1 on the difference between a rich man and a 
 rich prince; to the effect that "much money makes a rich man 
 but not a powerful prince." Gasser interprets Schroder as 
 meaning not that a prince should have no money, but that he 
 should have both money and power. Consequently, Gasser 
 urges that the two supporting pillars of the princely state are 
 "revenues from the country and well-to-do subjects in the 
 country, particularly in the towns." This theorem is the text 
 for a somewhat detailed argument upon the importance of 
 promoting diversified industries. 
 
 The author's Vorbericht closes with a promise to make 
 his lectures as valuable commentaries as possible, both by 
 explanation and illustration, upon the contents of the book. 
 Although it is aside from our main purpose, we may quote 
 the paragraph in which a pedagogical turn is given to this 
 promise, 8 viz.: 
 
 I propose also to set apart a designated hour on Saturdays in 
 which the work of those who comraendably choose to attempt prac- 
 tice at once will be examined, their mistakes pointed out and further 
 guidance given. For that purpose I shall assign to some the tasks 
 of drawing up the budgets [Anschlage] of estates, and of formulating 
 the special budgets of breweries, mills, brickyards, etc., belonging 
 to estates. Others will be required to draw up the customs schedules, 
 catastra, etc., on the lines indicated in the several chapters. When 
 these are read and discussed on Saturdays, other students will be 
 appointed as revisers and examiners, while the lectures will take 
 
 Furst. Schatt- und Rent-Cammer. Vide above, p. 153. 
 
 * Vide Justi's related remarks, below, p. 303 ff.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 213 
 
 them up further, and they will thus be considered as it were in full 
 session. In a word, each student will be encouraged to do his best 
 in the line in which he shows most inclination, while by listening to 
 the work of all he may gain a general idea of the whole subject. 
 
 The body of the book is, in a very narrow sense, technical. 
 As evidence of the progress of administrative technology it 
 would call for careful comparison with previous and following 
 handbooks. For our purpose its chief significance is negative. 
 That is, it shows that the horizon of cameralistic theory, as 
 the author understood it, was bounded by the rules of thrifty 
 management, first of the domains of the prince, and then of 
 the various gainful employments, sometimes viewed as lucra- 
 tive for the individual citizens, and sometimes as having their 
 chief importance as ultimate revenue creators for the prince. 
 
 Even this modicum of meaning is to be found in the book 
 only after patient consideration. The opening chapters, first, 
 on the meaning of domains in general, and especially on the 
 invalid distinction between Domainen-Guter, Tqffel-GUter, and 
 Cammer-GiUer, and second, on incorporation of new acquisi- 
 tions into the domains, have only the remotest visible connection 
 with all that follows. They have every appearance of having 
 been revamped from the author's old law lectures, and forced 
 into service in place of a general survey, which he could not 
 extemporize. They are an unkempt rabble of juridical archae- 
 ology, homespun philology, current legal usage, and common- 
 sense conclusion. To the modern reader, they are mostly 
 unintelligible. From the references to Seckendorff one derives 
 the impression that, beyond these incongruities, all the definite 
 instruction which the author imparted, after this impotent 
 preamble, was drawn from the Fiirsten-Staat. One other 
 obvious inference is that the author regarded the word-splitting' 
 which he summed up in these two chapters as a bad inheritance 
 from the civilists and the canonists. While he was not sufficiently 
 emancipated from the futile controversy to ignore it, his opinion
 
 214 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 was as frank in substance as it was Hibernian in form, viz., 
 "If the French writers had not broken the ice of the theorems 
 of the spiritual and secular state, the papal and glossarial yeast 
 would have got the upper hand!" (p. 3). 
 
 Without making any visible use of these two chapters on 
 the domains, the author plunges, without a word to account 
 for the abrupt change, into a series of chapters on the most 
 minute details of private thrift. 
 
 Chaps, iii-x inclusive begin with analysis of ordinary build- 
 ing processes, and end with details of assessment of tithes and 
 other tributes. Sixty-two pages are assigned to itemized 
 schedules of the cost of different sorts of construction, e. g., 
 a tile roof; a thatch roof; the carpenter's work on a country 
 house; estimate for a pigeon-cote resting on posts; estimate 
 of the cost of mason work; cost of wheelwright's work; cost 
 of pottery, etc., etc. The logic which calls for these exhibits 
 begins with the major premise: "To avoid being cheated, you 
 must know customary prices." 
 
 Details of a corresponding order constitute the substance 
 of the chapters just referred to. The aim in the author's mind 
 is made plain again by the opening sentences of chap, iv, 
 "On the budgets of estates in general, and particularly of agri- 
 cultural lands in three classes, and how such budget is to be 
 constructed, according to the amount of seed furnished or 
 otherwise." Thus: 
 
 As Columella observed of his own time, that all sciences, such 
 as military service, scholarship, commerce, building, nautical art, 
 even music, dancing, and such things, have their own guides and 
 teachers, yet agriculture has neither pupils nor teachers. The same 
 holds of our time. It consequently comes about that the minority 
 take occasion to think for themselves, but whoever lives in the coun- 
 try, or has an estate of his own, follows the custom of the majority, 
 and what is still wiser, if a specially good manager is in the locality, 
 the rest observe and try to imitate him.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 215 
 
 The passage goes on to say that doing the same thing which 
 the good manager does may not really be doing the same thing; 
 because there is a failure to note the different circumstances 
 of adjacent tracts, and to conform treatment to the varying 
 conditions. Thereupon follows an attempt to analyze classes 
 of soil and to show the processes of culture appropriate to each. 
 The following one hundred and forty pages contain abundant 
 evidence that technical and social administration of rural com- 
 munities was at this time a highly developed and convention- 
 alized art, but at the same time it was an art consisting of 
 aggregated rule-of-thumb practice. It had no secure basis 
 in fundamental principles. 
 
 The chief difference between the first ten and the remaining 
 twelve chapters of the book is not in the method of treatment 
 but rather in the fact that the former deal with technique of 
 more strictly private management, while the latter belong to 
 a larger degree in the realm of public management. In either 
 case the author's effort is to describe actual administrative 
 practice. He has before his mind the private or public func- 
 tionary, and he tries to schedule the kinds of information which 
 proprietors or managers of farms, or civic functionaries of 
 various grades, from bureau clerks up to the prince, would 
 have occasion to use in their respective positions. All this 
 was Oeconomie, as Gasser interpreted the term. It had the 
 same relation to pure economics, as we understand the term 
 today, which instruction in the technique of operating a gas 
 plant or an electric street-railway or a telephone exchange 
 would have to foundations of economic theory. 
 
 In order to get at the full significance of the cameralistic 
 foundations at Halle and Franckfurt a. O. 1 the writings of 
 Thomasius would have to be more carefully examined. As 
 our space forbids this, we may merely call attention in pass- 
 ing to another important factor in the movement, Ludewig, 
 
 1 Vide below on Dithmar, pp. 222 ff.
 
 2i6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 professor of law and chancellor of the University of 
 Halle. 
 
 On the occasion of the establishment of the new professor- 
 ship Ludewig wrote a quaint little book of 166 pages, explain- 
 ing and praising the king's purpose. The tract is a document 
 of firstrate importance as evidence sustaining our main thesis 
 about the center of interest in the whole cameralistic period. 1 
 Indeed, excess of cynicism could not justly be charged if one 
 should conclude that for reasons of his own the writer had 
 seized the opportunity rather for laudation of the re*gime of 
 Friedrich Wilhelm I than to promote cameralistic science. At 
 all events, the monograph is vivid confirmation of our diagnosis 
 of cameralism as fiscalism. 2 
 
 The essay seems to ignore the promise of the title-page 
 until forty-five of its fifty-six sections (one hundred and thirty 
 out of one hundred and sixty-six pages) are completed. The 
 argument begins with citation of the alleged dictum of the 
 Persian King Cyrus, "A select army and good management 
 [ Wirthschajft} of the subjects 3 are the two chief and surest means 
 of making a people rich and a land permanently happy." The 
 authority of Socrates, reinforced by Xenophon, is inserted 
 along with that of Cyrus, "although they wefe heathen who 
 
 ' Vide above, p. 6. 
 
 Die, von Sr. Koniglichen Majestdt, unserm oiler gnddigsten Konige, 
 auf Dero Universitdt Halle, am 14 Juli 1727, Neu angerichtete Profession, 
 in Oeconomie, Policey, und Cammer-Sachen wird, nebst Vorstellung 
 einiger Stiicke verbesserter Kon. Preussl. Policey, bekannt gemachet von 
 dem zeitigem Prorectore, Joh. Peter von Ludewig, let. Universitats-Cantz- 
 lern 1727- 
 
 3 It is impossible to decide from the context whether Ludewig clearly 
 chose between the subjective and the objective force of his genitive: i. e., 
 whether his thought was "on the part of the subjects" or "over the 
 subjects." From the succeeding discussion it appears that the two 
 aspects of the case were hardly differentiated in his mind, although the 
 emphasis falls heavily on management by the ruler.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 217 
 
 must somehow have obtained divine enlightenment," to sus- 
 tain this argument. Then follows, largely as an interpretation 
 of Columella, a justification of the dictum, chiefly on its eco- 
 nomic side, from the experience of the Romans, including the 
 Eastern emperors. As a transition to the immediate applica- 
 tion of the theme, Ludewig remarks (9) that it is very difficult 
 to find in ancient or modern history a ruler who is equally 
 great in war and in promotion of management (Wirtschaft). 
 Possibly Henry IV of France is one of the few exceptions. 
 After reciting at some length illustrations of that monarch's 
 wisdom and prudence, Ludewig continues: 
 
 But why should we pause so long upon a foreign and past exam 
 pie? Through a brave and wise king, God has placed this truth 
 before the eyes of our own times and subjects (sic). Wherefore we 
 could and should daily admire, honor and thank the perfect [grund- 
 gilten] God, for such a blessed government of his anointed. So long 
 as the world has stood, as may easily be proved from the authentic 
 history of all realms, no region of the earth has seen an army to be 
 compared with that of Prussia, etc., etc. (10). 
 
 Having continued this eulogy in some detail, Ludewig 
 specifies and partially describes in turn, as items in the excel- 
 lence of the Prussian system: 
 
 the administration of charity (14); the workhouses and penal 
 institutions (15); the homes for veterans (16); medical and sani- 
 tary institutions (17); colonies (18); the establishment of many 
 industries, and regulation of the same (19-24); settlement of 
 boundary disputes (25); redemption of waste lands (26); con- 
 struction of water-ways (27); development of salt works (28); 
 profitable farming of certain royal prerogatives (29); selection of 
 capable young men as subordinates in administrative offices (30) ; 
 written ordinances and laws for all functionaries (31); revision and 
 promulgation of the code of private law(32) ; standardizing of weights 
 and measures (33) ; transformation of feudal tenures into complete 
 property (34); introduction of money commutation for cavalry 
 service (35) ; removal of capitation, property and other taxes (36) ;
 
 218 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 reforms of the currency (37); establishment of the office of comp- 
 troller (38); careful signing of royal decrees (39); administration 
 of justice and expediting of legal processes (40) ; consequent improve- 
 ment of the royal finances (41); simplification of ceremonial (42). 
 
 Without notice of transition from eulogy to exhortation, 
 Ludewig ventures to offer three cautious suggestions, viz.: 
 
 That it would be well for the government to provide adminis- 
 trative, and especially the Policey, bureaus with national and special 
 maps and diagrams visualizing the conditions of the country at large, 
 and, in more detail, of the respective administrative divisions (43); 
 that certain feudal burdens should be removed (44); that the mili- 
 tary and fiscal administration should in certain features be reor- 
 ganized (45). 
 
 After this introduction, which occupies more than three 
 times the space reserved for the ostensible purpose of the 
 discourse, Ludewig turns to the supposed theme of the mono- 
 graph in this way: 
 
 But this should be enough about the details of good Oeconomie 
 and Policey, which by divine grace and blessing are daily before our 
 eyes in these lands. And as we have rendered ourselves liable to 
 all sorts of perverse judgments about this writing, which flowed so 
 easily from our pen and good heart, we will now set forth the motives 
 for the same, instead of offering excuses. For since his royal majesty, 
 our most gracious king and lord, in founding at Halle a new profes- 
 sorship of Oeconomie, Policey und Cammersachen, was, so far as I 
 know, the first in the learned world to take such a step; and since 
 he most graciously decreed that the intention and use of the same 
 should be made public; I have believed that neither the new Oecono- 
 mie-Projessor could receive a greater impulse to his labor nor the 
 students and apprentices [Lehrlinge] greater zeal for such courses, 
 than if they should turn their thoughts especially in aforesaid Came- 
 ra/, Policey und Oeconomie-Lehren, to the example of the great and 
 wise founder, in his kingdom, provinces, and lands; if they should 
 enlarge upon what I have said, and correct that in which I have been 
 in error, and especially if they should add the larger part which I
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 219 
 
 have been obliged to leave untouched. Besides this, I must call to 
 mind that, along with my administrative duties, the founder of our 
 Friedrichs-Universitat conferred upon me, along with the professor- 
 ship of history, the calling of a royal historiographer, in which 
 capacity I felt a strong impulse to use the present occasion for a contri- 
 bution to einer Oeconomie- und Policey-Historie. And as a matter 
 of fact great lords may- well be pitied for the money and appointments 
 which they bestow upon historiographos. The latter either use 
 their salary for their own enjoyment in learned idleness, or, if they 
 
 do any work, fall upon obsolete times and forget their founder 
 
 This may be partly, indeed, because the archives are closed to them. 
 .... Another extenuating item is that if the historian happens to 
 make a mistake about current affairs, certain people at once seize 
 the opportunity to discredit him at court. Moreover, if anything 
 is written about recent times, it is mostly about wars and rumors of 
 wars, and the great deeds at home [zu Hauss und im Lande] are 
 seldom mentioned. Finally, it is urged by the unintelligent that 
 there is no use in writing down what is known to everybody in the 
 land. These do not consider that subsequent times consume and 
 erase the preceding, and that what is now before our eyes and in 
 our hands fifty years hence will have become a secret and forgotten, 
 if not made a part of history. Such being the case, great lords are 
 unfortunate to labor only to be forgotten, and the praiseworthy, 
 wise and tireless princes who have done so much good for their lands 
 and peoples, and have left to good successors so many examples, 
 
 have no advantages over worthless rulers (Sec. 46 elaborates 
 
 still further the theme, "Make the history of good princes while 
 they are living.") 
 
 Sec. 47 goes somewhat more into detail about the develop- 
 ments that led to the new professorship, but in substance it 
 repeats Gasser's account above (p. 208). Sec. 48 discusses 
 the relation of the new professorship to the chairs of "practical 
 philosophy," "ethics," and "politics." Incidentally this section 
 exhibits in the most explicit way the content of the term 
 Oeconomie, as officially sanctioned in Prussia in 1727. Expand- 
 ing the proposition that, while Oeconomie at last belongs
 
 220 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 within the departments named, yet it requires special attention 
 as a subject by itself, Ludewig says: 
 
 It is easy to guess the secret why hitherto professors have taught 
 Oeconomie who were in doubt whether to look for ears of com on 
 trees or in the ground. For the sponsor 1 to whom they refer deals 
 in his economic books almost wholly with the morality of father, 
 mother, children, and servants. As to arable land, meadows, streams, 
 forests, gardens, plants; how to treat cattle in the stall; how to 
 increase the supply of manures; how to brew grain and to sell the 
 product; what a manager has to do and what to leave undone every 
 day in the year; what provisions he must keep in store for fire-pro- 
 tection, for food, in storehouse, in kitchen, and in cellar: of all these 
 things Aristotle has not a syllable. Hence his creatures, the Oecono- 
 mie Professores, up to the present time, have not concerned themselves 
 with these things, but they have considered themselves masters when 
 they could explain the "commandments" which the children recite. 
 This is the reason why among the hundred philosophical books which 
 treat of Oeconomia there is not a wholesome and practical line, and 
 thus this name conceals the greatest fraud. 
 
 With this indirect definition of the scope of the new pro- 
 fessorship we have the substance of the essay, so far as our 
 purpose is concerned. In writers to be noticed presently we 
 shall find intentional or unintentional echoes of these reflections 
 upon belated Aristotelianism. The points to be noted particu- 
 larly are, first, that the concept carried by variations of the 
 term Oeconomica at that time did not by any means make it 
 identical with the scope of contemporary Cameralwissenschaft; 
 second, that the term was equally contrasted with the nineteenth- 
 century term economics and its variations; third, that the 
 foundation of the Prussian professorships of Oeconomica, etc., 
 was of less immediate significance, either for cameral science 
 in general or for economic science as we now understand the 
 term, than was assumed by the men directly interested, and 
 even by later writers. The horizon of economics in a compre- 
 < Aristotle.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF GASSER 221 
 
 hensive sense dawned on the view of the Germans in a way 
 somewhat parallel with that by which the sociological outlook 
 in our time has widened from attention to certain remedial 
 problems to survey of the entire social process. 1 
 
 i In the two following sections (49, 50) Ludewig discusses the need 
 of more exact terms, and especially the possible substitution of the term 
 Wirthschaft or Haushalterschaft for Oeconomie. The remainder of the 
 essay repays careful analysis as an index of the author's knowledge about 
 the bibliography of the subject. He depends chiefly upon Seckendorff 
 and Rohr, both for general conceptions of the sciences with which the 
 new professorship is to deal and for clues to other writers. He is suffi- 
 ciently explicit that the men who understand Wirthschaft, as distinguished 
 from the commentators upon Aristotle, have ignored controversies about 
 mere words and names, and have written some good books about all 
 kinds of practical management.
 
 CHAPTER X 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 
 
 Justus Christoph Dithmar was born March 13, 1677, and 
 died on the anniversary of his birth in 1 737. We need to know 
 of his personality simply that he was professor of history, then 
 of Natur- und Volkerrecht, at Frankfurt a. O., and was desig- 
 nated to the chair at Frankfurt corresponding to that of Gasser, 
 practically at the same time with the appointment of the latter. 
 Both began their new duties October, 1727. Roscher remarks: 
 
 While Gasser took his point of departure from jurisprudence, 
 Dithmar passed from history to cameral science. It may be due 
 to this circumstance that he (Dithmar) is as far behind his colleague 
 in practical economic insight as he is superior to him in general 
 culture 1 (p. 431). 
 
 The two books which bear their names being taken as the 
 sole basis of comparison, Roscher is justified in his estimate 
 of the relative merits of Gasser and Dithmar. Roscher is 
 clearly in error, however, both when he says that the division 
 into "Oeconomie, Polizei- und Cameratwissenschaft" originates 
 with Dithmar, and when he credits him with the distinction 
 between the "land- und stadtwirthschafttiche Zweige der Volks- 
 wirthschaft." Both divisions are discoverable in Gasser.' 
 The latter is plainly formulated by Rohr. 3 It is true that 
 Dithmar is the first to use these distinctions as titles for sub- 
 division of a cameralistic syllabus. 4 Inama seems to have 
 
 1 This is merely Roscher's surmise. I have ventured (below, p. 229) 
 to locate the differences between them a little farther bark. 
 
 The former is implied, not quite precisely, in the title-page; the 
 latter is in chap, ii, in the subdivision of rural and town economy 
 in building. 
 
 3 Vide alxwe, p. 188. 
 
 4 All. d. Bib., in loc.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 223 
 
 repeated Roscher on these points, without examining the 
 evidence. Neither seems to have noticed that Stisser confi- 
 dently attributes to P. Fischer the distinction between Land 
 and Stadt Wirthschaft. 1 
 
 Although Gasser and Dithmar began the work of their 
 cameralistic professorships simultaneously, the latter does not 
 find it necessary to imitate the former in an apology for delay 
 in publishing on this subject. The book which appeared 
 four years after he assumed his new duties is a mere skeleton 
 of academic lectures. 2 In the Preface he gives virtually the 
 same account of the king's purpose in establishing the pro- 
 fessorship which we have already drawn from Gasser and 
 Ludewig with reference to Halle. Dithmar speaks in much 
 more terse and confident terms. He takes it for granted that 
 since "the welfare, power, and repute of a state rest on a well- 
 ordered economic, police, and cameral system," and since 
 people versed in statecraft have long wished that studious 
 
 1 Einleitung, i. Abth., 10. Vide below, pp. 238 ff. 
 
 Hn. Just. Christoph Dithmars, des Natur und Vdlkerrechts, ivie 
 auch der Geschichte und dconomischen Wissenschaften vormahligen offent- 
 lichen Lehrers und der konigl. preussischen Academic der Wissenschaften 
 zu Berlin Mitgleides, Einleitung in die dconomischen, Policey- und earner al- 
 Wissenschaften. Nebst Verzeichniss eines zu solchen Wissenschaften 
 dienlichen Buchervorrathes und ausfuhrlichem Register. Mit neuen 
 Anmerkungen um Gebrauch dconomischer Vorlesungen vermehret und 
 
 verbessert von D. Daniel Gottfried Schreber. Fiinfte Ausgabe 
 
 1755. With bibliography and index, pp. 328. According to Inama 
 (op. cit.) editions of this book were published in 1731, 1740, 1745, 1748, 
 1755, and 1768. The author's* preface to the first edition was dated 
 "16. Nov. 1731." I have used only this fifth edition, whose preface is 
 dated Halle, September 24, 1755. Of Schreber, the editor, Roscher 
 says: " . . . . the Leipzig Professor of Oeconomie, Polizei- und Cameral- 
 wissenschaft (1708-77), whose botanical knowledge was valued by Lin- 
 naeus, and who showed historical sense in his chief work: Abhandlung 
 von Cammergutern und Einkilnften, der en Verpachtung und Adminis- 
 tration (1743, II. Aufl., 1754)-"
 
 224 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 youth might be introduced to these subjects before entering 
 the employment of the state, the king's action in providing 
 such instruction settles the matter, so far as the academic 
 rights of the professorship are concerned. 
 
 It is more notable that Dithmar says, ''since no introduction 
 to such sciences existed." This is a significant reflection upon 
 Gasser, not to mention the earlier writers whom we have noticed. 
 It goes far as a sign that Dithmar perceived the provincialism 
 of previous writers, and had a broader conception than they 
 had shown of the necessary scope of cameralistic theory. He 
 confesses that his Part IV on Policey-Wissenschaft takes the 
 police ordinances of Prussia as the material to be explained, 
 with certain notable features of the civil law of other states. 
 
 Schreber's Preface to the fifth edition is in some respects 
 more instructive for our purposes than the book itself. The 
 editor says that he has been careful merely to correct the text 
 and to insert such brief notes as would menace neither the size 
 of the book nor the publisher's price. He used Dithmar's 
 book as the basis of his own lectures, probably first at Halle, 
 later at Butzow, then at Leipzig (vide Stieda, p. 38). His 
 estimate of the book is expressed in the judgment: 
 
 To the sainted author belongs this honor, viz.: Of the study 
 which he undertook to teach, the mistaken opinion prevailed, that 
 it could not be compressed into certain fundamental theorems, and 
 could not be taught in universities; yet he was a path-breaker in the 
 subject, and he showed, not only that both things were possible, 
 but that they were useful. In spite of its faults, his introduction 
 retains the value of the most convenient reading book on the sciences 
 of which it treats, and is used in various, including Catholic 
 universities. 
 
 Schreber continues: 
 
 I do not deny that since the book first saw the light we have had 
 more profound and elaborate introductions to the cameral sciences. 
 .... I know the writings of a Gasser, Zschackwitz, Stisser, Hof-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 225 
 
 mann, 1 Justi, and others, and I would not detract in the least from 
 the credit due either to them or to the eminent merits of Herrn Hof- 
 raths Zink (sic), who was the first to go deepest into these sciences, 
 when I nevertheless declare Dithmar's Einleitung the most available 
 of all for the purposes of academic lectures. 
 
 Schreber states that the day before writing the Preface he 
 had for the third time completed in a half-year the course in 
 which he used Dithmar's Einleitung as a syllabus, and he had 
 found no other book with which he could cover the ground in 
 the same time. The technical aims of his instruction appear 
 in his explanation of his pedagogical method. He kept in 
 mind the training of clerks for bureaus. 2 He closes with the 
 advice: "To those who desire detailed instruction in Kauf- 
 mannswissenschaft, either Lau's Entwurf wohteingerichteter 
 
 'Of G. A. Hoffman, Roscher says (p. 436): "His Klugheit 
 Haus zu halten oder Prudentia oeconomica vulgaris (IV, 1730-49) 
 purports to treat systematically all Wirthschajtslehrc. It pays attention 
 more, however, to the physico-chemical than to the police aspects." I 
 have not seen this work, and it does not seem possible that Schreber 
 could have seen the first edition of Justi's Staatswirthschaft. which was 
 published the same year this preface was written. Of Stisser I shall 
 speak below (pp. 238 ff.). I do not think it probable that Schreber 
 referred to Johann Adolph Hoffman, whose book, Politische Anmerkungen 
 iiber die wahre und jalsche Slaalskunst, was published in Latin in 1718, 
 and a German version by the author in 1725. (Vide Roscher, 
 p. 380.) 
 
 3 After explaining that he put before his students all the writers 
 on the subjects in question, he adds: " Sodann lege ich bey denen Theilen 
 wo practische Ausarbeitungen zur Erlauterung ndthig sind, nach vor- 
 ausgeschickten Grundsatzen, meinen Zuhorern theils selbst entworfene 
 Muster, theils Ausziige aus ergangenen cameral-Acten, Amtsbucher, 
 Manuale und Rechnungen, Anschlage, Steuercatastra, Cammer-Etats, 
 tabellarische Stadt- und Landbeschreibungen, Commercientabellen, 
 Kaufmannsbiicher und dergleichen Schemata vor die Augen, wobey 
 sie zugleich, wie Tabellen ordentlich zu verfertigcn sind, angefuhret 
 werden, wovon icb den Nutzen bey meinen ehemaligen Expeditionen 
 einzusehen Gelegenheit genug gehabt, etc."
 
 226 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Negotien, or another system, about to appear in print, is recom- 
 mended." 1 
 
 Of the syllabus itself little can be said without going into 
 the technical details by means of which comparisons might 
 be possible with those presented by earlier and later writers. 
 Such comparisons are excluded from our plan. In general 
 it may be noted that Dithmar furnishes abundant evidence 
 that analysis of the relations concerned was becoming both 
 more objective and more systematic. The scientific plane 
 which author and editor had reached may be indicated by a 
 few citations. 
 
 The first section proposes the following definition: 
 
 Economic science (die Oeconomische Wissenschajt, oder Hauss- 
 wirthschafts- und Haussltaltungskuns?) teaches how, through proper 
 rural and city occupations, support and riches may be gained for 
 the promotion of temporal happiness. 
 
 The editor adds the following leading propositions: 
 
 Economic science is not an art. a 
 
 The purpose of this science does not end with attaining, but 
 extends to preserving and applying, temporal income. 
 
 The difference between general and special Oeconomie must here 
 be shown. 
 
 It should be observed that the definition, and apparently 
 the editor's comments, put the subject of Oeconomie quite 
 distinctly on the side of private interests. The public aspects 
 of Oeconomie appeared to Dithmar rather under the other 
 two divisions of his subject. 
 
 After admitting that opinions differ greatly about Policey- 
 wisscnschaft, Dithmar expresses his own view in this form. 
 
 It teaches how the internal and external nature [Hfom] of a 
 state is to be maintained, with a view to general happiness [allge- 
 
 1 The reference may have been to Darjes, or Justi. 
 But the suffix Kunst was used with great freedom not only by 
 Dithmar in the formula above quoted but by a long line of successors.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 227 
 
 meinc Gluckseligkeil], in good condition and order, and accordingly 
 that the supreme magistracy of the country must have a care that 
 their subjects shall not only be kept in good numbers, God-fearing, 
 Christian, honorable, and healthy life and conduct, and that their 
 support and surplus of temporal goods shall be promoted by flour- 
 ishing rural and town occupations; but also that a land shall be 
 improved with well-laid-out cities, country districts and towns, and 
 all kept in good condition. Hence Policeywissenschajt is a part of 
 Staatsklugheit, but it can be taught conveniently with the economic 
 and cameral sciences, on account of its close connections with both 
 (viii, ix). 
 
 Dithmar's definition of Cameralwissenschaft runs: 
 It teaches how the princely domain and regalian rights [Rc%alien] 
 may be well used, and from them, as well as from the payments 
 [Prastarionen] due from subjects, and other public funds, the princely 
 revenues may be raised, improved, and applied for the maintenance 
 of the community [gemeines Wesen]. 
 
 The editor adds: 
 
 The difference between Finanz- and Renlwissenscliajl must here 
 be explained (x). 
 
 Dithmar accounts for the neglect of these three important 
 sciences in very nearly the same terms used by Gasser and 
 Rohr, 1 especially in the counts referring to Aristotle and the 
 monks, to the class pride which had relegated knowledge of 
 Hausshaltungswesen to the vulgar herd, and he repeats the 
 arguments that all three of these sciences consist of details 
 which must be learned by practice, or by association with experts. 
 Dithmar contends stoutly that the principles of these sciences 
 may be taught to advantage in the universities, while he recom- 
 mends observation of actual practice in the fields which they 
 severally occupy (xvi). 
 
 Having compressed his main propositions on these general 
 relations into the brief space of twenty-four pages, Dithmar 
 
 1 Vide above, pp. 209 ff.
 
 228 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 proceeds with the subject of Landbconomie. His emphasis 
 is less on the side of manual operation than Gasser's, and 
 more on managerial technique. In his way, he restricts 
 himself as closely to technical details as his predecessor. This 
 remark applies also to Part III, "Von der Stadtoconomie" 
 This Wissenscftaft is said to teach "how, through the occupa- 
 tions of citizens, sustenance and riches may be gained for the 
 happiness of each and of the whole." It would be easy to 
 point out curious combinations between the "science" so 
 marked off and the Policeywissenschaft of the same system, 
 but it is enough to remark that these pioneers were not yet 
 much troubled about consistency of classification. They were 
 chiefly concerned with concrete particulars. Dithmar defines 
 cities as "those societies which have Stadt- und Burgerrecht, 
 and are authorized to cany on city occupations [Stadtgewerbe] 
 or pursuits that furnish support for citizens" [biirgerliche 
 Nahrungen] ( i). The analysis deals consequently with the 
 actual situations only, without attempting anything more 
 fundamental than description of existing urban arrangements. 
 In the introduction to Part IV, on Policeywissenschqft, 
 Dithmar says: 
 
 t.--*"V- . :i^' V 1: t '.i . i T.)V ?.] 
 
 The Policey is grounded in civic society, in consequence of which 
 it is competent for the ruling prince to control the conduct and affairs 
 of his subjects, for the maintenance of the community [gemeinen 
 Wesens] (fv). 
 
 He continues: 
 
 Policey may rightly be called the life and soul of a state, and the 
 importance of Policeyunssenschajt is therewith evident. The more 
 the grievance that the same has been neglected ! In the Middle Ages 
 the Romish clergy were at fault for this. For their purposes good 
 Policey was not desirable, and consequently Policeywissenschaft 
 was suppressed by them along with other disciplines (vi). In modern 
 times there is no lack of political books, but little about Policey- 
 wissenschajt is to be found in them, without doubt because economic
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 229 
 
 and cameral sciences are lacking, with which Policeywissenscfiaft 
 is closely connected (vii). Such science is to be gained by knowledge 
 of the police systems of ancient and modern states; by meditation 
 upon what might be good for a state in view of its circumstances; 
 by associating with experts in police affairs; and by personal experi- 
 ence (viii, ix). 
 
 Instead of attempting to pass upon the value of Dithmar's 
 specific views in this connection, we shall allow Justi to stand 
 for this part of the cameralistic system. 1 
 
 Dithmar again indicates his conception of Cameralwissen- 
 schaft 2 in the proposition (p. 242) : 
 
 It teaches how the revenues of the reigning prince may be raised, 
 from time to time augmented, and so applied to maintenance of 
 the community [gemeinen Wesens]iha.t a surplus may remain annually. 
 
 As a mere outline of the subjects which belong under this 
 head, the syllabus puts its author in wholly respectable com- 
 parison with Justi. Of course it is impossible to compare 
 his knowledge of details with that of the later writer. 3 
 
 On the whole Dithmar must be regarded as in certain very 
 important respects more typical than Justi of German camera- 
 listic scholarship at the middle of the eighteenth century. He 
 represents both its weakness and its strength. The stage of 
 evolution through which this division of German social science 
 was passing may be characterized as a struggle for emancipa- 
 tion from a-priori, deductive methodology, into the freedom 
 
 ' Vide below, pp. 436 ff. 
 
 * In a note Dithmar gives the earliest explanation of the origin of 
 the term which I have found in the textbooks, viz., "The science has its 
 names from the word Camera, by which, according to the idiom of the 
 Middle Ages, the place was designated in which the revenues of the reign- 
 ing prince were guarded." He refers to "du Fresne, glos. v. camera." 
 Vide Zincke, below, pp. 232 ff. 
 
 3 On the use of Dithmar's book as a text by Ickstatt, at Ingolstadt, 
 1746, vide Stieda, op. cit., p. 241; also by Thorn in Giessen, 1757, ibid., 
 P- 'S3-
 
 230 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of empirical, telic discovery. Dithmar was evidently much 
 more conscientious in every way than Justi. He was extremely 
 respectful toward the past. He was cautious about encoura- 
 ging innovations. He was the first of the cameralists to present 
 a respectably classified bibliography of the subjects which 
 they treat; 1 and the groups of writers scheduled, ranging 
 from Xenophon, Geoponica, Cato, Varro, Vergil, and a score 
 of other writers on agriculture, to his immediate contemporaries, 
 on subjects which were creating a new literature, vividly reflect 
 the unconscious adjustment that was going forward between 
 authority on the one hand and observation and analysis on 
 the other. Dithmar has fortified the text of his little book 
 with more references to sources than are to be found in all Justi's 
 writings. Still further, there is a perceptible contrast between 
 his mental attitude and that of the legalistic publicists who 
 had no way of determining how to drain a swamp or work 
 a vein of ore, unless a precedent could be found in the law 
 books. On the other hand, Dithmar was no such man of the 
 world as Justi. He could draw upon no such varied experience 
 with affairs. His judgments were those of a scholar rather 
 than of a business man. He was therefore relatively modest 
 and conventional, though evidently intelligent and progressive; 
 while Justi was forceful and self-assertive, partly for the 
 reason that he had a much more restricted historical and 
 literary outlook than Dithmar. The bolder and more aggres- 
 sive type better visualized the active factors which were expand- 
 ing administrative theory. The less demonstrative type more 
 fairly represented the form in which the reconstruction was 
 impressing itself upon the universities. 3 
 
 1 I say this in spite of the fact that there had been many confused 
 lists of books. 
 
 3 A final estimate of Dithmar would have to consider his work as 
 editor and largely as author of the ten numbers of Oekonomische Fama, 
 the first German cameralistic journal, 1729. As I have seen none of
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DITHMAR 231 
 
 these numbers, I must be content to refer to Roscher's account of them 
 (pp. 431, 432). In this connection mention must be made of several 
 men of whose relative merits as cameralistic writers I am not prepared 
 to judge. These are, first, Johann Hermann Fiirstenau, 1688-1756, 
 "intrusted with the professorship Oeconomiae at the University of Rinteln 
 (Grundliche Anleitung zu der Haushaltungskunst und denen gehorigen 
 furnehmsten Schriften, Lemgo, 1736); second, Andreas Berch, 1711-74, 
 who was not in Germany, to be sure, but was professor of Oeconomie at 
 Upsala (an anonymous monograph, 1746, on Die Art durch die politische 
 Arithmetik die Haushaltung der Lander und Reiche zu erforschen, and, 
 in 1747, Einleitung zur allgemeinen Haushaltung, Grundsatze der Policey- 
 Oekonomie- und Kameralwissenschaft, the latter translated into German, 
 1763, by the writer about to be named) ; third, Daniel Gottfried Schreber, 
 1709-77, "the first to hold a professorship of the economic sciences at 
 Leipzig" (Abhandlung von Kammergutern und Einkunften, der en Ver- 
 pachtung und Administration, 1743, II. Aufl., 1754; Zwo Schriften von 
 der Geschichte und Nothwendigkeit der Kameral-urissenschaften insofern 
 sie als Universitatswissenschaft anzusehen sind: Entwurf von einer zum 
 Nutzen eines Staats zu errichtenden Akademie der dkonomischen Wissen- 
 schaften, 1763). I have been able to see none of the writings of these 
 men. Stieda (vide Index) adds important information, particularly 
 about Schreber.
 
 CHAPTER XI 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 
 
 No author, in the whole series which this study includes, 
 is more difficult to interpret and appraise than Zincke. The 
 most obvious reasons for this are, first, that he was a somewhat 
 voluminous writer, even if we take into account his camera- 
 listic publications alone. Moreover, his books do much less 
 than is usually the case to throw light upon one another. On 
 the contrary, his variations of terminology and classification 
 from book to book are bewildering. It is hard to decide 
 whether there is consistency and unity in the successive volumes, 
 or whether they are so many distinct trials at a baffling task. 
 In the second place, although Zincke presents his material 
 in highly analyzed form, his style is elusive, and his divisions, 
 subdivisions, and cross-classifications mystify more than they 
 elucidate. 
 
 It is also to be said that Roscher has conspicuously failed 
 to place Zincke in his true perspective. While it is necessary 
 to use Roscher in getting back to the facts about the cameralists, 
 he is in this case a stumbling-block as well as a stepping-stone. 
 
 From the sketch by Zimmermann, 1 the most salient points 
 in Zincke's checkered career may be summarized as follows: 
 
 Georg Heinrich Zincke was born in 1692, and died in 1768. 
 His father was a preacher, and both father and mother seem to have 
 done their best to induce the son to adopt the father's calling. The 
 boy twice interrupted his school career to enter the army. After 
 he had become Unterofficier he was captured and taken to France 
 as prisoner of war (1709), but escaped, and went to Jena, ostensibly 
 to study theology, but he gave quite as much attention to the legal 
 sciences. He was made Master in 1713, and was allowed to lecture 
 "on German and Latin style, morals and Gelehrtengeschichtc" 
 
 i All. d. Bib., in loc. 
 
 232
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 233 
 
 After a short engagement as Hojmeisler in a family, of slight impor- 
 tance, he went to Erfurt, and acquired the right to offer courses and 
 to preach. Presently, "because of love for the law, and a throat 
 trouble," he went to Halle, where he both lectured on his old sub- 
 jects and attended courses in the legal sciences by Ludewig, Bohmer, 
 Thomasius, etc. In 1720 he received the degree Dr. juris at Erfurt. 
 Returning to Halle, he was in turn "Ordentlicher Advocat; Secretar 
 und Syndicus bei den Coloniegerichten der Pfalzer daselbst, und bei 
 Commissioner, in Cammersachen besch&ftigt;" later, "Fiscal der 
 Kriegs- und Domanenkammer im Saalkreise und im Mansfeldischen, 
 dann wirklicher Commissionsrath und Criminalrath." The latter 
 position he retained till 1731, when he was called to Weimar with 
 the rank of Hofrath. He gained unusual favor with the Herzog, 
 and exerted influence much beyond his proper sphere. Whether 
 this actually injured the Herzog and the country, Zimmermann 
 declines to judge. At all events, Zincke made such enemies that a 
 judicial investigation followed, with the result that Zincke was 
 imprisoned for three years. 1 Ill, and weakened by prison life, he 
 was taken up by Herzog Christian in Saalfeld, and after his health 
 was restored he was on his way to take a teacher's position in St. 
 Petersburg when he was persuaded to change his plan and to remain 
 in Leipzig, offering courses in the Rechts- und Cameralvrissenschajten 
 (1740). Thereupon Zincke developed very influential literary 
 activities. His Attgenteines okonomishes Lexicon (1742) was re- 
 edited in a fifth edition by Volkmann (1780), a sixth by Leich 
 (1800), and Roscher speaks of a seventh in 1820. The scientific 
 reputation which he gained thereby is said by Zimmermann to 
 have been the occasion of his removal to Braunschweig at the end 
 of 1745, to accept an appointment as Hoj- und Kammerrath und 
 ordentlicher Professor der Rechte und Cameralwissenschaften am Col- 
 legium Carolinum, and soon as Mitcurator of that institution. In 
 Braunschweig Zincke did not acquire great influence. He was 
 charged with certain functions in the administrative bureaus, and 
 he lectured on Cameral- und Policeywissenschafl. The control of 
 the academic administration was entirely in the hands of the "Abt" 
 Jerusalem. Zincke published a criticism of the management in 
 1 Roscher has it "nearly six years" (p. 432).
 
 234 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 1748, but Jerusalem replied and was sustained by the highest author- 
 ity. Zincke appears, in consequence of this rebuff, to have aban- 
 doned further administrative ambitions. For at least another decade, 
 or till his sixty-seventh year, he continued to be productive as an 
 author. 
 
 It is difficult to fix upon an order of treatment which will 
 most clearly represent Zincke's contributions to cameralistic 
 literature. To what has already been said about Roscher's 
 work at this point, we must add that he really dodges the 
 "Zincke problem." 1 He quotes only the earliest and least 
 mature of Zincke's cameralistic books; 3 his reference to the 
 most pretentious of his books is inaccurate, and provokes the 
 suspicion that he knew it only through a catalogue. 3 
 
 We must remark, second, that Roscher's account of Zincke 
 is virtually a description only of the journal which he edited. 4 
 This emphasis deprives Zincke of his full due. At the same 
 time it calls attention to an important factor in the development 
 of cameralistic theory. Possibly Zincke's influence as editor 
 may have been more effective than the rest of his literary labors. 
 However that may be, his part in the development of camera- 
 listics would be very inadequately represented if we should 
 accept Roscher's showing as sufficient. His account should 
 
 > Rose her, pp. 432 5. 
 
 Grundriss einer Einleitung zu dcr Cameralwisscnsckaft, II Theile, 
 1742. 
 
 3 Anfangsgrunde. Vide below, pp. 256 8. The mere publishers' 
 description, "II, 1755," while technically correct, would hardly have 
 been allowed to stand as a sufficient index of the proportions of the work, 
 if it had been carefully examined. It is nominally in two parts, but each 
 part consists of two considerable volumes. The four volumes contain 
 respectively pp. 806, 1218, 998, and 662 + Index 62. 
 
 4 Leipziger Sammlungen von wirthschaftlichen, Policey- Cammer- 
 und Finant-Sachen, of which 184 numbers appeared, 1742-67. As I 
 have seen none of these numbers, I am obliged to depend upon Roscher's 
 testimony with regard to them.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 235 
 
 be read by every student of the period. 1 Letting that 
 contribution to the subject count for what it is worth, we must 
 introduce further evidence which at least widens the basis of 
 judgment. 
 
 Stieda has presented a much more sympathetic view of 
 Zincke in a compact sketch. A free rendering of the passage 
 will furnish a proper introduction to the later books. 2 
 
 In spite of the fact that he did not reach his aim, for he was never 
 Professor der Oeconomie, although he read lectures on this subject 
 at the University of Leipzig from 1740 to 1745, Georg Heinrich 
 Zincke nevetheless belongs in this connection. His views must have 
 had considerable influence upon the further development of the 
 Wirtschaftswissenscha/ten as subject-matter for lectures in univer- 
 sities. In the year 1741 or 1742 he published a Programm von 
 practischen Collegiis juridico-politico-cameralibus, the purpose of 
 which was to recommend the lectures which he proposed to give. 
 Since these four sheets met with approval he followed them up, in 
 the year 1742, with a Grundriss einer Einleitung zu den Cameral- 
 Wissenscha/ten. It consisted of two parts. A preliminary discus- 
 sion dealt with the question how young men should be instructed 
 theoretically in these sciences, and how they might be introduced 
 to the application of them. Zincke had at first the intention of using 
 Dithmar's Einleitung as his text, and after the death of the latter 
 negotiations were begun with Zincke, looking to his undertaking, 
 as editor, to bring out a revised edition. For unknown reasons the 
 plan failed. Zincke had come to the conclusion that there were serious 
 gaps in Dithmar's Einleitung: e. g., that it omitted too many neces- 
 sary subjects, that it afforded insufficient explanations to give thor- 
 ough knowledge, etc. Probably the author himself, if he had lived 
 longer, would have improved the book in these respects. At all 
 events these imperfections made Zincke feel the need of publishing 
 an outline of his own. 
 
 ' Op. cit., pp. 433-41. 
 
 Stieda, op. cit., pp. 25 ff. I cite this passage, first, because I have 
 been unable to obtain the two sources to which it refers; and, second, 
 because it coincides with the judgment of Zincke which I had formed 
 from study of his more mature works.
 
 236 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 There are but very few, declared Zincke, who at the present time 
 devote themselves with special diligence and with persistent effort 
 to the economic sciences. Most people regard their elementary 
 principles as merely minor considerations. This being the case, 
 there should be a use for the outline. Its aim is the common weal 
 [das gemeine Beste], not the advantage of each individual manager. 
 All the doctrines which it presents are connected with the Policei 
 or with the public arrangements for support [Nahrungseinrichtungen] 
 in a country. In Kameralvrissenschafl the special relation and 
 purpose of all these doctrines appears in their application to the 
 management [Wirtschajt] of the state and of the prince. The total 
 Polizeiurissenschaft as a system of management is, however, arranged 
 really with reference to the public and general weal. 
 
 It was Zincke's intention to present these sciences in the uni- 
 versities after the following manner. In the first place he would offer 
 every half-year a general fundamental course on the entire science, 
 and second on special portions. Third, he wanted to supply guid- 
 ance in the application of the science, i. e., a practical course. In 
 the latter it would naturally be impossible to impart to the future 
 official all the technique of economic transactions. Excursions in 
 actual application could be made, however, and the students could 
 be incited to prepare documentary exercises in economic and Policei 
 procedure. Zincke had the plan of proposing a subject, of having 
 the same worked up, part by part, through assignments to individuals, 
 and then of having it presented and discussed by the students as a 
 group. In other words, these details show that Zincke was planning 
 essentially the seminar method, and he hoped thereby to make the 
 new subjects particularly attractive. He probably leaned upon 
 Gross, Entwurj cines mil leichten Kosten zu errichtenden Seminarii 
 otconomico-politici. ' 
 
 In the year 1746 Zincke accepted a call as professor and Kuralor 
 of the newly opened Kollegium Karolinum in Braunschweig. With 
 his entrance into the service of Braunschweig-Lftfieberg he gave up 
 the realization of the plans contained in the above-mentioned pro- 
 gramme. Yet he considered his ideas so important that he hoped 
 they would be generally adopted. Hence in 1746 he returned to them 
 
 ' Vide Stieda, op. cit., p. 13.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 237 
 
 in the Leipziger Sammlungen, which he had begun to publish in 
 1742. He put them in more general form as Gedanken und Vor- 
 schldge von einem auj Universitaten auf die Cavneralivissenschajten 
 einzurichtenden besonderen Collegia Statuum Europae Camerali. 
 
 In this discussion he begins with the explanation of a Politicus. 
 He goes back to a concept with which we have become acquainted 
 in connection with Christian Weise. 1 He would not have the word 
 understood to mean a crafty man acting a part to the hurt of his 
 neighbor, but rather a man who possesses the talent, not only in his 
 private station, but also with respect to the common weal, to live 
 justly and wisely. A Politicus is thus a statesman. No one can 
 attain this character who is not intelligent about the state and has not 
 carried on political studies. To be sure there are different kinds of 
 knowledge necessary for a chancellor, a civic employee, a minister 
 of war or of finance. All these, however, find something which con- 
 cerns them in the political sciences. Hence they must in the first 
 place learn the whole in its general principles and rules. Every 
 political function, high or low, has in its affairs a definite relation 
 to the welfare and happiness of the state in general. The state, 
 however, has no other purpose than to improve and perfect all that 
 constitutes the temporal weal of its members. The Politicus must 
 learn whatever sciences, talents, and preparation are necessary for 
 the attainment of this purpose. 
 
 For this end it is not enough to have the mere knowledge of the 
 laws from the pandects and the theory of civic processes. Rather 
 is it one of the most important and necessary sciences of a Politicus 
 to know, in a way that is applicable to practice, how to make a land 
 progressively richer, how to make improvements in the application 
 of the riches to the security and need and convenient life of the mem- 
 bers of the state, etc. 
 
 The most general theorems and rules of this science are found 
 in the theory of general civic prudence [allgemeine Staatsklugheil}. 
 But this great portion of political science needs to be taught much 
 more thoroughly, dearly, and circumstantially than in this general 
 theory. This is done in the Kameralwissenschaften, which are 
 composed of General- und Special-Qekonomie, of the Polizeiwissen- 
 1 Vide Stieda, pp. 3, 4.
 
 238 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 schaft, which is based upon them, and of the science vom Finanz- 
 und Kammerwesen der Filrsten. 
 
 For further details Zincke refers to his Grundriss, in accordance 
 with which he had lectured and intended to continue his lectures. 
 Since however not everybody has the patience in detail, but people 
 rather content themselves with a historical concept and at the same 
 time with other fragments of knowledge in political and civic affairs, 
 that course in general civics is particularly to be desired. He urges, 
 moreover, after he has argued for the study of Kameralwissenschajt 
 in general, still another course "de notitia statuum," in which, for 
 the sake of general culture, the needs of those shall be supplied who 
 do not purpose to make a career in the departments for which he 
 speaks. He cites Gundling's Zustand der Europ&ischen Staaten, 
 and wishes to add statistics as an enlargement of the study. In 
 this course, which apparently was to have been of a more popular 
 character, the possible and actual condition of a state would be treated, 
 and the relations of the Policei and the financial system. 
 
 Passing these preliminary and elementary forms of his 
 theory, we must take into account the evidence afforded by 
 Zincke's work upon the second edition of Stisser's Einleitung. 1 
 
 Stisser (1689-1739), could be passed over with a few words, 
 if further reference to him were not necessary in order fairly 
 to report Zincke. Stisser was a student of law and philosophy 
 at Jena and Halle and might have gravitated into an academic 
 career if he had not evinced notable administrative talent. 
 
 1 Fried rich Ulrich Stissers, Ehemahligen Fiirstl. Braunschweig- 
 Liineburgl. Amtmanns und nachherigen K. Pr. Krieges- und Domainen- 
 Raths Einleitung zur Land-Wirthschaft und Policey der Teutschen. Zum 
 Unltrricht in Otconomic- Policey- und Cammer-Wesen eingerichtet. 
 Nunmero aber von neuen ubersehen, an vielen Orten verbessert, vermehret 
 und brauchbarer auf Verlangen gemachet, wie auch mil noch mehr His- 
 torischen Nachrichten von denen Geschdften und Schriften, auch mil 
 einer neuen Vorrede versehen von D. Georg Heinrich Zincken, Hoch- 
 furstl. Braunschweigischen wiirckl. Hof- und Cammer-Rath, Prof. Juris 
 und Cameralium auf der Universitat Helmstddt und des Hochfurstl. 
 
 Collegii Carolini in Braunschweig Curatore 1746. (First edition, 
 
 1735.) Roscher (p. 376) erroneously dates this second edition 1748.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZIXCKE 239 
 
 While in practical employment at Jena (1734-35), he was 
 allowed to lecture in the university on the economic sciences, 
 and the Forst- und Jagd-Wesen der Deutschen. 
 
 Besides the book just mentioned, Stisser published in 1734 
 Bin Programme, von der Moglichkeit, dass die oekonomischen 
 Wissenschaften in eine Lehrart gebracht werden konnen, massen 
 ein elendes VorurteU vormahls auch die grossten Gelehrten von 
 der Unmoglichkeit dieses Vornehmens eingenommen hatte. 
 In 1737 the work appeared which is rated as the most meri- 
 torious of his writings, Die Forst- und Jagd-Historie der 
 Teutschen. 
 
 It appears from Zincke's testimony that the publication 
 of the two books which marked his professional residence at 
 Jena was the occasion of speedy termination of Stisser's 
 academic career. The book on forestry and hunting was 
 dedicated to the king of Prussia, and that expert in manage- 
 ment was so much impressed with the author's knowledge 
 of affairs, as evinced by both this and the Land-Wirthschaft, 
 that he called him to Berlin, in order to test his information 
 and judgment orally. As a consequence, Frederich Wilhelm I 
 gave him an appointment at Stettin. 1 
 
 It was Stisser's plan to write a second volume, Stadt-Wirth- 
 schaft, and a third, Wirthschaft grosser Herren. In explaining 
 his relation to Stisser's book, Zincke says (p. 14): 
 
 As I began to lecture upon the Cameral-Wissenschajten to the 
 students at Leipzig, I looked for a complete hand- and reading-book 
 which would present the subject in brief and systematic form. I 
 found, to be sure, the sainted Herm Dietmar's Einleitung, which 
 surveyed the whole field, but in its special divisions consisted merely 
 of a few scattered observations, with defective fundamental ideas, 
 or none at all, and in many cases employing far too general theorems. 
 1 "Krieges- und Domainen-Rath in der Pommerischen Cammer 
 zu Stettin, mit einem Gehalt von 66 Rthl." Zincke's date for this trans- 
 fer (1734) is obviously a misprint for 1737. Stisser died two years later, 
 at the age of fifty-one.
 
 240 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The sainted Herrn Stisser's Einleitung was in many respects, especially 
 in organization of the material, more according to my taste. It 
 contained more complete conceptions, and united the Policey-Wesen 
 with Oeconomie in a practical way. At the same time it treated only 
 Land-Wirthschajt and Land-Policey, and was consequently not 
 complete enough to serve me as an outline of all Cameral-Wissen- 
 schaften. Beyond that, moreover, I valued highly the practical 
 and still compact arrangement of this little book: yet I was told that 
 it lacked much on the systematic side of pedagogy, that the sainted 
 man was neither a good methodologist nor an adequate philosopher, 
 and that a teacher of these sciences should be both. I was told that 
 certain fundamental ideas might be better defined, and that various 
 of Stisser's particular opinions were not accepted by all specialists 
 in Wirthschaft and Policey. For these reasons I could not use the 
 book for my purposes. Hence I decided to publish my well-known 
 Grund-Riss einer Einleitung zu denen Cameral-Wissenschajlen, in 
 two parts, 1742 and 1743. In the first part I presented the general 
 and special principles of the Land- und Stadt-Wirlhschaftl of the 
 Germans, and of Policey, with a view to their application by the sev- 
 eral Collegiorum, and also for pedagogical use. In the second part 
 I presented die Wirthschaflt grosser Herrn oder das Cammer- und 
 Finanz-Wesen. Yet this was a mere sketch of a much larger work 
 and of a much more complete treatment which would be of no use 
 
 for beginners Before coming to completion of this larger 
 
 work I fell back upon Stisser's Einleitung .... which I thought 
 I could make useful for beginners, at least in certain parts of .... 
 Land-Wirthschajt and Land-Policey 
 
 In his Preface Stisser says that Christianus Thomasius was 
 the first, so far as he knew, to give his hearers a collection of 
 brief propositions, as an accompaniment of his lectures. Then 
 Gentzke, Bierling, Beyer, Gundling, and many others imitated 
 him, including Professor Diethmar at Franckfurt and Herr 
 Hofrat Schmeizel at Halle. Apparently he meant to say that 
 these theorems were in German, for he emphasizes the fact 
 that after some hesitation, he decided to follow the lead of
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 241 
 
 Thomasius, and present the substance of his teaching "in 
 honest German garb." 
 
 After a quaint discussion of the current overvaluation of 
 the advantages to be gained by foreign travel, he urges that 
 Germans may profit most by studying the accumulated prac- 
 tical wisdom of their own country, the ways and means of 
 industrial thrift first of all. 
 
 He joins in the discussion of the question why this impor- 
 tant subject has had so little attention in the universities, and 
 curiously enough he puts the chief blame on the students. 
 He says they prefer to give their time and money, Veneri et 
 Baccho, to learning what would enable them to earn their 
 bread. At all events, they regard it as disgraceful and beneath 
 their dignity to soil themselves with "low-lived economic 
 sciences." Against this prejudice Stisser stoutly maintains: 
 
 These sciences are parts of the greatest Staats-Wissenschajt, 
 yes the soul in the civic body, and have the special use of showing 
 how a great lord may bring his land and people to prosperity 
 
 According to Zincke's explanation of his editorial work 
 on Stisser's book, it would be unsafe to pass judgment upon 
 the author, without comparing the original edition. Nothing 
 appears in evidence, however, to show that he was in any way 
 in advance of Gasser in the particular respects with which 
 we are concerned. We may therefore dismiss him from con- 
 sideration, and turn our attention again directly to Zincke. 
 
 The next evidence of Zincke's individual views appears 
 in his modification of the plan of Stisser's book. As he states 
 it in his Preface (pp. 20, 21), this modification consists in pre- 
 senting "first the Cammer-Wissenschaften, then in outlining 
 Oeconomie in general, of which the Land-Wirthschaft und 
 Policey of the Germans is only a special part." Then Zincke 
 explains that he has assembled "the most general rules of 
 management (Wirthschafftsregeln), and has furnished an 
 introduction to the study of oeconomischen Wissenschafft
 
 242 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 itself, in a form which is adequate preparation for these sub- 
 jects." Certain of the details in the introduction are impor- 
 tant way marks for our purpose. Beyond these, the book is 
 devoted entirely to rural management. We should note, 
 however, that Zincke has enriched the book with references 
 to authorities to such an extent that the authors' index fills 
 twenty-four and a half double-column pages. If we had found 
 no evidence of a similar sort in the earlier writers of this group, 
 Zincke's bibliography would alone be enough to demonstrate 
 the absurdity of the tradition which von Mohl repeats in the 
 passage quoted above. 1 
 
 The most significant propositions of the introduction may 
 be epitomized as follows: 
 
 The subject of the book is the rural management of the Germans 
 [Land-Wirthschaflt der Teutschen]. This is a special part of the 
 management [Wirthschafit] of this people in general, and this depends 
 to a certain extent upon the whole. It also presupposes various 
 general ideas of Wirthschafft and Hausshaltung (i). 
 
 The word Wirthschafft is sometimes used in a very comprehensive, 
 sometimes in a very restricted, sense. Thus, (a) for Wirthschaftts- 
 Geschdjte themselves; (b) for the ways and means of managing 
 (Wirthschafllen); (c) for a family, considered as managing (die da 
 wirlhschafttet); (d) for Land-Wirthschafft in particular; (e) for the 
 science and art of understanding one's own or another's management 
 [Haushaltung]; (/) for the theory and instructions [Lehre und An-wei- 
 sung] which lead to prudent ordering of Wirthschaflts-Geschajte. 
 This last is the meaning which the word has in this book. In the 
 same sense the words Hauss-Wirthschafll, Oeconomie, and Hauss- 
 haltungskunst arc in common use (2). 
 
 Wirthschafjl is thus a practical theory or Wissenschajt, in which, 
 according to their wisdom, prudence, and art, almost all learned 
 sciences are applied to proper gainful occupations, to the end that 
 not only necessary and comfortable subsistence, but also a surplus 
 for pleasure or need [zu Liebes- und Noih-Fallen], may be gained (3). 
 
 1 Vide pp. 12 ff.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 243 
 
 Accordingly Wirthschafit in general is a science which teaches 
 prudence in pursuing the callings which provide sustenance and 
 thus justly and prudently not only to gain means of subsistence, 
 but also prudently to hold, expend, and apply the same (4). 
 
 Wirthschafit is variously subdivided: especially into general 
 and special theory; this latter again into ofientliche Landes -Wirth- 
 schafit and Privat-Wirthschafit; or in other words general and special 
 Policey-Wissenschaft, which teaches how to order and to promote 
 for their several purposes, through good police laws and institutions, 
 the Wirthschafits-Geschafte of a country, a city or of an office (5). 
 
 Privat-Wirthschafit teaches how each individual member of 
 civic society may conduct his Wirthschafit wisely (6). 
 
 Privat-Wirthschafit is sometimes divided according to the strata 
 and persons that manage (wirthschafiten), sometimes according 
 to the things which are the objects of management, sometimes accord- 
 ing to the basic theorems of the processes concerned, sometimes 
 according to nations (7). 
 
 In the first case we have the Wirthschafit (a) of princes, rulers, 
 and great lords, with their Cammer- und Stoats -Revenues, i.e., die 
 Ho}- Stoats- und Militair-Wirthschafit; (b) of subjects, since pecul- 
 iar managerial relations spring from the social stratum and circum- 
 stances. These are consequently peculiar rules of Wirthschafit 
 for (i) the greater and lesser nobility: (2) soldiers; (3) travelers; 
 (4) citizens of high and low degrees; (5) scholars, at schools, univer- 
 sities, in church, school, and political offices; (6) rural populations 
 of higher and lower degree and peasants; (7) the male sex, e. g., 
 married and single persons, boys, young men, adults, and aged; (8) 
 the female sex, in parallel classes; (9) the poor; (10) the needy; 
 ( 1 1) the middle class; (12) the rich; (13) the servant class (8). 
 
 It would be an endless affair to treat of the Wirthschafit of each 
 of these strata in detail. Hence, with respect to differences of stra- 
 tum only the Haushaltung und Wirthschafit of great lords will be 
 considered. In the theory of Cammer- Rent- und Finanz-Wesen, 
 however, their particular maxims will be shown after the basis 
 has been laid in Oeconomische Policey-Wissenschafit. And precisely 
 therein consist today the so-called Cameral-Wissenschafiten in which 
 one learns WirthscJtafit chiefly with reference to the best common
 
 244 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 good [das genuine Beste] and for the service of great lords, the Privat- 
 Wirthschaftt of all others, who live as subjects or as obscure persons, 
 is shown along with the first part of Oeconomischer Policeywissen- 
 schaflt (9). 
 
 Conformably to the objects and transactions of Wirthschajfl, the 
 same is divided (i) in accordance with the chief branches of business 
 in Europe, into the theory of (a) Land-Wirthschaftt, (b) Stadt-Wirth- 
 schaftt, which division was first made by P. Fischer; (2) in respect 
 to the collateral processes (10). 
 
 We may briefly describe Land-Wirthschaftt as that part of Wirth- 
 schafit which teaches how one may carry on the cultivation of the 
 earth, both upon and below the surface, especially upon estates and 
 in connection with the appertaining rights, also cattle feeding and 
 particularly cattle raising, so wisely and prudently that one may 
 by appropriate means gain all sorts of profit and advantage, retain 
 the same, and turn it to thrifty application [haitswirthlich anwenden] 
 
 (13)- 
 
 Die Wirthschaftt consists of .various doctrines [Lehren]. It con- 
 tains especially general theoretical and practical theorems, which 
 are final rules. These consist either of fundamental theorems from 
 other sciences, or of fundamental theorems and rules peculiar to 
 Oeconomia generali. 1 The former are derived especially from (i) 
 general and special Rechts-Gelehrsamkeit; (2) Natur-Lehre, Chymie, 
 Anatomic, and Artzney-Kunst; (3) Mathematics, especially Rechen- 
 kunst, Geometric, Mechanique, and Baukunst; (4) general Staats- 
 und Privat-Klugheit (14). 
 
 Die Wirthschaftt consists further (2) of special theorems and 
 rules pertaining to the chief objects and transactions of Land- und 
 Stadt-Wirthschaftt, to their auxiliary transactions, and to the Wirth- 
 schafft of this and that sort of persons. Here we present the theorems 
 about the principal and subsidiary phases of Land-Wirthschaftt 
 and about the persons engaged in the same. This belongs under 
 the head Specialia (15). 
 
 1 Zincke remarks in a note, "These have been presented best by 
 Hr. Lie. Hofmann in his first book, Klughtit Haus zu halten." This 
 is G. A. Hoffmann. The remainder of the title of the book is: oder 
 pruderUia otconomica vulgar is; 4 vols., 1730-49. Vide Roscher, p. 436.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 245 
 
 Finally belong to Wirlhschafjt (3) Singularia or the most particu- 
 lar observations and devices. Moreover we must mention (4) the 
 Wirthschaftts-Termini or Kunst-W drier, Redens-Arten, and expla- 
 nations of the same 1 (16). 
 
 Die Wirtksckafft varies also with respect to nations or peoples, 
 and it is certain that the former [Wirtkschafft] vaiies as widely as 
 the latter, their soil and climate. Not to speak of the uncivilized 
 peoples outside of Europe, the Land- und Sladt-Wirlhschafll of the 
 civilized Europeans, for example of the French, Spanish, Italians, 
 English, Dutch, Poles, Swedes, etc., differs, in respect to very many 
 Wirthschaflls-Geschaflen, especially in respect to particular arrange- 
 ments, purposes, and objects, from that of the Germans, and indeed 
 the latter varies not only by contrast between the ancient and the 
 modern, but also by contrasts l>etween the various German j>eoples 
 and localities at present. Thus there are the differences between 
 the Ober-Sachsen, der Nieder-Sachsen, der Schwaben, der Schweitzer, 
 etc. Herr von Rohr accordingly, and not without reason, made a 
 plea for more information and cultivation of oeconomia harmonica. 2 
 Meanwhile it is the duty of Germans to pay special attention to the 
 most common features of the Wirthschafil of Germans, and to under- 
 
 1 The bibliography of this part of the subject, as cited by Zimkc, 
 is notable: viz., "(i) Das Cheminizische Oeconomische Lexicon, new ed., 
 Niirnberg, 1746; (2) Chommel Diction. Oeconomique; (.3) Das allge- 
 meine Oeconomische Lexic., so vormahls schon bey Glcditschen in Leip- 
 zig herausgekommen, an. 1744, aber von mir dem jezgen Edilore dieser 
 Einleitung, vermehret und verbessert herausgegebcn wordcn; (4) 
 Savery, Lexic. de Commerce, ed. n.; (5) Das bey Heinsio in Leipzig edirte 
 Handels-Lexic. sub. Tit. AUgemeine Schatz-Cammer der Kaufmannscha/, 
 in 4 Theilen und einem Supplem., ed. infol., 1741; (6) Beiers, Allge- 
 meines Handlungs- Kunst- Berg- und Handwercks-Lexic., von D. Strubcn 
 ed. in 410, an. 1722; (7) Das in Berlin von einem Gliede der Societal der 
 Wissenschaften herausgekommene Real-Lexicon der Wissenschaften; 
 (8) Das bey Gleditschen herausgekommene Natur- Berg- Cewerck- und 
 Handlungs-Lex.; (9) Minerophili Berg-Wercks- Lexicon; (10) Mein 
 D. Zinckens Manufactur- und Handwercks-Lexic., so jetzt untcr der 
 Presse und von Fuchsen allhier ediret wird." 
 
 In \iisHausshaUungs-Bibliothek, ed. 1726, p. 129. Vide also Hrn. 
 von Hohberg, Adlichen Land-Wirthschofft (Zincke).
 
 246 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 stand it according to the manner, customs, usages, laws, and civic 
 organization of their own country. This book is specially devoted 
 to that purpose (17). 
 
 This passage is at once symptomatic of the whole camera- 
 listic conception of economic problems, and it is a rather excep- 
 tionally clear and unequivocal expression of the conception. 
 It is thus one of the crucial exhibits in the body of evidence 
 which sustains one of the principal contentions of our argument : 
 viz., the theories of the cameralists were formulations of differ- 
 ent sorts of utility with reference to relatively parochial aims. 
 They were not attempted generalizations of universal economic 
 or civic relations, because universal relations of these orders had 
 not roused their attention or interest in an appreciable degree. 
 They were virtually attempts to answer the question: "Situ- 
 ated as we are, and being what we are, individually and politi- 
 cally, how can we use our opportunities so as most to further 
 our particular purposes ?" A stage of experience characterized 
 by this range of generalization must be taken for granted, and 
 accepted just as it was. We turn the reality of experience 
 into myth and fable if we interpret back into such intermediate 
 experience the states of mind which emerged at later stages. 
 In brief, we must interpret the cameralists as they were, not 
 as nineteenth-century economists. We do not satisfy this 
 requirement merely by pointing out that their conclusions 
 differed from those of nineteenth-century economists. That 
 way of stating it covers up and compromises the crucial 
 distinction. In an essential sense, the cameralists were not 
 concerned about the same problems ttiat engaged the nine- 
 teenth-century political economists. This experience of the 
 cameralists has value for modern men; and historical 
 scholars must find and utilize the value. The experience 
 has been shorn of its value by growth of a tradition which 
 vitiates our interpretation in advance by ignoring the radical 
 contrast between the Smithian and the pre-Smithian atti-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZIXCKE 247 
 
 tudc of mind toward economic relations. The introduction 
 continues: 
 
 Whoever would thoroughly learn Wirlhschafit in the special 
 department of Policey- und Cammcr-\\'esens must gain the knowledge 
 through instruction and experience. The instruction must consist 
 in part of coherent oral discourse upon IVirlhschnfit as a whole, and 
 afterward upon a portion of the same upon which one proposes to 
 place the chief emphasis; in part through oral instructions incidental 
 to practice itself, and through association wilh experienced ffunxs- 
 wirthen, and in part through the reading of good IVirlhschaffts- 
 Bucher (18). 
 
 Whoever will thus study Wirthsclmfit must have learned pre- 
 viously (i) to write and reckon well; (2) to form a good concept; 
 and the rudiments of (3) der Moral; (4) Natur-Lchrc und Ilislnriam 
 naturalcm; (5) die Chymie; (6) die Gcometriam, architccturam 
 civilem, and especially die Mechanique; (7) something of Mcdirin; 
 (8) something of the laws. Before all things, however, one must 
 attempt, through the grace of God, to put oneself in the situation 
 in which one can actually exercise the first general l\'irtlischu/]l<>- 
 Regel of the Christians: "Seek ye first the Kingdom of God and 
 his righteousness, and all these things shall be added unto you" ( 19). 
 
 Beyond this, all depends (i) on very careful consideration and 
 investigation of the wirthschafftlichrn Objecte, Zwecke und hfsonderer 
 Gcschajte, and especially upon understanding and choice of the 
 persons concerned: through all this, moreover, upon cautious deci- 
 sions in wirthschafillichen Din gen; (2) upon a diligent, careful, 
 energetic, and industrious carrying-out of the precepts and applica- 
 tions in general, to the end of gaining good returns from the occupa- 
 tion, of caring well for them through frugality and watchfulness, 
 without greed. Finally, upon applying to those ends all temporal 
 means according to God's law and according to wirtksckafltiichrH 
 Klugheit, and especially upon so ordering outlays that an annual 
 surplus will remain (20). 
 
 We now return to Zincke's own hooks. Most important 
 for our purpose is, first, the Cameralisten-Ribliothek. 1 
 
 1 I). Gcorg Hcinriih Zinc-kens, Herzogl. Braunsrhw. \vinkl. Hof- 
 unl Cammer-Raths, etc., Cameralisten Bibliothek, U'orinne ncbst der
 
 248 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 A general description of these compact little volumes would 
 afford but a vague idea of their contents. It will not be pos- 
 sible to present an adequate outline of Zincke's system, because 
 that would require as much space as can be given to the author 
 who may on the whole most fairly be taken as an epitome of 
 cameralism, viz., Justi. To differentiate Zincke's system from 
 Justi's, it would be necessary to go into comparison of technical 
 details in the two authors; and that would be foreign to our 
 purpose. Without attempting to pass upon the delicate ques- 
 tion of the relative merits of the two men, we must confine our- 
 selves here to certain specifications which show that Zincke 
 was among the formative factors in the social science of his 
 period. 
 
 Indeed, there are more evident motions in the direction of 
 Smithism, in Zincke's most general methodological observa- 
 tions, than in any other writer in the series. He perceived, in 
 a vague, abortive, fashion to be sure, that the details of camera - 
 listic policy required a center in more fundamental philosophy. 
 His attempts at foundation of such a philosophy are rather 
 pathetic, but on the other hand his contemporaries did not 
 even make the attempt. Whether Zincke actually saw deeper 
 than Gerhard had penetrated cannot be known. At all events 
 he published his ideas much more extensively, and it is plain 
 that his mind was maturing in the direction of such problems 
 
 Anleitung die Cameral-Wissenschaft zu lehren und zu lernen, ein voll- 
 stdndiges Verzeichniss der Biicher und Schriften von der Land- und Stadt- 
 Oeconomie, dent Policey- Finanz und Cammer-Wesen zu finden, so theils 
 kurz beurtheilet, theils umstdndlich vorgcstcllet warden. Der erste Theil, 
 
 von der Oeconomie 1751 (304 pages); "Zweyter Theil, von der 
 
 Policey- Wissenschaft, 1751" (270 pages); "Dritter Theil, von der Cam- 
 
 mer- und Finanz-Wissenschaft ^S 2 " (354 pages); "Vierter 
 
 und Letzter Theil. Nebst vollstandigem gedoppelten Register iiber 
 
 alle vier Theile 1752" (210 pages). In addition, the authors' 
 
 index occupies 58 pages, and the subject-index, 36 pages, besides four 
 pages of errata.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 249 
 
 as Smith afterward proposed. Zincke's place in the cameralis- 
 tic succession may best be indicated by a few characteristic 
 details. 
 
 Zincke was the first German writer, so far as I have been 
 able to discover, to insist strongly upon a sharp distinction 
 between vulgar and learned economic theory. Beginning in 
 the Introduction (pp. 7, 8), and continuing through the classi- 
 fications in the bibliographies, he tries to show the difference 
 between the folk-lore of familiar occupations, and "learned" 
 theory. His impulse was respectably scientific in its concep- 
 tion. He had not gone very far in his analysis of the kinds 
 of research which would be necessary before "learned" theory 
 could establish a relatively secure base. Zincke maintained 
 valiantly, against the overwhelming academic prejudice of his 
 time, that the subjects properly included within the scope of 
 cameralistics were capable of organization into a group of 
 sciences as methodical and respectable as those which had 
 already won academic recognition. 
 
 In supporting this thesis, Zincke argued (pp. 16, 17) that 
 a system of cameralistic science must rest upon applications 
 of doctrines accepted by philosophical, mathematical, legal, 
 and other sciences. "In so far as those theorems are truths 
 established by other sciences, we may take them for granted in 
 cameral science." The list of such truths which he cites as 
 the philosophical antecedents of cameralistic science hardly 
 impresses the modern reader with the solidity of the support, 
 but such as it is we may reduce it to this: 
 
 A means [MiUef] is something in which the sufficient ground is 
 contained through which to reach a given end. We all have a natural 
 longing for welfare. That is an end which all men by nature seek. 
 All our lives we strive for this condition, which we call happiness 
 \GlUckseligkeit}. Progress toward this condition we call temporal 
 happiness, and the things which contribute to it may serve either our 
 bodies or our souls or both. Such things we call our goods. A
 
 250 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 stock of such temporal goods we call temporal means [Vermdgen]. 1 
 Transactions with these means, or the actual use of the same for 
 the above specified end, we call, in a somewhat narrow sense to be 
 sure, livelihood [Nahrung].' 
 
 It need not be argued that the need of using these temporal 
 means for gaining our happiness makes it both the right and the 
 duty both of the individual man and of whole societies, especially 
 of those heads of societies to whom the citizens have intrusted the 
 supreme power over themselves, in order to insure temporal happi- 
 ness, to apply these means in every proper way to gain the happiness 
 of all. We have then the three most general kinds of transaction 
 in all management [Wirlhschaft], viz., the gaining, the guarding, and 
 the applying of temporal means. These three kinds of transaction 
 are explained in General-Oeconomic (13). 
 
 In the same portion of cameral science this principle will be 
 demonstrated, viz., a prince, as the ruling head of a civic society, whether 
 the same consists of a physical or a moral person, for the maintenance 
 in part of his sovereignty, his house, and his own exalted person, 
 partly the common good [gemeinen Bestens] of his state, must strive 
 to gain, keep, and apply a proportional amount of ready means 
 [bereitestes Vermdgen} (i4). 3 
 
 ' For reasons already alluded to (vide above, p. 76; cf. pp. 367 and 373) 
 and which will appear more fully later, it is necessary to render Mittel and 
 Vermdgen by the same term. We shall have little to do with the former 
 term in the technical sense which Zincke tries to impress upon it, while 
 the latter figures very prominently in the theories that follow. It is 
 necessary to protect it against the unauthorized legal additions forced 
 into it by the rendering "property." 
 
 * It is impossible to choose a rendering of such terms which can be 
 used consistently even in translating single authors. They vary indefinitely 
 in the usage of the writers in this group (SJio, u). 
 
 3 One of the incidental questions which this study raises is as to the 
 possible effect of this mere phrase upon the suggestibility of actual rulers 
 during the eighteenth century. The idea of the "readiest" means 
 undoubtedly carried with it the snap judgment of best means, and thus 
 one of the impulses was given to exaggeration in practice of the stimulus 
 applied to trade as a producer of national revenue.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 251 
 
 The keynote of cameralism is struck by Zincke in the next 
 paragraph : 
 
 The more a prince, by observance of this duty, is able to promote 
 his own and his country's welfare and more complete condition (sic), 
 the greater will he be. For herein is to be found the true ground of 
 the external greatness of a prince. The greater he becomes, however, 
 the more must he have ready means, and consequently the more 
 must he endeavor to procure, to guard, and to apply the same (15). 
 
 All ready means, and consequently those of a prince, consist 
 of income [Einkunften]. Hence there must be sources from which 
 it is derived. 1 An irrefutable and indubitable truth is therefore: 
 That a prince is bound [schttldig und verpflichtet] to recognize the 
 first general and permanent source of his ready means, and to estab- 
 lish the same upon that source (16). 
 
 Where then is this source to be found ? The source of the ready 
 means of the whole human race is well known. Created animate 
 and inanimate nature, especially however the earth with its creatures, 
 its forces, all men themselves, and created things outside of them, 
 are the sources from which they derive everything to be used as 
 means [Vermogen].* God himself is indeed the first founder of 
 this source, through his wise and beneficent creation, preservation, 
 and care of men. All powers of bodily movement and of the exer- 
 cise of the soul are to be included in this source. But each individual, 
 and each smaller or larger society, controls only a certain portion 
 of this source of ready means. This control is exercised partly by 
 virtue of the native power of the individual or the society, partly 
 through the two chief natural (sic) institutions of the world, namely, 
 property and rulership [Eigenthum und Herrscha/t]. Accordingly 
 ' Zincke uses the French word fond, but in apposition with it the Ger- 
 man words Quellen and Grund. The sense is sometimes merely " source " 
 in general; sometimes "fund" in a more special use, and sometimes a 
 close approach to the modern technical concept "capital." Without 
 representing the unstable condition of Zincke's ideas at this point, the' 
 term " source" will fairly translate the essential thoughts in this connection. 
 In this particular passage the author approaches as close as the 
 conceptions of his time would permit to the plain formula, "Nature is 
 the ultimate source of wealth."
 
 252 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 no one can bring the whole source under his property or rulership, 
 and it is therefore impossible and consequently foolish to make the 
 attempt (18). 
 
 The portion of the earth controlled by a collection of men must 
 then be the immediate source of their ready means (19). 
 
 Since endeavor after secure and comfortable life has made it 
 necessary for such collections of men to unite their property and 
 powers in the single will of a ruler, and to a certain degree, with respect 
 to these two chief matters, to subject themselves to the same, and 
 thus the concept state or civic society arises; it follows unquestionably 
 that the immediate source of the ready means of a ruler in general 
 can be no other than his land and people, or so-called Territorium 
 
 (20). 
 
 In order to show the local and temporal shading of this 
 idea in the cameralistic view the next section is translated 
 in full: 
 
 I assert with zeal that this is the immediate source of ready 
 means in general. For since lands, and the people in the same, in 
 spite of all this, according to the great law of God respecting the 
 social helpfulness with which human welfare is bound up, are in a 
 certain interdependence, and hence each land and people can and 
 must at the same time make use of the means of another land and 
 people for the welfare of the former, and conversely can and must 
 with its own means and powers help the other land; so one may 
 say that to a certain extent, and in an indirect or distant way, by 
 virtue of this interdependence of lands and peoples, the means and 
 the powers of the same are and must be of assistance as a source 
 of ready means for a ruler over land and people. Moreover one 
 of the most important portions of the cameralistic sciences is that 
 which shows the ways in which other lands may rightly and wisely 
 be made into sources of all sorts of revenues and profits (21). 
 
 Speaking now more precisely, the source of the ready means of 
 a ruler is to be found not merely in land and people, with all their 
 interconnections, but rather in a land and people placed in a con- 
 stantly flourishing condition o] their means oj livelihood. Hence 
 follows the principle: A prince who would better establish, maintain,
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 253 
 
 and preserve his ready means, must devote all his effort to put his 
 land and people in a constantly more flourishing condition of gaining 
 the means of livelihood, and must thus secure for them increasing 
 prosperity. Accordingly, the more services, things oj money value, 
 money, and credit increase, the greater and richer is the source and 
 ground of the ready means of a ruler (23). 
 
 Using means of livelihood is called managing \wirthschafjten]. 
 When the produce provides not merely the wants and conveniences 
 of physical life, but also that excess which we call riches, we call it 
 good management. If the means of livelihood for a land and people 
 are to be flourishing, good management must prevail among and 
 over them. It follows that the ruler, or those who assist him in 
 these important matters, must have the knowledge necessary to 
 insure good management, and must exert the utmost endeavor 
 to secure the application of this knowledge throughout the land 
 
 (23)- 
 
 This is necessary not only for the sake of promoting good manage- 
 ment in the land, and to put the people in the way of ready means, 
 but it is necessary in order to secure the sources of the prince's own 
 ready means (24). 
 
 It follows that a prince needs genuine and skilful cameralists. 
 By this name we mean those who possess fundamental and special 
 knowledge about all or some particular part of those things which 
 are necessary in order that they may assist the prince in maintaining 
 good management in the state (25). 
 
 A land can be put in a flourishing condition of the means of live- 
 lihood only through good Policey-Gesetze und Anstalten. Whoever 
 would serve the prince well at this point must not only know the 
 existing Policey-Gesetze, but he must understand how to invent and 
 introduce such laws and institutions. For this purpose he must 
 also understand the nature and structure of the means of livelihood, 
 or Wirthschaft. For the Policey-Gesetze und Anstalten have the task 
 of directing and improving the means of livelihood and the manage- 
 ment of a people. Hence it follows that the science of making police 
 laws and institutions can neither be learned nor applied without the 
 science and knowledge of management, which is properly called 
 die Oeconomie in distinction from der Oeconomic, which means the
 
 254 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 actual application. 1 Whoever, finally, would administer the ready 
 means of rulers, not merely prudently, but in close connection with 
 the constantly improving conditions of livelihood, and with super- 
 intendence of the same, which a wise ruler exercises through good 
 police laws and institutions he must have thorough knowledge 
 of Oeconomie and Policey (26). 
 
 After rehearsing the argument that all this cannot be left 
 to pure empiricism, but must be reduced to expert knowledge 
 and practice, Zincke compresses his case into this proposition : 
 
 Cameral-Wissenschajt is a learned and practical science, first, 
 of inventing, improving, and introducing all sorts of good police laws 
 and institutions drawn from the nature and conditions of the means 
 of livelihood of a land; second, a science partly resting upon die 
 Oeconomie, partly upon special rules and maxims which set forth 
 the rights and duties of a ruler, of wisely, prudently, rightly, and 
 skilfully founding, maintaining, increasing, and administering the 
 necessity, comfort, and riches of a land, and at the same time and 
 thereby the ready means needed by the ruler for the good of the state 
 and its ruler (29). 
 
 Zincke explains, half apologetically, that this description, and 
 the book itself, were written not for the learned, but for begin- 
 ners. He proposes the following as an alternative form: 
 
 Cameral-Wissenschaft is a learned and at the same time practical 
 science, having as its object thorough understanding of all means 
 of livelihood and on that ground the introduction of good Policey, 
 to the end of rendering useful services to states and rulers in cameral 
 and financial affairs (30). 
 
 Elaborating the idea that Cameral-Wissenschaft consists 
 of various Wissenschaften, Zincke continues: 
 
 1 But on p. 55 Zincke distinctly defines the word Oeconomie as mean- 
 ing "die Wirthschaft selbst." Again, in the Anfangsgrunde (I, p. 18), 
 Zincke assigns to the first part of Cameral-Wissenschaft: "Die Natur 
 und Beschaffenheit aller Nahrungsgeschafte insgemein, und besonders 
 deutlich und griindlich zu analysiren und einzuseheo. Und diesen Theil 
 nenne ich die gelehrte Oeconomie."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 255 
 
 In my Grundriss I presented die Oeconomic and Policey-Wissen- 
 schaft in the composite form of wirthschaftliche Policey-Wissenschaft. 
 I made Cameral-Wissenschaft the first main division, and Cammer- 
 und Finanvwissenschaft the second. I have reconsidered, however, 
 and this book will have three main divisions: (i) Die Oeconomic; 
 (2) die Policey-Wissenschaft; (3) die Cammer- oder Rent- und Finanz 
 Wissenschaft (32). 
 
 From the redundant and perplexing variations upon this 
 explanation in the most general part of the work, we abstract 
 only the following items: 
 
 Oeconomic attempts to teach the poor how they may advance in 
 means to the middle class, the middle class how they may become 
 rich. Policey-Wissenschaft shows not only how to decrease the num- 
 ber of the poor, but also how to promote the interest of all other 
 strata, so that each in its way may enjoy advancing prosperity (p. 60). 
 This does not mean that everybody is to be brought into the middle 
 class, or everybody to be made rich. This is quite as incorrect as 
 the other hateful idea of certain leaches, who teach that all, especially 
 the peasants, should be reduced to the barest necessities of life. It 
 means that all are to be put in the way of gains in prosperity propor- 
 tioned to the lot of each (pp. 61-63). 
 
 The first and most general principle of a good finance system 
 is that the administration shall aim to insure the ready means of 
 the ruler by such arrangements as will at the same time promote 
 the best good of the state. That is, neither (i) the interest of the 
 ruler, nor (2) the interest of the state must be allowed to infringe 
 on the other (pp. 68, 69). 
 
 The work as a whole compels the conclusion that Zincke's 
 methodological interests excessively handicapped his camera- 
 listic interests. To use a different figure, his stage machinery 
 is so conspicuous and so intricate that it conceals the play. At' 
 the same time it is evident that he was thinking ahead of most 
 of his academic contemporaries. His perceptions were indis- 
 tinct enough, but his attempt to find a firm basis for cameralis- 
 tic theory and to organize its pans into a coherent system
 
 256 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 entitles him to a place with the most intelligent of the series. 
 In one respect he is easily foremost among the cameralists. 
 He published the first bibliography which made a systematic 
 attempt to classify the literature, not merely according to sub- 
 jects, but according to degrees of scientific merit. He had 
 a code of letters indicating the two main classes of (a) "learned," 
 (b) "unlearned" books, and in each class the grades, (i) good 
 (2) very good, (3) moderately good, (4) bad, (5) very bad. 
 Besides this gradation, there are numerous quasi-critical and 
 other notes. The bibliography of the first part of Cameral- 
 Wissenschaft, or Oeconomic, contains 975 titles, of which 295 
 are on strictly agricultural topics, and 172 more relate to other 
 extractive industries (Part I, pp. 192-304); the second part, 
 " Policey-Wissenschaft" contains 502 titles, of which 164 
 refer to agricultural administration 1 (Part II, pp. 441-565); 
 the third part, "Cammer- und Finanz-Wissenschaft," has 570 
 titles (Part III, pp. 780-916); and in Part IV (pp. 1071-1134). 
 There are 243 bibliographical notes as addenda to specified 
 sections in the body of the work. 
 
 At the end of the text (p. 1134), is the devout ascription, 
 which flippant critics might render, to be sure, in a way that 
 would have an appositeness quite undesigned by the author: 
 "Gott meinem SchSpfer allein die Ehre. " 
 
 The existence of this bibliographical monument passes 
 into a curious historical problem, when we encounter the 
 contrast presented by the books of Justi and Sonnenfels. We 
 cannot go into the problem here, but must be content with 
 simply calling attention to it. 
 
 Passing to Zincke's more elaborate work, 3 we find another 
 
 > Again attention must be called to the absurdity of the tradition 
 voiced by von Mohl (above, p. 13), in view of this large body of litera- 
 ture on the extractive industries. 
 
 1 D. Georg Heinrich Zinckens Anfangsgrunde der Cameralwissen- 
 schaft, worinne dessert Grundriss weiter ausgefuhret und verbessert itnrd. 
 Des Ersten Theils, welcher so wohl die General als Special Land- um4
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 257 
 
 version of the Cameral-Wissenschaft, which however, as the 
 author says (I, p. 7), amounts to the same thing as the formulas 
 quoted above, viz.: 
 
 It is a learned and practical science, devoted to thorough under- 
 standing of all occupations that procure livelihood, to introducing, 
 in pursuance of this knowledge, good Policey, and to making the 
 livelihood of lands increasingly prosperous, to" the end however 
 not merely of better establishing, maintaining, and righteously and 
 wisely increasing the ready means of rulers and states, but also, by 
 means of wise income and expenditure, to secure good administra- 
 tion. 
 
 The judgment expressed above 1 must explain why it would 
 not be profitable to attempt a digest of this expansion of Zincke's 
 Grundriss. The author gives so much space to protestation 
 of what the different branches of camera! science should prop- 
 erly teach, and why, and how, and by what means, and to what 
 ends they should teach it, that it is easy to see how his contem- 
 poraries may have lost their patience before they found out 
 whether the science, as he advertised it, actually did any of 
 these things. So far as attention could be held at all at this 
 time by systematized cameralistics, the subject had to be 
 presented with details in the foreground. Very few people 
 cared for the more general methodological settings. Zincke's 
 books give ample evidence of profounder and more compre- 
 hensive views of the science than can be credited to Justi. 
 The former, however, was far too cameralistic to win his way 
 very widely with the traditional academicians, while he was 
 much too academic to make a strong impression upon the sort 
 of constituency which was favorable to cameralism. His 
 books cover the whole field of cameralism in a way which 
 
 Sladtoconomic (sic) und Policeywissenschaft abhandclt Des 
 
 Zweyten Theils, welche die eigentliche Finanz- und Cammenvissenschaft 
 
 enthalt Leipzig 1755. 
 
 1 Vide pp. 252 ff.
 
 258 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 was related to the interests of practical cameralists very much 
 as a treatise on the logic of ethics would affect the typical 
 modern legislator. This is not to say that they were on a 
 plane altogether remote from actual application. They con- 
 tain much, on the contrary, which is at the other extreme of 
 the tediously commonplace; for example, the twenty-three 
 fundamental rules for obtaining "means." 1 As a whole, 
 however, they are emphatically books of and for the study 
 rather than the bureau, and it is not surprising that they failed 
 to make an impression proportioned to their intrinsic worth. 
 As a general proposition, no one engaged directly in any division 
 of the activities which Zincke discusses could fail to be so well 
 informed, or to have such sources of information among his 
 associates in the occupation, that the author's treatment of his 
 interests would seem superfluous. On the other hand, to 
 most of the scholars of the time Cameral-Wissenschaft was as 
 much of an impertinence as sociology has seemed to the majority 
 of the same class during the past quarter-century. In the 
 Vorbericht to Theil II Zincke seems partly aware of this situa- 
 tion, and to choose his course in spite of it. a He declares that 
 he is not writing for the great masters in their subjects, whose 
 pupil he is willing to call himself, nor for those who want a 
 handbook of technical practice, still less for those self-satisfied 
 people who imagine that these subjects are too trivial for their 
 superior mim's. He believes that the book will be of use to 
 the students who have listened to his lectures for twenty years, 
 and he also expresses the hope that German rulers, from whom 
 ministers who disagree with the author do not contrive to keep 
 
 1 I, pp. 172 ff. Vide the nine rules on the relations of occupations to 
 one another (I, 205); the four fundamental rules for Policey (I, p. 266); 
 etc. On the other hand, the schedule of 38 "police questions" (I, p. 266) 
 is in spirit and in detail quite typical of the best practical standards of 
 the system. 
 
 (Especially pp. xiii ff.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 259 
 
 tJte book (sic!) will find in it something to approve and apply. 
 Lastly, he speaks as though he had definite expectations that 
 his work would be used as a text by tutors charged with the 
 education of young princes. 
 
 To sum up the case for Zincke, one can hardly study the 
 cameralistic sources without astonishment that this writer 
 has been allowed to fall into such an inconspicuous place in 
 the history of German social science. His merit is far above 
 his reputation. His more solid qualities have been obscured 
 by the more brilliant and audacious Justi. There is plenty 
 of internal evidence in the books of the latter that he was both 
 jealous and afraid of Zincke. He might well have been. 
 With all his versatility, his scholarship was not of an order to 
 gain by critical comparison with that of his less showy and 
 apparently less successful contemporary. Stieda has evidently 
 reached a somewhat similar estimate. He is well within bounds 
 when he concludes (p. 31): 
 
 Under all the circumstances Zincke seems to have been a very 
 respectable thinker. To be sure he sticks too closely, on the one 
 hand, to details of the particular gainful occupations, and as con- 
 trasted with the general principles of national economy he excessively 
 emphasizes Praxis. Nevertheless, what he was after was a study of 
 economic relations, and he wanted it to be systematic and thorough. 
 It would surely have been to the advantage of the University of Leip- 
 zig, if instead of allowing his migration it had put him in a professor- 
 ship of the economic sciences, which he would certainly have occupied 
 with all zeal. 
 
 In closing his discussion of the economic policy of Frederick 
 the Great, Roscher very aptly remarks: 
 
 Whoever would characterize a great general must use, for com- 
 pleting the picture, proportionate details about the qualities of his 
 most important subordinates. Hence something must be said about 
 a group of writers of the second and third rank 
 
 For the same reason, in order properly to shade our picture
 
 260 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of cameralism in general, we must mention briefly some of 
 the less important writers at the middle of the eighteenth cen- 
 tury. First in order, we may name Kottencamp. 1 The most 
 obvious fact about this mere tract of sixty-four pages is that 
 it is a eulogy of Frederick the Great, from the point of view 
 of a military man, to be classed with the similar eulogy of 
 Frederick's father, by Ludewig, speaking as an academician. 
 In the second place, the tract is notable as an apology for the 
 benevolent despot in contrast with the Machiavellian type of 
 prince. Without asking whether Kottencamp understood 
 Machiavelli, we find in him a very graphic sketch of the type 
 of government which cameralistic theory presupposed. 2 If 
 we were confined to this piece of evidence, the picture of the 
 cameralistic regime which could be reconstructed from it would 
 exactly correspond in tone with the account we have thus far 
 given; and there would be more than a suggestion of the main 
 divisions of technical detail which are presented by the text- 
 
 1 Kurtzer Abriss und wahrcs Ebenbild tines grossen Fiirsten und 
 erhabenen Geistes. Worinnen die attgemeinen Grundlehren der gesunden 
 Staatskunst in natiirlicher Ordnung abgehandelt, und mil den neuesten 
 Exempeln der Europdischen Geschichte erlautert seyn. Nebst einigen 
 Anmerkungen iiber die Lehrsatze Machiavels von der Regierungskunst 
 tines Fiirsten, verfasset und entworfen von Christian Friedrich Kotten- 
 camp, Audileur bey dent Ko'nigl. Preussis. hochlo'bl. Wallravischen 
 Pionnier-Regimente. . . . 1747. 
 
 * His subtitles are: "I. Von den verschiedenen Gattungcn, und der 
 Gemuths-Art der Fiirsten;" "II. Von der verschiedenen Fahigkeit und 
 Arten des Verstandes regierender Fiirsten;" "III. Von der Gerechtig- 
 keit, wie, auf welche weise, und wie weit souveraine Fiirsten solche gegen 
 ihre Nachbaren und Unterthanen beobachten miissen;" "IV. Wie ein 
 Fiirst seinen Staat erhalten und gross werden konne;" "V. Von dem 
 Staatsinteresse, und der Verbindlichkeit der Fiirsten in Betracht des- 
 selben;" "VI. Von dem Gliicke, und dem Einflusse desselben in die 
 Handlungen, und Staatsgeschafte der Fursten;" "VII. Ursachen, 
 wodurch die Reiche und Staaten verfallen, und die Fiirstenlichen Hauser 
 zu Grunde gehen."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 261 
 
 writers with whom we are chiefly concerned. Kottencamp 
 undertakes to show that the principles of true statemanship 
 are equally distant from Machiavellianism on the one hand 
 and from theological ethics on the other. Dismissing at once 
 the assumption that government can be conducted on a prayer- 
 meeting basis, he declares that while "honor, uprightness, 
 and virtue in general must everywhere be bound together with 
 sound politics," yet self-preservation, "which is the natural 
 impulse of all men," is "the plumb-line to which all doctrines 
 of statecraft must conform," and "the actual interests of the 
 state must therefore be placed at the foundation of all civic 
 maxims." "If the precepts of state adopted by cabinets often 
 seem severe, and in outward appearance to insult virtue, they 
 are nevertheless justified by grim necessity in this imperfect 
 human life." It is easy to read between the lines of this essay 
 unrecognized major premises which would in less than a 
 century dictate revolutionary conclusions. In form the mono- 
 graph rests without question upon the divine-right presupposi- 
 tion. In fact, princes are judged and classified by strictly 
 functional standards. 1 We shall find cumulative evidence of 
 this conflict between old and new standards of value in Justi 
 and Sonnenfels. Men at this time still expressed their belief in 
 princes in terms of divine right. They were already uncon- 
 sciously learning to form their working estimates of princes 
 by the criterion of their benefit or injury to their states. Kot- 
 tencamp formulates the first great commandment of statecraft 
 in the precept: "Seek to maintain thyself and thy state, and 
 to promote the best good of thy state." 2 While the first clause 
 was still paramount both in political policy and in political 
 
 'E.g., p. 19. Still more distinctly, p. 44, "Das wahre Staats- 
 interesse besteht in den Nutzen, .... aber .... dieser Nutze .... 
 konne von der Gerechtigkeit auf keine Weise getrennt werden." 
 
 * " Suche dich und deinen Staat zu erhalten, und deines Staats Beste 
 zu beforden" (p. 19).
 
 262 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 philosophy, the great dynamic fact in this period was the 
 gathering force of the second clause. Rulers and their advisers 
 regarded it as the formula of a gratifying incident of absolutism. 
 In the retrospect we can see that it was a revolutionary prin- 
 ciple, destined to supplant absolutism. 
 
 The prevailing assumption of the universal enmity of states 
 is presented in the essay as a matter of course. "To tell the 
 truth, it is with peoples and states as with the animal kingdom. 
 The stronger overcome the weak, and grow still stronger by 
 devouring them" (p. 20). Therefore, "a prince never trans- 
 gresses justice if he only restrains his desire to oppress others 
 and to appropriate their powers; and on the other hand has 
 only the purpose of his own preservation in all undertakings 
 against his neighbors" (p. 30). 
 
 Turning to principles of government Kottencamp bases 
 political wisdom on three "maxims": 
 
 A prince must rule his realm according to its own genius and 
 the disposition [Gemiithsart] of the people, and must understand 
 how to stop the sources of all internal unrest and disturbance (p. 33). 
 
 Then internal concord provided for, the prince has the 
 comparatively easy task of dealing with foreigners. Therefore, 
 second : 
 
 A prince must always put himself in such a condition as com- 
 pared with his neighbor that he is at least his equal in resources and 
 power, or, if this is impossible, that the inequality may be offset by 
 alliances and other arrangements, so that he need not fear destruction 
 or subjugation by his neighbor (p. 34). 
 
 In the third place, a prince who would provide against his own 
 fall anrl the destruction of his realm, must in his prosperity moderate 
 his desires and not covet more than he would be able in a natural 
 manner to protect and permanently retain (p. 37). 
 
 The thesis of the second part of the same chapter (iv), on 
 the question, How may a prince become great ? is: 
 
 The true greatness of princes is inseparable from the prosperity 
 and growth of the fortune and welfare of their lands (p. 39).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 263 
 
 To modern republicans such propositions are platitudes. 
 Their historical importance consists in their demonstration 
 that the times were generating essentially republican energies 
 while the absolutistic regime was superficially unquestioned. 
 
 Again, Kottencamp voices a deeper political philosophy, 
 rather than the creed of a governing class, when he defines the 
 interest of the state: 
 
 The interest of the state .... is whatever belongs to the growth, 
 prosperity, and welfare of a state (p. 43). 
 
 To be sure, the Germans had not yet fairly entered upon 
 that stage of their political education in which a thoroughly 
 rational content was to be given to the concepts "growth," 
 "prosperity," "welfare," and the like. The meaning of 
 these forms of expression may easily be exaggerated. They 
 may not be taken to mean all that they would suggest to modern 
 men. We argue from them here no more than that men were 
 well on their way toward abandoning the will of the prince 
 as the last norm of political desirability. They were learning 
 to set up more essential popular values as the valid ends of 
 civic action. 
 
 A second minor writer of this period is von Loen. 1 Roscher 
 says: 
 
 The extent to which at this period (1747) popular feeling had 
 adjusted itself to police guardianship may be seen from M. v. Loen's 
 Entwurj einer Staatskunst, worin die naliirlichsten Mittcl entdeckt 
 werden, ein Land macktig, reich und gliicklich zu machen (1747, 
 III. Aufl., 1751). The author recommends freedom as the first 
 means of promoting population, "this essential ground of all the 
 power of the prince and happiness of the state." Freedom is "the 
 true happiness of a state, the most precious possession of man, a 
 part of his life. He cannot be robbed of it without violation of 
 justice and violence to nature" (pp. 3 ff.). Yet according to von Loen 
 
 1 As I have been unable to secure copies of his books, this reference 
 is wholly a quotation from Roscher (p. 441).
 
 264 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 much constraint is consistent with this freedom. Tradespeople, 
 for example, "should hot be allowed to bring any foreign wares into 
 the country which are unnecessary and useless, and on the other 
 hand drive money out of the country." The manufacture of too 
 much gold and silver and of too much liquor should be forbidden; 
 likewise the founding of too many printing establishments, because 
 "most books are good for nothing, but merely make the common 
 people discontented, turbulent, and confused" (pp. 6 ff.). A mar- 
 riage bureau should forbid marriage's "whenever the parties are not 
 suited to each other" (p. 23). There should be sumptuary laws 
 regulating the costumes of the various social strata (p. 154). 
 
 Von Loen died in 1776. His best-known book is the novel, 
 Graf Rivera, oder der ehrliche Mann am Hofe : Its motive was the 
 improvement of life at courts. 
 
 The third writer to be recalled in this connection is Philippi. 1 
 This exponent of Prussian civic ideas is of the same general 
 class and type with Koltcncamp. He adds nothing to the 
 theory of cameralism, but he is good evidence of the kind of 
 commonplaces which had become orthodox tradition in the 
 quasi-absolutistic states of which cameralism was the theory. 
 Philippi's books contain not a little material which goes much 
 farther than he imagined in throwing light upon details of 
 political opinion as held in Germany at this time. Our limits 
 permit only a few indications of points in his argument. The 
 fundamental proposition is: 
 
 Everyone is bound to take care for the improvement of his tem- 
 poral circumstances and princes especially for the righteous aggran- 
 dizement of their states. * 
 
 The essay calmly takes for granted that the temporal happi- 
 
 ' Die wahren Mittel zur Vergrosserung eines Stoats, 1753. (166 pp.) 
 This essay is dedicated to Frederick II of Prussia. Der vcrgrosserte 
 Staat, von Johann Alhrcrht Philippi, Konigl. Preussischen Auditeur 
 
 Finckischen Regiments J 759- (.37 2 PP-) Dedicated to the 
 
 Prince of Prussia. 
 
 3 Die wahren MiUel, chap. i.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF ZINCKE 265 
 
 ness of subjects depends more upon providential care by the 
 prince than upon any other human means, and it is therefore 
 primarily a discussion of this cardinal factor. "The first 
 means of blessing and aggrandizing a state is a good prince." 
 It is also presupposed that there is divine guarantee of good 
 princes in hereditary succession, while there is no such guaran- 
 tee in an elective monarchy. Next to a good prince, true and 
 wise counselors and administrators promote the aggrandize- 
 ment of a state (chap. ii). Chap, iii begins with a typical 
 formula of the factor of population, viz.: 
 
 The great author of the anti-Machiavelli says with the greatest 
 justice: "He is not the greatest and most eminent who possesses 
 the most land. If he were, many an owner of agricultural land would 
 outrank a counselor of state, but on the contrary, we may say with 
 certainty that he is the richest prince who has unlimited sovereignty 
 over the most subjects." Accordingly, for the aggrandizement 
 of a state, all legitimate means must be used to maintain a constant 
 increase of the popualtion. 1 
 
 Next in importance for upbuilding a state is the maintenance 
 of armies (chap, iv); after these essentials, important means 
 are freedom of conscience (chap, v), freedom in gainful occu- 
 pations (Handel und Wandel), except possibly to the Jews 
 (chap, vi), promotion of commerce through promotion of 
 agriculture (chap, vii). 2 The remaining chapters on taxation 
 (chap, viii), the judiciary (chap, ix), the treasury (chap, x), 
 the improvement of higher and lower schools (chap, xi), and 
 Policey (chap, xii) contain nothing which calls for comment. 
 
 The second of the essays mentioned is merely a variation 
 
 1 Here and elsewhere Philippi cites von Loen as conclusive authority. 
 
 .* This part of the argument corroborates our generalization that the 
 traditional accounts of this mercantilist theory are largely fabulous. 
 Vide p. 14. Philippi quotes with approval a remark attributed to Pliny: 
 "The more diversified crops a land has, the greater its happiness and 
 wealth."
 
 266 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of the first. 1 The date of the Preface is May 21, 1759. 
 Although, as it proved, the third Silesian war was to drag along 
 nearly four years more, this Prussian militarist wrote in an 
 exultant tone. The second essay may be called an I-told-you- 
 so version of the first. The chapters are the same in number 
 as in the earlier essay with the exception of an added thirteenth 
 in the later, "Gedanken uber die Kameral- und Finanz-Wis- 
 senschaft;" they treat of the same topics; but now the point of 
 view is no longer prospective, it is retrospective. The recom- 
 mended means for aggrandizing a state had been used a half- 
 dozen years longer by the great Frederick, and Prussia was 
 now the already aggrandized state. This view of the situation 
 furnishes the occasion for elaboration of the eulogy upon Fred- 
 erick's regime, which had been more moderate in the earlier 
 essay. At the same time, there is reason for the suspicion that 
 this confident tone was merely a rhetorical device. The 
 author wanted to do his part toward keeping up the courage 
 and stimulating the ardor of his fellow-Prussians. Whether 
 the essay was merely a specimen of the " point- with-pride" 
 type of campaign literature, in which the pride is often in 
 inverse ratio with its real occasion, or a genuine expression of 
 belief about the assured results of Frederick's rule, it has the 
 same value for our purposes. It is the credo of a mediocre 
 man, in which we find such a man's reflection of the doctrines 
 taught by more eminent authorities. 
 
 1 I have used both a separately bound copy of the first, and a copy 
 in the same covers with the second. It should be added, however, that 
 the binding, though not very recent, is apparently of a much later date 
 than the publication.
 
 CHAPTER XII 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 
 
 Roscher speaks of Darjes as "undoubtedly the most impor- 
 tant of the cameralistic professors patronized by Frederick the 
 Great" (p. 419). 
 
 Like many Germans at this period who afterward gained 
 eminence in other spheres, Joachim Georg Darjes (1714-91) 
 devoted a considerable portion of his attention as a university 
 student to theology. He even preached a short time after 
 gaining his Master's degree. Turning, however, to juris- 
 prudence he received the degree of Dr. der Rechte (1739), 
 offered courses on the Institutes and Pandects, and in 1744 
 was made ordentlicher Professor der Moral und Politik, with 
 the title Hofrath. According to Richter (All. d. Bib., in loc.) 
 Darjes' academic success was so great that in his twenty-seven 
 years at Jena, he had more than ten thousand hearers. On 
 the invitation of Frederick the Great, he migrated (1763) to 
 Frankfurt a. O. as Konigl. preuss. Geheimrath und ordentlicher 
 Professor der Rechte. Here he founded the Kb'nigliche Gelehrte 
 Gesellschaft. He did not, however, acquire the same influence 
 as a university lecturer which he had enjoyed at Jena. He 
 became (1772) Direktor of the university, Ordinarius of the 
 law faculty, and the ranking professor of law. 1 Richter says: 
 "Darjes was of great service to the cameral sciences by 
 introducing them into university instruction." (Richter 
 1 Of his numerous writings (scheduled in Meusel's Lexicon), we 
 may name, irv addition to the book to be discussed below: Rlementa 
 metaphysica, 1743; Institutiones juris prudentiae universalis, 1745; 
 Philosophische Nebenstunden, 1740-52; Erste Griinde der philosophise he *i 
 Sittenlehre, 1750; Via ad Veritatem, 1758; Discurs iiber Natur- vnc. 
 Volkerrecht, 1762; Einleitung in des Freyherrn von Bielefeld Lehr- 
 be griff- der Staatsklugheit, 1764 (on J. F. von Bielfeld [sic] vide Rosrher, 
 pp. 426 ff.)- 
 
 267
 
 268 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 doubtless meant at Jena.) "As an author Darjes does not 
 stand particularly high. He lacked thoroughness, precision, 
 and talent for clear presentation." 1 
 
 This estimate by Richter is by no means to be accepted as 
 final. Indeed, if we recall Zincke for the sake of comparison, 
 we experience a deep sense of relief in passing from his much 
 less perspicuous, if more profound and comprehensive books, 
 to Darjes' clear and intelligent outline of cameralistics.* 
 Roscher further says (p. 419): 
 
 Darjes was an eminent pupil of Wolff, who wanted jurisprudence, 
 medicine, Wirlhschajlslehre, etc., to prevail only as applied phi- 
 losophy, but on account of his severely demonstrative method of 
 exposition J. J. Moser contemptuously labeled him "Modephilosoph." 
 With respect to the fundamental concepts of national economics 
 Darjes had learned much more from Hume than the majority of 
 his contemporaries in Germany. 
 
 Roscher cites only the second edition of the Erste Griinde, 
 published after the author had moved from Jena to Frankfurt. 3 
 In his estimate of Darjes' rank Roscher evidently did not 
 include Justi in the group of "Frederick's professors of came- 
 ralistics." He doubtless classed Justi as an administrator or 
 author, rather than as a professor. 
 
 1 Vide Stieda, pp. 52 and 78. 
 
 * Erste Griinde der Cameral-Wissenschaften, darinnen die Haupt- 
 Theile so wohl der Oeconomie als auch der Pblicey und besondern Cameral- 
 Wissenschaft in ihrer natiirlichen Verkniipfung, zum Gebrauch seiner 
 academischen Furlesung entivorfen von Joachim Georg Darjes, Hoch- 
 furstl. Sachsen- Weimar- und Eisenachischen Hof-Rathe, der Philosophic 
 und beyder Rechten Doctor, wie auch der Sitten-Lehre und Siaats-Klugheit 
 ordentlichen Professor zu Jena, des Senats der Churfiirstl. Maynz. Aka- 
 demie ntitzlicher Wissenschaften ordentlichem Beysilzer, der Jenaischen 
 Akademie i. d. Z. Pro-Rector und der Philosophise hen Faculty Decano. 
 .... 1756. (Pp. 664, exclusive of the Index, which fills 54 pages.) 
 
 3 All references in this chapter are to the first edition. I have not 
 seen the second.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 269 
 
 Darjes' own account of the origin of his book, as contained 
 in the Vorrede, is substantially this: He says that from boy- 
 hood he had been eager to search into the secrets of nature, 
 to find out how natural forces work, and thus to learn what 
 must be done when the attempt is made to imitate nature by 
 art. Following this impulse, he found frequent occasions, 
 in the course of lectures on other subjects, especially morals 
 and politics, to introduce practical reflections upon rural and 
 urban management. His hearers recognized the importance 
 of such considerations, and at length a petition came from 
 them for a separate course on the subject. 
 
 In adopting the suggestion, Darjes selected as his guide, 
 first, Dithmar's Einleitung. He pronounces the book admi- 
 rable [schon], but finds it somewhat too "remote" from the 
 aspects of the subjects which he wants to treat. That is, he 
 regards it as not sufficiently concrete. "It describes things 
 which occur in all departments of these activities [i. e., Wirth- 
 schaft, Policey, Cammer], but he does not explain how they 
 are to be carried out and improved." Then followed "the 
 excellent work which bears the title, Kluglieit zu leben und zu 
 herrschen." 1 He says: 
 
 I have more than once lectured with profit upon this work, and 
 I doubt if anyone can read it attentively without becoming more 
 useful. It lacks nothing except more specific explanation of the 
 grounds on which the activities of rural and civic management must 
 be judged. 
 
 Darjes says that he had also several times used Schroder's 
 Fiirstliche Schatz- und Rent-Cammer* and Seckendorff's 
 Fiirsten-Staat, 3 as the basis of his lectures, but at length he 
 was prevailed upon by his students and the publishers to print 
 his own ideas in systematic form. 
 
 1 Rohr's digest seems to have had an influence out of proportion to 
 its author's merit. Vide above, p. 190. 
 
 * Vide above, pp. 135 ff. 3 Vide above, pp. 61 ff.
 
 270 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The author's views of the instruction in cameralistic sub- 
 jects most appropriate to universities, and consequently to be 
 introduced by such a book, call for treatment midway between 
 abstract methodology on the one hand and details of admin- 
 istrative routine on the other. He points out very clearly that 
 it would be an endless task to describe in dftail each of the 
 separate processes that occur in the different divisions of 
 management. He is equally clear in his judgment that such 
 detailed description would be undesirable if possible. He 
 declares that many managerial processes must be compre- 
 hended under a common idea; that the important thing is to 
 understand this fundamental idea, in a single typical case, and 
 then anyone capable of independent thinking can find for 
 himself the relation of other cases to the same idea. He also 
 draws a very definite distinction between the science of manage- 
 ment and actual management itself, and he adds: 
 
 Those who carry out operations are often incapable of compre- 
 hending the science fundamental to the operations. They simply 
 do what they arc told, and their reasons for doing it do not extend 
 Ix-yorul the fact that they are told. Those who have charge of 
 operations, however, must necessarily understand the science of the 
 same. 
 
 Accordingly, Darjes calls his book "philosophical intro- 
 duction to ir/>//;.vr//a//" and he explains that his purpose is: 
 to dwell on the connection of tiuths which will make us capable of 
 judging all questions that would arise in practice, on their real 
 grounds, and to form clear and intelligible ideas of everything which 
 
 ociurs in Wirlhschajt The science of Wirthschajt should 
 
 make us ca|Kible of making an orderly Wirthschajt possible where 
 it has hitherto been impossible, and of guiding the same to the 
 advantage of human society. If we add that wisdom has its purpose 
 in promotion of the welfare of men, and second, that a great part of 
 the welfare of the state is founded in an orderly Wirthschajt, we have 
 the motives for applying the science of Wirthschajt to the state; 
 vix., first, to derive from the constitution of the state those means
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 271 
 
 by which the establishment of an orderly Wirthschaft in it is pos- 
 sible; second, to describe those means through which an orderly 
 Wirthschajt will be capable of promoting the prosperity of the state. 
 The first of these purposes is treated in the first and second parts 
 of this book, the second in the third part, the third in the fourth 
 part. 
 
 Darjes concludes with the specification : 
 
 The source from which I have drawn the special ideas is expe- 
 rience. Hence I may rightfully demand that the ideas be judged 
 not in accordance with the conceptions which others have constructed, 
 but in accordance with experience. That which experience teaches 
 us I have combined with general truths, partly in order to establish 
 a correlation, partly to confirm rules, the observance of which will 
 conduct us securely toward attainment of the end which we have 
 proposed. 
 
 As we have intimated before, 1 this appeal to experience, 
 particularly in the sense of personal observation, may be 
 taken as one of the authentic finding marks of the cameralists. 
 Beginning with Osse, we find increasingly evident tendencies 
 to break away from mere repetition of tradition and precedent, 
 and to consider state policy as means to certain rather clearly 
 defined ends not contained in conventional definitions. With 
 exceptions, and with varying degrees of emphasis on this phase 
 of their reasoning, the men whom we recognize as cameralists 
 have exhibited this trait. They were not equally aware of the 
 importance which they actually assigned to the empirical 
 element in their systems. Darjes is notable, however, as one 
 of the most outspoken in this respect. 
 
 But we must judge Darjes still more specifically. The 
 succession of cameralists furnishes several marked cases to 
 point the moral that reputation is not always in accordance 
 with an objective measure of merit. If we were to make out 
 from the type of evidence now under review the most exact 
 
 1 Vide p. 4 el passim.
 
 272 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 estimate possible of the growth of scientific consciousness 
 among the cameralists, the most significant signs would by no 
 means always be found in those writers to whom tradition, 
 as we have it, has awarded the most conspicuous place. Darjes 
 is one of the most notable cases in point. In spite of ihe 
 phrase quoted above, 1 readers of Roscher who do not compare 
 the authors discussed will hardly gain the impression that 
 Darjes marks a distinct stadium in the development of German 
 economic insight. My own judgment is that the Erste Griinde 
 contains the most striking evidence to be found in the came- 
 ralists thus far reviewed, that attention was turning toward 
 economic relations conceived approximately as in Adam 
 Smith's formulation of economic problems. A casual read- 
 ing of Darjes' book would detect in it merely insignificant 
 variations in form and content from the analysis and 
 treatment of previous cameralists. More careful scrutiny 
 discovers such differences of precision and clearness in the 
 perception of relations, that one feels bound to credit Darjes 
 with having advanced a long distance toward the standpoint 
 of positive science. Not only is his style more direct and 
 business-like than that of most of his class, but clear and 
 objective thinking furnishes a substantial content for his 
 language. Nor is progressiveness the only trait for which 
 Darjes is notable. His epitome of the aims and outlook of 
 cameralism is remarkably concise and comprehensive. No 
 single writer in the cameralistic succession gives a brief account 
 of the scope and purpose of their discipline which better 
 reflects the genius of the whole movement. 
 
 Although it may not be immediately apparent that it is 
 more than mere repetition of ideas which had become stock 
 properties among the cameralists, we should leave a serious 
 gap in our outline of the development of the subject, if we 
 failed to present, in a faithful rendering of his own words, 
 
 1 Vide p. 267.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 273 
 
 a digest of Darjes' introduction. He first pays his respects to 
 three objections, already familiar to us, urged by his contempo- 
 raries against Camerd-wissenschaft or Haushaltungskunst, viz. : 
 first, it is useless to try to make a science out of these subjects 
 they must be learned by experience; second, whether worth 
 while or not, a science of these subjects is impossible, because 
 so many contingencies are concerned, which cannot be foreseen, 
 and cannot be brought under general conceptions; third, it 
 is beneath the dignity of scholars to concern themselves with 
 subjects which are matters for peasants and plain citizens. 
 
 In answer to the first objection Darjes forcibly maintains the 
 proposition (2): "All works which men carry on for the advantage 
 of human society become at once, if not perfect, at least less imperfect, 
 if they are ordered and controlled by those who have a science and 
 a philosophical understanding of these works." In support of the 
 proposition he urges, in a spirit much more of the future than of 
 the past: "It is not difficult to prove this theorem, both from reason 
 and from experience. Reason draws this conclusion: a thing is 
 perfect when it is arranged according to its nature and its idea. If 
 then we are not to expect that a work shall be perfected by blind 
 chance, its completion must be governed by those who are skilled 
 enough to investigate the nature and idea of this work, and from 
 this understanding distinctly to conclude what determines the per- 
 fection and imperfection of the work. This is the idea of a science 
 and of a philosophical understanding. Is not this enough to furnish 
 conclusive support for the thesis: A science and philosophical 
 understanding of Cameralwissenschajt, or of Haushaltungskunst, 
 in the general acceptance of that word, is not only necessary, but 
 also profitable?" 1 
 
 To the second objection Darjes replies (4) : "People who say that 
 Cameralwissenschaft is impossible fall back on a prejudice created by 
 those who have proposed untenable conclusions in the name of such 
 
 1 In expanding the argument, Darjes cites, "for the benefit of those 
 who allow themselves to be influenced more by celebrated men than by 
 reasons, .... die vortrefliche Streitschrift . . . . de excolendo studio 
 oeconomico." (By Rohr. Vide Roscher, p. 378.)
 
 274 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 science. The answer must be given: We must distinguish the grounds 
 from inferences drawn from them. The alleged grounds are not to 
 be repudiated completely. In the first place it is true, and I can 
 prove it from my own experience, that in the application of economic 
 science [Sconomischen Wissenschaft] many circumstances emerge 
 which we could not have foreseen and which demand that we must, if 
 not completely abandon, at least in certain particulars modify our 
 plan. Among such circumstances I count the various states of mind 
 and capacities of men, by means of which our project must be carried 
 out; the various sorts of soil, determined partly by their inner con- 
 stitution, partly by their location; the various accidents due to 
 weather conditions, etc. In the second place, it is true that in various 
 writings which purport to treat Haushaltungskunst* scientifically, 
 matters are included which partly contradict experience, and which 
 
 partly, although they may be possible, are impracticable 
 
 This does not prove that a scientific treatment of Haushaltungskunst 
 and the camera! sciences is impossible. On the contrary, the fol- 
 lowing causes compel rejection of such a conclusion: first, no one 
 who acts intelligently rests his judgement of a thing upon the mis- 
 takes of those who represent it. Second, mistakes made by the 
 intelligent deserve special attention. They may show how to 
 discover what has been concealed, and how to make that which was 
 well known more useful and applicable. Who can make use of 
 such mistakes, however, but he who already has a science of such 
 things ? Such mistakes then are no proof of the impossibility of the 
 science now in question. They may rather extend and complete 
 the science. Third, he who possesses no science in the art of 
 management (sic)* must conform to old tradition, and it will be 
 hard for him to adapt himself to unexpected and altered circum- 
 stances. If things go well in such a crisis, it is his good luck; if 
 
 1 The substitution within a few lines of the term, "Haushaltungs- 
 kunst 1 ' for " dconomische Wissenschaft" is strictly typical. The clearest 
 thinkers in the group did not get their objects of attention so definitely 
 related that such terms as these received a precise and invariable content. 
 
 * " Wer in der Haushaltungskunst keine Wissenschaft besitzet." 
 However sane the fundamental thinking of men who expressed them- 
 selves in such fashion, they were outside the threshold of scientific
 
 275 
 
 they go ill, it is his misfortune, and the essence of it is his own stupid- 
 ity. Whoever on the other hand has a philosophical understanding 
 knows how these unexpected circumstances are to be considered, 
 how one may compare them with the nature of the matter, and thus 
 determine the general theory more exactly, and thereby make it 
 more useful. What then is proved by this addition of special cir- 
 cumstances? That a philosophical science of Haushaltungskunst 
 is impossible ? It rather confirms the contrary, and the necessity of 
 such a science. This may then be concluded that without experience 
 a philosophical science of management [eine philosophische Wissen- 
 schafl der Haushaltungskunst} cannot be made sufficiently definite 
 and applicable." Darjes assents to this conclusion, and declares 
 that his book will be composed accordingly. 
 
 To the third objection the answer is substantially this: The 
 people who regard attention to Haushaltungskunst as beneath the 
 dignity of the learned, appear to have a very great soul but a very 
 petty mind. They call themselves learned, but do not know what 
 learning [Gekhrsamkeit] is. They have perhaps forgotten that the 
 true learning is that which proves itself profitable among men and 
 in human society, and that the eminence of this learning depends 
 upon the quantity of this advantage. 1 To put it briefly, a philoso- 
 pher constructs general concepts, he infers from these the qualities 
 of things, and he consequently builds up a correlation of truths which 
 represents the essentials of all particulars which are to be treated in 
 this special division of learning. A philosopher will then become 
 practical if he determines his general understanding more accurately 
 through history and experience, and this is the natural way of build- 
 ing the special sciences. 
 
 Thus one determines one's ideas of what is right and wrong 
 through the customs of peoples and through the decisions of rulers, 
 
 precision, and without special evidence for each particular case, none 
 of their propositions are to be interpreted as carrying the same content 
 which their terms would connote in later, more critical, stages of social 
 theory. If Richter (vide above, p. 267) meant to accuse Darjes of lack of 
 precision in this sense, there is surely no reason for treating him as 
 exceptional. It was the fashion of the time. 
 Is "pragmatism" then a recent discovery I
 
 276 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and one becomes a jurist. The philosopher determines his under- 
 standing of the forces of things through learning how the human 
 body is put together, and through that which he is taught by expe- 
 rience in this connection, and he becomes a physician. Another 
 philosopher determines his understanding of the nature and workings 
 of things through that which experience in affairs [" Beschaftigungen"] 
 teaches him, and he becomes a manager. l Why now is the dignity 
 of the scholar more in question in the last case than in the others ? 
 Is he who constructs a science of preserving and extending the 
 riches of the state and of its inhabitants less useful to the state than 
 he who makes himself skilled in preserving the health of people, 
 or he who learns how to decide what is right and wrong in the 
 quarrels between people? The external welfare of men is related 
 to three factors, to riches, to the enjoyment of rights, and to health. 
 Each who is zealous so to determine his philosophy that it may be 
 useful in promoting any of these purposes (sic) is thereby zealous 
 in promoting the welfare of human society. Is it not a clear proof 
 of confusion and prejudice if one looks upon one of these factors 
 as opposed to the dignity of a scholar ? That which is really beneath 
 the dignity of a scholar is to deal in confused ideas, and to draw 
 conclusions from prejudice. 
 
 But, continues Darjes, I may have misunderstood these men. 
 Perhaps they merely mean that plowing, manuring, brewing, baking, 
 etc., are not proper occupations for scholars. If that is their mean- 
 ing, I have misinterpreted them, but it is their fault. Of course 
 we do not have these practical manipulations \wirthschajtliche 
 Handlhiernngen] in mind when we speak of a philosophical science. 
 
 1 The word is Wirth. Shall we translate It "economist"? If we 
 do, we introduce an ambiguous middle term which falsifies our whole 
 subsequent interpretation of evolution in German theory. One of the 
 constant motives of this book is to set forth enough selections from the 
 mass of evidence to show that English assumptions about the history 
 of German thought have almost completely failed to take account of the 
 actual process. In fact, the conception of the manager of economic 
 relations was much later than this, and with great difficulty differentiated 
 from the conception of the generalizer of economic operations. Con- 
 sequently the arts of economic management, and the science of economic
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 277 
 
 We turn then from these objections to a positive description of 
 cameral science (9). In the first place we must define certain uses 
 of terms. The chief theorem is this: Whoever wishes to count upon 
 a certain annual income, must look out for the source from which the 
 income may flow. The theorem is supported as follows: Our yearly 
 incomes flow either from an established source, or they depend upon 
 chance, and are thus beyond our control. Since it is self-evident 
 that in the latter case we can make no certain calculation upon the 
 yearly revenues, wisdom demands that we look out for a source that 
 is capable of producing our revenues. In a note Darjcs explains 
 that he uses variations of the word "certain" or "assured" in this 
 connection in the general sense in which such terms are employed 
 in the theory of morals and prudence; that is, not complete cer- 
 tainty, but a high degree of probability is the meaning. 
 
 There are two possible sources of annual income (10): (a) 
 skill in the application of our powers, or (6) an already secured 
 "good" which is capable of producing a yearly profit. This latter 
 is called in a special sense the source of annual revenues, the fund 
 [Fond], the capital. 
 
 "I am uncertain," says Darjes, "whether to give precedence to 
 the former or to the latter of these sources, or whether they are 
 equivalent in respect to yearly income (11). Thus A has a capital 
 of 10,000 Thaler and this yields a yearly profit of 500 Thaler. 
 B can earn with his skill 500 Thaler. Accordingly the one has as 
 great an income as the other. For many reasons it might be inferred 
 that in respect to yearly income the two sources are indifferent. 
 
 relations were (also much later than this, and never with quite the same 
 abstractness in Germany as in England) set distinctly over against each 
 other. Between the cameralistic period and the economic period in the 
 nineteenth-century sense, an evolutionary process intervened in which 
 the center of attention was shifted a long distance away from particular 
 operations and details of results toward correspondences of many opera- 
 tions, and formulas of relations between operations and results. German 
 experience before this process was matured has a value of its own, but 
 we have misconceived most of the value, because we have assumed it 
 without proper reckoning with this evolution of purpose by which it 
 must be interpreted.
 
 278 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 On the other hanrl it is urged that a capital is exposed to various 
 vicissitudes. \Vc may lose it by fraud, fire, flood, and other accidents. 
 Our skill on the contrary is secure against these attacks. Persons 
 of the opposite view reply: 'We can earn nothing with our skill 
 if we arc sick; moreover it depends in many ways upon the opinions 
 of other men whether we shall be able to apply our skill. It is 
 not always within our power to rouse the necessary opinions. A 
 capital, however, may show itself effective whether we are sick or 
 well, and whether men are of one opinion or the other.' ' 
 
 Most people would conclude that capital and skill should be 
 combined (12). Darjes expresses his own judgment, however, 
 that between capital and skill the former is the more secure source 
 of revenue, and for these reasons: The greater the number of 
 accidents which may interfere with the sources of our annual revenues, 
 the more easily these accidents may operate, and the more independ- 
 ent they are of our control, the less securely can we reckon upon our 
 yearly income. This uncertainty is greater in the case of skill 
 than of capital. Hence we can more securely count upon a yearly 
 income from capital than from skill. 
 
 In a note (13) the author specifics that he uses the word "cap- 
 ital" not in the narrower sense in which it is applied to a sum of 
 money which we borrow for the sake of making a profit, but in the 
 general sense, of those acquired means which we assume to be 
 permanent, so that they may annually be efficient for our advantage. 
 This use of the word, he says, is usual in all writers on Haushal- 
 tun^skunst whom he has read. "If there is no objection to the term, 
 I prefer to use the word Fond. I have no objection to any freedom 
 which others desire in this respecl." 1 
 
 The foregoing must be applied to the revenues of a prince 
 ($14). It is known from the law of nature that the prince, as a 
 member of civic society, must he distinguished from a prince as 
 such. 1 In the latter character the prince must be considered in his 
 
 1 Uarjcs gives no hint of the writers whom he had in mind in this 
 connection. The probability is that they were French, for I have found 
 in the earlier cameralists no rlireci attempt to define the use of the term. 
 
 This distinction seems to have been assumed by all the cameralists 
 more or less consciously. The most definite previous formulation of it 
 is in chap, vi; vide pp. 143 flf. above.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 279 
 
 relation to the state and the subjects. This gives us a ground for 
 dividing the yearly revenues of the prince into the personal and the 
 princely income. 
 
 The capital or the "Fond" of the princely revenues is the riches 
 of the state and of the subjects (15). 
 
 Whoever attempts to increase his yearly revenues either draws 
 upon his capital, or he seeks to increase his capital and make it more 
 fruitful (16). The former means is unreasonable, because it 
 either defeats the purpose or makes permanent attainment of the 
 purpose impossible. Hence the theorem: The increase of yearly 
 income is unreasonable when it is brought to pass by impairing the 
 capital. 1 
 
 In order that our attempts to increase our revenues may be 
 reasonable they must aim either to increase the accumulated capital 
 or to make it more fruitful (17). 
 
 To appraise the riches of the subjects, we must determine either 
 "the sum of their already accumulated capital, or the amount of 
 their yearly revenues. It, accordingly, we understand that the 
 capital of the princely revenues is the riches of the subjects, these 
 revenues are taken either from the capital, which the subjects have 
 already acquired, or from the yearly revenues of the subjects. If the 
 former method be chfisen, the income of the prince each time impairs 
 the capital of the subjects. This is unreasonable. If one will 
 accordingly follow reason, one must assume in this case that the 
 capital or the Fond of the princely revenues is the yearly income 
 of the subjects. Hence the general rule (19): The first care 
 of him whose task it is to raise the princely revenues, must be 
 to discover how the yearly income of the subjects may be increased. 
 Accordingly a prince is a rich prince when he has rich and skilful 
 subjects. 
 
 In the Middle Ages the word Camera designated the place where 
 the princely revenues were kept (21). Hence it occurred that men 
 
 ' The importance of this argument can hardly be estimated unless 
 it is connected with chap, cviii, in Schroder's Schatz- und Rent-Cammer. 
 We must allow for the persistence in practice, to a certain extent con- 
 fusing theory, of the less mature idea of which Schroder was the spokes- 
 man. Vide above, pp. 135 ff.
 
 280 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 understood by Cameralwesen those ordinances which defined the 
 Wirthschajt of a prince. An orderly Wirthschajt consists of three 
 chief points (sic) viz. : the maintenance, the raising, and the admin- 
 istration of the yearly revenues. This is enough to show why we 
 understand by Cameralivissenschajt that science which shows us 
 the reasonable way of preserving, raising, and applying the 
 annual revenues of a prince. There may be some who disapprove 
 the separation of these purposes, instead of combining them in one 
 expression. To satisfy them we may define Cameralwissenschajt 
 as a science of the reasonable Wirthschajt of a prince. 
 
 A cameralist is one who understands Cameralivissenschajt (22); 
 more particularly, he must be able to solve the following problems: 
 (i) How may an established source of the yearly revenues of a prince 
 be preserved? (2) How may the yearly income of a prince be 
 reasonably raised? (3) How is a reasonable application of the 
 yearly revenues of a prince possible ? 
 
 Cameralistic technique consists then, first: (a) in finding means 
 capable of realizing the riches of the state and of the subjects; 
 (b) in bringing the yearly incomes of the subjects into certain classes, 
 and in determining their amount as accurately as possible (23); 
 second, in finding reasonable ways of raising the annual revenues 
 of the prince, and consequently (sic) of making the subjects richer 
 and more skilful (24). 
 
 Our yearly revenues are either direct workings of nature or the 
 output of the latter is based upon our occupations, which in turn 
 presuppose a certain skill which we have acquired by our efforts 
 (25). These occupations either put nature in a condition to accom- 
 plish that which is possible for her, or out of natural products they 
 produce other things which are useful for the human race. This 
 taken for granted, it is clear that in respect to the second point, a 
 true cameralist must understand: (a) the true qualities of natural 
 objects, and what can be brought to pass by means of them; (b) 
 how nature can be made more skilful in bringing forth what is 
 possible for her; (c) how other things for the use of men may be 
 produced from the yield of nature. And the author adds in a note: 
 "We speak of 'the use of men' not in a moral, but in a political sense, 
 according to which everything is useful for the human race which
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 281 
 
 may bring about its preservation, happiness, and the improvement 
 of welfare. The science with which we are now concerned demands 
 that we should attach such a meaning to the word." 
 
 It is hardly necessary to point out that we have here a seed 
 of the sort of thinking which developed later into pure econom- 
 ics of the nineteenth-century type. The argument continues: 
 
 By these signs we may distinguish between a true cameralist 
 and a despoiler of the country [Landverderber] (26). There arc 
 people devoted to raising the revenues of a prince, who either through 
 wantonness or stupidity are restrained from taking the way which 
 wisdom prescribes, i.e., the way of increasing the yearly rwenucs 
 oj the subjects. They think they have fully discharged the duties 
 of their office if they find schedules which would increase the annual 
 payments of the subjects. These people increase the annual rcven ucs 
 of the prince by weakening the capital. This increase is of no 
 duration. The subjects and the state must eventually grow poorer. 
 This is enough to show that such people do not deserve the name 
 cameralist. They are the plague in the state, and for this reason 
 are called despoilers of the country. 
 
 On the contrary (28), the true cameralist proposes to increase 
 the yearly incomes of the subjects. The subjects must accordingly 
 not only be put in a situation in which it is possible for them to 
 increase their incomes, but their will must lead them to the necessary 
 occupation. This latter demands an awakening of their zeal for 
 labor. The former demands, first, an understanding of the possible 
 increase of revenues; second, possession of those means through 
 which the understanding may be skilfully applied; third, removal 
 of all those circumstances which might obstruct the execution of this 
 purpose. Accordingly, in respect to the second main task, a came- 
 ralist must further understand how the state is to be arranged (sic) in 
 order (a) to rouse in the subjects a zeal for labor; (6) to enable the 
 subjects to gain adequate understanding of the possible increase of 
 incomes; (c) to insure to the subjects adequate provision of means 
 and opportunity skilfully to apply the acquired understanding; 
 (d) to guard the subjects against hindrances to convenient disposal 
 of the things which they have produced.
 
 282 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The reason why a cameralist concerns himself with these points 
 is to raise the annual revenues of a prince (29). This is the principal 
 occupation through which he is distinguished from another scientific 
 manager [H^tr/A]. But this peculiar occupation demands that he 
 shall observe more than one rule. It follows immediately that he 
 must understand (a) how a prince may raise his yearly revenues 
 from the yearly incomes of the subjects, without weakening the 
 source of the same; (b) how, through the reasonable use of the 
 yearly revenues of a prince, the yearly incomes of the subjects may 
 be preserved and increased. 1 
 
 We come then to the third main task, viz., the reasonable use 
 ol the annual revenues of a prince (30). Whoever manages wisely 
 brings his revenues and his outlays into certain classes. He dis- 
 tinguishes the necessary outlays from those that are less necessary. 
 He compares the outlay with the income, and designates for each 
 class of outlays a particular class of revenues. Hence, in respect 
 to this third task, a cameralist must understand (a) how to bring the 
 revenues of a prince into certain classes; (b) how to determine the 
 yearly outlays of a prince, and how these are to be divided in certain 
 orders; (c) how to compare the annual outlays of a prince with his 
 annual revenues, and how a special class of the revenues may be 
 assigned to each sort of outlay. 
 
 It follows that an introduction to Cameralwissenschajt must first 
 outline the operations of nature. Accordingly we have as the first 
 part of the science, Landwirthschajt [Oeconomia rustica] (31). 
 
 A note upon this section offords another instructive sign 
 of the progress of analysis in this field. Darjes says: 
 
 Many who treat of Oeconomie interpret it in a moral sense, since 
 they regard us as in an interdependence of those rules in accordance 
 with which a reasonable Wirthschajt must be arranged, and we have 
 made a brief sketch of these in the philosophical theory of morals. 
 
 1 Throughout this discussion, and in the same connection in other 
 cameralists, there is ambiguity in the words which I have translated 
 "raise the revenue," etc. The meaning is sometimes "increase the 
 revenue," but it is not always clear to the writers themselves which they
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF DARJES 283 
 
 The cameralist presupposes this treatment, and he goes farther. 
 He investigates how these general rules can be applied to the works 
 of nature. For this reason he busies himself with Oeconomie in the 
 physical sense, yet not as a peasant, but as a philosopher. He works 
 out a conception of the workings of nature, of the natural causes 
 of these workings; of completeness in the workings of nature, and 
 of the means of making these causes capable of rendering the work- 
 ings complete. From these conceptions he deduces general theo- 
 rems which serve him as rules in a specific case, and hereby hi- 
 becomes a philosophical Lattd-Wirth, who is able to regulate the 
 Landwirthschajt in a country, and to make it more complete for the 
 profit of the state. 
 
 The passage calls for the observation that the development 
 of thought in Germany at this time, upon subjects afterward 
 differently allotted among nineteenth-century social sciences, 
 was by no means confined to the cameralists. \Ve must remem- 
 ber, while analyzing cameralistic thinking, that this was merely 
 one of the factors in the whole thought-movement of the time, 
 within the range which we may call in general sociological. 
 
 Darjes accordingly classifies the first part of Landicirtli- 
 schaft in three divisions, dealing respectively with (a) the 
 workings of nature and the means of making them more 
 complete; (b) agriculture; (r) cattle raising (32). He calls 
 the second part of Cameralivissenschaft, dealing with those 
 things which may be produced by artificial control of the 
 workings of nature, Stadtwirthschaft or Oeconomia urbana 
 (33). an( l i ts subdivisions deal with (a) Geu'erken in which 
 the forces of nature are employed in producing certain goods, 
 such as beer, alcohol, and starch; (b) Manufacture)! mid 
 Fabriquen, which produce things which nature by herself 
 could not produce (34). 
 
 Darjes makes Policeiwissenschaft the third part of Canie- 
 ralwissenschaft, and he explains: 
 
 The Greeks understand by the word *o\tT<la those laws of a
 
 284 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 state upon which its beauty and well-being rest. 1 The state is 
 accordingly beautiful, and its well-being is assured, if its subjects 
 have flourishing means of subsistence. This is sufficient to show 
 why the name has been given to this third part of Cameralwissen- 
 schajt. This part of the science is concerned with: (o) the popula- 
 tion of the state; (6) establishment of schools and universities; (c) 
 political establishment of the ecclesiastical system: (d) incitement 
 of subjects to labor; (e) arrangements of the state preserving the 
 health of subjects; (/) beauty of the country; (g) promotion of 
 security; (h) care of the poor, etc. (36). 
 
 The cameralist must finally apply the sciences thus described 
 to the Wirthschajt of a prince, as prince (37). This application 
 makes the fourth part of Cameralwissenschajt which has appro- 
 priated the name Cameralwissenschajt in a peculiar sense. Its sub- 
 divisions are: (a) determination of the various sources of the princely 
 revenues; (b) devising of ways and means to draw from these 
 sources; (c) description of the regular application of the annual 
 revenues of a prince.* 
 
 We are not concerned with comparative techique in any 
 part of the cameral sciences, and we may allow this general 
 description to represent Darjes' professional equation in the 
 cameralistic group. 3 
 
 Substantially the same explanation is given more at length, with 
 quotation from Xenophon's Athenian Republic, in Justi's Crundfeste, 
 
 1,5- 
 
 > The author promises to name, as occasion requires, books on the 
 various subjects; but he refers in general to Rohr's Haushallungs- 
 Bililiothek and "Zink," Cameral-Bibliothek. 
 
 3 If the sources had been accessible, I should have added an estimate 
 of Johann Jacob Moser as an index of the spirit of cameralism. I have 
 as yet no means of testing the reliability of Roscher's account (pp. 
 441 .)
 
 CHAPTER XIII 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 
 
 Since we have referred to Seckendorff as the Adam Smith 
 of cameralism, we may carry out the conceit by calling Justi 
 the John Stuart Mill of the movement. In each case, however, 
 the analogy rests upon points of resemblance which would be 
 rated as trivial after critical investigation. It is true, never- 
 theless, that, as a pioneer in reducing an administrative pro- 
 gramme to literary expression, Seckendorff occupies very much 
 the same relative position in the development of cameralistic 
 theory which Smith occupied later in the evolution of an 
 abstract theory of wealth. It is also true that Justi organized 
 the cameralistic technology which had been developed up to 
 his time into a system of theory which correlated the different 
 phases of cameralism, very much as Mill gave to the doctrines 
 of classical economics their most impressive rendering. It 
 would hardly be profitable to pursue farther the quest of like- 
 ness or unlikeness in either case. 
 
 The original plan of this book proposed to present Justi 
 alone as the type of cameralism in general. Further reflection 
 led to change of the plan to the programme here followed. 
 The principal reason was that, if the first intention had been 
 carried out, it could not have forestalled the criticism: "One 
 case cannot justify a generalization. Nothing appears in 
 evidence to prove that Justi was not an exception rather than a 
 type." Since the literature by which this objection is removed 
 is so inaccessible to Americans, mere assertion that it exists,' 
 or even copious references to particular passages, would fail 
 adequately to present the cameralists to English readers. 
 The alternative chosen was an attempt to survey the whole 
 cameralistic period and to divide attention in proportion to the 
 relative importance of the principal writers. 
 
 285
 
 286 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The most convincing biographical study of Justi has been 
 made by Frensdorff. We follow his conclusions in reducing 
 to the lowest terms such details as are necessary for our pur- 
 pose. 1 
 
 Johann Heinrich Gottlob von Justi, son of the Gerichthalter 
 Georg Heinrich Justi, was baptized December 28, 1717, in the 
 evangelisch-lutherische Kirche at Briicken an der Helme 
 (Kegierungsbezirk Merseburg, Kreis Sangerhausen) . The story 
 that he was born on Christmas eve of that year is thus not 
 improbable. Of his earlier years little is known. The traces 
 of his university career are rather dubious. The most reliable 
 of them are at Wittenberg. Partly within his student period 
 he had some army experience. "Although Justi's military 
 period was no longer than his academic career, it left traces 
 which may be observed for a long time in his writings. He 
 often made use of observations collected (1741-42) during 
 the war of the Austrian succession" (Frensdorff, p. 363). 
 Justi credited the lieutenant-colonel of the regiment to which 
 
 1 F. Frensdorff, "Ueber das Leben und die Schriften des Natio- 
 nalokonomen J. H. G. von Justi," Nachrichten von der Konigl. Gesell- 
 schaft der Wissenschaft zu Gottingen. Philologisch-historische Klasse, 
 aus dcm Jahre 1903. Gottingen, 1904. (Pp. 354-503-) It would be 
 an unfortunate misdirection of energy to enter upon examination of 
 Justi's career under the guidance of the previous accounts of his life: 
 e. g., the article in All. d. Bib.; Roscher's essay, in Archivfiir die Sdch- 
 sische Geschichte, 6ter Bd., pp. 77 ff.; the digest of that essay, Gesch., 
 pp. 444 ff., etc. My first loss of confidence in the reliability of Roscher 
 in matters of detail came from discovery of numerous inaccuracies in his 
 biography of Justi. These related to items on which the text of the author's 
 works is final. Frensdorff has used sources of other kinds, not accessible 
 in this country. He has not only discovered Roscher's mistakes in cases 
 of the type just referred to, but he has proved that previous biographical 
 sketches of Justi were largely fabulous. An earlier monograph by the 
 same author should be consulted: Festschrift tur Feier des hundert- 
 funfzigjahrigen Bestehens der Kdnigl. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften 
 zu Gottingen. "Bcitrage zur Gelehrtengeschichte Gottingens" (Berlin 
 1901), pp. 495 ff-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 287 
 
 he belonged with turning the course of his life to legal and scien- 
 tific pursuits. 
 
 Justi's first publication was Die Dichterinsel (1745), a 
 combination of Utopia and satire feebly resembling Swift's 
 Gulliver. At about the same time, Justi began, to publish in 
 Dresden a monthly magazine, under the title Ergetzungen der 
 verniinftigen Seele aus der Sittenlehre und der Gelehrsamkeit 
 tiberhaupt. During the remainder of his life Justi seemed 
 never content unless he was addressing the public through one 
 or more journals of various types. 
 
 In the course of the year 1747, Justi removed to Sanger- 
 hausen, where his name is known first as Advocai, then as 
 Rath der verwittweten Herzogin von Sachsen-Eisenach. 
 Although the term Witthumsrath, used in flippant allusion 
 to this incident, seems to indicate that the sonorous title was 
 not everywhere taken seriously, on the other hand, perhaps 
 without exceeding the privileges which at the time went with 
 any title whatsoever, Justi evidently regarded the designation 
 obtained from the Herzogin as an available asset, and he 
 made good use of it as a help to something better. 
 
 Justi's next step toward distinction was the composition of 
 a monograph on a subject calling for review of Leibnitz' theory 
 of monads. The subject was proposed for a prize contest by 
 the Berliner Akademie der Wissenschaften, and the prize was 
 awarded to Justi in 1747 (Frensdorff, p. 371). 
 
 Presently Justi changed his residence to Vienna. Of this 
 episode Frensdorff says (p. 375): 
 
 The period of his stay here is the most important of his life. 
 From this point dates the turning of his mind to the science which 
 was to give him his place in history. Up to this time he had traversed 
 many fields with his facile journalistic pen polite literature, phi- 
 losophy, history, jurisprudence, etc. He now began to cultivate the 
 economic sciences. His removal to Vienna had much to do with 
 this transition.
 
 288 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Justi arrived in Austria at precisely the time when Maria Theresia 
 had put her improving hand upon all departments of the inner life 
 of the state. The system of taxation and the organization of civic 
 functionaries were reconstructed, so that the government was 
 independent of the estates, and a central control of internal affairs 
 was possible. These reforms reached their most definite expressions 
 through Haugwitz, head of the political and cameral administration. 
 .... The reforms which he introduced in general administration 
 were also beneficial to the educational institutions founded at the 
 same period. Both the Theresianum, founded in 1746, and the 
 Savoysche Ritterakademie proposed to furnish a training for aristo- 
 cratic youths which would provide the state with more competent 
 servants both civil and military. 
 
 No sufficient explanation of Justi's initial success at Vienna 
 has been found. At all events, he was appointed, August 31, 
 1 750, to the "Professura eloquentiae germanicae" in theCollegium 
 Theresianum. In connection with this professorship, Justi 
 was instructed to offer lectures entitled "collegium oeconomico- 
 proi-ineiale," which included "Finanzen, Handel, Contribu- 
 tionale (Steuerwesen) und Manufartunt'esen." The immediate 
 occasion for this course, which was incidental to a larger 
 educational porgramme, was similar to that which had led 
 the king of Prussia, a quarter-century earlier, to establish the 
 cameralistic chairs at Halle and Frankfurt a. O., viz., the 
 desire to supplement the traditional courses at the university 
 by instruction which would be direct preparation for official 
 service. 
 
 The document which marks Justi's entrance into the 
 cameralistic series was in the nature of a report to the empress 
 (1752), containing a prospectus of cameralistic study. 1 
 
 At particular command of the empress, Justi was com- 
 missioned to deal specifically with the subject of mining. 
 
 1 Auj hochsten Bejehl an Sr. Rom. Kaiserl. und zu Ungarn und 
 Kuhmen Konigl. Majestdt erstaltctes alleruntcrtanigstes Cutachten von 
 dem vernunjtigen Zusammenhange und praktischen Vortrage aller Oeko-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 289 
 
 Thereupon he gave his attention not merely to the theory, but 
 to the actual development of the mineral resources of Austria. 
 This particular element in his activities may have had much 
 or little to do with the brevity of his stay in Vienna. At all 
 events his connection with mining administration proved to be 
 his final undoing. For reasons which are as confused as the 
 explanations of his coming to Austria, among them friction 
 with the ecclesiastical authorities, Justi returned to North 
 Germany in 1753. Stieda thinks (p. 33) that he did not even 
 begin his lectures on cameralistics in Vienna. Frensdorff, on 
 the contrary, is quite sure he was the first teacher of the eco- 
 nomic sciences in Austria (p. 389). Unless we presume that 
 Justi had forgotten the facts in less than eight years, or that 
 he deliberately lied, his own assertion, which Stieda seems 
 to have overlooked, is decisive. 1 
 
 Light is thrown on Justi's reasons for leaving Vienna by 
 his hints that the Jesuits were hostile to him, and had spies at 
 the doors and windows of his lecture-room. 8 He also says 
 that the rector told him flatly, "There is no need of Cameral- 
 wissenschaft und Policei; Austria has been prosperous a long 
 time without anything of that sort. If people are only pious 
 and say their prayers, God will bless the country without 
 such stuff."* 
 
 Reviewing the Austrian passage in Justi's career, Frens- 
 dorff says (p. 389) : 
 
 nomischen und Kameralwissenschaflen .... von Herrn Hofrat u. Pro- 
 fessor J. H. G. edlen Herrn v. Justi. Herausgegeben von Dr. E. VV., 
 Leipzig, 1754. According to Stieda's description (p. 32) this docu- 
 ment contains virtually the same programme afterward proposed in the 
 Preface of Staatswirthschaft. In the latter form it will be discussed 
 below. 
 
 It is quoted below; vide p. 336, note. 
 
 3 Staatswirthschaft, I, 119. It does not seem to me that Frensdorff 
 has given due weight to this evidence. 
 
 *Grundriss einer guten Regierung, p. 324.
 
 290 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Brief as was his stay in Austria, the time was not lost for Austria 
 nor for himself. As one line leads back from him to the most 
 eminent representatives of Volksivirthschaft under Kaiser Leopold I, 
 so another connects him with those who followed. Justi continued 
 
 the work of Becher, Schroder, and Hornick Each had at 
 
 heart the question how Austria might be made more prosperous by 
 means of Landesoekonomie or Volkswirthschajt. They solve the 
 question according to the principles of the mercantilists; and the 
 difference between them and Justi is his more abstract procedure. 
 He is not concerned in the first instance with a particular country. 
 He tries to lay down principles of universal validity, and while they 
 handle their material in a popular way, Justi puts his in the form of 
 a dogmatic and schematically complete exposition. 1 
 
 Justi left Austria during the year 1753. On New Year, 
 1754 at Mansfeld, he signed the prospectus of a new monthly 
 journal; 2 he appears to have been for a short time in Leipzig, 
 but in 1755 he appears in Gottingen. The reasons which 
 account for these movements remain unexplained. In Got- 
 tingen Justi combined the activities of Polizeidirector with the 
 academic function of lecturer on cameralistic subjects. 3 In 
 June, 1757, however, Justi left Gottingen. Again the reasons 
 are largely matters of conjecture. The action for divorce 
 brought by his wife doubtless had something to do with the 
 brevity of his stay. He next appears (1757) as Bergrath in 
 the service of the king of Denmark. This Danish episode 
 lasted less than a year. He moved to Altona, then to Hamburg, 
 where he made the acquaintance of the Prussian resident von 
 Hecht. From this time to the end of the Seven Years' War, 
 Justi did a great deal of political writing. He affected a 
 
 1 This estimate must be considerably qualified, especially as to the 
 contrast of purpose between Justi and his predecessors. I note my 
 partial dissent, however, without further comment. 
 
 * Neiu WahrheHen turn Vortheil der Naturkunde und des gesell- 
 schaf (lichen Lcbtns der Menschen. Vide Frensdorff, p. 391. 
 
 sFrensdorff, p. 393.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 291 
 
 manner which purported to set the issues of the day in the light 
 of a comprehensive political philosophy. 
 
 Justi appears to have remained in Hamburg until some 
 time between 1758 and 1760. From the spring of the latter 
 year 1 his books are dated at Berlin, and the title, "Kgl. Gross- 
 britannischer Bergrath" disappears. 
 
 Justi's occupations and status in Berlin are extremely 
 uncertain up to 1765, when he was appointed Berghauptmann. 
 From this vantage ground he secured the notice and favor of the 
 king, who indorsed rather extensive plans for the development 
 of mines. On the other hand Justi seems almost immediately 
 to have made enemies. These were partly personal creditors, 
 partly bidders for the opportunities which his office controlled 
 or influenced. Presently more serious trouble came. Ques- 
 tions were raised about Justi's financial administration. The 
 outcome was judicial investigation which resulted in his 
 arrest and confinement at Kiistrin (February 9, i768). 2 At 
 the time of his death, probably from apoplexy, he was carrying 
 on the legal fight for release. He maintained that the whole 
 case was trumped up by enemies, and according to his daugh- 
 ter's statement, he expressed his confidence, the evening before 
 his death, that the process would result in his favor. Although 
 it is possible, and even probable, that in the whole matter 
 Justi was "more sinned against than sinning," we must admit 
 that the incident at best deepens the impression left by the 
 most favorable version of his earlier life. With all his intel- 
 lectual versatility, Justi never shows a sign of moral strength. 
 
 Returning to our main interest, viz., the cameralists as 
 authors, not as individuals, we are obliged to disentangle 
 
 * Roscher says "from 1762" (p. 444); but the Vorrede of Vol. I 
 of the Grundfeste is dated "Berlin den 25. April 1760;" of Vol. II, "Ber- 
 lin, den 6. April 1761;" while the Vorrede of Natur und Wesen der 
 Staaten is subscribed, "Geschrieben zur Leipziger Michaelis-Messe 1759-" 
 
 * Vide Frensdorff, pp. 449 ff.
 
 292 THK CAMERALISTS 
 
 Justi's camcralistic works from a mass of miscellaneous writ- 
 ings. Mcusel's Lexikon schedules forty-eight works which 
 he published between 1741 and 1771, many of them in several 
 volumes. They fall into six groups: (i) aesthetics and belles 
 lettres; (2) philosophy; (3) natural science; (4) history; 
 (5) law and statesmanship; (6) camcralistics in the wide sense. 
 
 Most of his books were dashed off with genial carelessness, and 
 with notorious disregard of the literature of the subjects treated. 
 He despised all science which could not be turned to tangible uses, 
 philology, mathematics, astronomy; in the latter case showing his 
 ignorance by sneering at the inaccuracy of astronomical opinions. 1 
 Surh reaction against earlier one-sidedncss probably had a certain 
 value. At the same time it became itself very plain onc-sidedness 
 when, for example, Justi admitted the right to kill in self-defense, 
 but merely to preserve one's own life, not however "to preserve those 
 chimeras and absurd treasures which we have constructed out of 
 honor, and property, which is probably not in accordance with the 
 will of God, or out of female virtue, and perhaps even of virginity" 2 
 (Roscher in Archiv }ur Sachs. Ceschichte, Bd. 6, pp. 77 fT.). 
 
 One might read Justi's cameralistic books a long time 
 without happening upon express recognition that anything 
 worth notice had previously been written on the subjects 
 treated. Tardy and grudging references to other authors 
 occur, but they do not by any means give due credit for Justi's 
 drafts upon his predecessors. He succeeded in eclipsing 
 them partly because he had rather unusually acute political 
 instincts. Besides this, he was a skilled organizer of literary 
 material. If he was not a plagiarist in the strict sense, he was 
 a [>ersistent absorber and purveyor of other people's ideas 
 as his own. While this fact foredooms certain tendencies to 
 idealize Justi as an originator in the social sciences, it indicates 
 his value as a summarizer of previous social science. Justi 
 
 1 Slaatsu'irthschaft, I, xxiv. 
 
 Natur und Weaen der Staaten, pp. 176 S.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 293 
 
 repeatedly excuses his omission to cite other writers, on the 
 ground that such references merely serve to parade an author's 
 learning. 1 He has a euphemistic substitute for frank con- 
 fession in the following passage:* 
 
 I have never owned a book which I have not read entirely 
 through, and my memory was so strong that in case of all notable 
 passages I not only knew the volume in which they were to be found, 
 but also the chapter and usually the page. Indeed, I have often 
 introduced into my writings from memory passages many lines 
 long without again referring to the book. This extraordinary 
 memory has been growing weaker for several years, and I am learn- 
 ing the value of good tables of contents. 
 
 Our plan requires a review of the most important of Justi's 
 cameralistic books, as nearly as possible in their chronological 
 order. We shall find at least the elements of all his subse- 
 quent books in the Staatswirthschaft.* 
 
 We must give more than passing notice to the strategic 
 force of the expression on the title-page, "which are requisite 
 for the government of a country." The phrase at once puts 
 to the front the purpose and viewpoint of cameralism, viz.: 
 
 1 E. g., in the last paragraph of the V or rede of the first edition of 
 Grundsaize der Policeyvrissenschaft. 
 
 * Vorrede to the "zwoten Ausgabe" of the book just cited, 1759. 
 
 3 Johann Heinrich Gottlobs von Justi Staatswirthschaft, oder sys- 
 temaiische Abhandlung oiler Oekonomischen und Cameral-Wissenschaften, 
 die zur Regierung eines Landes erfodert werden. In zweien Theilen 
 ausgefertigt. Erster Theil, Welcher die Lehre von Erhaltung und Ver- 
 mthrung des Vermogens des Staats, und mithin die Staatskunst, die 
 Policey- und Commercien-Wissenschaft nebst der Haushaltungskunst 
 in sick begreifft. Zweyte stark vermehrte Auflage 1758. 
 
 The title-page of the second part of the book, bound in the same 
 volume, is varied as follows: Zweyter Theil, Welcher die Lehre von dem 
 verniinftigen Gebrauche des Vermogens des Staates, und mithin die eigent- 
 liche Cameral- oder Finanz-Wissenschaft in sich begreifft. Nebst einem 
 vollstdndigen Register iiber beyde Theile. 
 
 I have seen Professor E. R. A. Seligman's copy of the same edition. 
 It is bound in two volumes, but the binding is evidently much later than 
 that of the copy which I chiefly used.
 
 294 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 first, the paramount state whether the princelingdom of 
 Reuss or the kingdom of Prussia, is immaterial a dominant 
 conception of what belongs to thrifty state-housekeeping, and 
 Staatswirthschaft as the tradition of the technique which 
 accomplishes that species of thrift. 
 
 We must set it down as a fixed fact that this is an element 
 in the historical development of German social science, and of 
 German government, which accounts for certain of the typical 
 contrasts with English theoretical and practical tradition. 
 
 In order to obtain a general conception of the range of 
 Staatswirthschaft as Justi and others taught it, and as most of 
 the higher civic officials in Germany learned it, till a more 
 modern organization of science was brought into vogue by 
 Rau (Lehrbuch der politischen Oekonomic, 1826, etc.), the 
 Table of Contents should be examined. 
 
 The first impression which the book would make upon 
 any fairly intelligent person, who happened upon it with no 
 previous hints about its contents, would be that it was intended 
 as a digest of knowledge useful for civic functionaries. The 
 primary thesis which the book and all the other writings of 
 Justi on related subjects justify is that social problems pre- 
 sented themselves to the author principally as problems of 
 civic administration. That is, the autonomous, patriarchal 
 petty state was the ever-present working assumption. Justi 
 is thus strictly in line with cameralistic tradition as we have 
 made it out from the beginning. 
 
 Since Justi's work is in effect a recapitulation of cameralism, 
 we are justified in reproducing rather fully his own review of 
 the state of cameralistic knowledge at the time of writing. 
 The Preface to the first edition of Staatswirthschaft clears the 
 ground in this way: 
 
 The economic and cameral sciences are very old in the world. 
 The application of them occurred indeed the moment property was 
 introduced among men, and republics came into existence.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 295 
 
 This delightfully unconstrained style of historical free- 
 lancing at once illustrates Justi's irresponsibility to authorities. 
 Yet it would be unfair to treat him as exceptional in making 
 hearsay a sufficient basis for historical generalization. Europe 
 was still in its age of fable. It was half a century after the 
 writing of this preface when Niebuhr's first volume on the 
 history of Rome marked the dawn of the era of historical 
 criticism. If Justi felt at liberty to spin historical formulas 
 out of his imagination, he was exercising a liberty which was at 
 his time under no serious ban of disrepute. 
 
 It is important to notice that the word "republic" in Justi's 
 vocabulary is not an anachronism. It is merely the unprecise 
 term in frequent use at the time to denote any civic society. 1 
 
 Justi goes on to say that: 
 
 People have always been obliged to observe appropriate rules 
 in exploiting their estates, and rulers of republics have found them- 
 selves constrained to adopt expedient measures both for organizing 
 the state and for thrift and order in the same. This is the essential 
 in the economic and cameral sciences. 
 
 Then Justi cites Aristotle as evidence that theoretical 
 treatment of these subjects was very ancient, and we need not 
 challenge this phase of his retrospect. He proceeds to bemoan 
 the neglect of this branch of science: 
 
 All other sciences have workers in superabundance. To these 
 alone have they given little thought, and if we had not been able 
 to collect certain practical observations from people active in these 
 pursuits, but little devoted to learning, these sciences would be 
 everywhere barren and empty. There has been scarcely a thought 
 of teaching these sciences in the universities, and, although teachers 
 
 1 Vide Index, title "Republic." Justi applies the designation to the 
 beginnings of civic society, apparently making the origins of the institu- 
 tion of property and of " republics" simultaneous, if not identical. With 
 Justi, as with his predecessors, the word "republic" was a purely generic 
 term of the most general application to all sorts of civic societies in which 
 the relations of meum and tuum had begun to receive social sanction.
 
 296 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in excess have been provided for all other branches of knowledge, 
 centuries elapsed after the founding of these institutions before it 
 was found necessary to devote a single chair to these sciences. 
 
 From the following passage it is probable that Justi used 
 the same sources which we have quoted above (viz., the books 
 of Gasser and Dithmar, and possibly the tract of Ludewig); 
 but his readers would find no hint of these means of verifying 
 his statements. For the contents of the passage in addition to 
 the data given above, Justi offers no evidence beyond his own 
 assertion. He says (Preface, p. xii): 
 
 It was thirty years ago when the former king of Prussia, who was 
 himself a really great manager [H'tr/A], who appraised learning 
 wholly according to its use to the state, and consequently had no 
 very high ideas of the scholars of his time, set the example of estab- 
 lishing in his universities chairs devoted to the economic sciences. 
 This occurred in fact in Frankfurt a. O. and in Halle. That at 
 Halle remains; and in this case the king was so fortunate in his 
 first appointment as to find as an incumbent Privy Counselor 
 Gasser, who really had much talent for these sciences, although he 
 did not think with enough order and system to develop them thor- 
 oughly. The king thought so much of his teaching that a Prussian 
 subject stood little chance of promotion if he could not show a 
 certificate from Gasser that he had regularly attended the tatter's 
 lectures. This example of the Prussian king at last drew the atten- 
 tion of other states to the advantage of economic professorships. 
 Similar chairs were accordingly founded in Upsala, in Gottingen, 
 and some other German universities, as well as in some academies, 
 as in Vienna and Braunschweig.' 
 
 Justi expresses himself as highly dissatisfied with the results 
 of this movement. In the first place, cameralistic chairs were 
 still too rare. In the second place, when they exist they treat 
 
 1 While Justi is literally correct about the foundation of cameralistic 
 professorships, he overstates the neglect of these subjects. They were 
 treated more or less formally, oftener, however, on some other than the 
 cameralistic basis, by many men in Germany: e. g., Gerhard, as early 
 as 1713 at Jena. For further details vide Stieda (vide p. 206 above).
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 297 
 
 "only Haushaltungskunst und Landwirthschaft with less 
 incidentally about Policey, and the Regalien." That is, to 
 express the idea in today's idiom, Justi regretted that the 
 emphasis had been placed on the operative rather than on the 
 managerial side of gainful occupations. He supported this 
 judgment by referring to the textbooks which Gasser and 
 Dithmar had published in connection with their lectures. 1 
 These are the only text-writers whom Justi mentions here by 
 name, although the vague reference to "others" shows that 
 he knew more than he cared to tell or was willing to make 
 exact, about path-breakers in the subject. Enlarging upon the 
 criticism just quoted, Justi declares (p. xiii) that it is mere 
 patchwork to deal with these fractions of Cameralwissenschaft 
 and to neglect the rest. 
 
 Indeed [he exclaims], thanks to such samples, the statesmen and 
 practical cameralists have the idea that in these sciences no orderly 
 system of theory is possible, and this opinion has been uttered to 
 my face. On the other hand, the students find little that is impor- 
 tant in such books, but discover that they have to do mostly with 
 rural economy, which they expect to learn by experience, if they 
 have occasion for it. They therefore look upon these sciences very 
 coldly, and conclude that they can get along without learning them. 
 
 Justi adds that another obstacle in the way of these sciences 
 is found in the teachers themselves. They are apt to be people 
 not trained for university careers, and taken from the admin- 
 istrative service. They accordingly are seldom good instruct- 
 
 1 Vide above, pp. 207 and 223. He mentions Gasser and Dith- 
 mar again (Preface, p. xliii), where he also refers to "a new came- 
 ralist" (vide p. 309 below). On p. viii of the Preface to the second edi- 
 tion it appears that some reviewers had compared the first edition 
 unfavorably with Zincke's Grundriss. Unless the latter writer was the 
 "new cameralist" referred to (and such a phrase would have been both 
 inaccurate and insolent), I have no surmise about the man intended. 
 Justi takes up the matter again in the Preface of the second edition of 
 Grundsatzc der Policeywissenschaft (vide below, pp. 437, 438).
 
 298 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ors (p. xiv). On the other hand, the trained scholars of the 
 academic type who are charged with teaching these subjects 
 do not know enough about them in detail to make their instruc- 
 tion valuable. 
 
 At the same time Justi finds a brighter tint for the picture. 
 He thinks there is no doubt of the superiority of the Prussian 
 bureaus to those of other states, and some of this excellence is 
 due to the teachings of Gasser and his colleagues. The estab- 
 lishment of cameralistic chairs had also been accompanied 
 by more publication on the subject, and in most parts of Ger- 
 many there had been an evident increase of interest in camera- 
 listic science. The same appeared to be true elsewhere, notably 
 in Sweden, and Justi credits Sweden with more progress than 
 Germany in this field. He draws the inference that progress 
 in these respects would everywhere have been still more credit- 
 able if instruction in the universities had been more adequate, 
 and the remainder of the Preface is devoted to expansion of 
 this proposition. 
 
 Justi goes about his task of establishing the claims of 
 cameralistic science in a way that is quite in accord with the 
 methodology of the time. At first glance it seems not unlike 
 the general argument of Adam Smith. It is impossible, how- 
 ever, not to infer that the preliminary moral part of the argu- 
 ment sits more lightly upon Justi than upon Smith. In the 
 case of the former, it has rather the effect of an argufnentum 
 ad hominem addressed to people whose conventional views 
 were inhospitable toward his subject. It attempts to show 
 on their own grounds that cameralism has valid claims. He 
 begins with the proposition that there are different kinds of 
 knowledge appropriate to the different uses of life (p. xvi). 
 If we refuse to cultivate the kinds of knowledge necessary for 
 the fulfilment of our diverse duties, it is just as though we had 
 deliberately declined to perform the duties themselves (p. 
 xvii). Included in this necessary knowledge are "natural and
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 299 
 
 revealed religion, morals, or the theory of virtue, and the science 
 of civic law, which shows us our duties in our various stations." 
 
 Dividing knowledge into the "necessary," the "useful," 
 and the "attractive," Justi urges that the "economic and 
 cameral sciences" should be recognized as belonging in the 
 first class. "They give us precisely that insight which we most 
 need for the purposes of civic and social life (p. xix). The 
 government of republics cannot endure without them, and there 
 is no social institution or class or mode of life which could 
 do without them entirely." 
 
 Advancing to another premise of his argument, Justi 
 predicates of the universities as follows: 
 
 It will be enough if we attend to their ultimate purpose. This, 
 in so far as they are public foundations of the state, can be no other 
 than that of affording to youth properly prepared in the lower schools 
 adequate instruction in all intelligence and science which will be 
 needful for them, in order that they may some time, as servants of the 
 state and upright citizens, render useful services to the common- 
 wealth, 1 and be in a position fully to discharge their duties (p. xx). 
 It follows from the foregoing reference to the ultimate purpose of 
 the universities that it should be one of their principal efforts to teach 
 the economic and cameral sciences (p. xxi). 
 
 The argument is then developed by going into detail in expand- 
 ing the proposition: 
 
 There are very few positions of responsibility in the state in 
 which expertness in the economic and the cameral sciences would 
 not be the chief matter, if the duties of the position were fulfilled 
 and good service to the state performed (p. xxii). 
 
 We get something like a direct view into the state of thought 
 at the time by finding that it was necessary for Justi to argue 
 
 1 I give under protest this rendering to the phrase, "dcm gemeimn 
 Wesen." It has no exact equivalent in our idiom, and must certainly 
 not be understood to carry the associations which we attach to the 
 expression that must serve us as translation.
 
 300 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 against the idea that, while instruction was necessary in law 
 and medicine, civil servants could pick up casually all that 
 they needed to know about economics and cameralistics. 
 While we have a precise parallel with this situation in many 
 universities today in the case of sociology, the academic con- 
 ditions against which Justi argued have been transferred, in 
 England and America more than in Germany, to business and 
 government. That is, the universities are now eager to teach 
 these subjects, but the practical men are skeptical whether 
 the universities can teach anything about them which cannot 
 be learned better in practical life. 1 
 
 Justi's estimate of the part played by knowledge of the 
 Roman law in German civilization, and as substitute for more 
 specific cameralistics, is also instructive. He says (p. xxv): 
 
 The recovery of the Roman law, and provision for teaching it, 
 was the first step which Providence allowed us to take, in leading 
 us out of the thick fog of ignorance which everywhere surrounded 
 us. We therefore owe deep gratitude to Roman legal learning, and 
 it is remarkable that for several centuries it was believed that all 
 human wisdom was to be found in the body of Roman laws. To 
 knowledge of these laws it was chiefly due that we became intelligent 
 enough to begin the extermination of barbarism. Today's fortunate 
 organization of states according to the fundamental principles of 
 economic and cameral science is by no means old. Less than two 
 hundred years ago there was no knowledge of a cameral system in 
 Germany, and at that time men could scarcely have believed that 
 the prosperity [Aujnahme*\ of the trading classes, the encouragement 
 of the classes producing raw material, and the administration of the 
 revenues of the sovereign could occur in accordance with permanent 
 principles and methods. Consequently nothing was known of 
 cameralists. The most eminent magistrates [J ' ustizbcdicnten] of the 
 prince at the same time managed his revenues; or the matter was 
 
 1 Vide Spencer's argument in The Study of Sociology. 
 * This is one of the ambiguous terms which a literal translation 
 would not fairly render.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 301 
 
 held to be of such slight account that the consort of the prince took 
 charge of it, just as today the spouse of a well-to-do private person 
 manages his household. The good arrangements in the police and 
 other bureaus, which we now find in most states, came only gradually 
 into being, perhaps more through accidental suggestions than in 
 pursuance of coherent principles of the governmental sciences. 
 The organization of states is itself perhaps not yet brought to per- 
 fection, and perhaps it is only a beneficent fruit of our enlightened 
 century that we at last perceive that the great housekeeping [Wirth- 
 schaft] of the state, in all its economic, police, and cameral institu- 
 tions, rests upon coherent principles, which are derived from the 
 nature of republics, and incidentally are veritable sciences. 
 
 Justi at once reiterates the moral that these sciences are 
 now worked out in somewhat complete shape, and conse- 
 quently it would be a dereliction in high places if there should 
 be further delay in making them the subject-matter of univer- 
 sity instruction (p. xxvii). 
 
 One of the passages in the Preface indicates that Justi's 
 idea of cameral science pictured it as a social polytechnic, and 
 the cameralist as an all-around expert in this complex science 
 of government. Thus he says (p. xxxi): 
 
 We may admit, to be sure, that a merely practical cameralist, 
 if he has good natural intelligence, and industriously makes himself 
 acquainted with the institutions of other lands, may become a good 
 particular cameralist (sic) in this or that branch of civic adminis- 
 tration, but he can never become a good universal cameralist (sic). 
 From lack of coherent basic principles he will never walk with secure 
 steps. At every unusual occurrence he will waver and seize upon 
 questionable decisions. If he thinks he has introduced important 
 improvements in this part of the administrative organization, he 
 will at last come to the perception that he has thereby caused dis- 
 proportionate injury in another part of the great housekeeping of the 
 state, because he did not sufficiently understand the correlation of 
 this great system and the influence which all circumstances of the 
 entire system have upon one another. What can however be more 
 indispensable to a state than perfect universal cameralists? The
 
 302 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 welfare of the state rests heavily upon them. Most lands appear 
 in this respect to be seriously lacking. 1 
 
 Justi frankly puts the sciences of civic administration, as 
 professed technologies, in direct antithesis with "the other 
 sciences which merely serve to enlarge the human under- 
 standing" (p. xxxiii). He urges, however, against the con- 
 trary opinion of some scholars, that the former would not 
 interfere with the latter, but on the contrary, "the more we 
 discharge and respect our duties to the state, the more shall 
 we be inclined to improve our understanding." 
 
 But Justi is not content with arguing that the universities 
 should undertake instruction in cameralistics. His argument 
 is so cogent in his own mind that it carries him much beyond 
 his premises. Apparently inflamed by a zeal that is kindled 
 in the course of his discussion, he demands still wider scope 
 for his science. He concludes the first branch of his arugment 
 as follows (p. xxxiv) : 
 
 In my opinion I have sufficiently shown that it is necessary to 
 teach the economic and camcralistic sciences in the universities. 
 This theorem has the corollary that we must prepare youth for such 
 instruction in the lower schools, and there can be no doubt that every 
 new academic citizen* should bring with him at least ^the general 
 theories of Haushaltungskunst 3 as the basis for all the sciences 
 which are necessary for promoting the great housekeeping of the 
 state. Indeed, in the very meanest schools, in which the children 
 of the lowest rabble arc instructed, at least the most comprehensible 
 precepts should be taught, and the duties which they at some time, 
 as citi7,cns and inhabitants of the state, and as fathers of families, 
 will have to observe. In the case of institutions of this class, we 
 seem never to have thought that it is not less needful to educate good 
 and useful citizens than good Christians. 
 
 1 The rest of the paragraph (p. xxxii) reads like a memorandum for 
 Spencer's The Sins of Legislators. 
 
 3 1. e., every matriculant at the university. 
 
 s Without trying to make too much of it, we may notice that he uses 
 the art rather than the science concept.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 303 
 
 Justi then passes to a second consideration, viz., the proper 
 organization of cameralistic instruction. His proposal is 
 worth quoting at length (pp. xxxv ff .) : 
 
 It will hardly be supposed that I should regard a single man as 
 sufficient to teach the economic and cameralistic sciences in univer- 
 sities. At least two teachers should he appointed, of whom the one 
 should deal chiefly with police and commercial science, the other 
 with economics and finance. For if these sciences arc to be taught 
 completely, fundamentally and to real purpose, each of these profes- 
 sors must have time to treat of this or that portion of his sciences 
 in detail in separate courses of lectures, in order that each may have 
 opportunity to make himself proficient in that branch to which he 
 proposes to devote himself. Some will want to make a career in the 
 manufacturing system, some in the bureaus of taxation and revenue, 
 some in forestry, or the forestry bureau, and all must have oppor- 
 tunity to get detailed instruction in the selected specialty. 
 
 The traditional professorship of politics in the universities should 
 be so filled that future ambassadors and ministers could profitably 
 hear the occupant discuss statesmanship, and so that the doctrines 
 taught would not seem ridiculous to actual ministers and statesmen. 
 The professor of chemistry should be of such a character that he- 
 would be prepared to teach Probicr- und Schmelzkunst, and should 
 not give his time merely to the theory of compounding medicines, 
 which any apothecary's boy can learn without trouble. Likewise, 
 the teacher of mechanics should be prepared to explain the machinery 
 of mining operation and construction, and the professor of natural 
 science [Naturkunde] should be able to impart adequate knowledge 
 of ores and of fossils in general. These six professors, to whom we 
 might add the professor of civil and military engineering [burger- 
 lichen und Kriegsbaukunst], if talented, experienced, and expert men 
 were chosen, would compose a faculty that would Ix? uncommonly 
 salutary for civic life. It would amount to an oracle which could 
 with great advantage be called upon in many affairs of state for 
 which it is now often necessary, at great cost, to procure advisers 
 from foreign countries. 
 
 In respect to instruction in the economic and camcral sciences, 
 there is first of all needed a Collegium Fundamental, in which all
 
 304 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 these sciences are presented in a single coherent theory. This is 
 necessary in order that young students may get an insight into the 
 whole, that they may gain a coherent idea of all contrivances in the 
 great housekeeping of the state, ^and may be filled with correct 
 principles derived from the nature of republics. When they have 
 laid such a ground they will never be entire strangers in any part of 
 the housekeeping of the state, although it may be their intention to 
 emphasize some particular part of civic administration. This will 
 under all circumstances accrue to their advantage, because all 
 affairs of state have an inseparable influence upon one another and 
 an interconnection with one another. This course should properly 
 be heard by every student, unless he is determined not to become a 
 member of the civic organization. Should we not get acquainted 
 with the structure and nature of the civic body in which we live? 
 Should we not make ourselves acquainted with our obligations 
 toward the republic, and is there a scholar to be found who does 
 not need at least the rules of Haushaltungskunst ? 
 
 The many-colored naivete" of this passage gives it a high 
 value. The cross-lights upon the state of knowledge in general, 
 though not directly in the line of our inquiry, are altogether 
 worthy of attention. The observation most immediately 
 pertinent is that, although Justi's range of effective vision 
 covered only the operations of a system of bureaus developed 
 in the service of an obstinately statical type of state, yet the 
 soul of truth in his contention has gone marching on. We 
 now see that adequate social science presupposes analysis of 
 all the processes within which government is a mediate process, 
 until we have a survey of the whole cosmos of human purposes 
 in the whole complexity of their activities. In other words, 
 we have here an outcropping of the social logic which had never 
 been generalized in its present form until the last half-century. 
 The perception that we need to understand the social activities 
 of which we are factors permits no stopping-place until we have 
 compassed the whole range of activities within which there 
 are traceable connections of cause and effect in human lives.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 305 
 
 Our primary interest with the cameralists, however, is in 
 tracing the progress from their preoccupation with a mere 
 administrative technology to an economic theory which would 
 have the same relation to such technology that the science of 
 physics has to civil engineering. 
 
 Justi goes on to say (p. xxxvii) that the first part of his 
 Staatswirthschaft is for use as a textbook in such a Collegium 
 Fundamentale. 
 
 It contains in a coherent system the chief principles of all eco- 
 nomic sciences. First of all the chief theorems of statecraft [Staats- 
 kunst 1 ] are presented. Then the police administration is explained, 
 which in a broad sense includes the science of commerce. These 
 two sciences occupy the first book. The second book teaches 
 principally the immediate duties of subjects, in which duties are 
 involved the grounds of financial science, and then follow the general 
 rules of management, with the chief theorems of agricultural science. 
 
 Justi thinks that this part of the book can be covered in the 
 university in a semester (p. xxxviii). 
 
 This fundamental course taken for granted as an intro- 
 duction, Justi would proceed to develop the involved particular 
 sciences. First of these he says is "Oekonomie," and the term 
 is thus put in the place of a specific designation under the 
 generic terms "Staatskunst," "Staatswirthschaft," "Haus- 
 haltungskunst," etc. Justi at once explains his use of the 
 title "Oekonomie": 
 
 It includes not only the general rules of management [Haus- 
 haltung], but also the theory of municipal management, and especially 
 
 1 The undifferentiated conception of which the word was a symbol 
 at that time cannot be indicated by any English word now in use. The 
 rendering "statecraft" does not quite correspond with Justi's idea, yet 
 it would be more unfair to use the modern term "political science." 
 In the rough, Staatskunst as Justi knew it, was the methods of keeping 
 the civic machinery running and of assuring the ways and means on which 
 the machinery depended; including, however, much more management 
 of private affairs than Americans or Englishmen would admit into 
 political science.
 
 36 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of agricultural management. It is necessary to begin the special 
 sciences with these two, because they in turn are fundamental in 
 this field (p. xxxviii). 
 
 Again we must make the comment that the apparent validity 
 of this position is shaken by the fact that the "Oekonomie," 
 as Justi knew it, was systematized rule-of-thumb. It was the 
 procedure which had become the routine of the traditional 
 bureaucratic state. Its foundation was the sand of assumption 
 that this state was the universal state. "Oekonomie" was thus 
 essentially stereotyped usage, while "political economy" as 
 proposed by Adam Smith was essentially an inquiry into prin- 
 ciples of economic relationship antecedent to usage, and 
 destined to control usage. We must admit that usage on a 
 different plane set bounds to Smith's objective analysis, 1 yet 
 the contrast between the two systems was at bottom this: 
 Justi was formulating usage, Smith was referring usage to 
 underlying principles. Each procedure had justification after 
 its kind. Neither procedure has yet come to its full fruition. 
 On each side criticism has both brought out incompleteness 
 and found approach to correlation with the opposite procedure.' 
 
 Of this first fundamental science of the second order, 
 "Oekonomie" Justi adds (p. xxxviii): 
 
 It not only affords adequate ideas of the subject-matter con- 
 cerned in all these specific sciences, but its theorems are at the same 
 time an epitome of all the measures which are necessary in the great 
 management of the state. The great management of the state rests 
 virtually upon the same rules which other management must observe. 3 
 
 1 Vide Small, Adam Smith and Modern Sociology, pp. 56, 107, 125, 
 148, 1 60, etc. 
 
 This passage contains a part of the reply which I would make to 
 FrensdorfT's generalization. Vide above, p. 290. 
 
 3 While this proposition suggests the remark which Herbert Spencer 
 somewhere makes, to the effect that "the problems of the state are merely 
 the problems of the household enlarged and extended," the inferences 
 drawn by the two men from the same generalization were quite con- 
 tradictory.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 307 
 
 In both establishments the ultimate purposes are to acquire "means" 
 [Vernwgen], to assure what has been acquired, and to use reasonably 
 the goods possessed. The housekeeping of the state is merely of 
 incomparably greater extent than that of a private person. A 
 student who wants to learn the economic and cameral sciences 
 thoroughly, and at the same time wishes to end his studies early, 
 might therefore hear the Oekonomie while also hearing the Col- 
 legium Fundamental, yet it would always be better if he would begin 
 the more special courses after completing the more general. The 
 course on Oekonomie may also easily be completed in a semester. 
 
 Next to the economic lectures [continues Jusli] should follow 
 in order the course on police science. This is also the first part of 
 the great Oekonomie (sic) of the state, since it includes the chief 
 measures intended to preserve and increase the general means of 
 the republic. All the methods whereby the riches of the state may 
 be increased, in so far as the authority of the government is con- 
 cerned, belong consequently (sic) under the charge of the police. 1 
 The science of police is consequently the more immediate basis for 
 the cameral and finance sciences proper, and the expert in police 
 science must sow, as it were, in order that the cameralist in turn 
 may reap. Since this science is very comprehensive, the lectures on 
 it will demand a whole year, if one treats the subjects involved with 
 the proper thoroughness and completeness. 
 
 Then cameral and financial science proper completes the series. 
 This is, as it were, the second main division of the great Oekonomie 
 of a republic, since it deals with the reasonable use of the means of 
 
 the state, and the entire internal housekeeping This science 
 
 also is so inclusive that it can hardly be covered properly in less 
 than a whole year. 
 
 All these sciences are demanded if one is to attain thorough 
 knowledge of them, and to become a universal cameralist. But if 
 one is destined to become only a particular cameralist, one or the 
 other of these sciences may, if necessary, be dispensed with. For 
 instance, one who purposes to give his attention chiefly to the com- 
 
 1 The "consequently" is obviously a term of reasoning in a circle. 
 But why call attention to a spot on the outside of this cup and platter, 
 while the whole contents were a ragout of begged questions ?
 
 308 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 mercial system may omit the Oekonomic and Camtralwissenschaft, 
 and after the Collegium Fundamentale may turn immediately to 
 police science, etc. (p. xl). 
 
 Another specification shows that Justi's perceptions were 
 in more than one direction prophetic. He adds (p. xl): 
 
 It is not to be denied that it would be of great advantage if one 
 would begin this study with a course on the history of the police, 
 commercial, economic, cameralistic systems. This sort of history, 
 however, is not yet at all worked out, with the exception of a slight 
 beginning at Berlin, and there is a special lack of a suitable text- 
 book for this purpose. Meanwhile, each of the above-scheduled 
 courses should begin with a brief history of the subject. Thus in 
 the lectures on police one may introduce a discourse on the police 
 arrangements of ancient times, and of the rise and fall of countries 
 and cities; in commercial science one may rehearse the history of 
 shipping and trade, and similarly in the case of the other sciences. 
 
 The technological and vocational trend of Justi's ideas is 
 more evident than before in the paragraph in which he begins 
 to discuss the limitations under which instruction in these 
 sciences must proceed. His first proposition may be rendered 
 in modern academic jargon, "It is of course impossible to 
 conduct these courses by the laboratory method" (p. xli). 
 And he continues: 
 
 For in these sciences practice would not amount to much if it 
 consisted in preparing camera! documents or acting as a commission 
 in cameral affairs. That is perhaps not the hundredth part of the 
 practical labors in these sciences. In the case of each main division 
 there are numerous side applications. If one were to give specially 
 practical lectures, one would be drawn into repetition of exposition 
 and explanation which would amount to a review of the whole body 
 of science, and a series of years would not suffice for such a course. 
 Consequently every course on a special economic science must be 
 planned in a practical way, especially the courses on police, commerce, 
 and finance, and so soon as the instruction has reached the end of 
 a main division the instructor must exhibit pieces of work of the sort
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 309 
 
 that apply what has been explained. He must require the students to 
 imitate these samples, and he must pass judgment on them publicly. 
 This should be the practice at least with the more diligent students, 
 who have an interest in getting thorough mastery of the subject. 
 It would be impossible to treat in this way all the exercises that 
 might be submitted. 1 
 
 At the close of the Preface (p. xliii) Justi again refers to 
 Gasser and Dithmar, and expresses the hope that his work 
 will be found superior to theirs. He thinks these latter are too 
 defective to be used with advantage. Then occurs the phrase, 
 "a new cameralist," already noted. Justi says that so far as 
 extent of material is concerned this writer is measurably com- 
 plete. "But it would not be in accordance with the truth if 
 one should attribute to his work an organization firmly based 
 upon the essence of the subject." 
 
 In the Preface to the second edition, less than three years 
 later than the first, Justi says that the first edition was exhausted 
 a year and a half before the time of writing. 
 
 He betrays a rather innocent idea of the growth of science, 
 when, in apology for enlarging Part I, he says that an author 
 ought not to publish a book until he has reached his limit of 
 ability to treat the subject, so that changes will not be necessary 
 in later editions. He ought at most to publish additions as 
 appendices, but in separate sheets, so that the owner of the 
 first edition could use them with it. He conformed to this 
 requirement in part by making the changes chiefly in the 
 notes (p. iv). 2 
 
 Before entering upon an analysis of the text of Staats- 
 wirthschaft, mention must be made of the syllabus which 
 
 1 As an item of evidence bearing on the growth of the seminar 
 method in German universities, sec. xlii is worth consulting. 
 
 Sees, vi-ix of this preface contain curious circumstantial evidence 
 about the author's attitude toward other writers, and about the sort of 
 liberty which a commentator on political subjects might at that time 
 MMtme.
 
 310 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 preceded it. The main outline is identical with that of Staats- 
 wirthschaft, and the latter evidently incorporated the sub- 
 stance of the lectures given on the basis of the former. The 
 most notable feature of this outline is the prompt and definite 
 statement of its fundamental thesis: viz., after declaring 
 (2) that the ultimate purpose [Endzweck] of the economic and 
 camcral sciences is the common happiness [gemeinschaftliche 
 Gliickseligkeit], Justi declares (3): 
 
 Hence follows the first and universal principle, namely: all the 
 governmental activities of a state must be so ordered that by means 
 of them the happiness of the state may be promoted. 
 
 Our interpretation of this principle must be deferred. 1 
 In accordance with his theory, Justi begins Staatswirthschaft 
 with a "short history" of the financial systems and commerce 
 of all peoples. It occupies twenty-six pages. The status of 
 its historicity may be inferred from a note on the second page, 
 in which Whiston's estimate of the population of the ante- 
 diluvian world is cited as proof that navigation must have been 
 practiced during that epoch, because without it a population 
 twenty times as numerous as that of the modern world could 
 not have been supported! 
 
 1 Vide p. 319. The syllabus is entitled: Kurzer systematischer 
 Grundriss oiler Oeconomischen und Cameralvrissenschaflen. It is 
 reprinted in Justi's Gesam. Pol. u. Finanzschrifien, Vol. I, Abth. 2, 
 pp. 504-73; and in Vol. II, Abth. 2, pp. 303-77. A note to 2 says: 
 "I used this outline as the basis of my lectures at Vienna, and it had to 
 be submitted to the previous censorship of the ministry. Graf von 
 Haugwitz was so much pleased with it that he caused it to be circulated 
 among all the members of the General-directorii." This seems to settle 
 the case with Roschcr as to Justi's academic activities at Vienna. Vide 
 above, p. 289. 
 
 Both in the essay referred to above (p. 286) and in the Geschichle 
 (p. 444) Roschcr says that Slaatswirlhschaft was dedicated to Maria 
 Thcrcsia. Frensdorff (p. 385) assumes that such was the fact. I have 
 been unable to find a copy of the first edition, but have used the second 
 (1758). My copy seems to be in the original binding, but it contains no
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 311 
 
 The character of the historical propositions is seen in the 
 following samples: 
 
 The Phoenicians carried on extensive trade both on land and 
 sea; .... because her finances were not well administered, this 
 powerful republic in consequence, and also because of party spirit, 
 at last suffered total destruction; .... there were at the time [of 
 the first Ptolemiesl in Egypt 33,339 flourishing cities (p. 7); .... 
 the Romans, as the rest of their constitution was wise and excellent, 
 had also a well-ordered constitution of the financial system (p. 7), etc. 
 
 Justi mentions Livy, Josephus, Suetonius, the Capitularies, 
 etc., but not in a way which shows whether he had first-hand 
 acquaintance with them. The notes do not furnish evidence 
 of the authorities behind the statements in the text, but add 
 illustrative or cumulative material backed by nothing but the 
 author's assertion. 
 
 In the sixth section (p. 10) Justi declares: 
 
 The Roman commerce declined, just as this realm tended toward 
 its fall, on account of the bad administration of the emperor; and 
 although the Roman Empire in the Orient, especially in Constanti- 
 nople, in the beginning had a considerable trade, yet this declined 
 in proportion as the realm was weakened by the Arabians or Sara- 
 dedication whatever. The same is true of other copies of the same edition 
 on which I have obtained reports from libraries in this country. As the 
 Preface to the first edition was dated "Leipzig n April, 1755," i. e., in 
 the second year after Justi left Vienna, it does not accord with the cir- 
 cumstances of his departure, so far as theyare understood, to suppose that 
 he would have been in a state of mind to waste any veneration on the em- 
 press. Roscher seems to have been in error about the dedication. It is pos- 
 sible that the original of the Crundriss may have been dedicated to Maria 
 Theresia, and that Roscher confused the syllabus with the expander] work. 
 
 After the foregoing was written I received the following from the 
 library of the British Museum: "The first ed. of Justi's Staatswirthschaft 
 ( l l$S) is in B. M. and is dedicated to Maria Teresia. His Kurzer syste- 
 matischer Crundriss (1752 ?) is not in B. M." This puts Roscher right; 
 but it also shows that he missed the significance of the omission in the 
 second edition. 
 
 . .i::' : Tf* .
 
 312 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 cens. On the other hand all commerce passed over to these peoples, 
 especially after they had conquered Egypt. 
 
 Then in a note upon this paragraph Justi continues: 
 
 Not the division of the Empire, as many writers on history 
 believe, caused the fall of Rome, for both empires remained after the 
 division stronger than the most powerful realms. We must seek 
 the true cause of the fall of both empires in the insecure occupancy 
 of the throne and in the irregular succession, etc. 
 
 These platitudes and generalities are below the standards 
 of a modern "finishing school." They are mere space-fillers 
 in a book ostensibly introducing young men to practical govern- 
 mental careers. It is hard to believe that they could have been 
 regarded by their author as more than rhetorical flourishes. 
 
 Coming to the period of discovery and colonization, the 
 information vouchsafed contains this item concerning the 
 English possessions in America: 
 
 They possessed there Virginia, Carolina, New England, Scot- 
 land (sic) besides several other lands and islands (p. 17). 
 
 The more serious and practical purpose of the book might 
 be inferred, perhaps, from the points to which Justi calls 
 attention in the case of Germany. He says (p. 24): 
 
 In respect to the finances, Germany has been very careless for 
 several hundred years. Only at the end of the last century were 
 manufactures to some extent re-established through the Protestant 
 French refugees, and the former king of Prussia, who was himself 
 a very great administrator [Haushalter], by good management, 
 increased his revenues by one-half, and he gave equal attention to 
 manufactures. The present great and wise Prussian monarch has 
 not only retained the former management, but by forming great 
 maritime trading societies he has laid the foundations for sea com- 
 merce, etc. 
 
 A note to this paragraph declares: 
 
 In the Middle Ages, when almost all the revenues of the German 
 princes were derived from the crown estates, which produced little
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF JUSTI 313 
 
 enough, as a rule the consort of fhe prince, or the prince himself, 
 took charge both of the income and of the expenditure, without the 
 help of bureau employees. In modern times, and even within 200 
 years, questions of justice and finance, neither of which bulked very 
 large, were dealt with by one and the same body of officials. Land- 
 grave Philipp of Hesse, as appears from his will, had for all his admin- 
 istration two dignified officials, each of whom received fifty florins 
 salary. Elector August of Saxony (1526-86) is, so far as I know, 
 the first of the German princes to have organized an orderly cameral 
 system. 
 
 So far as a serious scientific or practical purpose may be 
 supposed to have stimulated this "historical" survey, so far 
 as it is to be regarded as something more than a mere rhetorical 
 embellishment, there appears to be but one object which it 
 can have served. It advertised the importance of adminis- 
 trative thrift. It did this not by analysis of cause and effect 
 which was above the grade of puerility, but merely by calling 
 attention to the matter-of-fact elements of ways and means 
 which romantic or speculative or heedless tradition had formed 
 the habit of neglecting. Perhaps the present state of mind 
 in the United States on the subject of forestry may be cited 
 as the most instructive parallel. Until very recently it was 
 almost impossible to make anyone of the academic or of the 
 political type take the slightest interest in the subject of forest 
 preservation. It was regarded as a matter that would take 
 care of itself, or if not, it was no concern of people whose chief 
 interest was in taking care of themselves. Justi's public was 
 in a somewhat similar state of mind about national revenues. 
 Evidently there was a reason for this in the fact that public 
 revenues were not in the same sense "public" that they are 
 today. They were the revenues of the prince and of his 
 government. While there had been great changes in the 
 technique of administration, and while the problems of pro- 
 ductiveness of different sources of revenue had been system- 
 atically calculated by the governmental bureaus, it was about
 
 3 14 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as hard, apparently, to create non-official interest in these 
 subjects, as with us at present in the subject of forestry. People 
 then said, "It is the prince's affair; let him look out for it;" 
 just as we now say, "What has posterity done for us? Let 
 future generations look out for themselves." Accordingly, 
 this historical retrospect, utterly without value as a contribution 
 to knowledge, for it was merely a recital of scrappy hearsay, 
 was a bit of homiletical practice. It was an appeal to the 
 suggestibility of hearers, and an attempt to put them into a 
 receptive attitude toward the technological considerations which 
 were to follow.
 
 CHAPTER XIV 
 
 ARGUMENT OF JUSTFS " STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT " 
 
 It is now in order to summarize Justi's epitome of cameral 
 science, not with reference to its technological details, but 
 especially with a view to the larger scheme of purposes which 
 these details, and cameralism as a whole, presupposed. In 
 this re'sume' much reappears that has been said or implied 
 either by Justi or his predecessors. 
 
 The argument begins with assertion of the necessity of starting 
 the teaching of any science by laying down fundamental principles 
 (p. 29), as distinguished from the programmes of teaching merely 
 through examples, or practice, or memory. 
 
 The importance of basing a system of teaching on principles is 
 peculiarly evident in cameral istics (p. 30). The forethought of 
 a wise government must extend to a thousand sorts of matters which 
 are most intimately connected with one another. If then one lacks 
 a general and connected idea of these governmental affairs, one will 
 in many ways cause injury to the body politic [gemeines Wesen], 
 when one attempts to be of use. 
 
 Again Justi implies, without dogmatically asserting it, 
 that these affairs of state have never yet been treated in a 
 single book as details growing out of fundamental principles. 
 His note on this proposition still more clearly reflects the 
 situation as he saw it. He says (p. 31): 
 
 We cannot assert, to be sure, that there has been a lack of books 
 along these lines. If we consider both home and foreign countries, 
 we may collect quite a library. Yet we cannot find a book among 
 them all which attempts to teach one or more of these sciences on 
 the basis of their correlations with the whole subject. Even the 
 Compendia are not exceptions. Usually they treat somewhat of 
 economy and of the royal revenues. If they are very ample, there 
 will be a few sections about the police, but in the fragmentary fashion
 
 316 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and disorderly arrangement in which they accidentally occurred 
 to the author. I am by no means inclined to blame others, and I 
 therefore refrain from mentioning names. The facts however are 
 open to the eyes of everyone. Without doubt the reason of it is 
 that, through some ordering of destiny which I do not understand, 
 philosophical minds have paid no attention to these sciences which 
 so intimately concern the welfare of social life. 1 
 
 We call the sciences dedicated to the government of a state the 
 economic as well as the cameralistic sciences, or the economic and 
 cameralistic sciences. 3 Economics or Haushaltungskunst has for 
 its aim to teach how the means of private persons (sic) are to be 
 preserved, increased, and reasonably applied. What economics 
 attempts to do in connection with the goods of private persons, the 
 governmental sciences aim to do in the case of the total means of 
 the state. Hence they properly bear the name, the economic sciences. 3 
 We give them the name cameralistic sciences, however, because the 
 high collegia which the sovereigns have established, to manage the 
 preservation, expansion, and use of the means of the republic, are 
 usually called Cammern or Cammercollegia (p. 32). 
 
 Our times are so fortunate that almost all rulers are eager to 
 secure for their states a flourishing trade, and for their subjects all 
 kinds of subsistence and temporal welfare. I do not venture to say 
 that this providence always springs from genuine sources, that is, 
 from love for the subjects and from paternal impulse to make them 
 happy. Self-love is here and there the chief motive. Yet there is 
 rather satisfactory consciousness on the part of princes in general 
 that they cannot be great and powerful if they have a land that is 
 poor and resourceless. All courts accordingly use language con- 
 sistent with the genuine sources of motive for political action. It is 
 
 1 Zincke's Cameralwissenschaft appeared the same year with Justi's 
 first edition. I fear he was a cad to publish such a reflection three years 
 later. 
 
 3 In Adam Smith and Modern Sociology, pp. 189 and 210, I have 
 called attention to the strange turn of affairs which led von Mohl to 
 declare that political science had nothing to do with political economy. 
 This antithesis must be looked into later. 
 
 3 The unsteadiness of the conception in Justi's mind is evident.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 317 
 
 our business to set in order the principles of these governmental 
 sciences, which the nature of things, truth, and sound reason demand. 
 These principles must be derived from the ultimate purpose of the 
 state. What then is a state, and in what does its ultimate purpose 
 consist? (p. 33). 
 
 It is evident that Justi is to a certain extent aware that he 
 is proposing ideal principles rather than those which are 
 actually accepted by the ruling classes. It is not so plain that 
 he saw the inherent antagonism between contemporary political 
 policies and abstract principles. He was apparently concerned 
 with generalizations primarily as a rational basis for existing 
 practice, and only secondarily, if at all, as a leverage for change 
 of practice. Yet the moment one begins to formulate human 
 society, in general, or a state, in particular, in accordance with 
 rational categories of whatever sort, one inevitably initiates a 
 reconstructive impulse. The problems are thereby presented: 
 Why does not the actuality conform to the theory ? and, What 
 is to be done, either to the actuality or to the theory, in view 
 of the discrepancy ? 
 
 Justi answers his own question in this way (p. 33) : 
 
 It is usually asserted that republics have been derived from fear 
 of incursions. It is more probable that they grew out of the govern- 
 ing skill of families; that is, the patriarch must necessarily have had 
 a certain prestige and power over his children and servants, which 
 descended at his death to his eldest son, until in the course of time 
 it amounted to a real rulership. We have many evidences that this 
 was the fact, but of course they do not account for great empires, 
 which have always been formed by force of arms. 
 
 With no further fact or theory or criticism as a basis, Justi 
 proceeds to the following definition (p. 34): 
 
 A republic or state is a unification of a multitude of people under 
 a supreme power, for the ultimate purpose of their happiness; or 
 we may say, a republic consists of a multitude of people who are 
 combined with each other by means of a general interdependence
 
 318 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 and certain fixed institutions, in order, with their united energies, 
 and under a superimposed supreme power, to promote their common 
 happiness. Republics are accordingly distinguished from Gesett- 
 schaften or Societaten, which, to be sure, have a certain best, and 
 sometimes happiness in general, as their aim, but have never sub- 
 ordinated themselves to a supreme power. The supreme power in 
 the state accordingly originates without doubt from the people; 
 a principle which today is as universally recognized as true as it was 
 formerly regarded as dangerous by little minds. 
 
 Hamlet's reflection, "What a piece of work is man!" 
 might be parodied from the opposite point of view, with such 
 generalizations as the foregoing as the point of departure, 
 With what Pickwickian states of mind do men fool themselves ! 
 In a political society in which government was primarily of, 
 for, and by the sovereign, a theorist could still suppose he was 
 dealing with realities in basing a technological system on the 
 presumption that the power of the sovereign is derived from 
 the people. Perhaps the anomaly is most striking when 
 inverted. Sovereigns could persist in acting as though they 
 had absolute rights as sovereigns, for generations after men 
 of thought had discovered that the powers of sovereigns come 
 from the people. The wonder is not so great as it seems, 
 because the anomaly does not by any means last so long after 
 the discovery as appearances seem to indicate. It is alto- 
 gether improbable, for instance, that to Justi the formula, 
 "The power of sovereigns is derived from the people," meant 
 what it means to us. Nor did it have precisely the psychologi- 
 cal sense in which it is a truism. It had rather a vague, dreamy, 
 mixed sense, made up in part of purely idealized notions of 
 the relation, partly of the historical hypothesis above expressed. 
 The thought-medium in which this idea was carried, however, 
 was a strong tincture of superstition about some sort of fore- 
 ordained fitness of certain hereditary lines to be the repositories 
 of these powers over their fellow-men; and accordingly it
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 319 
 
 carried an energetic presumption that the well-being of these 
 multitudes was to be thought of in terms of the pleasure of the 
 sovereign, rather than of the wants of the subjects. 
 
 Yet Justi seems to be very much in advance of his time 
 when he continues (p. 35) : 
 
 The ultimate aim of each and every republic is therefore unques- 
 tionably the common happiness It is unnecessary to enlarge 
 
 upon the proposition, therefore, that the subjects do not exist for the 
 sake of the ruler. 
 
 But it was precisely this principle which was to be the bone 
 of contention between sovereigns and subjects for the next 
 hundred years. The system which Justi was trying to inter- 
 pret, and for which he wanted to train recruits, was historically 
 an assertion of the contrary principle. 
 
 As previously in the Grundriss, 1 Justi formulates as "the 
 first and universal principle of all economic and cameralistic 
 sciences" the following proposition (p. 35): 
 
 All the administrative transactions of a state must l)e so ordered 
 that by means of them the happiness of the same (i. e., of the state) 
 shall be promoted.* 
 
 To what extent we have here a clue to the conflict of ideas 
 in Justi's mind, and in the civilization of the time, it would be 
 unsafe to infer with much positiveness. The confusion is 
 notorious, both in abstract thinking and in the current social 
 practice. Neither the psychology nor the logic nor the sociol- 
 ogy of it is our immediate concern, beyond mere observation 
 of the fact. We are at present interested in tracing the develop- 
 ment of scientific consciousness out of this situation. Merely 
 as a symptom of the situation, as a sign of the lack of precision 
 and consistency of view, we may note that in the previous 
 paragraph Justi had been talking about the well-being of 
 subjects, as the end for rulers to subserve, or "the common 
 
 1 Above, p. 310. ' Vide below, p. 327.
 
 320 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 happiness." In the formula which he now constructs to 
 enJbody that idea, the center of attention is the happiness of the 
 state. No long argument is necessary to show that there was 
 room for endless incongruity and inconsistency in theory and 
 practice so long as such variable common denominators were 
 used as "subjects," "the common happiness," and "the 
 happiness of the state." 
 
 In other words, there was not yet a precise and consistent 
 analysis of civic relations. Conceptions of civic relations 
 were fluid and shifting. As Hegel might have put it: Expe- 
 rience was only partially self-conscious. Theory was accord- 
 ingly in many ways in contradiction with itself and with 
 practice. Both theory and practice were unsystematically 
 feeling their way toward precision and consistency. Justi 
 bravely declares that the sequel will prove the theorem just 
 quoted to have the character of a universal principle, and to 
 be the source from which all doctrines of the state and of 
 government may be coherently derived (p. 36). 
 
 Then Justi classifies all "republics or forms of govern- 
 ment" (sic) into the three types: 
 
 (i) The monarchy or autocracy, in which the power resides in 
 one alone; (2) the aristocracy, or the government of the better class 
 [Vornehm]; (3) the democracy, or the rule of the common people. 
 Then there are mixed forms. 
 
 This whole type of analysis, not yet by any means out- 
 grown, makes form of political structure the decisive matter, 
 and does not press back to the psychological or even the socio- 
 logical meaning of the form. Commenting on the analysis, 
 Justi adds: 
 
 It is easy to prove that the monarchical form of government is 
 far preferable to all others, in consideration of the rapidity with 
 which it can grasp the means of happiness of a state, and because 
 many domestic disturbances and discords are thus prevented. It
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 321 
 
 is also certain that a single good monarch can do more good than 
 free republics could bring to pass in centuries (p. 38). x 
 
 Since the monarchical form of government is taken for granted 
 in this book, it is necessary to consider the various constructions 
 of the monarchical form: viz., (i) with reference to succession of 
 rulers; (2) with reference to unlimited or limited power; (3) with 
 reference to the connection of realms and territories which belong 
 to a monarchy (pp. 30-43). 
 
 The analysis under these heads is of the most elementary 
 and obvious sort, and dynastic convenience is throughout the 
 principal test of value. Thus Justi says that there are ample 
 grounds for the conclusion that women are not fit to govern a 
 state; yet he adds that the same reasons would exclude an 
 incompetent or ignorant man from the succession. Without 
 saying it directly, he implies that the fixed succession in the 
 male line is notwithstanding a lesser evil than uncertainty 
 about the succession. In a note he makes a remark which 
 throws light on the preconceptions which lead to this judg- 
 ment: 
 
 A realm is in its essence nothing but an estate [Landgut], which 
 might fall into the hands of an alien heir (p. 39). 
 
 The discussion is so general in its character that it is a 
 famous object-lesson in the futility of deciding upon social 
 arrangements by means of academic generalizations. Whether 
 a monarchy, limited or unlimited, an aristocracy, or a democ- 
 racy is the best government, proves to be a question quite 
 co-ordinate with the problem whether a saw or a hat or a loaf 
 of bread is the best piece of property. There is no universal 
 "best" in either case. The historical judgment in both cases, 
 that is, the actual working judgment, the judgment that holds, 
 is the judgment not of types but of workings. The academic 
 method thus illustrated by Justi must always sooner or later 
 
 As we have pointed out before, this is today one of the most con- 
 fident presumptions of industrial monarchy.
 
 322 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 give way to the pragmatic method best illustrated on a large 
 scale by British history. 
 
 At the same time it must be admitted that there was much 
 more pragmatism in fact than in form in Justi's theories; and 
 this is almost universally the case with social philosophers. 
 That is, he dealt with universal propositions, but they were 
 universals of which particular cases were given in the current 
 problems of German states, and more than he was aware he 
 was really asking: "Which of the possible alternatives will 
 work best in this situation ?" Questions of checks upon the 
 ruler, of succession to the throne, of relations between terri- 
 tories politically connected only through a common ruler, 
 were everyday affairs. The judgments passed upon them, 
 both by practical and theoretical reasoners, were in this form : 
 So and so works best with us just now: ergo, so and so is a 
 universal principle. This type of fallacy is long-lived. In 
 slightly less naive shape it underlies the Smith ian political 
 economy. Adam Smith knew, yet he did not know, that the 
 capitalistic order of society in which he lived was merely a stage 
 in historical evolution in the same series with community 
 ownership, and with feudalism. He believed, however, that 
 the social division, landlord, capitalist, and proletarian, worked 
 well. Hence he canceled the historical factor and concluded 
 that the stratification, landlord, capitalist, and proletarian, is 
 eternal; and he proceeded to draw all further conclusions 
 with this premise reckoned as a finality. The judgments which 
 Justi expresses are defective in a much more elementary way, 
 because they are based on a presupposition of a much more 
 precarious type. The corollaries which he immediately draws 
 are as follows: 
 
 (i) The fixed form of succession is necessary to the happiness 
 of a state, because otherwise the state can expect nothing but unrest, 
 wars, and disruption; (2) the territorial possessions, and the freedom 
 of those classes that are not harmful to the welfare of the state must
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 323 
 
 be preserved; (3) no new liberties and privileges must be conceded 
 which interfere with facile control of the means of happiness of a 
 state (pp. 43, 44); (4) various realms and lands belonging to a 
 monarch must be combined in a union and a general organization, 
 because separation hinders the use of the full powers of the state, 
 prevents complete employment of means of revenue, especially in 
 commerce, and leads to antipathy and jealousy between the different 
 territories. 
 
 In qualifying this conclusion Justi betrays the opportun- 
 ism that is really decisive in all his judgments (p. 46). 
 
 Further light falls on the standpoint of the whole system 
 in the elaboration of these clauses. Thus Justi observes that 
 some states seem to assume as a principle the opposite of 
 (2), i. e., liberties are suppressed as much as possible. There- 
 upon he remarks that "there are weighty considerations making 
 for the conclusion that a monarch does no wrong in adopting 
 this policy: for usually such liberties are no good to the state, 
 but are merely for the benefit of individuals." The two 
 terms, "state" and "individual," here brought into compar- 
 ison, were relatively unanalyzed concepts; and judgments 
 between them were necessarily rough. The leaning in favor 
 of the state as contrasted with private persons is, however, 
 plain and characteristic. When Justi puts into German 
 the familiar Roman epigram in the form: "The happiness 
 of the state is its highest law," we must understand him to 
 mean not what a Roman tribune would mean, nor what an 
 American democrat would mean. He meant: "The success- 
 ful carrying-out of the policy which the ruling power in the 
 typical German state sets up as its aim is the paramount 
 consideration." It is impossible to determine precisely how 
 much his frequent partial formulations of more popular stand- 
 ards should modify this proposition. 1 
 
 The nature of the presuppositions on which Justi's system 
 
 1 Vide below, p. 327.
 
 324 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 rests appears further in his analysis of the monarchical factor 
 in the state. Thus he begins with the definition (p. 47): 
 
 A monarch or ruler [Regent] is the supreme head of the state, 
 or of the republic, who possesses the highest power in order that 
 by means of it he may take care of all the affairs of the community 
 and may apply efficient means for promoting the common happi- 
 ness. 
 
 These words could of course be fitted out with an utterly 
 democratic meaning. Their connotations at the time were 
 at best patriarchal, and as a rule the patriarchalism was of a 
 sort which inverted the personal relations actually concerned. 
 That is, state policy was incarnated in the ruler, whose success 
 was identified with "the happiness of the state;" while the 
 individuals subject to the ruler were in the last analysis not 
 regarded as having any well-being which deserved to weigh 
 against "the happiness of the state" so conceived. This 
 appears always only in part, in formulas of the royal character 
 or powers. These theorems are never perfectly clear either 
 way. They contain elements of contradictory views. They 
 can be interpreted correctly, therefore, not by mere linguistic 
 rules, but by the light of the conduct in which they were 
 applied. Such partially ambiguous propositions follow, 
 e.g.: 
 
 The chief duty of the monarch consists therefore in guardian- 
 ship of the happiness of the subjects. 
 
 But in the next sentence the other conception reappears, 
 viz.: 
 
 We should form a very erroneous idea of the monarch if we 
 thought of him as an administrator or superintendent of the supreme 
 power and of the affairs of the community. In this way we should 
 make of the monarch merely the servant of the state, and place the 
 republic over him, so that he could not be distinguished from a 
 Staathalter. This is the false notion held by the Monarchomachi, 
 from which so many harmful and dangerous conclusions follow.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 325 
 
 In the note to this paragraph, the idea is made still plainer, 
 viz.: 
 
 The enemies of the supreme power, and especially of absolutism, 
 whom we are accustomed to call the Monarchomachi, adopt as their 
 chief principle the theorem that the whole people is above the ruler, 
 and hence may either call him to account for acts prejudicial to the 
 welfare of the community, or may resist him. From such damnable 
 principles came the unhappy tragedy of the unfortunate Charles I 
 of England, and from the same cause Henry III came to his death 
 in France. Nothing is more detestable than these ideas which arc 
 evidently contrary to the nature of a republic and open the doors to 
 all sorts of uproar and disorder (p. 47). 
 
 Here then we are dealing with the familiar fallacy of passing 
 judgments first on fragments of situations, and then promoting 
 those judgments to the rank of principles with universal 
 validity. With such beginnings, modern social science is still 
 not too far along in the juvenile grades of its education. 
 
 The supreme power [die hochste Gewalt} is next denned as 
 consisting "in the use of the total means and powers of the 
 state in order thereby to attain the ultimate end of the same, 
 viz., its common happiness" (p. 48).' 
 
 Again we must not take these eighteenth-century words as 
 indicating twentieth-century ideas. Every shade of meaning 
 has to be challenged, to be sure that the real thought is de- 
 tected. The clue to the difference between the earlier and the 
 later conceptions is in the antithesis between the conception of 
 the monarch and the state, as incarnations of the community 
 in a sense* which left the people in a status of tributary exter- 
 nality, and on the other hand, the conception of ruler or chief 
 magistrate as merely the representative and the agent of the 
 state, which is simply a name for the people in their political 
 relations. If this latter idea were forced into Justi's further 
 explanations, they would in a general way command present 
 
 Vide pp. 327, and 372, 373.
 
 326 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 assent. But the other idea has to be understood in connection 
 with the words, and they then describe what actually was in 
 German states at the time, but has to a considerable extent 
 been revolutionized out of them meanwhile. Thus Justi says 
 (p. 48): 
 
 We should limit the supreme power much too narrowly if we 
 should make it consist merely in laws, ordinances, penalties, etc. 
 To the means and powers of the state belong not only all sorts of 
 goods, both fixed and movable, within the boundaries of the country, 
 but also all the talents and abilities of the persons who reside in the 
 country. The reasonable use of all these things, then, and the 
 prerogative of such use, is therefore the supreme power. 
 
 The judgment passed above on Justi's generalization of 
 particular utilities into universal principles, in the case of the 
 monarch, would have to be paralleled if we went into particulars 
 about his opinion of the relations between the lawgiving, the 
 judicial, and the executive departments of government (pp. 
 
 Following these most general observations about the 
 organization of states, Justi returns to the fundamental propo- 
 sition which dictates the divisions of his book, viz. : 
 
 The business of a ruler falls into two great divisions, to wit: 
 (i) the preservation and expansion of the means of the state; (2) 
 the wise application of these means, both in use and in thrift. 1 
 Hence all the sciences concerned with the government of a state 
 fall into a twofold division. The first contains statecraft, Policey, 
 and commercial science, along with economy (Oeconomie), all of which 
 aim either to preserve or to increase the means of the state. The 
 second comprises the cameral sciences proper, which teach how to 
 use these means wisely and in promotion of the happiness of the 
 state. 
 
 Since the paramount aim of the state is to preserve and extend 
 
 1 1 translate the phrase " gebrauchel und damit gewirthschaftet" in 
 this clumsy way, to avoid premature use of the technical concepts "con- 
 sumption" and "production."
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 327 
 
 its means [Vermogen], this purpose must be regarded as the chief 
 responsibility of rulers, and Justi accordingly deduces the following 
 theorems (p. 53): 
 
 1. The monarch must make use of means and measures through 
 which the resources of the state may be preserved and expanded, 
 and his subjects may be made happy. 
 
 2. The subjects must facilitate these measures by their obedi- 
 ence and diligence [Fleiss]. 
 
 From these principles another follows, viz.: 
 
 3. The welfare of the ruler and the happiness of the subjects 
 can never be separated, and the one without the other can never 
 permanently exist. 
 
 There is more pathos and naivite* than conscious hypoc- 
 risy in this third proposition. It is true in the same sense in 
 which the familiar classical economic dogma about the unity 
 of interest between employer and employee is true; and it is 
 false in the same way that this economic dogma was false. 
 If there were some infallible arbiter of the interests concerned 
 in either case, the formula might be so construed as to express 
 the truth. The well-being of subjects is by no means neces- 
 sarily harmonious with the well-being of rulers, when the 
 rulers have power to determine both; any more than the 
 interests of employers and of employees are necessarily one, 
 when the employers have the power to pronounce upon both. 
 
 Justi's note on Machiavelli at this point is instructive 
 (p. 54). He cannot understand how his Italian predecessor 
 can possibly have meant some of his doctrines seriously; and 
 therefore adopts the theory that The Prince was a heavily 
 veiled satire. The more probable alternative from our present 
 point of view is explanation of Machiavelli and Justi on 
 precisely the same grounds. Each was a product of his 
 environment, with a sufficient force of variation to betray 
 innovating impulses that looked toward a modified environ- 
 ment. Contradiction and inconsistency were in both cases 
 an inevitable part of the situation.
 
 328 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 That Justi mixed much sentiment and idealism with his 
 programme of objective analysis, may be illustrated by citation 
 of the next paragraph (p. 55) viz.: 
 
 From the combined welfare of the ruler and the subjects alone 
 springs the real strength of a state. This strength consists prin- 
 cipally of the reciprocal trust and love which the wise ruler and the 
 fortunate subjects of a considerable state have for each other, while 
 they endeavor with united energies to preserve and extend the 
 resources of the state. For neither the well-filled treasury and the 
 formidable army of the ruler, nor a land living in riches and abun- 
 dance makes this strength. Such a condition, however happy it 
 appears to be, is by no means sufficient against all accidents. History 
 is not empty of examples of the most powerful and flourishing 
 realms which unexpectedly came to destruction. A monarch has 
 accordingly met with a great loss if he no longer enjoys the love and 
 confidence of his subjects. 
 
 It is impracticable to give an adequate account of Justi's 
 work without succumbing to his own tediously repetitious 
 style of exposition. We have already had occasion to notice 
 two or three variations of his general scheme. We come now 
 to still another explanation which we may reproduce in brief. 
 Of the sciences to be treated in the first part of the Staats- 
 wirthschaft, Justi says (pp. 60-62): 
 
 The chief purpose of Stoats kunst is to assure complete security 
 for the community, both against external and internal dangers. 
 The immediate reason for this purpose is that these dangers threaten 
 the common welfare, and weaken the resources and powers of the 
 state. Statecraft thus obviously seems to preserve the resources 
 of the state. 
 
 Policcywissenschajt is concerned chiefly with the conduct [Lebens- 
 wandd] and sustenance [Nahrung] of the subjects, and its great 
 purpose is to put both in such equilibrium and correlation that the 
 subjects of the republic will be useful, and in a position easily to 
 support themselves. 
 
 The name "commercial science" is applied to two distinct
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 329 
 
 sciences. The one teaches the ways and means of conducting 
 commerce, and the composition of goods with which commerce is 
 carried on. The other treats of the measures by means of which 
 commercial enterprises may be established and made to flourish, 
 so that as a result the sustenance of subjects may be more ample 
 and the resources of the country may be increased. The latter 
 presupposes knowledge of the former, so that it is not dependent 
 merely on the reports of traders themselves, and it (the latter) is 
 peculiarly appropriate for those persons who are charged with the 
 government of the state. Accordingly it may be called, in distinc- 
 tion from the first, civic-commercial-science [Staatscommercien- 
 wissenschaft]. Fundamentally it is a subordinate science of Policey, 
 and it is a subject which we shall presently discuss. It is evident 
 that this science, too, ends with extending the resources of the state. 
 
 Management [Haushaltungskunst] is particularly devoted to 
 showing how the resources of private persons may be preserved, 
 increased, and well used: and since rural thrift is of great im- 
 portance to the state, this branch of science, after referring to all 
 classes and vocations, gives special attention to the ways and means 
 of cultivation. The more thrifty the private persons, the greater and 
 securer the resources of the state. Again there can be no doubt that 
 the science of management is tributary to the preservation and 
 extension of the resources of the state. 
 
 Since the co-operation of ruler and subjects is necessary for these 
 ends, the subject-matter of these sciences involves two chief con- 
 siderations, viz.: 
 
 1. What means and measures has the ruler to adopt, in order 
 to preserve and increase the resources of the state, and thus to 
 promote the happiness of his subjects ? 
 
 2. What duties have the subjects in order to lighten the respon- 
 sibilities of the ruler? 
 
 The treatment is divided into two books in accordance with 
 this latter subdivision. 
 
 As a special introduction to the former of these subjects, 
 civics, or statecraft, on the side of the ruler, Justi attempts 
 to define the concept "happiness" [Glucksdigkeit], which is
 
 33 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the goal of statecraft (pp. 65 ff.). He distinguishes it in the 
 first place from the philosophical concept, "happiness," which 
 he describes as "perfection of our moral condition, and the 
 consequent felicity of the soul." On the other hand, the 
 happiness here in question is either the perfection of our external 
 condition, or some specially advantageous occurrence which 
 could not properly have been expected from our situation. 
 More definitely expressed, Justi means by the happiness of 
 subjects in the present connection: 
 
 such good arrangement and structure of a state that everyone may 
 enioy a reasonable freedom, and by his diligence may be able to 
 attain those moral and temporal goods which the demands of his 
 social station make necessary for satisfactory living. 
 
 In spite of himself Justi includes much more than material 
 goods in this concept, yet the moral elements which he inserts 
 in the specifications have to be scrutinized with great care to 
 distinguish them from the concepts which the same terms 
 now suggest to us. For instance, he explains that "the 
 freedom of the subjects is indispensably necessary to their 
 happiness," yet the whole treatise is in principle and in detail 
 a definition of relations between ruler and subject to which 
 our generation would deny the predicate "freedom." We 
 must emphasize our previous observation that the essence of 
 the situation of which Justi was a symptom must be formulated 
 as an effort to express, in theory and in practice, the purposes 
 involved in the situation in terms of the paramount governing 
 factor of the situation. This is a social solecism. Social 
 logic is a progressive demonstration of the fallacy. The 
 interaction of the interests represented by these two terms, 
 ruler and subject, or more generally, social control and individ- 
 ual initiative, is the process actually going on, so far as these 
 two terms at any moment are active factors of the process. 
 Justi accordingly had in mind a relatively local, temporary, 
 provisional phase of the social process, and he virtually at-
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 331 
 
 tempted to generalize this transient situation as a universal 
 condition, and to lay down the laws of its equilibrium as 
 laws of universal equilibrium. When we have pointed this 
 out, we have really closed the rational verdict upon the system, 
 and upon all others of which it is a type. But we are at work 
 upon something more than the mere appraisal of a piece of 
 archaic philosophy and technology. Our main interest in it 
 is as it functions as a term in the evolution of social science 
 in general. With this purpose in view, we must continue the 
 analysis. We must try to discover how the fallacies of attrib- 
 uting a static character to the evolving, and a universal 
 validity to the particular, progressively discredited partial 
 science and forced more valid representation of reality. 
 
 Justi specifies "freedom, assured property, and flourishing 
 industry," as the three chief factors on which the happiness 
 of the state and of the subjects depends. 1 These specifica- 
 tions completely omit the factor which modern democracies 
 have placed at the head of the list, viz., government of, for, 
 and by the people. The cameralistic conception of the state 
 was that of a population free to conduct their private affairs 
 for themselves, but not presuming to have thoughts or ac- 
 tions about public affairs except as they were dictated by the 
 ruler. This arbitrary distinction between private and public 
 interests could not withstand the wear and tear of the social 
 process; but before the artificiality of the distinction was 
 discovered civic life had to struggle on a long time under the 
 embarrass ment of the provisional absolutistic theory and 
 practice. 
 
 Entering upon discussion of the security of the state, Justi 
 urges (p. 70) that: 
 
 more must be understood under this head than the condition of the 
 subjects in which, freed from all violence and fear, they may peace- 
 
 1 In Grundriss einer guten Regierung, p. 65, Justi makes the con- 
 stituents of happiness, "freedom, internal strength, and security."
 
 33 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 fully enjoy their goods and pursue their vocations. The state 
 itself must be in such a condition that, without fear of a stronger 
 power, it may make use of all means and measures which it finds 
 necessary for its prosperity and for the happiness of the subjects. 
 The fact that such danger to the state itself may come from either 
 external or internal assault, makes it necessary to develop the theory 
 of state action with reference to each type of contingency. This 
 gives the classification of the material of this division into two 
 sections. 
 
 We come then to the specific teachings of the book. Since 
 Justi is much more significant as an epitomizer of the whole 
 cameralistic movement than as an original contributor to the 
 theory, it is necessary for our purpose to present the most 
 complete survey possible of his principal doctrines. We have 
 therefore compressed the most important sections in the volume 
 into a series of brief propositions, viz.: 
 
 1. A republic enjoys external security when it is fortified against 
 conquest and even against the excessive power of a neighboring 
 state (p. 72). 
 
 2. Interest is the moving spring of all actions of states, and when 
 two peoples insist on their irreconcilable interests war is the con- 
 sequence (p. 72). 
 
 3. Hence two things are necessary: first, discreet conduct to- 
 ward other free powers; and, second, a sufficient army (p. 73). 
 
 4. Discreet conduct toward other states involves: first, knowl- 
 edge of all other European states; second, adequate knowledge of 
 the home state, its physical and personal make-up (p. 74). 
 
 5. A state must perfectly understand the nature of its relations 
 to other states, the previous history of those relations, etc. (p. 76). 
 
 6. The so-called "balance of power" in Europe is an academic 
 invention. If there were such a system no one would have less 
 cause to conform to it than the house of Austria (p. 77). 
 
 7. A state must observe natural law, the law of nations, and the 
 social duties toward other states (p. 78).' 
 
 1 A note qualifies the proposition by asserting that this must never go 
 so far as the making of apologies by one state to another.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 333 
 
 8. A state must seek to discover the movements and intentions 
 of other states (p. 79). 
 
 9. For the foregoing purpose the most able and discreet men 
 must be selected as ambassadors (p. 80). 
 
 10. But no pains must be spared to get the necessary imforma- 
 tion by secret means (p. 81). 
 
 11. No state should invent schemes for the disadvantage of 
 others which would be disgraceful if discovered (p. 81). 
 
 12. When a state discovers such secret machinations, it often 
 performs a good service by informing the court of the country in 
 whose interest the plans are made, that the plot is known. This 
 usually leads to abandonment of the scheme (p. 82). 
 
 13. When the plan is abhorrent to natural and international 
 law, or to fidelity and faith, it may be made known at other courts 
 (p. 8a). 
 
 14. Discretion demands that the blame be put on the ministers, 
 not on the sovereign (p. 82). 
 
 15. A state must be particularly on its guard against another 
 state in which such a plot has been discovered, even though it was 
 dropped. The same animus is likely to hatch another (p. 82). 
 
 16. Measures for the foregoing purpose consist usually in advan- 
 tageous alliances, which are of two sorts, offensive and defensive, 
 each of which requires its own sort of consideration (p. 83).' 
 
 17. Allies against a hostile power must be sought among those 
 whose interests and policies are identical with ours (p. 86). 
 
 18. Guarantees, and other treaties, by which free powers 
 promise aid in stipulated cases, are also means of security for a 
 state (p. 89). 
 
 19. Another protection against outbreak or extension of war, 
 is the treaty guaranteeing the neutrality of a given territory (p. 87). 
 
 20. Frequently some European power, under a particularly 
 energetic prince, threatens to subordinate the rest of Europe. Then 
 a wise monarch is both privileged and bound to adopt means to 
 keep such a prince within proper limits (p. 88). 
 
 * Justi has a long note on this subject in which he takes decidedly 
 advanced ground against war except for the most important reasons. 
 Vide 56, p. 88, last sentence.
 
 334 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 21. Such measures vary according to circumstances, but they 
 must not include treachery (pp. 88-90). 
 
 22. Discreet conduct toward the other free powers is not a 
 guarantee of external security, but other means of defense will be 
 required (p. 92). 
 
 23. The chief of these is an adequate army (p. 92). 
 
 24. Recruits from the inhabitants of the state are preferable to 
 foreign mercenaries (p. 93). 
 
 25. The army must be in constant readiness for war (p. 95). 
 
 26. There are three ways to make an army brave and invincible: 
 (i) By honors and rewards, together with appeals to love of country, 
 after the example of the Romans; (2) by granting license to plunder 
 and ravish, as in the case of Tamerlain, Attila, etc.; (3) by main- 
 taining discipline through fear of punishment. The third only is 
 to be recommended (p. 97). 
 
 27. In a well-ordered state the military budget must take pre- 
 cedence of everything else (p. 98). 
 
 28. The monarch should be commander-in-chief of the army 
 (p. 99). 
 
 29. Fortifications are another means of security (p. 100). 
 
 30. Maritime nations also require a fleet (p. 101). 
 
 31. Incidental to these latter, various munitions of war must be 
 collected (p. 102). 
 
 32. Resort must be had in extremes to troops furnished by 
 allies, and to mercenaries (p. 103). 
 
 33. It is most advantageous when the allies make separate 
 invasions of the enemy's territory (p. 104). 
 
 34. It is a question whether subsidizing revolt in an enemy's 
 territory is a permissible means of security (p. 105). 
 
 35. It is permissible to destroy an enemy's trade and commerce 
 (p. 106). 
 
 36. Non-permissible means of defense are: assassination of the 
 hostile monarch or his ministers; bribed incendiarism, murder, or 
 similar treacherous violence; poisoned weapons; violation of truce. 
 
 ON THE DOMESTIC SECURITY OF A STATE 
 
 37. The domestic security of a state consists in such a well- 
 ordered constitution of the same that all parts of the civic body are
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 335 
 
 held in their appropriate correlation, and in the consequent repose, 
 while the persons and property of individuals are protected against 
 all injustice and violence (p. 108). 
 
 38. For the above purpose each class in the state must be 
 required to keep its appropriate place (p. 108). 
 
 39. The relation which subjects must observe toward the state, 
 as well as toward each other, is based on a moral foundation. A 
 wise government therefore will have a care for the religious failh 
 which the people profess (p. 109). 
 
 40. The state must care for the administration of justice (p. no). 
 
 41. The state must protect the subjects against frauds and vio- 
 lence (p. in). 
 
 ON THE ATTENTION OF THE RULER TO THE EXTERNAL CONDITION 
 
 OF CLASSES AND THEIR RELATION TO THE STATE 
 
 AND TO ONE ANOTHER 
 
 42. No one should be permitted to gain so much power and 
 wealth that he might be dangerous to the state or to his fellow- 
 citizens (p. 112). 
 
 43. The ruler has nothing to fear from the wealth of his subjects 
 if it is not too unequally distributed (p. 113). 
 
 44. The ruler must first of all give his attention to securing 
 the best talent for the high offices of state and of the army (p. 114). 
 
 45. No officer should be allowed to gain enough power to be 
 dangerous to the state (p. 114). 
 
 46. Hence no officer should be intrusted with lettres de cachet 
 (p. 114). 
 
 47. Offices should not be hereditary (p. 114). 
 
 48. Neither at court nor in the state should there be different 
 parties (p. 115). 
 
 49. No special class, family, or single person should be allowed 
 to gain so much power that disobedience to the supreme power 
 would be safe (p. 116). 
 
 50. No one should be permitted to possess fortifications or 
 maintain an armed force (p. 116). 
 
 51. Subjects should not be allowed to attach themselves to 
 foreign powers (p. 116).' 
 
 1 A note applies this proposition particularly to the Jesuits.
 
 33 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 52. No privileges should be permitted to subjects which are 
 harmful either to the state or to other subjects (p. 117). 
 
 53. No class should be permitted to monopolize the riches of 
 the country (p. up). 1 
 
 54. The ruler must not disregard the feelings of the subjects 
 toward himself or his ministers (p. 120). 
 
 55. The ruler must use all the wisdom possible in governing his 
 conduct in case disorders arise (p. 121). 
 
 ON THE ATTENTION OF THE RULER TO THE MORAL CONDITION 
 OF SUBJECTS, PARTICULARLY THEIR RELIGION AND CONDUCT 
 
 56. The moral condition of the subjects must be such as will 
 accord with the welfare of the state (Wohlfahrt des Stoats), and pro- 
 mote internal security (p. 122). 
 
 57. The ruler must not allow his own religious opinions to be 
 the sole criterion of the goodness or badness of the religion of his 
 subjects; but he must always treat that religion as true which has 
 been introduced by the fundamental principles and constitutions of 
 the state or by the treaties of his predecessors (p. 123). 
 
 58. The regent must nevertheless attempt to establish unity of 
 faith among his subjects (p. 124). 
 
 59. On the other hand the welfare of the state must be preferred 
 to unity of faith (p. 124). 
 
 60. The ruler must prevent the introduction of opinions about 
 religion which are blasphemous and disgraceful, and which tend to 
 demoralize the character of the subjects (p. 125). 
 
 61. For the forgoing reason, a censorship of books must be 
 established (p. 126).' 
 
 62. The ruler must try to stimulate the intelligence of his 
 subjects (p. 128). 
 
 63. The ruler should use the thousand means which are at his 
 disposal to put premiums on personal virtues of all kinds (p. 128). 
 
 1 Again a note states that this has special reference to the Jesuits, 
 and intimates that the author's teaching in this spirit in Vienna was one 
 of the causes of his becoming persona non grata. 
 
 * The qualifications which Justi adds would seem to the modern 
 mind sufficient to nullify the proposition itself.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 337 
 
 64. Yet the ruler must not go so far as to pry into the family 
 life of unsuspected persons (p. 130). 
 
 65. The ruler must not deny the subjects innocent pleasures 
 (P- 131)- 
 
 ON THE ADMINISTRATION OF JUSTICE 
 
 66. The supreme power must adjust strife between subjects 
 over property, pursuits, and transactions, and the decision must 
 rest on the constitution of the republic and on the principles of 
 morals (p. 132). 
 
 67. The administration of justice is to be distinguished from 
 the science of law. It belongs partly to statecraft, partly to Policey 
 
 (P- 132)- 
 
 68. The laws must correspond with the condition of the 
 community, with the character of the various groupings of the 
 subjects, and with the particular purposes which a wise government 
 proposes (p. 133). 
 
 69. The laws must be plain and intelligible (p. 134). 
 
 70. The laws must be brief and simple (p. 135). 
 
 71. Good laws will be in vain unless the government selects men 
 of high character for judges (p. 137).' 
 
 72. Even then the judges cannot be trusted without careful 
 supervision (p. 138). 
 
 73. Before all things the administration of justice must be non- 
 partisan (p. 139). 
 
 74. The judicial procedure must be prompt and brief (p. 139). 
 
 75. It would promote justice if the costs of court procedure 
 should be defrayed by the state and not by the litigants (p. 140).' 
 
 ON THE MEASURES OF THE RULER FOR SECURING THE PERSONS 
 AND GOODS OF SUBJECTS 
 
 76. Domestic security demands that the persons and goods 
 of subjects shall be safe (p. 141). 
 
 1 Just! cites the French Parliament as an example of a wise arrange- 
 ment of influence upon the ruler in an unlimited monarchy, from the 
 judicial department. He apparently had no suspicion of the verdict 
 which the Revolution was about to pass upon that same Parliament. 
 
 * Justi speaks on this point as though he considered his opinion 
 utterly impractical.
 
 338 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 77. This safety must be assured both against domestic and 
 foreign violence or fraud (p. 142). 
 
 78. Nations frequently regard the traders of another nation as 
 legitimate booty (p. 142). 
 
 79. Nations sometimes kidnap, the subjects of other nations 
 for soldiers (p. 143). 
 
 80. Nations sometimes encourage special sorts of lotteries, or 
 other fraudulent schemes for obtaining the property of the subjects 
 of other nations (p. 144). 
 
 81. The worst sort of domestic violence is nocturnal robbery 
 and murder, whether on country roads, the streets of cities, or in 
 private houses (p. 145). 
 
 82. If we seek the sources of these evils, they are to be found 
 chiefly in the defective education of youth, and in the consequent 
 excesses of adults, the scarcity of food in the country, or the defective 
 impulse to perform remunerative work, the oppression of the land 
 under heavy taxation and other wrongs of government (p. 145). 
 
 83. A wise ruler would not have much difficulty in adopting 
 measures which would remove these conditions (p. 146). 
 
 84. Meanwhile the minor civic officials must be required to 
 keep sharp watch of criminals (p. 146).' 
 
 85. Frequent visitations of roads, forests, and suspicious houses, 
 and the use of the militia on country roads and at night in the streets 
 of towns, are advisable. Also the closing of public houses at an 
 appointed time, and sharp watch of them after that hour, while 
 the watchmen themselves must be subject to the severest punish- 
 ments, if they take bribes to allow criminals to escape (p. 147). 
 
 86. Thieves are on the whole more dangerous to security than 
 robbers and murderers, and must consequently l>e zealously traced 
 and punished (p. 147). 
 
 87. Vagabonds of all sorts must be driven from the country 
 (p. 148). 
 
 88. Watch must be kept at the boundaries against such classes, 
 
 1 Again Justi, whether facetiously or as a mere excursus in academic 
 utopianism it is impossible to decide, suggests that it would be well to 
 imitate the Chinese custom of docking the pay of officials if they failed 
 to apprehend robbers or murderers within six months of the crime.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 339 
 
 and householders must be required to report the names and circum- 
 stances of the people who lodge with them (p. 149). 
 
 89. It is a question whether a wise government should tolerate 
 Jews. They surely cause much harm by their usury and sharp 
 practices. Yet it is also a question whether they have not been 
 forced to these and even criminal practices by the policies of govern- 
 ments toward them. Probably if they were admitted to all means of 
 gaining a livelihood they would be as useful to a land as other sub- 
 jects (p. 150). 
 
 90. A wise government must finally punish with severity all 
 other kinds of violence, such as duelling, outbreaks of apprentices, 
 and all ways of taking private steps to supplant the law in meting 
 out justice (p. 151). 
 
 91. To prevent these evils, the law itself must efficiently treat 
 the conditions which they are intended to correct (p. 151). 
 
 ON THE RICHES OF THE STATE 
 
 92. Besides security, sufficient wealth is necessary to the hap- 
 piness of a state (p. 152). 
 
 93. By the wealth of a country we understand a sufficient supply 
 of goods to satisfy the needs and conveniences of life, and by means 
 of which the subjects by diligence and labor may find adequate 
 sustenance (p. 15 2).' 
 
 94. Such being the nature of wealth, if a land yielded an abun- 
 dance of such useful things, and had no trade relations with other 
 lands, we might call it rich, even though it contained no trace of 
 gold and silver (p. 152). 
 
 95. Because of international transactions we need a ware 
 [Wo0re] which is rare, to which all peoples assign equal value, which 
 is durable and easily carried, to be used as a universal means of pay- 
 ment (p. 153). 
 
 96. Gold and silver possess these qualifications. Consequently 
 a land cannot be regarded as rich today unless it possesses a sufficient 
 supply (genugsame Mengc) of these metals (p. 153). 
 
 1 It is obvious at a glance that this description !s an unanalyzed 
 compound which presently had to be decomposed into the concepts, 
 "wealth" and "capital."
 
 340 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 97. Token currency is in no proper sense an addition to national 
 wealth, although it may be a means of increasing wealth (p. 154). 
 
 98. If a ruler could circulate token currency at will, he could 
 gradually absorb the whole national wealth (p. 155). 
 
 99. Such currency ought not to be used unless a definite term 
 is fixed for its redemption (p. 155). 
 
 100. We must distinguish (a) the wealth of the ruler; (6) the 
 wealth of private persons; (c) the wealth of the land (p. 155). 
 
 101. Gold, silver, and costly ornaments stored in the treasure- 
 chests of the monarch are of no use to the country and would not 
 alone tend to remove the land from poverty (p. 155). 
 
 102. The same is the case if there are many rich persons in a 
 country who either hoard their wealth, or keep it in foreign banks 
 
 (P- 155)- 
 
 103. The true conception of national wealth then is that it 
 
 consists of an adequate supply of money, distributed among the 
 subjects, employed in gainful pursuits, and constantly passing from 
 one hand to another (p. 156). 
 
 104. In order that the people may be able by labor and diligence 
 not only to support themselves but to supply the needs of the state, 
 the ruler must see (a) that all measures are taken which secure the 
 necessary means of increasing wealth; (b) that all necessary means 
 are used to insure the constant employment of this wealth in gainful 
 ways, and the circulation of it from hand to hand (p. 156). 
 
 ON INCREASE OF THE WEALTH OF THE STATE 
 
 105. A state cannot increase its wealth without guarding what 
 it already possesses. The first rule of a wise government therefore 
 should be to prevent by all possible means the unnecessary removal 
 of money from the country (p. 157). 
 
 106. This involves stopping, by the court, of purchases of 
 foreign goods and discouragement of customs which tend to take 
 the money of private persons out of the country (p. 157). * 
 
 1 The item chiefly in Justi's thought at this point is the custom of 
 deposit in foreign banks, and the antidote which he proposes is such a 
 firmly established domestic bank system that a premium will be put on 
 keeping the funds at home.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 341 
 
 107. The second fundamental rule of a wise government must 
 be that there should be constant effort to increase the wealth of the 
 state, for a land cannot be too rich (p. 158). 
 
 108. On the other hand riches must not be increased at the cost 
 of oppressing other peoples, for such means of obtaining wealth 
 demoralize those who so obtain it. The chief cause of the fall of the 
 Persian and Roman monarchies is to be found in their disregard of 
 this principle (p. 158). 
 
 109. There are three chief ways of increasing the wealth of a 
 land: (i) the increase of population; (2) foreign commerce; (3) 
 mining. 
 
 ON INCREASE OF THE POPULATION OF A COUNTRY 
 
 no. Increase of the population increases the means of a 
 country both because the newcomers bring goods into the country, 
 and because they stimulate circulation of money (p. 160). 
 
 in. It is thus certain that large population makes a state 
 prosperous provided its constitution is beneficent. 1 The talents of 
 the persons in the republic, indeed the persons themselves, are 
 among the resources of the state. The larger the number of people 
 living in the country therefore, the greater will be the means and 
 power of the republic. Hence the duty of the ruler to promote 
 increase of population (p. 160). 
 
 112. It is often asked whether a population cannot become too 
 great, so that some will obstruct the happiness of the rest. Nothing 
 is so unfounded as this objection. Given flourishing commerce, 
 manufactures, and trades, with well-administered police and govern- 
 ment in general, and there is no good reason why the population 
 should stop at any particular point. Holland and China are evidence 
 to this effect (p. 161). 
 
 113. There is no reason to fear that population could overtax 
 the food supply. Europe could feed six times its present popula- 
 tion (p. 162). 
 
 ' The expression is " seine Bescha/enkeit und Regierungrverfassuug." 
 This seems to be one of the rare cases in the cameralistic books of use 
 of the term Verfassung very nearly in the modern sense. Vide above, 
 PP- 34, 70.
 
 342 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 114. If we had wise police and economic administration, there 
 would be no need of allowing emigration to America (p. 163).' 
 
 115. To encourage increase of population the government in 
 the first place must be beneficent and mild (p. 164). 
 
 1 16. As a particular under this generalization, reasonable freedom 
 must be permitted to the subjects (p. 165). 
 
 117. The growth of population is scarcely possible unless the 
 ruler permits complete freedom of conscience (p. 165). 
 
 118. Freedom of conscience must be distinguished from complete 
 freedom of religious liberty. The latter is to be granted only under 
 approved conditions. The former, consisting of rights of belief and 
 household worship, should be allowed in so far as it is not harmful 
 to the state (p. 165). 
 
 119. A wise ruler will not leave the food supply and employ- 
 ment of subjects to take care of themselves, but will see that they 
 are systematically made abundant (p. 167). 
 
 1 20. Still further, the government must encourage the immigra- 
 tion of rich and talented people of all kinds, and may resort to titles, 
 honors, positions, and privileges as premiums to them (p. 168). 
 
 121. So far as possible, the government should relieve new- 
 comers who wish to build, of the taxes, building-permit fees, etc. 
 (p. 168). 
 
 122. Special encouragement must be given to skilled foreigners 
 who wish to introduce into the country desirable industries (p. 169). 
 
 123. The ruler should see that the laws are favorable to the 
 marriage relation (p. 170).' 
 
 124. A wise Catholic ruler will try to limit the growth of the 
 clerical orders, for they arc largely responsible for the unfavorable 
 contrast in population between Catholic and Protestant countries 
 (P- 173)- 
 
 1 The pious reflection is subjoined: "Nevertheless we must bow to 
 the wise providence of God, which perhaps in this way will make the 
 most remote regions of the earth moral, reasonable, and enlightened in 
 religion." 
 
 Certain fines and penalties for celibate men are suggested, and 
 it is further hinted that instead of requiring a payment to the government 
 for permission to marry, a reward should be given for marrying.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 343 
 
 125. A wise ruler will consider seriously the point of view of 
 population, before entering into war. He will especially encourage 
 all means of diminishing sickness and of preventing plague (p. 173). 
 
 126. A wise government will check drunkenness and other de- 
 moralizing vices (p. 173). 
 
 127. The art of medicine must be brought to the highest efficiency 
 (p. 174). 
 
 128. Surgery, midwifery, and pharmacy must for the same reason 
 be encouraged and regulated by the government (p. 175). 
 
 129. Provision must be made for assuring purity of foods (p. 175). 
 
 130. The cleanliness of cities must be assured, and this requires 
 attention to the building regulations (p. 176). 
 
 ON COMMERCE WITH FOREIGN PEOPLES 
 
 131. Commerce is transactions in means of sustenance in which 
 the goods and wares are exchanged with advantage either against gold 
 and silver, or against other wares, and by this process the needs and 
 conveniences of human life are satisfied. This explanation includes 
 everything which belongs to the nature of commerce and to com- 
 prehension of it (p. 177). 
 
 132. Only foreign commerce can increase the wealth of a land 
 
 (P- 178). 
 
 133. The first principle of commerce must be that more gold 
 and silver shall be brought in than carried out by it (p. 178). 
 
 OF KNOWLEDGE OF THE NATURE OF COMMERCE 
 
 134. The first distinction to be made is between goods produced 
 at home and those obtained from abroad (p. 179). 
 
 135. When commerce is carried on with domestic wares, the 
 wealth of the land always gains something by it, but this kind of 
 commerce may nevertheless be very disadvantageous to the state; 
 for if the wares are carried from the country in the raw and untrans- 
 formed condition, or arc drawn from foreign nations, the land loses 
 considerably from the earnings and support of subjects which might 
 have been enjoyed from the same (p. 180).' 
 
 * This paragraph is translated as literally as possible; the obscurity 
 is in the original.
 
 344 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 136. When commerce is conducted with foreign wares alone, 
 this is either because these wares are to be consumed at home, or 
 because they are to be traded, with profit, to other nations. The 
 first sort of commerce is wholly harmful to a country; for although 
 the special traders, certain commercial cities, and the tariff and 
 excise accounts of the ruler may temporarily profit, the land as a 
 whole cannot gain anything by such trade. On the contrary, if it has 
 no other sources of wealth, it must gradually lose all its gold and 
 silver, and this harmful trade must at last stop from lack of means 
 of payment (p. 180). 
 
 137. The second sort of foreign trade is incomparably more 
 profitable for the state (p. 181). 
 
 138. There is a great difference in goods with respect to the 
 source, or the lands from which they are derived. The trader must 
 know all about the differences, and he must know whether he receives 
 them from the first, second, or third hand, and where they can with 
 profit be sold. The cameralist, however, must know them so far 
 that he can judge what sorts are most advantageous for the entire 
 system of commerce, and for domestic manufacture, or with which 
 kinds the land may most easily carry on profitable trade (p. 182). 
 
 139. Another difference in wares springs from their essential 
 nature and composition. That is, they may be rough or fine, useful 
 or useless, superfluous or necessary, genuine or spurious, fresh or 
 spoiled, etc. Of all these differences, a trader must be fully informed. 
 A civic official in the commercial department must also be somewhat 
 intelligent about these things, in order to promote the transportation 
 of the wares, and properly to assess the duties and excises (p. 182). 
 
 140. There are also differences with respect to their external 
 and accidental condition; i.e., packed or unpacked: to be counted, 
 weighed, or measured; salable or unsalable and contraband the 
 latter only temporarily and in time of war forbidden. Both mer- 
 chants and cameralists need to be informed about these details 
 (P- 183). 
 
 141. These various sorts of goods occasion many sorts of trade; 
 e. g., the customary classification is: (i) Cloth; (2) Silk; (3) Spices; 
 (4) Groceries [Materialien]; (5) Hides and furs [Rauch- und Pelz- 
 handel}; (6) Gold, silver, or jewels; (7) Books. This however is
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 345 
 
 merely an approximate classification, for there may be as many 
 sorts of trade as there are separate sorts of wares. Indeed it is 
 advisable for a trader not to deal in too many wares. If he dares to 
 confine himself to a single one he can more effectively master the 
 conditions of that trade. Small traders who have to look out merely 
 for cost and sale may carry a miscellaneous stock (p. 183). 
 
 142. Trade comprises two chief types of transactions: (a) ob- 
 taining the wares; (b) marketing them (p. 184). 
 
 143. All domestic goods come either from cultivating the earth, 
 or from stock-breeding, or from industries [Gewerben]. As to 
 agriculture, a wise merchant will either himself engage in it, or by 
 advancing loans, storage, and favorable contracts will seek to get 
 the wares at a good price. As to products of stock-raising, he may, 
 by cash payments, by courteous conduct and minor attentions [eine 
 kltine Ergotzlichkeit], get the good-will of the shepherds and other 
 country folk who have such things for sale. The wares, however, 
 which come from the trades, are procured best through the estab- 
 lishment of manufactures and factories. Sometimes advances to the 
 manufacturers and hand-workers will secure the goods. A wise 
 government, on the other hand, will always see to it that all these 
 domestic wares are supplied at the required quality and price, in 
 order that the favorable balance in other countries may be retained 
 (p. 184). 
 
 144. As to obtaining foreign wares, they come either by wagon 
 or by boat from neighboring lands, and in such cases the factors 
 involved are essentially those just named; or they are brought from 
 long distances across seas. For that purpose the merchant must 
 either have ships of his own, if commerce is free to all, or he must 
 buy shares in trading associations, or in the great auctions he must 
 provide himself with the needed wares (p. 185). 
 
 145. By "shares" [Actien] we understand those participating 
 parts which a great privileged trading society at its organization 
 sells at a fixed price, in order thereby to bring in the sums which 
 must be used in the trade of the society. These shares, which there- 
 after may be resold, rise or fall in price, according to the success of 
 the society (p. 185). 
 
 146. Since seafaring is beset with many dangers, a wise mer-
 
 346 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 chant will never risk his whole resources, or a large portion of them, 
 at one time upon the waves. Consequently it is not only customary 
 for many merchants to join in fitting out ships, but many forms of 
 contract have been invented, such as shares in ships, insurance, etc. 
 The most important of these is insurance; that is, another party 
 undertakes to assure the cargo of a ship for a payment of 3, 5, 10, 20, 
 30, or more per hundred, according to the degree of danger to be 
 feared, and in case of loss to make it good (p. 186). 
 
 147. The second chief type of transaction, sale, depends prin- 
 cipally upon good correspondents, who protect the merchant by 
 giving him timely notice of rise and fall of prices and other circum- 
 stances which affect his trade. A good merchant must be able to 
 distinguish between a correspondent who can be relied upon to serve 
 his employer's interests and one who is seeking chiefly his own 
 advantages. The bourse, a house where in great trading centers 
 the merchants daily meet to transact business, is very prolific of such 
 reports, but they cannot be regarded with much confidence (p. 187). 
 
 148. Actual sale is of various kinds: e. g., for cash payment, 
 on credit, on instalments, on exchange, on venture, or on speculation 
 [a raventure ou en /'air], or by means of commission merchants, 
 factors, fairs [Afessen] or similar devices. A merchant must be well 
 instructed about these different sorts of trade, together with the cost 
 of transportation, tariffs, probable dangers, and the prices to be 
 expected, in order that by weighing these items over against one 
 another he may be reasonably assured of profits. He must also 
 assure himself about the reliability of the persons intrusted with the 
 transportation, also concerning the warehouses and other circum- 
 stances of the towns and roads through which the goods must pass 
 (p. 186).' 
 
 149. To keep all these things straight, bookkeeping is necessary. 
 It is customary to use the following books: The inventory book; 
 the manual, or memorial, or chief book; the journal; the debt book; 
 the credit book; the treasury book; the secret book; the stock 
 book; the expense book. All of these must be kept in the greatest 
 
 1 To those who imagine that commercial dishonesty is of recent 
 growth, Justi's note on types of rascality which have to be counted on 
 would furnish valuable information.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 347 
 
 order, and they must exactly correspond with one another. For 
 this reason, in large concerns a special bookkeeper is appointed ( !) 
 (p. 188). 
 
 150. The ultimate purpose of all these transactions is, on the 
 side of the republic, to export goods produced in the country, and 
 not needed, and therefrom to gain increase of wealth, as well as to 
 provide the land with all those goods which are required for the 
 needs and convenience of human life. On the side of the merchant, 
 however, gain is the single purpose of all his endeavor. In view 
 of the service which he renders to the state, of the danger which he 
 incurs, and of the labors which he undertakes, we should not begrudge 
 his gains. They consist in the increase of his goods and of his means. 
 The amount of his goods depends entirely on the value which they 
 have in terms of gold and silver. Consequently the single aim of 
 the merchant is to increase his resources in gold and silver, or in 
 goods which in comparison with these metals have a great value 
 (p. 188).' 
 
 151. Gold and silver is also in fact the ground (sic) of all 
 commerce* carried on in the world or at least among civilized or 
 somewhat intelligent peoples (p. 189). 
 
 152. Because merchants have constant occasion to transfer gold 
 and silver to one another, a large number of devices have been 
 invented to serve their purposes. Thus the important exchanges, 
 and the system of bank credits, whereby gold and silver are trans- 
 ferred only in imagination, yet with the same advantage to the 
 merchant as though the metals were actually delivered. The essence 
 of the matter is that one gives to a third party notice that the sum 
 due can be drawn at a certain place. This simple and natural way 
 of payment is then by the laws, by the different moneys, and other 
 circumstances, surrounded with a multitude of formalities and 
 special details, which today compose a considerable part of the 
 
 1 In such propositions as this, mercantilism seems to be less false 
 than crude and unanalyzed. 
 
 Transliteration of the vague term Grund is probably the best way 
 of indicating the altogether immature character of the thought in this 
 connection.
 
 348 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 science of commerce, not only for the merchant, but also for the 
 cameralist (p. 189). 
 
 153. A bank is a public institution of the state in which mer- 
 chants and other private persons may at will securely deposit sums 
 of money, in such a way that they may withdraw the same any hour, 
 or may use their deposits for payment to other persons by means 
 of the bank-credit system. Banks of this sort are called deposit 
 [Giro] or exchange banks, in distinction from loan banks (p. 190). 
 
 I53A. It must be repeated that not money, but gold and silver, 
 is the chief price and the universal means of payment for all goods. 
 Money, so far as foreigners are concerned with it, is in fact itself 
 nothing but a ware worth just what the gold and silver in it will 
 bring (p. 191).' 
 
 154. Those rulers who coin depreciated money miss their cal- 
 culation in expecting to gain by it. Foreigners will take it only 
 at its true value, and even something less. The bad money therefore 
 returns to the land that coins it. It is paid back by the subjects 
 into the treasury of the ruler, and he deceives himself if he supposes 
 he has in the treasury more than the actual gold and silver. This 
 flattering idea disappears as soon as the attempt is made to purchase 
 abroad. Meanwhile the subjects who have received the money 
 from the ruler at the imaginary value, and who must make foreign 
 purchases, suffer (p. 191). 
 
 155. The persons engaged in trade are either principals, sub- 
 ordinates, or auxiliaries. The duties of each of these classes must 
 be treated in the special textbook on commercial science (p. 192). 
 
 156. The fundamental principles of merchants must be dis- 
 tinguished from the measures and purposes of the government. 
 While the merchant aims only at gain, and is not always concerned 
 whether his gain corresponds with the advantage of the state, a 
 wise government, on the contrary, must give the chief attention to this 
 latter consideration. Hence the merchants may be much dissatis- 
 fied with the regulations of trade. Domestic manufacture and trade 
 are far less inviting to them on this account than the welfare of the 
 
 1 It is rather remarkable that Justi does not state in the same 
 connection that gold and silver are themselves essentially "wares" like 
 any other.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 349 
 
 state demands. It is not to be assumed, however, that the advantage 
 of the whole state is incompatible with the prosperity of the mer- 
 chants. The former may, however, require that the advantages 
 enjoyed by the latter shall be less than at some other periods. Even 
 in this case the merchants may offset the restrictions by interesting 
 themselves in promoting mining, manufactures, etc. (p. 194). 
 
 ON THE FOUNDING AND THE PROSPEROUS CONDITION OF 
 COMMERCE 
 
 157. No European country is entirely without foreign commerce, 
 but some of it is very harmful, and cannot continue without adequate 
 increase of wealth from other sources (p. 195).* 
 
 158. The establishment of commerce presupposes that it will 
 obtain a condition which promises permanence with advantage to 
 the state (p. 195). 
 
 159. The founding of commerce is not a mere matter of ap- 
 pointing and encouraging fairs and markets (p. 195). 
 
 160. If at these markets more foreign than domestic goods are 
 sold, then they are only a great vortex from which more gold flows 
 out than comes in, and the town where the fair is held is the only 
 gainer, and it consequently holds on to its advantage as long as 
 possible, in spite of the general poverty of the country (p. 196). 
 
 161. Prohibition of the exportation of money does not secure 
 profitable commerce. In the first place it cannot be effective, in the 
 second place it would deprive the subjects of many things which 
 their present standard of life requires, and in the third place it 
 could accomplish nothing of itself in the direction of establishing 
 commerce (p. 196). 
 
 162. The first principle of advantageous commerce with foreign 
 nations is, that more gold and silver shall come into the country as 
 a result than goes out, and on this principle must all measures for 
 establishing useful commerce be founded (p. 198). 
 
 163. Since commerce must be carried on either with domestic 
 or foreign goods, and since the mere importation of foreign goods 
 cannot possibly constitute an advantageous trade, there follows 
 naturally another principle, viz. : The value of the domestic products 
 
 1 Vide Proposition 135, above.
 
 35 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 exported must exceed the value of foreign wares imported. The 
 inferences from these two principles will give us all the measures 
 necessary for the establishment of commerce (p. 198). 
 
 164. The excess value of exports over imports can be secured 
 in only two ways: first, the quantity of imported foreign wares must 
 be diminished; or, second, the gaining and exportation of domestic 
 products must be increased (p. 198). 
 
 165. In fact these two methods must be combined in order to 
 assure the result (p. 199). 
 
 166. For this purpose a wise ruler must inform himself pre- 
 cisely about the exported and imported wares and their aggregate 
 values. These facts must be exhibited in tables drawn from the 
 tariff and excise registers, so that they can be reviewed at a glance. 
 For greater exactness the contents of the tariff and excise registers 
 may be tabulated separately and compared with each other. To 
 be still more certain, all merchants, artists, manufacturers, and arti- 
 sans may be required to report what kinds of wares they imported 
 during the previous year, and what domestic products they sent 
 abroad. By these three processes together the facts may be some- 
 what exactly ascertained (p. 199). 
 
 167. We call this casting the general trade balance. The 
 special trade balance is a similar showing of the imports and exports 
 between the home and a specified foreign country. A wise govern- 
 ment will every year keep both accounts (p. 200). 
 
 168. A wise ruler or his ministers will study these tables to 
 discover whether among the imports there are any which could be 
 produced at home, and thereupon it must be made a fixed rule that 
 nothing which can be produced at home shall be imported. The 
 necessary measures must then be adopted to promote production of 
 those wares (p. 200). 
 
 169. In this connection all kinds of textiles call for attention, 
 since they are for clothing and are accordingly necessaries of life. 
 Every land either has materials for these, or can easily get them. 
 Silk-weaving is also possible in northern countries. Wool may be 
 grown everywhere, and the fine wool to be mixed with it may be had 
 through trade, as the English importation of Spanish wool. Hence " 
 such manufacture ought not to be omitted (p. 201).
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 351 
 
 170. Yet foreign trade in such fabrics is not to be expected. 
 Our neighbors, England, Holland, France, and Wales, have already 
 too long start of us. But it will be advantage enough if we check 
 the import of foreign textiles (p. 201).' 
 
 171. The only variation from the last conclusion is in case we 
 can invent such improvement in the fabrics, that we can make 
 foreigners our debtors (p. 202).' 
 
 172. The same principle holds in the case of every sort of ware 
 which might be produced at home. As everything cannot be done 
 at once, beginnings should be made in the case of those wares which 
 are most used at home, and for which the largest sums are now 
 sent abroad (p. 203). 
 
 173. A second rule must be kept in mind along with the first, 
 viz., preference should be given to those industries which would 
 employ and support the most men (p. 203). 
 
 174. A third rule should also be followed, viz., to prefer those 
 industries for which the raw materials are produced at home (p. 204). 
 
 175. On the other hand, those industries must be stimulated 
 which will produce goods that foreign nations need (p. 204). 3 
 
 176. In order to exploit these resources it is necessary for the 
 government to rouse a commercial spirit among the subjects. 4 
 
 177. No monopolies in such domestic products, and no similar 
 privileges should be granted (p. 209). s 
 
 1 In such propositions it appears that Justi's generalization was 
 even narrower than its usual form would indicate. The problem was 
 not even that of the type of state then regarded as permanent, but of the 
 author's particular state. 
 
 Jusli's note on this section is a plea for governmental encourage- 
 ment of inventors. 
 
 3 A considerable list follows of German resources for such supply. 
 
 4 The picture of unthrift and indifference which follows is an im- 
 portant piece of culture-historical evidence. There is also a plea for 
 industrial education which has a truly modern ring, and also suggestions 
 about stimuli to individual effort. 
 
 s The reasons assigned for this rule make against protective tariffs, 
 and all the consequences which Justi suggests have been illustrated on 
 an enormous scale in recent years. Justi adds that this last principle
 
 352 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 178. Assuming such measures for promoting domestic produc- 
 tion, a wise government must give its attention to measures for 
 inducing foreigners to take the wares. Two factors must be assured: 
 (i) The wares must have the desired quality; (2) the price must be 
 satisfactory. It may be added that the beauty of the wares is also 
 a factor (p. an). 
 
 179. In order to insure the quality of wares, the government 
 must not merely promulgate certain ordinances and rules, but it 
 must also appoint certain inspectors who will examine the completed 
 wares, and will mark with a distinguishing sign those which conform 
 to the standards and those which do not. In case, as is certainly 
 advisable, complete freedom from tax shall be permitted to exports, 
 this immunity should extend to those wares only which satisfy this 
 test (p. 212). 
 
 180. It is also often necessary to stimulate production by cer- 
 tain prizes and rewards, and when the court learns that science 
 or skill is lacking for the production of certain wares, every effort 
 must be made to attract people with the necessary qualifications, 
 or by the necessary money payment to get the lacking information 
 from a foreign artist, since everything may be had for money (p. 212).' 
 
 181. If the wares are to be supplied at a favorable price, not only 
 must the articles requisite for supplying the necessities of life be 
 purchasable at moderate prices, for on this depends the amount of 
 the wages of the laborers, but the raw material of the wares must 
 also not be dear. The ruler must accordingly take all possible care 
 that not only agriculture but all the industries that supply the 
 necessities of life shall be in good order, so that no scarcity shall 
 occur, as one industry always sustains another. Before all things, 
 however, those crafts which deal with the necessities of life must 
 
 had come to be recognized in practice at his time. He also remarks that 
 "such privileges can have no validity in themselves," for it is presumed 
 that they are to be allowed only in so far as they make for the welfare 
 of the state, and the successor to the throne can in no way be bound to 
 continue them. He recommends the formation of a special company 
 for exploiting the mineral resources of the country (p. 210). 
 
 1 In a note Justi goes into considerable detail about the sort of 
 specifications that should be prescribed.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 353 
 
 be held under strict supervision, in order that they may not raise 
 prices by charging excessive profits, or by buying up the supply, 
 and other underhanded means (p. 2i4). x 
 
 182. When so much has been done for stimulation of domestic 
 production, it is time to establish fairs and great markets (p. 214). 
 
 183. But flourishing commerce must be described as something 
 more than enough to sustain fairs and markets established under 
 the foregoing conditions. The expression is properly used only 
 when flourishing trade in all sort of wares is carried on with all 
 parts of the world. This is hardly to be thought of unless it is 
 in connection with extensive merchant marine and foreign trade 
 
 (P- 5)- 
 
 184. Assuming that the land borders on the sea and has good 
 harbors, or at least the possibility of making them, or is crossed by a 
 navigable river which is at the command of the country to its mouth, 
 the beginnings of sea-trade may be made by the formation of a great 
 trading society, which can collect the guarantee or the capital for 
 its transactions by the sale of a certain number of shares (p. 216). 
 
 185. In order to induce both natives and foreigners to take 
 shares, either very great privileges must be granted to the society, 
 or the bad condition and management of foreign companies must 
 furnish the necessary stimulus, or the court must offer the company 
 material support. 
 
 186. The success of such a company depends principally upon 
 good management of its affairs. The court must consequently do 
 its best to insure the election of directors whose insight, talent, 
 diligence, and integrity are grounds for confidence; and the minister 
 of commerce and marine, who should possess all these qualities in 
 the highest degree, must know how to lead these directors in accord- 
 ance with his purposes (p. 217). 
 
 187. Such a company must be guarded against dangerous enter- 
 prises and needless outlay. A few unfortunate investments will 
 not only ruin the company, but it will be much harder for the state 
 afterward to bring about the formation of a new company (p. 217). 
 
 188. The power and prestige of the monarch go far toward the 
 
 i This paragraph gives more evidence of economic insight than any 
 that have preceded.
 
 354 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 success of such a company. Other nations that carry on foreign 
 trade look with jealous eyes on such a company, and try in every 
 way to put obstacles before it. The power of the monarch, however, 
 restrains them within such limits, that they cannot openly antagonize 
 it (p. 217). 
 
 189. It is proper that possession of a certain number of shares 
 should be a condition of sitting and voting in the meetings of such 
 a company. It is not so certain that a similar condition should 
 hedge election of directors, because it is not at all certain that wealth 
 enough to own shares is combined with the necessary qualifications 
 for such an office (p. 218). 
 
 190. It is a prime condition of success that such companies 
 start with sufficient capital for large operations (p. 218). 
 
 191. It must be insisted that the predominant effort of such 
 companies should be to sell domestic goods in foreign lands. If 
 they only bring in goods directly from foreign lands which have 
 previously been bought from middle-men, a saving of middle-men's 
 profits and of transportation charges of foreign ships is made, to be 
 sure; but nevertheless the money to defray the first cost of the goods 
 goes out of the country (p. 219). 
 
 192. Such a trading society must not count on founding estab- 
 lishments in distant lands at once, but must plan to gain them grad- 
 ually; i. e., not until they can pay good dividends to the share- 
 holders, and until there is a comfortable capital in reserve, so that 
 the cost of foreign establishments may be covered out of the reserve 
 without diminishing the dividends (p. 221). Such gains take large 
 fractions of the capital; societies formed by other countries, and 
 already operating there, conduct minor warfare with competitors, 
 and the monarchs cannot regard their quarrels as sufficient grounds 
 for actual war. If one such society is ruined under these conditions, 
 it is all the harder for subsequent ones to succeed (p. 219).' 
 
 193. When the trade of such a commercial company becomes 
 flourishing it is possible to organize other companies to operate 
 in the same territory in particular lines of goods. It is preferable, 
 
 1 Justi testifies to scruples, which must have passed as altogether 
 Utopian, about the grounds in justice for exploiting the territories of 
 weaker people.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 355 
 
 however, to sell more shares and expand the operations of a single 
 company. This prevents harmful jealousies, cross-purposes, and 
 manifold loss of advantage by the home company (p. 223). 
 
 194. After all, such companies are not absolutely essential to 
 the promotion of foreign commerce. Even if they have been used 
 to establish trade, the time may come when expansion of trade will 
 be best assured by opening it freely to all mariners and merchants 
 (p. 223).' 
 
 ON THE AUXILIARIES [Huljsmittef] TO COMMERCE 
 
 195. First of all we must name among the conditions of pro- 
 moting commerce, a mild government, and reasonable freedom of 
 conscience and action, as in the case of domestic prosperity. 3 People 
 engaged in foreign trade must for special reasons enjoy these immu- 
 nities, because they have special facilities for withdrawing their wealth 
 from the country (p. 225). 
 
 196. Second, a wise ordering of the tariff and excise system 
 is the principal means by which a wise government can guide foreign 
 commerce according to its purposes. Instead of being detrimental 
 to trade, since traders always have their own interest in view more 
 than that of the state, and it would be ruinous to leave the ways and 
 means of commerce to their enterprise, no trade can be carried on in 
 a way that is advantageous to the state which is not in this way 
 guided, controlled, and to a certain extent promoted (p. 226). 
 
 197. For purposes of tariff and excise, wares are of three classes: 
 (i) for export; (2) for import; (3) for transport. Wares of the 
 first class are either fully manufactured, or in raw or partially manu- 
 factured condition; those of the second class are either indispensable 
 or dispensable. Accordingly the tariff and excise laws must take 
 account of five classes of wares, and this makes five primary rules 
 necessary (p. 227). 
 
 198. RULE i. All exports of tnanufactured goods must be 
 
 i Justi fortifies this opinion by citing the opposition in England to 
 the great trading companies, and he expresses the judgment that they 
 had become more harmful than useful to the British Empire. On the 
 other hand he thinks it is not time for Holland to abolish the Dutch 
 East India Company (p. 225). 
 
 Vide above, Propositions 115-18.
 
 356 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 burdened with light imposts. The one profitable kind of trade 
 consists in commerce of this class, and a wise ruler must not merely 
 take care that the goods themselves are of high quality, but he must 
 see that foreigners are stimulated to take them. It is poor encour- 
 agement to foreign buyers to lay a tax on such goods. The exporta- 
 tion is of itself such an advantage to the state, that it is unnecessary 
 to burden it with imposts which make against the ultimate use of 
 exportation (p. 227).* 
 
 199. The only exception to this rule is in case the home products 
 are so cheap, or transportation is so cheap and easy, that the exports 
 can undersell competing products of foreign countries. Even in 
 this case, export taxes should not be imposed on articles the home 
 production of which is capable of indefinite expansion. It is better 
 to give the home merchants the opportunity to make the profit, so 
 that they will be stimulated to increase the volume of trade to the 
 utmost (p. 228). 
 
 200. Another corollary from this rule is that very low imposts 
 should be placed on raw materials when they are moved from one 
 part of the country to another for the purpose of being manufactured 
 (p. 229).' 
 
 20 1. RULE 2. Export o] raw material which is a home product 
 must either be heavily taxed or entirely prohibited (230). 
 
 202. RULE 3. All imports of dispensable wares must carry 
 heavy imposts; for if they are really dispensable the importation 
 brings the country great harm by useless foreign expenditure of money 
 (p. 23i).3 
 
 203. RULE 4. Imports of indispensable wares should bear only 
 light imposts. Tariff and imposts should not be the ordinary way 
 of collecting tribute from the subjects. They are justified as a 
 source of revenue only by some subsidiary purpose. Their main 
 purpose should be to direct the course of commerce (p. 231). 
 
 < Justi cites the wisdom of countries which put premiums on expor- 
 tation. 
 
 * Justi's illustration of harm to the book trade through taxation of 
 paper might be quoted as prophetic. 
 
 3 The author's discriminations between degrees and types of dis- 
 pensability are sociologically interesting.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 357 
 
 304. It follows that foreign raw material needed for chief or 
 subordinate purposes in home manufacture should be free of import 
 duties (p. 232). 
 
 205. RULE 5. Goods in transport should be free of imposts, 
 with the exception of trifling tolls (p. 232). 
 
 206. The only exception to this rule is when the carriage of an 
 article through the country takes a market away from a home product, 
 in which case we must be sure that imposition of high taxes would 
 not lead to reprisals (p. 232). 
 
 207. All the servants of the taxing system must be held under 
 strict discipline, both against 'peculation, and against needless 
 vexation of travelers (p. 233). 
 
 208. Commercial treaties with foreign countries are the next 
 most important means of promoting commerce (p. 235). 
 
 209. Next in order are good harbors and roads, and passable 
 rivers and canals (p. 236). 
 
 210. A well-organized system of posts, boats, and land carriers 
 is a further desideratum (p. 237). 
 
 211. The coinage is an essential factor of flourishing trade 
 (p. 238).* 
 
 212. Unpartisan and prompt rendering of justice in all trade 
 litigation greatly promotes business (p. 240). 
 
 213. To this end special commercial courts, both original and 
 
 For its bearing on the content of Justi's mercantilism, the note at 
 this point is worth translating in full, viz.: "There can be no doubt that 
 a low rate of exchange is very harmful for a country, and there are two 
 chief circumstances which put the exchange of a country on a bad foot- 
 ing: (i) when it must annually pay a large sum to other nations to 
 settle the trade balance; (2) when its coinage is depreciated. A land 
 which finds itself in these bad conditions is in a sorry plight. Bad will 
 go toward worse through the workings of exchange. All in all the coin- 
 age today is in an unspeakably bad condition. Under it twenty million 
 people suffer extreme disadvantage, and only in the neighborhood of 
 fifty dealers in coin [Miinzlieferantcn] and fifty money-changers enrich 
 themselves as leeches by sucking the blood of their neighbors. In such 
 a situation it would be a thousand times better that we had no coinage 
 at all, but simply settled our balances in gold and silver by weight " 
 (P-
 
 35 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 appellate, should be organized. They should be composed in part 
 of legal experts, in part of merchants, capable of bringing the most 
 exact technical knowledge to interpretation of the laws (p. 240). 
 
 214. The most flourishing commerce is hardly possible unless 
 the ruler organizes a special bureau of commerce. This must be 
 composed of members who, along with proved integrity, fidelity, and 
 wisdom, possess complete knowledge of trade, and especially of 
 civic-commercial science; and it is particularly advisable that no 
 merchants should be members of the bureau, because their purposes 
 are often different from those of the state. 1 In the largest countries 
 a special subordinate bureau may be organized for manufactures. 
 In this bureau former merchants and mining experts may be useful. 
 In both bureaus individuals must be placed in charge of divisions 
 of operations with which they are particularly acquainted, and 
 consequently only the most important and general matters should 
 be handled by the whole body. In every important seaport or 
 commercial center there should be at least one commercial councilor, 
 to supervise commercial and manufacturing relations at that point 
 under the provisions of the two bodies (p. 240). 
 
 215. Finally, a wise government must take care to remove all 
 obstacles which may embarrass commerce. These may come 
 either from foreign or domestic causes. Thus, under the former 
 head, war between other powers, with incidental hindrances to our 
 commerce; secret machinations of other powers against our foreign 
 traders, etc.* Among domestic hindrances may be named: Scarcity 
 of materials for shipbuilding and other production; lack of capital 
 in the country; existing privileges of certain lands and towns in the 
 matter of imports and exports of staples; the envy and jealousy of 
 certain lands and towns toward one another, etc. (p. 241). 
 
 ON MINES AS A MEANS OF INCREASING THE WEALTH OF A COUNTRY 
 
 The plan of this study excludes, as far as practicable, 
 consideration of opinions about merely technical, adminis- 
 
 ' Vide Prop. 156. 
 
 * A naive discussion follows in a note, as to whether the spirit of the 
 Christian religion permits a state to buy immunity from piracy of non- 
 Christian powers; and the comforting conclusion is reached that the 
 Christian religion surely cannot oppose any arrangements which make 
 for the real welfare of the state (p. 243).
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 359 
 
 trative, or operative details. We are concerned with the 
 main problems which cameralism proposed, and the relation 
 of the formulas and solutions which cameralism offered to the 
 development of social science in general. In order to fix 
 with certainty the meaning of the essential theories, we must 
 admit much evidence that is contained in subordinate details. 
 The importance of these minor applications in the routine 
 rules of the cameralists diminishes from this point, as we have 
 already epitomized the cardinal doctrines which reflected the 
 peculiar circumstances of the period, and which were modified 
 after the circumstances changed. At the same time, we have 
 seen in these characteristic theories some of the presumptions, 
 both theoretical and practical, which have retained, and in 
 some ways have gathered force in later German thinking. 
 These views have encouraged tendencies in German policy 
 which, for better or for worse, have produced evident con- 
 trasts between the civic and economic systems of Germany 
 on the one hand and of England and America on the other. 
 It will not be necessary to reproduce the remainder of Justi's 
 system as fully as the sections have been represented thus far. 
 It is in point however to translate in full the opening para- 
 graphs of the portion devoted to mining. The redundancy 
 of statement is a fair index of Justi's usual style. He says 
 (pp. 243 ff): 
 
 We come now to the third chief means by which the riches of a 
 country may be increased, viz., mining, whenever the natural 
 resources of the country include mineral deposits. In Germany 
 these resources are by no means rare. Few states of any size in our 
 Fatherland are without them. Yet the population of most parts of 
 the country lacks inclination to develop the mines, and the govern- 
 ments have not taken adequate interest in this source of riches. 
 Nevertheless this is almost the sole way in which well-founded hopes 
 may be cherished of increasing the riches of the country. Germany 
 has at only a few points facilities for navigation. In this respect, 
 as well as in manufactures, our neighbors have such a long start
 
 360 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of us, that we should he very foolish if we reckoned on more through 
 these means than merely retaining our money at home. Since, 
 moreover, the neighboring countries are giving more and more 
 attention to keeping their rich inhabitants at home, our mining 
 operations are in fact the only probable means by which riches in 
 the various states of Germany may be increased. 
 
 Since in our enlightened times the intelligence requisite for the 
 government of states has greatly increased, almost all European 
 states are exceptionally alert to prevent the outflow of money from 
 the country. In France, England, and Holland, careful reckoning 
 is kept of the wares annually sold to foreign nations, and of the 
 wares bought from the same nations. If attention to these subjects 
 continues, in fifty years it may easily occur that commercial treaties 
 will set limits to the amount of goods that a nation may annually 
 take from another. The same foresight will be used with reference 
 to the other ways by which money is drawn from the country. There- 
 upon the mines will be the only means of increasing the wealth of 
 the country. This resource alone is completely in our power, and 
 no counter-enterprises of foreign peoples can restrict us in exploiting 
 the same, or can make it valueless. 
 
 The mines not only increase the treasure of the country with 
 respect to the amount of gold and silver which they extract from the 
 earth, but they also furnish us the principal wares with which we 
 may expect to establish advantageous foreign commerce. In 
 addition to this the mines will support a multitude of people, and 
 this will have further an important influence upon the plane of 
 living in the whole population. Especially will the mountainous 
 regions be populated and exploited to the benefit of the revenues 
 of their districts and of the whole state, while the same districts, 
 without mines, would usually have a barren and empty appearance. 
 All this, it seems to me, furnishes more than superfluous proof of 
 the great utility of the mines. 
 
 Who then can doubt that the mines deserve the special attention 
 of a wise government ? So soon, therefore, as minerals are found 
 in a country, or as good evidences of them appear, or when informa- 
 tion is at hand that in earlier times mines had been operated there, 
 a ruler who is really concerned for the best good of his state will make
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 361 
 
 it a principal rule to establish mining and to develop it to the utmost. 
 To that end he must seize upon all useful and efficient measures. 
 I shall now do my best to show what such measures must be. 
 
 Propositions more summary in form than those in the 
 series up to this point will sufficiently indicate the scope of the 
 discussion, viz. : 
 
 216. Precious metals should be mined with the aid of govern- 
 ments even at a loss (p. 246).' 
 
 217. This is not a loss for the state as a whole. The sums 
 expended remain in the country and support many people. The 
 country as a whole will be richer by the amount of gold and silver 
 that is taken from the earth (p. 246). 
 
 218. In case of the other metals, even a small profit should 
 justify mining. By furnishing material to be sold abroad they add 
 to the nation's wealth as truly as the mining of gold and silver. 
 
 219. The measures to be adopted by rulers for promoting 
 mining fall into three groups: (i) for stimulating the population to 
 engage in mining; (2) for standardizing the operation of mines; 
 (3) for promoting mining science (p. 247). 
 
 220. Although all mining rights belong to the ruler, yet he 
 cannot work them, because that would too greatly enlarge his budget, 
 and make his income uncertain. The first requisite, then, is proc- 
 lamation of free mining rights, subject to the laws of the land, at 
 least to citizens, with reserve of the rightful royalties to the govern- 
 ment (p. 247). 
 
 221. The ruler should give assurance that he will not himself, 
 or through his ministers, engage in mining (p. 248). 
 
 222. The ruler must take care in many ways that those who 
 operate mines shall be free to carry on their enterprise under the 
 most favorable conditions (p. 249). 
 
 223. The government must assist unprofitable mines, by remitting 
 dues, etc. (p. 250).' 
 
 ' This doctrine goes back to Schroder, loc. cit., chap. bcv. 
 
 The idea here proves to be, not that mines should be operated if 
 the net outcome is to be a loss, but that mines at first unprofitable should 
 be assisted until they can be made to pay.
 
 362 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 224. Many changes in the mining laws are necessary, especially 
 because the introduction of machines, etc., has changed conditions 
 (P- 251). 
 
 225. An area of "at least two miles" should be assured for 
 the operations of a new mine (p. 252).' 
 
 226. This plan is recommended only for the precious and base 
 metals (p. 253). 
 
 227. For salts, coloring matter, and clays, commercial societies 
 are preferable (p. 254). 
 
 228. Schools of mines should be founded to train future man- 
 agers of mines (p. 256). 
 
 229. It will be useless to count on mines as a permanent source 
 of wealth unless provision is made for keeping up the supply of wood. 
 
 ON THE CIRCULATION OF GOLD IN THE TRADES 
 
 230. It is not enough that there should be wealth in the country, 
 but the ruler must take care that this wealth is constantly active 
 in the trades, and that it passes from hand to hand, for the true wealth 
 of the country depends wholly upon this. In this way the subjects 
 arc put in a position not merely by diligence and labor to provide 
 for their need and comfort, but also bear their share toward sup- 
 plying the needs of the state. In fact it is quite natural to represent 
 a republic under the figure of a human body. Wealth is the blood, 
 the trades are the arteries, and the government is the heart, into 
 which from time to time the wealth circulating in the arteries flows, 
 and thence again pours into all parts of the civic body through the 
 outlays of the state. We have now to treat of the means by which 
 this circulation is promoted (p. 259).* 
 
 231. The chief means of promoting circulation of money in the 
 trades are four, viz.: (i) that the sources of subsistence shall be 
 kept in good correlation; (2) that the land shall keep its credit high; 
 
 ' This apparently means two German miles square, and Jusli 
 recommends that such a reservation should be divided into four or five 
 hundred parts, whether for separate operation or merely in dividing the 
 proceeds is not clear. 
 
 * This paragraph is translated in full because it is a characteristic 
 expression of mercantilism, and contains its own evidence that the theory 
 v.us not so definite as tradition has made it.
 
 JUSTFS "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 363 
 
 (3) that manufacture and artisanship shall be kept prosperous; 
 
 (4) that idleness and beggary shall be abated (pp. 259-330).' 
 
 One or two incidental symptoms occur among the tech- 
 nological rules, in these sections. For example, while reiter- 
 ating the precept against allowing money to flow out of the 
 country, Justi adds: "A flourishing condition of the occupa- 
 tions by which the necessities of life are gained is, however, 
 the real strength and health of the state." This perception 
 again challenges the current reputation of mercantilism. 
 
 Justi denounces abstract science, and demands that the 
 learned class shall abandon profitless refinements and devote 
 itself to the useful arts. He would also have the government 
 weed out the student ranks by examinations difficult enough 
 to reduce the numbers of would-be scholars (p. 274). 
 
 After discussing at length the desirability and means of 
 preventing idleness and luxury, he adds a qualification which 
 is symptomatic of mercantilism in particular and of the pre- 
 vailing economic naivete* in general. He says (p. 328): 
 
 I will go further, and assert that the government has no need 
 of prohibiting extravagance and luxury. According to all rational 
 principles it is entirely a matter of indifference to the state in whose 
 hands the wealth of the country rests, if it is only in the country and 
 is distributed in proper proportions among the different classes and 
 orders of the subjects. Moreover, if the things with which extrava- 
 gance is practiced are not imported from foreign countries, it is a 
 blunder to suppose that extravagance is harmful to the state. On 
 the contrary the circulation of money and the support of the citizens 
 are promoted by it. Everything therefore which the government 
 needs to care for, is that those wares and things which arc used in 
 
 1 These sections are almost exclusively composed of rule-of-thumb 
 conclusions about practical details. They presuppose the essentially 
 patriarchal conception of the state which we have called the major 
 premise of cameralism. The state being the housewifely patron saint 
 of the people, specifications of the supervision to be exerted depend on 
 their efficiency in promoting the chief end of such a state.
 
 364 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 extravagance shall be produced at home, not imported from abroad. 
 A state composed wholly of misers, or frugal people, and in which 
 no luxury existed, would necessarily be the poorest, weakest, and 
 most miserable state under the sun. It would not be able to employ 
 and support a fourth part of the population of present states. How 
 many occupations would remain if we should restrict ourselves 
 strictly to necessities? Luxury in the use of domestic products, if 
 it is conjoined with industry, is the natural heat and fire in the civic 
 body, which gives it activity and vitality. Very few cases will be 
 found in which repression of luxury is required in the interest of the 
 welfare of the state. I have treated these cases in the Grundsdtzen 
 dtr Policey. 
 
 OF THE DUTIES OF SUBJECTS IN ORDER TO ASSIST THE RULER IN 
 PRESERVING AND INCREASING THE RICHES OF THE STATE 
 
 232. The nature of a republic necessarily involves common 
 and harmonious obligations, for when the subjects have placed over 
 themselves a supreme power (sic), 1 from which they demand that it 
 shall promote their happiness, they are naturally bound to conform 
 to those arrangements which that supreme power adopts for their 
 happiness, and to promote them in every way, otherwise they would 
 obstruct their own ultimate purposes (p. 333). 
 
 233. By subjects we understand all those who enjoy the pro- 
 tection of the state. This brief proposition gives us the clearest 
 idea of the essential characteristics of a subject, and in fact no more 
 essential finding mark can be determined than the enjoyment of 
 protection (p. 334). 
 
 234. The right cannot be denied to a ruler to demand that all 
 those who possess estates in his land shall either be permanently 
 domiciled upon them, or shall sell the estates to some person agree- 
 able to him (p. 340). 
 
 235. Subjects owe their duties to an unlimited monarch only 
 when he does not act as an enemy of the people. This situation 
 may never have occurred, because even the greatest tyrants had 
 apparent excuses, and it is consequently never quite clear that an 
 autocrat is acting as the enemy of his people (p. 345). 
 
 1 The Italics are mine, and the proposition is quoted for its bearing 
 upon our interpretation of Justi's fundamental political conceptions.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 365 
 
 236. Under mixed forms of government the subjects owe duties 
 not to the monarch alone, but also to the whole state, and to the 
 fundamental laws of the same. Consequently duty to the monarch 
 is not a valid plea in extenuation of action harmful to the estates 
 
 (P- 347)- 
 
 237. Duties of subjects are accordingly of two classes: (a) 
 immediate duties to ruler or state, springing from the essential nature 
 of the relation of subjects; (b) mediate duties toward ruler and state, 
 i. e., such as subjects owe primarily to themselves, and thus second- 
 arily to ruler and state. 
 
 OP THE IMMEDIATE DUTIES OF SUBJECTS TOWARD RULER 
 AND STATE 
 
 238. The immediate duties of subjects toward ruler and state 
 are those which are necessarily connected with the ultimate purposes 
 of the republic and with the relation of subjects, and which subjects 
 owe to the supreme power in the state alone (p. 349). 
 
 239. These immediate duties fall into three chief classes: 
 (a) exact obedience to the laws, commands, and ordinances of the 
 supreme power; (b) unimpeachable loyalty to the same; (c) con- 
 tribution according to ability to the support and best welfare of the 
 state (p. 349).' 
 
 240. Loyalty [Treue] consists of complete devotion, attachment, 
 and reverence toward the supreme power, with careful endeavor to 
 avoid, and so far as possible to assist in preventing everything 
 which might be harmful to the external and internal security of the 
 state and of the person of the ruler (p. 376).* 
 
 241. Subjects are released from loyalty to a ruler (i) through 
 absorption by conquest or otherwise into another country (p. 393) ; 
 (2) when the ruler abdicates (p. 397).' 
 
 1 The immediately following sections are a diversified homily on 
 the fundamental virtue of obedience, with extreme claims for the arbitrary 
 rights of rulers (pp. 351-73). 
 
 Again the treatment is rather hortatory than scientific. 
 
 3 The third type of duty (vide Prop. 239*:) is discussed in variations 
 of commonplaces adapted to the particular conception of the state on 
 which cameralism was based (pp. 402-28). The following division, 
 "On the Indirect Duties of the Subject," exploits the homely virtues of 
 the thrifty type (pp. 4*0-35).
 
 366 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 242. In order to treat at length of the mediate duties of sub- 
 jects, we must elaborate the whole housekeeping art [Hauslial- 
 tungskunst] since the obligation to operate well with our resources 
 can be fulfilled in no other way than through the rules which this 
 Haushaltungskunst teaches. But Oekonomie 1 belongs in the system 
 of the sciences which we have undertaken to expound, because 
 through the exercise of the same the resources of the state are main- 
 tained and increased. On that account it is the more evident that 
 all the sciences pertaining to government and to the large manage- 
 ment \Wirthschajt] of the state hang together most exactly in a single 
 system. Attempting therefore to treat of Haushaltungskunst com- 
 pletely and thoroughly, so far as the limits of the present work 
 permit, we shall in the first place present the general doctrines of the 
 same, then we shall treat particularly the two chief topics of Oeko- 
 nomie, viz., urban economy and rural economy, and shall apply to 
 them the general rules (p. 435).' 
 
 243. The name Haushaltungskunst or Oekonomie may really 
 be applied to two distinct sciences. When we speak of the Oekonomie 
 of the country, or of the great management \Wirthschajt] of the state, 
 all the sciences are involved which we treat in this book. When we 
 talk of Oekonomie or Haushaltungskunst simply, we mean that 
 science which we are now about to explain, and which is concerned 
 with the goods and with the gainful occupations of private persons. 
 Haushaltungskunst is, however, a science of so ordering the gainful 
 occupations and the thrift in town and country that means [Vermdgen] 
 will thereby be preserved, increased, and reasonably used, and the 
 
 1 Apparently used in this paragraph as a synonym for the former 
 term. In the following paragraph this is certainly the case, i. e., Prop. 243. 
 
 Of the whole following division, which has certain necessary 
 resemblances to political economy as Adam Smith used the term, yet 
 differs from it as kitchen work from chemistry, we may say that it con- 
 tains nothing beyond commonplace material which genius and humor 
 like Benjamin Franklin's might have coined into pithy Poor Richard's 
 proverbs. Sufficient samples are given to show the quality. It should 
 be observed that the presence of this department in Staatswirthschaft 
 again demonstrates the absurdity of the traditional accounts of mer- 
 cantilism as a theory.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 367 
 
 temporal happiness of private persons will be promoted; or more 
 briefly expressed, it is the science of applying our " means" to the pro- 
 motion of our temporal happiness (p. 437). 
 
 244. One sense of "means" [Vermdgen] signifies everything 
 that is within our power, or that which we are able to bring to pass. 
 In ordinary thinking "means" signifies all goods and aptitudes 
 which we possess and which we may employ in order to provide for 
 ourselves the necessities and conveniences of this life. In the 
 narrower sense we understand by "means" the possession of a 
 sufficiency of movable or immovable goods, which put in our hands, 
 according to our social position and make-up [Beschaftenheit], all 
 the conveniences and advantages of life. When we here use the 
 term "means," it is in the two last senses, principally in the third 
 
 (P- 438). 1 
 
 245. Except through accident, no obtaining of "means" is 
 possible unless our aptitudes and already-possessed goods are the 
 beginning and ground of the acquisition (p. 439). 
 
 246. By "goods" we understand in Haushaltungskunst only 
 those things which have a certain value and use for the need and 
 convenience of human life, and which at a certain value or price 
 can be transferred to others; i. e., things that have a money value 
 (p. 440). 
 
 247. Credit is to a certain extent to be reckoned among goods, 
 for it can be used as the ground and beginning of "means" (p. 440). 
 
 248. By "aptitudes" we understand those acquired capabilities 
 and skills by which we may be useful to others and to ourselves in 
 business and trades, or in social life in general (p. 441). 
 
 249. All "means" must be gained either by services [Dienste], 
 or by trades [Gewerbe]. The former require only "aptitudes;" the 
 latter require "aptitudes" and goods together (p. 441) 
 
 250. Services are a certain compact between the principal and 
 the servant, by which the latter, in return for a certain salary or 
 compensation, promises to apply his "aptitudes," in certain assigned 
 
 1 This paragraph sufficiently accounts for choice of the vague term, 
 "means" instead of a more technical term as a rendering for VermOgen. 
 We should misinterpret egregiously if we smuggled a later precise and 
 constant concept into the word. Vide pp. 76 and 250.
 
 368 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 occupations, for the benefit of the principal. These services are 
 either honorable or menial; they are also morally legitimate or 
 illegitimate (p. 442). 
 
 251. The two great classes of gainful occupations are (i) those 
 that procure livelihood in the town; (2) those that procure livelihood 
 in the country (p. 443). 
 
 252. From services or trades come "earnings" [Geurinnst]. 
 This is the advantage which accrues to us from a thing after deduction 
 of our applied outlay and effort. The justification of earnings must 
 have at its basis the revenue which the other can, and probably will 
 derive from the thing, for we are surely entitled to demand that the 
 other shall allow a just portion of the return to accrue to us which 
 he would not have acquired without our co-operation (p. 444). 
 
 253. In order to gain "means," one must first of all make & 
 plan of his mode of life, and of the ways by which he is to acquire 
 earnings. In this plan account must be taken of his aptitudes 
 and goods. Most men make the mistake of making no plan, and of 
 seeking their fortune in a merely haphazard way. Still others fail 
 because they draw back in fear from every obstacle (p. 453). 
 
 253.Y Before all things we must so apply our "aptitudes" and 
 our goods that they will actually promote our purposes (p. 455). 
 
 254. Further it is necessary to know all the details involved in 
 the success of our plan (p. 457). 
 
 255. This knowledge will enable us to choose the necessary 
 means for carrying out our plan (p. 457). 
 
 256. It is further necessary to combine these means in a skilful 
 way (p. 458). 
 
 257. By this skilful combination of "means" it is often possible 
 that one may at the same time accomplish several sorts of purpose, 
 and earn in several ways (p. 458). 
 
 458. But one will not acquire "means," cither by service or 
 trade, if one has not learned to save (p. 460). 
 
 259. In order to exercise this great art of saving, the first thing 
 in every establishment must be a budget or correct estimate of income 
 and outlay (p. 461). 
 
 260. The savings must then be used further to increase "means" 
 (p. 464)-
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 369 
 
 961. After all, the increase of "means" will be a tedious process 
 unless one takes some reasonable chances, and occasionally exposes 
 a part of his "means" to the hazards of fortune (p. 465). 
 
 262. Those who make such ventures should first possess 
 considerable "means," so that they could lose what they risk without 
 being reduced to want (p. 466). 
 
 263. Then the anticipated gain should be in proportion to the 
 danger to which one is exposed (p. 467). 
 
 264. The reasonable use of "means" is the chief purpose of 
 acquisition and of Haushaltungskunst. 
 
 265. "Means" contribute not a little to the end of a social 
 happy, and virtuous life. One is thereby much more qualified for 
 service to the community, and one can fulfil the duties of social life 
 in a much higher degree than those who have no means (p. 471). 
 
 266. The reasonable use of means depends upon three chief 
 rules: (i) The "means" must be so used that the substance (sic) 
 of the same will not be impaired (p. 471); (2) one must apply one's 
 "means" to the support of one's life and to the promotion of one's 
 temporal happiness, according as the social position and constitution 
 of each demand, and as the condition of one's "means" permits 
 (p. 481); (3) besides using our "means" for our own needs and the 
 convenience of our life, we must devote them also to the use of our 
 needy neighbor, and to the advantage of the republic (p. 485). 
 
 ON MANAGEMENT IN TOWNS 
 
 267. The life of towns has the most intimate connection with 
 human society and with the constitution of the republic. The towns 
 both form the bond of connection between the rural sustaining system 
 and the whole sustaining system of the country, and in them quite 
 unique occupations are pursued, which have immediate influence on 
 the weal of the state. The fundamental rules of management can 
 be applied here therefore only in a general way, because otherwise 
 it would be necessary to discuss each particular occupation. In the 
 case of rural management, on the contrary, there must be specific 
 application of the general rules (p. 490). 
 
 268. A town is a combination of societies, families, and single 
 persons, who live in a guarded [verwahrten] locality, under the over-
 
 37 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 sight and direction of a police bureau, or other persons charged with 
 administration of the police system, in order with better success to 
 maintain the operation and co-operation of those gainful pursuits 
 which are immediately demanded both for the needs and conveniences 
 of the country and for the unification of the whole sustaining 
 system. The protection [Verwahrung] is the essential finding mark 
 of the town, without which no locality can be called a town, how- 
 ever large and well built it may be (p. 490). l 
 
 269. The essential difference between towns depends therefore 
 on the fact that one kind must be guarded by art, that is, by walls 
 and ditches, another kind by nature, that is, by oceans, seas, rivers, 
 and inaccessible mountains, so that entrance may be had only at 
 certain places called gates or portals expressly designated for that 
 purpose. Otherwise the requisite police arrangements for the chief 
 purpose of the town are not available (p. 493). 
 
 270. Towns must accordingly be classified in various ways: 
 (i) Into (a) commercial towns; (b) manufacturing towns; (c) 
 mining and salt towns; (d) brewery and distillery towns; (e) market 
 towns; or (2) into (a) residence towns (i. e., of the court); (6) uni- 
 versity towns; (c) fortified towns; (d) border towns, etc.; or (3) into 
 (a) large; (ft) medium; (c) small; or (4) into (a) capitals; (6) 
 provincial towns (p. 496). 
 
 271. At bottom there are two principal types of occupation for 
 towns; first, the assembling of persons capable of carrying on the 
 various pursuits; second, the accumulation of all sorts of wares and 
 goods, and to this end all their establishments, measures, and en- 
 deavors must be directed (p. 497). 
 
 272. Since we are here exclusively concerned with the economy 
 of private persons in towns, we have to do principally with two 
 subjects, viz.: (i) What the general rules of management have to 
 say about management and organization of the sustaining occupa- 
 tions; (2) how management itself, without reference to occupations 
 in the town, may best be conducted (p. 497). ' 
 
 1 It is needless to comment on this typically cameralistic inversion 
 of essence and accident. 
 
 * This programme results only in slight variations upon the general- 
 ities indicated by Props. 253-64. Passing to treatment of occupations
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 371 
 
 273. Rural management is a complex of sustaining occupations' 
 to the end that through agriculture and stock-raising the resources 
 of the soil may be best used, and that all sorts of raw wares and 
 materials may be extracted from the same for human need and 
 convenience. The rural sustaining occupations consequently 
 differ from those of towns principally in this: in the former the 
 effort is to produce raw wares and goods, in the latter men are chiefly 
 engaged in transforming the raw wares and materials. While this 
 latter purpose requires unified societies and efforts, with police 
 supervision, the former can be carried on by separate families either 
 scattered at considerable intervals, or living in village groups" 1 
 (P- 
 
 THE THEORY OF THE REASONABLE USE OF THE "MEANS" 
 
 [Vermogen] OF THE STATE, INCLUDING CAMERAL OR 
 
 FINANCIAL SCIENCE PROPER 
 
 On the Reasonable Use oj State Revenues in General 
 On the second title-page of the second part, or volume, 
 the clause is inserted, "in which cameral science proper is 
 treated." It is not our present affair to debate with Justi the 
 insufficiency of his economic foundation, nor to go into details 
 about the overlapping and confusion of economic, camera- 
 listic, and police problems as they appear in his system. 2 We 
 are attempting to present this typical cameralist just as he 
 was, and to show how cameralism as a so-called science 
 reflected the immaturities and prejudices of the type of state 
 in which it was developed. We come now to a portion of the 
 system in which actual administration had worked out a 
 technique that was relatively precise. In so far as such a 
 
 which are not necessarily peculiar to towns, Justi lapses into extended 
 pseudo-technical discussion of brewing, distilling, vinting, truck-garden- 
 ing, and milling (pp. 505-17). 
 
 1 Then follows an academic version of the wisdom that every farmer's 
 boy is supposed to acquire (pp. 526-606). This then is as deep as Justi 
 goes into the theory of economics on the side of production proper. 
 
 3 Vide II, 63, and Prop. 219.
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 technique, not guaranteed by a conclusive economics, can 
 have a value for science, it is the most important part of Justi's 
 system. We must repeat, however, that the problem of cam- 
 eralism was not yet consciously the problem of modern 
 economics, and still less the problem of modern sociology, 
 viz.: What is the value of all mediate processes for the trunk- 
 line process of promoting the evolution of persons? The 
 problem of cameralism was merely the ways and means prob- 
 lem of the quasi-absolutistic governments of that period, viz. : 
 the quasi-absolutistic type of state being given, in which, in 
 effect, the state is the government, and the government is 
 the prince, how may the resources of that type of state be so 
 managed that its perpetual motion will be assured? 
 
 We shall show this in further detail by continuing the series 
 of propositions condensing Justi's argument. 
 
 274. To recapitulate: The common happiness, the ultimate 
 purpose of all republics, for attaining and realizing which the supreme 
 power exists in states, demands that the care and endeavor of this 
 sovereign power shall be directc'l chiefly toward two great activities, 
 viz.: first, securing and increasing the "means" of the state; second, 
 the reasonable and wise use of the "means." The great management 
 of the state consists then of these two chief employments. Part I 
 having been devoted to the former of these, Part II will deal with 
 the latter (II, 3). 
 
 275. The "means" of the state consist not merely in all sorts 
 of movable and immovable goods, possessed primarily either by the 
 subjects or by the state itself; but rather in all talents and skill of the 
 persons who belong to the republic. Even the persons themselves 
 must in a certain sense be included, and the general use of these 
 means of the state constitute the supreme power. 1 All ordinances 
 of the supreme power have for their object therefore the wise use 
 of the means and forces of the state for the realization of the common 
 happiness (II, 5).* 
 
 1 Vide I, 19, and this book, pp. 76, 250, 367. 
 
 * This proposition is typical of the vagueness of undifferentiated 
 cameralistic ideas. The original reads: "A lie Anordnungen dtr obtr-
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 373 
 
 ay6. In the widest sense, the reasonable use of the "means" 
 of the state includes all the rules laid down in Part I. In the special 
 sense we understand by the reasonable use of the "means" of the 
 state the wise measures of the ruler, to the end that the general 
 "means" of the state may be made to yield certain revenues, and 
 constantly available resources, without impairing the "means," 
 and in accordance with the demands which from time to time the 
 essential needs of the state may enforce (II, 6). x 
 
 sten Gcwali kommen also darauf an, doss sie von dem Vermdgen und den 
 Krdften des Staates *u der Bcwirkung der gemeinsckaftlichen Gluckselig- 
 keit einen weisen Gebrauck machet." I attribute the thoroughly non- 
 committal force in this connection of the phrase "kommen darauf an," to 
 an unreconciled antithesis of ideas. As it stands, the proposition dis- 
 tinctly means neither, "The objective goodness or badness of the acts of 
 a government is to be decided by its use, etc.," nor, " The intention of the 
 government is to use, etc." The former meaning would lead to a corol- 
 lary which is abhorrent to Justi (vide I, 47, above, pp. 335 ff.). The 
 latter meaning is always the reserve presumption on which to rest the 
 claim of the government to unquestioning submission. Yet, so long as 
 the latter claim maintained its orthodoxy, it was by smuggling into its 
 assets some of the credit which the former proposition would establish, 
 while that proposition was not admitted at full force. In other words, 
 the stage of thinking represented by Justi was a dodging between affirm- 
 ative and negative answers to the question, Are governments absolute, 
 and so unimpeachable, or are they fallible, and consequently to stand or 
 fall on the merits of their acts as determined by some objective standard ? 
 The quasi-absolutism which Justi represented resorted, when hard 
 pushed, to the affirmative. Cromwellism and the French Revolution, 
 and the American Declaration of Independence vindicated the negative. 
 We shall miss the full meaning of this treatise and of cameralism in 
 general, if we fail to keep in mind that they were straddles on this funda- 
 mental problem, with the working balance toward the arbitrary side 
 (P- SI3-) 
 
 i It should be remembered, that this discussion is in terms of Ver- 
 mdgen, not of Reichthum. One of the most subtle questions in future 
 historical criticism of the literature of economics will to a large extent 
 turn upon the fallacy of interchanging the two concepts. When Adam 
 Smith founded systematic study of problems of wealth, he carefully 
 delimited the concept The subsequent confusions in English thinking
 
 374 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 297. The first condition of reasonable use of the "means" of 
 the state is adequate knowledge of them (II, 6). 1 
 
 298. The wise ruler has a conception of a true happiness of 
 the subjects and of the state constantly before his eyes, and he has a 
 
 were not quite indentical with those in German theory, and one of the 
 reasons for the differences was strictly verbal. I am not prepared to 
 express a judgment about the relative importance of this factor. I have 
 not collected sufficient evidence to prove that much of the confusion in 
 English economic theories came from taking over arguments expressed in 
 unwarranted translations of German terms. I am convinced, however, 
 that this is the case. It is enough at present to point out that it would 
 shunt us on to a side track if we should render Justi's word Vermogen 
 by the primarily legal term "property;" still more if we should use the 
 more restricted economic term "wealth." The work of reducing this 
 and similar ambiguous terms to constant values has been a considerable 
 part of the difficulty of promoting the various social technologies assem- 
 bled as "cameralism" to relative distinctness and precision. 
 
 The idea of the divine foreordination of hereditary sovereignty 
 reappears as the constant motif in the cameralistic doctrines. We illus- 
 trated this in its most dogmatic form in the case of Schroder (above, 
 pp. 137 ff.). Thus Justi says: "The Eternal Being whose Providence 
 has appointed him to the government of the people put under him as 
 subjects will hold a ruler to strict accounting, etc." This was not 
 merely a pious phrasing of social order. It was literal interpretation, 
 and it carried the corollary that the Almighty alone, not the people of a 
 state, had the right to call the ruler to account. Justi employs formulas 
 of the ruler's responsibility which would mean to a twentieth-century 
 man almost all that we should assert about the responsibility of chief 
 magistrates (e. g., II, 10); but we must always construe these proposi- 
 tions in the light of the reserve clauses in the author's mind. These 
 latter virtually nullify those phases of democracy in the formulas which 
 a twentieth-century man would regard as crucial. 
 
 ' Much of the development of the proposition in subsequent sections 
 has already appeared in substance in our citations from Justi's Preface 
 and Introduction, and need not be repeated. For instance, a section 
 (II, 13-15) is devoted to the proposition that a ruler ought not to use the 
 "means" of the state without having a correct estimate of them. It 
 amounts only to a more pedantic way of reading the New Testament 
 moral: " What king going to make war against another king, sitteth not 
 down first and consulieth whether he be able, etc"
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 375 
 
 correct judgment of the relative proportions of the different needs 
 (II, 15; vide I, 66-69). ' 
 
 299. The wise ruler must take no steps for the welfare of the 
 state without taking care that "means" enough are devoted to the 
 purpose to insure its success (II, 17). 
 
 300. For the purposes of the state, great sums must be expended. 
 These "means" are mostly in the hands of private persons. The 
 portions necessary for the purposes of the state must be obtained 
 from the individuals in ways which will not impair the substance of 
 their "means," i. e., they must be taken from earnings [Gewinnste]. 
 Enough, however, must be left so that the subjects can live from 
 their earnings (II, 8). 
 
 301. The "means" so obtained must be at all times available 
 in the form of money, and we call it then "the readiest means" of 
 the state (II, 20). * 
 
 302. This "readiest means" of the state is the great subject- 
 matter of cameral or finance science proper, in so far as the same is 
 regarded as a subordinate science under all the economic and cameral 
 sciences required for the government of a state. All measures and 
 transactions of cameral science have to do merely with this "readiest 
 means," and have for their aim either the systematic raising of the 
 same or wise application or administration. Otherwise expressed, 
 Cameral or finance science is an adequate knowledge and facility 
 [Erkenntniss und Geschicklichkeit] in those transactions whereby 
 
 1 Although the proposition is supported only by the most common- 
 place generalities, it indicates, along with stalwart faith (for publication) 
 in the virtues of paternalism, a rather comprehensive view of the sorts 
 of interests which the benevolent despot should try to harmonize. Inci- 
 dentally, Justi again has his fling at the relative unimportance of the 
 learned class. 
 
 Justi has evidently used the term "means" now in a special sense, 
 i. e., the reserve plus the current revenues of the state. Whether this 
 idea is more cause or effect of the general mercantilist position it would be 
 fruitless to inquire. It is a typical case of fallacious transition from a 
 concept defined to include both goods and persons, to a concept sym- 
 bolized by the same term, Vermogen, but defined to mean gold and silver 
 coin.
 
 376 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 "the readiest means" of the state, for promotion of the common happi- 
 ness of the same, are well and economically managed (II, 21). 
 
 303. We easily see that cameral science is closely connected 
 with all other economic sciences which are treated in this book. 
 It teaches not merely how to use wisely and for the good of the state 
 those "means" of the republic which are founded, preserved, and 
 increased by Staatskunst, Policey, die Commercienwissenschaft und 
 Oekonomie, 1 but in the great management of the state it conducts, so 
 to speak, the internal management, to the effect that without its 
 co-working no governmental business of any kind can be undertaken; 
 because for all such undertakings "readiest means" are necessary. 
 In short, cameral science is absolutely indispensable to the happiness 
 of the state, because the greatest "means" of the state would yield 
 nothing, without skilful administration. Hence it has its ground in 
 the common fundamental principle of all the sciences which pertain 
 to the government and general management of the state.* It is 
 particularly based however on die Staatskunst und Policeywissen- 
 schaft, since it must derive its chief working principles from them. 
 Moreover it must make use of Haushaltungskunst and jurisprudence 
 as principal auxiliaries. The former will furnish the elementary 
 rules of managing "means," the latter will guard against unjust 
 procedure (II, 23). 
 
 304. The fundamental principle of cameral science is this: "7n 
 all transactions with the 'readiest means' of the state, the aim must 
 be to seek the common happiness of the ruler and the subjects" 
 (II, 24).* 
 
 305. The rules of raising the revenues without harm to the 
 
 1 As we have seen, these are categories which do not correspond 
 with recognized classifications in current social science. The essential 
 reason is that they were impossible as scientific categories. At a venture 
 we may offer as equivalents the terms, civic policy, police and commer- 
 cial science, and economy. 
 
 Vide above, pp. 298 S. 
 
 3 In spite of the arbitrary conception of the state in terms of which 
 this formula must be interpreted, it contains much saving grace of 
 correct moral valuation, while the context shows that the principle was 
 not always evident in actual cameralistic practices.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 377 
 
 subjects, and from current earnings, must also be applied to prov- 
 inces, so that the chief division of the state will not be favored at 
 the expense of minor divisions (II, 30).' 
 
 306. The theory of camera! science may be divided into three 
 chief parts. We accordingly divide this second part of the Staats- 
 wirthschaft into three books: (i) On the raising of revenues; (2) 
 on the disbursements of the state; (3) on the organization and admin- 
 istration of cameral business. This classification leaves nothing 
 lacking which is necessary for a beginner in cameral or finance 
 science, and in general about the reasonable use of the "means" 
 of the state (II, 39). 
 
 ON COVERING THE COSTS OP THE GREAT OUTLAYS OF THE STATE 
 
 307. A state often finds itself in need of resources which are not 
 supplied by the rules already given for raising the "readiest means." 
 This book is devoted then to the problems which those extraordinary 
 requirements involve (II, 40). 
 
 308. The problems of cameralism accordingly fall into three 
 chief divisions: (i) The establishment of the "readiest means" 
 which calls for the greatest skill and strength of the cameralist; 
 (2) the raising of the regular income of the state from the sources 
 that are common to almost all states; (3) the raising of emergency 
 funds (II, 42).' 
 
 309. Establishing the "readiest means" of the state depends 
 
 1 In this connection (II, 33) Justi admits that he is repeating rules 
 that have already been laid down, but he solemnly adds, "But in those 
 passages we were not yet treating cameral science proper. Since it is 
 now necessary particularly to define the fundamental principles of this 
 science, we must not be content with mere citation of the fundamental 
 principles reviewed above. Indeed these are not the same, since in the 
 former case we were talking of the use of the general "means" of the 
 state, while now we are speaking of the administration of the revenues 
 of the state. Nevertheless, everything that could be called a " principle " 
 is the same, even in Justi's version, and he was close to the perception 
 that cameralistics was not a science at all, but merely a technology without 
 a peculiar scientific content. 
 
 * From this point the treatment becomes more narrowly technical. 
 To what extent it was practical rather than academic, according to
 
 37 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 first upon developing a populous land, with the maximum amount 
 of wealth circulating in the gainful occupations (II, 44). 
 
 310. A second and more immediate foundation is necessary, 
 viz., either certain cstatus the proprietorship of which belongs 
 immediately to the state and to the ruler, and the whole revenue of 
 which accrues to the "readiest means," or certain rights reserved to 
 the supreme power. The proper name of these rights is the regalia 
 
 (II, 45). 
 
 311. The foundation of the revenues of the state is laid then, 
 first, in good management of the estates immediately appertaining 
 to the state or to the ruler (II, 45). 
 
 312. In the case of the regalia, the desideratum is a reasonable 
 use of the rights, in consideration of the common "means" of the 
 state, and of the common welfare of the ruler and of the subjects 
 (II, 46).' 
 
 313. The best standard of taxation is the persons of the subjects 
 in general, according to a just proportion of their immovable 
 "means" and industry, and especially the laborers and assistants 
 employed in such gainful occupations. In such case the commerce, 
 the industry, and the freedom of the subjects would not suffer the 
 slightest hindrance, as the number of the persons employed could 
 not possibly be concealed (II, 52). 
 
 314. It is possible for the state to raise so little revenue by 
 taxation that the total "means" of the state will fall far below the 
 normal level, and the welfare of the subjects will be harmfully 
 restricted (II, 53). 
 
 contemporary standards, it docs not fall within my province to decide. 
 The technical programme proposed has diminjshing pertinence to the 
 purposes of this book. I shall accordingly ignore the larger part of its 
 contents, and, as in the account of Adam Smith's purely economic chapters 
 (vide Small, Adam Smith and Modern Sociology), merely call attention 
 to incidental symptoms. 
 
 1 While our aim does not permit attention to details of fiscal tech- 
 nology, it should be noted that for investigators of the subject of taxation, 
 the rule-of -thumb conclusions scheduled by Justi are by no means 
 unworthy of consideration. For example, Justi's rules are quite close 
 approaches to the doctrines of free trade afterward promulgated by 
 Adam Smith (e. g., II, 48, 49).
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 379 
 
 315. The Regalia should be so administered that the welfare 
 of the state and the convenience of the subjects would remain the 
 first consideration, and the revenues the second (II, 54). 
 
 316. A reasonable cameralist will accordingly follow two rules: 
 (i) Direct management by the administration of complicated 
 economic processes must be avoided by arranging with competent 
 Entrepreneurs (sic) to carry on the enterprises at their own risk, 
 at a certain rate of dividend on the proceeds; (2) all needless extra 
 expense, such as unnecessary employees, must be avoided (II, 56).' 
 
 317. Subsidies from foreign rulers are not to be rejected, especi- 
 ally if they do not entail more costs than they amount to (II, 61-63). 
 
 318. The best and surest increase of the revenues of the state 
 comes from encouraging the laboring class [Nahrungsstand] 
 
 (II, 63). 
 
 319. A cameralist should at the same time be a police expert 
 and an economist (II, 63). 
 
 320. The first care of the cameralist must be for the develop- 
 ment and cultivation of unimproved and thinly populated sections 
 (II, 64). 
 
 321. A considerable budget must therefore be annually at the 
 disposal of the bureaus (II, 66). 
 
 322. Even without such capital the domains may by good 
 management be made to yield large revenues (II, 69-74). 
 
 323. Returning to the Regalia the most harmless increase of 
 revenues through extended use of the Regalia occurs (i) when they 
 are used in places where they had previously not been enforced. 
 Hence the intelligent cameralist must be on the watch for such 
 undeveloped sources of revenue (II, 75) ; (2) through improvements 
 of public works affected by the Regalia (II, 76) ; (3) through increase 
 of the rate of impost and of prices of products covered by the Regalia 
 
 (II, 77)- 
 
 324. The problem of increasing the revenues of the state in the 
 form of contributions, taxes, and other payments by the subject can 
 be solved only by improving the condition of the laboring class, and 
 
 1 A highly idealistic excursus follows on the possibility of painless 
 taxation. Justi declares that democracies might easily rea-Iize such an 
 ideal (II, 57).
 
 380 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 by increasing the population (II, 81), but this just portion of revenue 
 should be collected only when the needs of the state call for it. 
 
 325. The only exception is when a new impost may restrain 
 or cure a police evil, or may evidently benefit and enlarge the laboring 
 class. 1 
 
 326. The second chief responsibility of the cameralist is the 
 raising of the ordinary revenues of the state.' By the ordinary 
 revenues we understand the established arrangements for covering 
 the ordinary needs of the state by levies upon designated objects 
 (II, 88). 
 
 327. Following the Roman law, it has been customary in 
 Germany to distinguish between Fiscum and Aerarium. Under the 
 former are classed the revenues of the cameral estates and of the 
 Regalia. These are supposed to be for the support of the person of 
 the ruler and of his family, court, and servants, with all other expenses 
 necessary to maintain the princely dignity. It is the traditional 
 idea that the cameralists were to deal especially with these revenues, 
 and they are accordingly known as cameral revenues. The reve- 
 nues of the Aerarium are supposed to be especially for the protec- 
 tion and security of the country, and for promoting the general 
 welfare of the state (II, 89). 
 
 328. This distinction is groundless (II, 90). 
 
 329. Knowledge of the distinction is necessary, however, in 
 order to understand certain existing survivals and consequences of 
 the distinction in the present cameral organization (II, 92). 
 
 330. It is best to divide the revenues of the state according to 
 their four chief sources, viz.: (i) Those from the crown estates, 
 the cameral estates, or the domains (as they are variously named) ; 
 (2) those from the Regalia; (3) those from payments by the sub- 
 jects, in general taxation; (4) those which indirectly accrue in the 
 course of attaining other chief purposes (II, 95). 3 
 
 1 Justi's examples would fall in the class of sumptuary laws. 
 Vide Prop. 208. 
 
 3 The sections devoted in turn to these subjects contain almost 
 nothing pertinent to our purpose. They are strictly technological 
 (II, 97-305).
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 381 
 
 OF CONTRIBUTIONS, TAXES, AND IMPOSTS 
 
 This portion of the Staatswirthschaft is also chiefly tech- 
 nological, and thus not primarily germane to our purpose. 
 Since policies of taxation have their roots, however, so deep 
 in social philosophy, and since the theories of taxation occupy 
 so prominent places in the social sciences, we present a digest 
 of Justi's more general opinions. 
 
 331. The three chief sources of the necessary income of the 
 state are: (i) the contributions; (2) the taxes; (3) the excises paid 
 by the subjects. The domains and the Regalia are not sufficient 
 to cover the expenses necessary for the welfare of the state, especially 
 in the present armed condition of Europe. The magnificence of 
 courts has also greatly increased. To cover these costs the subjects 
 must contribute from their private means (II, 306). 
 
 332. There can be no doubt that the subjects owe this con- 
 tribution to the great expenses of the state. In so far as all subjects, 
 in respect to their common welfare, are in close unity with one 
 another, and represent a single body, or moral person, their private 
 means are at the same time the general, although mediate "means" 
 of the state (II, 307* vide I, 415, Prop. 239). 
 
 333. It is a fundamental rule to seek such ways and means of 
 levying the taxes now in mind, that the subjects will pay them with 
 willing and happy hearts, and at their own initiative. This is 
 possible even in monarchies, if wise use is made of the passions of 
 the subjects; e. g., if the people, with the exception of nobility and 
 scholars, are divided into classes, according to the amount of tax 
 which they pay; or, if certain lucrative occupations are permitted 
 only to persons who pay a certain minimum tax, as is stipulated for 
 example in* the case of brewers in Frankenhauscn, Schwarzburg, 
 etc. (II, 309). 
 
 334. A second fundamental rule is that the taxes must not 
 interfere with the reasonable freedom of human conduct, with the 
 credit of merchants, with the trades, and shall in general not be 
 oppressive to the industrial system or to commerce (II, 311). 
 
 335. A third rule is that the taxes must be levied upon all 
 subjects with righteous equality, since all are equally under obliga-
 
 382 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tion in this connection, and all share in the protection and other 
 benefits of the state. Yet the application of this rule must have due 
 respect to the second, for, although all subjects should pay taxes 
 in just proportion to their means, yet the nature and purpose of the 
 different species of goods does not permit that all objects can bear 
 equal rates of taxation (II, 312). 
 
 336. A fourth rule is, that the contributions and excises shall 
 have a sure, fixed, and un falsified ground, and consequently should 
 be levied upon objects not only upon which they may be promptly 
 and certainly collected, but in connection with which fraud and con- 
 cealment is not easy for the subjects, nor peculation for the officials 
 
 (II, 313)- 
 
 337. A fifth rule is, that the taxes shall be based on such objects 
 as will permit limitation of the number of collectors' offices, and 
 therewith of officials (II, 314). 
 
 338. The sixth and last fundamental rule is that payments 
 must be made as easy as possible for the subjects, and hence must 
 be divided into convenient parts, and made payable at appropriate 
 times (II, 315).' 
 
 339. It is not easy to hit upon an impost which satisfies all these 
 requirements. Vauban, Schroder, and others have proposed a 
 royal or general tithe, which should combine all desirable qualities. 
 Tested by above rules, however, the plan will be found wanting. 
 Others have proposed a combined poll and income tax, etc. (II, 316). 
 
 340. The nearest approach to application of the rules will be 
 through selecting three classes of objects for taxation, viz.: first, 
 immovable goods; second, the persons of the subjects; third, the 
 gainful occupations (II, 318). 
 
 1 Vitle Adam Smith's "four maxims," Wealth of Nations, Book V, 
 cap. ii, part ii, Bax crl., p. 351. Vide Small, Adam Smith and Modern 
 Sociology, pp. 229 IT. Smith's first maxim is approximately Justi's 
 third rule; the second maxim is nearly Justi's fourth rule; the third 
 maxim is almost identical with Jusli's sixth rule; the fourth maxim may 
 be compared with Justi's second rule, but is much more fundamental 
 and prc( isc. Justi's Rule i is nebulous; Rule 5 refers to one class of 
 consideration only whirh, with many others, enforces the much wider 
 generalization of Smith's Maxim 4.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 383 
 
 OF CONTRIBUTIONS AND TAXES ON IMMOVABLE GOODS 
 
 341. The propriety of taxing land rests on two facts: first, it 
 is mediately a part of the general property of the state; second, the 
 revenues from it are least concealable. Nor is there any hardship 
 in liability of the land for a portion of the expenses of the state 
 (II, 320).' 
 
 342. Lands of the different kinds, e. g., meadows, vineyards, 
 forests, etc., must be divided into three classes, good, medium, and 
 bad; and houses must also be classified as large, medium, and small. 
 Again, the regions in which the lands lie must also be classified, and 
 in like manner the towns which contain the houses. A calculus of 
 these different factors will give the rate of taxation (II, 324). 
 
 343. The productiveness of the land must be precisely reck- 
 oned, and the tax must be levied accordingly (II, 324).' 
 
 344. The revenues of the houses should also determine the 
 amount of levy upon them; and it should correspond with the just 
 rate upon the interest which would be derived from the selling value 
 of the same (II, 325). 
 
 345. An important duty of the bureaus relates to remission of 
 the taxes in case of providential losses by fire, flood, storm, drought, 
 etc. (II, 333). 
 
 346. It is a mistake for the ruler to reward services by grants of 
 freedom from taxation (II, 335). 
 
 OF PERSONAL TAXATION 
 
 347. The second chief taxable object is the person of the sub- 
 jects themselves. Not all subjects possess immovable goods. All 
 are however members of the community, and enjoy its benefits; all 
 consequently owe something in return. Personal payments to the 
 state even by those who also pay land taxes are therefore proper, if 
 they are rightly graded (II, 340). 
 
 348. The personal tax may be the chief tax of a country, virtually 
 
 1 The details which follow deal with the technique of assessing and 
 collecting land taxes. 
 
 It is not clear whether Justi regards this precept as a further 
 elaboration of 342, or as something distinct. There is no meaning in the 
 classification proposed in 342, unless it is a part of the process intended 
 by 343-
 
 384 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 summing up all the forms of income tax, or it may be an accessory of 
 the principal forms of taxation (II, 341). 
 
 349. There is no adequate standard of personal taxation 
 
 (II, 343)- 
 
 350. Personal taxes may be regarded as a means of collecting 
 a portion of their dues to the state from subjects who otherwise 
 would be wholly or partially exempt from taxation (II, 344). 
 
 351. Poll taxes on Jews are to be specified as one of the forms 
 of personal tax. They are levied at the same rate upon rich and 
 poor alike, and they are left to equalize the matter among themselves. 
 Usually the whole Jewish community is held responsible for pay- 
 ment of an aggregate sum reckoned in proportion to the numbers. 
 Since it is the choice of this unfortunate race to remain aliens among 
 us, we need "not bother ourselves about strict propriety and exact 
 justice (II, 346). 
 
 352. In some countries protection-money [Schutzgeld] is paid 
 by those subjects, or aliens, who possess no immovable goods. 
 It is sometimes reckoned by families, sometimes by polls. In either 
 case it is to be reckoned as a personal tax. This is an undesirable 
 levy in addition to a poll tax (II, 347).' 
 
 353. Various other taxes have been levied as personal, .which 
 are really occupation taxes or excise (II, 348). 
 
 354. In the same way, salt and tobacco taxes have been levied 
 as personal taxes (II, 348). 
 
 355. The chief duties of the cameralists in connection with these 
 personal taxes consist in so administering the same that the system 
 will be reasonable, conducive to the welfare both of the subjects and 
 of the state, and duly respective of the equality of the subjects. In 
 this respect a cameralist has an opportunity to show great skill and 
 wisdom. Decisions must be rendered as to cases in which personal 
 taxes should be remitted. The ground for this concession should be 
 services.* Particularly must the cameralists take care that personal 
 
 > Justi makes the Schutzgeld appear as a species of the genus now 
 known as "police graft." 
 
 Justi broadly hints that "the benefit of clergy" had German 
 forms which amounted to serious abuses, e. g., in freeing from personal 
 taxation as "Gelekrte," men who had made no good use of their time in 
 the university.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 385 
 
 and other taxes are collected by the same officials, so that the expense 
 of separate employees shall be saved (II, 351). 
 
 OF TAXES ON OCCUPATIONS, OR SO-CALLED EXCISE AND IMPOSTS 
 
 356. Since immovable goods can be burdened with taxes to 
 the extent of only one-fourth or one-third of their earnings, and since 
 no very considerable sum can be raised from personal taxation, the 
 gainful occupations must be the next source of revenue (II, 352). 
 
 357. Occupations may be taxed (a) on the materials which 
 they use, and on their output (excise); or (b) directly, according 
 to the extent of their operations (II, 353). 
 
 358. The former method is almost universal in Europe (II, 353). 
 
 359. The latter has a minor place (II, 353). 
 
 360. Various causes contribute to the vogue of excises in 
 Germany: thus (a) the limitation of tariffs by the laws of the Empire 
 gave occasion for excises as the most convenient and productive 
 substitute. Again (6) it was observed that large industries were 
 growing up in the towns without paying much into the national 
 treasury; (c) they are means of getting revenue from individuals 
 who have no immovable goods (II, 355). 
 
 361. It is not true that the owners of real estate can make the 
 taxes which they pay fall upon other subjects, because customary 
 price defeats this shifting of the incidence of the tax (II, 355). 
 
 362. A further reason for the use of excise is that it gives the 
 ruler a much freer hand than in levying land taxes (II, 356). 
 
 363. Excise is either universal falling upon all articles without 
 exception which are used for the support of life or come into the 
 channels of trade; or particular falling upon selected articles of 
 consumption or wares (II, 356). 
 
 364. Excise does not conform to the rules above given for 
 taxation; for (i) it limits the reasonable freedom of human action 
 (II, 358); (2) it is detrimental to crafts and commerce (II, 359); 
 
 (3) it does not spread the burden of taxation equally (II, 361); 
 
 (4) it has no secure basis, since fraud and peculation are afforded 
 large scope (II, 362); (5) its collection requires many officials and 
 large expense (II, 364). 
 
 365. The claims for excise are insufficient; viz.: (i) It puts a
 
 386 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 share of the common burdens upon all; (2) by limiting his expendi- 
 tures each may ease the burden at will; (3) it calls for only a 
 fraction of earnings a little at a time; (4) but almost without the 
 knowledge of the subjects it increases the "readiest means" of the 
 state; (5) no sheriffs' process (execution) is required to enforce it; 
 (6) aliens must bear their share; (7) it is a means of controlling the 
 commerce of the country, and of promoting manufactures (II, 365). 
 
 366. Since immediate abolition of excise is hopeless, the rules 
 for its employment must be stated, viz.: (i) All the rules previously 
 laid down in the case of tariffs, etc. (II, 288-300) ; (2) excise rates 
 must respect the rate of earnings of the different occupations, and 
 must call for only a small fraction of the earnings of those that deal 
 in the necessities of life (II, 368); (3) in order that moderation of 
 excise be not misused for unwarranted increase of profits, the police 
 must interfere and fix the price of necessities (II, 369); (4) larger 
 demands may be made upon luxuries (II, 369); (5) but the three 
 grades of luxury must be respected (II, 369; vide I, 231); (6) excise 
 is surely excessive when it amounts to more than the remaining 
 earnings of the craft, or when it amounts to a half or two-thirds of 
 an article on sale (II, 369); (7) excise must vary according as the 
 transactions are first, second, or third hand, and whether a craft 
 contributes or not to the completion or improvement of a thing 
 (H, 370). 
 
 367. Occupation-taxes [Gewerbe-Steuer] might be introduced, 
 in harmony with the fundamental rules of taxation, and to the 
 advantage both of ruler and subject (II, 373). 
 
 368. The essential principle of this type of tax is adjustment 
 to the scale of income of the occupation (II, 374-92).' 
 
 OF THE RIGHT OF THE SOVEREIGN TO IMPOSE SPECIAL TAXES 
 
 369. These revenues may be called accidental in a double sense: 
 First the sovereign power finds occasion to raise certain revenues 
 without making the revenues themselves the ultimate purpose, and 
 at the same time without prejudice to the actual ultimate purpose of 
 the state; second, these revenues may be called accidental because 
 
 1 Justi elaborates a scheme of occupation taxes in considerable 
 detail, and seems to regard it as wholly practicable and wise.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 387 
 
 they are based merely on accidental arrangements and certain 
 incidents, either of the whole republic or of the supreme power; or 
 of those subjects who contribute to these revenues. Such occasional 
 circumstances are so various that some of them are likely to be 
 present always, and their revenues consequently aggregate an 
 appreciable sum (II, 400). 
 
 370. These accidents may be grouped in five classes, and we 
 may arrange Jhem in the order of their probable value in yielding 
 revenue, viz.: (i) Revenues from overlordship of the state over 
 certain properties, to be distinguished from the Regalia (II, 401-11); 
 (2) rights of revenue that are incidents of the administration of 
 justice (II, 412-16); (3) the revenues accruing through administra- 
 tion of the police system (II, 417-21); (4) revenues incidental to the 
 war-making power, including subsidies (II, 422-25); (5) revenues 
 from sovereignty over the ecclesiastical system (II, 426-29). l 
 
 ON THE COLLECTING OF EXTRAORDINARY SUMS FOR THE 
 USE OF THE STATE 
 
 371. In case of war, or other crises, exceptional demands for 
 money arise. It is not for the cameralist to decide whether the 
 occasion actually demands the exceptional sums, but if the ruler has 
 so decided it is the task of the cameralist to find the ways and means. 
 These are chiefly two: (i) Extraordinary contributions of the sub- 
 jects; (2) the credit of the ruler and of the country (II, 430-33). 
 
 372. There are two ways of levying extraordinary contributions, 
 viz.: (i) By increasing the rates of ordinary contributions and taxes; 
 (2) by levying a new sort of contribution. The preference is to be 
 determined by the circumstances of the state. If the sums to be 
 raised are not too great, if there is no need of instant payment, and 
 if the ruler can assure the subjects that the increase will be only 
 temporary, the former method is preferable, because the technique 
 for raising such contributions is already in operation. The existing 
 taxes must, however, be at such rates that they do not absorb one- 
 third of earnings, or the other form must be adopted (II, 435). 
 
 ' These items as treated by Justi are so largely reflections of tem- 
 porary conditions, that the details yield nothing for our purpose that 
 has not appeared elsewhere.
 
 388 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 373. The best form of extraordinary levy is a tax on social 
 position [Wurdensteuer], that is, all subjects, lay and clerical, are to 
 be arranged in classes and subdivisions, and the higher the social 
 rank and dignity the higher must be the rate of this tax. Thus the 
 levy falls to a considerable extent upon persons who were not bur- 
 dened before, and who have the ready means of payment (II, 443). x 
 
 374. One of the first rules of a wise government must be to 
 preserve its credit, and this depends, first, on integrity in its trans- 
 actions; second, on prompt payment of interest (II, 452). 
 
 375. The establishment of a bank is also a useful means of 
 obtaining control of extraordinary sums (II, 455). 
 
 376. Another means is the provision of annuities, the capital 
 of which falls to the state on the death of the annuitants (II, 455). 
 
 377. So-called "Tontines," invented in France, and named 
 after their originator, Tonti, are also to be considered (II, 456) 
 
 378. Lotteries may also be used when exceptional sums are 
 needed (II, 458). 
 
 379. Scruples about the fundamental morality of annuities, 
 tontines, and lotteries are not sufficiently valid to estop the state from 
 Hsing them (II, 459). 
 
 380. Although it is impossible to exclude aliens from invest- 
 ment in annuities, tontines, and other forms of state debts, yet so far 
 as possible subjects should be preferred as investors, so that the 
 interest will not go out of the country. Whether money should be 
 borrowed abroad for the sake of winning other nations to our interest 
 is another question which belongs to Staalskunst (II, 461). 
 
 381. When the credit of the country makes borrowing difficult, 
 then one of the more common devices is to farm out certain fixed 
 revenues, and to obtain advances from the parties to whom they are 
 farmed (II, 461). 
 
 382. A similar device is to make over certain domains or other 
 revenues of the state to a lender (II, 462). 
 
 383. A still more desperate device is the pawning of domains 
 or even provinces (II, 463). 
 
 384. A cameralist will today scarcely recommend the absolute 
 alienation of territories and people for the sake of money (II, 465). 
 
 1 Additional minor taxes are discussed (II, 445-49).
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 389 
 
 OP THE EXPENSES OF THE STATE 
 
 385. The second chief responsibility of the cameralist is with 
 the disbursements of the state, and this is quite as important as 
 responsibility for the revenues (II, 469). x 
 
 386. Instead of being expended for the common happiness, the 
 means of the state are (i) often wasted; (2) used with shortsighted 
 niggardliness; (3) applied at the wrong point for the best results; 
 (4) unsystematically administered (II, 471). 
 
 387. In order to avoid these errors, the rules laid down in the 
 introduction must be applied, viz. : (i) Outlays must be in accordance 
 with the circumstances and revenues of the state; (2) the "readiest 
 means" of the state must be used for no other purpose than the best 
 good of ruler and subjects (II, 473). 
 
 388. From the previous fundamental principles we derive the 
 first rule of wise expenditure, viz., No outlay must be undertaken 
 without the most thorough previous consideration, and estimate of 
 the involved cost, and of the income likely to accrue from the same 
 to the state (II, 476) . 
 
 389. The second rule is, that the outlay should never exceed 
 the income (II, 478). 
 
 390. Rule three. For all outlays the "readiest means" must 
 be already in hand, and in no case should a start be made with a 
 debt (II, 479)- 
 
 391. Rule four. All expenditures of the state must be made 
 certain (II, 480). 
 
 392. Rule five. No outlay should be made which tends per- 
 manently to diminish either the available or the total "means" of 
 the state (II, 481). 
 
 393. Rule six. So far as possible, outlays should be so ordered 
 that the money will be expended within the state, and will get into 
 circulation in the sustaining system of the country (II, 482). 
 
 ' Justi accuses the cameralistic writers of having failed to give this 
 subject proportional attention, and assigns as one of the reasons that 
 they have had little faith that rulers would pay attention to cameralistic 
 precepts on the subject. Justi disclaims the purpose of instructing 
 courts as to their duties, but thinks k the duty of cameralists to system- 
 atize wise rules of administration, whether rulers adopt them or not
 
 39 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 394. Rule seven. The importance of every proposed outlay 
 must be measured by the amount of income that it is likely to return 
 for the welfare of the state (II, 484). 
 
 395. Rule eight. Outlays must be arranged in the order of 
 their usefulness for the common good of ruler and subjects (II, 486). 
 
 396. The great management of the state bears much similarity 
 to the housekeeping of private persons; hence the rules that are 
 valid in private housekeeping apply, with changed details, to the use 
 of the "means" of the state (II, 487). 
 
 396A. Rule nine. The necessities of the state must take pre- 
 cedence of all other demands, and necessities must be reckoned in the 
 following grades, viz.: (i) Those on which the stability of the 
 republic depends; (2) those which are of qualified necessity, i. e., 
 from omission of which the community would suffer great harm, 
 such as loss of industries through failure of proper promotion; 
 (3) those which might be omitted without positive injury, but without 
 which the maximum happiness of the state cannot be reached 
 (II, 488). 
 
 397. Even expenses of the first grade should not be covered 
 so extravagantly that outlays of the other grades would be impossible 
 (II, 489). 
 
 398. Rule ten. Only when all the necessary expenses are 
 provided for can the means of the state be appropriated to con- 
 veniencies (II, 490). 
 
 399. Rule eleven. After all outlay is provided for which is 
 required for the needs and conveniencies of the state, attention may 
 be given to comfort, dignity, display, and ornamentation (II, 491).' 
 
 400. Rule twelve. The aim should be to put the finances of the 
 country in such condition that not merely the necessities and con- 
 
 1 Justi adds: "I have no hesitation in giving the preference to 
 outlays for the display of the court: for since the chief purpose of these 
 outlays is to impress foreign nations with the prosperity and power of the 
 state, no better place of using the money can be found than at the court 
 of the monarch, where it most directly appeals to the eye of foreigners. 
 Still, that which is appropriate for the comfort and elegance of the 
 country in other places must not be forgotten. It is not consistent if 
 the residence charms the eye of foreigners, while the rest of the country 
 has a poverty-stricken appearance.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 391 
 
 veniencies, but also the comforts and elegancies may be secured 
 (II, 492). 
 
 401. Rule thirteen. If the government is to be in a situation 
 to make fair appropriations of all kinds, it must in all its outlays 
 observe reasonable economy (II, 493). 
 
 402. Rule fourteen. Care must be taken that economy be not 
 turned into greed, especially through contempt of the ruler for 
 certain needs of his subjects, while his passions lead him to favor 
 other outlays (II, 495). 
 
 403. Rule fifteen. The finance bureau must constantly have 
 the most exact information about the condition of all the funds 
 (II, 409). 
 
 404. Rule sixteen. No disbursements should be made except 
 upon strict account (II, 500). 
 
 405. Rule seventeen. Entrepreneurs should be used in all 
 cases which involve employment of a large number, and many 
 minor outlays (II, 501). 
 
 406. Rule eighteen. Nothing which can be obtained with a 
 lump sum should be subject to several charges (II, 305). 
 
 407. Rule nineteen. The persons expending the money of the 
 state should not themselves make additional costs necessary (II, 504). 
 
 408. Rule twenty. Everything must be supplied at the proper 
 time, with foresight and advantage, and by cash payments; and 
 when it is profitable stocks of goods needed by the state should be 
 kept. 
 
 409. Rule twenty-one. Strict accounts, in perfect order, must 
 be kept of the outlays of the state (II, 507).' 
 
 410. After provision for the military budget (II, 527-57), and 
 for the court budget (II, 560-86), the cameralistic expenses proper 
 may be divided into eight groups: (i) Moneys for the civil-list 
 and dowries (II, 588); (2) appropriations for the various admin- 
 
 1 The following section, viz., Division Two, "Of the Proper Ordering 
 of Expenditure, or the General Budget," contains simply considerations 
 still more strictly technical and does not call for analysis. We may note 
 one important precept, viz., // a European state wants to have influence, 
 it must devote at least two-thirds of its revenues to the military Budget 
 (H, 5*3).
 
 392 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 istrative expenses (II, 589) ; (3) the expenses of levying and collect- 
 ing the revenues, and of maintaining the sources from which they are 
 derived (II, 592) ; (4) the salaries and pensions of all civil servants 
 in the state, finance, police, and justice bureaus (II, 597); (5) the 
 expenses of bringing land under cultivation (II, 602) ; (6) the expenses 
 of buildings for the use of the state (II, 607); (7) the support of the 
 ecclesiastical and school systems (II, 609); (8) expenses for the 
 comfort and adornment of the country (II, 613). x 
 
 411. The organization and the correlation of the cameralistic 
 system, and of the bureaus belonging to it, is one of the most impor- 
 tant elements in the government of a state. The whole management 
 of a community rests upon it, and to a certain extent its whole internal 
 constitution rests upon it. The administrative police institutions 
 of the state are a part of the cameral system. At all events the two 
 arc inseparable, because the former constitute the ground of the 
 "readiest means" of the state and must in turn be supported by the 
 same. In this most general signification of the cameral system, it 
 comprehends not merely all police institutions and measures, and 
 consequently the commercial and agricultural administration, but 
 also the administration of justice, at least so far as concerns the 
 technique of the same, and the nature [Beschaflenheit] of the laws, 
 as well as the management of the military system. There remain 
 therefore only foreign affairs, which may be contrasted with cameral 
 business, and which constitute the second essential element in the 
 government of the state. Important as the constitution of the 
 cameral system is then in itself, it is especially so on account of the 
 peculiar traits of our times. Since the European powers have placed 
 themselves on a constant war footing, since they have made it a part 
 
 1 The remainder of this subdivision (II, 614-60) is entirely devoted 
 to the routine of cameralistic functions. Justi makes the topic of cor- 
 relating the different kinds of cameral administration co-ordinate with 
 (a) the raising of funds; (6) the reasonable use of the "means" of the 
 state. The technique of this organization as outlined in the remainder 
 of the Staatnvirthsckaft contains nothing directly material to our purpose. 
 Nevertheless, as a bit of shading for the picture of the state which we 
 have already found in the book, an abstract from Justi's introduction 
 to the section, is added.
 
 JUSTI'S "STAATSWIRTHSCHAFT" 393 
 
 of their programme to encourage commerce and manufactures and 
 the sustaining class, as well as the general culture of their countries, 
 the cameral system has taken on a quite other form. Those states 
 in which the rulers two or three hundred years ago either left the 
 finances to their consorts, or intrusted them as a minor duty to a 
 privy council or court, now have various great and important bureaus 
 for the administration of the same, and meanwhile the revenues have 
 increased five, six, and ten times (II, 664). l 
 
 1 The remainder of the book contains (i) a general sketch of the 
 administrative organization of the chief European states (II, 666-84); 
 (2) a brief discussion of propositions looking to improvement of the 
 cameral organization (II, 684-88) ; (3) Justi's own programme of reor- 
 ganization (II, 688-702) ; (4) the fundamental ordinances and technical 
 processes of cameral administration (II, 702-44). In this portion of the 
 book a conspicuous trait of Justi's method is particularly prominent, viz., 
 an appearance of studied effort to avoid giving credit to previous writers. 
 This peculiarity cannot be overlooked as a symptom of the literary 
 practice of his time, as the usage of previous cameralists sufficiently 
 shows. Justi was exceptionally unwilling to give other writers their 
 due unless they were safely dead. Montesquieu is the only author whom 
 he frequently mentions by name. Only three or four others are men- 
 tioned at all in this volume, and never with precise reference to passages 
 by which the correctness of the judgment passed upon them might be 
 decided. When Justi refers to "other cameralists" who have proposed 
 modifications of the system, he gives no clue to their identity, so that 
 their own grounds for their propositions might be examined. In this 
 respect his methods are as crude as his manners. 
 
 I regret that I have been unable to secure a copy of the work in 
 which Justi expanded his views of fiscal science; viz., Das System des 
 Finanzwesens, 1766.
 
 CHAPTER XV 
 IUSTFS POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 
 
 As we have seen from various points of approach, cameralism 
 was not primarily a philosophy, nor was it an economic theory 
 in the modern sense. It was a technique and a technology. 
 In so far as it rested on a basis of principles, they were prima- 
 rily political rather than economic generalizations. That is, 
 political purposes were chiefly in view, and economic means 
 were enlisted in the cameralistic technique to promote those 
 purposes. 
 
 If would be easy to cull out of Justi's books sentences 
 from which we might infer that he was, in the last analysis, a 
 full-fledged democrat. Such an inference, however, would 
 be as unwarranted as the contrary conclusion that he manifested 
 no democratic opinions or sympathies. The plain fact is 
 that his thinking had, so to speak, special apartments for 
 as many different orders of opinions, which would have treated 
 one another roughly if they had met face to face. Occupying 
 separate quarters they could ignore actual incompatibilities. 
 
 In his apartments devoted to the most general aspects of 
 life, the conspicuous motto on the wall was: "The Happiness 
 of Ruler and Subjects." 
 
 In the apartments assigned to the primary necessities of 
 life, the fireside talk was a ringing of changes upon "Earn and 
 Save!" 
 
 In the apartments reserved for plans and programmes 
 of political life was an undertone, always audible, droning 
 variations of the constant theme: "The clue to life is a good 
 king, with well-trained civil servants and docile subjects." 
 
 Now, it would be folly to class a house as "disorderly" 
 simply because its tenants were of such diverse types, but the 
 
 394
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 395 
 
 moment it becomes necessary for the lodgers to decide upon 
 a common standard the problem of harmonizing these con- 
 ceptions is imminent. It by no means follows that their 
 different outlooks upon life are essentially incompatible. In 
 composing them, however, it is inevitable that different forms 
 and contents and implications of each will from time to time 
 control, and that one of the main conceptions will dominate 
 the others. Men will ask one another, What is happiness ? 
 How is it composed? What does it involve? Is it one 
 and the same thing for everybody, or does it vary from 
 man to man, from time to time, from place to place ? To 
 what extent is it simply our own affair, and to what extent 
 does it depend on other people ? Again, they will ask, How 
 many ways are there to earn and save ? What do these ways 
 have to do with one another ? How do they depend on one 
 another? What advantages has one over another? How 
 far may the arts of earning and saving be developed beyond 
 present methods? To what extent may we discover more 
 fundamental and inclusive principles of earning and saving 
 and of guaranteeing to each all that he earns and saves? 
 Still further, men will ask, What proof have we that kings 
 are essentials to life, any more than stone hatchets, or bone 
 fish-hooks? Why may not kings and paternalism be out- 
 grown, just like wooden plows, and bows and arrows, and 
 flint and steel ? When are kings and kingcraft good and when 
 are they bad? What recourse have men when kings and 
 kingcraft fail? 
 
 Men need not have asked all these questions by any means, 
 nor others equally obvious, before they would be capable of 
 seeing that Justi's system, however useful for its purpose, 
 was very far from a conclusive science of the things with which it 
 was concerned. It contained rudimentary moral and economic 
 and political philosophies but neither of these philosophies 
 had been thought through, and the relations between them
 
 39 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 had been subjected to no critical analysis whatsoever. In 
 effect it was plans and specifications of the best paternalistic 
 government that could be devised, with the reservation that 
 no questions were to be asked about the finality of that pater- 
 nalistic government as an irreducible minimum. It was 
 accordingly a system of operating the paternalistic type of 
 state, first and foremost, so that it could maintain itself in 
 the rivalries of similar neighboring states, through systematic 
 superintendence and stimulation of approved thrift, without 
 prying behind the precepts of commonplace prudence, and 
 with such resulting happiness to the people as was to be gained 
 in the course of making the permanence and power of the 
 paternalistic state the supreme end. In other words, so far 
 as Justi's type of cameralism held the center of attention, it 
 postponed all larger questions of social science, and substituted 
 for them a catechism of the routine to be observed in govern- 
 mental bureaus, of the attitude which the ruler would main- 
 tain toward government and subjects if his views agreed with 
 Justi's, and of the attitude which the subject should main- 
 tain in any event toward ruler and administration. Otherwise 
 expressed, all the social science there was within the sphere 
 of cameralism was first, as we shall see presently, a more or 
 less explicit political philosophy, then a managerial ritual, 
 with no positive provision either for revising the ritual itself 
 or for reappraising the purposes which the ritual was supposed 
 to serve. It had the same relation to the problems of society 
 in general that a hook on tactics would have to statesmanship. 1 
 In applying the term "ritual" to Justi's cameralism, I 
 do not mean to assert that it was necessarily arbitrary in detail. 
 On the contrary, the larger number of its precepts were emi- 
 
 1 Parts of the contents of Justi's tooks might be cited as proof that 
 the comparison is an exaggeration, especially the volume, Natur und 
 Wesen der Staaten. If substance, not form, is decisive, the parallel is 
 exact.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 397 
 
 nently reasonable. The ritualism came from its relation 
 to the major premise, viz., the finality of the paternalistic 
 state. As items in the operation of such a moral economy 
 as present analysis discovers in human experience, these 
 same precepts might be no more ritualistic than valid rules 
 of hygiene. 
 
 This appraisal of Justi's system may be varied as follows: 
 It was an undigested mixture of judgments about means and 
 ends. It did not consciously encounter the previous question, 
 viz., How shall we know when such means as the type of state, 
 and ruler, and bureaucracy which we now take for granted, 
 and which are at present assumed to be indispensable for 
 the types of ends which we also take for granted, lose their 
 value as means, to such an extent that we can no longer take 
 them for granted as approximate ends ? The parallel question 
 would also have challenged the authority of Justi's system, 
 but it had not appeared above his horizon; viz., How may we 
 know when the types of ends which we take for granted cease 
 to satisfy the conditions of life, and consequently impeach the 
 means on which we have relied for the conduct of life ? That 
 is, the autocratic state and ruler and bureaucracy had so 
 imposed themselves on the thoughts and feelings of the time 
 that they were virtually valued as both means and end of 
 human purposes, and criticism of them to discover how far 
 they were merely provisional means to mediate ends was 
 marking time in the cameralistic technology. Meanwhile, 
 such larger social philosophy as ventured to show signs of 
 life within or around this technology was in its primary charac- 
 teristics more prominently political than economic. We shall 
 attempt to justify this judgment by an examination, first, 
 of the Natur und Wesen der Staaten, and second, of the Grund- 
 riss einer Guten Regierung. 
 
 Of these two books, which we shall notice not in ineir 
 chronological but in their logical order, we may first observe
 
 398 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in general, that they merely elaborate themes which were 
 contained in Staatswirthschaft. Indeed that volume in prin- 
 ciple exhausts Justi's cameralism. The later volumes con- 
 tain nothing except illustrative material which was implied, 
 if not expressed, in the earlier synoptic book. We shall there- 
 fore be able to do justice to these volumes, as expansions of 
 Justi's system, without the detailed analysis which was neces- 
 sary in presenting his general survey. 
 
 We turn to the more fundamental of these special treatises. 1 
 If thifr-beok had been written for the purpose of supporting 
 our main thesis about cameralism as essentially a political 
 rather than an economic theory, it could hardly have been 
 more unequivocal. 2 For our purposes the Preface is most 
 important, because the body of the book merely enlarged 
 upon principles which are sufficiently prominent in our account 
 of Staatswirthschaft. 
 
 The contents of the Preface may be summarized in this way: 
 
 Montesquieu's Esprit des Lois is in many respects an exemplary 
 book, but it contains certain errors which should be corrected. 
 
 This book may be regarded as an alternative treatise on the 
 spirit of the laws [Geist der Cesetze]. "After I have discussed the 
 essence and nature of states, and have pointed out the errors of 
 Montesquieu in this connection, I come to the essence [Wwfn] 
 of the laws, which are the means through which states must attain 
 their essential purpose,- namely, the common happiness \gemein- 
 schajlliche Gltickseligkeit], which means can be derived nowhere 
 else than from the essence and nature of states as their chief source." 
 
 1 Die Natur und das Wesen der Staaten, als die Grundwis sense haft 
 der Staatskunst, der Policey, und aller Regierungsivissenschaften, des- 
 gleichen als die Quelle aller Cesetze, abgchandelt von Johann Heinrich 
 
 Gottloh von Justi, Berlin, Stettin und Leipzig 1760 (488 pages 
 
 + index of 32 pages). 
 
 It was not from this book, however, that I arrived at my interpreta- 
 tion. Long before I discovered it, I had reached my conclusion from 
 equally decisive but less obvious evidence.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 399 
 
 "It will easily be seen that this book contains the fundamental 
 science of all the economic and camcral sciences, and that it con- 
 stitutes, so to speak, a sort of political metaphysic for all the govern- 
 mental sciences. For there can be no doubt that all these sciences 
 must be based upon the essence and nature of a (sic) state, and there- 
 from alone, as from their fountain-head [Plauptquelle], must be 
 derived." 
 
 We have inverted the order of Justi's paragraphs, so as 
 to place his more general propositions first, without affecting 
 his thought. The more specific reason which he assigns for 
 writing the book is in the earlier paragraphs of the Preface, viz. : 
 
 I made the plan of this work five years ago. 1 Meanwhile it has 
 reshaped itself in my mind, in accordance, as I think, with a better 
 general idea which I have meanwhile formed. The necessity of such 
 a work was evident to me" from the time that I began to write upon 
 the economic and cameral sciences. 
 
 All these sciences, and all those which are required for the gov- 
 ernment of a state, must in a word be derived from the general nature 
 and essence of states, and nothing can be securely established in 
 them if one does not constantly look back to the nature of civic 
 institutions [bUrgerlichen Verfassungen], If accordingly I would 
 justify this or that principle or rule in Staatskunst, in Policey, in 
 Finanz-Wissenschaft, and the other economic sciences, I had to 
 trace the grounds of the same very remotely [weitl&ujtig] from the 
 essence and the nature of states; and when this principle or rule 
 emerged in another portion of these sciences, it was necessary to 
 repeat the most important grounds, in order to show the harmony 
 of the same with the essence of civic institutions. I judged accord- 
 ingly that a special treatise on the essence and the nature of states 
 would serve my own as well as my readers' convenience, since I 
 would not then be under the necessity, in all my subsequent works, 
 
 1 If we take the statement literally, it would locate this passage in 
 Justi's thinking during the interval between his departure from Vienna 
 and his arrival in Gdttingen, i. e., about a year before publication of 
 Staatswirthschaft. It is not unlikely that revision of his notes for that 
 volume clarified his ideas in the direction of the book before us.
 
 400 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 repeatedly to show the correspondence of my fundamental proposi- 
 tions with the nature of a state. 
 
 Thus we have Justi's own direct testimony that all the 
 sciences embraced in the general sense of the term cameralism 
 were, in his view, deductions from a fundamental political 
 philosophy. Moreover, all activities in civic society were 
 to find their rationale in this a priori, viz., the presupposed 
 "essence and nature of states." This concept served in Justi's 
 thinking as the finality back of which analysis could not pene- 
 trate. A large part of the difference between this type of 
 thinking and modern sociological inquiry is a consequence 
 of penetration by the latter into the social processes antecedent 
 in time to the existence of states, or more general in content 
 than civic activities. The resultant perception that states 
 are but one of the many variations of means by which men 
 seek to accomplish their purposes displaces the concept ' ' essence 
 and nature of states" as the ultimate term in explanation of 
 civic activities, and substitutes the essence and nature of 
 associating persons, whose purposes give the sliding scale 
 of values to all their machineries. 
 
 The argument of Natur und Wesen may be compressed 
 into the following resume": 
 
 First, the assumption of an original condition of "natural free- 
 dom" (chap. vii). Justi's particular version of "natural freedom" 
 need not be analyzed in detail. While he does not arrive at a plau- 
 sible hypothesis of reconciliation between the notion of the freedom 
 of individuals and freedom of groups, within which there was no 
 freedom, he satisfies himself that there is enough in the idea for a 
 major premise, and he proceeds to build upon it. 
 
 Second, the derivation of social life from an inborn "social 
 impulse" is denied ({5). On the contrary, perception of advantage 
 from social reciprocity, i. e., in the last resort, reason [Vernunft], 
 is the cause of social life (6). With the development of circum- 
 stances, and corresponding development of wants, the utility of
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 401 
 
 extending social combinations appealed to developing reason. Fear 
 was one of the tributary motives. Some more intelligent men 
 began to see the advantage of using compulsion upon weaker men, 
 subjecting them to their laws, and making them serve their own 
 advantage and conscience. Thus the condition of compelling or 
 being compelled, the condition of war, took its origin. Hence come 
 consolidation of related societies into larger societies, in order to offer 
 more resistance to less closely related societies (7).* 
 
 Third, these aggregations of people in societies do not yet con- 
 stitute republics. Mutual aid [Beystand] is the purpose of societies, 
 but republics have an incomparably greater purpose. In these 
 societies all men lived still in the state of natural freedom. Each 
 was subject to his own will and laws in so far as he was not constrained 
 by others. Since they had not yet merged their will, the will of 
 each was entirely free. It was within the free choice of each to make 
 use of the advantage of reciprocal support, or to forego the same and 
 to live each for himself. This freedom to step out of society at will 
 is common to all societies which have no overlord, or which do not 
 live under the laws of a republic. Particularly, however, the differ- 
 ence between societies and republics consists in the latter having a 
 supreme power set over them, while the former have not. When 
 therefore the societies compel one of their members to conform to 
 their purposes and to the social compacts, this occurs according to 
 the laws and the condition of war, not however according to the nature 
 of a supreme power (9). 
 
 It may be asked whether it were not possible that men could have 
 lived in the condition of natural freedom in such societies, without 
 creating republics. In my opinion that is precisely the question 
 which is put in theology when is is asked whether it were not possible 
 that men might have continued in the state of innocence, .... 
 (fxo). 
 
 Rather is it probable that increasing vice and license, which 
 disturbed the internal peace of these societies, was the immediate cause 
 of adopting civic laws and institutions. When such disorders occurred 
 the most reputable and reasonable must naturally have set them- 
 selves up as arbiters, in order to abate the evils and to restore peace. 
 
 Justi rejects Hobbes's theory of the inborn propensity to domineer.
 
 402 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 .... This was a way to laws, or a beginning of them. The 
 approach to civic institutions became closer and closer, while people 
 were probably not conscious of it. ... (11). 
 
 The actual institution of republics was probably not after one 
 fashion, but (i) through the growth of patriarchal power into 
 actual overlordship (12); (2) through the respect and eminence 
 which certain men gained in their societies (13); (3) through 
 instruction of the people by skilled and experienced men, in the ways 
 of attaining the comforts of human life (14); (4) the leaders of new 
 
 colonies have thereby at the same time founded states (15) 
 
 The earliest states were small monarchies, these being the most 
 natural transition from freedom to civic institutions (16). All 
 these little monarchies were very mild and differed very little from 
 the condition of natural freedom The people in their assem- 
 blies always retained the law-giving power in their hands 
 
 The kings and princes had only the right to propose and to convince 
 by argument (vide Tacitus, Germania, chap. xi). Only in time of 
 war had the magistrates, according to the testimony of Julius Caesar 
 (de bcllo Gal., lib. vi), right over life and death. This however was 
 demanded by the nature of the case, if a commander were to 
 accomplish anything (17). From this slight removal of the first 
 states from the condition of natural freedom, as well as from the 
 unobserved growth of the civic organization, it follows in my opinion 
 indubitably that men never chose to subject themselves to a severe 
 form of government. This intention of the peoples is also founded 
 in the nature of the case. Men would have been the most insane 
 fools if they had been willing deliberately to exchange their most 
 precious possession, freedom, for a government under which they 
 would be slaves. The will of the peoples, upon entrance into repub- 
 lics, was thus doubtless this: that they would surrender their natural 
 freedom and subject themselves to the government and laws of another 
 only in so far as necessary for the ultimate purpose of the republics. 
 Who however would deny that this will of the peoples must not be 
 regarded in each and every government ?' Besides this, the impulse 
 
 1 Justi's frequent use of the double negative without the affirmative 
 force makes a puzzle of such a sentence as this, in which the meaning 
 cannot be positively fixed by the context. I think the above rendering
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 403 
 
 to dominate over others is not grounded in human nature It is 
 merely a consequence of a mediocre understanding. Men undoubt- 
 edly presuppose that they wish to be ruled by a perfect understanding. 
 This advantage, this quality, can alone move them to intrust to 
 another the government over themselves. Indeed, since finally God 
 has put us in the world with equal freedom, dignity, and rights, 
 I derive from all this the conclusion that it is the duty and obligation 
 of every government to limit the natural freedom of its subjects, only 
 in so far as the ultimate purpose of republics requires, and that always 
 the best government is the one which without interference with the 
 ultimate purpose of republics most nearly approaches natural free- 
 dom. This conclusion, which follows from the origin of republics, 
 I regard as a fundamental principle, which I shall often use in treat- 
 ing the sciences of government (18). 
 
 Justi appears to have entertained no doubt of the cogency 
 and conclusivcness of this patchwork of guesses and irrelevan- 
 cies and non-sequiturs. In contrast with Schroder, Justi had 
 exchanged the theological for a pseudo-rationalistic major 
 premise. There is no change in the finality, for practical 
 purposes, of the pseudo-absolutism which the premise supports. 
 The twentieth-century mind finds extreme difficulty in believ- 
 ing that an adult accustomed to reflection could ever have 
 rested content with the puerilities of either argument. We 
 flatter ourselves, however, by underestimating the capacity 
 even of the sophisticated mind for self-deception. The psy- 
 chological situation, in the case both of Schroder and of Justi, 
 was first the unquestioned concrete datum, the existing abso- 
 lutistic state; and second, the problem, to find a thread of 
 association which would act as binding-twine and hold together 
 with this datum the remaining assortment of ideas in the 
 
 faithfully reflects the ambiguity. The original reads: "\Vt-r \vollte 
 aber wohl laugnen, (lass dieser \Ville <ler Yolker bey alien und jeden 
 Regierungen nicht in Betrac lit gezogen \verden miisste ?" I understand 
 Justi to urge the antecedent probability that every government would 
 regard the will of the subjects.
 
 404 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 minds of the authors themselves and of their contemporaries. 
 The effectiveness of the notions which proved to serve this 
 purpose was evidently derived, not from logic but from sug- 
 gestion. The datum " absolutistic state" was no more deduced 
 from Schroder's or Justi's premises than the earth was deduced 
 from Atlas. A plausible justification for the cameralistic 
 state was set up, not so much in the uncritical explanation 
 of its origin, as in the presumption that it was supernaturally 
 devoted and adapted to its purpose of serving the general 
 interest. 
 
 Throughout Justi's writings the idea of the common good, 
 as the ultimate end of the state, repeatedly recurs. The impli- 
 cations of the idea are indefinite, but it unquestionably contains 
 elements which went into the structure of later democratic 
 conceptions. 1 A suspensive veto, so to speak, was held over 
 these democratic elements by the inveterate assumption that 
 the government was actually conforming to its destiny of 
 preternatural wisdom and righteousness in the interest of 
 all concerned, whatever might be the immediate appearances 
 to the contrary. Thus the actual order of thought in Justi's 
 political philosophy was, first, the state as it is must be accepted 
 as the ultimate human recourse for promotion of temporal 
 happiness; second, the details involved in the conception 
 "temporal happiness" must be learned by experience; third, 
 rulers must be relied upon to show the wisdom and righteous- 
 ness requisite for setting in operation, in due time, the measures 
 which will secure their subjects temporal happiness. 
 
 In a later paragraph (23) Justi emphasizes the crucial 
 conception in this philosophy, viz., the merging of the wills 
 
 1 This may be inferred from the very significant fact that Justi 
 sometimes uses the still more democratic phrase, Gluckseligkeit dor 
 Unlerthanen, as designation of the ultimate purpose of the state (e. g., 
 36). The whole conception was as yet, however, a matter of rhetoric 
 rather than a decisive factor in statecraft.
 
 45 
 
 of many free individuals into a single will. This conceit was 
 not the democratic idea of a constantly re-established consen- 
 sus between the members of the state. It was a notion of 
 transference of the individual wills to the ruler, and their 
 fusion in him into a transcendent will. This occurred once 
 for all. Subsequent generations had nothing to do but accept 
 the arrangement. The use to which this conception is put is 
 indicated in general in the opening paragraph of the third 
 chapter, as follows: 
 
 The merging of many wills into a single will is the first moral 
 ground of republics, and that which chiefly constitutes the civic 
 condition. If many wills are to be consolidated in a single will, 
 they must all have one and the same paramount purpose, and this 
 chief purpose of each must include all their special and incidental 
 purposes. In short, those who merge their wills must all have a 
 common paramount purpose which leads all their transactions. 
 The question then is, Wherein does this paramount purpose consist 
 which produces the merging of the wills in the founding and building 
 of republics? This ultimate purpose can be no other than the uni- 
 versal best [das allgemeine Beste], the welfare of each and every one 
 of the families which as aforesaid merged with one another, in a 
 word the common happiness [gemeinschaftiiche Glucksdigkcit] of 
 the whole state. 
 
 At this point a single comment will be sufficient. If Justi's 
 conception of the general welfare had actually been the prime 
 consideration in his reasoning, he would have been forced to 
 make it the major premise of an objective critique of the com- 
 petence of absolutism to attain the involved results. This 
 plane of reasoning was beyond Justi. It turns out that, in effect, 
 the perpetuation of the absolutistic state is the ultimatum in 
 his system, and that the general good comes to its own only as 
 a secondary consideration, in so far as it can subordinate itself 
 to the actually paramount interests of the quasi-absolutistic 
 governments which posed as embodiments of the welfare of
 
 406 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 their peoples. The striking peculiarity of the transitional 
 type of thinking which Justi represents was not its insistence 
 upon the welfare of the people as the ultimate aim. It was 
 rather its constant resort to the assumption that actual gov- 
 ernments were more inerrant in their pursuit of this end than 
 any other available civic system could possibly be. Herewith 
 we have in principle the whole of Justi's political philosophy. 
 His elaboration of it, on the institutional side, in the remainder 
 of this volume is merely an expansion of the corresponding 
 sections in Staatswirthschaft. We shall find more explicit 
 description of civic well-being itself, as Justi conceived it, in 
 the second of his volumes on political philosophy. 1 
 
 A general estimate of another factor in Justi's thinking 
 is pertinent at this point; viz., the evident line of cleavage 
 between the technological and the idealistic elements in his 
 books. Justi was apparently only half-conscious, if even so 
 much, of the mixture of elements. On the one hand he was 
 systematizing the actual technique of governmental adminis- 
 tration. On the other hand he was describing the spirit and 
 details of governments as they should be. If one were to read 
 him without this distinction in mind one might reach utterly 
 unwarranted conclusions about the modernness of his philoso- 
 phy. The reservation must always be remembered that his 
 theory had no place for an ultimate appeal beyond the authority 
 of the constituted government, as the last resort of peoples. 
 The government was the final moral arbiter, against whose 
 decrees the citizens had no recourse. This was not merely 
 the working condition, but the philosophical theory supported 
 the conditions. At the same time, parallel with this theory and 
 practice, a body of ethical judgments was taking shape which 
 constituted a standard of politico^ attainment destined pres- 
 
 ' Der Grundriss einer Guten Regierung. In Fiinf Biichern verf asset, 
 von Johann Hcinrich Gottlob von Justi, Koniglichem Grossbritannischcn 
 Bcrgrath. Frankfurth und Leipzig, 1759.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 47 
 
 ently to hail existing rulers before the bar of a more highly 
 evolved justice. This more far-seeing justice shows itself 
 in Justi's accounts of the purposes and technique of adminis- 
 tration. The dilemma presented by these two elements had 
 not yet been frankly admitted. The French Revolution 
 first brought it into distinct view. In a word it was this : The 
 proper moral standards of governments are such and such ; the 
 actual moral standards of governments are much inferior; 
 there is no recognized means of compelling governments to 
 adopt the higher standards; does the logic of the civic relation 
 then require men to leave moral standards at the mercy of 
 governments, or have men a deeper right to enforce subordi- 
 nation of governments to the higher sovereignty of morals ? 
 
 In the philosophy which Justi represents this inevitable 
 conjunction of ideas had not been reached. The two anti- 
 thetical, yet necessarily related conceptions and their corol- 
 laries were in existence side by side, but they had not been 
 reconciled, and the need of a reconciliation was not yet dis- 
 tinctly formulated. 
 
 The book just mentioned begins with a version of the 
 same argument which was presented in Natur und Wesen. 
 Avoiding repetition as much as possible, we may draw from 
 the present volume certain details in completion of the account 
 of Justi's system. 
 
 Without the proviso just urged, we should be inclined to 
 believe we had stumbled upon a prophet of modern democracy 
 when we read (i) : 
 
 The nature, essence, and ultimate purpose [Endzweck] of states 
 are the only criteria by which to decide what is a good government. 
 
 Passing propositions which have already been quoted in 
 other connections, we read (4) : 
 
 Every human being has an energy [Kraft] of his own. If many 
 human beings combine in a society, there results a composite energy, 
 which is in proportion to the number of persons. Every person
 
 408 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in society has a share in this composite great energy. He is thus 
 much stronger than the isolated man. Participation in the great 
 energy of society is thus the ultimate purpose of societies. 1 
 
 The will of each human being is to promote his own happiness. 
 When therefore many human beings combine their wills, and resign 
 to this combined will the use of their energy, i. e., when they set over 
 themselves a supreme power, and subordinate their particular will 
 to it, there can be no other intent than that each identifies his own 
 happiness with the happiness of the whole society. The common 
 happiness is accordingly the ultimate purpose of civic structures 
 (5; vide pp. 51 ff.). 
 
 1 Justi's form of expression seems to imply in the first place that the 
 "great energy" of societies is merely the arithmetical sum of the energies 
 of the individuals. This being the case, one wonders just how he pic- 
 tured the process of getting out of that total more than was put in. He 
 evidently assumed that something more than a mere addition took place 
 in society, but his account of the situation leaves the essentials to be 
 desired. The chief crudeness in this section of Justi's philosophy is 
 not in the description of the central fact of a state, but in the absence of 
 analysis of the sources of the "general will" or "supreme power." The 
 non sequitur is at once in operation that a certain representative or 
 repository of this "general will," say the monarch of a European state, 
 being given, the concurrence of social forces by which that monarch 
 came into existence has served its day and generation, and has gone out 
 of business, leaving the monarch virtually absolute. I find no direct 
 evidence that Justi consciously borrowed anything from Hobbes, but 
 the assumptions of the former are quite in accord with the philosophy 
 of the latter. Justi feels at liberty to tell when rulers ought to be ashamed 
 of themselves, but he has no recourse short of judgments of God if they 
 do not mend their ways (vide Grundriss, pp. 77 ff.). 
 
 * From this point the fallacy of confounding means and ends is con- 
 stantly on duty. The particular mode of uniting the associated wills is 
 assumed to be identical with, if not paramount to, the concept "common 
 happiness." Consequently this particular mode of controlling association, 
 the absolute state, is substituted as paramount purpose, for a developing 
 idea of "common happiness" which would hold any means of its own reali- 
 zation, e. g., any form of civic constitution, as constantly liable to answer 
 for its results, and to modification as the actual paramount purpose from 
 time to time seemed to demand.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 409 
 
 Hence arises a state, a republic, a "common being" [gemeincs 
 Wesen]. 1 These three concepts are identical, if one takes the word 
 republic in the most general sense, as its chief significance demands. 
 A state or republic, however, is a society of human beings who have 
 combined with one another in order to promote their common happi- 
 ness under a sovereign power; or, in other words, a state consists 
 of many families, that have united their energies and their will with 
 one another in order to combine the happiness of each particular 
 family with the common good (6). 
 
 Such a society of human beings is called a people [Volk], and it 
 is a ground of the state without which a state cannot be thought, 
 that such a people occupies a certain portion of the earth's surface, 
 which is their peculiar possession, and which we call the country 
 or land [Land] (8). 
 
 When a people thus unites its energy and its will, and intrusts 
 the use of the combined energy to the master- will; that is, when it 
 establishes a supreme power, this power rests in the beginning 
 unquestionably with the people, since it originates through the 
 unification of their energies and wills. The people can accordingly 
 either exercise this power themselves and make ordinances about 
 that exercise, or it can transfer such exercise to others. All power 
 in the state springs therefore from the people [F0/] which is always 
 the source of the same. The power therefore, by virtue of which 
 the people makes ordinances about the exercise of the supreme 
 power, or transfers such responsibility to others, is called the funda- 
 mental power [Grundgewdt] of the people, and is distinguished from 
 the active supreme power, which originates only through the ordina- 
 tion of the former. This fundamental power of the people is a part 
 of the essence of the state, and is always present, even with the most 
 unlimited supreme power. It can be overthrown only by destruc- 
 tion of the state, either through total subjugation by an alien enemy, 
 or through internal tyranny (9).* 
 
 No precise English equivalent for the content which Justi put into 
 this phrase can be found. 
 
 This is perhaps the most distinct formulation of fundamental 
 democracy to be found in Justi's books. It would be misrepresentation 
 if I should try to explain it away. It is simply a partially assimilated
 
 410 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 When a people, by virtue of its fundamental power, determines 
 how the active supreme power shall be exercised, it ordains funda- 
 mental laws. These institutions for the exercise of the supreme 
 power are called the government, and the external ways and means 
 in which the supreme powe? is exercised are called the form of govern- 
 ment. ' The form of government of a state can therefore be estab- 
 lished only through the fundamental laws (10). 
 
 In the establishment of the fundamental laws and of the form of 
 government, the fundamental power ot the people acts as law-giver. 
 But when this fundamental power, according to the standards of the 
 established fundamental laws and form of government, makes over 
 the supreme power to others, it acts not as law-giver, but as party 
 to a contract, i. e., it makes a contract [Vertrag] with the assumers of 
 the supreme power, to the effect that they will take upon themselves 
 and exercise the supreme power according to the standards of the 
 fundamental law. The fundamental power of the people can thus 
 not be a judge over the active supreme power, but all affairs and 
 controversies between them must be adjudicated according to the 
 nature of the contract (11).* 
 
 The supreme power of the state consists in the use of the united 
 energy by a united will (5). The supreme power then amounts 
 
 element of his system. It reflects a phase of reality which has always 
 haunted men's thinking, and which may be counted on to reopen every 
 supposed closed system of social philosophy so long as there remains 
 anything to adjust between the individual and the social factors in the 
 human process. What happened, however, in Justi's system, was that 
 working necessity so completely outweighed in his judgment the claims of 
 popular sovereignty in any applicable sense that political absolutism was 
 the unimpeached result. 
 
 1 Thus Justi identifies fundamental laws (Grundgeseize) and gov- 
 ernment (Regicrung). 
 
 1 Here Hobbesism comes into the open in contrast with the democ- 
 racy of $9. How and by whom adjudicated, if njt Vy the fundamental 
 power? Justi avoids that question here, but he has given his practical 
 answer in the passage already noted in the Staatswirthschaft, viz., "The 
 king can do no wrong," which any other power in the state has a right 
 to resist. The unconscious humor of the reasoning is appealing when
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 411 
 
 to the performance of two great activities, viz., law-giving and the 
 execution of law. Hence the supreme power may be divided into 
 two branches, each of which may be subdivided (13). The various 
 combinations of these subdivisions give the mixed forms of govern- 
 ment (14). 
 
 The body thus formed has at most only the means [Vermogen] 
 of activity. To be really active, it must have a peculiar ground of 
 movement or activity. This can be none other than love of the father- 
 land or of the form of government. The ground of all moral actions 
 of men is self-love, and the state, as a moral body, can have no other 
 ground of activity than love for itself, or for its essence and form. 
 This love, which is so natural in itself, must fill rulers and ruled, and 
 thereby all parts of the civic body will be vitalized (15).' 
 
 Although self-love is the ground of all moral action of human 
 beings, yet this self-love requires very judicious guidance if human 
 beings are really to attain happiness. Man must be virtuous, and 
 live according to the natural laws if he wishes to be happy. Just 
 so the civic body would fail to attain its happiness if love for the 
 Fatherland were not judiciously guided toward this end. The mov- 
 
 we reflect that the "contract" alleged is purely unilateral. In exchange 
 for total transfer of the citizens' freedom to the newly constituted supreme 
 power, no quid pro quo is provided for in the nature of an enforcible 
 obligation on the side of this new trustee to discharge the trust according 
 to the intention of the alleged grantors. 
 
 1 In pointing out the defects of Justi's reasoning I am of course not 
 blaming him for being merely a reflection of his time. Blame and praise 
 are not in question. The point is to detect precisely the strength and 
 the weakness of the methods of thinking of which Justi was an exponent. 
 The object is always to make use of these discoveries in criticism of cur- 
 rent methods of thinking. We must observe, then, in connection with 
 this paragraph, that it is a long leap to a conclusion which is not contained 
 in the previously adduced premises. Between self-love and the love of 
 the state the minor premise is implied, as already indicated (9, note), 
 that the only means by which self-love can attain its ends is through the 
 state as traditionally constituted. Logically the reasoning is the vicious 
 circle. Psychologically, the relation between self-love and love of the 
 state is unanalyzed. This latter is no wonder, as the analysis is still 
 incomplete.
 
 412 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ing spring of virtue is necessary, and this virtue consists in fulfilment 
 of duties toward the state and fellow- citizens (16). 
 
 The form of government is the special nature of each civic body. 
 Each body can move only in accordance with its special nature. 
 Each form of government requires its special spring of action, e. g., 
 monarchy, honor; aristocracy, moderation; democracy, love for 
 equality (vide Staatswirthschaft, above, p. 320) (17). 
 
 All forms of government are equally good, so long as they 
 preserve their ground of activity and their springs of action in full 
 strength (18). 
 
 If the springs of action are corrupted, well-organized mixed 
 forms of government are preferable (19). 
 
 Good organization of the mixed governmental forms depends 
 on a just balance between the different branches of the sovereign 
 power (20). 
 
 Despotism is not a special form of government, but merely an 
 abuse (21). 
 
 Every state consists of rulers and ruled. This division alone is 
 essential, and is peculiar to all states. All other divisions are merely 
 accidental. In monarchical states these two classes are ruler and 
 subjects. In republics all are subjects of the supreme power, but 
 not of the persons at the head of the government (23). l 
 
 The people, which in the democracy is everything, shrinks 
 in importance in the mixed forms of government, until in the aristoc- 
 1 Justi thus implies plainly enough the personal rulership of mon- 
 archs. In effect there was nothing in his political philosophy which 
 differed from the Stuart view of divine right. Such passages as p. 159, 
 in which legislation by a representative body is treated as best, do not 
 nullify this proposition. Weighed against the whole tenor of his system, 
 these flashes of modernness must be regarded as a sort of mirage, which 
 played about the edges of his theory but were not actually assimilated 
 with it. Justi's views of a representative legislature seem, moreover, 
 to have been not unlike those of the present Czar. In 1007 the latter 
 allowed the third Douma to be called, but he refused to acquiesce in its 
 declaration that he was no longer an autocrat. The boundaries which 
 Justi draws between the executive and the legislative powers leave the 
 former still in possession of a different type of sovereignty from that which 
 today goes with genuine representative government (vide op. cit., p. 163*).
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 413 
 
 racy and the monarchy it is only a very trifling something. Finally, 
 through abuse of monarchy in tyranny the people and its funda- 
 mental powers are reduced to nothing. The people consists of think- 
 ing beings. A thinking being, however, can never wholly and blindly 
 give over the care for its happiness to another. The people therefore 
 should in all states be something (27).* 
 
 The sovereign power and the people are parts of a whole because 
 the one necessarily demands the presence of the other, and because 
 neither can exist without the other. So soon therefore as the one 
 part undertakes anything which is harmful to the other it harms itself 
 
 (29)-' 
 
 The substance of all duties of the ruler is accordingly to make 
 his people happy, or to unite the happiness of each several citizen 
 with the general good. All duties of people and subjects may be 
 reduced to the formula, to promote all the ways and means adopted 
 by the ruler for thtir happiness by their obedience, fidelity, and diligence 
 (30). 
 
 The happiness of individuals and of the state consists of freedom, 
 internal strength, good conditions, and security (31). 
 
 Freedom may be separated into two concepts, political and 
 civic; or the freedom of the state and the freedom of the citizen. 
 The state is free when it is independent, i. e., when it is neither 
 wholly nor partially subject to another state. The citizen is free 
 when he can without hindrance realize his will. But the citizen has 
 merged his will into another, and this combined will can express 
 itself only through the laws. Consequently the citizen is free when 
 he suffers no other limitation of his will than through the laws. 
 The citizen is therefore really free because he is restrained by nothing 
 except rules for his happiness, rules to which every free and thought- 
 ful being must subject himself (32). 3 
 
 < Was Sieves' famous mot after all a plagiarism ? 
 
 Substitute for "sovereign power" and "people," "employer" and 
 "employee," and we have the familiar dictum of the classical economics 
 on the absurdity of supposed conflict of interests between wage payer and 
 wage taker. 
 
 3 Justi omits his apologies to the spider and the fly. The other 
 elements of happiness are described in terms that have already been 
 specified. Vide above, pp. 330, 331.
 
 414 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 A ruler must not impair the reasonable freedom of his subjects, 
 nor allow it to be impaired by his favorites and servants. No one 
 in his whole state must be directly or indirectly compelled to do or 
 to forbear from doing anything which the laws, made for the welfare 
 of the state, do not prescribe (39). 
 
 The property of the subjects must be the most sacred and invio- 
 lable object in the eyes of the ruler and his servants. Hence the ruler 
 may regard it as his greatest glory if in his private transactions the 
 subjects refuse to make over their property to him. Thac is always 
 the most royal mark of the goodness of a government (40).' 
 
 The ruler and his ministers should neither directly nor indirectly 
 interfere with the due process of law (41). 
 
 Never, except in the most extraordinary need, should the con- 
 tributions of the subjects be increased (42). 
 
 No war should be fought unless the preservation of the state 
 makes it unavoidable (43). 
 
 The text is then divided into five books, viz.: 
 
 I. On the ultimate purpose of a good government, and conse- 
 quently the general idea of a good government. 
 
 II. On the fundamental arrangements by means of which gov- 
 ernments are made good by nature. 
 
 III. On the goodness of the government which springs from 
 its own moderation. 
 
 IV. On the wisdom of a good government. 
 
 V. The errors and faults of bad governments. 
 
 It is unnecessary to go into further details of the argument. 
 From these generalizations it would be easy to anticipate the 
 substance of the elaboration of each topic. The state which 
 Justi outlines is an organization of people whose conceded 
 legal and moral rights do not include a voice in making the 
 laws which they must obey, and they do not include legal or 
 moral right to call ruler or ministers to account if the laws 
 which they decree are unjust, or if their administration of 
 them is oppressive. The few further passages to be cited will 
 
 E. g., the story of Frederick the Great and the miller at Potsdam.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 415 
 
 serve chiefly to illustrate this proposition. In general the 
 fact is that Justi's ideal of the achievements of a good state 
 was in the main intelligent, if no account is made of the stulti- 
 fication involved in this conception of the means by which the 
 ideal was to be attained. But in such a case we cannot sepa- 
 rate the end thus abruptly from the means. Freedom to do 
 our own experimenting with freedom is one of the proximate 
 ends which thinking beings propose to themselves if their 
 thinking is not suppressed; and this freedom to find our own 
 way to something that may be thought of as an ultimate freedom 
 is a more importunate aim than the conceivable ultimate free- 
 dom, if it could be conferred by a superior power. 
 
 Justi lays down the major premise: "No one can rule over 
 reasonable and free beings except with the intention of pro- 
 moting their welfare and making them happy" (p. 33). 
 
 Of the possible meanings of this sententious proposition, 
 the substance of Justi's system forces us to select this version, 
 viz., It is impossible to suppose that a ruler would desire any- 
 thing but the best good of his subjects. That is, it was a 
 purely ad captandum appeal for acquiescence in the prevail- 
 ing type of absolutism. With so much granted, all the rest 
 of the reasoning is unanswerable. 1 Once given an absolute 
 ruler with his existence justified, and no logic can depose him. 
 The only refutation possible is through destruction of the 
 major premise; and of course this was the actual first step 
 
 I find no evidence that there was intentional or conscious sophis- 
 try in Justi's argument. He was apparently a convinced advocate, at 
 least to the extent that he had not clearly thought out a feasible alterna- 
 tive; and he was not aware of weakness in his method of proof (vide op. 
 cit -> P- 35) Whether his occasional praise of the English system im- 
 peaches his sincerity as an absolutist, or merely punctuates the inco- 
 herence of his political philosophy, is, to be sure, an open question, but 
 on the whole, I incline to the view that these irreconcilable elements in 
 his thinking show that he had not faced the necessity of adjusting the 
 incompatible doctrines.
 
 4i 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in abolishing absolutism everywhere. Rulers being human 
 are both intellectually so narrow and morally so fallible that 
 they are incapable in the long run of performing the function 
 which absolutism assumes. Then another functionary and 
 another technique and another philosophy must be substituted. 
 Justi begins his detailed discussion with a proposition 
 which reflects the fundamental political conception of which 
 cameralism was an incident; viz., "To govern is to guide the 
 actions of other people in accordance with certain purposes." 1 
 The affair in which Justi was engaged, both as advocate and 
 as bureau official, was the operation of a legislative and execu- 
 tive organization conceived as something over and above and 
 superior to the people, although perforce in certain relations 
 of and for the people. So far as the relation had been thought 
 out and realized, it was not by the people, and it was for them 
 only so far as the persons who wielded the power of the organi- 
 zation were sufficient centers of light and leading to use it 
 for the real benefit of the nation in a democratic sense. The 
 first and typical idea and aim was to magnify the governing 
 power itself, and the rest of the nation was accordingly rated 
 as tributary to that paramount purpose. Justi proceeds to 
 build on his foundations of political philosophy after this 
 fashion: 
 
 Those who govern other men in the unobserved way, if they 
 are rightly constituted and honorable, will always have as their 
 
 object the best good of those whom they rule If the ruled 
 
 discover that they are controlled in another spirit, no matter how 
 simple they are, they will sooner or later break the fetters. Invisible 
 or unconscious government must consequently have the best good 
 of the people at heart; or, what amounts to the same thing, it must 
 succeed in keeping the people under the spell of assumption that its 
 best good is the foremost purpose. We have then to inquire what 
 
 ' " Regiercn heisst die Handlungen anderer Menschen nach gewissen 
 Absichten lenken" (p. 34).
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 417 
 
 must be the ultimate aims of those who openly govern other men 
 (PP- 35, 36). 
 
 Thereupon Justi constructs an argument along these specula- 
 tive lines; not an induction of the actual character of states 
 as they are, not a frank idealization of kinds of government 
 as he thought they ought to be, not even a modest inference as 
 to the requirements to which governments must eventually 
 conform. Instead of either of these, he actually expatiates 
 upon considerations partly of the second, partly of the third, 
 types, and then, as though such considerations were pertinent 
 evidence, he derives the basic inference that governments as 
 they are conform to those specifications of morals and long- 
 term expediency, which entitle them to the implicit acquiescence 
 of subjects. In short, his major premise is that actual gov- 
 ernments are essentially what they would be if the men in 
 power were divinely good and wise. 1 
 
 Justi constantly appealed to religious sanctions for beliefs 
 and actions. No evidence appears that this was a phenomenon 
 
 * Three distinct questions emerge here: first, Whether the policy 
 which this doctrine prescribed was the one best adapted to the stage of 
 evolution then in progress; second, Whether the philosophy expressed 
 by the doctrine was a valid generalization; third, What were the actual 
 effects of the doctrine upon the theories and practices of the period ? 
 We might answer the first of these questions in the affirmative, as indeed 
 I am inclined to do, yet we might most confidently answer the second 
 question in the negative, and we might find that there were most unfor- 
 tunate and confusing results to be scheduled in answer to the third 
 question. Our present study has no further reference to the first of these 
 questions. We are dealing with the second, principally, and with the 
 theoretical, more than the applied, aspects of the third. Thai is, we are 
 attempting to get first a clear view of Justi's political philosophy, because 
 it was the setting in which his cameralism has to be interpreted; and 
 we are to use this analysis of the principal and subordinate factors of 
 his system as a guide to the effects that the system, and others of which 
 it was a type, had upon the course of development in the social sciences 
 at large.
 
 41 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 with deeper roots than mere acceptance of the conventionalities 
 of his surroundings, and instinctive perception that this was 
 the type of argumentum ad hominem which would meet with 
 least express opposition. It is accordingly a matter of course 
 that he relies upon the claim that goodness will in the long run 
 be successful, and badness unsuccessful. Upon this ground 
 he urges that no ruler would be so unwise as to rule simply 
 in his own selfish interest. Even Machiavelli, he thinks, did 
 not teach that (p. 36 el passim) 1 and the worst tyrants were 
 probably not primarily enemies of their people, but they found 
 that without intending to rouse their hostility they had done 
 so, and thereafter supposed themselves to be unsafe unless they 
 ruled with a high hand. This is all a-priori reasoning, monarchy 
 being taken for granted, and the attempt being made to show 
 that the aim of monarchy must be the common good. There 
 is no trace, even in the last book of the volume, which at 
 hasty glance might seem to furnish the exception, of a genuine 
 attempt to measure the strength of this probability by induction. 
 In a word, as Justi expresses it, the outcome of this a-priori 
 reasoning is, that because it is stupid and wrong for a ruler 
 to govern with selfish aims, therefore, "His final purpose can 
 be no other than to guide the ruled to their best good, to pro- 
 note their welfare by wise measures in a word, to make 
 them happy." 
 
 The chapter ends with a homiletical exhortation apparently 
 intended both as a play upon the suggestibility of the people 
 on the one hand, and as the most direct appeal j>crmitled by 
 good form to the better impulses of princes: 
 
 When a ruler in this manner makes his subjects and at the same 
 time himself happy, something grand is before him in their eyes. 
 That is the honor, which accompanies all his ways and the glory 
 which attends the footsteps of all his actions. How beautiful, how 
 lordly, how glorious, how commendable is it to govern men, when 
 
 1 Justi thinks The Prince was a deeply veiled satire. Vide p. 327.
 
 JUSTFS POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 419 
 
 one makes them happy! That is the greatest, the most exalted of 
 all human activities, to which a reasoning being can attain, and other 
 kinds of human honor and glory are not to be compared with it 
 (P- 5). 
 
 The method of proving that men united in societies for 
 the sake of promoting their happiness is equally speculative, 
 but the more pertinent fact is that the conclusion did not go 
 so far as to justify the continuance of an effectively Ideological 
 attitude of subjects toward their governments after they were 
 once formed. For practical purposes Justi's philosophy meant 
 that the people must depend on the government to promote 
 their happiness, but more than that, they must in the last 
 resort trust the good intentions of the government even when 
 it is not apparently working in their interest. That is, Justi 
 posited absolutism mitigated by laws which the government 
 itself had made, by considerations of prudence, of religipn, 
 of benevolence, of reputation, each and all to be valued in 
 case of collision, not by the people, but by the ruler. 
 
 This is the typical confusion of ideas in the philosophy 
 of absolutism, and especially in the conflict in Justi's mind 
 between tradition and a valid estimate of social values. His 
 judgment of political ends reads almost like fundamental 
 democracy. The limitation of his reasoning is found in his 
 inability to accept the conclusion of social logic that the histori- 
 cally developed means of attaining human ends must, in the 
 long run, command the approval of the groups in which they 
 function, or be repudiated. He could not advance beyond 
 the dogma that the government, as constituted, must be accepted 
 by the people as an automatically self-correcting agency, not 
 to be interfered with by the subjects. That is, in creating 
 it men acted as practical utilitarians. In their attitude toward 
 it since it has been created, they must be essentially acquiescent. 
 Throughout Justi's writings standards of governmental action 
 are expressed which are prophetic of inevitable change of
 
 420 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 attitude toward governments. The crucial matter for his 
 views as a political philosophy, however, is that these ideals 
 are scheduled merely as standards which it is proper for the 
 people to desire, and right and wise for rulers to adopt, but 
 not as rights which citizens are free to enforce. 1 
 
 Then Justi reiterates his generality that the common happi- 
 ness of the state depends on "the three ideas, freedom, inner 
 strength, and security." Then these ideas are expanded in a 
 way which makes them quite compatible with the virtual 
 absolutism previously assumed (pp. 65 ff.). 
 
 The discussion which follows (pp. 67-109) of the means 
 of securing these three elements of happiness, is in substance 
 nearly identical with the treatment of the same subject in 
 Stoatswirtksckoft and we pass over all but a few incidental 
 variations. 
 
 For example, the "law of parsimony," of which so much 
 has been made in later economic theory, is recognized in the 
 fundamental theorems about political means, viz., first, the 
 means must correspond with the nature of the thing to be 
 attained; second, of the possible means they must be the best; 
 third, they must be the easiest, "for it is a law of nature and 
 reason that we do not accomplish a thing by means of a greater 
 force, which might be adequately brought about by a lesser" 
 (p. 67); fourth, they must also be just, "for reason, justice, 
 and virtue command us not to apply bad means for good ends." 
 "These are to be regarded as so many fundamental principles 
 of a good government, by disregard of which one will always 
 fall into notable errors" (p. 68). Justi nowhere contemplates 
 
 1 He says, to be sure (p. 64), "Whatever is plainly opposed to the 
 ultimate end and nature of a society can without doubt not be binding 
 upon the society." In the immediate context, however, he appears to 
 imply that this cannot be thought of anything that occurs under the 
 regular forms of law. He has elsewhere expressly denied that sovereignty 
 can at last be in the people as opposed to the government (vide p. 325).
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 421 
 
 any more effective sanctions of these virtuous generalizations 
 than the conscience of the monarch. If he is not so minded, 
 there is no appeal except to the inscrutable workings of divine 
 Providence. 
 
 Another betrayal of the abortiveness of the conception 
 of freedom posited in Justi's philosophy occurs in his elabora- 
 tion of the concept in 85. He says: "Freedom consists in 
 the unhindered exercise of his (the citizen's) will. But the 
 citizens who constitute a state have merged their separate 
 wills in a single will. This single will can show itself in no 
 other manner than through the laws." Thus freedom is 
 defined only in the same breath to be denied. In the state 
 which Justi contemplated, freedom had only an imaginary 
 existence. It was a fiction of the philosophy of consolation 
 applied as a balm to the feelings of subjects whenever they 
 were wounded. The reality which occupied the place of 
 freedom was just as much tether for the individual will as the 
 will of the monarch, expressed through laws which he made, 
 saw fit to allow. 
 
 The light in which the factor of population was contem- 
 plated in Justi's philosophy appears in the same context. It 
 was primarily a military consideration, and only secondarily 
 industrial. That is, in facing the prime problem of the strength 
 and security of the state against foreign aggression, the neces- 
 sary factors are found to be, first, well situated and fortified 
 territory, and enough of it; second, a sufficient population 
 living in such close community that they can act effectively 
 together. For, says Justi (84) : 
 
 Few people, scattered over a wide territory, cannot repulse 
 enemies invading from all directions. Thus they have much less 
 activity than the same number of people who live closer together in 
 a smaller country. It is easy to show mathematically how much 
 weaker a million people are who live scattered over a thousand square 
 miles than another million occupying two hundred and fifty square
 
 422 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 miles, other circumstances being equal. It is consequently essen- 
 tial to the strength of the state that its territory must be peopled 
 according to the measure of its greatness. Accordingly, the internal 
 strength of a state depends upon the situation of its territory, upon 
 the number of its inhabitants, upon the goods at its disposal, and 
 upon the talents and moral qualities of the people. 
 
 Enlarging, two pages later (p. 86), upon the second of these 
 conditions, Justi adds: 
 
 Two million people have of course more aggregate energy and 
 strength than one million, other things being equal. 
 
 The doctrine of population, taken in this obvious relation, 
 would seem to have had much less of the character of a distinc- 
 tive dogma than the commentators upon the history of eco- 
 nomic theory have represented. 
 
 The same may be said of the factor of wealth in this philoso- 
 phy of the state. It was less a dictum asserting some occult 
 potency of wealth than a matter-of-course reckoning upon 
 the obvious. Thus Justi says (p. 87) : 
 
 The internal strength of the state depends further upon riches of 
 all sorts which are required for the needs and conveniences of human 
 
 life Just as it is beyond doubt that those states have a much 
 
 more permanent ground for their welfare whose soil is by nature 
 adapted to the production of the necessities of life, so may we also 
 assert that, other things being equal, that state is always the strongest 
 and happiest which has to satisfy the fewest needs from other states. 
 Such a state is in no way dependent upon other peoples, and it will 
 have within itself all the means which are demanded for strength. A 
 good government must therefore give its weightiest attention to the 
 production of such riches and abundance of goods within the country. 
 
 Justi continues (p. 88): 
 
 I have here with great deliberation based the internal strength 
 of the state ndl upon riches in gold and silver, and upon the ways 
 that lead to such wealth, namely, commerce, mining, etc., but entirely 
 upon wealth in goods. This wealth in goods is also alone the true 
 wealth of the state which is requisite for internal strength. The
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 423 
 
 Spaniards, who imagined that they would be the lords of the whole 
 world, if they had all the treasures of America in their possession, 
 and for that reason entirely neglected wealth in goods, were in gross 
 error. With all their treasures they have since been the poorest 
 nation in Europe, and they could not be anything else, since they 
 lacked the real wealth of peoples If, however, a state pos- 
 sesses the real wealth in goods, and is sufficiently populous, it can 
 have all the internal strength of which it is capable, with neither 
 gold nor silver nor commerce nor other intercourse with foreign 
 nations, in so far as this isolation is compatible with its natural situa- 
 tion, its circumstances, and its form of government Riches 
 
 in gold and silver is only a relative wealth of the state, which relates 
 entirely to commerce and the interconnection with other peoples, and 
 is necessary merely on that account. It belongs to the external 
 strength of the state, and to aggressive power [Angriff], but not to 
 internal strength and defensive power, to which alone I now refer, 
 because aggression is not to be included in the happiness of a state. 
 If a state finds it in accordance with its circumstances and happiness 
 to have such connections and intercourse with other nations, then 
 its internal strength will require that it shall seek to export as much 
 as possible of its surplus in order to increase its relative riches in gold 
 and silver. Under these circumstances that is the strongest state 
 which has to look to other states for the fewest satisfactions of its 
 wants, and which exports the most of its surplus. 1 
 
 In confirmation of the general thesis as to the qualified 
 absolutism which was the ultimate term of Justi's political 
 philosophy, we may quote from a following section. Having 
 elaborated the proposition that the internal strength of a state 
 depends, first, on the fundamental virtue of obedience in the 
 subjects, Justi continues (p. 93): 
 
 The moral quality of rulers, which is demanded for the internal 
 strength of the state, may be expressed in one word. It is wisdom. 
 
 The relation between cameralism and mercantilism is reviewed in 
 the closing chapter (pp. 586 ff.). It is enough to say here that intimate 
 acquaintance with the cameralists punctures the myth that their concep- 
 tions of wealth were utterly bizarre.
 
 424 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 But this concept contains very much. If rulers are wise, they are 
 everything necessary to make their state strong and their people 
 happy. This quality, moreover, is so essential to the strength of the 
 stace that all previous means to internal strength in the largest measure 
 
 lose their force, so soon as wisdom is lacking in rulers The 
 
 perfection and wisdom of the government is accordingly the chief 
 means and the foremost quality whereupon the true power and 
 internal strength of the state rest. It is the soul of all previously 
 
 mentioned means, and it gives to them their full effect The 
 
 wisdom and perfection of a government, however, consists in the 
 positing of a wisely chosen plan and programme of government, and 
 the genuine fundamental rules: in government by the monarch 
 himself, through his own insight, not merely through his ministers, 
 and the concentration of all affairs in his strong hand; in his wise 
 choice of ministers and servants, and assignment of each to a post 
 of duty in accordance with his qualities and capabilities; in holding 
 all business and affairs in the most precise order and coherence and 
 the fighting forces in like order and discipline; and finally in putting 
 the state in the utmost possible condition of preparation against all 
 the misfortunes and accidents which must be anticipated. If a 
 state is governed in this way, and if it possesses at che same time 
 the before-mentioned means and qualities for internal strength, 
 it is certainly the most perfect machine for exerting an unspeakable 
 
 energy Meanwhile, although a perfectly wise and complete 
 
 government will never exist in the world, it is always an indubitable 
 truth that, of two states which are otherwise completely equal, 
 that one will always overcome the other, the government of which 
 is most wisely and perfectly conducted. 1 
 
 'The bathos of this conclusion is characteristic of the whole con- 
 ception of which the paragraph is an epitome. It involves the two factors 
 pointed out above: first, absolutistic government as the final term in 
 civic relations; second, homiletical moralizing upon the character that 
 rulers would have if they knew their best interests, with the implica- 
 tion that actual rulers are enough like this ideal to make obedience 
 to them the ultimate duty and recourse of citizens. This remark 
 applies also to the chapter (pp. 109-28) on "General Idea of a Good 
 Government"
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 425 
 
 In the introduction to the second book, on "The Funda- 
 mental Constitution of States, by Means of Which Govern- 
 ments Are by Nature Good," Justi promises to sketch "a sort 
 of Platonic republic, which to be sure never will be realized. 
 Meanwhile it is never useless to know how far human provision 
 can go in a probable way in the direction of the goodness and 
 excellence of the government " (p. 132). Before fulfilling the 
 promise Justi estimates in some detail the merits and defects 
 of different types of government (pp. 132-82). If this passage 
 were read without checking it up by the rest of his political 
 philosophy, the conclusion would be necessary that he was 
 in favor of a form of government more like that of England 
 in the Victorian period than that of the Stuarts (p. 175). It 
 would falsify the record to explain away the implications of 
 this chapter. They are plainly and rather unreservedly 
 democratic in the modern sense with the monarchical element 
 retained as an offset to democratic faults and inefficiencies. 
 If the whole system were contained in a compendium a thou- 
 sand years old, the higher critics might without remorse assign 
 this chapter to some interpolator of strange doctrines. The 
 actual explanation is in harmony with traits which are quite 
 evident in Justi here and there, particularly in the Staatswirth- 
 schaft. He allowed himself short flights of fancy which he 
 did not take much care to guard from confusion with his 
 working technology. Inasmuch as he opened the discussion 
 with the notification that he would end it with a castle in the 
 air, it is easy to infer that his feet left the ground much earlier 
 than he proposed. He simply permitted himself to rhapsodize. 
 The chapter is half -conscious Wahrheit und Dichtung through- 
 out. It is of a piece with the ideal ethics which the author 
 had previously held up to rulers as a righteous standard, with, 
 no thought of winning for it available political sanctions. He 
 meant it, in the unofficial, irresponsible compartments of his 
 mind which were open to the play of imagination. He was
 
 426 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 sincere about these unassimilated conceits, with a sort of 
 other-worldly longing that took refuge in them from literal 
 affairs; but as he gave partial notification in the confession 
 above quoted, he did not expect to be held accountable for 
 supposing that such visions could ever be actualized. Even 
 in the course of this excursus, when he is speaking of the checks 
 which must be put upon the different branches of government, 
 he touches his familiar earth with the reservation 
 
 The executive power, however, or the king, must, to be sure, 
 always be so sacred and so inviolate that he himself can never be 
 required to render such an account of his acts (p. 167). 
 
 In his summary Justi says: 
 
 If the legislative, executive, and judicial powers in the funda- 
 mental constitution of a mixed governmental form are so ordered, 
 as above pictured, we may declare that the government is good in 
 its nature. The king has all power which is requisite for execution, 
 and on reasonable grounds he can demand no more. In all external 
 affairs of state he has completely free hands, and nothing hinders 
 him from taking the resolves and measures which he regards as neces- 
 sary for the true welfare of his state. Since in matters of execution 
 he is not bound to obtain the consent of anyone, he can give to all 
 his undertakings the utmost swiftness, vigor, and efficiency, and 
 it is his own affair if his intentions and measures do not remain 
 secret. In short he has all power to do good, but no power at all 
 to do evil (p. 173). 
 
 Coming to the avowedly Utopian part of his discussion, 
 he begins as follows (p. 183): 
 
 Is then a governmental form possible, in which no errors and 
 imperfections would inhere, but which by virtue of the excellence of 
 its fundamental constitution would represent a type of government 
 which by its very nature would be always and completely good? 
 If the question were to be taken in all its severity we should be obliged 
 to answer without reserve in the negative. People themselves are 
 subject to a thousand limitations and weaknesses. All their actions 
 are led by their passions, and all too often do these passions raise a
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 427 
 
 storm which drives the wisest and best men hither and thither like 
 so much chaff. How is it to be expected, then, that people can erect 
 a mode of government which in the strict sense would be completely 
 perfect ? It is people who erect governments, and who are governed. 
 They are the stuff for the whole work. How can a highly perfect 
 work be composed of such meager and feeble material ? If, however, 
 we understand by the question, whether a form of government is 
 possible which is freed from all the major mistakes and failures 
 which we so often find in civic institutions, a form which can assure 
 to citizens all the security, freedom, and happiness to which by 
 means of their weak nature they can ever attain, and which at the 
 same time possesses all the strength and permanence against con- 
 tingencies within and without of which a state is capable, then we 
 must answer, Yes. We said above that we would construct a sort 
 of Platonic republic, which it would be ridiculous to expect to realize 
 in the present condition of realms and states. Nevertheless, we hope 
 to give our proposal such a form that fewer faults can be found with 
 it than with such idealistic structures in the past. 
 
 Reducing Justi's fantasy to the lowest terms, it is as follows 
 (pp. 184-207): 
 
 i. We must take men as they are, with all their desires and 
 passions. Accordingly, when a reasonable and moral people, living 
 by the side of similar peoples, wishes to choose a constitucion, it 
 must base its plan on the existence of these desires and passions. 
 They must be reckoned upon in the plan as the means of making 
 the structure of the state strong and durable. If we except love, 
 which is rather a natural impulse than a passion, the strongest among 
 all human passions is the desire for prestige [Vorzug], or the passion 
 for honor and glory. 1 Nothing is so natural to man as this passion. 
 The impulse which the wise Originator of nature implanted in every 
 man, to hold his own being most precious, in order that he might 
 
 1 This passage then is of more than curious significance merely 
 as presenting a Utopia. It is a first-rate piece of evidence on our funda- 
 mental theorem that Justi had not focalized the economic interest proper. 
 He had not heard of " the economic man." His fundamental assumption 
 was the personally ambitious man.
 
 428 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 take pleasure in maintaining himself and in fulfilling the designs of 
 the Creator, is that which brings forth the longing for prestige. 
 Consequently this is the passion of which chief use will be made in 
 a wise design for a civic constitution (p. 184). 
 
 2. Yet we must seek to establish and maintain virtue. All 
 passions may be evil as well as good, in the degree in which they 
 are guided and governed; and when they are left to themselves they 
 always tend rather to bad than to good. The desire for prestige 
 needs therefore another moving spring, whereby it is guided and, 
 as it were, geared, in order that it may be held back from excesses. 
 This second moving spring is virtue (p. 185). 
 
 3. A mixed form of govenment, composed partly of aristocracy 
 and partly of democracy, would serve best in employing these two 
 motive springs in all their strength. I see no probability that virtue 
 would be preserved in a form composed of king and democracy. 
 I would therefore forego the efficiency of a monarchy for the virtue 
 of a republic. To be sure, Sparta had kings, and virtue was per- 
 fectly maintained there. But our times are so different from those 
 of the Spartan republic, that we could not think of such a thing as 
 subjecting the king to the judicial judgment of the people, and his 
 morals and management to the guardians of the state. Our times 
 are so accustomed to combining with the royal dignity great outward 
 splendor and display, that a king without this frivolous, to be sure, 
 yet, on account of prejudice, necessary glitter, would be the laughing- 
 stock of all his neighbors. It will, however, never be possible to 
 banish vice from a state if it contains that degree of luxury which 
 so closely borders on vice, if the king and his court are not subject 
 to the institutions of the state for the maintenance of virtue (p. 187).' 
 
 4. It is non-essential what marks of distinction a government 
 adopts to stimulate the desire for prestige, so long as sufficient skill 
 is used to create a prejudice in their favor. To this end three means 
 
 1 What business Justi has to embarrass a Utopia by consideration 
 either of Spartan times or of "our times," it would be cruel to ask. He 
 was evidently not aware that he was trying to stand with one foot in the 
 clouds and one on the earth. This attempt at a free flight of fancy only 
 brings out more clearly his conviction that for mundane purposes the 
 quasi-absolute kings of his experience were necessary.
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 429 
 
 must be adopted: (i) the symbols of honor must be publicly bestowed; 
 (2) they must be given for actual merit only; (3) they must not be 
 made too common. Under these conditions a laurel wreath is as 
 effective as a golden crown bestudded with gems. The reason why 
 our times show so few heroic deeds is that our marks of distinction 
 are not bestowed according to these specifications (p. 188).' 
 
 5. Nobility should not be hereditary, and being obtained for 
 life only it will be a powerful spur to virtue (p. 190). 
 
 6. Virtue must be maintained by laws and morals which are 
 identical, and there must be a moral censorship [Sittenrichler]. 
 This college must consist of the most eminent, virtuous, and honor- 
 able men in the state, and the members must have a right of veto 
 upon an election by the people to a vacancy in the college in case they 
 know anything to the discredit of the person proposed. These 
 censors must not have the slightest connection with the government. 
 They must be the protectors of the fundamental constitution of the 
 state, the defenders of the laws, the maintainers of virtue and good 
 morals, the promoters of skill, of the arts, and of science. In all 
 these particulars they must have a quite unlimited power subject to 
 the fundamental laws, a power which should extend indeed over all 
 the administrative colleges of the state, and even over the represent- 
 ative of the people. They must have power to suspend or depose 
 and imprison any member of the government who is guilty of treason- 
 able or corrupting practices. There must be in front of the place 
 of assemblage of this college a receptacle in which citizens could 
 deposit testimony about anything of which the censors should be 
 informed (p. 191). 
 
 7. In the form of government which I here propose no one has 
 a peculiar interest in the welfare of the whole people. It is therefore 
 not necessary that the people should possess law-giving power. 
 The power of the people is never free from deficiencies and faults. 
 The people [V0/], however, which has (sic) little capacity for gov- 
 erning, is excellently endowed for selecting those who may be charged 
 with governing. I consequently propose that the whole work of 
 
 1 As our plan is to exhibit Justi's system objectively, as an attempt 
 at social science, rat! er than to examine its psychological presuppositions, 
 it is needless to comment on this naive mental philosophy.
 
 43 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 government, both law-giving and execution, should be reserved for 
 the personal nobility, and that the people should have no part in 
 governing beyond election of the officials (p. 194). 
 
 8. The common rabble should not be allowed to take part in' 
 elections. Electoral right should be based upon the rates paid to 
 the public treasury. The man who pays 20 Thaler yearly should 
 have one vote; he who pays TOO Thaler yearly should have two 
 votes, and for each additional 100 Thaler there should be one vote. 
 This would not only be just in itself, but it would bring about a more 
 willing payment of the rates. The personal nobility, as the only 
 class eligible for election, would not be permitted to vote, because 
 of their self-interest. In large states a representative system of elec- 
 tion must l>e adopted (p. 196). 
 
 9. The number of the nobility should be one hundred and fifty 
 in small states, three hundred in medium states, and six hundred 
 'n large states. Each of these should receive from the state an 
 annual allowance of three hundred to six hundred Reichsthaler 
 (p. 200). 
 
 10. The officials should be divided in the first place into three 
 chief colleges: (a) for law-giving, (h) for execution, (c) for judicial 
 functions. Members should be divided into three classes, one class 
 rctirin" from office each year (p. 200). 
 
 n. There should Ix.- in addition as many other colleges as are 
 at present customary in European states, but they should be subor- 
 dinate to the three principal colleges (p. 201). 
 
 12. In case of disagreement between the three chief colleges 
 which cannot be arranger! by conferences within thirty days, it shall be 
 the duty of the chairman of the colleges, on pain of banishment, 
 to lay the matter before the college of censors. The latter must 
 then summon the whole body of the nobility to investigate the 
 difficulty and to decide it by majority vote. The contending col- 
 leges must adopt the decision at once, for the total nobility is the 
 body in which the unlimited power should reside, although it does 
 not exercise it except in an extremity. Even then it must sometimes 
 proceed by choosing from its own number a dictator, who for a short 
 period should unite in his own person all might and power, in order 
 to save the republic from threatened destruction (p. 202).
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 431 
 
 13. Universal liability to military service for a term of six years 
 would be necessary (p. 204). 
 
 It is not worth while to analyze the implications of this 
 conceit, as Justi himself a third time (p. 206) reminds his 
 readers that it is aside from the serious purpose of his book. 
 Even the specifications of this Utopia, however, serve to 
 emphasize the literal preconceptions of Justi's working philoso- 
 phy. It was in the first place a presumption of static order 
 in the state; second, a reliance upon some institutional abso- 
 lute; third, an overestimate of the relative importance of civic 
 structure in the whole economy of life. 
 
 Passing to Book III, "On the Goodness of the Government 
 Due to Its Own Moderation," Justi begins with the proposition 
 that if we cannot have such "governments good by nature," 
 the only hope of good government is in the self-enforced 
 moderation of such governments as actually exist, "for every 
 unlimited and great power is by its very nature terrible, and 
 it has harmful effects on the subjects (p. 211). 
 
 In dealing with a body of thought which from our modern 
 point of view is so crowded with half-developed and arbitrarily 
 correlated ideas, there is always danger of making the anoma- 
 lies more extreme than they were. No other interpretation 
 can be put on this section, however, than the following: first, 
 we must in practice take for granted the absolutism of govern- 
 ment; second, "a government which 1ms unlimited power in its 
 hands, and can use that powt-r a< ii plrasis. can never be good 
 unless it moderates this power by its own initiative" (p. 211). 
 In other words, this is the literal formulation of the fundamen- 
 tal political conception which is known by the proverbial 
 phrase "benevolent despotism." This formula expresses 
 the cameralistic conception, as the legend, Vital c'est mol,- 
 symbolizes the ancien regime in France. Justi assumes that 
 the world being what it is, an absolutism embodied in a king 
 is a necessity. Yet many things go to make up that other
 
 432 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 conception, "happiness," which royal absolutism might easily 
 frustrate. This philosophy does not thereupon reconsider 
 its conclusion that political absolutism is necessary. It leaves 
 "happiness" at the mercy -of absolutism, with the hope that 
 the absolute monarch actually will be merciful. The present 
 section then is virtually a series of memoranda from the side 
 of "happiness," calling the attention of absolute monarchs 
 to points which they will observe if they want their rule to 
 result in the largest output of advantage for the state, in dis- 
 tinction from their own absolutism. 
 
 In other words, this political philosophy started with the lame 
 and impotent assumption that it is desirable for absolutism to 
 be good, rather than the assumption that absolutism is not a 
 good. Then it proceeded along the cautious path of specify- 
 ing how an absolutism would conduct itself if it were good. 
 If we were immediately engaged in tracing the course of 
 political evolution, we should have here an important clue to 
 the process. Even these dutiful reminders had a cumulative 
 force. Specifications of happiness presently came to have 
 another logical value. The inference drawn was no longer 
 that it is desirable for the absolute government to promote these 
 things, but that an absolute government is intolerable because 
 it can jeopardize these things. This is the gist of the whole 
 matter involved in this part of Justi's argument, and we shall 
 notice only one or two details. 
 
 The first chapter of Book III is dedicated to proof of the 
 proposition that "unlimited and great power is in its nature 
 terrible and dangerous." It takes as its point of departure 
 the theorem: "Every man is inclined to misuse his power" 
 (p. 212). The moralizings and mental philosophizings which 
 form the medium of the discussion need not be called to account. 
 For our purposes it is enough to set down the specifications 
 of danger which Justi discovered. In the first place, he con- 
 cluded that even virtuous men who are able to extend their
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 433 
 
 power fall into the way of thinking that such extension of 
 power is good in itself, regardless of consequences to others. 
 As Montesquieu says, "Even virtue needs limitations" (p. 213). 
 Great power tends to become arbitrary power (p. 214). Hence 
 such power is always to be feared (p. 215). The outcome of 
 arbitrary exercise of power is despotism in which the mere 
 will of the ruler is the highest law (p. 215). The whole power 
 of the state in the hands of one person is in itself to be feared, 
 apart from its resting upon the will of the ruler alone (p. 216). 
 Platitudes are Justi's specialty, but he seldom puts it on exhibit 
 more plainly than at this point. 
 
 The same level of bathos is maintained in the following 
 chapter "On the Moderation and Fixing of the Will Whereby 
 an Unlimited Government Becomes Good." It consists of 
 such "copy-book commonplaces" as these: 
 
 The misuse of unlimited power which is so harmful to the state 
 consists in the exercise of the will of the ruler according to his pleas- 
 ure and caprice (p. 222); hence a good unlimited government must 
 have two chief qualities: (a) its will must be moderated, (6) its will 
 must be constant (p. 223); the proper moderation of the will of an 
 unlimited government is through the guidance of reason, which has 
 no other aim than the best good of the state (p 223); a good ruler 
 must clearly distinguish his personal will from his will as a ruler 
 (p. 224); even if convinced that his personal will is a good will, a 
 wise ruler will not try to make it his governmental will; e. g., he will 
 not try to impose his religion upon his subjects (p. 226); constancy 
 of will in the government is necessary to prevent uncertainty among 
 the governed (pp. 227-32). 
 
 In the same general tone Justi proceeds, in chap, iii, to 
 schedule "the fundamental principles and rules of a good 
 government." These turn out to be: 
 
 The first and chief principle of a good government is unques- 
 tionably that of benevolence and moderation [Gelindigkeit] (p. 233) ; 
 (a) Since it is the aim and duty of a good government to make the
 
 434 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 people happy, one of its chief principles must be to make the people 
 rich (p. 237);' (3) General diffusion of wealth, rather than its 
 concentration in a few hands, is to be promoted (p. 239); (4) Fraud 
 and treachery as devices of statecraft are to be rejected on grounds 
 both of morals and of utility (p. 241) ;' (5) Cunning not involving 
 treachery may be used (p. 242); (6) "A good government will 
 observe five fundamental rules: (a) To assure the subjects a rea- 
 sonable freedom, (b) To regard their property as inviolable, (c) To 
 withhold its hands from interference with justice, (d) Not to increase 
 the imposts, (e) Except in actual necessity not to declare war (p. 243). 
 
 1 For its value as evidence in another connection the context is worth 
 translating, viz., "We understand here riches in all sorts of goods which 
 are based chiefly on a flourishing sustaining system [Nahrungsstand], 
 and without the same no people can properly be thought of as happy. 
 .... Today there is no doubt about this principle. If a corrupted 
 statecraft once believed that the wealth of the subjects must be hindered 
 in order not to feed the spirit of uproar, or at least of opposition to the 
 supreme power, we have today gone beyond that petty principle. We 
 have found that an impoverished people, which has nothing to lose, is 
 much more inclined to disorder than well-to-do citizens, and the credit 
 [A nsehtn] of the supreme power is today so well established by reasonable 
 rules of government, and by standing armies, that there is little to fear 
 
 from subjects in this respect There can be no doubt that the 
 
 riches and welfare of the subjects should be the main purpose, and the 
 consequent power and strength of princes the subsidiary purpose, and 
 not the reverse." (This last proposition is a plain negation of my fun- 
 damental theorem about cameralism. My justification throughout is 
 appeal to the whole system against its parts. I repeat that we must not 
 force upon inconsistent elements a coherent unity which did not exist. 
 Judged by the rest of the system as contained in Justi's books and in the 
 workings of the type of government which they formulated, the proposi- 
 tion quoted must be taken, along with the other idealistic elements, as 
 a symptom of partially assimilated insight, which would presently give 
 both to social* science and to governmental policy a changed perspective.) 
 
 Justi compares his own with earlier times in this respect in terms 
 which, taken literally, claimed that this theorem was the contemporary 
 working rule. Here again was an uncritical mixture of relative truth 
 and of sheer assertion of ideal value. The latter is demonstrated by 
 the admission which Justi makes at the close of the paragraph (p. 242).
 
 JUSTI'S POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 435 
 
 The fourth chapter of the book, on the restraint which a 
 good government should exercise in the matter of expense, 
 is merely a variation of commonplaces which governments 
 of the type that he had in mind observed or not, according 
 to the temper of their rulers. 
 
 Book IV, "On the Wisdom of a Good Government," is 
 a very slight variation upon corresponding passages in Staats- 
 wirthschaft. It contains nothing which in principle modifies 
 our previously expressed estimate of Justi's political philosophy. 
 As we intimated above, 1 Justi's confessed knowledge of abuses 
 in actual operation did not lead him to the conclusion which 
 has since become self-evident, viz., that the quasi-absolutism 
 of the eighteenth century was an intolerable anachronism, 
 In the last book, Justi catalogues enough faults of that type 
 of government to condemn it without remorse, but his expressed 
 inferences amount only to the impotent reflection that rulers 
 who permit such abuses ought to be ashamed of themselves, 
 and God probably has in reserve for them such averted glances 
 as are thinkable in the case of his anointed. It would be 
 profitless to rehearse specifications of delinquencies which 
 had no further meaning for human programmes. 
 
 1 E. g., pp. 406 S. et passtitt.
 
 CHAPTER XVI 
 JUSTI'S " POLICE YWISSENSCHAFT" 
 
 We now come to the most peculiar division of cameralistic 
 theory, the portion which, next to the fundamental absolutistic 
 political philosophy, contains most that is antithetic with 
 English and American theory and practice. In order to repre- 
 sent it most vividly we shall digest Justi's treatment, translating 
 as nearly as possible his own words. This will involve not a 
 little repetition. We cannot fairly represent Justi, however, 
 without reporting some of his self -iteration. We deal first 
 with Grundsatze der Policeywissenschaft. 1 
 
 The Preface to the first edition of this book is dated, Gottin- 
 gen, May 11, 1756. A second edition appeared in 1759. 
 Beckmann says the book had been used by various eminent 
 teachers as the basis of their lectures on the subject. 
 Meanwhile, several such introductions had appeared. The 
 editor refers to Justi's disregard of other writers, 3 and promises 
 to do his best in the notes to supply the gaps. In his own 
 Preface to the first edition (reprinted in the third) Justi discusses 
 the literature of the subject, and in order to show the state of 
 his information and opinions about other theorists his remarks 
 must be cited. In substance he says: 
 
 1 Jokann Heinrich Gottlobs von Justi, ehemaligen Konigl. Gross- 
 britannischen und Braunschweig- Lumber gischen Churfurstl. Berg-Roths, 
 und Ober-Policey-Commissarii, wie auch Mitgliedes der Konigl. Socie- 
 tal der Wissenschaften in Gdttingen, Grundsatze der Policeyvnsscnschaft, 
 in einen verniinftigen, auf den Endfiveck der Policey gegriindeten, Zusam- 
 menhange, und sum Gebrauche academischer Vorlesungen abgefasset. 
 Dritte Ausgabe, mit Verbesserungen und Anmerkungen von Jokann Beck- 
 mann, ordentlickem Professor der Oekonomie in Gdttingen . . . . 1782. 
 AH references are to this third edition. 
 
 Vide above, p. 292 ei passim. 
 
 436
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 437 
 
 This book is the first instalment of the promise to write text- 
 books on each of the cameralistic sciences. It is the outline of a 
 course to occupy one semester. It is the first complete treatment 
 of Policeywissenschaft. The common error has been to boil this 
 subject in one broth with Staatskunst. We have a countless number 
 [eine unbeschreibliche Menge] of books which contain the elements 
 of Staatskunst, but they do not assort their material. Staatskunst 
 has nothing for its purpose but the internal and external security 
 of the state, and its chief attention must be given to the conduct of 
 states toward each other, to increase of the power of the state in 
 relation to other states, and especially to wise conduct toward 
 other states. In like manner Staatskunst is concerned, on the other 
 hand, with adjusting the conduct of subjects toward one another 
 and toward other states. 
 
 Policeywissenschaft, on the contrary, is concerned with nothing 
 but the preservation and increase of the total "means" [Vermd'gen] 
 of the state through good internal institutions [Verfassungen] and 
 with creating all sorts of internal power and strength for the republic: 
 e. g., through (i) cultivating the land; (2) improving the laboring 
 class; (3) maintaining good discipline and order in the community. 
 In the last task it is the tool of Staatskunst in maintaining inner 
 security. 
 
 Other books have treated Policey in connection with principles 
 of Cameral- odcr Finanz-Wissenschaft, to the disadvantage of each 
 science, though they are nearly related. Policey is the ground (sic) 
 of genuine cameral science, and the police expert must sow if the 
 camera] ist is to reap; yet each science has its fixed and indisputable 
 boundaries. The one seeks to increase the total "means." The 
 other seeks to get from this the "readiest means," without harm 
 to the former* 
 
 In other books, Policey is treated along with Oekonomie; e. g., 
 Zink, 1 both in his Gntndnss and in his Anfangs-Grundf, starts with 
 certain general principles of Oeconomic, and then of Policey, and 
 then treats of more special economic questions first from the eco- 
 nomic, second from the police standpoint. This leads to constant 
 
 ' I have not observed an instance in which Justi follows his contem- 
 porary's spelling of the name.
 
 438 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 repetitions. Moreover, Policey cannot be completely treated in this 
 way, because it has a much wider scope than economic subjects. 
 In his Anjangs-Griinde, which is very diffuse, 1 Zink either wholly 
 forgets many important police subjects, or gives them only a few 
 lines. 
 
 The late If err Canzler von Wolff wrote a large number of books,* 
 and as, according to his profession, he wanted to be a system-writer 
 of all sciences, it was to be expected that he would write a Policey. 
 But the social life of human beings was the mistaken chief subject 
 of his work, which did not fit into the proper boundaries of the sci- 
 ences. His book therefore contains many valuable teachings about 
 Policey, but consistently with his ultimate purpose he mixed them 
 with so many principles of moral philosophy [Sittenlehre], of the law 
 of nature, and of prudence [Lebensweisheit], in general, that the work 
 is of no use as a system of Policey. Sciences must be separated from 
 each other to be complete, because many useful doctrines will be 
 overlooked if they are treated together. 
 
 Of the few books that remain on Policey proper, we name none 
 until the present (eighteenth) century. There has been, until late 
 years, no adequate idea of Policey, as is proved by such examples as 
 Boter, Griindlicher Bericht von Anordnung guter Policey, Strassburg, 
 1696; Schrammer, Politic historica, Leipzig, 1605; Reinking, 
 Bibliche Policey; etc. 
 
 Others in this century have a correct idea of Policeywissenschajt 
 but are not at all complete: e. g., Law, Entwurf einer wohleingerich- 
 teten Policey. The author was not equal to his undertaking. With 
 the exception of certain observations about the Policey of various 
 states, the book contains little that can be used. Again a pseudony- 
 mous "C. B. von L." published (1739) Ohnverfangliche Vorschldge 
 zu Einrichtung guter Policey. It is not a system, and contains much 
 that is chimerical and not pertinent to the science. Lucas Friedrich 
 Langemack published Abbildung einer vollkommenen Policey, Berlin, 
 1747. In this brief work the fundamental principles are very well 
 and philosophically presented, but on the whole it is not specific 
 
 i The pot is scandalized at the color of the kettle. 
 
 * Again "eine unbeschreibliche Menge," which is a trifle strong for 
 a critical treatise.
 
 JUbTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 439 
 
 enough for a system. The Mecklenburg Hojrath Velter published 
 several monographs on Policey: e. g., Unvorgreifliclien Gedanken 
 von Einrichtung und Verbesserung der Policey, 1736; more impor- 
 tant was Unterricht von der zur Stoats und Regierungswissenscltajt 
 geho'renden Policey, 1753. The author flatters himself, in the pro- 
 spectus of the latter book, that he is the first to treat this science 
 systematically, but no one with an orderly mind will admit this. 
 The book is not only confused, but leaves out much that should be 
 included, and has much affectation of wisdom from the ancients, 
 while betraying defective judgment. 
 
 The English and French have produced nothing better. De la 
 Marc's Traite de Police contains certain excellent and useful things, 
 but has no well'-grounded and connected system. 
 
 It has been said that Zink's book is more available as a text, 
 because it describes the police systems of other lands, and applies 
 the general principles of Policey to this or that particular state. On 
 the contrary, this ought not to be expected of such a textbook. We 
 should rather require of a textbook on the oconomischen Wissen- 
 schajten only the general principles, without this or that concrete 
 application. 
 
 "In this book I have followed my usual rule of not citing other 
 authors. A dogmatic writer 1 must present the subject conclusively, 
 and if he does this he does not need the authority of earlier writers. 
 Such citations smack of pedantry, unless they contain historical 
 facts, or unless some special circumstances call for them."* 
 
 Passing to the body of the book, our task is to abstract the 
 more general conceptions, within which the technology had 
 its setting, from the applications, which of course make up the 
 bulk of the contents. The material so abstracted is cumulative 
 evidence for our interpretation of cameralism. Reducing 
 Justi's propositions to the most compact form, we have the 
 following general outline: 
 
 1 Probably "didactic" would be nearer to Justi's thought than the 
 word thus literally rendered. 
 
 3 These observations by Justi tell their own story about the state 
 of the social sciences at his time, and comment would be superfluous.
 
 44 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 i. The name Policey comes from the Greek word r6X, a city, 
 and should mean the good ordering of cities and of their civic insti- 
 tutions. 
 
 |2, 3. Two uses of the term Policey are common today: first, 
 and most generally, "All measures in the internal affairs of the 
 country through which the general means [Vermfigen] of the state 
 may be more permanently founded and increased, the energies 
 [Krdjte] of the state better used, and in general the happiness of the 
 community [gemeints Wesen] promoted. In this sense we must 
 include in Policey die Commercienivissenschaften, die Stadt- und 
 Landdconomie, das Forstwesen, and similar subjects, in so far as the 
 government extends its care over them for the purpose of securing 
 general correlation of the welfare of the state. Some are accustomed 
 to call this die wirtkschaftliche Policey-Wissenschaft. This name 
 is a matter of indifference so long as it is not supposed to designate 
 a particular science. 
 
 3. In the narrower sense we understand by Policey everything 
 which is requisite for the good ordering of civic life, and especially 
 the maintenance of good discipline and order [Zucht und Ordnung] 
 among the subjects, and promotion of all measures for the comfort 
 of life and the growth of the sustaining system [Nahrungsstand]. 
 We shall treat here the general principles and rules of Policey accord- 
 ing to the comprehensive idea. In the special elaboration we shall 
 not stop to consider those things which .are the subject-matter of 
 other economic sciences, and meanwhile we shall discuss chiefly 
 the objects of Policey in the narrower sense. 1 
 
 1 The difficulty which we find in getting a distinct conception of 
 Justi's meaning is due to the fact that his own ideas were not clear. His 
 classifications have largely been abandoned, even by bureaucratic theo- 
 rists. The change begins to be visible with Rau, Lehrbuch der politischtn 
 Orkonomie, 1826, etc. In England and America the distribution of 
 activities, and consequently the theory of them, left no place for Policey 
 in Justi's sense. 
 
 The editor of the third edition adds as his own definition of " Policey," 
 the following (p. 26): "The science of governing the various occupations 
 [Gewerbe] according to the purpose of the state." Of course " Smithism " 
 was fundamentally a protest against the thing itself, but the thing itself 
 was the very genius of the cameralistic state. There consequently had
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 441 
 
 4. The purpose and consequently the essence of all republics 
 rests upon promotion of the common happiness. The general 
 "means" of each republic is the resource which it must use for pro- 
 moting its happiness. Hence the general "means" must be assured, 
 increased, and reasonably used, i. e., applied for the promotion of 
 the common happiness. This is the content [Inbegriff] of all the 
 economic and camera! sciences. The maintenance and increase 
 of the general "means" in relations with other free states is the 
 affair of Staatskunst. Policeywissenschajt, on the other hand, has 
 for its object the maintenance and increase of the same general 
 "means" of the state in connection with its inner institutions, while 
 cameral and finance science has for its task to raise from the general 
 "means" of the state, by a reasonable use of the same, the special, 
 or "readiest means," and to put into the hands of Staatskunst and 
 Policey the means of accomplishing their purposes. 
 
 5. The purpose of Policey is therefore to preserve and increase 
 the general "means" of the state; and since these "means" include 
 not merely the goods, but also the talents and skill of all persons 
 belonging to the republic, the Policey must have constant care to 
 have in mind the general interdependence of all these different 
 sorts of goods, and to make each of them contribute to the common 
 happiness. 
 
 7. Policeywissenschajt consists accordingly in understanding 
 how, under existing circumstances of the community, wise measures 
 may be taken to maintain and increase the general "means" of the 
 state in its internal relations [Verfassung], and to make the same, 
 
 to be a technology of it. The editor continues: "The occupations are 
 agricultural pursuits, aitisanship, trade, and personal services. The 
 first part of Policey accordingly treats of the responsibilities of the ruler 
 
 with respect to rural employments The second part of Policey 
 
 is urban, i. e., the Policey of the handicrafts and trade, as the two occupa- 
 tions peculiar to towns In the third part I reckon, for example, 
 
 medical practice, the ecclesiastical and educational system, etc. The 
 fourth part, or at all events the appendix, should treat of those abandoned 
 or unfortunate persons who will not pursue any of the occupations men- 
 tioned, and hence will or must live upon the diligence of other people; 
 i. e., beggars, almshouses, houses of correction, and workhouses.
 
 44 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 both in its correlation and in its parts, more efficient and useful for 
 promotion of the common happiness [gemrinschaftliche Gluckselig- 
 keif\. More briefly, Poeiceywissenschaft consists in the theorems 
 for preserving and increasing the general "means" of the state, and 
 for so using them that they will better promote the common happiness. 
 
 3. The general principle of Policeywissenschaft is accordingly: 
 The internal institutions of the community must be so arranged that 
 thereby the general "means" of the state will be preserved and increased 
 and the common happiness constantly promoted. 1 
 
 9-16. Hence follow three fundamental rules, viz.: 
 
 1. Before all things the lands of the republic must be cultivated 
 and improved.* 
 
 The development of the territories may take place in two ways: 
 (a) through external cultivation; (6) through increase of the popula- 
 tion, which may be called the internal culture of the lands. The 
 second sort of culture must be of three chief kinds: (i) Through 
 attraction of foreigners as settlers; (2) through means which promote 
 increase of the native inhabitants; (3) through prevention of sickness 
 and premature death. 
 
 2. Increase of the products of the cotmtry and the prosperity of 
 the sustaining system [Nahrungsstand] must be promoted in every 
 possible way. 
 
 3. Care must be given to securing among the subjects such capaci- 
 ties and qualities, and such discipline and order, as are demanded by 
 the ultimate purpose, viz., the common happiness. 
 
 Book I is devoted to the subject of "the external cultiva- 
 tion of the land," i. e., to all measures conducive to (i) removal 
 of impediments to occupation of the soil; (2) utilization of 
 the material advantages of the land in all its parts; (3) pro- 
 viding the citizens with means of obtaining shelter and support. 
 Chap, i treats of the improvement of the soil for the abode and 
 
 1 Vide below, p. 450 et passim. 
 
 Vide Grundfeste, I, ai. I cannot decide what difference in meaning, 
 if any, Justi associated with the two words Cultur and Anbau which he 
 sometimes seems to use merely as synonyms in oratio variaia and some- 
 times as cumulative expressions.
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 443 
 
 support of the inhabitants. Under these heads, means dis- 
 cussed are, in general: clearing superfluous forests, draining 
 ponds and swamps, protecting against flooding from seas or 
 rivers, bringing barren land under cultivation, construction 
 of harbors, making streams navigable and digging canals, 
 exploiting mineral and rock deposits, utilization of land formed 
 by recent action of the sea, or of islands, distribution of land, 
 provision for both large and small estates, establishment of 
 villages and attached arable areas [Fluhre], etc. 
 
 Chap, ii deals with the improvement [Anbau] and growth 
 of cities, and does not vary in substance from the corresponding 
 passage in Staatswirthschaft. The purpose of cities is said 
 to be to work up raw material and to carry on foreign com- 
 merce. All other institutions of cities must end in these two 
 purposes. Sites should be chosen which are favorable, the 
 general plans should conform to the needs, the dwellings should 
 not be left entirely to the caprice of the citizens, protection in 
 the shape of walls, gates, harbors, canals, water supply, and 
 drainage must be furnished, decisions must be reached about 
 extensions of the city, those who furnish material and labor 
 must be looked after, means must be taken to secure circulation 
 of sufficient money, wealthy and talented foreigners and arti- 
 sans must be attracted, the immediately neighboring land must 
 be made productive, diligence must be stimulated, means of 
 stimulating foreign trade must be devised, laws and statutes 
 must be passed, in accordance with the primary and secondary 
 purposes of the towns, and with the other characteristics of 
 the locality, city councils must be so organized that proper 
 correlation of all police activities will be promoted, there must 
 be special courts for manufactures and for trade, Ziinfte and 
 Innungen must be discouraged in new factories so far as pos- 
 sible, and in old hand-trades kept in close bounds. 
 
 Chap, iii deals with the convenience and ornamentation 
 of country and city, and discusses such subjects as roads,
 
 444 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 streets, postal systems, bridges, fountains, reservoirs, water- 
 mains, paving and cleaning and lighting of streets and alleys, 
 marking of time by bells, and by night watchmen, inns and 
 other places of refreshment, market-places, public conveyances, 
 aesthetic regulations, parks and pleasure gardens, amusements, 
 etc. 
 
 Chap, iv begins the subject of "inner cultivation of the 
 land, or the increase of population." At the beginning of this 
 chapter another of the passages occurs to which von Mohl 
 referred. 1 It is as follows: 
 
 All external improvement of a land would be of little avail, if 
 the same were not satisfactorily settled and populated. This popu- 
 lating is the internal cultivation which must give to external culti- 
 vation its soul and life. Hence increase of population is the second 
 main aim in the cultivation of countries, and just as the sustaining 
 system will always be more flourishing, the more people there are 
 in the country, so we must regard it as a fundamental theorem in 
 this division of the subject that a land can never .have too many 
 inhabitants. It is easy to protect this theorem against all objections. 
 
 However we may disagree with Justi's presuppositions and 
 with subsequent conclusions, we do not do him justice if we 
 charge him, as von Mohl and many others have done, with 
 teaching the opposite of Malthusian conclusions. The fact 
 is that he never considered the Malthusian problem at all. 
 He confronted a condition of under-population. The states 
 for which he spoke needed more population for their purposes, 
 and it was those purposes for which Justi was the spokesman. 
 He would have put the case precisely as he meant it if he had 
 said: 
 
 For the purposes of a practical cameralist today, the probability 
 of over-population may be canceled from the reckoning. 
 
 Although it had never occurred to him to pry far into the 
 relations that determined the limits of population, there is 
 
 * Vide below, p. 477.
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 445 
 
 nothing in his books to show that he supposed population could 
 be increased indefinitely. 
 
 86-96 develop devices for attracting immigrants. 1 97-108 
 develop a programme, first, for increasing population, second, for 
 checking emigration. 2 109-21 are on public hygiene. 
 
 Chap, vii, Von der Landwirthschaft, approaches the subject 
 rather from the approximate standpoint of the agronomist, 
 than of the economist. It begins (p. 109): 
 
 The promotion of the sustaining system in the country demands 
 in the first place that a sufficient number of rural products shall be 
 gained. To that end the rural Policey must constantly pay great 
 attention to those sources through which rural products are derived. 
 Here then the rural Oeconomica come first to attention, as the chief 
 means through which the raw materials for the products of the 
 country are brought into existence. These 3 are: agriculture, the 
 exploiting of natural and cultivated forests, the mines, and the 
 thereto appertaining smelting and refining works. In this sub- 
 division we deal first with agriculture. 
 
 Perhaps no part of Justi's cameralism exhibits better than 
 this division the contrast between the regime which he repre- 
 sented and the other extreme illustrated by American policy. 
 We must again call attention to the main question, viz., What 
 should government do about these matters? The American 
 answer from the beginning has been, "Nothing! Every man 
 knows best what he wants, and government has no right to 
 interfere, so long as each lets his neighbors alone." We have 
 therefore taken absolute individualism as our presupposition, 
 and have tried in every way to cover with soothing phrases and 
 fictions each departure from actual individualism which chan- 
 ging conditions have required. The most important Factor 
 in bringing about in reality, through our voluntaristic system, 
 
 1 Vide corresponding passages in Staatswirthschaft. 
 * Also parallel with same topics in Staatswirthschaft. 
 3 The reference goes back to Oeconomica.
 
 446 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 some approach to scientific use of our agricultural resources, 
 has been our legislation establishing agricultural experiment 
 stations, and systematic instruction in rural economy. The 
 thing that we have thus tardily and cautiously attempted on 
 the ostensible theory that it is primarily the affair of the indi- 
 vidual, has from time immemorial been frankly regarded 
 in the German lands as primarily the affair of governnuent. 
 It is no part of the present study to inquire about the relative 
 efficiency of the two policies. Two general remarks only are 
 in point : first, Englishmen and Americans would have treated 
 German social science in the nineteenth century more intelli- 
 gently and would have gained more from it, if they had been 
 more willing to judge it on its own grounds, and had been 
 less prone to damn "paternalism" and all its works; second, 
 whether on a paternalistic or an individualistic theory, much 
 that cameralistic administration worked out, especially in its 
 latest forms in modern Germany, is evidently enlightened 
 wisdom for a commonwealth. Bureaucracy, or no bureaucracy, 
 the things themselves need to be done, or at least a construct- 
 ive and coherent policy with reference to them needs to be 
 adopted. Study of the bureaucratic way of doing them may 
 tend to confirm most Americans in dislike of that way, but it 
 ought at least to make them more able to perceive that in point 
 of results we are at a disadvantage, and that our system is not 
 vindicated until its technical results compare more favorably 
 with those of the more paternalistic German system. 
 
 We have then in cameralism a body of officials presiding 
 over agricultural programmes just as a general staff conducts 
 the administration of a modern army. The Landes-Policey 
 deals with such subjects as the organization of larger and 
 smaller rural estates (124), the regulation of acreage devoted 
 to different crops on these estates (125), the adjustment of 
 taxation so as best to stimulate agriculture (126), the protec- 
 tion of cultivators against the interests of hunting or forestry
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 447 
 
 (127), regulation of other occupations which might draw the 
 peasants from cultivation of the soil (128), stimulation of agri- 
 cultural talent in the peasants (129), inducing production of 
 raw materials which would not be raised without special 
 stimulus (130), improvement of the quality of products (131), 
 employment of "economic inspectors" to supervise all these 
 things (132), adoption of uniform systems of measuring land 
 (133), adoption of rules of rotation of crops and other regula- 
 tions, like the wages of laborers, etc. (134), adoption of special 
 standards for particular products, kinds of seed to be used, 
 etc. (135), enactment of ordinances to protect growing crops 
 from thieves, etc. (136), particular attention to cattle-raising 
 (137), also to vineyards (138), and to horticulture (139). 
 
 In chap, viii cameralistic duties regarding forestry, mining, 
 and minor industries are analyzed (140-49). "Manufac- 
 turing and factories" are treated in the same relation in chap. 
 ix (150-80), and on these two presumptions (152): 
 
 A wise government must consequently have two theorems con- 
 stantly before its eyes, viz.: (i) Everything required fry the need and 
 comfort of the inhabitants 0} the country is to be produced as far as 
 possible within the country itself; (2) the government shall see that, 
 in the interest of the sustaining system, and of foreign commerce, 
 everything that the land produces shall, so far as possible, be worked 
 over to its complete form, and shall not be allowed to leave the country 
 in a raw and unfinished stale. To this end the government must 
 have precise extracts from the tariff, excise, and license sheets, on 
 such points as (a) all imported goods, in order to judge which of 
 them might be produced within the country; (h) all exported goods, 
 in order to discover whether domestic products in the form of raw 
 materials, or partially manufactured, are exported. 
 
 Thereupon the technique of keeping check upon raw. 
 material produced or producible in the country, of materials 
 which must be supplied by other countries, and of tools, 
 etc., needed for working up the materials is discussed (153-
 
 448 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 55), and then the programme for developing manufactures 
 (156-80). The whole is merely a somewhat expanded 
 reproduction of the corresponding part of Staatswirthschaft. 
 
 Chap, x treats very briefly the hand industries (181-90), 
 and chap, xi claims to offer only fundamental principles of 
 commercial administration, with the intention of devoting 
 a separate volume to the subject. Justi divides commerce 
 [Commercien] into domestic and foreign, applying to the former 
 the name trades [Gewerben], and repeating that a land might 
 conceivably be happy if the trades flourished, even if there 
 were no commerce. Then the fundamental condition of a 
 favorable balance is mobilized as the basic principle of com- 
 mercial administration. The details are not greatly in excess 
 of those indicated in Staatswirthschaft. 
 
 Chap, xii, on the circulation of money, contains little, for 
 our purposes, which does not occur elsewhere in Justi's books. 
 The fundamentally correct conception of gold and silver money 
 as a "ware," the weight and fineness of which are accurately 
 given, is repeated (221-23). The last of these paragraphs 
 is worth quoting as cumulative evidence: 
 
 If money and goods are to retain a constant ratio to each other, 
 no change should occur in either; and if such change could be totally 
 avoided, it would be a matter of entire indifference whether there 
 were much or little money in a country. A state which had no rela- 
 tions whatever with other peoples, and whose inhabitants consumed 
 all that they produced, would have a constantly unbroken circulation 
 of money. It would have all the power and strength of which it 
 was capable, and it would be as fortunate as another state of like 
 population with ten times as much gold and silver. But since no 
 state in our part of the world is in such circumstances, changes in 
 the value of money and of goods with respect to each other often 
 occur. We must explain the effect of these changes upon circulation. 
 
 In general Justi continues (2246?.): 
 
 If the amount of money in circulation diminishes, the price of 
 wares will increase, beginning with the most needless, the influence
 
 JUSTI'S " POLICE YWISSENSCHAFT" 449 
 
 extending gradually to all. If the quantity of money in circulation 
 increases, the most necessary wares will grow dearer. This stimulates 
 the activity of laborers and has its influence upon all wares. Money 
 becomes less desirable, interest falls, more wares are produced. 
 Gradually wares will again become cheaper, and thereby exporta- 
 tion is promoted, whereby the quantity of money in circulation is 
 more and more increased and the diligence of laborers more stimu- 
 lated. Accordingly it must be a first care of the government to pre- 
 vent diminution of the amount of money in circulation (226). 
 Lack of confidence and external dangers are prime causes of dimin- 
 ished circulation (228). Unfavorable trade balance is the most 
 effective cause (230). 
 
 Chap, xiii, on credit, is interesting for the historian of eco- 
 nomics proper, but is not immediately significant for our 
 purpose. The same is true of chaps, xiv and xv on means of 
 encouraging the laboring classes. 
 
 Book III, on the moral condition of the subjects, and 
 maintenance of good discipline and order, has value for our 
 present inquiry simply as cumulative evidence that the prob- 
 lem which Justi formulated was essentially patriarchal. The 
 point of attachment between this division of labor and the 
 whole purpose of the cameralistic state, appears at the outset, 
 as follows (270): 
 
 If the means of the state in its internal constitution are to be used 
 for the promotion of the common happiness, the subjects, apart from 
 the cultivation of the land and the promotion of the sustaining sys- 
 tem, must also themselves possess such qualities, capacities, and 
 talents that 'they can contribute their part to the realization of the 
 common welfare. In this view religion deserves first to be consid- 
 ered. The members of a community are made by religion incom- 
 parably more capable of fulfilling their duties as citizens; and a 
 state can hardly attain all the happiness of which it is capable if 
 public institutions of religion [ftusserlicher Gottesdienst] are not 
 introduced. The more this cultus harmonizes with the nature and 
 essence of men, and with the paramount purpose of republics, the
 
 45 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 more excellent will it be, and ihe more capable will it make the 
 citizens of the state to work for the common welfare. 
 
 The same point of view is adopted in considering the morals 
 of the people (285 ff.), and also in treating science and 
 education (295 ff.). 
 
 Whether religion, morals, and education are to be regarded 
 as primarily affairs of the individual, and thus not to be inter- 
 fered with by government, is a question to which Germany 
 has always assumed one answer, while the United States has 
 tried to apply the opposite answer. Our business in the 
 present connection is not to open the question of principle, but 
 merely to show the attitude of cameralism toward the question. 
 The state and its power to maintain itself against all assault 
 from within or without being the central aim, of course it was 
 a strictly logical inference that everything which could have 
 an effect on the strength of the state was properly within the 
 sphere of state supervision. 
 
 It is beginning to be possible for a few people to discern 
 that the old dilemma between the individual and the state 
 was purely fictitious in the abstract, and that neither horn of 
 the dilemma could be taken as the symbol of a concrete pro- 
 gramme without surprising results. Religion, morals, science, 
 and education have both individual and social relations, if 
 we choose to retain that distinction. We are at once in the 
 region of absurdity if we attempt to run a legal boundary line 
 between their individual and their social phases. The real 
 question for governmental theory is not whether they are the 
 one or the other, but to what extent and in what ways either 
 phase must be taken account of by the law. The arbitrary 
 character of the traditional criterion might be inferred from 
 the historical contrasts between theory and practice. The 
 German presumption at once runs counter to individual aspects 
 of each, which dictate a thus-far-and-no-farther to government, 
 while the American presumption not only gives itself curious
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 45 I 
 
 things to account for in our actual practice toward religious 
 institutions, moral conditions, and scientific needs, but it almost 
 wholly disappears in our systems of state education. 
 
 The chapters on administration of justice (339-59), 
 and preserving the peace and checking the lesser nuisances and 
 crimes (360-80), are notable only as indexes of the place 
 which cameralism assigned to these subjects in the civic struc- 
 ture. 
 
 The last book is a brief discussion of the technique to be 
 operated by the branches of government concerned with apply- 
 ing the foregoing principles of police science. Justi says that 
 in a certain sense the subject-matter of this book forms the 
 practical part of police science (p. 327). The following para- 
 graph confirms our account of the cameralistic state (382) : 
 
 The law-giving power in police affairs, since the internal arrange- 
 ment of the state chiefly rests upon it, can unquestionably be exer- 
 cised by no one but the sovereign power, the destiny of which is to 
 administer the affairs of the state for promotion of the common 
 happiness. In whosesoever hands the sovereign power is lodged, 
 he has also to enact the police laws which are to bind the state as a 
 whole. If now the sovereign power rests not alone in the hands 
 of the ruler, but at the same time also with the estates of the realm, 
 or with representatives of the people, obligatory police laws must 
 be agreed upon and promulgated by these conjointly. On the same 
 principle, the police laws which should affect the whole German 
 Empire should be enacted by the Kaiser and the estates assembed 
 in the Reichstag. 
 
 Again, 384: 
 
 Since the territorial sovereignty which the estates of the German 
 Empire possess is nothing else than the sovereign power in each 
 particular state, which finds its limitations merely in the proviso 
 that its exercise shall not extend so far as to prejudice the general 
 coherence and common welfare of the Empire; the estates of the 
 German Empire accordingly possess the law-giving power in Policey 
 affairs; and the above limitation does not prevent them from adopt
 
 452 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ing such Policey institutions and ordinances as will serve the advan- 
 tage and prosperity of their respective lands; even if this advantage 
 and prosperity might not harmonize with the interest of other 
 German states. Thus they could ordain that no wares should be 
 imported from neighboring German states for consumption within 
 their own territories. On the other hand, they could not forbid 
 the mere transportation of the wares of their neighbors; because 
 thereby the total coherence of the German states united in a common 
 civic body would be utterly destroyed. 
 
 The following sections (385 ff.) explain how this power 
 is actually exercised in the name of the sovereign. 
 
 To complete our account of Justi's Policeywissenschaft we 
 turn to the work in which the author has expanded the out- 
 line just reviewed. With the possible exception of the Finanz- 
 wissenschaft, the Grundfeste 1 is the most elaborately wrought- 
 out of Justi's works. We must nevertheless allow our resume* 
 of the Grundsatze to stand as the best index which our space 
 permits of the general contents of the more complete treatise. 
 The system of control outlined in the Grundfeste reflects a 
 regime which the people of the United States have thus far, 
 by almost unanimous consent, refused to reflect upon judicially. 
 They have dismissed it without a hearing, as "unamerican." 
 Nevertheless, it is safe to predict that the time will come when 
 thoughtful Americans will be able to deliberate about the system 
 exhibited in an immature form in these books, to weigh the pur- 
 poses which the system was designed to serve, and to conclude 
 that although the methods of control which the purposes pre- 
 suppose are impossible in America, yet the purposes themselves 
 must in principle be organized somehow into the most highly 
 civilized life. 
 
 This conclusion must be allowed to rest on the exhibit thus 
 
 i It is a fair surmise that Justi got this title from the heading of 
 chap, xxxiii, in Schroder's Fiirst. Schatz- und Rent-Cammer; vide 
 above, p. 167.
 
 JUSTFS " POLICE YWISSENSCHAFT" 453 
 
 far made of the different police systems. We may add merely 
 a few notes from the Grundfeste. 
 
 In the Preface to the first volume Justi says: 
 
 I have often noticed that there are very few people who have a 
 correct idea of Policey. That which in the narrowest sense is called 
 Policey, namely the Policey in the cities, is regarded by the majority 
 as the whole scope of this science. If this very limited signification 
 were the whole, I should have insufficient ground for calling the 
 Policey the main defense of states. Both the Grundsdtze and the 
 present work should make it plain that the scope of the science is 
 much wider. 
 
 Justi complains that most writers on Policey have not 
 sharply separated the subject from Staatskunst. 1 
 
 It will be found [he says] that as a rule those who have treated 
 Staatskunst have at the same time discussed Policey with Commer- 
 cien- und Finanz-Wissenschajt. This is the case, for example, with 
 the latest writer on Staatskynst* If our conception of Staatskunst 
 or Politik made it include not only all knowledge necessary for the 
 government of a state, but also all the details of institutions neces- 
 sary in civic society, those would be right who include in one system 
 of Politik, Policey, the Finanz-Wissenschaften, and all the other 
 
 1 Vide above, p. 328. 
 
 '"Baron von Bielfeld, born 1716, Hamburg, of an aristocratic 
 merchant family, died 1770. He was a friend of Frederick the Great 
 when the latter was crown prince. Was for a while guest of the latter 
 in Rheinsberg, and immediately upon his accession entered his diplomatic 
 service. After' 1741 he was Legationsrath in the foreign department, 
 later second Hofmeister of a Prussian prince; after 1747 Oberaufseher 
 of the Prussian universities, but without the least loss of the king's favor 
 retired presently to his estates. His writings, the most important of 
 which, the Institutions Politiques, appeared in 1760, suggest not merely 
 by their French dress, but also by their genial cosmopolitan tone, Fred- 
 erick the Great, much more than contemporary academic specialists. 
 Schlozer credits him with the immortal honor of having first introduced 
 learned politics at courts!" (Roscher, p. 426.)
 
 454 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 economic sciences. 1 But, in that case Staatskunst would be no 
 special science at all. It would be nothing but a general name for 
 almost all other sciences. Die Rechtsgelehrsamkeil, die Bergwerks- 
 Wissenschaften, die Mathematik, die Mechanik, and almost all other 
 sciences would belong to Staatskunst. For all these furnish knowl- 
 edge which is applicable in the government of a state, and necessary 
 for the institutions and practices of civic society. In a word, they 
 all contain knowledge of means whereby the state may be made 
 powerful, and the citizens happy. That is the explanation which 
 Baron von Bielfeld gives of Politik. 
 
 Justi declines to accept this description of Staatskunst. 
 He contends that it has been at all times not a general name 
 for many and almost all sciences, but a special and self- 
 sufficient science, sharply distinguished from Policey, Finanz- 
 und Commercien-Wissenschaft. Then he restates his definition 
 of Policey thus: 
 
 "// is that science which has for its object permanently to maintain 
 the welfare of the separate families in an accurate correspondence and 
 proportion with the best common good. 1 ' This definition is supported 
 by the comment: "The best common good [das gemeinschaftliche 
 Beste] is the ultimate aim of all civic institutions. But, we can ima- 
 gine no best common good without the welfare of the separate families. 
 To make these correspond with each other is accordingly in fact the 
 main defense of the state, out of which its power and happiness must 
 chiefly arise." 3 
 
 Justi elaborates in this connection his theory of the division 
 of labor between Staatskunst and the other "sciences." We 
 have already quoted from the Staatsivirthschaft his principal 
 propositions on this classification. * 
 
 ' In this case it is clear that the phrase "die oconomischcn Wisscn- 
 schaflen," which I have rendered "economic sciences," had a meaning 
 for Justi which would be more exactly represented to our minds by the 
 phrase "social technologies." 
 
 3 This definition is amplified on p. 4, also pp. 6-9. 
 
 3 Vide above, p. 328 et passim.
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 455 
 
 A curious measure of Justi's sense of proportion may be 
 found in the fact that he occupies five out of the fourteen pages 
 of his Preface with a discussion of the relative merits of differ- 
 ent printing establishments. His laudation of the publisher 
 chosen for this work, after relation of sad experiences with 
 others, one of them named, rouses the suspicion that a motive 
 less disinterested than zeal for improvement of the art of print- 
 ing was beneath this discourse. Incidentally he betrays a 
 characteristic trait of the whole Policey regime, as well as of 
 his personal theory, in this suggestion: 
 
 Perhaps we find here a lack in our Policey. It is without doubt 
 the duty of the Policey to look out for the quality of wares and work, 
 and to set the standard below which work shall be regarded as entirely 
 unfit, and to be made good to the person who suffers injury from it. 
 I doubt, however, if there is a country in which a standard of passable 
 quality in printing is enforced. The more our publishing system 
 becomes a staple ware (sic) the more will such laws be necessary. 1 
 
 Having discussed the evils of putting the emphasis in the 
 state either on the interests of the government, or on those of 
 the separate families, to the prejudice of the other, Justi offers 
 the following "general fundamental principle" of Policey- 
 wissenschaft, viz.: 
 
 In all the affairs 0} tlie country, the attempt must be made to put the 
 welfare of the separate families in the most accurate combination and 
 interdependence with the best common good, or the happiness of the 
 whole state. 2 
 
 1 Justi's most explicit attempt to explain the etymology of the term 
 Policey occurs on p. 5, Part I. He quotes from Xenophon's Athenian 
 Republic to show that the word IIoMTe/a meant "not only the internal 
 institutions of a state, but the whole governmental system of a community: 
 and even what we now express by the word republic." 
 
 3 The author calls attention to the divergence of this proposition 
 in form from that in Grundsdtzen der Policcywissenschaft Elnleitung, 
 {8, p. 7. He explains that the two formulas do not essentially differ. 
 (Vide above, pp. 442.)
 
 456 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 In the most emphatic terms he declares that this is the single 
 great object of police institutions, and that all the major and 
 minor rules of Policey must be derived from this central purpose. 
 
 Less fundamental, but more significant for the matter upon 
 which tradition has most stupidly misrepresented the cameral- 
 ists in general, is the main theorem which the first part of the 
 work supports, viz.: "The strength and the permanent happi- 
 ness of a state rest principally upon the goodness of the climate 
 and soil of the country. 1 ' Justi is not among the writers whose 
 attention is given chiefly to agricultural technique. He evi- 
 dently knew comparatively little about agriculture proper. Of 
 the extractive industries, mining was the only pursuit about 
 which he professed to write as an expert. Yet the place which 
 he assigned to agriculture in his theory leaves no valid excuse 
 for applying to him the label "mercantilist," if it carries the 
 traditional meaning "believer in trade as the sole source of 
 wealth." Instead of accepting this doctrine, Justi urges (27) 
 that "economic trade," as the phrase went, that is, the trade 
 of a nation of middlemen, like Holland in the seventeenth and 
 eighteenth centuries, is a precarious source of national pros- 
 perity and wealth. He says: 
 
 Economic trade is always based on the stupidity and laziness of 
 other peoples. So soon as a people perceives that it does better when 
 it gets its wares from the first hand, it is all over with this economic 
 trade. Upon quite as uncertain ground rest the manufactures of 
 such a country. A wise and industrious people will always seek to 
 manufacture its own raw materials. Hence this source of riches 
 rests on the stupidity and laziness of other peoples, and so soon as 
 these peoples get their eyes open, they will no longer furnish to 
 
 the trading nation a source of riches A nation which, by 
 
 virtue of its good and well-cultivated soil, exports a great quantity 
 of domestic products is also in a situation, according to the nature 
 and course of commerce, to draw to itself much easier and to retain 
 even the economic trade, than another nation which has few domestic 
 products.
 
 JUSTI'S "POLICEYWISSENSCHAFT" 457 
 
 From all this it is clear in my judgment, that the success and 
 permanent happiness of a people rest in a very important degree 
 upon the good character of its soil and climate, and that a people 
 which itself produces all its needs (sic) and many domestic goods 
 is incomparably more powerful and happy than a nation which must 
 obtain its necessities and wares for consumption from other peoples, 
 and thus is in a certain sense dependent upon them. 
 
 These considerations lead us to two theorems which will be of 
 great importance in the whole treatment of Policey: First, a prudent 
 nation must always take care to put itself in stick condition that it 
 is not under the necessity of obtaining its most important wants [Bediirf- 
 nisse] and materials from other peoples; second, a nation must seek 
 in every possible way to cultivate the area which it occupies and to 
 improve its climate. 
 
 This proposition is not only repeated in slightly varied form 
 in the following paragraph, but the body of the book expands 
 it, and Justi's whole philosophy presupposes it. 
 
 Along with this fundamental principle, Justi next reiterates 
 his second main theorem (30), viz.: 
 
 Since there can never be complete cultivation of the soil without 
 dense population, our second working theorem is, that a state must 
 in every way promote population. 
 
 These theorems are insufficient without a third, viz.: // a state 
 has only inhabitants devoted to cultivation of the surface of the earth, 
 
 its population can never be dense Consequently we have the 
 
 third fundamental principle: that government must constantly pay 
 the strictest attention to the building and growth of cities and villages 
 
 (31)- 
 
 A fourth theorem must be added, viz. : The Policey must devote 
 itself to works and institutions for the comfort of the inhabitants and 
 the ornamentation of the land (32). 
 
 Each of the four books of the first part of the Grundfeste 
 develops one of these four theorems. 
 
 In the Preface of the second volume Justi professes an entire 
 reversal of literary policy. He says: "The attentive reader
 
 458 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 will be able to judge how great pains I have taken to seek 
 out the most excellent thoughts of the greatest minds, in order 
 thereby to strengthen my discussion." The fact is that Justi 
 was from the start the most expert recoiner of other people's 
 thoughts that German political literature up to his time had 
 developed. He had not before approached so near to a con- 
 fession that he was more a codifier than a first-hand investi- 
 gator. The Preface is chiefly devoted to a defense against the 
 criticism of Baron von Bielfeld that Justi had included altogether 
 too much in Policeywissenschaft. The passage is so character- 
 istic of the time and of the author that no independent student 
 of the subject should neglect to read it. 
 
 Probably there is no more accurate and detailed contem- 
 porary picture of the policy behind Frederick the Great's 
 type of benevolent despotism, at least no picture of the policy 
 as it was idealized in the minds of theorists, than the views 
 presented in these two volumes of the Grundfeste, together with 
 the later work, System des Staatswesens (i 766). As the evidence 
 already presented is more than sufficient to support our main 
 contention, we must pass these volumes with the remark that 
 their contents are cumulative proof of the correctness of the 
 view we have taken of cameralism in general.
 
 CHAPTER XVII 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 
 
 To complete the exhibit which the compass of this book 
 permits us to make of Justi's views, we must draw from his 
 collected miscellanies. Without attempting to organize these 
 extracts into systematic form, we shall present them in the 
 accidental order in which they occur in the three volumes. 1 
 This chapter is therefore in effect an appendix, consisting 
 principally of notes which serve to emphasize certain features 
 already referred to in the author's theory. 
 
 The Preface to Vol. I of this collection is dated Berlin, 
 Sept. 3, 1760. It refers to "the present war" (i. e., the Seven 
 Years' War, 1756-63) as hindering the correspondence with 
 Austrian publishers, who wanted to get out a new edition of 
 some of these papers previously published in Teutschen 
 Memoir es. 
 
 The Preface to Vol. I repeats the theme of cameralism 
 in this form: 
 
 Money is today so largely the ground (sic) of all the activity 
 of the state, that the greatest courage and the greatest bravery of 
 a people in our time can have little success if it is not provided with 
 sufficient money, that great motive spring and nervous fluid of all 
 undertakings which are to attain fortunate results. We must go 
 farther; we must indeed affirm that the most wholesome and excel- 
 lent arrangements and institutions of a state will have little success 
 along with a bad condition of the financial system of the state. 
 
 Again, in the same preface (the pages are not numbered) : 
 
 I believe that we still lack a species of history which would be 
 
 peculiarly useful. The historical books of all peoples are concerned 
 
 1 Johann Heinrich Gottlobs von Justi, Gesammelte Politische und 
 Finanzschriften uber wichtige Gegenstande der Staatskunst, der Kriegs- 
 wissenschaften und des Cameral- und Finanzwesens 1761. 
 
 459
 
 460 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 almost entirely with extraordinary and unfortunate occurrences 
 with wars and slaughters which peoples have waged against one 
 another, with narration of extraordinary rascalities and villanies, 
 and the succession of rulers. In my opinion this is of least value 
 and least instructive in history. We should have a history from the 
 earliest times in which the chief attention would be given to the origin 
 of realms and states, to the efforts to found them and to bring them 
 into a flourishing condition, to the principles of government in 
 political, financial, and police affairs, to the attempts to cultivate 
 and people the lands, to the causes of the growth and decay of realms 
 and states, and especially to the governmental mistakes which rulers 
 and ministers have committed. On the other hand, the wars and 
 other matters which heretofore have filled the histories should be 
 mentioned only in passing, in so far as they have had a greater or 
 less influence upon the welfare or decline of civic societies. If a 
 history were so constructed, we could say that history is a mirror of 
 human transactions. As histories are now written I believe they 
 have very little claim to such a title. I have made up my mind to 
 write such a history. I will give it the title: The History of Mankind 
 as Citizens [Die Geschichte des Menschen, als Biirger]. 1 In my 
 opinion such a history, if it satisfied its purpose, would go far toward 
 extending a knowledge of true governmental and financial principles 
 upon which the happiness of peoples largely rests, and such a book 
 could incidentally not fail to be useful to civic society. 
 
 Again, in the same preface the author says: 
 
 If my efforts in the economic and cameralistic sciences have 
 thus far received the indulgent favor of the world, I do not credit 
 this to my own skill. I believe I owe it entirely to my efforts to estab- 
 lish all the theorems and rules upon the essential purpose of all 
 states, namely the happiness of the peoples. These are also the 
 principles on which I base the financial treatises in this collection. 
 In fact, one can never have other principles in finance. A cameralist 
 who bases his measures upon other principles cheats his master, 
 the state, and himself. 
 
 Examining these papers in turn, and selecting items which 
 1 The book never appeared.
 
 JUSTTS CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 461 
 
 are most significant for our puq)osc, we have the following 
 details of varying importance : 
 
 A usage that was common in this period, not in Germany 
 alone but throughout Europe, is illustrated in I, i, in the em- 
 ployment of the word "philosophy" as equivalent to "science." 
 The main point of I, 2, is in the paragraph on p. 17: 
 That which is the decisive factor in human affairs is "the allwise 
 Providence of the Highest which always has a hand in human activi- 
 ties and which orders the outcome of all things according to its great 
 wisdom." 
 
 A side-light on the application of Justi's theories to actual 
 conditions is in I, 6: 
 
 Should sumptuary laws be enacted in the interest of the happi- 
 ness of the state, especially when it is desirable to encourage com- 
 merce and trade? Of course superfluous display and waste or 
 luxury [Ueppigkeit] are contrary to the principles of sound morals. 
 What degree of outlay should be regarded as extravagant is a ques- 
 tion. It is not at all certain that the outlays which would harm a 
 single family are for that reason harmful to the whole state. For 
 strength against possible enemies the state needs available means. 
 If money were hoarded by the subject, to that extent the sources of 
 available means would dry up. The good of the state demands 
 that money should circulate. If the outlays for display and luxury 
 do not leave the country, they are not harmful to the state (p. 80). 
 Neither the power of the sovereign nor the total means of the state 
 lose anything by it. Hence such outlays should not be forbidden. 
 In the case of luxurious consumption of foreign goods, the best 
 regulation is by prohibiting import of the same (p. 89). Yet 
 certain luxuries should perhaps be forbidden: e. g., those that 
 consume gold and silver in perishable ornaments, or in gilding wood 
 or the baser metals. Probably, however, even the trades that furnish 
 these should be allowed freedom, as the amount of gold and silver 
 permanently lost to the state is trifling compared with the amounts 
 which craftsmen are able to earn in these trades. 
 
 The silver plate owned by the upper classes is so much dead 
 treasure. It is certain that this is not contributing to the welfare
 
 462 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of the community [genteincs Wesen], and it is to be wished that this 
 sort of display could be restricted (p. 91). Vet I cannot conclude 
 that possession of such things should be prohibited. A special tax 
 on luxuries would be a wiser means of restraining extravagance. 
 
 I, 8, compares the government of a state to a machine, and 
 makes the analogy a text for an argument for strict ordering 
 of the civil service. I, n, enters the field of social psychology 
 in this vein: 
 
 Peoples are governed by the help of prejudices [Vorurtheile]. 
 The passions are the first sources and motive springs of all human 
 actions. If we were controlled by reason only, we should need 
 neither republics nor forms of government. The strength and 
 weakness of a state depends accordingly upon the character of the 
 prejudices with which its citizens are filled, and the wisdom of the 
 government consists chiefly in producing prejudices by means of 
 which the state may attain to all the possible power of which it is 
 capable. 
 
 If ever there was a people that needed to change its prejudices, 
 we poor Germans arc the ones. Since the Saxon emperors (919- 
 1024), our strength has been steadily on the wane, and for two hun- 
 dred years we appear to have been the prey of all neighbboring 
 peoples. Our prejudices cannot be of the sort that put us in posses- 
 sion of our full strength. It is not the least of our lacks that we are 
 wanting in the impulse and genius that arc necessary for commerce. 
 We must change our prejudices so that commerce and manufacture 
 will rank higher, and will not be beneath the dignity of the nobility. 
 Is a nobility in general consistent with the nature of republics 
 (p. 151)? A hereditary nobility stops up a source which could 
 furnish a great number of rewards for services. 
 
 Justi seems to discuss the question seriously (I, 170, et 
 passim) whether it were not better to give up the idea of 
 developing commerce and to resume the idea on which the old 
 German nobility was based power and happiness by conquest. 
 The chief idea would then be not to have a sufficient army to 
 repel attacks, but an aggressive policy of conquest. This
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 463 
 
 would be to turn the nation into a robber among nations. 
 After referring to somewhat more admissible causes of war, 
 Justi continues (p. 175): 
 
 Moreover, in our day war is extremely costly. It is more a 
 sacrifice of unmeasured sums of money than of blood. If therefore 
 a poor nation should today determine to make conquests its chief 
 purpose, it would come to a very ridiculous resolve. A people that 
 today wants to be militant must accordingly also seek to be rich. 
 
 There is no other way whereby a people can become rich than 
 through commerce. If a people had in its power the richest gold 
 mines, without carrying on flourishing commerce, it would not thereby 
 be rich. Those foreign peoples who get control of its commerce 
 will also indirectly have its gold mines in their power. Spain furnishes 
 a very conclusive example. 
 
 Accordingly no people can today reasonably make conquests 
 its chief purpose without proposing commerce as an equally impor- 
 tant affair But let us suppose that a militant folk has brought 
 
 all Europe under its yoke. Would it therefore be happy ? By no 
 means. It would without doubt acquire vast plunder, but these 
 very riches, instead of promoting its happiness, would cause its ruin. 
 
 All riches which do not come into the state by way of commerce, 
 which do not make the industry of the citizens active in their voca- 
 tions, and which do not incidentally pour themselves into all parts 
 of the civic body, are the source of all disorders, which will presently 
 draw after them the corruption and total destruction of the state. 
 Not tbe German peoples were the real destroyers of Rome, but the 
 treasures of Attalus (sic) and other riches which came to Rome 
 
 through the plundering of so many peoples This destruction 
 
 would have been even more rapid if the Romans, after their conquests, 
 had not become merchants. But even this medicine could not 
 restore the humors once totally corrupted. They were only a strength 
 ening by which the wholly emasculated body was able to endure 
 for a period 
 
 All this amply proves, it seems to me, that a people can never 
 make conquest its chief aim, and thereby promote its happiness. 
 It proves that no people can be powerful without wealth, and con-
 
 464 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 sequently not without commerce, that a people without sufficient 
 power would be very foolish if it dreamed of conquests, that the othe* 
 European powers would soon enough make it repent of its silly 
 idea; yet, it proves that if a poor people, contrary to all probability, 
 gained the conquests it had desired, still without commerce it would 
 neither be happy, nor would it be able to retain the advantages it 
 had gained. 
 
 If, accordingly, all this is established, it naturally follows that 
 the militant origin of the nobility cannot be sufficient ground for 
 its devoting itself exclusively to the purpose out of which it originated. ' 
 
 In I, 13 (p. 198), Justi again explains his doctrine of the 
 importance of the factor of density of population as a compo- 
 nent of the strength of a nation. In brief his assertion is that, 
 other things being equal, a country with a million inhabitants 
 scattered over a thousand square miles of territory is much 
 weaker than a country of two hundred and fifty square miles, 
 with the same population. He continues (p. 199): 
 
 The more populous a state, the more prosperous will be its food 
 industries and trades, and the more active will be the circulation of 
 money, because all men have need of reciprocal aid and of a thousand 
 kinds of necessities from each other. If a state has foreign commerce, 
 it will constantly acquire more riches, with the greater number of 
 hands that labor on the domestic products and wares. This increased 
 
 1 The whole foregoing passage (I, 175-79), it must be remembered, 
 is incidental to discussion of the question, What is the relation of the 
 nobility to the state and commerce ? The main point in Justi's mind 
 was to establish the position that on the principle, noblesse oblige, a nobility 
 should justify itself by the sort of service which the state most needed. 
 His argument was that war was not the most radical employment of the 
 state, that commerce went much nearer to the roots of happiness, and 
 that, when promotion of commerce was needed, the nobility ought to 
 serve the state by assuming commercial responsibilities. The context 
 does not warrant any confident inferences from the passage in its bearings 
 upon mercantilism. There are traces in it, in the reference to stimulation 
 of domestic industry, of the actual association of ideas with the more 
 fundamental processes of production. We find the same cropping out 
 elsewhere in qualification of the supposed extreme mercantilist theory.
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 465 
 
 wealth will always set the industrious hands of the ix>pulation into 
 more active motion, and the wealth of the stale will the more increase. 
 This wealth will at the same time attract much folk from the 
 neighboring states, that barely support life: and thus this wealth 
 will increase the power of the state. The superiority of a people 
 depends today as much and more upon its wealth than upon its 
 numbers. A land which is wisely ruled, and has a flourishing sus- 
 taining system, can accordingly never have too many inhabitants. 
 
 A moral state must look to wedlock for the increase of its popula- 
 tion. How important to the state therefore are its marriage laws 
 (p. 200). 
 
 The monograph I, 19, is almost the modern "pace-making" 
 generalization which Professor W. I. Thomas has done so 
 much to develop. The paper glorifies the type that we now 
 call "promoters," while it denounces the merely adventurous 
 varieties of the type. I, 24, expands previous suggestions 
 about getting the most out of people by a system of honors. 
 
 Of the papers in the second division of Vol. I on financial 
 questions, we need note merely that (i) expands the view 
 previously expressed, that it is better to farm the Landesherr- 
 lichen Cammerguter und Aemter than to administer them 
 directly; (4) adds details on wise forms of taxation; (5) dis- 
 cusses excise, and a proposed substitute in the form of an occu- 
 pation tax; (6) gives further details of the duties of a cameral- 
 ist in connection with forests and forestry; (7) elaborates a 
 detail under the same head; (8) expands the discussion of 
 the proposition that subjects are not necessarily happy by 
 reason of low taxes; (9) enlarges on "Mauthen und Zolle," as 
 means of promoting commerce; (12) treats of taxation as a 
 means of developing and managing the sustaining system. 
 
 Passing to Vol. II, the first paper deals with division and 
 balance of power between the main branches of the government 
 in the fundamental constitution of the state. Justi makes 
 two primary divisions: first, the law-giving, second, the exec-
 
 466 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 utive power. The former has for its object both the main 
 purpose of the complete happiness of the state, and also the 
 subsidiary purposes. Justi slides over, however, into the 
 conventional legislative, executive, judicial classification, and 
 a main proposition is that neither all nor two of these branches 
 of power should be in the same hands. The most tolerable 
 combination is that of legislative and executive powers (p. 10). 
 
 If the executive power is entirely independent of the legislative 
 power, if the former has at its disposal all necessary resources, the 
 executive power will certainly attain such preponderance that the 
 legislative will presently be suppressed (p. 12). Either it will not 
 be convened at all, or it will be permitted to concern itself merely 
 with the most insignificant matters. "In all German nations legis- 
 lation rested at first mostly with the Volk. 1 ' 1 
 
 The paragraph continues: 
 
 But, because they* put permanently in the hands of the executive 
 power, or of their kings and princes, the means of execution, namely 
 the revenues of the state, in such a way that the executive power 
 had no more need of their co-operation, the result was that in Spain 
 and France nothing remains of the legislative power of the Volk, 
 and in most of the German states only a bare shadow. If on the 
 other hand the legislative power is entirely unlimited, and not at all 
 dependent upon the executive power, the former will presently abuse 
 its strength to suppress the executive. 
 
 1 I imagine that such a proposition, even with the explanations 
 immediately to follow, was possible only because of the ambiguity of 
 the term Volk. Some of the political philosophers of the time could 
 interpret the personal acts of their own ruling princes as constructively 
 the action of the Volk. That is, the latter term carried a content of 
 metaphysical theory. It did not necessarily mean the "people" in an 
 unequivocal democratic sense. 
 
 1 The implied antececJent of the pronoun is the plural "nations" 
 in the preceding sentence, not the collective and metaphysically con- 
 :irued noun Volk. The whole explanation would go to pieces under 
 analysis.
 
 467 
 
 The indubitable conclusion is it seems to me that a well-ordered 
 fundamental constitution of the state will be so arranged that the 
 two highest powers will always be in a certain sort of interdependence 
 or equilibrium. This equilibrium depends entirely on their having 
 the right to hinder each other when the one or the other goes too 
 far and loses sight of the welfare of the state, or tends to repudiate the 
 fundamental constitution. 1 
 
 The true freedom of the citizen in monarchies would be repre- 
 sented principally by two circumstances, viz., first, if the laws were 
 so clear and distinct that the decisions would be rather the decisions 
 of the laws than of the judge; second, if the accused, especially in 
 penal cases, were allowed to choose his own judges, or at least to 
 reject so many of them that the remainder would seem to be of his 
 own choosing. 2 
 
 Another passage occurs (Vol. II, p. 26) in which a leaning 
 toward the English form of constitution is expressed. More 
 important than symptoms of this kind is the touch of color 
 which we find in II, I, 9, Justi's inaugural address at the begin- 
 
 1 As in other passages, Justi goes on to speak of details which would 
 enable the ruler to commit the nation to policies that would constrain 
 the legislative power to acquiesce in the last instance on the principle 
 "my country right or wrong." It is not to be denied, however, that Justi's 
 theory in this passage really in a large measure anticipates the demands 
 of the constitutionalists of the following century (vide op. cit., pp. 21, 22). 
 Yet his illustrations of acts which would make an absolute sovereign 
 into a despot are far from indicating limitations that would remove the 
 conditions which to the modern mind amount to practical absolutism. 
 For instance, when Louis XIV declared his natural sons eligible to the 
 throne, and when Peter I of Russia claimed for the crown the prerogative 
 of designating the successor, each was an attempt to alter the constitu- 
 tion, and beyond the proper rights of the unlimited monarch. That is, 
 Justi argued in most cases for limitation of the monarch by the con- 
 stitution, not otherwise, and the constitution which he had in mind must 
 not be thought of as going into any such details as the written or un- 
 written constitutions of modern states. 
 
 I. e., Justi had his eye so closely trained on personal freedom that 
 he did not properly estimate the degree of its dependence upon political 
 freedom.
 
 468 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ning of his professorial work at Vienna. It contains among 
 other things, an anticipation of the idea of division of labor, 
 and the dependence of each upon the labors of all, so much 
 more minutely worked out by Adam Smith. 
 
 The address further glorifies "republics," as against the 
 fantasy of "the state of nature," and is in effect a plea for 
 acquiescence in the type of rule which the House of Habsburg 
 represented. 
 
 In the course of the address, after an outline of the tasks 
 that a state must perform in order to insure its happiness, a 
 passage occurs which is so full of the time-temperament 
 that we are unwilling to weaken it by translation. It reads 
 (P- US): 
 
 Ohne Zweifel, hochgebietliendt geheimde Conferenzminisler, 
 und wirkliche gelieimde Rathe, gnadige Herren, wie auch hochst und 
 hochgeehrleste Anwesende! hat Ihnen alien dieser geringe Abriss nur 
 Gclcgcnheit gegeben, sich unterdessen an der geheiligten Person 
 unscrer allerdurchlauchtesten Monarchin, eine weit wiirdigere und 
 erhabene Vorstellung von der Sache zu machen. Ich bin versichert, 
 dass sie unterdessen in ihren Gedanken diejenigen weisen und uner- 
 mudeten Bemiihungen welche diese wahrhaftig grosse Regentin 
 vor die Wohlfahrt ihrer anvertrauten Volker anwendet, an die Stelle 
 mciner unzuliinglichen Beschreibung gesetzt haben: und was vor 
 einc weit lebhaftigere und vollkommenere Abschilderung ist ihnen 
 nicht dadurch gerathen? Die osterreichischen Staaten haben 
 zwar allemal das Gliick genossen, das ihre Monarchen den anver- 
 trauten 7x:pter mit weiser Vorsicht, mit unermiideter Sorgfalt, mit 
 ciner Giitigkeit ohne Beyspiele, und mit der zartlichsten Licbe 
 gcgen ihre Unterthanen gefiihret haben. Allein die Hand des 
 unendlichen Weltbeherrschers, wenn er es seiner allgemeinen Haus- 
 haltung gemass befindet, dass die Gestalt der Zeiten verandert, der 
 Wuth der Verwiister des Erdbodens, die sich die Schwa'che ihrer 
 Nachbam zu Nutzc machen, Einhalt gethan, und die Ruhe des 
 menschlichen Gcschlechts dargestellet werden soil, bildet manchmal 
 in dcm Schoossc seiner Vorsehung ausserordentlich grosse Seelen,
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 469 
 
 wclche geschickt sind, ein Reich auf einen viel hohern Gracl dcr 
 Macht und der GlUckseligkeit zu setzen. Wenn also die glUck- 
 lichen osterreichischen Lander ihren Zepter jemals in weiscn Handen 
 gesehen haben; wenn jemals die hesten und wirksamstcn Mittcl 
 ihre GlUckseligkeit zu befordern, angewendet worden sind; wenn 
 sie sich jemals dem wahren Punkte ihrer Grosse, Macht und GlUck- 
 seligkeit genahert haben: so ist es itzo, und die gegenwartigen Zeiten 
 werden das GlUck geniessen, dass unsere spaten Enkel den Zeitlauf 
 von Oesterreichs vergrossertem Zustande bey ihnen anfangen werden. 
 
 Of course this impossible fulsomeness was largely a matter 
 of prescribed and perfunctory form. It would be absurd to 
 draw the conclusions from it which literal interpretation of the 
 language would suggest to modern democrats. At the same 
 time the fact remains that Justi was a pliant servant of a regime 
 which called for that sort of conventionality. Discount what- 
 ever is necessary for the demands of ceremony; discount too 
 the reservations in Justi's mind, and betrayed frequently in 
 his books; he remains the spokesman of the type of state of 
 which Maria Theresia is a symbol. In the remainder of the 
 address from which the passage is taken he employs rhetoric 
 of almost equal extravagance to express his pride in the vocation 
 of preparing youth for service in the administration of the 
 Habsburg state (p. 137). When a little later he found himself 
 no longer persona grata in Vienna, he went from state to state 
 of the same essential type, and left behind no credible evidence 
 of ever in his responsible moments having entertained the 
 thought that' in Germany an essentially different type of state 
 was feasible. The relation of Justi to the modern type of 
 political theory may be indicated in a perfectly fair illustration. 
 Suppose that in a hundred years Great Britain shall have 
 moved as far from her present type in the direction of socialism 
 as continental states, in becoming constitutional, have moved 
 from the absolutistic type in the direction of democracy. Sup- 
 pose that a historian at that date should take John Stuart Mill's
 
 47 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 record in connection with the Land Tenure Reform Association 
 as proof that he was not a nineteenth-century conservative, 
 but a twenty-first century radical. The guess would be no 
 wider of the mark than an interpretation of Justi as other than 
 a technologist of the Maria Thcresia type of governmental 
 theory. 
 
 In this same address (p. 142), in speaking of the conditions 
 which enable a state to accomplish its purposes for its citizens, 
 Justi puts "adequate riches" first, and "complete security" 
 second, and he continues: 
 
 We must not, however, form the same notion of the riches of a 
 state which we have of the riches of a private person. Not all riches 
 which a land may contain can be regarded as wealth [ein Reichthum] 
 of the land. Not chests filled with money in the treasury of the 
 monarch, not the hcaped-up piles of gold in the houses of private 
 persons, accumulated by greed and oppression, constitute the riches 
 of the state. Gold and silver, these lustrous metals, which seem 
 so l)cautiful to the eager eyes of men, lose all price and all worth 
 previously credited to them, and they turn again to trifling parts of 
 the globe, if they lose their ultimate purpose: namely, to be a uni- 
 versal means of determining the worth of all other sorts of goods, 
 and to serve for the establishment and promotion of the business 
 of men. Only that wealth is therefore the real wealth of the state 
 which is grasped by the busy hands of the inhabitants, and is daily 
 moved from one employment into another. 
 
 Apparently Justi had to defend his claims for the cameral 
 sciences against suspicion of being on a level with alchemy, 
 fortune-telling, etc. With changes of detail, his lot was not 
 unlike the situation in which even now sociology finds itself 
 when it presents its case to representatives of the older social 
 sciences. Apparently in part to outflank this phase of opposi- 
 tion to his subject Justi explained (op. cit., pp. 155-60) the 
 three methods of obtaining national wealth which he assumed 
 to be worth considering, viz., (i) mining; (2) commerce; 
 (3) inducing rich foreigners to become citizens.
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 47 1 
 
 The essay, "Proof that a Universal Monarchy Would Make 
 for the Welfare of Europe and the Human Race" (II, I, 17), 
 was first published anonymously in 1748. Justi acknowledges 
 that it is punctured by the consideration that there would be 
 no assurance of a succession of fit monarchs. It amounts 
 then merely to a fancy picture. He meant it, however, as a 
 means of expressing indirectly certain opinions which could 
 not be published unveiled. In general, he wanted to ring 
 changes on the idea that princes had no right to govern arbi- 
 trarily, but that right reason must control them. He took 
 the round-about way of arguing that it was not necessarily a 
 misfortune to subjects to have their prince subordinate to an 
 overlord, because he might enforce the reasonable principles 
 which might not otherwise prevail. 
 
 Justi argues that the present status quo of some hundred 
 and twenty ruling princes was regarded by the princes them- 
 selves as synonymous with the happiness of Europe; but he 
 argued that the personal preferences of these one hundred 
 and twenty are of relatively little moment (II, 246). 
 
 This essay tends to raise the suspicion that Justi was much 
 more of a skeptic in his early manhood about the prevailing 
 type of government than he found it expedient to remain. He 
 very explicitly declares that the curse of Germany is its multi- 
 tude of independent princes (II, 257). 
 
 The last 167 pages of Vol. II (i. e., 406-572) are devoted 
 to a technically very important monograph on causes of the 
 debasement of the currency, and means of removing the evil. 
 The view of gold and silver money which Justi expresses (II, 
 4276.) is essentially sound. The heading of 16 is: "The 
 supreme power cannot arbitrarily fix the price of gold and 
 silver." Again (22), he says: "The conditions of European 
 states make gold and silver necessary as the material of 
 money." There were, just before Justi's time, "silver cam- 
 paigns" in Germany. It was claimed that the currency evils
 
 47 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 were due to the fact of the unfair ratio of gold to silver, while 
 the ratio established by other nations did not correspond. 
 An act of the Empire in 1737 fixed the ratio at 15-1*5- to I - The 
 ratio in England and most other countries at the same time 
 was 14^ to i (II, 468; vide II, 544 ff.). 
 
 Justi makes the coinage right a consequence of sovereignty 
 over mines (II, 472-86). From Vol. Ill we gather the follow- 
 ing: First, a passage in the second paper (p. 23): 
 
 To be rich is to possess in abundance all that is demanded for 
 the needs and 'comforts of human life, just as he who can procure 
 for hmself in sufficiency the comforts of life is a well-to-do man. 
 [Wohlhabender]. According to the foregoing concept, a rich state 
 is the one which has within itself superabundant provision for all 
 the needs and comforts of life for a dense population. A well-to-do 
 or opulent state is one which produces an adequate quantity of the 
 goods which a dense population requires for its needs and comforts 
 (III, 26). 
 
 In the following pages Justi explains at length that money 
 is not merely the symbol of goods, but that it is itself a "ware." 
 "Gold and silver are in a certain sense necessary as money 
 only in trade with foreign peoples" (III, 31). 
 
 If a land possesses only one sort of wares, viz., gold and silver, 
 in superabundance, the surplus must be enormous if all the needs 
 and comforts are to be supplied by exchange for it to such an extent 
 that the gold and silver country will be properly called rich. Of 
 course in such case the price of gold and silver in the country would 
 
 be very low The foreign nations which supplied other goods 
 
 in exchange for these metals would make large profits, the metals 
 would go into the foreign lands, while no surplus of goods would 
 remain in their place to make the land rich. This is the case with 
 Spanish America (III, 34). 
 
 Another consequence of the supposed conditions is that such a 
 land is very thinly populated (III, 35). 
 
 All this sufficiently proves, in my opinion, that a state which 
 produces a surplus of only gold and silver, but not of other goods
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 473 
 
 demanded for the needs and comforts of life, can never be called 
 rich. On the other hand a state is always to be regarded as rich 
 which itself produces these goods in abundance. It possesses the 
 true riches of nature, which are much superior to those fanciful riches 
 which arise from the silent conventions of men. It possesses the 
 essential and the thing itself, and needs not to trouble itself about 
 the symbols of the same. It is quite independent of other nations, 
 and need fear no unfortunate consequences if its commerce with 
 them is cut off. Indeed, if it pleases such a state, it can terminate 
 all trade with other peoples, and enjoy by itself all happiness which 
 a wise government can procure. 
 
 We may even assert that such a state would be truly rich, if not 
 a pound of gold and silver were to be found in it; and such a state 
 would be able to continue all its connection and trade with neigh- 
 boring nations. This appears to be a paradox, because gold and 
 silver are necessary, particularly on account of foreign trade, and 
 the relative wealth as compared with other states has always been 
 regarded of great importance. Yet, since I have considered the 
 matter more carefully, I find that what I here affirm is strictly correct. 
 
 If it is presupposed that such a state produces in superabundance 
 all the goods pertaining to the needs and comforts of life, there will 
 certainly be many in the number which the neighboring nations 
 do not have in such abundance, which they must constantly seek 
 in the state in question. It is natural that such a state, which itself 
 satisfies all the needs and comforts of its people, requires few wares 
 from other peoples, and hence must have the balance of trade in 
 its favor, so that it has to pay little to other nations. Now let us 
 assume that such a state has no money in circulation, but only paper. 
 Sure enough! This paper, as the sole representative symbol for 
 which the wares of this state can be exchanged, will be eagerly sought 
 by the neighboring nations. It is so untrue that this paper will pass 
 at a lower value than real money, that in proportion to profit antici- 
 pated a premium will be paid for the paper above the value of the 
 gold that it represents. This is a natural and familiar experience 
 with all paper money and bills of exchange of a land to which neigh- 
 boring nations must pay more than they collect. Both the govern- 
 ment and the merchants and subjects of this state will accordingly
 
 474 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 rlo the same and more with their paper than if they used gold and 
 silver coins in their transactions with other nations (III, 36 ft.)- 
 
 The third paper in Vol. Ill contains a translation of the 
 letter alleged to have been written by Colbert to Louis XIV 
 in 1672, and first published in the Guardian. It has a scheme 
 of reasons why the French monarch could not subdue the 
 Netherlands. On the general question of the true power of 
 states, the essay premises: The state is not powerful because 
 of extensive territories (pp. 57 ff.); nor because of population 
 alone (pp. 60 if.); nor because of territories, plus population, 
 plus riches (pp. 62 ff.); nor even because of invincible armies 
 (pp. 65 ff.), with frequent and strong fortifications (pp. 73 ff.). 
 
 Then the positive doctrine follows: 
 
 The true strength and j>ower of a state rests entirely upon the 
 wisdom and completeness \Vollkommcnheit] of the government 
 (p. 74). This theorem involves very much. It means not only 
 that the whole correlation and fundamental constitution of the stale 
 i.i H'K'd; but the wisdom of the government must display itself in all 
 
 parts of the civic body; and it must neglect no kind of affairs 
 
 A slate will always be powerful in the degree in which its govern- 
 ment is completely organized [eingericklct] and wisely exercised; 
 and of two states, equal to each other in population and riches, that 
 one will always overcome the other the government of which is the 
 wiser and more complete (p. 74). 
 
 The development or justification of the theorem, which 
 Justi says will be new to many, is virtually a glorification of 
 cameralism as the technique of a wise and complete govern- 
 ment; although Justi admits that all lands are not to be gov- 
 erned in the same way. 
 
 In the sixth essay of the same volume, Justi schedules the 
 services of religion to the state. In brief these are: (i) It 
 may stimulate the citizens to cultivate the soil, and to increase 
 the population. In this respect Catholicism is pronounced 
 least efficient (p. 147); (2) it may promote diligence and
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 475 
 
 skill (p. 151); (3) it may promote civic virtues and stimulate 
 people to practice them (161). 
 
 Justi proceeds to consider the relation of Christianity in 
 particular to these services (pp. 169 ff.), and he does not think 
 that this religion is well fitted to be the dominant force in the 
 state because: 
 
 It is entirely heavenly, entirely spiritual, entirely devoted to God, 
 entirely withdrawn from this temporal life, and dedicated alone to 
 the future life. It is all too passive, patient, humble, with respect 
 to the earthly life, and so strongly and openly despises everything 
 which constitutes the welfare of citizens, that a civic constitution 
 could not be maintained among other powers by true Christians 
 only (p. 170). 
 
 The first paper in the second division of the volume, a 
 prospectus of the economic courses to be offered at Gottingen, 
 is dated June 20, 1755. It has the following variation of 
 scientific classification : 
 
 The sciences either contribute something directly to the discharge 
 of our duties and the improvement of our external condition or 
 they serve those purposes indirectly, and put us in a condition better 
 to fulfil our duties; or they are merely capable of amusing our 
 immortal soul (p. 222). 
 
 The economic and cameralistic sciences are those which teach 
 management on a large scale with the means of the state, or which 
 put us in possession of the measures by which the general means of 
 the republic may be preserved, increased, and reasonably applied to 
 its ultimate purpose of happiness (p. 223). 
 
 One of the impressions which the paper makes, from our 
 point of view, is that Justi was beginning to increase his atten- 
 tion to the economic emphasis, and second, that the presump- 
 tion of the prime and necessary first claim of the state was 
 still decisive. 
 
 Justi urges that the cameralistic sciences belong in the first 
 of the three groups just distinguished. He calls attention to
 
 476 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the lively movement at the time in favor of getting these sub- 
 jects taught in the universities (p. 226); and he repeats his 
 frequent reflection that, until recently, the learned were simply 
 engaged in exchanging esoteric views with one another, chiefly 
 in a language not understood by the people, instead of doing 
 something that would be of service to the general good. 1 
 
 In the sixth paper of the second division there is discussion 
 of problems of state revenues with respect to different circum- 
 stances of states and forms of government. In the seventh 
 paper an open secret of the cameralistic regime is confessed in 
 this wise: 
 
 The distribution and direction of the means of private persons 
 belong, to be sure, among the subjects which demand the special 
 care of the government. If the government could bring it about 
 that no citizen or resident should become entirely inpoverished, it 
 would thereby perform a service of the highest importance to the 
 welfare of the state. Ancient governments looked out for this. 
 Modern governments have neglected it almost completely. It has 
 been taken for granted that it was entirely a matter of indifference 
 for the state whose hands held the means and the wealth, if they 
 were only present and remained in the country. The contrary is 
 true wisdom. 
 
 Special and peculiar measures are demanded of the government 
 in the case of movable and immovable wealth respectively. Movable 
 goods are fruits of diligence and skill (p. 343). It is wisdom for the 
 state to add its encouragement in every way to stimulate diligence 
 and skill. Immovable goods, on the other hand, belong to the total 
 means of the state, and the means of a state is the chief ground of 
 its energies, its strength, and its power [Krajte, Starke und Macht}. 
 
 i An explanation which occurs on p. 343 confirms and partially 
 explains a detail of our knowledge of Justi's personal history, viz.: "Sr. 
 Konigliche Majestat von Grossbritannien und Churfurstl. Durchl. zu 
 Braunschweig-Luneburg haben allergnadigst geruhet mich in diesem 
 beriihmten Musensitze als Dero Oberpoliceycommisarium zu bestellen, 
 etc., .... zugleich .... Erlaubniss ertheilet in den Oeconomischen 
 und Cameral Wisscnschaften .... Vorlesungen zu halten."
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 477 
 
 It cannot thus be a matter of indifference to the state whether this 
 portion of its total means, which is in the hands of private persons, 
 is in good or bad condition, or whether it is well or ill employed. 
 .... The use and the good condition of private estates, however, 
 rests to a great extent upon the direction of a wise government over 
 the same, and upon the proper proportion and distribution of private 
 
 estates in the country If the movable goods belong, so to 
 
 speak, to the whole world, and circulate from one country into 
 another, the immovable goods are the real fixed and assured prop- 
 erty [Eigenthum] of the state. They are the terra firma [Grund und 
 Boden] of the Volk, because they belong to the country which pecul- 
 iarly pertains to the total Volk (p. 358).' 
 
 As a primary principle, government must see that lands shall 
 be in the possession of those who will live on them and cultivate 
 them (p. 359). It is also desirable that the peasants shall have a 
 proprietary tenure (p. 362). This will tend to increase the rural 
 population (p. 366). 
 
 In the eighth paper in the second division Justi tries to make 
 his views about population as emphatic as possible. He says 
 
 (P- 379): 
 
 If one should ask me whether the chief consideration of a genuine 
 and wise cameralist to which, according to the general principle 
 of the happiness of the state, his chief care must be directed, and 
 back to which he must refer in all his measures and operations 
 could be expressed with a single word and concept, I would without 
 a moment's hesitation cry out the word POPULATION. Yes! Truly! 
 POPULATION must be the apple of his eye, as compared with all other 
 measures. 2 
 
 1 The form of expression in the last sentence has a bearing on the 
 sense in which Justi thought of Volk, i. e., not in the ordinary modern 
 distributive sense, but as a more artificial collective concept. 
 
 2 Vide Grundriss der Policey-Wisstnschaft, p. 77 (vide above, p. 444), 
 and von Mohl, Gesch. u. Lit. d. Staatswis., Ill, 471. Von Mohl quotes 
 the second edition. I have referred to the corresponding passage in the 
 third. It is very evident that von Mohl had practically no knowledge 
 of the setting of the doctrine of population in Justi's system. In fact,
 
 478 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Many camcralists who glance at this monograph will certainly 
 not have expected this word. If they had been asked for such a 
 leading concept, they would certainly have called out in the loudest 
 voice: MONKY! REVENUES! "PLUS!" or something of that sort. 
 Most of them are so entirely convinced that the whole reason for 
 their existence is to bring together MONEY, or revenues, that all 
 the philosophers in the world could not convince them otherwise. 
 I am not now writing for these people. I will at this point attempt 
 to convince only those cameralists who, along with a good head, have 
 also a good heart, that money and revenues should at least be only 
 their second great aim, if they are not to fail of both population and 
 revenues (p. 379). 
 
 Someone will perhaps reply that my theorem might lead too 
 far. It might be possible for a land to be very well populated, and 
 to have a surplus of all goods required for the need and comfort of 
 human life, while still lacking money; or gold and silver, and con- 
 sequently to be poor in comparison with other states, as a result of 
 which it would be exposed to various harmful consequences. We 
 must therefore conclude that riches in gold and silver, if not more 
 necessary than population, are still equally necessary, and thus 
 deserve equal attention. 
 
 I reply: If a country possesses a surplus of all sorts of goods, 
 and therewith the true riches, there is scarcely a possibility that it 
 can suffer a lack of the representative signs of goods, namely gold 
 and silver. The signs automatically follow the thing which they 
 represent. The surplus of goods in this country will stimulate other 
 nations to exchange the same among us for the representative signs, 
 because the goods will be cheap among us, and the quantity of gold in 
 the country will presently be in proportion to the quantity of money. 1 
 
 he qualified it sufficiently to make von MohPs criticism gratuitous. He 
 no more believed that population could be fed in unlimited numbers 
 than Malthus did. For the practical purposes of the states in whose 
 interest he was elaborating a technique, population was the first consid- 
 eration, until, as he indicated in Staatswirthschaft, population should 
 reach three, four, or six times the number at his time. He never 
 formulated the more general Malthusian problem of population. 
 1 The last word is apparently a misprint for goods.
 
 JUSTI'S CAMERALISTIC MISCELLANIES 479 
 
 We have no instance of a country with a great surplus of goods, 
 which was still poor in money, provided that such a country carried 
 on commerce with other peoples. On the other hand, we have 
 examples of countries which possessed the richest silver and gold 
 deposits, and still were very poor in the goods of life, and thus in the 
 true riches. The representative signs at once followed the thing, 
 they entered the country which had the surplus of the goods of life, 
 and such a (gold-producing) country remained poor in spite of its 
 gold mines. 
 
 Justi's opponents in the above argument are men of straw 
 so far as evidence appears in the cameralistic books. He 
 must have had in mind cameralists of the bureau, men of 
 affairs rather than of theory, who wanted policies to be shaped 
 according to the contrary hypothesis. In the next paragraph 
 (p. 385) Justi continues: 
 
 But suppose that a well-populated land, supplied with a surplus 
 of goods, has not an adequate proportion of the "representative 
 signs" in gold and silver. This would be a very slight disadvantage. 
 In the country itself it would have not the -slightest harmful effect. 
 In respect to domestic circulation [Umlauf] the proportion of money 
 in the country is wholly indifferent. If the land is only well populated 
 and has a surplus of goods, exchange will be as lively with little money 
 as with much. Indeed, it may be dispensed with entirely. Such a 
 country could, without money, have all the happiness and strength 
 of which it is capable. 1 
 
 Then Justi goes on to say (p. 386) that of course the quan- 
 tity of money becomes important so soon as we consider rela- 
 tions with other states. That is, it is important chiefly when 
 a state is in an aggressive attitude toward others, and its policy 
 is to harm them. 
 
 1 This passage is notable as proof that Justi was not the sort of 
 mercantilist described as the traditional type. The naivete of his ideas 
 about the relative importance of a circulating medium is to be noted, but 
 it does not immediately concern our purpose, except that it was a very 
 natural incident of his predominantly administrative conception of the 
 state.
 
 480 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The true relative defensive strength of a country depends always 
 upon the larger population, other things being equal; although the 
 relative aggressive power depends more upon wealth in gold and 
 silver; or at least the relative wealth has in this connection the most 
 effect. 
 
 In the following pages (pp. 387 ff.) Justi resumes his main 
 line of argument on population, and elaborates rules for 
 encouraging a high birth rate. These are: (i) Means of earn- 
 ing a living must be made abundant; (2) the government 
 must not be oppressive; (3) the laws must encourage marriage; 
 (4) the chief means of promotion is that the rights of the pater 
 familias and of the husband, namely the lordship over his 
 house and his wife, which so undoubtedly belongs to him 
 according to the law of nature and of civic society, should be 
 restored (p. 393 ; vide Natur und Wesen der Staaten, 8. Haupt- 
 stuck, 240, 241) ; x (5) the state must exercise great care over 
 the education of poor children, and the training of children 
 in general (p. 395). 
 
 The remaining papers in the collection are so strictly tech- 
 nical that they add nothing to our knowledge of Justi's more 
 fundamental reasoning. 
 
 * It is more than possible that the first Frau Justi may have had a 
 mind of her own at this point, and that the domestic troubles of the 
 house of Justi may have turned on this issue.
 
 CHAPTER XVIII 
 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 
 ("INTRODUCTION") 
 
 The reasons for treating Sonnenfels as the last in the camera- 
 list ic series must be reserved for a later volume. More con- 
 ventional usage extends the present group to the time of Rau. 1 
 This summary measure of convenience is possible only by 
 ignoring the essential distinctions of purpose which distinguish 
 theorists of successive periods. 
 
 Roscher divides the history of German economic theory 
 into three great periods: First, the theologico-humanistic, 
 from the early humanists to the end of the Thirty Years' War; 
 second, the " polizeilich-cameralistische" to which no date of 
 expiration is assigned; third, the scientific, for which no dis- 
 tinct birthday is designated, but the implication is that it begins 
 with the favorable reception of physiocratic doctrines in Ger- 
 many, that is, during the last quarter of the eighteenth century. 
 As divisions of this sort are mere uncritical superficialities at 
 best, we need waste no time upon them, after pointing out 
 that they are worthless for purposes of precision. They magnify 
 accidentals, instead of penetrating first to the purposes which 
 are the ultimate marks of distinction between theorists, and 
 second, to the methodologies which are the variants of their 
 procedure. 
 
 If we compare Roscher's main analysis with the titles of 
 his subdivisions, we find that he falls back upon a collection of 
 uncorrelated characterizations after all. For example, he treats 
 Dithmar, Gasser, Zincke, and Justi, with others of lesser note 
 or of equal importance if studied primarily in relation to their 
 proper groups, under the subtitle, "the older eclectics of the 
 
 1 Lehrbuch der politischen Oeconomie, 1826, etc. 
 
 481
 
 482 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 eighteenth century" 1 He makes a subdivision under the 
 "scientific period," for Sonnenfels, with two or three others 
 of trifling consequence thrown in to keep up appearances, 
 with the label, "the later absolutistic eclectics." 2 This all 
 amounts to the veriest parody of analysis. Roscher gravely 
 declares that in the period from the predominance of Wolff 
 to the influence of Kant all German philosophy was eclecticism, 
 and at the same time national economy, from the end of the 
 Seven Years' War to the outbreak of the French Revolution, 
 was predominantly eclectic. We should say rather that 
 "national economy" was still what it had been for two hundred 
 years, an increasingly circumstantial and subdivided technology 
 of management of the state, considered as the patriarchate of 
 the prince, and that it was no more eclectic in principle than it 
 had been from the beginning. It is always uncertain whether 
 Roscher's term " Nationalokonomik" amounts to anything 
 more than a synonym for Justi's " Staatswirthschaft." If 
 Roscher meant to imply that there was in Germany, at the 
 period designated, an economic science of any sort differen- 
 tiated from the general system of civic management, in which 
 the power of the government was the decisive aim, no evidence 
 appears that the wish was not father to the thought. In this 
 period, and notably in Sonnenfels, a new spirit is evident. 
 The more obvious and extreme corollaries of quasi-absolutism 
 are challenged, indirectly at any rate, by sentimental rather 
 than formulated variants consisting of higher valuations of 
 the claims of citizens as such, in contrast with the older pre- 
 sumption that whatever the supposed good of the government 
 demanded must as a matter of course prescribe the terms of 
 individuals' rights. 
 
 Yet Roscher is correct in a way when he continues: 
 In such a time criticism is far from serious examination of funda- 
 mental ideas. It is rather busy rubbing down the sharp points, 
 ' Roscher, op. cit., pp. 430 ff. * Op. cit., pp. 533 ff.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 483 
 
 reconciling petty contradictions; that is, it is essentially eclectic. 
 Before the discussion of the Smithian system, all the German teachers 
 of public management [VolksTvirthschaft], the apostles of physiocracy 
 and the historical-conservative opponents of the new spirit excepted, 
 may be classed in two groups absolutistic and liberal eclectics, the 
 former attached to the two major German powers, especially Austria, 
 the latter to the medium and petty states of North Germany, par- 
 ticularly the Hanse cities. 
 
 For more than two generations Austrian national economy was 
 dominated by Joseph von Sonnenfels (1733-1817). He undertook 
 his professorship of Finanz- und Policeiwissenscfuift at Vienna in 
 1763. His significant literary influence began still earlier, and a 
 little later his political importance. The latter constantly grew under 
 Joseph II. In the troubled times of the French Revolution it encoun- 
 tered opposition, but on the whole it maintained itself so long that 
 until the publication of his own handbook in 1845 Kudler followed 
 the tradition of making Sonnenfels' works the basis of his lectures. 
 This, to be sure, does not speak well for the intellectual produc- 
 tivity of Austria, and the fact is that the country had to rely largely 
 on thinkers from the other German states. 
 
 Sonnenfels was the grandson of a Berlin rabbi. His father 
 moved to Austria, submitted to baptism, and assumed the name 
 Sonnenfels. He was a pioneer of German culture in Austria, and 
 some of his experiences remind one of the reception which Adam 
 Smith found in Scotland for the Oxford English which he had acquired 
 during his university residence. 1 
 
 Of Sonnenfels the younger, Roscher further says: 
 
 His general political view is a theoretical and insecurely founded 
 absolutism, mitigated by the sort of philanthropic ideas which were 
 prevalent in the second half of the eighteenth century. In a mono- 
 graph dedicated to Maria Theresia (1771) and entitled "On Love 
 of the Fatherland," he has much to say about monarchy, aristocracy, 
 and democracy, but with express adherence to the words of Pope, 
 
 For forms of government let fools contest, 
 The best administered is the best. 
 
 ' Op. cit., p. 534, n.
 
 44 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 He explains the origin of the state in the sense of Rousseau, and the 
 mottoes of all three volumes of his chief work were taken from 
 Rousseau. 1 At the same time he declares that the natural condition 
 of men is the social condition, and following Rousseau's own words, 
 to be sure, he compared the state with the organism of the human 
 body. Meanwhile, because "irresistibility is the most essential trait 
 of the sovereign power, the governments nominated by the aggregate 
 will are as unlimited as the will was whose .place they have taken." 
 Religion itself is by no means a positive limitation of the will of the 
 ruler. It is conceived rather quite in the sense of Joseph II, as a 
 guiding thread in the hand of the ruler, which the latter should never 
 neglect, and which was especially necessary in dealing with ordinary 
 people. Freethinking is also politically a crime, and there is no ground 
 for the fear that attachment to the laws of society could ever harm 
 religion and morality. Sonnenfels calls the censorship of books 
 one of the most necessary police regulations. He urges the shorten- 
 ing of processes before the courts, and the payment of advocates 
 by the state: thus impressing the most natural and expert organ of 
 the opposition into the service of the government. A favorite idea 
 of Sonnenfels was that in criminal cases the penalty of ascertained 
 guilt should be determined by the vote of the majority erf the judges; 
 the question of guilt or innocence however, as well as of the mitigating 
 or aggravating circumstances, should be settled only by a unanimous 
 vote. In practice this proposition would in most cases simply lead 
 to the release of the accused. 
 
 On the other hand, Sonnenfels gained a reputation in Austria 
 for his efforts to abolish torture.* This reform was decided in 1775 
 by the publication of a tract which was at the same time in defiance 
 of a decree of 1769 against "all too great freedom in writing," the 
 
 1 This is only partially true of the fifth edition, which I have used. 
 Roscher cites the third. The motto of the fifth edition of Vol. I is from 
 Cicero, De divin. i-iii, and on the page opposite the beginning of the 
 General Introduction, is a paragraph from Richard Hey, Observations 
 on the Nature of Civil Liberty. The motto of the third volume is from 
 Horace; while only the second takes its motto from Rousseau. 
 
 * Among the more creditable facts about Becher is his adhesion 
 to the same view. (Vide Roscher, loc. cit., p. 284, n. a.)
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 485 
 
 same being occasioned by his publications on the death penalty 
 and torture. Sonnenfels also opposed treatment of the pensions of 
 civic servants as charity. Again his curt demand that every obso- 
 lete law should be repealed, ran counter to a well-known maximum of 
 despotism according to which the ruler is never to admit that he has 
 erred, and reserves the choice between various fundamental prin- 
 ciples in dealing with a specific case. That in the case of every law 
 the purposes of the law-giver should be discussed so as to protect 
 right principles, is much more emphatically urged by Sonnenfels 
 than by Justi. 
 
 At the same time, it is characteristic of Sonnenfels' absolutism 
 to be more liberal at the expense of private rights than at the expense 
 of governmental power. Thus in the case of the obligations at- 
 tached to peasant holdings of the soil, he speaks, for example, of 
 the ancient imprescriptible human rights, in contrast with the tra- 
 ditional rights of possession. 1 
 
 The foregoing passage from Roscher has been cited not for 
 its value as an interpretation of Sonnenfels, but as a commen- 
 tary on Roscher's use of the term eclectic. The details recited 
 furnish a content for the word as he employed it. This usage 
 is to be distinguished from another which to some minds at 
 least is more appropriate. That is, we understand by eclecti- 
 cism an attempt to construct a system of thought by combina- 
 tion of two or more systems which are held by their extreme 
 adherents to be mutually exclusive, as for instance the Kantian 
 psychology and the Benthamite ethics. a According to Roscher's 
 specifications, he meant by eclecticism a certain degree of inde- 
 pendence in deciding whether traditional conclusions about 
 details necessarily follow from principles still regarded as funda- 
 mental. It is in the latter sense alone that Sonnenfels can be 
 called an eclectic. It is not true that he was a mediator between 
 the traditional philosophy of quasi-absolutism and a rival 
 political philosophy. It is true that his attempts to mitigate the 
 
 1 Vide Handlung, 5te Auft., p. 53; vide below, p: 549. 
 
 * Vide Century Dictionary, title " Eclectic," II.
 
 486 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 consequences of quasi-absolutism must be read at this dis- 
 tance as clear signs that a new thought-era was in the making. 
 The times were ripening for a system of political philosophy 
 which would openly challenge tradition. Specific valuations 
 were forming in men's minds which would presently amount 
 to repudiation of the old general theory. The reconstruction, 
 however, in the case of men like Sonnenfels, had gone only 
 so far as to produe a half-conscious conflict between the cogni- 
 tive and the emotional sides of political judgments. To put 
 it in paradox, Sonnenfels thought as an absolutist, but he felt 
 as a democrat. Like every other paradox, this is a very loose 
 statement. It more correctly characterizes the brcaking-up 
 process of which Sonnenfels was an index than any label which 
 purports to assign him a precise position in a schematic classi- 
 fication of theorists. The justice of this dissent from Roscher 
 will appear as we deal directly with Sonnenfels. 
 
 The work which is most important for our purpose, as 
 reflecting, so to speak, a fin de sikcle phase of cameralism, is 
 in three volumes, entitled, Grundsatze der Policey, Handlung 
 und Finanz. 1 The volumes are closely related, but each is 
 a distinct unit, devoted respectively Vol. I to Policey, Vol. II 
 to Handlung, Vol. Ill to Finanz. According to the author's 
 explanation in the Preface to Vol. I, the books were what we 
 should now call syllabi of the courses which he gave in the uni- 
 sity at Vienna on the corresponding subjects. This description 
 must be commented upon further in connection with the 
 several volumes. 
 
 A single observation should precede analysis of these books, 
 viz.: One feels in passing from Justi to Sonnenfels that a 
 watershed has been crossed, and that one is within the borders 
 
 1 The title-page has the further legend, "Zu detri Leilfaden des 
 politischen Studiums." The center of the page is occupied by a vignette 
 of Montesquieu, in itself a critical index of first-rate importance. The 
 first edition was published in 1765. I have used only the fifth edition, 1787.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 487 
 
 of another territory. Speaking literally, the mere fact that 
 Sonnenfels makes the conscious attempt at modernism in- 
 volved in adopting a corrected orthography makes the reader 
 aware of a transition. Typographically these volumes are 
 not an improvement upon the mechanical style of Justi's 
 publications. In their contents one detects a somewhat freer 
 spirit. Judging wholly from the internal evidence, one would 
 by no means rank Sonnenfels as Justi's equal in intellectual 
 strength. The later writer appears to have been of a more 
 receptive than creative type, but although they were in part 
 contemporaries the impressions which molded him contained 
 elements which were less active in Justi's world. If one were 
 called upon to defend this estimate, it might be said that while 
 Justi seems to have been intellectually more virile, he seems 
 also to have been less open to persuasion by the comparison of 
 moral values. Justi's personality betrays some of the signs of 
 quasi-absolutism at its worst. Sonnenfels shows affinities for 
 something superior to quasi-absolutism at its best. In spite of 
 this contrast, we should go astray if we followed the example 
 of Roscher in affixing a distinctive label to Sonnenfels. We 
 cannot make such men fit into any schematic classification. 
 They show that a new type was in the process of evolution. 
 They do not quite correspond with any general description or 
 definition. They are not entirely consistent with themselves. 
 They are partly of one tendency and partly of another. They 
 show survivals of traits which are logically incompatible with 
 the presence of other traits, yet the incongruities exist. His- 
 torical veracity consists in reporting them just as they were, 
 without attempting to conventionalize them in the image of 
 any conceptual type whatsoever. 
 
 Turning to Vol. I, Policey, we find at once in the Preface 
 literary symptoms rather favorably contrasted with those 
 observed in Justi. Sonnenfels begins by explaining why 
 he finds himself obliged to add a textbook to those already in
 
 488 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 existence. Some of them he thinks are too comprehensive, 
 others too narrow in their scope. At the same time he names 
 none of these works at this point, and we are obliged to search 
 the body of the book for desirable information about his con- 
 nection with other writers. 
 
 The Preface to the fifth edition discusses the criticism of a 
 reviewer that the Importance of rewards as means of securing 
 good civil service haA been overlooked in the earlier editions. 
 Sonncnfels replies that he did not forget the subject, but that 
 he intentionally omitted rewards from his schedule of means 
 of obtaining good government. He urges, however, that the 
 best way to stimulate a high quality of service is to make 
 distinction the prize of excellence. Rewards of any other 
 sort are really premiums to the unworthy who do not become 
 worthy in return for such payments. He contends that civil 
 servants should be punished for neglect of duty, but should 
 not receive premiums as means of making them perform the 
 duties that belong to their positions, and he supports his view 
 by citing Hume without locating the quotation. 
 
 This first volume contains 552 pages, of about 125 words 
 each, and is divided into 432 sections. As a rule, one of these 
 sections is a succinct statement of the substance of the author's 
 view upon the matter to which it refers, and elaboration rather 
 than addition was attempted in the lectures. The point of 
 view is partially indicated in the opening sections of the "gen- 
 eral introduction," 1 viz.: 
 
 The isolated human l>eing is not the human being in the state 
 of nature; his condition would be a condition of constant helplessness. 
 But he feels his lack. He feels that he is capable of remedying the 
 
 This "general introduction " occupies forty-nine pages. It includes 
 the chapter on computing the population. It was evidently intended 
 to introduce the three volumes as a whole. It is followed (p. 50) by an 
 introduction which relates specifically to Policey, the subject-matter 
 of the first volume.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 489 
 
 lack, of improving his condition. Reason, which distinguishes him 
 from the beasts, enables him to perceive the means by which he may 
 reach an improved condition. This means is socialization with his 
 kind [Vergesellschaftung mit seines Gleichen]. The natural condi- 
 tion of man is thus the condition of society: the domestic, the con- 
 jugal, the paternal society, are so many steps whereby he comes 
 nearer to the great society, which includes all others, and which, 
 since the minor groupings direct their gaze toward the weal of the 
 separate members, has adopted as its aim the best good of all societies. * 
 
 * In a note Sonnenfels comments: "The notion of the isolated human 
 being is perhaps merely a literary abstraction. Man is always in society, 
 and as Ferguson, in his Essays on the History of Civil Society, acutely 
 observes, 'a savage caught somewhere in a forest, no more proves that 
 man by nature lives alone, than a sheep straying in a forest would prove 
 that sheep do not flock together.' " 
 
 In the Preface to the third volume (5th ed.) the author says: " I have 
 cited only those books that I have read, and of which I can give assur- 
 ance that it will pay to consult or read them." The books which he 
 explicitly mentions will be carefully noted. He seldom locates the pas- 
 sages to which he refers, and I am unable to decide whether the remark 
 quoted applies to all three volumes, or whether he intended it to include 
 authors cited in this casual way. He later refers to Smith's Wealth of 
 Nations. Although a German translation of the Wealth of Nations bears 
 the date 1776, the same year in which the original was published, I am not 
 sure that the version appeared as early as the date would seem to indicate; 
 and I have no conclusive reason for believing that at the time of making his 
 first printed allusion to Smith's work Sonnenfels knew it except by title. 
 If he had actually read Smith and Ferguson in 1787, the leaven was 
 working in Germany rather earlier than is usually supposed. Even 
 Ricardo did not discover the Wealth of Nations till long after that date. 
 
 The phrase "so many steps, etc.," might be turned into evidence 
 that Sonennfels repudiated the "social contract" idea, and held the 
 evolutionary view of the origin of human society. A monograph recently 
 conceived ii) Berlin and published in Leipzig employs exegesis of this 
 sort to read into Adam Smith and Adam Ferguson a considerable cata- 
 logue of sociological concepts which their philosophy had never dreamed 
 of, viz.: Hermann Huth, Sociale und individualistische Auffassung im 
 18. Jahrhundert, vornehmlich bei Adam Smith und Adam Ferguson. 
 Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Sociologie. If Sonnenfels had consistently
 
 490 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Sec. 2 continues: 
 
 The great society is the state. The transition into the same 
 has given the members a new name, has put them into new relation- 
 ships. The human beings have become citizens, beings who, through 
 the nature of their self-chosen (sicf) status, have now, as parts, their 
 relationship to a whole, are united as members in a moral body. 
 The effect of this unification is unity of ultimate purpose, unity of 
 will, unity of force. 
 
 The three following sections expand the three principal 
 concepts in the last sentence. Thus (3) : 
 
 Unity of ultimate purpose, or of welfare, of the best, which now is 
 called the best good of the community das gemeinschaftliche Beste] 
 whereby the best of the single member, that is, private advantage, 
 remains constantly subordinated to the former, and cannot be other- 
 wise brought into the account than in so far as it constitutes a part 
 of the common best of the whole body. In case their private advantage 
 could not be reconciled with "the common best," the former must 
 necessarily be subordinated to the latter. Fortunately, however, in 
 the precise sense, there can be no thought of a contradiction between 
 the true permanent private welfare and the general welfare. For 
 upon closer examination it will always appear, either that what is 
 regarded as private advantage ceases to be such so soon as it works 
 in opposition to the general advantage; or frequently that a supposed 
 
 limitation of the common weal is not actually such The 
 
 welfare of the parts is based upon the welfare of the whole; but at 
 the same time the welfare of the whole springs only from the welfare 
 of the parts. 1 
 
 applied our logic, some of his phrases would have carried him nearer to 
 Darwin than to Rousseau. But !! 
 
 The next section contains typical evidence that interpretation of an 
 author by phrases isolated from the general tenor of his thought is impos- 
 sible. 
 
 1 Again, if we might credit the eighteenth century with the associa- 
 tions of the twentieth, we should say that here was a profession of the 
 most modern democratic political philosophy. What we actually find 
 here is evidence that valuations were coming into vogue which were 
 logically incompatible with the prevailing quasi-absolulistic political
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 491 
 
 Sonnenfels continues (4): 
 
 Unity of the will, which, in case something is involved whose 
 effects extend to community interests, suspends all contradiction, 
 upon the principle that no one can at the same time will and not will, 
 and makes the separate will of the individual subordinate to the 
 community decision. 1 
 
 In 5 the explanation continues: 
 
 Unity of force. In so far as the individual energies are necessary 
 for the attainment of the ultimate end of the community, they 
 should be exerted in no way except that toward which the community 
 energy is devoted. Whoever withdraws his share of this energy, in 
 case the common ends require a given quantity of force, leaves the 
 
 philosophy, and that they were accelerating the motion of the social 
 process toward retirement of the more arbitrary philosophy. 
 
 The perception had not yet been reached that this interdependence 
 of private and public good demanded a different means of adjusting in 
 practice the claims of the co-operating factors. That is, the rulers still 
 decided for the people what was for the people's good. This technique 
 presupposed that the rulers were not only superior in wisdom, but that 
 they were disinterested judges. Whether the former assumption was valid 
 or not, the latter was directly contrary to fact. The rulers were to a 
 considerable extent competitors with the citizens for things desired by 
 both. That the former should be perpetual arbiters about relations in 
 which they were perpetually interested parties, was the essential fallacy 
 of the old regime. I discover no evidence whatever that Sonnenfels 
 was aware of this weakness in quasi-absolutism. Until theorists arrived 
 at this perception, they were intellectually with the old re'gime, however 
 symptomatic their emotions may have been of a changing order. 
 
 1 Again the approximateness of Sonnenfels' philosophy must be 
 pointed out. The alleged principle was thoroughly modern in its abstract 
 statement. It proves to be still archaic when interpreted by the implica- 
 tions which clung to it. The crucial matter was to get a technique which 
 could properly ascertain the social will in contrast with the individual 
 will. The old regime simply seized the power to make the will of certain 
 individuals subvert the will of the overwhelmingly larger number of 
 individuals and count as the will of the society. The essence of quasi- 
 absolutism remained in force in political theories until the full significance 
 of this dilemma was admitted.
 
 49 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 general activity too weak; but if he turns his energy against the 
 general purpose the disadvantage is doubled, because the energy 
 of another person is thereby nullified. 
 
 In the sixth section Sonnenfels distinctly asserts the right 
 of each member of society to take part in deciding what meas- 
 ures should be taken to attain the common ends, and the con- 
 sent of all the members is necessary if this decision is to appear 
 in a law. 
 
 In the seventh section, however, doubt is cast upon the 
 connotations which the generalization had for the author's 
 mind. It seems to be more a historical hypothesis in the 
 sense of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau, than a moral principle 
 by which to test the technique of existing societies. By 
 means of this generalization Sonnenfels accounts for the transi- 
 tion "from the multitude to society, from anarchy to the sim- 
 plest democracy." He goes on to say, however, that confusion 
 must soon have appeared in council, universal agreement 
 must have been impossible. Decisions of some sort were 
 necessary. Out of this practical necessity grew the different 
 forms of government. Then follows (8) enumeration of 
 democracy, aristocracy, and monarchy, with the comment 
 (9) that: 
 
 in these three forms of jzovernrrient nothing essential to society is 
 modified, but merely the form in which the common will expresses 
 itself, i. e., either through the majority or through the elite, or through 
 
 the autocrat Thus, just as the decisions of all were binding 
 
 upon each individual, the same must be the case with the decisions 
 of those who take the place of all. This obligation on the one side 
 implies on the other side the right of compulsion, and irresistibility, 
 and thus the relations between rulers and ruled, between subjects 
 and the supreme power, were more specifically determined. Originally 
 (10) the use of the combined forces was determined by the will 
 of all the citizens. Since now the supreme power combines in itself 
 the community will, its prerogative is likewise to determine how the 
 community energies shall best be used for the common welfare.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 493 
 
 Gratitude is due to Sonnenfels for reducing this reasoning 
 to such a bare skeleton that its most serious dislocation is 
 evident. We can see at a glance, and it is hard to understand 
 why thinkers of Sonnenfels' ability did not perceive, that this 
 was merely an illusive collocation of a generalization about 
 political rights, a hypothesis about historical sequence, and an 
 utterly arbitrary begging of the essential question of fact about 
 the institution of monarchy. This special pleading was a 
 perfunctory excuse for taking quasi-absolutism for granted, 
 and proceeding to inquire how to make the best of it. If each 
 member of society has a right to his share in making up the 
 will of the society, nothing but sheer assertion appears in Son- 
 nenfels' reasoning to justify the conclusion that the monarch 
 must be accepted as vicariously exercising that right for all 
 the citizens, and must be obeyed because his will is virtually 
 the will of all. Thus, in spite of sentiments which make for 
 reconstruction of ideas, Sonnenfels' major premise was the 
 same old impotent makeshift of absolutism, the presumption 
 that royal power summarizes all the fundamental rights of citi- 
 zens, and that it is a political datum back of which our theories 
 of social technique must not pry. 
 
 In 11 Sonnenfels further elaborates his concept "welfare," 
 and it is in this direction that we find evidences of a force that 
 was generating as a variant both of the theory and the prac- 
 tice of quasi-absolutism. While criticism of the social logic 
 summed up in benevolent despotism was not admitted into 
 this type of social science, the concept "welfare" was becoming 
 more intensive and was thus looming up as a factor in the 
 modification of theory and indirectly of action. The syllabus 
 continues: 
 
 The ultimate purpose for the sake of which men enter society is 
 that best which they possess neither enough moral nor physical power 
 to attain alone; which in itself considered is, to be sure, the separate 
 best of each member. Since, however, this separate best is sought
 
 494 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 by each at the same time, and each by promoting the best of the 
 other thereby also confirms his own, it is called the community 
 best. The ultimate purpose of men entering into combination 
 might be expressed therefore as the indi^4dual best; the ultimate 
 purpose of combined men as the general best. In civic societies this 
 best, this ultimate purpose, has been security and convenience of 
 life, which combined constitute the public welfare. 
 
 Security is defined (12) as: 
 
 a condition in which we have nothing to fear. The condition in 
 which the state has nothing to fear is called public security, that 
 in which no citizen has anything Jo fear is called private security. 
 When the state is safe against attacks from without, the condition 
 is called public external security, and if no danger threatens from 
 its own citizens, there exists public internal security. If neither 
 the state, from within nor without, nor the citizens have anything 
 to fear, this fortunate condition is called the general security. 
 
 Tha convenience of life [continues the author in 13] is the facility 
 of providing one's support by diligence. Diligence will find its 
 support the easier the more diversified the gainful occupations. The 
 general convenience of life depends therefore upon diversification 
 of the gainful occupations. 
 
 The general welfare [as explained in 14] cannot be maintained 
 
 without cost The ruler must be provided with revenues, 
 
 which must be in proportion to his dignity. This outlay is made 
 for the best good of all the citizens. It is therefore proper that the 
 expense should be borne by all the citizens, but that it should be 
 drawn from them in a way that will promote the ultimate purpose. 
 
 Thereupon follows the definition (15) : 
 
 From manifold observations and experiences it is possible to 
 refer the various rules through which the general welfare may be 
 maintained, to reliable fundamental principles, and to give them 
 the form of a science, which is Staatswissenschajt in the most com- 
 prehensive sense; that is, the science of maintaining the welfare of 
 
 a state, the science of governing We are convinced that the 
 
 problematical and the variable does not reside in the principles of 
 the science, but in the circumstances and occurrences to which the
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 495 
 
 principles are to be applied. The mere empiricist in politics is 
 therefore as lictle to be regarded as a statesman as the empiricist in 
 the healing art is to be regarded as a physician. 
 
 When Sonnenfels takes care to warn against confounding 
 the practical administrator with the empiricist (16), and 
 when he describes the former as the man who is trained and 
 experienced in applying the rules of Staatswissenschaft to actual 
 conditions, he completes his demonstration that he is dealing 
 with a technology pure and simple. Sonnenfels took for 
 granted a certain general standard of life. He did not go to 
 the trouble of justifying the standard, but he counted on it as 
 a conceded major premise. Then his problem was to set 
 forth the governmental processes by which that standard 
 might be reached. Just as there was no question about the 
 authority of the standard, so there was no inquiry into the 
 assumption that responsibility for maintaining it belonged 
 to the government. In principle, therefore, as we have said 
 above, Sonnenfels was simply one of the series of spokesmen 
 for the dominant regime of quasi-absolutism. His humani- 
 tarian sympathies called for qualification of the system in detail, 
 but they did not produce the slightest variation in essentials 
 from the typical position of the earlier cameralists. 
 
 Sonnenfels replies (17) to the possible objection that poli- 
 tics is too inclusive to be the subject-matter of a science: 
 
 The ultimate purpose of states may be divided into four cardinal 
 subdivisions, which are connected with one another, to be sure, and 
 must join hands with one another, each of which stops, however, 
 with a subordinate end. Staatswissenschaft has accordingly been 
 divided into four sciences, viz. : external security; internal security; 
 diversification of gainful occupations; and raising the revenues neces- 
 sary for the expenses of the state. 
 
 The first of these sciences he calls (18) Staatswissenschaft in 
 the special sense; otherwise known as Staatsklugheit or Politik. 
 The second is his Polizeywissenschaft (19). The third he
 
 496 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 calls Handlungswissensrhaft (20). The fourth is Finanz- 
 wissenschaft (21). The extent to which this classification 
 varies from Justi's may be seen by comparison with pp. 303 ff. 
 above. 1 
 
 There is a surprisingly modern appearance on the surface 
 of 22, the last of the Introduction. It reads: 
 
 Natural science [Naturlehre] in all its parts, jthe mathematical 
 sciences, physical geography [Erdbeschreibung], the history, laws, 
 languages, are to be regarded partly as an indispensable preparation, 
 partly as reinforcing auxiliaries of the theory of Polizey, Handlung, 
 and Finanz. But the man of affairs, in actual administration, must 
 know the customs, habits, and statutes of peoples, the reciprocal 
 advantages and disadvantages of lands, the political conditions of 
 states, and if he is to participate with advantage in law-giving, he 
 must know men. 
 
 We should compare this dictum, however, with Justi's 
 prospectus of a school for cameralists, and we should not jump 
 to the conclusion that Sonnenfels had really advanced beyond 
 him in discovery of the proportions and relations of govern- 
 mental technology. 
 
 1 The note to 17 is an important literary landmark, viz.: "It may 
 be for this reason that numerous as are the writers upon special parts 
 of Staatswissenackaft, the catalogue of those who have undertaken to 
 cover the whole is extremely small, even if we add to Justi's Staatswirth- 
 schaft, and Bielefeld's Institutions politiques, St. Real's Staatskunst and 
 Stewart's Staaiswirtkschaft, together with certain so-called outlines and 
 elements of the Polizey- und Catneralwissenschaften, and if we honor 
 the Aristotelian and also the Hanoverian edition of the Wolffian political 
 books by allowing them to count as principles of Staatswissenschaft." 
 
 The "Stewart" mentioned in the note was evidently Sir James 
 Steuart, and there is more than merely verbal significance in the use of 
 the term Staatswirthsckaft as translation of his title, Inquiry into 
 the Principles of Political Economy. Probably no German was fully 
 aware at this time that the term "Political Economy" stood for a sort 
 of analysis which had not yet been proposed in Germany, and that its 
 lines of demarkation ran in quite distinct directions from those of Staats- 
 utirtkxchaft.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 497 
 
 The second chapter of Vol. I, Polizcy, is entitled, Funda- 
 mental Principle of Civic Science, and its Branches. 1 The 
 chapter begins with a brief homily quite in the spirit of its 
 time, upon the importance of a principle to serve as an a priori, 
 and the qualifications which such a fundamental principle 
 must possess. In 24 Sonnenfels adds: "The only one who 
 has referred Staatswissenschaft with all its branches to a uni- 
 versal principle is, so far as I know, Justi." If Roscher 
 discovered the bearings of this remark and of the context, 
 he certainly failed to make them plain to his readers. 2 The 
 passage is really one of the most compact illustrations to be 
 found, in any literature, of the crossings of judgments in a 
 period of scientific reconstruction. If the passage had been 
 made to order it could hardly have reflected more typicallv 
 the confusion introduced into theory by attention to new valua- 
 tions: 
 
 On the one hand, Sonnenfels truly interprets Justi as 
 building his whole theory upon the principle of "general 
 happiness" [allgemeine Gltickseligkeit].* On the other hand, 
 the point of the paragraph is its attempt to show that it is a 
 fallacy on Justi's part to depend on such a principle. In spite 
 of more evident sympathetic leanings than previous cameralists 
 had shown in the direction toward which Justi's principle 
 points, Sonnenfels rejects it as a major premise for civic science. 
 
 As we have seen, of the two men, Sonnenfels was far and 
 away more inclined than Justi to decide, in the concrete, in 
 favor of the alternative which promised most in the way of 
 general happiness in the modern or democratic, as distinguished 
 from the absolutistic, sense. Yet in this connection, instead 
 
 1 Hauptgrundsatz der Staatswissenschaft und ihrer Zweige. 
 
 * Op. cit,, p. 444. Roscher leaves the impression that Sonnenfels 
 commended Justi in this passage. The precise contrary was the fact. 
 
 a The sense in which Justi interpreted the concept has been discussed 
 above, p. 323 ft passim. Cf. Index, "Welfare."
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of praising Justi, Sonnenfels really blames him. His contention 
 is that "general happiness" cannot be made a test of civic meas- 
 ures, but that a more ultimate test must be found. Thus 
 Sonnenfels deliberately commits himself to a form of reasoning 
 which subordinates in theory the element which in the histori- 
 cal perspective makes him most conspicuous: and he reproves 
 Justi for an element in his formal reasoning which had much 
 less effect on his concrete technology than it had on that of 
 Sonnenfels himself. As a literary landmark the passage must 
 be cited in full. We must remember that it occurs as a part of 
 the argument on the necessity of an adequate logical principle 
 as the basis of a science. It reads: 
 
 The only one who has referred Staatswissensch-ajt with all its 
 branches to a universal principle is, so far as I know, Justi. He 
 assumed as such a principle the promotion of general happiness. 
 That is a true, but not a conclusive principle. The promotion of 
 general happiness is the object of all states, to be sure, in the period 
 of their origin, and it is their perpetual aim; for that very reason, 
 however, it cannot be taken as a principle of verification, or as the 
 general fundamental, because by means of this fundamental the 
 goodness of the measures, which consists in their harmony with the 
 ultimate purpose, must be tested. 
 
 To bring out Sonnenfels' thought as distinctly as possible, 
 we must translate the note to this section, viz.: 
 
 In his [Justi's] Staatswirthschaft when a law is to be given, or 
 any other device is to be decided on, about which it is doubtful 
 whether it would be advantageous for the state, the question is, 
 "does the proposed law promote the general happiness?" Here- 
 upon it must be tested by that principle, as the moral touchstone, 
 and when the judgment of benefit or injury is reached, the ground 
 for the judgment is given through that principle (i.e., "general 
 happiness"). In case, therefore, the promotion of general happiness 
 is assumed as the chief fundamental principle, the decision will 
 amount to this: "It promotes the general happiness because it pro- 
 motes the general happiness."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 499 
 
 This passage, by the way, may serve also as a sample of 
 the evidences which might be cited in support of the estimate 
 above expressed of the relative intellectual strength of Justi 
 and Sonnenfels. The former had few qualms about adopting 
 a frankly opportunistic principle and getting the benefit of 
 all the conclusions it would yield. The latter tried to be more 
 profound, but succeeded only in being confused. We shall 
 see in a moment that Justi's a priori was no more and no less 
 reducible to an identical proposition than Sonnenfels' sub- 
 stitute. The chief meaning of the section then is its profession 
 of faith in a deductive a priori rather than a functional test qf 
 social values. The next section shows how far Sonnenfels 
 was capable of going toward a test which was absolute in 
 form without being functional in essence. Sec. 25 is as follows: 
 
 Observation of how civic societies have arisen, and through 
 what means they have reached their end, will more surely guide to 
 the real fundamental principle. The isolated man was at the mercy 
 of every attack by a superior power. His security was not greater 
 than the forces with which he could defend himself against the 
 attack. Two men whose physical strength exceeded his own were 
 already dangerous to his security. He therefore sought to increase 
 his strength by combination with others. The isolated man felt wants 
 for the support of his life, sufficiency to satisfy which was within the 
 compass neither of his strength of body nor of soul nor yet of his 
 time. He sought to satisfy these wants by putting his diligence at 
 the service of the wants of other men, from whom he received as 
 compensation the supply of necessaries which -he lacked. The 
 isolated man' was deprived of a thousand comforts, the lack of which 
 he felt, the possession of which would make his external condition 
 more complete. He sought the comforts through socialization 
 [Vergesellschaftung] with others. The larger the society into which 
 he was merged, the greater was the quantity of the resistance which 
 he could exert in every case, and thereby assure his security. The 
 more numerous the society, the more frequent its wants, the easier 
 he found ways, by supplying what was lacking to somebody, to get
 
 500 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 from the same person what he wanted. The more numerous the 
 society, the more various were its products, and the easier was it 
 for him to supply each of his wants and comforts. Through. the 
 enlarging of the society therefore, and according to its bulk, was the 
 aim of civic societies reached, viz., the security and comfort o] life. 
 In later times this aim remains ever the same. The same means 
 will also remain effective. 
 
 Continuing the argument in 26, Sonnenfels adds: 
 
 The enlargement of the society thus contains in itself all subordi- 
 nate special means which in the aggregate promote the general 
 welfare. So soon then as it is proved of an institution [Anstalt], or 
 of a law that it makes for the enlargement of the society, or at least 
 does not hinder the same; this proof at the same time carries the 
 higher conclusion, viz., that the measure promotes, or at least does 
 not hinder, the general welfare either on the side of security or of 
 comfort. 1 I take, therefore, the enlargement of civic society, through 
 promotion of the increase of population, as the common fundamental 
 principle of Staatswissenschaft, with its included parts: and the 
 validating principle [Prufsatz] of every measure which is adopted 
 for promotion of the general happiness is this: Does it tend to 
 increase or diminish population?* 
 
 Further comment upon this explicit statement is unneces- 
 sary. It confirms our proposition about the uncertain charac- 
 ter of Sonnenfels' underlying philosophy. It is not our affair 
 to probe the logical fatuities of the cameralists beyond discovery 
 of their actual ways of thinking. It is not even necessary to 
 note that by turning Sonnenfels' method against himself his 
 
 1 I will not enlarge on this unconscious confession that the author 
 at last, in spite of himself, relied upon "general happiness," to give value 
 to "enlargement of society," rather than the reverse. I simply let him 
 speak for himself. (Vide pp. 493 and 531.) 
 
 * " Of that school of populationists which, after the middle of the 
 eighteenth century, may count as a revised edition of the mercantile 
 system, Sonnenfels is unquestionably the most important exponent in 
 Germany." Roscher, op. cit. t p. 536.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 501 
 
 supposed ultimatum is at once reduced to the identical 
 proposition "Promoting population is the main principle 
 because it promotes population." We go far enough for our 
 purpose when we find that Sonnenfels was content with the 
 generalization that increase of population promotes the general 
 happiness, and thereupon he persuaded himself that increase 
 of population is the ultima ratio of civic science. His system 
 turns out to be a technology in the interest now of " the general 
 happiness," now of "the promotion of population;" with more 
 inclination in practice than previous cameralists had shown 
 to treat the ill-defined concept "general happiness" as the 
 ultimate end, with corresponding tendency, inadvertent but 
 real, to revise valuations of all means whatsoever by judgment 
 of their adaptation to that end. 
 
 In the same connection, however, we find a methodological 
 indication of a more gratifying kind. It adds to the evidence 
 scheduled above to the effect that, so far as the cameralists 
 are concerned, it is very easy to overestimate the distance 
 between previous theories of population and that of Malthus. 
 Thus, in 27, Sonnenfels speaks as follows: 
 
 I must seek to avoid indefiniteness. The population contains 
 all the means which the common welfare [gemeinschafttiche Wohl- 
 fahrt] demands. All institutions of the ruler should accordingly 
 be directed toward maintaining and increasing the numbers of the 
 population. This number, nevertheless, has its limits, or a so-called 
 maximum: and these limits are drawn by the nature of states, by 
 the political and physical situation, and by the circumstances. 
 Genoa will never reach the populousness of France. The bare 
 rocks of Malta will never maintain as many inhabitants as fertile 
 Sicily, the sandy Mark Brandenburg never so many as Bohemia. 
 This, however, should not, on the other hand, prevent the Senate 
 of Genoa, the Order of St. John, the king of Prussia, from using 
 all means to assure for their territories the largest population which 
 they are capable of supporting. If man with all his efforts can 
 never be quite perfect, yet it always remains nevertheless a principle
 
 502 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of morals that man must strive for the highest perfection ! In poli- 
 tics, as in morals, if small states, less favored than others by nature, 
 never can become as populous as those which combine larger area 
 with rich soil, this does not invalidate the principle, the government 
 should always concern itself with promoting population to its highest 
 level: that is, the highest level which the means at its disposal make 
 possible. This explanation will remove most of the objections which 
 can be made against the fundamental principle of population. I 
 come then to the application of this principle to the separate branches 
 of Staatswissenschaft. 
 
 Thereupon. Sonnenfels indicates, in a merely formal way, 
 the application of this fundamental principle of population in 
 the different divisions of the science. Thus (28-31): 
 
 "The greater the number of the people, the greater is the quantity 
 of the resistance upon which the external security rests." A note 
 adds: "The smaller states are consequently of their own strength 
 capable of no high degree of external security. They combine 
 with others, so that with the same, in respect to the ultimate purpose 
 of defense, they may constitute a numerous society. Even the 
 promptness of diplomatic action is affected by the amount of power 
 at the command of the conferring parties." Then follow the con- 
 clusions: 
 
 (1) "Hence the fundamental principle of Politik." 
 
 (2) "The greater the number of the people, upon whose ready 
 assistance one may count, the less has one to fear from within 
 hence the fundamental principle of Polizey." 
 
 (3) "The greater the number of people, the more the needs, 
 hence the more various the gainful occupations within the society. 
 The more hands, the more abundant the products of agriculture 
 and industry, the stuff for external exchange. Hence the funda- 
 mental principle of Handlungswissenschaft" 
 
 (4) "The greater the number of citizens, the more are" there to 
 help bear the public expenses. The smaller therefore is the share 
 of each taxpayer, without decreasing the total amount of the public 
 revenues. Consequently the fundamental principle of Finanz- 
 wissenschajt."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 503 
 
 "The knowledge of population is therefore, in all parts of public 
 administration, indispensable. The means of surveying it, as a 
 whole and in its parts, belong therefore to no branch of Staats- 
 wissenschajt exclusively. They belong as introductory knowledge 
 to all." 
 
 If we were relying on the proof-text method of supporting 
 a foregone conclusion, it would be somewhat difficult to explain 
 away the formal principle either of Justi or of Sonnenfels, so 
 as to justify their inclusion in the cameralistic series, as above 
 defined (p. 6 et passim). We have not in any case relied on 
 detached propositions, but we have attempted to interpret each 
 writer's single propositions by the whole content of his writings. 
 We have made his promises and his performance confront each 
 other, and have tried to find the resultant. In fact both these 
 writers were centered about the fiscal needs of governments, 
 and their principles of ' ' welfare " and ' ' population " respectively 
 were in effect rather less distinctive of a particular type of 
 cameralism than regimental colors are of distinctive military 
 tactics. 
 
 Chap, iii bears the title "Means of Computing the Popula- 
 tion." It does not profess to contain a contribution by the author 
 to the statistical method, and is significant merely an as index 
 of the extent to which statistical theory had impressed men of 
 Sonnenfels' type. Beginning with the observation that, from 
 the earliest times, whether the doctrine of population was 
 taken as fundamental principle or not, states have been inter- 
 ested for practical purposes in ascertaining the 'size of the 
 population, the author distinguishes two methods of computa- 
 tion, viz., "political calculation," and "actual enumeration." 
 Under the former head he briefly discusses the uses and 
 uncertainties of estimates based on (a) the number of 
 deaths, (b) the number of births, (c) the consumption 
 of grain. We need notice merely that the authors to 
 whom Sonnenfels refers as the sources of his information
 
 504 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 about statistics are the following: Bielefeld (sic), Institutions 
 Politiques, 1760;' Zanoni, "VI. Band seiner Brief e delV agri- 
 coltura delV arte e del comercio, etc.;" 3 Siissmilch,* Kerseboom, 4 
 and Melon. s 
 
 1 Vide Roscher, p. 426, "Jacob Friedrich von Bielfeld." 
 
 These two writers are referred to as having furnished a brief history 
 
 of political computation, tracing it back to the middle of the seventeenth 
 
 century. 
 
 3 Gdttliche Ordnung in den Ver Under ungen des menschlichen 
 Gcschlechts aus dem Geburt, dem Tode und Fortpflanzung derselben 
 erwiesen. ist ed., 1742, 2cJ ed., 1761; vide Roscher, op. cit., p. 421. 
 
 4 Abhandlung zu eincm Versuche der wahrscheinlichen Menge des 
 Volkes von Holland und Westfriesland, etc.; vide Roscher, op. cit., p. 421, 
 "Kersseboom." 
 
 s Essai polllique sur le commerce, 1734; German, 1756.
 
 CHAPTER XIX 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS ("POLIZEY") 
 
 The special introduction to the first volume bears the title: 
 "The Simplest Concepts of Polizey and Consequently an 
 Outline in Accordance with Which They Will Be Treated." 
 
 Assuming that political institutions were, to a much greater 
 degree than appears probable today, premeditated anticipa- 
 tions of evils, Sonnenfels makes this formula: 
 
 When these measures and devices are assembled, and referred to 
 certain principles derived from the nature of the social purpose, there 
 results the science of founding and maintaining the internal security 
 of the state; that is, die Polizeywissenschaft. 1 
 
 The author's own comment will best indicate the relation 
 of this formula to previous conceptions of classification within 
 the boundaries of Staatsu4ssensdiaft. He says: 
 
 " By this formula I take issue with all authors who have previously 
 treated the subject. To a certain extent I give Polizey an entirely 
 different meaning. Perhaps I should say, my reason is because the 
 formulas hitherto offered seem to me too vague, too ill-defined, some 
 of them too limited, not including all which belongs within the scope 
 of Polizey: others too general, embracing much which does not belong 
 in Polizey. My intention is not, however, to repudiate other for- 
 mulas, but by means of my own to draw the proper boundaries of 
 Polizey according to my own views, and to exhaust the concept. I 
 think I have a right to demand that after the work itself has been 
 read the judgment should be passed whether I have acted in accord- 
 ance with my intention." In a note the author adds: "This inten- 
 tion is to treat the internal constitution of a state in its interdepend- 
 ence, and in all parts of the public administration, and at the same 
 time to investigate the sources of law-giving. Consequently I shall 
 frequently use the words Polizey and Gesetzgebung as synonymous." 
 
 1 He refers to Montesquieu, Esprit des loix, Vol. I, chap, xxiv, p. 26. 
 
 SOS
 
 506 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Sonnenfels' further analysis of his method of treatment will 
 afford the most direct means of comparing his outlook with 
 that of Justi. 
 
 The author proceeds to indicate his line of approach by 
 pointing out, first (44):' 
 
 that in a certain sense Polizey is principally defense against either 
 intentional or fortuitous occurrences of a harmful nature; second, 
 every occurrence which hinders the accomplishment of the ultimate 
 purpose of society must be regarded as harmful; third, from this 
 point of view Polizey regards every transaction which does not 
 promote this ultimate purpose as harmful. 
 
 In order to perform a harmful act, the will and the ability must 
 coincide. The law-abiding man has constant opportunities to per- 
 form harmful acts, but he does not want to. The imprisoned crim- 
 inal has the will to perform harmful acts, but he is deprived of ability. 
 Hence Polizey falls into two parts, first, directive, the intention of 
 which is that no one shall wish to perform harmful acts; second, 
 preventive, which seeks to make it impossible for anyone to commit 
 harmful acts even if he has the desire. 
 
 The will of the actor is determined by impulses [Beweggrunde], 
 and the more certainly and effectively the oftener the impulses toward 
 or against an action occur, or the greater the weight of the single 
 impulse which operates upon the actor. This is the invariable prin- 
 ciple of will, in which alone the great secret of law-giving resides. 
 If the law-giver only knows how to offer his people preponderating 
 impulses toward the good, he may be assured that he may lead them 
 as he will.' 
 
 The impulses to action are of two sorts first, attractive [ein- 
 ladend}\ second, preventive. Again, the nature of the advantages 
 or disadvantages to be anticipated from actions divides impulses 
 into general and special. The general impulses include all actors 
 and actions. For that reason they deserve the first rank in law- 
 giving. There is another reason, viz., there are actions in connection 
 with which it is difficult or impossible to discover a special attractive 
 
 1 The author's own forms of statement are now epitomized. 
 1 Speaking of identical propositions!
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 507 
 
 or preventive impulse. In such a case there remains for the law- 
 giver only the motive power of the general impulses, which may be 
 grouped in two classes: morals, and the high idea oj the excellence 
 0} the laws. 
 
 Morals, in the relation in which they are regarded by the law- 
 giving authorities, are devotion to the general order. As Toussaint 
 well says, "they very well supply the place of laws, but nothing is 
 capable of supplying the place of morals." Devotion to the general 
 order is the effect of combined institutions, which enlighten the 
 understanding of the citizen to the end that he may pass correct 
 judgments upon everything which affects the general order, which 
 guides the inclinations, which controls the passions and directs them 
 to worthy actions. The whole system of devices to this end I refer 
 to under the phrase attention to the moral condition. 
 
 Next in importance is effort to propagate a high idea of the excel- 
 lence of the laws; that is, to raise it, among all the citizens, to the 
 rank of an accepted, incontestable principle, that whatever the laws 
 command is good; that is, with respect to the whole, necessary; 
 and with respect to each individual, profitable. Whenever the 
 supreme power succeeds in establishing this presupposition, it is the 
 most reliable guarantee for the observance of the laws, through the 
 violation of which each will then believe that he will harm himself. 
 
 But given the willingness to obey the laws, insight into the 
 special actions that would conform to the laws is not thereby assured. 
 The ruler must consequently supply this lack by laws which specify 
 what is to be done and left undone. This is what Hume had in 
 mind when he said that the laws are to be regarded as reinforcement 
 of the insight of the individual. The subject-matter of these laws 
 is internal public and internal private security. 
 
 As previously defined, internal public security is a condition 
 in which the state, that is, the public administration (sicl), whatever 
 the governmental form, has nothing to fear from the citizens. Volun- 
 tary obedience to the law, and thus public security, is brought about 
 through the devotion above discussed. Compulsory obedience 
 springs from the consciousness of weakness against the superior 
 powers of the sovereign, or from impossibility of resistance. What 
 Montesquieu in another connection makes the fundamental prin-
 
 508 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 ciple of a civic structure [Staatsverjassung] may be applied here 
 with great accuracy, viz., "it is essential," he says, "that through 
 the order of nature one force holds another in check;" 1 that is, the 
 quantity of possible powers of resistance on the side of the citizens 
 must always be smaller than the quantity of the powers of coercion 
 on the side of the state. Hence the chief attention of the Polizey 
 and law-givers is demanded to prevent any stratum or single citizen 
 from attaining to such power that the public authorities may be 
 successfully opposed. 
 
 In 52 Sonnenfels repeats the definition given above of 
 internal private security, and he proceeds: 
 
 All good, which can accrue to the citizen, all bad, whereby his 
 happiness may be endangered, may be traced back to his business, 
 his person, his honor, and his goods. 3 
 
 It is difficult to understand why the elementary observations 
 which followed upon the workings of legal mandates and sanc- 
 tions were necessary or even tolerable in a university lecture- 
 room. As we have said above in the case of Justi, the most 
 plausible explanation is that they were of a piece with the 
 homiletical style of the period, the method of magnifying the 
 obvious. 
 
 The foregoing discussion furnishes the reasons for the sub- 
 
 ' Esprit des loix, Vol. I, Part II, chap. iv. 
 
 *"Auf seine Hondlungen, Personen, auf seine Ehre, und seine 
 GAter." The ambiguity of the term Handlungen might be used as one 
 of the stigmata of the untenable analysis in which it figures. The same 
 is true of the plural Personen, of Ehre as having a possible content not 
 gathered from the other three categories, and of Cuter, in distinction 
 primarily from Handlungen, and secondarily from the other two concepts. 
 The classification serves as basis of the technology which follows, but 
 the confusion which corresponds with the superficial analysis does not 
 much affect the larger relations which we are emphasizing, and we may 
 pass it with this notice. Sonnenfels adds the note (p. 63): "The English 
 writers compress all into the words Liberty and Property [Freyheit und 
 Eigenthum]. Freyheit has special connection with Handlvni'^H, Per- 
 sonen, and Ehre; Eigenthum with Cuter."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 509 
 
 divisions of the book. Except in details of classification and 
 of judgment about minor means, the remainder of the volume 
 affords little material for our purpose. Roscher has digested 
 the technical contents of the three volumes in which Sonnenfels 
 varies somewhat from the other cameralists. 1 The most 
 noticeable contrast with Justi, in respect to technique, is the 
 creation of the division Handling co-ordinate with Polizey, 
 instead of treating subjects falling under the former as subdi- 
 visions of the latter. In respect to the spirit of the treatment 
 I am able to adopt Roscher's judgments with but slight modi- 
 ficcition. 2 
 
 "For the development of German national economy, 
 Sonnenfels may be characterized most accurately in this way: 
 his standpoint reminds us essentially of Justi's ideas," but 
 he gave to the ideas an apparently firmer setting in the sort 
 of reasoning which was conventional in his day; and he was 
 rather more systematic in developing the consequences of the 
 ideas. "At the same time the demands of the ought-to-be 
 play with him a much more significant role than explanation 
 of the existing. Suggestion of practical propositions is in bulk, 
 as well as in the interest of the author, much more notable 
 than the scientific analysis of the subjects in question." 
 
 Although we shall be led into somewhat extended discus- 
 sion of numerous details, we have thus covered in principle 
 all that our main purpose calls for in the case of Sonnenfels, 
 and what follows amounts merely to illustrative specifications 
 under previous propositions. 
 
 The first section in the chapter on "Attention to the Moral 
 Condition" is worth quoting as a summary of Sonnenfels' 
 ethical preconceptions. He says (61): 
 
 Morals are a common subject-matter of religion, of ethics, and 
 of law-giving; but each treats them in the light of its own purpose; 
 Op. cit., pp. 536 ff. 
 * The original should be compared, op. cit., p. 536.
 
 510 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the first two as an end, the last only as a means, satisfied if corre- 
 spondence of conduct with the laws can be procured not by the most 
 lofty motives, but also merely by hope of an advantage or by fear 
 of punishment. Hence arises the idea of political virtue, which 
 differs from the concept of virtue demanded by ethics and religion. 
 Political or social virtue is the facility of ordering one's conduct in 
 correspondence with the laws of the society. The motor machinery, 
 whereby this correspondence is procured, does not fall within the 
 scope of the present explanation, since virtue of a higher order is not 
 to be dispsnsed with. Meanwhile there is no ground for the anxiety 
 that political virtue may be dangerous for religion and ethics [Sitten- 
 lehre]; that would be the case if political virtue and religious virtue 
 were in antithesis with each other: but this is by no means the case. 
 For the purpose of the law-giver, to be sure, the first is enough; 
 yet the second is not thereby excluded* but to a certain extent it is 
 presupposed by the first. A wise law-giver will always seek to base 
 social virtue \Gesellschaftungstugend} upon moral virtue, yet from 
 inadequacy of the means at his command he cannot always discover 
 whether each member of society in practice bases his social virtue 
 upon moral virtue. He must therefore be content to take knowl- 
 edge simply of the body of the transactions, and he leaves it to the 
 spiritual teacher to introduce the vitalizing spirit of religion. 
 
 Of course Sonnenfels is at this point merely a symptom of 
 the ethical and theological dichotomy which still succeeds in 
 keeping most of the population of the world under the impres- 
 sion that virtue is an affair of separate circuits, which may be 
 operated independently or be brought into communication 
 with one another. It was no peculiar demerit of his that he 
 could treat social virtue as different in kind from ethical or 
 religious virtue. It would simply plunge us into conflict with 
 speculative moral philosophy in general if we should enter 
 upon discussion of this part of the analysis. We may simply 
 allow him to show further, in his own idiom, what working 
 relation he presupposed between social virtue on the one hand 
 and religious virtue on the other. In 63 he says:
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 511 
 
 The chief and most effective means for the building-up of morals 
 are religion, education, and the sciences. Among these religion 
 deserves the first place. Religion is the gentlest bond of society. 
 Religion instructs through her venerable teachings in goodness. 
 Religion stimulates to the application of the same through promises. 
 Religion deters from evil actions by threats. Religion brings about 
 thorough repentance, which she produces in the sinner, and forgive- 
 ness, which she offers to the penitent, the improvement of the vicious. 
 Religion increases therefore the determining as well as the deterring 
 motives. Law-giving would in countless cases find itself inadequate, 
 if religion did not beneficently come to its aid. Whenever the eye 
 of the law-giver, and consequently also the penalty of the judge, 
 fails to accomplish the end, the exalted principle of the omnipresent 
 God, as witness and judge of all, even the most secret evildoers, is 
 the sole means of arresting evil undertakings. The whole world 
 is consequently in agreement with Warburton, that the doctrine of 
 a future life of rewards and punishments is utterly indispensable for 
 every civic society. The ruler may not disregard this leash [Leitrie- 
 men] given into his hand, and he must take care that every citizen 
 in the state has religion. From this point of view (64) freethinking 
 appears as a political crime, because to a certain extent it robs the 
 state of the means of guiding its citizens most completely. The 
 chancellor Bacon,*end President Montesquieu have never been under 
 suspicion as persecutors, yet the former writes: "No one denies God, 
 except those who have an interest in there being no God;" 1 the 
 latter: "From the opinion that there is no God comes our independ- 
 ence or our revolt." 2 Accordingly to them the atheist becomes 
 either a criminal or a disorderly citizen. Consequently the concord 
 and happiness of the state depend on intolerance of the declared 
 freethinkers; and circumstances might often make it necessary for 
 the public authorities to demand of everyone a visible sign of the 
 religion "to which he adheres." 3 
 
 1 Sonnenfels simply refers to " sermones fideles, etc." 
 * Esprit des loix, Vol. XXXIV, chap. ii. 
 
 3 A note to this section reads: " During the reign of Queen Elizabeth, 
 a penalty of twenty pounds was imposed upon anyone who absented
 
 512 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The argument continues (65): 
 
 From the necessity of religion, even for the temporal happiness 
 of the citizens, and the common security, are derived the right and 
 the obligation of the Polizey to extend its attention to the education 
 of the people in religious duties, to prevent abuses, and to watch 
 over the external order of religious functions and worship. The 
 instruction in the duties of religion, in the rural regions particularly, 
 is worthy of so much attention, because with the rural population 
 religion must largely take the place of education, and at the same 
 time it is the only means of making an impression upon their ways 
 of thinking. The first object to which the care of the Polizey should 
 be given in this respect should be sufficient and skilful curates. 1 
 
 On the ground of necessity for public morals, education 
 is then discussed as a section of the duties of Polizey. The 
 author says (70): 
 
 After religion, education has the greatest influence upon morals. 
 It is, to be sure, a peculiar duty of parents; but not only a son, a 
 citizen is also to be educated. Education can therefore, on account 
 of its connection with the common welfare, not be a matter of indif- 
 ference to the law-giver, and cannot be left by the state to private 
 whim. Parents must be compelled to give their children the neces- 
 sary education (71). In order that dependent children may be edu- 
 cated, academies, foundling and orphan asylums are necessary (72). 
 It is desirable that public schools should be attended by children 
 of the upper as well as of the lower classes, for the sake of making 
 these classes acquainted with each other (73). Sees. 74-79 go 
 into some detail about alternatives in the administration of found- 
 ling and orphan asylums, with respect to influence upon public 
 
 himself for a month from public worship." The authority for the state- 
 ment is given as, "Hume, Hist, de la maison de Tudor, Tome V." Evi- 
 dence of this and like kinds, in spite of occasional appearances to the 
 contrary, makes it probable that, whenever English sources were cited, 
 they were usually known to Sonnenfels by name only, or through transla- 
 tions, usually French. 
 
 1 The four following sections elaborate the last proposition, and 
 specify problems and duties for Religions polizey.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 513 
 
 morals, and 80-82 attempt to answer the question whether it is 
 worth while to'enlighten the people through "the sciences." Son- 
 nenfels urges instruction in the lower schools about ordinary civic 
 duties, and he argues for favors, like separate jurisdiction, for the 
 higher schools, in order that their prestige may be increased. Then 
 follow hints, rather than programmes, about the availability of 
 various minor means for promoting good morals (83-98); dis- 
 tinctions for exemplary citizens, the stage, with necessity of censor- 
 ship, and as another negative means, the censorship of books. In 
 connection with this last subject Hume is quoted, 1 to the effect that 
 the freedom of the press is absolutely assential to England's form 
 of government, in order that mind and talent may without any hin- 
 drance act in defense of liberty. "But," answers Sonnenfels, "this 
 author himself admits that this same means allows the spirit of resist- 
 ance, of revolt, and other harmful influences to be spread abroad. 
 He consequently holds the censorship as necessary for other forms 
 of government, especially for the ecclesiastical state. Perhaps 
 we are justified in replying to the Englishman, that the goodness 
 of a constitution which is capable of preservation only by such 
 dangerous means, must be very equivocal." 
 
 But Sonnenfels presently reaches conclusions which have 
 a firmer psychological basis, whatever be the estimate of them 
 in current economic or political theory. In 100 he begins 
 with the premise that law-giving wisdom must provide the 
 general and special means of preventing vagrancy and idleness 
 in general. The previous 99 lays down, as a major premise 
 for this dictum, the proposition that idleness produces immoral- 
 ity. Whether we should agree or not with the inference that 
 the government must prevent idleness, there is little doubt 
 among social theorists today that an orccupation is one of the 
 primary conditions conducive to moraUty in Sonnenfels' sense 
 of the term. The special arrangements which he recommends 
 for repressing idleness fall under the heads: prevention of 
 begging; careful inspection to see that everyone in the state 
 
 * Political Essays,Vo\. II, Part I, "Essay on the Liberty of the Press."
 
 514 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 is earning a living; checking of all useless occupations akin 
 to vagrancy; diminution of the number of students (because 
 in Austria they were said to be in excess of the positions requir- 
 ing highly educated men) ; good discipline of the servant class 
 (107-14), and as a means of making all these efforts efficient 
 well-ordered workhouses and penal institutions (119-21). 
 Everything of the nature of free soup, and indiscriminate 
 alms-giving, including gifts to begging students, is protested 
 against almost in the spirit of modern scientific charity (101- 
 6). The degree to which Sonnenfels relies on constraint, as 
 compared with his belief in attractive measures, is noticeable 
 at every step. The second phase of laws relating to the servant 
 class, viz., their protection against unjust employers, is treated 
 in 115, 116; and the third phase, provision for reducing 
 the number of the unemployed servant class, in 117, 118. 
 While he emphasizes the danger to good morals from all toler- 
 ance of pandering to sexual vice, Sonnenfels has only the 
 following as a programme (122): 
 
 All that can be demanded of a reasonable Polizey is, not that its 
 attention shall be carried to the extreme of increasing its numbers 
 for the purpose of spying and house-visitation, nor that by excessive 
 severity toward weaknesses it shall give occasion for greater and 
 more dangerous crimes, but that the Polizey shall restrict itself to 
 preventing public indecency, and outbreaking offenses, and that it 
 shall co-operate with parents, relatives, married people, who make 
 complaints about seduction of their relatives, or disturbance of 
 domestic order. Beyond that, religion, education, and reduction 
 of the number of the unmarried must do the most toward the restric- 
 tion of an evil which it will be possible for no foresight entirely to 
 uproot. 
 
 Finally the chapter concludes with this omnibus paragraph 
 
 (123): 
 
 The Polizey must, however, exert itself to remove all occasions 
 through which, directly or indirectly, moral disorders of another sort 
 may be increased. Here belong, for lessening drunkenness, and the
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 515 
 
 evils that flow from it, the restriction of the number of dram shops; 
 the ordinance that after a certain hour (at night) nothing more shall 
 be sold in such shops, and at no time to intoxicated persons; exem- 
 plary punishments for confirmed drunkards; prohibition of lodging 
 strangers except in recognized inns; and further, measures approved 
 by monarchs of insight, and readily granted by a head of the church 
 worthy of immortality, viz., for decrease of the number of feast 
 days. For it is certain that all time devoted to labor will be rescued 
 from vice and excess. 
 
 The spirit of chap, ii, "On the Means of Awakening a 
 High Idea of the Laws," may be indicated very briefly. The 
 fundamental proposition is that: 
 
 " on the average in a nation high respect for the law will be less a 
 result of persuasion than of antecedently formed opinion, that is, of 
 a favorable prejudice" (124). This prejudice must be aroused 
 and strengthened. It may be weakened or destroyed. The means 
 in either case are in the hands of those who give the laws. In repub- 
 lics, where laws are examined by representations of the people before 
 they are enacted, the presumption of the goodness of the laws springs 
 from the nature of the constitution. That is, it is supposed that the 
 law would have been rejected if its advantages had not been beyond 
 all doubt. In monarchies, that which occurs in republics before 
 the acceptance of a law should occur at the promulgation of the same. 
 This may take place in two ways first, by giving assurance that 
 consultation with estates, parliaments, councilors, etc., preceded the 
 decree; second, that every law should have a preamble, setting forth 
 the reasons why it was necessary for the public weal and bene- 
 ficial for the individual. "A government which imposes upon itself 
 the rule of accompanying its laws, so far as possible, with reasons, 
 shows confidence in its measures, honors the intelligence and integ- 
 rity of the citizens, appears less to command than to persuade. The 
 people itself imagines that it obeys less the law than its own insight." 
 Again (128) it is added: "Even if the law bears only some such 
 legend as 'moved by the public good,' the people will be inclined to 
 believe it." Furthermore, the conviction which assumes that the 
 laws are good is produced by laws of great age, and the invariability
 
 5i6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 of laws is the condition of their attaining great age (129). Con- 
 flicting interpretations of the law by experts weaken the presump- 
 tion in its favor (131). Nothing weakens the prestige of the laws 
 more than a distinction between obligation before the judge, and 
 absence of obligation in conscience (132). 
 
 Chap, iii, "On Provision for Holding Private Powers in a 
 Subordinate Equilibrium with the Powers of the State," may 
 also be epitomized very briefly. The main proposition is 
 that: 
 
 the powers of resistance on the side of the citi/ens must always be 
 kept inferior to the powers of compulsion on the side of the state 
 (xic) (136). This persistent antithesis between the citizens and 
 the state is one of the most essential traits of the pre-democratic 
 political philosophy. "The forces or means, which might hinder 
 the state in the exercise of its powers, consist of wealth, of the strength 
 oj a stratum of society, and of privileges." "While security of prop- 
 erty is one of the principal advantages to be gained by civic society, 
 wisdom seeks to prevent the accumulation of excessive private wealth" 
 (138).' It is not wise to prescribe the limits of wealth which indi- 
 viduals or families may possess (139); but the stale may set precise 
 bounds to the wealth of deathless societies. "This necessity has 
 been recognized in all states,* especially since Edward I set the 
 example with his 'amortization laws' " (140). "In case the laws 
 have neglected to provide against too great accumulation of wealth 
 in families, indirect measures may be adopted with advantage to 
 correct the evil; as when Henry VII of England allowed the division 
 of the estates of the nobility among several sons. If he had ordered 
 the division, it would have been resisted. The permission was 
 regarded as beneficent. Similar indirect measures may be taken 
 to limit the growth of deathless societies (141); and parallel action 
 is wise in the case of societies, parties, and organizations of many 
 sorts which tend to acquire excessive power (142 ff.). Sees. 149 ff. 
 deal with cases in which sedition of more or less violent sort breaks 
 
 1 Hume is again cited rather vaguely, p. 181. 
 
 Illustration cited from Hume, " Leben Edwards /," Geschichle 
 von England, T. 2.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 51? 
 
 out, from actual violation of laws against accumulation of riches or 
 power, to reflections on the government by public speakers, preach- 
 ers, teachers, actors, writers, etc.; and different kinds and degrees 
 of censorship by the police are rather vaguely recommended. The 
 duties of the police in case of disorderly assemblies are rather hinted 
 at than specified (155 ff.). 
 
 Chap, iv, "On Security of Action," is notable, first, because 
 it gives evidence that some of the concepts of an innovating 
 popular philosophy were beginning to call for attention in one 
 of the more conservative universities of the German countries. 
 Sonnenfels begins by saying that "security of action" and 
 "freedom of action" are. identical ideas. "They refer to the 
 condition in which we have nothing to fear with respect to our 
 actions." Thereupon he undertakes an analysis of the dis- 
 tinctions to be made between "freedom," "licentiousness" 
 [ZUgellosigkeit], and "independence" [Unabhangigkeit]. The 
 presuppositions of his argument are, first, "the laws of nature;" 
 second, "the social compact." These make "freedom" a 
 limited, not an absolute condition, and per contra they estop 
 licentiousness and independence. Regardless of the method 
 of the argument, the author urges the sane view, which he 
 phrases after Pope, that "he who obeys reason is free." He 
 finds that reasonable freedom or security of action may be 
 endangered, first, by the ruler, considered as law-giver and 
 judge; e.g., when he transgresses the limits of the law-giving 
 power, or when he falsely accuses, or unfairly conducts a pro- 
 cess in court; second, by fellow-citizens in various relations. 
 The succeeding discussion of the limits of the law-giving and 
 judicial power is literary rather than technical, but it marks 
 a rising tide of demand for laws and administration of them, 
 in conformity with needs which citizens feel to be reasonable. 
 In this connection (165-69), Sonnenfels presents his famous 
 objections to torture as a judicial measure. The infringements 
 upon security of action by fellow-citizens are scheduled under
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the heads, "servitude," "chattel slavery," "constraint by 
 parents, guardians, etc." (171-75). 
 
 Chap, v, "On the Security of the Person" (176-293), 
 covers a wider range of detail with a greater number of 
 specific topics, than any other main division of the book. 
 Although in many cases it indicates rather definite policies 
 about particular problems, yet on the whole it has rather the 
 force of a catalogue of subjects than of a codification of rules. 
 Its importance is technological, and a proper estimate of 
 its value could be made only by technologists in the different 
 subjects of which it treats. It does not furnish material which 
 falls directly within the scope of our inquiry. It should be 
 said, however, that it is another remarkable reflection of the 
 degree of attention which German administrative theory had 
 already given to details affecting public welfare. It discusses 
 a surprising number of relations by which physical well-being 
 is affected. These range from crimes of violence, to methods 
 of relieving poverty, caring for the sick, promoting public 
 hygiene, and securing pure food or pure air. It should be 
 noticed too that the chapter includes a strong and explicit 
 argument against toleration of duelling, and also against all 
 methods of procuring abortions. In the latter connection 
 Sonnenfels shows farsighted views about the policy which 
 the government should pursue toward mothers of illegitimate 
 children. 
 
 Chap, vi, "Security of Honor" (294-304), proposes to 
 treat of honor "considered as respect for the integrity [Recht- 
 schajfenheit] of a citizen." The viewpoint is indicated by 
 the propositions: "Whatever deprives the citizen of honor, 
 therefore, robs him of actual advantages, harms him seriously: 
 and the legal authority is bound to defend every citizen against 
 such injuries." The chapter accordingly specifies the following 
 subjects which should be taken into account in applying the 
 principle: supposed hereditary dishonor (295-97); supposed
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 519 
 
 dishonor on account of certain occupations, court servants, 
 spies, executioners, etc. (298); loss of honor through insult 
 and slander (300-303) ; loss of honor through seduction (304). 
 It should be observed that, whatever be the value of the means 
 recommended in these connections, the content of private and 
 public welfare in particulars of which this chapter contains 
 samples was much more justly estimated in the German civic 
 theories of the cameralistic period than in the practice of mod- 
 ern democracies. We have by no means improved in all 
 particulars upon the civic theories of the eighteenth century. 
 
 Chap, vii, "On Security of Goods" (305-51), contains 
 nothing that calls for special remark, except that it groups with 
 the crimes against property as ordinarily understood, various 
 injuries to possessions through oversight [Versehen] (337 ff.). 
 Under the latter head, Sonnenfels discusses protection against 
 damage by fire, including building-ordinances, fire-departments, 
 fire-insurance, protection against lightning, use of firearms 
 and fireworks, ordinances against vagrants, and various minor 
 devices. 
 
 Chap, viii, "On Penalties" (352-88), although not 
 strictly pertinent to our purpose, deserves brief notice because 
 it contains symptoms of the independence of thought about 
 details which led Roscher to apply the term "eclectic." 1 
 
 Sonnenfels begins by questioning the sufficiency of Grotius' 
 explanation of legal penalties, viz.: "Punishment is an evil 
 of sensation because of malice of action." The author 
 comments: 
 
 This aphorism, handed down from writer to writer, has given a 
 one-sided direction to reflection upon the subject. The viewpoint 
 from which the judge who enforces the penalty regards it, and that 
 of the law-giver who ordains it are quite different. The first punishes 
 because the law was disobeyed. The second threatens a penalty 
 in order that the law may not be disobeyed. With the former the 
 
 i Vide pp. 481 ff. above.
 
 520 THE CAMERALTSTS 
 
 penalty is a consequence of the conduct. With the latter the conduct 
 is a consequence of the penalty. With the first the affixing of penalty 
 is inculpation, with the second it is stimulus. Penalty therefore, 
 considered as an auxiliary, to protect the law, namely, by exerting 
 an influence upon the resolutions of actors, and by supplying the 
 place of other determining motives, is an evil which is attached to 
 the law as a means 0} influencing against infraction of the same. In 
 determining penalties, attention is to be paid, first, to the quantity; 
 second, to the kind of the same. 
 
 The attempt to find a principle on which to decide the former 
 question proceeds by considering four possible criteria, viz., 
 the conduct itself, its relation to the state, its consequences, 
 or its motives; and it reaches the conclusion (357): "The 
 general means of measuring punishment is, therefore, to be 
 sought only in the motives of the crime." The following 
 specifications are deduced: 
 
 "(i) The penalty must be as great as necessary to procure the 
 lawful action or restraint; (2) The penalty must not be greater than 
 necessary to procure the lawful action; (3) The strongest deterring 
 motive, that is, the most effective penalty, will always be that which 
 threatens an evil in direct antithesis with the motive which solicits 
 to the crime." In explaining the application to be made of these 
 principles, Sonnenfels recurs to his classification of evils to be 
 avoided, or of "securities" to be gained. As the evils have refer- 
 ence in turn to civic freedom, honor, goods, and corporal integrity, 
 the penalties should correspond. Thus, they should be variations 
 of "loss of all civic rights; loss of social standing [Standesrechte]-, 
 loss of rights of the family; loss of legal rights; or, in special 
 cases, banishment from the country; expulsion from the locality; 
 infamy; degradation [Standesentsetzung] ; confiscation of goods; 
 fines; corporal punishment, from minor inflictions to the death- 
 penalty." 
 
 Respecting the extreme penalty, Sonnenfels energetically 
 opposes the prevailing opinions and practices. He repeats 
 the theorem which he had published in 1764:
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 521 
 
 Death penalties are contrary to the purpose of penalties. Hard, 
 incessant public labor promises much more for that purpose, and 
 at the same time makes the punishment of the criminal profitable 
 for the state. 1 
 
 One paragraph in particular, in discussion of this question, 
 is notable more for its wider implications than for its immediate 
 bearings. Whether its author was aware or not that he was 
 betraying tendencies which were ominous for the old regime, 
 it is evident enough from our present viewpoint that we have 
 here one of the signs that absolutistic preconceptions were losing 
 some of their hold. On justification of the right of capital 
 punishment the author says (377): 
 
 The first question which must be investigated is without doubt 
 in respect to the right. Has the law a right to punish with death ? 
 If questions have been raised over this point, it was because writers 
 have fawned upon princes, and have sought the source of this right 
 in no one knows what form of a majesty derived immediately from 
 heaven, and assigned to them an unlimited right over life and 
 death. The source of this awful right is to be sought nowhere except 
 in the individual man, whose combination constitutes the state. 
 Man, thought of in the natural condition, has the right to protect 
 his security in every way, and if the violence of attack cannot other- 
 wise be warded off, it is his right to carry his defense even to the 
 death of the assailant. In civil society each separate member has 
 made over this right of defense to the whole, that is, to the sovereign 
 power that represents the whole; that is, not a right over his own 
 life, which no one possesses, but the right of each over the life of 
 every other who might become an assailant. In that way the 
 sovereign power acquired the right over all. 
 
 Our concern is not with the validity of this reasoning, but 
 with the fact that Sonnenfels exhibited a tendency to think 
 
 1 Reference is made to "die vortreffliche Abhandlung des Marchese 
 Beccari: Von Verbrechen und Strafen," which appeared almost simul- 
 taneously with the publication of Sonnenfel's first edition, and supported 
 his position on this subject,
 
 522 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 for himself about certain parts of the traditional philosophy 
 of the state. 
 
 The purpose of chap, ix, "On Institutions for Maintaining 
 Internal Security," is particularized in the opening paragraph 
 (389), viz.: 
 
 Under the name institutions we include all persons and devices 
 which aim at prevention and discovery of every action harmful to 
 civic security, including the higher as well as the lower stations and 
 functionaries that have to do in any way with guarding the peace, 
 with detecting seditious intentions, or dangerous persons, and finally 
 everything which has to do with punishment of the same. 
 
 As a survey of the civic structure which all the cameralists 
 have contemplated with variations of detail, the following 
 paragraph (390) is useful, viz.: 
 
 As the prerogatives of Polizey have been treated in this work, 
 the law-giving as well as the executive power lies within the scope 
 of its functions. The supreme administration of the same can 
 consequently be accredited only to the highest station in the state, 
 whatever be the name under which it exists. This is the directing 
 guidance of the state, where the principal laws and ordinances are 
 enacted. Execution, however, is, according to the variety of the 
 objects, committed to subordinate divisions. Moreover, the public 
 administration usually subdivides affairs, and retains for itself 
 law-giving, at least in general affairs of the country, or respecting 
 other more important matters; it turns over the civil and criminal 
 judiciary functions to special bodies, or so-called Stellen, and restricts 
 the operations of Polizey in the narrower sense to maintenance of 
 the public peace, good order, and discipline, to superintendence 
 over measures, weights, markets, cleanliness of cities, institutions 
 necessitated by the various dangers and accidents, and especially 
 over everything which demands emergency action. Since mention 
 has already been made of the different judicial offices, it remains 
 for this chapter to treat only of this last significance of Polizey. 
 
 The chief difference between Justi and Sonnenfels in this 
 division of the subject is not that they disagree in principle,
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 5 2 3 
 
 but that Sonnenfels has scheduled a larger number of concrete 
 details to which the principles apply, and that these specifica- 
 tions have the effect of considerably extending the apparent 
 consequences of the principles. A striking instance of this is 
 the argument for abolition of places of refuge (410-15). 
 
 Chap, x, "Use of the Institutions in Case of Great Accidents" 
 furnishes a sort of title for activities which in the nature of the 
 case cannot be thoroughly analyzed nor formulated, and no 
 very explicit prescriptions about them are possible. The refer- 
 ence is to occurrences which may be anticipated in kind, but 
 cannot be foreseen in time and place, and cannot be averted 
 by human power. The sort of foresight to be exercised is 
 suggested by the questions, What sort of accidents are probable 
 in a given locality ? How does the situation affect the proba- 
 bility of such accidents? What variations of the probability 
 are there at different times? Among such accidents, which 
 permit of provisional prevention ? Then action with reference 
 to such accidents may be in part thought out in advance by 
 dividing the calamity into stages, and by determining the sort 
 of conduct appropriate in each, viz., (i) before the actual 
 case; (2) during the same; (3) after the same. As an illus- 
 tration, Sonnenfels takes the case of a freshet in the Dan- 
 ube at Vienna, and specifies a programme for minimizing the 
 calamity, before, during, and after. It is evident that this 
 sketch is not a mere academic exercise, but it has the same 
 importance for civic conditions which the plans of a commissary 
 department have for an army. 
 
 With reference to the volume as a whole the curious fact 
 is to be noted that no one who had not been advised of the 
 author's alleged fundamental principle would discover a sign 
 of it in any paragraph of the book after the passage in which 
 it is discussed in the abstract. 1 From that point it disappears, 
 and no use is made of it whatsoever. A student of Justi who 
 
 1 Vide above, p. 500.
 
 524 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 omitted the first forty-two sections of the present volume, 
 and carefully studied the remaining three hundred and ninety, 
 would probably find no occasion for doubting that Sonnenfels 
 was completely in accord with his predecessor in making "the 
 general happiness" the criterion of civic procedure. The 
 argument does not close here, to be sure, and the author will 
 find a use for his alleged criterion later. We shall return to 
 the subject, and shall find it instructive about the unsettled 
 condition of the philosophy of which it was a symptom.
 
 CHAPTER XX 
 THE CAMERALISM OF SONNENFELS ("HANDLUNG") 
 
 The title-page of Sonnenfel's second volume, Handlung, 
 is identical with that of Vol. I, Polizey, except that the vignette 
 represents "Fortbonnais." 1 If Sonnenfels did not translate 
 Forbonnais' term commerce by the word Handlung, the scope 
 of his book would call for the version "industry," in the more 
 general sense connoted by ordinary American usage, not in 
 the more technical sense of the German ' ' Industrie. ' ' Although 
 the activities discussed include gainful occupations in general, 
 Sonnenfels prefers to consider them as "commerce," and that 
 term will be used as a translation of his word Handlung. If 
 all the passages in which it occurs were collated, they would 
 show a curious lack of precision in his analysis. To what 
 extent this classification of economic activities of different 
 kinds under a name proper to some of them and not to others 
 is cause or effect of important economic misconceptions is a 
 query which we merely register, without attempting to offer 
 an answer. 
 
 This second part is very largely a discussion of technical 
 phases of different kinds of business, more than investigation 
 of economic principles at the basis of all business. The intro- 
 ductory portions of the book, however, show traits that are 
 highly useful in marking theoretical tendencies. 
 
 The Preface declares that this "outline of political com- 
 mercial science 2 was not written for men in business, whose 
 
 ' On' p. 4 of the Preface the edition of Forbonnais' book which t 
 Sonnenfels used is referred to as " Eltmens du Commerce, vweyte Leydner 
 Auflage." 
 
 * Umriss der politischtn Handlungswissenschaft. I have not found 
 this expression in the earlier cameralists. It seems to me to be in itself 
 a sign that there was increasing instability in the notions of classification 
 
 525
 
 526 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 theories have been established by long experience, and have 
 become complete. If I wish to leave the book in their hands, 
 it is only in order that I may be corrected by them if any errors 
 have escaped my knowledge." 
 The Preface continues: 
 
 My ambition limits itself to the young friends to whom my calling 
 commissions me as a guide. If I have in some measure smoothed 
 their way to their duty, if I have made their preparation for their 
 calling easier, I have accomplished my purpose. 
 
 As an index of the intellectual conditions within which 
 Sonnenfels wrote, the next paragraph is instructive, viz. : 
 
 There is no lack, to be sure, of thorough writings on the subject 
 of commerce. The English and the French have always recognized 
 the importance of a subject which may be regarded as the foundation 
 of public welfare 1 [der oftcntlichen Wohlfahrt], since through multi- 
 plication of means of subsistence it is the basis of population. The 
 greatest men in all sciences, publicists [Staatskiindige], historians, 
 philosophers, have made contributions to the explanation of com- 
 merce. Mathematicians have believed that they were no less useful 
 to the world and to their fatherland when they spoke of the advan- 
 tages of a cloth factory than when they analyzed the profound theory 
 of the infinite. Their writings meanwhile are rather for the already 
 educated readers than for beginners. It appears that men of such 
 ability have been unable to put themselves on the level of the untrained. 
 Hence the obscurity of their writings. They presuppose knowledge 
 of which the uninitiated have no comprehension. The latter can- 
 not grasp conclusions from principles which they do not understand. 
 
 and methodology. Although Sonnenfels is far from generalizing eco- 
 nomic problems in the spirit of an abstract science, the prominence and 
 relative independence of business questions, as distinguished from fiscal 
 problems, is a still more meaning sign that general economic problems 
 were approaching the threshold of consciousness. 
 
 1 Perhaps it is mere fancy, but in Sonnenfels' usage this expression 
 seems to me to connote a less governmental and more popular center 
 of gravity for the concept " welfare " than was indicated by the corre- 
 sponding terms of the earlier cameralists.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 527 
 
 The profound author of the Elements o] Commerce declares at 
 the outset that he did not write for those who read only to save 
 themselves the trouble of thinking. If Forbonnais would admit only 
 thinking readers, did he reflect that his excellent book would remain 
 almost unread ? I take the liberty of confessing that my intention 
 is precisely the opposite of his. I write for those who are not yet 
 capable of thinking for themselves on this subject. This book is 
 to introduce them to it. My purpose is to prepare readers for Forbon- 
 nais. 
 
 Sonnenfels presently schedules the Austrian literature 
 of the subject as follows: 
 
 The catalogue of writings to which we can make claim as a 
 national possession may be read at a glance. It comprises in all 
 Oesterreich iiber dies mostly credited to Horneck, but partly to 
 Becher; 1 SchrStters Fiirstliche Schatz- und Rentkammer; 3 Meixner's 
 Amnerkungen iiber die Beschaftenheit der k. k. Erblande:* a book 
 which only arouses the wish that such a work might be undertaken by 
 a more competent and better informed man; and an anomymous 
 book entitled, Wahre und vortrefliche Mittel, wodurch die k. k. Erb- 
 kSnigreiche und Ldnder in einen glucklicheren und florissanteren 
 Zustand geselzt werden ktinnten, under which much-promising 
 inscription everyone would be likely to expect more than five pieces 4 
 which are shoved together without connection as without choice, 
 and of which, for the author's sake, I will attribute the much-profess- 
 ing title to one of the usual publishers' tricks to make eight paltry 
 sheets salable. 
 
 1 Vide pp. 129 ff. above. Vide pp. 135 ff. above. 
 
 3 Not mentioned by Roscher. 
 
 4 Sonnenfels' note: "I. Beweis, dass es den dsterreischen Fabriken 
 eben so leicht seyn werde, ein Konsumme in Pohlen zu finden, ah der 
 Churbrandenburg. II. Griindliche Anleitung zu regelm&ssiger Spren- 
 gung fester Steinfclsen u.s.w. III. K. K. Verordnung Kirchengelder und 
 Kirchenrechnungen. IV. Gonser's Abhandlung -von Torferde. V. Vor- 
 schlag zur Beleuchtung der StOdte." The author adds: "This Preface 
 was written in 1769. Since that time several works have been written 
 which have relations to the Austrian states."
 
 528 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Four books, or eight, if we reckon Becher's Bedenken von 
 Manu/acturen in Deutschland, 1 von Vogemont's (or Bogemont's) 
 Deutschlands vermehrten Wohlstand, Boden's Fiirstliche Macht- 
 kunstj* and Jorger's Vota Cameralia, from all of which no one would 
 be able to gather particularly important information. These are 
 all of this species, however, which Austria up to this time has to show. 
 The rest of Germany is not rich in writings of distinction, while other 
 nations are taught about all parts of commerce and finance by the 
 most excellent works. 3 
 
 Not less instructive is Sonnenfels' hypothesis in explanation 
 of Austria's backwardness in this respect (Preface, p. 8) : 
 
 This lack may have its cause chiefly in the difficulty of access 
 to those sources which occasion the speculations of writers, which 
 guide them, which must necessarily be made fundamental by them, 
 in so far as their works are not to remain merely indecisive and 
 mostly inapplicable thoughts. The strength and population, the 
 condition of commerce, of manufactures, the various changes, the 
 occasions of the same, the hindrances, the encouragements, the 
 increase of diligence, the condition of the public revenues, of the 
 national credit, all this is in other states known in detail, either from 
 public registers and tables, or it is readily made known to those who 
 desire to inform themselves about these matters. Competent men 
 then look upon it as their duty not to withhold from the state their 
 observations about the same, and their advice. In this way, as it 
 were, a whole nation unifies its insight. The number of its coun- 
 cilors is in certain respects not smaller than the number of its thinking 
 patriots. 
 
 With us such facts are still regarded as state secrets. There 
 
 1 I am unable to explain this title except on the assumption that 
 Sonnenfels quoted from memory and meant the Diskurs. Vide above, 
 pp. 109 ff. 
 
 Vide above, pp. 1 70 ff. 
 
 3 It is to be noticed that Sonnenfels does not claim Justi's Staatswirth- 
 schaft for Austria, although it was a product of the author's work in that 
 country. It was not devoted particularly to Handlung, to be sure, but 
 covered the subject to such an extent that the omission is surprising.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 529 
 
 may be many important grounds for this reticence, which are unknown 
 to me. Meanwhile I can cite this secrecy in general as the cause 
 of that dearth of political writings, the number of which I wish to 
 increase by publishing these elements. My merit may perhaps be 
 very slight, if a one-sided estimate is put upon the worth of my labor. 
 If, however, judgment is so generous as to consider the intention, 
 the endeavor, to be useful at my post, I have thereby earned at least 
 a certain measure of thanks. 
 
 In the evolution of the methodology of the social sciences 
 in Germany, no writer seems to me more symptomatic than 
 Sonnenfels of the tendency toward transition from a technology 
 of civic management, with the interests of quasi-absolutistic 
 governments as the determining aim and norm, to a technology 
 in which a co-ordinate position among the aims and norms 
 would be assigned to the interests of economic production, and 
 of popular welfare in a more modern sense than that which was 
 the content of the concept "welfare" in the philosophy of the 
 quasi-absolutists. For this reason, the entire introduction 
 to this volume Handlung must be adopted into this survey. 
 The alternative title given to the volume at this point is: 
 Elements of the Science of Commerce, and the particular sub- 
 ject of the introduction is "The Simplest Concepts of Com- 
 merce, and its Branches." 1 
 
 From one point of view, the work in a pure science upon 
 which all the subsequent details and applications are based, 
 is discovery of the categories in which the facts of the science 
 have to be thought. The methodology of a positive science 
 is a N rhythmic reaction between observation of isolated facts 
 and generalization of those facts into categories. From any 
 stage of discovery the way to an advanced stage is through pro- 
 cesses of further analysis of facts and assembling new facts, 
 to learn whether the relationships in which the facts occur are 
 
 1 Grundsdtze der Handlungsivissenschait, Einleitung. Die einfach- 
 sten Begrifle des Handel s und seine Zweige.
 
 530 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 generalized in a valid manner in the categories in use. A 
 history of economic science might with advantage be written 
 as an expansion of this proposition. Logically antecedent 
 to all quantitative formulation of economic laws must be static 
 formulation of the structural phases of economic processes. 
 Whatever other merits or demerits may be attributed to the 
 Smithian type of economic theory, it was the most potent factor 
 in nineteenth-century thinking in stimulating analysis of the 
 elementary economic relationships, and of bringing into use 
 relatively precise terms as symbols of those relationships. 
 
 In other words, a first step in passing from every less critical 
 to a more critical stage of a positive science consists in dis- 
 placing less adequately analyzed categories for more adequately 
 analyzed categories, as the qualitative conceptions of the 
 science. From our present point of view, the value of Sonnen- 
 fels' introduction to this second volume consists in its exhibit 
 of such economic categories in a relatively early stage of their 
 evolution. Their crudity is cumulative evidence in support 
 of our theorem that the cameralists are radically misunderstood 
 if we interpret them as economists in the classical sense of the 
 term. They were political scientists in whose minds distinct 
 economic categories were not differentiated until the Smithian 
 influence became a variant of German thinking. Sonnenfels' 
 own language is the most effective commentary on this 
 thesis which could be cited. We translate his introduction 
 in full: 
 
 The beneficent influence of commerce upon general happiness 
 [allgemeine Gliickseligkeit] was long overlooked by political philosophy 
 [Staatsklugheit]. No attention, no care, no promotion was supposed 
 to be due to this subject. Not as though Alexander, even in the 
 irresistible course of his victories, had not cast a glance upon com- 
 merce, and after the destruction of Tyre had not built Alexandria 
 as the emporium of eastern and northern wares: but ministers and 
 monarchs recognized in the son of Philip only the conqueror, and
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 531 
 
 only in that character did he seem worthy of imitation. Charles V, 
 Sully, Elizabeth, Colbert first enlightened, cabinets about the true 
 advantages of commerce. World-wisdom lent statecraft its insight. 
 Men who had received from Providence the calling of being teachers 
 of the nations instructed the world on this subject in deathless writ- 
 ings. Finally, as the principle gained prevalence the happiness 
 of the state consists in the number of its citizens 1 people began to 
 recognize the worth of a business [Geschaft] which, through multi- 
 plication of the means of support, contributes such a large portion 
 to this happiness. Thereupon commerce became an affair of the 
 cabinets. Attention was given to the principles by whose application 
 the largest number of people may be supplied with occupation. The 
 collection of these principles constitutes the political science of com- 
 merce.' Mercantile [die kaufmannische] science is distinguished 
 from this subject, because the private merchant has for his purpose 
 the increase of his own private means, without thought whether 
 thereby anything accrues to the general advantage of the state, or 
 whether the general advantage is endangered. Yet the political 
 commerce by no means works against private advantage. The 
 former seeks to use the latter as a tool to subordinate it as a means 
 to the general end: that is, to combine the advantage of the state 
 with that of the individual citizen. 3 
 
 1 Vide above, pp. 500 and 523. This is the first recurrence of the 
 proposition. 
 
 Die politische Handlungswissenschaft. The phrase is a snapshot 
 at the struggle for survival among concepts. The predominant problem 
 still was, What shall the government do about commerce ? There was 
 not yet independent analysis of commerce itself, apart from state 
 policy. 
 
 3 Sonnenfels' note to this paragraph is not a model of lucidity, but 
 it must be quoted to complete the evidence which we must consider in 
 deciding about the precise stage in the process of critical analysis which 
 the author represents. The note is on the phrase, politische Handlungs- 
 wissenschaft, and it reads as follows: "The multiplication of means 
 of support, through advantageous exchange of that which nature [das 
 Erdreich] and diligence produce, is taught by Handlungswissenschaft," 
 (the adjective "political" does not appear at this point). With reference
 
 532 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The occupation [Bcschdftigung] of human beings has for its 
 purpose the placing in their hands the means whereby they may 
 provide their support. They derive this support through receiving 
 something as compensation for that which they produce by their 
 occupation. 1 Thus barter comes into existence, and this is the 
 business of commerce in the most proper sense (2). 
 
 What one should accept as a compensation for that which one 
 has given must be of such character that one wants it. Want [Bedurfen] 
 is here not to be understood in the restricted sense which misan- 
 thropic worldly-wise have given to the word. Desire [Verlangen] for 
 greater comfort, the means to gratify this desire, the ability to find 
 pleasure in possession and enjoyment of the same, are not without 
 a purpose in the plan of nature. They are, to the same extent, 
 not without a purpose in the plan of Stoats klugheit (vide 10 
 below). Want [Bediirjniss] means accordingly everything the 
 use of which can give us advantage of any sort whatever, the 
 possession of which is meanwhile desired; and these wants, 
 whether they are real wants, without which human beings could 
 not exist, or imaginary wants, which the customary mode of life, 
 the standard of comfort or enjoyment, the pride of men, have made 
 
 to this definition, and to the paragraph just quoted, the work proceeds 
 (Vol. II, p. 3): "This explanation appears to vary from the ordinary 
 one; i. e., the most advantageous exchange of products. In fact, how- 
 ever, it leads to the same. For precisely this more advantageous exchange 
 occurs in order to keep a great number of people employed. Moreover, 
 exchange itself is the business of commerce, and in this fact is to be found 
 the explanation of the science which guides this business. Commerce 
 will also be regarded as the means of increasing the resources [Vermogen] 
 of the state. The increased wealth of the state is a constant consequence 
 of commerce, but not the ultimate purpose in the estimate of the state 
 to which riches without citizens would be useless." 
 
 1 Even the word "produce" is likely to have the effect of an anachro- 
 nism when used as a translation of terms employed at this period. The 
 word in this case is " hervorbringen. " " Erzeugen," "erzielen" (vide 
 below, pp. 534, 551. and 558), "verdienen" "gewinnen," and similar 
 synonyms, with their derivatives, occur without the precise technical 
 force of the English "produce," "production," etc.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 533 
 
 desirable, are equally an object of exchange through which wants 
 are traded for wants (3).' 
 
 If that which one can give for that which is offered were of such 
 a sort that it were everywhere found in abundance, it would have 
 no compensating worth, and by means of it, therefore, no exchange 
 could occur. The object offered in exchange must accordingly be 
 something which he, with whom the exchange is to occur, wants and 
 does not possess, or at any rate does not possess in the quantity which 
 he desires. That is, it must be relatively rare. Commerce is thus 
 a business which owes its origin to a reciprocal want. What one 
 may offer to another for the satisfaction of a want, is called a ware 
 [Waare] (4). 
 
 In the exchange of wares many sorts of hindrances presently 
 appear. It is possible that he who desires to acquire a ware cannot 
 offer for it precisely the ware which the other party wants at the 
 moment, or in the quantity in which it is offered, and the offered 
 ware is either entirely incapable of division, or the division diminishes 
 its worth. In such a case one must seek to secure what one wants 
 through a series of exchanges. Then again, that which one pos- 
 sesses may be of such a nature that it cannot, without difficulty or de- 
 terioration, be transferred from one place to another; the want may 
 be so imperative that one cannot wait for the circuit of exchanges. 
 These difficulties presently led men to look around for a means by 
 which the difficulties might be avoided, and exchange be made easy. 
 Something was sought which might, as it were, take the place of all 
 wares, and be regarded as a universal equivalent [Entgelt] for the 
 same. Not any stuff whatever could be adopted arbitrarily as such 
 equivalent. Each of the qualities which was sought in the same 
 should be a recourse against one of the indicated difficulties of 
 exchange, and these difficulties pointed to that stuff in which the 
 qualities were found united (5). 
 
 In order to relieve wants in as small portions as was necessary 
 
 1 In a context of this sort Bedurfnisst might more properly be 
 rendered "necessities," but in other cases the translation "want" is 
 nearer to the sense. I use it, therefore, as the most available equivalent, 
 although the subjective and objective phases of the words cannot always 
 be fitted in the translation to the original.
 
 534 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 according to circumstances, that which was adopted as the general 
 equivalent must necessarily be capable of very great divisibility 
 without loss of worth. Since, especially after the extension of com- 
 merce, the objects of exchange often had to be carried long distances, 
 durability and imperishability were demanded, both in order that 
 in the exchange itself, or in going from hand to hand, it might not 
 be used up, and also in order that, without danger of deterioration, 
 it might be saved up. In order that the carriage should not be difficult 
 it must be rare. In this way a small piece became an equivalent fora 
 considerable bulk of wares. At the same time a great sum could be 
 sent in a small space. But it is probable that only after many unsuc- 
 cessful attempts would the peoples discover the combination of these 
 qualities in the precious metals, which had elsewhere been sought 
 in vain. And therein lies the cause of the almost universal agree- 
 ment of the nations about gold and silver, which now are regarded 
 as the representatives of wares, and are called money (6). 
 
 After the introduction of money, to be sure, the turn-over [Umsatz] 
 was no longer called barter, 1 but purchase. But this change in the 
 words (sicl) did not essentially change the "commerce." The 
 money did not thereby come otherwise into consideration than in so 
 far as it represented those wants, or wares, which at another time 
 could be procured for it. The thing accomplished by the "com- 
 merce" is still always the exchange of one ware for another, or for 
 the representative of a ware (7). 
 
 Wares with which exchange is effected are either immediately 
 usable in their original form, or they must be transformed for 
 use by artificial labor. The occupation which devotes itself to 
 obtaining [Erzielung] the former is rural management [Land- 
 urirthschajt]. It embraces the natural produce of the earth, of 
 grazing, and of the waters. The occupation which makes the 
 natural products usable through imparting an artificial form, 
 or which multiplies their use, is called Manujaktur* The manu- 
 
 1 In the previous sections Sonnenfels had several times used the same 
 word Tausch in the more general sense of "exchange." This is the 
 first time in which the restricted meaning is strictly correct. 
 
 In a note the author adds: "Purists" (I do not know whether his 
 use of the term "Puritancr" in this sense was an intentional or an uncon-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 535 
 
 factures are dependent upon land management. The first attention 
 of the state must therefore be given to this latter. What land 
 management furnishes to the manufactures is called raw materials 
 or stuffs (8). 
 
 The original commerce consists therefore in the produce 01 the 
 earth and of artificial labor, 1 so far, that is, as both come to the 
 assistance of wants; and in those who devote themselves with their 
 produce, who furnish the means, of providing in turn their own 
 wants. This enables us to determine the extent of general com- 
 merce. It is equal to the sum of the wants of all consumers [Ver- 
 zehrenden].* In order to extend commerce, either the wants or the 
 consumers must be increased (9). 
 
 The wants of human beings, as already observed, are very limited, 
 if we attach to the word the strictest concept of real wants. But 
 in that case the occupations of the citizens will be kept within the 
 same narrow bounds. The multiplication of wants occurs through 
 introduction of comforts and of superfluity, both of which make 
 luxury. All declamations against luxury, therefore, are either not 
 well considered, or the objections which are urged against it are not 
 really directed so much against luxury, as against the one-sided waste- 
 fulness on the part of a few, while the other portion of the nation 
 ekes out a miserable existence. Luxury, in so far, on the one hand, 
 
 scions solecism) "in the vocabulary of commerce speak of Manufaktur 
 when hammer and fire are not used, as Tuchmanufaktur, Cottonmanu- 
 faktur. On the other hand, where these two are necessary, that is called 
 Fabriken, Stahlfabriken, Messing fabriken. Usage has almost abolished 
 this distinction. The word Fabrik is more general. We hear daily 
 Tuchfabrik, Cottonfabrik." 
 
 1 An explanatory note adds: "The word Kunslarbeit will constantly 
 be contrasted with Landwirtlischaft in order to indicate the class of 
 Manufacturatiten." We may translate this obviously inappropriate 
 term, "suppliers," as a mean between "manufacturers" which offends 
 modern usage if it includes farmers; and "producers" which would 
 attribute to Sonnenfels a generalization that he had not made. "The 
 word diligence [Aemsigkeit] will also be used." 
 
 The author's note reads: "The total of commerce is thus the 
 sum of two magnitudes, the wants and the number of consumers."
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as it increases the wants of citizens, and thereby perhaps makes it 
 harder for some to support themselves, increases on the other hand 
 the occupations; thus it incidentally makes gainful occupations 
 easier and more numerous; that is, the superfluity of one satisfies 
 the wants of others. And if here and there a citizen does not know 
 how to limit his outlays by the rules of private prudence, and ruins 
 himself, his wasted resources are, in the first place, no loss for the 
 state, because they merely pass out of one hand into the other, or are 
 transferred to many persons; second, the ruin of the one may per- 
 haps have provided the support of ten families of the laboring class 
 of the nation. With this explanation all, even the most plausible, 
 objections to luxury may be answered (10). 
 
 At the same time, however, the boundaries between useful and 
 harmful luxury may be determined. For without doubt there is a 
 sort of luxury which is harmful. All luxury, for example, is harmful, 
 which contradicts the purpose for the sake of which the state should 
 encourage it, which does not increase the sum of national occupations, 
 but diminishes it. This occurs in the case of unnecessary foreign 
 articles of luxury and also in the case of those which are not made 
 in the country itself, because these foreign wares always take the place 
 of a national ware, and crowd the latter out of the sum of national 
 occupations. One case only deserves to be regarded as an exception, 
 viz., when the foreign article of luxury has come in, not by purchase 
 but in exchange for a ware produced at home. In this instance 
 justice is done in advance both to national consumption and to all 
 demands of the foreigners who wanted to acquire it by purchase or 
 in exchange for wants. In this case, however, it is only the extension 
 of a branch of the occupation. The foreign article of luxury takes 
 the place of the national product (11). 
 
 The outlay that is restricted to domestic products cannot be 
 increased without end. The resources of those who use these prod- 
 ucts, and their number, constitute their necessary limits. Commerce 
 would thus not be greater than the possible national consumption. 
 There remains, however, the extension of the same on another 
 side, through increase of consumption. Takers of the wares will 
 be sought outside the country. The effort is made to supply other 
 nations with what they need, and through their consumption to
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 537 
 
 increase the sum of national occupation. Commerce thus divides 
 itself into domestic and foreign. Domestic commerce is that which 
 is carried on between the members of a state (12). 
 
 Foreign commerce is carried on with foreigners. It must neces- 
 sarily be based on domestic commerce, and it must give up something 
 to foreigners only when it has first satisfied the national wants. Thus 
 foreign commerce is carried on only with the surplus; that is, with 
 that which the national consumption can spare. On the other 
 hand a nation will take either only such wares as it really needs, 
 or those to the taking of which it is drawn by powerful stimuli. 
 These two grounds determine takers in general, but a state will be 
 moved to take from precisely this nation, inasmuch as the same 
 wares may actually be had from several sides, only through the most 
 advantageous, or the least disadvantageous conditions under which 
 a ware is offered. These conditions affect the price of wares, or 
 their qualities (13). 
 
 Scarcely any state or nation, at least under present circumstances, 
 and with the once introduced mode of life, will be sufficient unto 
 itself. What it does not possess, it must try to get from abroad 
 under the least oppressive conditions. To this end external com- 
 merce furnishes its aid, and in accordance with the division of its 
 occupation it is divided into two branches, viz., export and import. 
 It carries out, from the surplus; it brings in for a double purpose, either 
 to use the imported articles itself, or to export them again, with 
 advantage, to other nations (14). 
 
 This last makes a third branch of commerce, re-export [Wieder- 
 ausfuhr], called economic commerce [okonomische Handlung]. If its 
 advantage consisted only in the occupation of persons engaged in trade, 
 and in the increase of navigation or of wainage, re-export would even 
 then be highly important for a state. It would be giving occupation to 
 a part of the citizens at the cost of other nations. But this is not the 
 whole of the advantage, and the re-exporting state increases thereby 
 the national stock [Nationalhauptstamm] to the extent of the excess 
 of the selling price over the price of purchase, which is always a na- 
 tion's gain if it may not always be the gain of the merchant (15).' 
 
 1 A note explains the last clause as follows: "A merchant buys 
 cloth for 10 in England; the national capital is diminished by 10. The
 
 53 8 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The less a nation has to receive from others for its own wants, 
 and the more sales it can make to other nations, the more advan- 
 tageous is its commerce. But the situation in different regions does 
 not always afford to countries either the requisite quantity or the 
 variety of wares necessary for their own consumption and for export. 
 The commercial states, particularly the maritime provinces, turned 
 their gaze in consequence toward the islands, sought to subjugate 
 the same, and to secure possession through settlers transplanted 
 thither, whence they have the name colonies, or settlements [Pflanz- 
 orter}. Thence they may now draw a part of their wants, independ- 
 ent of other states and under self-imposed conditions, and they may 
 increase without limit the stuff to be exported thither (16). 
 
 The wants which are obtained from other states, and that which 
 is sent abroad, must be transported to the place of sale. This trans- 
 portation, which is denoted by the word "carriage" [Fracht], may 
 occur in various ways. The nation receives its own wants through 
 foreign carriage; and foreigners bring that which they are to receive 
 by their own carriage; or the nation brings in by its own carriage what 
 it receives from others, and returns by its own carriage what other 
 nations buy. In the former case the nation loses the whole advan- 
 tage of the occupation, which reciprocal carriage was capable of 
 creating; and its commerce is thus in a certain sense passive. In 
 the second case the nation appropriates this advantage and its com- 
 merce becomes more active. Every nation must therefore seek to 
 receive its wants through its own carriage and to deliver exports to 
 other nations with its own carriage (17). 
 
 Carriage is by land or by water. Land carriage depends on 
 good commercial roads and a well-conducted carrying system (18). 
 
 Water carriage is on rivers or on the sea. River navigation is 
 promoted by making and keeping rivers navigable, and by uniting 
 rivers by means of canals and locks. These arrangements cannot 
 be extended beyond the boundaries of a state. Sea carriage, on the 
 
 merchant pays for freight i, for storage, handling, etc., 3, so that the 
 cloth stands the merchant at 14; but because the ship was a national 
 ship, and the other outlays were within the country, or paid to citizens, 
 the national capital has not lost these 4. The merchant sells the cloth 
 for 18. The nation gains 8, the merchant, however, only 4."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 539 
 
 contrary, is of incomparably greater extent. It depends upon a 
 well-organized and supported merchant-marine (19). 
 
 The danger of carrying, especially at sea, would of itself frighten 
 from undertakings, because only few have enough courage to risk 
 their whole resources, or a considerable portion of them, for a gain 
 which is in no proportion to the possible and often very probable 
 loss. 1 The costs of carriage would also mount very high on account 
 of this consideration, because the carrier would take into account 
 the risk which he undertook. The danger of carriage may be 
 approximately estimated, and according to this estimate the goods 
 and ships may be made secure for a proportional compensation. 
 From this making secure the business has the name insurance or 
 assurance, whereby the courage for commercial undertakings is 
 produced and increased (20). 
 
 In the most favorable situation of a state, it is not possible greatly 
 to extend commerce, or to maintain already extensive commerce, 
 without a corresponding sum of money. The presence of money is 
 necessary from two points of view: the state must in general not 
 lack money as a promoter of national exertion; in particular com- 
 merce must not lack an adequate fund for its undertakings (21). 
 
 The physical presence of money in a state does not give to enter- 
 prise the energy which comports with the purpose of commerce. 
 It is necessary that the money shall do its work, and shall circulate 
 among the members of society. It is therefore a special duty of the 
 state to promote the circulation, and to remove all hindrances which 
 might obstruct the same (22). 
 
 In case, however, for whatever cause, the circulating sum of 
 money is either insufficient, or diminished, means must be sought 
 to replace the deficiency. The work [Verrichtung] of money is as 
 follows: to be to its possessors the reliable representation of a certain quan- 
 tity of wares, to tJie effect that whenever it pleases them they may exchange 
 the representation for that which is represented. If it is possible for a 
 state to succeed in procuring, for verbal consent, or for certain other 
 signs, the same confidence, that, as money represented the wares, 
 these signs represent the money, these arbitrary signs will then accom- 
 1 This is almost an exact repetition of Justi, but the proposition was 
 probably a commonplace at the time.
 
 540 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 plish the work of money, and will temporarily make up completely 
 for its absence. No care will therefore be too great which the ruler 
 may devote to the maintenance of public confidence (23). 
 
 If commercial enterprises are to be carried on energetically, they 
 will require great sums. Only a few individual citizens in a state 
 have the means or the credit, and those who have both have not 
 always resolution enough to risk so much in undertakings from which 
 to be sure great gain may be expected, which however are always 
 exposed to an uncertain outcome. Where the means of individuals 
 are not sufficient, an association is formed, each member of which 
 risks only a small sum the more resolutely because in any event 
 the loss would not impair his fortune; and yet the total of these 
 separate contributions procures for commerce the adequate fund. 
 The commercial associations accordingly contribute a large portion 
 to the extension of commerce (24). 
 
 Through export to foreigners and import from foreigners the 
 commercial nations become reciprocal debtors. The discharge of 
 these debts with ready money would be expensive, through the car- 
 riage of the money to the place of payment, and also dangerous; the 
 money in carriage would be a considerable time unused, and the 
 business of commerce would be plunged into tedious straggling \Weit- 
 laufigkeit]. It is possible to avoid these difficulties in whole or in 
 part, if a state exchanges its claims with another, whereby it dis- 
 charges its debts in so far as the condition of their commerce with 
 each other permits. This exchange of reciprocal claims gave rise 
 to the business of dealing in exchange, which to be sure is only a 
 private affair, but it is always worthy of public attention, because 
 it either facilitates or retards general commerce, and in addition fur- 
 nishes useful information for the guidance of the same (25). 
 
 In the present situation of science and knowledge, all cabinets 
 are in such wise enlightened about the great influence of commerce 
 that each nation must expect to be crossed [durchkreuzt] in all under- 
 takings by the states with which commerce is carried on, or through 
 whose territory the commerce will take its course, whenever it runs 
 counter to their purposes. It is necessary to anticipate these hin- 
 drances, and at favorable opportunities, by means of negotiation, to 
 assure advantageous conditions both for oneself and against other
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 541 
 
 rivals. Commercial treaties consequently constitute an important 
 part of Handlungspolitik (16). 
 
 In order to know the status of commerce in itself and relatively 
 and therefrom to conclude whether the course of affairs conduces to 
 the utmost expansion of population, states compare the amount 
 which they have supplied to others with that which they have received. 
 This comparison of import and export is called the balance: the 
 plumb line in the hands of the state to show where and in what parts 
 commerce requires special aid (27). 
 
 From the foregoing merely general concepts we see how numerous 
 and far reaching are the knowledge, purposes, combinations, and 
 plans which must be made the basis of advantageous commerce; 
 and the necessity of controlling this important business through the 
 combined insight of capable men, and incidentally of establishing 
 for the conduct of commerce a special Kollegium, or a special Stelle, 
 is thus very obvious. The name in itself is a matter of indifference, 
 but this Kollegium must embrace in the circuit of its activity every- 
 thing which can promote the advantage of commerce (28). 
 
 The most important features of the main argument in this 
 volume are discussed in the next chapter.
 
 CHAPTER XXI 
 
 THE CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 
 ("HANDLUNG UND FINANZ") 
 
 In two or three particulars more direct light is focused 
 on factors of firstrate importance for our argument by chaps, 
 i and ii of Sonnenfels' second volume, than by an equal portion 
 of any of the works thus far reviewed. 
 
 In the first place a relatively minor matter of methodology 
 deserves passing remark. Chap, i, on rural management, 
 occupies 116 pages, and chap, ii, on manufactures, 157 pages: 
 a total of 273 out of the 564 pages in the body of the book. 
 Attention is called to this division as a commentary on the 
 lack of precision in the title Handlung which for reasons stated 
 above we are obliged to render "commerce." 1 It must be 
 said, on the other hand, that a considerable portion of chap, ii 
 is concerned with relations of manufacture to trade, primarily 
 domestic, so that commerce in the strict sense creeps into the 
 discussion earlier than the titles of chapters would indicate. 
 Nor is the mere proportion of pages given to various topics 
 a safe guide to the logical value assigned to different portions 
 of subject-matter. It remains true, however, that Sonnenfels' 
 classification of material under the term Handlung was ex- 
 tremely uncritical. 
 
 In the second place, it must be admitted that we are not 
 entitled to infer from a book of this type anything very specific 
 about the actual administrations for which the book offers 
 a technology. To what extent the government of the German 
 states as a whole, or of any of them, approached the ideal set 
 forth in Sonnenfels' theory must be determined by other sorts 
 of evidence. Neither the original sources nor even the second- 
 
 1 Vide above, p. 525. 
 
 542
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 543 
 
 ary authorities on this line of evidence can be brought within 
 the compass of our present argument; the former, because they 
 are inaccessible to investigators on this side the ocean, the latter, 
 because a digest of the material would require a separate 
 volume. We must repeat then that we have to do merely 
 with the theory of cameral administration as it appeared in the 
 literary versions. 
 
 With these qualifications, we may state positively, third, 
 that one must be disqualified by invincible prejudice if candid 
 study of this book did not arouse a certain degree of admiration 
 for the comprehensiveness, and prudent attention to details, 
 involved in the ideals of cameralism. By comparison with 
 administrations which attempted anything approaching the 
 systematic and thorough management here outlined, democracy 
 as practiced in America has been slovenly, improvident, and 
 reckless. 
 
 In the fourth place, this second volume reflects at its best 
 the fundamental cameralistic conception of the state. With- 
 out referring to the more abstract legal theories of the relation 
 of the concepts "state," "government," "people," etc., the 
 working resultant of all these was an assumption of a com- 
 munity pictured as a great landed estate, 'which was such a 
 unity that every part and member had to be considered as 
 having an importance for the whole, and the task of the admin- 
 istration of the whole was to see that nothing was neglected 
 which might serve to insure that efficiency of every resource 
 within the whole which might contribute to the well-being of 
 the aggregate. Whatever our philosophical preconceptions, 
 they are tending toward a common expression in terms of values 
 ascertained and agreed upon in the course of experience. 
 Certain things are found to be worth while. If other things 
 interfere with those which we judge to be worth while, they 
 must drop out of competition and give place to the more highly 
 valued things. Suppose a modern democrat has no tolerance
 
 544 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 whatsoever for the basic political philosophy of cameralism. 
 He could hardly be intolerant enough to deny that in this book 
 Sonnenfels has done something worthy of praise. He has 
 drawn a wonderfully farsighted and inclusive sketch of things 
 that people must learn to provide for, in some way or other, 
 before they can make the most of life. It is difficult to show 
 this without reproducing his discussion in detail, but the follow- 
 ing pages contain an attempt to digest the argument in a way 
 that will confirm this estimate. 
 
 At the same time our purpose calls for attention to the 
 embryonic state of the concepts employed in the argument. 
 We must keep in mind that Sonnenfels' problems were not our 
 problems. His social science did not correspond precisely 
 with any division or definition of social science today, much 
 more than the "rhetoric" of the schoolmen tallied with any 
 field of knowledge recognized in modern classifications. 
 Especially must we discriminate between the administrative 
 problems which he proposed and problems of pure eco- 
 nomics. The latter are implicit in the former, but as we 
 have repeatedly pointed out, we misinterpret and misvalue 
 the theories of this period if we construe them as theorems 
 applied by their authors to the more general problems of the 
 abstract economists. 
 
 The last proposition is in order at once, when we begin 
 to examine the concept Landwirthschaft (chap. i). Neither 
 in England nor in America does anything exist today which 
 quite corresponds with the activities which Sonnenfels included 
 under the term. Let us render it as we have in previous cases, 
 "rural management." The term applies, however, to a con- 
 ception of the situation which it is difficult for Americans to 
 keep in mind. The whole national territory is presumed to 
 be virtually a farm, to be operated for the advantage of the 
 state; and it is the right and duty of the government to see 
 that every foot of the farm is thriftily cultivated. The occu-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 545 
 
 pants of the soil are regarded as indentured to the stale, and it 
 is the right and duty of the government to dispose of their 
 labor-ability so as to make the land most fruitful, just as it is 
 the business of the managers of a modern factory to organize 
 the help so that their combined labor will be most profitable 
 for the company. That is, "rural management" connoted to 
 the cameralist, and to the governments of the quasi-absolutistic 
 states, a plane of administrative function which correlated 
 individual extractive occupations in a way virtually unknown 
 in America. Our Department of Agriculture, our Geological 
 Survey, our irrigation and forestry enterprises, our agricultural 
 colleges and experiment stations are recent and partial approxi- 
 mations to certain features involved in the German system; 
 but they rest upon a quite different theory of the relation of 
 the state to individuals, and for that reason are essentially 
 unlike much that cameralistic "rural management" included. 
 On the other hand, this phrase did not include the special 
 technique of extractive industries. Both sides of this formal 
 description of the concept will be illustrated by details in the 
 following re'sume'. 
 
 Sec. 30 begins with betrayal of the complexity of the classi- 
 fication which the author adopted. He says: 
 
 Rural management is regarded in Polizey as the occupation which 
 provides means of life; in its commercial functions [Handlnngsleis- 
 tung] as also providing the material [Stofi] . 
 
 It is added at once that the phrase is used to include the 
 procuring of raw material from all three realms of nature, "the 
 vegetable kingdom, the animal kingdom, and the mineral 
 kingdom." Sonnenfels proposes, however, to deal principally 
 with agricultural management, including stock-raising, in so 
 far as the latter is combined with the former; and "only 
 in the political aspect, not in practical technique, which it is 
 the business of the so-called Oekonomie to treat." The stand-
 
 546 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 point from which tne discussion starts is further indicated 
 (31) by the specifications: 
 
 "Considered from the side of the state, the perfection of rural 
 management consists in the best possible utilization of the earth 1 
 in accordance with the demands of subsistence [Unterhalls] and of 
 commerce." A note adds: "From the side of the proprietor, it 
 is the best combination of the largest yield with the least expenditure" 
 [Vorauslage]. 
 
 This resuk will have to be sought: 
 
 I, by utilizing all the earth; II, by utilizing it in the best way 
 as respects systems of cultivation; and III, by utilizing it as required 
 by relations to the other connected or dependent occupations. The 
 use of all the earth, and the best use of the same, coincide in many 
 ways in obstacles and in furtherance. 
 
 Sec. 32 seems to start upon the trail of a cardinal sociologi- 
 cal distinction, but it is immediately dropped, and nothing is 
 done to follow out the fundamental implications of the distinc- 
 tion. The first sentence reads: 
 
 The earth is either private property, or the means of the state.* 
 
 The dictum follows that: 
 
 In order to make full use of private property, the proprietor must 
 have first the necessary power, and second the necessary motives. 
 
 'The word is Erdreich. We might of course render it "land," 
 but this would immediately force upon it an interpretation as equivalent 
 to that term in its later technical sense. Our version is chosen to avoid 
 that anachronism and to preserve the archaic connotations of the term. 
 
 * " Das Erdreich ist entweder Privateigenthum oder Vermogen des 
 Staates." This juxtaposition of Eigenthum and Vermdgen brings out 
 the fact previously noted, that the two terms are sometimes used inter- 
 changeably, and sometimes with an approach to respect for their ety- 
 mological distinctions. The result is uncritical and fallacious German 
 usage. Translation into English usually makes the matter worse. It 
 is a correct general proposition that at this period the class of writers we 
 are dealing with were unconcerned about precise discrimination between 
 the ethical, the legal, and the merely objective material connotations 
 of the two words.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 547 
 
 Lack of means for rural management may be regarded from two 
 sides (33) ; namely, the poverty of the rural folk as a class, or of the 
 particular cultivator. The former condition comes from such 
 unavoidable circumstances as first, wars, loss of cattle, failure of 
 crops, the poverty of the present possessor, or only from his tempo- 
 rary embarrassment. 
 
 Each of these types of misfortune is treated as deserving of pub- 
 lic attention. Means of extinguishing fires are to be provided by 
 the local administration; the dwellings are to be in village groups, 
 not scattered over the land, and the garden plots are to be located 
 between the houses instead of behind them, the barns to be separated 
 from the houses, etc., in order that there may be the minimum dan- 
 ger from fire with the maximum facility of controlling it. Districts 
 should also maintain systems of mutual fire insurance; proprietors 
 should be made to see that their interests demand such precautions. 
 In case such protection is lacking, the cultivator who is embarrassed 
 must be assisted either by the proprietor or by the state. Mere 
 negative help, which is customary, i. e., remission of the dues, does 
 not meet the case. Active help must be given, e. g., lumber, building 
 materials, farming implements; seed must be furnished gratuitously, 
 or at least on the easiest terms. If the individual proprietors are not 
 in a position to do this, it must be done by the state. The alternative 
 is sterilization of the soil, declining value of the revenues of the state, 
 and diminishing population. To remedy these conditions is more 
 expensive than to prevent them. The direct and indirect conse- 
 quences of cattle diseases are among the important objects of public 
 attention. To prevent them veterinary schools should be introduced 
 (36), and the causes of the diseases should be investigated. 1 The 
 price of salt, and provision that farmers shall have easy access to 
 it are important in this connection, and should be carefully looked 
 to by the state. In case of failure of crops, as in case of fire or war, 
 the cultivator must be helped either by the proprietor or the state 
 to raise his crops the following year. The state must take measures 
 to prevent exorbitant or oppressive terms in case of loans by individ- 
 
 A note states that the so-called Ecole vtttrinairt was opened in 
 Vienna in 1766. At first only treatment of horses was attempted, but 
 attention was later extended to all species of farm animals.
 
 548 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 uals (37). In case an individual proprietor is too poor properly to 
 cultivate his tract, the state is in danger of suffering loss of a portion 
 of its dues. There is therefore no reason why the state should not 
 have the right to require that the proprietor should permit others 
 to cultivate the land on shares, or to purchase it. The very circum- 
 stances which have caused the embarrassment of the proprietor may 
 make such purchaser or farmer hard to find. The flocking of per- 
 sons of means to the cities leaves the cultivation of the soil to an 
 inferior class of people. In case forced sale is necessary, the state 
 should provisionally take over the property at a fair price, in order 
 that the possessor may not be compelled to make too great sacrifice 
 (38). Land is often uncultivated, not by reason of the perma- 
 nent but the temporary poverty of the possessor (39). It is an 
 unpardonable mistake of the law-making power to aggravate this 
 helplessness by exaction of the usual dues. The proprietor who 
 has allowed the tenant to fall into arrears should be declared to have 
 forfeited the amount. 
 
 Laws should seek to prevent excessive debt by setting a limit to 
 the amount which may be borrowed (40). An exception should 
 be made in case the loan is necessary for actual cultivation of the 
 land, and the conditions of loans for that purpose should be made 
 especially favorable, and should be under the oversight of the proper 
 officials. 
 
 Unthrift on the part of proprietors will be checked by the intro- 
 duction of supervisors of rural management [Landwirthschajtsauj- 
 sicht] v4i), consisting of the officials of the circuit [Kreis] to whom 
 a subordinate might be added, and the private managers subordinated 
 to these. 1 
 
 A second means of preventing neglect of proper cultivation is 
 afforded by the dues to the state (42). That is, every piece of 
 arable land should be taxed on a moderate estimate of what 
 it would yield if properly cultivated. Thus the occupant will 
 be compelled to cultivate the land or to pay dues for land which 
 yields him no crop, while the industrious cultivator receives as it 
 1 The word Oekonomieaufseher is used later in the section apparently 
 as a designation for the officials constituted supervisors of agricultural 
 management.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 549 
 
 were a reward for his industry, in being assessed only on a medium 
 rate of yield. 
 
 If these means are not sufficient to secure good cultivation, a 
 third remains. It seems severe, but it is not if the others have failed 
 (43), viz.: In case a piece of land has remained uncultivated two or 
 three years, unless the proprietor can offer to the supervisors an ade- 
 quate excuse, it shall be declared forfeited, and transferred to some- 
 one who will cultivate it. Such a provision is based on the claim 
 which the state has upon the private property of the citizens, for 
 proportional contribution for maintenance of the whole. The 
 forfeiture here proposed can no more be regarded as an invasion of 
 property rights than the law of limitations. The security of property 
 is only conditionally assured by the state, viz., in case the private 
 proprietor does not impair the property of the state. 
 
 The lack of courage on the part of the cultivator has its ground 
 in the opinion that his labor is lost, and that he will not reap its fruits 
 (44). The insecurity of property, the rate of taxation, and the 
 excessively favored love of hunting, on the part both of the sovereign 
 prince and of the private owners, may be regarded as the chief causes 
 of this lack of courage, and the multitude of idle days may be added. 
 
 In case the insecurity of property has its origin in the defective 
 fundamental order [Grundverfassung] of a country, it will always 
 be difficult for the laws to limit the evil (45).' If the private posses- 
 sors .considered, however, that such fundamental order made against 
 their own advantage, they would not oppose abrogation of the same. 
 The right which is based on ancient possession is made very question- 
 able through the older and imprescriptible rights of mankind.* 
 Where the tenants in a certain sense are regarded only as farmers 
 
 1 The term Grundverfassung, in the idiom of this period, had the 
 effect of a pun. It seems to have carried partially a literal and par- 
 tially a derived meaning. That is, the concept in the author's mind 
 seems to have been a blur of the two notions, land tenure and constitution 
 in something approaching the modern sense. 
 
 8 This is the passage cited by Roscher in support of the proposition: 
 "It is characteristic of Sonnenfels' absolutism to be more liberal at the 
 expense of private rights than at the expense of governmental power." 
 Vide above, p. 485. Roscher's point appears to be well taken.
 
 55 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 [Pachtinhaber] the lords of the soil think they do wisely when they 
 transfer a thrifty farmer to the holdings of a negligent one. Instead 
 of increasing the industry of each, they ruin both. The negligent 
 one shirks work because he is negligent, because this negligence is 
 rewarded, and he keeps hoping for the same reason to be transferred 
 to a better cultivated location. The thrifty one is discouraged and 
 refuses to make improvements which would give occasion for another 
 transfer. Since this right has such great influence upon the condition 
 of rural management in general, we cannot but approve a system 
 which would assure to the peasants a tenure for life at least, and 
 the abolition of this freedom of transfer. 1 
 
 The evictions [Abstijtungen] which the officials are sometimes 
 empowered to make must also be reckoned as unfavorable to the 
 security of property (45, 46). They must consequently never be a 
 one-sided procedure. Even the economic supervisors must have 
 their hands bound in this respect; how much more the private 
 owners. 
 
 The tiller of the soil will work only hard enough to maintain 
 life, if all the rest of his produce is taken from him by landlord and 
 government (47). Experience proves how little statesmanship 
 there is in the proposition, "The peasant is most industrious when 
 he is miserable." 
 
 Sees. 48 and 49 recite some of the hardships which hunting rights 
 inflict on cultivators of the soil, and point out the depressing effect 
 of these hardships upon cultivation in general. The author observes 
 that the restrictions which the laws ostensibly put on these rights arc 
 always ineffective in practice. The indemnities allowed to the farm- 
 ers are awarded by the parties who inflict the losses, and conse- 
 quently do not compensate the loser, while it is impossible to repair 
 
 ' A note (p. 55) speaks of "Die okon. Gescllschafl zu Petersburg." 
 The note continues: "The organization in 1765 offered a prize on this 
 subject: 'Is it to the advantage of the state that the peasants should 
 jxwsess property ? Docs this question do credit to a government ? to 
 our century ? to mankind ? ' The better solutions are the monograph 
 which received the prize, under the title, La Felicite publique and another 
 by Bearde de 1'Abbayc. Meritorious also were those of Woelnor, Mark, 
 Ocder, and Merkel."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 55 1 
 
 the damage done to the national productiveness in general. The 
 time and loss of rest expended on protecting crops against game 
 are a great drain on the resources of the country. An ordinance of 
 Joseph II, dated January, 1786, is called a long-overdue attempt 
 to protect the general welfare of many against a very equivocal 
 pleasure of the few. 
 
 The depressing influence of fast days and other holidays upon 
 agriculture is referred to again in 49, and complaint is made that 
 "the obstinacy or the caprice of the pastor" determines whether the 
 peasants shall be permitted to take advantage of good weather on such 
 a day, after protracted rain, to make sure of the crop for which they 
 have toiled earlier in the season. While Sonnenfels here betrays 
 independence of ecclesiastical tradition, yet one detects in his tone 
 no such bitterness toward the clergy as is frequently exhibited by 
 Justi. 
 
 In 50 the author verges upon economic generalization in the 
 Smithian sense. Thus he says: "The more incentives to labor 
 are presented to the farmer, the greater will be his diligence. The 
 first motive for him is the support of self and family; the second, the 
 tribute [Entrichttmg] to which he is bound; the third, the desire 
 to lay by something in case of need, for the improvement of his con- 
 dition, or for his family. The products of the soil must not fall below 
 a value which affords the hope that all three motives may be satisfied. 
 In determining this price the interests of agriculture seem to be 
 to a certain extent opposed to those of other kinds of business [Hand- 
 lungsgeschajte]. If the price of agricultural products is high, the 
 price of every manufactured product must rise, whereby one of the 
 principal qualities of a ware, cheapness, is lost. If the price of agri- 
 cultural products is low, it is not sufficiently encouraging for the 
 farmer, and he finds it to his advantage to produce 1 less, because from 
 half the crop He can then receive a like sum, and save himself trouble, 
 time, seed, etc. Only the medium price remains therefore where 
 the interests of both branches can be combined. This medium price 
 may be considered in its essence or merely numerically." 
 
 The subject is continued in 51: "In its essence the medium 
 price is always and everywhere the same: the price, namely, which 
 > Erzielen; vide above, pp. 532 and 534.
 
 552 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 stands in such relation to the condition of commerce in general 1 that 
 thereby land management may get its proportional share of the gain 
 which comes from commerce. This sharing in the general advan- 
 tage is not only just, it is also necessary. The state is under obliga- 
 tions to observe and maintain equality between the members of society 
 according to the degree of their reciprocal contribution to the general 
 welfare. Where this equality is not observed the neglected part 
 lacks those encouragements which must be the spur to and the real 
 soul of diligence. It is also unavoidably demanded in order that 
 the worth of the agricultural products may procure for the seller 
 adequate means of satisfying his other wants, that in the degree 
 in which the wants either rise in price, or otherwise, as through the 
 prosperity of commerce, the prosperity of the working class, and 
 with the same the number of their wants increases the farmer shall 
 find enough in the price of his products to procure either the higher- 
 priced or the more numerous wants. If his way" to this result is 
 closed by an arbitrary fixing of the price, it would follow in the one 
 case that his wants would not be satisfied, whereby he would be forced 
 to interrupt his labor; or, in the other case, his condition would be 
 at least relatively more unfortunate than that of the other working 
 classes. The peasant class would consequently be abandoned, 
 because it would be eager to improve its lot by going over to the other 
 classes. Those that would remain in the class would be without 
 means, or would avenge themselves by indolence for the unrighteous- 
 ness of society." 
 
 The conclusion is drawn in 52: "It is consequently necessary 
 from so many grounds to assure to land management through the 
 medium price its share of the gains of commerce. But the regulation 
 of the medium price cannot occur through the taxes, but through 
 the reciprocal agreements of purchasers and sellers in the market 
 place, if no hindrances are otherwise placed in the way of the free- 
 dom of these compacts.' If the varying market price of several 
 ordinary years is compared, and the average reckoned, this will be 
 
 ' The word is Handlung, and with the variation noted in $50 it 
 illustrates the lack of uniformity in usage throughout the book. 
 
 * A note cites as such hindrance the ancient right of the lord to an 
 option on the produce before it is taken to market.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 553 
 
 taken as the numerical mean, which is variable according to circum- 
 stances." 
 
 Still further, in 53, Sonnenfels has an elementary statement of 
 the demand side of price, with the corollary that "the state must see 
 that the number of sellers is not too great, and also that a proportional 
 number of customers for agricultural products may be assured." 
 In 54 natural variations of demand and supply are further discussed 
 in contrast with forced variations, e. g., through constraint upon the 
 peasants to pay their taxes at a certain time. The closer this date 
 is to the harvest the greater the disadvantage to the farmer. The 
 cheapness of farm products at such a time is one of the principal 
 causes of the ruin of agriculture. "The state has therefore not 
 merely to moderate the fiscal burdens upon agriculture, but to pre- 
 vent cheapening of the produce by spreading the payment over 
 various periods." 1 
 
 The sections just epitomized (50-54) are notable for 
 several reasons. In the first place, they present the familiar 
 conception of the state as a something which is set over against 
 the component elements of the nation. In the second place, 
 they consistently presume that the state can and must regulate 
 prices. In the third place, they show that some of the elemen- 
 tary facts of market valuation, which eventually show the 
 impotence of statute law against economic law, were beginning 
 to make an impression. Sonnenfels does not go very far 
 toward drawing the involved conclusions, but the difference 
 between him and Justi in this connection is not so much in 
 variations of view about particulars, as in the extent to which 
 Sonnenfels betrays a sort of premonition that something deeper 
 than laws of the state is the key to the situation. 
 
 Sec. 55 analyzes demand into that of national and that of foreign 
 consumers. As to the former^ it is not enough that there should be. 
 a favorable proportion between agricultural products and consum- 
 ers, i. e., 'a large population; it is at the same time necessary that 
 
 1 A note names Michaelmas (September 29) as the time shown 
 by experience to be fairest for the payment of agricultural taxes.
 
 554 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 this population shall be distributed so that local demand and supply 
 shall be balanced. Otherwise the purchasers will control prices 
 at one point, and sellers at another. The former situation tends to 
 ruin agriculture. Hence disproportionate flocking of people to 
 chief cities is the main cause of the decline of agriculture (56). 
 Those states therefore are most prosperous in this respect which 
 have numerous provincial cities in which the landed gentry reside. 
 Here manufactures will also spring up, and become middle points 
 of consumption, through which money will circulate uniformly in 
 all localities. If these intermediate cities did not exist, this division 
 of consumers might be otherwise secured, e. g., by forbidding the 
 nobility not in the service of the government permanently to leave 
 their estates, and by distributing over the country those consumers 
 that are not necessarily located in the capital, e. g., factories, alms- 
 houses, universities, a great number of cloisters, etc. From the 
 same point of view 57 discusses the operation of intermediate tariffs 
 between provinces of the same state; the inference is that both 
 agriculture and the state suffer if artificial barriers limit the extent 
 of the market. 
 
 But the demand of national consumers cannot, at the present 
 rate of population, assure to agriculture the price necessary for its 
 encouragement (58).' Hope of foreign markets alone can stimu- 
 late the farmer to cultivate all his land, and give him courage for 
 better cultivation. This hope will be animated by freedom of export. 
 "Opinions about the advantage of free trade in grain, and about 
 the limits of the freedom, have varied among times, states, and writers 
 (59). Early times did not consider agriculture in connection with 
 commerce, and fear of scarcity long restricted export of grain. On 
 the contrary, writers of eminence have urged unlimited freedom in 
 this respect at all times and places. The purpose and the effect of 
 free export of grain must be to assure a sufficiently remunerative 
 price for agricultural products without embarrassing national con- 
 sumption. This combination is secured in a freedom of export 
 which is not directly limited in quantity but by rise of price above 
 1 The number that the land could support per square mile (German) 
 is estimated by Sonnenfels as 1,500; this after comparison with Siiss- 
 milch's estimate of 2,750, and Vauban's of 2,361.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 555 
 
 an accepted mean. In application this principle will have the expres- 
 sion: Everyone has freedom to export grain so long as the price at 
 such and such markets does not exceed such and such figures." 1 
 
 "If administrative policy adopts this view, it rests on the prin- 
 ciple that the mean price is a sign of adequate supply [Feilschajt] 
 (60). If this is not the case the state is infallibly and immediately 
 informed of it by the advancing price. At the same time the counter- 
 influence begins to work. Export ceases, and the national market 
 contains what had been exported. Thereupon the price falls. The 
 mean price and therewith freedom of export are restored. 
 
 "England began in 1689 to furnish the other nations an illus- 
 tration that freedom of foreign trade in grain not only supports the 
 cultivator in this industry, but is also capable of bringing agriculture 
 to perfection (61). Since that time other nations have tried still 
 harder to promote agriculture, and through this effort foreign trade 
 in grain has been greatly hindered. All the more must the law-giver 
 remove the internal hindrances and must assist the merchants by 
 external means, e. g., premiums on export, etc., so that they can 
 compete with the merchants of other nations." 
 
 These sections have been reviewed at such length because 
 they contain a neglected link in the chain of evidence which 
 accounts for the tendencies in political theory, both abstract 
 and technological, for the following half-century. The 
 remainder of the chapter is of minor importance for our chief 
 purpose. If affords cumulative evidence, however, of the 
 minuteness with which cameralism analyzed elements of 
 national prudence. 
 
 The immediately following sections (62, 63) refer to the prob- 
 lems of utilizing lands that for various reasons are wholly or partially 
 uncultivated. Sees. 64-79 develop the same problem in connection 
 with such details as means of assuring a proper proportion between 
 cultivators of the soil and other classes; discouragement of luxury; 
 restriction of the numbers of the servant class; the loss of labor 
 
 X A note begins with the words: "Die Oekonomisten, ein Zweig 
 der Encyklopedisten, fodern eine unter alien Umstlinden freye Ausfuhr." 
 The same use of the term Oekenomisten occurs in a note to 61.
 
 S5 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 through military service; colonization of laborers; means of making 
 new settlements prosperous; reclamation of waste lands through 
 clearing of forests, the draining of swamps, the construction of dykes 
 and protection of the same. Sees. 80-107 elaborate the following 
 proposition: "In order that the earth may be used to the best pur- 
 pose in respect to cultivation, it is necessary: 7, that the rural folk 
 shall possess the necessary knowledge of cultivation and of agricul- 
 tural improvements; II, that no hindrances shall stand in the way 
 of applying their knowledge; III, land which is devoted to other 
 purposes than cultivation must be managed with skill." 1 
 
 The center of attention under the first clause is the introduction 
 and development of various sorts of agricultural schools, and means 
 of scattering the information gathered by such schools among the 
 peasantry. 8 
 
 The second clause deals chiefly with hardships that come 
 from the methods of concentrating or dividing the land, from 
 the taxing system, or from survivals of feudal liabilities. On 
 the first subject it is asserted that "the French economists are 
 in general in favor of cultivation on a large scale, and assume 
 
 1 In this part of the book the following are referred to: "Wiegancl, 
 tier Verfasser des verniinftigen Landwirths;" no further clue is given; 
 "Young, Politische Arithmetik;" Ingram, in Enc. Brit., title "Arthur 
 Young," says: ". . . . in 1774 his Political Arithmetic, .... was soon 
 translated into several foreign languages." Other references are: 
 Nickols, Avant et Defavant, de la France, etc., e*dit nouvelle d'Amst. ; 
 Principes de la legislation universelle, author not named, but cited as repre- 
 senting "die franzosischen Oekonomisten;" Arbuthnot, Sur I'utilitf des 
 grandes Fermes et des riches Fermiers, traduit par Freville; Trait 6 poli- 
 tique et oeconomique sur les communes, ou observation sur I' agriculture, sur 
 I'origine, la destination et I'etat actuel des biens et communes, etc.; Getting, 
 Prcisschrift in dem hanoverischcn Magazin, p. 764; Peningthon, Rffte- 
 xions sur les avantages qui resultent du portage des communes pour itre 
 dffraichis et mis en clos; Schlettwein in dem hanov. Magazin, 704. 
 
 For instance, "An ordinance of the Austrian states, to the effect 
 that the calendars for the common people should not be printed, without 
 previous approval of the oconomischen Gesellschaften. These societies 
 are considered among the most important of these educational agencies.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 557 
 
 as certain that it is not possible to cultivate small holdings 
 profitably" (p. 128). In the same connection Arbuthnot is 
 cited as representing English opinion to the same effect. The 
 third clause is devoted to three classes of uses of the land by 
 which agriculture is the loser: meadows, common pastures, 
 and tracts reserved for beauty. 
 
 Chap, ii, on manufactures, begins with the definition: 
 "Manufactures, in the most extended and literal sense, are 
 all occupations which give a new form to any stuff whatsoever." 
 Millers, bakers, and all similar workers are expressly included 
 in the class of manufaturers. More specifically, manufac- 
 turers are those species of artisans who make a stock, or so- 
 called merchants' goods. 1 In the more proper sense, 
 
 Manufacture is the correlation of all the kinds of labor which 
 are demanded in order to make a ware complete, that is, to make 
 it marketable. The manufacturer is accordingly the citizen who 
 guides this correlation. 
 
 The purpose of manufactures, from the standpoint of the indi- 
 vidual manufacturer, is to provide support and gain; from the stand- 
 point of the whole stale, to increase the occupations; in other words, 
 through manufactures to give work and employment to a part of the 
 people which land management does not employ. 
 
 The paragraph continues: 
 
 From this point of view, from which manufactures must be 
 contemplated by the public administration, the designation by which 
 the economists 2 mean to depreciate the value of artisanship and of 
 the whole class of manufacturers, is a senseless play on words. The 
 amount advanced to manufactures is called by them "an unproduc- 
 
 1 Welche Verlag oder sogenanntes Kaufmannsgut machett. 
 
 3 The context brings out most clearly the shade of meaning which 
 Sonnenfels associated with this particular use of the term Oekonomisten; 
 that is, it was pretty nearly coextensive with the class Physiocrat and 
 it did not mean, as it did later, "one who is studying problems relating 
 to wealth." It meant "one who adheres to the peculiar theory about 
 sources of wealth advocated by the physiocrats."
 
 558 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 tive outlay" [unfruchtbare Auslage]; the class of manufacturers, "the 
 unproductive class," because, in the physical sense of the word, 
 they do not create [hervorbfingen] anything. The essential thing 
 is, however, not whether manufactures create, but, whether they 
 enlarge occupation, that is, whether they increase the means of sup- 
 port for the people, and herewith the population, the welfare of the 
 state from within, the security and prestige of the same from without. 
 This is the effect of manufactures. They themselves really originate 
 [erzielen] nothing; they are however the immediate occasion for 
 the origination of the stuff, which without the transformation of 
 artisanship would have no worth and consequently would not be 
 originated. 
 
 A note illustrates the author's meaning by the specification: 
 
 "Without the prospect of linen, flax would have little or no use. 
 Worked into Brabantian lace the price rises to such an extent that 
 the worth of the stuff entirely disappears." The text continues: 
 Manufacturers "are the immediate occasion for the enlargement 
 of agriculture, for they increase the consumption of the necessities 
 of life, which would otherwise be reduced to the demands of the culti- 
 vating families, and consequently would be without value. They 
 even occasion a real growth of national wealth. For, although, 
 according to the calculation of the physiocrats, in the case of an arti- 
 ficial product all parts of the investment [Vorauslage] can be resolved 
 into products of the soil [Erdreich], yet in the case of wares disposed 
 of abroad the gain of the merchant cannot be classified under that 
 head, but is a real addition either in equivalents of wealth [Numera- 
 rien] or in wares taken in exchange. 1 More than that, when the 
 Genevan clock-maker constructs of brass and steel worth perhaps 
 two gulden a clock which he sells abroad for thirty gulden, and then 
 in exchange for the thirty gulden imports fifteen measures of grain, 
 is not his skilled labor quite as fruit-bringing for Geneva as that of 
 a fanner who has got fifteen measures from his field ? On the other 
 hand, when a state raises a surplus of agricultural products, but is 
 
 1 A note adds the illustration: "A bale of cloth stands the merchant 
 in the marketplace of Sinigaglia 1,500. He sells it for 2,000. The gain 
 of 500 is increase of the mass."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 559 
 
 surrounded by states that are devoted to agriculture, its surplus 
 will find no sale, and because there is no prospect of disposing of it 
 no surplus will be raised. But a silk factory is established. The 
 laborers engaged in it consume the produce of the field. The silks 
 are exported. The state receives in exchange their worth. Is 
 it not indifferent to the state whether it exports grain in its original 
 form, or grain transformed into silk ? Only, that the skilled labor 
 obtained a sale which agriculture could not have obtained; only, 
 that the skilled labor furnishes a growth in occupation and so a growth 
 in population." 
 
 Sec. no draws the conclusion, which serves as the presump- 
 tion of the rest of the book: 
 
 Manufactures are thus, in the economy of the state, not unfruit- 
 ful, but a useful and an indispensable enlargement of occupation. In 
 the arranging [Anordnung] of manufactures the grades of promotion 
 are to be measured according to their contribution to the purpose 
 of the state, that is, according as the general mass of occupation is 
 enlarged and made more permanent. The general mass of occupa- 
 tion, however, gains only when artisan labor is a means of multiply- 
 ing the products of agriculture. 1 Those manufactures accordingly 
 deserve the first attention for which national stuff is either actually 
 in hand, or might be had with little trouble. Without observing this 
 consideration, agriculture not only loses a possible sale, and conse- 
 quently a portion of the occupation which it could appropriate; but 
 the manufacturing labor will be dependent upon those nations which 
 furnish the raw stuff. Therefore the occupation of the people, from 
 this side also, will exist only by favor [bittoveisc], that is, only so long 
 
 1 A note expands the argument in this way: "The harm which may 
 come to a nation in the various branches of its welfare is affirmative or 
 negative. The affirmative is diminution of the greatness which it pos- 
 sesses: if, for example, one thousand of the citizens emigrate, or a half- 
 million capital flows out without compensation. The negative is failure 
 to realize the growth which is within the power of the nation: if, for 
 example, the foreign trade is conducted with foreign carriage, whereby 
 the nation loses the cost of carriage in the selling price. In the calcula- 
 tion of political commerce, gains not made are entered on the debit side. 
 That is, what might have been gained and was not is reckoned as a loss."
 
 560 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as the nation from which the raw stuff is received either docs not 
 work it up itself, or it is not taken under more favorable conditions 
 by another nation, or for some reason or other the supplying nation 
 makes the export of the stuff more difficult, or finally for political 
 reasons the supplying nation stops production of this stuff altogether. 
 
 Continuing the argument, m proceeds: 
 
 It is worth while to draw out the consequences of such a situation 
 still farther, in order to reach conviction of another truth, viz.: that 
 it is less harmful never to have extended occupations above a medium 
 number, than ultimately to lose something from a greater number. 
 In the former case, to be sure, the state will enjoy only a moderate 
 degree of prosperity, but it will maintain itself on that level. In 
 the other case the reversal of its prosperity will be almost without 
 limits. In such circumstances many people lose their occupation. 
 That is, they no longer receive the sum of money which they pre- 
 viously used for their support. Since it is not easy at once to absorb 
 an unemployed number into the ranks of the general gainful agen- 
 cies, the laborers who have lost their employment will be reduced 
 to the most miserable circumstances, and perhaps find themselves 
 compelled to emigrate in order to find ways of earning a living. I 
 will not follow out the consequences of diminution of the number 
 of marriages and other harmful accompanying effects, but restrict 
 myself to the most immediate. 
 
 The section closes with a brief but clear indication of the 
 different effects of a contraction of the market through with- 
 drawal of the purchasing power of the unemployed. 
 
 It would be difficult to epitomize the remainder of the chap- 
 ter, and a very general description must suffice. It must be 
 said with emphasis that this chapter would repay study today. 
 The men who are engaged in callings which apply this sort of 
 knowledge usually prefer to get their information by doing 
 the thing itself, rather than by consulting books. The men who 
 are responsible for the parliamentary process of enacting public 
 demands into law do not as a rule in this country attain emi- 
 nence as students of comparative legislation. The programmes
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 561 
 
 of more than a century ago do not appear to impress them as 
 likely to throw light on the problems of modern life. The 
 fact is that democracy has yet to learn how to co-operate as 
 effectively on the basis of its fundamental conceptions, as 
 quasi-absolutism did on the basis which democrats repudiate. 
 The German benevolent despotisms of the eighteenth century 
 took a more comprehensive survey of the different factors 
 which must lay the foundation of general prosperity than 
 American democracy has learned to take. These benevolent 
 despotisms accordingly planned more intelligent co-operation 
 of their interests and agencies than Americans have yet devised. 
 The German system wasted at the governmental end, on the 
 expenditures of the court, and on the military system, much 
 that this prudent thrift at the popular end enabled states to 
 save. On the other hand, we lose in actual convenience, com- 
 fort, and security of life much that the German paternalistic 
 system secured. Without surrendering any principle of 
 democratic political philosophy whatsoever, Americans may 
 well study the details of German quasi-absolutistic adminis- 
 tration, in order to learn from it elements of public and private 
 prudence which our pride of individualism has caused us to 
 neglect, and greatly to our own hurt. 
 
 The remainder of the chapter elaborates an analysis along 
 these lines: 
 
 A manufacture occupies more people in proportion to the amount 
 of preparation necessary before the stuff which it handles becomes 
 complete wares, and in proportion to the generality of its use (112). 
 The more common use of a ware depends upon it's sale to the greater 
 part of the people; that is, it must be of a quality and price which 
 the small means of the great numbers can purchase (113). It 
 would be at bottom to the advantage of manufacturers to give to their 
 wares the four features: cheap price, good quality, external beauty, 
 and variety. Shortsighted manufacturers should be compelled 
 to recognize this principle, so that they would not in the end make
 
 562 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 foreign purchases more desirable, and thus diminish the amount of 
 home occupation (114). In order to be able to sell wares of a poor 
 quality at a high price, the manufacturer must be in a position to 
 control the supply, and it must be something that the public needs. 
 If competitors enter into rivalry, the conditions are reversed. The 
 conjunction of the above conditions alone can insure to manufac- 
 tured articles those qualities which will multiply their sale (115). 
 So soon as an occupation yields profits, it is attractive enough for 
 itself; hence, to promote the active combination of factors above 
 named, not only affirmative means are necessary, but also negative, 
 i. e., removal of all hindrances to industry and zeal, e. g., monopolies, 
 exclusive societies, special privileges, manufactures supported by 
 the prince, exclusive guilds, and disproportionate levies upon a 
 manufacture. Examination of these hindrances in order will call 
 attention to principles which may never be neglected in conducting 
 manufactures (116-32). l 
 
 Throughout this discussion the word Zusammenfluss defies 
 translation. Collating all the passages in which it occurs 
 one would decide that the concept which the author generally 
 associated with it was "concurrence of all the conditions neces- 
 sary to insure the four qualities of manufactured goods 
 enumerated above." In certain cases it is plainly used in the 
 sense of "concourse," either of buyers, or sellers, or laborers, 
 or capitalists, as the case may be. In other passages it means 
 "agreement between competitors;" in others it apparently 
 puts the emphasis on the competition itself; while again the 
 
 1 While containing no distinctly new view, these sections show decided 
 advance in maturity over Becher's treatment of Monopolium and Propo- 
 lium. Vide above, pp. izSff. Sonnenfels' major premise throughout the 
 discussion is that the maximum powers of the state are not developed 
 unless the conditions are maintained in which goods are manufactured 
 within the nation in conformity with the four specifications. A very 
 fair anticipation of the modern argument against governmental conduct 
 of industry appears in 126 ff. In 130 the reference occurs: " Sur les 
 compagnies et les maitrises traduit de PAnglois. Chinki histoire 
 Chochin chinoise, p. Coyer."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 563 
 
 chief reference seems to be to the idea of a confluence of manu- 
 facturing enterprise into channels that would provide a suffi- 
 cient supply of goods. Sonnenfels apparently regards the word 
 as a sort of technical term, but it is not confined to a precise 
 idea. 
 
 Passing to another phase of the subject the analysis con- 
 tinues : 
 
 If the hindrances mentioned are out of the way, the zeal of indus- 
 try will be unrestrained, and its fortunate consequence will be the 
 perfection of manufactures. Each of the qualities which we have 
 specified as necessary to this perfection springs from a multitude 
 of separate parts, knowledge of which is necessary, and it will not 
 be practicable in considering them not to cast side glances at foreign 
 commerce (133). 
 
 Thereupon still more intensive analysis is undertaken of 
 the qualities of wares posited as essential, and of the conditions 
 requisite to insure them. Sees. 134-68 might be set apart 
 under the title, "The Elements Which Enter into the Price of 
 Manufactured Goods." Sees. 169-82 might be entitled, 
 "The Elements Which Enter into the Quality of Manufactured 
 Goods." Under the corresponding title, "The Elements 
 Which Enter into the Beauty of Manufactured Goods," we 
 should mark off a briefer passage, 183, 184. In a general 
 way an appropriate designation for the remainder of the chap- 
 ter (185-202) would be, "Factors Involved in Assuring 
 Variety of Goods." The details are largely technical primarily 
 on the side, of manufacture, or trade, or administrative policy, 
 as the case may be; and so do not fall immediately within the 
 scope of our inquiry; but the underlying criterion gives the 
 discussion its principal significance. The persistent question 
 is always by implication ultimate: "What line of conduct 
 will conduce to the largest consuming ability of the largest 
 number of people, and so to the strength of the state ?" 
 
 The passage cannot be dismissed without certain minor
 
 564 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 observations. Thus, the discussion of the terms "cheap" 
 [wohlfeil], "price," and "value" reflects a critical spirit quite 
 in accord with that of Adam Smith. 1 
 
 The proposition with which Sonnenfels covers the whole 
 subject of the price of manufactured goods is : 
 
 The price at which the manufacturer can part with his wares 
 comprises the sum of all the separate outlays which were made up 
 to the time of sale, with addition of the profit (136). 
 
 This decidedly empirical formula is then translated into 
 detail. The elements of price upon what the author puts 
 emphasis are: 
 
 buildings, lumber, and all other common necessities, purchase of 
 material, wages, carriages, insurance premiums, import and export 
 duties, interest on the capital, exchange, in case of wares requiring 
 foreign purchases, and profit. 
 
 The discussion does not deal with abstractions, but general- 
 izes business prudence. The spirit of the whole may be illus- 
 trated by such a passage as the following: 
 
 Not even for the advantage of a manufacture established in the 
 province is it advisable to put restrictions on removal of raw material 
 to another province. For this outgo will not occur so long as buyers 
 are to be found in the locality of its origin who offer acceptable terms 
 of purchase. If it were desired however to give the manufacturer 
 a one-sided advantage, this would amount to promotion of industry 
 [Aemsigkeit] at the cost of land management. Then only can the 
 state hope for permanent advantage when it supports both at the 
 
 As evidence we may quote the note to 135, viz.: "Die Oekono- 
 misten erklaren den Werth: Das Maass des Bodens welches in dcr 
 Erzielung enthalten ist. Dieser BegrifT, ist eben so undcutlich, als 
 unrichtig. Das niimliche Maass Erdreichs von besserer oder schlech- 
 terer physischen Beschaffenheit mit besserer oder schlechterer Bestellung 
 tragt mehr: also wiirde die namliche Sache von verschiedenem Werthe 
 seyn. Der Verfasser des VVerts (Works ?) Essai sur le commerce en 
 gineral, Part I, chap, i, selzt dem Maasse des Erdreichs noch die Arbeit 
 bei, welches den Werth zwar naher bcstimmt, aber immer zu metaphy- 
 sisch ausdrtickt."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 565 
 
 same time . . . . ; so long as the producer can get a proper price 
 for raw material, constraint is unnecessary; so soon however as the 
 manufacturers take advantage of the constraint of export duties and 
 try to oppress the producer, the latter abandons the unremunerative 
 production, and the manufacturer suffers from lack of material 
 (141)- 
 
 The effect upon cost of raw material of duties on imports 
 and exports is discussed at considerable length. Again, the 
 effect of numerous holidays upon the price of manufactured 
 goods is analyzed, and on the ground of the advantage of the 
 state, the term in this case meaning the necessary material 
 prosperity of all classes, the advisability of reducing the number 
 is urged, in spite of the church. 1 Further (153), different 
 situations in which scarcity of laborers is the decisive factor 
 are intelligently treated. A paragraph follows (154) on the 
 advantages of the division of labor. It refers to the classical 
 passage in Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations,* and it borrows 
 from that passage the illustration of pin manufacture. Smith is 
 referred to merely as " one of the more recent English writers," 
 and no indication appears that Sonnenfels had discovered in 
 him any radical importance. The inventiveness of manufac- 
 turers, turned to construction of machinery which saves labor 
 and diminishes that item of cost, is next in order (155). In 
 this connection a qualification is entered which plainly illus- 
 trates the difference between the purpose which Sonnenfels had 
 in mind and the sheer capitalistic standard : 
 
 For the state, cheapness of manufactured goods is merely a sec- 
 ondary purpose, which must not be opposed to the paramount pur- 
 pose, viz., the multiplication of occupations. Everywhere, therefore, 
 where the ways to occupation are in such precise equilibrium with 
 
 1 In this connection we read (152): "Man liest bei Goldasten in 
 den Reichshandlungen;" and a little later, " Fortbonnais in Disc, praelim. 
 zum Negotiant anglois." 
 
 * Book I, chap. i.
 
 566 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 the population that the portion of people whose place would be 
 taken by machines could not be utilized for other labor, the introduc- 
 tion of machines would be harmful. This would be approximately 
 the situation of a state which had no foreign commerce of any con- 
 sequence. The same consideration is to be kept in view in the case 
 of agriculture. The introduction of agricultural machinery would 
 diminish the class of rural folk, and for the state nothing is so desir- 
 able as to see this class as numerous as possible. 
 
 In connection with the subject of export and import duties, 
 as a factor of the price of manufactured goods, another indica- 
 tion to the same effect appears (157). Referring to "the 
 almost universal assumption that customs dues are to be 
 regarded as a profitable branch of the public revenues," 
 Sonnenfels says: 
 
 Since increase of price in the first instance contradicts the para- 
 mount purpose of commerce it is necessary to criticize this theorem. 
 As certain as it is that the revenues of the state must cover the expen- 
 ditures, so certain is it also that inappropriate means may be selected 
 for raising these revenues. Those objects then will be inappropriate 
 in which the first purpose of the state, viz., to have a large population, 
 is hindered, because the impost has an influence on occupation; 
 in which case what may be gained on the one side may be more than 
 lost on the other, and in which by virtue of their very nature, no fixed 
 basis of assessment can be assumed; in which, finally, the collection 
 of the money revenues is not in accord with the main purpose, for 
 the reason that although large sums are collected the main purpose 
 is not promoted; or if this purpose is reached, the revenues would 
 have to be raised to an impossible amount. All of this may be 
 proved in the case of customs [Af&uthe]. 1 
 
 The argument is continued in 158-65. The claim is 
 urged that import duties are taxes on consumption and tend 
 to diminish the output of wealth. They are only admissible, 
 under ordinary circumstances, when they do not have this 
 
 > The author refers to his Abhandlung vom Mauthwesen in the tenth 
 volume of his collected works.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 567 
 
 effect. An export tax discourages foreign use of the ware, 
 and so limits domestic occupation. 
 
 Consequently the finances purchase their momentary advantage 
 at a much too high price, through the loss of land management 
 whose stuff is in less demand, and through the harm to industry 
 whose earnings are in the same degree lessened. 
 
 On the distinction between two kinds of commerce noted 
 above, a passage (p. 242) is a commentary. Speaking of the 
 part played by general frugality if it does not descend to a 
 stinginess which limits the national output more than foreign 
 trade extends it, Sonnenfels says: 
 
 A state which in the last analysis possesses only an economic 
 trade, cannot carry exclusiveness [Hauslichkeit] in its mode of life 
 too far without provoking other states, whose trade is based upon 
 their own products, to imitate this policy with equal vigor. 
 
 A sample of a different sort will show how minutely Sonnen- 
 fels' technology calculated cause and effect from the standpoint 
 of the state. It occurs in the sections on the relations of the 
 qualities of goods to price. The custom of requiring of young 
 artisans a certain number of Wander jahre before they were 
 allowed to work at their trade in their own locality had been 
 referred to as on the whole tending to vagrancy. The author, 
 however, adds (174): 
 
 Considered from one point of view, however, these migrations 
 should not be abolished, but better regulated. Only the most 
 talented should be sent abroad, and that with the previous knowledge 
 of the state, and with certain assistance. According to their branch 
 of trade the. places to which they should go should be designated, 
 and they should be recommended to the embassies at those places. 
 In this way the emigrations would be profitable in gaining for 
 domestic wares the envied perfection of foreign goods. 1 
 
 1 In continuing the subject of the effect of the quality of products 
 on price, Sonnenfels cites (note to 176) Savary, Dictionaire du Commerce, 
 T. IV, art. "Reglement," and Justi, Abhandlung von Manufacturen, 
 Fabriken Reglements.
 
 568 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 A little later (179) Sonnenfels epitomizes the objections 
 to Meisterrecht, and particularly to Manufaclurreglement, die 
 Inspektionen und Beschauanstalten, in a volume translated 
 from the English, with the title rendered from a French version, 
 Versuch iiber die Meisterschaften, The author's name is not 
 given. The book urges the abolition of the institutions named. 
 The reasons are evidently those of very narrow selfishness. 
 Sonnenfels takes the position that every one of them may be 
 answered in favor of continuing existing or similar regulations 
 and supervision, by consideration of the general welfare. A 
 little later, speaking of the policy of encouraging settlement 
 of skilled laborers from abroad, Hume, Geschichte des Hauses 
 Tudor, T. Ill, is cited as authority for the statement that 
 Henry VII, instigated by an outcry of women, drove 15,000 arti- 
 sans, mostly French, from London. Sonnenfels charges 
 England with still maintaining essentially the same attitude. 1 
 
 1 Further references in the chapter are as follows: "In den Briefen 
 dcs La Porte," cited from memory, p. 273; in a note on p. 279 the author 
 remarks: " Die Errichtung der Manufacturhauser ist vor Justi schon 
 von Bodcn in seiner furstlichen Machtkunst, von Schrodern in seiner 
 fiirstlichen Schatz- und Rentkammer, u. a. m., als ein niitzliches Mittel 
 angcpricsen wordcn;" then follows reference to Justi's monograph, 
 Von Manufacturen und Fabriken. Justi is blamed for giving Schroder 
 an empty compliment for proposing that manufactures should be assisted 
 by a scheme of landesfurstlicken Wechscl, an impracticable notion, in 
 Sonnenfels' opinion. Fortbonais, Elem. du Com., chap. Hi, reappears, 
 p. 283, and, in the same note, Hume, Polit. Essays of the Balance of 
 Trade (sic); alie Physiokraten are referred to at the same point, the 
 implication being that they universally support a prohibitive policy with 
 respect to imports; Rcimarus, Handlungsgrundsatze, is named without 
 indicating the reason; a second note on the same page (p. 283) contains 
 a rather pointed criticism, viz., "England, France, even Holland, has 
 prohibitions of imports, and what amounts to the same thing, high 
 entrance rights. When therefore many a writer confidently asserts 
 that commerce flourishes most in stales where universal freedom of trade 
 rules, we are justified in demanding that these states shall be specified;" 
 and finally (p. 299), Nickols; vide above, p. 556.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 569 
 
 We pass to chap, iii, "On Foreign Commerce." In the 
 previous chapter Sonnenfels had shown a decidedly oppor- 
 tunistic attitude toward regulation of foreign trade. On the 
 whole, he is inclined to assume that artificial restrictions of 
 the spontaneous course of trade are likely to work more harm 
 than good. At the same time he holds firmly that it is entirely 
 within the competence of the state to enforce all sorts of restric- 
 tions, provided they actually tend to promote the main end, 
 viz., the multiplication of '^occupations," and thus the increase 
 of population. Besides details under this principal proposition, 
 and technical specifications with which we are not concerned, 
 the chapter contains little that is germane to our purpose. 
 A leading theorem is that, "The ground of speculation 
 is knowledge of foreign countries" (p. 205). The author's 
 expansion of the idea shows sagacity of a high order, and again 
 it must be said that Sonnenfels might be read at this point 
 with profit by everyone who is directly or indirectly connected 
 with foreign trade or the diplomatic intercourse which is based 
 upon commercial interests. The rudiments of the duties of 
 diplomatic and consular representatives, as so long and well 
 understood in Germany, and so tardily practiced in America, 
 are distinctly set forth. Sonnenfels writes rather as a learner 
 from other nations on this subject than as a eulogist of German 
 policy. For example, he remarks (207): 
 
 England especially has selected as ambassadors men of funda- 
 mental insight into the commercial system; such were ''die Kecne, 
 Castres, Fallqucucr, Porter, Walpole" in Spain, Portugal, Turkey, 
 and France. 1 
 
 1 A bibliographical item is to be noted. Sec. 221 expands the con- 
 clusion: "Summing up both sides, we may say with Raynal: 'Fairs and 
 markets in themselves are a mischievous recourse, but occasionally they 
 are serviceable.' " A note adds: "Histoire polit. ft phil. des etablisse- 
 mens de deux Indes, T. IV. Der Verfasser fuhrt die Erfindung der 
 Messen zu dem ;ten Jahrhundert zuriick: als durch die Einfalle der
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The drift of the chapter may be gathered from a part of 
 the closing section (223). The opening sentences read: 
 
 In order therefore not to diminish the useful class of merchants, 
 the state should make common cause with them. Instead of grant- 
 ing letters of nobility to rich merchants upon retirement from business 
 it should rather ennoble the merchant only upon condition that he 
 shall continue to carry on commerce, and shall bring up his children 
 to the same occupation. The state should offer nobility to him who, 
 with certain resources, passes from another stratum into the ranks 
 of the merchants. On occasions where distinctions are to be drawn 
 between classes of the people, for instance, at court festivities, the 
 state should include the merchant class among the distinguished. 
 The protection of the state must be extended to the large, as well 
 as to the small trades, etc. 1 
 
 The standpoint of chap, iv, "On Colonies" may be indi- 
 cated in brief in accordance with the analysis in 224, viz.: 
 
 Colonies have the significance and the purpose, first, of promoting 
 external security; second, of promoting commerce; third, of promot- 
 ing navigation. 
 
 A fundamental presumption is frankly expressed in 225, 
 viz.: 
 
 The mother state will have the preference over every other 
 country in drawing from the colonies those wants which it will either 
 use itself or again export. And in general, whenever a decision must 
 
 Franken und Barbaren in Gallien die Handlung durch ungeheure, und 
 unzahlige Gebiihren gehemmet ward. Die erste Messe war zu St. Denys 
 gestiftct worden. S. den Art. Foire in der Encyclopedic, welche Turgot 
 zum Vcrfasser hat." The following section (222) has a reference to 
 "Coyer, La noblesse commerfant." 
 
 1 This note follows: "Die Selige Kaiscrin liess einst dem ganzen 
 Handelsstand die Adelung anbieten. Viele aus demselben machten 
 von diesem Anerbieten Gebrauch, und fiihren dann auch geadelt den 
 Handel immer fort. Die Erhebung in den Freyherren, und nachher 
 in den Grafenstand, und die Stelle eines K. K. Hofraths hielt H. Fries 
 nicht ab, seine Geschafte mit eben demselben Eifer fortzusetzen, als er 
 vorher gethan hat."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 571 
 
 be made between foreigners and the colonists, the state will seek 
 to secure the advantage for the latter. Whenever, on the other hand, 
 a question arises between the state and the colonies, the state appro- 
 priates the advantage to itself, and deals with the colonies in complete 
 accordance with the principles of foreign commerce. That is, 
 everything which the colonies supply will be accepted only in the 
 simplest form. On the contrary, whatever is supplied to the colo- 
 nies they must consent to take in the most complete form. Thence 
 the mother state derives the increased advantage: it gets its wants 
 in the easiest and supplies the wants of the colonies in the most 
 profitable way, since it increases occupation at home through the 
 consumption of the colonists. These advantages are all the greater 
 since the home government prescribes laws for the colonies, and can 
 exclude all rivals from trade with them. Consequently the mer- 
 chants of the mother state are to be regarded as to a certain extent 
 monopolists as respects the colonies. 
 
 After a few more specifications to the same effect, Sonnen- 
 fels shows that he is by no means in sympathy with the policy 
 which he faithfully analyzes. He says (228): 
 
 Such are the chief principles in accordance with which mother 
 states treat their colonies: principles of armed power, against 
 defenseless weakness, to the injustice of which the lust of expansion 
 
 and the mercantile spirit blind all nations When the English, 
 
 who regard private property in their own island as so inviolable, but 
 treat with contempt the property of inoffensive peoples in other parts 
 of the world, when they, even yet in our century, take possession of 
 every island on which they land, in the name of his British Majesty, 
 are they nevertheless in the eyes of mankind the honorable 
 [achtungswiirdig] nation in which the concepts of freedom and 
 right seem almost exclusively to have been preserved? .... But 
 however many the advantages which are drawn from the colonies, 
 their possession will continue only so long as the colonists are 
 kept in the ignorance, out of which time, the efforts of rival 
 nations, and the confluence of favoring conditions, will sooner or 
 later, but certainly, some time remove them, and will put an end to 
 their dependence.
 
 572 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 A note comments: 
 
 This was written in the year 1763; the outcome of the war with 
 America converts it into a prophecy. 
 
 Chap, v, on "Land Carriage, "calls for two observations only. 
 In the first place, we may note its bibliographical citations. 1 
 
 In the second place, we must recognize the continued atten- 
 tive elaboration of administrative detail. The chapter con- 
 tains hardly more than titles of subjects which have to be dealt 
 with in securing all possible advantage to the state from means 
 of internal communication by land, but merely as a programme 
 or as a catalogue of items to be kept in view by the state, it is 
 a notable reflection of the cameralistic spirit. The details 
 to be dealt with by government under this head are all con- 
 sidered as "means of increasing the national occupation." 
 They vary from construction and repair of roads, the encourage- 
 ment and control of carriers, the provision and regulation of 
 inns, stables, and storehouses for the men, animals, and goods 
 engaged in transportation, to maintenance of the various trades, 
 wheelrights, saddlers, smiths, etc., necessary for conducting 
 the repairs incidental to land traffic. 
 
 Substantially the same is all that need be said of each 
 remaining chapter in the book. In the first place, the printed 
 
 Viz.: first, referring to Cromwell's "Navigation Act" of 1651, a 
 note remarks (p. 351): "Ich kenne nur den Verfasser der Handlungs- 
 grundsdtze zur wahren Aufnahme der Lander, etc., 13, welcher gegen 
 wahren Vortheil dieser Akte einen Zweifel zu erheben scheint." On 
 p. 356 the following occurs: " Das Werk von Bergier, Histoire des grands 
 chemins d' Empire, ist alien unentbehrlich, die diesen Theil der Verwal- 
 tung zu besorgen haben. Gautier, Von Anlage und Baue der Wege und 
 Stadtstrassen aus dem Franz., ist eine kleine Schrift von vieler Brauch- 
 barkeit." Again, p. 358: "Sur les Corvees ist bereits in der Sammlung 
 von Mirabcau aus Schriften unter dem Namen: Ami des hommes, eine 
 schone Abhandlung eingeschaltet." On p. 363 the vagrant observation 
 appears: "Kines ungenannten Anmerkung iiber den Gebrauch und 
 Nutzen des Intelligenswesens."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 573 
 
 sources to which the author acknowledged himself indebted 
 must be noted. 1 
 
 In general it may be observed that dependence upon Forbonnais 
 becomes more evident from this point. On p. 367 is this note: "Es 
 kann meine Absicht nicht seyn, von der Marine anders zu handeln, als 
 nach der allgemeinen Verbindung derselben mit der politischen Handlung. 
 Um wenigstens sich nur einen Begriff derselben zu machen, wird La 
 Science de la Marine par Villeneuve, und das Dictionairc de la Marine 
 zureichen." 
 
 On admiralty law, the author remarks (p. 375): " Die Quellen dieser 
 Seerechte sind des Harmenopolus Sammlung der legum Rhodiarum; die 
 Spanische Sammlung von 1057, welche unter dem Namen consolato del 
 Mare bekannt, das wisbysche Wasser- und Seerechtsbuch, die olero- 
 nischen und hanseatischen Seerechte, die liibekischen Seerechte, von 
 denen Stein eine Abhandlung entworfen hat; die englische Akte; die 
 ordonnance de la marine von Luclwig dem XIV. Hierzu sind die Ver- 
 trage, und das Seeherkommen zu rechnen: von welchen in dem fiir die 
 innerdsterreichische Sehiffahrt entworfenem Editto Marino einige 
 Anwendung gemacht ist." A sentence or two before this passage, 
 Sonnenfels refers to Curland, Grundsdtze des europaischen Seerechts, 
 and this work was apparently his leading authority. 
 
 Referring to the history of men's efforts to improve inland water 
 communication, a note (p. 382) says: "Diese Geschichte hat H. Oberlin 
 in 3 lateinischen Werken gesammelt und bis auf unsere Zeiten fortge- 
 setzt. I, Prisca; II, media aevi; III, jungendorum marium fluminumque 
 omnis aevi molimina. Die osterreich. Staaten sind von vielen Fliissen 
 durchstromt, deren Vereinigung moglich ist, und worviber viele Entwiirfe 
 gemacht worden. Besonders miissen irgend in den Archiven, oder 
 Registraturen die Entwiirfe vom Philibert Luchese, iiber einige Fliisse 
 der Monarchic aufbehalten seyn. Vielleicht sind die Entwiirfe, welche 
 H. Maire iiber die Vereinigung der Fliisse, in den sammtlichen Staaten 
 des Hauses Oesterreich heraus gegeben, und in einem sogenannten 
 Memoir e raisonne sur la circulation inter ieure du commerce, etc., erklart 
 hat, nicht durchaus ausfiihrbar; aber dass es ein grosser Theil derselben 
 ist, kann nicht gezweifelt werden und die Entwiirfe zeigen: wie vor- 
 theilhaft die Handlung aller erblandischen Provinzen unter sich ver- 
 bunden werden konnte." 
 
 In chap, vii, on "Insurance" chiefly marine insurance the only 
 writer directly referred to is Forbonnais (p. 394, et passim). 
 
 In chap, viii (ix), on "Money," Justi is apparently the guide whom
 
 574 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 In the second place, these chapters are cumulative evidence 
 that the center of gravity in Sonnenfels' system was shifting 
 its position. It does not appear that he was conscious of it. 
 He does not directly substitute another aim for the strengthen- 
 ing of the state which had been ultimate with the other cameral- 
 ists. He returns frequently to some variation of the constant 
 theme that the state must look out that the proper thing is 
 done in all these relations, but the reader cannot fail to detect 
 an infusion of more of the spirit of gain for the sake of gain, 
 which distinguishes the specifically commercial from the typi- 
 
 Sonnenfels mainly trusts. On p. 423 he mentions him, and in a note 
 (p. 426) he says, of the particular monograph referred to (Ursachen des 
 verderbten Miinzwesens in Dentschland, und Mittel dagegen): "Dieser 
 Vorschlag ist eigentlich nur eine Zuruckfiihrung der Miinzenbenennungen 
 zu ihrem Ursprunge." In a previous note (p. 525) he says: "Die 
 Schriftsteller welche von den Grundsiitzen der Miinzpragung handeln, 
 haben iibej diesen Gegenstand so viele Dunkelheit verbreitet, dass sie 
 Anfiinger ganz kleinmuthig machen. Diese Dunkelheit riihrt daher, 
 well sie den Grundsatzen eine Menge angewendeter Rechnungsbeispiele 
 mit untermengen, die nicht zu den Grundsatzen, sondern Zum prak- 
 tischen Theile des Miinzwesens gehoren." 
 
 Sec. 291 cites Melon, Essai politique sur le commerce, 2te. Aufl.; 
 also, Dutot, Reflexions politiques sur les finances et le commerce, and 
 Fortbonnais, Anfangsgriinde, II. Tom., chap, ix, "De la circulation." 
 
 In chap, ix, on "The Circulation of Money," there is a reference 
 to "Montesq., Esprit des loix, Liv. 22, "Principes sur le commerce;" 
 to Hume, Essay of the Balance of Trade;" to " folgende Stelle Ustaritzes," 
 viz., Theorie & pratique du commerce, Cap. Ill am Ende; Vol. Ill, p. 150, 
 has the reference: " Ustaritz, Consider, sur les financ (sic) d'Espagne;" 
 to "Plinius, paneg. Traj.," to "X. Band meiner gesammelten Schriften: 
 Abhandlung von der Ursache der Theurung in grossen Stddten und dem 
 Mittel, ihr abzuhelfen;" on p. 494 Hume is quoted again as authority 
 for the statement that although during the minority of Edward (VI ?) 
 interest was prohibited in England, the rate was 14 per cent. (Inciden- 
 tally we may note that Sonnenfels uses "die Interessen" interchangeably 
 with "die Zinsen.") Raynal is cited (p. 496) as authority for tracing 
 disbelief in the justice of interest to the Middle Ages. The Justinian 
 Code is cited (p. 499): "4. Buch, 31. Tit., 26. Gesetze," and five pages
 
 CAMERALTSTICS OF SONNENFELS 575 
 
 cally political standpoint, and which was, consciously or uncon- 
 sciously, the animus of theSmithian political economy. Although 
 Sonnenfels had only in the faintest degree begun to generalize 
 economic problems in the Smithian manner, his dealing with the 
 technique of the subjects treated in the last half of this volume 
 was distinctly an approximation to the Smithian method. 
 
 For various reasons, Vol. Ill, Finanzwissenschaft, must 
 be much more summarily treated than the other two. A few 
 of its general characteristics, however, should be pointed out, 
 and this may be done in the form of disconnected notes. 
 
 later "der Verfasser des Werks, Des corps politiques." On p. 508, 
 referring to the advantages of a low rate of interest, a note begins: 
 " Dieser Gegenstand ist vorziiglich in englischen Schriftstellern behandelt 
 worden." Child and Culpeper are named. Then follows the remark: 
 "In der Sammlung von politischen Abhandlungen, die in V Banden 
 1750 zu Amsterdam bei Schenchzern erschien, sind die verschiedenen 
 fur und wider die Interesseherabsitzung in dem Parlemente gehaltenen 
 Reden, aufbehalten, am ausfiihrlichsten sind Lockes Briefe, welche unter 
 dem Titel: Betrachtung iiber die Miinze, Geldzinse, Finanz und Handlung 
 gesammelt sind. Auch die Vorrede, welche Fortbonais der Uebersetzung 
 des British Merchant vorausgesendet hat, ist eine eigene und mit vieler 
 Griindlichkeit geschriebene Abhandlung iiber die gesetzmassige Zinsherab- 
 setzung." On p. 519, "Dio Kassius" is drawn upon for an illustration 
 of the effect of a sudden increase of money in circulation in raising prices, 
 and at the same time lowering the rate of interest, and Hume's " Essay 
 of the Balance of Trade" is again referred to (p. 520). In chap, xi, on 
 "Trading Companies," Raynal, "Hist, polit, et Philos., etc.," is again 
 used as a source; in chap, xii, on "Exchange," Fortbonais, chap, viii, 
 again appears to be the author's point of departure, and Dutot (op. cit.) 
 is once more named. Siegel, Einleitung zum Wechselrechte, and the same 
 author's ''Corpus juris cambialis, welches Herr Usal fortgesetzt hat," 
 are listed at the end of the chapter. Chap, xiii, on " Commercial Treaties," 
 mentions "die kleine Schrift Les wantages que le Portugal pourroit tirer 
 de son malheur." Chap, xix, on "The Balance of Trade," quotes Hume 
 "in dem Versuch iiber die Handlungsbilanz." At the same time it is 
 asserted that "die Physiokraten halten die Berechnung der Bilanz fur 
 uberflussig." The volume closes with the note: "S. X. Band meiner 
 gesammelten Schriften Abhand. von der Mauth."
 
 576 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 The title-page is a duplicate of that of the first two volumes 
 with the exception that the vignette represents Maximilien de 
 Berthume, due de Sully. 
 
 In the Preface of the first edition the author indicates his 
 purpose to occupy an intermediate position between two 
 classes among the numerous writers on the subject, viz., first, 
 those who have exaggerated their systems into Utopias; second, 
 those who have tried to reduce policies of oppressive exploita- 
 tion to an art. These latter talk only of enriching the treasury. 
 They ask how much may be taken from the citizen without 
 bringing him to the threshold of extreme poverty. 
 
 These contemptible hirelings of tyranny resemble the hunting- 
 dog that scares up the game for the hunter in order to feed on its 
 entrails. 
 
 A third type which, to be sure, is very small, aims at a quite 
 different purpose, viz., the honor of standing for the interest of the 
 people [des Volkes]. These have to reckon with the ruler, and to 
 challenge every expenditure which exceeds reasonable needs. 
 
 In this passage Sonnenfels applies the word Kammeral- 
 schriftsteller to a class of writers on finance who correspond 
 to the term Oekonomieaufseher, as used above. 1 That is, he 
 asserts that they knew nothing of the broad principles of finance 
 but fill their books with the most minute details of private 
 thrift. These petty people should have confined their pride 
 entirely to writing for zealous administrative employees, who 
 might have read their books with advantage. According to 
 this passage, then, Sonnenfels repudiated the name "cameral- 
 ist;" but that was a matter of words, and it does not separate 
 him in fact from the series of writers whom we are considering. 
 
 As between the types thus characterized Sonnenfels hints, 
 rather than directly says, that he intends to write with a view 
 to the general prosperity, rather than chiefly in the interest 
 of the national treasury. He declares that he proposes to 
 
 ' Vide p. 548.
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 577 
 
 write principles of finance, not a finance encyclopaedia; and 
 he advertises the freedom and independence with which he 
 intends to treat the problems. In this last respect he gives 
 the impression of protesting too much. His language serves 
 chiefly to remind the reader of the difficulty of making any 
 presumption except the governmental one tolerable to rulers. 
 Although Sonnenfels praises the magnanimity of the empress, 
 which had protected his freedom of teaching, we read between 
 the lines that he was consciously approaching delicate subjects, 
 and he wanted to conciliate the civic powers as much as possible. 
 The Preface to the present edition contains a paragraph 
 which expresses the author's attitude toward bibliography, 
 viz.: 
 
 In respect to the books to which I have referred in this as well 
 as in the first and second parts, I have this to say: that my inten- 
 tion in such references was not to furnish a literary encyclopaedia. 
 The reader or student does not want a mere list of writings, brought 
 together from catalogues and unreliable journals, without selection 
 and very often without knowledge. He wishes to get acquainted 
 with good writings, from which he may extend the principles which 
 he has gained, and in which he may find further information about 
 this or that subject. With this purpose alone in view I have listed 
 books, and none others than those which I have myself read and of 
 which I can give assurance that they will repay the trouble of con- 
 sulting or reading them. 
 
 It is perhaps a virtue rather than a fault of the first two 
 volumes, that they appear to have been drawn more from obser- 
 vation than from previous writers. Whether it is a virtue or 
 not, the internal evidence does not strongly sustain a literal 
 version of the above claim to personal acquaintance with all 
 the books cited in the parts already discussed. In this third 
 part the citations are more frequent, but this fact merely 
 reflects the state of the available literature. 
 
 It should be noticed too that the volume now before us is
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 full of vivid side-lights upon the issues which were then seething 
 in all the political pots of Europe. Nowhere did the funda- 
 mental issue, government for the sake of the citizen or the 
 citizen for the sake of government, come to more distinct 
 definition than in policies of taxation. The day after the 
 Preface to this fifth edition of the third volume was written, 
 the Assembly of Notables at Versailles was dissolved. Reduced 
 to the concrete, the Revolution was an assertion that taxes 
 should thereafter leave Frenchmen a living. The Revolution 
 told the rest of Europe that the battle could be won. In this 
 academic book one feels the tug of the vested interests upon the 
 earnings of the masses, but what is better, one feels the force 
 of a moral judgment that the masses must not be sacrificed to 
 institutions. There is no assertion of a new social principle 
 here. There is, however, assertion that old social principles 
 must be applied with changed emphasis. So understood 
 the book is a vivid document of political reconstruction. 
 
 On p. 2 Sonnenfels gives his definition of the science of 
 finance, viz.: 
 
 The more necessary is it, therefore, for those interested in this 
 important part of administration to be guided by well-considered 
 principles according to which the revenues of the state may be most 
 advantageously raised. These collected principles are the science 
 of finance [Finanzwissenschaft]. 
 
 The author's formulation of the standpoint from which 
 these principles are to be considered may be summarized as 
 follows: In the first place, we may reduce the general process 
 of financial administration, according to his analysis, to four 
 stages, viz. : first, estimate of the needs of the state, and draw- 
 ing up a corresponding budget [Staatsaufiuandsuberschlag]; 
 second, determination of the resources of the state; third, by 
 comparing the former with the latter, discovery of the propor- 
 tion of the resources which it will be necessary to use in order 
 to cover the needs; fourth, the technique of assessing and col-
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 579 
 
 lecting the revenues. Without attempting to reproduce the 
 author's doctrines of the limits within which the idea of the 
 ordinary and extraordinary needs of the state must be denned, 
 we note, first, that the sources of revenue are divided into 
 two classes, viz. : the mediate and the immediate contributions 
 of the citizens (15). The former class includes revenues from 
 all those sources which are the common property of the citizens : 
 crown estates, regalian rights, etc. The second class includes 
 all revenues which are derived from payments by individuals. 
 As an ideal principle, the former class should cover the ordinary 
 expenses of the state, while the latter should be the means of 
 discharging the extraordinary expenses (18, 19). 
 
 Then follows a most characteristic and illuminating propo- 
 sition, viz.: 
 
 The contribution to the extraordinary expenses must be arranged 
 according to the multitudinous circumstances in which the state 
 finds itself, always however without allowing attention to wander 
 from the well-being of the citizens, which remains under all circum- 
 stances the ultimate purpose of every expenditure (20). 
 
 More than a mere verbal variation is involved in this dictum. 
 Instead of the conventional Wohl des Staates, or the noncom- 
 mittal phrase which occurs in the Preface of the first edition, 
 "die Sache des Volkes," we now have "das Wohl der Burger." 
 Of course it would be absurd to rest an important conclusion 
 upon a single phrase. It is hardly probable that Sonnenfels 
 was distinctly aware of meaning anything different by this 
 phrase from the ideas conventionally associated with the terms 
 in more frequent use. A difference between two stages of 
 civilization might be expressed in the contrasts between the 
 conventional concepts connoted by the technical phrases der 
 Staat, or das Volk, and the democratic phrase, die Burger. 
 The two former presuppose an entity in antithesis with the 
 individual citizens, or a mystic collectivity in which the r61e 
 of the individual citizen is an after consideration. The latter
 
 580 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 phrase connotes a conception that there is no whole except that 
 composed of the individuals whose co-operation gives reality 
 to the state. Even conceding that Sonnenfels consciously 
 meant less by substitution of the new phrase than it means 
 to us, the fact that he made the substitution may legitimately 
 be taken as a straw showing the direction of his own thought 
 and of current opinion. A change of emphasis was taking 
 place. The state as a self-existent entity was becoming less 
 real. The individual was becoming relatively both more real 
 and more important. 
 
 As a means of locating Sonnenfels with reference to another 
 important principle, the opening of 32 is significant, viz.: 
 
 The sources of national income are agriculture and industry 
 [Aetnsigkcit], under which latter everything is included which 
 increases the so-called numerical riches [numerHren Reichthum] of 
 a state. 
 
 Sonnenfels has been called the " systematizer of mercan- 
 tilism." Such a phrase would have to be defined very precisely, 
 and so as to remove most of its proper meaning, before it could 
 be accepted as covering the facts. 
 
 There is no more vigorous nor progressive passage in the 
 three volumes than the discussion (85 ff.) of exemptions from 
 taxation. Sonnenfels tersely disposes of the claims to freedom 
 from taxation on the part of nobility, clergy, and scholars 
 respectively. In a word, his argument is: first, these classes 
 cither are citizens or they are not; second, if they are, this 
 general designation, and the consequent advantages from the 
 protection of the community, carry with them the general obliga- 
 tion of sharing in the costs of government; if they are not 
 citizens, then it would be well for them to consider whether 
 they would gain by release of the state from the obligation of 
 protection which it owes to all citizens. As to the claim that 
 these classes perform a special service to the state, which entitles
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 581 
 
 them to exemption, Sonnenfels declares with rather unusual 
 warmth: 
 
 I at least lay my hand on my conscience, in order to concede 
 that the community could do without my writings better than it 
 could dispense with the labor of the rustic who produces our bread 
 by the sweat of his brow. But I am treating the matter more seri- 
 ously than it deserves. Every social stratum contributes after a 
 certain proportion its share to the common well-being. These 
 contributions therefore cancel one another, and the duty to contrib- 
 ute remains the completely equal responsibility of all. 1 
 
 In the course of the discussion of clerical claims to exemption 
 from taxation the author incidentally utters another opinion, 
 which may not properly be construed as intentionally asserting 
 all that would now be found in it. As a symptom, however, 
 of the fluid condition into which political philosophy was 
 lapsing it is decidedly instructive. Sonnenfels had shown his 
 reasons for concluding that no claim to exemption could be 
 maintained by the clergy on the ground of special divine right 
 or through the claims of an external power, such as the Roman 
 court, and he continues: 
 
 The concessions of princes are the only remaining ground for 
 the daim. Now, in so far as this exemption is a concession of the 
 ruler, it carries with it, like every concession of this sort, the tacit 
 qualification, provided the public welfare is not too nearly affected 
 thereby; in which case it is not alone revocable, but it must be revoked, 
 because no power extends so far as to [be free to] harm the community 
 for the sake of an individual or a class (91). 
 
 Quite as democratic in form, but perhaps even more vague 
 
 1 A note refers to "Justi, Staalswirth. 407," with the comment: 
 "He is the only writer in whom I remember to have read a claim for this 
 exception in the case of scholars. He demands it also for the clergy, 
 but for both only in the case of their personal dues; and he later finds 
 himself obliged, for the same reasons, to call for the same exceptions in 
 the case of all in the military and civic service of the state."
 
 582 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 in application, were Sonnenfels' principles for distributing 
 the burdens of taxation. Thus he says: 
 
 The payments of the individual citizen must be reckoned accord- 
 ing to a double relation: to his own means, and to the means of 
 the other tax-payers With reference to the former, this prin- 
 ciple must govern: the dues must not be so great as to impair the 
 earning-power of the citizen, or to affect his courage to continue 
 earning. That is, whatever is necessary to the continuance of his 
 earning must be free from tax; e. g., first, the necessary support; 
 second, the advance [Vorschuss] or the necessary and useful outlays 
 without which the income cannot be gained at all, or at least in full; 
 third, a portion of income large enough to stimulate the citizen to 
 continued labor. 
 
 In pursuing the argument, the author adds: 
 
 Men whose hearts are of steel and whose temper is hostile to the 
 citizens have tried to make it a principle that a people will be the more 
 
 industrious, the more it is loaded with taxes The difference 
 
 tetwecn stimulating and discouraging taxes consists in this: the 
 former increase the motives for industry, .... the latter diminish 
 
 the motives to labor Even if the slate had a right, therefore, 
 
 to extend the taxes to the limit of support and advance, the self-interest 
 of the state would forbid use of this right. The greater sum of one 
 year would be purchased too dear at cost of the deficit of the following 
 years through loss of energy and decrease of national zeal for labor 
 [Arbeitsamkeit] (99). 
 
 In the same connection Sonnenfels betrays uncertainty 
 bout the precision of the two tests of taxation which he has 
 proposed. Thus he says: 
 
 Certain writers have ventured to define numerically the fraction 
 of income which may be taken for taxes. Men of insight cannot 
 fail to have seen the impossibility of finding such a general numerical 
 ratio. . . . . '* 
 
 In the following section another angle of the subject is 
 encountered : 
 
 In order to determine the ratio of the payments for taxes to the
 
 CAMERALIST1CS OF SOXNENFELS 583 
 
 means of other tax-payers, this seems to be taken for granted as an 
 infallible principle, viz.. The portions to be paid should be to each 
 other as the incomes of (hose who are liable to taxation (100). 
 
 That is, as the context explains, if one citizen has an income 
 of 100, and another of i, the tax of the former should be 100 
 times that of the latter. But Sonnenfels at once points out 
 that this principle cannot be accepted without modification, 
 for, "suppose we consider not the sum which this principle 
 would take from the two citizens respectively, but the sum 
 which would be left to each after the payment." The one 
 might still be left in affluence after the payment, the other 
 might be crowded below the means of subsistence, and. the 
 exact principle is still left in question by the conclusion: 
 
 One sees that no point can be assigned for even an approximate 
 comparison of the abundance of the one with the misery of the 
 other. 
 
 In the next paragraph the attempt is made to help out this 
 vagueness by another specification, viz.: 
 
 Nevertheless one must be fair enough to admit that this striking 
 inequality is not the consequence of the disproportion in the lax, but 
 of the incomparability [Unebenmasses] of means, i. e., of the differ- 
 ence in the strata of civic society, and that the demand to reduce to 
 equality, by means of a finance system, this difference which, at least 
 in larger states, is not accidental, would be senseless. The thing 
 to be considered, in the case of definition of the reciprocal relation 
 between citizens, is that this inequality shall not be increased by a 
 disproportionate burden of taxation. This end will be approached 
 as near as possible by applying the following principle: "The sums 
 to be paid shall be to each other as the net incomes of the taxable 
 citizens; that is, as the sums which remain to each after subtraction 
 of support and advance." 
 
 In the closing section of the chapter (104) the general 
 marks of a good financial system are summarized as follows: 
 
 The same will have to raise the sum reckoned with reference
 
 584 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 to the general national income and adequate for the needs of the 
 state, in so far as the domains [Regalien] and accidental revenues do 
 not yield" the same according to a provincial apportionment cor- 
 responding to the balance of money, from the citizens assessed without 
 exception, in proportion to their net incomes, covering short specified 
 periods, at the time which is least inconvenient, through its own 
 system of collection, which must be as simple as possible. 
 
 Sonnenfels regards the Regalien as either essentially taxes, 
 and to be treated as such, or as auxiliaries of Polizey and 
 Handlung. He declines to elaborate the subject therefore on 
 the ground that Justi was strongest at this point, and may 
 be regarded as the best authority. 1 
 
 This epitome of Sonnenfels' views about finance in general 
 contains all that is necessary for our purpose about his ideas 
 of taxation. He enters at some length into argument with 
 the physiocrats, but his position may be inferred from what 
 has preceded. We may note his use of the phrase, "die einzige 
 Abgabe," for the physiocratic Vimpdl unique which has passed 
 into the modern "single tax." We may also note that while 
 the critique by which Sonnenfels defended his position was 
 quite different from the major premises of the modern single- 
 tax argument, his discussion contains the rudiments of all 
 that has been said for and against the "single tax" as an expe- 
 dient. 
 
 On the whole, Sonnenfels regards the consumption tax 
 \Verzehrungssteuer] as the least oppressive to the tax-payer, 
 and for these reasons: 
 
 First, because it is in proportion to earnings; second, because 
 it is collected at the time when the citizen has the means of payment; 
 third, because it is collected in rates which the payer feels less than 
 any other form of tax (180). 
 
 1 Reference is made to " Staatswirthschaft, System des Finanxwesens 
 und seine 2 Quart bande iiber die Polizey, unter detn Titel: Die Grund- 
 feste zur Gliickseligkeit der Slaaten."
 
 CAMERALISTICS OF SONNENFELS 585 
 
 A single quotation from chap, x, on "Financial Schemes," 
 may complete our study of Sonnenfels. He says: 
 
 Financial schemes are in great part the offspring of the spirit 
 of selfishness, which clothes itself, however, in the garb of zeal for 
 the public good. This must arouse the distrust of the financial 
 administration, and as the anonymous author of the Versuchs tibcr 
 die Staatseinkiinfte says, always rouse the more suspicion against them 
 the more they promise. Every proposition looking to the improve- 
 ment of the income of the state is a financial scheme. However 
 they may be dressed up, these schemes fall into three classes: I, 
 those which propose to facilitate collection, and incidentally to dimin- 
 ish cost of collection; II, those that propose to increase the amounts 
 raised on actually assessed objects; III, those that propose to assess 
 new objects. Before dealing with these in detail, the following two 
 observations may be advanced: I. Every proposition which promises 
 no other advantage than increase of public revenues in general, or as 
 the hirelings are accustomed to express themselves, den Nutzen 
 des atterhSchsten Aerariums, deserves no attention. For the incor- 
 rectness of the principle, the public revenues must constantly be raised, 
 has been exposed. A proposition which aims at the one-sided advan- 
 tage of the treasury is a scheme for exaction. II, Every pioposition 
 which promises larger sums for the state treasury, in spite of the 
 fact that the payers are to pay less, unless it discovers fraud c*- incom- 
 petence in the collection, is at first glance to be rejected. It prom- 
 ises a numerical increase by means of a subtraction. That is, it 
 promises a monstrosity.
 
 CHAPTER XXII 
 SUMMARY 
 
 1. It would be superfluous to argue with students of the 
 social sciences that German experience is instructive. What- 
 ever our opinion of the purposes which German polity has 
 proposed, or of the methods by which the purposes have been 
 pursued, the efficiency of the German civic system is beyond 
 dispute. As an adaptation of means to ends, it operates with 
 a remarkably low rate of waste. 
 
 2. In order to give this factor of efficiency its full valuation, 
 we must look back of German polity to German political 
 philosophy. Here too, for purposes of interpretation, we are 
 under no necessity of approving or disapproving the German 
 conception of the state. We are merely bound to understand 
 it. Americans cannot interpret German polity correctly so 
 long as we assume that its basic thoughts are identical with 
 our thoughts. Whether they ought to be or not is beside the 
 mark. The Germans have done what they have done while 
 aiming at a somewhat different goal from ours, while assum- 
 ing a somewhat different social reality from that which we 
 presuppose, and while consequently applying a somewhat 
 different scale of values to details of available ways and means. 
 
 3. In spite of the necessary inaccuracy of a brief theorem, 
 especially when it is antithetic in form, the contrast between 
 German and American conceptions of civic experience may be 
 stated approximately as follows: From the beginning the 
 Germans have regarded the state as primarily a unit, and only 
 secondarily an aggregate. From the beginning Americans have 
 regarded the state as primarily an aggregate, and only secondarily 
 a unit. This contrast is the necessary starting-point for 
 American interpretation of German polity. The theorem 
 
 586
 
 SUMMARY 587 
 
 is commonplace enough to American students of comparative 
 politics. It is indeed merely a variation of the familiar proposi- 
 tion that German political theory is primarily collectivistic, 
 while American political theory is primarily individualistic. 
 Americans have not given all the attention that would be 
 profitable to the bearings of this fact upon valuation of German 
 political experience. 
 
 If rigid and consistent logic ruled human conduct, the fore- 
 going formulas would not be as true as they are, nor on the 
 other hand would the degree of truth in them have permitted 
 the degree of similarity which actually exists between individual- 
 istic and collectivistic states. In all social affairs we are dealing 
 with relativities, not with absolutes. We have to do with 
 proportions, and emphases, and emotional attitudes, not with 
 fixed quantities. We find accordingly that there are certain 
 collectivistic types of civic conduct, but they are by no means 
 confined to states properly classed as primarily collectivistic. 
 In certain types of situations the most individualistic states, as 
 though with one accord, have recourse to the most extreme 
 types of collectivistic conduct. In like manner, the most 
 collectivistic states tend, in certain situations, toward individu- 
 alistic types of conduct. No state, therefore, can be truly 
 described as a product of either collectivism or individualism. 
 Each state is a resultant of individualistic and collectivistic 
 factors in the mental operations of its citizens and of other 
 peoples. To use a different figure, we may say that in Ger- 
 many collectivism has been the constant predicate, while 
 individualism has furnished the varying modifiers. In America 
 individualism has been the predicate, while collectivism sup- 
 plied the modifiers. 
 
 4. Nor must we allow ourselves to be distracted by the 
 fact that the German conception of the unity of the state has 
 often lent itself to perversions which no theory could excuse. 
 The state has not only been regarded as exterior to the citizens,
 
 588 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 as above and beyond them, as identical with the government, 
 but the government has sometimes been regarded as merely 
 an emanation from the prince, and the prince has been accepted 
 as a ruler by divine right, even when he respected no law that 
 might have restrained his arbitrary will. 1 
 
 We must remember, on the other hand, that individualism 
 as we know it in America has, in its turn, too often degenerated 
 into license of some to invade the rights of others. The argu- 
 ment from perversion cuts about as deep on the one side as on 
 the other. This argument is insufficient either to cast down 
 collectivism or to set up individualism. The legitimate con- 
 clusion from the facts is that neither policy is a self-sufficient 
 principle for control of civic action. Neither policy has been 
 finally correlated, in theory or in practice, with its necessary 
 correctives. The purpose of this book has not been to argue 
 for the one policy nor for the other, but simply to summarize 
 the evidence contained in the cameralistic books as to the 
 way in which the collectivistic idea was interpreted by the 
 Germans during the cameralistic period. This retrospect is a 
 necessary preliminary to intelligent interpretation of subse- 
 quent developments in German civic theory and practice down 
 to the present. 
 
 5. According to the cameralistic conception then, the state 
 was a magnified family with a big farm as its property.' The 
 unity of this family with its estate was symbolized by the prince. 
 Its interests were represented by the prince in such a way 
 that no one could very clearly discriminate between the per- 
 sonality of the prince and the interests of the state. The unity 
 of this farm -patriarchate-principality was so impressive that 
 at first very little occasion seems to have been found for dis- 
 tinguishing between the concepts "welfare of the prince," " wel- 
 
 1 Vide Index, titles "Slate, Theory of," "Quasi-absolutism." 
 
 2 Vide Index, titles "Cameralism as Political Theory and Practice," 
 "Cameralism, Meaning of," "Cameralists," etc.
 
 SUMMARY 589 
 
 fare of the state," "welfare of the people" (considered collect- 
 ively), and "welfare of the people" (considered individually). 
 It is approximately true that the cameralists did not distinctly 
 entertain the last of these conceptions. They implied it from 
 the beginning. They insisted upon valuations which became 
 motives of the German democratic movement after the Napo- 
 leonic period. 1 They furnished schedules which might be 
 adopted as the programme of a rather thorough individualism; 
 yet on the whole their theory, as far as it was published, treated 
 all civic problems as questions of situations within a literal or 
 mystical unity of prince and people. In the last analysis, 
 the knowing and feeling and willing for this unity was to be 
 done by the prince. On the other hand, the good citizen lived 
 and moved and had his being as a sort of organ of a body whose 
 center of consciousness was the prince. 2 
 
 Of course the relationship did not present itself in precisely 
 this form to the cameralists. We are expressing it in our terms, 
 not in theirs; yet it is not sure that a single one among them 
 would have rejected our form of statement. 3 
 
 In general it may be said that political evolution in Ger- 
 many, as everywhere else, has been a variation of adjustments 
 between the extreme conceptions, on the one hand that the citi- 
 zens may, can, and should exist only as functions of the state, 
 and on the other hand that the state may, can, and should exist 
 only as functions of the citizens. The latter conception was 
 latent rather than patent among the cameralists. It is not 
 within the scope of this book to inquire whether there is a pos- 
 sible synthesis of the foregoing thesis and antithesis. We are 
 dealing with men who would have said, and after a fashion did 
 say, that the two views are mutually exclusive. 
 
 1 Vide Index, title "Democracy, Symptoms of." 
 * Vide Index, title "Welfare and Kindred Terms." 
 3 Vide Index, title "Biological Analogy." Similar references might 
 have been multiplied.
 
 590 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 6. Considering the state then as an organism of which the 
 prince was the head and (again in modern idiom) of which 
 territory and population composed the tissues, the cameralists 
 easily reduced the questions of civic polity to this double 
 problem: How may it be well with this state-organism in its 
 internal operations and in its external relations ? l 
 
 By a process which does not fully appear in its elements in 
 the cameralistic books, the cameralists arrived at the major 
 premise that all the problems of "internal and external se- 
 curity" resolved themselves into the question of the princely 
 revenues. We must remember that the social preconceptions 
 of the cameralistic period were thoroughly static. Publicists were 
 apparently no more certain than every other social class that the 
 human lot was a permanent arrangement of social strata. It was 
 assumed that a certain standard of life was appropriate to each 
 stratum, and that, maintenance of this standard of life being 
 assured, it would be impertinent and presumptuous for mem- 
 bers of any stratum to long for satisfactions in excess of the norm 
 for their social level. If then the conduct of the different strata 
 of society could be so ordered by the state that the total 
 activities of the people could be made to result in an increasing 
 margin of material return, above the aggregate demands of the 
 different class standards, the state might appropriate that surplus 
 without injustice or hardship to the individual.* This, in a 
 word, was the programme which the cameralists undertook to 
 formulate. It might be expressed in this way: Given the 
 resources of a territory, the labor capacity of the population, and 
 the customary wants of the different strata, how may the state 
 .so exploit territory and people that the customary wants may be 
 .supplied, with an increasing surplus which may be claimed as 
 public revenue ? 
 
 7. Cameralism was accordingly in no sense an abstract 
 
 Vide Index, title "Security." 
 
 Vide Index, title "Taxes, Burdensome vs. Non-burdensome."
 
 SUMMARY 591 
 
 philosophy, except as every human action connotes to the 
 philosophical onlooker some implied preconceptions. Cameral- 
 ism was an administrative technology. 1 It was not an inquiry 
 into the abstract principles of wealth, in the Smithian sense. 3 
 It was much more closely analogous with grub-staking a 
 prospector or financing a street railroad. It was a theory of 
 managing natural resources and human capacities so that they 
 would be most lucrative for the prince in whose interest the 
 management was conducted. To be sure, just as any other 
 human activity tends to suggest generalizations, this camera- 
 listic technology visibly expanded its conceptions from rule-of- 
 thumb thrift to somewhat comprehensive industrial, commercial, 
 and political principles. It even cast its conclusions occasion- 
 ally at last in forms which seemed almost to anticipate abstrac- 
 tions of the classical economists. On the whole, however, 
 cameralism remained a technology, not a philosophy. It was 
 analogous with the rules of banking which one might learn in 
 the course of practical business. It was not like the philosophic- 
 reasoning in the economic treatises. Not until the Smithian 
 influence began to be felt in Germany did questions of material 
 ways and means cease to be treated on the one hand merely as 
 matters of domestic thrift, on the other hand, merely as matters 
 of political expediency. 3 It is accordingly a fundamental error 
 to treat the cameralistic technology as a system of economic 
 generalizations in the nineteenth-century sense. The theoreti- 
 cal setting of the economic ideas was the paramount political 
 opportunism of the period. The provincialisms of the came- 
 ralists were more essentially political than economic. 
 
 8. In expansion of the last proposition we may specify 
 that tradition has very seriously misconstrued cameralism, in 
 
 ' Vide Index, title "Cameralism as Political Theory and Practice." 
 * No one in the cameralistic series came as near to the Smithian 
 
 type of generalization as several British predecessors of the author of 
 
 The Wealth of Nation:. 
 
 3 Vide Index, title "Economy and Related Terms."
 
 59 2 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 consequence of treating it as a system of doctrines about nine- 
 teenth-century economic problems. The truth is that the 
 cameralists had not come within sight of those problems. 
 They were trying to answer the questions of expediency pro- 
 posed to them by the political opportunism which animated 
 the statecraft of their period. The controlling principle of 
 that type of politics was, let each state look out for its own 
 interests. This meant a policy of readiness for aggression or 
 for resistance to aggression. The foremost consideration was 
 ways and means to protect the state in the constant struggle 
 with other states. In this situation there was no more use 
 for doctrines of abstract economics than there was in the latest 
 special session of Congress, when the main concern was not 
 scientific tariff legislation but the most skilful trading of votes 
 in the interest of particular constituencies. The wonder 
 is not that the cameralists held narrow economic views, but 
 that their ideas of economic relations contained such a small 
 proportion of error. 
 
 The supposed economic fallacies of the cameralists might 
 he expressed as details of the policy known as mercantilism. 
 It would be irrelevant to open the question of the merits or 
 defects of the mercantilist policy in its historical time and 
 place. It would be futile to deny that the cameralists were 
 mercantilists. The significant fact, however, for the develop- 
 ment of the social sciences, is that mercantilism was not an 
 economic generalization at all, as we now understand that 
 phrase. It was a fiscal expedient. It is as fallacious to infer 
 fundamental economic doctrines from the mercantilistic 
 programmes as it would be to impute strange notions of 
 essentials of economics to the American legislators who prefer 
 a tariff to an income tax. 1 There is not a line in the cameralistic 
 books which forbids the conclusion that their authors under- 
 
 i Vide Index, titles "Mercantilism" and "Mercantilism, Its Rela- 
 tions to Cameralism."
 
 SUMMARY 593 
 
 stood as clearly as the physiocrats, or as modern economists, 
 that the extractive industries are the ultimate sources of wealth. 
 The mercantilists did not differ from the physiocrats about the 
 ultimate sources of wealth, but if they had expressed them- 
 selves in the modern way they would have said that was "a purely 
 academic question. " The real difference between mercantilists 
 and physiocrats was on fiscal policy. The former held that it 
 was wiser fiscal policy for governments to put their strength 
 into promotion of commerce than into encouragement of the 
 extractive industries. The latter insisted on inverting the 
 proposition. This disagreement about practical policy no more 
 proved a difference of opinion about basic economic relations, 
 than opposite views about the expediency of a corporation tax 
 in America today would prove that the opponents believed in 
 antagonistic systems of abstract economics. 
 
 In particular, it has been supposed that the mercantilists, 
 and especially the cameralists, held fantastic views of the 
 nature of wealth. This tradition is not supported by the 
 cameralistic books. Their essentially sane assumption about 
 wealth does not appear more clearly anywhere than in Justi's 
 propositions. 1 If a reader had heard none of the misrepre- 
 sentations of mercantilism, however, study of the cameralistic 
 books would impress him from the start with the authors' 
 sense of the urgency of fiscal needs; but he would find nothing 
 which could legitimately be interpreted as an essentially 
 different view of what constitutes wealth from that which the 
 most enlightened modern economist would exhibit if he owned 
 an elevator full of corn, but needed to raise ready money. 11 
 
 Less prominent in the list of alleged errors of the mercan- 
 tilists, and particularly of the cameralists, is their supposed 
 misconceptions on the subject of population. It is frequently 
 implied, rather than positively slated, in allusions to these 
 
 Vide above, p. 339. 
 
 Vide Index, titles "Gold and Silver," "Money," and "Wealth."
 
 594 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 writers, that they supposed increase of population might go 
 on without limit. In fact, so far as they are to be judged by 
 their books, they knew as well as Malthus did that population 
 must always be in proportion to the food supply. 1 They 
 believed that the German lands were undercultivated and 
 therefore underpopulated. They believed that there was no 
 immediate prospect of exhausting the resources of German 
 soil, and therefore it was good governmental policy to promote 
 increase of population by every possible means. They were 
 no more guilty of economic misconception because of this 
 judgment than Kansas farmers are when they advertise for 
 laborers from outside the state to help harvest their crops. 
 
 But the gravest of all the errors of cameralism is supposed to 
 be its connivance with paternalism. On this count we may 
 as well confess judgment at once, but our plea is that the facts 
 do not constitute a fault in the historic sense. The Germans 
 three or four hundred years ago confronted a task which was 
 hardly less appalling than that which Russia is facing at present. 
 The statesmen of the time saw certain elements of the problem 
 much more clearly than we can see them today. In a word, 
 the great masses of the Germans were infants infants in 
 knowledge, infants in experience, infants in feeling, infants in 
 judgment about the conduct of life. They lived in straightened 
 circumstances. No affluence of natural resources stimulated 
 their ambition and allured them to effort. They loved the piti- 
 ful measure of comfort which they could command, and they 
 were timid, even if they were wistful, about enterprises that 
 might improve their condition. How might the dormant 
 powers of these unaroused folk be awakened and enlisted in 
 the task of making the most of themselves and of their material 
 conditions ? 
 
 The method by which the German leaders undertook this 
 task was something like the method by which a levy of raw 
 
 ' Vide Index, title "Population."
 
 SUMMARY 595 
 
 recruits is made over into a regiment of disciplined soldiers. 
 The Germans were divided up into some hundreds of squads, 
 each controlled by a territorial prince who was within limits 
 absolute in his own land. This was of course not a scheme 
 invented out of hand. It was a stage in the historical evolu- 
 tionary process. The arrangement corresponded to the condi- 
 tions and fitted the conditions. Populations largely of peasants, 
 and the remainder mostly artisans who had been incubated in 
 the quasi-communistic guild organizations, and had never 
 learned to walk alone, populations politically and economically 
 in their swaddling clothes, and needing, first, nursery care, 
 then tutors and governors to bring them to maturity this was 
 the situation in which that paternalism culminated which 
 Americans have been taught to despise. The regime would 
 have been impossible in America, because of the difference in 
 conditions. It has been more than justified by its results in 
 Germany. 
 
 9. As was intimated in the Preface, 1 the chief motive for 
 this study was a desire to find out whether history had treated 
 the cameralists fairly, and if not to learn the lesson of this 
 unfairness for methodology in the social sciences. So far as 
 the facts are concerned, it is unnecessary to enlarge upon the 
 statements in the Preface. The cameralists have been mis- 
 understood and misrepresented simply because their own 
 center of attention was ignored, and they were judged as though 
 they were trying to deal with the problems which interested 
 their critics. The consequence has been that a series of writers, 
 unsurpassed by authors of any other period as exhibitors of 
 the social forces which were conducting the evolution of their 
 time, have either been neglected altogether, or they have been 
 represented as freaks, with unimportant relations to the social 
 process in which they occurred. 
 
 The cameralists not only gave voice to the constructive 
 
 1 Pp. xxi, xxii.
 
 59 6 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 civic ideas of an era, but the system which they formulated 
 contains all the essentials of German polity today. From the 
 close of the cameralistic period, and the turning of German 
 political thinking from its natural course by the Revolution on 
 the one hand and Smithism on the other, down to the formation 
 of the VereinfUr Socialpolitik in 1871, so many factors enter 
 into the reorganization of German social science that it is easy 
 to overlook the permanent cameralistic elements. To under- 
 stand modern Germany which is directly and indirectly exert- 
 ing such manifold influence upon the whole world, it is neces- 
 sary to take account not only of present activities in Germany, 
 but of those formative purposes and tentative institutions 
 which the cameralists represent. 
 
 The wider methodological generalization is that every 
 process of thought has its telic coefficient, which must be 
 accurately computed if the thought is to be objectively esti- 
 mated. In other words, we must know what the thinker is 
 consciously or unconsciously trying to do with his thought, in 
 order to value it correctly in the scheme of intelligence. 
 
 If the camerali.sts had been trying to determine the laws of 
 wealth, or value, or distribution, their thinking would have had 
 one force. Since they were attempting no such thing, but were 
 trying to work out a civic technology which would incidentally 
 provide for the necessities of citizens, and thereby furnish the 
 prince with money enough to pay his bills, their thinking has 
 a quite different force. Historical interpretation of the cameral- 
 ists not only turns the strongest light upon the later evolution of 
 fii'ic theory and practice in Germany, but it furnishes a typical 
 case for illustration of the theorem that every system of thought 
 must he interpreted in connection with its peculiar purposes.
 
 INDEX
 
 INDEX 
 
 Absolutism. Vide Quasi-absolu- 
 
 tism. 
 Accidents, public anticipation of, 
 
 523- 
 
 Adams, H. C., 159. 
 Agriculture, 155, 187, 214, 215, 230, 
 
 242, 283, 456 ff. 
 Alexander, 530. 
 A natomiren, 114. 
 Ancien rtgime, 431. 
 Arbuthnot, 556 ff. 
 Aristotle, 33, 210, 220, 221, 227, 
 
 295- 
 Artisanship, promotion of, 54. 
 
 Attila, 334. 
 Aufnahme, 300. 
 
 August, Elector of Saxony, 2, 38, 
 3'3- 
 
 Bacon, 511. 
 
 Balance of power, 332. 
 
 Balance of trade, 350, 541. 
 
 Baumstark, xvii. 
 
 Bearde de 1'Abbaye, 550. 
 
 Beccari, 521. 
 
 Becher, viii, xx, 25, 107-34, 136, 
 
 137, 290, 484, 527, 528, 562. 
 Beiers, 245. 
 Benevolent despotism, 78, 118, 
 
 43i 5 01 - ' 
 Bentham, 485. 
 Bereitestes Vermiigeii (cf. Vennii- 
 
 gen), 154- 
 Berch, 231. 
 Bergier, 572. 
 
 Beschriebene Gesetze, 27, 28. 
 Besold, xviii, 132. 
 Beyer, 240. 
 
 Bielfeld, 267, 453 ff., 258, 496 
 
 54- 
 
 Bierling, 240. 
 
 Biological analogy, 50, 589. 
 Bluntschli, xiii, xiv, xviii, xix. 
 Bode, 170, 528, 568. 
 Bornitz, xviii, 132. 
 Boter, 438. 
 Botero, 133. 
 
 British Museum Library, xxv, 311. 
 Bryce, James, 64, 67. 
 Bureaucracy, no, 446. 
 
 Caesar, Julius, 402. 
 
 Calvin, John, in. 
 
 Cameralism, as political theory 
 and practice, 3, 51, 54 ff., 66, 70, 
 7i, 72, 74, 75, 81, 83, 86, 87, 
 89, 109, no, 145, 146, 151 ft"., 
 188, 197 ff., 246, 252, 280, 282, 
 293, 301 ff., 307ft., 37 iff., 
 376 ff., 423, 451 ff., 459, 476 ff., 
 59 1 - 
 
 Cameralism, meaning of, vii, xiv, 
 1-20, 36, 43, 46, 51, 54 ff., 69, 
 73, 82 ff., 106, JIT, 116, 123, 
 
 135. rsS, l6 7> I( >5 ft- 213, 
 220, 224, 246, 251, 260 ff., 272, 
 277, 283, 294, 370, 394 ff., 434, 
 439, 477 ft-. 405 ff -> 53> 543 ''", 
 555, 572, 5 8} *, 590, 591 f., 595- 
 
 Cameralists, xi, xiii, xv, xix, xx, 
 xxi, xxiv, 6, 1 8, 105, 126, 148 ff., 
 197, 280, 576, 589. 
 
 Cameralu'esen, 280. 
 
 Cameralu'issenschaft, and kindred 
 terms, 18, 189, 211, 220, 222, 
 227, 229, 231, 234, 235 ff., 
 239, 240, 254, 256, 273, 280, 282, 
 283, 297, 298, 299, 315 ff., 
 37 'ft- 
 
 599
 
 6oo 
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Cammer, 148, 197, 229, 269, 279, 
 
 316. 
 
 Capital, concept of, 251, 277 ff. 
 Capitularies, 311. 
 Carlowitz, 205. 
 Casters, 569. 
 Cato, 230. 
 Censorship, 46. 
 Census, 46. 
 
 Chamber sciences, viii. 
 Charlemagne, xiii. 
 Charles I, 325. 
 Charles V, 531. 
 Child, 575. 
 Chinki, 562. 
 Chommel, 245. 
 Cicero, 484. 
 Cohn, 14. 
 
 Coinage, theory of, 52, 103. 
 Colbert, 63, 133, 474, 531. 
 Colbertism, 12, 13. 
 Collectivism, 586, 589. 
 Collegium fundamental, 305, 307. 
 Colonies, theory of, 570 ff. 
 Columbia University Library, xxv. 
 Columella, 214, 217. 
 Commerce, theory of, 52, in, 126, 
 
 174, 225, 343 , 376, 448 ff., 
 
 496, 52, 525 ff-, 542 ff., 567. 
 Community, and related terms 
 
 (cf. Gemeines Wesen), 104, 112, 
 
 227, 228, 229, 2i)i), 315. 
 Conrad's // undit'orterbuch, 2. 
 Consumption, theory of, 563. 
 Corporation tax, 592, 593. 
 Cornell University Library, xxv. 
 Cossa, viii. 
 Coyer, 562, 570. 
 Cromwell, 572. 
 Culpepcr, 575. 
 Curland, 573. 
 
 Daniels, W. M., 159. 
 
 Darjes, viii, 226, 267-84. 
 
 Darwin, 490. 
 
 Democracy, symptoms of, 145, 318, 
 
 394 ff-, 485 ff-, 526, 576, 578, 
 
 579, 589- 
 Dickinson, 108. 
 Diestel, 21. 
 
 Diminishing returns, 98. 
 Dio Kassius, 575. 
 Dithmar, viii, 106, 177, 186, 215, 
 
 222-31, 235, 239, 240, 269, 296, 
 
 297, 309, 48i. 
 "Divine right," 101, 137. 
 Dohler, 190, 199. 
 Du Fresne, 229. 
 Dutot, 574. 
 
 Eclecticism, 481 ff., 485, 519. 
 
 Economy, and related terms, xxiv, 
 12, 19, 36, 49, 50, 57, 109, 113, 
 126, 127, 130, 151, 172, 186, 187, 
 188, 193, 195 ff., 199 ff., 202, 
 209, 210, 21 r, 214, 217 ff., 220, 
 
 221, 222, 223, 226, 227, 228, 231, 
 2 35-38, 240, 241, 242 ff., 245, 
 247, 250, 253, 254, 255, 256, 268, 
 269, 270, 273, 274, 275, 276, 278, 
 280, 282, 283, 288, 290, 293, 297, 
 301, 305, 306, 307, 312, 316, 326, 
 
 329, 366, 376, 437 ff-, 445, 459 ff., 
 482, 483, 496, 531, 534, 544 ff., 
 548, 555, 55 ff-, 564, 5 ( >i. 
 
 Edward I, 516. 
 
 Edward VI, 574. 
 
 Eichhorn, K. F., 64. 
 
 Eigenlhum, 251, 477, 508, 546. 
 
 Eiscnhart, 41. 
 
 Elizabeth, 511, 531. 
 
 Rncyklopedisten, 555. 
 
 Ernst, Her/xjg, 60, 62, 166, 194. 
 
 Ethics of ruler, 100. 
 
 Eudaemonism, xx. 
 
 Extractive industries, 169, 205.
 
 INDEX 
 
 601 
 
 Fallquener, 569. 
 Ferguson, 489. 
 Finanz, 149, 174. 
 Finanzwirthschaft, 132. 
 
 Finanzwissenschaft, 70, 399, 437 
 ff., 453, 496, 502, 575 ff., 578. 
 
 Fiscalists, 6. 
 
 Fischer, F., 223. 
 
 Fischer, P., 244. 
 
 Forster, 207. 
 
 Fond. Vide "Capital." 
 
 Forbonnais, 525, 527, 565, 568, 
 
 572, 574, 575- 
 Frederick the Great, 63, 259, 264, 
 
 266, 267, 268, 414, 453, 458. 
 Freedom, 30, 80, 263, 330, 331, 
 
 413 ff., 420, 421, 467, 508, 517. 
 Frensdorff, 286, 287, 289, 290, 
 
 291, 306, 310. 
 Freville, 556. 
 
 Friederich Wilhelm I, 239. 
 Fttrstenau, 231. 
 Fries, 570. 
 
 Ganser, 527. 
 
 Gasser, viii, 186, 206-21, 222, 223, 
 
 224, 227, 228, 296, 297, 309, 
 
 481. 
 
 Gautier, 572. 
 Geburtsbrieff, 58. 
 Gelekrsamkeit, 275. 
 Gemeines Wesen, 104, 112, 227, 
 
 228, 229, 299, 315, 409. 
 Gentzke, 240. 
 Geoponica, 230! 
 Georg, Herzog, 21. 
 
 Gerhard, 175-84, 193, 206, 248, 
 296. 
 
 Gesellschaft, 318. 
 
 Gcsetzgebung, as synonym for 
 
 Polizey, 505. 
 Gleichmann, 174. 
 Gatting, 556. 
 
 Gold and silver, theory of, 131, 
 157 ff., 168, 205, 339 ff., 347 ff-, 
 448 ff., 471 ff-, 593- 
 
 Goldast, 565. 
 
 Government, forms of, 117 ff. 
 
 Government, purpose of, 88, 98, 
 99, I2 3- 
 
 Great Elector, 63. 
 
 Gross, 236. 
 
 Grotius, xv, 519. 
 
 Grundfeste, 167. 
 
 Gundling, 174, 206, 238, 240. 
 
 Hamilton, A., 148. 
 
 Handlung (cf. "Commerce"), 
 
 149, 496, 502, 525 ff., 552. 
 Harmenopolus, 573. 
 Harvard University Library, xxv. 
 Haugwitz, 288, 310. 
 Haushalter, 312. 
 Haushaltungskunst, 109, 297, 301, 
 
 34, 3S, 3i6, 329, 366, 367. 
 Haushaltungswesen, 227. 
 Hecht, 290. 
 Heeren, xxiii. 
 Hegel, 321. 
 Henry III, 325. 
 Henry IV, 217. 
 Henry VII, 516, 568. 
 Herrmann, 177. 
 Hey, 484. 
 
 Hobbes, 401, 408, 410, 492. 
 Horn, 190. 
 
 Hoffmann, G. A., 225, 244. 
 Hoffmann, J. A., 174, 225. 
 Hohberg, 245. 
 Hohenthal, 187. 
 Hornick, viii, xx, 107, 129 ff., 136, 
 
 137, J 55, '60, 290, 527. 
 Hume, 268, 488, 512 ff., 516, 568, 
 
 572, 575- 
 Huth, 489.
 
 6O2 
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Ickstatt, 229. 
 
 Inama, 40, 130, 185, 186, 206, 223. 
 
 Individual, concept of, 323, 450. 
 
 Individualism, 587, 589. 
 
 Ingram, ix, 556. 
 
 Interest, as civic force, 332. 
 
 Jerusalem, Abt, 233. 
 
 Jesuits, 335, 336. 
 
 Jevons, viii. 
 
 J6rger, 528. 
 
 Joseph II, 63, 483, 484, 551. 
 
 Josephus, 311. 
 
 Justi, G. H., 286. 
 
 Justi, J. H. G., viii, xx, xxii, 2, 86, 
 87, 91, 92, 116, 120, 146, 167, 
 176, 180, 183, 199, 203, 205, 206, 
 209, 225, 226, 229, 230, 248, 259, 
 260, 268, 284, 285-480, 481, 
 487, 496 ff., 498, 503, 505, 509, 
 522 ff., 528, 539, 551, 567, 568, 
 573. 58i, 593- 
 
 Justice, Osse's idea of, 32 ff.; 
 Justi's rules of administrative, 
 337 . 
 
 Justinian Code, 574. 
 
 Kameralwissenschaft, 2. 
 Kammer, 18. 
 
 Kammeralschriftsteller, 576. 
 Kammtrgericht, 2. 
 Kant, xviii, 482, 485. 
 Kautz, Julius, ix, xx. 
 Keen, 569. 
 Kerseboom, 504. 
 Klenck, 170, 171. 
 Klock, viii, 34, 132. 
 Klugheit, 191. 
 Konigliche Bibliothek, xxv. 
 Kolde, 62. 
 
 Kottencamp, 260 ff., 264. 
 Kressen, 177. 
 Kudler, 483. 
 
 Landwirthschaft (Wirth), 445, 534, 
 
 544 ff. 
 
 Langemack, 438. 
 La Porte, 568. 
 Lau, T. L., 173, 225. 
 Lau, 438. 
 
 Leib, J. G., 172, 182, 190. 
 Leibniz, xviii, 287. 
 Leipzig, University of, 31, 39. 
 Leopold I, 63, 290. 
 Lexis, 2. 
 Livy, 311. 
 
 Locke, xv, 492, 575. 
 Lohneyss, 40, 69. 
 Loen, 263 ff., 265. 
 Louis XIV, 467, 474, 573. 
 Louis XVI, 121. 
 Luchese, 573. 
 
 Ludewig, 215 ff., 223, 233, 260, 
 296. 
 
 Luxury, theory of, 535 ff. 
 
 Machiavelli, 327, 418. 
 Malthusianism. Vide "Popula- 
 tion." 
 
 Maimbourg, 61. 
 Maire, 573. 
 
 Malthus, 444, 501, 594. 
 Manufactures, 160 ff., 174. 
 
 Manufactures, productiveness of, 
 557 ff., 561 ff. 
 
 Marc, De la, 439. 
 
 Marchet, G., xix, xx, 136. 
 
 Maria Theresia, 288, 310, 311, 
 
 468 ff., 483 ff., 570. 
 Mark, 550. 
 Marperger, 172, 190. 
 Maximilian I, 2. 
 
 Means (Mittel) (cf. Vermogen), 
 
 249, 251, 258. 
 Meixner, 527. 
 Melancthon, 22.
 
 INDEX 
 
 603 
 
 Melon, 504, 574. 
 
 Mercantilism, 7, 8, 14, 131, 133, 
 
 159 ff., 187, 265, 363, 366, 422 ff., 
 
 456, 464, 479, 500. 
 Mercantilism, relation to cameral- 
 ism, 10, 12, 63, 151 ff., 1598., 
 
 580, 59*- 
 Mercantilists, ix. 
 Merchants, protection of, 570. 
 Merkel, 550. 
 Meusel, 267, 292. 
 Mill, J. S., 285, 469 ff. 
 Mining, 358 ff. 
 Mirabeau, 572. 
 Moser, J., xviii, 63. 
 Mohl, R. V., xiv, 12, 13, 242, 256, 
 
 444, 477 ff- 
 
 Monarchomachi, 324, 325. 
 Money, theory of, 131, 157 ff., 
 
 448 ff., 47 iff-, 478 ff-, 593- 
 Monopolio, no, 128 ff., 562. 
 Montesquieu, xv, 393, 397, 433, 
 
 486, 505, 507, 511, 574. 
 Moritz, Herzog, 21, 22. 
 Moritz of Sachsenzeitz, 61, 94. 
 Moser, J. J., 268, 284. 
 
 Nahrung, and related terms, 72, 
 189, 228, 236, 250, 254, 434, 
 442. 
 
 National management, 19. 
 
 Nationals konomik, 19. 
 
 Navigation, value of, 53. 
 
 Nickols, 556, 568. 
 
 Niebuhr, xiii, 295. 
 
 Oberlin, 573. 
 
 Obrecht, Georg, 2, 25, 34, 40 ff. 
 Obrecht, J. T., 42 ff., 201. 
 Obrigkeit, and similar terms, 25, 
 
 114, 1 1 6, 1 1 8, 124. 
 Oekonomieaufseher, 548, 576. 
 Oppenheim, 108. 
 
 Ordnung, 30. 
 
 Osse, 2, 21 ff., 45, 146, 166, 206, 
 208, 271. 
 
 Palgrave, ix. 
 
 Pascal, 94. 
 
 Paternalism, 446, 594. 
 
 Penalties, 519 ff. 
 
 Peter I, 467. 
 
 Philip of Macedon, 531. 
 
 Philipp, Landgrave of Hesse, 2,313. 
 
 Philippi, 264 ff. 
 
 Phlogiston theory, 107. 
 
 Physiocrats, viii, ix, 483, 568, 575, 
 593- 
 
 Pliny, 574. 
 
 Ploetz, 64. 
 
 Policey, 26, 28, 30, 33, 35, 37, 38, 
 46, 55 ff., 70, 74, 88, 1 10, 115, 
 126, 149, 160, 166, 174, 202, 218, 
 
 222, 225, 240, 253, 254, 257, 258, 
 
 265, 269, 297, 301, 326, 329, 
 
 376, 399, 487, 502, 505 ff. 
 Policeywissenschaft, 91, 167, 224, 
 
 226, 227, 228, 229, 231, 234, 256, 
 
 328, 336 ff., 495 ff., 505. 
 Political economy and kindred 
 
 terms. Vide "Economy." 
 IIoXiTefa, 283, 284, 455. 
 Political ethics, 100, 103. 
 Political science, and related terms 
 
 (cf. Stoats-, etc.), 70, no, 178, 
 
 180, 183, 191 ff., 209, 211, 227, 
 
 235 ff., 241, 35, 52- 
 Politische Handlungsu'issenschaft, 
 
 S3 1 - 
 
 Poly polio, no, 128 ff. 
 
 Pope, 483. 
 
 Population, theory of, 15, 97, 265, 
 341 ff., 421 ff., 444, 464 ff-, 
 477 ff., 500 ff., 503, 531, 553 ff., 
 566, 593- 
 
 Population, as norm of civic wel- 
 fare, 531.
 
 604 
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Porter, 569. 
 
 Pragmatism, 275. 
 
 Price, theory of, 551 ff., 563 ff. 
 
 Production, and similar terms, 
 
 532, 534, 551, 558. 
 Property (cf. Vermogen), 250, 
 
 374, 477, 546. 
 Propolio, no, 128 8., 562. 
 Pufendorf, xviii. 
 
 Quasi-absolutism, 63, 73, 74, 76, 
 77, 78 ff., 88, 89, 122, 124 ff., 
 137 ff., 145, 162, 181, 194, 198 ff., 
 262 ff., 265, 320 ff., 324, 325, 326, 
 328, 373, 374, 397, 403 ff-, 405, 
 408, 412 ff., 415 ff- 423 ff., 
 431 ff., 466 ff., 482, 485, 491, 
 493 ff-, 495, 588. 
 
 Ranke, Leopold, xii. 
 
 Rau, ix, 294. 
 
 Raynal, 569, 574, 575. 
 
 Ready means (cf. "Means"), viii, 
 
 154, 157 ff-, 250, 441- 
 Regalien, 297. 
 Reichskammer, 2. 
 Reichthum, 154, 156, 157 ff. 
 Reimarus, 568. 
 Reinking, 438. 
 Religion, civic value of, 474 ff., 
 
 511 ff. 
 
 Rcntwissenschaft, 227. 
 Republic, 112, 126, 181, 182, 251, 
 
 295, 299, 3 * 7, 3 8 > 320, 324, 409, 
 
 468. 
 
 Revenue, significance of to camc- 
 ralists, viii, 156 ff., 161 ff., 277, 
 279. 
 
 Ricardo, 489. 
 
 Richter, 267, 268, 275. 
 
 Rohr, 185-205, 209 ff., 221, 222, 
 227, 245, 273, 284- 
 
 Roman law, 300. 
 
 Roscher, Wilhelm, ix, xi, xii, xiii, 
 
 xvi, xviii, xix, xx, xxii, 18, 19, 22, 
 27, 61, 62, 63, 77, 83, 108, no, 
 127, 130, 132, 135, !7o, 171, 172, 
 173, 175, 186, 187, 207, 222, 223, 
 225, 231, 232, 233, 234, 238, 
 259, 263, 267, 268, 272, 273, 284, 
 286, 291, 292, 310, 311, 453, 
 481 ff., 485, 487, 497, 500, 504, 
 59, 519, 527, 549- 
 
 Rossig, xviii. 
 
 Rousseau, 484, 490, 492. 
 
 Rudolf II, 43. 
 
 Ruprecht von der Pfalz, 108. 
 
 Savery (Savary), 245, 567. 
 
 Savigny, xiii. 
 
 Scclelon polUicum, 114. 
 
 Schlettwein, 556. 
 
 Schlozer, 453. 
 
 Schmeizel, 240. 
 
 Schmoller, G., xx, 7, 8, 10. 
 
 Schonberg, 205. 
 
 Schrammer, 438. 
 
 Schreber, 174, 223, 224, 225, 231. 
 
 Schroder, viii, xx, 34, 107, 132, 
 135-74, 177, !86, 189, 190, 197, 
 203, 204, 205, 212, 269, 279, 290, 
 361, 374, 382, 403 ff-, 452, 527, 
 568. 
 
 Schroderismus, 135. 
 Seckendorff, viii, xx, 2, 41, 60-106, 
 109, no, in, 119, 135, 166, 175, 
 
 186, 190, 194, 217, 201, 212, 213, 
 221, 269, 285. 
 
 Security, 332, 334, 420, 47, 494, 
 5075., 517 ff., 522 ff., 590. 
 
 Seligman, E. R. A., 293. 
 
 Seminar method, 308, 309. 
 
 Serra, 133. 
 
 Siegel, 575. 
 
 Sieyes, 413. 
 
 Single tax, 584. 
 
 Smith, Adam, vii, x, 3, n, 12, 19, 
 69, 84, 105, 154, 156, 167, 168,
 
 179, 2 4, 246, 248, 272, 285, 298, 
 
 3(56, 316, 322, 366, 373, 378, 382, 
 
 468, 483, 489, 530, 551, 564, 565, 
 
 574, 575, 59i- 
 Social concept, 112. 
 Social conditions, duties of mon- 
 
 archs toward, 335 ff. 
 Social contract, 198, 517. 
 Social psychology, 72. 
 Social sciences, crudeness of, i. 
 Social strata, 114. 
 Societal, 318. 
 Sonnenfels, viii, 2, 86, 146, 260, 
 
 481-585. 
 
 Spencer, H., 179, 300, 301. 
 Spener, 94. 
 Staathalter, 324. 
 Staaisgelahrtheit, 177. 
 Staatshaushaltung, 50. 
 Staatsklugheit, 177, 178, 190, 237, 
 
 244, 495, 530, 532. 
 Staatskunst, 70, 178, 305, 327, 376, 
 
 399, 437, 441, 453 ff- 
 
 Staatslehrt, 178. 
 
 Staatswirtschaft, xxiv, 293 ff., 305, 
 315, 498. 
 
 Staatswissenschaft, xiv, 241, 494 ff., 
 498, 500 ff., 503, 505. 
 
 Stadtwirthschaft, no, 482. 
 
 State, Becher's definition of, 113; 
 Zincke's concept of, 252; Justi's 
 concept of, 323, 331, 400 ff., 450, 
 474; Sonnenfels' concept of, 
 490 ff., 499, 553, 579 ff. ; Ger- 
 man vs. American idea of, 586, 
 588, 589. 
 
 Statecraft, Justi's precepts of, 
 332 
 
 Steuart, 496. 
 
 Stewart, D., 179. 
 
 Stieda, 206, 224, 229, 231, 235, 236, 
 237, 259, 268, 289, 296. 
 
 Stinzing, 206. 
 
 INDEX 605 
 
 Sitsser, 106, 176, 223, 224, 225, 
 
 238 ff. 
 
 Stollen, 177. 
 St. Real, 496. 
 Struven, 177. 
 Subjects, duties of, 365 ff. 
 Sussmilch, 504, 554. 
 Suetonius, 311. 
 Sully, 63, 531, 576. 
 Surplus, 154 ff., 242. 
 
 Tacitus, 402. 
 
 Tamerlain, 334. 
 
 Taxation, 174, 381, 590. 
 
 Tax-dodging, 99, 580. 
 
 Taxes, burdensome vs. non-bur- 
 densome, 49, 590. 
 
 Thorn, 229. 
 
 Thomas, W. I., 465. 
 
 Thomasius, 22, 23 ff., 40, 45, 166, 
 171, 206, 208, 209, 210, 215, 240. 
 
 Tillinghast, 46. 
 
 Toussaint, 507. 
 
 Towns, management of, 369 ff. 
 
 Transportation, by land, theory 
 of, 572. 
 
 Traders, value of, 53, 127. 
 
 Treasury, public, necessity of, 
 254 ff., 142 ff. 
 
 Turgot, 570. 
 
 Ueberfluss, 154 ff. 
 Usal, 575- 
 Ustaritz, 574. 
 Utilitarian symptoms, 280. 
 Utopia, Schroder's, 143; Justi's, 
 425 ff. 
 
 Value, theory of, 564 ff. 
 
 Vauban, 382, 554. 
 
 Varro, 230. 
 
 Velter, 439. 
 
 Vereinfur Social poliiik, 596.
 
 6o6 
 
 THE CAMERALISTS 
 
 Verfassung, 34, 70, 341, 399. 44i, 
 
 508. 549- 
 Vergesellschaftung mil seines Glei- 
 
 chen, 489, 499. 
 Vergil, 230. 
 Verldger, 128. 
 Verm&gen, 76, 250, 251, 307, 327, 
 
 366. 367, 373 ff-> 375, 4t 44O, 
 
 532, 546. 
 Villeneuve, 573. 
 Vogemont, 528. 
 Volkswirthschaft, 290, 483. 
 
 Walpole, 569. 
 
 War, ethics of, 99, 102. 
 
 Warburton, 511. 
 
 Weakh, theory of, 131, 154, 156 ff., 
 
 168, 171, 203 ff., 253, 339 ff., 
 
 422 ff., 470, 592, 593. 
 
 Weise, C., 237. 
 
 Weitzel, xiv. 
 
 " Welfare, " and kindred terms, 30, 
 39. 58, 74, 86-88, 96, 112, 142, 
 173, 180, 181, 194, 226, 227, 236, 
 243, 244, 249, 250, 260, 262 ff., 
 
 264 ff., 310, 319, 323, 324, 325, 
 329, 404 ff., 413, 454, 461, 490, 
 492 ff., 497 ff., 501, 503, 524, 
 526, 530 ff., 579, 589. 
 
 Wiegand, 556. 
 
 Wildvogel, 177. 
 
 Wirth, 276, 296. 
 
 Wirthschaftslehre, 12. 
 
 Woelnor, 550. 
 
 Wolff, xviii, 438, 482, 496. 
 
 Young, Arthur, 556. 
 
 Zanoni, 504. 
 
 Zedler, 186. 
 
 Zincke, 206. 
 
 Xenophon, 230, 284, 455. 
 
 Zarncke, 21. 
 
 Zimmermann, 232. 
 
 Zincke, 14, no, 225, 229, 232-66, 
 268, 284, 297, 309, 316, 437 ff., 
 439, 481. 
 
 Zinzendorf, 108. 
 
 Zschackwitz, 224. 
 
 Zusammenfluss, 562.
 
 University of California 
 
 SOUTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY 
 
 Return this material to the library 
 
 from which it was borrowed. 
 
 JAN 15
 
 A 000519419 6